Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page i
Aesthetic Reason
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page ii
L i t e r a t u r e...
52 downloads
1231 Views
1MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page i
Aesthetic Reason
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page ii
L i t e r a t u r e
a n d
P h i l o s o p hy
A. J. Cascardi, General Editor This series publishes books in a wide range of subjects in philosophy and literature, including studies of the social and historical issues that relate these two fields. Drawing on the resources of the Anglo-American and Continental traditions, the series is open to philosophically informed scholarship covering the entire range of contemporary critical thought. Already published: J. M. Bernstein, The Fate of Art: Aesthetic Alienation from Kant to Derrida and Adorno Peter Bürger, The Decline of Modernism Mary E. Finn, Writing the Incommensurable: Kierkegaard, Rossetti, and Hopkins Reed Way Dasenbrock, ed., Literary Theory After Davidson David Haney, William Wordsworth and the Hermeneutics of Incarnation David Jacobson, Emerson’s Pragmatic Vision: The Dance of the Eye Gray Kochhar-Lindgren, Narcissus Transformed: The Textual Subject in Psychoanalysis and Literature Robert Steiner, Toward a Grammar of Abstraction: Modernity, Wittgenstein, and the Paintings of Jackson Pollock Sylvia Walsh, Living Poetically: Kierkegaard’s Existential Aesthetics Michel Meyer, Rhetoric, Language, and Reason Christie McDonald and Gary Wihl, eds., Transformation in Personhood and Culture After Theory Charles Altieri, Painterly Abstraction in Modernist American Poetry: The Contemporaneity of Modernism John C. O’Neal, The Authority of Experience: Sensationist Theory in the French Enlightenment John O’Neill, ed., Freud and the Passions Sheridan Hough, Nietzsche’s Noontide Friend: The Self as Metaphoric Double E. M. Dadlez, What’s Hecuba to Him? Fictional Events and Actual Emotions Hugh Roberts, Shelley and the Chaos of History: A New Politics of Poetry Charles Altieri, Postmodernisms Now: Essays on Contemporaneity in the Arts Arabella Lyon, Intentions: Negotiated, Contested, and Ignored Jill Gordon, Turning Toward Philosophy: Literary Device and Dramatic Structure in Plato’s Dialogues Michel Meyer, Philosophy and the Passions: Towards a History of Human Nature. Translated by Robert F. Barsky Reed Way Dasenbrock, Truth and Consequences: Intentions, Conventions, and the New Thematics David P. Haney, Ethics, Hermeneutics, and Romanticism: The Challenge of Coleridge
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page iii
Aesthetic Reason Artworks and the Deliberative Ethos
Alan Singer
The Pennsylvania State University Press University Park, Pennsylvania
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page iv
Disclaimer: Some images in the original version of this book are not available for inclusion in the eBook.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Singer,Alan, 1948– Aesthetic reason : artworks and the deliberative ethos / Alan Singer. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-271-02312-0 (cloth : alk. paper) 1. Aesthetics. I. Title. BH91 .S56 2003 111'85—dc21 2003007010 Copyright © 2003 The Pennsylvania State University All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America Published by The Pennsylvania State University Press, University Park, PA 16802-1003 The Pennsylvania State University Press is a member of the Association of American University Presses. It is the policy of The Pennsylvania State University Press to use acid-free paper. Publications on uncoated stock satisfy the minimum requirements of American National Standard for Information Sciences—Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Material,ANSI Z39.48–1992.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page v
Contents
Acknowledgments
vii
Introduction
1
1
The Adequacy of the Aesthetic
9
2
Aesthetic Community: Recognition as an Other Sense of Sensus Communis
41
Acting in the Space of Appearance: Incontinent Will and the Pathos of Aesthetic Representation
71
3
4
Beautiful Errors: Aesthetics and the Art of Contextualization
103
Aesthetic Corrigibility: Bartleby and the Character of the Aesthetic
139
6
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics
173
7
Living in Aesthetic Community: Art and the Bonds of Productive Agency
219
Notes
275
Bibliography
289
Index
297
5
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page vi
For Nora,Alex, and Anna, my best aesthetic reasons
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page vii
Acknowledgments
While this book honors the reasons art can give us to act, the act of its writing is indebted first and foremost to the continuity of reasoned discussion. I want to express my gratitude to colleagues and students who have contributed richly to the conversation. My graduate students in aesthetics and literary theory at Temple University and, most particularly, the mix of artists and students who have participated in the Temple Seminars in Art and Culture in Rome over the past many summers and helped focus the lines of perspective drawn here. My teaching colleagues in Rome, Susan Stewart, Robert Caserio, Evelyn Tribble, William Van Wert, Brunella Antomarini, and Pia Candinas have been inspiring collaborators in the enterprise. Many others have patiently and generously contributed to the progress of the arguments unfolded here: Daniel T. O’Hara has helped shape the structure of the manuscript from its first pages. Charles Altieri, Ralph Berry, David M. Rasmussen, Franca Camiz, Steven Cole, and Ross Posnock have read drafts of chapters and contributed astute commentary. I want to thank Sandy Thatcher,Tony Cascardi, and Gregg Horowitz at Penn State Press for their support and generous appreciation of this project. I must give particular mention to Allen Dunn and, once more, Robert Caserio for their sustained and energetic debate about matters of art and act, over many years.Without their conviction and principled critique I would have made many missteps. I would like to thank Professor Guido Traversa and the Accademia D’Ungheria in Rome for allowing me to present a portion of this book as an invited talk. A study leave from the College of Liberal Arts at Temple University enabled me to set the foundation for this work and hasten its completion. Finally, I wish to acknowledge the publication of earlier versions of some chapters in article form: “The Adequacy of the Aesthetic,”
Singer.book
9/12/03
viii
11:21 AM
Page viii
Acknowledgments
Philosophy and Social Criticism 20, no. 1/2 (1994): 39–72; “Aesthetic Community: Recognition as an Other Sense of Sensus Communis, Boundary 2, vol. 24, no. 1 (1997): 205–36; “Acting in the Space of Appearance: Incontinent Will and the Pathos of Aesthetic Representation,” Annals of Scholarship 11, no. 3 (1997): 239–71; “Beautiful Errors: Aesthetics and the Art of Contextualization,” in Thinking Through Art: Aesthetic Agency and Global Modernity (special issue) Boundary 2, vol. 25, no. 2 (1998): 7–34;“Aesthetic Corrigibility: Bartleby and the Character of the Aesthetic,” Journal of Narrative Theory 23, no. 3; “Scieglier e di Vedere: Rendere Visibile il Fare Estetico,” trans. Brunella Antomarini, Montag: Collana Periodica Filosofia 25 (July 1997).
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 1
Introduction
ARGUMENT In this book I defend the category of the aesthetic as a cognitive resource for literary study. The anti-aesthetic rhetoric that permeates much contemporary literary debate charges that the aesthetic either invites irrational sensuous indulgence or embodies elitist class-biased standards of taste, which are ideologically complicit with instrumental reason. The aesthetic is thereby judged inadequate to the tasks of social agency and ideology critique. Such conclusions have produced a curious disengagement of literary theory from literary art. They epitomize an unwillingness to own up to the aesthetic value of the literary artwork. By contrast, in this volume, I demonstrate the relevance of the aesthetic to practical rationality and, by extension, to the social context within which literary art is produced. Working out of Aristotelian ethics, the epistemological and formal features of classical tragedy, and Alexander Baumgarten’s seminal attempt to theorize a cognitive aesthetic in the early eighteenth century, I strive to reconcile post-Kantian aesthetics with the more worldly goals of contemporary literary theory. But this reconciliation will be made coherent with a comprehensive account of literary production. Treating the aesthetic chiefly as a presentation of sensuous particulars that compels a reconfiguration of conceptual wholes, I argue that the aesthetic has affinities with the logic of reversal/recognition in Greek tragedy, with contemporary thinking about human agency and with ethical theories of subject formation based on intersubjective recognition. These affinities suggest how the aesthetic might serve protocols of rational choice-making and ethical subjectivity that legitimate aesthetic practice as a meaningful social enterprise rather than as a guilty refuge from the conflicts of social existence. The past twenty years of literary study have witnessed a subtle disarticulation of theories of literary art from the category of the aesthetic.
Singer.book
2
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 2
Introduction
As a result the aesthetic has not only ceased to be a bridge between the literary text and the philosophical grounds on which notions of literary form (at least since Aristotle) have been erected, but it has also become the object of a concerted attack by cultural materialists, deconstructionists, neo-Marxists, new historicists, and popular culturalists. Works such as Terry Eagleton’s Ideology of the Aesthetic, Tony Bennett’s Outside Literature, Pierre Bourdieu’s Distinction, and Hal Foster’s anthology, The Anti-Aesthetic, are indicative of the current presumption that the aesthetic, in its complicity with class-based ideologies of distinction, its political disinterestedness, and its irrationalist, sensuous decadence, can no longer serve the socially responsible purposes of literary study. The aesthetic, thus caricatured as a nefarious tool of Enlightenment dogmatism, is judged to be woefully inadequate to the most urgent tasks of literary criticism. Literary judgment is now seen to be intertwined with imperatives of political agency and social justice that are, in turn, intended to remedy the ills of post-Enlightenment culture. For these reasons, my defense of the aesthetic is based on a realignment of our understanding of the aesthetic with Enlightenment rationality. I seek to redefine the conflicts between post-Enlightenment subjectivity and aesthetic experience. In this way I want to show how aesthetic theory is surprisingly well suited to the project of carrying through the project of Enlightenment without succumbing to the authoritarian excesses of the Enlightenment ego. In this purview we can envision an ethical legitimacy in aesthetic interests that cannot easily be dismissed by the political agendas of poststructuralist literary theory. Even more pointedly, we will envision an aesthetic interest that, because it is intimately connected to the wellsprings of subjective agency, might further political agendas in more convincingly political ways. Specifically, I will seek to engage the cognitive resources ascribed to aesthetic value by Alexander Baumgarten in the seminal works Reflections on Poetry (1711) and Aesthetica (1750). The nineteenthcentury drift of aesthetic theory in the direction of affectively based intuition and conceptually indeterminate judgments invites us to forget that Baumgarten originally gave currency to the term aesthetic by positing the parity of artistic production with methods of rationalist understanding. Paradoxically, Baumgarten’s assumption that the aesthetic is compatible with rationalist principles was quickly challenged by Enlightenment philosophy on the grounds that it lacked cognitive rigor. Consequently the category of the aesthetic, christened by Baumgarten, gained currency under the sway of later Enlightenment culture in the noncognitive guise of the Kantian judgment of taste.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 3
Introduction
3
Aesthetic theory pursued increasingly nonconceptual rationalizations of aesthetic perfection in works by Friedrich Schiller, Samuel Taylor Coleridge, Percy Byssche Shelley, Matthew Arnold, Walter Pater, Clive Bell, and Monroe Beardsley. For all these theorists, the aesthetic courted autonomy at the cost of community. It is not surprising, then, that noncognitive aesthetics, gaining prestige under the auspices of Enlightenment reason, paradoxically became increasingly independent of, if not alienated from, rational agency. Nevertheless, it came to be identified, in another paradoxical turn of fate, with the increasingly oppressive authority of Enlightenment reason. The late twentieth-century critique of Enlightenment reason consequently found aesthetic theory to be complicit in the reifying, instrumentalizing vices of Reason, despite the legacy of eighteenthcentury Reason’s contempt for aesthetic irrationality. As a result, we should not be surprised that the aesthetic is currently vilified for being both too affectively based, too irrational, and too ideologically invested in the instrumentalizing ends of rationalist ideology. I want to reconsider the cognitivist roots of modern aesthetic theory in order to salvage it from the cognitive dissonances of these contradictory claims. It will therefore not be presumptuous of me to propose that this work provides a basis for speculating how the category of the aesthetic serves to comprehend the role of the literary in relation to the problems of subjective agency, ideology critique, and ethical community. I believe that the premise for this claim is strengthened in observing that the cognitivist aims of Baumgarten’s aesthetic are strikingly coherent with an older Greek tradition of equating aesthetic judgment (in Aristotelian phronesis, and in the peripeteia of Greek tragedy) with protocols of human deliberation and rational action. These, in turn, are strikingly concordant with Schiller’s ideal of an aesthetic state. In Schiller’s model of the aesthetic state, artistic practice and social community are reciprocating projects, preempting the dualisms of art and life that now flourish in the rhetoric of the anti-aesthetic schools of contemporary criticism. Following the spirit of the Schillerian initiative, then, Aesthetic Reason posits a continuity between aesthetic value and rational value that inheres not so much in the ends but in the means of rational self-reflection and ethical action. As I have already said, much of the contemporary suspicion of the aesthetic seems to be based on the proposition that the formalist bias of aesthetic value is utterly incommensurable with the political activisms with which so many contemporary literary-critical schools are affiliated. But I want to suggest that it is precisely because aesthetic
Singer.book
4
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 4
Introduction
value is deemed to be too deeply complicit with the Enlightenment prejudices in favor of dogmatic subjectivity, that we risk a more damaging blindness. We lose sight of the fact that the political agendas of contemporary criticism require the very capacities of subjective agency that Enlightenment rationalism originally imputed to aesthetic judgment, at least in the work of Baumgarten. In this book, therefore, I will propose that only by restoring the aesthetic as a resource of rational deliberation, and hence a proving ground for undeluded human agency, can the purposes of its most vociferous critics be meaningfully served. It may prove feasible to speculate how the elaboration of aesthetic theory in postmodern culture is the unexpectedly necessary tool of postmodern culture’s critique of modernity. Stated differently, I propose a rerationalization of aesthetic practice and value that holds faith with the Enlightenment goals of rational action, without succumbing to the ideological traps of reifying reason. It buttresses a venerable Frankfurt School conviction that Enlightenment must be transformed, not abandoned. Because I seek to reintegrate aesthetic value with the joint projects of literary production and literary criticism—at a time when literary criticism is becoming increasingly alienated from the realms of art—my argument intimates how Enlightenment ideals are predisposed to aesthetic practices. If I can promote some reconciliation between literary criticism and literary art my work may serve as a reminder of how complicit the modes of aesthetic valuation are with the forms of cultural production at large. The structure of this work proceeds alternately through speculative argumentation and close readings of artworks. These include both literary and visual texts. In addition to literary works by Sophocles, Herman Melville, Samuel Beckett, William Faulkner, and James Joyce, I explore the formal-compositional complexities of Caravaggio, Hans Haacke, Cindy Sherman, Barbara Kruger, and Gerhard Richter. My desire to read beyond the bounds of orthodox literary aesthetic value is coherent with my wish to assert the premise that literary production is epiphenomenal of cultural production in other modalities of subjective human expression. The realm of the visual arts is a fully complementary field of production in which subjectivity, the locus of tragic experience and Enlightenment hope, pursues self-realization. I will try to persuade the reader that on both the verbal and the visual registers the stakes of subjectivity are the same, at least insofar as we see the mandate of self-recognition to be the imperative of engagement with the work of art.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 5
Introduction
5
ORGANIZATION In Chapter 1, I establish a context for these claims. The prospect for assessing the adequacy of the aesthetic is presented as a historical view of what we have arguably lost by eschewing the cognitive imperatives of aesthetic valuation. This is the legacy of Neoplatonism, Lord Shaftesbury, Francis Hutcheson, and, I will argue, even Kantian aesthetics. This view is balanced by a prospect of what might be gained by countenancing cognitive protocols of human choice-making as the threshold of aesthetic experience: an alternative legacy out of Baumgarten, Johann Gottfried von Herder, G. W. F. Hegel, Johann Gottlieb Fichte, and Theodor Adorno. In Chapter 2, I locate the situation of human choice-making within the context of a civic identity with its roots in the agonistic arena of the Greek polis. Hannah Arendt, among others, has extrapolated this civic identity to the Kantian aesthetic project of sensus communis. Inasmuch as Arendt’s own sense of what establishes this trajectory of thought (about the relations of art and politics) is epitomized in the forms of Greek tragic knowledge, I establish tragedy as a frame of reference for advancing a cognitive aesthetic. The argument is furthered in Chapter 3 through a focus on the epistemological dilemma of tragic character—the agonia of tragedy—in terms of the reversal of human will portended in incontinent action. This dilemma is what the ancient Greeks, and an important branch of contemporary ethical philosophy, engage as akratic character, where an agent seems to lose rapport with the best reasons for actions. Akratic character serves as a framework for contemplating the stakes of tragic reversal. In turn, through a close reading of Beckett’s late narrative Ill Seen, Ill Said—which I take as a paradigmatic tragedy—I will attempt to demonstrate that the intelligibility of tragic experience presupposes not the annihilation of subjectivity but rather the disposition of subjectivity toward a self-revising consciousness.The integrity of this consciousness derives from an Aristotelian lineage—namely, the practical agency extolled in the Nichomachean Ethics. In Chapter 4, I propose that the suffering of tragic character with respect to akratic action be joined with a broader consideration of the relation of aesthetic experience to the dynamics of error. The problematic of error in turn becomes a way of joining the self-revising subjectivity conditioned by tragic experience to aesthetic experience. This is accomplished through the rationalistic practices of contextual understanding. Here, discussions of Frederic Jameson, Louis Althusser, Hegel,
Singer.book
6
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 6
Introduction
and Jean-Luc Nancy serve to situate choice-making subjectivity with respect to a long-standing critical ambition to compensate human agency for the limitations of the contexts of knowledge in which action must be undertaken. The “tragic suffering” featured within the context of akratic action is here clearly identified as a quality of readerly attention distinct from the fatality of the tragic protagonist. It is nonetheless coherent with the choice-making imperatives that dignify tragic death. In this case, the “text” that dramatizes such readerly attention is Caravaggio’s The Conversion of Saint Paul. Chapter 5 contains a more explicit consideration of how the problematics of Enlightenment subjectivity must be seen to stand in a reciprocal relation with the formal densities of aesthetic experience. Or at least this is the case if we want to salvage a notion of the ethicopolitical usefulness of aesthetic value. My reading of Melville’s “Bartleby the Scrivener” is presented as a counterpoint to the paradoxically anti-aesthetic aesthetic stances—epitomized for the purposes of this argument by Guillory and Bourdieu—that trivialize the stakes of aesthetic experience in the gesture of valorizing it. Guillory and Bourdieu seek an admirable reckoning of the artwork with ethicopolitical practices that unfortunately necessitates a nullification of the artistic experience qua aesthetic form. I rely upon the reading of Melville’s “Bartleby” to advance the notion that the critique of Enlightenment subjectivity can be achieved only from within the precincts of the subject, and that our analytical grasp of this constraint is crucially mediated by the forms of engagement with aesthetic objects—in this case, the forms of readerly response conditioned by the verbal specificity of Melville’s text. In Chapter 6, I model in more detail the deliberative métier of the aesthetic character limned in previous chapters. Here I elaborate my original attempt to reconcile the aesthetic and the political on the epistemological topoi of tragic experience. Reacting against Nancy’s claim to reconcile aesthetics and politics by abandoning the determinants of human agency in favor of the indeterminacy of sublime intuition, I articulate more fully the deliberative means of aesthetic character. I employ a close reading of Joyce’s “The Dead” to think more practically about how works of art instantiate the kind of deliberative “space” that I posit both as a ground of aesthetic character and of the determinateness of aesthetic value. The value of aesthetic experience is thus defended in the elaboration of the warrant for choice-making that art imposes upon the subject. Again the “tragedy” of subjectivity—here dramatized in the character of Gabriel Conroy—is linked to a prospect for ameliorating human experience through deliberative action.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 7
Introduction
7
In Chapter 7, I conclude the argument by juxtaposing the ethicopolitical claims championed by anti-aesthetic criticism with the art practices patronized by those claims. I argue that these works of oppositional postmodernism (by Hans Haacke, Barbara Kruger, and Cindy Sherman) strive to evade aesthetic bad faith, the lapse into unworldly aestheticism, by eschewing the presentational values of aesthetic form. My point here is to tease out the inadequacy of such works with respect to the cognitive stakes inherent in the political justifications for their existence.Alternatively I reassert the necessity to tap cognitive resources of the aesthetic that depend upon the presentational densities of aesthetic forms and thereby to hold the attentive subject to a discipline of choice-making. It is this discipline that keeps faith with the project of Enlightenment mind and the “tragic” burdens of self-recognition and rationalistic self-justification that Enlightenment mind cannot dispense with. Ultimately my purpose in these pages is to found a reasonable faith in the aesthetic as a métier of human activity. This métier is grounded in the cultural knowledge of tragedy, where individuality contends with the recognition of human contingency. As I note in the final chapter, the aesthetic deepens reflection upon the question of how art is a resource for the kinds of agency we acknowledge in the recognition of contingency. More to the point, I believe that partisans of the aesthetic and the anti-aesthetic both agree that such self-knowledge must meet a test of adequacy. But the standard of adequacy here has nothing to do with judgments of canonicity or hierarchies of taste. Neither does it bear upon the relative truthfulness of the work of art vis-à-vis the scientific facts of nature or the political facts of human history as told from the vantage points of power or powerlessness. Rather, the adequacy of the aesthetic defended in these pages relates most eloquently to the sociopolitical pressures that human subjects contend with in the common deliberative prospect of sharing a common world.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 8
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 9
1
The Adequacy of the Aesthetic This amounts to enunciating the requirement that the Idea and its plastic mould as concrete reality are to be made completely adequate to one another. . . . But if so, the required truth of the Ideal is confounded with mere correctness, which consists in the expression of any meaning whatever in appropriate fashion so its import may be readily recognized in the shape created. The Ideal is not to be thus understood.Any content whatever may attain to being represented quite adequately, judged by the standard of its own nature, but it does not therefore gain the right to claim the artistic beauty of the Ideal. —Hegel, Lectures on the Aesthetic [T]he very disintegration and inadequacy of the world is the precondition for the existence of art and its becoming conscious. —Lukács, Theory of the Novel
I The claim of the inadequacy of the aesthetic proffers a perverse standard of adequacy in contemporary literary-critical discourse. The traditional identification of the aesthetic with appearance (Schein), by virtue of its presentation of sensuous particulars, has become a target of critique for literary theorists who discount appearance as an ideological counter of value. In this view, aesthetic form is, de facto, an instrumental lever of the institutional powers of art culture inasmuch as art culture itself is merely epiphenomenal of the power structures of post-Enlightenment reason. Ironically, the partisans of this critique propose to redefine the culture of oppression promulgated in selfconsciously “aesthetic” literary representations, by recourse to the very liberational rhetoric that was formerly the property of Romantic literary aesthetics. But now this rhetoric is put in the service of a largely unarticulated standard of political efficacy. This standard seeks to vitiate the so-called artistic content of the artwork by transcending its formal features and the sensuous scope of its presentational powers.
Singer.book
10
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 10
Aesthetic Reason
A keynote of the anti-aesthetic is sounded in Hal Foster’s preface to his anthology volume, The Anti-Aesthetic: Essays on Postmodern Culture. There he declares that the “anti-aesthetic . . . signals a practice, cross-disciplinary in nature, that is sensitive to cultural forms engaged in a politics (e.g., feminist art), or rooted in a vernacular—that is, to forms that deny the idea of a privileged aesthetic realm” (xv). However admirable this goal of secularizing art may be, I want to point out that its articulation here comes at the expense of a recalcitrant dualism of art and politics.1 By soliciting the political “others” of the aesthetic in order to demonstrate the emptiness of the category of the aesthetic, Foster effectively reprises the very dualism he seems to deny. In order to challenge this dualism, I seek to defend the aesthetic. But contrary to privileging the aesthetic realm as a refuge of sensuous immediacy or sublime irrationalist transport, I want to defend the cognitive efficacy of the aesthetic. By my emphasis on the cognitive, I want to expose the artistic as well as the political impotence of any critique predicated on treating the aesthetic as a “realm” of its own. By the same token, I will show that the partisans of the anti-aesthetic, by eschewing the “aesthetically formed” sensuous particulars of art (which I will engage in Chapter 7 as the presentational field of the artwork), and by their corollary attack on literary formalism, can only give an inertly conceptual and passively descriptive account of the very “cultural forms” that they promise to redeem from the representational injustices of aesthetic practice. Partisans of the anti-aesthetic such as Foster stress the “privileged” status of aesthetic form as though it obtained strictly as a condition of reified sensation. They thereby minimize the productive aspect of the artwork. If, alternatively, aesthetic form were taken to be an active proliferation of sensuous differences, we would see how it possesses a cognitive efficacy equal to the warrant it presents for making choices among differences. We would see how making choices among differences presupposes a discipline of intersubjective recognition. By evading these cognitive constraints of aesthetic form, by succumbing to a descriptive protocol that can only enumerate the ideological distortions said to be perpetuated in the aesthetic register of the artwork, the anti-aesthetic is complicit with what it criticizes. The anti-aesthetic thus fails to take an analytical stance that might actually produce ameliorative social and artistic change. Alternatively, my position will be that such productivity falls within the cognitive precincts of the aesthetic itself. Precisely because the partisans of the anti-aesthetic preclude formal particulars in favor of the factual par-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 11
The Adequacy of the Aesthetic
11
ticulars of lived experience, they cut us off from the productive agency without which the very appearance of factual particulars is unintelligible. They invite us to forget that facts are intelligible only in the context of conceptual choices. As I have already intimated, the preface to the Foster anthology bears witness to a telling irony here: the rhetoric of the anti-aesthetic echoes the rhetoric of multiculturalists, new historicists, feminists, and neoMarxists, for whom the agenda of social change is the clarion selfjustification. The oppressive powers of autonomous or instrumental will, which each of these groups ascribes to the subjective, expressive bias of aesthetic form, leads them invidiously to posit a knowledge of social-historical particulars that purports to be unmediated by egotistical distortions. Notably, a majority of the essays in the Foster anthology (by such politically motivated critics as Fredric Jameson and Edward Said) boast a descriptive authenticity vis-à-vis lived cultural life. They presuppose a universalist or collectivist rationale, free of subjective prejudice.The problem for such would-be critical insurgencies is that the project of social justification, conceived along these lines, threatens to preclude the ever more tragically fated personal self that presumably warranted a program for social justice in the first place. A more reasonable solution to the problem would therefore seem to require the theorizing of an agency that could carry out the program of social justice without ignoring the impediments to social justice latent in such agency. I n keeping with this goal, my appeal to a cognitive aesthetic seeks to obviate the need for transcending subjective distortions by rationalistically reconciling the distorting perspective of subjectivity with other subjective perspectives. Subjective agency is therefore not sacrificed to social justice; nor is politics sacrificed to morality. Furthermore, because I want to try to resolve the debates about the axiological prospect of literary-theoretical discourse, not in terms of simply redescribing a collective good, but in terms of the ethical agency that could produce such goods, I will follow a philosophical direction that is in line with the work of neorationalists such as Jürgen Habermas and pragmatic-realists such as Hilary Putnam for whom ethical community is a function of ethical action. 2 They are, in turn, indebted to Hegelian and Nietzschean models of expressive agency that, for all their post-Enlightenment skepticism, bear out their continuity with Enlightenment values. I n following the methodological lead of Habermas’s communicative action and Putnam’s “internal realism,” I seek to reconnect the category of the aesthetic to a cognitive ground
Singer.book
12
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 12
Aesthetic Reason
that might establish its efficacy as a protocol of rational choice-making. I n that capacity, the aesthetic constitutes a lever of social change that does not seek to transcend its own means to such an end. The protocol of choice may thus be seen to establish a minimal condition both for thinking responsibly about social action and for grounding the valuation of artworks in attentiveness to the particulars of sensuous appearance as form. Getting at the merits of the formal analysis I have just proposed will of course involve a reckoning with the concept of ideology. It should already be clear that the literary aesthetic stands indicted by partisans of the anti-aesthetic under the sign of ideology. Ideology is understood to be a corollary of the false appearance configured in the sensuous form of the artwork. A critic such as Pierre Bourdieu is indicative of this stance. Bourdieu pegs sensuous appearance qua art form to a Kantian disinterestedness within which, he alleges, the most hegemonic class interests may be plainly seen to cloak themselves.3 I can most succinctly indicate my reasons for wanting to rebut this claim by observing how the critique of the aesthetic, as ideological delusion, furtively resurrects the old realism-antirealism dichotomy. The putative truthvalue of literary art has traditionally, if misguidedly, been based on this dichotomy since the earliest attempts to redeem the work of art from Plato’s judgment in book 10 of the Republic. By purporting to expose the “ideological” premise of the claims for artistic autonomy, wherein all differences are “apparently” reconciled, the partisans of the antiaesthetic are in effect appropriating the historically authoritative place of realist truth, wherein all differences are scientifically authenticated. By this means the aesthetic may be relegated, at least rhetorically, to the status of a decadent antirealism.This rhetorical maneuver insinuates the frivolity of imaginative acts of mind—linked as they are to the aesthete’s proverbial detachment from, or disinterestedness with respect to, the putative real. This charge of complicity between ideology and the aesthetic is an attempt to subordinate the political efficacy of the study of literature, among other arts, to a broader program of ideological demystification. Since the eighteenth century, the will toward such demystification has found expression in a suspiciously diverse array of critical manifestos including the social reformist projects of Thomas Love Peacock, Matthew Arnold, Karl Marx, Georg Lukács, Raymond Williams, and Michel Foucault.4 In what follows, however, I will show how the demystifying power mustered by ideology critique too easily devolves to a descriptive “exteriority” rather than to a participative “interiority” with
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 13
The Adequacy of the Aesthetic
13
respect to the social realities that might be embodied by literary representations. I have already suggested that this inherently more ideological exteriority is conditioned by a particularly stubborn political fact: if the anti-aesthetic purview eschews the formal armature of choice-making, the critic remains so resolutely divorced from the productive capacity of active imagination or creative mind (anchored in appearance), that he or she can proffer nothing to put in the place of the social injustices that literature would be authorized to critique. Without gaining some purchase on agency through the choice-making imperatives of aesthetic form, the anti-aesthetic, polemicized in terms of ideology critique, itself falls prey to the kind of judgment usually voiced in the charge of feckless aestheticism. In other words, the partisans of the anti-aesthetic indulge too much abstraction from the very social particulars that would instantiate the social agency they otherwise seek to valorize. The anti-aesthetic indictment of the ideological character of the aesthetic, in this way, succumbs to its own ideological corruption.
II The polemical scope of the anti-aesthetic, which serves as the springboard of my argument here, is usefully epitomized in Tony Bennett’s diatribe, Outside Literature. Bennett sums up an argument that had its most perspicuous formulation in Foucauldian and Althusserian revisions of Marx in the 1970s. In choosing to theorize a literature “deliberately severed from the aesthetic,” Bennett proposes to treat the artwork as a means of knowing more concretely, rather than transcending subjectivistically, the diverse practices of social life that otherwise seize hold of the subject under the tyrannical will of a bureaucratically interpellating “official culture.” Marx’s argument in the Grundrisse, that the concrete is the concrete because it is the concentration of many determinations whose interaction can only be grasped by the violent abstraction of thought thus embodies a methodological orientation that is precisely the reverse of that of philosophical aesthetics. It suggests, for example, that questions relating to the effects of works of art require that the labour of theoretical abstraction be orientated to examining the modes of interaction of the complex concatenation of factors regulating the reception of such works. Within philo-
Singer.book
14
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 14
Aesthetic Reason
sophical aesthetics, by contrast, the process of abstraction pulls in the opposite direction. Here, it embodies a procedure for disengaging works of art from the mundane particularities regulating their reception in different contexts in order to arrive at a conception of their effects as being always subject to the influence of an invariant aesthetic relation, itself rooted in an unchanging faculty of the subject deduced from a transcendental analysis of the constitutive properties of art in general. (Outside Literature, 119; emphasis added) I believe that the chief liability of Bennett’s thinking here derives from his tendentiously British empiricist view of what constitutes philosophical aesthetics in the first place. Bennett’s perspective is resolutely oblivious to the Continental tradition linking sense to action and aesthesis to practical activity. Rather, in the passage just cited, the aesthetic is deemed to be inadequate to the demands of social practice insofar as the social agency of the practical subject is posited as the crucial counter of value. Yet within the devoutly materialist constraints of his thinking in Outside Literature, Bennett can give no substantive basis for constituting the social agency, which he alleges to be displaced by the aesthetic sublimation of “concrete determinations” into an increasingly metaphysical judgment of good taste or beauty. It is for this reason that Bennett’s idea of a critical discourse that could display the array of “diverse social practices” that the aesthetic meaning of the artwork obscures, is fated to follow a paradoxical trajectory of self-attenuating description. He renders the goal of social justice proffered within that description an increasingly virtual prospect because it fails to animate the “social practices” in which its self-justifying burden of political change resides. The conceptual poverty of Bennett’s stance here elicits an eloquent contrast with the history of the very philosophical aesthetic he wants to impugn as hopelessly impractical and haplessly apolitical. The contrast is nowhere more striking than in the German tradition inaugurated by Alexander Baumgarten, who founded the aesthetic as a scientia cognitionis sensitivae in 1735. For Baumgarten the category of the aesthetic sustained a fundamental concern for the materially formative, rather than the metaphysically preformed unity of things, the latter having gained ascendancy under the powerful influence of natural-right philosophies and the theory of taste. For Baumgarten, aesthesis, understood as immanent to formal or perceptual complexity, is necessarily manifested as a determinative agency. He postulates that the more sensate determination there is in the artistic form, the more actualizable is the aesthetic realm as a site of human activity.5
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 15
The Adequacy of the Aesthetic
15
It is furthermore important to realize that the specifically cognitive terms of the aesthetic that was founded by Baumgarten in Reflections on Poetry and Aesthetica summarizes or culminates the regrounding of value in experience that was begun by the neophyte humanist philosophy of Pico della Mirandola and sustained through the early Enlightenment by Thomas Hobbes and Giambattista Vico. It could be argued that the utilitarianism-inspired British theory of taste (a late eighteenth-century phenomenon), which seems to be presupposed in Bennett’s agentless valorization of “mundane particularities,” constituted an interruption of this more critical German tradition.That is, Bennett’s attack on the adequacy of the aesthetic may be seen as presuming upon tenets of taste that figure more prominently in a literary aesthetic strictly divorced from rigorous philosophical principles, than in the philosophical aesthetic which is Bennett’s declared target.The aesthetic subject, so reductively featured in Bennett’s account, is closer to the caricature “man of taste,” who locates the beautiful in Nature.This is a sensibility exemplified in the loosely ethical tradition of such thinkers as Hutcheson, Shaftesbury, and Arnold. It sustains its polemical purity by ignoring the more strictly cognitive tradition that locates a standard of aesthetic value in cultural practices and the analytics of action embedded in those practices.The genealogy of this tradition includes Baumgarten, Herder, Hegel and more recently, John Dewey, Ludwig Wittgenstein, and Nelson Goodman. The inadequacy of the tradition out of which Bennett is working is perhaps most starkly dramatized in a consideration of the competing etymological claims upon the German word for taste, which inflects the history of the philosophical aesthetic and marks it off from its empiricist rivals.There are two etymological frames of reference here: geschmack, a decidedly metaphorical reference to the subjective synthesis of sensuous particulars (as on the palate or tongue) that is ordained as a prerational intuition, and Tasten or Tastende, a more practical reference to the utility of the sense of touch in probing and experimenting with the world of physical phenomena as a mode of synthetic intuition. As Howard Caygill explains in Art of Judgement, his astute overview of the historical development of aesthetical judgment-power, Herder is the pivotal figure in this etymological controversy. By invoking this etymological distinction against the more empiricist theories of taste, Herder turns the discipline of aesthetics away from taste and in the direction of act. For my purposes, this is the direction of cognition and choice.6 According to Herder, the aesthetic object is only productive of occasions for cognitive activity when it obviates that premise of the theory
Singer.book
16
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 16
Aesthetic Reason
of taste that, in a Humean fashion, derives the act of judgment from natural rather than social contingencies. Hutcheson’s and Shaftesbury’s theories of beauty, for example, denoted a correspondence between a human faculty (the “aesthetic attitude”) and a natural harmony.7 For Herder, and for theorists of an emergent cognitive aesthetic, the beauty of the aesthetic inheres as a human act of differentiation. This is the productive power of judgment per se. Ironically, however, the term production itself has recently become a fulcrum for critique of the aesthetic, where the productive dimension of the aesthetic has been crudely equated with the instrumentality of subjective rational action. For instance, Jürgen Habermas has alleged that the production paradigm, intrinsic to the aesthetic, inhibits the emancipatory politics of a noninstrumental will.8 This claim, I believe, merely typifies a refusal on the part of critics of the aesthetic to distinguish instrumental from strategic agency. I t represents a refusal to see agency as vitally situational rather than as an oppressively inexorable universality.Thomas McCarthy has alleged this refusal to be the crux of Michel Foucault’s failure as a social theorist. In Foucault’s later works, subjective agency—virtually synonymous with “Power”— becomes so amorphously pervasive a concept that the only prospect for liberation from its effects entails our imagination of a vacuum of social interactions, a quasi-stoical cessation of productive imagination.9 As I will speculate later, this might be not the least of Foucault’s motives for returning to the personal subject at the end of his career, in order to postulate a project of self-realization or self-production that he characterizes explicitly as an “aesthetics of existence.”10 For the moment, however, suffice it to say that the weakness of the argument against productive agency, like the weakness of the argument against the aesthetic in general, stems from an even more fundamental failure to understand the nature of aesthetic production. For reasons that are in fact harmonious with the political idealism of the anti-aesthetic, I want to establish the adequacy of the aesthetic on the basis of its capacity to challenge an inert, ideological, and politically oppressing—which is to say, unproductive—lifeworld. But I would stipulate other conditions: this notion of adequacy must be seen to acknowledge a constitutive gap between productive value and the recognition of productive value to be part of the activity of production itself. Recognition marks the interface of agency and intersubjectivity. Accordingly, the historical view of the aesthetic that I will develop in the next section will lead us to see that, because the productive
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 17
The Adequacy of the Aesthetic
17
aesthetic, understood as the legacy of Tastende, entails a reflective register, it also entails a transformative register. This obtains specifically in recognition of the gap between artistic production and audience recognition. I am assuming that such a gap is exigent in the temporal distantiation occasioned by any act of aesthetic-making that demands from its audience a new construal of contextual boundaries to facilitate its making whole: in other words, achieving terms of fit with the culture of its intelligibility. The gap therefore invokes the standard of adequacy as a commensuration of differences—the differentials of formal production and recognitional value—on a temporal axis. Revealing an affinity with tragic emplotment that will be elaborated in later chapters, the gap between production and recognition thereby favors the reversibility of logical perspectives, rather than the punctual instantiation of a transcendental logic, as its totalizing imperative. Thus the adequacy of the aesthetic will be seen to inhere in its going beyond judgment power, conceived as a universalistic subsumption of the manifold, according to what Tony Bennett calls “an unchanging faculty of the subject.” In effect the notion of the aesthetic I promote here denotes a capacity to interrogate the concept of adequacy itself. Moreover, we shall see how it is precisely because the historical progress of philosophical aesthetics—from metaphysical truths to cognitive acts—increasingly acknowledges the gap between production and recognition that we can now pass beyond the specifically Kantian threshold of aesthetic judgment that post-Romantic literary aesthetics subsists upon. Kantian judgment presents a faculty constrained by a universalizability that—indistinguishable from necessity and thus uncomfortably like a “thing in itself”—is the definitive inhibition to recognition. Conversely, aesthetic judgment, determined by the dialectic of production and recognition, will be seen to intimate a capacity for construing artworks as contexts for contemplating rational choices. Specifically these are choices within the realm of action that is endowed by cognitive interests. For interestedness in this perspective quite explicitly denotes an intersubjective (not universal) reciprocity of necessary knowledges. Such reciprocity thwarts the caricature of the post-Romantic Kantian aesthetic as a disinterested enterprise. It is furthermore just such cognitive interest that guarantees the status of the aesthetic as a nonaestheticizing phenomenon: one that eschews any reification of the sensuous medium upon which its cognitive agency presumes to work.
Singer.book
18
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 18
Aesthetic Reason
III We have seen that for critics of the aesthetic such as Tony Bennett, the most dubious authority of aesthetic theory is its claim that artistic meanings transcend the social determinations of artistic practices. For Bennett, this claim obtrudes the chief obstacle to what he otherwise anticipates, in almost millenarian terms, as a “sober materialist analysis of the relations between artistic practices and social practices” (Outside Literature, 146).Yet, while Bennett faults even so socially engagé a theorist as Lukács for having the transcendental blindness of the disinterested aesthete, he ignores a salient possibility: that what he is dismissing as indeterminately transcendental in the aesthetic may be more positively construed as an “other” order of determination. For it is one that cannot be anticipated within the binary opposition of abstraction and concreteness that furtively props Bennett’s polemic. I will argue that this determinative order is vitally continuous with social determination.This is the case when we appreciate how aesthetic theory historically prioritizes the phenomenon of determination in the realms of both artistic and social practice. My task here is to show that the possibility of understanding aesthetic theory as a subsuming of both the social and the artistic under the determinative enterprise of value-making is precluded by Bennett’s critique. Only in this context will it make sense to go on to demonstrate how aesthetic value-making per se entails or arises in the very production-recognition gap which the anti-aesthetic polemicists ironically blame it for opening under the epistemological delusions of a productionist ideology. I believe that the idea of “aesthetic transcendence” has only ever presented a threat to our rapport with the materiality of existence when its own determinations have been ignored or forgotten—when it has not been treated in the context of aesthetic cognition. It is precisely this forgetfulness that we risk perpetuating if we persist in the blanket indictment of what Terry Eagleton calls an “ideology of the aesthetic.”11 With this phrase, Eagleton joins Bennett in inhibiting our knowledge of the potential conceptual continuity of aesthesis with the interests and methods of ideology critique: a continuity key to my claim for the reciprocity between production and recognition. Because he insists that there is a coercive and eudaimonian substrate of aesthetic ideology, Eagleton furthermore obscures the degree to which the methods of ideology critique have, as Karl Mannheim has famously observed, disowned their own ideological interests.They unwittingly carry the
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 19
The Adequacy of the Aesthetic
19
taint of their own aestheticizing bad faith. Since the publication of Auguste Comte’s Cours de philosophie positive (1842) the “science” of ideology critique has purported to transcend the egocentric will— a site of production—by conflating it with a collective will, a site of recognition.This is a transcendence that cannot be effected except as a negation of all that is at stake in the choice-making prerogative of any individual will. So the most fundamental error of anti-aestheticism that I want to redress here is its de facto conflation of production with recognition. I must show how this conflation perpetuates the caricature of art as an ideological phenomenon, as an expressive power that reifies through its productive agency. Dating from the precipitous spirituality of Hegel’s Aesthetics, the conflation of production and recognition has been widely acknowledged to be the premise of positive aesthetic production, and of the subjectivist hermeticism for which the aesthetic has consequently been blamed. On this basis, the conflation of production with recognition could be said to be at the root of the preemptive universalism for which many social critics hold aesthetic judgments accountable, especially within the formalist canons of literary art. The crucial flaw in such thinking is that where production is confused with recognition, the subject-object dichotomy reasserts itself as an irresolvable dualism and hence as an obstacle to rational regimens of choice.We can see this in the fetishistic mutual exclusiveness of subjectivism and objectivism that was Plato’s legacy to art theory. Plato’s disenfranchisement of art promulgates the original confusion of production and recognition. Plato makes philosophical truth depend on a subjectivity that is wedded to its objects.Yet it is a philosophical truth that may never be adequately embodied in those objects.This schema points up the difference between epistemology and ethics. I t thus links the disenfranchisement of art to a crisis of ethical community. More to the point, however, it does so in a way that anticipates how the phenomenon of recognition might offer a remedy, if only by establishing discursive grounds of judgment. Otherwise the scope of ethical decision-making is minimized in Plato. For according to the Platonist aesthetic, the knowledge instanced in the particularity of the artwork allows judgment only in the absence of the very sensuous (which is to say discursive) discriminations (as opposed to sense percepts) that warranted the judging imperative in the first place. Accordingly, I believe that the philosophical inadequacy of the Enlightenment theory of taste is most unsatisfactory in its own conspicuously Neoplatonist aspect. It is implicated in Plato’s ethical bad
Singer.book
20
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 20
Aesthetic Reason
faith, by its setting up standards of beauty that are deemed to be universal before there is any particular instantiation of beauty that might call the universal standard of taste to any meaningful account. Enlightenment taste, like the Platonic truth it mimes, and despite its Lockean grounding in the percept, proffers a concept of the beautiful without conceiving a cognitive agency for that concept.We have already noted that for Shaftesbury, Hutcheson, and David Hume, such agency had a virtual existence in the basically utilitarian consensus they presupposed as the relevant context of judgment. But now we must also realize that the fundamentally reproductive mindset of utilitarianism effectively preempts that aspect of productive imagination that might otherwise correlate a standard of conceptual clarity with the extensional register of sensuous experience. I n Shaftesbury, Hutcheson, and Hume the philosophy of taste thus founders upon that threshold of experience where the presumed “natural harmony” between mind and world begs the question of the provenance of natural law that presumably governs it.The existence of such a law would be assumed as a necessary but necessarily mysterious condition of its articulation in the consensus of taste. The genealogy of the problem begins with Shaftesbury. As I’ve anticipated, in Shaftesbury’s Characteristics (1711) the correlation between the “unity” of the beautiful object and the sense of taste or the “inward eye” of its apprehension exhibits Neoplatonist idealism.This remains the case so long as the mandated disinterestedness of Shaftesbury’s taste precludes any ascription of qualities to the object of judgment. As Shaftesbury explains, the meaning of beauty is to be considered an “emblematic symbol” as opposed to “conventional” or “iconic” symbols. The emblematic beauty is coterminous with the unceasing and plastic manifestation of God in the transformations of Nature. But whatever qualities might be intuitable are, on that basis, neither cognitively nor formally productive. Emblematic beauty encourages judgment (i.e., the act of judging) to revert to an ahistorical spiritualism. In the Inquiry into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue (1725), Hutcheson seems to open the possibility for endowing Shaftesbury’s emblematic symbolism with discernable productive “qualities” by distinguishing percepts as an external sense and taste as what he terms an “internal sense.” 12 This internal sense is reactive, arising from an idea of beauty that is coordinate with a percept but not bound by a Lockean determinism. Its objectivity is intrinsic to forms of human experience. But on the basis of this distinction between internal and external senses, Hutcheson establishes the “disinterestedness” of taste
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 21
The Adequacy of the Aesthetic
21
as an effectively nondiscursive premise of judgment.This disinterestedness is quite comparable to Shaftesbury’s own internal sense of taste devoid of qualitative differentia. For an internal sense as Hutcheson describes it has no specifiable relational status with respect to the sensorium from which it derives an expressive efficacy. Its disinterestedness is thus a condition of experience but not a counter of any self-knowledge that would be shareable as such, or through which the self could reflectively relate to itself as experience. Hume’s apparently more practical emphasis on the power of distinction articulated in the standard (faculty) of taste would seem to achieve an advancement upon the ideal of a beauty without qualities promoted by Shaftesbury and Hutcheson. As we have seen, it was by their elision of differentia that Shaftesbury and Hutcheson precluded choice as an agency of taste. By contrast, Hume’s “Of the Standard of Taste” (1757), extols the power of making distinctions as a learned experience. In a famous anecdote borrowed from Miguel de Cervantes, Hume relates the prowess of wine tasters who—against the grain of common sense and Nature—discern a “taste” of leather and iron in a hogshead of wine. When the hogshead is drained, its dregs reveal an iron key with a leather thong attached to it. Hume here exemplifies a standard of taste whereby the picking out of qualities by an aesthetic judge augments the quality of mind upon which judgment depends. Unfortunately he fails to specify the agency of that learning beyond the “connoisseurship” of specialized knowledges or the more fundamentally inductive pursuit of pleasurable feeling.This ultimate recourse to pleasure, which is the social glue of Humean ethics, amounts to reprising the “disinterested” standard of “unity in variety” upon which Shaftesbury and Hutcheson predicated taste and according to which they elided differentia. Such a formulation inevitably induces a collapsing of objective into subjective or subjective into objective registers. Hume’s thinking is even more problematic in the Treatise of Human Nature (1739), where he accepts the dichotomies of practical versus formal utility, and reason versus sentiment. For example, in distinguishing sentiment from reason, Hume states that sentiment refers to “nothing outside of itself” but is itself presupposed by a prior regularity between object and mind. Although this regularity is instantiated formally, form itself is mystified because in its presuppositional status it is, rationalistically speaking, cut off from the very practice it might be expected to authenticate. So while taste is equated with moral universalism, for each of these thinkers, the very inhibition of cognitive agency inherent in the uni-
Singer.book
22
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 22
Aesthetic Reason
versalistic judgment (which is to say moralistic-aesthetic judgment) they promote would appear to preclude ethical choice. By ethical choice I mean of course the practical application of a belief in moral duty. Because for Shaftesbury, Hutcheson, and Hume, cognitive activity is a prerequisite of the universalistic knowledge that attests to cognition’s universality, moral (theoretic) and ethical (practical) realms seem to be rendered incommensurable and mutually exclusive. I would argue, nevertheless, that our awareness of the incommensurability between the moral and the ethical itself depends upon a prior acceptance of the phenomenon of recognition as a variable of the judgment of taste. After all, recognition predicates understanding on an acknowledged discrepancy of perspectives. Such a discrepancy is the threshold and warrant of recognition, without which it would be unintelligible.And by contrast with the constraints of universalist or disinterested criteria of judgment, the phenomenon of recognition gives access to a realm of choice-making: one that in fact induces new cognitive constraints, because all constraints of knowledge are, under its auspices, intersubjectively contingent. Such constraints by definition purvey no universalistic values, though they possess a universalizing rationale insofar as the demand for recognition is always susceptible to new standards of self-justification. Production and recognition are thus made coherent because they are acknowledged to be continuous enterprises. Furthermore, only such cognitive constraints as are embodied in the project of recognition enable the productive faculty of mind to escape the taint of transcendental reason or truth that most Enlightenment aesthetics or theories of taste propound. In fact, on this basis, we might see how recognition could be deemed to be already intrinsic to the judgment of taste and hence to production if, as I have alleged, taste is construed as an incipient dialecticism with respect to its own cognitive constraints. In other words, there may already be within beauty theory a potential for intersubjective recognition that the theorists of the beautiful failed to exploit, and that requires our exposition if we are to salvage the efficacy of the aesthetic as an analytical lever of art production and art criticism.
IV The failure of beauty theory to exploit its own immanent dialecticism, and thereby to reckon with recognition, is partly explained in term of its adherence to a naturalistic fallacy.The naturalistic fallacy operative
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 23
The Adequacy of the Aesthetic
23
in beauty theory rejects any distinction between what is and what ought to be counted as a conditionality of human judgment. Because this failure to acknowledge the distinction between the practical and the theoretical eschews the intersubjective register as a condition of individual character and agency, it mires analysis in an irremediable, because mistakenly characterized, conflict between human consciousness and Nature. For the “Natural self,” in which beauty claims to be anchored, is doomed to compete with the unencompassable universality of Nature that it is otherwise assumed to mirror. Consequently, conflicted consciousness is the tragedy that comes home to roost in the egocentric domain of the naturalistic fallacy.The vaunted autonomy of the natural self gives way to the old problematics of Cartesian divisions within the self, most emphatically in recognition of the ineluctable temporal successiveness within which self-consciousness arises. Nevertheless, out of this tragic knowledge we may be prompted to ask a different question, with a decidedly Hegelian cast: if the existential conflicts that divide the self from itself were deemed to be originally internal to the self, would they then be palatable in ways that escape the more absolutist thinking that defensive Cartesianism gave rise to? In this case it might be argued that subjective experience is indistinguishable from intersubjective experience and that the dialectic of production and recognition (rather than the radical opposition of subject and Nature) would be a more practicable premise for the kind of elaborations of selfhood that artworks are meant to promote. In the following section, this insight will ramify the specific grounds for a cognitive aesthetic that I want to adduce out of a reading of Theodor Adorno’s Aesthetic Theory. Adorno’s defense of artistic autonomy in that text offers what I see as the strongest retort to a materialist inspired anti-aesthetic. It is perhaps the most constructive contribution of postmodern philosophy to this debate over the status of aesthetic values. But rather than leaping in one conceptual bound the historical chasm between the Enlightenment theories just summarized and postmodern aesthetics, I would like to draw some more inferences from the failure of beauty theory, vis-à-vis production and recognition. Without a more considered view of what their failure inhibits, Adorno’s cognitive aesthetic will seem to have less consequence in the service of the literary and the visual arts than I am counting on. In his very useful article “Beauty and the Genealogy of Art Theory,” Noël Carroll addresses the naturalistic fallacy as a prime cause of the logical contradictions that plague modern speculation about the mean-
Singer.book
24
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 24
Aesthetic Reason
ing of art. Carroll sees the tradition of taste, arising out of Hutcheson and leading to Clive Bell and Monroe Beardsley, as a blatant contamination of art theory, which predicates the judgment of taste on cultural production, with beauty theory, which predicates the judgment of taste on natural sentiment. He counts this as an abiding confusion, at the heart of aesthetic theorizing, that threatens its usefulness in the context of contemporary critical discourse about specific artworks. He argues that the easy conflation of natural sense with the art theorist’s formalism has the effect of removing the artwork from any context of judgment that is conceptually determinate and socially grounded. Or, at least, it has the effect of inhibiting any discussion of the “cognitive and moral significance of art” (330) in analytic theory. Because this argument is consistent with my sense that the anti-aesthetic perpetuates a confusion between production and recognition, I am strongly in accord with Carroll’s conclusions. But I think Carroll misses an even more important implication.The distinction between beauty theory and art theory that he would foster as a corrective intimates a specific cognitive regimen for the project of aesthetic valuation: one that requires, in its turn, a more dialectical protocol of judgment. Although Carroll fails to advance this alternative, he nonetheless offers a framework for its articulation. Carroll’s critique of an aesthetic theory that cannot distinguish beauty from artistic practice focuses on a standard of judgment enunciated most influentially by Clive Bell in Art (1958). Bell, defending the aesthetic as a realm of autonomous value, nonetheless anticipated the polemical anti-aestheticism that I see as equally blind to the potential for cognitive knowledge harbored within aesthesis. Indeed we can hear in Bell’s rhetoric the motive for Tony Bennett’s indictment of the political bad faith that Bennett insists aestheticism is heir to:“[T]o appreciate a work of art we need bring with us nothing from life. . . . Art transports us from the world of man’s activity to a world of aesthetic exaltation. For a moment we are shut off from human interests; our anticipations and memories are arrested; we are lifted above the stream of life” (Bell, Art, 27). Carroll’s objection to this stance, like Bennett’s, is rightfully directed at the standard of disinterestedness that derived from eighteenth-century beauty theory, and that is accordingly inapplicable to the presumptive interestedness of artistic practice or production. Carroll makes it clear that by failing to distinguish beauty theory from art theory, Bell actually opens an experiential gulf between the realms of art production and consumption. Seen in this way, I believe that Bell’s man-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 25
The Adequacy of the Aesthetic
25
ifesto gives fresh urgency to my own sense that a duly cognitive aesthetic could serve to rationalize the relations of beauty and art. Contrary to Bell’s reasoning, such a goal would be precisely to construe our interaction with the artwork as a transport into the “world of man’s activity.” What is implicit, but never acknowledged in Carroll’s critique of Bell, is that the ticket to such transport would necessarily be an interestedness that maintains the force of the concept as a threshold of knowledge. I will argue that the concept must nonetheless transcend the particularity of its own praxis by a historically transformative rather than by a metaphysical means, since the vitality of the concept is a variable of its enactment. But how is this transport to be effected if, as Carroll acknowledges, the prevailing attitudes toward the aesthetic—epitomized by Bell, and later by Beardsley—demand our sacrificing the concept to an “exaltation . . . above the stream of life?” I would simply suggest that the self-contradictoriness of Bell’s stance gives us no alternative. In fact, it might be fair to say that the specific logical impasse toward which Bell’s thinking leads motivates the “crisis” of the aesthetic that was the initial point of departure for this chapter. In other words, it is precisely what necessitates the speculative turn toward cognition as a mode of aesthetic judgment. More important for my purposes, it intimates how the critics of the aesthetic might discover their own best interests in a new protocol of aesthetic valuation based on a choice among competing interests. Since I have already mentioned the Foucauldian argument against the instrumentalism of interest as an influential pretext of the anti-aesthetic, it might now make sense to note how the career of Foucault’s thought follows the perilously self-contradictory logical path I have just traced in Bell. But the same self-contradictory problematic in Foucault yields a richer result. Quite aptly for my purposes, Foucault’s adherence to (what I have characterized, in reference to Comte, as) a positivistic disinterestedness in the archeology of discursive formations leads him to a methodological reversal that specifically invokes the aesthetic as its ground. We shall see that Foucault’s appeal to the aesthetic puts him unexpectedly in sync with the Frankfurt School’s emphasis upon cognitive agency and thereby anticipates my own refutation of the political critique of the aesthetic that Foucault himself has inspired in critics such as Bennett. I suggest that if we can hear the echo of Bennett in Bell, we should listen for the echo of Foucault. This will give us the deepest knowledge of what is wrong with the stance that would make aesthetic valuation and social transformation mutually exclusive projects.
Singer.book
26
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 26
Aesthetic Reason
For the early Foucault, as for Bennett, the sublating of particularized human practices to the kind of dedifferentiating aesthesis fostered in Bell’s formalistic manifesto is deemed to be symptomatic of Enlightenment culture. Foucault’s remedy calls for challenging the autonomy of those human agents in whom, as Bell would have it, an “aesthetic emotion” arises to lift us “above the stream of life.” For both Foucault and Bennett however, this ambition led precipitously to the foreclosure of subjective agency as a locus of judgment, in order to better honor the particularity of social practice that nonetheless instantiated such agents. That such a paradoxical proposition was posed as an alternative to an intractably instrumental rational formalism makes it no less paralyzing a paradox. We must therefore decide if paradox must be the limit of our knowledge in this domain. We will remember that for Foucault, as distinct from Bennett, the dedifferentiating power of autonomous subjectivity prompted his own redefinition of power as depersonalized force fields of contesting interests.These force fields are alleged to be ever more particular in their accession to unending conflict. In Discipline and Punish power is so radically desubjectivized that it promotes an effectively disinterested ethos, reminiscent of Enlightenment aesthetics. After all, Foucauldian power promotes an emancipation of human will only insofar as it inhibits the preeminence of any particular will.Yet in his final works, specifically in The Care of the Self, Foucault’s desire to objectify or explain this freedom as a realm of ends led him to posit a historical precedent in the social/sexual practices of Greek and Roman culture. This body of practices he conspicuously dubbed “an aesthetics of existence.”Aesthetics here seems to denote a self that is parsimoniously constituted in practices. Because in Greco-Roman culture these practices were indexed to material pleasures not reasons or conceptual desires, they represented for Foucault an exemplum for the dismantling of the conceptual apparatus of Enlightenment autonomy. Or, as Dreyfus and Rabinow see it, on the basis of the cultural precedent of GrecoRoman praxis, Foucault’s most mature critique of reason calls for a shift in ethical substance from “desire to pleasure” and a shift in telos from autonomy to aesthetics of existence.13 The difficulty for Foucault is that such a calculated divestiture of autonomy seems to require a reflective power of mind that is indistinguishable from the very subject who would otherwise be the locus of autonomy. For me, however, the fact that Foucault has recourse to the “aesthetic” in his articulation of this paradox reveals the intersubjective, recognition-based identity structure which underlies even the rigorously materialist praxis he espouses.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 27
The Adequacy of the Aesthetic
27
It indicates, at the heart of Foucault’s materialism, a need for conceptual, which is to say, rationalistic, leverage that his early work devalues as a means for ameliorating the otherwise purely destructive effects of power. This point is borne out most evocatively in the passages of The Care of the Self that deal with what Foucault calls an “ethics of control.” In this third volume of The History of Sexuality, the “aesthetic” pleasure achieved in the self-reflective emancipation of the self from the traps of autonomy is linked to recognition through the implicitly rational “power” of predication. It is specifically manifested as a power of selftransformation or self-conversion, as contrasted with the transformation or conversion of others: [T]he final goal of all the practices of the self still belongs to an ethics of control.Yet in order to characterize it, moralists are not content with invoking the agonistic form of a victory over forces difficult to subdue. . . . [Instead, t]his relation is . . . conceived in terms of the juridical model of possession: one “belongs to himself,” one is “his own master” . . . one exercises over oneself an authority that nothing limits or threatens; one holds the potestas sui. (Care of the Self, 65). Self-knowledge here is not a power of naming oneself (the claim of autonomy) but of changing oneself and thus appealing to some generalizable standard of selfhood.The goal is to become one’s own property. But the most important thing to observe here is that one becomes one’s own property (possession) not through any reification of selfpresence, whether autonomous or agonistic, but through predicative agency. And precisely because this predicative agency demurs a Nietzschean agonism, it entails a power of choice respecting properties that might be predicated on one’s self, which Foucault can therefore invoke (without self-contradiction) as rational (64). I would conclude that the normative and intersubjective or recognitional imperative of this rational knowledge inheres in the requirement of the self-possessing subject to know one’s self as something other than what one already is. For Foucault significantly links this consciousness to the emergence of the marital couple in Roman civil society. The relation of the conjugal couple supplants the more abstract relation of the individual to civil statutes. Foucault calls the civil bond a less complex “aesthetics of life.” It is less complex insofar as the subject’s “adequacy” to public statute demands a basically denotative reg-
Singer.book
28
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 28
Aesthetic Reason
ister of self-knowledge: “One seeks to make oneself as adequate as possible to one’s own status by means of a set of signs and marks pertaining to physical bearing, clothing and accommodations, gestures of generosity and munificence, spending behavior, and so on” (85). By contrast, the relationality of the conjugal relation fosters an expressive register of self-knowledge.The standard of adequacy is subsumed to the activity of soliciting recognition of adequacy. Ethical content is now indistinguishable from its aesthetic métier because adequacy is effectively elided with adequation: as Hegel, in the epigraph I have taken from the Aesthetics, urges us to see, adequacy comes into relief only against the background of a statutory standard of correctness that it challenges. The reciprocity of divergent perspectives that obtains in this “new” relationship of the couple is the only context within which self-possession makes sense as rational self-mastery. Or, as Foucault admonishes: the purpose of striving to possess a self “is not to try and decipher a meaning hidden beneath the visible representation [of self]; it is to assess the relationship between oneself and that which is represented, so as to accept in the relation to the self only that which can depend on the subject’s free and rational choice” (Care of the Self, 64; my emphasis). I would argue that such an assessment is conceivable only in the context of discriminations that proliferate criteria for further assessment.14 Otherwise, the cognitive efficacy of choice is dissipated in its degree of instrumental or utilitarian success. In the second half of The Care of the Self, Foucault of course narrates the fate of this Roman activity of pleasure (63–64) as it was transformed over centuries of “enlightenment” into an increasingly metaphysical discipline of desire: self-conversion ceased to be active and was displaced by metaphysical counters of pious or sacred identity.The important thing to observe here is that Foucault’s chronicle of this transformation, which has its outcome in the didactics of Victorian moralism, descries, above all else, the divorce of ethics from aesthetics, hitherto wedded in the legal institution of Roman marriage. He identifies this divorce with the triumph of the universality of reason, as opposed to what we might otherwise be more free to characterize as a universe of rational practices: within this characterization, the instrumentality of reason would be mitigated by its dependence upon human interaction. The goal of universality would be secularized within the constraints of historical self-consciousness.15 As I have anticipated, the idea of an unreasoned severance of the aesthetic from the ethical (rational) is preeminently what Theodor Adorno wants to redress through his reclamation of the concept of the aes-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 29
The Adequacy of the Aesthetic
29
thetic from historical abuses at the hands of the philosophers of disinterestedness or the philosophers of a “radical nominalism” (Aesthetic Theory, 457). In a way I have been treating Foucault as a thinker who, until his postulate of “aesthetics of existence,” vacillates between the positions of disinterestedness and nominalism. He only transcends the opposition by returning to the conceptual dynamic of reflection theory, without which the notion of an “aesthetics of existence” would be fundamentally incoherent.That the underlying principle eliciting a reconciliation of the aesthetical and the ethical in both Foucault and Adorno depends upon a reflective and therefore conceptual lucidity is apparent in their common, if ambiguously acknowledged, rootedness in Hegelian aesthetics. In the introduction to the Lectures in Aesthetics, Hegel condemns the “genial Godlike irony” promulgated by Romantic aesthetics (Fichte and the Schlegels) in which the subjectivizing “concentration of the I into itself” becomes the counter of artistic nature by breaking all bonds with social otherness. In Hegel’s point of view, what is posited in such a stance is an aesthetics of pure “self-enjoyment” from which reflective agency is exempted by sense-certainty. In this exemption, however, the aesthetic self is decisively denatured as a philosophical consciousness. It thereby ceases to be a strong enough warrant for theorizing the aesthetic in the first place. After all, we are bound to remember that in the Lectures, Hegel starts with the proposition that art/beauty is already a presupposition of philosophy and is therefore implicated in the laborious intersubjective strivings of Geist. Thus any severance of the aesthetic from the ethical in effect threatens the conceptual or philosophical efficacy of both categories. It reaffirms the necessity of their reciprocity if they are to have the kind of historical thrust that their competitive universalisms point toward.
V However divergent the ultimate purposes of his Aesthetic Theory, Adorno maintains the force and trajectory of Hegel’s critique of any aesthetics cut off from the historical production of intersubjective mind. This is explicit in Adorno’s will to maintain the aesthetic as a realm of conceptual autonomy. His aesthetic theory sustains the integrity of the concept of artistic or formal autonomy because it sustains the efficacy of the concept per se. I believe that it is no distortion to claim that, in Adorno, the concept is retained because it conditions intersubjectivity. Or this would be the case insofar as the concept seems
Singer.book
30
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 30
Aesthetic Reason
to entail recognition in Adorno’s construal of the aesthetic as an emphatically cognitive enterprise. Within the Adornian scheme, aesthetic cognition would be rendered unintelligible without a structure of recognition. For the link between the concept and aesthetic cognition is tacitly a phenomenon of choice. Choice is what distinguishes cognition qua concept from aesthetic cognition. I am well aware that, in featuring Adorno’s cognitive investments in the aesthetic, I ignore much in Adorno’s thinking that insists upon our respecting the limits of rationality. Critics such as J. M. Bernstein, Richard Wolin, and Thomas Huhn have ably represented this dimension of Adorno’s thinking, particularly with respect to the impossibility of writing poetry after Auschwitz. But my emphasis on choice-making here dictates my faith in a more rationalistic Adorno.16 We must of course first be willing to see that the imperative of this choice-making arises in the instance that Adorno acknowledges to be a sine qua non of artistic experience and aesthetic knowledge: “Every aspect of aesthetic illusion carries with it aesthetic inconsistencies in the form of contradictions between what the work of art pretends to be and what it is” (Aesthetic Theory, 149). For Adorno artistic knowledge obtains only where conceptual truth, a self-conscious illusion, articulates its illusoriness as a contingency of what is not illusion. Artistic knowledge thus depends upon a dialectical exchange of perspectives that cannot be abstracted from an intersubjective realm of reference because it does not permit any abstraction from the contingency of meaning.What is not illusion is intelligible as a rational preference conditioned by the exigencies of the knowledge of illusion.17 Here we might further understand choice to be consistent with the epistemic claims of Hilary Putnam’s “internal realism”: where we take something to be true in a consensus based on a choice of alternatives.18 The consensus is a function of the need to see alternatives as more or less desirable within a community of mutually recognized needs. Inherent in this understanding is the idea that need induces community through the mediations of recognition. Recognition, within which the scope of alternatives arises, is for that reason an ethical corollary of rational choice-making. Recognition in effect makes the difference between need and desire where we count the distinction between need and desire as a barrier between individual and communitarian ethos. After all, need without recognition is mere difference, which would devolve in the course of conflicting wills to a demand for recognition and, given the oppression of that demand, a correlative desire for alternative choices.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 31
The Adequacy of the Aesthetic
31
In this regard we might assert even more convincingly that need, and emphatically the need for recognition, is a de facto annunciation of communitarian ethos because its intelligibility entails what is needed as a ratio of self and other.Adorno intimates the point himself when he says in Negative Dialectics “[N]eed is where we think from” (408; my emphasis). He goes on to complete the thought in a way that compels us to follow a logical path from need to desire, from being to acting and so from individuality to community: “[T]he motor of the need is an effort that involves thought as action.The object of critique is not the need in thinking, but the relationship between the two.” By pegging critique to the “relationship,” the reciprocity between passive need and active thinking, we can more richly appreciate that need becomes a threshold of recognition.This is most clearly the case in the inducements to self-transformation that are inevitable within the framework of any such conscientiously relational knowledge. Since by choosing in the eyes of others one is choosing to be chosen, one is always implicitly choosing to change.The heightened relationality marked by Adorno between need and thinking helps us to see how choice between alternatives is decisively subordinated to choosing agents rather than abstractly ordinational principles or rules. In other words, choosing agents are bound ethically by dint of the very self-transformational impetus understood here to be a feature of choice itself. Such a valorization of choosing agents is at the heart of Adorno’s project in Aesthetic Theory where he distinguishes art from other conceptual mediations.Adorno figures the distinctiveness of art by calling it a “second reflection.” Reflective of the process of the formation of the concept, Adorno’s second reflection is decisively a re-cognition. This doubly reflective “process” is precisely what reveals illusoriness to be, as I have already noted, a “meaningful” contingency of what is not illusion. In second reflection we can perhaps see more clearly than before that what is not illusion is thereby a touchstone of transformation.19 In the case of “second reflection” we are effectively acceding to the inexorable transformability of form per se. So long as form must be conceived under the constraint of recognition (the recognition that it is articulated in relation to other needs and thereby submits to protocols of self-justification),“second reflection” signals the necessary “reversion” of form to the enabling conditions of formalization. Here it is useful to observe how Hegel’s account of “Romantic art,” despite its ultimate capitulation to a narrative of spiritual apotheosis, epitomizes the dynamic of this “reversion” as an effective “revision” of the contextual
Singer.book
32
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 32
Aesthetic Reason
determinants of form. In that way it dovetails with the formal imperative of Adornian aesthetics. Hegel’s valorization of Romantic form is predicated upon a transformative capacity: the form of the artwork serves as the “self-consciousness of a defect in the form” or rather, as an appreciation of the form itself as something “transient and fugitive,” a consciousness of the form as something else.20 In these terms Hegel means to herald the freedom of Spirit as a counter for a consciousness of contingency that does not unphilosophically converge upon a reifying concept of contingency. In Aesthetic Theory, Adorno seems to endorse this self-consciousness of form. It renders form “transient and fugitive,” inasmuch as we respect the determinative (determinative of what is not transient and fugitive) density of the self-consciousness instantiated within those constraints. Ironically, however, Adorno is closest to Hegelian intentions where he is furthest afield from Hegelian conclusions. This is clear where we can correlate Adorno’s speculation on aesthetic form with Hegel’s insistence that the standard of aesthetic judgment must be one of the “adequacy,” rather than the “correctness,” of the form. For Hegel the standard of correctness or perfection in the form is effectively a Kantian-style rule of taste. Correctness epitomizes the preemption of Spirit that obtains in any one-sided appeal to external registers for the consciousness of form. Correctness inhibits the notion of form as transformational because the externality of the judgment of “correct” form constitutes a concession to the laws of a Natural determinism. By contrast with the standard of correctness, the standard of the “adequacy,” according to which Hegel valorizes the authenticity of art production qua action, entails a freer determination. Specifically, it entails a freedom from the Natural determinations of physical existence, a freedom “owing to [the fact that] the sensuous appearance sinks into worthlessness” (Introductory Lectures on Aesthetics, 116–17). It is no surprise that Hegel asserts poetry to be the truest “embodiment” of this “Romantic art,” because the embodying sensuous form (language) through which the idea is animated is, in this case, already a sign. It is thereby inevitably a medium of adequation, more even than a nominal standard of adequacy.Adequation establishes the efficacy of adequacy as a praxis of truth rather than as a judgment of truth. It checks the judgers’ temptation to embrace either the kind of metaphysical or materialist one-sidedness, which a consciousness conditioned by subject-object dualisms is otherwise susceptible to. It is of course the subject’s hapless “confinement” within subject-object dualisms that Adorno sees as the tragic self-inhibitor and nemesis of Hegelian dialectic.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 33
The Adequacy of the Aesthetic
33
Thus Adorno’s “second reflection”21 strives to overcome precisely the kind of one-sidedness that Hegel claims is imposed by a standard of correctness; unlike Hegel, however,Adorno “overcomes” by seeking to make “non-identity” the telos of identity rather than by a teleology of Spiritual identity.22 It is important to note that when Adorno valorizes aesthetic reflection he does so by contrasting it invidiously with rational intention. Rational intent, he says, should be equated with idealist truth. He argues that philosophical truth and reflection are, in that traditional equation, rendered antithetical. As such they constitute an insuperable inhibition to artistic production.They reprise the theorypraxis split upon which Plato’s fateful disenfranchisement of art was so self-servingly founded. Second reflection is thus proffered as a way of making truth once again immanent to reflection. It is a means of reconditioning spirit to experience. Adorno elaborates his understanding of aesthetic cognition in Aesthetic Theory as the “reliquifying” of objective spirit. With this formulation he strives to reverse the Hegelian idea that the aesthetic follows historical change. On this basis he can assert that “history is intrinsic to the truth content of aesthetics” (490). In other words, the kind of history invoked here does not subordinate itself to a Hegelian objectifying spirit that mandates the transcendence of art. Furthermore, Adorno’s interest in the claim that history is intrinsic to the truth content of aesthetics is clearly intended to construe the constitutive interestedness of the subject as an unbreakable bond between the aesthetic and the social.Thus he marks a selfconsciously polemical contrast with Kantian “disinterestedness.” By these means,Adorno would obviate the invidious distinction between art and philosophy that Hegel saw as the self-sacrificing discipline to which the artwork must submit, if subjectivity was to be guaranteed a secure passage from art into life. Accordingly, in a chapter of Aesthetic Theory aptly titled “Society,” Adorno gives us a phenomenological account of the transformative selfconsciousness induced by the artwork in terms that preserve the historical thrust of Hegelian “truth.” But unlike Hegel, Adorno pursues this truth within a recognition model of selfhood that does not entail the sacrifice of “lived experience” (Aesthetic Theory, 348). Although this discussion is contextually remote from the expository passages on second reflection per se, I believe it offers a convincing gloss on the reflective agency Adorno wants to endow in his use of the term. In this way he intimates its ties to a choice-making protocol. The chapter “Society” thereby helps to refute the persistent charge that in second reflection Adorno invites Hegel’s nostalgia for a utopian “reconciliation” of self
Singer.book
34
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 34
Aesthetic Reason
and world rather than a pragmatic labor of self-differentiation. The gist of my argument here is implied in Adorno’s definition of reconciliation, resonant as it is with the Hegelian representation/negation of form as something “transient and fugitive”: “Reconciliation . . . refers to the mode of conduct of works of art in so far as they become conscious of the non-identical in their midst” (Aesthetic Theory, 194). The task of defending Adorno’s aesthetic as a pragmatic, cognitive enterprise here is to show how consciousness of nonidentity remains a lever of rational agency—that is, how recognition completes the meaning of reconciliation.The chapter “Society” gives us the new term “subjective tremor” to buttress the case. Tremor is Adorno’s way of understanding the subject as a counterpart of the artwork: such that recognition determines the subject’s self-knowledge in a sustasis of cognition beyond the limit of a single concept of the artwork.Tremor (Erschütterung) is specifically a “concern” triggered by “great works of art” when the subject “gives himself over to the work. He loses his footing, discovering that the truth embodied in the aesthetic image has real, tangible possibilities.” By “tangible possibilities”Adorno intimates an effective weakening of the ego that nonetheless is distinguishable from the “weakening of the ego induced by the culture industry,” since it reminds the ego of “its limits and finitude” (347). That tremor is a counter for Adornian mimesis in this respect is clear enough. But that its purchase on nonidentity implicates it in recognition comes clear only with Adorno’s further linkage of mimesis to deixis.This linkage is a way of indicating the cognitive boundedness of tremor. I want to suggest that this linkage might also be a fulcrum of intersubjective communication. It would thus belie the contention of critics such as Habermas and Albrecht Wellmer that Adorno’s aesthetic theory lacks a “communicative moment”: one that could be judged adequate to or could do justice to its ethical purport. Deixis, a distinctly public gesture, presupposes an other whose recognition makes reference into a conceptual proposition, however provisional or self-critical it turns out to be.23 Deixis points to a particular object whose particularity is indistinguishable from the mediating attention of another’s consciousness. Similarly, according to Adorno, tremor displays the way in which “art works seem to point a finger at their content” (Aesthetic Theory, 347). This anthropomorphic pointing invokes a demand for “self-recognition” that is necessarily conditioned upon a desire to be “someone in particular.”The double-sidedness of this deictic reference mirrors the double mediation of second reflection. It thus elucidates the non-identical component of nonconceptual
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 35
The Adequacy of the Aesthetic
35
mimesis. Since mimesis, analyzed by Adorno in the context of tremor, is furthermore deemed to be an “adaptive response” to the deictic gesture, I want to propose that it entails a reciprocal subjective act that could only be intelligible in terms of a choice to be recognized as one making a certain kind of choice. Here is the crux of my claim that Adornian aesthetics is staked in the idea of the inherently productive agency of second reflection. It rebuts the charge of subjective universalism that would otherwise nullify the choice upon which I am saying second reflection is predicated. We have seen that it is precisely this charge of subjective universalism that critics like Wellmer hurl against Adorno on the basis of their demand for a “communicative moment,” an objectifiable measure of “reciprocity” between subjective consciousness and the intersubjective “Other.”This demand arises from their conviction that Adornian reconciliation demurs any such discursive mediation. We shall now see, however, how this critique depends on a highly selective reading of Adorno’s aesthetic theory: one that too glibly privileges the concept of reconciliation over the concept of tremor in the account of Adorno’s second reflection. Here an affinity between Adorno’s Aesthetic Theory and Johann Gottlieb Fichte’s Science of Knowledge (Wissenschaftslehre, 1794) offers a compelling perspective for rethinking the relative efficacy of reconciliation and tremor. For Fichte, the preeminent post-Enlightenment, proto-Hegelian philosopher of the subject-as-activity (“self activity”), the freedom of an otherwise alienated self-consciousness is unthinkable except under the condition of intersubjective recognition. I want to show how the specific mode of Fichtean recognition devolves to choice, much as I saw choice embedded in Adornian tremor (second reflection).A brief account of the threshold of that choice—expressed as subjective freedom in Fichte—might motivate a reading of Adorno’s aesthetic theory that reverses the priority of reconciliation over tremor and obviates the objections of his critics.We might even see Adorno’s proximity to the specifically communitarian ideals that Wellmer and Habermas wield against him. A master term in Fichte’s Science of Knowledge, Aufforderung, is the motor of my argument here. For like tremor, in which the subject gives itself to the work, Aufforderung, or “summons,” is purveyed as a ground for subjectivity that eludes any transcendental conditionality and thus entails reciprocal recognition as the key to its intelligibility. It is no coincidence that Fichte, like Adorno, is subject to the charge of subjective universalism for his predicating self-consciousness on an
Singer.book
36
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 36
Aesthetic Reason
active subject. But close attention to Fichte’s sense of the Aufforderung as a nontranscendental grounding of the self challenges this appearance. By analogy, it prompts us to see how Adorno extricates himself from the ethical impasse of subjective universalism “as if” on the model of Fichtean subjectivity. For Fichte the impasse of subjective universalism inheres in the idea that any ethical action predicated on the self, even if it is a self-alienating self, is inevitably recessed into an ontological realm exempt from the privileges of choice that are public and social. Quite to the contrary, in the most fully articulated version of Fichte’s argument, the term Aufforderung denotes an active solicitation of subjectivity by another in an act of recognition (Anerkennung).This denotes recognition by the self of its dependence on the solicitation of its selfhood from the place of the Other. J. M. Bernstein, in The Fate of Art, has characterized the “cognitive claim of aesthetic culture” in Adornian aesthetics, which I have located in Adornian tremor, as a solicitation of nonidentity by the artwork. Bernstein has suggested that this solicitation serves Adorno as a vehicle for redeeming “the abstraction of modernism directly” (Fate of Art, 192), wedded, as it otherwise is, to the universality of subjective ego. The remaining burden of my exposition, then, is to show how a solicitation, which is clearly intersubjective in Fichte, may be construed as parallel to the solicitation that plays between the subject and the work of art in Adorno. First, however, I must emphasize how, in both cases, subjectivity is self-positing not in a transcendental sense, but in a highly situational one.This is by virtue of the fact that neither Fichte nor Adorno see the solicitation in Aufforderung or in tremor as a solicitation of the being of freedom that subjectivity is a counter for. Subjective freedom (and responsibility) is carefully stipulated to be a solicitation of the consciousness of freedom, not the being of freedom.This was already intimated in the insight that the self “summoned” in Aufforderung is mediated by a kind of deixis. For Fichte in particular, the recognition of the other, which constitutes the other’s solicitation of self, does not, as in Kant, create a circumstance where I infer my freedom from the freedom of others. Rather, I posit my freedom in the act of choosing to accept the other’s recognition of me. The act of the other is prior to the act of the self, but its intelligibility depends upon the “decision” of the self to recognize it.24 In effect, one posits that one is posited, a condition that Fichte elsewhere characterizes as a “determination to selfdetermination”25 Thus it is that Fichte, despite his granting the subject the authority of self-positing, insists that this is a nontranscendental posit. Even more
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 37
The Adequacy of the Aesthetic
37
disarming of the traditional critique of German Idealism, Fichte asserts that the self is not a ground since “the ground falls outside what it grounds.”26 Fichte in effect grounds this assertion by perpetrating a confusion between Aufforderung and an earlier evocation of its problematic in the Wissenschaftslehre as Anstoss. Anstoss means “blockage” or “shock.” 27 The Anstoss is the restriction of the freedom of the selfimposed by the other which guarantees the community of the freedom of others from whence the freedom of the self can be seen to arise. As Robert R.Williams argues, Anstoss is the more primitive, transcendental, conditional premise of recognition that the nontranscendental Aufforderung complements in its more specific articulation of recognition as a form of social reciprocity.The fact that Fichte deliberately blurs the line between the transcendental (nondiscursive) Anstoss and the nontranscendental (situational) Aufforderung (in the development of his thinking from Wissenschaftslehre [1794] to the Naturrecht [1796]) suggests a desire to throw off any appearance of subjective universalism by refusing to allow a presumption that otherness could be nonreciprocal. Certainly Anstoss, as a blockage against the flow of subjective free will, displays an affinity with the shock of Adornian tremor. But more implicitly, and especially if we acknowledge Fichte’s stratagem of making Anstoss reciprocal with subjective agency in Aufforderung, it recalls the cognitive bearing of the shock presented to the subject by the artwork. It is an imperative to choose one’s-being-posited in certain terms. It thus locates the cognitive urgency of Adorno’s aesthetic, which I have been asserting is crucial to second reflection.This is especially the case if we observe that tremor, construed as analogous to Aufforderung, must be treated in Adorno’s framework indisputably as an event. In that regard, it is independent of the universalism that its affiliation with reconciliation seemed to burden it with. Adorno himself seems to invite this logic in a trenchant critique of Bertolt Brecht that serves as the contextual setup for the exposition of tremor. Brecht is faulted for mistaking the “alienation effect,” which is a kind of Anstoss/tremor, as the full scope of the “reflective attitude” art is meant to induce. Adorno charges that Brecht is too one-sided, forgetting that true reflection requires a structural “ambiguity,” by contrast with a self-inflating Brechtian didacticism.With reference to this ambiguity Adorno seems to evoke or “summon” a reciprocity of knowledge, vis-à-vis the subject’s apprehension of the artwork, that gains the status of “event.”This is consistent with the notion of event as contingent upon nonsubjective elements (Aesthetic Theory, 344). Such reciprocity is acknowledged in what Adorno calls an “externalization” of the
Singer.book
38
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 38
Aesthetic Reason
subject through the artwork. Its “cognitive” consequence obtains in the artwork’s capacity to summon (through tremor) the most primitive identificatory self into an intersubjective force field: one that forces the self out of itself (345) without submitting to a Hegelian sublation.
