Brill's Companion to Herodotus
Edited by Egbert J. Bakker, Irene J.F. de Jong and Hans van Wees
EDITED BY
EGBERT J...
357 downloads
3985 Views
111MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
Brill's Companion to Herodotus
Edited by Egbert J. Bakker, Irene J.F. de Jong and Hans van Wees
EDITED BY
EGBERT J. BARKER IRENE J.F. DE JONG HANS VAN WEES
BRILL
LEIDEN · BOSTON · KÖLN 2002
This book is printed on acid-free paper. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A C.I.P. record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN 90 04 12060 2 © Copyright 2002 by Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, The Netherlands. Koninklijke Brill NV incorporates the imprints Brill Academic Publishers, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers and VSP. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, translated, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without prior written permission from the publisher. Authorization to photocopy items for internal or personal use is granted by Brill provided that the appropriate fees are paid directly to The Copyright Clearance Center, 222 Rosewood Drive, Suite 910, Danvers, MA 01923, USA. Fees are subject to change. PRINTED IN THE NETHERLANDS
In memory of David Asheri and Heleen Sancisi
CONTENTS
List of Abbreviations
X 1
x 1 1 1
List of Contributors
x
List o f Maps Editors' Introduction Egbert J. Bakker, Irene J. F. de Jong, Hans van Wees
v
*vii
HERODOTUS AND HIS WORK 1. The M a k i n g of History: Herodotus' Histories Apodexis
3
Egbert J. Bakker 2. Herodotus and Athens John Moles
33
3. Oral Strategies in the Language of Herodotus Simon R. Slings
53
4. The Histories and W r i t i n g Wolfgang Rosier
79
HERODOTUS AND HIS WORLD 5. Epic Heritage and Mythical Patterns in Herodotus Deborah Boedeker 6. Herodotus and Tragedy Suzanne Said 7. Philosophy, Science, Politics: Herodotus and the Intellectual Trends of his T i m e Kurt A. Raqflaub
97
117
149
viii
CONTENTS
8. Religion in Herodotus Jon D. Mikahon
187
9. Popular Morality in Herodotus Nick Fisher
199
10. Women in Herodotus' Histories Josine Bloh
225
T H E HISTORIES AS N A R R A T I V E 11. Narrative Unity and Units Irene J. F. de Jong 12. '1 didn't give my own genealogy': Herodotus and the authorial persona Carolyn Dewald 13. Short Stories in Herodotus' Histories Vivienne Gray
245
267
291
T H E HISTORICAL METHOD
14. Herodotus and the Past Hans van Wees
321
15. Herodotus as a Critic: T r u t h , Fiction, Polarity Paul Cartledge and Emily Greenwood
351
16. Herodotus and his Sources of Information Simon Homblower
373
17. The Organization of T i m e in the Histories
387
Justus Cobet
CONTENTS
I*
HISTORY A N D E T H N O G R A P H Y
18. Egypt Alan B. Lloyd
4
1
5
19. Scythians Stephanie West
437
20. The Ethnography o f the Fringes Klaus Karttunen
457
21. Babylon Amélie Kulut
475
22. Archaic Greek History Robin Osborne
497
23. Greek History, c. 525 480 BC Sara Forsdyke
521
24. The Persian Invasions Viomas Hanison
551
25. The Personality of Xerxes, K i n g o f Kings Heleen Sanaa- Weerdenburg
579
Bibliography
591
General Index
629
Index o f Passages
641
ABBREVIATIONS
AcliHisl D-K FGrll Fornara IG K-A KRS L-P LSJ ML
Achaemenid History H . Dicls and W. Kranz, Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. 10th ed. (=VS) F. Jacoby, Die Fragmente der giiechischen Historiker C. W. Fornara. Archaic Times to the End of the Peloponnesian War, 2nd ed. Inscriptiones Graecae R. Kassel and C. Austin, Poetae Comici Graeci G. S. Kirk, J. E. Raven and M . Schofield, Tlie Pesocratk Philosophers, 2nd. ed. E. Lobet and D.L. Page, Poetarum Ltsbiorum Fragmenta H . G. Eiddeü, R. Scott, and H . S.Jones, A Greek-English Lexicon, 9th edition. R. Mciggs and D. Lewis, A Selection of Greek Historical Inscriptions, revised ed Supplementum Epigraphicum Graecum W. Dittenberger, Syiloge Inscriptionum Graecarum, 3rd ed. M . N . Tod, A Selection of Greek Historical Inscriptions H . Diels and W. Kranz, Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, 10th ed. (= D-K). ;
SEG Syll./SIG Tod VS
LIST OF
CONTRIBUTORS
Professor EGBERT J. BARKER, Centre d ' É t u d e s Classiques, Université de M o n t r é a l , Canada Professor JOSINE Netherlands
BLOK,
Instituut Geschiedenis, R U Utrecht,
The
Professor DEBORAH BOEDEKER, Department o f Classics, B r o w n University, Providence, United States Professor Kingdom
PAUL CARTLEDGE,
Professor JUSTUS Essen, Germany
COBET,
Clare College, Cambridge, U n i t e d
Fachbereich Geschichte, Gesamthochschule
Professor IRENE J. F. DE JONG, Klassiek Seminarium, Universiteit van Amsterdam, The Netherlands Professor CAROLYN DEWALD, Classics, University of Southern California, Los Angeles, United States Professor NICK FISHER, School of History and Archaeology, University, United Kingdom
Cardiff
Professor SARA FORSDYKE, Classical Studies, University of Michigan, A n n Arbor, United States Professor VIVIENNE GRAY, Classics and Ancient History, University o f Auckland, New Zealand D r EMILY Kingdom
GREENWOOD,
St. Catharine's College, Cambridge, United
D r THOMAS HARRISON, School of Greek, Latin and Ancient Histoiy, University of St. Andrews, United K i n g d o m
LIST OF CONTRIBUTORS
Xiv Professor Kingdom
SIMON HORNBLOWER,
Professor
KLAUS KARTTUNEN,
Professor
AMELIE KUHRT,
History, U C L , L o n d o n ,
United
Heisingin Yliopisto, Helsinki, Finland
History, U C L , London, United K i n g d o m
Professor ALAN B. LLOYD, Classics and Ancient History, University o f Wales, Swansea, United Kingdom Professor JON D . MIKALSON, Classics, University o f Virginia, Charlottesville, United States Professor
JOHN MOLES,
Classics, University o f Newcastle, U n i t e d
Kingdom Professor Kingdom
ROBIN OSBORNE,
K i n g ' s College, C a m b r i d g e , U n i t e d
Professor KURT A . RAAFLAUB, D e p a r t m e n t o f Classics, B r o w n University, Providence, United States Professor W .
ROSIER,
Institut für Klassische Philologie,
Humboldt-
Universität zu Berlin, GermanyProfessor
SUZANNE SAID, Department
o f Classics, Columbia University,
New York, United States Professor HELFEN SANCISI | , Formerly o f Instituut voor Oude Geschiedene, R U Utrecht, T h e Netherlands Professor SIMON R. SLINGS, Vakgroep Grieks en Latijn, Vrije Univcrsiteit Amsterdam, T h e Netherlands Dr
HANS VAN WEES,
Professor
History, U C L , London, United Kingdom
STEPHANIE WEST, Hertford
College, Oxford, United Kingdom
LIST O F MAPS
Egypt
416
Scythia
438
T h e world according to Herodotus
458
Babylon
476
Greece
498
T h e Persian Empire
552
EDITORS' I N T R O D U C T I O N Egbert J. Bakker, Irene J. F. de Jong, Hans van Wees
'As one must beware o f the beetle in the rosebush, so must one beware o f the slander and gossip lurking under its pleasant and gentle surface', said Plutarch o f Herodotus' Histories (On the Malice of Herodotus 43). Plutarch was not the first or the last to appreciate Herodotus' literary qualities but question his merits as a historian and ethnographer. I n a more sympathetic but no less critical spirit, this Companion to Herodotus seeks to illuminate both sides o f his work. T h e following chapters fully reflect the rich, complicated, and sometimes controversial nature o f the Histories. Sometimes they are i n disagreement with one another, testifying to Herodotus' ever enigmatic position at the beginning o f historiography, as well as to his own avowed intention not to provide easy solutions, but to let the reader choose from the alternatives he has assembled in his histonê. Often, chapters overlap, showing the extent to which many o f the issues which Herodotus raises are part o f an intricately woven network o f themes, reflecting a consistent view o f the world and its history. The opening chapters examine the nature of Herodotus' work and its place within the oral and literary traditions of the late fifth century BC. Egbert Bakker begins by addressing the questions raised by Herodotus' famous opening sentence, in particular the meaning o f the terms historié and apodexis. H e concludes that rather than referring to the publication o f the work, the term apodexis presents the work as a lasting achievement and at the same time as a potentially controversial statement. John Moles proceeds to modify the widespread idea that one purpose o f the Histories was to praise Athens. Herodotus acknowledged this city's important role when the freedom o f Greece was at stake, but he implicitly and subtly suggested that the Athenian empire o f his own day resembled the tyrannical and oriental empires o f the past, and i n doing so hoped to alert the Athenians to the dangers inherent i n their present behaviour. I n the next chapter, Simon Slings addresses the problem o f the style o f the Histories. He argues that Herodotus' language is characterized throughout by 'oral strategies', which can at times also be put to
XV111 EGBERT J. BAKKER. IRENE J. F. DE JONG, HANS VAN WEES rhetorical effect. The complementary thesis o f Wolfgang Rosier is that it was the spread o f written texts i n the second half o f the fifth century BC which inspired Herodotus to write down, at the end o f his life, all the material which he had collected. A n important sign that the Histories are directed at readers rather than listeners is Herodotus' frequent use o f the past tense when referring to his own time, thereby adopting the perspective o f future readers o f his book. The next six chapters broaden out into an investigation o f the range o f contemporary influences—literary, intellectual, religious, moral, and social—which helped shape Herodotus' work. Deborah Boedeker reviews the ways in which Herodotus' narrative is shaped by the legacy o f the epic past and by general patterns o f mythic storytelling. Such a shaping, she stresses, is never involuntary, and Herodotus is no less creating a voice for himself than he is following the story patterns from the past. Suzanne Said's contribution critically evaluates the claims made by scholars regarding the tragic nature o f the Histories. Working through the verbal echoes, literary techniques, themes, 'tragic' episodes (such as the stories o f Croesus, Polycrates, and Cypselus), and above all the account o f the battle of Salamis, she arrives at the conclusion that the differences between the Histories and tragedy are greater and more important than the similarities. K u r t Raaflaub proceeds w i t h an analysis o f the intellectual context in which the Histories were created. The Herodotus that emerges from his discussion not only participates fully in the contemporary debates on politics and science, but is also closer to Thucydides than is commonly supposed. Next, Jon Mikalson discusses the religious dimension o f the Histories, stressing the importance o f popular religion and local cult (rather than Olympian religion as presented in Panhellenic poetry) in Herodotus' dealing w i t h the divine. I n his chapter, Nick Fisher argues that Herodotus is clearly interested in exploring major moral issues, such as divine punishment for injustice, excessive revenge or overconfidence in prosperity, and the contrast between tyrannical and luxurious Eastern Empires and freedom-loving, modestly living Greeks. There is no worked-out system, however, but rather a flexible set o f interconnected themes, hints, and explanations, which are delivered in speeches, in narratorial comments, and by the thematic organization o f the material. The remarkably central role played by women in the Histories forms the subject of Josine Blok's chapter. Is their importance an echo o f historical reality or is it the result o f Herodotus' storytelling imagi-
EDITORS' INTRODUCTION
xix
nation? Both views have found their defenders. Blok offers the suggestion that it might be Herodotus' tendency to view the polls in terms o f an oikos which opened his eyes to the mutual dependence of men and women. Herodotus' much-admired skill as a storyteller is analysed i n the next three chapters. First, Irene de Jong discusses the many attempts to defend the unity o f the Histories, and suggests that the structure o f this text is best understood i n terms o f the narratological concept o f 'time': analysing 'digressions' i n terms o f analepses and prolepses helps to understand their place and function within the story as a whole. Some o f the conventional labels for the smaller units within the Histories—Exkurs, novella—arc best banned from Heroclotean scholarship. Carolyn Dewald continues the survey o f Herodotus' narrative by concentrating on the ways i n which Herodotus' authorial voice is expressed and represented; she proposes a distinction between two 'voices', dtat o f a narrator and o f a 'histo?, each with a specific function i n the text. One kind o f smaller unit within the Histories, the short story, is the subject of Vivienne Gray's contribution. She shows that these stories often display the same narrative patterns, and that, even i f the link between them and the main story is not always clear at first sight (hence the older idea o f Herodotus randomly inserting 'digressions'), there often is a connection i n the form of analogy. The second half of the volume tackles Herodotus as a researcher— historian, ethnographer, geographer, and general critic. Hans van Wees assesses Herodotus i n the role for which he is most famous, Father o f History, highlighting the ambitious scope o f his universal history and the sophistication and originality o f his treatment o f origins, the rise and fall o f empires, and the causes o f war. Emily Greenwood and Paul Cartledge then investigate Herodotus' critical methods and his remarkable self-presentation as a critic, which set him apart from most ancient historians, as well as one o f his guiding principles of interpretation, polarity. T w o key aspects o f the historical method are explored by Simon Hornblower, who discusses the nature o f Herodotus' sources and his handling o f them, long a controversial question, and by Justus Cobet, who investigates the no less vital and controversial issue o f Herodotus' interest i n , and handling of, matters of chronology. A l l these general themes are picked up again in a series o f detailed studies o f aspects o f the Histories, beginning with four chapters on
XX
EGBERT J. BARKER. IRENE J. F. DE JONG, HANS VAN WEES
the history and ethnography o f 'barbarian' peoples. Alan B. Lloyd and Stephanie West scrutinize the two major accounts o f non-Greek nations, covering Egyptians and Scythians, respectively, while Klaus Karttunen investigates Herodotus' ethnography o f the more remote parts o f the world, and Amélie K u h r t presents a particularly in-depth study o f Herodotus' account o f Babylon, a small but important part of the Histories. Each chapter explains the pattern and rationale o f Herodotus' ethnography w i t h the aid o f archaeological and other evidence which helps assess the reliability of his often sensational reports. The final four chapters turn to the history o f Greece and the Persian Wars. Robin Osborne deals with the earliest material concerning Greece, from the heroic age to the late sixth century BC, while Sara Forsdyke discusses the increasingly abundant information relating to the period from c. 525 B C to the Persian Wars, a time within living memory when Herodotus began his work. Both pay particular attention to the ways i n which the Histories shaped, and were shaped by, their sources. T h e structure, thematic significance, and historical accuracy o f the culminating account o f the Persian invasions o f Greece is analysed by Thomas Harrison, and just as the section on barbarian nations ends w i t h an especially detailed case-study, so this section concludes with a re-publication o f Heleen Sancisi's close investigation o f the main actor i n Herodotus' story of the Persian Wars, K i n g Xerxes. These last two chapters replace planned contributions by D a v i d Asheri o n the Persian Wars and by Heleen Sancisi o n the Persians. The untimely death o f these two great scholars sadly deprives us of their work, and this volume is dedicated to their memory.
* * * T h e editors wish to thank Ms Linda W o o d w a r d for her expert work on the editing o f the manuscript and M s M é l a n i e Fortin (Université de Montréal) for her help i n compiling the bibliography. Egbert Bakker gratefully acknowledges support for his part i n the project from the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council o f Canada as well as from the Institute for Advanced Study i n Princeton and the Alexander S. Onassis Public Benefit Foundation i n Athens.
H E R O D O T U S A N D HIS W O R K
CHAPTER ONE
T H E M A K I N G OF HISTORY: H E R O D O T U S ' HISTORIES APODEXIS Egbert J . Bakker
Action, in so far as it engages in founding and preserving political bodies, creates the condition for remembrance, that is; for history. Hannah Arend, The Human Condition
Most readers o f Herodotus' work call it History, or the Histories. The name is doubly motivated. N o t only does it follow Herodotus h i m self i n the way i n which he refers to his own literary and intellectual achievement; it also views Herodotus through the tradition o f which we have made h i m the 'father'. As the term kistoria (or historié as Herodotus would have pronounced it) comes closer to us on its long way from the fifth century B C E through Greek Antiquity, it becomes more and more closely associated with writing, as appears from its j o i n i n g w i t h the verbal root graph, to form such composite concepts as histonographos or historiogmphia. Such 'writing of history', however, is quite alien to Herodotus' understanding of historié. 'History' for h i m is not an object o f study, something you write, or write about; it is an intellectual tool and a communicative activity. The essential link for h i m is not with graph but w i t h another verbal idea, as appears from the most famous mention o f histonê in history, i n the Proem to Herodotus' Histories: 1
Ηροδότου Άλικα ρνησσέος Ίστορίης άπόδεξκ; η δε. ώς μήτε τα γενόμενα έξ ανθρώπων τφ χρόνω έξίτηλα γένηται, μήτε εργα μεγάλα τε καΐ θωιιαστά. τα μεν "Ελλησι, τα δέ βάρβαροισι άπο^εχθεντα, άκλεα γένηται, τά τε άλλα και δι ή ν αίτίην έπολέμησαν άλλήλοισι. * This is the apodexis of the historié of Herodotus of Halicarnassus, put forth to prevent what has been made to happen by men from fading
Translations of passages from Herodotus in this chapter are my own.
EGBERT J. BARKER
I
with time, and (to prevent) great and marvellous deeds, some accomplished by Greeks, others by barbarians, from losing fame, and in particular through what aitiê they came to war with each other. There are blanks left i n the translation: this chapter, in dealing with Herodotus' historié as the prehistory o f our notion o f 'history', does not want to take too much for granted. So we will make the meaning not only o f historié, but also o f apodexis, the object o f investigation. T h e latter term is the action noun o f the verbal idea apo-deik, which will concern us in particular. O u r main source o f information will be the evidence that Herodotus' Histories provides itself as it has come down to us through the ages. A n d the first evidence we have to face is the interpretation o f the Proem as the primary context o f historiés apodexis. Herodotus' first sentence, to begin with, seems to lack precision in the way i n which it delimits the work's subject. While Thucydides tells us exacdy that his subject is the Peloponnesian War, and that he started working on it from its very beginning, Herodotus does not tell us that the subject o f his work is the Persian Wars. What he indicates is at the same time much broader than that subject— erga megala 'great accomplishments', for example, can be understood as including 'monuments', 'architectural achievements'—and narrower: according to the wording o f the Proem, his historié will concern not so much the war itself as its ailïé, another term, usually translated as 'cause', whose interpretation is at stake. Nor does the narrative itself seem to do much to remedy the problem. Its long 'digressions' and varied subject matter have prompted various hypotheses concerning the unity and publication o f the work, each betraying i n its own way the preconceptions o f the time. The lack o f a clear focus on a well-defined subject has been explained as due to genetic factors. The work as we have it was seen as showing signs o f an intellectual development by which Herodotus passed through various stages, from the travelling geographer and ethnographer who wrote the Egyptian logos that is now our Book T w o , to the historian who left us Books Seven through Nine, and who, it was thought, had made much progress toward the Thucydidean ideal of the objective historian.' The tension between history and geog2
2
Mösl authoiitatively Jacoby (1913) 275 ff.; cf. De Saudis (1926), Powell (1939), Latte {1958} 7 ('Er hat nicht als Historiker begonnen, sondern ist es geworden');
THE MAKING OF HISTORY: HERODOTUS"
HISTORIES
ARODKXIS
raphy, between the present and the past, was resolved through the history of the work itself. This 'analytic' standpoint provoked, on the analogy o f the Homeric Question, a 'Unitarian' reaction on the part o f scholars who viewed Herodotus' work as historical ab ovo: for them, geography and ethnography are part of the overall historiographical conception of the Histories* The ensuing 'unity' was not unproblematic, and often it was necessary to depict Herodotus as somehow incapable, or, rather, 'not yet' capable of making the distinctions and decisions that are normal for historiography as we understand it, or to impose on himself the kind of limitations we associate with purposeful writing. A variant version of this idea presents us a Herodotus who is capable of those things, but who is hampered by the constraints of an 'archaic', paratactic way of expression (Immerwahr (1966) 7). I n more recent times, 'archaic style' and its associated concepts has come to be replaced b\ 'oralityV arid the supposed lack of focus in Herodotus' choice o f subject matter is seen as simply due to the fact that the intellectual context in which he wrote was 'predisciplinary', unfamiliar with the modern boundaries between geography, anthropology, and history. 3
In all these cases, the implicit question seems to be whether Herodotus was the first historian, a good or bad historian, merely a historian (want la lettre, or a historian at all. Herodotus is set against some modern notion o f 'history*, a norm to which he either conforms only in the course of his intellectual development, or not (yet) quite, in some way or another. I n part, the modern reception of Herodotus has been the search for attenuating circumstances. It is only in the most recent research that the terms 'historian' or 'history' have come to be charged with cultural weight. The Herodotus that emerges is viewed in a way that entirely suppresses any modern notion o f 'history' not without new controversy, as we shall see.
I'ornara (1971a); an analvtk: reading of Herodotus' first sentence itself is offered in Hornmel (1981).' E.g., Regenbogen (19301)): Pohlenz (1937), Immerwahr (1966), Cobet (1971), Drexler (1972). For the problem of" unity in the Histories, sec de Jong, this volume (Ch. 11). E.g.. Lang (19845; on 'oral strategies' in Herodotus, sec also Slings, this volume (Ch. 3). Evans (1991) 3, Thomas (2000'; 161 ff. Sec also the problem of Herodotus* 'reliability* as discussed by Cartledge and Greenwood in this volume (Ch. 15). 3
1
3
EGBERT J. BARKER Interpreting the Proem Any attempt to understand Herodotus' notion of 'history' must start from Herodotus' own use o f the term historié in the Proem, to which we now return. A t stake is not only the term's lexical value, but also the way it functions i n the syntax of the Proem. This rich sentence is best taken as a tripartite structure, beginning" with a phrase characterizing the work as a whole, and inscribing the name of its author in it (1), followed by two negative purpose clauses of parallel structure in which the work's intended achievements are specified (2a and b), and rounded off with an indirect question that has at first sight an unclear relation to what precedes (3). Following the analysis of T i l m a n Krischer, we can present the construction as follows: 6
1. Ηροδότου Άλικαρνησσέος Ίστορίης απόδεξις ηδε, 2. ώς
a) μήτε
b) μήτε
(α) (β) (γ) (α) (β)
τα γενόμενα έξ ανθρώπων τω χρόνω έξίτηλα γένηται, εργα μεγάλα τε και θωμαστά, τα μεν "Ελλησι, τα δέ βαρβάροισι άποδεχθέντα, (γ) άκλεα γένηται,
3. τ ά τε ά λ λ α και δί ήν α.νΐίην έπολέμησαν άλλήλοισι. Krischer has pointed out that the problematic, final colon (3) is best explained when we assume that Herodotus' proem is modelled in its syntactic articulation on a typical epic Proem. The last clause, 3 in the presentation above, reaches back to the first clause, thus com plementing it and ensuring the coherence of the Proem.' Furthermore,
6
Krischer (1965) 159 60; cf. Nagy (1990) 217, the latter analysing colon 3 as an indirect question; cf. Erbse (1956) 215, who analyses it as a relative clause (see also Lang (1987) 204); critical grammatical discussion in Drexler (1972) 3-11. A different articulation of the sentence is presented in Hommel (1981) 277 ff. Erbse (1992) 123-5 reviews the scholarship on the Proem, rightly pointing out that any attempt to see the Proem as announcing the content of the Histories is likely to cre ate confusion. Compare the proem of the Iliad, where 1. 6 έξ ού δή τα πρώτα διαστήτην έρίσαντε 'from the moment at which they slood first apart in quarrel' picks up μήνιν αειδε. θεά of the first line. See Krischer (1965) 162; Nagy (1990) 220-1 n. 34; on Homer specifically, see Bakker (1997c) 293. Krischer notes that the indication of Herodotus' 7
THE MAKING OF HISTORY: HERODOTUS"
HISTORIES
APODEXIS
7
just as i n epic, the final clause o f the proem provides the link with the beginning o f the narrative proper: it contains the word aitiën 'cause', which is picked up i n the first sentence beyond the proem in the form o f aitious 'guilty', 'responsible':" Περσέων μεν νυν ο'ι λόγιοι Φοίνικας αιτίους φασί γενέσθαι της διάφορης· (1.1.1) Now the chroniclers o f the Persians claim that the Phoenicians have been responsible for the conflict (lit: 'difference').
Beyond syntax and stylistics, the important semantic and conceptual consequence o f Krischer's analysis is that the semantic nuclei o f the first and last clause, histories apodexis and aitiën, are connected with each other: Herodotus' project is the historié o f an aitïë, whatever sense we will attribute to these terms in the final analysis. A further Homeric echo can be detected in the cola (a) and (γ) o f 2b: great deeds and their connection w i t h kleos. This important detail will concern us later on. 9
But i f the Homeric reminiscence is unmistakable, so is the paral lel with more contemporary stylistics. T h e two purpose clauses i n the middle (2a~b), with their symmetrical internal structure (isocolon) and their identical closing sounds (homoioteleuton), conform to the style that had become popular i n sophistic contemporary rhetoric, mainly due to the Sicilian orator Gorgias. Herodotus' Proem, then, displays a curious mixture o f old and new. We may ask whether this co-existence o f epic and sophistic elements is confined to stylistics or extends into thought and menta lité as well. T h e latter possibility is rejected by Krischer ((1965) 165), 10
name and the characterization of his work functionally occupies the slot of the invocation of the Muse(s) in the traditional epic proem (on the relation between iCTTOpiTi and the Muses, see pages 27-28 below). Doubts as to the epic connotations of Herodotus' syntax in Hommel (1981) 281 n. 44, who analyses (pp. 284-7) the final colon as a later addition, an editorial intervention on Herodotus' part to make the Proem reflect the new historical turn the work has taken in the course of ils development. Krischer (1965) 160, Nagy (1987) 180; cf. Latciner (1989) 15. The first epic parallel is die proem of the Iliad, in which the phrase 8iao"cn,Tnv epiaavte 'the two of them stood away from each other quarrelling' in line 6 is picked up by epi5i 'in quarrel' (8) in the beginning of the narrative. '* For a different interpretation of the Proem, and of a k i n in particular, sec van Wees, this volume (Ch. 14) p. 321. Kennedy (1963) 64-5; on the influence of sophistic rhetoric on Herodotus' style, see.Jacoby (1913) 333; Aly (1921) 286-96; general remarks in Lateiner (1989) 19. a
111
EGBERT J. BARKER who holds that the epic parallel testifies to Herodotus' acknowledging epic as a stylistic and literary model, not his continuing the Homeric tradition o f conferring kleos to the heroes o f the past. Yet the position o f Herodotus between the poetic tradition of the past and the intellectual developments o f the present is by no means clear. I n particular the meaning o f the crucial phrase histories apodexis has recently become the center o f a controversy that fully confirms Herodotus' enigmatic status. Histories apodexis is usually rendered with such expressions as 'publication o f research' or 'public exposition o f an inquiry'. I t remains to be seen, however, whether these translations are o f much help. 'Publication' is no less a culturally determined concept than is 'history' or 'research', and we may ask what i t might have meant for Herodotus' work to have been 'published' i n its original intellectual context. The notion o f publication, i n fact, becomes increasingly important i n recent research, suggesting that the o l d controversy between the analytic and the unitarian approach has never been really resolved. Exactly what is being 'published' according to this phrase: an ethnographical core or the work as we have it? A n d what does 'published' mean? Does apodexis apply to the work as a whole or to the oral delivery o f its parts? Some scholars have recendy endorsed the latter possibility, arguing that 'publication' is an anachronistic concept that does not capture the reality o f the reception o f Herodotus' 'Inquiry* by its original public. Rather, they argue, we must think o f 'prcpublication' o f 'work i n progress' in the form o f lectures. 11
12
The idea o f Herodotus presenting his work orally, for which there
" E.g., 'performance [literally, 'display'] of the enquiries' (Gould (1989) 17); 'demonstration of his research' (Lateiner (1989) 7); 'public presentation' (Nagy (1990) 217); 'exposer son enquête' (Payen (1997) 82). 'AJIÔÔEÇK;, the Ionian form for aTroSei£iç, is just as éjuôeiçiç, (ÈTciSe^tç) a nomen aclionis derived from the verbal root ÔEIK'show', 'display', 'point . In Herodotus' Ionian, another verbal root, 5UK- (for Attic 'receive , 'accept', yields in principle the same form (cf. eicöe^iv (Hdt. 7.3.3)); aorist forms of either verb are also identical: (àicjeSéÇctTo from (ànoJoeÎKVuaSai and (éç)eÔÉ^axo from (éç)ôéxouat). Some scholars (most recently Rosen (1993)) actually go so far as to view ànôôe^iç as a form of àrco-Sérouai, which would turn Herodotus into a receiver of established tradition, rather than one who expounds original, individual research. See Erbse's (199.3) reaction. Nagy (1987) 176 n. 3 speaks of a 'conflation' of the two verbs. See also the comments by Lang (1987) 203 and Nagy's 9
1
replv ((1987) 209). 12
Evans ( 1 9 9 1 ) 9 0 , 9 9 100, Thomas ( 1 9 9 2 ) 125 6; ( 1 9 9 3 ) ; ( 2 0 0 0 ) 2 5 7 - 6 0 (see
further below).
THE MAKING OF HISTORY: HERODOTUS'
HISTORIES
Ai'ODEXIS
13
is some ancient anecdotal evidence, has been entertained in particular by Rosalind Thomas, who has sought to locate Herodotus' work in the world o f early scientific, discourse as is evidenced by the mode o f presentation o f many o f the treatises i n the Hippocratic corpus. Herodotus' work, especially the Egyptian logos, she argues, displays the same agonistic and combative tone that G. E. R. Lloyd signals in the early Hippocratic writers and that must go back to sessions at which knowledge was transmitted, and contested, orally. Thomas' notion o f the publication o f Herodotean historié envisages oral presentation and reception o f ideas, while explicitly allowing for the existence o f written texts. Such a blend o f the spoken and the written is the realm o f rhetorical epideixis. According to a recent account, this term denotes 'the displaying or revealing (orally) o f what was already i n existence beforehand'—that is, the discourse written. This idea of'display' is for Thomas very close to Herodotus' apode(i)xis, which she conceives o f as the kind o f proof characteristic o f the sophistic and rhetorical milieu o f the end o f the fifth century: the emphatic assertion and demonstration o f one's own historié 'research' conducted in competition with others. One of the treatises in the Hippocratic corpus opens i n fact in a particularly suggestive way from the point o f view o f Herodotus' Proem: 14
15
16
Είσί τίνες ο'ι τέχνην πεποίηνται τό τάς τέχνας αίσχροεπείν, ώς μεν οΐονται οι τοΰτο δ ι α π ρ η σ σ ό μ ε ν ο ι , ούχ Ô εγώ λέγω, ά λ λ ' Ιστορίης οίκείης έ π ί θ ε ι ς ι ν ποιεύμενοι. ( H i p p , De arte 1) Some there are w h o have made an art o f vilifying the arts, though they consider, not that they arc accomplishing the object I mention, but that they are making a display of their o w n knowledge.
For Thomas, the parallelism between historiés. . . epideixin here and Herodotus' own histories apodexis 'provides the most vivid suggestion that Herodotus' opening sentence had contemporary connotations within the contemporary quest for knowledge. It also implies that the ideas o f proof and demonstration might rapidly imply or shade into display, and then into the display lecture. Herodotus seems then, in his very first sentence, to be using the fashionable language o f
13
E.g., Lucian, Herodotus 1 (on Herodotus performing at the Olympic Games). Cf. Pohleir/ (1937) 208, Powell (1939) 32 ff.i critical discussion in Johnson (1994). "' Thomas (1993); (2000) 249 f l ; Lloyd (1979) 86-98: see also Homblower (1987) 20. Cole (1991) 89. T r . Jones (1923) 191. 15
l(i
Μ)
EGBERT J. BARKER
the time, language which had precise connotations in a period where, increasingly, any display o f erudition and knowledge could be made in an oral presentation, an epideixis . It remains to be seen, however, whether the preverbs apo- and epi- are so easily interchangeable; but before we turn to that ques tion, we need to address an alternative modern approach, rejected by Thomas, which seeks to situate Herodotus' project, not in con temporary scientific thought, but within the perspective o f the gen eral Greek preoccupation with the past. Herodotus in this perspective, put forward by Gregory Nagy in particular, is not so much a scientist as a logios, a master of prose narrative, whose function it is, along with the aoidos, the epic poet, to confer kleos. Nagy characterizes Herodotus' work as 'the product o f conventions in an oral tradition of prose'. I n this account, apodexis is not ' p r o o f or 'display', nor a one-time event, a display lecture or epideixis, but a 'public presenta tion', a performance, a link i n a chain o f transmission starting with the events i n the past and ending with the public exposition o f Herodotus' his tone. 1 11
18
T h e Proem, in fact, invites us to pay more attention to Herodotus' interest in the past than Thomas would allow. There is a concern w i t h kleos, expressed in the two parallel negative purpose clauses, whether or not we consider that concern to be epic in mentality. The second o f those two clauses (2b, P), furthermore, contains a sec ond occurrence o f the verbal idea apo-deik. T h e crucial attribute o f the 'great and wondrous deeds o f Greeks and barbarians', whose kleos should not be lost, is that they are apodekhlhenta, which Nagy translates as 'performed'. For Nagy, there is a relation between the achievements o f the past and Herodotus' apodexis in the present: 'per forming a deed is the equivalence o f publicly displaying a deed because it is ultimately being publicly displayed by the History o f Herodotus'. Apodexis, then, according to Nagy, is the proclamation o f kleos in an ongoing oral tradition, as against the insistence on 19
20
17
Thomas (2000) 262-3; cf. (1993) 242-43. Nagy (1987) 175; (1990) 224, arguing on the basis of a parallelism of λόγιος (glossed as 'masters of speech', ibid. 223) and αοιδός. See also Hartog (1991) 285 (English tr. p. 276), referring to Havelock (1963) 53-4 η. 8. Nagy (1987) 178. Ibid.; see also Erbse (1956) 211, who stresses the parallelism of Ίστορίης άπόδεξις and έργων άπόδεςις, on which, sec further below, pages 24-28. 18
18
2 0
THE MAKING OF HISTORY: HERODOTUS'
H1ST01UES
APODEXIS
11
proof, display, and personal achievement that is inherent in Thomas' account o f the term. Herodotus could hardly have been pulled in two more different directions. Against Thomas' modern scientific Herodotus, firmly rooted i n contemporary intellectual debate, we have Nagy's conception o f a prose storyteller who subsumes the preceding epic tradition. The term apodexis is crucial for either position, but neither 'proof/display' nor 'public performance' exhausts its semantics, as we will see. In fact, both positions leave aspects o f the term unexplored that make possible a more integrative interpretation, yielding a Herodotus whose ' p r o o f i n the present, is not incompatible w i t h his rendering o f the past. Yet in spite o f the apparent difference between Thomas' and Nagy's positions there is agreement in that both take apodexis to refer to the oral delivery of Herodotus' work, and i n this they are not alone among modern authors." As we begin to understand more o f the composition, publication, reception, and transmission o f discourses i n times other than our own, to say that there is an 'oral' component to prose works o f the fifth and fourth centuries comes close to being a truism. True, for Herodotus' work in particular we can be more specific and the case for at least an oral reception is easier than in the case o f Thucydides or Xenophon. As Thomas notes herself, Herodotus' own voice is abundantly present in the form o f the grammatical first person, most often i n the ethnographical passages, but not infrequently in the narrative sections as w e l l . There is a constant concern with the marking o f the beginning and end o f sections, and on numerous occasions Herodotus refers back to what precedes, using the 'real time' temporal adverbs prolei on 'earlier' and 1
22
23
21
E.g., Gould (1989) 17; Evans (199!) 3; Hartog (1991) 285; assessment of the 'oralily' of the term in Moles (1999) sect. 8. It is worth pointing out that this whole discussion (including the controversy between Nagy and Thomas) suffers from a fundamental and persistent ambiguity in the use of the term 'oral', in that it refers both to the 'mentality' or 'conception' of a discourse ('oral' vs. 'literate') and to its mode of presentation ('oral' vs. 'written'). For discussion, see Bakker (1999a) 29-37. See, e.g., Pohlenz (1937) 208 -10; Lang (1984); Munson (1993). - Thomas (1993) 240-1; Dewald (1987) 150 as well as Ch. 12 in this volume. Thomas uses the first-person verbs as an argument against the idea of the 'oral storyteller', who she thinks is much less present in the text. Signs of speaking in Homer, however, may be less straightforward, but they are unmistakable once noticed; see Bakker (1997a). Against Thomas' and Dewald's stance with regard to the first person hi the Histories, see Svenbro (1993) 150, who approaches the first person in Herodotus and other historians as a necessary 'fiction'. 2 2
:i
Ι:·>
EGBERT J . BARKER
kusteron 'later', the same adverbs that are also used for the temporal relationships between the events recounted in the narrative. We are surely entitled to infer from these apparent attempts at monitoring the information flow that Herodotus is working hard, noticeably, to facilitate the reception of his work to a listening public. But all this is not our point. The question is whether the idea o f the oral delivery o f logoi is expressed as such by the noun apodexis. Does Herodotus refer i n the opening words o f what must be the published, ostensibly written version o f his work, to its oral delivery? Or i f that work is, as an integrated whole, meant to be orally deliv ered after all, would not a reference to its own, oral, mode o f pre sentation be redundant? I f apodexis merely refers to the medium o f presentation, why is the term present at all, and did not Herodotus simply call his work 'historic? The second occurrence o f the verbal idea apodeik- i n the proem may help us realize that there is more to apodexis than what meets the eye at first sight, and that histories apodexis is a phrase consisting o f two key terms i n Herodotus' intellectual and conceptual vocabulary. It also invites us to study Herodotus' own use o f those terms i n some detail, and to bring that internal evidence to bear on the interpretation o f the proem. A survey o f Herodotus' own use o f the nouns historie and apodexis and the verbs historeein and apodexasthai reveals that histories apodexis, far from being a mere title or a characterization o f the 'medial' aspects o f the work, is a bold, even provocative, expression stating nothing less than the communicative purpose and ambition o f Herodotus' work. W h a t it says was apparently new and not obvious, and sufficiently marked for the subsequent historiographical tradition to avoid it studiously. In the following sections, we will first deal with historie and then with apodexis; a picture will emerge i n which these terms are not only two 24
23
2,1
On beginning and end of sections, see Imrnerwahr (1966) 52 8; Dcwald (1987) 164-5. The importance of the particles μεν δή . . . δέ in this process is demonstrated in Bakker (1993). On pointing backward and ahead, see also dc Jong, this volume (Ch. 11) pp. 259-263. - ' Three times a forward cross-reference remains unfulfilled. It is to be- noted that in these cases Herodotus docs not use ϋστερον (2.101.2, referring to 2.149.1), but an explicit mention of λόγοι (1.106.2 έν έτέροισι λόγοισι, on (he fall of Nineveh; 1.184 έν τοίσι Άσσυρίοισι λόγοισι, on the Babylonian kings; 7.213 έν τοίσι οπισθε λόγοισι, on the death of the traitor Ephialtes). Are these references to parts of the work that were never written or to lectures that were never incorporated in the final redaction? Cf. Nagy (1990) 235 n. 91. See also Rosier, this volume (Ch. 4, note 17) and Cobet (Ch. 17, note 40). ''" Hornblower (1987) 8 11. But sec pages 31 32 at the end of this chapter. >:
THE MAKING OF HISTORY: HERODOTUS'
UlSl(IRIIlS
M'UDEXIS
13
constituents of a famous syntagm, but also two interrelated concepts, whose semantics, and pragmatics, blend to form a unified whole.
Historié: Interrogation and Difference The abstract noun historié as well as the; verb historeô arc etymologically related to the verbal root wid-/weid-lmoid- 'see', 'know'. This might yield the idea o f gathering knowledge through actual perception, autopsy, as the central meaning o f historié}' Such a meaning would seem to be in concordance with the idea of Herodotus the critical researcher that has recently been proposed by Thomas, as we saw. Her understanding o f historié presents us with a Herodotus who is not sifting traditions and probing the past, but investigating natural phenomena in the present, such as the nature of the mysterious Nile. " Again we may contrast Thomas' views with those of Nagy, who sees in historié an essentially juridical concept: the investigation o f the cause o f the war between Greeks and barbarians. '' This highlights the relation between historié and ailië, which, as we saw, is something the syntactic articulation of the Proem invites us to do. 1
2
2
This relation is, in fact, more significant than is commonly supposed, since Herodotus is not the only contemporary writer to present his historié in this way. We can observe that in early medical and scientific writings there is a mutual expectancy between historia and aitia. The author of the Hippocratic treatise On Ancient Medicine, for example, states that knowledge about 'nature' (phusis) is impossible without knowledge of man, and that the latter involves 'historié to know (eidenai) what man is and through what cause [di hoias aiiias) he comes to be what he is' (ch. 20). Similarly, Socrates in the Phaedo (96a) tells that in his youth he had a passion for 'natural science* [peri phuseôs historian) which he specifies as "knowing (eidenai) the causes (aitias) o f each thing'. I n the scientific treatises o f Aristotle, especially those dealing w i t h 'natural history', the connection between historia and aitia is also well attested. Apparendy, historié is ?
50
'" Sndl (1924) 59 71, Nagy (1990; 250, Dcwald (1987) 153 n. 18; Darlxj-Pcschauski (1987; 184 (-recherche sur le terrain'); Thomas (2000) 161. * Thomas (2000) 161 -7. Nagy (1990) 259-62. w
E.g., De Caelo 29862; Hist. an. !91all 12; Incessu an. 70467 11: Pad. an. 6l6a8-12: 696614 17.
EGBERT J. BARKER
14
not for Herodotus alone the search for what 'causes' the subject of investigation. The difference between the natural historians and Herodotus the historian is that for the latter aide is not a matter o f nature or the human body but of human behaviour (we recall the la genomena ex anthrëpnn of the Proem). A n d so the 'cause' of the researcher's object of study does take on the sense of 'guilt' or 'responsibility'. I n fact, the agent noun from which historié morphologically derives, histor (or istor), is used in that very semantic sphere. The term does not occur in Herodotus, but is attested in archaic poetry and inscriptions in the sense o f 'judge', 'adjudicator', or 'witness (to an oath)'. - Even though Herodotus never uses the term, his work shows, as Robert Connor ((1993) 9) has noted, 'a remarkable similarity to the way histores functioned in early Greek society'. Just as apodexis, then, historié can and has been used to push Herodotus into two almost mutually exclusive directions: the search for a guilty, 'responsible' agent in the conflict between the Greeks and the barbarians, as Nagy would have it, and the critical geography and ethnography advocated by Thomas, notably in die Egyptian logos. For the assessment o f the difference between the two positions it is relevant to observe that Thomas' account obscures the fact that the direct object of Herodotus' historié of Egypt, both grammatically and notionally, is not the land or its mysterious river, but people interrogated, informants: it is the Egyptians themselves who tell Herodotus about the wonders o f their l a n d . This is not to denythat historié in contemporary medical writing may pertain to the authority o f the researcher having seen for himself, but from this it does not follow that Herodotus' project is identical to the natural 31
5
31
" On αΐτίη in Hippocratic and other contemporary texts, see also Sauge (1992) 257 ff, who stresses, even for scientific texts, the link with αίτεΐν (δίκην) 'demand satisfaction (from an accused party)'. See further below, p. 18. Attested usage of ϊστωρ/ϊστωρ: //. 18.501, 23.486; Hes. W&D 792; Soph. E . 850; Plat. Cral. 40663: Hipp. OaÜi 2 (it is ironic that the term should be used in the Hippocratic oath i n this juridical sense). See also Nagy (1990) 250-9. In Dewald (1987) 153 if. the notion of histor is used metaphorically, as a narratological function: the authorial persona of the Histories; i f . her more recent views in Ch. 12, pp. 271 2 below. See also Cartledgc and Greenwood, this volume (Ch. 15 note 21). E.g., the investigation of the Nile: Ίστορέων αυτούς ηντινα δύναμιν εχει ό Νείλος. 2.19.3; ελεγον . . . μοι . . . ιστορέοντι, 2.113.1. CT. already Pohlen/. (1937) 44 ('die eigentliche Ίστορίη, das Verhör von Augenzeugen, von dem, was nur durch Hörensagen überliefert ist'). 3 2
:ii
THE MAKING OF HISTORY: HERODOTUS' HISTORIES APODEXIS
15
and medical science of his day, as Thomas implies; rather, we have to allow for the possibility that Herodotus borrows contemporary terminology to establish the authority of an enterprise that is entirely his own: investigating the past, and scrutinizing the traditions that give access to it, instead of receiving and accepting them wholesale. Herodotus often stresses his 'having seen', most frequenll) and conspicuously in his account of his researches of the Egyptians and the Scythians, but the proper term in his vocabulary for autopsy and observation is not historie or its cognate expressions. That concept can actually be contrasted with autopsy, as a means to gain infor mation through heanng™ "Αλλου δέ ούδενός ουδέν έδυνάμην πυθέσθαι, ά λ λ α τοσόνδε μεν ά λ λ ο επί μακρότατον έπυθύ^ην, μέχρι μεν Έλεφαντίνης πόλιυς αυτόπτης έλθών, τό δ ' άπό τούτου άκοη ήδη Ίστορέων. (2.29.1)
I have not been able to learn anything from anyone else, but this much I have further been able to gather as far as I could, having come myself as far as the city of Elephantine as an eyewitness, and beyond that point making my researches through hearing. Yet historie is not merely a matter o f listening either. I n another wellknown passage, Herodotus contrasts historie as critical listening, along with opsis 'seeing' and gnome 'opinion', to the more passive reception of accounts (logoi) as he heard them: Μέχρι μεν τούτου οψις τε έμή και γνώμη και Ίστορίη ταύτα λέγουσα έστι, τό δέ άπο τούδε Αιγυπτίους έρχομαι λόγους έρέων κατά τά πκουον; προσέσται δέ τι αύτοΐσι και της έμής ϋψιος. (2.99.1)
Up to that point my own observation as well as my judgment and my inquiiy are at the basis of what is said, but from now on I will be presenting Egyptian accounts as I heard them; still, there will be an clement of personal observation in it. Historie, then, seems to be looking through the eyes o f one's infor mants and making up for their imperfect point o f view by the power of judgment and discrimination. Needless to say, historie is the inter rogation of specially selected informants, and aims at proving or dis proving their view of the truth. The concept is therefore obviously connected with knowing, but it does not necessarily involve actual seeing as source of knowledge. For this reason, another etymology
M
On this passage, see also Sauge (1992) 252: on the next passage (2.99.1), see Cartledgc and Greenwood, this volume (Ch. 15), p. 355.
EGBERT J. BARKER
16
has recently been proposed by Edwin Floyd, who derives historic (and hislor) not from the root wid- but from the verb hizein 'to seat'. This yields the idea o f convening two or more parties and listening to what they have to say. This would certainly suit, the earliest occurrence o f hislor at Iliad 18.501, in the description o f the juridical scene on the Shield o f Achilles, where the juridical sense of'judge', 'arbiter' is particularly clear. We do not have to decide whether or not the alternative etymology is linguistically correct to see that the semantic idea behind it provides a plausible interpretation o f Herodotus' own conception of historic. The core o f the concept is not so much seeing yourself as acquiring knowledge through the interrogation o f others who have seen, and who therefore know, or claim they know. This applies to the characters in the narrative no less than to the narrator: they, too, may be interested in what is beyond perception, remote in space or time. Croesus the Lydian king, for example, 'inquired' (historeon) which of the Greek states were the most powerful, and in doing so (hisloredn) found out that the Lacedaemonians and the Athenians were dominant at the lime (1.56.1-2). A n d the Egyptian priests claimed they had secure knowledge about Menelaus' stay in Egypt through their own 'investigations' (historieisi, 2.119.3). 51
The result o f Croesus' and the Egyptian priests' investigations is self-evident and incontrovertible, as in the case o f some o f Herodotus' own researches. Concerning the question as to the real nature o f Heracles, for example, Herodotus can report that 'the results o f the investigation (ta historemend) indicate clearly (deloi sapheds) that Heracles is an old god' (2.44.5). It remains, however, that historic is not firstdegree, absolute knowledge based on perception, but relative knowledge, an approximation o f the facts o f the matter, based on a judicious assessment of the pretended first-hand knowledge of others. Sometimes Herodotus states explicitly that his inquiries have yielded only partial and limited results: 'so far as I have been able to reach in m y investigation'. A n d the logoi resulting from an investigation may be 36
!
" Floyd (1990) 161. Floyd bases his objections to the traditional etymology primarily on the rough breathing on tcrrwp, icrtopta (which is not easy to harmonize with the verbal root fi5-). As Rosen (1993) 146 n. I points out, however, the collocation of" the suffix -xcop with a reduplicated present stem i^-Etv (<*$/-.«/) is not without problems either. "' 2.34.1 en'cioov uaKpotatov ioTopEovtr/. TIV e^uceoGai; 4.192.3 oaov fuiac iatopeovtec erci uaKpoTatov oioi TE EyevoueOai eE,tKeo0at. J
THE MAKING OF HISTORY: HERODOTUS'
HISTORIES
APODEXIS
17
!/
conflicting. There may be 'différence' between them, as he informs us in his discussion o f the number o f Scythians: Π λ ή θ ο ς δε το Σ κ υ θ έ ω ν ο υ κ οίος τ ε έγενόμην ά τ ρ ε κ έ ω ς π υ θ έ σ θ α ι , ά λ λ ά διαφόρους λόγους περί τοΰ άριθμοΰ ήκουον (4.81.1)
As for the multitude of the Scythians, I have not been able to learn anything about it with precision: I heard different versions about their number. Herodotus' historié may aim, among other things, at knowledge about subjects o f scientific interest, such as the sources o f the Nile or the demography o f Scythia, but its basic material is language, logoi. A n d historié proceeds through judgment and discrimination, as an implicit dialogue between the opinions o f the researcher" and those of his informants. Historié, as Herodotus' History implicitly informs us, is always a question to which the information solicited is a response; it therefore always provides a context for whatever the interrogated informant has to say. For an illustration o f this idea, let us return to the beginning o f the narrative. W e saw already that the idea ait- (ailién, aitious, 'guilt(y)', 'responsibility/responsible') serves as conjoining device linking the Proem to the narrative and setting the latter in motion. Since the Proem explicitly links historié to the aidé o f the war, we can safely assume that historié is at work from the very start o f the narrative. Even though the investigation into the mythical 'cause' o f the conflict is a dead end for Herodotus himself, soon to be abandoned for more meaningful research, it does provide a basic insight into the semantics, indeed, pragmatics, o f historié. T o repeat the first sentence o f Herodotus' account proper, as it emanates from the Proem: Περσέων μεν ν υ ν oi λόγιοι Φοίνικας αιτίους φασι γενέσθαι της διάφορης· (1.1.1)
Now the chroniclers of the Persians claim that the Phoenicians have been responsible for the conflict (lit: 'difference'). T h e conflict between the Greeks and the Persians is reformulated as a diap/wrë, literally, a 'difference', 'variance'. We can imagine what the Persian logioi 'say' (phasiti) as a response to a question o f the
17
E.g., Devvald (1987); Connor (1993).
EGBERT J. BARKER
18
histör. ' W h o according to your national tradition arc ailioi o f the 'difference' between the Greeks and the Persians?' O r even, i n an imagined courtroom: 'The Greeks consider you guilty of the diaphore. What do you have to say in defence?' The very state o f being aiHos, in fact, is the obligation to 'respond', as in English 'responsible'. T h e verb used for demanding satisfaction from a 'responsible' party is the ctymologically connected ailed, which is used several times in the Persians' account as it is rendered in Herodotus' indirect discourse: the Colchian king sent heralds to Greece to 'demand satisfaction (aiteein dikas) for the rape o f Medea and demand back (ap-aiteein) his daughter' (1.2.3). A little later, both i n mythical time and i n Herodotus' story time, the Greeks will do exactly the same for Helen in T r o y . This mutual demanding o f satisfaction does not stop with the earliest dealings between the Greeks and the barbarians; it continues into the historic o f which Herodotus gives us here the results: the Persian logioi apparently speak in defence, claiming that i n having launched a wholesale attack on Troy the Greeks are the real ailioi tes diaphores. The end o f this imaginary 'trial' is well known. Herodotus leaves this inconclusive case for what it is and turns to the man whom he 'knows' (oida) to have started the hostilities against the Greeks (1.5.3). But meanwhile he has given togoi on the subject, and he has shown their difference. 38
The attempt to retrace the earliest aide for the 'difference' between the Greeks and the barbarians points up a case o f precisely what Herodotus' work, as presented in the Proem, claims to be able to prevent: 'things made to happen by men' (genomena ex anthröpön) that have become 'fading [or extinct] with time', tot khronöi exitela.™ Yet the very impossibility o f the recovery o f these remote events reveals an essential aspect o f Herodotus' historic:, its inherently dialogic nature. T h e search for the aitie o f human behaviour generates new human behaviour i n the form o f language: opinions that answer the histör''?, question, responding to each other, contradicting each other, either rejected or accepted by the discriminating investigator. Historie, i n other words, takes the diaphore 'difference, conflict' o f the historical
M
1.3.2 άπαιτέειν τε Έλένην και δίκας της αρπαγής αίτέειν. Cf. 2.118.3; 4.164.1; 6.114.1. On the relation between αίτιος and αίτέω in this light, see also Sauge (1992) 257 fT, who goes as far as to gloss αίτίη as 'demande de reparation' rather than 'cause'. See also Dewald (1987) 169. 3 9
THE
MAKING OF HISTORY: HERODOTUS' HISTORIES
APODEXIS
19
process to a new, semantic, level, since it creates the space for a diaphore between two or more logoi, always including the histoid own. T h e beginning o f the narrative merely puts in practice this essen tial aspect o f Herodotus' method. Later on he will explain at vari ous points. 'Let anyone to w h o m such things are credible', he says at 2.123.1, 'do what they want to do with what the Egyptians say; I myself stick to the principle that underlies all o f my account: 1 write what 1 heard being said by either party.' A n even fuller dis closure is prompted by the controversial subject of the role o f Argos in the war with Xerxes: 'Whether Xerxes sent a herald to Argos with this message', he says (7.152.1), 'and whether messengers from Argos went to Sotisa to interrogate Artoxerxes about their friend ship I cannot say with certainty (οιά. . . atrekeôs), nor do I express an opinion {gnômën . . . apophainomai) on these matters other than the one expressed by the Argives themselves'. These words are complemented a few lines later with the following declaration: w
41
Έγώ δέ οφείλω λέγειν τα λεγόμενα, πείθεσθαί γε μεν ού παντάπασιν οφείλω (καί μοι τούτο το έπος έχέτω ές π ά ν τ α τόν λόγον)· (7.152.3)
I am bound to record |lit. 'say', legem] what is being said, but I am not at all bound to believe ii and this word (epos) will hold true for the whole of my account. I n light o f these statements o f method, the phrase ta genomena ex anthröpön from the Proem acquires a new and essential meaning: 'things made to happen by men' is not limited to things done, but includes things said. Historie as conducted by Herodotus provides a forum for the works and the words o f the past. Conflict, difference, is in the nature o f the object o f Herodotus' historié, which presents itself as the search for an aillé o f a difference; but it is also the product of Herodotus' historié, in the conflicting logoi for which historié provides the context. I n investigating the causes of the conflict, the histör becomes responsible for what his project purports to investigate: he becomes aitios diaphores 'responsible for difference'. We shall see in the next sections how a study of apodexis complements this deep connection between the researcher and the characters o f the story he tells.
'"' This negative phrase is significant in light of the formula yvtounv anoSe^aoBai (rather than drcoipaiveouca); see note 47 below. " On this passage, sec Jaeoby (1913) 408-9. See also 3.3.1; 3.9.2. See also Cartledge and Greenwood, this volume (Ch. 15, p. 356).
20
EGBERT J. BARKER
Apodexis: Proof in Context In his discussion o f the size o f Egypt, Herodotus criticizes the erro neous ideas o f the Ionians. The argumentation requires h i m to use three times the verb apodeiknumi: If we want to accept what the Ionians maintain about Egypt (who hold that Egypt is only the Delta [. . .]). then wc would be proving (άποδεικνύοιμεν αν) that at some point the Egyptians did not have a country at all. (2.15.1) So if my reasoning about these matters is correct, the Ionians have false ideas about Egypt. But suppose the opinion of the Ionians is right: then I am proving (άποδείκνυμι) diat the Greeks and the Ionians them selves do not know how to count. (2.16.1) My claim that the extent of Egypt is such as I am proving in mv present discourse (άποδείκνυμι τω λόγω) is also confirmed by an oracle of Amnion about which I learned after my own opinion (της έμεωυτοΰ γνώμης) about Egypt was formed. (2.18.1) This is o f course the world o f demonstration and proof that Thomas highlights. It is, however, important to note that apodeiknumi is not merely a matter o f 'proof', but also the act o f proving something, as a response to a specific situation. I n the first two instances, this situation is given in a conditional clause in which the Ionians' opin ion is expressed, hypothetically. I n the first example, the idea that Egypt is only the Delta is shown to be invalid, since it amounts to a manifestly absurd claim. The act o f apodeiknunai is not performed for its own sake, but is invoked, as the inevitable consequence o f a false belief. Likewise, i n the second example, Herodotus' ' p r o o f that the Greeks cannot count is conditioned by a specific context. Without diat context, the act o f proving would not have taken place. Similarly, in the last passage, Herodotus' demonstration o f the size of Egypt is prompted by the Greeks' ignorance. In another geographical pas sage, the proof required by a given claim cannot take place, sup posedly due to lacking or insufficient historic 12
τον δέ Ώκεανόν λόγω μεν λέγουσι άπό ηλίου άνατολέων άρξάμενον γήν περι πάσαν ρέειν, έργω_δ_ε ουκ άποδεικνύουσι. (4.8.2) They [sc. the Greeks] say in their account that Occanus, starting from the East, is flowing all around the world, but they do not prove; this with hard fact.
'•' Thomas (2000) 176. with discussion of the passages cited. See also DarboPesehanski (1987) 161.
THE MAKING OF HISTORY: HERODOTUS'
HISTORIES
AWDEXIS
21
T h e mutual expectancy between proof and context is here a matter o f the polar contrast between logoi and ergot, which is underscored by the use o f men . . . de: proof is required and anticipated, but does not follow. The notion o f context remains equally important also when we leave the agonistic sphere o f p r o o f and opposing claims: each and every instance o f the verbal idea apo-deik- in the Histories is an act that is performed as a response to a specific situation. The shepherd, i n the story o f Cyrus' birth, who says he is ready to 'show' (apodeiknunai, 1.113.2; cf. 1.110.3) the body of the infant does so at a. specific request: he has to prove to Harpagos that the newborn prince is dead in order to avoid severe punishment; the Persians who 'show' (apodeiknunti, 1.136.1) their children do so for a specific purpose: special gifts are promised by the king for die man who has the most numerous offspring; the Egyptians who 'showed' the body of their father (2.136.2) did so as part of a well-defined transaction: as borrowers they were required by law to provide a security to the lender; the army division that was required to 'bring' (apodexaien, 8.35.2) the treasures of Delphi to Xerxes acted on specific military orders. This contextualization of the act of 'dcixis' is due to the force of the preverb; on account of its meaning 'back again' (LSJ D.4), apocan lend a supplementary contextual dimension to the basic meaning of a verb. I n the case o f verbs denoting speech, the addition of apo- turns the sensibility to context into an immediately dialogic sense: apo-logeomai 'speak in return', 'defend oneself against', apo-krinomai 'reason i n return', 'answer'. I n a recent study o f apo-plitliegma as a 'performance of wisdom', Joseph Russo has aptly formulated this as 'the sense of giving back an utterance particularly called forth by the social context operating upon the speakers'. 43
14
At this point it may be useful to change the preverb and turn for a moment to epi-deik. Herodotus' usage clearly shows that far from being synonyms, the two verbs have very specific and different meanings. When Candaules' wife says to Gyges that her husband has 'shown her naked' (erne epedexato gunmen, 1.11.5), she means the gratuitous display o f her body, uncalled for and not i n response to any
i !