VI I have acknowledged that this reciprocity is the quite admirable goal of Albrecht Wellmer’s ethical-political analysis of modernity. For Wellmer, modernity is morally inhibited by the Kantian postulate of a universalistic ought in particular will.The moral impasse is roughly analogous to Wellmer’s sense of the fatal lack in Adorno’s Aesthetic Theory: its appearance of sacrificing communication to reconciliation. But because we can now understand how Adorno’s discussion of tremor answers Wellmer’s objections, it makes sense to conclude by assessing the validity of Wellmer’s own insistence upon reciprocal recognition as a way of maintaining the communicative efficacy of the aesthetic and thereby establishing its cognitive value. In an important essay,“Ethics and Dialogue,” in The Persistence of Modernity, Wellmer reveals that his strong interest in the aesthetic depends on his belief that universalistic morality can be said to be cognitive only under the specific condition that its normativity is secured by the application of norms, not by a grounding of norms. Here his critique of modernity quarrels openly with Kant’s desire to sublate the I ought into I will, which he understands as an ethical corollary of aesthetic judgment.Wellmer revises Kant in order to put this ideal within a practically cognizable perspective: “[T]he view that I am propounding is that the validity of moral norms only stretches as far as the validity of the moral judgments that can be—not grounded, but—expressed through these norms” (“Ethics and Dialogue,” 204). In light of Wellmer’s denial of the possibility to ground normativity universally, we must infer that expressivity is specifically a matter of reciprocal recognition. In other words, for Wellmer, Kant’s categorical ought is rationalizable into a practical will only if we accept that “the development of a universalistic morality can then be understood as the successive elimination of the foundations of a particularist understanding of . . . structures of reciprocity” (208). Only when we recognize that the universal ought is without foundation does it become “accessible to reason,” a reason that thereby possesses a vitally “situational index” (204). After all, recognition of the “elimination of the foundations of a particularist under-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 39
The Adequacy of the Aesthetic
39
standing” (208) is possible only within a specifiable circumstance of need or crisis like that actualized in Adorno’s tremor. Here recognition accedes to the aesthetic. If we can sustain the notion that Adornian tremor, seen in the light of Anstoss and Aufforderung, instantiates need as something that must be mutually recognized, we might assert that the efficacy of the cognitive subject, in Adorno and Wellmer both, depends on something like a regimen of training in reciprocal recognition. The protocol of such training portends the emancipation from the universalist traps of Enlightenment that both Adorno and Wellmer aspire to. Wellmer is explicit on this point, insisting that a lack of moral sense is not “a cognitive deficiency” but a recognition that the “person concerned has not been adequately trained in reciprocal recognition” (“Ethics and Dialogue,” 210).The possibility of “training” intimates an “aesthetic education of man” more amenable to ethical agency than that imagined by Schiller in his anticipation of an aesthetic state.28 We might even say that such training is remedial for the Schillerian curriculum humanitas because the only reconciliation it proffers is one that submits to the diverse interests— to the irreducible interestedness—of the parties to any reconciliation. They would be obliged to see themselves produced in the idea of the reconciliation they seek. Indeed, the appeal to “training in reciprocal recognition” helps to sharpen the distinction between what I want to evoke in the name of a cognitive aesthetic and the phenomenalist and formalist paradigms of aesthesis against which the anti-aesthetic directs its fervent political critique. Earlier in this chapter I indicated how the phenomenalist aesthetic, epitomized by the philosophy of taste, and the formalist aesthetic, epitomized by a standard of emotional response, are both universalist in their privileging of disinterestedness. Phenomenalist aesthetics (Shaftesbury, Hutcheson, and others) takes Nature as its realm of inquiry and taste as its standard of judgment. Formalist aesthetics (Bell, Beardsley, and others) takes culture (the artifactual) as its realm of inquiry and an “aesthetic emotion” or “significant form” as its standard of judgment. In the former, disinterestedness is the proof of the rule of taste in artistic sensibility. In the latter, disinterestedness is the effect produced upon the artistic sensibility by the artwork, in other words, an “aesthetic effect” conditioned by a “significant form.”The liability of both traditions is their putting production and recognition in barren opposition to one another, thus opening a chasm between aesthetic form and a “possible world” of political action. By comparison, the cognitive aesthetic that I have tried to lay the
Singer.book
40
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 40
Aesthetic Reason
groundwork for in this chapter takes culture as its realm of inquiry, but makes active choice its standard of judgment. In this respect, aesthesis essays to maximize dimensions of the artwork by increasing the aesthete’s (the judger’s and the maker’s) power of making distinctions. Choice, as opposed to disinterestedness (whether valorized as a proof of the universal and immanent to taste, or as the universalizing effectivity of the judgment of taste) makes production and recognition duly reciprocal.And because this reciprocity is a variable of choice, its meaning is vested in the unapologetic interestedness of a purposive but plausibly counterideological agent of change. When the standard of adequacy is assimilated to the exigency of act, the activity of adequation serves the adequacy of the aesthetic. What is proposed here, then, is a stance toward aesthetic valuation that stresses the active mode of subjectivity. If we can, in this way, countenance analytical terms for interpretation of the artwork that preempt the reigning universalisms of aesthetic tradition, we might render the artwork, and our responses to it, plausible sites for thinking about how to demystify the mutual exclusion between art and politics, the artwork and the polis.The partisans of the anti-aesthetic must perpetuate these dichotomies in order to remedy the social ills for which they hold the aesthetic accountable. Because, for them, aesthesis is the opposite of action. And yet the Greek polis, an arena of civic action in which the vital aesthetic tradition of tragedy arises, presupposes precisely the inextricability of the deliberative mind of the prospective agent from the worldly and sensuous involvements that aesthesis grounds. The ensuing chapters of this work develop out of an account of the affinities between aesthetic valuation and political agency that originate within the cultural framework of the “tragic” polis. Accepting these affinities forces us to recognize the common stake of aesthetic valuation and political agency in cognition.This acknowledgment imposes upon our appreciation of the artwork burdens of reflective subjectivity without which work and world would be mutually inconceivable.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 41
2
Aesthetic Community: Recognition as an Other Sense of Sensus Communis In man, otherness, which he shares with everything that is, and distinctness, which he shares with everything alive, become uniqueness, and human plurality is the paradoxical plurality of unique beings. —Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition
I In her last published work, Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy, Hannah Arendt extrapolates from what she takes to be the socializing aptitude of Kantian aesthetic judgment and implicitly revives a longdormant project of Western philosophy: the ideal of the aesthetic state. In the act of imagining a politics for Kant,Arendt evokes the Greek faith in making political order out of aesthetic judgment: the ethical artifice of the polis. Within the specifically Aristotelian tradition that Arendt works so productively, there is no invidious hierarchy of aesthetic and political values.This admittedly partial view of the Greek polis nevertheless shows aesthetical and political values to be determinable within a context of human choice-making constrained by social recognition. Such was the spirit of Greek republicanism as Arendt saw it, a spirit that I will argue contemporary aesthetics is bound to reckon with again in its pursuit of ethical and political goods. In The Aesthetic State:A Quest in Modern German Thought, Joseph Chytry has sketched a historical basis for the link between aesthesis and republican government in a way that highlights the relevance of Arendt’s work on Kant to contemporary debates about the relation of art to political life in postmodern culture.1 Chytry traces the ideal of the aesthetic state originally to Paris’s judgment of Hera (property as power), Athena (authority, martial success), and Aphrodite (the procurer of beauty). Prior to the act of judging, the three divinities present a problematic configuration of the disciplines of the ethical, the
Singer.book
42
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 42
Aesthetic Reason
political, and the beautiful as alienated from one another.This mutual alienation of the disciplines bears a striking resemblance to the perceived overspecialization of science, morality, and aesthetics that Jürgen Habermas, among other communitarian universalists, has descried as a specter of civic injustice, not to say doom, upon the modern state.2 In fact, Chytry’s glance backward shows how well founded Habermas’s conscientiously forward-looking concern might be. After all, the healing of the split between the disciplines is precisely what was proffered in Paris’s judgment, a judgment whose efficacy was promulgated in the ideal of beauty. By rewarding Paris with Helen, Aphrodite heralded a “presencing of beauty” that brooked no divisions between power and authority, politics, and ethics. The ideal of judgment purveyed in Greek myth had its political analogue in fifth-century participatory democracy, under the beneficent rule of Solon. The paradigmatic sense of justice for which the name Solon is emblematic follows from his extending participatory rights, a protocol of choice, to the lowest classes, the “Thetes,” and thereby fostering a universality of judgment within a practicable public sphere.3 On this basis, it could be said that the idea of beauty or the judgment of the aesthete, an individuality determined in the realm of aestheta (the sensorium of experience), locates a concern for a practical particularity that is not sacrificed to an abstract universality. Correspondingly, the “presencing of beauty” in an act of judgment shows itself to be preferable to the insubstantial, metaphysically abstract ideals, otherwise proffered independently by politics and morality: it has provenance in the offices of human rather than Natural or divine ordination. Under the auspices of beauty, judgment is securely anchored within the realm of malleable appearances over which human choice exercises an inclusive will.Willful human nature is coextensive with appearances. In this way it projects an optimistically historical rather than a fatalistic and metaphysical trajectory of knowledge. It plausibly incorporates both political and ethical interests rather than setting them tragically, because mutually exclusively, against one another. In Chytry’s narrative of Greek social institutions, the realm of the aesthetic only split off from the political and the ethical again at a distinctly “metaphysical” moment in the history of the Athenian polis. At this time, the participation of particular individuals in the governance of the state ceased to be a reality of civic life. Such was the consequence of the decline of the Ionian League and the loss of Athenian independence that climaxed with Sulla’s razing of the city in 86 b.c.4 In other words, subsequent to the dissolution of a political structure,
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 43
Aesthetic Community
43
which promoted the particular rights of individuals as participants in power, the understanding of the aesthetic as a locus of universality displaced the understanding of the aesthetic as a locus of particularity. Painted in admittedly broad strokes, this is a story of cultural dissolution, which we might see usefully, if tragically, reprised in the waning of the Florentine Renaissance, and which Habermas influentially (following Horkheimer and Adorno) equates with the historical vicissitudes defining the movements of Romanticism and modernist formalism. Not coincidentally, these are three signal moments of Western cultural history (Renaissance humanism, English and German Romanticism, and international modernism) when artistic production resumes its antagonism with political and ethical institutions by presuming its transcendence of them, thus leading judgment back into a realm of metaphysically absolutizing mutual exclusions. I would suggest that it is precisely the dissolution of a political structure dependent on the productive acts of particular human agents that Hannah Arendt means to redress in the Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy. Her purport here is to refocus attention on the particular human agent such that agency is susceptible to universalization without succumbing to a preemptive universal.This is a defining concern of Arendt’s work beginning with The Human Condition (1958) and extending through the incomplete The Life of the Mind (1978). The Lectures (1982) remain the last clue about how this project would have been concluded. I will argue that, specifically in the Lectures, Arendt’s appropriation of the Kantian concept of “exemplary validity,” in order to bridge aesthetic judgment with political agency, rearticulates, for the late twentieth century, rudiments of the Greek political enterprise: of making judgment universalizable within a social universe that can accommodate the particular as particular. It will therefore be my contention in this chapter that the redemption of such particularity ought to be an ethical common concern of aesthetics and politics. Particularity constitutes the genealogical link between the “aesthetic state” and the aesthetic ideal of ethical community (politics) that Kant famously reformulated in the term sensus communis. 5 Sensus communis, identified with the judgment of taste in Kant’s third critique, denotes a common sense that is neither commonplace nor ahistorically universal, but constitutive-analytical of the idea of community itself. Sensus communis is therefore a resource of reflective mind that, particularly in Arendt’s reading of it, has political consequence because it elides community with the communicability of individual nature.Aptly in one of his last essays,“Perpetual Peace” (1795), Kant himself purveys
Singer.book
44
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 44
Aesthetic Reason
a notion of community that shows strong affinity with the political principle of Greek republicanism: the freedom of the members of a society “accords with the principles of the dependence of everyone on a single, common [source of] legislation (as subjects), and . . . accords with the law of the equality of them all” (“Perpetual Peace,” 112). In the following pages we shall see that as the idealism inherent in the aesthetic state or sensus communis was for the Greeks, for the Florentine Renaissance, and for Kantian idealism, so it ought to become, for the sake of contemporary debates, the preferred framework within which any discussion of the category of the aesthetic as a value-making enterprise takes place. It will not be my purpose to assert the truth or even the scholarly success of Hannah Arendt’s subsumption of Kantian aesthetics to a politics he never wrote.6 Rather, I wish to see how her reading of sensus communis gives a more general warrant for rethinking the category of the aesthetic, in light of what we might describe as the political exigencies of human judgment.This rethinking intimates a productive reckoning between the artwork and social community, such that the idea of social community may be seen to be consistent with ideals of justice and perfectibility that have long been assumed to be touchstones—albeit spiritual—of artistic truth and practice. I take Arendt’s work as emblematic of the need to respond to a world in which aesthetics and politics have succumbed to a singularly unproductive dualism, where aesthetics has been corrupted into aestheticism for the mutually destructive sake of making invidious distinctions on both sides.7 To show the urgency of a warrant for rethinking the aesthetic along such lines it will therefore be necessary to rehearse the historical reasons that precipitated the dualism.These reasons concomitantly explain the disappearance, until recently, of the ideal of the aesthetic state or sensus communis as a lever of cultural creativity.Then we shall see how Arendt’s revisionist reading of sensus communis, in Kant’s third critique, both reflects these reasons and the history that embodies them. We will furthermore see how Arendt anticipates the resurgence of the ideal of sensus communis in postmodern philosophy, and the corresponding resurgence of ethical concerns in poststructuralist literary theory, where the gap between poetics and politics has become an increasingly anxious locus of critical inquiry. I think that Arendt’s work of the 1960s and 1970s constitutes a prescient corrective to the prevailing noncognitive reconstructions of the aesthetic in the poststructuralist era. Contemporary literary criticism has given new currency to the ideal of sensus communis, but at the expense of a credible sociopo-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 45
Aesthetic Community
45
litical agency.As if in response to recent valorizations of an essentially disinterested and hence unreflectively pluralistic “political aesthetic,” promoted by Baudrillardians, Lyotardians, multiculturalists, and feminists,8 Arendt’s work permits us to speculate that the category of the aesthetic, and its speculative corollary in sensus communis, might lead us toward a notion of the political that has real cognitive-rationalist potential for maximizing the choice-making capacity of the members of a social community. Such a program would confer the ethical nature of these members with more authority than they might otherwise muster from regnant noncognitive and antirationalist agendas, which valorize pluralism at the expense of human plurality. It might, along these lines, offer a framework for rescuing aesthetics from aestheticism.
II If we are to approach the history of sensus communis as an encompassing of the aesthetic and the political (not a reduction of one to the other) we must begin where the classical etymology of aesthetics begins, with sense, the proverbial ground of the beautiful and the locus of individual experience. Since the ill-fated struggle of Neoplatonism to reconcile “intelligibles” with “sensibles,” we have accepted that sense qua sensation is always multiple in our deferral to a discriminatory faculty by which we might gain a reflective purchase on it.Yet insofar as this discriminatory faculty calls each individual’s particular experience to account, it implicitly solicits a standard of publicity and consensus. Following Plato, the universalist consensus presupposed successively by classical, neoclassical, and Romantic aesthetics has eluded the contradiction between privacy and publicity by positing in beauty or sublimity a community of judgment that lacks an effectual protocol of individual judging.9 It is the inescapable self-contradictoriness of this proposition that has induced the consequent and recurrent alienation of the aesthetic from the political. In other words, the alienation of art from politics accrues in proportion to the tendency to ignore or forget the provenance of consensus in the capacity for discrimination (choosing) itself. I have already noted that in the 1770s Johann Gottlieb Herder worked in the service of an emergent cognitive aesthetic to preempt such forgetfulness of the provenance of consensus in the capacity for discrimination. He characterized this capacity as an “apperceptive discrimination.” 10 In his Essay on the Origin of Language (1771),
Singer.book
46
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 46
Aesthetic Reason
Herder wanted to distinguish a passively sense-bound connoisseurship of taste—which he associated with classical theories—from an active, conceptually productive philosophy of taste. By this designation Herder made the point that we reflect upon experience not by recognizing properties in objects, but by recognizing properties that distinguish objects from one another.11 This insight imposes a burden of communicability on the formation of consensus. Herder himself became more mystically minded about the consensus forged in the judgment of taste. But if we confine ourselves to his pre–Sturm und Drang writings, we may extrapolate that insofar as classical and Romantic aesthetics evade a standard of communicability in judgment, they produce an impoverished social consensus.12 The judgments they promulgate will tend to be objectifying rather than reflective, owing to their inability to distinguish the properties of objects judged from the capacity of judgment endowed by the discursive situatedness of the judger. Even more important for the argument that follows, I believe that this impoverished consensus is underwritten and perpetuated by a flawed concept of human self-recognition: one that is relatively unreflective insofar as it is nonreciprocal. Recognition is, in fact, key to the republican idealism of the aesthetic state—and the concomitant ethical charge of sensus communis—because it indexes self-knowledge within a social consensus to human activity or interaction with another. To put this in its richest historical perspective, we must remember that the exemplar for this interaction with another within the Greek polis—which in turn gives us the prototype of sensus communis, albeit by Roman extraction—is the discipline of eristics or sophistic persuasiveness. Peitho, the goddess of persuasion, was the assistant and double of Aphrodite in Athens, a fact that suggests the entailment of rhetoric in the knowledge of beauty, and correlatively, the rhetorical pragmatism of the beautiful.13 Although in the age of its flourishing it contended with mystical counterforces abroad in Greek culture, eristics, the salient techne of sophism, is a touchstone of reciprocal recognition: whatever truths may be propounded within the dialogic structure of its discourse depends upon what Hannah Arendt will call a mode of “representative thinking.” Representative thinking promotes the insight that thought cannot be thought directly but only in relation to the means of our representing to ourselves that which we do not perceive—an indirection predicated on proliferating the “standpoints I have present in my mind” (Lectures, 107). We will see shortly that Arendt qualifies the practical sociality of this idea. But for the moment suffice it to say that the operative indirectness of eristics indexes the agonistic other.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 47
Aesthetic Community
47
Eristics or sophism is a dialectical métier of argumentation that subsists on a highly thespic protocol of questioning “the Other.” It intimates the idea of a world of sense—aistheta—that is potentially communitarian, by virtue of the priority given to communication over sensuous ecstasy.This communication, because its intelligibility within the scope of “representative thinking” defers strategically to another, depends on a structure of discursive reversibility: the sense dependent on a sign presupposes the acceptance of its (the sign’s) meaning by another.This acceptance in turn submits to a standard of knowledge claims rendered revisable in its very implementation. It is this principle that guarantees the reciprocity of recognition as a predicate of what I am calling the cognitive aesthetic. We can more clearly see the special affinity of eristics for the aesthetic if we realize that the principle of reversibility, so integral to its practice, both recapitulates the peripety (and anagnorisis) of Aristotelian tragedy and proffers an extension of the knowledge purveyed in tragedy.This will be a topos of discussion in all the ensuing chapters. Specifically, eristics recapitulates peripety insofar as tragedy marks the recognition of the limits of self. By the same token, eristics extends tragic knowledge inasmuch as it is related to Aristotelian phronesis (prudential judgment). For Aristotle, phronesis is the motor of tragic action. In that capacity it also denotes an ideal of self that emerges at the threshold of a limit.14 The self emerges by positing ends beyond the knowledge of self.Teleology submits to contingency, yet without forcing the abandonment of the teleological perspective.The contingency of tragic fate is of course distinguished from the contingency of phronesis because phronesis, as an aspect of human practical judgment, eludes the fatality of the tragic protagonist. In fact, for Aristotle, the difference between art and phronesis is that art is end-bound while prudential praxis is means determinant.15 This difference is critical where Aristotle stipulates the conditionality of phronesis upon a deliberative process. Deliberation is typically understood as the procedure by which an agent gives himself a rule through action, rather than following a preconstituted rule or fate. 16 As Aristotle says, one does not deliberate where ends are already known (Ethics, 118) or, we might add, where they are formally necessary, as I will argue is the case in tragic drama. More important, in book 3 of Ethics, where Aristotle considers the actions that determine the quality of the good life, phronesis is deployed in such a way that it encompasses both praxis and poetics. The practicality of phronesis follows from its situatedness in a crisis that demands action. Its relation to art follows from the assertion that the arts (poiesis), which Aristotle alleges “call for more deliberation than
Singer.book
48
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 48
Aesthetic Reason
the sciences,” take as their field of deliberation “that which happens . . . when the result is obscure and the right course not clearly defined.”17 Ethics and tragedy intersect here in the interest of a self-knowledge that is not self-blindingly ego-logical.Whatever rational “ends” are countenanced here, they do not succumb, like the tragic hero, to that fatalistic knowledge whereby éthos is determined in a fulfillment of preordained ends.18 Interestingly, the tragedy that historically befell eristics as a source of knowledge in the Greek polis, and, consequently, the tragedy that befell tragedy—most notoriously in Athens—was the institutional polarization of eristics and metaphysics; afterward, eristics led human ethos in the direction of political action, while metaphysics led to contemplative reverie.19 We will recognize that this is prototypical for the alienation of praxis from poetics and devolves to the severance of the aesthetic from the life of the polis. It ensures the alienation of the aesthetic from the community as a locus of credible political agency. Indeed, such an alienation in the Greek polis sets the pattern for the alienation of politics and aesthetics that Arendt wishes to remedy by reviving the idea of sensus communis. But before we leap across the centuries to contemplate a remedy for this problem, we must continue to sketch the historical-institutional markers by which we can identify it as a problem that denotes a plausible continuity between classical and modern cultural crises. Only in this way will the historical urgency of Arendt’s argument be persuasive enough to credit her relevance to our moment of doubt about the political usefulness of the aesthetic. We must return, therefore, to the observation that the polarization of eristics and metaphysics occurred between the fifth and the second centuries b.c. as a result of the collapse of the Ionian League and the retreat of intellectual individuality from the public sphere. Because this division of labor, so to speak, was legitimated within the Athenian academy as a split between the sophists and the metaphysical philosophers, it had widespread practical consequence in the everyday lives of citizens. Inasmuch as eristics and sophism promoted the rule of persuasion over passion or violence (bia—the antagonist of Peitho) 20 as a political means, it was a philosophical stance that encouraged the leveling of the social barriers of class and ethnicity and precipitated an unprecedented level of public conflict. 21 The dialectical spirit thus advanced an agonistic ethos and a tide of democratization in the polis that threatened aristocratic and authoritarian social establishments. Antidemocratic forces fatefully met this threat by espousing an ideal of beauty in the place of the praxis of argument.This was a conveniently
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 49
Aesthetic Community
49
metaphysical truth with which to mediate social conflicts and check the decentralizing drift of power in civil society.Where formerly beauty’s link to judgment denoted an exercising of participatory political rights in the practice of the art of persuasion, the eclipse of a public sphere, within which those rights could be exercised, displaced them into a meditative sphere.This was correlative with a new valorization of the belief that beauty was an inborn value that in turn licensed a return to feudal and monarchical forms of government. Just when a practice of judgment linked to the aesthetic might have heralded something presciently akin to the Herderian prospect for a cognitive philosophy of taste (a mode of judgment pegged to the active production of concepts), it disappointingly gave way to the attenuated conceptuality of aestheticism, namely, sublimity and the arrogance of connoisseurship. Active reflection succumbed to a contemplative judgment. We can even better understand the difference between aesthetics and aestheticism implicit in this history by observing how the Florentine republic, in the early fifteenth century, reprised the fate of the Greek model we have just reviewed.The dawn of Florentine Hellenism, the importation of Neoplatonic philosophy from the east, coincided with the rise of the Florentine civil state as a locus of republican activity.22 Insofar as beauty and the patronage of art were intimately linked with this innovation of civic government, they were likewise linked with a Greek sophistical tradition. Leonardo Bruni’s Laudatio Florentinae Urbis (1403) is an exemplar of this ethos of civic humanism in its equating of beauty with the constitutional delegation of social powers, such that the “aesthetic vision of a material city” becomes an imperative of the vita activa. 23 The constitutional guarantees of the free access of citizens to the offices of the republic presuppose a reciprocity of the recognition of the civic roles of individual citizens and their representatives.24 But no sooner was the role of the artist equated with the creation of the state, through participatory action, than the Medician introduction of councillor government co-opted the artist’s public prestige. Drawing upon Neoplatonist and hence nonsophistical models of the artist/creator who can impose a unity without disclosing the rules of its production, the Medici promulgated an idea of the state as a work of art.This ideal is of course correlative with a prevailing institutional ideal of political autonomy at the time—autocracy. Following the pattern of the Greek displacement of sophistical beauty with metaphysical beauty, the Florentine notion of the state as a work of art drew upon a model of recognition that, because it was nonreciprocal, would not submit to any cognitive threshold of access.
Singer.book
50
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 50
Aesthetic Reason
In the late Renaissance the fusing of the concept of the beautiful with the political structures of aristocratic oligarchy was completed and epitomized in treatises such as Baldassare Castiglione’s Courtier (1582), which characterized the relation of art to politics in terms such as “an aesthetic utopian ideal.”This utopianization of sense is tantamount to the supplanting of experience with affect and attitude, what has been aptly called a “poetic theology.”25 Indeed, such terms demonstrate how the particularity of sense experience, attested to in the aesthetic, is sublated into a social sentiment and rendered metaphysical. This metaphysical community of sentiment, by contrast with what we might imagine to be a more sociable community of rational Sense, comes at the expense of the constitutive roles of individuals in the very social structures that claim to be predicated upon their individuality. When the Florentine Grand Council, which at one time was composed of three thousand citizens representing diverse strata of society and enjoining reciprocal responsibilities between individuals and classes, gave way to councilor control, it reconstituted social community in symbolic rather than participatory terms.This shift in social structure indicates the degree to which the aesthetic, cast in the epistemic shadow of a modernity driven to abstraction by an increasingly deactivated social agency, represents an antithesis of the premodern techne of Greek sophism. It accommodates nothing like the social structure of the polis wherein we might, for example, soberly equate dramatic with political representation. It is well known that Greek tragic drama was performed for citizens by citizens.26 In the absence of such practices, dramatic representation becomes a more one-sided proposition comparable to the one-sidedness of nonrepresentative, nondemocratic political regimes, wherein the particularity of political participation is supplanted by the abstract universality of citizenship. I take Kantian aesthetics, almost three hundred years after the Florentine Enlightenment, to be the next significant moment for theorizing the aesthetic state, precisely because Kantian aesthetics holds faith with particularity as a ground of judgment. In the complex and controversial aim of sensus communis, Kant augurs for the resurgent political efficacy of the aesthetic. And yet a famous problem ensues from Kant’s own universalizing imperative, marked as it is by the convergence of aesthetic with moral doctrines. As Hans Georg Gadamer has pointed out in Truth and Method, and by invidious comparison with Aristotle and Vico, Kant’s persistent merging of aesthetic judgment with morality (moral feeling contrasted with interested pleasure)27 tends to “de-politicize” or to “aestheticize” the ideal of sensus communis.28 By
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 51
Aesthetic Community
51
this critique, which specifically harks back to Greek and Roman civil society, Gadamer wants to redeem a substantive as opposed to a merely formal notion of the ideals of beauty, taste, and community.The incipient split between the willful agency of community and the communitarian ideal that produces the depoliticizing effect diagnosed by Gadamer ominously echoes the split between the Greek sophists and metaphysicians insofar as Kant’s moral duty seems to preclude reflective volition. In fact, reflective judgment—which is as close as we come to a practical province of art in the third critique—is deemed by Kant to be instrumental to community precisely insofar as it is noncognitive. It is therefore my desire in what follows to secure the potential cognitive usefulness of aesthetics as a means for rationalizing human community. It dictates that I go beyond the terms of Gadamer’s critique and negotiate this famous Kantian impasse within the purview of Hannah Arendt’s reading of Kantian judgment.
III I anticipated in the first section of this chapter that what is lost in sacrificing cognition to aesthesis is particularly well comprehended in Hannah Arendt’s project of reading political implications into the métier of Kantian judgment.The keystone of this reading is her solidarity with the Kantian goal of an “enlarged thought” (also called “enlarged mentality”; “broadened way of thinking”) which, for her, shapes much of the argument of the third critique and has particular resonance in number 40,“On Taste as a Kind of Sensus Communis.”While “enlarged thought” is explicitly pegged to noncognitive aesthetic judgment by Kant,Arendt’s reading of Kant’s text hints at a cognitive agenda latent in the communicative imperatives of enlarged thought.These imperatives constitute, for her, the lever of a plausible politics. According to Arendt, enlarged thought is the result of first “abstracting from the limitations which contingently attach to our own judgment,” of disregarding its ‘subjective private conditions . . . , by which so many are limited’ . . . which, according to Kant is not enlightened or capable of enlightenment but is in fact limiting” (Lectures, 43). Here the standard of disinterestedness, so famously set as the condition of aesthetic judgment, has a decidedly volitional cast whereby the eschewing of “private conditions” signals the preeminence of “thinking” qua discriminatory act. Enlarged thought provides a further springboard for Arendt’s extrapolation to politics from Kantian aesthetics, because it points up the con-
Singer.book
52
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 52
Aesthetic Reason
tradictoriness of moralizing beauty. Gadamer had seen this to be the inescapable drift of Kant’s philosophy, especially where the discussion of the sublime in the third critique dovetails with the deontological premises for the metaphysic of morals.Arendt sees this self-contradiction most clearly in terms of the tension between human dignity and human progress that is harbored within the prospect of enlarged thought.Arendt points out that the possibility of human dignity for Kant demands that human judgment (of the beautiful) be particular. Such particularity is the sine qua non of the aesthetic. But she notes that to think the impetus of enlarged thought means to generalize (Lectures, 76). And indeed such generalizability is a crux of moral duty.To compound this paradox, Kant insists that the fate of the human species, which guarantees the integrity of thinking particulars, depends upon a principle of “infinite progress” actualizable only in the feats of generalization or communication.29 “Dignity,” a corollary of the aesthetic, and “preservation of the species,” a corollary of morality/universal reason, are thus mutually dependent but mutually exclusive propositions. I have suggested that Arendt seeks to overcome the contradiction by focusing on Kant’s term “exemplary validity” as a vehicle for producing “enlarged thought.” Interesting enough, Arendt’s fullest account of exemplary validity charts a path from the particular to the general that secures grounds for speculating productively on the prospects for bridging the gap between art and politics.The point would be to escape the deontological strictures of Kantian moral duty without giving up a purchase on rational agency. For Arendt, the communicability of the idea of “bridging” itself serves as the exemplifying instance of her reading of exemplary validity. Exemplary validity for Arendt obtains in an exigency of communication where one seeks to express an idea for which there is no concept that could solicit perception in the mode of active imagination. Arendt specifically sees the warrant for exemplary validity in the formal necessity of the Kantian “schema,” in the bridging activity of the faculty of the imagination. Imagination links a percept with a concept in Kantian judgment.This schematizing function she conspicuously characterizes as compensating for a deficit of recognition: “without a ‘schema’ one can never recognize anything” (Lectures, 81). Her excursus on exemplary validity is an extension of this point:“Suppose someone comes along who does not know ‘bridge,’ and there is no bridge to which I could point and utter the word. I would then draw an image of the scheme of a bridge which of course is already a particular bridge, just to remind him of some schema known to him such as ‘transition
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 53
Aesthetic Community
53
from one side of the river to the other’” (83; my emphasis). Interestingly, because Arendt makes the particularity of the bridge an irreducible feature of its conceptualization, exemplary validity seems to denote the dependency of the concept upon a transition between particulars, such that no particular is adequate to its concept and no concept is adequate to the imagination’s power of adducing particulars. As we shall see more explicitly later, exemplary validity seems to make the threshold of knowledge tantamount to a mode of linkage between particulars that effectively bridges the distance between particulars and universals. More important it does so without any concessions to the unsituated intelligibility or the metaphysical adequacy of the metaphor of the bridge itself. In order to fully appreciate the thrust of Arendt’s thinking here however, it helps to remember that her original impetus for an exposition of exemplary validity seems to derive from her reading of section 59 of Kant’s third critique,“On Beauty as a Symbol of Morality” (Critique of Judgment, 84). Curiously enough she characterizes this section of the third critique as a discussion of schema in which Kant solves the problem of combining universals with particulars that otherwise—in the absence of a cogent account of schematization—remains intractable. She notes that the act of thinking the particular itself impels Kant to find a tertium quid to mediate the otherwise incommensurable registers of general and particular knowledge involved by such thinking (Arendt, Lectures, 76).The example, the particular bridge, understood to be analogous with a schema, is this tertium quid. For my purposes, however, the real force of Arendt’s reading of section 59 depends paradoxically on our knowing that section 59 itself is not given over preeminently to an exposition of schema, as Arendt implies, but to mastering a distinction between schema and Kantian symbol. I believe that this prompts us to see the potential for reading a reciprocity (adequation) of recognition into Kantian schematization (adequacy) and hence into exemplary validity.The distinction between schema and symbol itself entails a strong intimation of this reciprocity. I will furthermore suggest that Arendt’s reticence about marking the significance of both the Kantian symbol and reciprocity as aspects of exemplary validity weakens the argumentative force of her own account of exemplary validity. My task, then, will be to complement her reading of exemplary validity, in order to buttress her claim for its importance vis-à-vis a political aesthetic precisely where her own conclusions do not fully justify the claim. For Kant, both schema and symbol are examples of Kantian hypoty-
Singer.book
54
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 54
Aesthetic Reason
posis. Hypotyposes render a concept sensible (Critique of Judgment, 226). In the cases of schema and symbol, one is a direct and the other an indirect representation of a concept. Kant goes to considerable lengths to explain the latter. By indirect representation, Kant means that “[s]ymbolic exhibition uses an analogy (from which we use empirical intuitions as well), in which judgment performs a double function: it applies the concept to the object of a sensible intuition; and then it applies the mere rule by which it reflects on that intuition to an entirely different object of which the former object is only the symbol” (227). Schematic hypotyposis, according to Kant, denotes a direct relation between a concept formed by the understanding and our intuition of it. By contrast symbolic hypotyposis entails the application of the rule that conditions our reflection on an intuition “to an entirely different object.” It thus imputes a transitional linkage between particulars that I would compare with the bridging function already imputed to exemplary validity. Kant’s well-known exemplification of the principle of symbolic exhibition is as follows: a monarchy ruled by constitutional law would be presented as an animate body and a monarchy ruled by an absolute power would be presented by a machine such as a hand mill (227). We are meant to understand that insofar as the presentational power of the symbol (which is a vehicle for “our reflection” [228]) depends on a “transfer of our reflection,” our reflective purchase inheres as a condition of transition between particulars. Following from Kant’s distinction between the schema and the symbol, it makes sense to note that Arendt equates the access to enlarged mentality with the imperative to “train one’s imagination to go visiting” (Lectures, 43).30 In light of what I have just observed about the affinity of exemplary validity with symbolic hypotyposis, exemplary validity plausibly facilitates this “training” in the following way. Like the symbol, the presentation of an image that is the crux of exemplary validity does not depend on the status of the image as a kind of Platonic ideal. It is not an image in itself, to which all experience must conform.31 Neither is it a deduction from the experience of particulars that would transcend the register of particularity from whence deduction originates.The exemplary image of exemplary validity has a different status.As Arendt puts it,“This exemplar is and remains a particular that in its very particularity reveals the generality that otherwise could not be defined. Courage is like Achilles” (Lectures, 77).While Kantian beauty is an end in itself, eschewing cognitive linkage with other instances of beauty, exemplary validity would seem to depend instead on an interaction (hence training—in other words, imagination goes visiting) that
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 55
Aesthetic Community
55
has no generalizable end except the enlargement of the community of knowledge it instantiates. In this case the imagination is trained to go visiting, so to speak, by virtue of the insufficiency of the image to itself, as implicit in symbolic hypotyposis.The insufficiency of the image to itself determines its articulation with (that is, recognition in light of) another particular.This mandates generalizability without succumbing to a historically inert generalization. In the existing text of the Lectures, Arendt herself stops short of articulating this understanding in these terms. She puts her emphasis on the example as something that is temporally prior to the meaning it exemplifies: “this particular table is valid for all particular tables” (Lectures, 83).What she misses here is the fact that recognition of the table as “valid” is the condition for a reciprocity of recognition, insofar as the criterion of validity subtly changes with each new particular, for example, each new table adduced as possessing exemplary validity.That is, exemplary validity conjures an activity of making the image adequate, rather than granting the adequacy of the image independent of the agencies of its use. We will remember that in the case of the Kantian symbol it is similarly the reflection on whatever rule presents the image (intuition) to a concept that is material to the intelligibility of that image.32 Arendt is quick to point out that this makes the intelligibility of the image equivalent to its communicability (Lectures, 83). Arendt asserts that what makes particulars communicable “is that in perceiving a particular we have in the back of our minds . . . a ‘schema’ . . . and . . . that this schema is in the back of the minds of many different people” (83). This of course evokes a decidedly nonreciprocal recognition tantamount to the subsuming of particularity under a concept. But on the same page Arendt also links communicability with Kantian reflective judgment, as invidiously distinct from determinant judgment with its irreversible subsuming of the particular under a concept. For Arendt, reflective judgment—understood as the act of “bringing [the particular per se] to a concept” as opposed to “subsuming [it] under a concept”—gives exemplary validity its strong purchase on communicability.This in turn conditions the political efficacy of human community. If we can equate the communicability she privileges here with the notion of exemplary validity as an activity of adequation rather than a conceptually preemptive standard of adequacy (determinant concept), then Arendt’s argument may appear to suffer less glaringly from internal contradictions. Her argument will be seen to show stronger solidarity with the vita activa.After all, the vita activa is strategically integral
Singer.book
56
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 56
Aesthetic Reason
to the historical precedents that she adduces for a political aesthetic going back to the Greek polis. This may take us several steps toward mitigating the fact that, in her other mature works,Arendt retreats problematically in the direction of the vita contemplativa. She seems to abandon the deliberative sphere of action that her sense of the political would otherwise seem to depend upon for its historical efficacy.33 Arendt herself gives us the strongest impetus to assert this equation of exemplary validity with an activity of adequation/reciprocal recognition in her striking claim that the exemplary particular, upon which judgment presumes, “has exemplary validity to the extent that the example is rightly chosen” (Lectures, 84; my emphasis). Although this imperative of choice appears as a kind of postscript to the Lectures proper—a coda entitled “Imagination”—I believe that it indicates Arendt’s interest in a reflective aspect of judgment.34 It mitigates the appearance elsewhere in this text that the concept of exemplary validity is collapsible into the schematic priority of the example (mere adequacy). Rather, Arendt’s postscript on imagination intimates precisely what her discussion of exemplary validity at the conclusion of the Lectures does not: that the exemplarity of exemplary validity is communicable only because the recognition of it is reciprocal. In the caveat of “right choice,” Arendt seems to conjure the very recognition of a recognition as valid to be key to its efficacy.The constraint of the recognition of recognition—which I believe is implicit in the requirement that exemplary validity satisfy a standard of “right choice”—depends of course upon taking the mandate to train the imagination to go visiting as the driving insight behind Arendt’s politicization of Kant. Right choice demands extending a maxim to cover a multiplicity of cases such that what is being exemplified is both reflected and reflected upon as a reflection: for example, the name Napoleon only exemplifies the qualities that are constitutive in the person when they are recognized in successive instantiations of what would count as examples (Lectures, 84). Their counting as examples is a function of their linkage, rendering the content of exemplification an effectively cumulative rather than a strictly intuitional phenomenon.Accordingly, Arendt herself stipulates that exemplarity is something that is made (“we . . . proceed to make it ‘exemplary’” [Lectures, 85]). When she affirms that examples lead us and guide us she is strictly in step with Kant’s more deontological doctrine of moral duty. But when she appends a requirement of right choice, she goes beyond Kant to intimate that we are led in turn to lead.35 If exemplarity is contingent on a multiplicity of contextual imperatives (particularly if we must choose
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 57
Aesthetic Community
57
rightly), if it is contingent on a proliferation of cases, then the judgment it facilitates appears to have at least as much affinity with Aristotelian phronesis, as with Kantian morality.As we have seen, phronesis promulgates a protocol of deliberation or training insofar as it forces a reconciliation of discrete temporal moments and contexts through a perforce, rule-generative practice of judging. We “go visiting,” so to speak, insofar as this reconciliation cannot be conceptualized independent of our inhabiting particular standpoints other than our own. It thus constitutes a solicitude of others. Without saying so explicitly, Arendt suggests, by this course of reasoning, a solution to the original contradiction between the particularity of dignity (a basis of cognitive experience) and the generality of progress (a noncognitive basis of experience). She makes the actual transition from particular to particular the condition of a virtual generality, namely, by stressing the virtuality of the general. I do not deny that what is purveyed here privileges precisely that modality of linkage between instances of judgment that is anathema to Kantian beauty. As we have seen already,Arendt understands quite well that Kantian beauty must be posited as an end in itself “—without linkage . . . to other beautiful things.” Interestingly, however, Arendt’s Lectures break off with an acknowledgment of the difficulty of sustaining the contradiction that “[i]t is against human dignity [particularity] to believe in progress [generality]” (Lectures, 77). It is as if she seeks an alternative that she cannot supply out of the resources of her own argument. So I would admit that my construal of the implications of exemplary validity in some ways goes against the grain of Kantian beauty. But only by reading exemplary validity in this way does Arendt’s grasp of aesthetic judgment accommodate precisely what, at the end of the Lectures, she fears will be lost in the capitulation of dignity to progress: “[a] point at which we might stand still and look back with the backward glance of the historian” (77). In other words, the alternative Arendt seeks here involves some mode of linkage if her proposed assimilation of the aesthetic to the political is to have the pragmatic consequence implied by her dual emphasis on exemplary validity and enlarged mentality.The backward glance of the historian would seem to be the logical corollary of that pragmatism.36 In this connection Ronald Beiner points out that the destination of Arendt’s final projected volume of The Life of the Mind, on judging, would have been a return to the concept of history (Arendt, Lectures, 131). This speculation is supported in Arendt’s own postscriptum to the first volume, on thinking, where she alleges an etymological link
Singer.book
58
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 58
Aesthetic Reason
between the judge and the historian that follows the logic of exemplary validity itself.The historian, by relating to the past, is bound to sit in judgment of it.The mandate of Historein, not unlike that of Theorein, is “‘to inquire in order to tell how it was’” (Life of the Mind, 5).The juxtaposition of the activity of inquiry with the activity of telling promulgates the Kantian ideal of a “general standpoint.” Significantly, in the Lectures, Arendt approaches this general standpoint by formulating the imperative to “go through” (Lectures, 44)—as in pass through—the particular conditions of any discrete standpoint.This formulation contains the strong inference that every particular standpoint is thereby reconstituted retrospectively by transition to a new set of particular conditions.The active stance of the imperative to “go through” seems to be the crux of the matter. For it intimates specific terms according to which the imagination might “go visiting” in a realm where the “general [or universal] standpoint” is coherent with the world of appearances—the world where Kantian judgment itself is securely anchored.37 We might recall in this context that the aim of the enlarged mentality, which prompted us to go visiting in the first place, was tantamount to an admonition against prejudicial attitudes. It was an admonition to take another’s point of view. Kant of course does not want to be misunderstood to be advocating mere empathy. One cannot move into another’s consciousness. He is careful to insist that one can only take another’s point of view with respect to a notion of one’s self as constituting the limit that one must go through to arrive at the more “general standpoint” (the standpoint of the other). Indeed, Kant holds quite rightly that the literal assumption of another’s point of view is as fatefully prejudicial as closing oneself up in a personal standpoint, since one would still be bound within a nongeneralizable circumstance. 38 Nevertheless, within Arendt’s purview, Kant’s requirement for achieving a general standpoint is seen to be just as self-deceiving as a blindly empathic identification with another: after all, the deontological self that Kant admonishes to adopt the general standpoint is at odds with the requirement to go through particular conditions of knowledge in any credibly pragmatic way (Arendt, Lectures, 43–44). My position is that one could not meaningfully go through without soliciting recognition,39 unless the imperative for the imagination to go visiting (to move from particular to general) is to be rendered as antinomical as dignity and progress. On the contrary, if we solicit recognition, we in effect concede a cognitive scope (enlarged mentality) for noncognitive ideals (general standpoint). In other words, I am suggesting that Arendt’s valorization of exemplary validity as a crux of
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 59
Aesthetic Community
59
Kantian judgment reorients us to the Kantian contradiction between dignity and progress, such that we can contemplate a modification of the Kantian position. Arendt establishes a plausible relation between the cognitive dimension of dignity and the noncognitive, deontological dimension of progress by treating the imperative to go through and to go visiting as a strictly historical phenomenon.This of course entails surrendering the rigid dichotomy between cognitive and noncognitive dimensions of experience, which Kant adamantly maintains.40 We might speculate, therefore, on how to keep faith with the ideals of Kant’s exemplary validity and enlarged mentality (as Arendt wishes to do), without succumbing to the methodological impasses that,Arendt indicates, reveal these ideals to be significant in the first place. The vicissitudes of this idealism can perhaps best be indicated by Arendt’s own concession in The Human Condition: that Kant makes the faculty of judgment inherently tragic because he never resolves the antinomy of dignity and progress, of the cognitive and the noncognitive.41 Human action inevitably “falls into the determinism of natural laws” and judgment “cannot penetrate the secret of absolute reality” (Human Condition, 235 n. 75). Unfortunately,Arendt finesses the difficulty by making a virtue of necessity. She abdicates any effectual analytics of this tragedy by pointedly abandoning the vita activa (which had been the impetus of The Human Condition) for the vita contemplativa, which she ultimately justifies in terms of the Kantian valorization of disinterested spectatorship. I think Ronald Beiner correctly points out that, in this move,Arendt is abandoning what was in the earlier installments of Life of the Mind a productive tension between a view of judgment as cognitive, in the guises of representative thinking, enlarged mentality, dignity and so on and a view of judgment as noncognitive, in the guises of retrospective judgment, disinterestedness and infinite progress. In my mind Beiner realistically assesses the costs of resolving these terms: Arendt tries to overcome this tension [at the end of Lectures] by placing judgment squarely within the life of the mind, yet it remains the mental faculty that verges most closely upon the worldly activities of man. . . . By adhering to a firm disjunction between mental and worldly activities, Arendt was forced to expel judging from the world of the vita activa, to which it maintains a natural affinity. The upshot is that her more systematic reflection on the nature of judging resulted in a much narrower . . . concept of judgment. (Lectures, 140)
Singer.book
60
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 60
Aesthetic Reason
I now want to show how this expulsion of judgment from the world of the vita activa constitutes an evasion of the tragedy of judgment, with emphasis on the traditions of Greek tragedy.As such,Arendt’s viewpoint promulgates an ethically and reflectively useless corollary of Aristotelian catharsis. In her demurring from the vita activa, she concedes what Paul Ricoeur calls the “unanalyzable mixture of constraints of fate and deliberate choices” (Oneself as Another, 242) at the heart of tragedy. 42 In light of Arendt’s own political interests, the role of “awestruck spectatorship” it fosters would seem to be a profoundly inapt response to human tragedy. Contrarily, I now want to speculate how the cognitive aesthetic, which I alleged Arendt intimates but does not herself articulate, may be duly articulated by a social theorizing that desists from treating human tragedy as a mode of resignation to an “unanalyzable mixture” of fate and choice.This resignation is tantamount to the acceptance of an antinomy between dignity and progress. In this case the storytelling function of tragedy, which Arendt herself professed to value for its capacity to renew human agency through reversal43—a prototypical “going through”—could be shown to have cognitive consequences consistent with Arendt’s earliest stake in political agency, where the province of judgment remained the vita activa.Arendt herself sees that in the peripetic structures of tragic drama, thinking becomes judging insofar as it [thinking] returns to the world of appearances to reflect on particulars.44 It goes without saying that this world of appearances is the threshold of the aesthetic, which Arendt must cross in her extrapolation of a Kantian politics from the judgment of taste. So, in keeping with the gist of argument to this point, the theoretical perspective with which I now propose to complement Arendt’s stance toward judgment will be seen to suffice insofar as it deepens our understanding of what would be entailed in restoring a protocol of reciprocal recognition—derived from paradigms of tragic emplotment—to the project of judgment generally, and to aesthetic judgment in particular. In this way they may both be seen as instrumental to reconceptualizing the goal of sensus communis as the responsible political enterprise that was intimated in Arendt’s own gloss on exemplary validity.They will give us an exemplification of going through that is not effectively a going outside of the historical, cognitive situation of tragic experience.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 61
Aesthetic Community
61
IV If the ideal of sensus communis is inhibited by the failure to make recognition reciprocal—which I see as corollary to the split of dignity from progress, reason from duty, knowledge from universality—we can begin to see what might be gained from resituating that goal (sensus communis) in the framework of Greek tragic knowledge specifically. In Greek tragedy, recognition is keyed to reconciling the form of human fate with the exigencies of human understanding. Likewise in Greek tragedy, recognition is strictly conducive to reciprocity. I have already noted how, because the tragic self emerges on the threshold of a limit, it posits ends beyond the knowledge of self. Furthermore, I would assert that this is conceivable as a nontranscendental posit in tragedy. For it defers to another positing agent in the reversibility of fate denoted by catharsis. As we saw earlier, this implication of the intersubjective substrate of tragedy is consistent with the social and cultural imperatives of its Greek prototype. We must note that in R. G. A. Buxton’s account of Greek tragic drama and its relation to the art of persuasion, he intimates an affinity of catharsis—the structural core of tragic experience—with sophistic modes of argumentation promulgated within the cult of Peitho. Buxton further emphasizes that the name of the deity Peitho evokes the susceptibility of all action (praxis) to the Pythagorean maxim: where two antithetical sides of an issue present themselves— the site of catharsis—there is an inexorable third term.This term arises not logically but discursively from the recognition of contradiction: which is perforce the threshold of discursivity itself.45 This fact mitigates the popular conception that catharsis is a blind access to the irrational.The equation of catharsis with irrationality has perpetuated the idea that tragedy, precisely in its structural emphasis on catharsis, elicits a detachment and disinterestedness from practical experience that is altogether comparable to the stance of the Kantian judge of beauty. Hence we have the modern imputation of the political impotence of tragic drama in particular, and of poiesis in general. Such detachment would of course presuppose the rigid distinction between cognitive and noncognitive modes that we have been resisting, and which we shall see in a moment is strictly antithetical, to both the cult of Peitho and the efficacy of persuasive praxis in overcoming radical (noncognitive) differences.Tragic catharsis otherwise compels us to confront these differences without rational recourse.
Singer.book
62
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 62
Aesthetic Reason
It is after all precisely this distinction between cognitive and noncognitive protocols of experience that we have seen Arendt maintain at the cost of her desire to assimilate aesthetics to politics in sensus communis. Consequently, we might now contemplate the possibility that sensus communis is a social ideal that, barring the distinction between cognitive and noncognitive modes, Arendt herself might have seen as an overcoming of differences compatible with tragic Peitho. After all, her linking of sensus communis to a standard of communicability, in the test of exemplary validity, already charts a parallel rhetorical path. It is for this reason that I want to suggest that tragedy ought to be seen as inducing sensus communis, not as an end in itself, but as a condition of the solicitude that tragic experience reveals, putting sensus communis and tragedy into a potentially dialectical relation.This solicitude is especially pertinent to tragedy conceived under the influence of eristics and Peitho, where dialogue is an imperative of the recognition of differences, where all questions about the self are predicated on the disposition of another to give an intelligible answer.We would thereby be led to construe tragedy not simply as the misrecognition of the other—the impasse of deliberative action—but, in a more Hegelian mode, as an anxiety about the possibility of mutual recognition of equality, which such misrecognition arouses. Within Buxton’s discussion of the cult of Peitho as a cultural underpinning of Greek tragic drama, we can imagine how this anxiety is both conditioned by and appealable through a contextualization of selfrecognition. Furthermore, such contextual recognition is compatible with a principle of reversibility. Because Peitho makes persuasion depend on a recognition that must be solicited across a boundary of difference and a threshold of inequality, it portends an intersubjective dynamic that thwarts finality of argument. This follows from the fact that every solicitation is modified, in its discursive effectivity, so as to augment its discursivity. Its reversibility follows as a ratio of effectivity and discursivity. By the same token, the standard of Peitho/persuasion belies the metaphysical limit of absolute otherness or impasse otherwise implicit in tragic fate where catharsis is deemed to mark only the collision of incommensurable wills. One of the tenets of Peitho most famously attacked in Plato’s “Gorgias”46 is the ongoingness of reasonability in debate, namely, the deferral of final truths. My point is that this need not be seen as inducing the relativity of infinite differences. Rather, we may more positively construe it as the reconciliation of differences within historically provisional frameworks of consensus. For where the power of Peitho does not submit to a higher logos, it is self-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 63
Aesthetic Community
63
regulating in its very ongoingness.As I have anticipated, reconciliation here is a rhetorical, not a metaphysical, proposition.That is, the stance of solicitude implicit in persuasion is at once temporally determinate and temporally open-ended in its very dialogic dimension. It is an artifact of an irreducible, because inexhaustible, social praxis that bears further fruitful comparison with Aristotelian phronesis. That this stance of solicitude has social institutional ramifications, within the worldview fostered by tragic knowledge, is furthermore evident in Buxton’s characterization of the realm of Peitho as a key site of interaction between public and private arenas.47 This interaction was posited by the Greeks in the highly conventionalized opposition of Peitho to violence (bia) where we understand violence to be a touchstone of the radical difference that instantiates tragedy.The opposition Peitho/bia recurs in Greek oratory as well as tragedy where Peitho proffers an antidote to violence from above (tyranny) and is correlative to nomos (tradition) as an antidote to violence from below (mob rule). Indeed the pair Peitho/nomos intimates something like the dynamic of reciprocal recognition I wish to elicit from tragedy. For presupposed within it is the idea that one cannot have community of rule (nomos) without recognition (Peitho) of it, in other words, its publicity. But, by the same token, one cannot have recognition without rule, since the efficacy of rule depends on its acceptability, without which violence and the mutual exclusiveness of private and public arenas would be inevitable.48 There is a striking analogy to the “stance of solicitude” limned above with Hegel’s well-known ideal of “forgiveness,” which, by no small coincidence, is the telos of Hegelian tragedy.49 As is the case in the Greek prototype, Hegelian tragedy has the function of binding private and public realms. For Hegel, tragic catharsis seen only as misrecognition would, by contrast with forgiveness, imply the irreversibility (contra peripeteia) of human actions. There is a complex set of reasons why this is unacceptable to Hegel. Again, following Greek precedent, Hegelian tragedy assumes the inevitability of the individual’s trespass against others in the exercise of personal will. 50 This inevitability obtains in the necessity to act from a law of subjective moral consciousness, as if its universality with respect to the other could be presupposed. But for Hegel such presuppositions constitute a cardinal “hypocrisy” (Phenomenology of Mind, 670). The determinateness of negating consciousness, while it “determines from itself alone,” depends for its content on “sensibility,” which is the “circle . . . within which determinateness as such falls” (654). Sensibility, in this capacity,
Singer.book
64
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 64
Aesthetic Reason
entails a gesture toward the physical world that, for Hegel, is socially mediated in the imperatives of Sittlichkeit, or social situatedness (651, 658). In deference to Sittlichkeit, Hegel characterized the hypocrisy of taking subjectivity for objectivity as a kind of indulgent aestheticism.The concept of “the beautiful soul,” which he judged to be symptomatic of this aestheticism, required a remedial understanding: that moral selfconsciousness involves a revaluation of the subjectivity of consciousness. This is the birth of “conscience.” Conscience, by contrast with self-consciousness is, for Hegel, the “substance in which the act secures . . . reality [because it is] the moment of being recognized by others” (650). Precisely because subjective conscience is determined by the difference and distance obtaining in intersubjective action, it constitutes a de facto injury to the other. For this reason it requires forgiveness. Just as important, however, we must note that Hegelian forgiveness prompts us to conclude that where tragedy is conceived of as an impasse of action, namely, a conflict of perspectives, it also acknowledges an inexorable slippage between the ideal conditions of knowledge presupposed within the self and the actualizable claims of knowledge dictated by its social situatedness (Sittlichkeit). This slippage would be a necessary constraint of any social self-understanding conditioned by the original Hegelian distinction between selfconsciousness and conscience: under that constraint the identity of self-consciousness is ironized by the contingency of conscience. 51 Furthermore, the correlation of Hegelian action (difference and distance) with a slippage between ideal conditions of knowledge and the actualization of knowledge, potentially militates against the fatalism of tragedy: Hegel comprehends that the necessarily discursive determination of tragedy is mandated in the elision of substance and recognition.All this goes to say that tragedy harbors a beneficent insight about the social dynamics of self-knowledge that, according to the Hegelians, only the phenomenon of forgiveness yields access to. I believe that this insight is most perspicuously signaled for us in the necessity to think that where the subject of Hegelian action trespasses against another, that other can only speak in a mode of solicitude.That is, the other can only speak of the wrong done to him or her in a language that assumes the inadequacy of the knowledge of the trespasser. It thus appeals to a standard of knowledge yet to be articulated.52 Such a judgment demands a compromise of competing perspectives, since they must otherwise be accepted, paradoxically as mutually exclusive and mutually dependent. As such, they would be unacceptably inde-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 65
Aesthetic Community
65
terminate.This compromise of perspectives in turn acknowledges that “perfect knowledge” must therefore be a variable of the inherent variability of the conditions for imagining it. Contrary to the notion of tragic catharsis, understood as a terminal or nonnarrative misrecognition that does not offer scope for this variability, Hegelian forgiveness proffers the possibility of undoing (reversibility, not irreversibility) what has been done in the realm of human action.This is specifically achieved by submitting it to a further constraint of contextuality. But in this case undoing would still constitute a dutiful doing.The slippage between ideal conditions of knowledge and actualizable knowledge claims devolves to a dutiful reciprocity of recognition at least insofar as one presupposes the other as its necessary but unfulfillable condition of intelligibility. Here we conjure the sense of sensus communis out of a potential for judgment that remains within the constraints of knowledge and experience that instantiated it. Hannah Arendt in The Human Condition evokes this Hegelian appreciation of forgiveness—which she calls a “redemption from the predicament of irreversibility”—as a “constant willingness to change [one’s] mind and start again” (240). Arendt furthermore pegs forgiveness to an intersubjective “plurality” (237), in direct refutation of the common charge that Hegelian forgiveness is hopelessly monosubjective.53 There is both in the condition of changing one’s mind and in the condition of acceding to an intersubjective publicity—if we accept these as intrinsic elements of tragedy—precisely the possibility I imagined earlier: that the burden of tragedy is, above all, to establish a standard of recontextualization for human self-understanding that obviates any strong distinction between cognitive and noncognitive experience. The force of this discussion of Arendt/Hegel on the subject of forgiveness furthermore intimates that in pursuing a rational consensus (sensus communis) based on forgiveness we would in fact be obliged to conscientiously blur the distinction between cognitive and noncognitive modalities of experience: only in this way can catharsis be a mode of self-transcendence. Only in this way can it be a release from the consequences of our actions, a redemption from the “predicament of irreversibility.”Arendt observes,“Without being forgiven, released from the consequences of what we have done, our capacity to act would, as it were, be confined to one single deed from which could never recover” (Human Condition, 237). On this basis, we might speculate that the impetus to blur the distinction between cognitive and noncognitive registers of knowledge, implicitly sanctioned in forgiveness, ought to be a necessary condition
Singer.book
66
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 66
Aesthetic Reason
for speculating pragmatically upon the prospects for sensus communis/the aesthetic state, which prompted our consideration of tragedy in the first place. This would be emphatically the case if, as I have already proposed, we see the idea of sensus communis not as an end in itself but as the condition of solicitude that tragedy reveals.This way of thinking satisfies our previously stated desire to elude the inherent tragedy of judgment where the rigid distinction between cognitive dignity and noncognitive progress is maintained.Thus the aesthetic determinant embedded in sensus communis might be elucidated as a socially constructive response to tragedy. Such a project would be alternative to the evasion of society that otherwise looms in Arendt’s ultimate willingness to treat tragedy as a necessary sacrifice of the vita activa to the vita contemplativa. Another way of understanding the deliberate blurring of distinctions between cognitive and noncognitive knowledge as a positive social practice consistent with the recognition value of tragedy is to put it in terms of what Raymond Geuss, in The Idea of a Critical Theory, has called the “freeing” of recognition from self-deceiving constraint.This he takes to be the cardinal aim of critical theory. Geuss reminds us of the strong continuity between my advancement of a cognitive aesthetic and the legacy of post-Enlightenment expressivist thinkers—from Hegel and Nietzsche in the nineteenth century to Freud and Adorno in the twentieth.They take the human propensity for self-deception to be the tragic circumstance upon which artistic and philosophical enterprises must subsist. Critical theory, says Geuss, arises from the need to escape the inherently tragic circumstance of being unable to recognize what our real interests are, in that conflictual encounter with the “Other” that is also and inexorably the expressive threshold of human action. In other words, our pursuit of self-interest compels us to confront the incommensurability between our idealizations of knowledge and the less-than-perfect conditions under which such ideals could be imagined or realized. Geuss in fact sees the possibility of “freer” recognition as a ratio of ideal conditions and perfect knowledge, very much like the relationality that governs in Hegelian forgiveness and tragedy. For Geuss, however, this ratio exists in lieu of a tenacious double bind. Geuss points out that knowing our real interests depends on the possible convergence of perfect (ideal) knowledge with optimal conditions for attaining such knowledge. But he concedes that “to be in ‘optimal conditions’ is not only to be in conditions of freedom but also not to lack any relevant knowledge. We cannot be fully free without having perfect knowledge, nor acquire perfect knowledge unless we
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 67
Aesthetic Community
67
live in conditions of complete freedom” (Idea of a Critical Theory, 54). Geuss’s way out of the double bind is disarmingly to accept it, but to stipulate expressivistic terms for this acceptance: though we may not live in the utopia of judgment that self-knowledge requires, the knowledge of what we don’t know in this case is “enough to recognize how we might act to abolish some of the coercion [ignorance of conditions] from which we suffer and move closer to optimal conditions of freedom and knowledge” (54). Insofar as knowledge of real interests here concedes the asymmetry of perfect knowledge and ideal conditions, it also seems to demand their reciprocity.After all, the only available alternative would seem, by contrast, to require the mediating office of a third term. But this would neutralize the temporal/narrative praxis of tragic recognition that I have alleged to be the salient determinant of self-knowledge in the previous episodes of this argument. In effect the moral charge of critical theory, construed in this case as a freeing of recognition from the limiting cases of knowledge, is not an appeal to a far-from-optimal freedom per se—where knowledge departs from experience—but a conscientious elaboration of the experiential protocols of recognition (knowledge) that denote the prospect for such freedom. This reasoning makes what Ricoeur accepted as the “tragic unanalyzability” of fate and choice promulgated in catharsis amenable to analysis.54 In this way analysis is made equivalent to a choice-making activity. To grant the constraint of unanalyzability, by contrast, would be to reduce the aesthetic dimension of tragedy to the counterrationalistic caricature of its most politically minded critics: in other words, to catharsis per se.This would consign its meaning to the solipsistic sensuous registers of tragic spectacle and visual gestalt, and to perpetuate the very violent incommensurability of perspectives that tragedy otherwise seems designed to avert. Quite to the contrary, my contention from the start of this chapter was that aesthetics must be seen as a constraint to think what in catharsis appears, qua appearance, to be unthinkable. In this way it better serves a Herderian aim of making the sensuous counter of visual spectacle more dialectical with cognitive decision making, namely, a faculty for marking differentiations. In this way thought crosses a threshold of activity.This course of action ratifies Herder’s censure of the elision of sensuous with noncognitive experience that occurs within the protocols of art connoisseurship. Moreover it supplants the connoisseur’s metaphysically inclined standard of artistic perfection with a more political standard of prospective perfectibility.
Singer.book
68
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 68
Aesthetic Reason
The privileging of knowledge over perfection here does not mean, however, that aesthetics is subsumed to philosophy once and for all, as if to satisfy the demands articulated in Plato’s infamous disenfranchisement of art. Rather, it means we propose to draw a distinction between the Platonist version of aesthetics as teaching “the truth” (which devolves to uncritical moralizing and varieties of political repression) and what we may now call an “Arendtian” version of the aesthetic as expressly teaching imagination to go visiting. Or, in the recent parlance of Albrecht Wellmer, we might think of the artwork as producing a regimen of training in reciprocal recognition.55 For such teaching constitutes an activity (praxis) within which the political remains a contingency of the historical. The “freeing” of recognition that I have postulated as the project of tragedy and that I see as consistent with Geuss’s “idea of critical theory” helps us to draw precisely this distinction between merely didactic teaching and teaching to go visiting. In other words, it is the strongest warrant for seeking the cognitive aesthetic I have been adducing in this chapter. With this warrant I have tried to meet the demand of Arendt’s project for a political judgment of taste/sensus communis without incurring the liabilities that arise from the deontological bias she shares with Kant in pursuit of that end. Specifically, we go visiting when we formulate the interests of others—upon which the freeing of recognition depends—because such a formulation entails a conscientious prolepsis.As Geuss explains, in formulating the interests of others we may impose upon them a determinateness they didn’t before possess. . . .When I describe the epistemic principles of the “addressed” agents from which the critical argument begins, this description itself is proleptic; the epistemic principles are “theirs” in the sense that they can be brought to recognize these principles as a good rational reconstruction of conceptions underlying their behavior. But, of course, the basic assumption of the critical theory is that simply bringing certain attitudes, beliefs, behavioral patterns etc. to full consciousness changes them. (Idea of a Critical Theory, 94) I would say that the difference between teaching and teaching to go visiting is captured in this account of prolepsis as a potential aesthetic tenet insofar as Geuss understands how the field of choices from which we solicit recognition expands in proportion to the knowledge possessed: where the proleptic status of such knowledge is stipulated as knowledge of what we do not know. For with this stipulation the
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 69
Aesthetic Community
69
knowledge of what we don’t know remains a yet rationalizable contingency rather than a stigmatically irrational misrecognition.We can reasonably call it a mode of visiting because prolepsis dictates that any reconciliation between self and other arising from it is understood to be constrained by a standard of acceptability (an exigency of time), not a standard of truth (an exigency of ontology). When we are asking for acceptance, we are conceding a communitarian interest where a change of consciousness is perforce constitutive, not destructive, of social identity. It is predicated on a real instead of a virtual intersubjectivity. The change of consciousness that Geuss solicited as the recognition of “how we might act to abolish the coercions” implicit in what we don’t know (i.e., the interests for which we cannot acknowledge cogent motive) is, I would now argue, coterminous with the cognitive prospects for the augmented scope of reflection.This “enlarged mentality” is purveyed in tragedy and in the paradigm of reciprocal recognition that tragedy imposes upon aesthetics. Indeed, it might now be fair to say that the real sensus communis of tragedy is that common sense of anxiety about prospects for the equality of recognition from which we all suffer.To confront this anxiety without seeking to allay it, but only to make it more cogent, is the task that I have tried to promulgate here. I have tried to show how the attitude of solicitude, which expresses that anxiety, lends itself to procedures of self-recognition based on freer choice-making.This procedural imperative is what is at stake in the prospect of teaching the imagination to go visiting. It is perhaps the most pragmatic intimation of what the idea of aesthetic community can bring to the enterprise of social conscience.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 70
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 71
3
Acting in the Space of Appearance: Incontinent Will and the Pathos of Aesthetic Representation The space of appearance comes into being whenever men are together in the manner of speech and action . . . it does not survive the actuality of the movement which brought it into being, but disappears not only with the dispersal of men—as in the case of the great catastrophes when the body politic of a people is destroyed—but with the disappearance or arrest of the activities themselves. —Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition To scrute together with the inscrutable face. —Samuel Beckett, Ill Seen, Ill Said
I The realm of appearance has always been a well-worn threshold of the aesthetic, whether in the Platonist-inspired critique of art as sensational (delusional appearance), in the German idealist valorizations of art as universal or Spiritual (allegorical appearance), or in the objectifying canons of modernist formalism (instantiating appearance). Appearance remains the fulcrum of debate about the relevance of artistic practice and appreciation in postmodern culture, even as the balance is now being tipped by the partisans of a vehement anti-aesthetic, who want to abdicate the presentational field of the artwork in favor of a political battlefield. The anti-aesthetic sentiment voiced by historicist and materialist literary criticism advocates subordinating the aesthetic to the project of salvaging the public sphere (and its correlative political agencies) from an increasingly alienating and crisis-ridden cultural horizon.This antagonism toward the aesthetic pegs the presentational field of the artwork as a fetishizing of appearance (a fetish of affective sense). In this way, it is alleged, the aesthetic evades the very social conflicts that must consequently be made all the more urgently apparent
Singer.book
72
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 72
Aesthetic Reason
in the service of any prospective, and therefore potentially ethical, political change. The subtext of this polemic sets up a radical opposition between a caricature of the aesthetic as “mere appearance” (Vorstellung) and an anti-aesthetic politicization of “appearance as enactment” (Darstellung).1 This invidious comparison so resonant of the familiar thought-feeling dichotomy is meant to galvanize the human agent out of the affective stupor induced by pleasurable beauty.The evasion of conflict ascribed to the aesthetic is unmasked as a culpable premise for the mutual exclusivity of art and politics. What this critique of the aesthetic ignores, however, is that the animus of human conflict is irreducible even in the realm of appearance, even in the realm of “mere appearance” from which the aesthetic can never be cleanly severed. Hegel observes this to be the case in the dialectic of recognition that drives the master-slave relation.The insight of course arises first in the exigency of action that, for Hegelians, the fact of publicity per se imposes. Publicity is perforce recognition. As we have already seen, in the previous chapter, what appears for me appears precisely because it appears to another, subject to the contest of interpretations and the conflict-engendering initiatives to act that are latent in all intersubjective recognition. Likewise, we have seen that for the Greeks, the realm of appearance was fundamentally the realm of politics because it precipitated the actions of diversely interested agents recognized by virtue of their common stake in concerted public actions. If in her influential account of the Greek polis, Hannah Arendt is right that “[t]he space of appearance comes into being whenever men are together in . . . speech and action” (Human Condition, 99), then publicity is a site of recognition because it is a site of conflict, if only a conflict between the registers of speech and action: these are the realms of what is seen and what is said. This truism is the core of Greek tragedy, where recognition is a cardinal principle. It is a de facto imperative of the public agora, from whence tragedy arises and from whence the no-less-tragic Hegelian perspective itself was projected. Ironically enough, then, it is within the prototypically “aesthetic” tradition of Attic tragedy that we find strong intimations of precisely the vital relationship between art and politics (the polis) that partisans of the anti-aesthetic are inspired to deny in the name of the very political ideals that Greek tragedy so influentially disseminated. Furthermore, by taking tragedy as a point of reference, I might minimize the controversy of equating the realm of appearance that is politics with the sensuous threshold of appearance so commonly equated with the presentational field of aesthesis. It should be clear
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 73
Acting in the Space of Appearance
73
from this methodological point of departure that I am still advancing an account of the aesthetic that is decidedly cognitive.As such it lends itself to a mode of production that would be strictly at odds with the sensationalistic and naturalistically impersonal canons of conventional beauty theory.As it has been from the start of this enterprise, my stake in the cognitive resources of the aesthetic is intended to reanimate a dormant political dimension of the aesthetic—one that I believe is integral to the ethical agency of tragic protagonists. Certainly, tragedy is the place in Western culture where the constituent persons of the polis submit to a mode of rationalistic reflection through a discipline of self-recognition. The Dionysian festival stages the dialectic of daimon, the appearance qua appearance of the actor to the chorus, and eudaimonia, the mode of action that instantiates the ethical agent according to a necessary temporalization of appearance. Eudaimonia is not a quality. According to Aristotle, it is “acquired . . . by some kind of study or training” (Ethics, 80) . . . [and is a] “virtuous activity [in which] one can take part” (81).The ineluctable temporality of eudaimonia adumbrates the moral frame of reference for the audience. For it designates the time of their spectatorship as a corollary of the tragic protagonist’s life “training.”There is a strong implication here that the mode of inhabiting time as a self-reflective medium is de facto a training protocol for ethical self-understanding. Between daimon and eudaimonia there obtains, above all other considerations, the changeability of the self in time. It is thus fair to say that tragedy is an exemplary cultural site where appearance mediates human agency and where the inexorable split between human intention and human action—always the trigger of tragic insight—is displayed with unusual scrupulousness. The notion of akrasia (literally, weakness of will), or incontinent judgment, is the Greek ethicophilosophical touchstone for this experience. For Aristotle, akrasia specifically denotes acting against rational best intentions, that is, best reasons.Akrasia is typically delimited by appetitive drives that overrun rational knowledge. Following the lead of post-Aristotelian philosophy, I will be broadening the definition to include the intersubjective repercussions of acting akratically. I will argue that akrasia figures the gap between intentions and actions as reciprocity because it dictates a retrospective view of the self as erroneous, needing to be called to a better account of itself (Ethics, 237). Even Aristotle stipulates that one only knows akratic action after the fact, since its intelligibility inheres strictly in an enactment of beliefs.
Singer.book
74
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 74
Aesthetic Reason
Because this figuration of the gap between intentions and actions accrues within an expressly public forum, we could say strategically that akrasia unites both contesting senses of appearance—as “mere appearance” and as “enactment”—within a potentially therapeutic frame of reference. In other words, to act akratically (however irrational) is to purchase reflective distance on one’s actions in a way that no inanimate belief structure can hold faith with, because public accountability requires personal change.The polis is always already an arena of akratic self-knowledge because the ineluctable publicity of actions incurs a calling of individuals to account. Moreover, any calling to account is an occasion to revise the criterion of judgment that one submits to in the trials of self-recognition. I believe that this is a fact that is too easily lost sight of outside the structural dynamics of the polis that are both represented in and enacted by tragic drama. Furthermore the aesthetic, particularly in the mode of tragedy, taps this potential. Outside the context of the polis, that is, public recognition, akrasia succumbs to mere self-deception, the mere alienation of belief from action. Where the discrepancy between intentions and actions recedes from public scrutiny it increasingly defers to an ideational sphere of value. Political agency reifies into private ideological belief.2 In this chapter I will therefore explore the ways in which the aesthetic, seen as an outgrowth of the circumstances of tragic knowledge—epitomized by the slippage between intention and act, the akratic moment—eloquently glosses the exigencies of acting in the space of appearance. If that space can be seen to mark an overlap of the aesthetic and the political, then the aesthetic proves its ethical relevance to secular cultural practice, and to the energetics of an evermore-viable public sphere. Obviously such an expansive claim on behalf of a category that has typically been criticized for unduly narrowing the sights of cultural experience—perpetuating the recurrent dualism of art and politics— requires a perspicuous recontextualization of the issues. Above all, it demands a redefinition of the artwork as that which reveals the realm of appearances in the above terms, rather than merely appearing within that realm as an exemplification of its factitious “reality.” For me, Hannah Arendt’s definition of the political, the polis in particular, as “acting and speaking together . . . [in the] space of appearance” (Human Condition, 198) is a logical point of departure. For she explicitly correlates it with protocols of aesthetic judgement. As I noted in the previous chapter, her analysis of the judgment of taste is specifically an occasion to argue linkage between Kantian aesthetics and the public sphere.3 In that way
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 75
Acting in the Space of Appearance
75
she intimates how the political inevitably circles back to the aesthetic. As Arendt sees it through the lens of the Greek polis, politics is not framed by institutions but, because it is instantiated as an active sharing of words and deeds, always potentially expands the institutional frame of reference that bounds social activity. It follows that the judgment of taste for her is perforce a standard of communicability or publicity within which both individuality and rational normativity might be compatible.The status of appearance is thus inextricable from an idea of community, a sensus communis. I have tried to show, however, that, in a notable departure from Kant,Arendt shows us how this community requires the choice-making agency of those who would predicate their existence on the choice of belonging to it.4 It is relatively uncontroversial for me to allege that a principle of community has in fact always propped the project of the aesthetic, even in the most unworldly guises of ego-driven Romantic genius, or in the urbane impersonality of high modernist formalism. For, seen in its broadest historical and anthropological outlines, the aesthetic pursues a perennial reckoning of human making (poesis) with the monstrous indeterminacy of Nature (physis). Out of this reckoning the structure of classical tragedy itself arose. I will follow the consequence of this assumption in Chapter 6. But now, I want to concentrate on how the ideal of nomos—culture or tradition—which is assiduously served by tragedy, presupposes the artifice of sociality, if only in the recognition of a shared ideal of human personhood: the universally desirable good life.This idealism is the operative sine qua non of the tragic agon of physis-nomos, discussed in Chapter 2 as a background of the culture of Peitho.Yet I want to suggest that it is the desire for simple self-recognition that underscores the venerable binary of nature and culture, and unwittingly renders it a problem, both in ethical and in aesthetic theorizing. For a recognition predicated on such binarism is far too simple, in its tendency to make human freedom from Nature depend upon the transparency of a self-recognizing subject. The liability of this mode of recognition is typified in Hans Georg Gadamer’s referencing of the aesthetic to symbol, specifically the tesserae hospitalis, a clay emblem, broken between host and guest in Greek society on the occasion of a social gathering. When host and guest meet again they “recognize” each other by presenting their fragment token of a preexisting whole.This reconciliation in terms of a preexisting whole, which, for Gadamer, is generalized as the touchstone of artistic sensus communis, poses an obstacle to any real reciprocity between individual and group. For it begs the question of what one is
Singer.book
76
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 76
Aesthetic Reason
recognized as, independent of the concrete desires out of which such recognition is solicited.5 By following Arendt’s definition of politics as implicitly an outgrowth of the aesthetic—inasmuch as for the Greeks art was linked to politics by the realm of tragic appearance—I want to complicate this precipitously metaphysical standard of recognition. I propose to do this by showing how the richest account of recognition will depend upon a protocol of training in reciprocal recognition like that sketched out at the end of Chapter 2.This is a protocol that I believe is latent both in tragic drama and in the states of akratic knowledge that tragic drama illuminates. It is one that does not evade the knowledge that recognition, in its particularity, constitutes a choice among other particulars. In that way, we might persuasively redraw the boundaries of the aesthetic as a more inclusive and prudential community of human agents. The burdens of training in reciprocal recognition will be seen to outweigh the moral valuations borne by any more generalized and idealized recognition of human identity.