E.g., djto-oiocoui 'give back what is expected'; drto-KaGiatriui 'return what is due', 'restore'; drco-Xappdvca 'receive what is one's due', 'arc-aiteco 'demand hack' (p. 18 above). " Russo (1997) 59.
EGBERT J. BARKER
22
previous request. When Croesus' servants 'show' (epedeiknusan, 1.30.1) Solon the king's vast treasuries, the unnecessary display fails to impress the king's guest and so misses its point. T h e action noun epidexis occurs once, in the sense o f 'surprising spectacle', used for the hegoat that mounted a woman in full view o f everybody (2.46.4). O n account o f the meaning o f epi- ('besides', ' i n addition to') the act o f epi-deiknunai may create a certain distance between the display and its witnesses: the spectacle is an addition to a given context, or its witnesses are external spectators o f the display. The examples o f epi-deik and apo-deik reveal a further difference, which will prove important for the meaning o f apodexis in the Proem. T h e object o f epideixis is always shown as is; it existed before it was shown or displayed and is not changed or modified by it. Zeus shows his face to Heracles (2.42.2) or Atossa her breast to Democedes (3.135.2) i n acts o f epideixis that leave the objects shown unaffected. What is 'shown' in an act denoted by apo-deik, by contrast, is always changed in the act, and may not even have existed before. The person or thing pointed at i n an act o f apodeiknunai acquires a new function according to the requirements o f the context. Apodeiknunai is 'proving' that the person or thing 'pointed at' is different from what he or she was before; thus the verb frequently means 'assign a specific function', 'appoint', and Herodotus expresses the healing o f Darius' foot by Democedes as 'he proved him to be healthy' (hugiea min eonta apedexe, 3.130.3; cf. 3.134.1). 45
The examples o f apo-deik shown thus far are all in the active voice. They display semantic features that are relevant for our purpose, but we move closer to the meaning o f apodexis i n the Proem when we turn to the instances where apo-deik is used in the middle voice. Wc will sec that the middle voice, in accordance with its basic meaning, stresses the involvement o f the subject i n the act, which yields the idea o f personal achievement as an important feature o f the semantics o f apodexis. 40
'· 1.124.3; 1.125.2; 1.127.2; 1.162.2; 3.63.2; 4.167.1: 5.25.1: 5.25.2; 5.32; 5.32; 5.64.1; 5.83.3; 5.97.3; 5.99.2; 6.57.2; 6.94.2; 6.95.1; 7.2.1; 7.3.4; 7.4.1; 7.81. Cf. Erbse (1956) 209-11. 46
THE MAKING OF HISTORY: HERODOTUS' HISTORIES
APODEXIS
23
Recording A ccomplishment T h e dialogic 'giving back' to a context, which, as we saw, is the sense o f the prcverb apo-, is central in the important Herodotean phrase apodexasthai ten gnomen which Τ will translate as 'perform/put into practice one's opinion'. This expression is used frequently by Herodotus for situations o f speech and decision-making in his nar rative. The act o f apodexasthai is not simply the expression or pre sentation o f an opinion or a belief tout court, but a constructive contribution to an evolving communicative reality. T h e gnome is pointed out not as a display for its own sake, but i n response to other gnomai or with the intention o f shaping subsequent ones. I n fact, it may be i n overt conflict with other views presented i n the particular context. For example, when all o f Cyrus' advisers suggest that the Persians await the attack o f the army o f Queen Tomyris, Croesus alone, 'finding fault' (memphomenos) with this advice, presents a view that is opposed to the opinion at hand (apedeiknuto enantien tei prokeimejiei gnomei, 1.207.1); similarly, when Mardonios has spoken i n favour oi invading Greece, no one o f the Persians present dares 'pre sent an opinion against the one at hand' {gnomen apodeiknusthai antien tei prokeimenei, 7.10.1 ) . 4/
When Herodotus' own gnome is the object o f the verb apodexasthai, the sense of conflict and difference o f opinion is equally strong: on the subject o f the importance o f the contribution o f the Athenians to the war with Xerxes, Herodotus says that he is obliged to put forth a view (gnomen apodexasthai) that will not please everybody: Έ ν θ α ΰ τ α άναγκαίη έξέργομαι γνώμην άποδέξασθαι έπίφθονον μεν προς των πλεόνων ά ν θ ρ ω π ο ι , ομως δέ, τή γέ μοι φαίνεται είναι αληθές, ούκ έπισχήσω. (7.139.1)
At this point I cannot but put forth an opinion which in fact is odi ous to the majority; still, in so far as it seems to me a matter of true fact, I will not withhold it.
17
Other examples: 1.170.1; 1.171.1; 1.207.1 (μεμφόμενος); 3.74.4; 3.81.3; 3.160.1; 4.97.2; 4.98.2; 4.137.3; 6.41.3; 6.43.3; 7.3.1; 7.6.5; 7.10.1 ίάντίην τω προκειμένη): 7.46.1; 7.99.3; 8.68α1; 8.108.2 (έναντίην); 9.58.3 (disapproval: δειλοτάτην). Notice that the supposedly synonymous phrase αποφαίνομαι την γνώμην (e.g.. 1.40: 1.207.2: 2.120.5: 3.71.1; 7.852; 7.52.1; 7.143.3; 7.152.1: 8.49.1; 9.5.2} appears to he more neutral, and does not convey the same sense of controversy and conflict (the under lined examples represent Herodotus' own opinion; see also note 40 above).
24
EGBERT J. BARKER
Without the Athenians, Greece would surely have fallen into Persian hands, despite the apodexis o frnegalaerga on the part o f the Spartans. T h e mysterious behaviour o f the Nile yields another characteris tic moment: Ei δε δει μεμψάμενον γνώμοχ τάς προκειμένας αυτόν περί των άφανέων γνώμην άποδέ ξασθαι , φράσω δ ι ' ο τι μοι δοκέει πληθύεσθαι ό Νείλος τοΰ θέρεος(2.24.1)
If I must, after criticizing the theories mentioned, put forth a view myself about things invisible, I will say what is to my mind the cause of the flooding of the Nile in the summer. Herodotus' personal gnome is here obviously part o f his historié o f a controversial topic, a matter o f scientific proof and argument, but again we observe that Herodotus' own practice is similar to that o f characters in his tale outside scientific contexts. " The apodexis of historié apparently has something in common with the apodexis o f a gnômë, with counselling" and deliberation. Both deal with difference. It has something in common also with an equally important type of behaviour i n the historical process. The verb apodeiknusthai is frequently combined, as early as the Proem, as we saw, with the standard phrase ergarnegala,yielding a formula that denotes a key concept in Herodotus' thought and w o r k . T h e use o f apodeiknusthai erga rnegala is especially frequent in Book Two, where the record o f achievement o f the Egyptians and their kings is being reviewed, but it remains common throughout the Histories.* I n the Battle o f Salamis, the Acginetans, for example, are said to have 'performed noteworthy deeds' (erga apedexanto logon axia, 8.91); and in the Battle o f Plataea 'by far the best' (aristos makrôi) on the Greek side was Aristodemos, the sole survivor o f the three hundred Spartiates who had died earlier at Thermopylae, who wanted to make up for this dishonour: desiring to die a most glorious death, he 'left the ranks in his battle rage and wrought great deeds' (lussônta te kai ekleiponla ten taxin erga apodexasthairnegala,9.71.3). 1
43
,0
1
T h e idea o f 'achievement' expressed with ergarnegalaapodexasthai is so central to the meaning ol" apo-deik that even without any object
ll!
In the two remaining instances, 2.146.1 and 8.8.3, the context is again conflict between accounts. '" On the relation between ίστορίη and γνώμη, sec also Sauge (1992) I I . See also Erbse (1956) 211. ''' On έργα μεγάλα (τε και θωμαστά), see Raubitschck (1939).
THE
MAKING OF HISTORY: HERODOTUS' HISTORIES
MODEMS
25
the verb continues to convey the idea o f personal accomplishment. In the Battle o f Plataea, for example, the allied troops o f the Persian army 'fled without accomplishing anything' (oute ti apodexamenos epheugon, 9.67). T h e nature o f the accomplishment can also be expressed with a more specific term substituted for ergo, megala: o f the remark able works o f irrigation o f Queen Semiramis o f Assyria we learn that she 'accomplished dykes all across the plain, very much worth visiting' (apedexato khomata ana to pedion eonta axiotheela, 1.184). The direct relevance o f this sense o f apo-deik for the interpretation of histories apodexis in the Proem is underscored by the fact diat all of the four other actual occurrences o f the action noun apodexis in the Histories are used to convey the sense of 'achievement' or 'accom plishment'. Croesus advises Cyrus to cross over to the territory of the Massagetae and lure Queen Tomyris' army with a sumptuous banquet, which will 'leave' to Cyrus' army the 'accomplishment of greet deeds' (leipetai apodexis eigon megaton, 1.207.7); Egyptian priests assure Herodotus that 'no record o f achievement' (oudemian ergon apodexin, 2.101.1) exists for the remaining kings from the list; the common memorial o f the Twelve Kings o f Egypt, a labyrinth situ ated a little above Lake Moeris, surpassed in cost and labour all the 'walls and public works' (teikhea le kai ergon apodexin, 2.148.2) o f the Greeks; and, finally, Mardonius' assessment o f the military situation after the defeat o f the Persian fleet at Salamis was that his Persian troops were not responsible for it, and 'anxious for achievement' (boulomenoisi sphi genoit' an apodexis, 8.101.2). In all these cases it is obvious that no accomplishment or achieve ment whatsoever precedes the apodexis. The apodexis o f great deeds is their accomplishment, their enactment, not their display or showing. Those o f the Medes and Persians who proved their virtue in the Battle o f Plataea (apedeihiunto aretas, 9.40) did not make a mere dis play, but they proved their worth in the very situation. ' Before we proceed with asking what this means for the apodexis o f Herodotus' own histarie, we have to address another question. I f the essence o f the act o f apodexis is its contcxtualization and 'situatedness', as was 1
52
Cf. 1.176.1; 7.23.3; 7.223.4. There is an instructive difference between 7.24 (Ξέρξης) έθέλων τε δύναμιν άπρδείκνυσθαι και μνημόσυνα λιπέσθαι and Thue. 6.47.1 έπιδείςαντας . . .την δύναμιν της Αθηναίων πόλεοος (cf. Tunc. 6.31.4): Xerxes wanted to prove his power by leaving a great achievement to posterity (see below), whereas the Athenians merely wanted to display their military (brce.
26
EGBERT J. BARKER
suggested above, then what is the context for the apodexis o f great deeds as we see it throughout the Histories'? We move i n the direction of an answer to this question when we consider another typically Herodotean phrase. Throughout the Histories, Herodotus imparts to the players in the historical process the desire to distinguish themselves in the eyes o f posterity, to leave signs by which their existence on earth can be remembered. The typical phrase for this is mnëmosunon (ninërnosuna) lipesthai 'to leave things (of oneself) to be remembered'. T h e mnêmosunon is usually an artifact or monument, but not necessarily so. Examples o f mnêmosuna include the waterworks o f Queen Nitocris o f Babylonia (1.185.1, 186.1), the gigantic statues erected by Sesostris in front o f the temple o f Hephaestus (2.110.1), the brick pyramid o f Asychis (2.136.3), but also the bon mot o f Dieneces the Lacedaemonian belonging to the oral tradition feeding on the Battle o f Thermopylae (7.226.2). A l l o f these examples belong to the sphere of apodexis ergon megaton. The description o f the mnêmosuna o f Queen Nitocris follows closely on that o f the achievements o f Queen Semiramis for which, as we saw, the verb apedexato is used; the description o f Asychis' pyramid is part o f a list o f the achievements o f this king, rounded off with the phrase touton men tosauta apodexasthai ('this [king], then, is said to have achieved this much', 2.136.4). T h e two phrases apodexasthai (erga megala) and mnêmosuna (lipesthai), i n fact, are very much i n each others semantic orbit. T h e latter can be the direct object o f the former (apodexasthai mnêmosuna, 'to have achieved things to be remembered', 2.101.2, said o f the Propylaia o f K i n g Moeris), and the two phrases can complement each other i n one complex expression (e.g., ethelôn te dunamin apodeiknusthai kai mnêmosuna lipesthai, 'wanting to put his power in practice and to leave achievements to be remembered', 7.24, said o f Xerxes and the canal through the Athos Peninsula). :,s
T u r n i n g now to the question as to the context o f the apodexis ergon megalôn, we notice that there is a reciprocity between on the one hand the intentions o f the Greeks and barbarians engaged i n the making o f history and on the other hand the intentions o f Herodotus himself i n making his historié. The desire to leave mnêmosuna is mirrored and answered by Herodotus' wish to record them as erga megala
;li
On uvnuoauva tanéaBou and its connection with renoôeÇaaBai, see also Drcxler (1972) 23-5.
THE MAKING OF HISTORY: HERODOTUS' HISTORlRS APODEXIS
27
apodekhlhenla. In other words, what is recorded wants to be recorded and the context i n which die deed is performed and accomplished is nothing other than posterity, more specifically, the Histories o f Herodotus. We are reminded here o f the heroic condition as presented by the Iliad, i n particular o f Hector, who speaks about the future at various moments, e.g.: 54
μη μάν άσπουδί γε και άκλειώς άπολοίμην, ά λ λ α μέγα ρέξας τι και έσσομένοισι πυθέσθαι. (//. 22.304-5)
It will certainly not be without great effort and great fame that I per ish; no, that will happen after I have accomplished a great deed, for people of the future to hear about. Hector uses a negative compound form o f the root kle(w)~ (akleios) to designate an undesirable state in the future, and he combines the root (w)reg (a morphological alternative to {w)erg i n ergon) with mega (mega rhexas): a way o f speaking that points ahead to the future o f Herodotus' Proem with its intention not to let megala erga become akleaP It looks as i f Herodotus, as the present argument progresses, is becoming more and more dependent on the Homeric conception o f heroic achievement. Yet i n spite o f the reminiscence there is an essential difference. For Hector and the epic tradition that envelops him, great deeds carry dieir own kleos, perpetuated unproblematically through epic poetry under the authority o f the Muse. I f there is a lack o f kleos i n the future, this is due to a hero's not perform ing a great deed in the present."' T o this epic scenario, Herodotus opposes the destructive force o f time, the substance that makes human achievements lose colour and lustre (the tdi klironoi exitela from the Proem). Without proper recording, any great deed, however heroic, 5/
14
Also //. 7.89-91, where he diinks of the tomb of one of his defeated oppo nents as a sign pointing to the past, Hector's glorious present; see also Cobet (Ch. 17} and Bocdeker (Ch. 5), this volume (p. 389 and p. 99, resp.), as well as Bakkcr (1997a) 165-6; (1997b) 33. On Herodotus and epic intentions, see also Erbse (1992) 122. Within Herodotus' narrative, cf. 6.109.3, 7.220.2. See also Pelliccia (1992) 74 n. 23. This happens in the Histories at 9.72.2, where Callicrates, in truly Homeric manner 'the most beautiful man in the Greek camp', died without having been able to accomplish (d7io5e£aa9ai) a great deed; ironically, he does get his kleos, in the framework of Herodotus' apodexis. On this passage, see also Nagy (1987) 178. " On E^itnXa, see Moles (1999) sect. 8, who argues that this term creates an 55
28
EGBERT J. BARKER
will lose its kleos. But recording is not a matter o f merely receiving the report from the past; it takes selection, discrimination, and research. In Herodotus' conception, historié, with its positive results and the questions which it leaves or raises, has taken over the authority o f poetic memory and the Muses.'" We can now reappreciate the seemingly unnecessary rendering, i n indirect discourse, o f the stories o f reciprocal bride-stealing that the Persian logioi adduce as the aitië o f the conflict between the Greeks and the barbarians. Such mythologizing, the domain o f myth, poetic memory, and the Muses, is unable to answer the questions that historié poses. But historié remains linked with the Muses as source and safeguard o f information. Homer, when faced with die intimidating number (plëlhus) o f the Greek leaders i n the Trojan W a r (//. 2.488), uses this moment to confess to his human shortcomings and invoke the Muses to assist h i m . When Herodotus finds himself confronting a similar problem (i.e., the number o f Scythians (Jdêtlios), 4.81.1, secpages 16-17 above), he offers us a sentence that reads as a conscious stylistic evocation o f the famous Homeric passage; but he gives us at the same time one o f his most characteristic descriptions o f historié as a matter o f 'differing logo?. T h e difference between human shortcomings and divine vision has yielded to a difference between human visions. T h e intellectual load o f discriminating between them is a heavy one, and accordingly apodexis is not only the accomplishment o f great deeds, but also their recording, which cannot fail to become a great accomplishment itself, a mega ergon, in the process.'' 1
Herodotus, Thucydides, and the Making of History The Herodotus that emerges from the foregoing discussion o f historié and apodexis is neither an oral storyteller nor an accomplished modern scientist. O r rather he is both, using the vocabulary o f the lat-
'inscriptional' atmosphere, either in its genealogical sense of 'extinct' (cf. 5.39.2), which points to funerary monuments, or in the sense of 'fading', which would contrast the durability of Herodotus' work with the transient nature of material artifacts. On the Proem as an inscription, see pages 29-32 below. See also Darbo-Peschanski (1987) 162, Boedekcr, this volume, Ch. 5, p. 100. One may wonder whether Herodotus was aware of the parallel with Tclcmaehus, who set out on a voyage to inquire after the kleos of his father (Od. 3.82), to win kleos himself in the process {Od. 1.95). 5 8 3 8
THE MAKING OF HISTORY! HERODOTUS'
HISTORIES
29
APODEXIS
ter to revolutionize the practice o f the former. Historié, the term o f choice for contemporary critical research based on autopsy, becomes in Herodotus' hands a displaced viewing, a critical examination o f the opinion o f those who have seen. Herodotus shares with the epic poet his not having been on the spot and his not having seen, but he makes up for it, even appropriating an authority that is denied to the epic poet, by adopting the intellectual stance o f the day. Historié, then, is not merely 'research', nor is apodexis merely its 'publication' or 'presentation;' apodexis, as we see it develop i n the course o f the Histories, appears to be, rather, the enactment o f an accomplishment. W i t h i n the framework o f the Histories and i n the historical reality that it evokes, historié is what makes apodexis possible, either in the form of opinions presented by historical personalities or as a matter o f accomplishment on the part o f agents in the historical process: the great achievements o f the past that become an apodexis specifically in the context o f Herodotus' History. A n d , significantly, both the opinions and the accomplishments create 'difference', in the form o f either controversy in debate or conflict i n history, o f which the diaphorë between the Greeks and the barbarians is the overarching example. But 'difference' is more than something that is represented within Herodotus' rendering o f the past; as we saw, the very process o f historié is a matter o f difference as it reveals conflicting accounts of problematic subject matter, not to mention the cases where Herodotus' own opinion is overtly controversial. T o the extent that Herodotus' historié itself leaves questions unanswered or raises problems, the final decision is deferred to the Histories' public, then and now. Anyone who reads Herodotus' work is invited to judge the achievements o f the past through the achievement of Herodotus himself, which writing has prevented from becoming 'faded with dme'. In being asked to conduct their own historié, Herodotus' future audiences make possible the apodexis o f Herodotus himself. M)
In this light we can consider a final element o f the Proem, to which too little attention has been paid: the deictic pronoun hide which modifies histories apodexis. This pronoun, as it is used in narrative, is often treated, without much overt discussion, as the cataphoric pronoun that points ahead to what follows i n the text. ' This 1 1
1,1
On 'writing', see also the contribution of Rosier (Ch. 4) to this volume. As in the common formula to introduce direct speech έλεγε τάδε 'spoke as
30
EGBERT J. BARKER
would imply dial Herodotus himself, i n the act of writing, is the deictic centre o f the Proem: 'what follows (i.e., what I have before me) is the histories apodexis o f Herodotus o f Halicarnassus', or 'the his tories apodexis o f Herodotus o f Halicarnassus is as follows'. Such a dis course-internal function o f hide, however, does not exhaust the possibilities o f this demonstrative; indeed, the cataphoric use o f hode is not even its primary function. W h e n used in interacdve discourse contexts, the proper facus o f this proximal deictic element, hode is typically discourse-external, either marking something as close to die speaker and the hearer, or referring to the discourse itself, even to the speaker himself i n the act o f uttering i t . This would mean for the Proem that the deictic centre o f histories apodexis hede is constituted by the reader, who is conceived o f as stand ing before Herodotus' monumental achievement. T h e deictic ori entation o f the prologue would then become that o f an inscription. As is known, dedicatory or funeral inscriptions can refer to them selves as lode sema or lode mnema 'this t o m b / m o n u m e n t here', locat ing themselves as close with respect to the passerby, the monument's reader.'' T h e passerby, cast by the monument's inscription i n the role o f speaker, is made the origo o f a deictic act that will be per formed as long as the monument is standing, and read. Herodotus' first words thus become an implicit version o f the sphragis o f the cor62
03
04
5
follows', e.g., 1,11.2; 1.36.2, etc.; or the cases where δδε, used predicatively, refers ahead to the content of, e.g., a γνώμη, e.g., 1.132.1; 2.17.4; 2.17, etc. Cf. KuhnerGerth (1898-1904) 1: 646.^ See also dejong, this volume (Ch. 11}, p. 259. Thus, Herodotus can present things as close to himself and his public, e.g., 1.1.1 τήνδε την θάλασσαν 'this sea', as opposed to the Red Sea mentioned just before; 2.106.4; 4.118.1 τήνδε την ήπειρον, as opposed to τη ήπείρφ τρ έτέρη (it is not necessary to take this use of the deictic as a trace of oral delivery of the work; it seems preferable to see the deictic as uttered within the deictic centre of the Greeks, regardless of a specific moment). For the link between οδε and the first grammatical person, see, e.g., δδε τοι παρ ει μι as uttered bv young Cyrus before Astyages (Hdt. 1.115.3); cf. Svenbro (1993) 33 fT. (see note 63)'and^Bakker (1999b) 10 on Hesiod's self-presentation at 7h. 24. On the future orientation of the Histories, see also Rosier (Ch. 4, this volume). For this idea, see now Moles (1999), with extensive discussion also of Thucydides 1.21-22 in this connection, and, earlier, Svenbro (1993) 149-50, focussing on the author's referring to himself in the third person as a 'monumental' way of saying. In other words, the monument is 'speaking' of itself in the third person. See Svenbro (1993) 26-34, who argues that this deictic orientation was preceded by an 'ego-centric' phase, in which the monument 'spoke' in the first person, with the transition point somewhere around the middle of the 6th cent. BCE. A simple example is the dedicatory epigram cited by Thucydides (6.54): μνήμα τόδ' ής αρχής Πεισίστρατος Ίππίου υιός I θήκεν Απόλλωνος Πυθίου έν τεμένει. 6 2
M
ω
THE MAKING OF HISTORY: HERODOTUS' HISTORIES
APODEXIS
31
pus o f Theognidean elegy, which actually cites its readers or listen ers (the difference is immaterial) in the act o f acknowledging the authenticity o f the text before them: ' A n d so will every one say: "These are the words (epe) o f Theognis o f Megara, who is named among all humans"."'*' I f Herodotus' Proem is understood along these lines, then its deic tic orientation underscores what our study of apo-deik in the Histories had already revealed: die recording of 'great monuments' (architec tural or otherwise) becomes a great monument itself, an achievement on a par with the megala erga apodekhthenta, whose kleos it intends to preserve.'' I n speaking o f apodexis hede, then, Herodotus appears to be no less oriented toward the future o f his work than is Thucydides, who famously characterizes his own work as a kiema es aei 'a pos session for all time'. T h e understanding o f apodexis that I have proposed in the pre ceding pages, i n fact, may shed light on Thucydides' supposed ref erence to Herodotus. The focus of interest is the phrase i n which Thucydides describes the kind o f ephemeral public utterance to which he pretends to oppose his own durable creation: agonisma es to parakhrema akouein 'a performance to be listened to i n the immediate present' (1.22.4). T h e phrase presumably conveys the idea o f the intention to please an immediate, contemporary, audience. Agonisma is usually taken as 'declamation' or as 'competitively presented lecture', but a recent survey o f the earliest occurrences o f the term in fifth-century texts goes i n a slightly different direction. According to W i l l i a m Johnson, agonisma means 'the accomplishment of a notable act' with a focus 'not so much on the intrinsic value o f the achievement as (on) the popular favour that it brings'. '' Under such an understanding, 7
y
68
1
b
1
" Theogn. 22--3 (cf. 20: τοΐσδ* επεσιν). On Herodotus future-oriented stance, see also Connor (1987) 258, Lateiner (1989) 5n8 as well as Raaflauh, this volume (Ch. 7). For the opposite view that Herodotus is not interested in reaching beyond his immediate audience (Thucydides' supposed hint at 1.22.4, but see below), see, e.g., Fornara {1971a) 60. Moles (1999) section 4 discusses κτήμα as 'monument'. The future orientation of Thucydides' undertaking is also apparent in the aorist verb (Θουκυδίδης) ςυνέγραψεν, which occurs in the Proem as well as in the recurrent formula for the end of a year (Th. 2.103.2, etc.): the verb '(Thucydides) has written' implies the time of a reader in the future, see Bakker (1997d) 30. '•'''Johnson (1994) 232-8; citation p. 233. Johnson notes that in Thucydides the term αγώνισμα usually means the glory that results from a notable achievement; the term is used (7.56.2) to represent the Syracusans' own characterization of their victory over the Athenians. 1
EGBERT J. BAKRER the term begins to resonate with respect to Herodotus' apodexis, and may even be meant to supplant it consciously: the choice o f agonisma would subtly present Herodotus' work as a mere achievement in the present, devoid, unlike Thucydides' own work, o f lasting importance for the future. However that may be, and whether or not Thucydides' choice o f words betrays an indirect challenge to the monumental aspirations of Herodotus' work as a competitor for the favour o f future audiences, an essential difference between the two remains. Where Thucydides sees his work, polished and authoritative, as a standard for analysing the events o f the future, which will always be comparable given the constancy o f human nature (kala to anthropinon, 1.22.4), Herodotus, more involved i n the actual process o f historie and intent on showing it in practice, asks his future audiences to be more involved as well. Far from pleasing the c r o w d in an immediate present, Herodotus' apodexis^ as we have seen, does not shun controversy, and looks ahead to the audience o f the future. In reading the inscription on his monument, we not only become, implicitly, speakers who acknowledge Herodotus' achievement; we are also are cast in Herodotus' own role. Standing not before the publication or presentation o f the Inquiry, but before the Inquiry itself, its enactment, we are asked to do what Herodotus did himself: to listen critically, to question, and to judge. We are also asked to do what Herodotus did with the monuments and megala erga he encountered: to record. T h e present volume is among the many proofs that Herodotus achieved what he aspired to.