II Literary theories of recognition have too often ignored the fact that recognition is always a choosing to be recognized as something in particular. Only under that assumption do we understand that recognition is necessarily communicable or it would be strictly irrational. In the absence of such an assumption we have been content to sever recognition from rationality, producing exactly the alienation of art from politics descried by the partisans of the anti-aesthetic.To illustrate the point, we need only think of the force of the eighteenth-century doctrine classique, which proffers the standard of the beautiful as a selfrecognition pegged to obliterating all prejudicially individuated sentiment.6 In beauty theories, the universals of sensibility crowd out the particular sense percepts that are their occasion. Indeed, no modern philosophical discourse is as culpable of obviating the necessity to choose the terms of self-recognition vis-à-vis the contingent relations with a “particular other” as aesthetic theory itself, in its mission to bestow the imprimatur of beauty. Such is the enormous historical influence wielded by the neoclassical edicts assigning social valuations to art, that the abbé Dubos could confidently declaim in his Critical Reflections (1719) (which Voltaire called the most useful book ever written on this subject) that artistic taste may be judged on analogy
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 77
Acting in the Space of Appearance
77
with culinary taste: “one tastes the stew and, without even knowing these rules [governing its production], one knows if it’s good.”7 Here, if recognition underwrites aesthetic value, it is only as a counter of consensus that supersedes the concrete formality of the artwork, let alone the social formation of consensus itself. It begs the question of aesthetic production. Beauty theory is almost tautologically a name for the involuntary consensus of “men of good taste.” Nicolas Boileau (1636–1711) is the most famous disseminator of this standard of beauty and the anticognitivist recognition it perpetrates, though, unlike Dubos, his claim to authority roots itself in the pretense of scientific objectivity, rather than subjective universality.The irony is that Boileau’s appeal to science blurs the very boundary between subjective and objective knowledge that he otherwise wishes decisively to cross in the direction of establishing scientific or empirical norms. In Art poétique, Boileau makes the judgment of the beautiful depend upon a standard of public agreement, a mode of strictly mutual as distinct from reciprocal recognition, since it appeals to a de facto community of refined sensibility. In the 1701 edition, he proclaims that “a work which is not at all to the taste of the public is a bad work.” Crucially, there is nothing in Boileau’s own work, or in the work of his immediate successors such as Dubos, Dominique Bohours, and Charles Batteaux, that adduces any methodology to produce or motivate that agreement.The agency of artistic production is obviated by the naturalness presupposed in the prevailing Lockeanism of these views. In fact, any preoccupation with the means or agency of artistic production would be judged heretical within a philosophy that seeks to denigrate imagination as an idiosyncratic obstacle to the intuition of common experience. In this purview, reciprocity is a figment of recognition’s imagination, manifested in the guise of an uncritical universalism. Indeed, we must accept that the basis of whatever public agreement can be posited here is an intrinsically unreasonable—because noncognitive—presupposition of aesthetic theory, and in no way an efficient methodological lever for potentiating its purported social efficacy. In this proposition we have a presumption of community interest, but only an ex post facto mode of expressing or accounting for it. By denying access to the rule-making agency that underwrites them, such tastemaking propositions promulgate a rule governance that is every bit as politically abstruse as the standard of Kantian disinterestedness that it anticipates. It is even more important to see that the conspicuous paradox of beauty theory (whether science based or sensibility based) is that it
Singer.book
78
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 78
Aesthetic Reason
seems to privilege sense, and anchor judgment, in the practical world, while actually idealizing that world. As we saw earlier, in the cases of Hutcheson and Shaftesbury, beauty theory posits a faculty of taste in which the sensibility and the natural world are in markedly unspoken, and therefore irrational, because nondiscursive, agreement. Taste is a kind of shadow cognition that is designed to make sense an increasingly transparent medium of empirical reality. In consideration of this irony, we may be better disposed to consider an alternative paradox. Perhaps only a cognitively based aesthetic, one that is discursively mediated and on that account seems to eschew sense, might engage the practical world (which sense begets) as productively as beauty theory made a mere pretense of doing.After all, the cardinal Enlightenment cognition is a choosing between differences, a movement from sensation to idea that mimes Lockean empiricism. I will argue that in postulating the judgment of taste (and the desire for public/communal recognition historically implicit in it) as an active choosing between differences, we do indeed acknowledge that choosing to be recognized is always choosing to be recognized as something in particular.And since this constrains any analysis of act to the unequal variables of choice, it motivates reciprocity. Reciprocity remains a virtually irreducible variable of choice wherever public standards of choosing have currency. By thus reversing the polarity of sense and reason, between which poles beauty theory gets articulated, we might redress the flawed concept of recognition that constitutes the irrational underpinning of the doctrine classique. Furthermore, I want to emphasize how the recognition that choosing to be recognized is always choosing to be recognized as something in particular quite explicitly constrains judgment to acting in the space of appearance. Particularity is, after all, the common medium of appearance and aesthesis. In this respect, recognition inhibits beauty theory’s transcendental predilections.The requisite mediation of a public space presupposes that the significance of action denoted in such choosing is an ineluctable solicitation of the opinion of others. Such solicitude may not rest at the reflective poles of self or other, for the reason that its restlessness is a function of an irreducible intersubjectivity.That is to say, the mode of reciprocal recognition I’m promoting here, far from instantiating a de facto community, would take up the burden of producing public agreement that mere affective recognition reflects as an abstraction. Perhaps, then, by imagining a protocol of training in this mode of reciprocal recognition, we might come closer to actually producing the communitarian ethos/consensus that Boileau and beauty
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 79
Acting in the Space of Appearance
79
theory rendered incoherent, by consigning it to a preemptive universalism. We must of course add the proviso that any such communitarian ethos, since it is a “goal” of training, remains a heuristic contingency of imaginative activity. Finally, my claim that what is entailed by a protocol of training in reciprocal recognition (and the concomitant production of a communitarian ethos) is best viewed from the perspective of tragedy will be most persuasive if I can spell out precisely what needs are satisfied by reciprocal recognition and match them with the needs traditionally served by tragedy, both formal and historical.We must then look closely at how this protocol of training is adumbrated in a specific aesthetic form. Samuel Beckett’s Ill Seen, Ill Said—a work that construes the tragic as a speculative reckoning with error rather than as a positive assimilation of knowledge claims—will serve to exemplify my belief in the aesthetic as a training ground for recognition.A reading of this text might make it possible to articulate more convincingly how the significance of the category of the aesthetic is directly proportionate to the perceived significance of the problem of akratic action. After all, for the akrates (the akratic agent) the inescapable task of closing the gap between knowing and acting, thinking and feeling, reveals the stakes of every recognition-based cultural identity. From the time of the Greek polis—if we accept the Arendtian perspective—this task of making knowledge reciprocal with action is the fundamental challenge of acting in the space of appearance. Only in these terms can knowledge serve as a space of convergence for the aesthetic and the political that would tolerate no hegemonic allegorizing of the individual to the social other and no utopian recourse to a spiritual hypostasis of Otherness itself. As we shall see, in order to satisfy this test, the space of appearance must in turn be mapped upon narrative coordinates.
III Three needs served by reciprocal recognition match up with the traditional rewards of tragic drama: (a) the need for recognition of the indeterminacy of human actions (the slippage between intentions and acts; (b) the need to make this recognition self-conscious—which we gain rapport with in the dynamic of akrasia; and (c) the need to make akratic judgment productive by understanding that it follows a narrative trajectory, namely, by understanding that the choices it prompts are expressible as a tension between discrepant temporal moments. On this
Singer.book
80
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 80
Aesthetic Reason
basis we will understand how the remedy for akrasia is inseparable from posing the kind of unity/totality of knowledge we typically equate with standards of artistic success. Only by maximizing the tensions of discrepant moments under a totalizing imperative are they made amenable to a morally edifying activity: one that recognizes the indeterminacy of human actions to be an urgent premise of deterministic drives.This is, after all, the aim of Aristotelian tragedy.As “an imitation of an action that is serious and complete,” it strives to encompass potentially incommensurable variables of human agency within a totalizing framework that, in turn, begs the question of its own adequacy to the task.8 We can start with the proposition that the desire for recognition of the indeterminacy of actions confronts the risk of error, of hamartia, the abiding structural pivot of tragic drama.9 Though hamartia is commonly taken as a flaw of character, its meaning is effectively realized through actions that point up a discrepancy between intentions and consequences.They are actions deprived of knowledge in a way that figures the problematic of akrasia. Hamartia, like akrasia, effectively collapses the perspectives of the human agent into the world of fated events. It is a daunting obstacle to any project of self-realization whereby one expects action to be reconciled with intentional knowledge.After all, where action may be reconciled with intentional knowledge tragedy might be averted. In other words, under the sign of hamartia, the desire for recognition must contend with the dilemma of the unintended consequences of the action through which such recognition is solicited.10 Arendt reminds us that for the Greeks, the great liability of action (deliberately contrasted with poesis or making, that is, craft) was its potential boundlessness and uncertainty of outcome (Human Condition, 195). If recognition were reciprocal it would provide a check against hamartia or unintended consequence by bounding it within a circuit of human communication. This would not, however, extinguish the possibility of future intentional action, which the moment of reversal (peripety) so apocalyptically portends, because reciprocal recognition entails a reconfiguration of intentions according to other criteria of action and motivation. Recognition then could be seen to harbor the reversal of reversal where it holds open the prospect of reciprocity in a discursive situation. Furthermore, by preserving a framework for intentional action within the contextual constraints of unintended consequences, reciprocal recognition satisfies the need dramatized in classical tragedy for imagining a community in which human plurality (otherness) does not preclude human uniqueness (situated/individuated identity). Only where this is the case can intentional agents truly preserve a claim on ethical agency.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 81
Acting in the Space of Appearance
81
The stakes of this proposition are in fact epitomized, as we saw earlier, in the dialectic of daimon and eudaimonia. The dialectic is both reflected and represented by the antagonistic roles of the tragic chorus—in its dithyrambic objectifications of the protagonist—and the tragic protagonist—in his or her embodiment of a mode of action that might obviate the simple opposition of spectator and actor.This is the expressly ethical meaning of the Greek eudaimonia. Under the auspices of eudaimonia, one goes beyond the subject-object dichotomy that the daimon is otherwise caught antinomically within.11 In fact, individuals do not have their own daimon except by interaction with those who know them from the outside and hence impel their introspective conscience toward deeds of self-realization that carry them away from the community of judgment. As Hannah Arendt observes in her discussion of the dramatistic aspects of action in classical Greek culture, human “uniqueness” has the status of a dialectical third vis-à-vis the qualities of “otherness” and “distinctness,” where “otherness” denotes sheer multiplicity and “distinctness” denotes an expressive capacity upon which the recognition of multiplicity depends (Human Condition, 176). The striving for “uniqueness” thus parallels the logic of eudaimonia. It arises from the otherwise intractable incommensurability of otherness and distinctness. It is the self-distinguishing expression of human distinctness that renders the knowledge of human plurality a locus of uniqueness or, in Arendt’s words, “a paradoxical plurality of unique beings” (178). Furthermore, if “otherness” can be seen as a marker for the situation of the spectatorial chorus, and “distinctness” can be seen as a marker for the situation of the objectified (and hence necessarily misunderstood) tragic protagonist, then the knowledge that devolves to the audience of tragic drama may be comparable to the knowledge of uniqueness: exhibiting a eudaimonian imperative to know oneself through the continuity of otherness and distinctness.This self-knowledge is the audience’s privilege above the actors on stage. It is the audience’s access to motivations that the protagonist’s hamartia precludes, but that are nevertheless continuous with the identity that the protagonist represents to the audience.This self-knowledge is, to use the Hegelian phrase that grasps the dialectical dimension of intersubjectivity, a kind of “reflection of reflection.” Anything else would render the project of human self realization too preemptively finite in time and space, which is to say, transcendentalized or reified by the self-imposing limits of a single deed (194). Of course eudaimonia has typically been mistranslated as sheer happiness or pleasure. It has been accordingly misconstrued as a counterpart
Singer.book
82
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 82
Aesthetic Reason
of beauty theory, as the counterpart of a noncognitive pleasure aesthetic, and hence as an escape from the inconstancies of human action. To be fair, the Greeks did treat the actions through which eudaimonia was allegedly realized retrospectively.Those actions would thus appear to be cut off from the temporality of their occurrence and implicitly from any meaningful reflection upon temporality. In that way, we might think the Greeks incurred the paradox of making the concept of eudaimonia ultimately antithetical to life itself (Aristotle, Ethics, 193–94). They, in effect, would have reasoned themselves into the logical corner where it is concluded that death is the price of happiness.12 Contrary to these plausible hypotheses, however, I want to argue that the action denoted in eudaimonia, just as credibly fosters a distinctly cognitive and therefore worldly/life-perpetuating trajectory. After all, eudaimonia might be said to presuppose reversal by its very bridging of otherness and distinctness. In doing so it would confer a reflective purchase on the imperative to act. It would clear an avenue for approaching the aesthetic as a space of appearance wherein action may be productively reconciled with thinking, and thinking might be actualized in appearance.This logic is compatible with Aristotle’s own linkage of eudaimonia with phronesis (Ethics, 78), a term that he puts decisively at odds with poiesis on the grounds that poiesis demands the mutual exclusiveness of thinking and acting. Or at least this is the case where poiesis constitutes an inducement to finite totalizing action (208–9).After all,Aristotle’s eudaimonia always presupposes a life lived in linked actions, as opposed to punctual pleasures. To be eudaimonia, Aristotle avers, is to complement the relative punctuality of daimon with whatever “reason” might sustain the daimon over a succession of temporal moments. The daimon suffers from an inability to see himself because, standing in the place of the actor, that is, in the immediacy of the action, he is excluded from the possibility of reflection. So in eudaimonia, the meaning of daimon is made available to the actor as well as to the spectator.The space of appearance adumbrates a self-reflective protocol of recognition that reanimates the daimon.Thus Oedipus sees his ruination in the chorus’s pronouncements of his fate, but is, in turn, awakened to his need to act on behalf of that ruined personage. Only with this understanding does it make sense for Oedipus to go on as he does, like an anachronistic Beckett character. For he does go on, under the auspices of a resurrected will, at least to suffer exile on his own terms and against the will of both Creon and the oracle.13 If we juxtapose Aristotle’s linkage of eudaimon and phronesis in the Ethics with his rationalization of tragic insight in Poetics, we might see
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 83
Acting in the Space of Appearance
83
how peripeteia—epiphenomonal of linked actions—tends to displace catharsis—a phenomenon of punctual pleasure—as the more important fulcrum of tragic understanding. It would once again give greater urgency to tragic form as a prompt to cognitive over noncognitive initiatives. It might thereby augur for a more open-ended understanding of tragic action. We can now fairly equate this cognitive trajectory with a narrative constraint and with the framework of akratic knowledge already understood as a warrant for figuring the gap between intentions and actions. This figuration is, after all, tragedy’s threshold of moral efficacy. For narrative constraint is the place where the needs satisfied by reciprocal recognition most consequentially meet the needs satisfied by tragedy. The common interest of both is finding a corrective to error, to the unintended consequences of action. Narrative is the “space of appearance” within which these interests can be pursued as the continuation of action, where appearance elides with recognition and the burden of judgment. We have already seen that akratic knowledge obeys a comparable narrative constraint that is essentially tragic because, unlike mere selfdeception, where belief is divorced from action and proffers an escape from reflection, akrasia presupposes the unremitting tension of distinct moments, as its condition of possibility. Unlike mere self-deception, akrasia is act dependent.14 What discrepancies play between intentions and the consequences of action entail acknowledgment of another position of knowledge locatable beyond the temporal locus of the original intentions. What makes this narrative constraint specifically cognitive is that when we ask why an agent acts akratically—since we must ask in the context of a tension between two disparate but not mutually exclusive moments—we are furthermore required to solicit reasons not as causes but as choices vis-à-vis other reasons. This is the case because the discrepancy between intentions and unintended consequences appears strictly on the threshold of social mediations that denote an always potentially wider discursive field of reference. Where intentions are valued independent of consequences, that is, where akrasia is judged to be an obstacle to, not a test of, knowledge, causality obtains in such a way that reasons are subordinated to a transcendent intention. From my point of view, this purveys a weak form of self-recognition, evading as it does the conflictual provenance of human agency. The recognitional structure latent in akratic causality offers a useful contrast: in akratic causality, actions and choices are understood to be continuous, because acts submit to act descriptions
Singer.book
84
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 84
Aesthetic Reason
in their mere publicity. Akratic causality thus possesses a correlative ethical purport not unlike the anagnorisis of tragic emplotment. In anagnorisis, the defeat of personal intentions seems to demand (if only on the part of the spectator) the improvisation of new motives. It demands remediation of the loss of self-control suffered by the protagonist in the disastrous outcomes of otherwise seemingly rationally motivated actions. Correlatively, in the context of both the Greek polis and tragic drama, akrasia’s ethical remedy and opposite number is identified as enkrateia, or self-control. But inasmuch as enkrateia is postulated as a cognitive remedy for akrasia, it denotes a cognitive faculty underpinning akratic action itself, if only by the acknowledged default of enkrateia in akratic acts. Hence enkrateia obtains not as a duality visà-vis akrasia, but on a continuum with akrasia.The postulate of this continuum follows from the understanding that akrasia, in its presumption of a best reason for acting, is implicated in the reciprocity of the general and the particular. According to the classical scholarly consensus on akrasia set out influentially in Walsh’s “Aristotle’s Concept of Moral Weakness,” and cited by J. M. Bremer,“[A] man may be said to act against his [best] knowledge if he exercises his knowledge of the universal premiss but does not exercise or even possess knowledge of the particular premiss; the failure to exercise or to possess the knowledge of the particular premiss must be related to appetite” (106–12).Thus, if akrasia is to be judged remediable, it requires a resituating of the claims of a general perspective within a concrete context of application.The burden is upon the akratic subject to find new motives or reasons for invoking the relevant generality. According to Alfred Mele, who follows this principle when he asserts the necessity to accept irrationality as a medium of rational pursuit, the attempt to exercise enkratic self-control presents two obstacles: (a) to know akrasia to be the case, and (b) to possess skills for resisting the temptations of incontinence.15 What is clear here is that without an expectation of success or the prospective integration of intent and act denoted by enkrateia, akrasia is altogether irrelevant to human experience. Indeed, Mele’s account of enkrateia subtly reveals how the focus on akrasia is necessarily a concern for thinking totality in action, at least as long as the alternative enkratic self-control remains its ultimate critical measure.The akrasia-enkrateia continuum is, as I have anticipated, a métier that is strikingly amenable to protocols of training, since any such totality in action produces a retrospective agency dependent on reconfiguring that totality within the exigencies of time that mark its own existence in time. In fact, here training, rather than truth, becomes
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 85
Acting in the Space of Appearance
85
the salient counter of human agency, since the unending pressure to totalize yields to the open-endedness of the totalizing enterprise. Narrative is the crux of this training because, by its maximizing of tensions between temporal moments, it exemplifies human error as remediable in time. Such remediation would be credited to one’s mastery of the recognition of error understood in turn as a counter of temporality. It would be credited to a capacity for self-revision, the only human skill practically commensurate with this temporality. Since this discussion of akratic agency is meant to get us back to aesthetic issues, we now need to attend to the fact that the concern for totality featured in the akrasia-enkrateia continuum implicitly mirrors the privileging of totality in formalist art practice.We have already noted the irony that, within contemporary art theory especially, this totality is invoked only to be debunked and scapegoated.16 It is good only for exposing the valorization of aesthetic unity to the charge of metaphysical or empirical reification.There are other considerations, however.We must take note that the striving for totality exhibited in akratic action obtains only inasmuch as it possesses a narrative structure. We must also consider that without a concern for totality (expressed as an impossible reckoning of intentions with unintended consequences), we would have no warrant for making akrasia or incontinence a locus of moral scrutiny. On that basis, then, we might be prepared to see how the maximizing of the tensions that play between disparate parts (moments) in aesthetic structure, and upon which narrative peripety depends, might possess a corollary warrant for moral scrutiny. 17 We might then concede that the access to the problematics of totality availed by akrasia offers a way of revaluing the goal of totality in tragic emplotment/art.We are now able to countenance it as a métier of ethical conduct rather than as the dubious precept of ethical dogma that has become the easy target of anti-aesthetic polemicizing. In other words, the remedy of enkrateia or self-control inevitably prompted by knowledge of akratic action might now be seen as relevant to a richer understanding of the demand for recognition of totality implicit in narrative art.The mandate for training in reciprocal recognition, which I am arguing inheres in aesthetics generally, thus becomes coherent with the structural articulation of the artwork.This is especially true if one accepts my prior claim that the structural articulation of the artwork is cognate with the continuum of akrasia and enkrateia in action: their incommensurability is their reciprocity.The “concern” for totality modeled in enkrateia proffers an ethical motive inversely proportionate to the unrealizability of totalizing action that is so unfailingly exemplified
Singer.book
86
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 86
Aesthetic Reason
by works of art when they are held to the same standards of knowledge. Between artistic creation and art consumption, the same detotalizing totality of judgment obtains.The benefit of this insight is the prospect it offers: that the critic’s concern for totality in aesthetic form may come to displace the more burdensome ontology of totalization that he or she otherwise seems doomed to justify. So I am suggesting that self-control or enkrateia—where enkrateia presupposes a revisable standard of the adequacy of act to intention— might be construed as a proper medium of aesthetic expression, as it is in ethical practice. Self-control and aesthetic totality are both approached through a discrepancy between intentions and consequences, through akratic detours. I do not, however, mean simply to blur the lines between ethics and aesthetics here. Rather I want to suggest that the social consensus (ethical norm) sought so righteously by a neoclassical (Boileau’s) beauty theory, though it lacked the resources of human agency to produce that consensus, might discover the necessary resources for doing so along the akrasia-enkrateia continuum. It might do so in a way that binds ethics more closely to aesthetics. Enkrateia proffers a means of marrying the demand for a generalized norm of self-control, or best reasoned behavior with the situational exigencies of events in time. For, along the continuum between akrasia and enkrateia, agreements about what counts as best reasoned behavior are necessarily predicated upon changing conditions, hence upon judging reasons among reasons that warrant recognition.18 Indeed, the ethical challenge for the human agent, moving from akrasia to enkrateia, is to be increasingly responsive and sensitive to changing conditions of recognition.The continuum between akrasia and enkrateia will therefore count as a useful correlative to aesthetic practice, if we understand aesthetic form as modeling the condition of this attention to changing conditions. In its bid for totality, aesthetic form replicates the crisis of akrasia by anticipating new conditions of recognition, that is, by promulgating an expressly prospective recognition of totality.
IV I want to exemplify these claims in the context of a late narrative by Samuel Beckett, Ill Seen, Ill Said. My reason for choosing Beckett is that his métier in this narrative is an ethical agency that I might now meaningfully call prospective pathos. In its prospective recognition of totality, it both exemplifies the cognitive exigencies of akrasia and dramatizes
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 87
Acting in the Space of Appearance
87
the anticipation of those new reasons for invoking general premises of knowledge that I’ve alleged akrasia exposes. It thereby serves the project of reciprocal recognition as a mode of enkratic self-control. I will argue that Beckett’s innovation as a narrative artist is his dramatization of human pathos, not, as is commonly asserted, as a function of the impossibility of action, but as a function of our “being” only in the prospect of acting.This prospective imperative of being is determined by Beckett’s linkage of character and narrative to a site of error—not coincidentally, the dramatic topos of akratic judgment. Beckett’s opus notoriously features protagonists whose condition of existence depends upon what seem to be insuperable obstacles to action, but for whom the imperative to act is nonetheless an uncompromising proposition. Such, after all, is Molloy’s firm infirmity:“I can’t go on. I’ll go on.” I believe that this circumstance is given new emphasis in Beckett’s final triad of short fictions, Company; Ill Seen, Ill Said; and Worstward Ho! Interestingly, the hallmark of these works, each struggling with the human craving for company, is the pronominal instability of protagonists and narrators. In these fictions, existence plays uncertainly between first- and third-person pronouns, a circumstance that exacerbates the quandary of how to go on. More explicitly, we are led to know this constraint of being, this slippage between pronoun and referent, self and other, as conditioning a threshold of error that, inasmuch as it denotes a lack of self-knowledge, figures a mode of self-deception. As we’ve seen, both tragedy and the philosophy of akratic action seek to remedy this circumstance in the name of a more dignified human agency. In this regard, the existential error that burdens Beckett’s characters becomes a correlative strategic burden for the reader. For this reason I want to characterize Beckett’s prospective pathos as a method whereby one (the reader through narrator or character) comes to self-knowledge by soliciting the recognition of a concrete other, at least inasmuch as the pronominal self in error is already a kind of other to itself. Because the antecedent (retrospective) knowledge, upon which the pronominal self generally presumes, is made suspect in these fictions, the alternative prospective trajectory is the more credible imperative of otherness. Some reckoning with the other has after all been the abiding stake of reciprocal recognition in the discussion so far. So it will not be surprising if I propose that such recognition serves, within the context of Beckett’s Ill Seen, Ill Said, as a means for us to more intensely appreciate the continuity of akrasia with enkrateia. It has been widely argued that moral theorists from Kant to Habermas have not been able to make this recognition by a concrete
Singer.book
88
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 88
Aesthetic Reason
other sufficiently reciprocal to accommodate a realistic sense of both self and the world to promote a credible Sittlichkeit where ethical selfrealization would be compatible with moral autonomy.19 Rather, moral theory that seeks undeluded or enkratic self-knowledge has typically appealed to the unworkable concept of a general or generalized “other,” incommensurable with the “concrete other.”The most controversial paradigm of this thought is the agent of Kantian moral duty who is charged to act in such a way that the maxim of his or her actions might be a universal law of nature.20 We might notice with Seyla Benhabib, who has written persuasively against the predicate of the generalized other, that the opposition of a general and concrete other was rendered intractable in Kantian morality because it subsisted on a strict dichotomy of cognition and emotion.We will not lose sight of the fact that this is the very dichotomy that has traditionally severed the aesthetic from the political in most post-Platonist aesthetics. All the more reason, then, for me to propose that Beckett’s aesthetic form evokes the concrete other without incurring the problematic incommensurability of a general and concrete other: without incurring an unpayable debt of injustice. Instead, Beckett makes the project of self-recognition reciprocal through a kind of thought experiment, whereby the narrating subject strives for self-realization at the limit of self-knowledge, without attempting to personify that limit beyond the dynamics of self-expressive need.The other does not have to speak for itself, because the narrative self performs this thought experiment on the threshold of error. In Beckett’s text we might persuasively speak of a procedural other rather than an ontological other, without risking Kantian idealism. For in Beckett the threshold and the limit of selfknowledge are coincident in consciousness of error. This is the case because error, in Beckett’s text, is always extendable along a narrative trajectory. In effect the concrete other is merged with error. And this is what constrains the pathos of Beckett’s narrator to a mode of prospectivity. As long as error arises on a self-reflective narrative trajectory, the self in question must adapt perspectivally to the situational mandates for self-reflection.21 Of course I am suggesting that the point of positing the other as a ground of recognition at all is to know boundaries of self that are conspicuously available in the epistemic matrices of akrasia or error. Certainly self-recognition without the pressure of self-limitation would be precisely the circumstance in which akratic action is inevitable. But now I am suggesting that this fact does not require us to reason that self-limitation be read as ontologically intersubjective. One could fol-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 89
Acting in the Space of Appearance
89
low alternative post-Aristotelian accounts such as Alison McIntyre’s, where the akratic agent is understood to be, de facto, self-revising according to the “recognition of a new consideration”22 that arises in the split of actions from intentions. One could argue that the inexorability of a “new consideration” is what drives the intelligibility of akrasia in the first place. On this basis, McIntyre invites our belief in akrasia as the vehicle for attaining what Hannah Arendt has called “an enlarged mentality.” 23 The idea is that when events reveal the inappropriateness (error) of our motives, we might see how this potentially gives us evidence of what we could be motivated by as a result of further reflection.24 This is the possibility that I anticipated by imagining how akrasia might occasion the intuition of new motives for the akratic subject. The aim of “enlarged mentality” comes more quickly to the fore of our ethical/aesthetic considerations as we pursue this line of thought, because it reminds us how much of Aristotle’s Ethics hinges on cultivating the capacity to change one’s mind (7.1151b110–1152a). While “enlarged mentality” is unequivocally a Kant-inspired ethical resource, it is nevertheless understood by Arendt and Benhabib25 as a threshold of otherness that is tantamount to error or self-deception insofar as it is predicated on a knowledge that the intentional “I” is also a “me.”This self is emphatically not transparent to itself, but nonetheless continuous with itself. Furthermore, it should be clear that there is nothing in this reflection on the “me” that precludes our thinking of the other as an aspect of self that is reciprocal, in a procedural rather than an ontologically intersubjective sense.This was precisely the case where we discerned the “prospectival” narrative underpinning of the continuum between akrasia-enkrateia. Furthermore, we will recall that in Poetics, Aristotle pegs recognition to the movement from ignorance to knowledge.Aristotle’s corresponding subordination of character to action shows us that this is not necessarily a movement across the threshold of distinct subjects. The point is consistent with my sense that akrasia ought not to be treated as merely a falsifiable (nonnarrative) tenor of rationality, but narratively, as a vehicle of self-revising rationality.As I have already stated, akrasia promises to be more useful as a figuration of the gap between intentions and actions than as a conceptual means merely to discredit the rationality of intentions.26 Here is how this ground gets staked out in Beckett. In Ill Seen, Ill Said, the reciprocity of self-recognition stays within the bounds of the narrator’s subjectivity without devolving to an ethically dubious monologue that has no rapport whatsoever with otherness. The title of
Singer.book
90
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 90
Aesthetic Reason
Beckett’s novel is the watchword of his method. In Ill Seen, Ill Said, what is seen is linked to what is said by the mutual susceptibility to error that the opposition of these faculties (seeing and saying) brings to light.The prevailing illness is strikingly symptomatic in the author’s admonitory voicing of the narrative action as a cautionary against going on. Beckett couches this symptom in the dramatic situation of the book’s narrator: the narrator is presented as one consciousness striving to know another within the hedging predicates of an awareness that does not trust itself to risk the other’s confirmation of what he knows about otherness.The hallmark of the narrator’s rhetoric is therefore the persistent cautionary deixis that becomes a veritable refrain of the text: “careful,”“slow,”“quick, move on.”These are all cues for the narrator to avoid the trap of reckoning with a real other about whom what is said is always ill said. In Ill Seen, Ill Said, the particular other, toward whom we look for confirmation of whoever says what is there to be seen, appears to be an old woman approaching the proverbial Beckettian endgame. Here is where Beckett’s thought experiment with respect to self-other relations is particularly resourceful. For he tantalizes us with the prospect of knowing a concrete other.Yet that palpable “otherness” is only available in the self-revising locutions of the narrator.And yet the narrator’s every new initiative seems in turn to be triggered by the inescapability of error. Error persists in the patterns of admonitory deixis that turn the narration into an ever more yawing chasm between the narrator’s act of witness and the old woman who is the testimonial object of his scrutiny. In other words, there is no vicarious escape into a generalized other in order to realize the self free of error. But, at the same time, the self-revising narrator does generalize beyond the conditions of his own concrete self-instantiation.The vehicle of this self-articulation, which I would count as a kind of heuristic other, is the “parsimonious syntax” that is the stylistic signature of all of Beckett’s last narrative experiments. By parsimoniously withholding key counters of syntactical completeness, Beckett appears to be striving to go beyond the effect of the stichomythic dialogue that was so instrumental to advancing the philosophical theses in Godot and in the trilogy Molloy, Malone Dies, and The Unnameable. In those texts, the self, starved of existence, fed ravenously on reciprocity with another so as to deflect from solipsistic self-consciousness. In Ill Seen, Ill Said, Beckett’s narrative internalizes the project of deflection.Whereas the other in stichomythic exchange is assimilated to a depersonalizing verbal process, which nonetheless frees the self from the task of independent self-realization, the other
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 91
Acting in the Space of Appearance
91
obtruding in parsimonious syntax accrues as a self-consciousness, increasingly implicated in the task of self-realization, but no less dependent on the recognition of otherness. In fact, it is an other invisible interlocutor who is most instrumentally evoked in the gapped locutionary progress of the narrative of Ill Seen, Ill Said. In this way Beckett avoids the potential self-deception of posing the narrating self against an other whose “real” otherness might relieve the burden of self-understanding that the narrating self must otherwise attest to as the self in error. That is to say, Beckett avoids the trap of positing the other as an escape from struggling with the ambiguous act of positing an other. To illustrate how parsimonious syntax works to this effect, let me take a typical admonition for the invisible interlocutor (the reader?) to “Look,” to “See,” in this case to inspect a long greatcoat, picked out in a telltale fragment sentence as “A man’s by the buttons.” Specifically, what is to be seen is deliberately marked by the deletion of what would be said, if the voice were addressing itself to another. The voice of the other, a kind of invisible company solacing the narrator’s solitude, is assimilable to the absence of the syntactical connectives.The absent connectives evoke a ghostly intersubjectivity. I bracket the “absent” syntactical connectives to make the point: “[I can tell it is] a man’s by [looking at the] buttons” (Ill Seen, Ill Said, 42). In other instances the effect is worked more radically to imply a deep dialogue between the compulsively observant narrator and the ghostly intelligence present in the elided parts of speech. Here is the greatcoat again, serving as curtains over the old woman’s only window. Once again I have bracketed the missing syntactical connectives: “A black greatcoat. [It is] Hooked by its tails from the rod it hangs [upon] sprawling inside out like a carcass in a butcher’s stall. Or [it would be] better [to say] inside in for the pathos of the dangling arms. [There is the s]ame infinitesimal quaver as the buttonhook and passim” (47). Beckett’s parsimonious syntax sets up a curious spectatorship whereby the reader is projected into the action not on the register of the (so to speak) “visible” protagonist (the old woman and her pathos) but in the verbal lacunae that paradoxically voice the presence of an invisible interlocutor, to whom a virtual completion of the syntax would be otherwise ascribable.The postulate of an invisible interlocutor in this text then is quite aptly poised between what is seen and what is said.This is a threshold of error where pathos is necessarily deferred or made prospective. For the tension between what is seen and what is said mandates an accommodation of contingency, as a condition of, rather
Singer.book
92
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 92
Aesthetic Reason
than an obstacle to, intelligibility.The tension between what is seen and what is said is furthermore a variation on the daimon-eudaimonia reciprocity that we have accepted as an ethical as well as a formal armature of tragedy. Parsimonious syntax appeals for a standard of lucidity to a scene that is distinctly not seen in the conspicuous ill-saying of what is reputedly here to be seen.What can be seen depends upon our willingness to assume the place of the invisible interlocutor. The most persistent testimonial to the presence of the invisible interlocutor in Beckett’s text is the inquisitorial refrain of the narrator: “What the wrong word?” (Ill Seen, Ill Said, 17).This expostulation is the ever present guidepost of such dramatic action as there is in the novel. In every instance it prompts a cautionary deceleration of the narrator’s narrative progress. More important, this expostulation typically occurs in tandem with the dissolution of the scannable visual image into a blind syntactical scansion.The reader’s (invisible interlocutor’s?) possibilities for erroneous scenic construal are thus arrayed as distinctly unvisualizable verbal ambiguities. I think that something like a protocol of training in reciprocal recognition is densely dramatized here.The question “What the wrong word?” serves as a kind of training where it obviates the hypothesis that there is a right word at all, where it obfuscates the adequacy of the word to a visual register of truth. The fact that the blurring of the image always redounds to, at least, a duplicity of potentially decidable but always as yet undecided syntactical meanings points up the degree to which the imperative of choice-making imposed in the threat of error—of choosing the wrong word—must be understood as rule generative, not rule adherent. In this way it is strictly compatible with the conceit of the invisible interlocutor, assuming the interlocutor’s invisibility confers the imperative to see anew by mustering prospectively a criterion of choice that will be necessarily retrospective, that is, a consequence of error.Within this paradox, knowing reciprocates with error in the solicitation of recognition. Indeed the invisible interlocutor typically appears in Ill Seen, Ill Said in the disappearance of certainty about what can already be seen to be the case.The first admonition by the narrator to be “careful” of making simple retrospective (in other words, foundational) assumptions arises from the first attempt to set the scene of this narrative: “The cabin [where the old woman endures]. Its situation. Careful.” Of what we are meant to be careful we know nothing, except what is contingent upon the imperative to go on: “On. At the inexistent centre of a formless place” (Ill Seen, Ill Said, 8). The invisible interlocutor deliberately spurred “on,” in this opening gambit of narration, is thus linked to the
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 93
Acting in the Space of Appearance
93
source of tragic knowledge, namely, the wrong word, by a procedural scruple of countenancing error as the only prospect (means of going “on”) for self-understanding. The appearance of the word tears—denoting nominatively those mirrory globes of human grief and verbally the tearing apart of otherwise commensurable registers, which is after all the source of tearful grief—constitutes the first occasion of this error-driven knowledge in Beckett’s narrative. Perhaps Beckett is showing us that tragedy, the fount of tears, is the reflective medium par excellence, insofar as in tragedy one learns to see oneself in reversal (peripety) as one is not, that is, in error.The inaugural tears in the tragedy that is Ill Seen, Ill Said both flow from the intensity of the old woman’s own visual focus and anticlimactically blur it:“Riveted to some detail of the desert the eye fills with tears” (17). These tears born of the exercise of the knowledgeseeking eye, trying to see what is there to be known, curiously blur vision in the manner of a perverse corrective lens. For the curvature of this lens indicates no trajectory of correction that might count as a certifiable prescription, a remediation of what is wrong. Our evidence for this claim is that the word tears in the ensuing sentences is successively “visualized,” so to speak, in multiple registers of implied analogy. However, for all their solicitation of imagistic resemblances, the analogies thwart visuality altogether: “Riveted to some detail of the desert the eye fills with tears. Imagination at wit’s end spreads its sad wings. Gone she hears one night the sea as if afar. Plucks up her long skirt to make better haste and discovers her boots and stockings to the calf.Tears. Last example the flagstone before her door that by dint by dint her little weight has grooved.Tears” (17–18).Tears are “made apparent” analogically, as sad wings of imagination, the water of the sea, rents in stockings, and perhaps even the water that grooves the stone in the manner of the human step. In other words, Beckett’s narrator posits all that can be seen in terms of what he will fixate upon, later in the text, as the discrepancy between two eyes—“one of flesh and the other.” The binarism of this analogizing—visual and verbal, eye and I, seen and said—clearly exhibits symptoms of an illness already evident in the structure of analogy itself: the condition that rightness and wrongness of judgment are determined as inherently revisable standards. Revisability is of course a threshold of error itself. From such binaries, which proclaim their inadequacy by their proliferation of grounds for comparison, the narrator surmises that the only escape is to strategically “ill say the contrary.”This he has done himself, by counterposing the “eye of flesh” with an “other” that, because it is merely “the other,”
Singer.book
94
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 94
Aesthetic Reason
lacks any particularity sufficient to articulate its otherness as binary with respect to the self. By thus privileging error (“ill saying the contrary”) over the tantalizing reconciliations of analogy, he makes the stakes of knowledge conform to the very expectation of change-revisability that analogy otherwise essays to preempt.Analogy hedges assiduously against the “wrong word.” Beckett’s narration, instantiated thus on the threshold of the question “What the wrong word?” suggests the way in which the training aspect of a self-revisable subject is conditioned by the absolute “givenness” of the wrong word. It is keyed to the impossibility of knowing the right word independently of some deliberative, or comparative, procedure.A veritable lexicon of pseudoneologisms serves as the most subtle currency of this “givenness of the wrong word” in Beckett’s prose. Throughout the work, arcane diction such as “dimmen,”“strangury,”“collapsion,”“scrute” abounds. By their juxtaposition with perfectly colloquial idioms, these words present the erroneous appearance of neologism. They are the wrong words in more ways than one. But in this capacity they recapitulate the very temporal confusion of prospective pathos; they recapitulate the reversibility and revisability that we saw evoked in the instances of pronominal instability, in the competing analogical registers that obtrude through parsimonious syntax, and finally in the difference between the two eyes: between what can be seen (eye) and what can be said (I). Contrary to these manifestly inadequate resources of knowledge, what Beckett’s narrator strives for in the desire to bear scrupulous witness to the old woman’s predicament is a lucidity that surpasses difference. Differences after all breed the confusions of trying to avoid confusion: the topos of analogy per se. By confusing “things and their imaginings,” analogy thereby invites a potentially exhausting deliberative vigilance in its concession to shifting contextual horizons. Above all, Beckett’s narrator sues for release from the self-discipline of such deliberations. It is a goal that he would pursue even at the price of irreality:“If only she [the old woman] could be pure figment. Unalloyed. This old so dying woman. So dead. . . . How simple all then. If only all could be pure figment” (Ill Seen, Ill Said, 20). The reader attuned to the varieties of Beckettian skepticism already anatomized here, and thus wary of the ambition to simplify the tasks of knowledge by neuturalizing error, will know that the “figment,” purified of the imperative to compare, dangerously oversimplifies things. Such oversimplification removes the warrant for deliberation itself: it will become clear that the cost of eluding error is the loss of an expres-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 95
Acting in the Space of Appearance
95
sivity, which the narrator’s text everywhere unwitting supplies. Here Beckett’s sense of tragedy resonates with a growing suspicion among classicists on the subject: that we have permitted our emphasis on the ends of clarity and insight in tragic drama to blind us, even in an Oedipal manner, to the scope of Greek skepticism about the value of any human knowledge that comes free of the exigencies of error.27 We are no less aware that the category of the aesthetic, coined by Alexander Baumgarten in 1735, specifically transgressed the prevailing philosophical binary of conceptual clarity and sensuous confusion upon which the distinction between art and thought had previously subsisted. Alternatively, Baumgarten posited in the aesthetic a quality of “confused clarity.”28 Baumgarten licensed an expressivity that, in a sense, legitimated error by correlating the imperative for conceptual unity with the distinction-making imperatives operative in complex sensory gestalts.The complexity of the sensory gestalt, under the sign of confused clarity, sustains conceptual unity as an active modality. Conceptual unity obtains as an augmenting of the quantity of distinguishable elements within its grasp, thus challenging the limits of the mind’s powers of distinction/ordination. 29 It is this kind of complexity that Beckett’s prose contrives, even against the rhetorical pull of the narrator’s wish to entertain “pure figment.” We see this strikingly in the way that the risks of error, which incite the narrator’s circumspection and spur his romance with pure figment, are balanced by a desire to keep up with inexorable changes within the field of vision: the woman and the cabin set within its perimeter of white stones. Pure figment could never compass these changes. It is a circumstance that inevitably reprises the menace of error. Consequently the word change (the concept of changeability) becomes the refrain of the narrator’s attentiveness to the world and to the figure of the old woman who marks its horizon.The old woman’s physical movements, mapped within a perimeter deliminated by an ominous stone—tombstone or benign milestone, we never know—adumbrates the pattern of this attentiveness. Here the narrator is challenged to decide whether in the relatively closed circuit of the old woman’s comings and goings (toward and away from the totemic stone) her movements change or simply follow the grid upon which they can be charted:“Changed the stone that draws her when revisited alone. Or she who changes it when side by side. . . . Is it to nature alone it owes its rough-hewn air. Or to some too human hand forced to desist? Michelangelo’s from the regicide’s bust” (Ill Seen, Ill Said, 43; my emphasis).
Singer.book
96
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 96
Aesthetic Reason
Like everything that changes under the focus of the narrator’s errorworrying scrutiny, the question of what is the right perception (echoing “what the wrong word”) here depends on adequating and augmenting the motives for construing these changes one way or another.The threat of error that hovers over this decision in the quoted passage is shrewdly mimicked by the tense change (“changed,” “changes”) that instantiates change as active and passive in the very act of posing the question, Is it active (culture) or passive (nature)? The activity of change then assumes a significance greater than the causal stakes that might otherwise prevail in our reckoning with its effects, were we preoccupied with simply knowing the difference between what constitutes a right and a wrong decision, independent of the process of decision-making itself.This deployment of the word change, like a kind of white magic, produces the compensatory, if not altogether salutary, effect of changing the picture of what is to be gained and lost through the vicissitudes of error. For it involves the reader in a process of change: one that would otherwise loom as the brutally impersonal contingency of error. As if to elaborate this perspective several pages later, when we are invited to contemplate how the natural light changes things, the word change is deployed in such a way as to elicit the temporality of physis. And yet it elicits this temporality not in the guise of the proverbial antagonist of nomos—which, as we saw earlier, masks the need for protocols of social recognition—but in the manner of the sculptor’s hand that hews the stone to give it a “Natural air.” In this context the changing light is reciprocated with by the recognitions of the “changeable eye” that is trying to keep up with it.Accordingly, Beckett’s prose enacts the passage of time, the changing light, as a passing across contextual horizons, such that the reader’s passage incurs a duty to recontextualize. Once again, the contingency of the subject with respect to error is assimilated to the agency of its perception.This assimilation is ingeniously cued by the “apparent” structure of a run-on sentence, which obtrudes that much more urgently in the conspicuous absence of a “real” grammatical error.“The eye has changed.And its drivelling scribe. Absence has changed them [“all the ill seen ill said”]. Not enough. Time to go again.Where still more to change”(Ill Seen, Ill Said, 51;my emphasis). The confusion perpetrated by the idiomatic temptation to run-on “Not enough” with the first word of the grammatically distinct construction “Time to go again,” exemplifies Beckett’s way of involving the reader in the process of change as something more than a spectator. Indeed, I believe that this “structural effect” is at work throughout Ill
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 97
Acting in the Space of Appearance
97
Seen, Ill Said, even in those passages that do not deal explicitly with time/change.The error of reading the “correct” idiom,“not enough time” (which negates existential time), reciprocates with the relative error of reading the correct punctuation—“Time to go again,” (which proliferates existential times)—by exposing complementary but incommensurable meanings.The divergent referents of the separate locutions —“Not enough” refers to “changes” that do not yet suffice to mark meaningful distinctions, and “Time to go” references the future tense, where the persistence of change vitiates the hope for distinction altogether—cause us to see how one reflects upon the other without canceling the other in a concession to indeterminacy. For they both yield versions of “Not enough time.” On the one hand, if we privilege grammatical correctness we must admit that in the future, where it is always “time to go,” there is, in effect,“not enough [time].”This is a knowledge that might impel us to suspend the grammatical in favor of the idiomatic rules by which we construe meaning here. On the other hand, if we resort to idiomatic correctness, conceding that there is “not enough time” we possess a motive, if only out of the desperate lack of meaningful alternatives,“to go again.”This returns us to the force of grammatical rule. Thus, the two registers of meaning “run on” in this passage make the site of error a dramatic threshold of deliberation.As such it proffers the kind of usefulness, as a vehicle of training for reciprocal recognition, that I anticipated earlier.This was my reason for making Beckett the exemplar of claims about the ethical bearing of the aesthetic in the first place. Since the appearance of the run-on invokes competing criteria of choice for making contextual sense, it poses a plurality of stances that might be taken toward the predicament of there being “not enough time.”And since this predicament, tantamount to changeability itself, is what makes error inescapable, it returns us to the arena within which the choice of which rule to follow is the de facto solicitation of a reflective judgment. This, I have suggested, is comparable to the solicitation of consensus. If nothing else, I have argued, change and changeability make us—at least procedurally—other to ourselves and, in that way, solicitous of reconciliation with ourselves. By miming this problematic, the construable run-on syntax in this passage also lends substance to the “invisible interlocutor.” His presence, we have already noted, lurks problematically in the narrator’s cautionary admonitions, conjuring error as a paralyzing indeterminacy elsewhere in Beckett’s text. Quite to the contrary, in this passage and others where parsimonious syntactical elisions purvey a multiplicity of combinatory possibilities, determination and decision
Singer.book
98
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 98
Aesthetic Reason
making are de rigueur. And this is decidedly preferable to the relative rigor mortis that might otherwise pass for an acceptably postmodern indeterminacy of meaning in such contexts. It was with this understanding, I alleged earlier, that the “invisibility” of Beckett’s interlocutor confers upon the reader of Ill Seen, Ill Said the imperative to muster new criteria of choice retrospectively as a consequence of error. We can perhaps see this imperative take shape most clearly in the concluding section of Ill Seen, Ill Said.This episode invokes “decision” as a thematic corollary to the problem of closing a narrative that has struggled with the menace of error in large part because error thwarts the aim of closure. Of course, the decision that is impending at the end of Beckett’s narrative has been looming all along in the narrator’s unceasing flirtation with error. One must decide, after all, how to come to the end of the worry that one has not got it right. How does one take the decision to desist from the activity of knowing so that one can rest in the confidence of error-free knowledge? Beckett’s answers are surprisingly compelling. Having exhaustively tracked the old woman’s elusive presence,“all ill seen,” Beckett’s narrator at last abandons her with the abortively absolutizing proclamation “Absence [is a] supreme good and yet” (Ill Seen, Ill Said, 58). Here the juxtaposition of a run-on construction with an instance of syntactical parsimony exhibits their rhetorical complementarity as vehicles for exercising what Aristotle might call a “deliberative virtue,” locatable somewhere on the akrasia-enkrateia continuum.30 For absence might indeed serve as a “supreme good” but only in the stoic repose of a finite perspective.This is precisely the perspective that is here annexed to the antithetical contingency of knowing that there is something more (“and yet”) to be said about it, however ill said it may turn out to be. What else remains to be said becomes apparent if we observe how the absence of the verb in “Absence supreme good . . .” robs the statement of its declarative power in much the way that the uncompleted run-on “. . . and yet . . .” invites a continuation of the very line of thought it otherwise (by way of punctuation) seems to finalize. The “illness” of what remains to be said is even more symptomatic in the next sentence:“Illumination then go again and on return no more trace” (58). Light, the bearer of presences, which the narrator intended to be quit of in the resignation to absence, returns here as something to be abandoned again, in the hopes that one more concession to its presence will guarantee its absence.The resolution of the problem, the move toward error-free closure, seems to be the most intractable problem.That this paradoxical notion does not merely give way to an idle
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 99
Acting in the Space of Appearance
99
play of indeterminate forces becomes apparent when, on the final page of the text, the word decision itself is configured as a conscientious reflector for the akratic will that we have just observed to be wavering between stoic absence and fully “illuminated” presence.“Decision no sooner reached or rather long after than what is the wrong word? For the last time at last for to end yet again what the wrong word? Than revoked” (59). While it is counter to akrasia,“decision” here is not a stand-in for perfect enkrateia. It is not a will to act according to uncompromising or single-minded intentions, which we have seen can often have the paradoxical effect of decontextualizing and hence derealizing its agency. On the contrary, the syntactical interruptus of the decision “no sooner reached . . . than revoked” puts an emphasis upon the process of reaching a decision that threatens to preempt the content of the decision itself.This, I will argue, is its saving grace. For the decision to end here gives way to a deliberation upon the motives for ending, making the point that the full intelligibility of motivated agency depends upon the knowledge of motivation constituted as choices between other motives. The syntactical consummation of “decision” in the word “revoked,” which might otherwise have terminated the agency of the decision maker, is both identified as “the wrong word” correctly, and rendered operative as a word that does intellectual work other than what was intended as correct. In other words, the wrong word is, error notwithstanding, a word that speaks to other words.The fact that the idiom “No sooner reached . . . than revoked” is belated with respect to its own declarative purposiveness—by virtue of the intervening and parodistically time-mongering phrasing “For the last time at last for to end yet again”—vitiates the power of the verb revoke to revoke time. Is not time the very source of error itself? The narrator’s idiom here decisively puts under suspicion the expectation that decision can be an end in itself. Instead we must countenance the epistemological burden of accepting that every end is a beginning, albeit the beginning of a contextual reorientation that doesn’t seek to escape contextualizing imperatives. Literally, what has not been revoked in this passage is revealed in successive qualifying accounts, to have been “dispelled . . . a little very little like the wisps of day when the curtain closes. Of itself by slow millimeters or drawn by a phantom hand. Farewell to farewell” (59). What is “dispelled,” in lieu of “revoked,” spells out a range of new topoi from which to orient expectations of meaningfulness. The spectacle of incontinent narration we witness, where the rhetor-
Singer.book
9/12/03
100
11:21 AM
Page 100
Aesthetic Reason
ical qualifications imposed upon declarative sentences consistently act against the best intentions of the narrator’s will to eschew error, brings us back to the topos of akrasia. But we return with a more sanguine picture of how such frustrations have their own rewards.“To end yet again” which the narrator essays to do in virtually all of the last sentences of Ill Seen, Ill Said, reveals what unexpected resources have been born of failure.This phrase is in effect our “farewell to farewell.” For it is the narrator’s awakening to the necessity of spelling things out by producing a prospective standard of accountability to his own intentions. Like the akratic subject in his inescapable deference to the prospective knowledge that comes of reckoning with the unintended consequences of action, Beckett’s narrator jettisons the error-haunted ego of his own intentionality. He does so most conclusively in the seemingly unintended—at least unanticipated—consequence of the final declarative sentence of Ill Seen, Ill Said: “Know happiness.” I believe we can make the best sense of this utterly surprising last sentence by following the dialogical impetus of error-threatening confusion so pervasive elsewhere in the devices of Beckett’s prose. If we do so, we must read this final declaration as an irrepressible pun. After all, up to this point in the text, the narrator’s most imaginable “happiness” has always taken a negative trajectory in the aspiration towards a stoic “absence.”The emotional fullness conjured as the consummation of physical absence in this last sentence—and anticipated as it is by the complacent aestheticism of the phrase that invokes it,“Grace to breathe that void” (59)—invites us to doubt the seriousness of the testimonial itself. Indeed, if the knowledge of happiness toward which the narrator has been striving is thwarted by the ungovernable changes (proliferating differences) that make up the field of play for his cognitive attention, then “no happiness” is both the logically inescapable conclusion of this narrative enterprise and, even more pointedly, its own prompt to “know happiness” otherwise. Or, we might say, the happiness, pursued in the name of absence, the abortive “decision” to abort presence, was perhaps the wrong kind of happiness for this narrator to court, epiphenomenal as it is of the “wrong word.”We might then count the recognition of this error as the reader’s own coming into play as a counterpart of the invisible interlocutor.After all, the presence of the invisible interlocutor has dogged the narrator’s watchful admonitions to “be careful,” to be “quick,” to “move on.” In effect, these admonitions anticipate a meaning that obtains only as an unintended consequence of the error about to be perpetrated in the knowledge hazarded at any given moment of the narrative.This is where decision gives way to deliberation.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 101
Acting in the Space of Appearance
101
That is to say, the abortive “decision” that precipitated this final “episode” of Beckett’s narrative might be read as a version of “no happiness” but with the understanding that only “no happiness” could sustain our human striving after pleasure as a mode of knowledge. Only in this way does “decision” remain in play. Only in this way does “decision” yield a prospective view of the contingencies that define it, rather than preempting those contingencies in the retrospect of knowing what happiness was meant to be. In short,“know happiness” is the wrong kind of happiness because, in its presumption to immediacy, such happiness is unsituated.The simple declarative “Know happiness” sacrifices the status of happiness as an object of knowledge and hence as a vital register of experience. We can usefully recall that the Greek eudaimonia was stipulated to be “no happiness” as long as the happiness it looked for was imagined as a state of being independent of the temporality out of which it was cognized. If, in our reading of Beckett’s Ill Seen, Ill Said, “Know happiness” also is “No happiness,” then the pleasure of reading Beckett’s text at this juncture is rendered coherent with the human project of knowing as acting. Upon this knowing Aristotle’s most noble pleasure, the pleasure of ethical life, depends. Furthermore,Aristotle is careful to insist that the continence of ethical character, that is, the best reasons summoned to action, are always invoked within a highly specific context of time, place, and manner (Ethics, 7.1151a32–b4). In Beckett’s prose the decision-making protocol orchestrated on the threshold of error—the baffles of parsimonious syntax, the directional miscues of run-on constructions, the multiregistered referentiality of puns—all impose a similar constraint of knowledge: the limits of intelligibility are made apparent only where the reader’s situation entails a deliberative protocol equal to, or reciprocal with, the complexity of choices for contextual construal that are dramatized by the narrator’s horror of error. We need to remember that “happiness”—as much the lure of beauty theory as it is the lure of Beckett’s narrator—has historically inhibited aesthetics by seeming to make pleasure an end in itself.We might now imagine that by replacing happiness with a discipline of increasingly conscientious dispositions toward happiness, as Beckett does in Ill Seen, Ill Said, we aspire to reinvent aesthetic purpose.We circumscribe it within the field of deliberative action that it otherwise seems bent upon transcending. Finally, it is worth noting how the late twentiethcentury complaint that aesthetics is an inducement to erroneous actions, inviting affective infringements upon cognitive responsibilities, echoes Plato’s complaint against akrasia.31 In Protagoras, Socrates
Singer.book
9/12/03
102
11:21 AM
Page 102
Aesthetic Reason
insists that one only acts against best reasons out of a failure of cognitive will.And indeed we have seen that Aristotle also identified akrasia with the mind overcome by bodily appetites. Perhaps, by now understanding how the dynamics of akratic judgment make a fit with Beckett’s narrative poetics, we can finally suspend the misconception that artistic motives are exempt from, or discontinuous with, the problematic of human motivation that is inevitably exposed within the horizon of unintended consequences. Our compensation would be the knowledge that what makes human failure such a rich resource for art makes art a serviceable hedge against the kind of self-deluding intentionality that, by ignoring the contingencies of self-recognition, precipitates ever more tragic reckonings with the world. In the following chapter I will contemplate more fully the question, What strange beauty can error bestow on art? We shall see that if nothing else, it would instantiate a value that cannot be equated with the ideal of aesthetic perfection that both error and failure necessarily belie. It would consequently serve to further demystify the auratic function of art by implicating its practices more inextricably in the temporality that aesthetic truth struggles to defy.The truth of beauty will give way to the contextualization of the judging subject.The beauty of art will inhere as an actualization of knowledge that does not mitigate the density of act.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 103
4
Beautiful Errors: Aesthetics and the Art of Contextualization What strikes me is the fact that in our society art has become something which is related only to objects and not to individuals, or to life. —Foucault, Foucault Reader Error about life necessary for life. —Nietzsche, Human, All Too Human
I Particularly in the idealist guise of the beautiful, perfectionism remains a hallmark of aesthetic value and aesthetic judgment. But as long as aesthetic perfection remains a prime rationale of art production and appreciation, interpretive languages will inevitably founder on this contradiction: the claimants of artistic knowledge must bracket the very criteria of rationality that otherwise offer to make art and knowledge commensurable.The standards of artistic perfection canonized in the eighteenth century by Nicolas Boileau, Lord Shaftesbury, and Kant— and particularly in the paradigmatic modalities of genius and sublimity—have consistently put aesthetic production at odds with the pragmatics of rational assessment.1 They have systematically elided the rules of production with the product qua intuited object. In fact, the identification of the aesthetic with the ideal of perfection is already an impediment to thinking the aesthetic as an aspect of processural reality, by its axiomatic presumption that the aesthetic object embodies a timeless unity: the aura of timeless beauty is the indefatigable nemesis of aesthetic making. Process is, after all, a sine qua non of the protocols of rational deliberation. And it is rational deliberation that perfectionist aesthetic theory has most vociferously eschewed by repressing the problematic of error.This has been the hallmark of the aesthetic’s ongoing defensive maneuvers against the Platonist disenfranchisement of
Singer.book
9/12/03
104
11:21 AM
Page 104
Aesthetic Reason
art.The repression of error has served as the fulcrum of aesthetic autonomy whenever autonomy has been the standard of aesthetic perfection, and for good reason, since, as we’ve already noted, error exposes art to the hazards of time.The contradictoriness of this logic of course deepens in the conclusion that what preserves the authority of art atrophies its connection to life.2 If paradox can remedy contradiction, however, my purpose in this chapter is to advance the idea that error, both the logical and affective nemesis of perfection, may grant us efficient leverage to reinstate the rationality of the artwork as the fulcrum of its expressive powers rather than as the inevitable antagonist of artistic will.Thus it might serve to scuttle the Romanticism that too simplistically equates artistic will with irrationality or the unconscious.The paradox I take on here of course intensifies in our awareness that error is typically the standard by which rationalists have invidiously judged the aesthetic, in relation to more parsimonious empirical accounts of human experience. Similarly, error has been the touchstone of political critiques that would discount the aesthetic as a hopelessly unworldly preoccupation, for which more rationalistic protocols of worldly engagement might be seen as the morally compelling remedies.According to this set of biases, famously articulated in Socrates’ debunking of aesthetic-perceptual intuitionism, the artwork projects a demonstrably erroneous view of the world. 3 Socrates believes it is concomitantly a measure of the perfectibility of the world that rational methods are capable of precisely measuring the artist’s deviation from correlatively calculable truths. Whereas perfection, for Socrates’ caricature aesthete, is typically an anticognitivist surpassing of the infinitely fallible methods of truth (methods of proof), the critics of the aesthetic see perfection as the methodological leverage that truth gains over the affective and ahistorical intuitionism of art.What is more important than the differences between them, however, is that both the aesthetes, and the political/scientific critics of the aesthetic, share a common stake in the standard of perfection. For this intimates their even more fundamental common dependence upon the liability of error. Error, after all, makes perfection originally warrantable as a goal. In this context I want to allege that error might be a salutary link between the aesthetic and rational cognition, one that might suspend the mutual exclusions otherwise predicated between them. I will try to show how the aesthetic puts error into play so that art can thereby do the work of rationality without which its ability to do anything beyond “being” beautiful remains a dubious proposition.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 105
Beautiful Errors
105
My use of the term error references itself most acutely to the relation between a rule and a contingent practice: namely, the situation of its implementation.This relation, quintessentially a threshold of error, is precisely what guarantees the vitality of aesthetic experience. Such a view is famously asserted by the Nietzsche of Human All Too Human, struggling as he was in the late 1870s to disentangle his thinking from the metaphysical enchantments of Birth of Tragedy. Nietzsche’s more empirically interested championing of classicism against romantic individualism in Human, All Too Human stresses the cognitive responsibility (131) that obtains, for the artist, under the constraint of formal rigor.4 Formal rigor, after all, denotes an assessment of representational practice founded on the possibility of discerning a deviation from a rule, a cardinal incidence of error. Nietzsche was notoriously an enemy of perfection and perfectionism because “[w]hen something is perfect we tend to neglect to ask about its evolution” (145). He judged that only under the stresses of a self-imposed fetter, by “dancing in chains” (140), could the artist come to a self-understanding that might evade the two tragic self-deceptions to which artists are otherwise typically prone: purveying the immediate intelligibility of public convention as universal truth, or indulging the masquerade of originality that is predicated on belligerent unintelligibility. Both stratagems are evasions of the calling to account that is presupposed in the cognizance of error. On the contrary, from Nietzsche’s perspective the intelligibility of artistic form obtains only in relation to what it constrains. Or, because constraint entails contingency, we might say that the rationality of the artwork, in relation to a rule, seems to depend on the irrationality of the contingencies that the rule would otherwise constrain. If we follow the genealogical ways of Nietzsche’s own perspectivism, we might, however, view the possibility of error as a phenomenon of contextuality, and not as a mutually exclusive wrong versus right.Then our cognizance of error would become a threshold of negotiation between the wrongs of irrationality and right reason. It would mitigate the morally precarious abstraction of both when they are taken to be mutually exclusive of each other. It is particularly important to stipulate that these negotiations would unfold in narrative order as a learning process. Errors can only come to light within an emergent context of judgment.The emergent context reveals prior conceptions to be inadequate to the intentionality instantiated through their deployment. Errors, after all, are the premier instance of unintended consequences. In this chapter I entertain the possibility that broadening the scope of these negotiations is the significant ethical responsibility and cul-
Singer.book
9/12/03
106
11:21 AM
Page 106
Aesthetic Reason
turally appointed social work of the aesthetic. I choose to see the problem of how to augment the scope of these negotiations, or the skills of contextualization in this regard, as homologous with the challenge of translating apparently incommensurable languages: conflicts of meaning that seem to defy mediation.As I have suggested, the aesthetic has been deeply complicit in the logic of this dilemma because aesthetic perfectionism (particularly in the eighteenth-to-nineteenthcentury rhetorics of genius and the sublime) presupposed the alienation of artistic languages from the discourses of life against which they are often charged to react.This reaction is, in effect, a predisposition to assume the untranslatability of aesthetic knowledge vis-à-vis quotidian existence. As I have alleged in previous chapters, carrying this burden of reaction requires some protocols of reciprocal recognition among human agents, so that reaction does not simply elide with negation.5 Brute negative art—the perennial negation of avantgardism—is, as we shall see in subsequent discussion, too much its own nihilistic nemesis in its effort to purge the ideological corruptions of social life. The relation of art to life posited by aesthetic perfectionists (among whom the activists of the avant-garde must be seen to be the most traditional) casts the aesthetic as the humanistic discourse that most selfservingly promotes the idea of a conflict of languages as the guarantor of its autonomy. Since Claude Henri de Saint-Simon brought the term avant-garde into currency in the 1820s,6 its strong-willed alienation of artistic languages from the practices of bourgeois society remains a threshold of error that cannot be reckoned with except in mutually exclusive counters of experience, at the limit of translatability. The avant-gardism of aesthetic theory, even before there was a theory of an avant-garde, was de facto in the alleged impermeability of artistic languages to the discourses of science, philosophical truth, empirical history. As early as Sir Philip Sidney’s “An Apology for Poetry” (1595) the chauvinism of “the erected wit, which maketh us to know what perfection is” sets the pattern.7 Aestheticism is perfectionism in this claim because, by obviating the search for a rule that would commensurate differences, it indulges a belief in the artwork’s independence from any external criterion of adequation.Worse yet, it nullifies the deliberative process that the task of adequation otherwise occasions.After all, this process constitutes an arena for social exchange within which the very freedom touted by avant-gardists can thrive.The twentieth-century aesthetic “movements” of surrealism and Dada present conspicuous examples of this self-alienating project. But as the earlier example of Sidney
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 107
Beautiful Errors
107
intimates, it is a transhistorical phenomenon. It is operative in the eighteenth-century neoclassical decorums of “general nature,” in the inward trajectories of nineteenth-century Romanticism, and in the runaway ironies of postmodern kitsch. I will take issue with the most reductive versions of this tradition in order to plausibly distinguish cognitive aesthetics from noncognitive aestheticism, but without altogether blurring the line between aesthetics and other discourses of cognitive knowledge. I would therefore suggest that if the aesthetic entails a problem of translation between seemingly discrepant languages, the stakes of translatability are not simply error understood as a divergence from a system of truth such as syntactical or semantic rule, but error understood as a site of potential, though remediable, self-deception.The continuity of the self through the vicissitudes of error will be an important crux of my distinction here. After all, the endurance of the self as a site of contested identity mandates some protocol of reconciliation between the discrepant languages (circumstances) of self-identification. By this means, identity can be generalized beyond the particular moment of its epistemological crisis without transcending the conditions of particularity altogether in the manner of deontological universals. Thus deliberation may be contemplated as the necessary corollary of translatability. More to the point, translatability rather than untranslatability will prove a stronger motive for entertaining the conflict of languages as an edifying basis of the aesthetic. It facilitates the communicability of the artwork along with the community-building resources ascribed to the aesthetic by aesthetic perfectionists.This is the case even if avantgardists, under the banners of surrealism or Dada, would essay to improve society by destroying it. I would point out, by contrast, how all such incommensurable language versions of the aesthetic (from Longinus to Kant) eschew or inhibit deliberation in their stand against translatability. In effect they obviate the possibility of the mutual recognition of human agents, without which the moral imperatives touted by perfectionist epistemologies of classical aesthetics must remain stubbornly heuristic. We have seen that classical aesthetics, in its Neoplatonist perfectionism, always sought a more universalist end.This was, ironically, why it was attacked by late eighteenth-century methodological partisans of the Enlightenment.They sought to discredit any upstart universalism that would refuse to submit to rational tests. Unduly loose tests of aesthetic value such as Shaftesbury’s “Je ne sais quoi” and Lord Kames’s “amor patria” invited the harsh disciplines of Christian Wolff and Adam
Singer.book
9/12/03
108
11:21 AM
Page 108
Aesthetic Reason
Smith that followed in their wake. 8 A constructive irony of my own argument will come into play when I demonstrate how a recouping of the rationalistically deliberative resources of the aesthetic might rescue the rationalist Enlightenment subject from its current ill favor. It has fallen into disrepute for the very instrumentalism (inspired by the likes of Wolff and Smith) that it originally wielded against the aesthetic. Not accidentally, the most commonplace critique of the Enlightenment —stigmatizing it as the dogma of modernity—took root in the late nineteenth century, just at the moment when the aesthetic began its return to cultural prominence. And many of the most vehement late twentieth-century critics of Enlightenment, Foucault, Gilles Deleuze, and JeanFrançois Lyotard, are epistemologically earnest partisans of the aesthetic in their efforts to check the rampant instrumentalism of late capitalist technoscientific reason. Later in this chapter I will try to disclose the odd complicity of these boosters of the aesthetic with the very weaknesses of aesthetic theory that originally made it vulnerable to Enlightenment reason. For the moment, however, my concern for the aesthetic will prove to be indistinguishable from the late twentieth-century preoccupation with the fate of the Enlightenment. It is premised upon the belief that the fates of the aesthetic and the Enlightenment are tied in error’s persistence as a constraint of subject formation.The success of my argument must hang on my ability to demonstrate that these fates are tied in such a way that an anatomy of the entanglement will be more fruitful than any attempt to sever the bond.
II Viewed in very general terms, the aesthetic has been in productive tension with error for many of the same reasons that the ego of modernity took up the cause of Enlightenment. Enlightenment thinkers took on the calamity of error in the guise of that long history of unintended consequences that we countenance as the failure of traditional culture.9 Concomitantly, we understand that error is conflict. Conflict is the nemesis of a social world bereft of universals and their attendant certitudes—beliefs that can sustain the disappointments of human experience by transcending the temporal ravages against human intentionality. Of course, the Enlightenment, best epitomized in this respect by Hobbes, is in many ways intended to serve as a hedge against conflict, if only to cower in conflict’s shadow. But it is important to remem-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 109
Beautiful Errors
109
ber that the late twentieth-century critique of Enlightenment—for example, Foucault’s critique of Kant—reacts against the ineluctable instrumentalism of reason on the basis of a new willingness to accept conflict.10 I believe that the willingness to see the aesthetic as a site for negotiating conflict, rather than as a refuge from conflict, is key to the project of establishing the relevance of art and the efficacy of the discourses of art under the political and economic regimes of postEnlightenment, late capitalist culture. For it is under these regimes that the problem of a context-specific self-realization of the human subject—which was stymied by the rigidity of Enlightenment precepts— has acquired a fresh urgency.The failure of Enlightenment devices to potentiate human self-realization gives us the best motive for seeking resources beyond the usual disciplinary boundaries—political science, philosophy, law, economics—all endowed with social prestige by the prescriptions of Enlightenment wisdom. For my purposes, it will be essential to accept the proposition that aesthetics takes us beyond the usual disciplinary boundaries. Recognition of that fact alters the boundaries of the aesthetic. As I implied, by my earlier insistence that the aesthetic needs to be understood in relation to error, the conflicts that undergird that relation must in turn be seen specifically as sites of cognitive tension: the cognitive tension arises from the fact that the artwork, by dint of its formal originality, brings a theory of the world into contact with a state of affairs that has yet to be accounted for. The intelligibility we can impute in the mere formality (what Kant would call the “finality of form”) of the artwork—to the degree that the form is innovative—solicits its own revision.Although I have been calling this fault line between knowing and not knowing error—and declaring it to be the threshold of our engagement with the artwork—recent philosophical speculation on the possibilities of scientific explanation offers an instructive analogue to this phenomenon that brings error, and implicitly aesthetic production, into more constructive attunement with contingency. “Anomaly theory” holds out a prospect for thinking through error as a modus operandi of human purposiveness. As formulated by Willard Humphreys, anomaly theory contends that scientific explanation (and hence rationalistic judgment) ought to be treated not as a programmatic chain of reasoning, in the modes of deductive-nomological truth telling, but as a rationalistic imperative wherein an anomalous state of affairs is at stake.11 Artistic form, in the defamiliarizing aspect that has most often been touted by aesthetic theory as the hallmark of its identity, plausibly evokes an “anomalous state of affairs.” It accordingly solicits
Singer.book
9/12/03
110
11:21 AM
Page 110
Aesthetic Reason
a normativizing language that is most practically conceivable as a transformation of norms. What is crucially at issue in anomaly is the possibility of knowing error as a lever for some self-revising scruple. Cognitive tension, after all, presupposes a warrant for establishing better terms of fit between principles of self-understanding and the always “anomalous” circumstances within which the applicability of those principles is mandated. Furthermore, and inasmuch as cognitive tension denotes a locus of human intentionality, it serves as a guarantor of moral self-transformation, the bringing of the self into accord with others or other perspectives.What is implied here, however, is that the transformation of the self, inexorable in the incidence of anomalous circumstance, requires a protocol of translatability if we are to “read” correctly the otherwise obscure message of unanticipated or unintended consequences that accrues to the self-transforming actions of intentional subjects. Epistemologically this is an old problem. It is the vehicle of most dualistic-transcendental propositions, inclined as they are to posit a transfigurational springboard for the project of human self-realization. Here, however, I am proposing that, in the context of our desire to understand the work of art as a determinate practice, we ought to take the paradigm of translatability quite literally as an already built-in feature of the contextuality of the artwork itself. In literary art, contextuality is the most literal register of experience. Composition is ineluctably contextualization, in its assimilation of particularities under the constraint of its own temporal contingency.To treat the aesthetic epistemologically as an “art of contextualization” would thus be to implicate it in the project of self-realization, structurally as well as thematically. We are only too comfortable with the popular thematic account of this involvement. It is part and parcel of the traditional cultural enthusiasm for treating artistic unity as a key to the typologies of human self-realization—allegorically embodied, as it is, in canonical artistic forms. Inasmuch as canonical forms are coterminous with the egotistical rewards of received knowledge, this proposition has served the universalizing purposes of aesthetic perfectionism first underwritten by Platonist aesthetics.To treat the artwork as structurally, rather than just thematically, integral to the project of self-realization, would prove to be more controversial, because it portends countenancing art (substantially rather than metaphorically) as new knowledge. It puts art potentially at odds with any abiding universalist rationales, unsettling the protocols of intelligibility that legitimate those rationales. At the very least, this shift of emphasis would constrain us to understand
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 111
Beautiful Errors
111
as a distinctly nontranscendental enterprise the process of universalization conventionally reverenced in the work of art.12 Anomaly theory, because it entails a logic of contingency, is already focused on the idea that universalization must submit to the very openendedness that would threaten to nullify its epistemological warrant: as a necessary corrective for the manifest error of taking particularity at face value. Perhaps the desire to finesse this recognition—that universalization must submit to temporality—explains why so many contemporary aesthetic theories, especially those that profess political consequence, seek to reassert the universalist claims of classical aesthetics in the guise of a contextual relativism.Theorists such as Walter Benjamin, Jameson, and Lyotard prevail upon the category of the artwork in order to imagine the means of social transformation or political change. But, for them, the universalism of the artwork—often articulated in Kantian parlance as a sensus communis—is tied to a subjectless mobility. Such mobility is conferred by the artwork on subjects who would otherwise be self-deceiving victims of egotistical drives. It ought to be apparent already that this subjectless grounding of the aesthetic, whereby the incommensurability of discursive positions serves as a refuge from intersubjective conflicts (inducements to abuses of power and unjust domination), is just another version of the untranslatability argument within which more conventional aesthetic theories insulate their moralizing pretensions. It is a nod to making the process of universalization open-ended without having to take into account the situational particulars or the contextual markers that are so relativized, and without taking on the burden of justifying the situation within which universalizability could be posited. As I have anticipated, what is sacrificed in this gambit are the deliberative rigors whereby contextual boundaries are determined as reasoned choices among competing possibilities. Only in that way would they be rationalized under the threat of error that menaces any honestly conflicted perspective. I want to insist, on the contrary, that such conflict ought not to be, and cannot be, so easily avoided, as my willingness to accept the implications of anomaly theory should have made quite clear.What is more, the evasion of conflict perpetrated, however unwittingly, by such representative poststructuralist figures as Foucault and Lyotard is effectively a trivialization of error, making it into little more than a reprise of the caricature aesthete’s ever more self-romanticizing quest after a truth that passeth understanding. Not surprisingly, within these neoRomantic schemes, the disposition toward contextual relativism depends on prejudicially conflating reason with instrumental, dogmatic thinking.
Singer.book
9/12/03
112
11:21 AM
Page 112
Aesthetic Reason
In this way reason becomes the scapegoat antagonist without which any such aesthetic quest cannot proceed to the sanctifying pedestal of pure art.The conflict between reason and the aesthetic becomes the motive for the aesthetic evasion of conflict. In order to demonstrate that countenancing conflict is no impediment to theorizing the aesthetic, and thereby to displace the manifestly unproductive historical polarization of the aesthetic and the rational along the lines just sketched out, I will take a two-pronged approach. First, I propose to examine two representative contextual-relativist defenses of the aesthetic that are, at least implicitly, predicated on a principle of untranslatability: Althusser and Jameson.Then I will counter with a look at a contextualist defense of rational choice-making that is predicated on a principle of translatability: Alasdair MacIntyre.This latter is very clearly intended to augment the deliberative repertoire of rational agents. I have been arguing that deliberative repertoire ought to be seen as the real stakes of aesthetic practice. Because this rationalist-contextualist argument originates in the nonartistic discourse of act-based moral psychology or practical ethics, it will also provide an occasion for showing how aesthetics proves its relevance to worldly action through its methodological affinity with practices that are emphatically uninterested in art. Here at last is a disinterestedness that, pace Kant, can justify a practical interest in art.
III I have already linked the names Benjamin, Jameson, and Lyotard by their common investment in a subjective mobility that, because it borders on subjectlessness, is tantamount to a principle of untranslatability. For each of these aesthetic theorists, the incommensurability of subject positions (the register of untranslatability per se) curiously endows the aesthetic with a unique political efficacy. Before I address the cogency of such claims, however, I must now add the name of Althusser to the list. I do so because, for my purposes, the Althusserian aesthetic best indicates the mistake of making untranslatability a premise of the aesthetic, particularly in the interests of transcending the self-limiting devices of nonaesthetic discourses: the self-deceiving traps of ideology. Further, Althusser is a theorist of ideology before he is an aesthetic theorist, and because he addresses the aesthetic most directly as a political lever for mobilizing subjectivity against ideological self-deceptions, he might serve as the best prism through which to refract the critique to which, I believe, each of the other political aesthetics is susceptible.13
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 113
Beautiful Errors
113
We need only consider Althusser’s controversial yoking of aesthetic lucidity to scientific knowledge. As a result, the “knowledge effect” of aesthetics is deemed to be dependent on its disqualification as a site of articulable knowledge. In his well-known “A Letter on Art,”Althusser is unambiguous:“Art (I mean authentic art, not works of an average or mediocre level) does not give us a knowledge in the strict sense, it therefore does not replace knowledge (in the modern sense: scientific knowledge), but what it gives us does maintain a certain specific relationship with knowledge.”14 That “certain specific relationship” is a crux of uncertainty with respect to how one would know the knowledge of art from the relation to knowledge that art is supposed to occasion, not to mention how one would know the difference between “authentic” art and “mediocre art.”The morass of value here is a failure of judgment power, or rather an evasion of the responsibility to translate or grant the mutual translatability of feeling and cognition. In this essay Althusser strongly admonishes his “correspondent,”Andrè Daspre, not to confuse what art gives us with what science gives us (Lenin and Philosophy, 222). Science is a “different domain of reality,” structurally heterogeneous with respect to lived experience and to the locus of individuality that is the boundary of its respective domain. But because by “lived experience”Althusser designates the self-representation of individuals interpellated ideologically, and because he understands this to be the métier of aesthetic practice, his stipulation of the difference between art and science reveals that the object presented by art and the object presented by science are surprisingly one and the same: ideological practice.15 Nevertheless Althusser persists in distinguishing the forms of presentation of this common object, bifurcating our ways of seeing, perceiving, and feeling it aesthetically from the implicitly singular way of knowing it scientifically or conceptually. Latent in this bifurcation is a healthy suspicion of the causality that presupposes conscious intentions to be unproblematically realizable in an illusory world of compatible actions. Because Althusser’s critique of ideology presupposes a gap between intentions and actions (Marx’s maxim—in “The Eighteenth Brumaire”—that men make history but not as they wish to), he must argue that this knowledge can be rendered intelligible according to logical causality only insofar as causes follow effects, or, as Althusser puts it most explicitly, insofar as we come to know conclusions without premises (Lenin and Philosophy, 244).This is precisely the work that Althusser himself charges art to perform. In effect, this is a predication of knowledge on error that is consistent with the reflective energies I want to mobilize, on the threshold of error and in the name of the
Singer.book
9/12/03
114
11:21 AM
Page 114
Aesthetic Reason
aesthetic.This predication guarantees what Althusser calls an “inner distantiation” (222), a reflective distance from the object necessary for critical leverage. Consequently Althusser’s insistence that art must be consigned to the presentation of conclusions without premises—while science renders causes undistorted by subjective biases—leads him to beg the question of the agency of scientific knowledge, in the very act of valorizing its particular knowledge claims. Since the agency of art is mooted by its complicity in ideology,Althusser renders art and science incommunicable with each other, except by virtue of their confused immanence to ideological practice. Correlatively, what I am calling the untranslatability of one register (art/feeling) into the other (science/thought) produces a contextual relativism, where the boundaries of the two contexts of concern cannot be adjudicated or deliberated upon except by their mutual exclusiveness. As I’ve noted, this untranslatability is sought by Althusser in order for him to escape the predicament of having to deliberate within the precincts of interpellated subjectivity. But the proscription against translatability comes at the cost of any contextual boundaries within which a deliberative process could occur at all. In the absence of deliberative process, the stakes of ideology critique, let alone art, would seem to be lost. Contextual boundaries, which I’ve already indicated are a sine qua non of a deliberative process, can only be known when one realm of knowledge is meaningfully related to another, not merely relative to another. Clearly my appeal here to a standard of meaningfulness that would hold realms of knowledge accountable to one another is a motive for translatability. By invoking some standard of translatability, we might bring art to consciousness, so to speak.This allows us to draw a contrast with the impenetrable unconsciousness mandated in Althusser’s characterization of the aesthetic as the presentation of conclusions without premises.That translatability is not in the interest of Althusser’s aesthetic theory is clear from his chosen exemplars of the aesthetic, Honoré de Balzac and Alexander Solzhenitsyn, both of whom he says are capable of revealing the ideology of their respective historical moments only unwittingly:“They make us ‘perceive’ (but not know) in some sense from the inside, by an internal distance, the very ideology in which they are held” (Lenin and Philosophy, 223). Precisely because they are in the grip of what they do not know, their revelatory prowess is haplessly “symptomatic.” I deliberately employ the term symptomatic, which functions elsewhere in Althusser’s work as an ascription of phantom agency to the unconscious “knowledge” har-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 115
Beautiful Errors
115
bored within the contradictions that prey upon subjective consciousness. But once again, the absence of a protocol for translating the register of unconsciousness into consciousness (for sorting out the attendant contradiction between intentions and actions) seems to mitigate the political efficacy promised as a dividend of maintaining the distinction between them. Curiously enough, Althusser points out that the malignant “beauty” of ideology is precisely that it works all by itself. Subjects “work by themselves” (Lenin and Philosophy, 181) without the promptings from a consciously instantiated agency.This is true in the sense that subjective (small s) practices arise from the epistemological flattery incurred by the subject’s slavish mirror relation to the big S of interpellating ideology. So how could Althusser not see that, in a perverse way, the mirror structure of identity he articulates in his theory of ideology is itself a mirror of the agentless subjectivity he ascribes to the aesthetic? In this light,Althusser’s definition of aesthetic could be criticized as aestheticizing aesthetics, with the understanding that the difference between aestheticism and aesthetics, like the difference between conscious and unconscious mind, is, above all, the difference that deliberative consciousness makes. In other words, what it is in ideology that prompts Althusser to theorize aesthetics is oddly replicated in his aesthetic theory: an imagistic, deceptively empirical appearance that is cut off from the possibility of self-understanding except by a nondiscursive intuition. Lacking a deliberative protocol, Althusser is forced to treat the aesthetic as a mode of presentation that is ironically exempt from the judgment of error. The judgment of error would otherwise allow some discursive continuity between presentation and the representational frames within which its valuation is originally possible. In Fredric Jameson’s furtherance of a neo-Marxist aesthetic, he follows Althusser by privileging a formal incommensurability between aesthetic modes of presentation and available means of knowledge. I take Fables of Aggression:Wyndham Lewis, the Modernist as Fascist, as my reference point here because Jameson claims that he finds in Lewis a better example (than Balzac or Solzhenitsyn) of Althusser’s sense of how art “uses and transcends its ideological raw materials” (Jameson, Fables of Aggression, 21). He also purports to muster the evidence for this claim from a meticulous anatomy of Lewis’s style, as if to correct what I am alleging is the Althusserian error of decontextualizing style from the forms of knowledge it makes available. 16 But because Jameson ends up characterizing the effect of Lewis’s style too simply as a dereification of commodified forms of life, he ends up
Singer.book
9/12/03
116
11:21 AM
Page 116
Aesthetic Reason
reprising the Althusserian differentiation of the mode of presentation (which in Lewis boils down to a shift from metaphor to metonymy) from the deliberative framework that presents the variables of the act of presentation. In fact, both Althusser and Jameson seem to subscribe to Marx’s granting of a cognitive dimension to the aesthetic, strictly as an ex post facto agency.17 In the Grundrisse, Marx famously characterizes Greek art as naive about its status as art. It lacks what Althusser would call scientific knowledge of its production, its status as artwork, because its birth in Greek culture is “premature.” It exists before the advent of concepts that can display its status as a made object. So, for example, the “charm” of Greek art apparent in its mode of presentation (qua affective presentation, what we perceive, feel, and so on) is accessible to cognition only as a product of a conceptual language that subsumes it rather than translates it.This is to say that the artwork is denied the status of a language that any translator would need to possess or know, according to articulable rules, in order to engage it. Thus, the agency entailed in aesthetic practice is only virtual with respect to the means of its production. It is immune from the vicissitudes of error that otherwise prey upon it, since we must countenance the rule that authorizes intelligibility here to be mechanically retroactive and nonvolitional. Likewise, according to Jameson’s account,Wyndham Lewis’s formal innovation in the novel might be said to defer to a comparable mode of retroactive intelligibility: “great art distances ideology by the way in which, endowing the latter with figuration and with narrative articulation, the text frees its ideological content to demonstrate its own contradictions” (Jameson, Fables of Aggression, 22–23).These contradictions, because they are revealed retroactively, make the artwork an involuntary diagnostic. Furthermore, since the diagnostic power attributable to the artwork is involuntary, this aesthetic theory inevitably fosters a contextual relativism that inhibits translatability.The “demonstrative” agency in Lewis’s prose, for example, demonstrates only by virtue of its mutual exclusivity with respect to the virtual agency that generated the relevant contradictions.The political efficacy of Lewis’s reinvented sentence, according to Jameson, depends upon the default of what it can make intelligible in its own words.The effect acknowledged here is uncomfortably close to an all-too-gestural baring of devices or a Brechtian alienation effect, the cause of which must be remanded to a more lucid discourse for any satisfactory remediation. It suffers from the conceptual liability that, because the cognition immanent to the artwork is not articulable in the artwork, the aesthetic remains per-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 117
Beautiful Errors
117
versely above cognition and so below the ground of rational suspicion. It comes as no surprise that Jameson’s analysis of the “aesthetic” effect in Lewis’s prose resorts to Deleuze and Felix Guattari’s opposition of the molecular (the here and now of sentence construction) and the molar (the mediate forms by which we seek to recontain the molecular) (Jameson, Fables of Aggression, 7–8) in order to preempt such criticism. The pair of the molecular/molar, an armature of Deleuze and Guattari’s theorizing the “schizophrenic text” in Anti-Oedipus, is candidly appropriated as an “aesthetic” (Fables of Aggression, 7 n. 6) in Jameson’s elucidation of the formal innovations of Lewis’s style: he sees Lewis’s prose as wrought from the contradiction between formal innovation and thematic reaction. Schizophrenia is, of course, the perfect perverse metaphor for alleging intuition of aesthetic value in this context. It renders the reputedly revolutionary and liberational constitutive elements of Lewis’s sentences incommensurable with the fascistic closure of the ideological languages that they otherwise seem to subtend. By accepting their mutual exclusivity (nontranslatability), Jameson and Deleuze and Guattari can keep the diagnostic power of the aesthetic—mined from the contradictoriness that plays between the levels of the molecular and the molar—safe from the traps of any rationally determinate knowledge. For rational determination would, in its turn, succumb to ideological reification. But it is important to observe that Jameson and Deleuze and Guattari procure this therapeutic benefit at a high cost: they indulge an analytical indeterminacy that merely registers the symptoms of ideological interpellation. Unfortunately, those symptoms await some more determinate, and, in Althusser’s therapeutics, some more scientific diagnostic efficacy. Jameson’s further appropriation of the analytical model of “libidinal apparatus” from Jean-François Lyotard’s protoaesthetic manifesto Economie libidinale only adds to the problem. Adopting the therapeutic model of libidinal apparatus in order to locate the agency of ideological critique within the aesthetic/formal devices of Lewis’s narrative, Jameson gives further evidence of an inherent bias against translatability in his characterization of aesthetic discourse. In that way he seems to invite an indeterminacy that would stymie the political purposes meant to be served by it. The term libidinal apparatus isolates “an independent narrative function in psychic life” (Jameson, Fables of Aggression, 8) that would otherwise be decipherable by depth-psychological transcendence to the “private psyche” (11) of the artist or the allegorical domestication
Singer.book
9/12/03
118
11:21 AM
Page 118
Aesthetic Reason
of artistic practice to a collectively endowed social position.According to Lyotard’s account, this “behavior” is understood instead as a “quasimaterial . . . object which can lead a life of its own and has its own inner logic” (10). Its value is a function of processes of appropriation and reappropriation.They work unconsciously in the annals of history and always cast their light retroactively: they figure the incoherence of the libidinal apparatus with respect to the context of value within which it is appropriated. For example, Jameson alleges that the “ugly” sexism purveyed in Lewis’s prose is “so extreme as to be virtually beyond sexism” (20). In other words, we may take aesthetic pleasure in the figuration of impulses that would ordinarily be judged “ideologically offensive” precisely because the question of taste is displaced from the locus of authorial persona (on the level of thematic representation) into a stylistic effect. Style, by concomitantly dissolving the authorial ego (on the level of the sentence), obviates the condemnation of all of the familiar causes of ideological offense. Confusingly enough then,“art can be said to ‘produce’ the ideological as an object for our aesthetic contemplation and our political judgment” (22) by, in effect, mystifying causality. Here is an ominous echo of Althusser’s “conclusions without premises.” It is a decidedly “schizophrenic” symptomatology that would accord with Deleuze and Guattari’s anti-Oedipal diagnosis of self-realization. Lewis the artist displaces Lewis the fascist by making him speak in a language that is ultimately unintelligible (that needs to be translated) with respect to whatever intentionality is otherwise ascribable to that persona: he must “hear blurted out in public speech what even in private was never meant to be more than tacitly understood” (23). Indeed, when it comes to anatomizing Lewis’s aesthetic production per se we see how reductive is Jameson’s admiration for devices such as hypallage (the superpositioning of metaphoric structures upon realistic acts), prose descriptions that depopulate the affective realms of experience, and the even more depersonalizing metonymic dissemination of metaphoric structures.All these devices of Lewis’s prose style are adduced merely to buttress the generalization that “[t]here . . . comes into being a language beyond language” (86). Curiously, the devices of Lewis’s prose praised here are ones that invite recognition of differences as reasons for reframing the terms of recognition. By instancing an excess of the meaning ordinarily denoted in the linguistic structures they presuppose, these devices each invite a recontextualization of knowledge through the matrices of error.The stakes of meaning are an anomalous state of affairs, an evocation of the normativizing logic of
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 119
Beautiful Errors
119
anomaly theory itself. But Jameson’s predilection for treating these aesthetic effects strictly in terms of the overcoming of limits (“a language beyond language”) rather than in terms of the transition between frames of reference—the translatability of one framework of value with respect to another—obviates any rational reckoning with limits. Ironically, it is the Kantian sublime that Jameson most strikingly, if most unhelpfully, evokes in his efforts to equate aesthetic production and political judgment. What Jameson praises in the devices of Lewis’s prose, in the language beyond language, reveals a dynamic of consciousness that is oddly kindred to Kant’s mathematical sublime.The mathematical sublime subsists specifically upon the excess of apprehension vis-à-vis comprehension. In Lewis’s shift from what Jameson in Fables of Aggression calls national allegory (the “semantic and structural givens which are logically prior” [94] to Lewis’s text) to libidinal apparatus, there is an unequivocal emphasis on the pure “psychic effectivity” (95) of discursive forms. But, because this effectivity is peremptorily cut off from the informing intentionality of the devices that produce such effect, the shift from national allegory to libidinal apparatus obviates contextuality, translatability, and deliberation, as aspects of aesthetic intuition. Lewis’s language beyond language is an index for the inadequacy of particularized language (apprehension) to any measure of knowledge that could be fully constituted as systematic language (comprehension), that is,“the impossible plenitude of a primary language that,” Jameson avers,“has never existed” (86). I am under no circumstances alleging that adequation of a secondary language to a primary language is the proper task of the aesthetic. But, as I will demonstrate more elaborately in the following section of this chapter, there might be a less-than-antithetical alternative. If we could contemplate the task of adequation without any presumption of adequacy, we might possess the means to cognize the “beyond” or excess of apprehension, gestured toward in Althusserian/Jamesonian aesthetics, as error rather than as deracinated effectivity. Perhaps then we might redeem it to the protocols of deliberative agency and see the potential within the aesthetic for an ideology critique that does not have to give up on rational pursuits. We would not have to choose between inarticulable knowledge and instrumental reason, between art and science.We would not succumb to the ultimately Romantic proposition that the aesthetic consists, as Althusser attests, in disarticulating the form of the work of art from knowledge, or, as Jameson attests, in the dereification of forms of presentation.
Singer.book
9/12/03
120
11:21 AM
Page 120
Aesthetic Reason
As I already suggested, both positions, insisting upon the incommensurability or untranslatability of realms, unwittingly set up the aesthetic as a refuge from valuation and judgment. They are perversely reminiscent of one of the most orthodox bourgeois aesthetic theories of the late eighteenth century: that found in Karl Philip Moritz’s Schriften zur Ästhetik und Poetik (1785). Moritz posits the nontranslatability of the artwork as its premier virtue: the artwork denotes a perfection that is in essence immune to error because of the inexhaustibility of the interpretation it invites. Here is the seminal articulation of what remains a strong prejudice in favor of sequestering the artwork from the hurly-burly of practical life, on the grounds that it secures a haven of coherent understanding. Coherence here is inextricable from a standard of formal organicity that is, of course, inimical to the political engagements that both Althusser and Jameson believe the aesthetic can inspire.This standard of coherence coheres only too well with the aesthetic perfectionism that I judged earlier to be an impediment to making the aesthetic count as a rational métier for eluding the traps of rational instrumentalism. It is now necessary to look for the cognitive means by which we might clear that obstacle from the path of Althusserian and Jamesonian rationales, thus to see the aesthetic as a more purposive site of political engagements.
IV In order to imagine a way of making those engagements more practicable in relation to theorizing the work of art, I propose accommodating an alternative standard of coherence to the enterprise of aesthetic valuation. I would adopt a coherence model that counts as true that which serves within a specifiable context of tradition to correct errors. In promoting this model of coherence I am drawing upon the work of Alasdair MacIntyre and his analysis of the problem of communication between alien traditions. Most particularly, I want to engage his notions of how contesting traditions of rationality can be reconciled within a theory of translatability. The focus of my attention to MacIntyre’s argument is admittedly narrow. I will confine myself to the last three chapters of Whose Justice? Which Rationality? with the understanding that its value for the present discussion will be strictly proportionate to my interest in bridging the ethical and aesthetic. I will bracket MacIntyre’s wish to defend a reconstruction of Aristotelian ethical practice as a refuge for tradition-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 121
Beautiful Errors
121
based rationality. I admit that the aesthetic is not an apparent object of MacIntyre’s consideration or concern in this enterprise. I would, however, suggest that the aesthetic entails an interpretive predicament analogous to that faced by MacIntyre’s “typical” ethical agent. MacIntyre observes that the self-justifying agent of any rational tradition of knowledge typically treats the stability of that tradition as dependent upon a context-transcending universality.This is always assumed, in turn, to be adequate to the task of resolving contradictions that arise within its horizon. So, as we have seen in the case of the prototype bourgeois aesthete Karl Philip Moritz, the justification of the artwork depends on a context-transcending principle of untranslatability. It precludes the possibility of an internal contradiction that might destabilize the tradition of the artwork’s canonicity. For MacIntyre, however, contexts will inevitably arise within which the implementation of any rational tradition (or world construction that may serve as a rough analogue to the artwork) must succumb to internal contradictions. In other contexts, such contradictions would remain benign or invisible. We must assume that these contradictions accrue to any rational tradition by virtue of its increasingly dogmatic, because increasingly systematizing, perseverance over time. Every tradition, whether it recognizes the fact or not, confronts the possibility that at some future time it will fall into a state of epistemological crisis, recognizable as such by its own standards of rational justification, which have themselves been vindicated up to that time as the best to emerge from the history of that particular tradition.All attempts to deploy the imaginative and inventive resources which the adherents of the tradition can provide may founder, either merely by doing nothing to remedy the condition of sterility and incoherence into which the enquiry has fallen or by also revealing or creating new problems and revealing new flaws and new limitations. (Whose Justice? Which Rationality? 364; my emphasis) MacIntyre goes on to explain that the adherents of such a tradition in crisis may well seek refuge by countenancing, in a new way,“the claims of some particular rival tradition.They would now come . . . to understand the beliefs and way of life of this other alien tradition, and . . . learn . . . the language of the alien tradition as a new and second first language” (364). The relevance of MacIntyre’s discussion here, to an understanding of what kind of knowledge the aesthetic purveys, is perhaps more
Singer.book
9/12/03
122
11:21 AM
Page 122
Aesthetic Reason
sharply apparent if we see that the blindness to self-contradiction, otherwise revealed in the epistemological crisis is, once again, a de facto denial of contextuality. The fact is, failure to recognize the epistemological crisis would produce a self-understanding that is mutually exclusive of an otherwise essential learning process. Here we can see that error is a touchstone of this learning process by its appeal to an articulable standard of judgment that is not yet articulated.The prospect of this state of affairs invites MacIntyre’s speculation that the uncoupling of error (contradiction) from learning would make any endogenous resolution of epistemological crisis impossible. What is worse, it would preclude the remedy of appealing to another, external context of knowledge.The problem is that the nature of error, because it is cognized within the first context of knowledge on the basis of a contexttranscending reason, is effectively incommensurable with any other context of knowledge. For MacIntyre this is a representative instance of the rational impasse of incommensurable languages or the untranslatability of traditions of self-justifying knowledge. It is a predicament that fits with my earlier critique of the communicative boundedness of the artwork when construed within the framework of idealist/perfectionist aesthetics where the meaning of the artwork is only the measure of its autonomy.This is so even if its autonomy is deemed to be, as in the case of Jameson/Lewis, dereifying and disruptive of the political systems we equate with autonomy. MacIntyre treats such a predicament as unacceptable within the purview of rational agency.Alternatively, he argues that the communication between alien traditions or languages, prompted by epistemological crisis, requires a transformation of the identity of the learning subject caught between them: hence it requires a contextuality driven by the recognition that one tradition is necessarily superior to the other.This is the kind of contextuality that I have been suggesting the aesthetic ought to enable/inform if it is to remain coherent with the problematic of error and the cognate epistemological crises of “cognitive tension” and “anomaly.” In this respect MacIntyre speaks to the evasions of conflict that I have disapprovingly identified with perfectionist aesthetics. On the contrary, he insists that conflict between rival traditions is the only arena within which a rational standpoint is achievable. He thus takes a position consistent with my desire to equate the aesthetic with a deliberative protocol, such that the universalist claims on behalf of the artwork are acknowledged to be fundamentally situational. Concomitantly, the universality of the artwork must be seen to be strictly nontranscendental. This would be so along the lines of the
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 123
Beautiful Errors
123
rationalization of anomalous circumstance that I took as a marker for aesthetic knowledge in the second section of this chapter. In MacIntyre’s advocacy of the kind of contextuality I describe above, he sets up a circumstance where the possibility of “passing through epistemological crisis” depends on seeing that one tradition stands in relation to another solely on the basis of its criticizability or susceptibility to the judgment that error is in occurrence. It is therefore inevitable that MacIntyre’s rational subject, whose rationality he stipulates will depend upon a willingness to “confirm or disconfirm over time” (Whose Justice? Which Rationality? 394) the coherence of his or her traditional viewpoint, must acquire a “second language-inuse” (or second first language) in order to confront the epistemological crisis.This acquisition of a second language MacIntyre calls a “work of imagination whereby the individual is able to place him or herself imaginatively within the scheme of belief inhabited by those whose allegiance is to [a] rival tradition” (394).The second language-in-use presupposes that the epistemological crisis itself is fundamentally an acknowledgment that there is a problem in the first language-in-use. It cannot be resolved on that site because the problem is known only in the fact of its inarticulability. Correspondingly, the burden of the second language-in-use is to articulate the inarticulable. It does so not in the paradox-mongering “play” of the poststructuralist sublime (I think of Lyotard here), but in determinative, rational steps. Because they can be volitionally “taken,” such steps portend a deliberative agency that might demystify “epistemological crisis” rather than fetishize it as a metaphysical limit. In fact, MacIntyre stipulates that there are three requirements for the solution to a genuine epistemological crisis, insofar as the goal of a “solution” mandates the invention of new concepts. Because this mandate for new concepts arises from the recognition that coherence will inevitably break down, within the repertoire of all traditional concepts, the first requirement is that internal coherence be restored to the tradition of inquiry. Second, the new coordinates of the systematicity of tradition must produce an explanation of the impediments to coherence that previously stymied systematic inquiry within the coordinates of the old tradition.Third, the first two requirements must be satisfied in a way that exhibits some “fundamental continuity” of the new tradition and the old. Furthermore, our rendering the inarticulable articulable will dictate that what we are calling the second language-in-use is by no means translatable back into the problematic or incoherent first language-in-use.This is the case notwithstanding that the second
Singer.book
9/12/03
124
11:21 AM
Page 124
Aesthetic Reason
language-in-use would have no currency without its precursor. As Jürgen Habermas has usefully pointed out, MacIntyre is clearly trying to reconcile an antirelativist thesis with a contextualist one.18 MacIntyre contests the relativist stance by showing that if we count the inaccessible or inarticulable only as a function of the inadequacy of one set of terms to another, we in effect posit untranslatability as a paradox that is absolutely recalcitrant toward rational intervention. MacIntyre counters with the idea that such a belief in the pure inaccessibility or inarticulability of knowledge would founder on the greater paradox that we must already know what is inaccessible or inarticulable in order to have grounds for believing in it as such.This is to say that inaccessibility or inarticulability is always de facto already translated into an original (first) language-in-use (Whose Justice? Which Rationality? 387). If we take MacIntyre’s point that the condition for positing the inaccessible or inarticulable is “a matter of two stages, in the first of which we acquire a second language-in-use as a second first language, and only in the second of which we can learn that we are unable to translate what we are now able to say in our second first language into our first language,” then the inaccessible or inarticulable succumbs to a kind of translatability.This is the case only on the condition that a transformation or augmentation of the context of meaningfulness obtains. McIntyre’s very willingness to countenance the practical oxymoron of a “second first language,” indicates the extent of his faith in the idea that context entails a volitional practice. It is responsive to the sort of temporal exigencies that I earlier argued must be appreciated as an inescapable formal constraint upon the concept of contextuality. Thus having put relativism in abeyance, MacIntyre’s corollary defense of contextualism proceeds from his assumption that the best reason to accept the warrant for an understanding of translation as augmented context is as follows. It enables speakers who encounter an alien tradition with a different language-in-use to discover that while in some area of greater or lesser importance they cannot comprehend it within the terms of reference set by their own beliefs, their own history, and their own language-in-use, it provides a standpoint from which once they have acquired its language-in-use as a second first language, the limitations, incoherences, and poverty of resources of their own beliefs can be identified, characterized, and explained in a way not possible from within their own tradition. (387–88)
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 125
Beautiful Errors
125
This is the feat of passing through epistemological crisis that I was looking for the aesthetic to accomplish earlier. In this capacity the aesthetic might help us to realize more realistically the counterideological aims of Althusser’s and Jameson’s unduly relativist aesthetic theorizing. In MacIntyre’s account, passing through the crisis is arguably an occasion for intuiting error as a duly cognitive relationship to unexamined assumptions.The intellection of these assumptions follows the paradigm of translation precisely insofar as that paradigm comprehends an enhanced repertoire of interpretive skills. More to the point, because I am not concerned with MacIntyre’s need to stake any adjudication among competing traditions upon a hegemonic truth claim, the relevance of his argument about translatability here is effectively limited: it makes available a deliberative protocol that can take us beyond the bias against translation and deliberation that remains so forceful in even the most reputedly radical traditions of aesthetic theory cited earlier in this chapter. In a statement that strikingly echoes Althusser’s/ Jameson’s aesthetic (but without indulging their problematical predisposition toward decontextualizing conceits of political liberation), MacIntyre speculates upon what we could easily call the “political” effects of his own thinking. He invites a privileging of deliberative protocols even above the stability of the traditions those protocols endow: “Only those whose tradition allows for the possibility of its hegemony being put into question can have rational warrant for asserting such a hegemony. And only those traditions whose adherents recognize the possibility of untranslatability into their own language-in-use are able to reckon adequately with that possibility” (Whose Justice? Which Rationality? 388). I would argue that deliberation, rather than the negation implicit in absolute untranslatability, is already specifically mandated by MacIntyre’s proviso that translation must be understood as a two-stage process. Precisely because the second first language-in-use secures the knowledge of what could not be said in (or is hence not translatable into) the first language-in-use, the respective user of that second first language comes to the threshold of self-knowledge with a rigorously procedural standard of judgment. Because such a self would be intuitively open to the possibility that hegemonic belief could be put into question, the epistemic questions it is capable of asking are likely to be less apocalyptic in their acceptance of the necessity to change those beliefs. In this perspective, error looms neither as an apocalyptic end nor as an all-too-innocent beginning. Rather, we might more constructively say that the translatability
Singer.book
9/12/03
126
11:21 AM
Page 126
Aesthetic Reason
latent in the cognitive tensions that inevitably play between the first language-in-use and the second promotes a practice of translation that is unfettered by a test of adequacy. Moreover, the untranslatability that might seem to be latent in any notion of translation that does not submit to a test of adequacy need not be construed invidiously as a capitulation to inadequacy. Instead, what governs here is not a principle of adequacy at all but a principle of adequation whereby the practices of self-understanding subordinate the claims of selfhood to the learning process. This is by no means a nod to the familiar poststructuralist account of the dissolution of the subject into the depersonalizing stream of ideological discourse. Rather, it is an acknowledgment that the subject is always only a learning subject.Accordingly, the subject is not terminally “subjected” to the interpellations of a crudely deterministic, impersonal will, but to the choices that challenge its internal coherence. The coherence of human subjectivity is thus predicated on an imperative of choice-making that is consistent with expectations of rational assent without giving in to the ideological hegemony of rational will. And, if we follow MacIntyre’s stipulation that “only those whose tradition allows for . . . its hegemony being put into question can have rational warrant for asserting such a hegemony,” the right choices will presumably be a function of choosing to give up the contextual bearings that warrant self-assertion, whenever this assertion succumbs to the inevitability of its own incoherence.This is what time will tell. It brings us back to the reckoning with temporality that I initially alleged perfectionist aesthetic theory would not willingly face up to. By embracing this position we are, in effect, translating the problematic of translation into a mode of transition from one set of contextual coordinates to another. In this notion of translation as transition, the error of incoherence that catalyzes the transition is interestingly coherent with a key term of classical aesthetics: hamartia. This term, often confused with an essentializing character flaw, actually denotes a deliberative (related to phronesis on these grounds) procedure whereby one understands that the immediate context of self-recognition requires supplementation. Specifically, it solicits a context that could not be anticipated, except by a discipline of self-effacement, determined at a volitional distance from the self. Far from being a function of chance or fate, a purely involuntary quality of character, hamartia designates a dimension of the character’s activity, namely, a transition from one context to another. As J. M. Bremer explains in Hamartia: Tragic Error in the Poetics of
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 127
Beautiful Errors
127
Aristotle and in Greek Tragedy, the “ignorance” of the character afflicted by hamartia constitutes an “indirect causality” (21–23) through which the peripeteia of plot occurs. That is, the intelligibility of the character’s error is correlative with the passage of time through which the character arrives at a reversal of fate: a knowledge of self that entails the reconfiguration of contextual markers within which such a self could meaningfully seek recognition. For Bremer, the hamartia of the tragic hero “is his involuntary and inevitable ignorance of one or more of the particular circumstances involved” (Hamartia, 26).And yet the word “involuntary” is potentially misleading. Since the disposition toward error here is explicitly linked to peripeteia as causality, it must be linked to the context of knowledge within which the apparent passivity of the tragic hero is translated, so to speak, into a frame of reference for action.At least this is so insofar as it solicits “one or more” particulars of circumstance that would otherwise constitute a blind spot of personal perspective (26–27). The sense of error associated with hamartia is proleptic, then, anticipating a kind of second first language-in-use: where the impoverishment of resources in the first language is articulated out of a deliberate and strictly voluntary retrospect. In these respects, my characterization of “translation as transition” describes the learning curve of subjectivity that I have been working to map onto the field of the aesthetic in these pages.This learning curve is, in fact, material to Aristotle’s sense of the superiority of tragedy to comedy. He perspicuously distinguished hamartia as preferable to the alternative double-plot structure of comedy where the apportionment of a good fate to a good character and a bad fate to a bad character vitiates the tragic hero’s burden of choice by rendering conflict as divergent paths of action for different agents. This obviates the temporal contingencies that otherwise constrain the individually conflicted subject to transitional agency, without which, after all, learning is not conceivably a dynamic aspect of character.19 If the aesthetic can be contemplated in relation to a learning activity on the model of hamartia, where hamartia mandates that error or incoherence be handled within the framework of a single fate, then the hazards of error are plausibly continuous with the cognitive burdens of contingent personhood.The hazards of error prevail upon us to try to make the transitional modality of choice-making subjects (proharisis) suffice for an account of artistic making and aesthetic valuation. It would be an account that does not redeem contingency to meaning in an idealist stroke of conceptualization—in the manner of anti-aesthetic rationalists. Nor would it be an account that idealizes the irony of con-
Singer.book
9/12/03
128
11:21 AM
Page 128
Aesthetic Reason
tingent experience with which we have so dubiously crowned the fate of tragic heroes, making fate inexorably fatalistic—in the manner of antirationalist aesthetes.To the contrary, and as we have seen, where hamartia ceases to be a finite quality, it ceases to be a term of fatalism. It is inextricable from a potentially open-ended protocol of contextual activity that (open-endedness notwithstanding) subsists on the positing of ends as its threshold of intelligibility. In this perspective, we may impute a more edifying measure of heroism to tragic fate than classical tragedy could purvey: for now it entails knowledge of the making, as well as the unmaking, of human intentions. It thereby holds the one accountable to the other. In this way, contextualization promises to displace the perfectionist test of adequation that, since Plato, has conditioned aesthetic judgment upon a rational value independent of the artist’s form-giving agency.As long as it remains a fulcrum of choice, contextualization might then suffice as a preserve for that “work of the imagination” that MacIntyre counts as the access to rival traditions. I would argue that it is the means by which the artwork can give us access to the laborious enterprise of learning. Under this arrangement, within this ambit of the aesthetic, we could plausibly make the world of tragic errors into a habitation for reasonable practices.
V My best exemplification of the foregoing claims about how error and choice-making articulate new parameters of the aesthetic presumes upon the most enduring threshold of error attributable to the artist. It is Plato’s invidious distinction between seeing and thinking, where visuality is emblematic both of the fallibility of sense experience and the imperative to fetishize error as a counter for binary logic. Indeed, Plato’s idea that seeing and thinking are incommensurables persists in the late twentieth-century willingness to equate the aesthetic with sense-determinate experience, from which the judging mind is all but excluded. As the partisans of the anti-aesthetic unceasingly remind us, our current motives for maintaining the invidious distinction between seeing (aesthesis) and thinking (logos) are deeply entangled with the postmodern critique of Enlightenment reason. Reason, in its manifest instrumentalism is “seen,” so to speak, to have reified our perception of the world precisely in the manner of the arresting gaze. Postmodernist critiques of reason, especially in the guises of Lyotard’s “libidinal apparatus,” Baudrillardian “spectacle,” and more recently Nancy’s “patency” or sen-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 129
Beautiful Errors
129
sible “obviousness,” have paradoxically reverted to the senses, and very particularly to a radical visuality, in order to combat reason’s tyrannizing effect. For example, radical visuality in Nancy’s aesthetic of patency deploys itself as an intransitive “presentation of presentation,” a making manifest of that which requires no explanation. Such a beneficently deracinated sense is intended to dispel the “gaze” of instrumental reason.20 Thus it might hold the ideologically malign abstractions of the Enlightenment in check. It might keep the reifying will of rationality in flux. Plato’s opposition of seeing and thinking is still in place, but with an inverse polarity and an opposite trajectory. That this postmodernist inversion of the Platonist hierarchy of thinking and seeing might be as unproductive as the metaphysic from which it derives should be apparent in its clear perpetuation of the burdens of Platonist dualism.The Republic’s disparagement of art (epitomized by visuality), on behalf of civil freedom, produces a society that cannot “see” its other and thus promulgates a rationalist hegemony. Just so, the postmodern disparagement of reason (epitomized by the deracinated image), on behalf of a counterideological politics, sees only itself and thus promulgates increasingly solipsistic resistance to the social mediations of discursive reason. Hegel, in his capacity as a rather unorthodox aesthetic theorist, is astutely cognizant of the liabilities of the dualism that I have just identified as an impediment to aesthetic experience. In his Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion, where it is specifically the thought of the deity that would be seen, Hegel intimates an alternative to the mutual exclusions of seeing and thinking. He speculates about how the visibility of the invisible might be sustainable as a medium of thought. Because Hegel’s own thoughts about religion famously take him beyond the bounds of art, however, I want to suggest that the richest implication of his thinking about aesthetics might be profitably explored elsewhere: in the visual field projected by Caravaggio’s unorthodox religious painting of the Conversion of Saint Paul. By taking a Hegelian cue in order to read the complex surface of Caravaggio’s spectacular vision of vision, I may propose a way of appreciating an unexpected continuity of seeing and thinking. My view of Caravaggio’s aesthetic practice here is intended to anticipate a broadening of the stakes of my argument in the last chapter of this work.There I will engage the presentational field of postmodern painting as a corollary of the linguistic densities in literary art. By such means we may escape the disabling dualism between classical anti-aesthetic philosophizing and postmodern “body aesthetics” indulged at the expense of purposive mind.
Singer.book
9/12/03
130
11:21 AM
Page 130
Aesthetic Reason
Image not available
Fig. 1 Caravaggio, The Conversion of Saint Paul, 1600–1601.Alinari / Art Resource, New York
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 131
Beautiful Errors
131
Nancy’s recent work The Muses offers a particularly economical way into the proposed argument. I will take up a more complete view of Nancy’s radical revision of Enlightenment aesthetics in Chapter 5. But here I want to concentrate on the nature of his complicity in postmodern Platonism. Nancy powerfully exemplifies the problematic postmodern reprisal of the Platonist dualism that I have already begun to redress through Hegel. Not coincidentally, Nancy does so by reflecting himself on Hegel’s Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion. Nancy both confirms Hegel’s relevance to the problem at hand and indicates, through what he embraces of Hegel, the warrant to go beyond Hegelian thinking. Specifically, Nancy addresses Hegel’s observation that the “birth of art” is coincident with the desire to make the deity sensibly apparent “in his determinate being” (Muses, 48).Where the intuition of the divine being apparently “corresponds to the concept of the deity,” Hegel explains that it is not a sign,“but gives expression at every point that it is produced from within, and corresponds to the thought or inner concept” (Hegel, Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion, 376). The “essential point” for Hegel is, however,“that the determinate being is still a mode of sensible visibility” (Nancy, Muses, 48). For Nancy this idea is important because it features a vital tension between the making aspect of art, its techne, and the spiritual excess of the “concept made apparent,” which he equates with the threshold of sublimity.We might imagine that where techne and sublimity come into contact, seeing and thinking find some ground for reconciliation. But Nancy’s insistence on the incommensurability of techne and sublimity (corollary to the incommensurability of seeing and thinking) devolves disappointingly to the belief that “[a]rt disengages the senses from signification” (Muses, 22). In effect he concedes that the power of sense, of visibility in particular, depends on its functional indeterminacy in relation to what it means to reveal.To be sure, Hegel’s own gloss on “sensible visibility” invites an indeterminate relationship between sensible form and an always yet to be apparent Spirit. In both cases indeterminacy threatens to abstract the sensible visibility in a way that alienates it from any compelling account of human making.21 Such difficulties notwithstanding, I do believe that Hegel’s and Nancy’s shared stake in the site of sensible visibility, as a threshold of techne, suggests a way of thinking about seeing that need not compel an impossibly abstract fusion of the horizons of the particular and the universal. Nancy’s deference to Hegel’s “essential point that the determinate being is still a mode of sensible visibility” intimates that the uni-
Singer.book
9/12/03
132
11:21 AM
Page 132
Aesthetic Reason
versality of the deity—bodied forth in Nature—might induce us to reconfigure the particularity of the moments in which sense experience constrains our bodies to recognize that Nature, qua particularity. Recognition of the deity would therefore seem to entail a self-consciousness of the formative agency that sense implores us to exercise. Indeed, sense particularity would otherwise be our dissolution into mere naturality. It would be the moribund embodiment of the deity in us. For these reasons specifically, I believe that the fullest appreciation of Hegel’s and Nancy’s shared investment in the site of “sensible visibility” demands that we go beyond the limits of their own arguments. Nancy, explicitly, and Hegel, implicitly, see techne and sublimity respectively as counters for the exteriority of aesthetic form and for the unreachable interiority from which it may be presumed to emanate. But, in that way, they invite an endless conversion of one counter of value into its other, what Nancy himself characterizes as the “rhythming” of “the visible with the invisible” (Muses, 98).Their mode of articulation with each other would appear to be a negative correlation and consequently an infinite play of otherwise indiscernible differences. In order to resist this drift toward an all-consuming indeterminacy, I prefer to think of the determinate finitude of techne as recontextualized, rather than negated, by the indeterminacy of the sublime. In that way we might convert the incipient paradox of their interface into a site for salvaging human making as the threshold of aesthetic knowledge. Furthermore, I want to contemplate the fusion of the horizons of the particular and the universal, instantiated on that threshold, as a protocol of deliberation that could be invoked between them. In the view I will now sketch out, this protocol would dictate that seeing can be made commensurable to thinking through choosing. Choosing is thus made apparent as a viable protocol of seeing. There are, in fact, key moments in both Hegel’s and Nancy’s thinking about the incommensurability of techne and sublimity that invite us to see (however provisionally) production, qua determinate human making, as a threshold of aesthetic experience. It is glossed in Nancy’s insight that, for Hegel, beauty “in the proper sense, non-submission to naturality,” always presupposes the “freedom of production” (Nancy, Muses, 49).And, of course, the irreducible plurality of the world is precisely what constrains Hegel’s nonsubmission to naturality.This matches Nancy’s own grasp of the irreducible plurality of sense. According to Nancy, every sense is inextricably knowable only in relation to another sense. This is his explanation of the fact that there are several muses instead of one.Thus, it might be fair to say that the plurality in relation
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 133
Beautiful Errors
133
to which techne makes itself intelligible, in both Hegel’s and Nancy’s arguments, potentially mandates a protocol of choice. Such a protocol could vitiate the indeterminacy that irreducible plurality otherwise invites.22 Nancy himself is scrupulous to observe that the primitive meaning of the Greek tekhne, captured in its Latin translation ars, links art to the concept of articulation (Muses, 26). Articulation here evokes the cognitive addition of one singularity to another, such that the latter is rendered a problematical plurality. Articulation, as Nancy tells us, has “the structure of a singular plural” (26): it is additive with respect to a totality whose unity is reconfigured by the addition. It is therefore arguable that the articulation of the self of techne could only gain any self-reflective purchase, with respect to the excess of plurality, on the threshold of an exclusion.What is added excludes the principle of unity that the addition de facto modifies. Exclusion is of course the choice to be what is not excluded. Thus articulation (and ars-aesthetics by implication), in effect, entails a recontextualization of the choosing subject: it puts the subject’s self-understanding in the service of a warrant for moving the contextual horizon beyond the subject’s own threshold of self-recognition.
VI Here I would like to make the terms of my argument more concrete by looking at Caravaggio’s Conversion of Saint Paul.23 We might well imagine that my aim to convert the paradoxical “interface of techne and sublimity into a site for salvaging human making as the threshold of aesthetic knowledge” is made palpable in a painting that graphically displays the double meaning of conversion. Conversion denotes both the practical techne of articulating (or transforming) one register of value with another, and the formless sublimity of absolute spiritualization. Just as I have been challenging the mutual exclusivity of seeing and thinking, so I will argue that Caravaggio challenges the mutual exclusivity of techne and sublimity—the making visible and the miracle of visionary transport—by making the one task reciprocate with the other. The transitivity of visionary transport is comprehended in the painting as a transition to another way of seeing: it reciprocally excites the faith that there might indeed be a way of seeing that surpasses thought-full vision. But the transcendence of thought, in this case, only sees its way to new modalities of thinking.
Singer.book
9/12/03
134
11:21 AM
Page 134
Aesthetic Reason
Caravaggio’s painting is a kind of genre piece in its aim to represent the scene of conversion.As such, it takes for granted the power of picturing the invisible.After all, this painter has ample evidence, from no less formidable picture-makers than Michelangelo (1545) and Raphael (tapestry) before him, that the subject matter of spiritual conversion (specifically, The Conversion of Saint Paul) can be made into a picture. In Michelangelo’s and Raphael’s precedent-setting compositions, however, the emphasis falls decisively upon Saul, the man of action, as if to confirm the artist’s capacity to adequately comprehend or compass the duality of the visible and the invisible. In those earlier works, the scene of action, the Roman warrior falling/fallen from his horse amid the field of clamorous military spectacle, is visualized from the vantage of an objectifying planometrical distance that implies, by its omniscience, access to a transcending perspective. In striking contrast, Caravaggio’s composition occludes the action by inserting the blinding presence of Saul’s horse between the viewer and the scene of Saul’s enlightenment. Furthermore, the vision-struck protagonist of the piece is brutally foreshortened and thus paradoxically marginalized in the foreground of the painting. Eyes closed and sprawled beneath the image of the horse, Saul is a personalized and subjective marker for a line of sight that nonetheless is deprived of projection into a plausible visionary space. Neither human nor divine vision is facilitated here.24 What is original in Caravaggio’s deceptively passive conversion scene (as Giovanni Pietro Bellori says,“[A]ffato senza attione”) is precisely the conversion of the scene (the picture of visionary transport) into a seen (the horse).This conversion is a palpable blow to the viewer’s own spiritual aspirations. What is on view falls upon the viewer—as heavily as the horse threatens to fall upon the figure of Saul—as a blockage of what the scene, qua conversion, would otherwise portend to make available on the register of the visible. Indeed we cannot doubt that the occlusion of vision is as much the subject of this painting as what it makes visible. For the horse, which figuratively blocks our transport to the visionary sublime, literally obscures another man: standing behind it and gripping the beast’s harness. Presumably the man (a groom?) will prevent the horse from trampling the prostrate Saul, from stamping out the heavenly vision with its earthbound hooves.What we are likely not to see right away, however, is the fact that the body of the groom itself is no less obscured to us than the passionately anticipated vision of Saul. Furthermore, the body of the groom is obscure in two ways that recapitulate the original struggle of the viewer to see the action of the scene as what cannot be seen.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 135
Beautiful Errors
135
Our view of the groom is blocked by the body of the horse, which already blocks the transcendent view. But in this case the presence of the horse itself also distracts our eye from something that is there to be seen: the manifest artlessness of the drawn figure of the groom. As Walter Friedlander points out, the top of the groom’s body does not correlate with the bottom.25 The lack of the painter’s craft, thus embodied by the groom, is conspicuously disguised by the obtrusive physicality of the horse. In other words, the obstacle to sublimity—the horse—reveals the labor of techne, the figure of the groom, notwithstanding the crudity of execution by which it is denoted. In fact, the crudity of execution is all the more an admonition against our aspirations to transcend the labor of techne. In the history of visually representing conversions of Saint Paul, we are presented only with versions of visions, in lieu of that transcendent vision that would prove the independence of seeing from thinking. Just so, within Caravaggio’s composition, the notion of vision as version is paramount. The different versions of vision within the painting—the horse, the groom, the soldier, the portent of the invisible—orchestrate a drama of choice-making not unlike the choice between sacred and secular posed in the existential prospect of conversion itself. Here, however, right on the threshold of the incommensurability of techne and the sublime, choice-making—choosing between competing versions of visions—is conspicuously the métier of seeing as thinking. Conversion is of course typically treated as an involuntary phenomenon, and so, divorced from thought. But here, because conversion is so self-consciously a proffering of versions, and because the con of conversion denotes the articulation of one choice with respect to what has not been chosen, it brings deliberative volition into the field of vision, as a veritable armature of composition. We might say that conversion, in Caravaggio’s painting, is literally the convergence of techne and sublimity because it articulates the concept of transcendence within the fundamentally syntactical constraints of the necessity to see one thing as the choice to exclude another. Articulation—the articulation of the visible (the decision to see) and the invisible (the decision not to see)—identified by Nancy with the substance of ars, does not succumb to indeterminacy here. By contrast with the sensuous immediacy of retinal vision—that might indeed excite our hopes for the sublime transcendence of thought—choicemaking is unequivocally an artifact of techne. It can, after all, only be articulated syntactically. In the sublime we seek release from those cognitive limits of seeing, where what we would otherwise see requires
Singer.book
9/12/03
136
11:21 AM
Page 136
Aesthetic Reason
articulation (specifically the mediation of linguistic rules) as the concomitant contextualization of sense. On the contrary, in The Conversion of Saint Paul, Caravaggio contrives a circumstance where, by letting the viewer see the blinding mechanics of techne, in the guise of representing the scene of sublimity, he forces the viewer to construe his own perspective as a site of production. Because we are caused to see the poor draftsmanship of the groom figure as an effect of recognizing the horse to be an obstacle to transcendent vision, we comprehend the act of seeing as a techne in its own right. In other words, because the visible must be seen conjointly as conversions, because the versions of seeing in the painting subsist explicitly in relation to one another as variables of a syntactical order, they will never be consubstantial. Consubstantiality, after all, is precisely what our indulgence of the realms of miraculous vision and sublimity would invite us to believe in. Instead of dramatizing the mutual exclusivity of seeing and thinking, Caravaggio thus makes mutuality and exclusiveness—what Nancy would agree are the plurality and singularity respectively of articulation—articulate with each other. Articulation is thus construable as a recontextualization of the vantage point of seeing that is thereby invested in going beyond what has already been seen. But, contrary to the “beyond” that beckons in the miracle and in the sublime phenomenon, this “going beyond” is strictly a cognitive mode of deciding or choosing to see in a different way. Although Caravaggio’s Conversion maps itself onto Hegel’s/Nancy’s conception of the birth of art, as the desire to make the deity sensible, form and spirit are articulated with each other here in a way that neither Nancy nor Hegel would countenance: for both techne and sublimity are assimilated to a subtly teleological activity. There may be no better way to exemplify this activity than by reference to Caravaggio’s compositional dependency on the device of foreshortening. In the Conversion, the device of foreshortening is conspicuously what makes the figure of Saul “fit” into the canvas, physically and conceptually. In a way, the foreshortened figure is an epitome of the articulation of form and spirit, or the visible and the invisible: the visible form of the figure is evoked out of a dramatization of a visible absence of space. In foreshortening, the viewer is always choosing to see the figure as present, by virtue of what cannot be seen, what is occluded in the mechanics of recession. These mechanics are nevertheless quite evident in the truncation of the bodily trunk. We have already noted that the figure of Saul—who in another con-version will become Paul—projects a line of sight through the horse to the groom.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 137
Beautiful Errors
137
In fact their heads line up vertically on the picture plane to remind us that such planarity cannot be penetrated even by the device of foreshortening. Thus, because the visionary line of sight projected by foreshortening returns the viewer to his or her own devices—in recognition of the bad draftsmanship of the groom and of the planarity that his background presence foregrounds in relation to the head of Saul (the “seer”)—the groom becomes the marker for the irreducibility of techne.Techne can only be mastered by the viewer’s ongoing attention to technique. So foreshortening in this painting reminds us once more that we are bound to choose our perspective on the “action” as a choice between form and spirit. But more important, because our viewing of the choice between form and spirit proffered here is a variable of the contextualization of form and spirit, the painting becomes the condition of a momentous self-recognition: that we are ourselves preeminently choice-makers.We have little choice but to see ourselves as such. Given the choices teased out in this way, choosing is emphatically a making, the touchstone par excellence of Aristotelian telos. An aesthetic theorist such as Nancy sees the stakes of appreciating the incommensurability of techne and sublimity as the bringing to presence of a pure “patency” or “obviousness” of the visible, rather than as a making visible. He therefore discounts the activity of deliberative judging, which I believe Caravaggio’s canvas reflects as a compunction of human seeing.We must not forget that choosing has been bound up with the aesthetic since the judgment of Paris, itself an icon of the history of painting.The judgment of Paris remains a controversial site of origin for the aesthetic precisely because it seems to confuse a divine task with a human capacity.26 I reject the indeterminacy of what I think Nancy risks deifying as “patency,” because I want to secure a more properly human habitus for the powers of judgment.We have too often abdicated those powers to the indeterminacy in which we cloak an all-too-godlike artist, when we release him from the burdens of choice.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 138
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 139
5
Aesthetic Corrigibility: Bartleby and the Character of the Aesthetic For it is clear that the person who acts incontinently does not think it is right before he finds himself in the situation. —Aristotle, Nichomachean Ethics On errands of life, these letters speed to death. —Melville,“Bartleby the Scrivener”
I In this chapter I continue to argue for a necessary complementarity between the responsibilities of human action and the formal densities of aesthetic experience. In all the previous episodes of this argument I take it as an Aristotelian given that human action and aesthetic form share their most common ground in the understanding that both are epiphenomenal of productive subjective agency. I have pointed out that this is a strong predicate of Poetics inasmuch as Aristotelian mimesis is stipulated to be an imitation, not of individuals, but of actions. I now wish to focus more carefully on the exigencies of human choice-making through which subjective agency gains expressive scope in the realms of both action and the aesthetic. Indeed, I will continue to show how the exigencies of choice-making compel the reciprocity of these realms. More important, we must look further into how the scene of human choice-making, in which subjective agency comes most vitally to life, is circumscribed by the risks of error and the hopes for self realization. I have already intimated how it demands a protocol of negotiating error. Subjective agency knows itself within the inescapable narrative constraints of attempting to coordinate intentions with actions such that the slippage between them does not become a threshold of self-annihilation, that is, a tragedy of unintended consequences. By focusing on how aesthetic practice specifically is so constrained, I want to demonstrate that the force of aesthetic knowledge must entail
Singer.book
9/12/03
140
11:21 AM
Page 140
Aesthetic Reason
a standard of ethical corrigibility. Reciprocally, we will see how corrigibility, with respect to actions that produce unintended consequences, exhibits a most conspicuously aesthetic aspect: it imposes a mandate upon subjectivity to recontextualize those actions according to some more coherent structure of knowledge.1 Indeed, corrigibility, understood as a capacity to remediate error, exhibits a disposition toward change that accords well with the long sustained, and just as long ridiculed, belief that the aesthetic, and art more generally, might have political consequence—might even change something so grandiosely imagined as the world. We will seek, in that disposition toward change, a prospect for elaborating aesthetic theory in the direction of practical rationality and thus for revitalizing the terms of aesthetic production. Because the relevance of corrigibility to the aesthetic must be viewed therefore as coherent with the productive aspect of art—since agency is registered in the products of willful action—it is important to stipulate that my account of aesthetic corrigibility will be predicated on the dynamic or economic aspect of corrigibility, rather than on its more abstract value dimension. Here is where my desire to revise the concept of the aesthetic vis-à-vis a world of practical actions must, once again, challenge the history of aesthetic theorizing. For any general account of the history of the aesthetic reveals that it was precisely the productive aspect of the artwork that was eclipsed from view by postEnlightenment aesthetic theory. Enlightenment rationalists from Dubos and Boileau to Shaftesbury, Hutcheson, Hume, and Kant systematically repressed the productive or economic aspect of the aesthetic, fetishizing the aesthetic object at the expense of aesthetic practice.Therefore, my interest in promoting the idea of aesthetic corrigibility is also an effort to reinstate the paradigm of production as a fulcrum of aesthetic knowledge/experience. After all, aesthetic knowledge without production undercuts the ground of any claim for the aesthetic as integral to social agency. If we need to see the claims I am asserting as antagonistic toward conventional aesthetic theory, it makes sense to avail ourselves of the historical view proffered in the recent work of John Guillory. For this work specifically foregrounds the issue of productive agency as a variable of aesthetic value. It will thus give us a useful ground for remapping the territory of aesthetic valuation along lines conducive to, but ultimately inadequate to, those I have already outlined. Guillory’s work thus supplies a premise for countenancing an aesthetic value that plausibly supports social agency. But it will also set a standard for measuring how far we must think beyond Guillory’s perspective, if that enterprise is to succeed.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 141
Aesthetic Corrigibility
141
In Cultural Capital, Guillory gives a valuable account of the trends of eighteenth century thought that ultimately eclipsed the economic aspect of aesthetic value. In this regard, Guillory reminds us that the eighteenthcentury view of the aesthetic is typically identified with the conceptual ends of social consensus and the suppression of difference. Both goals formally mitigate economic thinking.This mitigation is, of course, complementary to the eighteenth-century standard of disinterestedness that becomes so notably an obstacle to an account of aesthetic production in Kant’s “Analytic of the Beautiful.”While Kant’s Critique of Judgment remains the most widely generalized pre-text of “modern” aesthetic theory, it nonetheless gives notoriously short shrift to the work of art as a productive enterprise. For Kant, and despite indications to the contrary in his “Idea for a Universal History,” the judgment of taste seems to operate in lieu of productive artistic agency as the underpinning of his “sensus communis.”2 I have already noted that it is the ideal of sensus communis—the universalist consensus of judgment that binds the social totality. It teases out the eighteenth-century analogy between a civic totality and the formal totality of the work of art.This analogy has tantalized aesthetic theorists ever since for its ready assimilation of art to life.3 Guillory, however, points out the paradox that, behind the valorization of the aesthetic as a sensus communis, there abides a tradition of maintaining the aesthetic as a refuge from the conflicts of quotidian experience: the qualities of disproportion and disharmony. It goes without saying that these are the qualities of contingent experience, without which there is no practical impetus for productive agency. It is for this reason, as we have seen, that earlier theorists such as Shaftesbury, Hutcheson, and Hume saw the universality of aesthetic value as precluding deliberation and practical experience.This way, they fostered a literally counterproductive idealization of the work of art: the artwork is posited as a totality whose unifying rule is most firmly grasped as a principle of form, amenable to sensuous appreciation, rather than as a principle of action amenable to rational deliberation. Guillory is particularly persuasive in his critical view of this theoretical heritage because he is able to show how aesthetics, in the eighteenth century, actually gained its cultural ascendancy on the basis of an alleged affinity with economics and technical production (techne). The former Platonist sequestration of aesthetics in the affective realms of sensible pleasure or in the moral precepts of Renaissance, Christian Neoplatonism, had guaranteed its irrelevance to the scientific regimens of truth predominating in the Age of Reason. On this basis, Guillory makes it particularly easy to see how perverse it might seem in the late twentieth century to continue to indulge a view of aesthetics in which
Singer.book
9/12/03
142
11:21 AM
Page 142
Aesthetic Reason
production is split off from valuation. I will resist the temptation to recapitulate too exhaustingly Guillory’s elegant narrative of the rise of aesthetics in tandem with the rise of political economy/moral philosophy and its subsequent divorce from those worldly pursuits. For my chief concern here is to adduce a view of the aesthetic that is conducive to the practice of corrigibility. Nevertheless, because my account of aesthetic corrigibility does seek its own reconciliation with moral philosophy, it depends upon key aspects of Guillory’s historical narrative. Chief among these is his recognition that the acceptance of conflict, as well as the open-ended adequation of differences that instantiate conflict, is a constitutive feature of aesthetic practice. For this reason I am obliged to give Guillory’s text a schematic gloss. Guillory’s narrative of modern aesthetics begins with the problem of rerationalizing the unity of a civil society that was no longer rationalized by the institutions of monarchy.This was the political circumstance that set the stage for what we might characterize as the aestheticization of civil society in the late seventeenth and early eighteenth centuries.“Once the order of society ceased to be legislated from the top, it ceased to be conceived as simply the execution of rationally prescribed principles. . . . Rather the order, proportion, or harmony of the social totality could be represented as analogous to the order, proportion, or harmony of a work of art, or any object of beauty. It was the order of the sensible rather than the intelligible” (Guillory, Cultural Capital, 305). The transition from the divinely or mysteriously ordained unity of the monarchic state and the ever more self-conscious order produced under the auspices of civic agency induced the presumption of an analogy between the order of the state and the order of human sensibility, between the objects of the political world and the art object.The linchpin of the analogy is the individual agency that is bound to the collective will of the state through commodity production. Unlike the monarchic regime, the civil state is manifestly a made thing and thus presupposes an intelligible maker. For Guillory the extrapolation to thinking of the state as the site of production and the commodity as the site of consumption was almost inevitable. Guillory credits such thinkers as Hume and Adam Smith with shoring up the foundation of this analogy by positing a “continuum of production/consumption” (308) whereby the agency of the producer is understood to reciprocate with the commodity as a framework for some revisionary self-consciousness.This continuum translates methodologically into at least the desire for an adequation of forces of production and forces of con-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 143
Aesthetic Corrigibility
143
sumption.This adequation takes the form of a principle: the value, that is, the beauty of the commodity is proportionate to the uses it serves in the social order.A harmonics of production and consumption is figured here insofar as production is seen as a variable of the needs of consuming subjects. Or to put it more simply, the continuum of production and consumption permits the assimilation of the already traditional distinction between the work of art and the commodity— which since Neoplatonist aesthetics had kept the artwork well insulated from secular life—to the commodity per se. If the work of art is like the commodity, it is manifestly part of the process of production. This line of thought beneficently preempts the caricatures of decadent aestheticism with a more rationalistic aesthetic pragmatism.The duly aesthetic commodity, like the market commodity, exhibits aesthetic perfection where its social value is coordinate with the social motives and the means of its production.This is to say, aesthetic perfection is duly commensurable with work and thereby reprieved from the self-trivializing pursuits of imaginative free play, to which it would have been otherwise consigned by beauty theory. Guillory goes on to explain that, in the course of the mid-eighteenthcentury capitalist expansion, however, with the evolution of market economies and ultimately with the maturation of Adam Smith’s own political economy, the commodity was peremptorily disjoined from production.This was most directly a consequence of the economist’s realization that the value of the commodity was in reality incommensurable with the labor of its production. Where the value of the commodity was proportionate to the uses that mandated production, its production was now deemed to be a function of formerly invisible labor costs that were strictly abstract from the subjective needs of consumers.As the dynamic proportionality that formerly played between production and consumption was disrupted in economic theory, so the artwork came to be disarticulated from its identification with the commodity. Its value was hence decoupled from a calculable source of determinateness, without which aesthetic theory can make no practical claim upon the field of practical actions. Indeed, from this point on, aesthetic theory could sustain only a metaphoric relation between the production of the artwork and economic production.The scientific premise of aesthetic experience was no longer integral to an intelligible and efficient economic system. Its explanatory power and cultural value were disjoined from any standard of efficient productivity. It consequently became incorrigible with respect to the production of value, alienated from the forces of value production.4
Singer.book
9/12/03
144
11:21 AM
Page 144
Aesthetic Reason
Not surprisingly, as the commodity became increasingly distinct from the artwork, the ideal of the artwork became an increasingly indistinct, metaphysically tinged standard of “perfection.” I have already discussed in Chapter 4 how art, judged in terms of perfection, ceased to be readily understood as an efficient, productive practice. We see the effects of this transfiguration unmistakably in the amorphous standards of taste that were popularized in the protocols of nineteenth-century aestheticism, where pleasure prevails as the test of aesthetic authority.5 While remaining critical of the eclipse of aesthetic production, perpetrated in the decoupling of the notion of the commodity from the notion of the artwork, Guillory is nonetheless prepared to grant the consequent abstraction of aesthetic value as a historical inevitability. He concedes this point on the grounds that, under capitalism, production must ineluctably come to be seen as already consumption.This is what Marx himself already saw in the Grundrisse. Guillory alludes to Marx’s insight that, because what is consumed constitutes a need for its re-production, production itself inevitably becomes a counter for desire, for surplus value altogether. Ultimately it devolves to a counter for the indeterminacy of value.Thus extrapolating from the economic to the aesthetic, Guillory is prepared to see how an account of the artwork, as a site of surplus value and infinite desire, makes a fitting compromise with the facts of political economy and philosophical orthodoxy. After all, he points out, this compromise notion of aesthetic value already has cultural currency under the judgmental auspices of Kantian play. It is a compromise that, scrupulously enough, acknowledges the unavoidable split of the economic/political values from cultural values without explicitly eliminating the aesthetic from the field of sociological study. Nevertheless, from my point of view, Guillory’s analysis seems unduly self-preempting at this juncture and, above all, too explicitly contradictory of his own earlier judgment against aesthetic theories that were not amenable to the pragmatics of economic production.
II I want to suggest that no such surrender to a metaphorics of aesthetic value—where aesthetic value is abstractly equated with desire and desire, in turn, departicularizes the formal articulation of the artwork— is inevitable. Among other things, what is missed in this theoretical stance is any significant bearing the aesthetic might have on the self-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 145
Aesthetic Corrigibility
145
productive exigencies of human subjectivity.This stance is a de facto concession to Walter Pater’s “thick wall of personality” behind which the subjective aesthetic experience remains a solipsistic pursuit.6 For these reasons, I want to explore the possibility that the concept of corrigibility evokes a better sense of the aesthetic. Corrigibility grasps the aesthetic as integral to the production of the subject, in what we must take to be the inherently akratic arena of action. It thereby offers a meaningful alternative to accepting the alienation of aesthetic production from the commodity—hence the alienation of the artwork from an economy of production—as an irreversible phenomenon. By contrast with the ill-fated economic metaphors for aesthetic value that litter Guillory’s historical account, corrigibility denotes an evaluative process that is arguably coherent with the economic sources of metaphoric aesthetics, without itself succumbing to metaphorization. Thus when we speak of corrigibility we might still speak of production literally, as we did before the advent of capitalistic consumerism, and before the aestheticizing of the aesthetic that it unwittingly brought about.A more persuasively literal correlation between the artistic commodity and forces of production survives in this conceptual framework. The biggest advantage of adopting it will be that the ideals of the artwork might once again be made commensurable with work per se, with a standard of aesthetic production (practice) more than with a standard of aesthetic perfection (metaphor). My overall ambition here is nonetheless not strikingly divergent from Guillory’s. Guillory is well aware of Marx’s compunction to peg the intelligibility of political economy to the terms of production, in order to dispel the abstraction-mongering metaphors entertained in the concept of exchange value. He resolutely insists upon the primacy of production over the commodity, and its malignant consumer-cultural fetishes.As Guillory stipulates,“Marx resorts to the aesthetic analogy in order to maintain the priority of production” (Cultural Capital, 321). But Guillory seems less acutely attuned to the fact that Marx’s formulation “production is immediately consumption” (90) mandates, above all other considerations, an alternative dialectical relation between production and commodity. Otherwise Marxist critique cannot hold all reality-corrupting abstractions at bay.7 This is consistent with Marx’s unwillingness to countenance the possibility that production ever succumbs to abject purposelessness (Marx, Grundrisse, 91). Neo-Marxists treat Marx’s intuition of the dialectic of production and consumption as prescient critique of the decadence of late twentieth-century consumer culture. They likewise see the consumer
Singer.book
9/12/03
146
11:21 AM
Page 146
Aesthetic Reason
culture as a culpable corollary of the “purposiveness without a purpose” by which Kant took the aesthetic out of circulation in the economy of human actions. Correspondingly, Marx makes conflict and disproportion important counters of artistic value.As Guillory explains: “The ‘object of art’ stands for what is momentarily in excess of present need” (Cultural Capital, 321). But instead of seeing the disproportion between production and consumption embodied in the work of art as a determinant conflict— namely, one with its own contextual imperatives of understanding— Guillory treats it merely as a token of insatiable need.8 On this pretext he equates the principle of desire with the totality of production.The dialectical tension between production and consumption is conflated in this, once again, overly metaphoric conceptualization of their relation. Disappointingly, Guillory’s desire to state strongly the limitations inherent in Marxist aesthetics preempts the possibility of thinking more broadly in Marxian terms. Guillory himself points out that, for Marx, the relation between production and consumption is vital precisely and exclusively because it is an asymmetrical relation.We might speculate, therefore, that where production reciprocates asymmetrically with consumption there will always be a slippage—the threshold of error and corrigible action— between theory and practice, desire and agency, abstraction and concreteness. Generality will subsist with particularity in this view (Guillory, Cultural Capital, 321). For Marx, the commodity/artwork is no doubt a locus of desire, but we need not decontextualize or absolutize desire, as Guillory seems to do, by making the indeterminacy of desire the ultimate means of comprehending the artwork’s relationship to the work of the world—which we must note, it thereby shirks. I would argue that one does not even need to concede with Guillory that the “analogy [between political economy and aesthetics] never amounted to more than an analogy” (325).This is why I have already suggested that corrigibility will serve as a better term than desire if we, along with Marx, wish to maintain production as a conceptual armature for aesthetic practice. Since it is conditioned by the errors of action, corrigibility entails production as an aspect of knowledge, if only because such knowledge is, by definition, contextual. What is at stake under the sign of production in both discourses—the economic and the aesthetic—is access to the determination of value.This is precisely what Guillory seems to have sacrificed in holding fast to the concept of an absolute desire as the master trope of aesthetic experience. In contemporary literary criticism desire has of course become an
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 147
Aesthetic Corrigibility
147
increasingly global conceit for comprehending the aesthetic.This has been especially true where there has been a willingness to blur the line between aesthetic agency and an a priori—either Hutchesonian or Kantian—aesthetic disposition. Guillory himself identifies this disposition with the partisanism of contemporary combatants in the canon debates, who have sought to discredit aesthetic judgment insofar as it appears to carry an exclusionary judgmental force.Their eagerness to treat the aesthetic as a threshold of infinite desire does two things. It acknowledges the culpable ideological tendentiousness of canonical aesthetic judgments and, at the same time, licenses the proliferation of alternate sites for assigning aesthetic value. Paradoxically, this supplanting of aesthetic judgment with aesthetic desire, has led to the ultimate aestheticization of experience. It promotes precisely the radical value relativism that Guillory himself deplores and that, for my purposes, constitutes a tragic impediment to deliberative agency. Correlatively, it stymies the ethical purposiveness that I have alleged the aesthetic might otherwise serve. Contemporary critics of the aesthetic have typically made the accusation that aesthetic value strives to transcend the otherwise violently contested values of everyday experience and so stands irresponsibly aloof from the political reality denoted in them. But it should be just as clear that stripping the aesthetic of all judgmental protocols, all means of making distinctions—and hence of the resources for choice-making—amounts to a transcendence of practical life in the opposite direction: toward a radical particularity that turns out to be as politically feral as the most Platonic regimens of tasteful wisdom. I am of course in agreement with the critics of the aesthetic who, along with Guillory, wish to ameliorate the disjuncture of aesthetic value from the practical entailments of the commodity.They stand in line with historical figures from Baumgarten to Nietzsche to Hegel and Dewey, for whom the aesthetic needs to be squared with the demands of practical action. Ultimately, they all wish to reassimilate the artwork to the epistemological tasks of production. But my agreement with such opinion does not extend to the fashionable conflation of the forms of attention conditioned by aesthetic objects to the modes of sociological analysis that purport to locate them in the field of social production. Guillory himself warns that we ought to be extremely wary of those critics of the aesthetic who, in their zeal to equalize the social forces contending within the horizon of aesthetic judgment, often lose sight of the resources for determinant value inhering in it. For, in the process, such critics confuse the discourse of the aesthetic with aesthetic practice.
Singer.book
9/12/03
148
11:21 AM
Page 148
Aesthetic Reason
Notwithstanding Guillory’s underlying empathy with sociological empiricism, he unwittingly shows us that Pierre Bourdieu is a case in point. Bourdieu’s critique of the aesthetic on grounds that it is a discourse of power, dependent on a protocol of social exclusions, seems utterly blind to the ways in which aesthetic objects transfigure the discourses that purport to grasp their significance. Because Bourdieu sees the artwork as almost exclusively epiphenomenal of the critical language that licenses its exclusionary powers, his bid for the universalization of standards of value that do not otherwise have democratic distribution within the universe of language users is still too one-sided.9 Bourdieu’s “sociological” remedy for the tyranny of elitist tastes merely seeks universalization of the access to critical languages, in lieu of engaging the objects they describe. He has still obviated the relevance of the artwork to the project of universalizing the values ascribed to it. Or, at least, he gives no concrete account of the place of the artwork, and the agency of the artist, in the project of universalizing the conditions of access to the values ascribed to the artwork. In this respect I would argue that Bourdieu’s notion of universalization is itself too “aesthetic” in what I think he must agree is the worst sense. It is important to note that Bourdieu gives scrupulous attention to social conditions of production when he articulates the sociological viewpoint per se. But the values he assigns to the artwork, in his account of aesthetic universalization, tend to reflect the conditions of their consumption, hence their commodification, more than the terms of their production.10 Indeed, the “distribution of the aesthetic disposition” seems to matter more to Bourdieu than any analytical recasting of the “aesthetic disposition.” Specifically, he misses the opportunity to construe the aesthetic disposition in act-based terms that might be more attuned to the “epistemological tasks of production” embodied in the artwork. His universalization procedure would therefore seem relatively oblique to the sociological problems it is supposed to ameliorate.11 Bourdieu’s lack of interest in the form of the artwork sacrifices the historical exigencies, produced therein, to the history that produced the artwork. He treats them as if they were mutually exclusive avenues of inquiry. Not surprisingly, because Guillory is too much in solidarity with Bourdieu, he does not find a clear compromise position between the ills of aesthetic theory and the ills of anti-aesthetic sociological critique. Indeed, he ultimately calls for a universalization of access to the cultural capital vested by aesthetic judgments. In my view the same liabilities attach to his bid for universalization of access, as attach to
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 149
Aesthetic Corrigibility
149
Bourdieu’s. Because this access is posited as an absolute ground of judgment, it has the status of a generative principle that remains formally distinct from its concrete determinations in the specific works of art it sanctions.This standard of universalization, which Bourdieu thinks of as a beneficent “corporatism of the universal,” invites precisely the problems it would ameliorate.12 Because it brackets the formal specificity of the artwork, it renders the act of making distinctions, otherwise fostered within the formal constraints of the artwork, rather less important than the commodified social distinction enjoyed by its critical exponents and its consumers. Judgmental agency, with respect to the formation of the artwork itself, thereby comes under the same epistemological/political threats that loomed for Marx in the economic globalization of consumption. It is out of a wish to ameliorate this paradox that I propose seeing how corrigibility might help us to get at universality without sacrificing Bourdieu’s and Guillory’s concern for the greater social good that might be served by reconceptualizing aesthetic value in relation to its social effects. Better than Bourdieu’s and Guillory’s perspectives, however, a principle of corrigibility does not risk lapsing into a utopianism that would be as abstract, with respect to the purposes of social change, as conventional aesthetic value was corrupt, with respect to the social privilege it seemed to confer. Bourdieu’s “corporatism of the universal” simply cannot articulate a context-specific ground of motivation without compromising its claim to universality. For that claim is presupposed as a principle of necessity, not of efficacy. Alternatively, corrigibility, the contextualization of human agency conditioned by error, proffers a relatively learnable universalizing procedure in the place of a certifiably truthful standard of universality. Because it is not generative for universal truth claims, corrigibility does not preclude that deliberative activity that depends on protocols of rational choicemaking in order to imagine a subject fit for the tasks of aesthetic agency.
III Herman Melville’s “Bartleby the Scrivener: A Story of Wall Street” offers an especially rich prospect for testing these hypotheses: it is an exemplary instance of ethical incorrigibility masquerading as aesthetic practice.The famous benedictory epitaph that Melville’s narrator confers upon Bartleby,“Ah Bartleby! Ah, humanity!” has the unmistakable ring of a voice striving for artistic eloquence. Even more recognizably, it
Singer.book
9/12/03
150
11:21 AM
Page 150
Aesthetic Reason
resonates with the universalist aspirations of the most mainstream aesthetic theories—sampled in part one of this chapter—that make the transcendence of experience the perverse test of aesthetic authenticity.Aesthetic authenticity presupposes its universality. In “Bartleby the Scrivener,” the rhetorical trajectory of the narrator’s benedictory expostulation points in the illustrious direction of just this universalist detachment: intended as it is to confer nobility on the character capable of such a distancing sensibility. But instead of elevating the narrative above the artless world of quotidian observation, the self-conscious aesthetic flourishes of the narrator’s rhetoric throughout the narrative show us the unsightly mirror of his ethical vanity.Thus Melville’s reader must contend with the familiar paradox—decried by critics of the aesthetic—that aesthetic sensibility, so finely and so exclusively attuned to the universals of human nature, is incompatible with any existential commitments to the world of “real” human beings. By contrast, the narrative engine of Melville’s assiduously ethical novella is the reader’s increasingly burdensome questioning of the authenticity of the narrator’s presumption to speak with the aesthete’s self-acknowledged “universal voice.” As we know, the universal voice was Kant’s famous index for the de facto ethical consensus forged in aesthetic judgment.The universal voice, coordinate with the test of disinterestedness, instantiates knowledge of the beautiful and thereby unites the “attuned” sensibility with all humankind.13 In “Bartleby the Scrivener” however, the narrator’s professional identity as a Wall Street attorney alerts us to the prospect that we will have to invoke lawlike criteria, perhaps as rigorous as Kant’s own, by which we might negatively judge the fit between the narrator’s self-congratulatory moralistic intentions, purveyed as artistic truth, and his morally dubious actions. Accordingly, Melville’s “characterization” of the narrator will reveal itself to be a veritable staging ground for the analysis of akratic action that I have already adduced as an important corollary of aesthetic experience: because akrasia problematizes the fit between intentions and actions it mandates a scruple of human productivity, a labor of creativity. Now we must see if the narrator’s self-styled aesthetic enterprise, in retailing Bartleby’s “life,” accords well enough with the notion that akratic action—because it coheres with a principle of corrigibility—confirms our faith in aesthetic practice as a medium of rationalistic learning. Melville establishes his narrator’s aesthetic credentials immediately in “Bartleby.” But he executes this business in precisely the terms that have historically stigmatized the artist figure, whose most caricatured
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 151
Aesthetic Corrigibility
151
persona the narrator aspires to measure himself against. Self-aggrandizing from the start, the narrator avows that failure to tell Bartleby’s tale in full, i.e. to assume the role of the artist, would be an “irreparable loss to literature” (“Bartleby the Scrivener,” 13). He furthermore establishes his own voice by invidious comparison with the anaesthetic likes of John Jacob Astor, characterized in turn as “a personage little given to poetic enthusiasm” (14).As if to illustrate the point, he immediately turns the name John Jacob Astor into a labored poetry: it is “a name which, I admit I love to repeat, for it hath a rounded and orbicular sound to it and rings like unto bullion” (13). Indeed, the text we are about to read is proudly tendered as a test of the narrator’s adequacy to the task of producing comparable aesthetic pleasures.The elegant irony of Melville’s conceit is, of course, that the narrator already measures up only too well to a standard of aesthetic adequacy that, in its pompous aloofness from reality, can only call his humanity into disrepute. It is precisely the caricature aesthete’s notion of the aesthetic, as a standard of knowledge that can be known before it is met—a truthfulness that preempts experience—that was called into doubt by the historical alienation of production from consumption. So it should come as no surprise if I propose that it is the efficacy of this doubt that is the proper measure of Melville’s own aesthetic accomplishment in “Bartleby the Scrivener.” The narrator’s adequacy to the role of the aesthetic judge is fittingly tailored to every detail of the caricature of aesthetic decadence: he has chosen the “easiest way of life” (“Bartleby,” 14). He practices his vocation on paper, distanced from the fray of litigation, of contesting wills. He is a resolute but curiously dispassionate recluse from the world of actions and his only deeds are the proofs of property ownership. Property deeds are as effectively alien from the free will to act, to perpetrate deeds, as legal wills are from the living agent who puts them into play as legal instruments. The life of the legal will, after all, presupposes the death of the willing agent. Correspondingly, the narrator considers his self-worth to be proportionate to his disciplined disengagement from the worldly struggle with other living wills. Will is, nevertheless, the conflict-engendering crux of the narrator’s quandary about Bartleby’s apparent will not to act. Voicing the credo “I prefer not to,” Bartleby seems to defy the order of the workplace by so avowing his disengagement from all professional duties.Thus challenged by what he calls Bartleby’s “passive resistance,” the narrator faces a terrible imperative: to judge Bartleby’s own quasi-aesthetic aura of disengagement from the world in such a way that he must compromise
Singer.book
9/12/03
152
11:21 AM
Page 152
Aesthetic Reason
the disinterestedness that underwrites his own aesthetic pretensions in the telling of the tale.We must wonder if the narrator recognizes in Bartleby an enviable realization of the aesthetic ideal of detachment that he himself strives to attain. We are given every reason to believe that, in the narrator’s mind, such a fall from aesthetic grace would be tantamount to a loss of moral authority, not to mention an end to narrative. And the conflict only intensifies beyond this threshold. Precisely to the degree that Bartleby’s gnomic credo “I prefer not to” is ambiguously an expression of will, it calls the reader’s attention, that much more skeptically, to the fact that the narrator’s own will depends on an aesthetic will-lessness, which is increasingly subject to paradoxical interpretation. For example, faced with Bartleby’s refusal to perform his copyist’s duties, the narrator clearly intends to will his own salvation in the aesthetically judicious eyes of the divine creator. He resolves to produce an ethically flattering image of himself, as supremely tolerant of Bartleby’s allegedly willful behavior by a disciplined exercise of will-lessness. Bartleby’s apparent abdication of will, however willful, will be no match for the narrator’s own will-lessness. In his own words, the narrator sees his passive tolerance of Bartleby’s belligerent presence as a way to “purchase a delicious self approval. To befriend Bartleby; to humor him in his strange willfulness . . . while I lay up in my soul what will eventually prove a sweet morsel for my conscience” (23–24; my emphasis). Even more suspiciously, the ambiguity or split intentionality of the narrator’s will (in the guise of will-lessness) comes to resemble the split between production and consumption, which we have seen to be an impediment to ethically purposive aesthetic practice. For the will of the narrator, exercised as a highly theatricalized will-lessness, produces the unintended consequence of revealing the narrator (in the reader’s eyes) to be a pathetic failure of will. Such pathos belies his aesthetic mastery of the tale.The narrator’s willful passivity unintentionally produces a situation in which a candidly active will seems to be the preferable modus operandi.After all, the narrator’s hypocritical tolerance for Bartleby only seems to increase the ever more irksome freedom of his antagonist’s “willful” presence on the premises of the narrator’s place of business. The more the narrator “exercises” tolerance, the more imposed upon he feels himself to be.The narrator’s error of judgment thus reveals him to be caught in a predicament of akratic action/knowledge.This is a fact that becomes increasingly hard to ignore as his errors of strategic planning proliferate in proportion to the seemingly unlim-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 153
Aesthetic Corrigibility
153
ited hidden contingencies that come to menace his situation, as a consequence of Bartleby’s will not to.When he resolves to let Bartleby not do as he pleases, the narrator incurs the displeasure of his other employees. When he treats Bartleby’s preference not to as an intimidation, it reveals Bartleby’s humility. When he vows to show humility before Bartleby’s eccentricity, it devolves to his humiliation before Bartleby. Even the narrator’s attempt to vacate the premises that Bartleby will not decamp from produces a public recognition that, legally speaking, he is responsible for the roof over Bartleby’s head. Here I want to argue that akratic knowledge—typified in the instances just cited—is very explicitly keyed to the thematic of corrigibility in “Bartleby.” I believe we can most deftly capture the thematic unity of this fiction by arguing that Melville’s narrator mistakes the unconsciously akratic behavior that is his own narrative métier, for art qua aesthetic truth. He therefore remains incorrigible with respect to that misconception. By contrast, akrasia becomes an emphatically selfconscious aspect of Melville’s own aesthetic production—both with respect to his deployment of narrative strategies and with respect to the reader’s engagement of them.The errors of the narrator tutor the reader’s self-revising awareness of what might constitute best behavior in the narrator’s situation. I take this to be a structuring irony of Melville’s aesthetic in “Bartleby” because it proffers consciousness of akratic knowledge as a kind of discovery procedure, rather than as a mere blind spot.This consciousness marks the difference between the character of Melville’s narrator and the arguably better character of Melville’s reader. It is especially important, for my purposes, to speak of both the narrator and the reader in terms of character, since the difference between them can now be seen to figure the field of akratic action as a site of corrigibility. In other words, to treat narrator and reader alike in characterological terms permits us to see them on a continuum of action. This obviates the usual thematic distance that obtrudes between narrator and reader as an artifact of the virtual dimension of “fictional reality” that is, otherwise, so unassumingly dramatized on the page.We will see that in Melville’s fiction, narrator and reader are markers for two sites of intentionality that nonetheless cohere in the complementarity of their difference. Such coherence is specifically the crux of akratic subjectivity: the erroneous action of the akrates is experienced as two discordant moments of intentionality, which are yoked in the necessary self-consciousness of one’s failure to act in accordance with a previous sense of best reasons.