CHAPTER T W O
HERODOTUS AND ATHENS' John Moles
Most older scholarship considered Herodotus an admirer both o f Persian-war and contemporary Athens.- This view had diverse props: Herodotus' presence in Athens i n the 440s and perhaps later; an ancient tradition that he was a supporter, even flatterer, o f Athens, which allegedly paid h i m ; his knowledge of the city, its history (hypothetically largely Alcmaeonid-derived and Alcmaeonid and 'Peridean' in sympathy) and its political terminology and gossip; his supposed membership of 'Pericles' intellectual circle'; Pericles' alleged Panhellenic appeal; and Herodotus' praises of Athens. Strasburger and others attacked some of these props, whose quality certainly varies. But die question involves all the problems of interpreting Herodotus. 3
4
Modern critics seek to interpret texts rather than uncover their writers' beliefs. Notwithstanding theories of 'constructed' or 'implied' authors, Herodotus problematizes the distinction. His is the 'voice' of the text:-' he repeatedly obtrudes his own person/' The uncertainties o f Herodotus' work multiply the problems. His final production was
1
Jacoby (1913) 226-42; Wells (1923) 151-61: Kleinknecht (1940); Strasburger (1955); Harvey (1966); Lcgrand (1966) 104-13: Fornara (1971a) 37 58. 75 91; Gillis (1979) 1 -13, 45 58; Hart (1982) 168 74; Evans (1979b); (1991) 92-4; Forrest (1984); RaaHaub (1987); Ostwald (1991): Stadter (1992); Derow (1995); Moles (1996); Romm (1998) 52 5, 185-90. Meyer (1899) 198; Jacoby (1913) 240, 357-60: Sclunid and Staehlin (1959(1934)) r 2: 580; Pohlcnz (1937) 185: Powell (1939) 81, 88; Myres (1953) 12; Ehrenberg (1954) 137; dissentient older scholarship: How and Wells (1928) I : 7 8. 447-8; Focke (1927) 27-8. '.Jacoby (1913) 226 42; How and Wells (1928) I : 6 7, 41-3; Myres (1953) 10 13; Legrand (1966) 29-37: Evans (1979b); Gould (1989) 14 18; Pod'lecki (1977 (Herodotus never in Athens)) is untenable. Strasburger (1955); Koruara (1971a) 37 58; Forrest (1984): Raaflaub (1987): Thomas (1989); Ostwald (1991); Stadter (1992); Derow (1995): Moles il996); contra Harvey (1966); Evans (1979b). ' Svenbro (1993) 150; Moles (1999). " Marincola (1987) 122 n. 5, 137; Dewald (1987); and Ch. 12 in this volume. 2
1
r
JOHN MOLES
34 7
8
a unified text, designed primarily for reading. But, as with Thucydides, the Kompositions-Fragfi disturbs. Herodotus gave oral performances and readings in different places; his sources were predominantly oral. H o w organic is this text? H o w 'oral' in outlook and style is his writing? H o w independent is he? Does he ever fabricate? Most crucially, does Herodotus' narrative reflect implicitly on political developments from 479/8 to contemporary times? The text's dating is itself controversial;' some datings invoke alleged contemporary allusion. Such allusion is not theoretically excluded: commemoration can allow contemporary application. Explicit allusions to events from 478 to the early 20s indicate no 'generic' ban on post-478 events. Positive arguments or criteria canvassed include: " the influence o f contemporary events on Herodotus' becoming a 'historian'; his conception o f the Persian Wars to the present as a continuous period;" need to appeal to contemporaries; devices that put audience/readership 'within the t e x t " (text as journey; metaliterary elements; 'tragic' narratives; 'internal audiences'); recurrent patterns that logically should include contemporary audience(s)/reacters; the sense that the text 10
!l
12
3
14
13
1
8
7
How and Wells (1928) 1: 15 16: Focke (1927): Regenbogen (1930b); Bornitz (1968); Cobet (1971); Lateiner (1989) 4-5; cf. also note 9 and Ch. 11 in this volume. Florv (1980); Moles (1999): and Ch. 4 in this volume. Jacobv (1913): How and Wells (1928) 1: 9-45, 447-8; von Fritz (1936); Pohlenz (1937); Powell (1939): Mvres (1953) 20 31; Lattimore (1958); Kornara (1971a) 1 23; 75-91; Marincola (1999). "-' How and Wells (1928) 1: 6; Thuc. 1.22.4; Moles (1999); and see Ch. 1 in this volume. For this question, see Ch. 3 of this volume. Meyer (1899) 196-8; Fornara (1971a) 40 7, 60-74, 79 91; (1981) 152 3, 6; Redfield (1985) 115; Konstan (1987) 72; Lateiner (1987) .100; (1989) 47-8; Stadter (1992) : Moles (1996) n. 99: contra de Stc. Croix (1973); Gould (1989) 1 16-20; Pritchett (1993) 328-53; van der Veen (1996) 71 n. 180, 91, 105 n. 266. Jacoby (1913) 229-32; How and WelLs (1928) 1: 9, 448; Legrand (1966) 18-23; Fornara (1971a) 43 n. 13; (1971b); (1981): Cobet (1977); Smart (1977) 251-2; Evans (1979a): (1981); (1982): (1987); (1991) 89-90: Florv (1980) 23 6; MacDowell (1983) 151; Sansone (1985); Raaflaub (1987) 236 n. 40; Gould (1989) 18; Moles (1996) 280 n. 9; Pelling (2000) 154-5; both c. 426 and c. 415 have arguments (post-404 (Smart) is untenable). Städter (1992) 782 n. 2; Moles (1996) 277; pace Gould (1989) 116-20. Schmid and Staehlin (1934 (1959)) I 2 590 n. 9; Fornara (1971a) 32-4; (1981) 149-51. Raaflaub (1987); Städter (1992): Moles (1996). " 6.98.1 3; Pohlenz (1937) 175 6: Fornara (1971a) 82 n. 10; Städter (1992) 788-91: Moles (1996) 276. Lateiner (1989) 30-3. 11 !l
M
12
13
H
15
16
18
HERODOTUS AND ATHENS
35
variously anticipates the future; contemporary political vocabulary, slogans, debates, and national stereotypes; parallels and contrasts with contemporary events; temporal and spatial narrative dislocations; validation o f implicit allusion by culminating explicit allusion; cumulative force o f all these criteria. But implicit allusion requires both demonstration (through such criteria's practical implementation) and explanation o f function. This survey considers sections individually before comparing others, and, where isolated contemporary allusions are merely possible, it uses the verb 'might' (admitting 'might not'); but it also takes the sections sequentially, to allow the possibilities o f organic interaction, consistent contemporary implication and coherent interpretation.
Croesus and Solon
19
(I.5-33)
I n response to the prefatory question, 'for what cause (aide) Greeks and barbarians went to war against each other', Herodotus 'signals' 'the man w h o m I myself know to have "first-begun" (huparxanta) unjust deeds towards the Greeks': causality involves moral j u d g ments. Then, ' I shall advance forwards in the account, going through small and great cities o f men alike. For those that were anciently great, the majority of them have become small, and those that were great in my time, were previously small' (1.5.3-4); this timeless concern with political rise and fall encourages perception o f historical parallels, as well as suggesting a Panhellenic readership.' ' The man 'signalled' is 'Croesus, Lydian by race, son o f Alyattes, turannos o f the tribes this side o f the Halys, . . . the first o f the barbarians w h o m we know to have subjugated some o f the Greeks to payment o f tribute but to have befriended others. He subjugated the Ionians and Aeolians and the Dorians in Asia but befriended the Spartans; for before Croesus' "first-rule" (arkh.es), all the Greeks were free' (1.6). The struggle between freedom and tyranny/slavery is foregrounded, the former (seemingly) quintessentially Greek, the latter barbarian; 20
2
Städter (1992) 795-8; Moles (1996); Pelling (1997b). Temporally crucial: Moles (1996) 278-9 arid Ch. 3 in this volume. - Cf. e.g., 4.99, 7.139; Momiglia.no (1978) 6 0 - 1 ; Flory (1980); Raaflaub (1987) 235; Städter (1992) 783 and n. 6. 2 0
1
JOHN MOLES
36
and arkhe seems intrinsically unjust, cf. the interaction between huparxanta and arkfies.-' Does this paradigm evoke the tribute-defined descendant of Croesus' empire, the contemporary 'tyrant city', Athens?' Herodotus' description of Alyattes' annual operations against Miletus (1.17.1—3), a sea power invulnerable to siege, might recall Spartan invasions of Attica.The summary of the peoples 'subjugated' by Croesus (1.28.3) includes 'the Lydians': Croesus' tyranny is also 'internal'. Now, 'there arrive in Sardis, at the peak of her wealth, all the sophistai there happened to be at this time . . . and above all Solon, an Athenian' (1.29). This setting involves both spatial and temporal dislocations. Corrupt Greek 'sophists' Hock east, to the capital that subjugates Greeks. Their numbers are vastly exaggerated. They are ambiguously associated with the incorruptible Solon, who represents (among much else) Herodotus himself, Odyssean wanderer, sightseer, visitor to Egypt, and Solonian moralist. This anachronistic encounter is fabricated after Odysseus and the Phaeacians' ' and dramatizes the arrival of Herodotus and numerous sophists in Athens, self-proclaimed imperial and cultural capital of Greece. 1
1
2
Since Solon's teaching is universal and its conclusion, 'you must look to the end o f everything, to see how it will turn out' (1.32.9), is echoed by Herodotus (1.33), Athens comes within the frame. But more: Solon is Athenian; likewise 'the most blessed o f humans', Tellos; 'Croesus' is an Athenian (Alcmaeonid) name; Solon's/Herodotus' denial of the possibility o f total self-sufficiency, whether of individual or land (1.32.8), rebuts Athenian claims (made e.g., i n the Epitaphios, including Pericles').' ' Croesus himself, arch-imperialist, treasurer, possessor o f an Alcmaeonid name, king and tyrant, evokes Pericles, 'monarch' or 'tyrant', ' of Athens. I f Solon met Croesus, Herodotus met Pericles and judged him deluded. I n this programmatic episode Herodotus warns the Athenians at their peak, his attitude to their empire radically negative. " 21
2
2
» For the play. cf. 8.142.2; Raaflaub (1987) 241-2. - 3.89-97; 6.42; Thuc. 1.121.5; 122.2; 124.3; 2.8; 71.3; 3.63.3; Rcdlicld (1985) 115; Raaflaub (1987) 224; Stadler (1992); Derow (1995) 45-6. Herodotus and the Archidamian War: Fornara (1971a) 75-91: (1981). Od. 7.134-13.87. Name: Moles (1996) 266: self-sufficiency: Thuc. 2.36.3: 41.1; Raaflaub (1987; 236 n. 40; Scanlon (1994) 145-56: Moles (1996) 267-9. 'Monarch': Thuc. 2.65.9; 'tyrant': Plu. Per. 3.5. For a different view, see Ch. 14, pp. 342- 3 and note 45. !
25
2 b
27
28
37
HERODOTUS AND ATHENS Peisistratus' 'Tyranny (1.5 6 64j"-
Herodotus' history o f mainland Greece begins by comparing Athens and Sparta. Seeking allies. Croesus 'inquires' who are die most powerful Greeks; Croesus' playing the historian invests his findings with Herodotus' own 'author-ity' and brings the past closer. Anachronistically, Croesus 'finds' the most powerful to be the Lacedaemonians and Athenians (1.56), leaders respectively o f the Dorians and Ionians, the former originally Greek and 'much-wandering', the latter Pelasgian, indigenous and non-Greek. Athens, under Peisistratus' tyranny, is militarily ineffective; Sparta, once worst governed of the Greeks, having obtained Lycurgan eimomia, is militarily strong. This reconstruction contrasts with the Epitaphios tradition (which Herodotus knew),' whereby the Athenians were always Greek, militarily superior to the Spartans and victorious over foreigners, having enjoyed democratic government since Theseus (the Peisistradd tyranny being a brief intermission), and must have surprised contemporaries. 10
51
T h e Peisistratus narrative utilizes standard motifs: triadic patterns (Onion's three warnings to Peisistratus' lather; the three rivals, o f whom the youngest and seemingly weakest triumphs; Peisistratus' three coups); the trickster-figure whose deceptions include a beautiful woman; and contests between intelligence and stupidity. Details underscore Herodotus' typology o f tyranny: perversion o f nature - (the 'rending' o f the body politic, the 'rooting' o f the tyranny, the omen of Peisistratus' birth, the woman's name, Phuc ('growth'), Peisistratus' 'unlawful' intercourse); deception; popular gullibility; acquisition o f a bodyguard; general military inactivity; co-operation with fellow tyrants. 5
33
These stock elements do not so much indicate poverty o f information about sixth-century Athens (there arc some hard facts, while others Herodotus deploys elsewhere) as reinforce the political analysis. Nor does the account, doubtless partly Alcmaeonid derived, evince Alcmaeonid bias: Peisistratus' tyranny is not represented, apologetically, as irresistible, nor Megacles' co-operation with Peisistratus' second coup concealed. The Peisistratus narrative subverts the Athenians'
Gray (1997), bettering Uvelle (1993) 87-106: and see Ch. 23 in this volume. * Naturally, Croesus muundenkmds his 'findings'. On Croesus" fustorie, see also Ch. 1 in this volume. 7.161.3; 9.27. "» Vernant (1982): Ogden (1997). Name-plays: Harrison (1998) n. 145. :;}
: a
JOHN MOLES
38
self-image: Peisistratus' and Megaclcs' trick with Phue was 'far the most simple-minded ever since the Greeks were judged cleverer than barbarians', and this 'against the Athenians . . . said to be first o f the Greeks i n cleverness'. Throughout, Athenian credulity and inability to read signs contrast, implicitly, with Spartan cleverness. I f the History is post-425 Peisistratus' purification o f Delos (1.64) might evoke the Athenian purification o f 4 2 6 / 5 , itself modelled on Peisistratus', the culminating contemporary allusion validating general 'contemporary' interpretation. Certainly, contemporary preconceptions are systematically challenged. 34
35
Hie Peisutratids' expulsion
(5.55-78)*
3
Herodotus agrees w i t h Thucydides ' that Athens was not liberated by Harmodius and Aristogeiton but by Spartan intervention orchestrated by the Alcmaeonids, who bribed the Pythia to tell the Spartans to liberate Athens. Nevertheless, the liberation is unequivocally good (5.62.1; 66.1) and causes an increase i n Athenian greatness (5.66.1, 78.1). Yet Herodotus' account o f Cleisthenes, 'founder o f Athenian democracy', is unenamoured. Reputedly the briber o f the Pythia, Cleisthenes essayed reform only because, worsted i n 'dynastic' struggle, he took the people into his 'party'. Moreover (5.67.1; 69.1), his reforms imitated his grandfather and namesake, the Sicyonian tyrant. As in the accounts o f Peisistratus and Solon and Croesus, Alcmaeonid connections with tyranny are clear. A t Isagoras' appeal, Cleomenes demands the expulsion o f 'the Accursed', the Alcmaeonids and their allies who sacrilegiously killed Cylon, would-be tyrant before Peisistratus. Contemporaries might recall similar Spartan demands before the Peloponnesian War. 38
After Cleomenes' repulse, Herodotus enumerates the various Spartan invasions o f Attica (5.76); readers might recall contemporary invasions. T h e continuous Athenian successes inspire Herodotus' celebration of'equality o f speech' (isegorie) (5.78): 'So the Athenians had
M
Homblowcr (1991) 519. Parallels between Peisistratid and Periclean Athens: Plu. Per. 7.1, 16.1. Strasburger (1955) 7-15, 18-19; Thomas (1989) 242-51, 261-82; Asheri (1997) 165-6. 1.20.2; 6.53 9. • Strasburger (1955) 15; Fornara (1971a) 54-5. 3 i
3,1
i;
5!!
HERODOTUS AND ATHENS
39
grown. Equality o f speech shows not in one thing only but everywhere that it is a worthwhile thing, i f the Athenians too when tyrannized were better in matters of war than none of those who lived around them, but when they were freed of tyrants became far the first. These things show that when repressed they deliberately behaved basely, as working for a. master, but when they were freed each himself wished to work for himself.' This passage praises 'equality', exemplified by Athens, but does not privilege Athenian democracy among forms of 'equality'. ' As in the Peisistratus narrative, the links between internal political freedom and external power and between internal tyranny and external weakness are emphasized. After discovering Alcmaeonid impiety, the Spartans feel that they have suffered doubly—having exiled their friends without securing Athenian gratitude, and they are disturbed by prophecies of many misfortunes from the Athenians; also, 'they saw the Athenians growing and not at all ready to obey them, considering that i f the Attic race were free it would become of equal weight to their own, but i f held down by tyranny weak and ready to obey their rule' (5.91). The consistent political analysis now includes Spartan-Athenian rivalry. T h e Spartans decide to reinstate Hippias w i t h allied support. O n l y So(si)cles o f Corinth voices disapproval, in the History's longest single speech, evidently strategically placed. He argues that promotion of tyranny would overturn previous Spartan policy and experience; Corinth had actually experienced tyranny. This account contains standard items of tyrannical typology: political repression, reversal of nature, physical abnormality and sexual misdemeanour; and an oracular comparison of Cypselus to a ravening lion. The otherwise unrecorded So(si)cles 'saves' the 'good fame' both o f himself and Sparta, upholding 'equality of speech' and 'equal governments' against tyranny. T h e n Hippias, understanding the prophecies best, swears that one day the Corinthians above all will long for the Peisistratids. But the allies agree with So(si)cles and deter Sparta from further intervention (5.92-93). 3 1
40
T h e prophecies anticipate future events. Uncomfortable ironies accrue: had the Spartans been allowed to reinstate Athenian tyranny,
n
Jacoby (1913) 357; How and Wells (1928) 2: 44; Strasburger (1955) 10; Fornara (1971a) 48 50; Romm (1998) 185-7; cf. 5.97.2 and 3.80; van der Veen (1996) 90 ft". * Strasburger (1955) 7 15, 18 19; Stahl (1983); Raaflaub (1987) 223-4; Gray (1996): van der Veen (1996) 68-89; and see Ch. 23 in this volume.
JOHN MOLES
40
they would have avoided the injustices inflicted on them by a free Athens; by behaving justly, the Corinthians incur, long-term, Athenian injustice. Readers might contrast the Peloponnesian conferences before the Peloponnesian War, when pre-eminently Corinth, advocated war against a tyrannical Athens. Certainly, Herodotus implies a paradox: a free Athens herself inflicted tyranny upon other Greek states. Further, these anticipations invest So(si)cles' admonition (5.92a2 ' i f you had experience of it like us, you would be able to make better decisions about it') with metaliterary force, '- itself conducive to contemporary allusion. 11
4
The Alcmaeonids and Pericles (6.121—131)** Herodotus defends the Alcmaeonids against the accusation of raising a shield to the Persians: the Alcmaeonids were pre-eminent tyranthaters, i n exile throughout the tyranny ' and orchestrators o f the Peisistratids' fall, i f i t was they who persuaded the Pythia to tell the Spartans to free Athens (thus Herodotus' previous account). Their high repute rules out their having had a grudge against the people. A shield was raised, but as to who raised i t , Herodotus 'can say nothing further than these things' (6.121-4). T h e allusion to the Alcmaeonids' high repute segues (125.1) into an account o f their history which proves their fame. 4 1
Herodotus' claim that the Alcmaeonids were always 'tyrant-haters' conflicts with his earlier account where Megaclcs co-operated w i t h Peisistratus for a period (1.60-1). Is this conflict trivial? Is the earlier account forgotten? T h e claim also conflicts with the Alcmaeonid aspects o f Croesus (1.29 IT.) and Cleisthenes' imitation o f Cleisthenes of Sicyon (5.67, 69). Are these 'oral' inconsistencies? Is Herodotus' defence just rhetorical? T h e account o f Alcmaeonid history has been variously interpreted, as: 'diversionary' after a thin defence; " favourable 1
" Thue. 1.68-71; 119-24. Stacker (1992) 782. How and Wells (1928) 2: 115: Strasburger (1955) 15- 18; Fornara (1971a) 5 3 6; Gillis (1.979) 1.-13, 45-58; Hart (1982) !-16;Develin (1985); Thomas (1989) 247-51, 261 82; and see Ch. 23 in this volume. " Alcmaeonid pleas: Isocrates 16. Gillis (1979) 51. ,|;)
4 5
HERODOTUS AND ATHENS 40
41
4
lo the Alcmaeonids; unfavourable; ' the allusion to Pericles, the only explicit allusion in Herodotus, as: ad hoc, integral, neutral, honorific, ambiguous, and hostile. The first item, Alcmaeon's assistance to Croesus' envoys at Delphi, recalls Alcmaeonid use o f Delphi in their campaign to free Athens, but what of their association with Croesus, in the Solon-Croesus narrative 'tyrant' and 'subjugator' of Greeks? Does the story of Alcmaeon's exploitation of Croesus' generosity (whence Alcmaeonid wealth) recall Greek corruption at 1.29? The family was further elevated by 'the Sicyonian tyrant'. T h e two most favoured suitors o f Cieisthenes' daughter are Athenians: Megacles, son of Alcmaeon, and Hippoclidcs, the latter through his ancestral relationship with the Cypselids. Mention of Megacles makes it harder to forget Herodotus' account of Peisistratus. After Hippoclides dances away his chances, Cieisthenes chooses Megacles: 'in this way the Alcmaeonids became talked about throughout Greece. From their marriage was born the Cieisthenes who established the tribes and democracy for the Athenians, having the name o f his maternal grandfather the Sicyonian. T o Megacles was born also Hippocrates and from Hippocrates another Megacles and another Agariste, having the name of Agariste daughter of Cieisthenes, who married Xanthippus the son of Ariphron and when she was pregnant saw a vision in her sleep: she thought that she had borne a lion. A n d after a few clays she bore Xanthippus Pericles' (131.1-2). Alcmaeonid 'fame' climaxes in Pericles ('far-famed'), " but portents demand interpretation. 18
4
The account explicitly links the 'tyrant-hating' Alcmaeonids with tyrants, which renders implicit links plausible. Even as a royal symb o l the lion i l l befits the Alcmaeonids qua pluralist democrats. But the oracle concerning Cypselus (5.92) also has 'bear a lion'; in the account's general intermixing of Alcmaeonids and tyrants 'Cypselids' are mentioned; images o f unnaturalism suit tyrants; and in political 50
s
\Jacoby (1913) 238, 612. Strasburgcr (1955) 17; Thomas (1989) 271. Implicit allusions: e.g., 1.173.5 with Evans (1991) 93 4; 3.82.4 with Raadaub (1987) 244 n. 58; Homblower (1991) 346; 7.162.1 with Fornara (1971a) 83-4, pace Gould (1989) 118; also Polycrates: Raatlaub (1987) 244 n. 58. Forrest's 'Pericles was not an Alcmaeonid' ((1984) 4) is technically correct but contextually obtuse. How and Wells (1928) 2: 119. 17
4 8
1,9
w
JOHN MOLES
42
debate i n Attic comedy the lion can symbolize the tyrant: as i n the Solon-Croesus narrative, Pericles is a tyrant, Herodotus' account conveys the Alcmaeonids' long co-operation w i t h tyrants, both Greek and barbarian, to present times. This threatens the defence. T h e Alcmaeonids' role i n Hippias' deposition is unaffected, but the specific accusation is strengthened. Either defence and account are inconsistent, or the account undermines the defence, which emerges as ironic.'' Since the account is adroitly contextualized and its negative implications reinforced by interaction with earlier sections, aesthetics support the second interpretation. Hence the defence's closing ambiguity: ' I cannot say anything further than these things'; though 'these things' seemingly looks back, it also signposts the material undermining the defence. Herodotus subtly subverts the Alcmaeonids' anti-tyrant credentials. 11
2
33
Praises of Alliens** Three strategically placed passages praise Athens: (a) 7.138—9: the Persian campaign was against all Greece. Some Greeks medized, some refused. T h e Persians had to be opposed at sea. Whichever side Athens joined would have won. Athens saved Greece, because she chose freedom, energised resistance and w i t h stood the invaders, despite frightening Delphic oracles. This j u d g ment is the more emphatic for its acknowledged unpopularity and iconoclasm;" historically penetrating; and (like the other passages) strongly Panne Hen ist. W o u l d the contemporary readership contrast the present-day tyrant-city? (b) 8.2—3: the Spartan Eurybiades became overall commander, since the allies refused Athenian leadership. The Athenians conceded, 'correctly realizing that, i f they had strife about leadership, Greece would be destroyed; for national strife is worse than concordant war to the same degree as war is worse than peace . . . and so long as they had strong need o f them, they continued to yield. For when
51
Strasburger (1955) 17: Thomas (1989) 271. Hart (1982) 12. De so used: Denniston (1954) 170. + Kleinknecht (1940); Fornara (1971a) 46-7, 85-6; Hart (1982) 169-72; Demand (1987); Marincola (1996) 591 n. 28, 597 n. 50. '"' See Ch. 1, p. 12 on Herodotus' use oi apodexis in this connection. 5 2 5:i
s
HERODOTUS AND ATHENS
43
having driven away the Persian they were already making the contest about his land, holding out Pausanias' violence as a pretext, they wrested the leadership from the Spartans'. This passage praises Athens' concession but finishes critically: the Athenians, always after the leadership, act duplicitously; further Spartan-Athenian dissension is foreshadowed. ' (c) W h e n M a r d o n i u s offers the Athenians a Persian alliance, Herodotus gives the Athenians two speeches (8.143-4). T h e first (to Alexander o f Mace don) champions liberty and perpetual enmity to the sacrilegious Xerxes. T h e second (to Spartan ambassadors) is nobler still: o f many deterrents to medizing and enslaving Greece, the greatest is the destruction o f Athens' temples and statues, but there are also the claims o f Greek identity, shared blood, language, temples, sacrifices, and customs. Is this nobility ironized by the contemp orary political context: Athens' subjugation o f Greeks, peace w i t h Persia, and her (and Sparta's) seeking Persian help i n the Peloponnesian War? T h e textual context provides support. T h e Spartan remark—'you aroused this war, we not at all wishing i t , and the contest was over your "first-beginning" (arkhesy —brilliantly evokes the Croesean connection between 'first-beginning' and 'first-rule'; then, when the Athenians, albeit as a diplomatic ploy, threaten to ally with Persia and fight Greeks, their noble sentiments arc compromised, the inconcinnity reinforcing contemporary thoughts. lf
:u
38
lliemistocles Herodotus' Themistocles is, uncontroversially, a 'new man', highly intelligent and far-sighted, a penetrating military analyst, persuasive, tricky, deceitful, venal, rapacious,''" minatory, and conceited. But the portrayal has been variously adjudged inconsistent (through conflicting sources), ' grudging (because o f hostile sources), fulfilling contemporary 1
1 0
01
1
•"' Strasburger (1955) 20; Raaflaub (1987) 240; Herodotus doubts Pausanias medism: 5.32;'cD also 6.138 40: Derow (.1995) 48-9. -" 8.1.42; the paradosis convinces: Fornara (1971a) 84 n. 14; How and Wells ad toe. are unsubtle. Fornara (1971a) 85-6; van der Veen (1996) 105 8. Barth (1965); Marr (1998) 88. Bums (1896) 89: Masaracchia (1977) xx. How and Wells (1928) 1: 42 3; Marr (1998) 4 5. 5 8
19
m
M
JOHN MOLES
44
2
3
expectations, a 'literary construct', unified,*' ambiguous,*' and historically just."' Three sections are critical. (a) Themistocles enters alter Herodotus' claim that the Athenians saved Greece, when the Athenians are debating the second Delphic oracle: 7.143 'there was of the Athenians a man newly (neosti) advancing into the first men, whose name (men) was Themistocles, and/but (de) he was called the son o f Neocles'. There follow Themistocles' positive oracular interpretation, his proposal that the Athenians prepare to fight at sea and an earlier intervention: 7.144 'another opinion o f Themistocles before this prevailed opportunely, when, many monies having accrued to the Athenians i n the public treasury, monies which came to them from the mines at Laurion, they were about to share them out amongst themselves at ten drachmas each; on that occasion Themistocles persuaded the Athenians to desist from this division and to make two hundred ships from these monies for the war, adducing the one against the Aeginetans. For the occurrence o f this war saved Greece on that occasion, compelling the Athenians to become sea people. The ships were made but were not used but i n this way accrued to Greece at the necessary moment. These ships, then, having been previously made, were available to the Athenians and it was necessary to make others. They resolved in their debate after the oracle to receive the barbarian oncoming into Greece with their ships in full force, obeying the god, together with those o f the Greeks who wished'. 1
Themistocles' 'new' prominence allegedly depreciates Themistocles' earlier career, from his 493 archonship, and his family.'" But why 'whose name was Themistocles a n d / b u t he was called the son o f Neocles'? Herodotus, nomen/omen specialist, plays' ' on neosti, name, jYeo/clcs, lliemisto/cles and called (ekaleeto): his arriviste name ('son o f "New-fame"') is less true o f h i m than 'Themistocles', which means 'famed for his rightness' or 'rightly famed/named'. Herodotus 'redefines' Themistocles by his intrinsic worth, fulfilling the Preface's project o f 1 1
lt!
The latter three: Fornara (1971a) 66 74. Strasburger (1955) 21-2, cf. Fornara (1971a) 66: Konstan (1987) 70-2: Romm (1998) 187-9. " Hart (1982) 150 2; Evans (1991) 75-80. How and Wells (1928) 1: 42; Hornblower (1991) 139; Marr (1998) 69 71; contra Davies (1971) 213. * Other literary defences: Fornara (1971a) 68; Evans (1987) (parallel with Mardonius: 6.43); (1971) 75; full exposition: Moles (2000). !>:;
6 5
HERODOTUS AND ATHENS
45
-
heroic naming /faming: kka andrdn. But a new arrival's immediately scaling the political heights is additionally praiseworthy: Herodotus also 'redefines' 'New-fame' as 'Young-fame'. Doubtless, a hostile source provided misleading facts, but Herodotus' virtuosic punning subverts their implications. Chapter 144 is also held depreciatory, on the ground that Themistocles thinks only of the Aeginetan war, whereas Thucydides has him already foreseeing the Persian threat. ' But Herodotus' subtle wording allows the latter possibility (Aegina being Themistocles' public argument) and 144 is wholly laudatory. Qua ideal statesman, Themistocles alone counsels 'opportunely'. His opinion concerns the Aeginetan war, ' which 'saved Greece, compelling the Athenians to become sea people', just as at 139.5 'the Athenians were saviours of Greece'; the ships he caused to be built 'accrued to Greece at the necessary moment'; on Themistocles' second intervention, in 4 8 1 , the Athenians accepted his interpretation, and resolved to 'receive the barbarian oncoming into Greece', just as at 139.6 'they stayed and endured to receive the oncoming invader of the land'. The interaction between Herodotus' own claim and the narrative creates a causal chain: the Aeginetan war, the building o f the navy, the Athenians' acceptance o f Themistocles' interpretation of the oracle and their heroic stand, a chain whose single and brilliant artificer is Themistocles. M
1 8
1 9
(b) A t Salamis, when news of Athens' sack impels some of the generals to prepare immediate departure and the rest to plan defence of the Isthmus, Mnesiphilus arrives by night, argues the decision's folly—the Greeks, no longer fighting for one fatherland, will scatter and Greece will be destroyed--and urges Themistocles to get the decision reversed (8.56-7). Is this fictitious intervention to Themistocles' discredit or does it create dramatic emphasis? 70
Mnesiphilus' almost divine intervention is dramatic. But his analysis is cogent, reprising the arguments of 7.138-9 (Herodotus h i m self) and 8.2-3 (the Athenians' insight). (Themistocles' reluctance to
bl
Debate over the meaning of'Neocles': Harvey (1980); Bicknell (1982); Romm (1998) 187. «* Hornhlower (1991) 48, 138-9. Itself, paradoxically, inglorious: van der Veen (1996) 100 2. How and Wells (1928) 1: 42: 2: 254, 378; Hignett (1963) 204; Fornara (1971a) 72 n. 19; Marincola (1996) 595 6 n. 18; Polling (1997); Marr (1998) 74. 70
46
JOHN MOLES
use these arguments publicly is dictated, as Herodotus notes, by tact.) Themistocles' reaction is exemplary. Almost uniquely, the worldly leader heeds his wise warner well, his 'pleasure' connotes not delusion but understanding, and there follows a contest between intelligence (Mnesiphilus/Themistocles) and mere power ('Eurybiades'), and their successful fusion: Themistocles himself assumes the role o f adviser to Eurybiades. A t council, Themistocles, after initial overenthusiasm, shows further tact i n his handling o f Adimantus and appeals to Eurybiades' military pride; his military analysis is powerful, reflecting both the experience o f Artemisium and 'good counsel' (instead o f 'counsel-lessness'), and angled to Spartan self-interest. Only when stung by Adimantus' further racist jibes does Themistocles abuse h i m and the Corinthians, menace them with the Athenian fleet, threaten Eurybiades w i t h Athenian migration, and again appeal to his better nature. The threat, opines Herodotus, decided Eurybiades in Themistocles' favour (8.58-63). Themistocles judiciously blends tact, appeal, hard military analysis, and threats. His climactic words before Eurybiades 'learns' aright (8.62: 'you Spartans, isolated from allies such as us, will remember m y words') emphasize that the philia that should bind all Greece, not just individual patrides, is the key to success. His effective assimilation with 'Mnesiphilus' ('remembering philoi') clinches his credit. Again, Herodotus, accepting a hostile source's 'facts', overturns their implications. The sole negative is the threatened use o f Athenian sea power against other Greek states, particularly C o r i n t h , which, while a rhetorical ploy, might have uncomfortable contemporary resonances. When the Greeks again lose resolve, Themistocles employs another trick, secretly sending Sicinnus to urge immediate Persian attack. The trick is justified by results, but might recall Themistocles' future dealings w i t h Persia. T h e intervention o f Aristides, with his news o f Persian encirclement, enacts the historian's own role, enhancing Aristides' 'authority', and replays Mnesiphilus' intervention. Aristides' insistence, welcomed by Themistocles, that the two sublimate their personal stasis into (as it were) patriotic stasis, enacts on the personal and Athenian levels the need to overcome stasis within Greece against the common enemy. Herodotus' judgment (8.79) that Aristides ('best in appearance') was 'the best and most just man ever produced by Athens'" underlines his moral superiority. Nevertheless, Themistocles Cf. also Plu. Arist. 3; Timocr. 410.