Singer.book
9/12/03
154
11:21 AM
Page 154
Aesthetic Reason
Of course the relationship between reader and text in literary fiction is commonly a site of corrigibility, especially in morally didactic fiction. We need only consider the ironies of William Makepeace Thackeray as they accrue to the reader’s moral detachment from the world, so factitiously exhibited in the aesthetic artifice of a text such as Vanity Fair. But because the akratic continuum between narrator and reader in Melville’s text is, quite explicitly, also a stake of aesthetic production on the narrator’s part, the author is able to exhibit the interdependence of akrasia and corrigibility as a crucial underpinning of the aesthetic project for which the reader consequently bears a correlative responsibility. In turn, Melville provides a basis from which to generalize about how the aesthetic project might be linked to the formation of human character. He furthermore elaborates the terms of this linkage in a way that potentially closes the gap between the realms of production and commodity, intentions and unintended consequences, rationality and irrationality.Akrasia is, after all, and perhaps more than anything else, a ground upon which to predicate a theory of character, if we respect the Aristotelian postulate that character is first and foremost a function of act. In other words, we must accept the postulate that action blurs the line between knowledge and experience. Melville’s own aesthetic practice, particularly by contrast with his narrator’s aesthetic pretensions, thus reveals itself to be a decisively effectual action. It presents a striking antithesis to that aesthetic disposition that critics such as Bourdieu have faulted as incorrigible with respect to social responsibilities that ought not be shirked, within the realms of art, anymore than without. Furthermore, Melville’s agency, as an aesthetic maker, is nowhere more decisive than in his ability to show how akratic action ought not to be seen as terminally irrational. In “Bartleby” the narrator’s akratic action is revealed to be a resource of rationality insofar as the reader is prompted to pierce the narrator’s aesthetic pretensions by producing better reasons for the disposition to act in such troubling circumstances. In this frame of reference I believe we locate the efficacy of the aesthetic as a fulcrum of corrigibility and, concomitantly, adduce the reasons for alleging that we need some notion of corrigibility to understand the specificity of aesthetic value. We will see in more detail how the narrator’s akratic predicament in “Bartleby” becomes increasingly apparent in the pattern of energetic rationalizations that parodically diminish his authorial agency. But first, we must look at how Melville exhibits the narrator’s errors in contrast with actions that presuppose a richer protocol of choice-making than
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 155
Aesthetic Corrigibility
155
what is available within his limited rational means.As those limited means are exhibited in their fullest impoverishment, the knowledge of alternative choices comes more readily within the reader’s own powers of choosing.What enables the reader’s evasion of the akratic predicament is precisely the narrative sensitivity that the presumption of alternative choices guarantees and that the narrator so painfully lacks. It needs to be said here that theorists of akrasia are themselves frequently insensitive to the narrative dynamics of akratic action because they do not, as Alfred Mele recommends, put akrasia on a continuum with its complementary standard of corrigibility, enkrateia or self-control. In the standard account that asks us to take akrasia as simply irrational or antithetical to rational decision making, rationality itself is treated as a resolutely a priori principle, a simple disposition. On the contrary, I believe Melville is prompting us to a more practicable understanding of akrasia.This anticipates a position that is now gaining currency among philosophers like Alison McIntyre, whose highly original article “Is Akratic Action Always Irrational?” helped me to introduce the relevance of akrasia in Chapter 3. She points out that if we ignore the contextualist and narrative pressures impinging upon our desire to explain akrasia, we risk rendering it a useless tool of ethical judgment. McIntyre is shrewdly alert to the fact that agents are frequently unaware of how factors that motivate their sense of best reasons for acting might impel them to rely upon other reasons, if those factors could be seen in fuller contexts of motivation.This is a kind of implicit corrigibility: “If the agent is sensitive to something that constitutes a reason for him but he doesn’t see that it does, and if this consideration is what motivates him to perform the akratic action, then these are not two separate errors canceling each other out; they are two different ways in which the justificatory force of this consideration can be manifested.”14 Clearly, for McIntyre, akrasia is more than acting against a principle of best knowledge. It is, rather, a way of granting that best knowledge may be strictly a function of acting. As I already suggested in Chapter 3, if one takes akrasia primarily as “figuring the gap between intentions and actions as [a mode of] reciprocity” it can be seen as a way to broaden the context within which “justificatory force” can be mustered. Or as Robert Dunn in The Possibility of Weakness of Will has more pointedly suggested, akrasia locates “a breach between evaluation and action” (9) that one could presumably close only by deliberative means, by a procedurally scrupulous revaluation of the relevant contingencies of action. In other words, I am suggesting that akrasia may be a resource for rational deliberation or evaluation as much as it seems to menace our
Singer.book
9/12/03
156
11:21 AM
Page 156
Aesthetic Reason
ideals of rational instrumentality. In this way it helps us to see that the ethical warrant of the aesthetic—where it is informed by akrasia—is not the familiar grandiose prompt to intuit universal truths. We are, rather, prompted to the more modest enterprise of making ourselves better deliberators, tapping our latent corrigibility.After all, McIntyre’s astutely novelistic point is that we should not assume that “agents are fully aware of the considerations that count, for them, as reasons” (“Akratic Action,” 382). She is emphatic that an akratic action will not be irrational if an agent is motivated by some apparently lesser reason, that nonetheless could lead her to revise the reasoning that prompted the rationally dubious act (390) in the first place. Corrigibility is, among other things, a complementarily novelistic prospect for imagining what might count as better reasons. In “Bartleby the Scrivener” Melville opens this prospect for us by pursuing the question of Bartleby’s apparent willfulness—does he possess a will or is he the victim of a pitiable fate? Melville undertakes this inquiry in a way that engages the more ethically resilient account of akrasia proposed by McIntyre. If Bartleby has no will, and the narrator is an acknowledged akrates, then the reader’s impulse to correct the narrator’s erroneous judgment (that Bartleby is at fault because he is willful) demands that the reader, in his or her turn, assume the deliberative duties of the willful agent.The reader does so by the default of there being any other competent agent in the world of the text.That Melville sponsors this thinking is initially evidenced in his strong inducement that we see Bartleby differently from how the narrator does: as not simply incorrigible in the willfulness of “I prefer not to.” After all, Bartleby’s apparent willfulness lands him paradoxically in the Tombs, a place of conspicuously nullified will and so a marker for the seeming default of his self-knowledge.And yet, here, where we would least expect a lucid response from a character already radically at odds with the principle of lucid response, Bartleby delivers his most sobering declaration of positive knowledge in the novel: “I know where I am.” Unlike the akrates who is defined by acting against best knowledge, Bartleby here demonstrates knowledge by/in default of action. Knowledge is radically split from action rather than action working against knowledge. At this moment we may be tempted to infer Bartleby’s lack of will, or his extreme weakness of will, and mistakenly conclude that abstinence of will is being proffered as the path to knowledge. But because it is more precisely lack of action that makes his will-to-knowledge so unintelligible, Bartleby’s personal cognizance is effectively eliminated as a springboard for further interpretation.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 157
Aesthetic Corrigibility
157
Where Bartleby is represented as a site of knowledge without intelligibility, and in light of the akratic narrator’s diminished capacity for such knowledge, only the reader remains to imagine what might count as better reasons for crediting the intelligibility of Bartleby’s experience. In this way, the reader is bound to correct both the narrator’s notion of Bartleby’s will as strong, and his or her own notion of Bartleby’s will as weak. But we must not fall into the trap of thinking that the simple choice between weak and strong will constitutes the basis of knowledge that we seek here.“Weakness of will” is of course one commonplace definition of akrasia. And adopting it, we might even be tempted to balance the fault we find in the narrator with a comparable fault in Bartleby.We would thus be licensed to wash our hands of both of them. But it is precisely the commonplace definition of akrasia that I have resisted in these pages, because it presupposes an a priori and fixed standard of rationality. It instances a mode of reasoning that is not unlike the discreditable stance adopted by the narrator, when he ties Bartleby’s fate to the dead letter office: “Dead letters! Does it not sound like dead men?” (“Bartleby,” 45). If only because the knowledge denoted in this crudely reductive causality narrows the otherwise expansive narrative scope of human experience, we would be well advised to seek an alternative strategy. I believe that we would do better to engage the process of contextualization, rather than any privileged context of rational expectation, in order to arrive at a satisfactory explanation of Bartleby’s character in this fiction. In fact, weakness of will, understood in strictly Platonic terms as a failure to make action accord with an a priori principle of judgment, precludes the course of action that I am alleging the reader is set upon here, precisely insofar as it shirks the burdens of contextuality. Socrates’ understanding of akrasia as a practical syllogism—x is the correct action where y is the case; thus everywhere that y, x is necessarily rational— is inadequate precisely because it precludes any ambiguity about what would count as y. In “Bartleby,” of course, we are deprived of just this privilege of self-certainty, by the ultimately seismic unsettling of the ground of the narrator’s judgment. It is perhaps because all such judgments, and emphatically those of Melville’s reader, are revealed to be densely situational, and thus resistant to the purity of a priori principles, that the Aristotle of the Ethics contradicted the Socrates of the Republic: Aristotle proposes that incontinent reasoning can be remedied by “good deliberation” (euboulia) (Ethics, 262). Good deliberation would be an explicitly calculative enterprise sensitive to contextual
Singer.book
9/12/03
158
11:21 AM
Page 158
Aesthetic Reason
variability over time. For the same reason,Aristotle unexpectedly postulates a “good incontinence” (Ethics, 229) where, by demurring the presumed best reasons for acting, one avoids the pitfall of converting an a priori principle into a stubborn compulsion. It corrects an insensitivity to the contextual particularity of the situation in which one musters reasons for one’s actions.Thus, to unthinkingly adhere in one’s actions to a presupposition of best reasons would be, for Aristotle, tantamount to mere obstinacy in the face of quotidian mutabilities. It would inhibit the capacity to change one’s mind that is the rational prerequisite of corrigibility and my prime reason for adducing akrasia as a framework within which we might see aesthetic practice as a mode of cognitive corrigibility.15 Correlatively, Aristotle argues against the notion that incontinence is a feature of character that could be considered independent of the character’s contextual situation.To determine an act to be incontinent with respect to a rational standard of best-reasoned action,“it becomes necessary to inquire with regard to the condition in question. . . . For it is clear that the person who acts incontinently does not think it is right before he finds himself in the situation” (Ethics, 228; my emphasis). In fact Aristotle stipulates that good deliberation, in this context, assumes that rational choice must be treated as distinct from rational wish.This is because he takes choice to be a situational variable of the narrative ordering of events, proairesis. No less significant, in the Ethics Aristotle makes an invidious comparison between art and virtue, seeming to admonish the artist to assume new ethical burdens beyond the bounds of aesthetic artifice.16 In the artwork, merit is embodied as a quality of the object. Virtuous acts, by contrast, are not meritorious because they possess a quality, but because “the agent acts in a certain state” (my emphasis), in other words, the agent “chooses” what he or she is doing. It is worth noting here that the field of narratology—a quasi-ethical substrate of literary studies—similarly does not countenance narrative intelligibility independent of some protocol of choicemaking, even in the pursuit of universals.17 Narratology thus lends some support to my construction of Melville’s narrative art as a crossable bridge between aesthetics and ethics. It perhaps even helps us to understand Aristotle’s tendency to confuse the realms of aesthetics and ethics, by chiasmically interweaving the technical terms that bear on choice in the texts of Poetics and Ethics; proairesis, phronesis, peripeteia, and hamartia are Aristotelian counters for choice that have roughly equivalent consequence in the forms of tragic drama and the drama of ethical life.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 159
Aesthetic Corrigibility
159
Indeed, choice-making in a narrative dimension orients every particular to a moving horizon of universalization. For the good deliberator, then—whether under the banner of aesthetics or ethics—it would seem that acting upon any a priori principle necessarily entails the modification of that principle, where the particular case that solicits its application is nonetheless not a perfect fit. Changing one’s mind then becomes as important a variable of striving for continence or enkrateia as knowing what it is right for the mind to make itself up to do. It should go without saying that the mind makes such knowledge a trajectory of adequation rather than a standard of adequacy. In this regard, it is worth remarking that good deliberation, or Aristotle’s good incontinence, would seem to be a matter of reconciling a universal with a particular in a situation where, because the terms of fit between them are mediately indeterminate, there is a mandate for scrupulously determining new relations of fitness. In that way the concept of character is made coherent with the problematic of development, not to mention the ethical imperatives of dramatic emplotment. What is more, if the person whom we suspect of acting incontinently “does not think [of what is right] before he finds himself in the situation” then the judgment that akrasia is in occurrence might arguably be assimilable to the project of accommodating a progressively capacious scope of contextual knowledge.As I have already indicated, for this reason if no other, it becomes virtually impossible to think of akrasia and enkrateia except as a continuum of experience. Likewise, it becomes difficult to think of error apart from a scenario of corrigibility. I am, of course, suggesting that this is the situation in which Melville’s reader finds him- or herself in “Bartleby”: especially in recognizing the continuity of his or her own interpretive task with the “aesthetic interpretations” that are ever more antagonistically promulgated by the narrator. And as I have claimed previously in pointing up continuity between the “character” of the narrator and the “character” of the reader, this situation may be seen as the most beneficent complement to the narrator’s bad incontinence. Despite his precipitous and compulsive recontextualizing of his own actions toward Bartleby, the narrator’s stated best reasons for any given interpretation of Bartleby’s conduct reprise an obstinately self-justifying rationality that mitigates the ethical purport of rational purpose. It effectively preempts the situational complexity unfolded in Bartleby’s seemingly obstinate presence on the narrator’s premises. Consequently, what so graphically appears to be Bartleby’s obstinacy in the narrator’s blame-casting rhetoric becomes a counter for the not-so-apparent obstinacy that under-
Singer.book
9/12/03
160
11:21 AM
Page 160
Aesthetic Reason
writes the narrator’s own aesthetic enterprise.We only need to remember that he quite unselfconsciously proposes that the work we are reading redeems what would otherwise be “an irreparable loss to literature.” Since his every response to Bartleby is so relentlessly an effort to authenticate the aesthetic merit of his own narration, the professed disinterestedness of his aesthetic motive now deserves to be exposed as the art forgery it is.Any belief we might want to sustain in the ethical stakes of art depends on it. We have already seen that what the narrator alleges would be lost to literature is purveyed, at the beginning of the narrative, as the reader’s own stake in the narrator’s aesthetic competence. Because the fate of literature, so to speak, thus devolves, through the unraveling of the narrator’s aesthetic pretensions, to the reader’s deliberative burden, we now have a plausible basis for reformulating what counts as aesthetic competence.And because this standard of competence is explicitly linked to changeability of mind, it is conducive to treating corrigibility through akratic knowledge as the means of assessing that competence.
IV The best test of the reader’s aesthetic competence is thus met by determining how Bartleby’s own apparently will-less knowledge can be reconciled with a proper—neither akratic nor obstinately egotistical— willfulness, what we might call, after Aristotle’s prompting, a good incontinence.As usual, we are guided onto this path of more beneficent willfulness by the narrator’s bad example.The narrator’s fallibility on this score is most egregious in his lengthy and self-consciously artful appreciation of the nicknames of his employees, which he somewhat disingenuously asserts were mutually self-conferred: Turkey, Nippers, and Ginger Nut.The narrator’s fastidious disclaimer, that he did not impose the names himself, is rendered dubious by his meticulous rationalization of the names. He is only too quick to demonstrate how the names are duly an “expression of their respective persons” (“Bartleby,” 15). In any case, the aestheticizing smoke screen of the nickname—nicking personhood in the gesture of personification—even more egregiously obscures the narrator’s evasion of a decisive action with respect to Turkey’s and Nippers’s employment. It is not lost on us that the narrator would otherwise have to accept his duty to fire the incompetence that the nicknames confess, as a test of his lawyerly professionalism.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 161
Aesthetic Corrigibility
161
Turkey, whose name is intended to evoke his florid,“pursy” demeanor and portly stature, is fit for work only in the mornings. Nippers, afflicted with a “brandy-like disposition” (“Bartleby,” 16), and Turkey’s antithetical complement in pallor and physique, is fit for work only in the afternoons. The “fit” between their names and their natures endows the metaphorical logic by means of which the narrator contends with their complementary periods of unfitness. He improvises the poetic justice, so to speak, of their perfectly complementary schedules:Turkey is put on call in the morning, Nippers in the afternoon. Nevertheless, what the narrator purveys as the aesthetically pleasing feat of balancing weaknesses against strengths serves him as an overly generous reason to retain the two employees in lieu of the harder, which is to say, more consequential, choice-making that would demand a standard of higher performance from each or require dismissing them both.“I made up my mind to let him [Turkey] stay” (16) the narrator avers in the most decisive tone. But in his exhaustive proof of the ways in which Nippers’s eccentricities balance against Turkey’s, the narrator reveals how the making up of his mind amounts to a stark evasion of decisionmaking. He is making up his mind—putting on the appearance of decisiveness—in the manner of the stage actor, not the competent agent. Here we recognize the telltale symptom of akratic judgment, propped conspicuously in this instance on a weak sense of aesthetic value.The dubious “beauty” of the balancing act supplants any understanding, in the narrator’s mind, that the circumstance he contends with is an imperative of action.The beautiful balance beautifully exemplifies the occasion for a dissociation of aesthetic value from practice, or productive agency. It is exhibited in the manner that I earlier associated with eighteenth-century trends toward a diremption of aesthetic theory from moral theory and political practice. By conjuring the dubiously “aesthetic” appearance of efficiency in his office, in lieu of the efficacious fact, the narrator himself might appear as an admonition against what could ensue from the reader’s own failure to assume the duty of distinguishing appearances from facts. It is a duty that, of course, assumes the very productive agency that passively indulged appearances otherwise negate. And we can easily intimate how such a productive revaluation of appearances would have the further advantage of remedying the dissociation of value from practice. The concomitant threat and challenge to the reader’s sense of this duty is posed most urgently when the narrator links the “success” of his aesthetic practice as an office manager to evidence of the reader’s
Singer.book
9/12/03
162
11:21 AM
Page 162
Aesthetic Reason
own “nice perceptions” (“Bartleby,” 22). He subtly posits the aesthetic sense as a bond of universality between himself and the reader. Needless to say,“nice perceptions” constitute our most clichéd touchstone of the theories of taste and beauty. So the reader’s suspicions should be aroused when the narrator essays to conduct a “taste” test to authenticate his expert judgment of the reader’s gifts. The narrator relates an inflammatory remark—tendered before noontime by an employee whose name he withholds—made in response to Bartleby’s first insubordination. The narrator then solicits the reader’s identification of the speaker in question, by a process of logical deduction that is only too ready to hand: our knowledge of the administrative design of the law office allows us to conclude that only Nippers could exhibit such a fiery humor in the morning hours. In so flattering the reader’s ability to appreciate the “beauty” of this logic, the narrator is presuming upon the reader’s solidarity with his “designing” will, in the naturalizing guise of a “proven” aesthetic attunement. It is emblematically a passive consensus, rather than a working protocol of reasoned agreement. Therefore, if the reader of “nice perceptions” is to avoid complicity in the narrator’s increasingly dubious personal conduct, he is almost perversely encouraged to disclaim the aesthetic register of perception altogether. And, as is always the case where aesthetic judgment is invoked to disguise the substitution of an ornamental value for the active production of value—where value precludes practice, art supplants life—the reader’s only recourse to remaining within the looking glass of appearances is an assumption of agency that looks as little like the narrator’s axiological self-deception as possible.This choice is paradigmatic for all of the episodes in Melville’s narrative. In each, the reader’s competence may be gauged by his or her distance from the narrator: such distance obtrudes whenever the narrator’s fallibility is exposed as a will toward aestheticized value, where a value-producing aesthetic will is wanted in its place. Thus is the notorious quandary of Bartleby’s will subtended to a standard of aesthetic value that the reader is compelled to produce, by the default of that which the narrator produces for the reader. By increasingly vivid contrast, the narrator produces only the akratic spectacle whereby an image of action is substituted for the relevant act, where the ethical universal that the narrator’s aesthetic idealism aspires to is belied by the narcissistic motive that the narrator’s aestheticism most immediately serves. In a manner of speaking, the stakes of this narrative thus come to depend on the reader producing a better artwork
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 163
Aesthetic Corrigibility
163
than the narrator. In other words, Melville solicits the reader’s artfulness as an amelioration of the akratic predicament that earmarks the narrator’s art as a flawed enterprise in the first place. With this frame of analysis, I of course realize that I am proposing a radical departure from the prevailing critical commentary on Melville’s text, preoccupied as it is with more abstract speculation upon the state of Bartleby’s will. In my defense, I would suggest that the advisability of that line of interpretation is sufficiently mocked by the narrator’s own fruitless scholarly perusal of “Edwards on the Will, and Priestly on Necessity” (“Bartleby,” 37), to discourage us from pursuing it. If the akratic will cannot be remediated by the narrator’s resort to canonical philosophical meditations on free will and necessity, we are bound to invoke a mode of agency more pragmatically suited to the peculiar circumstances of the case at hand. So, I believe, rather than worry about the strength of Bartleby’s will, it makes better sense to imagine that the reader, caught in the recognition of the narrator’s akratic dilemma, must distance him- or herself by means that resemble, if not a more perfect continence, then, perhaps, the perfectibility of Aristotle’s good incontinence. A quick overview of the narrator’s many akratic maneuvers throughout Melville’s plot cues the reader’s need to improvise such alternative actions.The reader is admonished to prefer, to take an active part, rather than passively to assume, that is, to retreat into the kind of imaginative speculation that has so manifestly failed the narrator.This admonition is clear in the narrator’s own confession that assumptions, compared with preferences, make one vulnerable to overpowering feelings of pity, vanity, pain and anger.18 For these are the sentiments that flow from the narrator’s ill-fated assumptions about Bartleby’s nature. These touchstones of sentiment are the evidence of the narrator’s own ineffectuality and, less self-consciously, the earmarks of his self-indulgent aestheticizing of Bartleby’s character. Indeed, from the moment that the narrator touts Bartleby’s serviceability in “purchas[ing] a delicious self-approval,” the reader is alerted to the purely decorative nature of the narrator’s feelings. We must begin to suspect the personality that such ornamentation is intended to flatter. The first of the narrator’s akratic maneuvers sets the pattern of culpable aestheticism. The narrator’s discovery that Bartleby has been inhabiting his premises rather than working on them elicits what he announces is a sense of pity. But apparent pity is quickly exposed as a self-serving occasion for more poeticizing, replete with the telltale artistic embellishments of allusion, elaborated image, melodramatic expostulation, and locutionary rhythms of eloquent homage:
Singer.book
9/12/03
164
11:21 AM
Page 164
Aesthetic Reason
What miserable friendlessness and loneliness are here revealed! His poverty is great; but his solitude, how horrible! Think of it. Of a Sunday,Wall street is deserted as Petra; and every night of every day it is an emptiness.This building too, which of week-days hums with industry and life, at nightfall echoes with sheer vacancy, and all through Sunday is forlorn.And here Bartleby makes his home; sole spectator of a solitude which has seen all populous—a sort of innocent and transformed Marius brooding among the ruins of Carthage. (“Bartleby,” 27–28) The most eloquent irony in all this is that at the end of this paean to pity, the poetry of the narrator’s strong feeling is exposed as the pretext for a brutal disaffection. A crudely rational deduction takes over, driving him to the conclusion that unrequited pity converts to personal pain and therein constitutes a license for emotional revulsion.The irony is torqued by the alacrity with which he couches this emotional logic in the terms of his own aesthetic nature:“To a sensitive being, pity is not seldom pain” (“Bartleby,” 29). Presumably, those sensitive enough to feel pity as pain are entitled to compensate themselves with a release from the responsibilities of feeling that jettisons all objects of compassion.The “natural” conversion of a highly theatricalized pity for the scrivener, into a solicitation of our empathy with the narrator’s own pain, highlights the narcissistic underpinnings of the narrator’s aesthetic goodwill. And the reader who can see how every appearance of the narrator’s goodwill toward Bartleby—for example the modulation of pity into poetry—registers as a conversion of thought into feeling will not forget that feeling is precisely the bad faith premise of the noncognitive aesthetic that I have been so suspicious of from the beginning of this discussion: for its compulsive scapegoating of reason, for its evasion of the duties of action. When Bartleby implores the narrator to “see reason for yourself” (“Bartleby,” 32), the better to comprehend the scrivener’s decision to quit writing altogether, the narrator concocts a nakedly self-delusional rationalization: too much copying has dimmed his employee’s vision.The reason that the narrator summons to warrant such a notion, thereby once more relieving himself of the burden of taking action against Bartleby, is conspicuously tendered as a feeling—“I was touched” (32). But because this feeling is aroused exclusively by the narrator’s own aesthetic fabulation of good cause for Bartleby’s otherwise mysterious behavior, and not by Bartleby himself, it is discreditable as nothing more than autoaffection, a further
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 165
Aesthetic Corrigibility
165
ornamentation of the egoism to which the self-mystifications of the noncognitive aesthetic is prone. In fact, the aura of mystery has habitually been conflated with the aesthetic aura by the ego-inspiring theories of genius and sublimity that flesh the intellectual spirit of English and Continental Romanticism. On the one hand, the conflation is typically explained, by the critics of imagination, as a compensation for the unequivocal lack of “good reason” in art. On the other, it is explained, by acolytes of the Romantic imagination, as the intimation of a good sense that is beyond the power of reason. Melville glosses this debate by having the narrator characterize his plan to dismiss Bartleby from the premises in terms that almost grotesquely mimic both attitudes toward aesthetic perfection/valuation. The narrator purveys the subtlety of his plan as an instance of superior genius. But it is also a “beautiful thought.”The more he thinks it, the more he is “charmed” by the thought. When the plan fails miserably to produce its desired rational effect, to drive Bartleby from the premises, the failure is interpolated into the metaphysical register of an “all-wise Providence,” another familiar counter for strong feeling. Again feeling releases one from the duties of choice-making and action.The narrator concedes,“Others may have loftier parts to enact; but my mission in this world, Bartleby, is to furnish you with office room” (37; my emphasis).The narrator’s, by now, telltale aestheticization of action is exhibited in the understanding that the charity he would show to Bartleby, by surrendering to the role of his brother’s keeper, manifests his indisputable disinterestedness (37) with respect to his personal pursuit of worldly pleasures. From the reader’s viewpoint, this pursuit of worldly pleasures has always been the narrator’s most unselfconscious touchstone of aesthetic inauthenticity. The crowning irony is that we must consequently contend with the impoverishment of ethical concern that lurks within the narrator’s standard of aesthetic disinterestedness. In the final episode of Melville’s narrative, the reader is once again (and contrary to appearances) given occasion to contemplate the aesthetic attitude as an immoral divestiture of those responsibilities that we bear toward other persons that human interestedness, other-wise as it is, otherwise entails. Disinterestedness, the metaphor for metaphysical interests that the narrator entertains as a self-congratulatory “virtuousness,” is shamefully literalized in the narrator’s final abandonment of his patronizingly aestheticized other to the prison-house of physical materiality: a state that is judgmentally echoed in the entombing walls of Bartleby’s final confinement. On his final visit to the Tombs, the narrator comes upon Bartleby’s
Singer.book
9/12/03
166
11:21 AM
Page 166
Aesthetic Reason
corpse, apparently sleeping in the prison yard.That Bartleby’s demise must be comprehended through the deceptive semblance, and hence aestheticizing appearance, of sleep alerts the reader to the need of some more artful account of events, if we are to have access to what appearance obscures. What is called for at this moment is precisely what is missing from each of the narrator’s other akratic maneuvers, purveyed as they are in the guise of aesthetic rationalizations.We will recall that, typically, they are culpable by inhibiting a deliberative rationality that might mitigate the moral dilemma otherwise so obstinately apparent in Bartleby’s presence on the narrator’s premises. In fact, we might consider that the common literary-critical practice of treating Bartleby as an uninterpretable or unreadable case,19 aestheticizes his behavior in the very manner that I want to hold the narrator accountable for. It makes passive appreciation an excuse for evading the deliberative burdens that any further imperative to action would impose. This foreclosure of deliberation, in the name of aesthetic detachment, presents the definitive obstacle to ethical understanding/action. In the absence of such understanding, Bartleby’s case remains the most meretricious ornament of the narrator’s attitude of disinterestedness. In other words, absent some deliberative means greater than those the narrator exhibits, his aestheticization of Bartleby seals that character’s fate hermetically— and, not coincidentally, in the manner of museum curatorship. Bartleby becomes an exhibit in a glass case to which the narrator holds the key. By thus cordoning Bartleby off from the reader’s deliberative agency, the narrator denies to Bartleby the very solidarity with humanity that his own final aestheticizing benediction so sentimentally implores albeit on his own behalf. And yet I do not want to place undue emphasis on the trammeled sentiments of Bartleby’s character. Melville’s readers have not infrequently observed that Bartleby is as little a full-blooded character in this narrative as his “I prefer not to” is a forcible illocution. I tend to agree. I believe that Melville makes Bartleby serve more strategically as a counter for the question,What kind of deliberator can the reader be by comparison with the narrator? than as a locus of empathy with the character. I therefore want to suggest that this author’s more urgent purpose is to elicit from the reader a finer articulation of the deliberative disposition to which the narrator turns a blind eye. Although it is leveraged against Bartleby’s “character,” I believe that the conundrum of the reader’s deliberative skills is most conspicuously figured in the narrator’s elaborate couching of the codex of the dead-letter office in
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 167
Aesthetic Corrigibility
167
a rhetorical question. For the question too theatrically presupposes an answer (or the reasons that might guide an answer) that the narrator disingenuously confesses that he himself cannot articulate:“When I think over this rumor [of the dead-letter office] I cannot adequately express the emotions which seize me. . . . Dead letters! Does it not sound like dead men? . . . can any business seem more fitted to heighten [a pallid hopelessness]?” (“Bartleby,” 45). In this context, the overdramatized unanswerability of the rhetorical question obliquely infers a deliberative means that might be available to the reader, if only because it now invites us to be abstemious of judging/interpreting Bartleby according to the “principles” of the narrator’s “story of Wall Street.” Such abstemiousness is obviously not to be confused with the attitude of disinterestedness. It is more significantly the potential for an interest in other explanations of Bartleby’s fate, particularly ones that do not so reifyingly serve the self that brings the story to its self-inflating poetic conclusion. On the contrary, were we to accept the glib poetic logic of the dead-letter office, we would become complicit in foreclosing deliberative possibilities by equating aesthetic value with the narrator’s own efficient closure. Such complicity would confer the legitimacy of the narrator’s ethical course, under a standard of aesthetic success that has already been revealed to be only too manipulable as an ethical dodge. I believe that a careful reader cannot ignore the ethical burden imposed by this line of thought. It clamors for recognition in the irony that all the narrator’s moralizing about dead letters—“on errands of life they speed to death”—causes us, at the most climactic moment of the plot, to contemplate his professed compassion for Bartleby in terms that evoke the most dispositive knowledge of the liabilities of akratic action. Dead letters are, after all, the most moribund presentiments of unintended consequence. Moreover, their own unintended evocation of the menace of akrasia prompts us to an account of better intentions with respect to Bartleby’s fate. Given our cognizance of the deliberative obstacles posed in the narrator’s rhetorical questions—and because they are an index of the obstinate narcissism of his aesthetic practice— any account of better intentions would be bound to entail a mode of self-questioning that is coherent with Aristotle’s faith in a good incontinence. This will seem especially apt if we recall that good incontinence, for Aristotle, mitigates personal obstinacy by inducing a more expansive horizon of choice-making.20 The reader, dissuaded from crossing the universalizing bridge proffered between Bartleby and humanity in the narrator’s concluding benediction, stands on a threshold of the incommensurability of particularity
Singer.book
9/12/03
168
11:21 AM
Page 168
Aesthetic Reason
and universality. But because the choice between these terms is no longer a foregone conclusion, as it was for the narrator, inveterate universalizer that he is, the act of choosing must devolve to an open-ended questioning of the criteria by which we choose. Felicitously, this questioning would be an inducement to contemplate distinctions rather than to mitigate them—as the narrator does by his glib generalization of Bartleby’s fate to the limits of the human condition,“Ah humanity!” The candidly acknowledged epistemological gulf that would open between the reader and Bartleby, upon our refusal of the narrator’s benediction, thus presents the very condition of intelligibility that the narrator himself could not abide (sentimental aestheticism likewise does not abide such differences) when it yawned between himself and his ever more artfully rendered protagonist. I am not, however, suggesting that by obtruding this distance, Melville means to absolutize incommensurability.This would be tantamount to conceding an indeterminacy, as unproductive as that conjured in the ethos of aesthetic disinterestedness. Rather, I think it is fair to speculate that Melville’s prompting us to accept the difference/distance between ourselves and Bartleby intimates a course of action that ought to have presented itself as the more ethical alternative to the narrator, in his opportunistic aestheticization of Bartleby. It is a course of action that we might now usefully characterize as reasonable adaptation to difference. I believe that adaptation would be de facto deliberation where the meaning of Bartleby’s behavior remained belligerently indeterminate, and our responsiveness to that difference respected its built-in narrative constraint—I am thinking of the narrative circumstance in which every inadequate response to a situational conundrum tutors a fuller account of the means of response that will be available in any future encounter. In this case indeterminacy would be the leverage of more diverse determinations. We are certainly acquainted with the notion that ethical idealism demands a willingness to accept the difference of others as a mandate for selftransformation—one’s own adaptability. Contrastingly, we have judged the narrator’s aesthetic attitude to be ethically malign where it was fastidiously designed to match (rather than adapt to) the aesthetic indeterminacy of Bartleby’s “I prefer not to.” That is to say, the narrator mirrors the indeterminacy of Bartleby’s ambiguous locution with the comparatively bogus indeterminacy of his own scruple of disinterestedness.21 I believe that the unwitting irony of the narrator’s success in this didactic, aesthetic mirroring of differences is that it introduces the issue of art forgery and the specter of his own culpability on that score.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 169
Aesthetic Corrigibility
169
Not coincidentally, the grub-man in the Tombs, answering the narrator’s suspicion that Bartleby is “a little deranged,” replies: “I thought that friend of yourn was a gentleman forger.”The narrator’s reply,“No, I was never socially acquainted with forgers,” confirms, by belying it, his knowledge of the forger’s art. Forgery is after all the premier métier for belying differences under the delicate ruses of aesthetic harmony and autonomy. Harmony and autonomy are the ever more conspicuous stock-in-trade of the narrator’s dubious artifice as he fastidiously knits up the loose threads of his tale. If, alternatively, aesthetic authenticity can be given parity with thinking how the difference of others demands a self-differentiating scruple on our part (because neither harmony nor autonomy will do), then the reader’s own ethical responsibilities must issue in the production of “other” stances toward Bartleby that do not disingenuously offer to stand in his place.The content of these other stances is not nearly as important as the disposition to take another stand toward that object, which, fallible inquiry concedes, it will never absolutely comprehend. That is to say, I am more interested here in the reader’s cultivating a disposition toward adaptation than in any specific, and perforce idealized, adaptation that would purport to do perfect justice to Bartleby’s condition. Such forbearant understanding on the reader’s part would represent a measure of corrigibility. It beneficently contrasts with the way in which the narrator’s representations of Bartleby perpetrate the displacement of his humanity. In retrospect, such representations might be fairly seen as forgeries of the aesthetic, insofar as they alienate aesthetic production from the world that it purports to represent— what I earlier saw in terms of the dissociation of production and consumption.The reader who understands the liability of such representation is bound to make better art than the narrator, just as the akratic character makes a better character for himself out of the knowledge of what he did not suspect about himself—or more specifically what he did not know to expect from that grasp of the world in which he aspired to act. Such corrigibility in human character depends on something like granting Bartleby’s difference from all other men, not as an ontological proposition, but as a labor of self-reflection for the ever more tolerant self. In fact, the standard of aesthetic “authenticity” I have identified as “thinking with a self-differentiating scruple” remarks the logical underpinning of the case so far. I have subjected both the aesthetics of disinterestedness and the philosophical conflation of akratic action with pure irrationality to considerable critical scrutiny in this essay. I have
Singer.book
9/12/03
170
11:21 AM
Page 170
Aesthetic Reason
objected to their metaphysical disjoining of the “chosen” self from that which differs from it: the mind from the body, the reason from the passions. Melville, in my reading of “Bartleby,” invokes an alternate version of the aesthetic that, precisely because it obviates such dualisms and thereby refuses to disjoin choice from choice-making, shows us once more the necessary continuity of akratic experience with enkratic character.According to the principle of that continuity, the self depends on what is different from itself as a source of questions about what might suffice as reasons for one’s own best behavior. One might ask if the more appropriate response to Bartleby should not entail a query about the narrator’s and, by extension, the reader’s tolerance for self-alienation.What else can one think of one’s own impatience with the eternally patient Bartleby than that there are other ways of being patient? Thinking with a self-differentiating scruple is always a matter of answering questions one would not have posed oneself, thus opening a pathway beyond the inhibition to becoming (rather than merely being) oneself. Such a process of becoming participates conceptually in the continuity between production and the commodity.This appreciation of Melville’s art helps us to see that where we understand that corrigibility is character, and does not presuppose it, it is perhaps the best exemplar of aesthetic making. This understanding accords with my broader effort to generalize the reference of the aesthetic beyond the comparatively narrow confines of the artwork, without losing sight of the artwork as the indispensable fulcrum of any such labor.The liabilities of that narrowness I hope are apparent in my view of the narrator’s injustice toward Bartleby.That injustice is most glaringly manifest in the rationalizing machinations that succeed (at least from the narrator’s point of view) in turning Bartleby into a reputable artwork, namely, one that will display the refinement of the artist’s sensibility as an example to all.We cannot fail to notice that the unambitious lawyer, who introduces himself as a lone voice in the first pages of Melville’s narrative, ends with an exhortation to all humanity as if he has earned the entitlement to that audience. Hence, my reading of Melville’s aesthetic practice (and especially by invidious comparison with Melville’s ironic deflation of the aesthetic practices of his narrator) anticipates a wish to shift the reference of the term aesthetic from the denotative register of the artwork qua object. It would more suitably reference a métier for coming to terms with the formal and hence actantial constraints that the work of art imposes on knowing. In this case, Bartleby’s status as a work of art depends on the reader’s ability to labor, ever more particularly, under
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 171
Aesthetic Corrigibility
171
the constraint of that character’s inscrutability, without conceding inscrutability to be an essence of character. What is most conspicuous in Melville’s trumping of the aesthetic ambitions of his own narrator is how the matrices of akratic action have served the necessity of this stance.They make the aesthetic enterprise into a practicable métier of human character—one that outstrips the devices of characterization that are, otherwise, so self-preemptively grounded in the banal repertoire of the narrator’s aestheticism. By this means, they make it possible to shore up the invidious distinction between the narrator’s passive aestheticism and the activity-based repertoire of aesthetic practices to which Melville’s reader is so conscientiously recruited. Most important, the corrigibility of the aesthetic character in this regard does not presuppose a standard of correctness. Rather, it mandates the adaptability of standards to the reflective needs of subjects: particularly subjects who know they cannot fully anticipate the circumstances within which they can ever give a full account of their best purposes. We will see in the following chapter that it is the possibility of giving a credible account of these purposes that most emphatically aligns Melville’s reader with the enterprise of the Enlightenment. Since the eighteenth century, aesthetic theory has alternately subscribed to and fallen afoul of Enlightenment ideals. This has been the result of its efforts to reconcile subjectivity with the tragedy of unintended consequences. I have attempted to show how such tragic knowledge inflects personhood as character. Now it is appropriate to consider how the postulate of an aesthetic character, advanced in this chapter, might be conceived as precisely what makes the enterprise of Enlightenment an ever more viable humanist pursuit. Melville gives us reason to think it might be so, even in the face of a crisis ridden modernity that is most bedeviled by the avatars of Enlightenment subjectivity.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 172
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 173
6
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics [E]veryone can be happy, if only he will capitulate fully and sacrifice his claim to happiness. In his weakness society recognizes its strength, and gives him some of it. His defenselessness makes him reliable. Hence tragedy is discarded. Once the opposition of the individual to society was its substance. It glorified “the bravery and freedom of emotion before a powerful enemy, an exalted affliction, a dreadful problem.”Today tragedy has melted away into the nothingness of that false identity of society and individual, whose terror still shows for a moment in the empty semblance of the tragic. . . .This liquidation of tragedy confirms the abolition of the individual. —Max Horkheimer and Theodor Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment
Enlightenment is proverbially a movement to trump the inscrutable laws of what affects us as Nature’s chaos with the strict scrutability of human lawfulness.1 The tragic circumstance that inspires Enlightenment is commonly figured as a condition of darkness. It glooms in the absence of that insight that might otherwise light a human path through the natural world. For the tragic Greeks, the conditions of this darkness were diagnosable in terms of the fallibility of instrumental reasoning: reversal of fortune, the incurring of unintended consequences, the irony of fate.While reason was conceded to be a belated enterprise, by comparison with Natural or mythic necessity, the condition of belatedness was nonetheless embraced by the Greeks as a serviceable—however imperfect—project of knowledge.Without even a belated rationality such as that conferred on Oedipus, or more accurately on the demos of the Dionysian festival, the meaning of experience would be oppressively general. It would be so in the indistinguishability of human fates, in their submission to the departicularizing anonymity of the unknown. Such generality chokes off the motivation for particular
Singer.book
9/12/03
174
11:21 AM
Page 174
Aesthetic Reason
agency and forecloses on the historical purpose that tragedy potentially endows upon Enlightenment learning. I have discussed at length how the aesthetic is, by its anchorage in the senses, a preserve of particularity and so a culturally conspicuous resource for checking this tragic generalization of the meaning of experience. Aristotle’s aesthesis, which David Wiggins has aptly called a mode of “situational appreciation” is, in that characterization, already a vehicle of human choice-making, a prompt for action within a context of competing prospects.2 In this regard the aesthetic proffers itself as an unexpected but fortuitous collaborator with the enterprise of Enlightenment against the specter of tragic fate: without which the selfrecognition of the Enlightenment subject—our particularist antidote to tragic generality—is arguably inconceivable. For, as the scene of suffering in tragic drama so vividly attests, it is only on the threshold of aesthetic nature that the enlightened subject can solicit recognition of its freedom from the thrall of unenlightened existence.The aesthetic is furthermore an unexpectedly apt collaborator with Enlightenment insofar as it is well attuned to the condition of belatedness that Enlightenment rationality concedes as an inescapable point of departure. Because aesthesis begins with the senses but attains self-realization through a transformation of the givenness of sensuous existence, aesthetic experience is structurally deferential to what we now might call the deliberative imperative of narrative development. Aesthetics, even in the pre-Aristotelian practices of Greek poetry, and certainly after the theorizing of Locke and Hume, takes the adequation of particularity to a moving horizon of experience as the staging ground for self-recognition.The aesthetic thus puts the subject on a course of judgment that subordinates truth to the variability of modes of confronting it. It might be said that the aesthetic lends itself most productively to the project of continuing Enlightenment by grooming a character suitable to the deliberative rigors of the scene of self-recognition—where what one sees depends on a capacity to diversify and develop the practices of seeing.The fate of Oedipus hangs in the balance between these possibilities. This is a character whose expressive will, as we have seen in earlier chapters, resides in the skills of adaptation and learning, in a repertoire of deliberative practices that presuppose the essentiality of act to knowledge. Under the auspices of this character, it is arguable that the cause of agential knowledge, which Enlightenment ambition (from the fifth-century b.c. Greeks well into the eighteenth century in Europe) sought to carry successfully against the tragic circumstance of hapless human
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 175
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics
175
ignorance, cannot hope to succeed without recourse to the aesthetic. Such an idea is of course inimical to the assiduous compartmentalization of the aesthetic implemented by Enlightenment rationalists in the reigning eighteenth-century theories of taste and beauty.The Enlightenment theories of taste and beauty had the paradoxical effect of certifying aesthetics as a proper discipline of knowledge only so long as it had almost no range of practical application in the world of rational choices.What the eighteenth-century Enlightenment tragically accomplished in that feat of compartmentalization was a diremption of mind and body so total that it rendered reason a threshold of self-alienation. Or such is the diagnosis delivered in Horkheimer and Adorno’s critical retrospect of Enlightenment that, not surprisingly, seeks recompense in a rethinking of the aesthetic.And indeed much has been made of the paradoxically “tragic fate of Enlightenment thought” along these lines.3 But seldom is this facile “aestheticization” of Enlightenment diagnosed in terms of a failure of Enlightenment aesthetics itself. In this chapter therefore I am motivated to show how inflecting aesthetics as a deliberative practice may undo the sequestering of the aesthetic from reason, by which Enlightenment aesthetics confounded its means with its end and, in that way, potentiated the “tragic fate of Enlightenment thought.”This revision of aesthetic value thus proposes to realign the aesthetic with the philosophical means, and not merely the too readily fetishized ends, of Enlightenment thought. I will try to make the case that aesthetics might thus render Enlightenment thought a more effective antagonist against the tragic experience which Enlightenment was unwittingly led to recapitulate: especially when it failed to recognize the rigors of tragedy as a resource of the aesthetic. Not surprisingly, for my purposes the least aesthetic of theorists, Ludwig Wittgenstein, gives us the most powerful corroboration of the rightness of subordinating the standards of taste and beauty—which instantiate the man of taste—to the deliberative practice that instantiates the tragic protagonist.Wittgenstein performs a comparable opening up of the sacred temple of Enlightenment idealism onto a field of quotidian practices. As Richard Eldridge avers in Leading a Human Life, Wittgenstein himself essays to continue the Enlightenment by questioning our post-Romantic desire to elide practical performance by “subliming explanation” of our actions into a faculty, such as reason, or a disposition, such as virtue.4 For Wittgenstein, this amounts to a shirking of the responsibilities of action in the name of something higher, which, by such dubious exaltation, mystifies the relation of action to knowledge.Wittgenstein’s relevance to the task of revising Enlightenment
Singer.book
9/12/03
176
11:21 AM
Page 176
Aesthetic Reason
aesthetics, in order to put it more in sync with the goals of Enlightenment, is apparent in the way the terms of his critique—the subliming of explanations—echo the jargon of conventional aesthetic theory and intimate its reform. Such subliming of reasons has been the standard operating procedure for high Enlightenment aesthetics.This practice continues under the sanctions of latter-day aesthetic theorists who take their cue from the category of sublimity per se: the aesthetic attitude school of Monroe Beardsley, the emotivistic theories of Suzanne Langer and R. G. Collingwood, and the psychic distance theory of Bullough, not to mention the formalism of the American New Critics. A Wittgensteinian appreciation of the way in which principles can only be known in the performance of practices, therefore, dovetails well with my effort to turn the aesthetic away from the noncognitive sanctification of immanent values cut off from the very productive practices that give them issue. Just as Wittgenstein proposes the interdependence of concepts and conceptual performances, so my advancement of a cognitive aesthetic proposes some meaningful habitation of the gap between affective states and the world of their implementation. Only such an initiative holds out a reasonable hope for reintegrating the aesthetic with the life of practices out of which the inner life of subjective expressivity is continuously produced. Let me be clear, however. I am not proposing a full-scale Wittgensteinian reading of the aesthetic. Rather, I appeal to the subject of Wittgensteinian inquiry as an indication that the revision of aesthetics in relation to yet unfulfilled Enlightenment goals is powerfully coherent with otherwise seemingly nonaesthetic, philosophical efforts to reconcile reasons with experience.The subject of Wittgensteinian inquiry merely intimates the philosophical merit of my efforts to imagine an aesthetic subject that would be a suitable match for the tragic experience that philosophy so “heroically” contends with. Such a subject continuously produced, and so reciprocating with the means of productive agency (without reifying the agent), has already been characterized as fundamentally choice-making: adaptive, learning by error, all in all a scrupulous deliberator.We have likewise seen that she is the prototype of the tragic protagonist. And it is here that the affinity of aesthetics with Enlightenment thought is most urgently marked by the Enlightenment’s address to tragedy.The point of view I am adopting here depends upon seeing that the aesthetic, conceived as a preeminently productive practice, is as much an antagonist of tragic experience as tragic experience is the nemesis of Enlightenment— notwithstanding that the aesthetic may indicate a different way of using
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 177
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics
177
reason toward Enlightenment ends. In any case, I warrant that it would be a way that is consistent with a Wittgensteinian pragmatism, directed against the metaphysical drift of Enlightenment rationalism. Paradigmatically, tragic experience poses the menace of the unknown to Enlightenment mind. It is the warrant for a mentality that “aims at liberating men from fear and establishing their sovereignty.”5 It is a warrant for activity. And yet, as Horkheimer and Adorno point out, the Enlightenment, by addressing the menace of the unknown through the systematizing rigors of epistemological universalism, makes the mistake of seeking the complete transparency of Nature as the only adequate countermeasure.This produces the hegemony of experientially indeterminate abstract principle and invites the diremption of theory and practice. In short, it heralds the return of the unknown in the guise of a “knowing” subjectivity divorced from active life. For Horkheimer and Adorno the liability of this abstraction is most apparent in our recognition of how it is anathema to the Greek beginnings of Enlightenment played out in tragic drama. It is most egregiously so in the way that the rationalist goal of perfect transparency marginalizes the irony of action, that is, the complexity of the world in lived, as opposed to principled, experience. Greek tragedy is certainly a crucible for the struggle of mind against the unknown. But in its specifically poetic function—in the structural dynamics of emplotment, especially—it shows us how much the aesthetic is implicated in a struggle for subjective self-realization that cannot devolve to indeterminate principles such as those of high Enlightenment reason.This is the case precisely because the tragic protagonist is so inescapably caught up in the necessity to choose his or her fate in a determinate context of insufficient knowledge, rather than in an indeterminate context of perfect knowledge. Indeed, conventional aesthetic theory founders repeatedly on a comparable ideal of formal perfection: too often the ideal of formal perfection tends to mitigate any account of the practical knowledge that would enable its attainment. In that respect, aesthetic theory is the best index of how far removed we are from its own origins in the tragic arena. Horkheimer and Adorno contend that we must return to that arena if we are to become honest brokers of our fate.
I Jean-Pierre Vernant and Pierre Vidal-Naquet’s important reconfiguration of Greek thought and literature, Myth and Tragedy in Ancient Greece, provides a compelling framework for examining what I am character-
Singer.book
9/12/03
178
11:21 AM
Page 178
Aesthetic Reason
izing as the struggle of the aesthetic against indeterminate and metaphysically fixed principles: principles that would otherwise put aesthesis in league with the eighteenth-century Enlightenment idealism of reason. By the same token,Vernant and Vidal-Naquet implicitly show how the aesthetic artifice of tragedy serves our desire to fend off tragic experience in a way that can be construed as carrying on the Enlightenment under a different protocol of reason.Thus we need not revert to the incommensurability of sense and reason that, for Horkheimer and Adorno, produced the increasingly brutish tragedy of twentieth-century political history. The relevant artifice here is the unequivocally productive and defiantly speculative will that Vernant and Vidal-Naquet identify with the tragic protagonist, formed as he or she is in the rigors of reversal and recognition. Almost anticipating the argument I am advancing here, Vernant, in his sections of Myth and Tragedy, sees the tragic protagonist most paradigmatically as a counter for the realms of art and politics. For the tragic protagonist has provenance in a political selfconsciousness, relatively new to fifth-century b.c. Athens, that assiduously blurs the lines between these realms.Tragedy is invented in the seventh and sixth centuries b.c. by the tyrants (Vernant and VidalNaquet, Myth and Tragedy, 185),“those early representatives of civic community,” whose power and position was understood to be a function of individual abilities rather than heredity or constitutional inheritance.6 The turranos, a prototype hero who reigns under the authority of his actions, not his blood, is “a model of human rationality and theorizing [with] the capacity to move beyond accepted boundaries and opinions in order to image what was previously unimaginable, to transform the world through the power of one’s mind and speech, severed from the bonds of birth and history.”7 And yet the tyrant became a figure to be ritually purged (pharmakos). This scapegoating was literally theatricalized in public rituals of ostracism in the century before Sophocles.8 Those rites expressed popular suspicion of any individualism that claimed a sanction beyond the articulable and hence shareable rule of civic conduct. Vernant takes the quintessential tragic protagonist, Oedipus, to be the quintessential turranospharmakos. He is a problematic combination. He is the agent of a free will that escapes all bounds of civic law. But he is concomitantly the object of a civic hostility that will not countenance any individual’s pretending to embody the group by going outside its regulative bounds. Vernant points out that the moment of tragedy’s invention, in a form that features this two-sided protagonist, occurs coincidentally when
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 179
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics
179
the Greek law itself lacks a consensus about the proper conduct of individual agency. Greek law thus becomes a site for problematic knowing.9 In this moment the members of the demos must alternately trust that the law comes either from above or from within, without confidence that actions conducted under one assumption will not be thwarted by the other. The Dionysian festival, arguably an artifact of legal culture organized under the authority of the chief Athenian magistrate, the archon, and according to the same rules that operated in popular assemblies thus became an arena for programmatically doubting the nature and provenance of law.10 Vernant wants us to see that this contradiction is a hallmark of Greek enlightenment generally, and specifically fosters the deliberative burden with which individual agency, caught in such a contradiction, must contend. In other words, the figure of the tragic protagonist, whose actions outstrip the predictability of the law, and are therefore condemnable, has its precedent in a civic circumstance that is conducive to the behaviors by which that protagonist is so stigmatized. It is worth reminding ourselves, in this context, that the eighteenthcentury Enlightenment’s striving toward an ideal of the absolute transparency of law represents precisely the opposite case: it dictates an obeisance to the idea of universal law, or what I earlier called indeterminate principle of reason, as instrumentally prior to any conceivable action. On this account, as Horkheimer and Adorno elaborate it, the ideal of absolute law too readily serves the paranoid compulsion to address human behavior suspiciously—as fundamentally incontinent (akratic) with respect to the law.The Greek moment, by comparison, marks a time before the continent subject is imagined as an autonomous ideal.That is, Vernant gives us a picture of early tragedy as arising from a context of understanding in which something like akrasia assumes priority over enkrateia (continence). He thus encourages our thinking, along familiar Nietzschean lines, that continence is more a response to incontinence than a principle that incontinence betrays. Even more to the point, this modality of akrasia, fostered within the polis as a crux of both aesthetic and political life, militates against any notion of a law or rule that could be deemed to be independent of the practices in which the fallibility of the rule-follower is instantiated. It thus gives stronger motive to my sense that our proper redress to Enlightenment law, in its pursuit of overweening mastery, might involve a return to Greek tragedy. It would be best to take the tragic mode as a framework for human enterprise wherein law can be thought more expressively in relation to the most unpredictable needs of the law-
Singer.book
9/12/03
180
11:21 AM
Page 180
Aesthetic Reason
abiding citizen. Because the orthodox versions of rational law in the eighteenth century brook no akratic performance, they are arguably incommensurable with the human drama to which Vernant believes tragedy responds. Indeed, from Horkheimer and Adorno’s point of view, this insight might have forestalled the Enlightenment’s “liquidation of tragedy” (Dialectic of Enlightenment, 155)—aptly characterized in Dialectic of Enlightenment as a paranoid reaction to the bogeyman of akratic action.11 Inasmuch as they want us to see the paranoia motivating the “liquidation of tragedy” as a falling away from the practical culture of Greek tragic knowledge, Horkheimer and Adorno invite a provocative hypothesis: that the real ills of modern Enlightenment stem from our perpetuating the mutual exclusiveness of enkrateia and akrasia, under a law of reason that unjustifiably presupposes a standard of perfect enkrateia. In previous chapters of this work, I have asserted a counterintuitive continuity between akrasia and enkrateia that belies our rationalistic pride in unproblematic continence and correlatively inspires confidence in aesthetic practice. Here I prefer to focus on how the circumstance of the protagonist in tragedy epitomizes the continuity of akrasia and enkrateia. By such means I might explain better why I am alleging that the tragic protagonist is complementary to the aesthetic character, whose image I have limned in my account of the skills of adaptation, learning, and deliberation. I want to speculate that these aesthetic practices follow naturally from tragic artifice, since the definitive circumstance of the tragic protagonist is one in which the meaning of character, qua ethos, that is, under law, gives way to yet ungovernable circumstance itself. In this view the aesthetic crux of the tragic protagonist is precisely his or her mandatory deliberation about what is the most relevant context of knowledge in which to act. It is expressly a deliberation that does not presuppose a character to whom the action could be unequivocally attributed as a personal quality. Oedipus’s character, ungoverned by a law that has authority independent of his actions (and the errors proliferated in them), will ultimately be a function of which context of argument—Tiresias’s, Creon’s, the messenger’s—he assimilates to the question of who he is. Indeed, all of this reminds us that tragedy in Greek society is spectacle for thought (object) before it is dianoia (thinking subject) or even before it is poetics.Tragedy renders deliberative circumstance effectively prior to the character who deliberates. This is very like the circumstance, already discussed, in which the uncertainty of Greek law in the polis seems to render akrasia prior to enkrateia as a condition of human lawfulness.That charac-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 181
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics
181
ter is so deliberately a deferred proposition in tragic drama is indeed confirmed in Aristotle’s late but enduring formulation of plot in Poetics: there the quantitative register of complex, episodic plot action in tragedy trumps the qualitative register of character. Correspondingly,Vernant and other classical scholars make the point that the real novelty of fifth-century b.c. tragedy inheres in its discontinuity with mythic tradition, where lawlike knowledge did preempt experience. Likewise this innovation may be read as a break with an established concept of character. In sixth-century b.c. tragedy, knowledge of the mythic ideal comes to be mitigated by unpredictable determinants of plot. Mythic time is supplemented with narrative time. According to Vernant, such mitigation is most powerfully effected in the sixth- and fifth-century efforts to foreground the fictionality of a dramatic protagonist (Vidal and Vidal-Naquet, Myth and Tragedy, 243), whose exploits in literature would have been deemed real, in the era before that character was put on stage. Now this character has become a problem. Now as the action unfolds and through the interplay of dialogue, what used to be praised as an an ideal, the touchstone of excellence, is brought into question before the public.The hero becomes the subject of a debate and interrogation, that through his person, implicates the fifth-century spectator, the citizen of democratic Athens. From the point of view of tragedy, human beings and human action are seen, not as realities to be pinned down and defined in their essential qualities, in the manner of the philosophers of the succeeding century, but as problems that defy resolution. (242) The simple fact that the actor’s presence in the theater is taken as “a sign of an absence in the day-to-day reality of the public” (187) presumably makes the individual members of the public mindful of their own need to look beyond themselves for recognition of what they might hope to be. For Vernant the dawning of this problem reflects the degree to which the audience, and the demos that sponsors the play, had become so closely linked that the play could be fairly characterized as the civil body transforming itself into a theater (185–86). In doing so, the demos implicitly solicits that reciprocating recognition with otherness that the self-rationalizing spectatorship of the theater conscientiously tutors. By comparison, it is a skill that the “real” individual in the “real” social group subtly loses touch with in his or her
Singer.book
9/12/03
182
11:21 AM
Page 182
Aesthetic Reason
increasingly automatic conformity to group behaviors. Because this simple shifting of the ground of theatrical convention from myth to society denotes an insecurity about self-recognition, it might even be construed as a defensive bid, by the citizens of the demos, for diversifying the standards of self-recognition through which they know their places to be in doubt. In other words, I am suggesting that a psychological need occasioned by the realization of “the individual Greek in the audience who discovers himself to be a problem in and through the presentation of the tragic drama” (186) can perhaps find its satisfaction on a signal condition: that his mode of self-presentation becomes a practice of adaptation to other modes. In Vernant’s account, the effective subordination of character to life-circumstance is a “living” threshold of political identity, whereby the theatergoer crosses into the role of citizenship and vice versa. Such a métier for reconciling politics with art is a matter of making qua producing character, rather than finding one’s character in one’s daimon or fate, as the modes of myth would otherwise instruct. This reasoning begins to make more concrete sense of what I alluded to in Chapter 5 as the prospect for seeing the aesthetic as a “practical metier of character.” It furthermore underscores Vernant’s conclusion that “[t]ragedy thus opened up a new space in Greek culture, the space of the imaginary, experienced and understood as such, that is to say as a human production stemming from pure artifice” (Vernant and VidalNaquet, Myth and Tragedy in Ancient Greece, 197). My point here, however, is not simply to tease out an analogy between the audience and the demos, or by extension, an analogy between art and politics. Rather, I want to imagine what might be gained by thinking about how one’s place in the audience of tragic drama, as Vernant represents it, can be made into a knowledge that bears on the deliberative challenges—action in the world—of spectatorship.This is an alternative to conceding the caricature of the audience stuck in the narcissistic privileges of passive subjectivism—the historical the cul de sac of character identification. Because this challenge to passivity—which the member of the demos takes on as a civic duty—is now linked to aesthesis, both in the figuration of the tragic protagonist as well as in the tragic protagonist’s mirroring of the demos, it gives occasion for us to think afresh. We may consider how the aesthetic might be viewed more generally as a crux of human action in all contests between practice and principle, precisely because it denotes a situation where one does not have to choose between being an actor or a spectator, a subject or a citizen. Where this choice is not a strict imperative of identity, the scope of human activity is potentially broadened.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 183
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics
183
There is precedent for this ambition in the canons of Greek political thought about how deliberative practices instantiate character in action.The deliberation by which the protagonist turns him- or herself self into an agent does not presuppose a standard of fitness between a practice and a principle, which I take as rough counters for the roles of actor and spectator. Indeed, deliberation consists not in the application of a principle or end, but in the “chain of judgments by which reason reaches the conclusion that certain practical means can or cannot lead to the imposed end” (Vernant and Vidal-Naquet, Myth and Tragedy, 58). The act of taking a deliberative decision, what Aristotle called proairesis, is thus more a question of actively inhabiting competing contexts of choice-making than of transcending them in a globalizing principle, according to whose logic all relevant choices would be foregone conclusions. For in the “chain of judgments” that determine choice, it is the means available to the deliberator, more than the ends, that count.And intuiting the availability of the means is the practice of judgment par excellence. For example, Vernant explains, the choices made by a character/agent in the interests of good health do not aim at good health in an “abstract manner” because [t]he last judgment, made at the end of the deliberation, concerns the last means in the chain; it presents it as not only possible on the same grounds as all the others but furthermore as immediately realizable. From this moment on the wish, instead of aiming at health in a general and abstract manner, includes within its desire for the end the concrete conditions by which it can be realized. It concentrates on the last condition that, in the particular situation in which the subject finds himself, effectively brings health within his grasp. (Myth and Tragedy, 58; my emphasis). With this exposition, Vernant wants to make it perfectly clear that Greek culture had no corollary to our modern notion of will. Indeed, it saw choice as something that did not emanate from character or carry one to a predetermined realization of character (49–59), even if the ends of action were deemed to be coefficient with character.The deliberation that makes the hero a hero depends, in a way, on the evacuation of character conceived as a first or a final principle. For agency is something that exists fundamentally within the act of choice-making itself, in the persistent adequation of one’s “particular situation” to another. It is this distinctly unmodern idea of agency that appeals to me as a way of rescuing the modern enlightenment agent from the tragedy of self-alienated reason, so dourly lamented by Horkheimer and
Singer.book
9/12/03
184
11:21 AM
Page 184
Aesthetic Reason
Adorno. For it returns us to the framework of tragedy as an aesthetic form where our respect for the constraints of character have consequence for the refiguration of character. It is furthermore relevant to note that, in Greek society, any such consideration of deliberation as bearing on a refiguration of character must take into account the necessary conjoining of two key terms that are the actantial underpinnings of Aristotelian proairesis: hekon (what is willed spontaneously, volitionally) and akon (what is willed in spite of one’s spontaneous desire) (Vernant and Vidal-Naquet, Myth and Tragedy, 56).The conjoining of hekon and akon restricts decision making to a register of subjective changeability. It obtains in the requirement that the choice be immediately acted upon. Thus change bears upon the decision as a literally extenuating circumstance, namely, extending the range of applicability of dispositions to meaningful frames of action. Like the Kantian-Hegelian terms Willkür and Wille, hekon and akon speak for a continuity of practical desire and self-revision, without which any full appreciation of the decision maker as a self-expressive entity is unimaginable. More obviously, this hybridization of concepts of the will shows how willful choice-making inheres in a structural ambiguity not unlike the ambiguity structuring the arena of Greek law, out of which the tragic protagonist arises as a problematic character. In such circumstances as these, which Vernant equates with the “development of subjective responsibility” (69), it makes eminently more sense to see characterological enkrateia dialectically, with respect to a reversal of meaning, rather than to see it nominalistically. Such reasoning occasions a circumstance that is more conducive to elaborating the terms of deliberative necessity than to imposing a deliberative necessity in the manner of an indwelling Platonic character. Indeed, many critics favorable to this view agree with Horkheimer and Adorno that dialectic—because it vitiates a Platonic notion of character, and blurs the boundaries of deliberative will by treating contradiction as a defining feature of active mind—functions as the inner mechanism of tragic drama.Without it, tragedy cannot serve the deliberative needs of the Enlightenment subject. In Horkheimer and Adorno’s judgment, our post-Enlightenment debasement of tragedy, not coincidentally characterized as “the impoverishment of aesthetic matter” (Horkheimer and Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment, 124), follows from our abdication of the cognitive tensions of dialectic.We are dupes of those modes of undialectical and uncritical character-identification that, in the end, purge individuality in the name of “the individual.”
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 185
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics
185
Horkheimer and Adorno entertain the invidious contrast of a “good” versus a “bad” Enlightenment on this basis. It is a bid to “prepare the way for a positive notion of Enlightenment which will release it from entanglement in blind domination” (Dialectic of Enlightenment, xvi). In the interests of something like the elaboration of deliberative necessity, they equate dialectical self-consciousness with a broadened capacity for moral reflection. Accordingly, Horkheimer and Adorno’s critique of post-Enlightenment culture puts the emphasis not on character but on audience: the arena of spectatorship that we have seen the Greek notion of agency devolve to, in the fullest understanding of tragic form.What Horkheimer and Adorno have in mind here is an invidious comparison between the Greek demos and the mass audience of modern consumer culture, figured as activity and passivity respectively.The relevant tragedy here is that the mass audience of post-Enlightenment culture does not know itself as produced spectator. We have seen that the Greek tragic audience possesses knowledge of its being produced by the play, in light of the play’s “making” the member of the audience/demos into a problem.The mass audience is unenlightened because, as Christopher Rocco explains in Tragedy and Enlightenment, the culture industry, unlike Greek tragedy, “aims not to encourage moral reflection, invigorate debate or to elucidate distinctions that make judgment possible” (192). This is specifically interpreted as a default on the Greek understanding that the significance of tragedy “lay in a hopeless resistance to mythic destiny” (Horkheimer and Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment, 152). “Hopeless resistance,” like the stance of the subject instantiated in proairesis, presumes a stake in subjectivity that defers self-knowledge, by countenancing openness to action. What results, in lieu of Greek tragic knowledge, is an assimilation of the individual to the group so absolute that any contradiction that might otherwise have been a lever for critical reflection is obliterated.The unconflicted intelligibility of the world thus comes to be equated with a forfeiture of understanding. Unfortunately, too many sympathetic analyses of Horkheimer and Adorno, Rocco’s included, unwittingly perpetuate the failure of Enlightenment culture anatomized in Frankfurt School critiques, by undermining the praxis of politics itself. Rocco is justly inspired by the fact that the authors of Dialectic of Enlightenment construe Greek tragedy as a “model of critical political education” (Tragedy and Enlightenment, 197). But his enthusiasm for dialectic as a bridge between art and politics leads him too quickly to imagine that the remedy for undialectical Enlightenment is simply a full reflection of
Singer.book
9/12/03
186
11:21 AM
Page 186
Aesthetic Reason
contradictions (178). He imagines that a mere acknowledgment of differences, otherwise too efficiently rationalized away, will free knowledge from the self-imprisonment of rational success. But Rocco’s endorsement of thought reflecting “on its own contradictions” looks too simplistically forward to a “proliferation of possible sites and spaces where cultural meanings . . . might be (re)appropriated in order to resist . . . the imperatives of the commodity system” (196). We can see the political paucity of Rocco’s investment in the proliferations of meanings when we understand that it is meant to be an antidote to the Enlightenment investment in the production of meaning. By implication, Rocco holds the production of meaning culpable for the ideologically produced subject, as if the productive will leads inexorably to a reified agency. Paradoxically the acknowledgement of the produced nature of mind ends up making what is commonly construed as the “production paradigm of Enlightenment subjectivity”12 a scapegoat of the very critique it mobilized. Because (among other reasons) it vitiates rather than develops the subject/protagonist as a category that can sustain self-transformative understanding, this solution to the ills of Enlightenment precludes all that I have sought to engage by invoking the complexities of Greek proairesis. These complexities signal how tragedy produces a dialectical subordination of character to circumstance, such that character is still staked in a productive agency: albeit one that eschews any deliberation upon truthful necessity, in favor of what I have characterized as “the elaboration of deliberative necessity.” Contrary to Rocco, these formal deliberative incentives of Greek tragedy entail a knowledge of subject-production as a productive means in its own right.
II Rocco’s stance is, of course, a recognizable reflex of poststructuralist attitudes toward the metaphysical foundations of the totalizing subject. The irony is that French poststructuralism in particular has recently recast its critique of the subject as an attempt to reunite art and politics: the very union that I am claiming is already operative in tragic form, if only we would attend to the aesthetic aspects of tragedy. JeanLuc Nancy’s “aesthetic of fragmentation” is such a gambit. Nancy’s return to the aesthetic by way of the critique of absolutizing reason represents a new consensus of aesthetic theorists—including Deleuze, Derrida, and Lyotard—for whom the fate of Enlightenment mind
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 187
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics
187
remains the motivating context of thought.As I anticipated in Chapter 4, however, Nancy is particularly relevant to this discussion, and warrants extended treatment here because he makes the link between Enlightenment and tragedy a touchstone of his rethinking the aesthetic. He thus provides a framework for further examining the prospects of the aesthetic as a way of continuing Enlightenment in the face of tragic prospects. In The Sense of the World,13 Nancy takes the pre-Romantic, Enlightenment diremption of art and politics as the strongest motive for resorting to the aesthetic in the context of failed Enlightenment ideals. For Nancy, the return to sense, marked in aesthesis, portends an end to our “suffering” the unity of experience that is imposed upon us in our rationalistic forgetfulness of the multiplicity of sense experience. He proffers his argument as an attempt to avoid a “new tragedy” (150). But Nancy’s invocation of tragedy is not melodramatic. He sees tragedy as a touchstone for suffering that flows from a failure of the “sense” of Reason, namely, the failure of the Rational Sense.This, as we know, was Reason’s original motive for scapegoating the aesthetic sense—aesthesis per se. Nancy sees the genealogy of this suffering in a formulation that is not so different from that of Horkheimer and Adorno: Reason’s revenge against the frailties of sense always devolves to a sadistic mastery of all that does not “conform to the rule of computation and utility” (Dialectic of Enlightenment, 6). In Nancy’s account, Enlightenment Principle (meaning) opposes itself to the world of the senses (materiality). Under the authority of Enlightenment Principle, rational Sense then seeks to colonize the world by producing an ideal meaningfulness. It is doomed to fail in inverse proportion to its attempts to marginalize sense (aesthesis). For mind, driven by rational principle against the vicissitudes of experience, gives way to a paranoid consciousness of the world as merely the “brute sense” of physical suffering. Like all brute Nature, it is therefore perceived to warrant rational persecution. In order to escape this tragedy of culture, to get past the scene of suffering, Nancy urges us to see that the “world isn’t merely the correlative of sense, it is structured as sense and reciprocally sense is structured as world” (Sense of the World, 8). In this analysis Nancy wants us to comprehend our “suffering” of sense in a new way, that is,“without any kind of dolorousness whatsoever” (151). We are implored not to be seduced by that Enlightenment conflation of sense with tragic fate that fetishizes suffering.That conflation only recapitulates the very polarization of sense and reason, which alienated Enlightenment rationality ironically perpetuates, by obsessively returning us to its own point of departure.
Singer.book
9/12/03
188
11:21 AM
Page 188
Aesthetic Reason
Nancy’s assessment of what we have lost by disparaging the aesthetic as a corrupting handmaiden to Reason—as that sense of the world that too much needs to be made Sense of—strengthens my belief that the aesthetic, in the guise of Greek tragedy, might well serve our pursuit of Enlightenment goals: at least where the responsiveness of Reason to contingent experience is at stake. This is particularly so in light of Nancy’s insistence on the reciprocity of sense and world, and in light of his intuition that the critique of the Enlightenment world of Sense will lead to a “praxis of the sense of the world” (Sense of the World, 9): an aesthesis that does not get co-opted by conceptual understanding. But Nancy’s usefulness for my argument is most urgent to the degree that his “praxis of the sense of the world” perpetrates its own undoing—owing to what I would call an inadequate appreciation of the very conceptual complexity of Greek tragedy that Vernant purveys. I am, of course, in agreement with Nancy’s wish to put the aesthetic in the cause of ameliorating tragic experience, especially where the relevant tragedy is “the sacrifice of the senses” to the god of truth. But I am bound to dispute his wish to ameliorate tragic experience by eschewing tragedy altogether.This move is blind to the important formal-recognitional aspect of tragedy. I think Nancy’s own commitment to recognizing the multiplicity of the senses implicates him in this recognitional aspect. Unfortunately, in his worry that even to acknowledge the reciprocity of sense and world would risk a reversion to rational dialectic, and a reprise of the tragic sublimation of sense—the eclipse of aesthetics—I believe Nancy misses the prospect for a more practical relation between sense and world.This, I have been arguing, inheres in tragedy as a fulcrum of deliberative agency. Indeed, recompensing just such an oversight would seem to have been one reason for Horkheimer and Adorno’s nostalgia for the Greek world.Their diagnosis of modernity, as the impoverishment of the aesthetic, stems specifically from our modern will to liquidate tragedy rather than to reinhabit its forms. My discussion of Nancy therefore is intended to clarify why I think deliberation based on dramatic reversal, which is the structural pivot of tragic form, might be a better remedy for the diremption of thought and feeling than Nancy’s own posit of a nondialectical reciprocity of sense and world. Because this reciprocity obliges us to accept a fragmentation of experience that nullifies recognition, I see it as antithetical to the prospect for inhabiting tragic form. It is tantamount to Rocco’s licensing of unlimited contradiction as an antidote to tyrannical rationality. Nancy’s fragmentation is, in fact, a prospect that threat-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 189
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics
189
ens his own political utopianism, to the detriment of both art and politics. For Nancy rightly sees the diremption of thought and feeling as perpetuating the mutual exclusivity of art and politics. It invites the twin absolutisms of the nihilism of sensuous particularity on the one hand, and the terminal abstraction of rational myth on the other. Yet while his case for reciprocity is a valiant effort to dissolve the ideological polarities of sense and reason, nihilism and myth, by reversing them, he is ultimately fostering a reversal without end. Because Nancy effectively forecloses recognition in promoting unceasing reciprocity, he likewise promotes a praxis that would be all techne and no product. By so preempting any place for the aesthetic, as a work of art, as a proper poiesis, he also inhibits any understanding of form as bearing on formative agency. It might now be useful, therefore, to state this problem more directly in terms by which I have already characterized the form of the tragic protagonist in relation to the political formation of the demos. In that relation, art and politics are more mutually supporting propositions. If the license Nancy gives to the unceasing reciprocity of sense and world really expresses a preference for praxis over poiesis, giving priority to the agent over the work, we can see how he is bound to ignore the relation of the artwork to the creation of a deliberative space. Likewise he alienates himself from the original deliberative space in the Greek demos, which figures for me as a fulcrum of aesthetic production. Nancy’s preference for praxis is no doubt based on his well tutored post-Enlightenment suspicion that production qua product is always subject reifying. But by exercising this preference, he risks rendering art as an inactive and intransitive knowledge that would, in that way, be decidedly corrosive to political identity.To complicate things, while Nancy is suspicious of conceding that the aesthetic has anything to do with making art, insofar as he equates all making with making Sense at the expense of sense, he nevertheless does not want to give up art’s relation to activity. He therefore consistently appeals to the register of activity to authenticate the authority of sense experience. In this respect, Nancy’s “idea” of art seems inexorably linked to a principle of transitivity that courts some reckoning with productivity qua product or poiesis. We can see the full dimension of his problem where he strives to distinguish this activity from either idealist or subjectivist creation: he demurs to call art either poiesis or praxis. For him art is “another kind of doing” (Sense of the World, 134).Yet his ability to elucidate this doing only musters a negative, and hence relatively inactive, agency dubiously characterized in terms of the suspension of the
Singer.book
9/12/03
190
11:21 AM
Page 190
Aesthetic Reason
“enchainment of signification” (134).This familiar recourse to an “other” of signification weakens the claim that “another kind of doing” can do something better than poiesis or praxis, because it eludes any standard by which it could be known to be done. Things get worse at this point. Nancy, like Gadamer before him, exemplifies the suspension of the enchainment of signification by reference to the Greek artifact of the symbolon: the shard of a clay emblem of hospitality.14 It is broken upon the departure of friends who anticipate a future reunion to be formalized by joining the shards into a whole. For Nancy the symbolon, a token of the aesthetic,“has its truth in being divided” (Sense of the World, 136).What Nancy ignores in valorizing this fragmentation is that such doings, if the culture of the symbolon can sustain any analogy to action, are specifically done by virtue of an activity of recognition.Without an act of recognition brokenness itself is unrecognizable as such. Certainly the dividedness Gadamer glosses, by allusion to this symbolic practice of the ancient world, was, in that world, a pretext for community. Nevertheless, because the symbolon served as a threshold of self-recognition, as well as recognition of another, we ought not to take dividedness as an end in itself. However much recognition of dividedness, from Nancy’s viewpoint, is a necessary step in checking the impulse to identify the part with a metaphysical whole, or (extrapolating to the political arena) however much it is a necessary step to checking the Enlightenment coercion of the individual to identify with the already constituted group, we ought to resist the temptation to privilege dividedness over identity in such absolute terms. I do understand that, by way of the symbolon, Nancy means for us to see Enlightenment aesthetics as the failure of sensibility to actualize a nonrational sense that might resist the conceptual identifications otherwise inhibiting individual experience. This failure of sensibility to properly sense perception is pegged by Nancy as a tactical error of Enlightenment mind: induced by its too precipitous flight from Nature’s necessity. But, unlike Nancy, I prefer to treat this as an eminently corrigible rather than a fatal error of Enlightenment thinking.We can then imagine how the fragmentation that aesthesis forces reason to submit to need not be equated with such a radical suspension of “the enchainment of signification.” It might give way to the test of recognition that sensibility foists upon rational sense, when fragmentation remains a counter of cognition. More important, we could then imagine what such a test makes possible: the ensuing drama of learning. In this view the community ordained by the symbolon—when the symbolon is a
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 191
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics
191
token for the fragmentation of reason by sense—is assimilable to the role of the spectator who understands him- or herself to be a produced and hence a self-producing entity.That is to say, if one recognizes the fact of one’s being produced, one appropriates, in that recognition, the terms of productive agency by which one’s self-perpetuation can be understood as a purposive social enterprise. Nancy would instead give us the more limited proposition of the agent who exists at the expense of the spectator. Indeed, the way in which the form of tragedy can be seen to produce the spectator as a self-producing agent prompts us to see how the aesthetic dimension of the demos that it serves—where the spectator perceives him- or herself to have “become a problem”—induces the subjective labor of integrating fragments of experience without simply sublating parts to an organic whole. Nancy, in substantial agreement with the critics of Enlightenment such as Horkheimer and Adorno, fears that this sublation is inevitable under the production paradigm of Enlightenment truth. I agree with Nancy that truth “today . . . is no longer a matter of interpreting the world but of transforming it” (Sense of the World, 8). But the transformation he has in mind is extraformal, that is, a transformation that “affects the agent not the work” (9). It therefore indulges belief in the possibility of self-transformation as something that can happen without a practically reflective register for the self. Not surprisingly, for Nancy, the critique of the Enlightenment world, made possible by aesthetic means, looks toward the “end of the world” as a specular register of human activity.The end of the world is coming in the end of that concept of the world as existing “in relation to some other (that is, another world or an author of the world)” (8). When, Nancy says, there is no longer an essential relation between the world and another world or author, we must accept the proposition that “the world no longer has a sense, but it is sense” (8).This sense is meant to bring about a kind of suffering that is no longer tragic, because it no longer entails the sacrifices of the senses. But precisely because this sense cannot make sense, nor need not (that would be a compulsion of the production paradigm), it cannot be recognized as such. As we saw in Nancy’s seemingly contradictory swing between a bid for transitivity and a refusal of the agential resources of the production paradigm, his own grasp of the difficulty of his position is apparent in his assertion that the world that “is sense” is nonetheless dependent on “being toward another” (7).The new sense of the world that is sense does indeed seem to need some test by which it can be sensed otherwise.
Singer.book
9/12/03
192
11:21 AM
Page 192
Aesthetic Reason
Nancy seems doomed to produce such a contradiction between the sense that meets standards of recognition and one that is free of that constraint, because he is so bent upon disentangling poiesis from praxis. For he is too wedded to the understanding that poiesis subtends the oppressive telos of production. The possibility of praxis without poiesis is, for Nancy, a bid to salvage agency without telos. As I have already suggested, this might be a compelling position, in the face of ruthlessly instrumentalized Enlightenment teleologies, if the account of tragedy that I have unfolded here did not so clearly allow for an alternative point of view. Within that purview poiesis cannot be opposed to praxis.The production paradigm (poiesis, the work) does not preclude the self-transformative knowledge, or self-productive knowledge that Nancy otherwise seems committed to in the terms of “some Enlightenment” (8), albeit a “truly post-Romantic” one. Furthermore, I believe that the fairness of my posing this alternative here, as well as all the possibilities mapped within it, are conceded by Nancy himself when his pursuit of a praxis without poiesis prompts the question, “Could it be that one has to surmount (?) the distinction [between praxis and poiesis] and to manage a poiepraxis or praxipoetic thought?” (100). For me, the problem with raising the question in a form that privileges a simple reversibility of praxis and poiesis—in poiepraxis or praxipoiesis—is that Nancy seems bound to leave it as a rhetorical question. I would rather give the question its due. I would suggest that the question only really counts in the context of an answer such as that which the tragic protagonist gives in the ensuing action of plot, that is, in the moment when an agent accommodates new information to his or her sense of purposiveness in action. Nancy’s alternative idea that art, by demurring the presentation of an essence, becomes necessarily the “presentation of presentation” (Sense of the World, 138) is, in fact, not theatrical enough for my purposes. It does not accommodate an understanding of the way in which the constitution of the audience in Greek tragedy obviates a choice between being a spectator or an actor, while not dispensing altogether with these markers of identity, or giving up on the notion of a positional subjectivity inherent to them. Nancy’s distance from this knowledge is most appreciable when he explicitly calls for a “politics without denouement . . . without a theatrical model, or a theater that would be neither tragic nor comic” (111). But his seizing on denouement as the crux of the theatrical model misses the crucial aesthetic feature of tragedy that, I imagine, could be appreciated alike by Vernant and Horkheimer and Adorno: where we do not need to see an epistemological barrier between spec-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 193
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics
193
tator and actor (and yet respect their difference), we understand the difference between them as a field of choices that grows incrementally complex.We need to think of the shifting boundaries of identification between actor and spectator as a set of calculable ratios of what is known and what is deemed knowable. It prompts something like what rationalist game-theorists might call a motive for preference ordering. It makes a contrast with the terminal reordering of value that we equate with plot denouement, where divergent perspectives are reducible according to a fixed denominator of knowledge.The motive for preference ordering alternatively denotes a rational imperative to see divergent perspectives as integral to an augmented axiological calculus. In other words, by invoking preference order, I do not wish to imagine a specific hierarchy of values so much as a narrative of valuation, whereby one’s sense of what one wants is self-consciously tutored in the experience of error or failure to achieve one’s aims. Spectator and actor are one. In this circumstance, what is preferred depends on interaction with alternative contexts of expectation.This is what we presuppose in the fact of human intersubjectivity and what the theater figures in the very fact of performance. Despite important differences of intent between the rationalistic enterprise of ranking preferences in game theory and in tragic drama, both pursuits spring from the same motivational ground: the reciprocating knowledge of differently informed minds.The knowledge imperative of preference ordering, like the transitivity between spectatorship and agency in tragedy, sustains preference as a marker for subjective positionality. By means of this analogy between the plight of the tragic protagonist-in-demos and the rational agent, therefore, I want to see if we can escape what Nancy sees as the Enlightenment trap wherein transformative agency is transumed into interpretation. But by the same token, I want to elude Nancy’s own trap of valorizing transformation to the exclusion of any intelligible prospect for production.This approach to the concept of transformation makes it unworkable: literally incompatible with a program of human labor.As we have seen epitomized in the eighteenth-century theories of taste and beauty, and in the tenets of the aesthetic attitude schools, without an account of the productive labors inherent in aesthetic valuation, the category of the aesthetic is too easily “spiritualized” or subsumed to a glib aestheticism.We will not lose sight of the fact that aestheticism, in this respect, is a proposition that naively figures spectatorship as an autonomous role. In other words, I do think that we might surmount the distinction between praxis and poiesis that Nancy’s aestheticopolitical theory laud-
Singer.book
9/12/03
194
11:21 AM
Page 194
Aesthetic Reason
ably anticipates. But we may not do so, as Nancy imagines, by a praxis that he too tellingly valorizes as the nonpositional “absolutization of [their] relativization” (Sense of the World, xvi).This “absolutization” produces only the nonpositional and therefore highly untheatrical spectacle of one thing turning into another (xxvi). It invokes only the most pathos-laden sense of production as just another nod to terminal incommensurability (114). It reprises a perverse aestheticism in lieu of a potentially normative aesthetic valuation. It should be clear by now that I believe that tragedy tells us more convincingly that what connects praxis and poiesis is its own nonabsolutizing development of the idea of production. Because the tragic keeps productive agency in tension with spectatorship, it might be best understood, once again, by affiliation with the pragmatist Wittgensteinian point that standards (poiesis) and practices (praxis) are necessarily developed together.15 Indeed, this pragmatist insight comes with the admonition that conceiving them apart precludes that possibility of development altogether. Certainly Vernant’s respect for the deliberative register of the tragic hero is inconceivable along these lines. It is development, after all, that tragic emplotment presupposes as its most ineluctable condition of intelligibility. With these observations I mean of course to challenge once again the axiological drift of Enlightenment aesthetics, whereby the concept of genius—and the creation of its corollary, the formally perfect beautiful object—promulgates norms, which, by default of enough representational self-consciousness, seem to set the artwork free of the necessity of practice.We have seen that this produces a standard of taste that is as alienated from productive life as most standards of pure reason are alienated from the variables of pragmatic activity. I do not doubt that Nancy was right to thwart this state of affairs. But the alternative is not, as he seems to believe, to vitiate standards altogether, by abdicating any test of recognition that would keep standards and practices in play.The Wittgensteinian proposition urges us toward a better course: to realize that because standards are what practices produce, understanding how to make perfect, so to speak—according to any standard of artifactual making, aesthetic or otherwise—will require practices that alter our expectation of what any single practice can conceivably make perfect. It will raise the question of what standards might become applicable for future practices. Otherwise, the notion of making itself becomes incoherent with or irrelevant to conceptions of agency. The premise of this familiar pragmatism is already operative in tragedy, viewed as the spectacle of human need that drives tragic
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 195
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics
195
emplotment and constitutes a threshold of human self-recognition. But, under the auspices of the Wittgensteinian precept, we must also consider the proviso that need, like most human facts, is inconceivable without choices. Needs are real on the basis of how we recognize them, which is to say, how we create them on the basis of appreciating the interdependence of standards and practices.16 This version of reality, which Hilary Putnam inflects as “internal or pragmatic realism,” is specifically linked to reanimating the relationality of the agent position and the spectator position (Many Faces of Realism, 77).The agent position and the spectator position, as Nancy showed us, are unduly alienated from one another by the praxis-poiesis distinction. But unlike Nancy, who shuns making because he cannot see it as a complex of standards and practices, Putnam (following Wittgenstein and Nelson Goodman) has presented an idea of making that entails knowledge of the conditions under which the standard inherent in a specific “making” practice can be superseded by a new practice (78). In this regard, what we might now call poetic is already practical in the mandate it imposes for recognizing what needs are not satisfied, such that a new practice is necessitated. We cannot ignore the fact that fulfilling this mandate is, in large part, the spectator’s role with respect to the protagonistic agent of Greek tragic drama. Here we are reminded once more that tragic artifice implicitly figures spectatorship as an aspect of agential learning.17 Just as tragedy gives us a model for surmounting the praxis-poiesis distinction—by making us see how recognition (standards) and creation (practices) are complementary imperatives of our reality, namely, by making agent and spectator coherent—I now want to suggest that any aesthetic project, modeled on the practice of tragic poets, has epistemological repercussions coherent with Putnam’s realism and its address to the dichotomous ways of Enlightenment reason. By pointing up the affinity between the choice-making imperatives of the tragic protagonist and the standards and practices of Putnam’s realist disposition, we can see how such an aesthetic project might honestly purport to ameliorate certain Enlightenment dilemmas by producing a new narrative of valuation: understanding that all meaningful production is a working out of preferences, and that the imperative to do this amounts to a learning experience that sustains the agent’s fluency with spectatorship. Such a project aims at precisely the universality that art has long been touted to be a refuge for. But it does so in a way that is more conducive to the spontaneity of life that universality usually threatens to
Singer.book
9/12/03
196
11:21 AM
Page 196
Aesthetic Reason
denature, especially in the most naturalizing orthodoxies of artistic form. We have come to a point where we can now imagine the aesthetic doing the work of the universalizer, but in a way that forces a recontextualization of the universalist gambit itself. In this way it does not inevitably devolve—as it does in the paradox of Enlightenment perfection—to the frustration of art practice. It may therefore be the best reason to imagine art practice as a service to Enlightenment philosophy. At the beginning of this chapter I cited David Wiggins’s idea of the aesthetic as a “situational appreciation,” as a way of thinking about the aesthetic as a field for deliberative action. It is now appropriate to note that Wiggins’s characterization of aesthesis was specifically a response to the standard universalist proposition: that ideals of human existence must be approached through a deliberative protocol—where a rule can be presupposed for any attempt to realize a goal.This is comparable to the way in which the conventional notion of character ethos—thwarted in tragic plot—assumes the meaning of an action before the character embarks on the fulfillment of an action. And this is precisely the universalism that, in Horkheimer and Adorno’s view, must be laid at the doorstep of Kantian aesthetics. For these Frankfurt aestheticopolitical critics of the Enlightenment, the Kantian postulate of a maxim that would be fully adequate to a contingent practice—and could be summoned independently of the conflicts to which it would be adequate— fully motivates the Enlightenment flight from tragedy where conflict is an insuperable fact of life and artifice.Therefore, it is important to see how, against this account, Wiggins asserts an older position maintained by Aristotle. Aristotle, he says, simply does not permit rational agency, however secure in its maxims, to so spare itself “the torment of thinking, feeling and understanding that can actually be involved in reasoned deliberation.”18 That Wiggins characterizes the difference between these two positions in terms that indulges a “scene of suffering” as a beneficent site of deliberative agency, and that he equates thinking with torment and understanding, reaffirms my linking of the aesthetic to tragedy as a way of carrying forward Enlightenment ideals. In the role of the Aristotelian deliberator, Wiggins puts at stake the possibility of a reason that— because it does not subordinate itself to explanation or, in Nancy’s terms, to the “sense of the world”—suffers a pain that is productive. It is not the egregiously counterproductive, self-sacrificing pain of Horkheimer and Adorno’s enlightenment Odysseus.The scene of suffering, as Wiggins explains it, arises specifically in the Aristotelian knowledge that “in aisthesis . . . explanations give out.” This is to say that
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 197
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics
197
thinking becomes more laborious than truthful. Hence,Aristotle demurs from the rationalist’s temptation to deliver a maxim. Instead, as Wiggins explains, Aristotle gives us a framework that bears a striking resemblance to the productive vicissitudes of the tragic protagonist in demos: . . . what Aristotle provides—namely, a conceptual framework which we can apply to particular cases, which articulates the reciprocal relations of an agent’s concerns and his perception of how things objectively are in the world; and a schema of description which relates the complex ideal the agent tries in the process of living his life to make real to the form that the world impresses, both by way of opportunity and by way of limitation, upon that ideal. (Needs, Values, Truth, 237) What Wiggins’s deliberative universalizer and the protagonist-in-demos hold most conspicuously in common, by this account, is their openness to a reciprocity of relations with the world.This disposition privileges the widest repertoire of adaptations to any circumstance of human inquiry.There is an implicit understanding here that the ideal practical deliberator brings to bear on any situation the greatest number of pertinent concerns and understandings commensurate with the context of deliberation. Deliberative universalizing, therefore, is a maximizing of considerations rather than a maxim by which our worldly considerations are already valued.What is more to the point, however, is that Wiggins’s construal of this practical universalizer requires a “public scene” in which “moral agents are at once actors and spectators, and in which the ways actors act informs the way they see things and the way they see things regulates the way they act” (82). This of course recapitulates the experience of the tragic protagonist as an artifact of the political arena in fifth-century b.c. Athens. There we understood the political arena to be, in turn, a “stage” for carrying on, in the exercise of civic duties, the knowledge of reversal produced in the realm of the theatrical event. Indeed, when Wiggins evokes the “public scene” of his deliberative universalizer, and specifies that it is like the “events comprising a public rite” (82), he could be invoking the public scene of the Dionysian festival, which produces my sense of the aesthetic subject as just such a deliberator. These thoughts prompt a generalization that draws together several threads of my discussion so far.The aesthetic is now profitably seen as instantiating a public space where an agent’s maximizing of considerations—based, not on a presumptive rational practicality, but on the
Singer.book
9/12/03
198
11:21 AM
Page 198
Aesthetic Reason
reciprocity of actor and spectator—are put in the service of an ideal of practical deliberation.This “space” encompasses everything that has been at issue in my speculative view of the aesthetic as a vehicle for making us better deliberators and, hence, a practice that obviates the question of the immanence or transcendence of art. Such practice produces a beneficent blurring of the line between art and life. It is compatible with my earlier focus on protocols of training: training in reciprocal recognition, training the imagination to go visiting, training to accommodate error and translation.These are all perspectival frames wherein attempts to understand the nature of the aesthetic subject dovetail with the account of a subjective learning. It now remains to think more practically about works of art. I am especially interested in literary works that represent this instantiation of a public deliberative space as a mode of engagement with tragedy that, nonetheless, mitigates the inhuman determinism of tragic fate.We need to learn what to look for if we are to fully exploit the opportunity that I am alleging aesthesis, in this capacity, confers. Furthermore, if what is crucial to this enterprise is the dovetailing of a learning subject with an aesthetic subject, our inquiry will have to direct itself to works that expressly challenge the privilege conventionally given to spectatorial character over fictional character. My reasoning here is consistent with the Aristotelian idea, embraced by Wiggins, that character formation does not presuppose the choices of practical agency, with respect to the contexts of the character’s choosing to act like himself. Faith in character as an essential ethos, a standard of enkrateia, is complicit with the mistaken assumption of Enlightenment idealism that, as Wiggins typifies it, seeks “to circumscribe practical rationality by enumerating in advance its bases or its grounds” (378). Character’s tragic nemesis, in this respect, is the inescapable realization that our reasons for counting bases or grounds as our own, as belonging to our character, are incommensurable with our nature, coming to us as they do over the necessarily episodic, differentiated course of time in which we pursue them. Such pursuits constitute our perpetually short-sighted effort to secure faith in the possibility for an ultimate self-recognition, which no tragedy of fate can possibly obfuscate.That faith is a dream of commensurability—one that obviates deliberative necessity altogether. So it would seem that a specifically more rational alternative would be one that makes incommensurability itself an occasion—I have been arguing that tragic drama is already such an occasion—for refiguring character, rather than a melodramatic site of witness to the sacrifice of character. Such was the mythic arena that, Vernant avers, tragedy dis-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 199
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics
199
placed with the more deliberative arena of the civic agon.The alternative, to make incommensurability itself an occasion for reconfiguring character, would be procedurally compatible with what I referred to earlier as a circumstance that gives cause for “elaborating the terms of deliberative necessity.” It is antithetical to the deliberative exigency that is otherwise imposed upon personhood as a blanket judgment in the Platonic paradigm of character: the standard of perfect enkrateia or continence. Not coincidentally, this prospect for elaborating the terms of deliberative necessity arose out of an attempt to think about dialectic. Understood by Horkheimer and Adorno as the inner mechanism of tragic drama, dialectic displaces our identification with character— where necessity is a mythic rather than deliberative imperative of both art and politics—into a spectatorial arena. In the spectatorial arena our acknowledgment of the reciprocity of actor and spectator makes politics concede its ineluctable relationality to art and makes character accede to development without a predetermined end.We should understand this in the way that our abiding Aristotelian assumption—that the threshold of character is choice-making—dictates a standard of knowledge that will “never be exhaustively transposed into any finite set of objectives that admit of finite specification” (Wiggins, Needs, Values, Truth, 369). At this point we might therefore hazard a broader claim to be developed in the following section: that art is fundamentally about character development, with the proviso that it is the character of the actor-spectator that is pivotal.Aesthetic character, in my account, by its extrapolation from tragedy, already assimilates Wiggins’s conviction that “moral agents are at once actors and spectators.”Their common identity as practical deliberators under this presumption gives aesthetic work its ethical bearing and its most beneficent Enlightenment purpose.
IV One might well imagine at this point that the only literary form that could help us to think more practically about works of art that represent such an instantiation of a public deliberative space—giving art the ethical bearing noted above—would need to be the work of a high modernist Greek: only such an unlikely centaur would know how the engagement of tragedy entails an escape from the conception of character as an essential ethos or a standard of perfect continence. It should
Singer.book
9/12/03
200
11:21 AM
Page 200
Aesthetic Reason
be no surprise then if I look to James Joyce, whose thematics mark a confluence of Greek and European thought, and whose artifice cultivates the notion of the aesthetic as an overriding motive for art.There are few major literary oeuvres that so plausibly situate themselves in the nexus of the tragic and the aesthetic, with the purport of giving a broad account of Enlightenment modernity. And yet the Joycean novel, above all others in the canon of literary modernism, has become an icon of aesthetic autonomy, vested in a shamelessly uncritical notion of the “character” of the author. What is worse, Joyce’s well known principle of impersonality—stepfathered by Stephen Dedalus in dubious impersonation of two putative fathers of the aesthetic, Aristotle and Aquinas—seems to indulge precisely the Enlightenment prejudice of autonomous will that courts the cultural tragedy of the Culture Industry. In other words, my choice of illustrative text seems counterintuitive. I want to see represented in the Joycean text a Greek-tragic-born aesthetic that exploits the resources of tragedy for the sake of an Enlightenment that does not precipitate its own tragic reversal. I am therefore bound to show how Joyce’s aesthetic form permits us to read against the grain of the aesthetic pretensions ascribed to it. Accordingly, any attempt to see what family resemblances obtain between Greek tragic aesthesis and Joycean artifice will require the dismemberment of that “god of creation” through which the Joycean aesthetic has fleshed out the most patriarchal principle of modernist formalism. Only then might we see how Joyce promotes an understanding of the aesthetic as clearing the much touted deliberative space in which the fate of human character might be seen to be productively at stake, rather than ornamentally enshrined. I take this constraint of circuitous argument to be a salutary challenge, since, in the resistance it presupposes, it confirms the degree to which the aesthetic—true to the form of tragedy—compels knowledge out of krisis: whether it is knowledge of character per se or of any characterization of the aesthetic as a character-like principle that obtains outside the deliberative arena of human conflict. Moreover, by seeing in Joyce’s text how an authoritative aesthetic practice overthrows an authoritative aesthetic norm, we may be able to renew our faith in the necessity for theorizing the aesthetic in the closest proximity to artistic practice. For obvious reasons, I choose a work by Joyce that I think conforms, in its aesthetic complication, most closely to tragedy and to the Enlightenment-furthering prospect for reconciling tragedy with human productivity. I have alleged that this distinctly unsentimental reconciliation is proffered from Sophocles to Horkheimer and Adorno. In the
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 201
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics
201
structure of “The Dead,” Joyce enacts the displacement of character to a spectatorial arena in terms that are coherent with the Sophoclean burden of Oedipus: coming to knowledge through vicissitudes of selfreconfiguration. Indeed, in the organization of the Dubliners stories, taken as an ensemble, the continuity of character emerging, through an array of superficially multifarious protagonistic avatars, is the armature of emplotment. Joyce’s own pronouncement that, in the multiple protagonists of Dubliners, we see a “progression from childhood to maturity, broadening from private to public,” hints at how his aesthetic project overlaps with a view of aesthetic character predicated on the possibility of movement across the barrier between character and spectator. I have suggested that this easy movement is conferred in the deliberative arena of the Greek protagonist-in-demos, whose suffering is describable as a death of expectations for a previously imagined self. Therefore, we might pay special attention to the fact that the tragic fate of the protagonist of “The Dead” is orchestrated as a slippage between character and spectatorship that is figured as tragic death. In “The Dead” it becomes ever more starkly apparent that a death of character, in character, is the only viable “becoming” of personhood. Indeed, what is typically missing in readings of Oedipus the King that focus on the fate of character, rather than the resources for action harbored within character, is a full appreciation of the degree to which character in Sophocles’ play is conceded to be a process. In Oedipus the King, incommensurability of actions in time explodes the unity of characterological identity, but sustains the project of ethos as a practical exigency of living. Oedipus startlingly survives his personal identity, if only in the activity of the deliberator. He persists on stage in his ability to compel choice-making, or set conditions that refigure both the terms of recognition and the trajectories of life that such recognition might reflect. We need only consider the ambiguous closure of Sophocles’ play: Oedipus: I shall go—on this condition. Creon:What condition? I am listening. Oedipus:That you will send me away. Creon:That is the gods’ decision, not mine. Oedipus:The gods will not care where I go. Creon:Then you shall have your wish. Oedipus:Then—you consent? Creon: It has nothing to do with my consent. Oedipus: Let me go away from here.
Singer.book
9/12/03
202
11:21 AM
Page 202
Aesthetic Reason
Creon: Go then—but leave the children Oedipus: No! Do not take them away from me! Creon: Do not presume that you are still in power. Your power has not survived you. (lines 1510–22) When Creon answers Oedipus,“Your power has not survived you,” he unwittingly confirms, by his manifest complicity in the deliberative process, the survival of Oedipus’s character in a protocol that negotiates the incommensurables, in this case, powerlessness and power. It is conspicuously a protocol that is operative across the threshold of actor and spectator.The performative contradiction of Creon’s denial makes for the undeniability of Oedipus’s power. Likewise, I want to show that when this process is revealed to be at work on Gabriel Conroy, the protagonist in Joyce’s story, it focuses a reading of human tragedy as a métier for proactively accommodating the deliberative predicament in which tragic character might otherwise have to submit to a ritual of sacrifice.We might better appreciate the degree to which such an apparently antidramatic construal of Joyce’s story is nonetheless rich with the prospects for character development. I have held that no ideal of character based on a standard of continence can give insight to such development.This is especially clear if we follow Wiggins’s acknowledgment that all the real dilemmas of human life are defined by incommensurability. Incommensurability is, of course, an exigency of all plot conflict, where competing values make “autonomous, mutually irreducible demands upon us” (Needs, Values, Truth, 377). Wiggins reflects that when writers who have historically dwelt on the tragic or morally impossible in this respect have resisted capitulating to it, they have realized that “normal life” ineluctably ensues.We “learn” how, with proper training—such as I am alleging art avails us of—we can reach (that is, produce) accommodations between “autonomous mutually irreducible demands.”Thus we can learn to live with them.The prospect for such learning to live with “autonomous, mutually irreducible demands” is, I believe, what accrues to the reader who seriously contends with the rhetorical complexities of Gabriel Conroy’s fate in “The Dead.” Not insignificantly, such learning holds out the prospect for a kind of life after death. “Living with” denotes precisely the problematic conjunction of character and experience that is Gabriel Conroy’s nemesis in “The Dead.” At the same time, however, our recognition of the complexity of this challenge permits us to salvage some beneficent resonance from Joyce’s
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 203
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics
203
title. Otherwise, we are obliged to let it melodramatically echo the tragic fatalism to which I would suggest his character, taken as an embodiment of continent principle, is inescapably doomed.“Living with” is an idea of living that is anathema to Gabriel Conroy’s most intimate sense of the value of life. For it requires an accommodation of the apparent incommensurables of personality and family, art and politics, history and experience. Gabriel’s unsuitability to the task is most starkly apparent in his aspiration—everywhere in the narrative—to become a monument to character rather than an agent of character. It is an aspiration that is ironically projected in the narrator’s persistent observation of Gabriel’s likeness to the Wellington Monument.The monument stands immutably in the park, outside the social theater in which Gabriel must perform his most precarious roles: husband, nephew, patriot, and, most portentously, artist. The snow-covered monument is seen by Joyce’s reader to be as stiffly postured beyond the glass of the Misses Morkans’ window, as Gabriel himself seems to be, preening before the window in rehearsal for the dinner table speech by which he hopes to deliver himself of the most flattering self-image. The frosty glass to which Gabriel is repeatedly drawn is increasingly a mirror into which Gabriel looks to discover himself perfectly unrecognizable to his best intentions.What is worse, there is no recourse of communicability with what is so incommensurable to his desire. Gabriel Conroy is unable to “live with” others in very much the same way that the Greek tragic protagonist cannot live in a world where the “autonomous, mutually irreducible demands upon us” cannot be accommodated to one another. In Gabriel’s character this predicament is marked as a personal failure of deliberative resourcefulness, one that warrants invidious comparison with Wiggins’s good deliberator. The good deliberator succeeds by accepting an Aristotelian compromise: the best the agent can do in the process of living a life, in order to realize an ideal of self-worth, is to “articulate the reciprocal relations of an agent’s concerns and his perception of how things objectively are in the world” (Wiggins, Needs, Values, Truth, 237). This is a straightforward concession to the deliberative imperative of “situational appreciation.” “Situational appreciation” was, after all, Wiggins’s original paraphrase of Aristotelian aesthesis, and my point of departure for contemplating the relevance of a theory of practical deliberative reason to aesthetic value. Gabriel’s character, in respect of his own unwillingness to accept the Aristotelian compromise, is menaced by tragic fate in the most classical sense. His personal existence is placed at risk on the very grounds
Singer.book
9/12/03
204
11:21 AM
Page 204
Aesthetic Reason
upon which I established my first understanding of what forces tragedy marshals against Enlightenment desire: reversal of fortune, unintended consequence, irony of fate. I want to suggest, however, that Joyce, after Wiggins, prompts us to see how these are all versions of a fate that might prove to be less fatal if they were exploited as situations to be better appreciated.We might imagine that better appreciation would require an understanding, like the one Wiggins urges upon his normative rationalist antagonist, discontented as the rationalist is with having to trade off explanations for situations. It is a disposition to see how the accommodation of incommensurables depends more on the adaptability of concerns that lead us to invoke specific incommensurable values and commitments than on any attempt to change the values and commitments themselves.Those values and commitments are, after all, anchored more immutably in the circumstances of our acting. Given this disposition, a circumstance that would otherwise be fatefully accepted as a principle of rational cause—even one as seemingly terminal in its foreclosure upon a life of choice-making as the revelation of Oedipus’s crime—might reveal itself to be the matrix of an irreducibly practical knowledge: where choice-making ensues as an ineluctable fact of even the most unpromising fate (Wiggins, Needs, Values, Truth, 369).This is so for the demos of the Dionysian festival— bearing witness to Oedipus’s fate—even if the promise of life for the audience must extend beyond the limits of character.We have already seen how tragedy impels an understanding of character that self-consciously crosses the boundary between actor and spectator: Oedipus outstrips his audience’s understanding of his character just as he outstrips the terms of his character in claiming to know it better than anyone else. Now we must see how Joyce’s deployment of character induces a comparable activity of mind. Here it might make sense to speak of the reading experience itself as a “scene of suffering.” In this crucible of knowledge, the reader’s character is beneficently true to the caricature of the boundary crossing turranos-pharmakos, whom Oedipus both epitomizes and exemplifies. Gabriel Conroy’s lack of aptitude for “situational appreciation” as a métier of human identity—subscribing as he does to a more Platonic faith in a principle of continence—declares itself most frankly in his unresponsiveness to the manifold exigencies of choice-making that frame his actions.This unresponsiveness is indicated by his willingness to believe that human choice-making is a prerogative of imaginative will, unencumbered by the self-refiguring pressures of proairesis that burden the Greek protagonists. The vulnerability of Gabriel’s belief,
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 205
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics
205
however, is portended in the fact that its touchstones are exclusively topoi of artistic form/expression: there is the critical refuge of Gabriel’s reviewership at the Daily Express; the self-defining characterization of Browning’s poetry as “thought tormented music”; his recycling of the phrase as “thought tormented age” for the after-dinner speech; the conversion of his wife, Gretta, into a painting that,“if he were a painter,” would be titled Distant Music.These artifacts of Gabriel’s artful mind, inasmuch as they are markers of aspiring agency, are correlatively sites for choice-making that all presuppose an autonomous subject position. This is conspicuously opposed to the reciprocal positionality of actors and spectators denoted in proairesis.We need only remember the propitious conjoining of hekon and akon in the discipline of proairesis to understand what is at issue. In other words, Gabriel’s is precisely the aesthetic stance that Joyce’s own narrative will disabuse us of in the tragic spectacle it makes of his character: the unraveling of Gabriel’s aesthetic gambits will be seen as coincident with the demise of his character. Insofar as each of these aesthetic initiatives will be understood as sites for reversal of fortune, the tragedy of Joyce’s character will begin to appear to be a pretext for theorizing an aesthetic agency that will not submit to objectification in the work of art. Rather, it will subsist as a relation to the work of art. Joyce’s narrative, in the way that it rebukes his character’s unresponsiveness to the pressures of situational appreciation, follows the trajectory of Wiggins’s new universalizability. The mandate for universalizability in “The Dead” accrues, by the default of the characteraesthete, to the aesthetic practice of the author and the recognition of the reader.As was the case in Melville’s “Bartleby,” we will see here that the aesthetic development of the work obtains as a modification of the aesthetic precepts of the character. On this familiar threshold of the displacement of character by spectator (author/reader), the universalizer may then appear to be an even more relevant figure than I have already alleged, for comprehending artistic practice as something like the instantiation of a deliberative arena. For, as I noted earlier, Wiggins’s new universalizer does not make judgments out of will—rational or irrational. He subjects them to publicity tests, where incommensurable facts are adjudicated by appeal to a yet unarticulated standard of knowledge. In “The Dead,” Joyce perpetrates his character’s subjection to publicity tests by orchestrating ironic reversals that proliferate throughout the narrative. Even more to the point, we shall see how ironic reversal thus registers as a site of comparison for incommensurable values.
Singer.book
9/12/03
206
11:21 AM
Page 206
Aesthetic Reason
It is worth noting that, in Joyce’s text, ironic reversals of character fate have a distinctly Flaubertian ricochet. That is to say, greater and greater contextual freedom accrues to the reader in recognition of how the validity of his or her judgments bows to the exigencies of applying those judgments.The reader thereby comes to keener appreciation of a precept that Leo Bersani credits to Flaubertian aesthetics as an indispensable corollary to the concept of the novel: the universalizing aspect of art has to do not with the metaphysical aura of the work of art as a refuge for “immortal” truth, but with the fact that “art is a mode of being produced by a certain type of human work” (Bersani, Culture of Redemption, 135). 19 Bersani attests that such work, epitomized, for example, in the character-surpassing rhetoric of Bouvard et Pécuchet, cannot be disentangled from the reader’s appreciation of a necessity to always judge again the judgment of received wisdom.20 It is the task for which Flaubert designed his Dictionnaire des idées recues. It furthermore reflects the practical scruple of Wiggins’s universalizer, which can only be served by recognizing how our expectations of rationality must reconcile themselves to a plurality of ends. Or, at least, this is the case if we want rationality to be more than a closed system of belief. By this reckoning, we will see how Joyce’s ironic reversals are not just nullifications of judgment.They come closer to the feat of “elaborating terms of deliberative necessity” that has been of such salient interest in these pages because it offers a prospect for making judgment more integral to action. Because the relevant action in this case has to do with the belief formation of the individual readers, every complication of choices that requires a more elaborate claim of necessity in the course of this narrative brings them closer to the choice-making heroics by which the tragic protagonist redeems him- or herself from brute fatalism. The “work” of art, when rendered so laborious a discipline of choice-making, surpasses the knowledge availed by the ordinary universal artwork. For, in its presumptive immortality, the ordinary universal artwork effectively sublimes the exigency of choosing. I cannot imagine a better prompt for thinking of tragedy (along with Horkheimer and Adorno) as a means of enlightenment that does not succumb to Enlightenment’s temptation to purge tragedy. In order to draw the contrast between the distinctly unheroic character of Gabriel Conroy’s personal aesthetic, and what we might now call the “deliberative heroics” of reading, it is worth noting how Gabriel epitomizes what Dieter Henrich has called “the individual who lives under the self-image of autonomy.”21 This is a philosophical stance that Henrich traces to Jean-Jacques Rousseau’s willful confusion of freedom
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 207
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics
207
with natural beauty. In this perspective, the lack of any necessity to make distinctions in Nature is mistaken for the ontological truth of perception. It has the undesirable effect of severing the connection between aesthetic experience and structures of cognition. My contention here will be that Gabriel’s own aesthetic stance carries the seeds of this dilemma. The tragedy of Gabriel’s aesthetic, in this regard, is nowhere more clearly established than in his encomium to the “three Graces of Dublin.” Here an aesthetic gambit, placed in the service of a social ideal, tragically founders upon an unwillingness to make choices. Gabriel uses the occasion of celebrating the hospitality of his three hostesses to flatter his own good taste. He is trading in the very aesthetic attitudes that, we will retrospectively understand, have conspired to assure his selfdelusion, namely, his lack of spectatorial distance.What is most immediately emblematic of this fact is the reader’s recognition that Gabriel’s encomium is an unwitting parody of the “judgment of Paris,” itself the anecdotal beginning of aesthetic theory. For in invoking the paradigm of choice, Gabriel is nevertheless demurring choice: “I will not attempt to choose between them.The task would be an invidious one and one beyond my poor powers” (Joyce,“The Dead,” 204). As Gabriel himself puts it in disclaiming the possibility of doing justice to beauty, he would ask us to accept the “will for the deed.” Such a compromise constitutes the ethically culpable form of that abstraction from act to which any demurring of choice typically capitulates. Such abstraction is indeed what confers the metaphysical aura of art in place of the political experience that deliberation might otherwise confer. I might say more generally that Gabriel’s problem as a character is that, unlike Paris, he simply will not deliberate.This forbearance is the earmark of an aestheticism that rings most hollow in the pretentiously wrought phrase that Gabriel flourishes—in a review of Robert Browning’s poetry—as disingenuous evidence of his own artistic ability:“thought tormented music.”The phrase “thought tormented music” reprises the equally tortured dualism of reason and art that we have seen Enlightenment mind contending with in the pursuit of its cherished universal truths. Here the torment of thought or reason is stood in invidious contrast with the indivisible pleasure of art. It antagonistically evokes the deliberative necessity that typically obtains for judgment only in the absence of the kind of universalizing maxim that aesthetic beauty is commonly thought to supply. Ironically, it is the same deliberative necessity that Wiggins asserts the rationalist philosopher strives to avert when he or she rejects aesthesis or situational appreciation, preferring to
Singer.book
9/12/03
208
11:21 AM
Page 208
Aesthetic Reason
believe that all rational decisions can be made by taking refuge from experience in the logical order of the maxim.That Gabriel himself takes such refuge in formulating his critical maxim about Browning’s poetry implicates him in the sins of aestheticism and rational universalism alike. Indeed, the nugget of paradox contained within the phrase—that thought is its own victim—guarantees the judgmentally indecisive abstraction of the phrase from any context of practical meaning or application.The phrase thus becomes an aesthetical truism that obviates any distinction between its pure meaning and the contexts of its practical application And yet when the phrase is subsequently instrumentalized in the context of Gabriel’s dinner table speech—“Ours is a thought tormented age”—we have cause ourselves to deliberate critically on the hypocrisy embedded in it: that a truth that purports to transcend its contexts of usage can be so opportunistically, which is to say differently, used. When the phrase is so self-righteously recycled by Gabriel to characterize the age in which the “three Graces” are denied their aesthetic due by an impoverished public sensibility or taste, it becomes a pretext for our thinking how much the aesthetic pleasures, purveyed here, come at the cost of accounting for the differences by which the iteration is made possible. Gabriel’s discounting of the differences that his recycling/repetition of the artful phrase makes obvious links his aesthetic acumen to a fault of character. More important, it reminds us that without an accounting of such differences, no character—let alone phrase-maker—can make a claim to be meaningfully him- or herself over a course of successive moments in time. Without one’s own account of the differences that beset one’s experience as seeming incommensurables, not the least of which, in this case, is the incommensurable of generational experience that divides Gabriel from his aunts, one risks becoming the victim of others’ cognition that difference is the case. It opens the door to the kind of reversal of meaning/fate that Gabriel’s totemic aestheticism gives rise to here in the instance of its repetition. For Gabriel’s act of recycling the “artful” phrase “thought tormented music” does denote the occasion of the difference it belies, but in a way that subverts rather than realizes his identity.The reader will not forget how, earlier in the story, the evocation of this phrase by his colleague Molly Ivors betrayed the secret of Gabriel’s reviewing for the Daily Express, an English publication.The revelation of Gabriel’s authorship licensed Miss Ivors to deliver Gabriel’s comeuppance when he shied away from admitting the public identity—man of letters—that
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 209
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics
209
the review was privately intended to confer.The irony is that he could not acknowledge publicity, because the only identity that would be recognizable from a byline in an English publication would perpetrate a confusion of aesthetic and political purposes. By so hoisting Gabriel on his own petard, Joyce wishes us to see how the kind of aestheticism that Gabriel would indulge in here invites character reversal: without the recompense of any cognitive means by which such a reversal could be made coherent with character development. It is this fate that now I want to suggest Joyce spares his reader. Joyce’s art puts the reader under the deliberative compunction that his character shirks and thereby coaxes from the reader a more sophisticated aesthesis than Gabriel’s aspiring aestheticism can possibly comprehend. The crowning irony of all this is that the phrase “thought tormented music” mimics the very torment that Gabriel suffers, pulled as he is in his Christmas dinner speech-making between the sobering reason of social tradition and the intoxicating music of his lyrical autonomy. Joyce admonishes us that there is no escape into art from this torment.This is so to the degree that Gabriel’s artfulness delivers him from the responsibilities of the tragedy of his split nature. In effect, his artfulness denies him the reflective resourcefulness to see his split-ness as such. He thus succumbs to indecisiveness about being an agent or a spectator, instead of taking the tragic protagonist’s initiative to be both an agent and a spectator. Gabriel’s entire performance as a character alternates between the roles of actor and spectator. But never is one articulated with the other. He does not “suffer” these contradictions as incommensurables, so that some more general way of ranking the differences they instantiate imposes itself upon the situation and, in that way, coerces his character to change. The risks attendant on this stoicism are, as I have anticipated, all too apparent in the leitmotif of the glass pane through which Gabriel yearns to pass outside himself, only to collide catastrophically with the reflective surface of things. Another way of putting this would be to say that Gabriel does not suffer the problem he has become to himself, in the laudable manner of the tragic protagonist-in-demos. By eschewing the requirement that character formation accommodates incommensurable demands—without which any deliberative scruple will not come to bear—Gabriel inhibits the reciprocity of actor and spectator that otherwise gives deliberative scruple its social trajectory in Greek tragedy. Gabriel’s personal tragedy is in fact signaled in the manifest lack of fitness of the mutually exclusive roles of actor and spectator within some more capacious context of role-playing. Instead, Gabriel preempts himself in a
Singer.book
9/12/03
210
11:21 AM
Page 210
Aesthetic Reason
succession of mutual exclusions. He presents himself as the fellow of Gaelic brotherhood, or the defiler of tradition-bound historical fate, the artist hero of his age or the slavish admirer of the previous age, the robust mate of Gretta’s passionate nature or the sterile “penny boy” to a set of maiden aunts. Because he merely alternates between these roles, he eludes the cognitive dissonance without which their potential for tragic revelation—and the Enlightenment knowledge of reversal—is nil. The scene of suffering that will finally reveal Gabriel’s problem in terms that might put his tragedy in the service of Enlightenment idealism—the very idealism which, for Horkheimer and Adorno, was betrayed by the Culture Industry’s evasions of tragedy—waits for the final episode of Joyce’s story. There the bounds of what can be known are rendered integrable to the process by which all boundaries are surpassed. In the aftermath of the dinner speech, Gabriel catches his wife in a contemplative stance, poised alone on the staircase. Silently attuned to a song echoing from an upper room, she is lost in a reverie of what will prove for Gabriel to be the most “thought tormented music” of all. In this instant of Gretta’s own aesthetic appreciation, to which Gabriel is portentously insensible, all the complexities of Joyce’s own aesthetic design are prismatically scintillating, in such a way as to highlight an impending choice between aesthetic modes.There are several things to contemplate at once. First, Gabriel’s view of his wife recapitulates the succession of windows through which we have seen him struggle toward his own image. Here Gabriel’s voyeurism/narcissism is revealed to be intrinsic to the most intimate structure of his personal identity. It hints at the necessity for a subjective mobility toward which we know him to be constitutionally indisposed. Second, the perceptual reality of the moment is riven by incommensurable registers of the audible and the visual, a schism that goes unacknowledged in Gabriel’s grasp of the “scene.” But most important, the urgency of our making sense of this moment, in specifically aesthetic terms, is imposed by Gabriel’s spontaneous transfiguration of the image of his wife into a painting; “If he were a painter he would paint her in that attitude” (Joyce,“The Dead,” 210).This most glaringly aestheticized vision induces Gabriel’s spectacular blindness to Gretta’s experience, so brightly illuminated by Joyce’s artful construction of the ending of the story.Thus does Joyce prompt the choice between incommensurable aesthetic practices, without which Gabriel’s own aesthetic impotence would amount to mere anticlimactic pathos. As we shall see in what follows, Joyce’s irony, by reframing Gabriel’s aesthetic judgments with a proliferation of competing judgmental
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 211
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics
211
parameters, sets the stage for a deliberative scruple. Because the character cannot exercise that scruple himself, it is an incentive for the “character” of the reader to develop in the direction of Wiggins’s new universalizability. If we continue to trust this universalizability as a site for culturing deliberative agency, we can say that it is the role of the active universalizer, rather than the metaphysical universality of authorial control purveyed in naive aestheticism, that bears most dramatically on Joyce’s theater of ironies.We are not meant to see the reader’s judgment as transcending the character that was its occasion. Rather, to use the terms by which Wiggins himself characterizes the practical role of the universalizer, we should see the reader’s role as “straightening out” and extending an existing “corpus of judgments” or matrix of judgments, according to which the intelligibility of the character was first available.As this protocol envisages for Wiggins a “public scene . . . in which moral agents are at once actors and spectators” (Needs, Values, Truth, 82), so we must recognize it to be an expressly aesthetic project that eloquently shows up the limitations of Gabriel’s own compositional skills,“if he were a painter”: He stood in the gloom of the hall, trying to catch the air that the voice was singing and gazing up at his wife.There was grace and mystery in her attitude as if she were a symbol of something. He asked himself what is a woman standing on the stairs in the shadow, listening to distant music, a symbol of. If he were a painter he would paint her in that attitude. Her blue felt hat would show off the bronze of her hair against the darkness and the dark panels of her skirt would show off the light ones. Distant Music he would call the picture if he were a painter. (Joyce,“The Dead,” 209–10) The most conspicuous fact about Gabriel’s spectatorship here is that the spectacle he purveys is a clumsy disguise for his will toward autonomy. Because this spectacle denotes an agency denied the publicity of spectatorship, we are not surprised that it produces, in Gabriel’s fastidious mind’s eye, an “artwork” that succumbs to the comparatively hermetic ethos of symbolism. Symbolism, by its one-sided valuation of experience, is congruent with the principle of continent character and the abstract principle-mongering of the maxim, already cast in such a suspicious light by the rhetorical workings of Joyce’s narrative. It is no coincidence that I have previously linked both continent character and maxim to the preemption of Enlightenment mind. Enlightenment mind otherwise find its resources for deliberative agency by contending with differences that outflank the unifying structure of character. In the
Singer.book
9/12/03
212
11:21 AM
Page 212
Aesthetic Reason
Greek tradition, this outflanking strictly determined the tragic predicament as an arena of productive knowledge. In the gesture of symbolizing his wife’s inner life, and quite conspicuously at the expense of her sentient presence—a “difference” he would otherwise be challenged to interact with—Gabriel thus puts the roles of actor and spectator out of phase with one another. Furthermore, because of the aesthetic pretensions inherent in that act, it is worth contemplating how this putting out of phase is a rough corollary for the artistic dispositions denoted in the terms genius and connoisseurship. I believe that they lurk within Gabriel’s motivation as coordinates for mapping the drama of character onto the field of aesthetic valuation. Indeed, conducive as they are to a dualism of theory and practice, these two terms, which sustain the discursive life of art, do so too often at the expense of any coherent view of art as a practice.As these terms tend to preempt thinking of art production and appreciation together, they invite an unthinking substitution of one activity for the other. As a result they become mutually obscuring and excluding enterprises. Gabriel’s view of his wife is emblematic of just such a confusion. His spectatorship is strictly ornamental—one might even say symbolic of spectatorship—precisely to the degree that the “artist,” who here determines the world of his wife’s possibilities, is pretending merely to see them rather than to produce them. Because the gap between actor and spectator is foreclosed upon in this pretense, the differences between them, the pretext of their incommensurability, is not available as a ground for further determination of relations of fitness. In effect, character is elided as an arena of activity. Thus we might say that the death march that Gabriel commences from this moment on in the story is perversely spurred by the inactivity of his indecisive spectatorship. So handicapped, he does not understand how the validity of his own spectatorial situation depends on a transition to a standpoint from which it might be assessed, as worthy itself, of having been chosen. In other words, only by transition to another viewpoint is one aware that the viewpoint from which one looks at his choices is itself a product of choice-making, a production in its own right. It is this transition, so key to the concept of turranospharmakos, and to the most beneficent Enlightenment consequences of tragedy, that is effected for the reader by the devices of ironic reversal orchestrating the finale of Joyce’s drama. What is more, the transition is effected in such a way that Joyce’s reader passes, so to speak, on the mortal “passing” to which Gabriel, on the last page of the story, succumbs: when he fatalistically resigns himself to the self-abjecting recognition that his wife loved another.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 213
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics
213
We best can anticipate the workings of this transitional mind if we acknowledge Joyce’s controlling conceit: years before, when Michael Furey was courting Gretta, that young man had stood before the window, figuratively speaking, through which we have seen Gabriel yearning to pass, in the succession of leitmotif panes that reflect his tormented introspection throughout the story. For Michael Furey, of course, the pane of glass was no mere window of spectatorship.The gravel Michael Furey tossed against the glass shattered that barrier between the audible and the visual that holds Gabriel in thrall at the bottom of the stairs. It solicited response. Michael Furey’s gesture toward the glass makes a sharp, if not shattering, contrast with the narcissistic silence enshrining Gabriel in his purely specular, which is to say not sufficiently spectatorial, reverie before the image of his wife on the stairs. By Gabriel’s reluctance to choose the “situation” of his life over what symbolizes it, by his reluctance to accept the Aristotelian lesson that works of art give us “situations,” not explanations—“in aesthesis explanations give out”—Gabriel, in the final episode of the story, places himself repeatedly—figuratively as well as literally—before a window of spectatorship, behind which we see he is doomed to recede from the possibility of action. Joyce figures the density of the “situation” that wants appreciation here—what for Wiggins counts as an elemental access to aesthesis— by using the conceit of the window to open the distance between actor and spectator without which, he knows, the one could not meaningfully articulate with the other. So in the last pages of “The Dead” we witness Gabriel’s longing to physically possess the portrait he has “painted” of his wife. But his ever more lustful approaches to her image are refracted by ironic perspective—where reflection formerly held sway—in such a way that the reader’s own spectatorship is figured to be a more plausible site of agency. Inasmuch as Gabriel’s solicitation of his wife’s affection amounts to a demand that she reflect his desires, his desire throws into relief what it does not include. Gabriel’s actions will thus be assimilated to a field of spectatorship from which he is excluded, by a focus upon what he wants to see. Spectatorship will thus dramatize the choice of what Gabriel cannot choose, because the differences between what he would see and what he does not see go unengaged.This marks Gabriel’s “situation” as tragic in the “bad enlightenment” sense. Horkheimer and Adorno might diagnose the problem as the “blind” transparency of the “view” through which Gabriel wants to sustain his agency, and for which the window is only too woefully symbolic, in the manner of his doomed portraiture of Gretta.As I noted early in this chapter, it is precisely the evocation of a windowlike
Singer.book
9/12/03
214
11:21 AM
Page 214
Aesthetic Reason
transparency of mind for which Horkheimer and Adorno faulted Enlightenment reason, and its consequent marginalizing of the irony of action. In this way instrumental reason tragically missed the complexity of the world that tragic knowledge ordains by countenancing the opacity of contingent relations. And so it is fitting that the figure of the window, the transparently fragile glass “I” of Gabriel’s self-ideal, becomes the medium through which Joyce’s reader is invited to “view” each successive moment when Gabriel’s expressive self is undone. For this undoing is nothing less than the revelation that what Gabriel sees through denotes the necessity of another vantage of seeing. Thus does the reader’s eye open onto the arena of the protagonist-in-demos, at least as that arena is intimated in the alternations of the “eye” and the “I” that get played out here. Gabriel’s increasingly desperate attempts to mate with his wife’s image take him through a succession of impenetrable looking glasses in which the image of his desire is painfully reversed: a “heliotrope envelope,” through which Gabriel recollects a love letter, shows us instead the hothouse insularity of his love; a “grated window,” in which he cherishes a remembered intimacy early in his marriage, shows us instead his inability to communicate through it; the glass of a “swinging mirror,” in which he sees his wife beginning to undress as a portent of his fulfilled desire, shows us instead her distraction.With each successive frame in this montage of windows Joyce builds the scene of reversal that culminates in the recognition of Gabriel’s nemesis, Michael Furey, standing at Gretta’s window so many years before. In other words, each instance of this building is a focusing of the reader’s gaze upon what Gabriel does not see, until, when Gabriel must finally look though Michael Furey’s eyes, he is obliged to see himself as nothing: “Generous tears filled Gabriel’s eyes. . . . The tears gathered more thickly in his eyes and in the partial darkness he imagined he saw the form of a young man standing under a dripping tree. Other forms were near. His soul had approached that region where dwell the vast hosts of the dead. . . . His own identity was fading out into a grey impalpable world: the solid world itself which these dead had one time reared and lived in was dissolving and dwindling” (Joyce,“The Dead,” 223).What is notable, however, is not the simple ironic reversal of fate so clearly on display here. There is a more complex proposition latent in the obvious fact that Gabriel’s will to see things transparently, carried to the extreme of this self-abjecting gaze, produces the self as nothing.This spectacle is, no doubt, the very specter of doom that haunts the reversals of Greek tragedy. But the more urgent irony is that the “generous tears” that
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 215
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics
215
signify this nothing (especially in their thickening to virtual lenses) magnify our consciousness of the bad-faith refuge Gabriel is taking here. It is an evasion of the deliberative burdens that the gesture of grief otherwise essays to dignify. By abjecting himself so fatalistically in the emotional transparency of those tears, by thus appearing to give himself so selflessly to Gretta, to Michael Furey, Gabriel is presuming upon the transparency of the other. It is the very same transparency of mind that obtained in the blind spectatorship, from which every deliberative scruple was excluded in all his previous episodes of transparent viewing.The tears are tokens of a false generosity.They consequently give a false appearance of Gabriel’s choosing his fate, as if the journey westward were indeed a volitional transport. Horkheimer and Adorno provide an apt coda, in their analysis of modernity’s liquidation of tragedy, where one has “become aware of one’s own nothingness, only to recognize defeat . . . one is one with it all. . . . tragedy has melted away into the nothingness of that false identity of society and individual, whose terror still shows for a moment in the empty semblance of the tragic” (Dialectic of Enlightenment, 153–54). The “semblance of the tragic” shines in Gabriel’s tears with the glow of a false enlightenment. In contrast to the “bad” Enlightenment epitomized by such transparency, I want to say that Joyce bids for something like a “good” Enlightenment in the final paragraph of the story. At the moment of Gabriel’s dawning fatalism, Joyce interposes the familiar window conceit, this time between the reader and the reader’s final “view” of the story. This most explicit instantiation of the reader as the viewer, standing in Gabriel’s place, just as Gabriel stands in Michael Furey’s place, is nonetheless actively distinguished from Gabriel’s viewpoint. Joyce orchestrates a rhetorical density that precludes spectatorship as an autonomous vantage point. Here a concatenation of verbal effects impose an inescapable deliberative protocol as the condition of viewing. A few light taps upon the pane made him turn to the window. It had begun to snow again. He watched sleepily the flakes, silver and dark, falling obliquely against the lamplight.The time had come for him to set out on his journey westward.Yes, the newspapers were right: snow was general all over Ireland. It was falling softly upon the bog of Allen, and, farther westward, softly falling into the mutinous Shannon waves. It was falling, too, upon every part of the lonely churchyard on the hill where Michael Furey lay buried. It lay thickly drifted on the crooked crosses and headstones, on the
Singer.book
9/12/03
216
11:21 AM
Page 216
Aesthetic Reason
spears of the little gate, on the barren thorns. His soul swooned slowly as he heard the snow faintly falling through the universe and faintly falling, like the descent of their last end, upon all the living and the dead. As I indicated earlier, the taps on the windowpane, reprising the sound of gravel on Gretta’s window, become a cue for seeing, but not with the eyes. Although, descriptively speaking, the prose here opens a view of the street that offers to universalize Gabriel’s perspective, in the purely spectatorial manner of Platonizing aesthetics, the passage simultaneously invites the reader to oscillate between the spectator role and the actor role. For the reader must sift the sounds that obtrude in the descriptive language as an insuperably immediate burden of linguistic opacity—reading qua act of reading. The sounds are consequently an impediment to universalizing spectatorship.As was the case in our coming to effectively aesthetic terms with Gabriel’s Distant Music, understanding obtains here as the reciprocity between two registers—of sight and sound—which, by their split-ness, presuppose deliberative purposiveness.This final paragraph of the story thus orchestrates a refrain of sounds that make the “journey westward,” upon which Gabriel is said to embark, into a curious scene of choosing. The disturbingly proximate music of “falling . . . falling,” first “softly falling” then “falling softly,” harmonized with the s consonances and their declension to f consonances, from “softly” to “faintly,” has the effect of prompting a choice: first between seeing and hearing but then more urgently between apparent similarity and difference.What is more, the stakes of the distinction between them remain to be worked out as a contingency of reading.Thus must the reader set out on that conspicuously nonallegorical journey between knowing and not knowing. It is a subtle evocation of the public space of the demos, where activity takes precedence over identity. Aptly, it is the activity of choosing, not the content of choice-making, that matters in Joyce’s bodying forth the reading mind that, by its own accelerated activity here, demurs to any moribund identification with Gabriel’s mortal soul. This is obviously not choice-making on the order of the momentous moral deliberation that can sometimes be so thoughtlessly thematized in novels. Rather, it gains its significance by its mere derivation from a tragedy of character: precipitated by this character’s nondeliberative stance toward personal fate.The choice-making imperative of Joyce’s story gains further significance perhaps by the suggestion that, just as deliberation is seen to offer an alternative to tragic characterization, so
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 217
From Tragedy to Deliberative Heroics
217
it proffers an alternative to the tragedy of fate menacing any reader who would be caught up in the dumb spectacle of character identification. In this way, and not coincidentally, the protocol of choosing also constitutes something like a role-reversal of reader and character.The character, the conventional agent, sees uninterruptedly, spectatorially, the expanse of the universe “all over Ireland” and thus succumbs to the role of the spectator.The reader, the conventional spectator, is obliged to contend with choices of what to attend to, urged as he or she is to sort semantic differences from the same sounds, and thus assumes the role of the agent.The reversal occurs in such a way that we might peg the reversibility of roles as the thing that makes reading, in this instance, originally possible. Indeed, in the absence of reversal, the universalizing view of character would have eclipsed the very register of particularity that sustains the active mind that Gabriel nonetheless resigns to the reader.That the reversal asks us to contemplate an affinity of reading with tragedy is no liability here, because, unlike Gabriel’s “journey westward,” the tragedy augured by the devices of Joyce’s prose is not an “empty semblance of the tragic.” On the contrary, what would have been nothingness in a reader’s acceptance of Gabriel’s self-indulgent demise—however piously he suffers it—incurs, instead, something of a consequence that is both beyond the scope of Gabriel’s knowledge and yet rigorously dependent on it.This consequence persists as an imperative of cognitive activity that Joyce will not permit us to read out of the story.That is to say, in the matrices of Joyce’s prose, we may not abstract our reading selves from the circumstance of needing to choose. In stark contrast with the allegorical “west” toward which Gabriel hearkens, the circumstance of needing to choose literalizes the experience of reading as a contextproducing enterprise, as much as it is a context-determined one. In this capacity, Joyce’s artifice serves my purpose to prescribe a cognitive aesthetic as antidote to the morbidly tragic pathos of noncognitive aestheticism.22 I have anticipated that my exemplar text joins the larger argument of this work on the ground of a public deliberative space, a demos, because it is the plausible site of a tragedy that need not be fatalistically tragic for the agents who contend within its bounds. In other words, the continuity between Sophoclean tragedy and “The Dead” is manifest in Joyce’s figuration of the deliberative agent as a principle of continence that does not presuppose character but rather develops it. Just such a prospect is held open by Horkheimer and Adorno’s intuition that the beneficently tragic individual is enlightened by what can ensue from thought as an articulation of “the negative truth
Singer.book
9/12/03
218
11:21 AM
Page 218
Aesthetic Reason
of suffering” (Dialectic of Enlightenment, 131). Enlightenment ensues from an acceptance of the “fluctuating relation with nature” (61) rather than the clever rationalist evasions of Natural necessity with which we have historically confused it.This is stridently antithetical to the aesthetically pleasing “freedom from thought” by which the Culture Industry desensitizes social agents to the deprivation of their individuality (144). Such a view dovetails with a crucial premise of my argument that I think takes Horkheimer and Adorno’s rhetoric beyond mere condemnation of the Culture Industry: the pleasure of tragic pain is the knowledge of alternatives that development articulates. In development, therefore, the pleasure that has long epitomized the aesthetic, in the discourse of beauty theory and in the theories of taste, might be passionately remarried to the worldly interestedness of the rational agent whom aestheticism so precipitously divorced. We will not forget that Vernant “characterizes” the Greek concept of the agent by which we distinguish the Homeric from the tragic (Aristotelian) individual as “the development of subjective responsibility” (Vernant and Vidal-Naquet, Myth and Tragedy, 69). As the key innovation of tragedy, this concept of the agent as development displaces the modern idea of will—too psychological to accommodate the distinction between “an action carried out of one’s own volition and one performed despite oneself” (69).What is imagined here, and what I believe is implicit in Horkheimer and Adorno’s own distinctly nonpsychological ideal of Enlightenment character, is a subjective reawakening to the constraints of a nonfatalistic tragedy. Just so, we might recognize the nonfatalistic tragic hero of a plausible enlightenment that dawns in the aesthetic practices of Joyce’s reader.This reader is distinctively a creature of the world of alternatives that development subsists upon. We may now imagine this realm of alternatives, that is, of choice-making, to be the real problem of and promise of tragedy. In this way we may think about it as the glow of an enlightenment that is arguably brighter than the light by which we otherwise flatter the profile of an unduly rationalized pessimism.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 219
7
Living in Aesthetic Community: Art and the Bonds of Productive Agency [T]he world of a work of art is “unreal” in the ordinary sense of this word: it is a fictitious reality. But it is “unreal” not because it is less, but because it is more as well as qualitatively “other” than the established reality.As fictitious world, as illusion (Schein), it contains more truth than does everyday reality. For the latter is mystified in its institutions and relationships, which make necessity into choice, and alienation into self realization. —Marcuse, The Aesthetic Dimension
I Herbert Marcuse’s notion that our most urgent need of the aesthetic is the corrective it brings to mystifications of human choice, and his pursuit of the freedoms to be won in that correction, are allied with my motives for promoting a cognitive aesthetic. Consistent with my emphasis on rational choice-making as a constitutive aspect of aesthetic knowledge, Marcuse affirms the “cognitive function” of the artwork as a “vehicle of recognition and indictment” (Aesthetic Dimension, 9–10). Recognition of the world as alienating individuality entails the individual’s estrangement from the world.This is an indictment by which one chooses otherwise. Indeed “recognition and indictment” are means by which transformations of the context of human agency are fundamentally imaginable. Since the transformation of human contexts for action is what gives choice-making its significance, Marcuse inspires confidence in our speculation that the aesthetic has ethical-political consequences precisely to the degree that it is inextricable from transformative activity. Unfortunately, the best Marcuse can do to elucidate the pragmatic means of such transformation is to foster the conceit of the artwork as a woefully reactive “otherness” vis-à-vis an otherwise intractable “real.” In this way he means to stigmatize the world so efficiently instrumentalized in the schemes of rational rule. Contrary to his stated purpose,
Singer.book
9/12/03
220
11:21 AM
Page 220
Aesthetic Reason
however, this has the effect of positing a community that is bound, not by a positive choice, but by negation. In fact, since Marcuse pegs art’s autonomy to its contradiction of the world’s representation of itself in all its givenness, he seems to equate the effect of the artwork on the subject more with estrangement than development (72). In a curious way, then, the cognitive function of art, for Marcuse, is effectively a bracketing of the very self that would know itself in terms of the métier of transformative self-development that, for me, is integral to aesthetic practice. Despite his ardent defense of the aesthetic, Marcuse’s aesthetic negation comes perilously, and quite ironically, close to the stance of contemporary partisans of the anti-aesthetic. We have seen how the anti-aesthetic theorists propose an emancipatory sociopolitical solidarity based upon a noncognitive bracketing of what they would call the rules of art.Anti-aestheticism deems those rules to be darkly complicitous with the instrumentalizing rule of Enlightenment reason. In the domain of the anti-aesthetic, art can only be art in its banishment of the recognition of what is art. In observing this affinity of Marcuse’s aesthetic with the anti-aesthetic initiatives taken by contemporary critical theory, we can perhaps see the motive for a perverse thesis. My purpose in this chapter will be to point up the conspicuousness of the contradiction in Marcuse’s aesthetic theory. On the one hand, he favors a cognitive function for art. But simultaneously he fears art’s complicity with the instrumentalized cognitive function of Enlightenment mind that negates art as an irrational affectivity and, therefore, begs to be negated by art. Whatever Marcuse means by championing artistic cognition in this context, is certainly at odds with the cognitive bearing of that practical “everyday reality” in which he wants to make use of art for the purposes of beneficent social change. I now want to suggest that our sorting of this contradiction might be precisely the thing to help us see how the emancipatory goals of the anti-aesthetic could be best served by a, albeit grudging (from their point of view), return to the aesthetic. I believe that this proposition could be tenable precisely to the degree that we recognize how any further aesthetic theorizing intended to resolve Marcuse’s contradiction would, in all likelihood, weaken the motive for distinguishing the aesthetic from the anti-aesthetic in the first place. An important clue about the source of Marcuse’s contradiction, and hence about what recourse we have to it, is his inability to see that the term production, while it is certainly a counter for the mystifying powers of Enlightenment reason, nevertheless also denotes an aspect of the artistic agency without which the cognitive function of art that he
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 221
Living in Aesthetic Community
221
defends would certainly remain an impotent heuristic of his aesthetic theory. Quite to the contrary, Marcuse’s polemic in The Aesthetic Dimension asserts that the potency of art is its “separation from the process of material production,” thus enabling it “to demystify the reality of the process.”When he further asserts this role of the artwork as the access to a desublimated realm of “rebellious subjectivity” (7), an “emancipation of sensibility” (9), a feeling of freedom, for which he can nonetheless supply no cogent cognitive agency, the narrowness of his concept of production becomes apparent.The problem reveals itself along lines I have already discussed with respect to Guillory’s and Bourdieu’s transposition of production into a sociological basis for, rather than an exigency of, practical subjectivity.1 In Marcuse’s case, the narrowness of the concept of production is most obviously problematic as an impediment to the task of epistemological demystification. This is especially true if we realize that the “reality of the process” that would be debunked is inseparable from the duty of recognizing that it is indeed illusory. Such a recognition must exist in a relation of reciprocity with a specifiable other. It cannot be, as Marcuse seems to suggest, merely an index of otherness.Without reciprocity, recognition itself would come to be tantamount to negation.While Marcuse charges the aesthetic to demystify the social “necessity” that masquerades as personal choice, he himself loses sight of the necessity to choose a context in which mystification can be recognized to be the case. In other words, Marcuse relies too heavily on the idea that the “process of material production” is always self-reifying and, for that reason, to be vigorously resisted. His admonition against it comes in the spirit of those post-Enlightenment critics who instruct us to eschew the abstract transformation of material Nature (material production) by which Enlightenment ideology dignifies human enterprise, if we want to free ourselves from the depressing instrumentalism of that rational dominion. From my point of view, this plea for abstinence is simply too literal minded. What is missing from this account is the knowledge that the materiality of the “process of material production” is itself belied by the contextuality of the producing agent. This knowledge calls for other methodological means such as I have already appealed to in previous chapters: marshaling the concepts of translatability, deliberation, choice, and training in reciprocal recognition as the argumentative touchstones for a cognitivist aesthetic.All are strategies for revising contextual selfunderstanding out of the circumstance of error whereby self-recognition is stymied by otherness—either internal incoherence or external conflict.As I ventured in Chapter 1, these strategies are based on grant-
Singer.book
9/12/03
222
11:21 AM
Page 222
Aesthetic Reason
ing that the subjects formed in relation to aesthetic experience “would be obliged to see themselves produced in the idea of the reconciliation [with otherness] they seek” and hence as inherently self-transformative. Production thus need not be a preemption of the transformability of the subject, as the partisans of the anti-aesthetic descry it. Neither can it be so easily appropriated as a pretext for maintaining the rift between intellect and emotion that both Marcuse and the partisans of the anti-aesthetic deepen. By equating transformability with the Romantic spontaneity of feeling—which they claim the rational purposiveness of production threatens to inhibit—they in turn inhibit efficient communication between intellectual and emotional faculties. Indeed, I would argue that Marcuse’s effective splitting of the “process of material production” from the “desublimated” feeling of freedom aroused by the artwork risks the very ontologizing of feeling of which Nietzsche warned in Human, All Too Human. In that aptly anti-aesthetic aesthetic polemic, Nietzsche admonished against the corruption of aesthetics that occurs when it becomes a substitute for religion. Although Marcuse clearly intends the opposite, he seems to buy into the logic of mutually exclusive choices between feeling and rational instrumentation of the “feeling body,” which would invite a mysterious spiritualization of the artwork. It is worth noting that twelve years after Marcuse,Terry Eagleton, in The Ideology of the Aesthetic, has claimed this mutual exclusion to be, almost inescapably, the fate of the aesthetic in postmodern culture.2 For Eagleton, the specter of this fate is likewise a motive for an anti-aesthetic activism that subverts the autonomizing rules of art and frees us to a habitation of the sensuous world that valorizes sentiment: “Only when governing imperatives have been dissolved into spontaneous reflex, when human subjects are linked to each other in their very flesh, can a truly corporate existence be fashioned” (24).The recognizably Kantian ambition inherent in the goal of “corporate existence,” and anchored in feeling, strikes me as too precipitously a flight from the conflicted situatedness of the tragic subject that warrants cognitive initiative. Implicitly, Eagleton’s endorsement of a community based on feeling elides the productive agency of those who would otherwise make up that community out of their habitation of the very split between and mind and body that Eagleton himself declines to engage as a source of relevant knowledge.3 My point is that if Marcuse is really opposed to the mystifications of choice that art can ameliorate, as he seems to be in my epigraph, he would have to see how false is the choice posed by critics such as Eagleton, precisely because it seems to weaken the agency of choice-making. Marcuse
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 223
Living in Aesthetic Community
223
might then see the merits of the notion, advanced in these pages, that only a rationalistic reengagement of the form of tragedy can meaningfully restore choice to the subject who is faced with the conflicting claims of thought and feeling.Tragedy can serve this end by promoting a deliberative protocol, corollary with the métiers of translatability, reciprocal recognition, deliberation, and so on that assiduously debunk the myth of the mutual exclusivity of feeling and reason. As we shall see, in this context choice becomes a standard of production itself. Marcuse’s inability to come to terms with production without falling afoul of the thought-feeling dichotomy can be blamed, I believe, on a view of tragedy that, in the course of his argument, seems to confuse tragic form with mythic tragic fate. It thus elides productivity as an element of its intelligibility: “Tragedy is always and everywhere” (Aesthetic Dimension, 56).The hallmark of Marcuse’s confusion here is his predisposition to privilege catharsis, a register of affect or feeling more than cognition, as the premier aesthetic effect and even purpose of tragedy. Quite to the contrary, in previous chapters of this work I have been at great pains to show the coordinate efficacy of recognition and reversal (peripeteia), which makes tragedy into a staging ground of choice instead of a site of overwhelming pathos. Marcuse’s move amounts to ranking the sublimely inarticulate moment of catharsis over the more articulated temporality inherent in Aristotle’s postulate of the interdependence of recognition and reversal. I believe that this is why, for Marcuse, the artwork remains a substantially utopian enterprise. Because the work of art, in Marcuse’s view, only serves to negate the present modes of instrumental reason, in effect producing an “other” reason that remains contextually free or detached from the necessity of a specific context of recognition, it is tantamount to a deferral of human agency. The work of art so justified is merely indexical of difference rather than substantively responsive to what it differs from. My own account contends that tragedy teaches us a different lesson: production does not inevitably invite the utopianism implicit in the mutual exclusion of feeling and thought.This is because, in tragedy, productive agency is embedded in the very protocols of choice-making that the twin levers of recognition and reversal compel.This is to say that tragedy, because it is based on a version of subjectivity that is very deeply rooted in the problem of contextual reconciliation, is therefore intrinsically about self-transformation.These observations now provide a staging ground for contrasting tragedy, as a form of knowledge where recognition is earned in the vicissitudes of choice-making, with some examples of artworks endorsed by contemporary anti-aesthetic theorists.
Singer.book
9/12/03
224
11:21 AM
Page 224
Aesthetic Reason
I do not mean to invoke a criterion by which to make invidious judgments between good art and bad art, but to elaborate what I consider to be the epistemological pitfalls of anti-aesthetic theorizing vis-à-vis the prospects for artistic production. My point will be that the artworks promoted by anti-aesthetic theorists, works that are touted to be more political than anything orthodox aesthetic theory can produce or explain, problematically presuppose recognition as a given of interpellated ideological identity.Where recognition is a given it is not produced. I want to suggest that these works, by eliding the complexities of productive agency, are distinctly anti-tragic.They thus preclude staking human subjectivity in the kinds of action that tragedy makes imperative for rational subjects.This, not coincidentally, belies the political efficacy of the anti-aesthetic. In other words, such versions of anti-aestheticism have the perverse effect of aestheticizing subjectivity. Along these lines, John Brenkman has commented that Marcuse’s faith in aesthetics as a didactic disclosure of otherness presents an impediment to productive recognition similar to that which I’ve identified with the anti-aesthetic. Brenkman characterizes this stance as self preemptively “critical” in contrast to what he sees as the prospect for a more “adaptive” stance of the artwork toward the world of otherness (Culture and Domination, 106). It is worth noting that the “critical” effect that Brenkman identifies with the disclosure of otherness presupposes, in the manner of catharsis, a break with time and development. In Marcuse specifically this break is occasioned by the artwork’s exhibition of a Lukacsian contradiction between the wholeness of the aesthetic object and the dividedness of the social realm in which it is valued. Brenkman concludes that because the baring of this contradiction simply puts the artwork at a critical distance from alienating forms of bourgeois culture, it becomes a self-inhibiting limit of Marcuse’s account of the political beneficence of the aesthetic. This “critical” modality thus turns out to be idealizing of subjectivity in a way that contradicts the aims of Marcuse’s own politics, where social change more than social identity is the priority of critical understanding. Brenkman laudably suggests that “adaptation” would better serve Marcuse’s purpose of rescuing the “aesthetic experience of bourgeois culture from the bourgeois idea of culture” (Brenkman, Culture and Domination, 106)—presumably because adaptation, by acknowledging the reciprocity that plays between producer and consumer, mitigates the commodification of cultural objects. My concern in these pages is to show how the aesthetic inflects subjectivity as learning through choice-making, that is, how it produces
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 225
Living in Aesthetic Community
225
subjects “obliged to see themselves produced in the idea of the reconciliation they seek.”This prospect is posed as an alternative to what I might characterize—after Brenkman—as the “critical” modality that animates anti-aesthetic theorizing. My version of aesthetic subjectivity furthermore instantiates a scruple of adaptation that is counteridealizing in its making reconciliation responsive to the choosing imperatives of productive agents. It is no coincidence that such counteridealism is an effect that I have argued is integral to the deliberative protocols of translatability, choice, and training in reciprocal recognition.These are all markers for my advancement of a cognitive aesthetic on the basis of contextually determined self-recognition. For these reasons, I now propose to compare the “adaptive” aesthetic subject, which arises from the plot exigencies of tragedy, and which we saw tutored in the compositional forms of Caravaggio, Beckett, Melville, and Joyce, with subjective modalities promulgated by self-consciously critical artworks, patronized by post modernist anti-aestheticism. I hope this comparison will reveal that what is lost in the evasion of tragedy might be a good index of what can be gained through art.The success of this claim will depend on my showing how the nontragic anti-aesthetic artworks, associated with a predominantly critical function visà-vis artistic tradition, are formally and rhetorically boundary-erasing enterprises. We will see that the critical negation animating anti-aestheticism is reflected in aesthetic practices that too simplistically dramatize the contingency of our recognition of traditional aesthetic forms.4 Accordingly, we will see how knowledge accrued merely in defeating the categorical regulations of literary formalism lacks resources to redirect traditions of learning about forms. I must show that the aesthetic works associated with adaptation might be characterized, by contrast, as boundary-negotiating under the deliberative imperative of tragedy.Adaptivity in this instance gives us a view of the proper work of the aesthetic in terms of adequacy. It eschews that standard of expressive inadequacy that has been valorized by anti-aesthetic theorists as the only proper critical stance toward the expressive pieties of artistic tradition. Ironically enough, this goal of inexpressibility is typically equated with sublimity, a mainstay of Romantic theories of the aesthetic. Within this purview, inexpressibility constitutes a refuge from the inevitable conflicts of subjective agency. The Romantic preoccupation with the impossibility of expression vis-à-vis an eternal human essence is something that the aesthetic practitioners who were discussed in previous chapters of this work unanimously thwart. Alternatively, they are interested in adequating
Singer.book
9/12/03
226
11:21 AM
Page 226
Aesthetic Reason
human production to changing circumstances of human recognition, without of course ever indulging faith in any standard of perfect adequacy.Within the framework of this new “aesthetic attitude,” I believe, we can speak less circumspectly about aesthetic production as a social good.We need not fear that it will be glibly unmasked as merely a pretext for the asocial, apolitical, contemplative solipsism elicited by the autonomous aesthetic form.After all, inasmuch as adaptivity is a reciprocal subjectivity, the “good” it represents is de facto the good of community. But unlike the sensus communis typically envisaged by the boundary-erasing anti-aesthetic ethos, this “sense” of community is strictly cognitive: by virtue of its deliberative, boundary-negotiating contextualism.Thus it is indebted only to the needs of the subjectivity it instantiates. In other words, I might generalize that the tragic adaptive modality of the aesthetic improvises a contextual pragmatics that would serve well to check the more metaphysical drift of the anti-tragic, critical modality of the anti-aesthetic. Furthermore the interests represented by such a pragmatic contextualism would seem to presuppose a subject astutely poised for action in a world of practical choices. I can think of no more apt custodian of the political motives of the anti-aesthetic. For this reason, and as I suggested in formulating a perverse thesis for this discussion at the outset, the result of our contrasting aesthetic and anti-aesthetic stances might be the revelation of a deeper continuity between them.
II My linking the ways of pragmatic contextualism to tragedy is meant to remind us that the boundedness of experience is precisely what motivates the deliberative recourse of subjects to comparative contexts. In my reading aesthetic subjectivity out of the form of tragedy, I have tried to appreciate how the imperative for self-justification, especially in the instance of peripetic reversal—a paradigmatic case of comparative context—implicates the subject in the interests of a communitarian identity. This is so if only because the self in tragic error can only reconstitute its agency in the choice of a new standard of self-recognition. Such an exigency entails solicitation of other contexts of knowing. Once again, this is to say that it entails an irreducibly cognitive negotiation of boundaries. I have invidiously contrasted this version of aesthetic community with the noncognitive aesthetic community based
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 227
Living in Aesthetic Community
227
on a Kantian disinterestedness—an ultimate condition of unboundedness—because I believe that such a model of community lacks a convincing point of entry for aesthetic agency. On the contrary, where there is an error of judgment about which context of meaning obtains for the protagonist’s best self-understanding, there is always a warrant to recontextualize. I have identified this warrant to contextualize with “the pleasure of tragic pain” in order to keep in mind that this entails a process of nonteleological subjective development, dependent on the knowledge of hitherto unseen alternatives. Now I want to explore the compatibility of this goal of discovering motives for alternative action with the self-described political aims of the anti-aesthetic. I will therefore proceed by adducing specific examples of artworks executed under anti-aesthetic assumptions that nonetheless specifically default upon the political avowals behind those assumptions. In this context I want to speculate upon the failure of anti-aesthetic artworks to achieve credible political ends. I will contend that the postmodern partisans of the anti-aesthetic mistakenly posit the remedy for tragic error in some bridging of the gap between the realms of the sensible and the supersensible.This speaks loudly for an interest in erasing boundaries. In the most extremely polemical cases partisans of the anti-aesthetic equate such unboundedness with winning democratic freedoms and guaranteeing civic equality.5 I want to suggest, however, that this too glib account of tragic error inhibits the partisans of the anti-aesthetic from seeing how the gap between the sensible and supersensible might serve as a lever of adaptive process. It both precludes any dualism that requires bridging in the first place, and practically benefits the self as learning subject. I have already suggested how the anti-tragic métier aspired to in the boundary-erasing gestures of postmodernism is coherent with the postmodern enthusiasm for sublimity. Sublimity stands as one of the most strategic topoi for bridging the gap between the sensible and supersensible realms in postmodern critical theory.And yet if we are to put this fact in useful perspective it must be noted that, in many ways, Walter Benjamin’s negative, antiproduction aesthetic sets the pattern for this postmodern gambit and curiously inspires its bias against the aesthetic. Benjamin’s valorization of Dada, with its erasure of all rules; his banishment of the “aura,” thus erasing the boundary between art and nonart; and his intimation that such artistic practice could be a form of beneficent politics, or, as he says, a form of practicing art as politics (Illuminations, 224), assume that aesthetic value is only legitimated in the transcendence of frames of reference that typically
Singer.book
9/12/03
228
11:21 AM
Page 228
Aesthetic Reason
instantiate bourgeois subjectivity.6 Benjamin’s thinking is even more relevant to my interests here, since his source for this argument is his reading of Trauerspiel.Trauerspiel, a species of German baroque art, is quintessentially a site for erased boundaries. More significant, Benjamin pointedly acknowledges Trauerspiel’s affinity with the sublime and— by its catachrestic and desubjectivizing proliferation of associational vectors of knowledge—its connection with tragic experience. In other words,Trauerspiel is a form of tragedy that is at odds with the deliberation-promoting mindset of Greek tragedy. By contrast with the act-oriented Greek form of tragic knowledge, German tragic drama makes contemplative melancholy (a de facto inhibitor of deliberative mind) its object.7 Henry Sussman has recently observed that the form of German tragic theater seems to interest Benjamin mostly for the way in which it becomes “the site of an anti-aesthetic, the basis for a cultural and aesthetic monstrosity that achieves the certification of major cultural creations that violate, in their very nature, the wisdom offered by pre-existing metaphysical, historical, psychological, and theme-based methods of interpretation” (Aesthetic Contract, 102). Interestingly, when Sussman generalizes the features of the anti-aesthetic epitomized by the Trauerspiel, he organizes his list of traits in concordance with postmodern art practices that I have already linked to the patronage of antiaesthetic theorizing: historical discontinuity, juxtaposition of categorically discontinuous entities, freedom from logical procedure (106). Not surprisingly, the most generally defining feature of Trauerspiel for Benjamin is its wholesale violation of Aristotelian unities (103).8 From my point of view, there are two liabilities of Benjamin’s valorization of the German tragic theater. Not only does the boundary erasure implicit in its staunch anti-Aristotelianism muddle moral choices in the presentation of character; it correlatively tends to mitigate the choice-making capacity of its audience. Benjamin avers that “[t]he allegorical character of the figures [characters] is betrayed in the infrequency and the hesitancy with which the plot refers to their particular morality” (Origin of German Tragic Drama, 191). The resulting melancholy evokes, on the part of the reader, a deep affective ambivalence. This accords with the motif of boundary erasure, not least in its mitigating of the motive for comparative valuations of context. As we have seen before, all this indeterminacy seems to stymie productive agency.While Benjamin seems to be overtly invested in the idea of the artist as a producer—asserting nothing less than the need to bring the artwork closer to the “work” of the proletarian “producer”— the essay in which he voices this belief,“The Artist as Producer” (1934),
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 229
Living in Aesthetic Community
229
problematically predicates the idea of artistic making on Brecht’s term, Umfunzionierung (functional transformation) (“Artist As Producer,” 228).This term mandates that the artist-producer inexhaustibly transform the forms of expression through which he or she asserts productive agency.This means that the artwork, in effect, never resolves into a production qua product.As was true in the instance of Marcuse’s adamant suspicion of production, Benjamin’s enthusiastic endorsements of the Trauerspiel, of Brecht, and of sublimity collectively mount an attack on the relevance of the idea of development in art. Or, to be more precise, Benjamin seems to be advancing a concept of production without development. The open-endedness of the transformative act, denoted in Umfunzionierung, seems intended more to “alienate the productive apparatus from the ruling class” (229) than to sustain contextual reciprocity between the productive apparatus and any specifiable productive agency that would be caught in its meshes. In this way Benjamin eliminates scope for comparative contexts as a resource of pragmatic action. Of course, in the Romantic theories of the sublime, the basis for comparative context is comparably eliminated in the effective transcendence of the subject. In the Kantian mathematical sublime, for example, comparative measure succumbs to indeterminate measure and hence objectless fascination.9 One might be tempted to infer that this aspect of the sublime is ethically akin to the “redemptive” destruction of the Greek tragic hero and thus to reconcile the differences between German tragic theater and Greek tragedy. But I have been arguing precisely the contrary point in my preoccupation with the relation of the category of the aesthetic to Greek tragedy. The destruction of the tragic hero is mitigated in Greek texts by the fact that the audience takes up the burden of the development of knowledge that is lost to the hero’s experience. Not coincidentally, this was the mode of subjectivity judged to be at stake in my accounts of Beckett, Melville, and Joyce.The deliberative efficacy of character was seen to be supplanted by the deliberative authority of the reader in a way that furthered the act of reading qua act. And yet it is the sublime transcendence of the subject that the partisans of the anti-aesthetic insist is the only means of drawing attention to the repressed content of cultural production.Their political ambitions rest upon this undertaking. Pierre Bourdieu, in what may be his most vehement anti-aesthetic discourse, The Rules of Art, characterizes this repression—in which he says the literary author and reader are complicit—as a “denegation” of that reality that literature presents as form. Literary form, Bourdieu asseverates, veils knowledge of any real
Singer.book
9/12/03
230
11:21 AM
Page 230
Aesthetic Reason
content of cultural production. Literary form is the site of the illusion of the artist’s mastery of an—albeit fictive—object world. Concomitantly, it is a site of the reader’s narcissistic identification with the sui generis powers of genius. Both self-delusions are oblivious to the social forces of cultural production that initially made the formal artifact necessary. Bourdieu thus makes it absolutely clear that the content of cultural production can only be known by a parsimonious via negativa (Rules of Art, 32).And yet in this negation there is revealed to be precious little resource for the kind of development of subjective agency that would make the term producer transitive for a culture where production might be a significant enterprise. As for Marcuse and Benjamin, so for Bourdieu, the recourse to negation, despite the most pragmatic sociological pretensions attached to it, seems to seek something like the autonomy of sublimity. It seems to invite the very melancholic and stoic spectatorship that goes too merrily along with the purge of subjective interests.The most conspicuous self-interest at stake here, of course, is the interest in recognition that drives and destroys the hero of Greek tragedy. Without it—so I have been maintaining—any notion of production would be lacking a complete grasp of the world of productive forces. So conceived, production thwarts that active development of the context of worldly circumstance without which tragedy is unrecognizable as a normative form of experience or as an aesthetic object. In other words, from this anti-aesthetic point of view, the only subject worth countenancing as a producer would seem to be one that has no stake in producing anything specific.What is specific would already be implicated in the comparison of one context with another and the personal self-interestedness such comparison cultivates, potentially at the expense of other points of view. I do think the worries that drive such partisans of the anti-aesthetic as Bourdieu to indulge this “sublime” paradox of a producer without prospects for production are historically legitimate. But we still need to ask ourselves if it is worth continuing to worry this paradoxical knowledge should it mitigate our motives for considering production as relevant to understanding any practical mode of subjectivity. Or, what reasons have we for fetishizing this paradox if it only cultures the kind of strictly negative subjectivity that we originally saw to be so undermining of the political impetus of Marcuse’s aesthetic theory? Furthermore, we have already seen how this negative subjectivity, operative in the conceptual project of sublimity, thwarts the tragic prospect in which we might anticipate the subject’s development as a maker of choices, a creature of comparative contexts. In that capacity the sub-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 231
Living in Aesthetic Community
231
ject is a quintessential deliberator. By my own account of the work of Beckett, Caravaggio, Melville, and Joyce, production stages occasions for acknowledging comparative contexts.Within this horizon of experience, a reader’s self-recognition can be solicited in a way that prompts self-consciousness about protocols of choice-making and thus augments the repertoire of choices available to deliberative consciousness. Now I must demonstrate that when we lose rapport with this understanding we risk the loss of the artwork altogether as a site of subjective development. It would mitigate all claims of political efficacy that postmodern theory seeks to derive from what I think is its decidedly Pyrrhic victory over the aesthetic. It is interesting to note that a thinker as resistant as Bourdieu is to the notion that art bears on development nonetheless does not escape the realization that choice-making implicates even the ideology critic in the distinctions that obtain as a condition for reading a literary text qua text. Bourdieu discovers this in the midst of his most concerted dismissal of the aesthetic as inviting a subjective self-recognition that plays naively into the hands of instrumentalized identity. He alleges that the work of art obtains as a province of ideological complicity insofar as we identify the properly aesthetic dimension with the presentational field embodied by the artwork. Bourdieu is more interested in a “critical” decoding of the reasons for the currency of the presentational form of the artwork as they might be representable in a sociological account of its conditions of production. Paradoxically, Bourdieu makes the aesthetic dimension of the work depend on the distinctions that obtain in seeing it against the backdrop of the culture of its production.This is to the exclusion of the distinctions that might obtain as an imperative for engaging the presentational field itself vis-à-vis the “productive” mind of the audience. In this way, Bourdieu disqualifies the work of art as a site of cognition unto itself. Alternatively, he privileges the cognitive prowess inherent in sociological analysis, which sees the work of art as a product of decodable cultural decisions/distinctions.Thus, in a curious way, the artwork can only allegorize the dynamism of social forces.The artwork is thereby consigned to a redundant aestheticism. In effect, Bourdieu is only reasserting the familiar and seemingly intractable dualism of feeling and rationality in his theorizing of the aesthetic. And yet he reveals the weakness of the proposition himself in one of the most methodologically uncharacteristic representations of his position. He ironically follows a method that we might identify with the high modernist aesthetic of “close reading.” In “A Theory of Reading in Practice,” Bourdieu’s
Singer.book
9/12/03
232
11:21 AM
Page 232
Aesthetic Reason
account of William Faulkner’s “A Rose for Emily,” his analysis reveals itself to be implicated in a familiar notion: self-recognition of the reader entails a protocol of choices, instantiating deliberative consciousness on a threshold of error. Faulkner’s narrative about a small town in which the actions of the title character provoke increasingly erroneous speculation seems especially apt. Here the kinds of self-deceptions I have previously associated with akrasia or rational incontinence present the stakes of subjective development to be a plausible crux of narrative art and so a significant lever of aesthetic judgment, arguably indistinguishable from aesthetic practice.What is more—as was laudably the case with Marcuse—the stakes of the aesthetic are here indistinguishable from the stake we have in overcoming the self-mystifications of human subjectivity, without which no meaningful development could ensue. It is worth pointing out that Bourdieu’s analysis of Faulkner begins by implicating the reader’s agency, in stark contrast with the most celebrated principles of Gustave Flaubert’s aesthetic practice.What makes this notable is that elsewhere in The Rules of Art Flaubert stands as the cardinal exemplar of Bourdieu’s aesthetic theorizing and his modeling of novelistic practice.The virtue of Flaubertian style, for Bourdieu, is its signature subordination of the reader’s agency to authorial agency: it is specifically the authorial negation of subjective dispositions that Bourdieu himself calls habitus. Habitus denotes the social conditionings according to which subjects are instantiated as mere instrumentalized actors rather than free agents of their actions. This occurs in much the way that Althusser’s concept of interpellated identity accounts for the “ideological” conversion of illusory subjective agency into actual and fatal subjective passivity.10 It should not be lost on us that the “revolutionary” animus behind Bourdieu’s anti-aestheticism here promises to supplant the political passivity of aestheticism with political action towards freedom. Along these lines, Bourdieu endorses Flaubert’s aesthetic as “[t]he double refusal of opposed positions in different social spaces and of the corresponding taking of positions which is at the foundation of an objectifying distance with respect to the social world” (Rules of Art, 29). The author aims for what Roland Barthes called “generalized asyndeton.” Bourdieu calls it “a negative manifestation” (31) coincident with the withdrawal of the author from the text. So the political beneficence of Flaubert’s aesthetic is clearly its anti-aesthetic deferral to a de facto sociological praxis. No doubt Bourdieu’s reading of Faulkner sets out to persuade us of this American author’s usefulness in further exemplifying the “double refusal.” It
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 233
Living in Aesthetic Community
233
licenses the sociologist to reassert the conviction that a “pure” aesthetic is indistinguishable from pure negation. But the uncharacteristic subtlety of Bourdieu’s literary analysis leads fortuitously in quite another direction. Bourdieu asserts that the artistic integrity of Faulkner’s narrative is most notably coherent with a sociological acuity, and presumably a revolutionary politics, in its manipulation of plot chronology. Faulkner shuffles the chronology in order to enlist the reader’s presuppositions about what might happen, only to discredit them. What distinguishes this defeat of readerly presupposition from the banality of mere crime solving, as in detective novels, is that the reader does not discover a set of misleading clues about an unchanging set of facts. Faulkner’s plot is not a case where the solution of the mystery does not change when one reflects upon the false clues that one entertained along the way. Rather, the reader of “A Rose For Emily” becomes implicated in a reflection upon the terms of the “self-deception into which he has been led” (Bourdieu, Rules of Art, 326).Thus, in reconstructing the chronology of events, correcting his or her mistakes, the reader is reconstituting his or her own temporal agency (327).As Bourdieu puts it: “Agents temporalize themselves in the very act by which they transcend the immediate present towards the future implicated in the past of which their habitus is the product; they produce time in the practical anticipation of a still-to-come [a-venir]” (328). Here Bourdieu acknowledges the relevance of the idea that a transfiguration of subjective agency is intrinsic to aesthetic form. Contrary to Bourdieu’s more characteristic bid to trivialize the aesthetic object qua object, his inclination to view “A Rose for Emily” in terms of the reader’s self-mystification about his or her best reasons for choosing evidence of what is really going on in the plot leads him to a de facto rethinking of his stance toward aesthetic form. For here he acknowledges how the presentational form of the story itself is indistinguishable from temporalizing agency, rooted as such agency is in an exigency of “self-deception” (Rules of Art, 326). Thus I believe that Bourdieu—though he certainly does not mean to—invites us to see how the temporalizing of the act of reading, so lucidly put on display in Faulkner’s story, might be understood as a way of rendering the reader “other” than the mere creature of habitus. After all, his account of Faulkner seems to make the reader’s self-understanding depend upon a set of conscious plot choices that would be inversely proportionate to unconscious decisions, otherwise intelligible as the “untemporalized” subject positions of habitus.These subject positions are represented in
Singer.book
9/12/03
234
11:21 AM
Page 234
Aesthetic Reason
the story by what Bourdieu calls a practice of “‘naively’ novelistic reading” widely indulged by Faulkner’s characters (325). So we might think of Faulkner’s narrative, as Bourdieu describes it, as oddly compatible with my claim that production in the artwork amounts to “staging occasions for comparative contexts.” Such artfulness may even invite “the pleasure of tragic pain” that I established earlier as a premise for appreciating the accomplishments of Beckett, Caravaggio, Melville, and Joyce. In those instances such pleasure subsists on openness to hitherto unacknowledged alternatives for the construction of knowledgeable perspectives. I have already admitted that this reasoning goes against Bourdieu’s invidious desire to sequester the presentational field of the artwork as a noncognitive counterpart to the more responsible cognitive judgment of the sociologist. In most of Bourdieu’s work, the aesthetic judgment per se, characterized in terms of elitist “distinction,” denotes a manipulation of the artwork by the cognitive interests of its cultural promoters (critics) and commercializers. But now it is conceivably an aspect of the artwork qua presentational field.This allows for the possibility that there are cognitive stakes vested within, as well as without, the text. Inasmuch as Bourdieu seems to recognize how much of our sense of ourselves as “acting agents” (Rules of Art, 327) depends on our adeptness at reflecting on our temporal experience, he locates a cognitive condition of self-knowledge that is not dissociable from the presentational métier of narrative form, at least as it is worked out by Faulkner.This offers a pretext for my insisting that the expressive register of the artwork is inextricable from a cognitive account of who we are to constitute such a ground of expressivity in the first place. Such thinking preempts the presupposition of any dichotomy between action (the realm of lived experience) and the narration of action (the realm of represented experience, of habitus) as relevant to our sorting of aesthetic values from the values of social practice. Without being able to privilege this dichotomy, Bourdieu would lack a strong enough warrant for arguing that sociology needs to serve as a rational or cognitive remedy for the affective delusions promulgated from the aesthetic realm. That Bourdieu nonetheless clings to this bias is evident at the end of his Faulkner essay (329).There his analysis of the reader’s temporalization in “A Rose for Emily” abruptly, and we might even say self-preemptively, resolves into a cautionary tale about the epistemological inhibitions fostered by habitus. Instead of seeing how Faulkner’s aesthetic practice—by inculcating the demystification of subjective
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 235
Living in Aesthetic Community
235
agency—constitutes an imperative to engage comparative contexts, Bourdieu sees it as merely a touchstone for the inescapability of a contextually single-minded habitus. Bourdieu fixates on the inescapability of habitus because he can only see Faulkner’s aesthetic practice in terms of the negation of frameworks of expectation. In other words, he sees it exclusively in the mode of Flaubertian irony. The even richer irony is that Faulkner’s aesthetic practice makes the recognitional imperatives precipitated on the threshold of error a performative register of reading. It therefore lends itself to our thinking critically about the analytic inhibitions that are built into the concept of habitus itself. As we have seen to be the case with Althusser’s concept of interpellation, the concept of habitus proves too unsupple in its comprehension of human subjective agency. It cannot comprehend the transition from one contextual order to another as an integrative feature of agency. Such suppleness, after all, has been the sine qua non of tragic adaptivity, and what I have argued are its enabling notions: akrasia and translation. Because Faulkner’s text so eloquently exhibits this suppleness—and in a way that even prompts Bourdieu to dub it a “reflecting” story—it shows the relative impoverishment of the scope of reflection entailed by habitus.The production of Faulkner’s text is presented as a frame for reflective activity that is apparently not bound within the limits of the culturally produced reflections of the human subjectivity coerced by habitus. Instead, or at least potentially, it opens up the activity of production itself to a freer repertoire of agency. Bourdieu himself attests that Faulkner’s text is written in the fashion of an experimental text that requires a “divided reading,” combining “the impressions of the first naive reading, and the revelations it arouses with the second reading, the retroactive illumination that the knowledge of the ending (acquired at the end of the first reading) casts on the text, and especially on the presuppositions of a naively ‘novelistic’ reading” (Rules of Art, 325). It is worth observing that the temporalizing of the reading agent, which Bourdieu enthusiastically sanctions here, implicates his thinking in the two paradigms of cognition that have previously been instrumental to my argument for a cognitive aesthetic. Bourdieu’s analysis of Faulkner bears striking resemblance to Willard Humphreys’s anomaly theory, which locates agency in the “cognitive tensions” imposed by temporalized subjectivity. It likewise recalls Alasdair MacIntyre’s more elaborate account of the ethics inherent in the “occasion” of cognitive tension: the circumstance of epistemological crisis. Specifically for
Singer.book
9/12/03
236
11:21 AM
Page 236
Aesthetic Reason
MacIntyre, cognitive tension, exemplified in the conflict of languages seeking to “explain” a putatively common existence, licenses the transition from a first language in use to a second first language.This makes possible the “translatability” of the human agent across the threshold of contextual change. Bourdieu’s account of first and second readings might seem to echo MacIntyre’s focus on first and second languages as a way of grounding agency in the exigencies of change. But there is considerable dissonance in their respective applications. MacIntyre’s emphasis on the threshold of change, as a premise of value, cannot be accommodated by the concept of habitus. Bourdieu’s “second reading” ignores precisely what is at issue for MacIntyre in his desire to strive for the commensuration, however fleeting, of a first language in use with a second first language, even as the second supercedes the first. MacIntyre shows us that, without the latter, the former cannot be used in a new context, in which case there is no point in addressing the differences between languages as anything but a realm of hapless contingency. I therefore proposed in Chapter 5 that the artwork, understood in MacIntyre’s terms, gives rational structure to the revision of contextual knowledge. On the contrary, because Bourdieu’s “second reading” is always conditioned by the past, any contextualization entailed in the accommodation of the “a-venir” is compulsively negative. It is thus fair to say that Bourdieu is ultimately interested more in the incommensurability of temporal horizons that expose the contradictions within habitus than Humphreys and MacIntyre were. In their pragmatics of transition, they revealed a deeper interest in recognition. For this reason Bourdieu cannot take the next step in thinking about temporalizing agency, which, I have suggested, makes contradiction correlative with adaptation/development. What I am saying is that it would be preferable to see the transitions between the shifting temporal horizons of Faulkner’s text in terms of what I referred to in Chapter 4 as cognitive tensions that arise from the artwork by dint of any such exhibition of formal originality. As I postulated then, formal originality has its own temporalizing imperative: formal innovation brings “a theory of the world into contact with a state of affairs that has yet to be accounted for.”This hope for the commensurability of contextual frames in aesthetic practice may even harmonize with Bourdieu’s notion of the “a-venir” (Rules of Art, 328), a modality of the work of art that he values, at least in Faulkner’s case, because it rejects “the metaphysical representation of time as a reality in itself, exterior and anterior to practice” (328).The difference would be that what is to come, in the context of my cognitive aesthetic, is not
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 237
Living in Aesthetic Community
237
simply a proof of the irrationality of what we already comprehend as habitus. Instead it is a métier of comprehension. It makes practicable our desire to keep faith with the rationality of our relation to contingent experience. This, after all, is the gist of tragedy as an aesthetic modality. It is the chief warrant for maintaining the premise of their mutual intelligibility.