HERODOTUS AND ATHENS
47
again responds excellently to external intervention. Then, at embarkation, Themistocles 'of all spoke right sentiments' in a speech of notable moral and philosophical weight. His logos everywhere excels (8.74 83). (c) Themistocles dominates the debate whether to cut Xerxes off. Themistocles advocates this but when Eurybiadcs' counter-argument, that it would be safer to let Xerxes escape and fight over Xerxes' own land, wins Peloponnesian support, Themistocles addresses the Athenians, the most annoyed at the enemy's escape and the keenest to sail to the Hellespont, i f necessary alone. He switches, arguing that the defeated are dangerous, that the Greek victory was lucky, and that not they but the gods defeated the impious Xerxes. They should return home and sail for the Hellespont in the spring. When he then contacts Xerxes (unhistorically), claiming to have dissuaded the Greeks from cutting h i m off, his 'intention was to make a deposit to the Persian, in order that i f any disaster should overtake h i m from the Athenians, he should have a refuge to turn to; which indeed occurred': clearly glossing his ostracism and flight to Persia (8.108-10). Themistocles' behaviour embraces the patriotic and militarily penetrating, the pragmatic, the self-interested and the duplieitous, but this duplicity reflects foresight, not yet treachery to Greece (the campaign will resume). The Athenians are persuaded: now that 'having in the past been thought clever and o f good counsel, he had been shown to be truly clever and o f good counsel, they were ready to be persuaded by h i m i n all circumstances' (8.110). Themistocles' name again speaks true. 7
715
The siege o f Andros, a Panhellenic operation, as Herodotus belatedly implies, is dominated by Themistocles, his rapacity, the largely Athenian fleet and secret exactions from other islands (8.111-12). After the allusion to his ostracism and flight to Persia, these activities must reflect Athenian brutalities towards the Delian League and the speed o f their inception. Nevertheless, Themistocles receives due honour, both at the Isthmus (implicitly) and at Sparta (unequivocally): 'Tliemistocles, rightly named both at the beginning and end o f his narrative (8.123-4). Herodotus' text, triumphing over his sources' bias, acclaims Themistocles cleverest o f all Greeks and saviour o f 74
" Marr (1998) 112-13. Pace Fornara (1971a) 71-2. Strasburger (1955) 21; Immerwahr (1966) 200 n. 29; Raallaub (1987) 227. 239. M
71
JOHN MOLES Greece against Persia. But the genuinely negative elements—the bribery, rapacity, self-interest, incipient medism, proto-imperialist bully-boy tactics, though source-derived, are not source-driven. Herodotus' Themistocles is a unity, the negatives the obverse o f the positive, an Odyssean or Promethean figure, Athens' outstanding leader, seen both in his time and in his future, paradigmatic also o f Persian-war and later Athens. ' 73
71
7
Athens at the end of the war'
A t Mycale, the last battle, 'Ionia revolted from the Persians for the second time' (9.104); the narrative rings back, via the Ionian Revolt, to Croesus' original conquest. But closure fails. Herodotus' enumeration o f the best fighters includes Hermolycus, killed a few years later in war with Carystus (9.105): a possible contrast between the Panhellenic struggle and Athenian imperialism. The debate about whether to transplant the Ionians or protect them in situ problematizes Greece's boundaries (9.106) and rings back to Bias' 'most useful' proposal after the Persian conquest, " but again the narrative advances: the Athenians asserting their rights over their colonists, and the Samians, Chians, Lesbians, and other islanders joining the alliance and swearing not to revolt: from one arklie into another . . . T h e story o f Masistes'' one o f sexual and political intrigues and misdemeanours and barbarous cruelty—realfirms Xerxes as tyrant, rings back to Gyges and Candaules and anticipates Xerxes' downfall (9.108-13). The allusion to Protesilaus (9.116) rings back to the very beginnings o f Greek-barbarian conflict,' and again problematizes boundaries. T h e omen o f the leaping salt fish (9.120) rings back to Cyrus' negotiations with the Ionians and portends Ionia's escape 7
)
10
75
Fornara (1971a) 72-3; Evans (1991) 78. 80. Konstan (1987) 72. " Lateiner (1989) 46-50, 132-5; Herington (1991a); Städter (1992) 791 4, 798: Derow (1995) 34-51; Moles (1996); Dewald (1997); Pelling (1997b); (2000) 354. Space and dating imponderables marginalize the case that the Persians sometimes reflect the later Athenians: e.g., Fornara (1971a) 84 n. 13: Hunter (1982) 254-7; Raaflaub (1987) 228 9, 236 n. 40; cT. Rood (1999) 150. 1.170.1. cf. 5.106, 124; 6.22. Wolff (1964); Marincola (1996) 601 n. 51. Boedeker (1988); Marincola (1996) 601 n. 52. 7(i
7!!
7 9
HERODOTUS AND ATHENS
49
from Persian enslavement: but the fish are cooked. T h e punishment of the cruel and sacrilegious Persian governor o f Seslus, Artayctes, itself just and precisely calibrated both spatially (on Xerxes' bridges into Europe) and temporally (as requital for Persian sacrilege from Artayctes and Xerxes back to the original maltreatment of Protcsilaus), is conducted by Xanthippus in a form that might pre-eeho Pericles' vengeance against Samos in 440 and includes his son's stoning before Artayctes' eyes (9.120): shades of Xerxes. Nor will the Athenians accept this geographical division. The narrative close 'and in this year nothing further than these things was done'—intimates that 'further' things will be done. T h e concluding story o f Artembares, Artayctes' grandfather, and the advice or warning o f Gyrus (9.122), recapitulates major themes and rings multiply with the beginning: back to the beginning o f Persian expansion to empire from poor beginnings, to Croesus, to the eternal struggle between ruling and slavery. But Cyrus' warningis flawed—he himself ignored it—and in one sense misdirected, because he does not give it to the Persians at the proper narrative moment. So, implicitly, the warning is Herodotus' and includes Athens, the coming imperial power, already at the History's end pushing against the re-established and natural geographical boundaries, already erupting beyond the textual boundaries. The series o f ring structures enacts the close o f one 'cycle' and die beginning o f another. 81
82
83
Conclusions While emphasizing that Athenian support o f the Ionian Revolt ultimately caused the Persian invasion,"' Herodotus hails the Atheniansparticularly Thcmistocles—as Greece's saviours and Athenian greatness as deriving from political freedom. Both judgments attest admiration for Persian-war Athens, as well as remarkable historical penetration, independence, and impartiality, particularly in contemporary circumstances. Admiration includes objectivity. Herodotus does not
81
w
M
8J
Plu. Per. 28.2; also Hrlt. 7.33: Dcrow (1995) 38. Gould (1989; 58 60; Raaflaub (1987) 244-6. Moles (1996) 275. 5.97.3, 105.1: 7.1.1; 8.142.2; van der Veen (1996) 90 tl
50
john
moles
conceal- he underlines Athens' early jostling for Greek hegemony; his p o r t r a i t o f city and leader contains negatives and ominous préfigurations. Not only does Athens contribute most to Persia's defeat: she is foregrounded in the History's architecture. Initially, Sardis, Lydia, and Croesus represent (inter multa alia) Athens, her empire and Pericles; Herodotus' first treatment of mainland Greece, a sustained comparison o f Athens and Sparta, subverts contemporary preconceptions; the History ends with Athens driving the Greek war-effort and herself reaching towards empire. Prospective allusions, explicit and implicit, establish the contemporary political world as an important sub-text and a dominant context for the text's reception. Why? T h e question becomes more urgent because Herodotus' history o f events between c. 560 and 479/8 (with retrospects) and their causes, is also a timeless examination o f the political process o f rise and fall. Herein, the History concerns the Athenian empire as much as Lydia or Persia, and So(si)cles' remarks apply to any readers. Solon's/Herodotus' advice to 'look to the end o f every thing' logically includes 'things' beyond the 'end' o f the History, an 'end' which, appropriately, is both an end and not an 'end'. The timeless frame necessarily encompasses contemporary Athens, and the History's timclessness is immediately validated by its relevance to a context outside its chronological limits. But since this relevance is conveyed by implicit rather than explicit allusions, it poses readers interpretative challenges, like those faced by figures within the text, thereby reinforcing another important aspect of Herodotus' project: its practical usefulness. T h e implicit prospective allusions also extend Herodotus' investigation o f causality, from 'why things happened then' to 'why we are where we are now'. (Herodotus preempts Thucydidcs I!) But why is Adiens so important? Fundamental to the History is the struggle between political freedom and enslavement. Freedom is initially conceptualized as Greek and good, slavery/tyranny as barbarian and bad. The History is full of tyrants, so named or of similar type, and tyranny features i n the Constitutional Debate. True, most o f the tyrants in the History are Greek; not all tyrants are bad or not always; some produce 'great and wonderful achievements'; and there is debate whether 'tyrant' and cognates are necessarily pejorative in Herodotus. Hence some 83
How and Wells (1926) 2: 338-47; Fcrrill (1978); Vernant (1982); Gammie
51
HERODOTUS A N D ATHENS
see the initial conceptualizations as problematized: wrongly. T h a t ideals are compromized in practice, while 'disturbing', 'challenging' etc., does not impugn the ideals. Herodotus' theoretical position is radically anti-tyrant: tyrants subjugate their own people and stunt their growth; they are a perversion of nature; they, or their descendants, are appropriately overthrown (e.g., 3.142.1; 7.164). M a n y contemporary Greeks saw the Athenian empire as Persia's tyrannical successor. Hence the paradoxical concept of 'the tyrant city'; a concept which Herodotus applies, implicitly, to Athens. Herodotus admires Athens qua saviour o f Greece but condemns the empire: a position consistent with two other aspects o f his thinking: hatred o f w a r (for which Athens bore most responsibility in fifth-century Greece) and genuine Panhellenism. True also, Herodotus celebrates the growth o f Athenian power after the Peisistratids' expulsion; such 'growth' led to 'tyranny'; and the History repeatedly allows a voice to the 'rule-or-be-ruled' existential choice so familiar from Thucydides. T h e answer remains the same: the Athenian 'tyranny' was different because it controlled systematically and exacted tribute; Sparta's control over her allies was much looser. N o r is tyranny's 'growth' inevitable: it is a perverted growth. Herodotus does not himself endorse the rule-or-be-ruled apologia beloved o f tyrants. It is not 'tragically inevitable' that people should aggressively impose servitude on others (or that others let them):'" they choose to do so, when, Herodotus rightly thinks, they are w r o n g . 86
87
88
89
510
92
T w o further factors inform Herodotus' judgment o f contemporary Athens. Firstly, Athens' tyranny is also 'internal'. I f that estimation o f Pericles' power underestimates Athens' democratic mechanisms, it
(1986); Hartog(1988) 322-89; Latcincr (1989) 154-5, 166-7, 170-85; Ogdcn (1997); contra Waters (1971); Gray (1996) 364-6; van der Veen (1996) 66-89; Dewald (2002). "" E.g.. 5.97.3: 6.98; 8.3.1; Cobel (1986). E.g., 1.6; 7.138 9; 8.3.1-2; 8.143-4; Mitchell (2000). E.g., 5.105.2; Hdt. 1.46.1, 71.1, 207.3; 6.98.2; 7.11.2-3; Ashed (1997). Not that Sparta is 'innocent': cf. 1.6 (friendship with Croesus); 1.68.6; section 3; 6.98.2 'the leaders warring over the arihi'; Lateiner (1989) 133; Stadter (1992) 809; van der Veen (1996) 108-10; Herodotus on Sparta is another, less critical, story. Pace Fornara (1971a) 78. "' E.g., 3.143.2; 6.11-12: Stadter (1992) 803-8. " E.g., 1.5.3, 206; 3.21.2: 6.98.2. i!?
8 9
,JU
2
52
JOHN MOLES
was a widespread contemporary view, although, as by Thucydides, it could be glossed positively. N o r was it naive to associate Pericles with Athenian imperial tyranny. Secondly, both Solon's encounter with Croesus and the History's end include implicit warnings to the Athenians. W h y warn an established imperialist, especially when, like Thucydides, the History acknowledges the practical dangers of relinquishing tyranny? But such warnings (paralleling the numerous explicit warnings to more or less tyrannical figures throughout the text) matter. They may prevent greater excesses: it would have been worthwhile averting Melos or the Sicilian Expedition, both for Athens' suffering enemies and for herself; it is something i f even the profoundly deluded make some moral progress (as Croesus, even Xerxes, do, before their falls). T h e obliquity with which the warnings are conveyed also signifies: both to provoke thought and to illustrate the relatively safest and best way o f warning tyrants.'" Should the warnings fail, they may deter future readers, because they can learn from the Athenians' demonstrated folly and consequent overthrow. The process will also validate both the History's usefulness and Herodotus' prescience. I t is astonishing, but morally pregnant, that when the Athenians first appear, they are stupid. 93
95
Athens is in the History's conception: the Athenian empire/tyranny turned Herodotus to history-writing.' A m o n g the many sources o f the History's greatness is its moral seriousness, including advocacy o f political freedom, at least within the Greek world. Athens is not thereby the History's central concern: she is a paradigm o f universal processes, albeit for contemporaries the sharpest one."' 16
E.g., 3.143: Thuc. 2.63.1 f.: Raallaub {1987} 226. Hohti (1974); Urtemcr (1989) 184; Moles (1996) 269-70. ''·' The more strikingly, ij"the Historv dates to c. 415. * Meyer (1899) 198; Fornara (1971a) 14 5, 86-91; Meier (1973/80) 427 ff.; (1987) 51 4. I. thank: the Liverpool Seminar (7/12/99); NEGRO'S (8/12/99); Franco Basso; Bob Fowler; Lynette Mitchell; Chris Pelling; Peter Rhodes; Tony Woodman: and Irene de Jong. 9 1
1,7
CHAPTER T H R E E
O R A L STRATEGIES I N T H E LANGUAGE OF HERODOTUS Simon R. Slings
It is a platitude to say that Herodotus stands on the watershed between the oral and literate phases o f Greek culture. M a n y idiosyncrasies o f his style suggest that he stands i n a tradition o f telling stories, and that the written language in his time was only i n its infancy. T h e challenge is to turn this impressionistic triviality into scholarship. One branch o f linguistics, called Discourse Analysis, mayhelp us out here. Most linguistic studies are concerned with language as a system, the langue in Saussurean terms. But Discourse Analysis typically focuses on the concrete manifestations o f the system, the parole. Discourse Analysis is first and foremost a part o f the study o f living languages, i n which it analyses linguistic behaviour in certain communicative situations. But its results may also be applied, and have been applied with great success, to texts, literary or otherwise. Now, it is o f course a drawback that Ancient Greek is not a living language, even though few classical scholars seem aware o f the extent o f the limits which this sets on our knowledge. But even though the real spoken language o f the Greeks is lost irretrievably, there is no need for a confession o f total aporia. First, we do have an ample corpus of people portrayed i n conversation: tragedy, comedy (old and new), philosophical dialogue. A n d secondly, even though each language is different from all others, there are some universals o f oral speech which there is no good reason to doubt were true o f Ancient Greek as well. So by dint o f careful extrapolation from Discourse Analysis o f oral use o f modern languages and comparison with the corpus o f quasi-spoken language preserved from Ancient Greek we may try to learn something more concrete on Herodotus' place i n the oral/written continuum. There are several ways o f doing this. One way would be to concentrate on what I have elsewhere called 'downslip'. I t is a characteristic o f all spoken language, as we can observe daily ourselves,
DI-
SIMON R. SLINGS
that speakers tend to start sentences o f a relatively complex structure; in the course o f the sentence the structure proves too complex, so the speaker shifts to a more simple structure. Downslip creates all sorts o f anacolutha: from part to whole, from paraphrasis to the entity that is paraphrased, from indirect to direct speech, from infinitive to finite verb, from subordinate clause to main clause, and from marked case (dative, genitive) to unmarked case (accusative, nominative). I have studied downslip in H o m e r and in Plato (Slings (1994) and (1997a), respectively). I n the present study I will concentrate not on such involuntary phenomena but on strategies used on purpose in oral language to make information more accessible. The primary difference between speech and text, oral and written language, is the organization o f its units. I n text, there is a central syntactic unit, the main clause: the writer is at liberty to add subsidiary information i n various types o f embedded clauses, which are organized around the central unit. By contrast, speech has as its basic unit the chunk, a unit which in spoken language is recognizable by its intonation pattern, and which is therefore often called intonation unit. These intonation units are information units at the same time: sometimes they give new information (Focus) about an already given entity or state o f affairs (Topic): in these cases the information unit is a clause. I n other cases information units consist o f one constituent only; i f so, they precede a clause and help to understand it (Theme) or follow i t and give additional comment or information (Tail). For instance:^ 1
2
(1)
As for J o h n IIIKMK,
he ran away ci-s, the poor chap A«.It is perhaps the most typical property of the flow o f information in speech that 'the density o f information packing in spoken language is appropriate for the listener to process comfortably' (Brown and Yule (1983) 18). (1) is an illustration o f how what might be a feasif0
1
T
This is a simplification in that some subordinate clauses, for example restrictive relative clauses, cannot be said to provide subsidiary information; vice versa, not all main clauses contain foreground information, for example main clauses introduced by means of the particles yap and, to a certain extent, uév. But as a rough outline of the entirely different principles of organization of speech and text, the above may suffice. With the following, cf. Bakker (1997a) 17 8; Slings (1999) 61 2; (2000) 21-5. See Slings (1999) 61-2 for further analysis of diis example. 3 3
1
O R A L STRATEGIES IN T H E LANGUAGE OF HERODOTUS
55
bit* text sentence 'Poor John ran away' is chunked into three sepa rate information units. O f course these two ways o f using language are not mutually exclusive. A n y given stretch o f units can have speech and text prop erties (cf. Bakker (1997a) 8 9), and this is what we should certainly expect to find in Herodotus. But within the bounds o f this study the only way to locate him more precisely within the speech/text con t i n u u m is to concentrate on some o f the most distinctive features of speech and text, and I will deal with the former.^ 4
Speech Exemplified To illustrate some features o f speech, I will quote the beginning o f the story o f Gyges and Candaules' wife (1.8.1), split up in chunks, with some comments. (2a)
Ούτος δη ών ό Κανδαύλης ήράσθη της έωυτοΰ γυναικός 1
Now this Candaules was i n love ' with his own wife' Candaules had first been m e n t i o n e d at. 1.7.2: ' T h e r e was o n e Candaules, whom the Greeks call Myrsilus, a descendant o f Alcaeus son o f Heracles', a sentence which starts with en (Rdndaules), a favourite device in Greek to introduce new Discourse Topics, cf. D i k (1995) 221-8. I t seems to me typical o f Herodotus' style that the precise status o f this verb is often difficult to determine when so used. Here Τ would prefer to analyse it as the main verb, not the copula, which is why I do not translate: 'C. was tyrant o f Sardes'." After Candaules' first mention comes an embedded sequence, giv ing subsidiary information to link Candaules with Alcaeus, marked
I
Cf. Slings (1999) for an attempt to place Bacchylides in this continuum. On the textualily of Herodotus, see Rosier, this volume (Ch. 4). 1 disagree with the traditional analysis of the aorist ήράσθη as ingressive. If the aorist of a verb with stative 'Aktionsart' is to be interpreted as referring to the beginning of that state, there must be clear signals in the context that a state begins. Since this is not the case here, I prefer to take the aorist indicative as presenting a state in the remote past as an event that took placer in the past i'complexive aorist'). Translations from Herodotus are my own, and are as literal as possible in order to highlight the strategies used. But I owe a debt of gratitude to Waterfield's trans lation, from which I have taken over a phrase here and there. Cf. below, the analysis of (2e). 5
h
7
II
56
SIMON R.
SLINGS
by the P U S H particle gar at 1.7.2. This embedded sequence ends at the end of 1.7.4, and in (2a) the main narrative line is resumed bymeans o f the P O P particle on. T h e pronoun houlos selects Candaules as Topic o f this clause, a strategy which is very common indeed after an entity has been introduced as a new Discourse Topic; our instance is slightly atypical because o f the embedded sequence that comes between the first mention o f Candaules (in 1.7.2 as quoted above) and clause (2a), i n which he is first assigned Topic function. T h e Focus o f the clause is o f a relatively rare type called complex Focus (cf. D i k (1995) 29-30; 71-3): 'he was in love, with his own wife'. 9
(2b)
έρασθεις δέ being in love
This is probably to be taken as a Theme, preceding the clause proper, although it could also be part of the clause, in which case we would have to assign it the pragmatic function called Setting or Orientation. I n any case, this type o f repetition o f the main verb o f the preceding clause by means o f a participle o f the same verb, which is one o f the best-known features o f Herodotus' style (cf. Fehling (1969) 147-8; M ü l l e r (1980) 61-3), is one o f several phenomena which bring about clause linking, known in Discourse Analysis as tail/head links. T h e close-knit succession o f information units is typical of speech. Participial tail/head linking is also a way o f announcing Topic continuity: the reader/listener is prepared for the next information unit to be about Candaules as well. (2c)
ένόμιζέ ol είναι γυναίκα κολλόν πασέων καλλίστην he believed he had the most beautiful wife in the world
Since this information unit contains an embedded clause, the w o r d order is different from the one i n simple clauses. For main clauses, H e l m a D i k has discovered the o r d e r i n g rule T o p i c F o c u s Predicate—X (1995). W i t h i n the embedded clause, the pronoun hoi, which refers to the Discourse Topic, has a position determined by Wackernagel's Law. Einai gunaika is inferable from or given by the 10
·' A PUSH is a place where an embedded sequence begins, a POP one where it ends, for an illustration of 'embedded' and 'embedding', see below, the discussion of example (16). For further details on P U S H / P O P analysis, cf. Slings (1997b) 101-4. See also Bakkcr (1997a) 112-15 on yap and ouv as well as de Jong (1997). ' X ' stands for pragmatically unmarked constituents. Iu
O R A L STRATEGIES I N T H E L A N G U A G E OF HERODOTUS
preceding discourse, and as such these words precede the Focus pot ion paseon kallislen. xx
(2d)
ώστε δέ ταΰτα νομίζων as he believed this
Another participial tail/head link, slightly unusual i n that Herodotus far more often uses aorist participles than present ones to link clauses. 12
(2e)
ήν γ ά ρ o i των αίχμοφόρων Γύγης Δασκύλου άρεσκόμενος μ ά λ ι σ τ α among his guards was Gyges son o f Dascalus, who pleased h i m most
Gar indicates a PUSH: the narrator interrupts himself to give back ground information, which is necessary for the reader/listener to understand the flow o f the story. When such an embedded sequence actually causes a syntactic break in the governing sequence, this is called 'background repair' (cf. SchifFrin (1987) 3 0 0 1 ) . i n this case there is probably no break, depending on whether (2d) is considered a separate unit or not (see the analysis o f (2b)). But an interruption there certainly is. Herodotus is probably the Greek author who makes most use o f 'parenthetic gar\ The background sequence here serves to introduce a new Discourse Topic ('presenlative clause'), As we already have seen, such clauses often start with en. I n this case, there is, besides, a deviation from normal w o r d order. We have here to do with what Τ have elsewhere called 'crescendo sentence' (Slings (1992) 99 n. 19), a clause i n which every next constituent contains more information than the preced ing. Here the information load o f en is almost n i l , ton aikhmophorfm names the group to which the Discourse Topic belongs, and only with the Focus Guges ho Daskuiou does the clause do its j o b . Again, 13
14
11
Perhaps είναι γυναίκα is Topic of the embedded clause; cf. Dik (1995) 207 35 on predicates as Topics, and (1995) 229 on the status of 'dummy Topic' of exis tential είναι. O f course, this case is different in that I would prefer to take both constituents together as Topic, a possibility argued for by Dik (1995) 69-70 ('extended Topic'). '- But cf. 5.4-2.2 όίστε ών οΰτω φρονέων. An investigation of the pragmatic func tions of the so-called participle particles ώστε, οίον, οία, and άτε will no doubt be very rewarding, but falls outside of the scope of the present study. As often in Herodotus, cf. Stein (1883) 12, who cites seven more instances from Book One alone. The order of constituents may, however, be reconciled with Dik's rule i f it is assumed, first that ήν has Topic function ('dummy Topic', see above n. 11); and, , J
H
58
SIMON R.
SLINGS
the main Discourse Topic is referred to by means o f hoi, which is placed according to Wackernagel's Law. I t cannot be made out w i t h certainty whether areskomenos malisla is an information unit by itself (a Tail.) or not, although I have analysed the w o r d order on the assumption that it is not. Herodotus' predilection for fuzzy syntax, especially w i t h regard to en, i n presentative clauses, makes it impossible for us to determine whether en is the existential verb ('there was among his guards', 'to his guards belonged') or a periphrastic auxiliary (en . . . areskomenos = eresketo). I t could well be the latter, i f one assumes that the periphrastic con struction was used precisely because o f the fact that Gyges is here first introduced. I f so, the fuzziness reflects one o f the main traits o f oral language use, to w i t dual functionality: '' en would then be both. But the clause would then be crammed w i t h new information (ton aikhmophoron, Guges ho Daskulou, areskomenos malista), which is rather avoided i n oral language use, so perhaps it is best to take areskomenos malista as a separate information unit. 1
(2f)
τ ο ύ τ ω τ ω Γΰγη κ α ι τ ά σ π ο υ δ α ι έ σ τ ε ρ α των π ρηγμάτων ύπ ε ρ ετίθετο ό Κανδαύλης
to this Gyges Gandaulcs confided his more serious business A t the P O P corresponding to the P U S H o f the previous clause, the new Discourse Topic is brought i n as clause Topic, by means o f the pronoun houtos, as i n (2a). Note that this is also a form o f tail/head link: the identity o f the clause Topic w i t h the new Discourse Topic links the two clauses (2e) and (2f), and the repetition o f the proper name underlines this. T h e clause Topic is followed by the Focus ta spoudaiestera ton pregmaton, which is modified by (corresponsive) kaithis particle serves at the same time as a forward link, i n that it pre pares the reader/listener for another entity, to be put on a par w i t h 'the more serious business'. T h e predicate follows the Focus, and ho Kandaules is put i n the X-position as pragmatically unmarked infor mation. V e r y often, as here, this is given information which the author could have suppressed but inserts i n order to enhance the cohesion o f the clause complex.
second, that a Setting (in this case των αίχμοφόρων) may be placed between Topic and Focus, as I have argued in Slings (1997a) 173 n. 14. For another possible exception, see the discussion of example (13) below. Cf. Slings (1994) 414 20; (2000) 23-4. ,rj
ORAL
(2g)
STRATEGIES IN T H E LANGUAGE
O F HERODOTUS
59
κ α ι δ ή κ α ι τό είδος της γυναικός ύπερεπαινέιον
praising abundantly more in particular his wife's beauty There is a syntactic incongruence here, inasmuch as the participle huperepaineon corresponds pragmatically to huperetithelo i n (2f}, and the two clauses are connected by means o f kai. . . kai de kai. Since the cluster kai de kai serves to combine the connective ('and') and the focal ('also', 'even') values o f the particle, one should have expected huperepeinee. W h a t has happened, I think, is that to eidos tes gunaikos starts as another object with huperetitheto, but towards the end o f this clause this link has been lost sight of, and the beauty o f Candauies' wife becomes the starting point for a new information unit. This unit is presented as an Elaboration o f the former, so that a partici ple, rather than a finite verb, is used: participles that follow the pre dicate often have this pragmatic function."' I t remains to be seen whether the anacoluthon was actually per ceived as such by Herodotus' contemporary readers/listeners. As I have argued on a number o f occasions ((1992) 9 6 - 1 0 1 , (1997a) 169-70), our sensitivity to syntactic correctness is conditioned by the ways and means o f the w r i t t e n language, a language w h i c h i n Herodotus' time was still i n its infancy. A person who writes is able to order his thoughts i n all tranquillity and put them together; a person who speaks has to present them i n chunks that are com fortable to process, and i n doing so has to accept irregularities which maybe he does not even feel are there. This analysis has yielded various traits that I consider typical o f Herodotus' oral style. T w o o f these will be the object o f further study i n this contribution: chunking and cohesion strategies—chunk ing as illustrated i n the juxtaposition o f seven information units, cohe sion as illustrated by the tail/head links.
1(1
Stein (1883) 13 compares 8.58.2 Έ ν θ α ΰ τ α ό Θεμιστοκλέης παριζόμενός οΐ καταλέγει έκεΐνά τε πάντα τάήκουσε Μνησιφίλου, έωυτοΰ ποιεύμενος, και άλλα πολλά προστιθείζ. where the pragmatic structure is similar, even though there need not be an anacoluthon (καί may couple the two participles, or it may be a Focus par ticle modifying άλλα πολλά). Cf. also 9.10.1 κ α ί . . . τάξεντες.