III If my objections to Bourdieu are to serve the larger argumentative purpose of this chapter we must now see how they dovetail with my assertion that only an understanding of what is lost in the evasion of tragedy can show us what stands to be gained through art. I have pegged the stakes of tragic knowledge to an invidious comparison between the agential resources of the “adaptive” aesthetic subject, arising from the plot exigencies of tragedy, and the “critical” subjectivity purveyed out of anti-aesthetic practices, bent as they are upon thwarting tragic knowledge. It now remains to be seen if such a comparison of art practices does indeed strengthen the claim that the adequacy of the aesthetic inheres in its usefulness for comprehending, but not capitulating to, the limits imposed upon human actions in the exigencies of tragic experience. For this task there is no better segue than Pierre Bourdieu’s own recent collaboration with the German-born (resident of the United States) visual artist Hans Haacke, in a work titled Free Exchange.This text might be fairly characterized as a “dialogue” on the inherent “tragedy” of a culture where the ability of artists to orchestrate value debates that might issue in significant cultural production—as opposed to merely reproducing institutional values—is hampered by the ideological co-option of value. A view of Free Exchange will therefore serve several purposes of the argument I have been advancing here. First, it will show how Haacke’s quite laudable critical agenda as an artist is deeply invested in context and contextual framing as a ground of critical reasoning. But just as clearly it will show how Haacke’s grasp of contextual rationality ultimately lacks a métier for engaging the full complexities of comparative context. It thus lacks rapport with the choice-making, deliberative modalities of subjectivity that, I have been asserting, such methodological means might otherwise actualize. I will show that this is chiefly because Haacke’s artistic practice makes boundary erasure (promoting categorical confusions), rather than
Singer.book
9/12/03
238
11:21 AM
Page 238
Aesthetic Reason
boundary negotiation (promoting categorical revisions), the crucial stake of engaging contexts of action in which we are compelled to own up to our subjectivity. In this way, Haacke typifies the post-Enlightenment ethical imperatives of the anti-aesthetic. Even more important, my referencing of Free Exchange will illustrate how the adaptivity conditioned by comparative context—as opposed to critical negation—is a more efficient exploitation of the contextual knowledge that governs when our ability to act purposively is our highest priority. Subsequently I will also take up the work of Cindy Sherman and Barbara Kruger.This contextualizing of Haacke’s practice, and Bourdieu’s theory, will help me to round off my discussion of boundary erasure as a lever of critique and as a touchstone for, or locus of, postmodern sublimity. I will then be in a position to more fully state a contrast with the boundarynegotiating resources cultivated in the aesthetic practices of Caravaggio, Beckett, Melville, and Joyce. I will conclude with a view of the work of the contemporary German painter Gerhard Richter as a way of generalizing the practical virtues of a cognitive aesthetic, without abandoning the field of postmodern art’s honest and urgent contestation with ideology. I want to make it clear once again that in using Haacke, Sherman, and Kruger to set up a comparison between aesthetic and anti-aesthetic practices, I am not proposing to epitomize types or schools of aesthetic practice.That would be to indulge what Bourdieu would rightly condemn as the ideological bad faith of making distinctions between good and bad art, or even aesthetic art and anti-aesthetic art. I am unquestionably committed to the aesthetic. But I commit to it as a métier for deepening reflection upon the question of how it is a resource for the kinds of agency that partisans of the aesthetic and the anti-aesthetic both agree ought to meet a test of adequacy: adequacy with respect to the sociopolitical pressures that human subjects contend with in the prospect of sharing a common world. In Free Exchange, Bourdieu is quick to note the relevance of context to the critical intelligence upon which his own judgment of Haacke’s anti-aesthetic value depends. Indeed, Bourdieu’s praise for the specificity of context in Haacke’s work dovetails with his attack on positive aesthetic valuation.The “museum effect,” which Bourdieu avers is virtually auratic in high-culture canons of aesthetic value,“extracts the work from all contexts, demanding the ‘pure’ gaze” (Bourdieu and Haacke, Free Exchange, 92). Haacke’s accomplishment, against the hegemonic odds of an art culture that sustains its authority by the disembodiment of contextual judgments, is to have made the context of the
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 239
Living in Aesthetic Community
239
artwork’s reception indistinguishable from the artwork’s production. In a curious way, however, this compositional logic devolves to something like the circumstance in which the success of the artwork is correlative with its producing its own reception. This de facto closing of the circuit between production and reception (recognition) smacks ironically of the autonomizing ideals that eventuated the very political isolation of the artwork for which Bourdieu sees Haacke as the remedy. We can best understand Haacke’s vulnerability to this irony by following his rearticulation of Bourdieu’s insight about how the artist’s sense of context determines the reception of his installations: “The context in which the public encounters my works also plays an important role.The people who came upon my installations in the public places of Graz, Munich, and Berlin are different from the museum public. . . . I often work deliberately for a specific context.The social and political character of the exhibition locale plays a role, as do the architectural peculiarities of the space. In fact, the symbolic qualities of the context are often my most essential materials. A work made for a specific site cannot be moved and exhibited elsewhere” (90–91). What is most notable here is Haacke’s conceptual investment in physical site as a relatively fixed and finite context of recognition. Indeed, the negative imperative that I earlier identified as Haacke’s modus operandi could be seen to follow from this sense that context is so strictly deterministic for subject positions.Another way of seeing the weakness of Haacke’s position here is to observe that he frames his negative motives too simplistically within the mutually exclusive choices of something like a Greenbergian formalism (which he alludes to as his own straw man) and the “real world” constituted as a determinative context of value. In considering the dilemma of the contemporary artist who seeks to bridge the art world with the world of the ordinary citizen, Haacke concedes the necessity to navigate between the formalist prejudice that says the objects constituting the history of art are produced in a social vacuum, and the kind of journalistic fidelity to sociopolitical determinants that would make the artist complicit with what he seeks to criticize.What Haacke misses, I want to suggest, is that one need not accept what he calls the “separatism” (89) of choosing between the forms of aesthetic detachment or the forms of social ideology, if one has a more complex appreciation of form as formative agency. A relevant example of how Haacke’s sense of context risks inhibiting his sense of agency is found in his 1990 work Freedom Is Now Simply Going to Be Sponsored—Out of Petty Cash, a work intended
Singer.book
9/12/03
240
11:21 AM
Page 240
Aesthetic Reason
Image not available
Fig. 2 Hans Haacke,“Freedom Is Now Simply Going to Be SponsoredOut of Petty Cash,” 1990. © 2003 Artists Rights Society (ARS), New York / VG Bild-Kunst, Bonn
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 241
Living in Aesthetic Community
241
for the Finiteness of Freedom group exhibition in Berlin. The work occupied the strip of land that formerly marked the border between East and West Berlin. Flanked by two unscalable walls and electrified fencing, it was officially labeled the “border of peace.” Popularly it was known as “the death strip,” the scene of numerous fatal escape attempts during the cold war.The area was surveilled by watch towers mounted with powerful searchlights. Haacke’s installation was a strident reversal of the “discoveries” illuminated from those towers. It entailed replacing the searchlights with a rotating Mercedes Benz star—the company logo—thus mirroring the Mercedes star mounted on the roof of the nearby Europa Center in the most fashionable shopping district of West Berlin. Similarly, Haacke refitted the windows of the tower with glass to mimic those of the Palasthotel in East Berlin, a luxurious residence for official guests of the German Democratic Republic. As an advertising icon, the Daimler-Benz star is a contextual marker, a recognitional boundary, so to speak, in its own right. But the ironic richness of the image, for Haacke, depends on our knowing that Daimler’s most recognized advertising campaign in recent years traded in self-conscious display/deployment of a comparable set of contextual markers, equating cultural capital with the consumer currency of Daimler-Benz’s product. In an ad campaign waged in the New York Times, Daimler-Benz appropriated the classics of Western literature. Shakespeare’s “The readiness is all” (which Haacke translates into German as Bereit sein ist Alles) and Goethe’s “Art will always remain art” (Kunst bleibt Kunst) became captions for cars. In other words, Daimler’s appropriations denote the appropriateness of one’s recognition that the product suits the buyer. Wishing to put this comprehension on display for his own audience, Haacke adorns the opposite sides of his watchtower with these quotations in bronze lettering, thus underscoring the durability of art, not as a formal artifact, but as an appropriable object of material socioeconomic-political powers. So, in effect, the line of sight of the watchtower, the trajectory of surveillance, is reversed by Haacke’s installation. Haacke himself refers to the effect as a “scrambling” of our “categories of classification” (Bourdieu and Haacke, Free Exchange, 97). Emphasizing his own wish to step outside what he calls “the art context” (97) in this work, Haacke intimates, by this account, how boundary crossing in his visual rhetoric tends toward boundary erasure. Freedom Is Now Simply Going to Be Sponsored—Out of Petty Cash works to make the context of totalitarian confinement indistinguishable from the context of capital expansion and to confer this knowledge in a way that eludes either the
Singer.book
9/12/03
242
11:21 AM
Page 242
Aesthetic Reason
representation of or the instantiation of a positional subjectivity. Because Haacke appears to be wedded to the binary logic of art-world versus real-world contextualism (formalism versus ideological determinism), it is easy to appreciate his willingness to think that boundary erasure might foster a subjectivity that can plausibly resist the seductions of contextual reification, whether the instrumentalizing ideology is political or commercial. Haacke’s motives are thrown into clearest relief by his own referencing of these strategies to the legendary boundary-erasing gesture of Marcel Duchamp’s Fountain, which he observes also worked insofar as it “aimed at a specific context” (Bourdieu and Haacke, Free Exchange, 96), namely, the museum. We will not fail to observe that the museum, rendered unbounded, would produce precisely the aesthetic sphere instantiated by Haacke’s art practices. Both Haacke and Bourdieu invite the presumption that such an unboundedness makes possible a “free exchange” between subjects, wherein the freedom that obtains is not beholding to any specific subjectivity. I want to suggest, however, that such tactics, if they are accurately represented by Haacke’s Berlin installation, come perilously close to cultivating something like the “pure gaze” that Bourdieu himself indicted as the premier aesthetic inhibition of cognitive agency. It is the most formidable obstacle to the kind of critical initiative that would otherwise be charged to break the gaze.This liability of Haacke’s theorizing is nowhere more apparent than in our realization that—from a not-so-oblique perspective—Daimler Benz’s advertising has already achieved what Haacke strives for, precisely insofar as it invites us to see the practices of the artist as indistinguishable from the practices of the merchandiser. In a compounding irony, Haacke’s work would then risk an unwitting reprise of formalism: the form of Haacke’s artwork threatens to eclipse its vaunted political content once we realize that what makes Daimler’s formal iconography appropriable in the first place is the medium of appropriation itself, which Daimler can deploy no less deftly than can the artist. In the absence of a more positioned subjectivity to ground it, the métier of appropriation takes center stage as a decentering imperative of understanding. In a trumping irony, we cannot fail to notice that, in the instance of Haacke’s installation, appropriation exhibits an unboundedness that Daimler has already, too successfully, deployed to the arguable advantage of a consuming subject who is thereby pleasurably disembodied in the alembic of capital exchange. I admit that from Haacke’s perspective, I am putting undue emphasis on the place of the subject vis-à-vis the form of the artwork. This
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 243
Living in Aesthetic Community
243
goes against Haacke’s clear wish to elude the risk of producing reified subjective positions. He must fear that these ensue from locating the cognitive function of the artwork in the matrices of its formal density— that is, its presentational dimension as contrasted with its site specificity. The boundary-erasing gestures of what I think it is not too paradoxical to call Haacke’s “anti-aesthetic/aesthetic practice” are certainly meant to minimize the formal armature of the putative aesthetic object as a threshold of cognitive engagements. It could be said, therefore, that Haacke’s emphasis on the site specificity of the work is orchestrated to defetishize the epistemic situation of the viewing subject.Another way of saying this, of course, is that Haacke’s work attacks aesthetic value in Bourdieuian terms. It makes the presentational field increasingly marginal to or abstract from the situation of the audience’s engagement. Inasmuch as that engagement demands a condition of relative unboundedness, however, it must accordingly be posited as a realm that remains external to any specific site of subjective reflection.This strikes me as an unwittingly self-preemptive gesture on Haacke’s part. If I seem to discount Haacke’s commitment to boundary erasure as a way of preempting the viewing subject’s—ideologically predisposed—dependence on the “aesthetic” densities of presentational form, it is nevertheless because I want to think about how to keep faith with the indispensability of the subject to the political purposes that Haacke himself is staked in. For he is staked in these no less tenaciously than he is staked in his skepticism toward aesthetic form. In other words, I need to point out that Haacke’s practices disable the subject in the very capacities the artist himself most wants to exercise. Quite simply, the resources of critical mind that both Haacke and Bourdieu are allied to mobilize, in installation art and sociological practice respectively, presuppose qualities of subjective response and attunement to the world that only the specificity of formal densities can occasion. For this reason the artist’s demurring of the presentational field as a site for such subjective engagements seems a particularly perverse scruple. In pursuing this point, I want to take a more general critical perspective with respect to the postmodern oppositional discourses that Haacke and Bourdieu champion, precisely on account of their efficient purge of perceived formalist biases. For this purpose I want to enlist the work of Charles Altieri. Altieri strikes me as the theorist who has most astutely observed the gap between postmodern art and the agencies it would mobilize to political effect. Altieri attributes this gap in large part to the lack of rapport exhibited by oppositional theories/ rhetorics with respect to the complexities that the presentational
Singer.book
9/12/03
244
11:21 AM
Page 244
Aesthetic Reason
dimension of the artwork can muster as an occasion for human responsiveness. By eliding the complexities of the presentational dimension of the artwork, thinkers such as Haacke and Bourdieu risk losing the very stage upon which the enactment of political conversions must be performed, if such enactments are to be believed as viable instantiations of personal agency. In his disputation with politicizers of the aesthetic and the oppositional modes of postmodern art,Altieri begins to imagine for us an aesthetic that might be fully adequate to the critical imperatives of postmodernity—where the legitimacy of the artwork is increasingly judged according to its efficacy in resisting forms of cultural oppression. Altieri has demurred a direct response to the question of what would constitute an adequate political art (Postmodernisms Now, 225). Nevertheless, I think his recent work provides a rich framework for beginning the task on our own. Out of his intimations of what would suffice as a good account of political art I believe we can begin to speculate about the conditions for a cognitive aesthetic agency that makes concentrating on the inner workings of the artwork relevant for our most constructive interests in imagining ennobling civic works. I will pay closest attention to three essays in Altieri’s collection Postmodernisms Now: “The Powers and Limits of Oppositional Postmodernism,”“On the Sublime of Self-Disgust,” and “The Four Discourses of Postmodernism.” Not the least of Altieri’s accomplishments here is raising a cogent suspicion that oppositional aesthetics—Hal Foster and Victor Burgin are the representative cases here— paradoxically cannot handle the intricacies of strong works of art. In “The Powers and Limits of Oppositional Postmodernism,” Altieri notes that in contemporary debates the framing opposition between “aesthetic concerns and the political work of intervening in the field of representations” (Postmodernisms Now, 230) tends to organize our thinking along oversimplifying binary lines, such as we have seen Marcuse fall afoul of. The binaries of self-other, and public-private, become pretexts for the ultimate, and so ultimately unbridgeable, binary of the aesthetic and the political (230). Earlier, in a striking footnote to the same essay, Altieri surmises that instead of thinking that art’s primary role is a critique of representations that instantiate oppression, perhaps we should think of it as a métier for the “development of certain kinds of knowledge about the oppressed” (224).This no doubt entails knowing that knowledge of the oppressed can only be accessed through a representational repertoire that is otherwise blamed for their oppression. It seems to me that the resonance between these moments in Altieri’s essay estab-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 245
Living in Aesthetic Community
245
lishes a basis for appreciating his stake in aesthetic principles that bear on how the intricacy of the artwork relates to the purposiveness of subjective development. Such principles would sustain experiential continuity between the aesthetic and the political, because both are rendered dependent on presentational particularity. As Altieri is quick to point out, this is precisely what the oppositional artists and their postmodern critical patrons risk being blinded to by their extreme suspicions of the subject. Although Altieri might quarrel with my emphasis on the cognitive, I believe that he sees what I would be looking for in my own advancement of a cognitive aesthetic. If the purpose of art is conceived simply as critique of representations and the presentational modalities that sustain them, aesthetic theory makes a curious concession to the Platonist disenfranchisement of art: that the only reality that counts lies outside the domain of art. Among other liabilities, such thinking inadvertently justifies sacrificing the aesthetic to the methods of scientific inquiry, unencumbered as they are with the presentational burdens of formal composition/aesthetic production.This, of course, is precisely what sociological critics such as Pierre Bourdieu are only too happy to encourage. In this perspective, the work of art becomes aestheticized in the worst sense. It becomes purely gestural, an allegorical pretext for soliciting expertise from competing disciplines of knowledge. I want to get deeper into these issues through Altieri’s revisionary engagement of the Romantic sublime, postulated here as a sublime of self-disgust. The “sublime of self-disgust” is Altieri’s countermeasure against postmodern culture critics who deploy the sublime as a site of oppositional otherness: one that self deceivingly or self preemptively advocates transcendence of the realm of appearance. Altieri rightly insists that aesthetics has a claim on us expressly in this presentational realm—without which we cannot hope to bring ourselves into accord with our best motives for wanting to appear to one another in the light of just actions. Self-disgust is Altieri’s homeopathy for the disease of narcissistic self-effacement that is promoted by so much postmodern aesthetic cant that embraces the sublime. The reigning postmodern sublime is, of course, understood in its antipresentational modality, as an antidote to that popular scapegoat of postmodern politics: the Enlightenment ego. Altieri sketches the representative Lyotardian and Nancyian appropriations of sublimity as a refusal of the presentational field. He then reminds us that Kantian art, by contrast, has impact for us precisely because it “brings the negatives of the sublime back into complex ‘aesthetic ideas’” (Postmodernisms Now, 270); Altieri’s con-
Singer.book
9/12/03
246
11:21 AM
Page 246
Aesthetic Reason
strual of Kant as using “aesthetical ideas,” in a sense to make the sublime presentational, is crucial to his finding a site for aesthetic activity: one that is conducive to freeing subjects from the self-preemptive social roles that indenture them to Enlightenment standards of self-recognition. Altieri’s stated ambition, after all, is for us to attune ourselves to works of art that “can produce awareness of the conditions of desire that make design significant and that allow inventions to become modes of taking possession of what otherwise could only remain alien or unknown” (253–54). Altieri strongly suggests that this “taking possession” has to be coupled with the complexities of aesthetic formal presentation. Otherwise the alienation of the self precipitated by our Enlightenment reasons for being is likely to become—in the hands of postmodern political critics of Enlightenment—a motive for negating altogether those particularities upon which aesthetic form subsists as an experiential register. Altieri reminds us how this negation is purveyed, by oppositional postmodernists, as an identification with Otherness.This identification, by its very generality, promises a release from the pressures of ideologically determined existence. In the process however, it unwittingly trivializes the stakes of our recognition of ideological existence by attenuating the determinateness of that existence. What is wrong with this version of the postmodern sublime, as Altieri assesses it, is its undue dependency on negative knowing, and its grossly departicularized identification with otherness. Not surprisingly, Altieri reserves his most severe critique for what amount to contemporary caricatures of the sublime as a grandiose humility toward otherness. Grandiose humility purports to reconfigure our relations with others by scrupulous askesis of the grandiosity of our self-interest (264). In this noble raiment we indulge the hypocritical gesture of renouncing the limitedness of what we can claim for ourselves as rationally overmastering egos in favor of the unlimitedness of the place of the other, to which we would too willingly “sacrifice” ourselves. By such means, we enjoy, in the most self-congratulatory way, a recouping of our self-interest in the name of a more selfless expansion of the powers of mind (260). Altieri’s sublime of self-disgust, by contrast, allows for the possibility that the real powers of the sublime only get tapped when it holds us specifically accountable—and in some rationalistic terms—to the very affects and commitments by which the postmodern renunciation of the self was originally made possible and thus convertible into a selfless sublime (259). Altieri in effect privileges the self’s otherness to itself above those rhetorics of otherness that are pitched as virtually infinite openness to experience. He objects to the way such rhetorics
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 247
Living in Aesthetic Community
247
construe humility as an abdication of those states of mind to which we could otherwise be held practically or phronetically (264) responsible. In Altieri’s view, we need to see more clearly how “all our predications about empirical experiences seem limited or problematic” (Postmodernisms Now, 260). But we do not need to follow the postmodern sublimicists who say that the limitation counts as a reason to negate the self altogether. Altieri points out that the advantage to be gained by rejecting such conclusions is that the sublime is then mediated by self-reflection. In this way sublime negativity is brought to bear on empirical attitudes that we formerly identified with—at the cost of significant critical self-awareness—in order to produce a critical selfawareness that need not resort to self-annihilation. Altieri identifies this sublime with authors such as Beckett, Jorge Luis Borges, and Robert Coover who see to it, in the formality of their compositions, that “the sublime retains substantial negative force, never inviting translation into any mode of self-assertion recoverable within a practical account of psychological powers” (261). Altieri points out, however, that such negativity, which in the hands of too many postmodern sublimicists exhausts itself in irony, precipitates more positive determinations in the hands of Beckett, Borges, and Coover. Sublimity comes to define capacities of mind that we can inhabit rather than capacities of mind that exile us from the self-representations through which we otherwise come to know our actions as inadequate. For these authors, there is no abdication of our responsibility for bearing identifications that we might nonetheless also see good reason to reject.The sublime of selfdisgust resigns us to a laborious recognition of the limits of empirical understanding, in a way that does not abandon the work or the workings of understanding. Instead it drives us, as Altieri says,“to reformulate our specific uses of the old tools (and that in turn supplements [our] concern to undo those grandiose versions of humility that blind us to those resources that we might in fact be able to manipulate and reorient)” (265). Our reformulation of the uses of “old tools” intimates a practice of cultivating the adaptivity, rather than indulging the hubristic negativity, of post-Enlightenment subjectivity. The recovery of an adaptive agency stands out here as a prospect for showing how works of art, epitomized for Altieri by Borges, Beckett and Coover, can play what he calls “significant corrective and projective social roles” (Altieri, Postmodernisms Now, 261).What is even more important, from my point of view, is Altieri’s capacity for appreciating, in these roles, a political aptitude of the aesthetic that is not bound to abdicate its own expressive means, contaminated as they might be by
Singer.book
9/12/03
248
11:21 AM
Page 248
Aesthetic Reason
subjective commitments to Enlightenment values. Instead, this aptitude proffers an experience that readers can reckon with (by engaging forms like those deployed by Beckett, Borges, and Coover) in order to adapt more idealistically the expressive resources that are funded by their identifications with the world around them. Interestingly, Altieri equates the knowledge availed in the aesthetic practices of Borges, Beckett, and Coover with “the cold capacity to accept in bleak playfulness what is most disturbing in the blindness to which our egos cannot but succumb” (259). For Altieri, this is a glimpse of what Kant nobly pursued in the interests of a depersonalized reason, and for which the aesthetic served as a kind of subreptitious register of experience. Correspondingly, Altieri’s “sublime of self-disgust” proposes an acceptance of the “figures we recuperate through the negative moments the sublime fosters” (259–60) that nonetheless enjoins us from any narcissistic identification with those figures. I would put the emphasis on how this capacity for acceptance is proportionate to the ways in which it instantiates adaptability as an accommodation of the self-critical imperatives that can be mined from egoistic blindnesses. I will not rehearse Altieri’s persuasive readings of Borges, Beckett, and Coover in order to defend this claim. I would prefer to defend it by considering Altieri’s accounts of postmodern oppositional artistic practices in the visual arts—particularly in the work of Hans Haacke. For, as my previous discussion of Haacke made clear, in the arena of visual art the presentational stakes of aesthetic value are particularly vexed. Looking at the work of such a high-profile anti-aesthetic artist as Haacke, Altieri gives us a view of how what I am calling a protocol of adaptability might better serve the acceptance of what is disturbing in our egotistic blindness. Specifically, I will argue that a protocol of adaptability is preferable to the baldly negative and transgressive ideals of artists who espouse the critique of that ego and the purification of the presentational field, in which it is instantiated, as the prime justification of artistic expression. In effect,Altieri faults these artists for not fully appreciating how this critique ought to entail “a transformation of typical aspects of agency” (239)—rather than indulge a drift toward pure negation, which must ultimately be self-defeating. In other words, Altieri wants us to imagine “an art that can take responsibility for its own purposiveness, its own capacity to shape a significant particularity” (239). Here the linkage between an art that can “take responsibility” and the “shaping of particularity” intimates a rearticulation of subjective agency as métier. For these reasons, I think Altieri finds his best staging ground for the
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 249
Living in Aesthetic Community
249
question, How do we imagine an aesthetic more adequate to the critical imperatives of postmodernity? when he confronts theorists and artists who make the test of artistic value its debunking of art’s complicity with the ideology of the Enlightenment subject.This complicity—commonly identified by oppositional postmodernism with the seductions of sensuous/formal presentation—is a crux of anti-aestheticism. And yet Altieri seems to want to recuperate this complicity to art’s capacity for shaping “significant particularity.” Admittedly, in challenging the postmodernist’s bid to politicize art by means of an unduly self-serving negation of the self, Altieri does not use the term adaptability. But I believe that he signals its relevance in the tenor of his forceful declaration that art has a politics “to the degree that it carries certain qualities or makes comprehensible and authoritative certain attributes that propose modifying the investments that its audience makes in its own social relationships” (Postmodernisms Now, 239).The kind of social power that this thinking would confer on works of art implies an adaptive agency, in the sense that any modification of investments must entail a negotiation of boundaries and limits, not their mere transcendence.Altieri’s deeply appreciative but ultimately “critical” readings of the work of Kruger and Haacke are exemplary for the insight they yield about how negotiable boundaries—rather than transcendable boundaries—are important for understanding that the qualities featured in the presentational field of the artwork are crucial to the task of modifying investments. The register of presentational appearance, which Altieri credits Kant with making essential to the aesthetic (267), establishes the relevant boundaries within which the work of art exhibits its possibilities for modifying the investments of its audience. And yet we will not forget that it is precisely this presentational aspect of the work that has come under attack by postmodernists whose stake in negation dictates preferences for an art that eschews the presentational field. Hal Foster, for example, equates the indulgence of the presentational field, artworks that depend too much on formal complexity, with betrayals of free subjectivity. Foster infers that the presentational field invites the preemption of a more authentic subjectivity. That authenticity is otherwise repressed in the ideologically interpellated identities so deceptively purveyed to us on the presentational register by the “media” of official culture.There are of course good reasons for critics such as Foster to be suspicious that the presentational assertions of the old-fashioned political artworks, which strove to represent a specific political ideal in sensuous terms, indulged something like a fetishistic nostalgia for
Singer.book
9/12/03
250
11:21 AM
Page 250
Aesthetic Reason
the image (Altieri, Postmodernisms Now, 233). Foster worries with good reason that any attempt within the presentational field to represent our investment in political ideals hearkens toward a universalistic mentality that cannot resist ideological interpellation.Altieri, however, wants us to see that radical skepticism toward the presentational register—so often implied in the stance of resistance to ideological representations—risks the just-as-damaging paradoxical effect of making the artwork depend on the abstract expectations of an art world in which the artist’s intentions purchase recognition. In this case, it is recognition of a political identity unmoored from the choice-inducing densities by which formal embodiment otherwise holds us to a discipline of practical knowledge. Such recognition comes at the high cost of any credible field of practical, not to say political, action. As Altieri concludes,“[A]rt as resistance is necessarily bound to an art world that can recognize it as political gesture, so that the art will be haunted by the possibility that it is nothing more than gesture” (234). Altieri invites us to see, then, how artists such as Barbara Kruger and Han Haacke are imbued with Foster’s suspicion by their common practice of making presentational assertions into an unduly “gestural” site for negation rather than identification.The cultural self-recognition of the viewer is thus rendered too abstractly as a given rather than as a consequence of engagement with the work. While Altieri is appreciative of Kruger’s use of the tensions between the verbal and the visual to “depsychologize the I,” and Haacke’s deftness at using the artwork to reveal social affiliations, which frankly manipulative artistic styles otherwise hide or disguise, he is ultimately suspicious that both Kruger’s and Haacke’s audiences do not really need the art to have the politics they purvey (252). In effect, the practices of these artists derealize the ground of particularity upon which “individual purposive differences” (240) count as the crucial register of experience.After all, the ground of particularity is the place where one’s investments are modifiable, because they are compellingly one’s own. Only in these terms are investments a plausible feature of the kind of agency whose transformability, Altieri suggests, may be our only realistic basis for faith in art as a vehicle of political change. It is with this understanding that Altieri proceeds to show us how Haacke’s attempt to expose the political horrors of South African apartheid fails to engage the level of subjective experience animating our sense of the political precisely insofar as it is cut off from the wellspring of subjective choice-making. In Voici Alcan (1983), Haacke displays the Alcoa aluminum company’s complicity with apartheid through
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 251
Living in Aesthetic Community
251
the ironic imposition of an aluminum window frame, blending “the frame provided by advertising technique with the literal image of an Alcoa aluminum window in order to concentrate on leading us finally to see what lies on the other side of that window, namely the reality of Alcoa’s South African subsidiary supporting apartheid” (226). Altieri understands the revenge motif that is implicit in this visual rhetoric: “‘You advertise windows,’ [Haacke] tells them,‘so I will show you how advertisement can fully realize the role of windows’” (Altieri, Postmodernisms Now, 226).The problem Altieri wants us to see here is that the principles of political resistance that are meant to be at work in this composition are already too transparently clear on the moral level, which the art work addresses through its overtly rhetorical aperture.The fact is the political institutions of apartheid themselves have succeeded as well as they have precisely by making morality abstract from subjective particularity.Altieri cogently observes that it is far more likely that “art can affect policy in South Africa only by modifying sensibilities . . . by making fully compelling the qualities of subjective life that are denied under apartheid” (252). Such subjective qualities would give density to the presentational field which Haacke and, as we shall see in the following section, Kruger thin out or oversimplify by displacing the viewer’s faculty for the discrimination of qualities to a purely ideational field. Altieri persuades us that by denying access to modalities of subjective particularity—which Foster might likewise dismiss as irremediably interpellated identity—Haacke and Kruger’s art practices inhibit real subjective needs that can only know themselves, however erroneously, as instantiated in representable ideals.The operative assumption here seems to be that subjects can only change their identity on the basis of their embodiment in representable ideals.They depend upon the representability of the ideals in order to reject them. Along these lines,Altieri shrewdly leads us to think about how art practices that eschew identification with representable ideals paradoxically result in an idealization of the gesture of resistance itself.They mitigate the particularity of the identity that is meant to be resisted in the presentational field of the artwork, and without which there is no real ground for resistance.Alternatively,Altieri would like us to consider that when the presentational field is engaged by artists and critics—for example, the artist Jennifer Bartlett—who countenance that particularity as a métier for the “transformation of typical features of agency” (239), it can become a more productive arena for political resistance. Such artists as Bartlett, he believes, let us see the necessity of entertaining an identification with representable/representational ideals, in
Singer.book
9/12/03
252
11:21 AM
Page 252
Aesthetic Reason
order to render resistance less ideal. In doing so they make the artwork more real to us as a site for contestatory subjectivity. In response to the idealizing oversimplification of the presentational field that is—however unwittingly—perpetrated by Haacke, Altieri reminds us of a fundamental fact of artistic purposiveness with respect to the task of political resistance. It is that the “crucial act of resistance [responds] to the dullness of life and sensibility basic to most forms of tyranny—from the Left or from the Right and from the inside as well as the outside” (239). It is on the level of the dullness of life and sensibility that we are unarguably rooted in the representational. Resistance on this level is bound to entail a transformation of “typical features of agency,” because on this level we inhabit boundaries of identification as a necessary condition of knowing what our identificatory gestures cannot avail. This is a context within which subjectivity is held to a standard of particularity that suits Altieri’s (240) conviction about the need for humbling political art to the realization that its proper domain must be the place where it can forge “nuanced and flexible psyches” (253).This seems to be proposed as an alternative to the public domain in which those psyches know their suffering too definitively as mere alienation—an unduly self-congratulatory alienation at that. So it comes as no surprise that, in the final analysis, Altieri sees Haacke’s art as too cynical precisely because it gives its audience no other “theater of self-consciousness” than one in which subjective moral differentiations remain on an impossible level of generality.This generality preempts the cultivation of purposive differences (240) by which subjects know how to assess the commitments that bind them to the occasion for moral choice-making.Above all else it is this occasion that artists such as Haacke admirably strive to promote. Unfortunately, Haacke’s practice invites an only too complacent and selfrighteous identification with the stance of moral rectitude. In the process he loses rapport with the constitutive ground of “nuanced and flexible psyches” from which such identifications arise and that, for Altieri, remain the more compelling “domain.” In this domain, art plays a role in what I characterized earlier as the adaptivity of the subject. Altieri refers to it as the project of “adapting ourselves to the sources of those comforts unromantically but profoundly shaping what we can live in as intimate space” (253). For him it is a version of recognizing our dependency on the orders that we critique. It is this recognition that buttresses what I take to be Altieri’s most compelling aesthetic prescription: “Art has to develop ways of showing how agency and responsibility are realized most fully in processes of responsiveness and
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 253
Living in Aesthetic Community
253
attunement, not in subordinating the self to categorical imperatives or according to duty” (289). I cannot think of a better premise from which to argue for the political efficacy of the artwork. It makes the threshold of significance those human powers that are never easily subsumed to the universalizing trajectory of power.Altieri convincingly warns us that we might otherwise only ever know them in the depersonalized righteousness of our political alienation. In that capacity we are helpless to change anything that would convincingly count as art or politics.
IV I now want to use Altieri’s account of the self-inhibiting practices of postmodern oppositionalism as a pretext for imagining how the adaptive subject and the deliberative métier of “pleasurable tragic pain,” which I have said that subject trades in, can serve the purposes of aesthetic and anti-aesthetic theorists alike.To be fair, the anti-aesthetic aesthetic partisans whom Altieri critiques do not present themselves (as Haacke certainly does not) in the rhetoric of negation and radical skepticism. But I want to show that this negative stance is ineluctable, given the oppositional postmodernists’ predilection for a mode of irony that precludes comparative context. I have said that comparative context is mandated whenever we grant embodiment of the subject as a relevant condition for knowing it. I have acknowledged that oppositionalists/anti-aesthetic partisans do not want to accommodate comparative context because they are so suspicious of the “ready-made” embodiments of human subjectivity by which such comparisons would be authorized.Those ideologically interpellated social roles court the political oppressions of reason. But I have also insisted that there are other versions of embodiment. The embodiment of the subject that is operative for Altieri in the presentational mode of the artwork is usefully compared at this point to Paul Crowther’s complementary efforts to locate a ground of human responsiveness, and a resource for attunement between human mind and world, in Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology.11 What makes this path of inquiry even more decisive for my argument is the fact that MerleauPonty deploys the notion of embodiment, if only implicitly, as a logical pretext for comparative context. It thus posits a plausible access to an augmented deliberative capacity. Crowther usefully develops this implication. He points out that insofar as this “embodiment” entails the subject’s intuiting itself as a unity in the course of temporal change,
Singer.book
9/12/03
254
11:21 AM
Page 254
Aesthetic Reason
self-transfigurative agency must be a means of self-realization or selfstylization.The reason is, Crowther elaborates, that the body can only hold its physical place in existential space if it can “mobilize the resources of its past experience in a lucid way” (Critical Aesthetics, 200). What presents itself as new is assimilated to its unity: “Hence, when such a subject expresses itself—in language or by the creation of artifacts—what is expressed can bear the imprint of this stylization. This is not simply a quantitative ‘mix’ of existing idioms and techniques. Rather it is a qualitative transformation of them” (201). This understanding, for Crowther, means nothing less than accepting the proposition that as long as art is produced by such embodied subjects, and serves as a site for instantiating them,“the possibility of creativity exists” (201).This proposition launches Crowther’s own critical initiative against poststructuralist skepticism when it is expressed as negation of presence, meaning, and subjectivity. In Crowther’s mind, these negations prompt art practices that can amount to little more than “empty eclecticism,” an unduly reflexive, which is to say not reflective, modality of boundary erasure and a counterpoint to the imperative for boundary negotiation that I think Crowther anticipates. This imperative is likewise the predicate for my own sense of investment in aesthetic knowledge where what is to be known entails the burden of activity. Crowther accordingly avers that sustaining aesthetic experience under the condition of embodiment demands something like a protocol of development. It entails “opening ourselves not only to new works, but also to new sets of relations in terms of which works are situated” (208). He offers what he dubs a “principle of reciprocity” to undergird this idealistic prospect. Crowther makes the iterability of form, in particular embodiments of subjective existence, a condition of the intelligibility of these embodiments.Accordingly, comparative context becomes an indispensable tool of self-understanding. He explains that we know a thing according to our implicatedness in new contexts of experience—intuitable as they expressly are—in relation to what is iterated.Therefore, an item of experience, real or representational, possesses meaning “by virtue of its reciprocal relation with a broader field of items and relations.”This reciprocity, which Crowther understands on the order of figure-ground relations, is equivalent, he says, to “our capacity for productive imagination” (24). It is epiphenomenal of Merleau-Ponty’s more generalized sense of the reciprocity of mind and world. But Crowther moves Merleau-Ponty’s assumption into a more rationalist perspective. Crowther presupposes that the continuity of embodied subjectivity across contextual boundaries carries with it the
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 255
Living in Aesthetic Community
255
responsibility for reconciling one context with another. Indeed, he equates the rationalistic burdens of embodied subjectivity with the warrant for comparative context that arises in cases of anomalous perception.Whereas in normal perception we tend not to notice reciprocal relations, Crowther asserts, “the perception of a problematic space makes them manifest.To describe such a space is to find an appropriate reciprocal relation or set of such relations around which it is organized” (24).This traces the arc of a learning curve that I see as roughly conducive to Altieri’s call for “nuanced and flexible psyches.” Although Altieri and Crowther are different in important ways, Altieri’s suspicion of irony as a self-sufficient critical mode concurs with Crowther’s scruple against the notion that subjectivity can be meaningfully instantiated as a proliferation of differences through irony.12 He rejects this proposition on the grounds that it promotes a depersonalized disembodiment of value, quite incompatible with the irreducible formal embodiment of the artwork itself.And since such embodiment compels comparative context, where choice and continuity must inhere as formative elements of subjectivity, we can perhaps now better see the justice of my argument to this point.When comparative context is obviated, recognition becomes too patly a given of the interpretive circumstance, and so promotes an anti-tragic ethos.Where there is no reciprocity between competing contexts of knowledge, contrary to the example of Greek peripeteia, the bearer of ironic knowledge evades tragic reckoning with what his or her knowledgeable perspective differs from. Concession to such irony is tantamount to taking an antideliberative stance. It invites an unexpected regression to formalist grounds of value. In fact, it risks reverting to the very Greenbergian formalism that the anti-aesthetic ironists of the postmodern art world want to displace. As anticipated, the work of Cindy Sherman and Barbara Kruger offers further exemplification of the problem. It typifies an art practice that, while passionately resistant to aesthetic formalism, nonetheless makes recognition too much a given of its circumstance, and so precludes any augmenting of the context of recognition, such as comparative context affords.This work might therefore help to illustrate how a recognition unearned in the tragic vicissitudes of error is comparatively inarticulate in the circumstances of human learning. Kruger makes “typography”—the material form of linguistic communication—the armature of her culture critique. Sherman makes “type,” as persona, the métier of her negation of the consumerist stances to which we are recruited by the culture. In both cases the imperative to recognize the self-alienat-
Singer.book
9/12/03
256
11:21 AM
Page 256
Aesthetic Reason
ing elements of cultural identity is coordinate with the artist’s recognition that value, meaning, and so on are uniformly preempted by the forms of communicative competence that solicit our pseudoactive participation in cultural life. Nevertheless, Kruger, by blurring the line between art and advertising, visual and verbal fluency, and subjectobject relations (addresser-addressee of media context), and Sherman, by blurring the line between personal and public identity formation, both perform a boundary erasure that obliterates the imperative for comparative context.We shall see how these practices unintentionally promote a nonpresentational, virtual contextlessness, which is arguably equivalent to the “autonomy” of the classic modernist artwork. By their gestures of radical boundary erasure, Kruger and Sherman evoke the mode of autonomy that Marcuse himself identified with self-mystifications that only art can remedy: mistaking necessity for choice, mistaking alienation as the only, albeit delusional, access to self-realization. Of course, we saw how Marcuse’s own critical erasure of the boundary between self and other vitiated the very productive agency upon which choice depends, if it is to be sustained as an effectual practice rather than merely venerated as an emblem of metaphysical freedom. In Marcuse’s analysis it became an unwitting impediment to self-knowledge. So here I am asserting that Sherman and Kruger follow a similarly troubled course. Self-knowledge, after all, is what is most explicitly and laudably pursued in the boldest gestures of Sherman’s and Kruger’s boundary-erasing visual rhetoric. But the suspicions of the self that animate their questioning are so virulent that they risk concluding that self-annihilation would be the only acceptable answer. In that case we are left to contend with the paradox of freedom as mutually exclusive of knowledge.This is, of course, a familiar topos of sublimity, but one that has not served art or aesthetic theory particularly well. The question remains in the work of Sherman and Kruger, as it does in Marcuse’s: How does the self come to terms of knowledge that sustain its self-questioning across the threshold of otherness? Or to put it in Crowther’s perspective, how does the self keep faith with the unitary principle of embodiment—the self’s de facto motive—while accommodating the artwork’s justifiable suspicion of the ways in which aesthetic formalism collaborates with the oppressive forms of subjectivity it is otherwise inspired to challenge? In other words, I want to assert that inasmuch as artists such as Sherman and Kruger are self-consciously invested in subject critique, they cannot afford to shirk their investment (albeit unselfconscious) in forms of rational accountability. Let me suggest that
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 257
Living in Aesthetic Community
Image not available
Fig. 3 Barbara Kruger,“You Are Not Yourself,” 1982. Courtesy Mary Boone Gallery
257
Singer.book
9/12/03
258
11:21 AM
Page 258
Aesthetic Reason
those forms of accountability are nothing less than the philosophical counterpart to the presentational power presupposed in or mobilized by the aesthetic. Unfortunately, by making the presentational register hinge on a recognition that is too ironically informed, and thereby eliding the subjective grounds of self-understanding with the critique of those grounds, such artists as Kruger and Sherman risk making rational accountability incoherent with the responsibilities we assume in seeking it. See, for example, Kruger’s deployment of the perversely interpellating admonition “You are not yourself” in the work that bears the phrase as its title (1982). The words, which are collaged over the black-andwhite photo of a fractured mirror image, have their emphatic punctuation in what appears to be an intact bullet hole. It shatters the gaze while focusing the composition. As a result, the self that “is not” here exhibits a quasi-Parmenidesian countenance. If Plato’s Athenian Stranger in the Sophist (2.28–29) doubts that one cannot speak of what is not, Kruger’s impetus to convey that the subject “is not” rings similarly hollow. Of course the hollowness appears to be deliberate. But I think it is deliberate in a way that is not entirely witting. Kruger wants to empty the subject of all but the most echoic resonance of being.Yet she does so in a way that seems too literally empty. Compositionally, the hollowness of subjectivity here is indexed to a recognition that the irony of the shattered mirror reflects only too holistically. Not to be one’s self in this circumstance is too much a given of seeing that one sees perforce through the eyes of another, with whom no self can ever be fully correlative.This wisdom is hollow in a double sense. First, otherness is rendered meaningless, so to speak, by the lack of comparison. But more important, the “truth” of this wisdom, by virtue of its indeterminacy, opens upon no further avenue of insight, and thus gains no depth from being contemplated. We could say that what we see is too reductively what we get in this composition, or that if we “get the point” about shattered subjectivity, our comprehension merely recognizes what seeing makes possible.The prompt to self-divestiture in Kruger’s piece is perhaps most clear in the mirroring of fracture as a trait of language—represented here as an assemblage of cut-out words in Letraset. But in this way it actually precludes the kind of reciprocity that, for Crowther, would obtain as a compositional stricture when subjective embodiment is the relevant compositional ground. I would go further to suggest that where reciprocity is the issue the embodying form of the artwork de facto instantiates errors of perception as a deliberative burden. After all, embodiment stands always in a reciprocal relation with the variability
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 259
Living in Aesthetic Community
259
of its contexts of understanding. Kruger’s piece, by virtue of its rhetorical transparency, does not stage occasions for comparative contextualizing. In a sense, because the nullification of subjectivity is the only term of intelligibility in this piece, it fails to make recognition depend on contexts of knowledge outside its own field of reference. It thus fails to entertain error as a significant variable of viewing. Its compositional field lacks the kind of density that was exhibited in the earlier discussions of Melville, Joyce, Beckett, and Caravaggio, with the proviso, of course, that we understand such density in those works to be a correlate of reading mind, not exclusively a formal decorum. And indeed, in those works, the stakes of formal innovation entailed a subjectivity born of the deliberative rigors of reading. Kruger’s inhibition of comparative contextualizing is most evident in the ways in which the verbal and the visual are rendered overly concordant registers of value in such works as You Are Not Yourself. In contrast to the practices of Melville, Joyce, Beckett, and Caravaggio, the compositional field improvised in Kruger’s piece does not incite contextualization so much as it purveys recognition of an already formed idea. Notwithstanding the urgency of that idea—warning us against the delusional perspective inherent in all merely self-serving formative agency—it here constitutes a context of understanding that is all too one-sided, because it is all too infinitely generalizable. Because, in the compositional perspective of this work, we are already well outside the context of reflective experience afforded by the mirror—inasmuch as the mirror is shattered or debunked—our “reading” is deflected from any preoccupation with the division between one reflection and another. That is the “place” of embodiment per se.Absent that threshold, there is little scope for tragic slippage between one context and another, and hence no subjective imperative to choose. Such “tragic” perspective could only be attained if Kruger’s investment in the image entailed a relation to presentational powers not already realized within it.This relationality, Crowther claims, is what embodiment intrinsically portends. In other words, Kruger’s oversimplification of the presentational field produces the antithesis of that deliberative exigency that I am alleging to be a threshold of cognitive aesthetics. Only a presentational field determined in recognition of the possibilities of error, where perceptual densities can be made the occasion of their rational intelligibility, would suffice to carry the deliberative burdens that aesthetic embodiment imposes. I have been saying all along that the category of the aesthetic might constructively bear these burdens if the purely self-presentational purposiveness, which we otherwise equate with decadent aestheticism,
Singer.book
9/12/03
260
11:21 AM
Page 260
Aesthetic Reason
can be reconfigured for a different register of subjectivity. Because Crowther insists that embodiment is not self-presentational so much as self-transformational, his investment in the presentational field on this account does seem to mandate that we engage presentation as I have proposed: as a relation between the presentational field and those presentational powers that are not already realized within it. We might speculate that what would make Kruger’s challenge to subjectivity more decisive would be a compositional form wherein the subject’s recognition of coherent perspective obtains as an adaptation of viewpoint to the incoherencies that otherwise locate its attentions. Such “incoherencies,” of course, presuppose the irreducibility of contextual boundedness as the crucial register of subjectivity. They likewise necessitate a protocol of boundary negotiation as a precondition of recognizing such boundedness to be the métier of the subjective agency it instantiates. We can see a bit more clearly what is missing compositionally by noting a salient point of resemblance between Kruger’s and Sherman’s works. Here a comparison may serve to tutor comparative context where it is most lacking in artistic practice. Like Kruger’s, Sherman’s compositions figure a mirror for self-recognition that necessitates a critical self-effacement.They thus obviate distinctions between viewer and viewed in the manner of a negative identification.Whether we are talking about Sherman’s movie stills or her historical portraits, the presentational field—in accordance with Kruger—situates us with respect to a boundary erasure where, in effect, only one contextual counter of recognition obtains. These works orchestrate a curious spectacle wherein there is the disappearance of the boundary between the face of the represented subject (the artist in this case) and the recognitional value that its typological “look” is meant to solicit from the viewer. Because we are meant to take the particulars of the image too typically as the token of interpellated identity, the counters of self-identification proffered in this work are bereft of any meaningful range of comparative reference. This is what makes recognition in Sherman’s work so problematic with respect to any prospect for deliberative subjectivity and, in that way, so unconducive to learning. Hal Foster tersely sums up the artist’s objective: “Oppositions of original and copy, inside and outside, self and society all but collapse. . . . Sherman seems to expose her own self but in fact exposes the type of the exposed self” (Recodings, 67). In other words, the typological warrant for the viewer’s attention lacks sufficient accountability to what it does not already comprehend.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:21 AM
Page 261
Living in Aesthetic Community
261
The phenomenon is best epitomized by Sherman’s “history” portraits that derive their register of historical particularity from mannerly imitation of historical painting. In works such as Untitled #206, the relatively forgiving irony that in a photograph we are confronting the history of subjective illusionism in painting is trumped. For the register of ironic judgment entails recognition of the rather less forgiving reality of the author’s face. It looms ominously in the place where the historical subject should be.While the mise-en-scène is dense with historical-cultural particularity—costume, drapery, apple—they are all too transparently props of the debunking allusion to painterly illusion. So the illusionism that confuses photography with the medium that it once threatened to displace, as a more secure habitation of subjective reality, becomes an admonition to vacate subjectivity as an unsuitable habitat for reality. In effect, the sensuous plenitude of a world ordained by patriarchal viewing practices is thus reincarnated, by photomimesis, as a disembodiment of that patriarchal eye, blamed as it is for the selfoppressing metaphysical ills of post-Enlightenment subjectivity. But just as I have argued is the case in instances of the postmodern sublime, critical disembodiment of the subject here threatens to become an obstacle to adaptive practice. After all, I have alleged this practice to be the necessary complement to Marcuse’s ascription of a plausible cognitive function to the aesthetic. Sherman’s work presents such an obstacle to adaptation precisely in the way it obviates the necessity of the viewer to reconcile perspectives.Adaptation is an exigency of incomplete knowledge. Indeed, without this motive for adaptation, subjectivity tends to epitomize the very discarnated point of view that we typically identify with the reifying authority of the rationalist ego. We have already seen that what ensues in the absence of a motive for adaptation is the rational amelioration of error, the default of comparative context, and the evasion of tragic recognition. Error, comparative context, and tragic recognition are the human resources upon which I have asserted that aesthetic value subsists if it is to remain credible as a counter of knowledge that has social and political relevance. Only under the auspices of these knowledge conditions might art enlighten us about what individual agents do not know in soliciting recognition of what they want to be known as. I warrant that this is the cognitive function most relevant to aesthetic idealism.This cognitive function would furthermore be conducive to Marcuse’s idealism about art as a demystification of vaunted necessity, as plausible choice. Sherman’s “portraits” miss the view of this knowledge in their ironic totalizing of the subjective viewpoint.They miss it by their sublimation
Singer.book
9/12/03
262
11:22 AM
Page 262
Aesthetic Reason
Image not available
Fig. 4 Cindy Sherman,“Untitled #206,” 1989. Courtesy the Artist and Metro Pictures Gallery
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 263
Living in Aesthetic Community
263
of the representational field into an overly abstract idea of the preferability of otherness to guilt-ridden selfhood. Let me repeat, however, that I take the examples of Haacke, Kruger, and Sherman not because they simply epitomize postmodernist oppositionalism, but because they equate anti-aestheticism with antisubjectivism. Thus they present an occasion for putting pressure on the question of whether or not aesthetic value can be reconciled with subjectivity in a way that favors the extra-aesthetic, political interests of such artists as Kruger and Sherman. Both of these artist’s métiers commit them to thwarting the subject’s susceptibility to the habits of consumerism. And they are perfectly right to read consumerism as a structural weakness to which political agency is “naturally” heir.To the extent that it mitigates subjective production, it threatens to denature the human altogether. For just these reasons, I have been insistent that production (with its links to recognition and tragedy) is a sine qua non of theorizing the aesthetic, if such theorizing is to elude the commodificational traps laid by fetishistic aestheticism. I have characterized production as that which shows us our implicatedness in what we do not know about the commitments that prompt our solicitation of recognition. It therefore presupposes an engagement with objects that does not postulate, however idealistically, the adequacy of the subject to its desires.These are exactly the terms of knowledge that error, tragedy, and contextualism hold us to, and toward which I have attempted to orient the theory of the aesthetic. Now, in order to turn the discussion more conclusively toward the promised view of a cognitive aesthetic that is fully responsive to these terms of subjective constraint, I would like to contrast the artistic practices of Haacke, Kruger, and Sherman with those of Gerhard Richter. Richter’s images exemplify my reasons for thinking of the presentational field as a scene of boundary negotiation that, in turn, figures choice as a pretext for recognition. I offer this as a beneficent alternative to making the givenness of recognition a reason for abandoning the responsibilities of choice-making, and thereby conceding the stakes of a socially and politically useful aesthetic. Superficially, Richter seems to keep faith with Haacke’s, Kruger’s, and Sherman’s purposes of oppositional culture-critique as these purposes bear on the consumer habits of subjectivity. But I want to attend to the way in which Richter, unlike the others, maintains a stake in subjective embodiment.As a result, his subjective critique remains engaged with its object at the level of the determination of presentational powers. Thus Richter honors a determination of subjectivity in relation to what
Singer.book
9/12/03
264
11:22 AM
Page 264
Aesthetic Reason
it does not know, and hence sustains it as a viable choice-making enterprise. For the purposes of my discussion, I will take only one aspect of Richter’s remarkably heterogeneous project as visual artist. It is nonetheless an aspect that I believe reveals Richter’s own aesthetic scruple to be more on the side of adaptation than on the side of negative critique. By this means I will deploy a view of Richter’s work that unapologetically props my own sense of things: that appreciating the fit between aesthetic cognition and adaptive subjectivity might give us a way to imagine aesthetic community that is concordant with Marcuse’s political ideals, set out at the beginning of this chapter. Moreover, we shall see that this view holds faith with the political spirit of the anti-aesthetic school, animated as it is by vigorous resistance both to the mental habits of consumption and to the dubious political identity that such habits cultivate. Richter himself is unambiguous about his resistance to the idea of a community in which his work would have significance on the basis of a consumerist recognition. But he is careful to remind us that the artist’s every defamiliarizing refusal of recognition is, nonetheless, an elaboration of the modalities of recognition in which subjectivity knows its limits, which is to say, its conditions of possibility: To paint is to create an analogy with the imperceptible and the uncomprehensible, which takes form in this way and becomes accessible. Creating such uncomprehensibility prohibits one from doing any old foolishness, because foolishness is always comprehensible. “The uncomprehensible” is “unconsumable,” therefore essential. It also presents an analogy with all that fundamentally exceeds our understanding, but which understanding allows us to deduce.13 What is most significant here, for my purposes, is Richter’s conviction that the “unconsumability” of the “uncomprehensible” is not simply reducible to the proposition that the “uncomprehensible” equates with what “exceeds our understanding.” Richter does not want to be a painter of the sublime. Instead, his commentary here holds out the possibility of understanding how an accommodation of error might best capture the sense-making strategies inspired by his images. For if Richter says that understanding can inspire analogy to what exceeds its powers, as well as instantiating the obstacle to comprehension that inspires analogy, it occasions precisely the contextual slippage according to which any adjudication of error is originally possible. In this regard, I want to narrow my discussion further to a consid-
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 265
Living in Aesthetic Community
265
eration of Richter’s photo-blur paintings. As I have already conceded, this choice slights the full range of Richter’s work. But it will better dramatize the stakes of what I have already said about understanding the artist’s investment in the presentational field as a realization of presentational powers—one that only embodiment can occasion and only deliberative mind can compass.After all, the photo-blur is, on the most superficial account of the presentational field in Richter’s work, an allusion to error.This allusiveness is manifest in a wide range of canvases (landscapes and portraits) produced since the 1960s that deliberately blur vision, to varying and at times imperceptible degrees. They thus occasion deliberative doubt about correct standards of viewing. In a moment I will try to epitomize the conceptual underpinnings of this practice by a close reading of Richter’s Ema, Nude on a Staircase (1966). Its allusiveness to error is complicated by an illusionism that haunts the history of painting generally and, very specifically, the historical moment of Duchamp’s Nude Descending a Staircase, which exerts its own allusive pull on the viewer of the painting. But first it must be said that, as a group, Richter’s photo-blur paintings address an assumption about painting as a genre (as well as its place in the age of mechanical reproduction) that Duchamp himself was responding to. The camera, which the photorealist métier of Richter’s photo-blur paintings alludes to most forcefully, was historically the device that challenged the epistemic grounds of painting. Photography promoted the hypothesis that painting’s true representational powers are only adequately tested by comparison with more efficient representational techne (methods), as if method preceded matter axiomatically.Within this frame of reference, the fidelity of the painted image to the real object is debunked by the manifestly higher resolution of the photoimage. It will not be lost on an ironically turned mind that the co-option of the natural object by human techne (in this case mechanical technology) entailed by this logic invites the very inhibition of comparative context that I identified with ironic negation and the anti-aesthetic purge of subjectivity carried out in the photo-techne of Kruger and Sherman. Concomitantly, we do not miss the fact that the technology of the camera is a paradigmatic embodiment of the rationalizing rule of Enlightenment. It epitomizes the Enlightenment precept that abstract rule determines reality independent of contingent matter.And yet the highest degree of technorational resolution in Richter’s photorealist works is conferred on the “irrational” blur. Indeed, the viewer who approaches the picture plane of the photo-blur paintings, as if to adjust the focal length of the viewpoint, discovers a heightening resolution
Singer.book
9/12/03
266
11:22 AM
Page 266
Aesthetic Reason
Image not available
Fig. 5 Gerhard Richter,“Ema, Nude on a Staircase,” 1966. Museum Ludwig, Köln (photo: Rheinisches Bildarchiv Köln)
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 267
Living in Aesthetic Community
267
in the brushstrokes of the blur as an inverse proportion of what would otherwise be the blurring distance. In other words, the techne of the camera, which historically testified to painting’s more fallible relation to the object, becomes the salient object of attention here, with respect to just that aspect of photographic process that marks its susceptibility to error. Looking at a range of paintings executed in this blur modality, we can say that Richter has used a photorealist technique to reproduce that which reveals photography to be subject to the very weaknesses formerly ascribed to painting by photography. For the blur, which obtrudes the focal plane as an armature of composition, epitomizes nothing less than a paradigmatic slippage between contextual fields and hence a compelling pretext for comparative context. Or to put it in terms more analytically appropriate to the question about what social uses the aesthetic lends itself to, we might observe that this slippage in Richter’s work is nothing less than a plausibly adequate representation of temporality.Temporality belies the rational controls of photographic technology and, in that respect, is a quintessential modality of error, in the guise of the nemesis of rational truth.The blur unequivocally marks the encroachment of time on the idealized space of the camera’s rationality: shutter speed is surpassed by the haptic pace of physical action. Of course the blur’s affinity with categorical, albeit corrigible, error is marked most conspicuously by its correlation with the fallibility of the human hand. The hand holding the camera trembles in its uncertainty that the rules that inform the intention to photograph, and the rules that animate the mechanism of the camera, are compatible in the action of pushing the shutter release. So something quite different from what is purveyed by Haacke, Kruger, and Sherman is proffered in Richter’s compositions, with reference to the critique of rationalized subjectivity. In the photograph, the haptic or irrational register of the blur—because it simply nullifies the image—releases us from the mandates of the optical rationale that otherwise govern the presentational field. But in the painting, when the blur is rendered with perfect sharpness, the optical rationale is made curiously coherent with the haptic—perforce irrational—register of chance.This happens in a way that gives unique density to the presentational field. Furthermore, I want to suggest that it instances embodiment as choice. For we must consider that the blur in the painting—unlike the blur in the photograph—persists as a correlation of focal point with human movement in space.That is, one needs to see the sharpness of what blurs as well as the blurred picture. One’s knowledge is a function of one’s relation to the choices construable under
Singer.book
9/12/03
268
11:22 AM
Page 268
Aesthetic Reason
that constraint.Thus the blur in the painting remains an irreducible presentational counter of what the image is an image of. It remains a presentational counter of what is imaged as an instance of imagining, independent of any preformulable intention to visualize according to abstractable rules of imaging. We stand in a strange relation to the mimetic enterprise here. And the qualities of this relation come most clearly into focus when we realize that the pathos of the photo-blur paintings has so much to do with the fact that the human—the prime locus of mimeticism and what is typically eclipsed by the overexposing, unambiguous light of late twentieth-century photorealist technique—is represented most explicitly here in the fallibility of techne.As I have anticipated, this is especially dramatic in the canvas titled Ema: Nude on a Staircase, where the “adequacy” of Richter’s rendering of the human is usefully problematized by allusion to Duchamp’s famous nude. For Duchamp’s mode of abstracting the figure into a montage effect could easily be read as a refusal to let the nude appear. It is as if the artist wishes to preempt the recognition of the inadequacy of “appearance” to the frame of temporality in which the nude could be expected to arrive to descend the stairs. In other words, Duchamp’s abstraction seems intended to preempt the fallibility, the error of relying on perception where embodiment is in doubt—as it must be whenever spatial representation seeks to accommodate temporality.To the contrary, in Richter’s composition the fully embodied exposure of frontal, female nudity is subtly blurred by the figure’s precarious descent into a vertiginous space. Although perspective tells us we can claim this space as a secure viewing point, it also impels our less secure recognition of the necessity for a reciprocal motion. That recognition is, after all, the only efficient mode of address to the blur that could promise rapport with a shifting focal plane.The viewer must move in some compensatory correlation with the blurred and thus moving figure to find an adequate focal point.The nakedness of human contingency is thus embraced rather than modestly “covered up,” but in a way that has nothing to do with the nakedness of the nude itself. In other words, Richter makes the Duchamp “re-appear” in such a way that its appearance owes nothing to the inert temporality that governs in the relation of image to object, where the question of adequacy could be mistaken for a simple matter: a one-step resolution of focus, up or down stairs, so to speak. Instead, appearance here is a more explicit marker of the viewer’s necessary adaptation to the persistent variability of what embodiment renders visible. It is not so distinct from
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 269
Living in Aesthetic Community
269
the formal or compositional challenges of the staircase, which the frontality of the figure’s nudity makes even more conspicuously a matter of step-by-step negotiations. The figure inhabits a spatial context that is knowable only by the adjustments it compels us to intuit. Embodiment quite literally determines comparative context here, in much the way that Crowther explained: when a subject expresses itself under the conditions of embodiment, its assimilation of disparate moments to a unity of experience is not just a “mix of existing idioms” but “a qualitative transformation of them” (Language of TwentiethCentury Art, 201). Specifically, in Ema, Nude on a Staircase the transformative element, namely, the subtly out-of-focus figure, marks a boundary between what is knowable and what is unknowable in a way that mandates negotiation, for it portends no transcendence to a final term of fitness or of lack of fitness between the image and what it re-presents. Finitude is a value here, but in a way that more richly determines the scope of our reflection upon powers of comprehension, rather than by determining any ultimate comprehension of the object. In Richter’s composition, the conventional photorealist seduction to complete perceptual candor, in anticipated revelation of the nude body, becomes an inducement to resolve focus without a single set of parameters. Along these lines, Richter says,“I have painted photos precisely in order not to have anything to do with painting.”14 Painting would seem to be too wedded to transcendence in the following sense. Its presentational field is too readily an image of something, the revelation of which would entail the sublimation of the presentational powers that enabled its appearance. Richter seems to want a different rapport with the image than what merely allows the painter to achieve either of the equally deceptive lucidities of reference or sublimity. For both these options countenance the uncomprehensible as inaccessible to the modalities of its representation. Indeed, neither painting nor photography, each by itself, possesses the expressive means afforded by painting and photography in Richter’s photo-blur paintings. Here, as Richter himself says, he is committed to making the uncomprehensible more “accessible” rather than subliming it. I would argue that what is at stake in the access to the uncomprehensible here is a humanity importantly distinct from what is cultured by conventional representational practices in the service of reference or sublimity. Specifically, by comparison with the popular thesis that “real” painting aspires to the transparency of the photographed object, we could say that Richter’s practice reveals how such painting potentially
Singer.book
9/12/03
270
11:22 AM
Page 270
Aesthetic Reason
dishonors the human. For it puts the image too much in the service of representing the object, independent of the full potentiality of mimeticism.We must remember that Aristotle, in Poetics, honors mimesis as a kind of human essence. In chapter 4 of Poetics, the mimetic impulse defines human nature. It is a capacity that Aristotle intimates might be countenanced as an end in itself: “The instinct of imitation is implanted in man from childhood.”15 Indeed, I want to suggest that Richter’s photoblur paintings conjure a frame of reference in which we must construe Aristotle to mean that it is the mimetic impulse that warrants representation more than what can be represented by it. For the imitation of the blur—not to mention Richter’s practice of painting brushstrokes qua subject matter—in a sense renders the image a place where mimeticism takes priority over mimesis.The blur alludes to what otherwise hides mimeticism in a standard of mimetic adequacy. One standard of adequation disguises the potential for adequation to other standards.This orientation chimes with the way in which the photo-blur paintings energetically thwart the idea that they are paintings about the reappropriation of painting from photography. In that case meaning would be arrived at by some inverse measure of what is negated, as if the blur were merely a reference to the standard of photographic image resolution. On the contrary, I think it is more accurate to say that Richter’s blur instances a techne where the boundedness of practice is made commensurable with knowledge of what exceeds its boundary, inasmuch as lucidity in Richter’s work is a choice between salient particulars. This intuition is keyed to Richter’s making the focus of the brushstrokes in the blur an inescapably deliberative counter for the viewer’s attentiveness.The accessibility to the uncomprehensible that Richter thus endows upon his viewer must in turn be taken up by the viewer as a mandate to countenance an engagement with the field of particulars that makes seeing the relations between them a deepening of the sense of how subjectivity underlies their connectedness.This is alternative to intuiting terms of connection that purport to subsume subjectivity. The slightly fuzzy figure on the stairs gives a push to the viewer’s necessary descent from one contextual register to another, as if the proper focal length of viewing were coterminous with the extensibility of perception. It is a phenomenon that is calculable only by comparative assessment of what is missing from each extension, and thereby warrants another choice of contextual parameters. Or, more important, we might see that it warrants a sense of respect for the improvisational bearings of selfhood that we can be attuned with only through accepting that one’s human work in the world gets done most responsibly in
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 271
Living in Aesthetic Community
271
recognition of the duties that embodiment imposes on us: the duty to know ourselves in relation to what is beyond us not as irrationality but as rational adaptability. It is a way of contending with the limitedness of experience as a rational bridge to the realm of indeterminacy. Indeed, Richter’s photo-blur paintings do not make lack of focus an issue in and of itself. Focus is not missing here. Rather, it makes more sense to say that lack of focus is effectively a métier for focusing beyond a single line of sight. Far from capitulating to indeterminacy, Richter’s compositions offer a set of determinations with respect to what resists determination. Jean-Philippe Antoine rightly concludes that the burden of Richter’s achievement is carried by the viewer who must “decide what is indeterminate in the painting” (“Photography, Painting, and the Real,” 65). Between “deciding” indeterminacy and the indecision of indeterminacy lie the stakes of the question,What is the efficacy of the artwork with respect to human activity? Coupled with Richter’s own pronouncement that “I never found anything missing in a blurry painting. On the contrary, one sees much more than in a sharp image” (65), we can intuit the effect of such aesthetic practice as a corollary of the burdens imposed upon tragic subjectivity. As Jean-Pierre Vernant attested, tragic subjectivity must contend with a paradoxical continuity between modes of continence and incontinence, where rationalizing principle is consequently inseparable from seemingly irrational practice. Thus it might be fair to say that Richter has engaged tragic knowledge in the very nonfatalistic modality I elaborated out of my reading of Vernant and Vidal-Naquet’s Myth and Tragedy in Ancient Greece: a mode of “development of subjective responsibility” (69). I feature the morally weighted term responsibility not because the determination of meaning in Richter’s work is finalized in the figure or the portraited face, or the landscape, but because in each instance the determinateness of the viewing subject is enhanced by the shifting protocols of attentiveness to which the viewer is recruited.The actual mechanical process of the photo-blur painting is an instructive analogue here.The image evolves from a complicated procedure that might be described as a reciprocating reversal of contextual boundaries.The artist begins by subordinating his brushwork to the “guiding outline” of a projected photo-image, where the line is starkly a rationalist imperative of form. Then, by overpainting, he subordinates the resolved focus of the camera’s/projector’s optical register to the haptic forces of brushwork. Just so, the qualities of attention these paintings solicit correlate with a sense of the viewer’s infringement upon a preexisting context such
Singer.book
9/12/03
272
11:22 AM
Page 272
Aesthetic Reason
that its boundedness becomes the salient variable of viewing something else.Viewpoint, in this case—like focal length—can only be established by a decontextualizing movement, one that in turn resolves its meaningfulness in terms of a recontextualizing agency.
V At this moment of surprisingly rich reconciliation with blurred perspective, which in no way vitiates our investment in the subjective embodiments that perspective can rationalize for us, it is important to step back from Richter’s images and their exemplifications. It is time to see how they relocate my original focal point for this discussion of the aesthetic as a cognitive enterprise. From the beginning of this project I have alleged that, in the purview of a cognitive aesthetic,“the standard of adequacy is assimilated to the exigency of act,” such that “the activity of adequation serves the adequacy of the aesthetic.”16 My ambition was to move the discussion of the aesthetic toward reflection upon an aspect of mind that we are all staked in, according to our inescapable human complicity with the circumstance of the tragic protagonist. According to my approach, the tragic protagonist denotes a practical agency that might shed light on aesthetic theory if we can see how that agency is itself already informed by the complexities that are operative in aesthetic practice and aesthetic form. In either case, what is at issue is a prospect for human self-realization that is only opened by a disposition of consciousness to accept the contextual incompleteness of human action. This disposition thus constitutes a laboratory within which human subjectivity can develop its resources for reflecting upon the limitedness of context-bound experience. In that way new boundaries can be drawn to suit the expressive needs of a consciousness transfigured by reflecting on its limits. At key points in this argument, I have remarked upon the entanglement of this ambition with the very fallible presumption of perfect continence in subjective agency. Perfect continence, after all, is the anti-mask of the tragic protagonist.Alternatively, I have invoked the concept of incontinence or akrasia as a quasi-technique for attending to the boundary between rationality and irrationality. For this boundary appears in the tragic slippage between our intentional best judgments and the conflict-engendering evaluative frames that are imposed upon us by the unforeseeable course of practical actions.Admittedly, my use of the term akrasia is an unconventional one. Unlike philosophers of
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 273
Living in Aesthetic Community
273
action, I have been more interested in what the incidence of akrasia can tell us about the conditions for maximizing deliberative and contextualizing agency than in using the account of an act against putative best reasoning to mount an inquisition against irrational intentions. I have, for this reason, followed the lead of neo-Aristotelians such as Alison McIntyre who challenge the proposition that akratic action is always irrational.As we saw in Chapter 3, this is the intuition that if an agent is motivated in the “akratic act” by a “new consideration,”17 that is, one that would have prompted a strategic revision of the original reasoning that led to the presumed practical conclusion (e.g., akratic act), then akrasia might be seen as an occasion for deliberative reasoning. It would denote a possibility for self-realization that is otherwise preempted by orthodox standards of continent judgment. Accordingly, my interest in the artwork as a framework for reflections in which the enterprise of finding new reasons, that is, respecting “new considerations” for rationalizing familiar contexts of experience, has had a sociopolitical trajectory. My willingness to share Hannah Arendt’s faith in the continuity between aesthetical and political experience likewise derives from her commitment to those elements of the Greek polis that anchor the political protagonist in an arena of self-revising accommodation toward “otherness.”What is presupposed in all these attitudes is a subject whose threshold of self-realization is the recognition of the lack of complete knowledge about what would count as the best justification for the actions (practical and interpretive) in which he or she might be instantiated. My stance here ought not to be confused with a mere deference to otherness. Nor should it be confused with Marx’s overly facile reconciling of the known with the unknown by assuming that the universality of the particular is everything that is lacking in the particular.18 This kind of thinking puts the task of human self-realization on a historical trajectory of generalization that vitiates (for analytical purposes) the contextual circumstance of any particular subject who claims selfknowledge by choosing the terms of contextual self-recognition. Quite to the contrary, my reliance on the analytical topoi of translatability, reciprocal recognition, imaginative visiting, and so on sustains an overriding interest in the subject who seeks to pass the self-deceiving constraints within which his or her choices are circumscribed. I started with the proposition that such choices are inevitably circumscribed by what Raymond Geuss characterized as a fundamental incommensurability between the tasks of seeking perfect knowledge and setting conditions for perfect knowledge. My most general con-
Singer.book
9/12/03
274
11:22 AM
Page 274
Aesthetic Reason
clusion is that the suffering of the “tragic protagonist” figured in this circumstance is what aesthetic value most properly caters to.The artwork in its presentational particulars—at least where presentational values are made to count by virtue of the artist’s formal choices—is thus seen to be a relevant scene of suffering. For, in this capacity, it entails choice-making about what is significant in a circumstance that concedes the impossibility of ascertaining perfect conditions for knowledge.And yet the presentational field of the artwork never relieves the subject of the burden of aspiring to them.The aesthetic subject, in this regard, resembles the agent forming an intention—as distinct from the agent making a cognitive judgment. Forming an intention is activity oriented, while judgment remains a theoretical pursuit. In other words, the artwork is conceived of here as the cognitive counterpart to a subject who, by accepting his or her complicity in error, is predisposed toward community.The bonds of community are forged in the deliberative exigency of choice-making. This communitarian disposition, however, is not determined by a Kantian-style disinterestedness that self-preemptively disembodies agency. Rather, it is duly embodied by the requirement that this agent’s interests get expressed only in the context of a recognition that the expression of those interests must help to form. Because such recognition is occasioned by cognitive engagement with a distinctive presentational métier/capacity, we might say that what motivates the subject here—artist and interpreter alike—is a trust in continence, insofar as the ideal of continence is a desire to maximize the available reasons for self-understanding that can be occasioned by the artwork. But this trust in continence is not to be confused with faith in the realization of continent intent. Rather, I am suggesting that we should see how the idealistic drive for continence is a universal circumstance of subjectivity that, within a tragic historical record of widespread incontinent behavior, ever more crucially warrants the aesthetic as a métier of human culture. My purpose here has been to give aesthetic theorists and artists an alternative to thinking of the aesthetic as an ornamental accessory to continent subjectivity. In that case, the aesthetic would be subsumed to rational norms rather than offering to become a participant in forging the contexts within which such norms have their rationalizing force. Only in the latter circumstance is the artwork guaranteed a place in a culture that is distinguishable from the historic “placements” that subjectivity has endured in its struggle for self-determination. Only in these terms can the artwork have a meaningful role to play in the historical development of a culture that might, consequently, reconcile itself with the productive mandate of artistic enterprise.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 275
Notes
Chapter 1 1. The problematics of this dualism are strikingly analogous to the dualism between politics and morality that troubles Kant’s Groundwork for a Metaphysic of Morals. Hannah Arendt gives a persuasive gloss on Kant’s attempts to reconcile the apparently divergent trajectories of action and duty, in her posthumous Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy. Her appeal to a communicative imperative is compatible, I believe, with my own sense of the community-building imperative of choice-making put forward in this chapter. 2. My points of reference here are Habermas’s The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity and Putnam’s The Many Faces of Realism (two works that, it must be admitted, express little tolerance for the aesthetic). In the present chapter I do not offer proper scope for an appreciation of these works in the particularities of their argumentation. See Chapter 2 for further discussion. 3. See Bourdieu’s postscript to his Distinction, titled “Towards a ‘Vulgar’ Critique of ‘Pure’ Critiques.” 4. Here I make reference to a broad range of recent literary theory that advocates what Raymond Williams has called a “militant particularism.” See Ross, Universal Abandon; Smith, Discerning the Subject; and Sinfield, Faultlines. 5. See Baumgarten, Reflections on Poetry, 43–46. 6. See Caygill on Herder, in Art of Judgment, 180–81. 7. Hutcheson refuted Locke’s claim that beauty is a complex idea built up out of percepts. 8. See Habermas, “The Production Paradigm,” in Philosophical Discourse of Modernity. Here Habermas lays blame at the door of the “older Hegel,” who opened the way to technological overspecialization of the lifeworld. 9. See McCarthy’s judicious assessment, in Ideals and Illusions, 68–70. 10. See Foucault,“An Aesthetics of Existence,” his 1984 interview with Alessandro Fontana, for the first formal exposition of this idealism. His comments in this interview represent an admittedly embryonic stage of thinking on this question. Foucault, of course, did not survive to resolve the question. 11. Eagleton’s book The Ideology of the Aesthetic remains an influential text for critics who seek a way out of the social decadence of beauty theory and the nineteenth-century aestheticisms founded upon transcendental universals. Nevertheless, as I will show, Eagleton’s analysis yields little prospect for aesthetic theory as a resource of subjective agency. 12. This work is divided into two parts: “Concerning Beauty, Order, Harmony, Design” and “Concerning Moral Good and Evil.” See Peter Kivy’s edition of the former (published by Martinus Nijhoff, 1973), which bears on this context of analysis.
Singer.book
9/12/03
276
11:22 AM
Page 276
Notes
13. See Dreyfus and Rabinow, afterword to Michel Foucault, 257. 14. Nelson Goodman’s extensive exposition of the cognitive dimensions of the aesthetic are of course a vital context for this assertion, and for the goals implicit in it. See especially the criteria of “repleteness” offered as part of Goodman’s symptomatology of the aesthetic in Languages of Art and in Of Mind and Other Matters. 15. Here one must look at the discussion of the affinity of aesthetic and ethical criteria of existence assumed by Foucault in Care of the Self, 67. 16. See especially Bernstein, Adorno. 17. See especially the chapter “Illusion and Experience,” 148–60. 18. See The Many Faces of Realism, 17–21 for the full exposition of this term. Putnam’s point, in large part, is to distinguish relativism from relativity: “Conceptual relativity sounds like ‘relativism,’ but has none of the ‘there is no truth to be found . . . true is just a name for what a bunch of people can agree on implications of relativism.’” For a considered judgment of Putnam’s stance within the historical scope of the aesthetic that I am assessing here, see also McCormick, Modernity, Aesthetics, and the Bounds of Art. 19. Interestingly, it evokes Foucault’s reflective turn back to the subject when he realizes the necessary reciprocity of genealogy and archeology.The genealogical appropriation of a system of power relations entails an excavation of the constraints of its systematicity of power.This is so insofar as appropriation yields to the internal contradictions of its own self-justificatory logic.These self-justifications are inevitable in the slippage between past and present.Adorno makes a similar point about the dynamic relation of the familiar and the new in any theoretically charged explication of the artwork. 20. Hegel’s famous commentary on the transient and fugitive dimension of art is relevant here. See the introduction to Lectures in Aesthetics. 21. See especially Adorno’s lengthy discussion of second reflection, in Aesthetic Theory, 487–92. 22. It is telling with respect to this point that in Aesthetic Theory, Adorno both resurrects the conceptual relevance of Dilthey’s verstehen and insists upon making new sense of it, not as an obscure inwardness of experience, but as a “many-sidedness” open to analysis in terms of its predicative variability.This, for me, is another inference of the choice-making imperative driving second reflection. 23. See Tugendthat’s postulate that all relations of self to the self are inherently propositional, in Self-Consciousness and Self-Determination, 46. 24. Williams has given the most astute account I know of this aspect of Fichte’s argument. He indicates that the summons is an occasion for decision insofar as “the self can accede to the summons, deny it or ignore it. The summons of the other presupposes the capacity for, and mediates the consciousness of, freedom in the one to whom it is directed” (Williams, Recognition, 59). 25. This is Williams’s translation from passages in the Naturrecht where Fichte undertakes the transition from Anstoss to Aufforderung. See Williams, Recognition, 56–59. 26. In Wissenschaftslehre, Fichte stipulates the point in a way that resonates through everything else he writes regarding self-determination specifically: “There can be no objection at all to the proposition here established. . . . Should someone say . . . that the concept of ground ought to be explained in some other way, we certainly cannot prevent him . . . however. . . . If this [the above] meaning be not accepted, the possibility of philosophy in our sense would accordingly have to be denied” (8). 27. Here I am following Williams’s note on the translation of this term: “The term Anstoss means literally a push, or an encounter with an initiative from elsewhere; metaphorically it means an impulse which in English is burdened with psychological connotations” (Recognition, 67).
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 277
Notes
277
28. For a more optimistic reading of Schiller, particularly as related to the possibility of translating an appreciation of natural beauty into intersubjective relations, see Chytry, Aesthetic State, 88–91.
Chapter 2 1. In this context it is worth pointing out that the Athenian polis (particularly in light of Aristotelian politics) is a crucial touchstone of Arendt’s reading of Kant. It is a conspicuous resource of argument where the political trajectory she imputes to Kant’s thinking about judgment exceeds any textual warrant, especially in the third critique. 2. See the full text of “Modernity: An Incomplete Project” and The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, 1–22. For the more general dissemination of this stance among communitarian universalists, see Benhabib and Dallmyar, Communicative Ethics Controversy. 3. W. Robert Connor suggests how the commitment to this social class indexed the “disinterestedness” of civic leadership. This standard of disinterestedness and the protocol of political friendship in Athens will bear comparison with the notion of aesthetic disinterestedness that underwrites Arendt’s linkage of aesthetic and political judgment. See The New Politicians of Fifth-Century Athens, 73–84. 4. See Chytry, The Aesthetic State, xxxix–xl. Here I ought to acknowledge that my view of the Greek institutions that are so suggestive for theorizing a cognitive aesthetic is, like Arendt’s and Chytry’s, candidly instrumental. It cannot compass the range of competing institutional and religious forces that would count as a fully adequate historicism. 5. Our point of departure here must be Kant’s own formulation in no. 40 of the third critique: “[W]e must [here] take sensus communis to mean the idea of a sense shared [by all of us], in our thought, of everyone else’s way of presenting [something], i.e., a power to judge that in reflecting takes account (a priori), in our thought, of everyone else’s way of presenting [something], in order as it were to compare our own judgment with human reason in general and thus escape the illusion that arises from the ease of mistaking subjective and private conditions for objective ones” (Critique of Judgment, 160). However, we shall see in what follows that for Arendt’s purposes, particularly in the last pages of the Lectures, sensus communis carries a burden of action that Kant eschews. See also Beiner’s quotation from unpublished lectures that correlates Arendt’s attempts to equate political action with deliberative judgment (Beiner,“Interpretive Essay,” 141). This instantiates the public realm as she defines it in The Human Condition. 6. Arendt herself is quite candid about the liberties she takes with the Kantian text. See Arendt, Lectures, 31, 33. 7. Here I am thinking of the increasing animus against the category of the aesthetic.This antagonism arises in art-critical circles where the pretext of political ends inspires a reprise of the very dualism of sentiment and reason that ironically launched the aesthetic as a creditable political enterprise in the eighteenth century. See especially Foster, Anti-Aesthetic; Bennett, Outside Literature; and Benjamin and Osborne, Thinking Art. 8. For the range of this “political aesthetic,” which I believe too reductively confuses cognition with instrumentalism/political domination, see Lyotard, Postmodern Condition; Fraser, Unruly Practices; and Eagleton, Ideology of the Aesthetic. 9. Here the authoritative precedents are set by Boileau, Shaftesbury, and Hutcheson. 10. Howard Caygill makes this characterization in his account of Herder’s Origin of Language (1771). Herder expands upon Alexander Baumgarten’s theory of the relation of perception to human action in the seminal Enlightenment aesthetic treatises
Singer.book
9/12/03
278
11:22 AM
Page 278
Notes
Aesthetica (1711) and Reflections on Poetry (1735). See Caygill, Art of Judgment, 177–78. 11. See Herder, Essay on the Origin of Language, especially 34–35. 12. For a useful assessment of the degree to which Sturm und Drang insisted upon the nondiscursive nature of aesthetics, particularly in J. G. Hamann’s Aesthetica in nuce (1765), see Beiser, Fate of Reason, especially 29–43. 13. Chytry, Aesthetic State, xi. 14. See book 5 of Ethics for the exposition that bears most directly on this aspect of my argument. 15. Ethics, bk. 6, v. 16. Ibid., 118, 119, 209, 213. 17. Ibid., 119. 18. Paul Ricoeur points up a “quasihomonymy” between éthos (character) and ethos (habit, custom) that chimes with my suggestion that there are good reasons to read Aristotelian phronesis as encompassing both praxis and poetics. See Oneself as Another, 121. 19. William Scott Ferguson gives the broad historical sweep of this development in Hellenistic Athens. 20. Buxton, Persuasion in Greek Tragedy, 58–63. 21. Chytry, Aesthetic State, xlii–xliii. 22. For a full account, see Holmes, Florentine Enlightenment; Garin, Italian Humanisms; and Baron, From Petrarch to Leonardo Bruni. 23. See Chytry, Aesthetic State, xlvii. 24. See Bruni, Humanism of Leonardo Bruni, 18–19; and Baron, From Petrarch to Leonardo Bruni, 171–75. 25. Garin provides a valuable context for comprehending this term in his discussion of how the contemplative drag of Platonism constrained the work of Landino (Garin, Italian Humanism, 84–85). 26. Buxton, Persuasion in Greek Tragedy, 17. 27. Kant, Critique of Judgment, 167. 28. See Gadamer, Truth and Method, part 1. 29. For Arendt’s contextualization of infinite progress and dignity, see Lectures, 77. 30. For a consideration of the attendant “right to visit,” see Kant, Perpetual Peace, 118. 31. Indeed, the image seems to be most relevant to Arendt’s concerns here insofar as it denotes what is not there: “(i.e., we have a kind of ‘intuition’ of something that is never present) and by this he [Kant] suggests that imagination is actually the common root of the other cognitive faculties, that is, it is the ‘common, but to us unknown, root’ of sensibility and understanding” (Lectures, 81). 32. See Kant, Critique of Judgment, 227. 33. There is more evidence that Arendt’s apparent defection from the vita activa is hedged with doubt. Ronald Beiner cites Arendt’s identification with historical moments of futile rebellion, such as the Warsaw Ghetto–moments when dignity and progress intersect. Beiner quotes the Warsaw Ghetto resistance: “Not one of us will leave here alive. We are fighting not to save our lives but for human dignity” (Beiner, “Interpretive Essay,” 127).Where Arendt valorizes such instances of human action, particularly where she adduces them as instances of “exemplary validity,” she seems to indicate a will to overcome the clash of judgment and action that otherwise inhibits the political thrust of her reckoning with Kantian judgment.We will see how Hegelian recognition and his correlative theory of forgiveness might be construed as a methodological remedy for the cultural/historical “melancholy” that,Arendt herself confesses, Kantianism gives rise to in the incommensurability of dignity and progress. 34. “Imagination” is composed of notes from a seminar on Kant’s third critique that Arendt delivered at the New School for Social Research in the fall of 1970. Beiner
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 279
Notes
279
says that these notes supply “an indispensable piece in the puzzle if we hope to reconstruct the full contours of Arendt’s theory of judging” (“Interpretive Essay,” 79). 35. Arendt keys the meaning of action etymologically to the Greek archein, “to begin, to lead” (Human Condition, 177; my emphasis). 36. For a corroboration of this nod to a more materialist pragmatism, see Arendt’s own excursus on the role of the historian as an extrapolation from Nietzsche’s “eternal return,” in Thinking, chapter 20. 37. For the basis of what ensues vis-à-vis the aestheticopolitical implications of the “general standpoint,” see Kant, Critique of Judgment, 161. 38. Ibid., sec. 40. 39. Paul Ricoeur offers a rich meditation on the notion of solicitude as access to the lack without which self-reflection would seem to be a tautological proposition (Oneself as Another, 192–93). 40. Again see Beiner,“Interpretive Essay,” 137. 41. Beiner provides useful commentary on this point, explaining that “[tragic judgment] continually confronts a reality it can never fully master but with which it must nonetheless reconcile itself. Arendt finds in Kant a unique expression of this tragic quality associated with judgment.This helps us also to see why the image of the spectator is so vital, and why the burden of judgment is conferred wholly upon the judging spectator” (“Interpretive Essay,” 143). 42. The particular relevance of Ricoeur’s characterization of tragedy obtains in his notion that tragedy constitutes the warrant for a stance of solicitude. Whereas, in my argument, solicitude warrants a redefinition of tragedy, for Ricoeur it threatens to merely confirm tragic knowledge as a phenomenon divorced from action. See Oneself as Another, 242. 43. Here I am extrapolating a principle of reversibility from Arendt’s notion of the hopefulness inherent to historical storytelling.This hopefulness obtains insofar as every ending of a story is, perforce, a new beginning. For Arendt, this is the case if we stay within the perspectives of judgment. See Arendt,“Understanding and Politics,” 388–89. 44. Beiner,“Interpretive Essay,” 154. 45. Buxton, Persuasion in Greek Tragedy, 29. 46. Ibid., 56. 47. The figure of Peitho is linked to eroticism where the public and private realms intersect. This intersection is marked most conspicuously in prostitution and a consequent blurring of the lines between persuasive reason and physical disposition. See Buxton, Persuasion in Greek Tragedy, 32–33. 48. Ibid., 59. 49. See Hegel,“Evil and Forgiveness,” in Phenomenology of Mind, 667–79. 50. Robert R. Williams supplies a useful correlation of Hegelian forgiveness with Arendt’s faith in an intersubjective plurality underlying the moral code. See Williams, Recognition, 209. 51. See Arendt, “Thinking and Moral Considerations,” in which she sees the realization of thinking as bound to judgment, on the model of this dialectic between conscience and self-consciousness. 52. The affinity of this stance with Jean-François Lyotard’s recent exposition of the differend bears scrutiny. See Just Gaming and The Differend: Phrases in Dispute. 53. Robert R.Williams offers a corroboration of the bases of Arendt’s thinking along these lines, in Recognition, 209. 54. See Ricoeur, Oneself as Another, 242. 55. See The Persistence of Modernity, 210. See also my discussion in Chapter 1 for an amplification of the notion of training as aesthetic practice.
Singer.book
9/12/03
280
11:22 AM
Page 280
Notes
Chapter 3 1. For an overview of the arguments that bolster this distinction, see Foster, AntiAesthetic.The essays by Said and Jameson included in this anthology make the strongest cases. My couching this distinction in the terms of Vorstellung and Darstellung ironically has its most serious precedent in Althusserian aesthetics.Althusser does not subscribe to any mutual exclusivity of art and politics. His work is therefore a convincing measure of the distortions of expressive mind and social reality that such exclusivities can wreak. Althusser’s most focused remarks in this regard can be found in “A Letter on Art” and “Cremonini, Painter of the Abstract,” both in Lenin and Philosophy. 2. See Amelie O. Rorty’s discussion of the ramifications of maintaining a distinction between akrasia and self-deception, such that we put the former on the side of actions and the latter on the side of beliefs (“Self-Deception,Akrasia, and Irrationality”). 3. Arendt’s final work, Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy, is the site of this argument. 4. There is interesting precedent for this in a tradition divergent from Kant: Viconian history. Vico’s distinction between coscienza, that which is to do with consciousness (fact, event, custom) and scienza, that which has to do with il vero, depends upon some protocol of choice. As he says: “Philosophy contemplates reason, whence comes knowledge of the true; philology observes that of which human choice is author, whence comes consciousness of the certain.” See The New Science, 130. I believe that Arendt’s thinking accords with the Viconian premise that we can only have knowledge, even of the universals of scienza, according to what we make or do. Choosing is the first thing we do, since it is only in this capacity that coscienza comes to terms with scienza in order to salvage a broader sense of its significance. Coscienza, broadening the reference of scienza, is all that makes the latter term serviceable in the title of Vico’s work, where making and creating are always modalities of choosing. 5. See Gadamer, Relevance of the Beautiful, 31. 6. Peter Bürger, who aptly points up its provenance in the context of seventeenthcentury French theater, explains how the doctrine classique deliberately confuses social norms with aesthetic rules. This is on the assumption that social norms are already rationalized. My point would be that this confusion severs rationality from rational agency in a way that is tantamount to the elision of choice in orthodox (nonreciprocal) theories of tragic recognition. See The Decline of Modernism, 6–9. 7. Luc Ferry provides a useful view of Dubos’s role in the debates devolving from Boileau’s aesthetic (Ferry, Homo Aestheticus, 40–45). 8. See Aristotle’s Poetics, sec. 1. 9. J. M. Bremer, in Hamartia, provides a complete overview of the assimilation of this term to the discussion of Western tragedy. 10. Bremer explains that akrasia differs from hamartia for Aristotle in its being triggered by passionate affect. This is what links it to Platonist attacks on the affective weakness of will induced by the aesthetic. For this reason it serves as a useful ground upon which to resurrect a cognitive aesthetic, a notion of the aesthetic as demurring affective states. See Bremer, Hamartia, 19. 11. Arendt cites Sophocles as the source of our understanding that, to one degree or another, we are all blind to our own daimon and in that respect constitutionally at odds with the enterprise of eudaimonia. See Arendt, Human Condition, 193. 12. Ibid., 192–93. 13. See Sophocles, 72, in vol. 2. 14. Again see Rorty’s commentary on the differences between self-deception and akratic action, in “Self-Deception, Akrasia, and Irrationality.” 15. See Mele, Irrationality, 60–61.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 281
Notes
281
16. Here I make reference to the familiar collusion between antifoundationalist philosophy and postmodern aesthetics, especially the metafictionist turn. 17. Bremer makes the point that peripeteia is quite explicitly a reversal of human intentions, not a mere counterpart of objectifying fate (Hamartia, 17). 18. This roughly follows the model of a Kantian reflective judgment but without the metaphysical superstructure. In reflective judgment the accord of imagination and understanding cannot be achieved but by the understanding giving itself a rule that cannot be abstracted from the imaginative presentation that prompts it. See Kant, Critique of Judgment, sec. 22. 19. This discussion is carried on in several different schools of thought ranging from Elster’s rational choice theory to Alistair MacIntyre’s neo-Aristotelianism, to a variety of prudentialist accounts of human action, by Alessandro Ferrara (“Universalisms: Procedural, Contextualist, and Prudential” in Universalism Vs. Communitarianism, ed. David Rasmussen), Seyla Benhabib (Critique, Norm, and Utopia), and Maeve Cooke (Langauge and Reason: A Study of Habermas’ Pragmatics). 20. My reference point here is Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals. 21. Maeve Cooke’s protocol of “rational accountability” offers a useful corollary. She is interested in making human self-realization compatible with the moral aims of autonomy by stipulating dialogical terms for self-realizing postconventional subjects. See “Realizing the Post-Conventional Subject,” 97. 22. See McIntyre,“Is Akratic Action Always Irrational?” 391. 23. Both Seyla Benhabib and Nancy Fraser have picked up on Arendt’s concern for making this Kantian ideal realizable within the framework of political agency. See Arendt’s own discussion in Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy along with Benhabib’s conclusion to Benhabib and Dallmyar, Communicative Ethics Controversy; and Fraser, Unruly Practices. 24. Again see McIntyre,“Is Akratic Action Always Irrational?” 399. 25. See Benhabib and Dallmyar, The Communicative Ethics Controversy, 128. 26. For further ramifications of this assumption as it bears on rational choice-making within a technical philosophical framework, see Mele, Irrationality; McIntyre,“Is Akratic Actional Always Irrational?”; and Elster, introduction to The Multiple Self. 27. See Eliot Jurist’s Hegelian appreciation of this intrinsic wisdom of tragic drama, in “Tragedy in/and/of Hegel.” I take Simon Goldhills’s Reading Greek Tragedy as my point of reference for the classical scholarship on this point (86). 28. See Baumgarten, Reflections on Poetry, 76–79. 29. See also my Baumgartinian appreciation of the aesthetic as a determinative phenomenon in The Subject as Action, 121–26. 30. Alison McIntyre usefully points up the ways in which continence can be strikingly antithetical to the deliberative ideal of Aristotelian phronesis. When we equate continence with obstinacy, persistence, and inflexibility they are “merely traits of character and not virtues, because they could lead an agent to perservere with any decision, whether right or wrong” (“Is Akratic Action Always Irrational?” 396). 31. In this case erroneous action is the corollary of unknowledgeable action, hamartia, and political apathia. All these establish the pretext for the claims I am asserting on behalf of the aesthetic in this chapter.
Chapter 4 1. Kant of course brackets perfectionism in the “Analytic of the Beautiful.” But he does so only with respect to a rule that is independent of form. Here I am invoking perfection to denote a purely intuitive conflation of rule and form.This conflation is commonly taken for granted in popular notions of the beautiful object.
Singer.book
9/12/03
282
11:22 AM
Page 282
Notes
2. For Kant, of course, the autonomy of the aesthetic judgment is bound to the indeterminacy of value.This has long been the obstacle to socializing the Kantian aesthetic or contemplating its prospects for social changes that would otherwise be consistent with the amelioration of social ills.Adam Smith’s Treatise on Moral Sentiment and Shaftesbury’s Characteristics exemplify the degree to which eighteenth-century theories of the aesthetic were invested in this ethos. Both thinkers view the aesthetic as a potential check against the moral fragmentation of society threatened in the displacement of monarchic government by market economies. For the fullest exposition of these views, see Guillory, Cultural Capital; and Bourdieu, Rules of Art. 3. See Plato,“Ion.” 4. Julian Young summarizes Nietzsche’s case in Human, All Too Human in this way: “Art in a secular age provides, as it were, a catacomb in which the religious habit of mind can continue to exist. For what it offers is religious feeling without cognitive responsibility” (Young, Nietzsche’s Philosophy of Art, 65). 5. For a full view of these issues, see Chapters 2 and 3 in this volume. 6. See Ferry, Homo Aestheticus, 197. 7. See Sidney,“Defense of Poetry” as excerpted in Hazard Adams’s critical anthology Critical Theory Since Plato, 158. 8. See Howard Caygill’s extensive survey of this history of the reciprocity between theories of taste and the practices of civil society, in Art of Judgment, 38–101. 9. David Kolb usefully distinguishes modernity from traditional culture in the terms of the epistemological inflection given by the Latin modern, meaning “in this time.” Subsequent English usage bifurcates, on the one hand designating modernity as “contemporaneity,” and on the other, stipulating the sense that we live at a distance from the classic. See Critique of Pure Modernity, 1–2. 10. See Kant,“What Is Enlightenment?” 11. For a detailed consideration of the reasons why we might want to predicate scientific explanation on anomalies rather than deductive-nomological models, see Humphreys, Anomalies and Scientific Theories. See also Paisley Livingston’s discussions of the potential impact of anomaly theories on practices of literary interpretation, in Literary Knowledge, 228–30. 12. David Wiggins, in “Universalizability, Impartiality,Truth,” in Needs, Values, Truths, argues that we ought to avoid thinking, as Kant did, of universalization as a generative process. Rather, we ought to treat it as always working upon already recognized moral principles: “Universalization is no longer a method or any part of the method for the initial generation of moral ideas and principles. It works on what is already fully moralized. . . . [T]he univeralizer . . . is bidden onto the scene not in the role of an explorer or first map-maker but in the role of a surveyor visiting a scene already discovered and directly known” (78–79). In other words, universalization verges upon deliberative process and presupposes the protocols of deliberation that foster dialogue and community. 13. See Paul de Man’s precedent for linking Benjamin and Althusser (and by extension, Jameson) as a set of exemplary “aesthetic thinkers.” De Man alleges that “these thinkers preclude, for example, any valorization of aesthetic categories at the expense of intellectual rigor or political action, or any claim for the autonomy of aesthetic experience as a self-enclosed, self-reflexive totality” (Aesthetic Ideology, 139, 140–41).The difference between my grouping of these figures and de Man’s is his belief that they are precisely not susceptible to the cognitive corruptions of “aestheticism.” I am of course arguing that, despite their best intentions, these figures cannot transcend the critique of aestheticism they mount in a way that accommodates more philosophically hard-headed reckonings with aesthesis. See de Man,“Hegel on the Sublime,” in Aesthetic Ideology. 14. See Althusser, “A Letter on Art,” in Lenin and Philosophy and Other Essays, 222.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 283
Notes
283
15. “The real difference between art and science lies in the specific form in which they give us the same object in quite different ways: art in the form of ‘seeing’ and ‘perceiving’ or ‘feeling,’ science in the form of knowledge (in the strict sense, by concepts)” (ibid., 223). 16. Althusser’s theory of ideology is a decontextualizing of error insofar as it renders contradictions purely symptomatic 17. See Marx, Grundrisse. Michael Sprinker, in Imaginary Relations, has a balanced discussion of the genealogical links between Marx and Althusser on this point. 18. See Habermas, Justification and Application, where Habermas usefully places MacIntyre’s arguments in the context of Rorty, Davidson, Putnam, and Rawls. See especially 95–105. 19. See Bremer, Hamartia, especially 23. 20. In the concluding chapter of The Muses, Nancy promotes the idea that visuality, in this perspective, approaches “a proliferation of views [vues], the visible or the sensible itself in multiple slivers [èclats] which refer to nothing” (94). 21. See Hegel, Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion, 366. Choice guarantees that “real subjectivity posits differences essentially in its determination . . . where there can be for me several different things that are defined as good, so that there is the possibility of choice. . . . [Only then] does the subject rise above particular purpose . . . and becomes free from the particularity.” 22. Here I must note that Nancy is more interested in the being of the excluded plurality as an aspect of phenomenological becoming. I am more interested in the denser determinateness of the excluded agency. See Nancy, The Muses, 26. 23. Caravaggio is acknowledged to have painted two Conversions. I am writing about the Conversion of Saint Paul commissioned on 24 September 1600 by Monsignor Tiberio Cerasi for his chapel in Santa Maria del Popolo, where it still hangs. A second Conversion, in the Balbi Odescalchi Collection, has been an object of controversy with respect to both attribution and dating. Furthermore, it is worth noting that the foreshortening in the composition is potentiated by the placement of the painting. It is hung on the right wall of the chapel, putting the viewer at an oblique angle to the picture plane. The narrowness of the chapel makes the obliquity of the view as untranscendable as the horse itself. 24. This makes a useful contrast with the Balbi Odescalchi Conversion where the “vision” is visualized in the figure of a solicitous angel and a mediating figure of Christ. 25. See Caravaggio Studies, 18–19. 26. See Damisch,“The Theme of Choosing,” in Judgment of Paris.
Chapter 5 1. Derrida provides a useful historical and conceptual perspective on the inexorably aesthetic nature of error. He observes that in the Theodicy choice, being a default of the limitedness of human action, is in that regard a source of pleasure that distinguishes man from God. God does not know the anguish of the choice between possibilities. It is an index of human expressivity that Merleau-Ponty confirms for Derrida in saying: “‘Communication in literature is not the simple appeal on the part of the writer to meanings which would be part of an a priori of the mind; rather communication arouses these meanings in the mind through enticement and a kind of oblique action.The writer’s thought does not control his language from without; the writer is himself a kind of new idiom construction himself’” (quoted in Derrida’s The Gift of Death). 2. For Kant’s famous account of the “unsocial sociability of men,” see “Idea for a Universal History,” in On History, 15. In Kant’s version of the judgment of taste proper,
Singer.book
9/12/03
284
11:22 AM
Page 284
Notes
however, the social conflict that art seems to engage, as a productive aspect of human anthropology, lacks any specific agency. 3. See Hannah Arendt’s extrapolation of Kantian judgment to the political sphere, in Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy. I have tried to test the limits of this enterprise in Chapter 2. 4. Indeed, corrigibility, in this context, might seem the aptest of all metaphors for an aesthetic value cut off from its means of production. It would seem to authorize a context for the justification of artworks in which their value must be presupposed, since it cannot be rationally determined. This would, however, make it impossible to predicate aesthetic value upon a justificatory process that is perforce contextual, i.e., corrigible in the sense that such value is not predetermined. 5. As I have already suggested, corrigibility is a term that can denote a static, predetermined value dimension such as perfection: it is a counter for an intrinsic predisposition to goodness. But unlike perfection it is also a term that can be generalized beyond the context of moral goodness in the abstract, to denote the dependency of human value on human action or self-production, rather than on reified self.That is to say, corrigibility entertains a vital reciprocity between agency and contingent standards of evaluation that perfection does not. This has specific relevance in the context of Guillory’s ultimate view of the eighteenth-century alienation of the artwork from the commodity. 6. See the conclusion to Pater, Studies in the History of Renaissance. 7. One cannot overstate Marx’s insistence on the reciprocity of relations that play between production and consumption and how this reciprocity sustains the concreteness of the terms. Having explained generally how production creates consumption, he stipulates that production gives consumption its specificity. Marx goes on to note in the Grundrisse that “the object [of consumption] is not an object in general, but a specific object which must be consumed in a specific manner” (92). 8. In line with the previous note, I should emphasize my belief that Guillory’s reading of the introduction to Grundrisse understates Marx’s stipulation. He asserts that, whether in consumptive production or productive consumption,“[t]he immediate unity in which production coincides with consumption and consumption with production leaves their immediate duality intact” (Guillory, Cultural Capital, 91). The result of this understatement is to lose track of the materialist trajectory of Marx’s thinking, even as it obtains strictly on the analogical register of the aesthetic. 9. Indeed, Bourdieu all too simplistically conflates the artwork with the Kantian prejudices against function and consequence. He is too quick to accept the notion (fostered by Harold Osborne, among others) that the “aesthetic attitude” or “aesthetic disposition” is “characterized by the concentration of attention (it ‘frames apart’ the perceived object from its environment), by the suspension of discursive and analytic activities.” See Rules of Art, 285–86 and 299. I am simply suggesting that Bourdieu has unnecessarily circumscribed the field of definition for the aesthetic in order to denounce it as a field of reference for assessing human values. 10. See Bourdieu’s scathing assessment of the illusionary premise that aesthetic value is predicated on an essence that gives primacy to form over function (Rules of Art, 288). 11. Bourdieu’s preoccupation with the “distribution of the aesthetic disposition” seems to preclude any analytical or discursive engagement with the formal qualities of the artwork that determine or produce whatever social consequences might be attributable to it. In other words, Bourdieu’s sociological critique seems to fall into precisely the “aesthetic attitude” he himself already descried in the work of Harold Osborne. See note 10 in the present chapter and Rules of Art, 299. 12. See Bourdieu,“Corporatism of the Universal,” 103. 13. See Kant, Critique of Judgment. 14. See McIntyre, “Is Akratic Action Always Irrational?” See also my discussion
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 285
Notes
285
of McIntyre’s approach to the issue of phronetic action, in Chapter 3 of the present volume. 15. See Ethics, 246–47 for a sense of how Aristotle’s (by contrast with Plato’s) view of akrasia bears on character in a way that complements his Poetics: where character is subordinated to action. In Poetics character is presented as a threshold of changeability that, in accordance with the devices of peripeteia and hamartia, entails contextual protocols of knowledge. 16. See Ethics, 97. 17. See particularly Bal, Narratology. 18. See “Bartleby,” 43, where Melville deploys some variant of the term assumption. 19. See Miller, Ethics of Reading. 20. It is worth considering in this regard that Melville’s library featured a text by Samuel Warren (The Moral, Social, and Professional Duties of Attorneys and Solicitors), published in the year before “Bartleby” was written.The ethical concerns addressed in this work focus upon clients about whom it is revealed, only after their demise, that they were not properly served by counsel. See Sealts, Melville’s Reading, 104. 21. In The Gift of Death, Derrida has a brief but evocative discussion of Bartleby. His close attention to Bartleby’s preference “not to” yields a meditation on indeterminacy that complements my point nicely: “I would prefer not to looks like an incomplete sentence. Its indeterminacy creates a tension: it opens onto a sort of reserve of incompleteness; it announces a temporary or provisional reserve, one involving a proviso. Can we not find there the secret of a hypothetical reference to some indecipherable providence or prudence?” (75; my emphasis). It is precisely the prudential or deliberative reserves of indeterminacy that I am alleging could be tapped in the imperatives of adaptation.
Chapter 6 1. See Rocco, Tragedy and Enlightenment, 34–67, for its focus on the affinity of Greek culture with that of eighteenth-century Europe. 2. Wiggins takes his cue here from Aristotle’s notion that standards of reasonableness in philosophy are dependent on the constraints of practical knowledge.Within those constraints, one’s sense of how well a rule fits its object reflects the degree to which we exercise judgment in “confrontation with some actually given particular situation—a situation described very specifically, though not in a way that makes it impossible to inquire for the relevant difference between it and other situations calling forth similar or dissimilar decisions” (Wiggins, Needs, Values, Truth, 379).Aristotle stipulates that where the rule is not presupposed for the judgment, because the degree of fit between the rule and the object is not predetermined,“the decision lies with our perception” (Ethics, 1126 b10; my emphasis).Wiggins’s sense of the aesthetic as a case of “situational appreciation” here derives from Aristotle’s use of the term perception. 3. See Rocco, Tragedy and Enlightenment, 171. 4. See Eldridge, Leading a Human Life.As his title, with its subtitle, Wittgenstein, Intentionality, and Romanticism, suggests, Eldridge links the habit of “subliming” explanation to the conceptual weaknesses of Romantic theories of the self. For a resourceful account of what alternatives present themselves in relation to the subject’s reliance on rule-following and practical norms of self recognition, see especially his chapter 9 (“Inner Experience, the Exhaustion of Temptation, Remembrance, Gratitude— #243–308”), 242–90. 5. See Horkheimer and Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment, 3. 6. See Rocco’s agreement with Vernant on this point (Rocco, Tragedy and Enlightenment, 40–41; Vernant and Vidal-Naquet, Myth and Tragedy, 127).
Singer.book
9/12/03
286
11:22 AM
Page 286
Notes
7. Arlene W. Saxonhous quoted in Rocco, Tragedy and Enlightenment, 41. 8. Ibid., 133–34. 9. Ibid., 25–26. 10. Ibid., 185 11. The counter of incontinent action in Dialectic of Enlightenment is the individual whose identity will be countenanced only if it is generalizeable beyond any circumstance of action that is plausibly his or her own. Consequently,“[i]n the culture industry the individual is an illusion not merely because of the standardization of the means of production. He is tolerated only so long as his complete identification with the generality is unquestioned. . . . What is individual is no more than the generality’s power to stamp the accidental detail so firmly that it is accepted as such” (154). 12. See Habermas’s stigmatizing of this formula in The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity. 13. See Sense of the World. 14. See Gadamer,“Relevance of the Beautiful.” 15. See Putnam, Many Faces of Realism, 79. 16. Ibid., 78–80. 17. Putnam stipulates his preference for the place of the agent over the spectator, though his concern at this moment is only with the relative merits of each viewpoint vis-à-vis the fixity of the relevant worldview. Elsewhere it is clear that his sense of the deliberative agent does entail a relation to spectatorship, at least insofar as “taking the agent point of view . . . leads to a fallibilism, a pluralism and a version of realism that includes some objectivity.” See McCormick’s useful discussion of this point, in Modernity, Aesthetics, and the Bounds of Art, 326. 18. See Wiggins, Needs, Values, Truth, 237. 19. Unfortunately, Bersani’s case depends more on the premise that the “work” of art, i.e., particular labor by which being is produced, has consequence in the world only insofar as it negates meaning. In that way it constitutes a defensive maneuver against ideology. I reject this argument on the same basis that I finally invoked in my assessment of Nancy’s fragmentary aesthetic. In effect, Bersani subscribes to Nancy’s motto for the “negative” status of art: art is a “representation of representation.” 20. See Bersani, The Culture of Redemption, 135. 21. See Aesthetic Judgment, 69. 22. It is worth noting that Vernant makes an invidious comparison between action depicted in Aeschylus and Sophocles with Euripides’ focus on the pathetic mode. Vernant agrees with J. de Romilly that the shift of emphasis to a human life in which the frame of reference is simply character, unconflicted by an external determining force (which he identifies with the order of the gods), comes at the cost of meaningful scope for responsible action. See Vernant and Vidal-Naquet, Myth and Tragedy in Ancient Greece, 83–84.
Chapter 7 1. See Chapter 5 for my discussion of Guillory’s and Bourdieu’s drift toward universalizing abstraction, in direct contradiction of their stated intentions to restore sociopolitical bite to an otherwise decadent aestheticism. 2. For the basis of this generalization, see especially chapter 1,“Free Particulars,” in The Ideology of the Aesthetic. 3. Here it is worth considering a similar initiative taken by Edward Said in his Musical Elaborations. Said essays to remediate the exile of feeling from theories of artistic form. His appeal to what Raymond Williams had called “the structure of feeling” as the basis of an aesthetic community that might rebuild civil society from
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 287
Notes
287
the ground up, rather than from the top down, is a bid for an aesthetic theory that eludes the traps of hegemonic taste. But in support of this emotion-based aesthetic, Said’s recourse to the example of Arabic song cycles reveals the cost of abdicating cognitive structures. The Arabic song cycles, which work on a principle of virtually infinite self-elaboration, put the expressive self in radical doubt.They invite abstract universalizing precisely where particularizing agency would seem the most relevant resource of creative will. Oddly enough, this example presents an impasse of theorizing that bears striking resemblance to that which afflicted Curt J. Ducasse, R. G. Collingwood, and Suzanne Langer, all of whom solicited emotional grounds for aesthetic universals. 4. For an elaboration of how a strategy to redirect traditions of learning about form might suffice as an artistic métier, or as a ground of aesthetic valuation, see Crowther, Critical Aesthetics, especially 195. 5. For exemplification of these enthusiasms, see Cascardi, Consequences of Enlightenment; and Butler, Psychic Life of Power. 6. Benjamin generates considerable enthusiasm for Dadaism’s use of picture frames to enclose the detritus of quotidian life.The effect is to negate the way in which the frame “ruptures time” and so falsifies its production. My point here is that Benjamin’s aesthetic agency constitutes no more than a corollary rupturing of the frame. See “The Author as Producer,” in Illuminations, 229. 7. See Sussman, Aesthetic Contracts, 110. 8. This point is referenced to Benjamin’s discussion in Origin of the German Tragic Drama, 60–61. 9. See Kant,“On Estimating the Magnitude of Natural Things . . . ,” in Critique of Judgment, 108–9. 10. Bourdieu’s fullest account of habitus appears in Outline of a Theory of Practice, 78–87. 11. Crowther’s books, Critical Aesthetics and Postmodernism; Art and Embodiment; and, most recently, The Language of Twentieth-Century Art, are elements of an ongoing argument: “The central thesis of these works is that what is fundamental in our cognitive relation to the world is our inherence in it as embodied beings. How the world is structured and how we negotiate it through the unified operations of all the senses are reciprocally correlated” (Language of Twentieth-Century Art, 3). 12. See Crowther’s riposte to Altieri in the Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53, no. 1 (1995). Specifically, Altieri is critical of Crowther’s account of the historical agent, in and out of the artwork.Altieri raised his objections in a review of Crowther’s earlier work.This review is incorporated by Crowther into the conclusion to his recent Language of Twentieth-Century Art, 230–31. 13. See Birgit Pelser, “There Is No There: Gerhard Richter at the Carré d’Art in Nimes,” in Richter, 100 Pictures, 146. 14. Antoine,“Photography, Painting, and the Real,” 63. 15. “Poetics,” 50. 16. See Chapter 1. 17. McIntyre,“Is Akratic Action Always Irrational?” 389. 18. Anthony Cascardi usefully considers the extrapolation of the Marxist precept by Lacanians, preeminently Zizek. See Cascardi,“Difficulty of Art,” 40–41.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 288
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 289
Bibliography
Adams, Hazard, ed. Critical Theory Since Plato. New York: Harcourt Brace, 1992. Adorno, Theodor W. Aesthetic Theory. Edited by Gretel Adorno and Rolph Tiedemann.Translated by C. Lenhardt. London: Routledge, 1970. Althusser, Louis. Lenin and Philosophy. Translated by Ben Brewster. New York: Monthly Review Press, 1971. Altieri, Charles. Postmodernisms Now: Essays on Contemporaneity in the Arts. University Park: Penn State University Press, 1998. Antoine, Jean-Philippe. “Photography, Painting, and the Real: The Question of Landscape in the Paintings of Gerhard Richter.” In Gerhard Richter: Paintings, edited by I. Michael Danoff, Roald Nasgaard, and Terry Neff. London:Thames and Hudson, 1988. Arendt, Hannah. The Human Condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958. ———. Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy. Edited and with an interpretive essay by Ronald Beiner. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982. ———. The Life of the Mind. New York: Harcourt Brace, 1978. ———.“Thinking and Research: A Lecture.” Social Research 38 (1971). ———.“Understanding and Politics.” Partisan Review 20 (1953). Aristotle. Ethics.Translated by J.A. K.Thomson. London: Penguin, 1985. ———. Aristotle’s “Poetics.” Translated by James Hutton. New York: Norton, 1982. Bal, Mieke. Narratology: Introduction to the Theory of Narrative. 2d ed., revised and expanded.Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1997. Baron, Hans. Petrarch to Leonardo Bruni. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1968. Baumgarten, Alexander Gottleib. Reflections on Poetry. Translated by Karl Aschenbrenner and William Holther. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1954. ———. Aesthetica. 1750. Hildesheim: G. Olms, 1961. Beck, Lewis White. On History. Indianapolis: Bobbs Merrill, 1963. Beckett, Samuel. Ill Seen, Ill Said.Translated by Samuel Beckett. New York: Grove Press, 1981. Beiner, Ronald.“Interpretive Essay.” In Lecture’s on Kant’s Political Philosophy, by Hannah Arendt. Edited and with an interpretive essay by Ronald Beiner. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958. Beiser, Frederick C. The Fate of Reason. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1987. Bell, Clive. Art. New York: Capricorn, 1958.
Singer.book
9/12/03
290
11:22 AM
Page 290
Bibliography
Benhabib, Seyla. Critique, Norm, and Utopia. New York: Columbia University Press, 1986. Benhabib, Seyla, and Fred Dallmyer, eds. The Communicative Ethics Controversy. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1990. Benjamin, Andrew, and Peter Osborne, eds. Thinking Art: Beyond Traditional Aesthetics. London: ICA, 1991. Benjamin, Walter. Illuminations. Edited by Hannah Arendt. Translated by Harry Zohn. New York: Schocken Books, 1985. ———. Origin of German Tragic Drama. Translated by George Steiner. London: Verso, 1998. ———. Reflections. Translated by Edmund Jephcett. New York: Schocken Books, 1986. Bennett,Tony. Outside Literature. London: Routledge, 1990. Bernstein, J. M. Adorno: Disenchantment and Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001. ———. The Fate of Art: Aesthetic Alienation from Kant to Derrida and Adorno. University Park: Penn State Press, 1992. Bourdieu, Pierre.“The Corporatism of the Universal:The Role of Intellectuals in the Modern World.” Telos 81 (1989): 103. ———. Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgment of Taste. Translated by Richard Nice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1987. ———. Outline of a Theory of Practice. Translated by Richard Nice. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1977. ———. The Rules of Art: Genesis and the Structure of the Literary Field.Translated by Susan Emanuel. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1996. Bourdieu, Pierre, and Hans Haacke. Free Exchange. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1995. Bremer, J. M. Hamartia: Tragic Error in the Poetics of Aristotle.Amsterdam: Adolf M. Hakkert, 1969. Brenkman, John. Culture and Domination. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1987. Bruni, Leonardo. The Humanism of Leonardo Bruni: Selected Texts. Edited by Gordon Griffiths, James Hankins, and David Thompson. Binghamton: Medieval and Renaissance Texts and Studies with the Renaissance Society of America, 1987. Bürger, Peter. The Decline of Modernism.Translated by Nicholas Walker. University Park: Penn State Press, 1992. Butler, Judith. The Psychic Life of Power. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1997. Buxton, R. G. A. Persuasion in Greek Tragedy: A Study of Peitho. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982. Carroll, Noel.“Beauty and the Genealogy of Art Theory.” Philosophical Forum 1 (Summer 1991): 307–34. Cascardi, Anthony J. “The Difficulty of Art.” In Thinking Through Art: Aesthetic Agency and Global Modernity. Edited by Daniel T. O’Hara and Alan Singer. Special issue, Boundary 2, vol. 25 (Spring 1998): 40–41. Castiglione, Baldassare. The Book of the Courtier.Translated by George Bull. New York: Penguin, 1976. Caygill, Howard. Art of Judgment. London: Blackwell, 1989.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 291
Bibliography
291
Chytry, Joseph. The Aesthetic State: A Quest in Modern German Thought. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1989. Connor, W. Robert The New Politicians of Fifth-Century Athens. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1971. Cooke, Maeve. Language and Reason. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1994. ———. “Realizing the Post-Conventional Subject” Philosophy and Social Criticism 20, no. 1/2 (1997): 87–101. Crowther, Paul. Art and Embodiment: From Aesthetics to Self-Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001. ———. Critical Aesthetics and Postmodernism. New Haven:Yale University Press, 1996. ———. The Language of Twentieth-Century Art: A Conceptual History. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1997. Damisch, Hubert. The Judgment of Paris (Analytic Iconology I).Translated by John Goodman. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996. Deleuze, Gilles, and Guattari, Felix. Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Translated by Helen R. Lang and Robert Hurley. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota, 1985. de Man, Paul. Aesthetic Ideology. Translated by Andrzej Warminski. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1996. Derrida, Jacques. The Gift of Death.Translated by David Willis. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995. Dreyfus, Hubert L., and Paul Rabinow. Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983. Dunn, Robert. The Possibility of Weakness of Will. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987. Eagleton,Terry. The Ideology of the Aesthetic. London: Blackwell, 1990. Eldrige, Richard. Leading a Human Life: Wittgenstein, Intentionality, and Romanticism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1997. Elster, Jon, ed. The Multiple Self. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987. Ferguson,William Scott. Hellenistic Athens: An Historical Essay. London: Macmillan, 1911. Ferry, Luc. Homo Aestheticus.Translated by Robert De Loaiza. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993. Fichte, Johann Gottlieb. The Science of Knowledge (Wissenschaftslehre [1794]). Edited and translated by Peter Heath and John Lachs. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988. Foster, Hal, ed. The Anti-Aesthetic: Essays on Postmodern Culture. Seattle: Bay Press, 1983. ———. Recodings: Art, Spectacle, Cultural Politics. Seattle: Bay Press, 1985. Foucault, Michel. “An Aesthetics of Existence.” In Michel Foucault: Politics, Philosophy, Culture. Edited by Lawrence D. Kritzman. London: Routledge, 1988. ———. The Care of the Self.Translated by Robert Hurley. New York: Pantheon, 1986. ———. Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison.Translated by Alan Sheridan, New York: Pantheon, 1977. ———. The Foucault Reader. Edited by Michel Foucault and Paul Rabinow. New York: Random House, 1984. Fraser, Nancy. Unruly Practices. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1991.
Singer.book
9/12/03
292
11:22 AM
Page 292
Bibliography
Friedlaender, Walter. Caravaggio Studies. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1974. Gadamer, Hans Georg. The Relevance of the Beautiful and Other Essays.Translated by Nicholas Walker. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987. ———. Truth and Method.Translated by Garrett Barden and John Cumming, New York: Seabury Press, 1975. Garin, Eugenio. Italian Humanism: Philosophy and Civic Life in the Renaissance. Translated by Peter Munz. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1965. Geuss, Raymond. The Idea of a Critical Theory: Habermas and the Frankfurt School. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981. Goldhills, Simon. Reading Greek Tragedy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986. Goodman, Nelson. Languages of Art. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1968. ———. Of Mind and Other Matters. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1984. Guillory, John. Cultural Capital: The Problem of Literary Canon Formation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993. Habermas, Jürgen. Justification and Application: Remarks on Discourse Ethics. Translated by Ciarin Cronin. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1994. ———.“Modernity: An Incomplete Project.” In The Anti-Aesthetic: Essays in Postmodern Literature, edited by Hal Foster. Seattle: Bay Press, 1983. ———. The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity. Translated by Frederick Lawrence. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1987. Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art.Translated by T. M. Knox. 2 vols. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1975. ———. Introductory Lectures on Aesthetics.Translated by Bernard Bosanquet, with an introduction and commentary by Michaeal Inwood. New York: Penguin, 1994. ———. Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion.Vol. 2. Edited by Peter C. Hodgson. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1988. ———. On Art, Religion, Philosophy. Edited by J. Glenn Gray, New York: Harper, 1970. ———. Phenomenology of Mind.Translated by J. B. Baillie. New York: Harper and Row, 1967. Henrich, Dieter. Aesthetic Judgment and the Moral Image of the World. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1992. Herder, Johann Gottfried von. Essay on the Origin of Language.Translated by John H. Moran. New York: Ungar, 1967. Holmes, George. The Florentine Enlightenment: 1400–50. New York: Pegasus, 1969. Horkheimer, Max, and Theodor W. Adorno. Dialectic of Enlightenment.Translated by John Cumming. New York: Continuum, 1990. Hume, David. Of the Standard of Taste and Other Essays. Edited by John W. Lenz. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1965. ———. A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by P. H. Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1981. Humphreys,Willard C. Anomalies and Scientific Theories. San Francisco: Freeman Cooper, 1968.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 293
Bibliography
293
Hutcheson, Francis. An Inquiry Concerning Beauty, Order, Harmony, Design. Edited Peter Kivy.The Hague: Martin Nijhoff, 1973. Jameson, Fredric. Fables of Aggression: Wyndham Lewis, the Modernist as Fascist. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1979. Joyce, James.“The Dead.” In Dubliners. New York: Penguin, 1993. Jurist, Eliot L.“Tragedy in/and/of Hegel.” Philosophical Forum 25, no. 2 (1993): 151–72. Kant, Immanuel. The Critique of Judgment. Translated by Werner S. Pluhar. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987. ———. Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals.Translated by H. J. Paton. New York: Harper and Row, 1956. ———. ”Idea for a Universal History.” In On History. Edited by Lewis White Beck. Translated by Lewis White Beck, R. E. Anchor, and E. L. Fackenheim. Indianapolis: Library of the Liberal Arts, 1963. ———. Perpetual Peace and Other Essays. Edited by Ted Humphrey. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1992. ———. “What Is Enlightenment?” In On History. Edited by Lewis White Beck. Translated by Lewis White Beck, R. E. Anchor, and E. L. Fackenheim. Indianapolis: Library of the Liberal Arts, 1963. Kolb, David. Critique of Pure Modernity: Hegel, Heidegger, and After. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1986. Livingston, Paisley. Literary Knowledge: Humanistic Inquiry and the Philosophy of Science. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1988. Lukács, Georg. The Theory of the Novel.Translated by Anna Bostock. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1971. Lyotard, Jean-François. The Differend: Phrases in Dispute. Translated by Georges Van Den Abeele. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1988. ———. The Postmodern Condition.Translated by Geoffrey Bennington and Brian Massumi. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984. Lyotard, Jean-François, and Jean Loup Thebaud. Just Gaming. Translated by Wlad Godzich. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1985. McCarthy,Thomas. Ideals and Illusions: On Reconstruction and Deconstruction in Contemporary Critical Theory. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1993. McCormick, Peter J. Modernity, Aesthetics, and the Bounds of Art. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1990. MacIntyre,Alasdair. Whose Justice? Which Rationality? Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988. McIntyre, Alison.“Is Akratic Action Always Irrational?” In Identity, Character, and Morality: Essays in Moral Psychology, edited by Owen Flanagan and Amelie Oksenberg Rorty. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1993. Marcuse, Herbert. The Aesthetic Dimension: Toward a Critique of Marxist Aesthetics. Boston: Beacon Press, 1978. Marx, Karl. Grundrisse.Translated by Martin Nicolaus. New York: Modern Library/ The Marx Library, 1973. Mele,Alfred. Irrationality: An Essay on Akrasia, Self-Deception, and Self-Control. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987.
Singer.book
9/12/03
294
11:22 AM
Page 294
Bibliography
Melville, Herman. Piazza Tales. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1998. Miller, J. Hillis. The Ethics of Reading: Kant, de Man, Eliot, Trollope, James, and Benjamin. New York: Columbia University Press, 1987. Moritz, Karl-Philipp. Schriften zur Ästhetik und Poetik. Edited by Hans Joachim Schrimpf.Tübingen, Germany: M. Niemeyer, 1962. Nancy, Jean-Luc. The Muses.Translated by Peggy Kamuf. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1996. ———. Sense of the World.Translated by Jeffrey S. Librett. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1998. Nietzsche, Friedrich. Human, All Too Human. Translated by Marion Faber and Stephen Lehmann. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1996. Pater,Walter. The Renaissance: Studies in Art and Poetry. Edited by Adam Phillips. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998. Plato.“Ion.” In Critical Theory Since Plato, edited by Hazard Adams. New York: Harcourt Brace, 1971. ———. Plato’s “Sophist.” Translated by Seth Benardete. Chicago: University of Chicago, 1986. Putnam, Hilary. The Many Faces of Realism. LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1988. Rasmussen, David, ed. Universalism vs. Communitarianism. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1990. Richter, Gerhard. 100 Pictures. Edited by Hans-Ulrich Obrist.Translated by Brian Holmes. Ostfildern-Ruit, Germany: Cantz Verlag, 1996. Ricoeur, Paul. Oneself as Another. Translated by Kathleen Blamey. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994. Rocco, Christopher. Tragedy and Enlightenment: Athenian Political Thought and the Dilemmas of Modernity. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1997. Rorty, Amelie O.“Self-Deception, Akrasia, and Irrationality.” In The Multiple Self, edited by Jon Elster. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987. Ross, Andrew. Universal Abandon. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1989. Said, Edward. Musical Elaborations. New York: Columbia University Press, 1991. Sealts, Merton M., Jr. Melville’s Reading: A Check-List of Books Owned and Borrowed. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1966. Shaftesbury, Anthony. Characteristics of Men, Manners, Opinions, Times. Edited by John M. Robertson. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1964. Sidney, Sir Philip.“An Apology for Poetry.” In Critical Theory Since Plato, edited by Hazard Adams. New York: Harcourt Brace, 1971. Sinfield, Alan. Faultlines. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1992. Singer, Alan. The Subject as Action: Transformation and Totality in Narrative Aesthetics.Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1993. Smith, Paul. Discerning the Subject. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1988. Sophocles. The Three Theban Plays.Translated by Robert Fagles. New York: Penguin, 2000.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 295
Bibliography
295
Sprinker, Michael. Imaginary Relations: Aesthetics and Ideology in the Theory of Historical Materialism. London:Verso, 1987. Sussman, Henry. The Aesthetic Contract: Statutes of Art and Intellectual Work in Modernity. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998. Tugendthat, Ernst. Self-Consciousness and Self-Determination.Translated by Paul Stern. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1986. Vernant, Jean-Pierre, and Pierre Vidal-Naquet. Myth and Tragedy in Ancient Greece. Translated by Janet Lloyd. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1988. Vico, Giambattista. The New Science of Giambattista Vico.Translated by Thomas Goddard Bergin and Max Harold Fisch. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1984. Wellmer,Albrecht. Endgames: The Irreconcilable Nature of Modernity.Translated by David Midgley. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1998. ———. The Persistence of Modernity: Essays on Aesthetics, Ethics, and Postmodernism. Translated by David Midgeley. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1991. Wiggins, David. Needs, Values, Truth. Cambridge: Blackwell, 1991. Williams, Robert R. Recognition: Fichte and Hegel on the Other. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1992. Young, Julian. Nietzsche’s Philosophy of Art. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992.
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 296
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 297
Index
adaptation, adaptive agency, 168–69, 171, 174, 182, 224–26, 238, 247–48, 252, 261, 264, 271, 273 Adorno,Theodor W., 5, 43, 66, 187, 188, 191, 192 Aesthetic Theory, 28–38, 276 nn. 17, 21, 22 culture industry, 34 Dialectic of Enlightenment, 175, 177–85, 195, 199, 206, 213–15, 217–18, 286 n. 11 Negative Dialectics, 31 on “reconciliation,” 34–37 on “second reflection,” 31–35 on “tremor (Erschutterung),” 34–39 aesthesis, 14, 24, 26, 39, 51, 174, 182, 186–88, 196, 198, 213 and reason, 190 aesthetic attitude, 15, 165, 226 aesthetic perfection, perfectionism, 103–7, 110, 120, 122, 126, 144, 282 n. 1 aestheticism (versus aesthetics/aesthesis), 44, 49, 63, 100, 106, 115, 143, 144, 163, 166, 167, 168, 171, 193–94, 209, 232, 263 aesthetic state, the, 41–44, 50, 66 agonia, 3 akon (will in spite of desire), 184, 205 akrasia, akrates (the akratic agent), akratic action, 3, 5, 73–74, 79–89, 98–102, 145, 150, 152, 158–61, 166, 169, 171, 179–80, 232, 234, 235, 272–73 distinguished from hamartia, 280 n. 10 Althusser, Louis, 112–16, 117, 118, 119, 120, 125, 232, 235 on ideology, 112, 114–15 Lenin and Philosophy, 280 n. 1 “A Letter on Art,” 113–14, 283 nn. 14, 15, 16 Altieri, Charles, 243–55
on “On the Sublime of Self-Disgust,” 244–48 review of Crowther, 288 n. 12 anagnorisis, 47, 84 analogy, 94 anomaly theory, 109–11, 119, 235 anti-aesthetic (ideology of), anti-aestheticism, 5, 7, 10–14, 16, 19, 23, 39, 71–72, 76, 85, 127, 128, 220, 222–28, 230, 232, 238, 248–49 Antoine, Jean-Philippe, 271 appearance (Vorstellung, Darstellung), 71–75, 79, 82, 268 Aquinas, St.Thomas, 200 archon, 179 Arendt, Hannah, 41–69, 72, 273, 275 n. 1, 277 n. 1 on “enlarged thought,”“enlarged mentality,” 51–55, 59, 69, 89 on “exemplary validity,” 43, 52–57, 59, 62, 278 n. 33 The Human Condition, 43, 59, 65, 74–75, 80–81, 277 n. 5, 279 n. 35, 280 n. 11 on “imagination,” 56, 279 n. 34 on Kantian “schema,” 52–55 Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy, 46–60, 277 n. 6, 278, nn. 29, 31 The Life of the Mind, 43, 57–59 on “representative thinking,” 46–47 Thinking, 279 n. 36 “Understanding and Politics,” 279 n. 43 Aristotle, Aristotelian theories of art, 41, 47, 50, 63, 154, 158, 174, 196, 198, 200, 203 Aristotelian catharsis, 60–65, 67, 83 on distinction between tragedy and comedy, 127 on incontinent action, 157–60, 163, 167
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 298
298
Index
Aristotle, Aristotelian theories of art (continued) on interdependence of reversal and recognition, 223 Nichomachean Ethics, 3, 5, 47, 73, 82, 89, 101, 278 nn.15, 16, 17 Poetics, poiesis, 82, 89, 139, 181, 270, 280 n. 8, 285 n. 15 on proairesis, 183–86, 204–5 Arnold, Matthew, 12, 15 ars, 24 Auschwitz, 30 avant-garde, avant-gardism, 106–7 Balzac, Honoré, 114 Baron, Hans, 278 n. 22 Barthes, Roland, 232 Bartlett, Jennifer, 251 Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb, 1–2, 15, 147, 275 n. 5, 277 n. 11, 281 n. 28 on “confused clarity,” 95 scientia cognitionis sensitivae, 14 Batteaux, Charles, 77 Baudrillard, Jean, 128 Beardsley, Monroe, 24, 25, 39, 176 beauty, beauty theory, the beautiful, 20, 23, 24, 29, 42, 45, 48, 50–52, 57, 61, 73, 76–79, 82, 101, 103, 132, 143, 175 Beckett, Samuel, 13, 231, 234, 238, 247–48, 259 Ill Seen, Ill Said, 79, 86–102 and parsimonious syntax, 90–94, 97, 98, 101 Beiner, Ronald, 57–60, 277 n. 5, 279 nn. 40, 41, 44 Beiser, Frederick C., 278 n. 12 Bell, Clive, 24–25, 39 Bellori, Giovanni Pietro, 134 Benhabib, Seyla, 88–89, 281 and Fred Dallmayr, 281 nn. 19, 23, 25 Benjamin, Walter, 111, 227–30, 287 n. 6 “The Artist as Producer,” 228 Bennett,Tony, 2, 6, 12, 14–18 Bernstein, J. M., 30, 36, 276 n. 16 Bersani, Leo, 206, 286 nn. 19, 20 bia (passion/violence, antagonist of Peitho), 48, 63 Bohours, Dominique, 77 Borges, Jorge Luis, 247–48 Bouleau, Nicolas, 77–78, 86, 103, 148, 280 n. 7 Bourdieu, Pierre, 6, 12–17, 140, 148–49, 221, 245
on the “a-venir,” 236 Distinction, 275 n. 3 Free Exchange (with Hans Haacke), 237–44 on “corporatism of the universal,” 149 The Rules of Art, 229–37, 282 n. 2, 284–85 n. 9, 285 nn. 10, 11 Brecht, Bertolt, 37, 116, 229 Bremer, J. M., 84, 126, 280 nn. 9, 10, 281 n. 17, 283 n. 19 Brenkman, John, 224–25 Bruni, Leonardo, 49, 278 nn. 24 Bullough, Edward, 176 Bürger, Peter, 280 n. 6 Burgin, Victor, 244 Butler, Judith, 287 n. 5 Buxton, R. G. A., 6–63, 278 n. 20, 279 nn. 45–48 Caravaggio, (Michelangelo Merisi), 4, 231, 234, 238, 259 Conversion of Saint Paul, 129, 133–37, 283 n. 23 Carrol, Noël, 23–24 Cascardi, Anthony J., 287 n. 5 Castiglione, Baldassare, 50 choice-making, 10–12, 15, 22, 25, 27–29, 31, 35, 36–37, 39–40, 41, 45, 56–57, 67, 69, 75–76, 78, 83, 99, 112, 126–27, 132–33, 135, 137, 139, 147, 149, 159, 165, 167–70, 174, 176, 183–84, 201, 204, 206, 211, 219, 222, 231, 250, 263–64, 274 and learning, 224–25 in relation to need, 194–95 and reversal, agency, reading, 216–17, 223 catharsis, 223 Caygill, Howard, 275 n. 6, 282 n. 8 Chytry, Joseph, 41–42, 277 nn. 28, 4, 278 nn. 13, 21, 23 Collingwood, R. G., 176, 287 n. 3 communitarianism, 31, 42, 47, 50, 69, 78–79, 226 Comte, Auguste, 19, 25 Connor, W. Robert, 277 n. 3 Cooke, Maeve, 281 nn. 19, 21 Coover, Robert, 247–48 contextuality, contextualizing, 105–6, 110–15, 122, 126, 155, 157–58, 237–39, 241–42 and comparative context, 253–60, 267, 269 and pragmatic contextualism, 226–27, 236
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 299
Index and recontextualizing agency, 135–36, 272 versus relativism, 123–28 corrigibility, 139–40, 145, 149–50, 153–59, 169–71, 284 n. 5 critical theory, 66–67 Crowther, Paul, 253–60, 269, 287 n. 4 on “principle of reciprocity,” 254–55, 258, 287–88 n. 11 response to Altieri, 288 n. 12 Culture Industry, 200, 218 Dada, 106, 107, 227, 287 n. 6 daimon, 73, 80, 82, 92, 182 Damisch, Hubert, 283 n. 26 Daspre, André, 113 Derrida, Jacques, 186, 283–84 n. 1 The Gift of Death, 285 n. 21 Deixis, 34–36, 90 Deleuze, Gilles, 108, 117, 118, 186 deliberation, 6, 47–48, 56, 94–95, 97–101, 103, 107, 114–16, 119, 122, 132, 137, 141, 155–56, 174, 175, 176, 188, 196–201, 207, 216, 229, 253, 274 and demystifying “epistemological crisis,” 123–25 euboulia [good deliberation], 157–58 as a mode of adaptation, 168, 180, 182–83, 203 de Man, Paul, 282 n. 13 demos, 173, 179, 182, 189, 191, 204, 217 versus “mass audience,” 185 desire, 146–47 development, 218 versus estrangement, 220 Dewey, John, 15, 147 dianoia, 180 Dilthey, Wilhelm, 276 n. 22 disinterestedness, 24, 29, 33, 39–40, 51, 77, 141, 150, 160, 165–68, 277 n. 3 doctrine classique, 76, 78, 280 n. 6 Dreyfus, Hubert, 26, 276 n. 13 Dubos (the Abbe), 76–77, 140, 280 n. 7 Ducasse, Curt J., 287 n. 3 Duchamp, Marcel, 242, 265, 268 Dunn, Robert, 155 Eagleton,Terry, 2, 18, 275 n. 11 The Ideology of the Aesthetic, 222, 277 n. 8 Eldridge, Richard, 175 on “subliming” explanation, 286 n. 4 Elster, Jon, 281 nn. 19, 26 embodiment, 253–55
299
Enlightenment, the (also enlightenment), 23, 28, 78, 107, 108–12, 129, 140, 171, 173, 265 and activity, 177 postmodern critique of, 128–29, 186–87, 191, 221, 244–48 enkrateia (continent character), enkratic action, 84–89, 98–99, 155, 159, 170, 179–80, 184, 198–99, 202–3, 273–74 eristics, 46–48, 62 error, 4, 88–105, 108–9, 113, 115, 116, 118, 119, 120, 139, 193, 221, 259, 264–65, 274 and learning (corrigibility), 122–28, 149, 159, 255 ethics and aesthetics, 28–29, 42, 74, 80, 86, 97, 105–6, 120–21, 158–59 ethos, 47 eudaimonia, eudaimonian, 18–19, 73, 80–82, 92, 101, 280 n. 11 Faulkner, William, 231–36 Ferguson, William Scott, 278 n. 19 Ferrara, Alessandro, 281 n. 19 Ferry, Luc, 280 n. 7, 282 n. 6 Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, 35–39, 276 n. 26 on Anstoss (blockage), 37, 276 nn. 25, 27 on Aufforderung (“summons”)Anerkennung (recognition), 35–39 Science of Knowledge (Wissenschaftslehre), 35–38 Flaubert, Gustave, 232 Bouvard et Pécuchet, 206 Dictionnaire des Idées Recues, 206 Flaubertian irony, 235 Florentine Renaissance, 43, 49–50 foreshortening, 136–37 forgery, 168–69 Foster, Hal, 2, 10–11, 244, 249–50, 260, 380 n. 1 Foucault, Michel, 13, 16, 25–29, 108, 275 n. 10, 276 n. 15 The Care of the Self, 26–29 Discipline and Punish, 26 on genealogy/archeology, 276 n. 19 Frankfurt School, 25, 185 Fraser, Nancy, 277 n. 8, 281 n. 23 Freud, Sigmund, 66 Friedlaender, Walter, 135 Gadamer, Hans Georg, 50–52, 75–76, 190, 278 n. 28, 280 n. 5 game-theorists, 193 Garin, Eugenio, 278 n. 25
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 300
300
Index
Geschmack, 15 Geuss, Raymond, 66–69, 273 Goldhills, Simon, 281 n. 27 Goodman, Nelson, 6, 15, 195, 276 n. 14 Greenberg, Clement, and Greenbergian formalism, 239, 255 Guattari, Felix, 117, 118 Guillory, John, 6, 221 Cultural Capital, 140–49, 282 n. 2, 284 n. 8 Haacke, Hans, 237–43, 249, 250, 253, 263, 267 Freedom is Now Simply Going to be Sponsored—Out of Petty Cash, 239–42 Voici Alcan, 250–52 Habermas, Jürgen, 11, 15, 16, 34–35, 42–43, 87, 124, 275 nn. 2, 8, 277 n. 2, 283 n. 18 habitus (in Bourdieu), 232–37 hamartia, 80–81, 126–28 Hamman, J. G., 278 n. 12 Hegel, G. W. F., 9, 22, 24, 28–29, 31–34, 38, 64–66, 71, 81, 136, 147 on “the beautiful soul” and “conscience,” 64 on “forgiveness,” 63–66, 278–79 nn. 33, 49 Lectures in Aesthetics, 29, 276 n. 20 Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion, 129–32, 283 n. 21 hekon (volitional will), 184, 205 Henrich, Dieter, 206–7 Herder, Johann Gottfried, 15, 67 Essay on the Origin of Language, 45–46, 278 n. 11 history, historical self-consciousness, 28, 33, 57–58 Hobbes,Thomas, 15, 20, 108 Holmes, George, 278 n. 22 Horkheimer, Max, 43, 187, 188, 191, 192 Dialectic of Enlightenment, 175,177–85, 196, 199, 206, 213–15, 217–18, 286 n. 11 Huhn,Thomas, 30 Hume, David, 20–22, 140, 141, 142, 174 Humphreys, Willard, 109, 235–36, 282 n. 11 Hutcheson, Francis, 15, 16, 20–24, 39, 77, 140, 141, 275 n. 7 hypallage, 118 hypotyposis, 54–55 ideology, ideology critique, 1, 112, 119, 224, 231, 246 intersubjectivity, intersubjective mind, 16, 27, 29–30, 35–36, 62, 65, 69, 78, 91 Ionian League, 42, 48
Jameson, Fredric, 11, 111, 112, 120, 122, 125, 280 n. 1 on Deleuze and Guattari 117 Fables of Aggression, 115–19 on “libindinal apparatus,” 117–19 Joyce, James, 200, 231, 234, 238, 259 “The Dead,” 201–18 judgment, judgment power, 20–22, 40, 42–44, 46, 48, 52, 59–60, 78, 97, 113, 120 Jurist, Eliot, 281 n. 27 Kames, Lord, 107 Kant, Immanuel, 2, 3, 17, 32–33, 36, 38, 41, 50–61, 68, 87, 88, 102, 107, 108, 111, 140, 150, 195–96, 222, 248, 282 n. 2 and “aesthetical ideas,” 245–46 on the “Analytic of the Beautiful,” 282 n. 1 Critique of Judgment, 141, 277 n. 5, 278 nn. 27, 32, 279 nn. 37, 38, 281 n. 18 on “finality of form,” 109 Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, 281 n. 20 “Idea for a Universal History,” 284 n. 2 on the mathematical sublime, 118, 229 “Perpetual Peace,”, 43–44, 278 n. 30 on “play,”“purposiveness without a purpose,” 144, 146 “What is Enlightenment?,” 282 n. 10 Kolb, David, 282 n. 9 Kruger, Barbara, 238, 249, 250, 255, 263, 265, 267 “You Are Not Yourself,” 258–60 Langer, Suzanne, 176, 287 n. 3 Lewis, Wyndham, 115–19, 122 Livingston, Paisley, 282 n. 11 Locke, John, 20, 21, 77–78, 174, 275 n. 7 Longinus, 107 Lukács, Georg, 12, 18 Lyotard, Jean-François, 108, 111, 112, 117–18, 128, 245, 277 n. 8, 279 n. 52 MacIntyre, Alasdair, 112, 235–36, 281 n. 9 Whose Justice? Which Rationality?, 120–26 Marcuse, Herbert, 219–24, 229, 230, 244, 256, 264 on cognitive function of art, 220–21, 261 Marx, Karl, 18, 113, 145, 149, 273 Grundrisse, 13, 116, 144–46, 283 n. 17, 284 n. 7 McCarthy,Thomas, 16, 275 n. 9 McCormick, Peter J., 286 n. 17
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 301
Index McIntyre, Alison, 89, 155–56, 273, 281 nn. 22, 24, 26, 30 Mele, Alfred, 84, 155, 281 n. 15 Melville, Herman, 231, 234, 238, 259 “Bartleby the Scrivener: A Story of Wall Street,” 6, 149–71 Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, 253–54, 284 n. 1 Michelangelo, 134 Miller, J. Hillis, 285 n. 19 mimesis and mimeticism, 35, 270 Mirandola, Pico della, 15 Moritz, Karl Philip, 120, 121 Nancy, Jean-Luc, 6, 128, 135–36, 186, 196, 245, 286 n. 19 The Muses, 131–33, 283 nn. 20, 22 on “patency,” 137 on the plurality of sense, 132–33 Sense of the World, 187–94 narrative, narratology, 27, 79, 85, 89, 158–59 narrative time versus mythic time, 181–82 naturalistic fallacy, 23 need and desire, 29–31 New Critics (the American), 176 Neoplatonism, 5, 45, 49, 107, 141 Nietzsche, Friedrich, 27, 66, 147, 179 Human, All Too Human, 105, 222, 282 n. 4 non-identity, 33–34 nomos (rule of law-tradition), 63, 75, 96 norms, normativity, 38 Oedipus the King (Sophocles), 82–83, 95, 173–74, 178–80, 201–2, 204, 281, n. 13 Osborne, Harold, 284 n. 9 Pater, Walter, 145, 284 n. 6 Peacock,Thomas Love, 12 Peitho (goddess of persuasion), 46, 48, 61–63, 75, 279 n. 47 Pelser Birgit, 288 n. 13 peripeteia, peripity, 3, 47, 63–64, 80, 83, 93, 127 phronesis, 3, 47, 57, 63, 82, 126 Plato, 19–20, 33, 45, 68, 103–4, 110, 128, 141, 184, 282 n. 3 distinction between seeing and thinking, 128–29 Gorgias, 62 Protagoras, 101–2 Republic, 129 Sophist, (the), 258
301
on “weakness of will,” 157 poiesis versus praxis, 189–91, 193–95 polis, 40, 41, 46, 48, 50, 56, 72, 74, 79, 84, 179, 273 political action, agency (vis-à-vis the artwork), 39–40, 41 post-Enlightenment, 35, 66 postmodern aesthetics, culture, 19, 41, 129, 227–28 postmodernism and oppositionalism, 243–53, 263 poststructuralism, poststructuralist era, 44, 71, 186 presentational powers, presentational field of the artwork, 19, 71, 231, 234, 235, 244–74 protagonist-in-demos, 193, 197, 201, 209, 214 production (production paradigm), 39–40, 103, 132, 135, 140–69, 182, 191–92, 223, 263 and the artistic producer, 227–30 and the cognitive function of art, 220–22 of meaning, 185–86, 195 and recognition, 223–26 “prospective pathos,” 86–87, 91, 94 public sphere, 42, 48, 71, 74 Putnam, Hilary, 11, 275 n. 2, 276 n. 18, 286 n. 17 on “internal (or pragmatic) realism,” 30, 195 Pythagorian maxim, (the), 61 Rabinow, Paul, 26, 275 n. 13 Raphael, 134 reason, 28, 38, 175–78 and game theory/preference ordering, as it relates to narrative, 193 and sense (in Nancy), 187–90 recognition, recognitional imperative, 22–23, 26–27, 29–31, 34–39, 41, 46, 49, 52, 53–56, 58, 60–68, 72–73, 75–86, 88, 92, 102, 107, 174, 181–82, 189–91, 201, 224, 250, 255, 264 Renaissance, Renaissance humanism, 43–50 Richter, Gerhard, 238, 263 “Ema, Nude on a Staircase,” 265, 268–69 Ricoeur, Paul, 60, 67, 278 n. 18, 279 n. 39 on solicitude, 279 n. 42 Rocco, Christopher, 185–86, 188, 285 n. 1, 286 n. 6
Singer.book
9/12/03
11:22 AM
Page 302
302
Index
Romanticism, Romantic art, 29, 31–32, 43, 111, 165, 225 Rorty, Amélie O., 280, n. 2, 281 n. 14 Ross, Andrew, 275 n. 4 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 206 Said, Edward, 11, 280 n. 1 on emotional grounds for the aesthetic, 287 n. 3 Saint-Simon, Claude Henri de, 106 Saxonhous, Arlene W., 286 n. 7 Schein (appearance), 9 Schiller, Friedrich, 3, 39 Sealts, Merton M., 285 n. 20 self-justification, 22, 31, 122 self-revising subjectivity, self-revising rationality, 89–90, 94 self-transformation, 27, 31, 186, 191–92, 222, 223 Sensus Communis, 43–48, 50, 60–62, 65, 66, 69, 75, 111, 141, 226, 277 n. 5 Shaftesbury, Anthony (Lord), 15, 16, 20–22, 39, 77, 102, 140, 141, 282 n. 2 on “Je ne sais quoi,” 107 Sherman, Cindy, 238, 255–58, 260, 264, 265, 267 “Untitled #206,” 261–63 Sidney, Sir Philip, 106, 282 n. 7 Singer, Alan, 281 n. 29 Sittlichkeit, 64, 88 Smith, Adam, 107–8, 142–43 Smith, Paul, 275 n. 4 Socrates, 101–2, 104 Solon, 42 Solzhenitsyn, Alexander, 114 Sprinker, Michael, 283 n. 17 subjective agency, 16 sublime, sublimity, (subliming), 45, 52, 103, 106, 119, 131, 135, 165, 175, 225, 227, 230, 256, 269 as an obstacle to choice-making, 206 postmodern sublime, (the), 227–28, 238, 261 Romantic sublime, (the), 229, 245 and techne (tekhne), 131–33, 135–37 Sulla, 42 Surrealism, 106, 107 Sussman, Henry, 228
symbol, symbolism, 20, 211 Symbolon, 190–91 Tasten, Tastenden, 15, 17 techne, 189, 265–68, 270 Thackeray, William Makepeace, 154 Thetes, 42 tragedy, Greek tragedy, tragic knowledge, 3, 5–7, 22–23, 40, 47, 50, 60–66, 68, 69, 72–79, 84, 92–95, 174–81, 187–95, 223, 271 and the deliberative agent, 217 translation, translatability, 107, 110–28, 236 “translation as transition,” 126–27 Trauerspiel (compared with Greek tragedy), 228 Tugendthat, Ernst, 276 n. 23 Turranos, 178 Turranos-pharmakos, 178, 204, 212 Vernant, Jean-Pierre, and Vidal-Naquet, Pierre, 177–84, 188, 192, 194–95, 198–99, 218, 271, 286 n. 6 on varieties of action in Aeschylus, Sophocles, Euripides, 286–87 n. 22 Vico, Giambattista, 15, 50 on distinction between scienza and coscienza, 280 n. 4 visual image (in tension with verbal sign), 91–93, 215–16 Vita Activa-Vita Contemplativa, 49, 55–60, 66 Voltaire, 76 Warren. Samuel, 285 n. 20 Wellmer, Albrecht, 34–35, 38–39, 68, 280 n. 55 Wiggins, David, 174, 196–99, 202–7, 211, 213, 285–86 n. 2 “Universalizability, Impartiality,Truth,” 282 n. 12 Williams, Raymond 12, 275 n. 4 Williams, Robert R., 25, 27, 279 nn. 49, 53 Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 15, 175–77, 194 Wolff, Christian, 107–8 Wolin, Richard, 30 Young, Julian, 282 n. 4