60
SIMON R. SLINGS
Predicate Repetition Λ chunking device that is virtually restricted to Herodotus (cf. Fehling (1968) 143-4; Slings (1997a) 180) consists i n repetition of a verb i n what we would consider the middle o f a sentence. A well-known example is: (3)
τον Σάλμοξιν τοΰτον έόντα ανθρωπον δουλεΰσαι έν Σάμω, δουλεΰσαι δέ Πυθαγόρη τ ω Μνησάρχου. (4.95.1)
This Salmoxis was a human being and served as a slave on Samos, a slave of Pythagoras son of Mnesarchus The verb is repeated because there are too many constituents that contain all-new information, and therefore i n principle eligible for Focus function. After the clause Topic ton Salmoxin louton and a Setting (Orientation) eonta anthropdn, which serves to contrast the information given about Salmoxis in this chapter with that given i n the previ ous one (in which Salmoxis is said to be a god), the constituents douleusai, en Samoi. Pulhagorei toi Mnesarkhou all give 'brand-new' infor mation (cf. Prince (1981)). It stands to reason that not all o f these can be placed in the same clause, because i t would become too com plex for the reader/listener to process. T h e strategy used here con sists o f adopting two all-new constituents into the clause, and repeating the verb douleusai as the Topic of a new clause (cf. D i k (1995) 210). Thus, two successive, paratactically juxtaposed clauses are used to refer to the same state o f affairs, a constellation akin to anaphora, which I shall call non-serial anaphora. ' As I have shown elsewhere ((1997a) 176-84), chunking is the origin o f anaphora i n Greek lit erature i n general. I n oral language, anaphora is a typical chunking strategy, which speakers can adopt i n order to arrange their thoughts as they are formulating them. 1
The verb-repeating anaphora as illustrated by (3) stands apart from other types o f anaphora, i n that normally the repeated constituent is the first o f two parallel clauses. I n (3), however, the strategy is different. W h a t is repeated is the first all-new constituent i n a clause that is already a long time on its way, and the clause contains a second all-new constituent besides the first, before it is chunked by
17
For a discussion of'normal' anaphora. I refer to Fehling (1969) 187 218; Slings (1997a) 176-84. The three oral strategics to be discussed here are mentioned together as related to each other by Stein (1883) 75.
O R A L STRATEGIES I N T H E L A N G U A G E OF HERODOTUS
61
means o f the verb repetition. This means that the first clause has a complex Focus (cf. above, on (2a)). Presumably, Herodotus wished to avoid a triple Focus clause. I n some instances the two Focuses are separated by an X-constiiuent containing unmarked old information: 18
(4)
πέμψας Καμβύσης ές Αϊγυπτον κήρυκα αΐτεε "Αμασιν θυγατέρα, αϊτεε δέ έκ συμβουλής ανδρός Αιγυπτίου. (3.1.1) Cambyses sent a messenger to Egypt and asked Amasis for a daughter o f his, which he d i d at the suggestion o f an Egyptian.
I take pempsas. .. kenika as Setting/Orientation, and the clause proper to start with the predicate, which has Focus function. T h e second Focus thugatera is separated from the first by means o f Amasin, which is given information i n this context. Again, the clause cannot con tain a third Focus, so chunking has to be applied. In one case the circumstances are roughly similar i n that a focal predicate is repeated because it is followed by two participial clauses, both o f which contain all-new information. A third participial clause cannot be accommodated i n the sentence without repetition o f the predicate: 19
(5)
έ ξ ε κ ά λ ε ε , π έ μ π ω ν κ ή ρ υ κ α , ό ν ο μ α σ τ ί λ έ γ ω ν τ ω ν Α ρ γ ε ί ων τ ο ύ ς έν τω ι ρ ω άπεργμένους, έξεκάλεε δέ φ α ς κτλ. (6.79.1) H e called them out by sending a messenger, calling by name each o f the Argives w h o were shut up in the sanctuary, and did so by saying t h a t . . .
Normally the repeated predicate is connected to the preceding clause by means o f de. Occasionally, one finds kai. I f so, the second pred icate setves as Topic to a Focus that specifies the manner i n which the State o f affairs described i n the first clause takes place:
18
Cf. 1.64.2 (predicate καθήρας between two all-new constituents); 1.75.4 (a clause with a Topic/Focus structure of its own depending from the predicate ποιήσαχ); 1.112.2 predicate followed by και εγώ (Focus particle); 1.114.1 predicate έπαιζε fol lowed by an all-new constituent followed by an identifying relative clause; 2.32.7 (ρέειν); 2.158.2 predicate the first constituent of the clause (with, I think, Focus function) followed by another focal constituent plus given or inferable unmarked information); 4.139.1 (λύειν); 6.89 (διδοΰσι); 8.76.1 predicate άνήγον followed by Focus plus Orientation participle. Cf. Dik (1995) 207-8; 210-11. Cf. 3.4.2 μεταδιώκει (Focus) ό "Άμασις (given) σπουδήν ποιεύμενος έλεΐν (sec ond Focus), μεταδιώκει δέ etc.; 5.100 α'ιρέουσι Σάρδις (given) ούδενός σφι άντιωθέντος, α'ιρέουσι δέ etc. !i>
62
SIMON R. SLINGS
(6)
ώς ών ετοίμου του γε έ ν θ ά δ ε έ ό ν τ ο ς . π ο ί ε ε τ α ΰ τ α κ α ι π ο ί ε ε κ α τ ά τάχος (1.124.3)
Take it that everything here is ready and do as I say, and do it without delay Here the focal value o f the imperative ('you must indeed do this') may be considered too high for the clause to accommodate the allnew kata takhos as well. But another factor may play a. part. Harpagus has used various arguments to persuade Cyrus to march against Media. The first clause o f (6) epitomizes this command. But there had been nothing in the preceding text to argue for it being neces sary to march without delay, so i f kata takhos had been brought in in the same clause as poke tauta, the sentence would lose its rhetor ical effectiveness. I n one instance only one all-new constituent is sufficient to trig ger this chunking device: 20
(7)
διαβάντες τήσι ν η υ σ ι τον Έλλήσποντον έπορεύοντο δια της Ευρώπης, έπορεύοντο δέ επί τε Έρέτριαν και Αθήνας. (6.43.4)
Having crossed the Hellespont by ship they marched through Europe, and did so against Eretria and Athens. Here I suspect that the clause is chunked not so much because o f the density o f information—after all, once you have crossed the Hellespont you will automatically be in Europe, so the Focus o f the first main clause ( I take eporeuonto to be its Topic) is more or less predictable. Rather, I believe chunking is applied to mark the impor tance o f the event told in this sentence, which also contains a reg ular anaphora (sunelekhthe men . . . sunelekhthe de). T h e event i n question is the beginning on European soil o f the abortive Persian expedition o f 492, the first o f the three military struggles between Persia and mainland Greece. There is an important lesson to be drawn from this instance: chunking devices may be used as literary devices. I n Slings (1997a) 175 I formulated the general rule for detecting such phenomena, and formulated it within the framework o f reader-response stylistics: 'As a general rule it may be stated that the more complex the infor mation supplied in a clause or sentence is, the higher the chances are for one o f these distribution phenomena (i.e., chunking) to occur.
Cf. 4.189.3 κάρτα γαρ ταύτη χρέωνται αί Λίβυσσαι κα'ι χρέωνται καλώς.
ORAL STRATEGIES I N T H E LANGUAGE OF HERODOTUS
63
In reader-response stylisdcs it follows automatically that the simpler the information supplied in a clause or sentence is, the higher the chances are that the distribution phenomena were experienced as being "literary". Put differently: A figure o f speech is a fixed strategy tised for arranging information, borrowed from everyday language but employed i n such a way that the competent native reader/lis tener will recognize it as untypical o f everyday language and inter pret it as literary.' In Herodotus, extract (7) is not an isolated case. One of die most famous sentences in his work is chunked not because the information load is too dense, but because it is the dramatic climax o f a story: (8)
ώς δ έ κ α τ ά ν ώ τ ο υ έ γ έ ν ε τ ο ϊ ο ύ σ η ς τ η ς γ υ ν α ι κ ό ς έ ς τ η ν κ ο ί τ η ν , ΰπεκδύς έχώρεε εξω. καΐ ή γυνή έπορα μιν έξιόντα. (1,10.2)
When the woman had turned her back and gone to bed, Gygcs slipped sofdy out of the room, but the woman, she saw him leaving. T h e position o f mm indicates that after kai, there are two informa tion units, not one: kai he gune and eporai min exionta (cf. Slings (1997a) 1 9 4 - 5 ) . Since 'the woman', ' h i m ' , and 'leaving' are all given infor mation, only eporai is new, so no chunking device is called for. When Herodotus uses one nevertheless, this is one indication (the historic present being another, see Sicking and Stork (1997) 1 4 5 6) that a special rhetorical effect is intended, or to put it in reader-response terms, that the reader will interpret the chunking, given the simple information structure o f the sentence, as literary. A t the same time, this instance teaches us an important lesson about Herodotus as a stylist. Since the type o f chunking illustrated in (7) and (8) is typically a phenomenon o f the spoken language, which in general has far more need o f chunking than written prose, the use o f chunking as a literary device at a dramatic climax shows that he wants his style to be oral. The major part of his sources are oral traditions, and the writer wishes his style to reflect the content. A n d 1 do think we should take seriously the reports that Herodotus read his work before an audience, even i f oral strategies are Mo caelo different from strategies that may have been used by 'performers' who proceeded aurally (cf. Slings (1992) 1 0 1 ) . 21
For a different view of Herodotus' reading, sec also Rosier, this vol. (Ch. 4); see also Ch. 1 and Ch. 7, this volume.
SIMON R.
64
SLINGS
Chunking of One Constituent So far we have examined cases in which whole clauses are chunked because they have too many constituents to be processed comfort ably. I n a fair number o f cases, it is not a clause but a single con stituent that is subjected to chunking. Sometimes this strategy is used simply to give extra information to a Focus: (9)
της γαρ Λιβύης τ ά μεν κατά την βορηίην θ ά λ α σ σ α ν ά π ' Αιγύπτου άρξάμενοι μέχρι Σολόεντος άκρης, ή τελευτά της Λιβύης, παρήκουσι παρά πάσαν Λίβυες και Λιβύων έ'θνεα πολλά. (2.32.4)
Along the coast line of the northern sea, from Egypt to Cape Soloeis, which is where Libya ends, along the whole of this line live Libyans, many tribes of them. The clause parhekousi para pasan Libues, in which I would take parhekousi as Topic, para pasan as Setting and i n which obviously Libues is Focus, cannot also accommodate the information that there are many tribes among the Libyans. Therefore the constituent is chunked. I n another information unit Libuon is now Topic and ethnea polla Focus. More often, chunking a constituent has the function of narrow ing down its referent: (10)
τ ά ετι και αμφότερα ές έμέ ήν κείμενα έν Θήβησι, και Θηβέων έν τω νηφ του Ίσμηνίου Απόλλωνος. (1·52)
Both these things were still lying in Thebes in my day, namely in the temple of Ismenian Apollo. The strategy is identical to the one used i n (9): from a Focus (en Uiebeisi) a Topic for a new information unit is derived (likewise put in the genitive) which serves as a foil for the precise location. One may wonder why the two locations are not simply put in apposi tion: en Thebeisi, en toi neoi tou Ismeniou Apollonos. The information would still be chunked in the same way, but the apposition en toi neoi tou Ismeniou Apollonos would have the pragmatic function T a i l (for this function, see the discussion above o f (1)). I suspect that this is the reason why Herodotus does not use an apposition here: a T a i l can contain focal information but does not do so necessarily. By chunking it in the way he does, he achieves maximum ideality o f the information. 22
'-- Cf. 1.102.2; 3.136.1; 4.151.2; 9.21.3. 8.17 ήρίστευσαν Αθηναίοι και Αθηναίων
O R A L STRATEGIES
I N T H E LANGUAGE OF
HERODOTUS
65
Also to be considered under this head are instances where a con stituent is repeated in the same case, as a Theme preceding an infor mation unit about the repeated constituent: (11)
από δέ Πελοποννήσου Φείδωνος τοΰ Άργείων τυράννου παΐς Λεωκήδης, Φείδωνος [δέ] του τα μέτρα ποιήσαντος Πελοποννησίοισι και ύβρίσαντος μέγιστα δή Ελλήνων απάντων, ος έξαναστήσας τους Ηλείων άγωνοθέτας αυτός τον έν Όλυμπίη αγώνα εθηκε, τούτου τε δή παις, και Αμίαντος Λυκούργου Αρκάς έκ Τραπεζοΰντος. (6.127.3) From the Péloponnèse came Leocedes son of Pheidon the tyrant of Argos, Pheidon who created a system of weights and measures for the Pcloponnesians, and who did the deed of greatest arrogance in the whole Greek world, by expelling the Elcan agônotlietai and organizing the Olympic games himself, a son of this man, and Amiantus son of Lycurgus, an Arcadian from Trapezus.
There is far more the matter here than the common-place use of de to connect phrases standing i n apposition (cf. Denniston (1954) 163). Pkeidônos is repeated from the Focus constituent of which is was only a part (Pkeidônos tou Argeiôn turannou pais Ijdkêdës), and given the function of Theme for a number of clauses, two participial ones, and two relative clauses working out the second participial clause. Small wonder that the reader has to be brought back to the original storyline by means o f the resumptive information unit toutou te dé pais. 23
Participial
Tails
A third chunking strategy consists in repeating the predicate as a participle in a T a i l constituent, in order to accommodate further focal information. Normally speaking thus new information is a cataphoric element, i.e., a pronominal or adverbial form announcing that new information will be given in the next clause or sentence. (12)
ό μεν δή οί έλεγε τά περ όπώπεε, ό δέ έννώσας το. λεγόμενα συνεβάλλετο τον Όρέστην κατά τύ θεοπρόπιον τούτον είναι, τήδε συμ βαλλόμενος- (1.68.3)
KXeivin,s does not belong here, since Herodotus wants to make two different state ments, one about die Greek nation that was the bravest, one about the individual within that nation. CD 7.121.1; 9.73.1. :M
(»6
SIMON R. SLINGS
This man thus told him what he had seen, and he, having con sidered his words, concluded that this was Orestes, according to the oracle, concluding this from the following considerations. The accusative and infinitive clause ton Oresten kata to theopropion teu ton einai is Focus.' Since cataphoric elements are normally Focus themselves, and are strongly focal in any case, teide cannot be accom modated i n the ho de clause, so a special information unit is created for i t by means o f a participle that repeats the predicate. This strategy is not unlike the non-serial anaphora discussed above, (3)-(7). One may therefore wonder why the predicate is not simply repeated, as it is i n that strategy. The answer must surely lie in the fact that participial Tails are used for cataphoric elements, and nonserial anaphoras never. Apparently, a cataphoric element is not strong enough to trigger a non-serial anaphora.-'' This i n its turn confirms the suspicion I uttered above about the Tail position: it is less suited for full Focus, but it can apparently accommodate a cataphoric ele ment, whose information, after all is only provisional. I n a minority o f cases a participial Tail is used i n a more com plex clause conglomerate: 4
(13)
περιημεκτέων δέ τή σύμφορη, δεινώς έκάλεε μεν Δία καθάρσιον, μαρτυρόμενος τ ά υπό του ξείνου πεπονθώς ε ϊ η , έκάλεε δέ έπίστιόν τε και έταιρήιον, τον αυτόν τούτον όνομάζων θεόν, τον μέν έπίστιόν καλέων, διότι δή οίκίοισι ΰποδεξάμενος τον ξεΐνον φονέα τοΰ παιδός έλάνθανε βόσκων, τον δέ έ τ α ι ρ ή ι ο ν , ώς φ ύ λ α κ ο ν σ υ μ π έ μ ψ α ς α υ τ ό ν εΰρήκοι πολεμιώτατον. (1.44.2)
Since he was terribly upset about what had happened he called upon Zeus as the god of purification to witness what he had suffered at the hands of his guest-friend, and he called upon him as god of the hearth and god of friendship, thereby addressing the same god. He called upon the god of the hearth because he had taken the foreigner into his house and unwittingly had been feeding his son's killer, and upon the god of friendship because he had sent him as a guard but found him to be his worst enemy. 2 1
Since 6 clearly refers to the Topic, the pragmatic role of ouvEpdAAeTO is prob lematic. I f it is neither Topic nor Focus, its position as a Predicate should be after the accusative and infinitive clause. Perhaps the very length of this clause has here caused a deviation from the normal rule of word order: Topic- Setting (evvcocacjPredicate- Focus. I f this is indeed a rule in Greek word order, it would be iden tical to the Tat-things-overboard' principle in Dutch prescriptive linguistics, cf. Slings (1997a) 198. (1 am told by my undergraduates that this is originally a strategy used in algebra.) Cf. 1.67.1; 94.2. M
O R A L STRATEGIES I N T H E LANGUAGE ΟΕ HERODOTUS
67
Here the participle kaleon cannot be chunked i n any other way, because the sentence already contains the anaphora ekalee men . . . ekalee de. I f instead o f kaleon Herodotus had written ekalee de once again, he would not have brought out the hierarchy o f the various information units: kaleon and the complements and clauses depend ing from it explain why Croesus used the epithets o f Zeus given i n the anaphora. The constituents ton men epistion kaleon together are Topic o f a newclause in which the dioti clause is Focus. Similarly, ton de helaireion is Topic and the hos clause Focus. 26
Chunking of Ixirger Segments Chunking is not only a strategy used to help the readers/listeners to process comfortably the contents o f a clause complex or sentence, it can also be applied to larger segments. Its function there is basic ally the same: it helps the reader/listener to keep track o f the devel opments as the stoiy is told. T w o major strategies to achieve this are resumptive, sentence-initial hos clauses and resumptive, paratactic men de clauses (for the latter, see Muller (1980) 76-8). 2
I will illustrate this by means o f the following passage, ' which for the readers' convenience I interrupt with comment on the clauses containing one o f these two strategies. All o f the five clauses o f which the Greek is quoted between brackets contain given and inferable information, sometimes only given information. (14a)
26 27
[5.12.1] There were two Paeonians called Pigres and Mastyes, who wanted to rule Paeonia as tyrants. When Darius returned to Asia, Pigres and Mastyes went to Sardis, bringing their sis ter, who was a tall, beautiful woman. [2] They waited until Darius had established himself just outside the Lydian city, and did the following (τοιόνδε). They dressed their sister in the best clothes they had and sent her to fetch water; as well as carry ing a jar on her head, she was leading a horse with the reins around her arm, and was also spinning flax. [3] As the woman passed by (ώς δέ παρεξήιε ή γυνή), Darius' interest was aroused.
Cf. (5.98.2 (γενόμενα repeats έγένετο). Translation is YVaterfield's, with some modifications.
68
SIMON R. SLINGS
It is not given that the girl passed Darius, but it is o f course inferable from the preceding description o f her being dressed up and sent off and o f her brothers watching Darius that she was meant to do so. Therefore this clause has a low information load. I f we examine the clause i n its broader context, two things should be noted. First, the story had been slowed douai by the description o f the girl's preparation (this had been announced by means o f epoiesan toionde i n 12.2), and it now regains its speed. Epoièsan toionde probably marks this description as an embedded sequence (cf. below on (15b)), so there is a ΙΌΡ at the has clause. Second, Darius, who is one of the Discourse Topics but has been temporarily lost sight of, is retrieved in the main clause (epimeles toi Dareiôi egenelo), probably as Focus.'*'" He will be the main Discourse Topic until the end o f 12.3. So this is a point in the story at which there are several changes at the same time, and I would hazard the guess that the has clause with its low information content helps the reader/listener to 'process comfortably' (cf. Brown and Yule as quoted above, in the discussion o f (1)), i n this case not the clause but the story. (14b)
Darius' interest was aroused, because (γαρ) her actions were not typically Persian or I.ydian, or indeed Asian in general. As his interest was aroused (επιμελές δέ ώς οί έγένετο), he sent some of his personal guards after her.
The second has clause i n 12.3, epimeles de has hoi egeneto, contains onlygiven information. I t serves as a sort o f tail/head link, however in this case not with the preceding information unit but with the ear lier clause (epimeles toi Dareiôi egeneto), which is on the same level w i t h it: after epimeles toi Dareiôi egeneto there is a PUSH, marked by the particle gar, opening an embedded sequence i n which the cause o f Darius' interest is given. Note that i n the embedded sequence Darius, who had just been presented as a renewed Discourse Topic, is again lost sight of. After the POP the has clause resumes the last clause before the PUSH. This is o f course ring composition; we shall sec presently thai ring composition is a highly necessary strategy i n order to help the reader/listener keep track o f the main story line. The left-dislocation o f epimeles is caused, I presume, by the wish
2 B
1 would regard επιμελές τω Δαρείω as complex Focus, rather than taking επιμελές as single Focus, which would make τω Δαρείω pragmatically unmarked OX'), and its position before rather than after the predicate irregular.
ORAL STRATEGIES I N T H E LANGUAGE OF HERODOTUS
69
to make the tail/head link with the clause before the embedded sequence as clear as possible. This strategy makes the has clause proper virtually devoid o f content. T h e point in the story is doubly crucial. Not only is there a POP, and therefore a resumption o f the narrative line and a reintroduc tion o f Darius as Discourse Topic, but this is also where Darius first comes into action. (14c)
he sent some of his personal guards after her, with orders to observe what the woman did with the horse. |4J These men followed her (οί μεν δη οπισθε εϊποντο), and the girl (ή δ έ ) . . .
It is not given but certainly inferable that the guards obey Darius' orders (it may be the case that the particle dê is here used to underline the self-evidentiality o f their action more often it seems to appeal not to the reader/listener's reason but to his knowledge o f the story as it has just been told so far).-"' T h e last sentence o f 12.3 dealt w i t h three different Discourse Topics: Darius, the girl, and a brand-new Discourse Topic, the personal guards. Therefore another low-information clause is in order. Its form is dictated by the multiplicity o f actors in the story at this point. Again Darius is shelved, and the remaining two Discourse Topics are contrasted by means o f hoi men . . . hë de. (14d)
and the girl (ή δέ), when she got to the river, watered the horse, filled the jar with water, and then retraced her steps, carrying the water on her head, using her arm to lead the horse, and constantly using her spindle. [13.1] Darius was impressed with what his men told him they had seen her doing, on top of what lie had seen with his own eyes, and he gave orders for her to be brought into his presence. When she had been brought (ώς δέ άχθη),
Again the has clause is not entirely given, although the correspon dence agein autën ekeleue : akhlhë should be noted. It is in any case inferable. In the preceding sentence Darius had again been reactivated, and he had remained sentence Topic throughout. The scene
*' There is, besides, the following to consider. *μέν δέ is not a possible particle cluster in Greek (cf. Slings (1997b) 107 n. 17). Therefore alternatives have to be found. It is normally thought that κ α ι . . . μεν and α λ λ ά . . . μεν step into the breach. But with forms of the pronoun ό both arc extremely rare at the beginning of the sentence in Herodotus. It would seem therefore that ό μεν δη is the 'default value' whenever two Discourse Topics are to be contrasted in two successive clauses.
70
SIMON R. SLINGS
is now set for the denouement. Note that there is necessarily a lapse of" time between the action o f the previous sentence and the one o f this clatise. (14e)
When she had been brought (ως 6έ άχθη), her brothers (who had been watching the proceedings from somewhere close by) were Uiere as well. Darius asked where she was from, and the young men answered that they were Paeonians, and that she was their sister. [2] Darius asked who the Paeonians might be, and whereabouts they lived, and why they had come to Sardis. They replied that they had come to submit themselves to him, that Paeonia was a settled country on the River Strymon, not far from the Hellespont, and that they were originally Teucrian emigrants from Troy, [3] They told him all these details (ot μεν δη ταΰτα έκαστα ελεγον), and Darius (ό δέ). . .
Again, two Discourse Topics are contrasted by means o f a men de. . . de complex. The men de clause consists entirely o f given information (tauta hekasta is probably a slightly ironical authorial comment, but a neatly hidden one). T h e situation is similar to the first lids clause in 12.3, discussed after (14a): the detailed reply had necessarily slowed down the pace o f the story, and again Darius has to be retrieved from memory. (14f)
[3] They told him all these details (οι μεν δή ταΰτα έκαστα έ'λεγον), and Darius (ό δέ). . . asked them i f all the women there were as industrious as their sister. They eagerly replied that they were: all their actions had in fact been designed to lead pre cisely to this point.
We have seen in the story paraphrased above that at all major turns, resumptive strategies are used in order to assist the reader/listener to process it comfortably. A t all major turns, that is, except one: Darius' reaction to the report o f the guards who had been follow ing the girl (13.1). Here there is a signal absence o f chunking strate gies: ihdmazdn de ho Dareios ta te ekouse ek ton kalaskopdn kai la aulas horn, agein aulen eketeue heautdi es opsin. Here it is the sudden reappearance of Darius as Discourse and sentence Topic that creates, as it were, a new paragraph. There is some resumption, but it is to be found in the two relative clauses ta te ekouse ek ton kalaskopdn kai ta autos hdra. I n the first, we are told by implication that the guards who had been following the girl came back to report, and in the second we are brought back to 12.2. The participle thdmazon points backwards to epimeles tdi Dareioi egeneto, and to its repetition epimeles de has hoi
ORAL
S T R A T E G I E S IN T H E L A N G U A G E
71
OF HERODOTUS
egeneto, but only partly so, since he was not only impressed (tlwmazon) by what he had seen but also by the guards' report. This, then, looks much more like a written strategy' than an oral one, and it is certainly no coincidence that oral strategies are absent at the most important point i n the story.
Ring Composition T h e whole story is itself presented as an embedded sequence. 1 will now quote the surrounding segments: (15a)
Δαρεϊον δέ συνήνεικε πρήγμα τοιόνδε ΐδόμενον έπιθυμήσαι έντείλασθαι Μεγαβάζω Παίονας έλόντα άνασπάστους ποιήσαι εκ της Ευρώπης ές την Άσίην. (5.12.1) It so happened that Darius saw the following, which made him wish to order Megabazus to round up the Paeonians and deport them from Europe to Asia.
(15b)
Ένθαυτα Δαρείος γράφει γράμματα Μεγαβάζω. τον έλιπε έν τη Θρηίκη στρατηγόν, εντελλόμενος έξαναστήσαι έξ ήθέων Παίονας και παρ' έωυτόν άγαγειν και αυτούς και τά τέκνα τε και τάς γυναίκας αυτών. (5.14.1)
Then Darius wrote a letter to Megabazus, the military com mander he had left in Thrace, ordering him to uproot the Paeonians from their native land and bring them to him, together with their children and women. Note the verbal correspondences: apart from the names o f Darius, Megabazus and the Paeonians, the two forms o f enteilomai; anaspastous poiesai in (15a) is varied by exanastesai ex etheon i n (15b). I n (15a), the story to be told is referred to by means o f pregma toionde. This strongly suggests that the story itself is an embedded sequence, with a P U S H at the beginning o f (14a), where the presentative sentence en Pigres kai Mastitis andres Paiones should be noted, and a POP at. the beginning o f (15b). I t is perhaps the case that this POP is marked by the adverb enthauta, which when placed at the beginning of a sentence often marks an important new stage i n a story (Muller (1980) 38). R i n g composition i n Herodotus has often been studied, so a 30
3 0
See especially Immerwahr (1966) 54-8; Beck (1971); and for an analysis of the use of tenses in ring composition, Rijksbaron (1988). See also Boedeker, this vol ume (Ch. 5, note 22, p. 104) as well'as de Jong (Ch. 11), pp. 260-1.
72
SIMON R .
SLINGS
detailed treatment is superfluous here. But two general points about it should be stressed. T h e first is its importance i n the hierarchical structuring o f the text. I borrow the following example and its treat ment from Slings (1997b) 103-4: (16)
(d) έσέβαλε μεν νυν στρατιήν κ α ι ούτος, έπείτε ήρξε. ές τε Μίλητον και ές Σμύρνην, και Κολοφώνος τό άστυ ειλε. (ο) ά λ λ ' ουδέν (c) γαρ μέγα ά π ' α υ τ ο ύ ά λ λ ο έργον έγένετο β α σ ι λ ε ύ σ α ν τ ο ς δυών δ έ ο ν τ α τεσσεράκοντα έ'τεα, (b') τούτον μεν παρήσομεν τοσαύτα έπιμνησθέντες, "Αρδυος δέ τοΰ Γύγεω μετά Γύγην βασιλεύσαντος μνήμην ποιήσομαι. (d) Ούτος δέ Πριηνέας τε εΐλε ές Μίλητόν τε έσέβαλε. (1.14.4-15.1)
(a) Once Gyges was king, he sent a military expedition against Miletus and Smyrna and captured Colophon. (/;) However, (c) since he achieved nothing else of significance during the thirtyeight years of his kingship, (//) we will say no more about him beyond what ΐ have already said, and I ' l l mention his son Ardys who succeeded him. (d) Ardys captured Priene and attacked Miletus. The embedding sequence consists o f (16«) and (\6d)—note the sim ilarity i n verbs and tenses (esebale, hale) i n both o f these clauses. The embedded sequence (\6bcb') is set off from it by a change i n tense (the futures i n [\6b')) and in person (first singular and first plural). The first person plural also points to an interactionality between author and reader: in a conversation one might say 'Well, we'll skip him, won't we?'. The point o f the embedded sequence is, of course, to replace one Discourse Topic (Gyges) with another (Ardys). There is a deictic shift after the POP: touton i n (166') refers to Gyges, liontos in ( 1 6 i ) to Arclys. A n d finally the P U S H replaces a narrative with auctoria! comment, at the POP the narrative is resumed. The function o f the ring composition is here manifest: it sets off hierarchically lower material, i n which the author explains why he is substituting one Discourse Topic for another, from the main line of the story. I n (15a) and (15b) ring composition has a similar aim: it marks the story about the Paeonian girl and her brothers as hier archically subordinate to Darius' order to Megabazus to transport the Paeonians from Europe to Asia. * 1
,l
1
The thematic importance of the Paeonians for Herodotus' work as a whole can hardly be overestimated. We first hear about them (apart from a mention in passing in a geographical passage. 4.49.1) in an excursus in 5.1, when the first Greek city on the European continent, Perinthus, has been conquered by the Persians. The story of their transportation from Europe to Asia, already thematic
ORAL STRATEGIES I N T H E LANGUAGE OF HERODOTUS
73
T h e second point to be made about ring composition is that it is not a typical propensity o f the archaic mind—whatever value might be attached to such an abstract concept, but a very common phe nomenon in spoken discourse, more in particular in situations where a speaker is given the floor for a longer stretch o f discourse. Clusters of information units need to be organized in such a way that their position within the entire discourse is easy to understand for the addressee. R i n g composition helps speakers to do just that. A com pleted ring functions as a signpost, helping the addressee to keep track o f the line o f thought. But r i n g composition is not just a help: it is a highly necessary ingredient o f speech. Precisely because speech consists o f juxtaposed information units, there must be a clearly rec ognizable principle o f organizing blocks o f information units. 42
Keeping 'Track of Discourse 'Topics Another feature o f Herodotus' style, related to repetition as it chunks and surrounds segments, is repetition within segments used to assist the reader/listener in identifying Discourse Topics once they have been introduced. The following passage, again an embedded sequence (plus a tail/head link that functions as a POP to the main line o f the narrative) illustrates this. Darius returns to Persia, having appointed Otanes commander o f the coastal regions o f Asia M i n o r . (17)
τοΰ τον πατέρα Σισάμνην βασιλεύς Καμβύσης γενόμενον των βασιληίων δικαστέων, οτι έπί χρήμασι δίκην άδικον έδίκασε, σφάξας άπέδειρε πασαν την άνθρωπηίην, σ π α δ ί ξ α ς δέ αυτού το δέρμα ιμάντας έξ αυτού εταμε και ενέτεινε τον θρόνον ές τον ΐζων έδίκαζε· έντανύσας δέ ό Καμβύσης άπέδεςε δικαστήν είναι άντι τοΰ Σισάμνεω, τον άποκτείνας άπέδειρε, τον π α ί δ α τού Σισάμνεω, έντειλάμενός οι μεμνήσθαι έν τω κατίζων θρύνω δικάζει. Ούτος ων 6 'Οτάνης, 6 έγκατιζόμενος ές τούτον τον θ ρ ό ν ο ν , τότε δ ι ά δ ο χ ο ς γ ε ν ό μ ε ν ο ς Μ ε γ α β ά ζ ω τ η ς σ τ ρ α τ η γ ί η ς Βυζαντίους τε ειλε κτλ. (5.25.1 -26)
in itself, comes right after Histiacus has been given Myrcinus (5.11.2), which wilJ eventually lead to the Ionian revolt and thus to the great conflict between Persians and Greeks: it reads as a foreshadowing of the fate of the Eretrians after the same Ionian revolt (6.119.4). And the Paeonians return to their original area directly after the arrival of the Athenian ships, which άρχή κακών έγένοντο (5.97.3, with a clear allusion to //. 5.63). ' Of. Slings (2000) 10-15 and 25 for a more fundamental critique of this term. !
74
SIMON R. SLINGS
whose father Sisamncs, who had been one of the royal judges, Cambyses, because he had taken a bribe to deliver an unfair verdict, had slit his throat and flayed off all his skin; having flayed off his skin he had thongs made out of it and he strung with them the chair on which he had used to go and sit to deliver his verdict; having strung it Cambyses appointed to be a judge instead of Sisamnes, whom he had flayed after having killed him, Sisamnes' son, telling him to remember on what chair he would go and sit to deliver his verdict. This Otanes, the man who used to go and sit on diat chair, then having become the successor of Megabazus' command took Byzantium and etc. Syntactically speaking, the embedded sequence consists o f one long digressive relative clause, which has definitely reached its end at houtos on ho Otanes. This shows that the whole sequence is intended to introduce Otanes further to the reader/listener. T h e relative clause is chunked twice by means o f participial tail/head link: spadixas de, (note the careful variation in the choice o f words here; not only apedeire: spadixas, but also pasan ten anthropeen: to derma) and entanusas de.™ A t the start o f this passage, there are three main Discourse Topics: Darius, Megabazus (Otanes' predecessor as commander o f the coastal regions), and Otanes, who had just been introduced as a New Topic. In the embedded sequence, three more Discourse Topics are referred to: Otanes' father Sisamnes, the judicial chair, and the previous Persian king Cambyses. Let us examine how each o f the three, as well as the relatively new Discourse Topic Otanes, are presented. Sisamnes is first identified as the father o f Otanes (tou tan patera Sisamnen), next by means o f the accusative followed by the nominative (ton patera Sisamnen basileus Kambuses) as target o f some as yet unspecified action o f Cambyses, and then as a former royal judge. After this information we hear the action Cambyses took against Sisamnes i n great detail. .After the story is over Sisamnes is referred to with his full name plus a digressive relative clause (anti tou Sisamneo, ton apokteinas edeire), and again his full name is given when Otanes is reactivated as Discourse Topic (ton patera tou Sisamneo).
Xi
' One may well wonder i f this was felt by Herodotus' readers/listeners to be still a subordinate clause until the very end, but it seems quite arbitrary to me to print a high point before evtavucoic, 8e, as most editors do. It is in the nature of spoken language that there is a grev area between main clause and subordinate clause (cf. Slings (1994) 414-20; (2000) 23-4), and it won't do to force this clause (or clause complex, rather) onto the Procrustean bed of the syntax of the written language.
ORAL STRATEGIES I N T H E LANGUAGE OF HERODOTUS
75
The throne is first mentioned as a more or less inferable entity (ton thrown es ton hizon edikaze) when Cambyses reupholsters it; since Sisamnes is expressly introduced as a judge, this presupposes a spe cial throne. Next, it is mentioned by Cambyses i n the advice he gives Otanes (enteilamenos hoi memnesthai, en tdi kathizdn thronoi dikazei). A n d finally, after the POP at houtos on ho Otanes, it serves to secure the identification o f Otanes (ho enkathizomenos es touton ton thrown). * By contrast, Cambyses is simply referred to as basileus Kambuses. Although he is clause Topic for most o f the embedded sequence, there is no Topic expression, except once as ho Kambuses (after a rel ative clause which first identifies the throne). He has long remained inactive as a Discourse T o p i c (he had been mentioned more or less in passing at 4.165.3 and 4.166.1), but since he had played such an important part i n Herodotus' history, very little is needed to reacti vate h i m . As for Otanes, I have already noted that the whole embedded sequence is i n fact meant to introduce him. He is first mentioned simply by his name, which is the antecedent o f the relative clause in which the embedded sequence consists—by implication, the embed ded sequence identifies h i m as son o f Sisamnes. W i t h i n the embed ded sequence, he is indeed presented as such (ton paida ton Sisamneo) and he remains an active Discourse Topic after that (hoi; unexpressed subject o f dikazei). After the POP, he is formally identified as clause Topic by means of houtos on ho Otanes (cf. the introduction o f Candaules at (2a)), and the story told i n the embedded sequence is resumed i n order that there can be no mistake whatsoever about his identity (ho enkathizomenos es touton ton thrown). 34
3
This is i n fact a double tail/head link: houtos on ho Otanes connects the sequence after the POP w i t h the embedded sequence, because as we saw Otanes had already been an active Discourse Topic before it. The participial phrase about h i m (atypical i n that it is a sttbstantivated, not a circumstantial participle that is used i n a tail/head link) resumes die second half o f the embedded sequence. There is, to the modern reader, a certain fullness of references here. For example, instead o f anti tou Sisamneo, ton apokteinas edeire, ton
M
Compare τον θρόνον ές τον ϊζων έδίκαζε with 1.14.3 τον βασιλήιον θρόνον ές τον προκατίζων έδίκαζε. '' Mullcr (1980) 51-5 stresses Herodotus' use of anaphoric pronouns in securing maximum cohesion. (
76
SIMON R. SLINGS
paida ton Sisamneo, we would have understood the story equally well had Herodotus simply written ant' aulou ton paida. A n d we would not have missed anything (except a highly pleasant aesthetic experience) i f the subs tan tiva ted participial phrase ho enkathizomenos es touton ton thronon had been omitted. But this is typically a reader's reaction. Herodotus' style is such that he wishes to be readily understood by listeners as well as by readers. A n d for listeners, repetitiveness is a crucial condition for understanding a story about a brand-new Discourse Topic, and a story with so many other Discourse Topics as well. Here again, Herodotus sometimes uses this typically oral strategy when the conditions that make it necessary do not apply, probably in order to heighten the dramatic effect. A particularly noteworthy case is: (17)
"Αδρηστος δέ 6 Γορδίεω τοΰ Μίδεω, ούτος δή ό φονεύς μεν τού έωυτού άδελφεοΰ γενόμενος, φονεύς δέ τοΰ καθήραντος, έπείτε ήσυχίη τών ανθρώπων έγένετο περί τό σήμα, συγγινωσκόμενος ανθρώπων είναι τών αυτός ηδεε βαρυσυμφορώτατος, έπικατασφάζει τω τύμβω έωυτόν. (1.45.3; But Adrastus son of Gordias the son of Midas, he who was the killer of his own brother and the killer of his purifier, when it was quiet around the tomb, realizing that he was the most wretched man among those he knew, slaughtered himself at the tomb.
Adrastus has been an activated Discourse Topic all along; he had not been mentioned i n the very short clause which precedes this sen tence, i n which the tomb is introduced as a Discourse Topic. So there was really no need for h i m to be identified i n such a heavy way. T h e reader/listeners know the name o f his father and his grand father, they know that he had killed his brother and Croesus' son (phoneus de ton. katherantos is metaphorical, because Croesus himself, not his son, had been Adrastus' purifier, but that repeats Adrastus' own words hos. . . ton kalheranta apoldlekos eie at 45.1). Consequently, a strategy devised to keep track o f Discourse Topics is used not i n order to help the reader/listener identify a particular Discourse Topic, but for the sake o f dramatic effect. I t will be clear from the above that Herodotus uses many oral strate gies, and he does so i n a natural way because he has an audience o f listeners i n m i n d . Yet he also uses oral strategies where they are
O R A L STRATEGIES I N T H E L A N G U A G E OF HERODOTUS
77
not required by the needs o f the audience, i n order to highlight important events i n his story. T h a t is to say, although his is basically an oral style, he can use oral strategies as rhetorical devices when it suits h i m . These devices reinforce the oral character o f his language, and show that the choice o f an oral style was a natural one for Herodotus to make, because it suited his subject matter. T o contrast Herodotus and Thucydidcs as typical representatives o f the oral vs. the written style is not tin useful, but it misses an important point to the extent that for either historian, content dictated form. Let me finish by stating a thesis. I t is useless, when dealing w i t h classical Greek authors, to point out a figure o f speech and leave it at that (cf. Slings (1997a)). T h e habit can become positively harmful when such a figure is invested w i t h all sorts o f meanings, although the harm is often diminished when on closer inspection such meanings turn out to be utterly vague ones like 'emphasis'. The only useful way o f studying style is audience-oriented, linguistic and more in particular pragmatic. We should start from the native reader/" who is Chomsky's native speaker, whose feeling for style is conditioned by having read or listened to a great amount o f the literature o f his own culture. We cannot be native speakers o f Greek, but it is our duty as interpreters o f Greek texts to come as close to them as possible by observing what goes on i n natural language use in living languages. O n l y in this way can we hope to achieve anything fruitful at all.
Cf. Fish (1980); Austin (1984).
CHAPTER FOUR
T H E HISTORIES
AND WRITING
Wolfgang Rosier
Herodotus, Thucydides and the New Era of Greek Literacy Thucydides is righdy regarded as an outstanding representative o f the cultural change which took place from the second half o f the fifth century onwards. The Greeks had had an alphabetical script for more than three centuries, but only now had written texts become so plentiful and ubiquitous that one may speak o f a new era. Perceptive men could not help making two related observations. I t was obvious that the significance o f books and writing was increas ing and would continue to do so (just as is the case with the use o f computers in our days). A t the same time, looking back they saw that writing could preserve a logos for a long time. I t was not only great works o f poetry, from H o m e r onwards, which had been pre served i n this way, but also prose such as the book o f Heraclitus,Once these two observations had been made, they inevitably led to a new, 'modern' idea o f the production o f written texts. 1
This new concept is realized and exemplified with especial con sistency and clarity i n the historical writing o f Thucydides. His work is no longer addressed to an audience listening to a recitation, it is directed towards a future reader. T h a t is why Thucydides can describe it as 'a possession for ever' (κτήμα ές αίεί: 1.22). This entails a crucial consequence: its length is no longer dictated by the traditional con straints o f a logos. Previously it was an implicit rule that a written
1
The outlines of this development (with particular regard to Athens) were sketched in by Turner (1952). Since then numerous investigations have substantiated and also refined his account. Thucydides' role in this development had already been clearly established by Harder (1943) 107. - The sophist Hippias (86 Β 6 D-K) was able to read a mass of preserved writ ten texts, and compile from them what he himself' called a 'work new in kind and various' (τοΰτον καινόν και πολυειδή τον λόγον), in which he assembled from works of poetry and prose 'the most important and akin matters' (τά μέγιστα και ομόφυλα). Cf. Snell (1944); Patzer (1986;
80
W O L F G A N G ROSLER
prose text, a syngraplie, was geared to the length o f an oral logos. Thucydides' history throws off this restriction in a radical manner. Although it remained unfinished, it is possible to make a rough estimate o f what its length would have been, had Thucydides lived to finish i t . I t would have been somewhat longer than the only other work from the fifth century which is comparable w i t h Thucydides in this respect: the Histories o f Herodotus. The chronological relationship o f these two works is more complicated than the simple difference of age between the two writers— more than twenty years—would lead one to surmise. When Thucydides conceived the idea for his work and began preparing it, Herodotus' work d i d not yet exist. For, as Thucydides tells us i n his first sentence, he began his account right at the beginning o f the Peloponnesian War. A t that time Herodotus was still busy writing down his own work. This is shown by references to the first two years o f the war in Books Six, Seven and Nine. The summer o f 431 is the terminus post quern for at least a good third o f the Histories (6.91 to the end of the work), and we should not imagine a considerable interval o f time between the composition o f this and the preceding parts o f the work (as I shall be argtiing below). I t is thus plausible that both writers—not only Thucydides, but also Herodotus—had, on the basis o f identical observations, almost simultaneously reached the conclusion that the time was ripe to create an entirely new type o f text. I t was not only Thucydides who was destined to have such an innovative idea. Herodotus too shows himself fully aware o f the historic change i n the conditions o f communication, when he gives an account o f the Greeks' adoption o f the Phoenician alphabet which is basically correct (5.58). I n any case, these considerations led both writers to create a text o f a length regulated by content, and nothing but content, a text intended from the outset to reach readers beyond their own time and age.' 4
•' It is true that the lost mythographical work of Pherecydes of Adieus (approximately contemporary with Herodotus) is reported to have contained 10 books (FGrHist 3). From the mere number of books, however, one can only roughly estimate the size of a work, as can be seen from the fact that Xenophon's Cyropaedia, although containing 8 books, like Thucydides' work, is only half as long as the latter. Already Hecataeus' Genealogiae were relatively long, consisting of 4 books {FGrHist 1 F 1 -35). 6.91 (summer 431); 7.137 (late'summer 430, the latest date mentioned) 7.233; 9.73. Cf. Jacoby (1913) 230 f. For other points of contact between Herodotus and Thucydides, see ch. 7 in this volume. 1
5
T H E HISTORIES
81
AND WRITING
An Old Man 'Takes to Writing Thucydiclcs expected (1.1) that the Peloponnesian W a r would be 'great, and therefore more worthy o f record than all previous wars' (έλπίσας μέγαν τε εσεσθοα και άξιολογώτατον των προγεγενημένων); hence he began taking notes as soon as the war broke out. Less clear is the connection between the (imminent) otitbreak of war and Herodotus' decision to commit his historv to writing. A t this lime Herodotus was already i n his mid-fifties, i n other words he composed his Histories relatively late in life. I t is reason able to assume that he had previously been active as a logographos. ' What this meant is explained by Thucydides when he contrasts his own historiography with texts intended for oral delivery, such as logographoi compose (1.21 f.). According to Thucydides, oral delivery has significant consequences: such texts are angled 'not so much towards telling the truth as towards pleasing the audience' (έπι τό προσαγωγότερον τη άκροάσει ή άληθέστερον), diey are targeted at 'the immediate effect on the audience' (ές τό παραχρήμα ακούει ν).' But this period o f life now lay behind Herodotus. For some time he had been a citizen o f the colony o f T h u r i i i n Magna Graecia; here, at a certain physical distance from events i n the mother country, the expectation that the impending war would be very great, similar to that expressed by Thucydides, might have led h i m to the conclu sion that lecture tours would be difficult, i f not impossible, in war time conditions. 1
In Herodotus' case this conclusion must have led to yet another, more fundamental reflection, one which was connected with his own passing years. As an 'oral historian', Herodotus had accumulated an exceptionally extensive knowledge, one which he alone possessed. He drew on this knowledge for his lectures. He had built it up by means of his own historic (inquiry), i.e., by autopsy and interviews, largely during his numerous travels, often under difficult circumstances. But 8
It cannot be denied that there is no strict evidence for this (Erbse (1979) 139 ff., following others; Johnson (1994) 240 ff.). Jacoby admitted, (1913) 242: 'Eigentliche 'Zeugnisse' haben wir natürlich nicht unci können sie nicht haben', yet added that lecture tours were typical of that period. This is confirmed by Thucydides himself, when he distances himself from the logographoi (see below); we may also, in a wider context, point to the lecturing activities of the sophists. The ephemeral character of logographic texts is highlighted by the antithesis παραχρήμα (κτήμα ές) αίεί. " l'or historié, see Ch. 1 in this volume. 7
W O L F G A N G ROSLER
82
9
most of this knowledge was stored only i n his memory, and even manuscripts which he had written as logographos ες το π α ρ α χ ρ ή μ α άκούειν d i d not have an existence independent o f their author. A t the same time as Thucydides was considering writing a history o f the Peloponnesian War, Herodotus must have decided to provide his body o f knowledge with a life independent o f his own existence, so that it would no longer rely on being disseminated by Herodotus the 'oral historian'. It was clear that this would create a work o f considerable extent, such as there had never been before. But now this seemed possible. The development from orality to literacy had reached the point at which such a work could appear. A t this junc ture Herodotus becomes not only the pater histonae but at the same time it is he, the former logographos, and not Thucydides, who gives birth to an entirely new medium: the massive text written for read ers i n the future. 10
Writing the Histories: Arrangement and Procedure Herodotus' decision to put his stock o f knowledge into written form for posterity posed a fundamental question: how should this knowl edge be 'organized' i n the text? O r a l lectures such as Herodotus had been used to giving must always have dealt w i t h a more limited sub ject matter. N o w he was embarking upon a completely new enter prise. Herodotus solved the problem by establishing a main theme, the conflict between the Greeks and the barbarians, from the begin nings until the final repulsion o f the Persian invasion i n 479. This was the main road along which he could progress. His knowledge,
It might be an anachronism to picture Herodotus using written notes. He could rely on his memory as can be seen from his account of the pyramid of Cheops (2.125): there is an inscription, he says, recording in Egyptian characters how much has been spent on radishes, onions, and garlic for (as is apparently the meaning) the health of the workers; 'and, as 1 well remember, the interpreter who read out the hieroglyphics told me that 1,600 silver talents had been spent' (iced ώς έμέ εύ μεμνήσθαι τά ό έρμηνεύς μοι επιλεγόμενος τά γράμματα εφη, εξακόσια και χίλια τάλαντα αργυρίου τετελέσθαι). '" The view which I suggest here, which connects the development of Greek lit eracy in the second half of the fifth century with the scale of the Histories and Herodotus' personal situation at the beginning of the Peloponnesian War, has grad ually taken shape over the course of two decades. It is presented here in a con densed form.—As for the readers for whom Herodotus and Thucydides were writing, we should not necessarily imagine diem as reading aloud (cf. Gavrilov (1997)).
T H E HISTORIES
83
AND WRITING
however, extended further than this single huge subject. Ancient crit ics already pointed to the poikilia o f the Histories, and modern crit ics have viewed the combination o f historical narrative with countless digressions and additions, varying i n length and subject matter, as the product o f an uncontrolled appetite for story telling. However, this structure can be shown to be precisely calculated. Herodotus makes this clear at one point in the Histories where one digression branches off into several more (4.28-30). He is writing about the coldness o f Scythia, then about its effect on horses, mules, and donkeys, as well as upon the growth o f horns on cattle, which brings him to the question why mules do not thrive in Elis despite its pleasant climate. A t this point Herodotus realizes that he owes his readers an explanation, and he adds i n lapidary fashion; προσθήκας γαρ δή μοι δ λόγος έξ αρχής έδίζητο ('from the beginning m y logos sought digressions': 4,30.1). The reason behind this digressional structure becomes obvious i f one considers the date and the goals of Herodotus' composition. Tf it was indeed his advancing age that urged h i m to give his knowledge an existence independent o f his own, then omit ting any piece o f it meant consigning it to oblivion. This is why again and again Herodotus turns from the main road, the story o f the conflict between Greeks and barbarians. In this way he incor porates the mass o f additional material which he possessed. What from merely formal analysis appears as a l a c k of discipline' is on the contrary a precisely calculated, highly disciplined plan. 11
12
It is, however, less easy to reconstruct the concrete process o f putting the material into written form. The following hypothesis was suggested by Jacoby i n his epoch-making article 'Herodotus' in the Real-Encyclopadie der classischen Altertumswissenschaft, an entry o f book length which laid the foundations for twentieth-century Herodotean scholarship. He regards the composition o f the Histories mainly as a work o f editing rather than actual writing. T o his mind much o f it is collage, a 'scissors and paste' j o b ('Arbeit mit der Schere'). Herodotus, says Jacoby, tried 'to utilize everything which he had previously presented in lectures' ('alles zu verwenden . . ., was cr bishcr in Vortragen . . . geboten hatte') and 'as far as possible to re-use his Vi
" References in Ricmann (1967) 73 if. See Ch. 11 in this volume. "Jacoby (1913). The quotations which follow arc from coll. 361 and 366. 12
84
WOLFGANG RÖSLER
stock o f lectures i n their existing form' ('den Bestand an V o r t r ä g e n möglichst in der vorhandenen Form zu verwerten'). There is more than one reason to doubt this scenario. Admittedly, there is an ancient parallel for the assumed procedure, in Plato's Pkaedrus, when Socrates caricatures the syngrapheas as someone (278d) who over a long time turns the text over and over, sticks bits together and separates them again (ανω κάτω στρέφων έν χρόνω, προς ά λ λ η λ α κολλών τε και άφαιρών). Herodotus, however, was definitely not like this caricature; as an oral historian he would hardly have given read ings exclusively from manuscripts. A closer parallel can probably be found in the Platonic Hippias' account o f his appearance at Olympia (Hipp. min. 363 c-d): 14
17
. . . εί Ό λ υ μ π ί α ζ ε μεν εις την των Ε λ λ ή ν ω ν πανήγυριν, όταν τά Ό λ ύ μ π ι α ή, άει έπανιών οίκοθεν έξ "Ηλιδος εις τό ιερόν παρέχω έμαυτόν και λέγοντα οτι αν τις βούληται ών αν μοι εις έπίδειξιν παρεσκευασμένον ή, και άποκρινόμενον τω βουλομένω δτι αν τις έρωτα . . .
. . . when I go to Olympia for the festive assembly of the Greeks, whenever the Olympic Games take place, going from my homeland Elis to the sanctuary, and I make an appearance there and give a talk as requested by one, from those that I have prepared for the show, or answer a question put by another. . . I f one deviates from Jacoby's hypothesis and postulates that the entire Histories were actually put into writing i n T h u r i i , this would fit i n w i t h Lattirnore's observations concerning Herodotus' 'progressive style'. H e points out that errors and incomplete references which Herodotus notices as he works on his text are corrected or com pleted at the very point which he just happens to have reached. I n other words, they remain in the text, the text is not reworked Over a long time'. This—along with the (quite rare) instances o f unfulfilled announcements''—indicates a process o f continuous writing pressing towards a conclusion. A n d it is the stylistic unity o f the very work 16
11
Cf. Heitseh (1991). This consideration aside, the general arguments put forward by Dorandi (1991) would yet give us cause to remain sceptical about the postulation of such a procedure. l^attimore (1958). Latdmore seems, however, to be inconsistent in assuming (p. 19) the composition to have taken an extremely long time (about twenty years). 1.106 and 184 (for the recent debate about the announcement of further Assynoi logoi, see Nesselrath (1999) 201 f. and note 25 in ch. I , note 40 in ch. 17 of this volume); 7.213, 15
l!i
17
T H E HISTORIES
85
AND WRITING
that confirms this explanation. Eduard Meyer aptly described this impression, when he called the Histories a work aus einem Guss'.' !
8
'The Histories and Herodotus the Oral Historian Modern critics often pay too little attention to the fact that we cannot get to know Herodotus the oral historian from the Histories, except in an indirect way. This text contains only traces which can with due caution be used to reconstruct the oral Herodotus. Yet the Histories did not themselves provide the text for Herodotus' public appearances. O n the contrary, their composition should be seen as a late break with his past as an oral teller o f tales. The recitation o f the entire work has been calculated to have required at least fifty hours; this makes such a recitation impossible. Equally improbable is the explanation that the Histories were a store o f separate narratives for use in oral recitations. We have already spoken o f the material being organized along a main 'road', i.e., the conflict between Greeks and barbarians. I n what follows we will show more precisely that this arrangement only makes sense i f we presuppose that the author intended the work to be received as a whole, as the result o f an individual act o f reading. 19
20
21
22
A t the beginning o f the Histories the aitie o f the enmity between
!
" Meyer (1901) 244 (= (1944) 227 n. 1). Meyer said the essential in the following two sentences: 'Von KirchhofTs Untersuchungen . . . bleibt als einziges Ergebniss, class die Geschichte der Perserkriege während der ersten Jahre des archidamischen Krieges geschrieben ist. Dies Ergebniss gilt aber für das ganze Werk, da dasselbe nach einer einheitlichen, sorgfältig entworfenen Disposition gearbeitet und durchaus aus einem Guss ist.' Even plainer is Johnson's statement, (1994) 230: ' D i d Herodotus write his history with oral performance in mind? Such has been the almost universal assumption.' An attempt at diis has recently been made by Dorati (2000). For the 'oralily' of the Hulories, see Chs. 1 and 3 in this volume. Flory (1980) 14; Cf. Johnson (1994) 250 f. An early voice (Schöll (1855) 419): 'Nach allem was seit: Creuzm "historischer kunst der Griechen" für die einsieht geschehen ist, wie sinnreich der manniehfallige inhalt sämmtlicher 9 bücher des Herodot in seinen theilen zusammcngeschlungen und zur einheit verbunden ist, wird auch klar, dass in dieser ausarbeitung der schriftsteiler auf ruhig und anhaltend folgende k'ser gerechnet hat.' Today it is still necessary to present virtually the same argument (Johnson (1994) 251): 'The elaborately constructed attempt at unity implies that the author intended the work to be presented as a whole. Yet the size of the work seems to preclude oral performance as a suitable means for such a presentation.' 1!l
2 0
21
2 2
86
W O L F G A N G ROSLER
Greeks and barbarians is considered on two levels. Right away the Proem raises the question 'for what reason they fought each other' (δι' ήν αίτίην έπολέμησαν άλλήλοισι). O n a first level Herodotus recounts a Persian interpretation o f four Greek myths (with a Phoenician appendix), which is designed to show that the Greeks bear the responsibility. H e declines to take sides himself (1.5): 23
Έ γ ώ δέ περί μεν τούτων ουκ έρχομαι έρέων ώς οϋτως ή άλλως κως τ α ΰ τ α έγένετο· τον δέ οίδα αυτός πρώτον ύπάρξαντα αδίκων έργων ές τούς "Έλληνας, τοΰτον σημήνας προβήσομαι ές τό πρόσω του λόγου . . .
Concerning these things 1 will not say that it happened like this or differently; but the man whom I myself know to have first started unjust acts against the Greeks, him shall I point out and then push on with my logos... This takes Herodotus to a second level, where he is able to answer the question o f the aitie on the basis o f his own knowledge. For our purpose i t is important to note the redundant formula used to intro duce the man who first started unjust acts (Croesus). Further empha sis is given by a matching sentence i n the next chapter (1.6): Ούτος ό Κροίσος βαρβάρων πρώτος τών ημείς ΐδμεν τούς μεν κατεστρέψατο Ε λ λ ή ν ω ν ές φόρου άπαγωγήν, τούς δέ φίλους προσεποιήσατο. Κατεστρέψατο μεν "Ιωνάς τε και Αίολέας και Δωριέας τούς έν τη Ά σ ί η , φίλους δέ προσ εποιήσατο Λακεδαιμονίους.
This Croesus was the first of the barbarians of which we have knowl edge, to subject one part of the Greeks to pay tribute; the other part he made his friends. He subjected the Ionians, the Aeolians, and the Dorians of Asia Minor, and made the Lacedaemonians his friends. The strong emphasis on this 'being the first' is a clear indication that the conflict will be followed up beyond Croesus.'""' This thread is then explicitly taken up again after the description o f the conquest of Ionia by Cyrus' troops (1.169): Ουτω δή τό δεύτερον Ίωνίη έδεδούλωτο ('Thus Ionia had been enslaved for the second time'). The transi tion from Cyrus to Cambyses at the beginning o f Book Two pro4
3 3
I am currently preparing a study on this section: 'Der Frauenraub-Mythos der persischen Logioi bei Herodot'. The famous announcement following the first of these passages (1.5), too, con cerns the entire work: Την άνθρωπηίην ών επισταμένος εύδαιμονίην ούδαμά έν τώυτφ μένουσαν, έπιμνήσομαι αμφοτέρων ομοίως (Ί know that human prosperity does not endure, therefore I shall speak of both [great and small cities]'). 24
T H E HISTORIES
AND WRITING
87
vides die opportunity to point out the connection once more (2.1): Τελευτήσαντος δε Κύρου παρέλαβε την βασιληίην Καμβύσης, Κύρου έών παις και Κασσανδάνης της Φαρνάσπεω θυγατρός . . . Ταύτης δη της γυναικός έών παις και Κύρου Καμβύσης "Ιωνας μεν και Αίολέας ώς δούλους πατρωίους έόντας ένόμιζε, επί δε Αϊγυπτον έποιέετο σ τ ρ α τ η λ α σ ί η ν , ά λ λ ο υ ς τε παρ α λ α β ώ ν των ήρχε και δη και Ε λ λ ή ν ω ν των έπεκράτεε.
After the death of Cyrus. Cambyses became king, being the son of Cyrus and Gassandanc, daughter of Pharnaspes . . . Being the son of this woman and of Cyrus. Cambyses regarded the Ionians and the Aeolians as slaves inherited from his father, and he undertook an expe dition against Egypt, taking with him others over whom he ruled and especially those Greeks whom he had in his power. After the narration o f the Egyptian logos, which occupies all o f Book T w o and ends with his discussion o f K i n g Amasis, Herodotus picks up the thread again in a very accurate way (3.1): Έ π Ι τούτον δη τον "Αμασιν Καμβύσης ό Κύρου έστρατεύετο, άγων ά λ λ ο υ ς τε των ηρχε και Ε λ λ ή ν ω ν "Ιωνάς τε και Αίολέας . . .
Tt was against this Amasis that Cambyses, son of Cyrus, mounted an expedition, taking with him others over whom he ruled, and of the Greeks Ionians and Aeolians . . . Thus Greeks do forced service in the army of a king who oppresses them. Most, of Book Four is taken up by the account o f Darius' expedition against the Scythians. Here, too, the Greeks o f Asia M i n o r participate as Persian subjects. Darius crosses the Danube on a bridge constructed o f their ships. Before he returns, the Greeks discuss whether to demolish the bridge in order to prevent the return o f the Persian army (4.137-9). A l l of a sudden, here is an opportunity to liberate Ionia ( έ λ ε υ θ ε ρ ο ΰ ν Ί ω ν ί η ν ) . The Scythians themselves advise (4.136): ά π ι τ ε χ α ί ρ ο ν τ ε ς ε λ ε ύ θ ε ρ ο ι ('Go, rejoicing to be free'). The opportunity, however, to reverse what Croesus and his initial kalastrepsasthai had begun, is not taken. Emphasizing the freedom within reach, Herodotus makes this connection clear. Book Five starts the concentrated narrative o f the Graeco-Persian clashes i n the fifth century, from the Ionian Revolt to the Battle o f Plataeae. T h e Histories end w i t h the liberation o f Ionia, thus reaching a preliminary conclusion to those clashes. This shows that the work was conceived from the beginning with a view to its second half, that it was conceived as a whole. Even the final chapters (9.120-2),
Mi!
WOLFGANG
ROSLER
which have been wrongly seen as evidence dial the work remained unfinished. - are part of the larger plan: at the end the Athenians gather up the remains of the bridge of boats across the Hellespont, over which Xerxes had led his army into Europe in order to conquer Greece. This is a finale with great symbolic power. The fact that one last digression follows, a propos the mention of Artayctes, Persian governor o f Sestos, shows that Herodotus follows the principle o f the organization o f his material consistency to the very end. 2
1
Legem and graphein We have established that Herodotus composed his Histories with future readers in mind. I n the following sections we hope to show that there are further signs of this intention. First let us examine how Herodotus describes his own activity as author of the Histories?' His favourite word for it is doubtless λέγειν. I t is frequently found in contexts such as: τά δέ λέγεται υπό Χαλδαίων, ταΰτα λέγω ('What is told by the Chaldeans, I too say': 1.183) or νοήσας δέ πρότερον αυτός ή άκουσας άλλων λέγω (Ί say this having understood it myself earlier than having heard it from others': 2.104). What. Herodotus 'says' is linked with what others 'say' or 'have said'. One could get the impres sion that this is an oral element preserving the style of his lectures. One should not, however, overlook the fact that Herodotus repeat edly uses γράφειν too: ώς ων Περσέων μετεξέτεροι λ έ γ ο υ σ ι . . ., κατά ταΰτα γράψω ('As one part of the Persians say, I will write it down accordingly': 1.95); ή δ ' ων έμοι δοκέει άξιωτάτη άπηγήσιος είναι, ταύτην γράφω ('What seems to me to be the way most worth telling [of var ious ways to hunt crocodiles] that am I writing down': 2.70); των εγώ είδώς τ ά ούνόματα ού γράφω ('Although I know their names, I am not writing them down': 2.123); τό μεν δή είδος όκοΐόν τι εχει ή κάμηλος, έπισταμένοισι τοΐσι "Ελλησι ού συγγράφω (Ί am not writing down what the camel looks like, since the Greeks know i t ' : 3.103); ταύτα εί μεν έ'στι άληθέως ουκ οιδα, τ ά δέ λέγεται γράφω ('Whether this is really so
2 j
Among others Jacoby (1913) 372 ff. The controversy continues; three recent articles argue that the Histories are complete: Herington (1991), Oswald (1995) 57 fF., and Dewald (1997). In general on the authorial persona, see Ch. 12 in this volume. 2 6
T H E HISTORIES
89
AND WRITING
I do not know; but I am writing down what is said': 4.195); τό ένθεΰτεν ούκ εχω άτρεκέως συγγράψαι οϊ τίνες τών Ιώνων έγένοντο άνδρες κακοί ή αγαθοί έν τη ναυμαχίη ταύτη ('From this point on I cannot write accurately which o f the Ionians proved cowardly or courageous men in this sea battle': 6.14); τάδε δέ κατά τά λεγόμενα υ π ' Ε λ λ ή ν ω ν εγώ γράφω (Ί write what follows on the basis of what is said by the Greeks': 6.53); τούτον αϊτιον γράφω ('This one I write down as guilty': 7.214).*' I f one imagines the situation o f an oral performance, it is imme diately clear that γράφω said by somebody speaking is out o f place; it is addressed to readers. O n the other hand, the interchangeable use o f legein and graphein indicates that both verbs mean the same. I f legein were really to be understood as a reflection o f orality, we would have to admit a tension between two different styles preserved in the Histories. But this option can easily be ruled out: Herodotus knows and applies the metaphorical use o f legein that is paralleled in modern languages: 'to say something in a written text.' Thus we see Herodotus use legein i n the introductory formula o f a letter: "Αμασις Πολυκράτεϊ ώδε λέγει ('Thus says Amasis to Polycrates': 3.40), and above all one may point to 1.124: τά δέ γράμματα έλεγε τάδε ('The letters said this'). 28
29
As one can see, the examples οϊ graphein are found throughout the entire Histories. T h e conclusion, however, that Herodotus did i n fact wish the entire Histories to be regarded as a written work, intended for readers, does not follow from this observation alone. One last example, which has not been cited before, must be adduced here (2.123): έμοι δέ παρά πάντα τον λόγον υπόκειται οτι τά λεγόμενα ύ π ' εκάστων άκοη γράφω ('Throughout my entire logos I act on the prin ciple that I write down whatever is told me as I have heard it'). There is little reason to assume that Herodotus is referring here only to the Egyptian logos, not the entire Histories. For we find compara ble general statements, w i t h identical or similar phrasing, i n two other passages, where it is impossible to believe that they apply to only a section o f the work. One passage has been discussed already
-' Cf. also 1.93: θώματα δ έ γ η <ή> Λυδίη ές συγγραφήν ού μάλα εχει (Tydia has not many wonders worth writing down'). This argument is already found in Rose (1879); cf. Powell (1939) 31 f. It is neglected by Hartog (1980) 292 ΑΓ., esp, 294. For examples from Isocrates. see Usener (1994) 98 ff. 3
a n
MO
W O L F G A N G RÖSLER
(4.30): προσθήκας γαρ δή μοι ό λόγος έξ α ρ χ ή ς έδίζητο ('my logos from the beginning'—which must mean 'the entire logos'); we will discuss the second passage below i n greater detail (7.152): Έ γ ώ δέ οφείλω λέγειν τά λεγόμενα, πείθεσθαί γε μεν ού παντάπασιν οφείλω (καί μοι τοΰτο τό έπος έχέτω ές πάντα λόγον). I a m obliged to say what is said; to believe it, however, I am not i n the least obliged (and this statement shall apply to the entire logos).* 0
Thus there is no reason not to read Herodotus' statement of principle at 2.123 as the author's explicit confirmation o f what we have so far been inferring: Herodotus composed the Histories for future readers, with a clear-cut concept and in a continuous process o f writing. 51
Ixgein ta legomena We have seen on the basis o f a selection o f examples that Herodotus usually states that he says or writes what others say or have said. However, he goes further than this. I n the last o f the discussed pas sages he refers to his obligation 'to say what is said'- even when he believes it to be incorrect. The statement that this rule must applyto his entire logos is connected with two further statements o f the same principle. W e have already cited 2.123; which i n its full form runs as follows: Τοΐσι μεν ν υ ν ϋ π ' Αιγυπτίων λεγομένοισι χράσθω δτεω τά τοιαΰτα πιθανά έστι· έμοΐ δέ παρά πάντα τον λόγον υπόκειται οτι τά λεγόμενα ϋ π ' εκάστων ακοή γράφω. What is said by the Egyptians, that should he use w h o finds it cred ible. T h r o u g h o u t my entire logos I act on the principle that I write down whatever is told me, as I have heard it.
A n d finally 3.9: Ούτος μεν δ πιθανώτερος των λύγων εϊρηται· δει δέ και τον ήσσον πιθανόν, έπεί γε δή λέγεται, ρηθήναι.
:t
" The translation does not distinguish between πάντα τον λόγον (2.123) and πάντα λόγον (7.152; τον does, however, appear in one MS ( M | and in Plut.: ef. Rosen (1997) ad lac). Nouns with πας but without an article where one would expect one, also occur elsewhere in Herodotus (Kühner and Gerth (1898) 633 f.). " Strictly speaking, this one statement (2.123) alone seriously contradicts Jacoby's theory that finished manuscripts were worked into die Histories.
T H E HISTORIES
91
AND WRITING
The most credible version is recounted here; but the less credible must also be given, since it is being told. T h e obligation Ί ο say what is said' even when it is not credible is thus one o f the essential principles o f the concept underlying the composition o f the Histories:''- Tt is obvious that it results from the same motivation which we have observed for the digressions. As the latter, it can be inferred from the t i m i n g and the intention o f Herodotus when he wrote clown his Histories. When, at an advanced age, he decided to give to his store o f knowledge an existence inde pendent o f his own, anything omitted would be consigned to obliv ion. Even where Herodotus himself was doubtful, someone else might still, as he puts it, 'make use' o f i t (χρασθαι).* 5
Herodotus and 'Historicizing' His Own Time T h e Histories contain a fairly large number o f passages (about thirty) which are striking because Herodotus speaks o f his own time in the past tense. They are easy to recognize because an indicator o f time such as έ π ' εμεί), κ α τ ' έμέ, ές έμέ or μέχρι(ς) έμεΰ ('in my own time', 'until my own time') is used with a past tense, usually the imperfect, or the equivalent participle. Occasionally one encounters a present tense, but this is very much the exception. Thus the usage is obvi ously deliberate. Let us take a closer look at three o f these passages. Among the dedicatory gifts which Amasis sent to Greece (2.182) were two wooden statues for Hera o f Samos which represented him self and 'stood i n the great temple until my own time, behind the door' (αϊ έν τω νηω τω μεγάλω Ίδρύατο έτι και το μέχρις έμεΰ οπισθε των θυρέων). One is inclined to take this to mean 'when I last visited Samos'. Because Herodotus cannot be sure that there have not been changes, he does not say α ϊ έν τω νηω τω μεγάλω Ίδρύαται έτι και τό ν υ ν . But this explanation would not hold good for a passage like 5.45: H
35
» Cf. 2.125; 3.56; 4.195; 6.53. Cf., in addition to 2.123, 2.146: Τούτων ών αμφοτέρων πάρεστι χρασθαι τοϊσί τις πείσεται λεγομένοισι μάλλον ('As for these two [Dionysos and Pan], people can make use of the version which they will find more convincing*}, What follows is discussed in more detail in Rosier (1991), cf. Johnson (1994;· 252 n. 58 and Naiden (1999). The present retractatio goes further from a theoretical point of view. * Such a turn of phrase is not alien to Herodotus, e.g., 1.50; 1.69 (very similar); 2.111. 11
92
WOLFGANG
ROSTER
O't 6' α ύ Κροτωνιήται άποδεικνύουσι Καλλίη μεν τ ώ Ή λ ε ί ω εξαίρετα έν γή τή Κροτωνιήτιδι π ο λ λ ά δ ο θ έ ν τ α , τ ά κ α ι ές έμέ ετι ένέμοντο o i Κ α λ λ ί ε ω απόγονοι...
The Crotoniates, on the other hand, point to many select estates on Crotoniate territory given to Callias of Elis. which were still used by Callias' descendants until my own time . . . This cannot be a case o f caution ('this was so when I last visited Croton; 1 do not know what may have happened since'). Croton is not far from T h u r i i , where Herodotus was writing: he would have known i f any o f the heirs had lost their land. T h e past tense is all the more striking, as the sentence begins w i t h a present tense: 'The Crotoniates point today, i n my own time . . .' This creates an imma nent contradiction: the writer's 'own time' seems to be set both i n the present and i n the past. By accepting the contradiction, Herodotus shows that the use o f the past tense is deliberate. Above all it is important to mention 1.5, one o f the fundamental statements i n the Histories. This is where Herodotus for the first time and with programmatic emphasis pronounces his theory o f historic change, the 'circle o f human affairs' ( κ ύ κ λ ο ς τ ω ν ά ν θ ρ ω π η ί ω ν π ρ η γ μ ά τ ω ν : 1.207): . . . τούτον σημήνας προβήσομαι ές τό πρόσω του λόγου, ομοίως μικρά και μεγάλα άστεα ανθρώπων έπεςιών. Τά γ ά ρ τό π ά λ α ι μεγάλα ήν, τ ά π ο λ λ ά αυτών σμικρά γέγονε· τ ά δ έ έ π ' έμέο ήν μεγάλα, πρότερον ήν σμικρά.
. . . him shall I point out, and then push on with my logos, dealing equally with small and great cities. For those that were once great, most of them have become small, and those that were great in my time, had previously been small. This example may even more clearly show the contrast o f tenses within one sentence. Herodotus re-creates himself as a figure o f the past, to which he, as the author, looks back. T h e writer's glance back at himself coincides with the perspective o f the future reader, whose perception o f the Histories as a work from the past is antici pated i n the text. One hardly needs to add that this would have been quite impossible in an oral deliver)'. Here is a further indica tion o f the work's late date o f composition and its author's novel objective. Even i f the subtle technique o f making himself a figure o f the past is not carried out w i t h perfect consistency, it deserves atten tion as an important-—and, from a theoretical point o f view, espe cially sophisticated—part o f the plan which Herodotus developed for the composition o f his work.
T H E HISTORIES
93
AND WRITING
The purpose o f this strategy is clear. I t was Herodotus' intention to cut, as it were, the Histories loose from the time and the circum stances i n which they were written. T h e 'historicizing' o f the work makes it, paradoxically, appear to have been written both by Herodotus and after Herodotus. This creates the impression o f a vacuum i n time during which the Histories came into being. Once wc have grasped that this smoke screen was put up deliberately, we immediately under stand the distance which Herodotus puts between himself and the contemporary event o f the Peloponnesian W a r — a t the few places where he refers to it. We can read i n Thticydides (2.8) how the out break o f this war put all the Greeks into a state o f the highest emo tional excitement. W e do not see much o f this i n Herodotus: the anger o f the hero Talthybius 'awoke once again a long time there after, i n the war between the Peloponnesians and the Athenians ( χ ρ ό ν φ δέ μ ε τ έ π ε ι τ α π ο λ λ ώ έπηγέρθη κ α τ ά τον Π ε λ ο π ο ν ν η σ ί ω ν και Αθηναίων πόλεμον: 7.137). This sounds as i f he were speaking o f some quite distant war. A n d elsewhere we read (9.73): There has been a friendship between Deceieans and Spartans dating back to the mythical past, 'so that even in the war which broke out many years afterwards between the Athenians and the Peloponnesians, when the Lacedaemonians laid the rest o f Attica waste, they did not touch Decelea' (οΰτω ώστε και ές τον πόλεμον τον ύστερον πολλοΐσι έτεσι τούτων γενόμενον Α θ η ν α ί ο ι σ ί τε καΐ Πελοποννησίοισι, σινομένα>ν την άλλην Άττικήν Λακεδαιμονίων, Δεκελέης άπέχεσθαι). 5,1
The Function of the Histories Several i n d i c a t o r s c h r o n o l o g y , organization o f the material, and commitment to legein ta legomena have shown that the Histories were put into written form because Herodotus fell the need to give his knowledge an existence independent o f his own, and to preserve it for posterity. This conclusion, however, need not rely on indirect evidence. Herodotus spells it out himself very clearly and i n a very prominent place, the opening sentence o f the Histories: Η ρ ο δ ό τ ο υ Άλικαρνησσέος Ίστορίης άπόδεςις ήδε, ώς μήτε τά γενόμενα έξ ανθρώπων τω χρόνω έςίτηλα γένηται, μήτε έργα μεγάλα τε και θωμαστά, τά
3 6
The contemporaneity of the Peloponnesian War likewise remains unexpressed in 6.98.
94
W O L F G A N G ROSLER
μεν "Ελλησι, τά δέ βαρβάροισι άποδεχθέντα, ά κ λ ε α γένηται, τά τε ά λ λ α και δΐ' ήν αίτίην έπολέμησαν άλλήλοισι. This is the publication of the inquiry by Herodotus o f Halicarnassus, so that what has been done by men shall not be lost w i t h time nor shall great and amazing deeds, some done by Greeks, some by bar barians, be forgotten among other things for what reason they fought each other. 3
M a n y interpretations have been suggested for this sentence. ' I f we look at i t i n the light o f what we have observed so far, i t turns out a clear and precise statement about the author's central motivation. This, then, was the function o f the His tones: to prevent oblivion, to ensure lasting knowledge (kleos). T h a t is why, at the end o f his life, Herodotus wrote a work such as had never existed before, the work that we possess. This statement—that we possess the work—is more than a mere truism. I t points to the fact that Herodotus, the former logographos, achieved his objective. T h e information which he had assembled and had until then stored i n his head and passed on orally, this knowl edge has by the act o f writing it down, and by that act alone, been saved from oblivion. T h a t the Histories i n their own time were no α γ ώ ν ι σ μ α έ ς τ ό π α ρ α χ ρ ή μ α ά κ ο ύ ε ι ν has already been shown. But we may just as well apply Thucydides' contrasting description o f his own work to his predecessor: Herodotus' Histories already were intended as a κ τ ή μ α έ ς α ί ε ί , a 'possession for ever' and so they are.
For a discussion, see Ch. 1 in this volume.
H E R O D O T U S A N D HIS W O R L D
CHAPTER FIVE
EPIC H E R I T A G E A N D M Y T H I C A L PATTERNS I N H E R O D O T U S Deborah Boedeker
T h e Histories is a work o f monumental originality, and one that springs from monumental traditions. Readers o f Herodotus both ancient and modern have found the imprint o f Homeric epic on all levels o f his text, from the occasional use o f special poetic words, to literary tropes such as set speeches and dialogues, to overall range and purpose. Herodotus occasionally refers to epic characters and deeds; moreover, story-patterns familiar from myths emerge from time to time i n the Histories—but attributed to historical characters and situations. Without wishing to minimize the extent to which Herodotus is a fifth-century author w i t h contemporary intellectual and political concerns, I will consider i n this chapter how epic and mythical traditions interact with his work, both by shaping the narrative o f events and by influencing the scope and style o f the work as a whole.
Herodotus Hornerikotatos? I n the second century B C , an elegant elegiac inscription listing Halicarnassus' many claims to fame was set up i n Herodotus' hometown. Prominent among the sources o f civic pride is a list o f literary figures, headed by Herodotus, who is described as 'the pedestrian (i.e. prose) H o m e r o f historiography' (ton pezon en historiaisin Homeron). A few generations later, Dionysius o f Halicarnassus, as i f paraphrasing the inscription, wrote that Herodotus produced pezen phrasin 'pedestrian speech' that resembled 'the most powerful (kratiste) poetry' (On Thucydides chap. 23; 6.865). Other ancient critics seem to have agreed 1
1
Ci". Isagers ed.il.io fmnceps (1999), with further commentary by Lloyd-Jones (1999).
98
DEBORAH BOEDEKER
with Dionysius. T h e first-century C E author o f On the Sublime called Herodotus (along with Stesichorus, Archilochus, and Plato) homenkotatos 'most Homeric'. I n the late second century C E , the rhetorician Hermogenes o f Tarsus wrote that Herodotus 'uses all kinds o f mythical concepts and poetic diction throughout' (kai gar tais ennoiais mulhikais skhedon hapasais kai lei lexei poielikei kekhretai diholou; Id. 408 Rade). M o d e r n critics too have not failed to find large- and smallscale reflections o f Homeric epic in the Histories* Aristotle, however, w r i t i n g a century before the Halicarnassus inscription, emphasized the differences between epic and historiography. He maintained that Herodotus' work, with its focus on the particular (what actually happened) rather than the general (what would plausibly happen), would still be history and not poetry— which Aristotle considered a more 'philosophical' genre—even i f the Histories were put into verse (Poetics 9, 1451a b). Aristotle also asserted that Herodotean history lacks the kind o f organic unity that characterizes poetry (Poetics 23, 1459a). For example, when Herodotus reports that the battles o f Himera i n Sicily and Salamis near Athens were fought on the same day (7.166), Aristotle declares that the two victories have merely a chronological connection i n the Histories, for they do not share a single goal (telos). Aristotle's criticism has itself been called into question, yet clearly the lines have long been drawn between sophisticated readers of Herodotus who view him as a 'poetic' historian, and those who emphasize the gulf between history and poetry.' A look at convergences and divergences i n a few salient areas will help us assess both o f these perspectives. 2
1
5
1
O n the broadest level, the parallels are very significant. The Histories shares both the Iliad's focus on a great war fought by a coalition o f Hellenes and the Odyssey's interest i n distant places and foreign cus-
2
(Longinus) Subi 13.3. Cf. other ancient sources on Herodotus and Homer, esp. Strabo 1, p. 18; Lucian De hist, comer. 14; more generally, Quintilian 10.1.27 and
10.1.31: hisloria est proximo, poelis el quodammodo carmen solution. ;!
See e.g.. Asheri (1988) lx-lxi for a concise list of resemblances: also Stambler (1982) 210-12, Huxley (1989), and Herington (1991b). Brillante (1990) 104-5, however, points out that myth is also concerned with particulars. For a critique of Aristotle's position, cf. Gomme (1954) 73-6, arguing that Herodotus 'regularly forsakes the chronological for a logical order' and is thereby 'the "poet'' of his plot'. For Herodotus and tragedy, see Ch. 6 in this volume. On Herodotus' own criticism of poetry, see Bocdeker (2000) 103-6. 1
3
6
EPIC H E R I T A G E A N D M Y T H I C A L PATTERNS I N HERODOTUS
99
toms; as more than one critic has discovered, Herodotus i n some ways resembles the curious and well-travelled Odysseus. Moreover, both epic and the Histories are concerned with preserving memory and conferring glory (kleos). I n Homeric epic, characters and narra tor alike are well aware o f the fame that accrues to those who are remembered, presumably i n song: Penelope worries that Telemachus, who has slipped off to sea and is now threatened by the suitors on his return, will not even leave behind a name for himself (Od. 4.710); Hector, challenging the best o f the Achaeans to light h i m , hopes that he will kill his man and his kleos will never perish (//. 7.91). Homer's Helen at one point even uses the idea o f future poetic fame to explain the events 'happening' in epic: she laments to Hector that Zeus placed an evil fate on Paris and herself so that they would become objects o f song (aoidimoi) i n the future (//. 6.356-8)." Herodotus stresses even more directly the importance of his nar rative for preserving fame. I n the Proem to the Histories he explains the veiy purpose o f his work as the preservation o f memory, '. . . so that human accomplishments may not become faded (exitela) with time, nor may great and marvellous achievements, some performed by Greeks and some by barbarians, be without their fame (akled)'.' Though the importance o f preserving fame is common to both genres, they point to slightly different objects o f kleos. I n epic, kleos is presented as primarily important for the heroes, the characters who will be remembered, whereas Herodotus highlights the great achievements (ergo) of Greeks and barbarians, and more generally 'the things that have come about from human beings' (ta genomena ex anthrdpori). Herodotus' concern with preserving a record o f events contrasts somewhat with epic's interest i n providing its heroes w i d i immortality. 7
J
10
7
For Odysseus-like characteristics of the Herodotean narrator, see Nagy (1990) 231-3 and Marincola (1997b). Herodotus' ethnographic passages differ greatly from those in the Odyssey, however, not only in the details supplied but in the focus they receive in the narrative. Herodotus typically describes a wide range of customs (espe cially sexual and funereal), geographical features and 'wonders' of the natural or human world. The Odyssey also describes the ways of others, but only as they affect Odysseus, whereas Herodotus includes ethnographies of many peoples who never cross paths with his protagonists. See also Cobet, this volume (Ch. 17, pp. 388-9). On the first sentence of Herodotus, see Nagy (1987) with bibliography as well as Bakker, Ch. 1, this volume, with more discussion of kleos (άκλεδ) and έςίτηλα. '" On the fundamental similarity of έργα and γενόμενα here, see Ashcri (1988) xviii. 8
;i
100
DEBORAH BOEDEKER
Another important and obvious distinction between the Histories and epic is reflected in the first words o f each work, which indicate the speaker's source o f knowledge about the past." The two epic invocations, 'The W r a t h sing, goddess, o f Peleus' son Achilles', and 'Sing i n me, Muse, the man o f many turns', call on a source o f knowledge very different from that reflected in the opening clause of the Histories, 'This is the presentation o f the inquiry o f Herodotus of Halicarnassus.' Nonetheless, it is significant that both Herodotus and Homer call attention to their sources o f information—the Muse for Homer, his own investigations for Herodotus—as they begin their narratives. Rather than presenting a wholly mimetic work i n the manner o f drama or fiction, both authors emphasize at the outset that they are telling a story o f past events and rely on sources (in part) external to themselves to do so. Herodotus frequently recalls his use o f and critical relationship to a variety of sources, most o f them oral, i n the course o f his work, whereas the epic poet very seldom mentions his reliance o n the Muse(s)—let alone criticizes the goddess' veracity. Despite these variances, at the beginning o f each work (Iliad, Odyssey, Histories) the narrator signals that he is not 'making it up'. This factor contributes to the sense of a truth that exists independently o f the narrative and serves as a control for it. For all its differences from a Muse-inspired song, Herodotus' text shares with archaic epic the important perception that there is an external referent to the narrative. I n addition to the large-scale resemblances i n theme and purpose, the Histories in some ways sounds like Homeric epic as well. Herodotus' language is a form o f Ionic Greek, which was the literary language typical o f 'scientific' prose works in his day—attested also in die medical treatises o f Hippocrates o f Cos, the geographic writings o f Hecataeus o f Miletus, and the philosophical prose o f Hcraclitus o f Ephesus. This dialect, however, has much i n common as well w i t h the earlier Ionic that is the largest component o f Homer's traditional poetic language (see Hermogenes Id. 336 Rafoe). and sometimes that resemblance comes to the fore in the Histories.
11
Romm (1998) 20: 'No longer can the Muse be invoked as a guarantor of authenticity; human powers of investigation and reason have been called upon to take the place of this reverend goddess.' Thomas (2000) 267 suggests that Herodotus' Proem 'present(s) a daring mixture . . . of Homeric reference and hints of the currently fashionable language of intellectual activity.'
EPIC H E R I T A G E A N D M Y T H I C A L PATTERNS I N HERODOTUS
101
Especially i n the speeches he ascribes to his characters, Herodotus uses a number o f phrases that clearly recall the formulations o f epic. ' I won't hide it away from you or pretend I don't know . . . but I will tell you exactly', says Pythius the wealthy Lydian to Xerxes, who inquired how rich he was (7.28.1). Menelaus says much the same thing to Telemachus, when asked what news he has o f Odysseus: ' I will hide no word o f this from you nor will I conceal i t ' (Od. 4.350). Even more strikingly, Syagrus the Spartan tells Gelon, the tyrant o f Syracuse, that 'Agamemnon would groan aloud' (e ke meg' oimöxeie) i f he heard that Gelon and the Syracusans had seized the leadership o f the Greek forces from the Spartans (Hist. 7.159), just as Nestor says that Peleus would do (e ke meg' oimöxeie) i f he saw all the Achaeans shrinking before Hector (II. 7.125). Herodotus probably did not borrow directly from the Iliad or Odyssey every expression that has an epic parallel, nor was it necessary for his audience to recall specific Homeric passages whenever such a phrase is used especially i f that phrase is the only 'echo' o f epic i n its passage. Expressions such as ' I won't hide the truth from you', or 'So-and-So would groan i f he heard that . . .' might have originated i n epic language but passed into rhetorical commonplaces; they might just as well have come to epic from ordinary speech. For Herodotus' audience such phrases would doubtless have a generally poetic quality (such as Hermogenes Id. 336 Rabe attributes to the Histories), but probably not a specific referent. 12
13
A more developed echo o f epic is found i n Herodotus' use o f the metaphor 'on a razor's edge' (epi xurou akmes) to describe a crisis calling for decisive acdon. Nestor uses the phrase in rousing Diomedes to warn h i m o f the threatening Trojans: Now indeed it stands on a razor's edge for all, whether there will be very great destruction for the Achaeans, or survival. But go now, awaken swift Aias and Phyleus' son, since you are younger, i f you pity me. (Iliad 10.173-6) In Herodotus' account o f the Ionian rebellion, the Phocaean commander Dionysius, exhorting his fellow Ionians to fight the Persians, speaks similarly: l
- The following examples and others are collected in Jacoby (1913) 502-3. " See Giraudeau (1984b) 4-5 for a succinct collection of Homeric images and expressions attested also in Herodotus.
102
D E B O R A H BOEDEKER
Our affairs are on a razor's edge, men of Ionia, whether we will be free or slaves—and these would he runaway slaves. Now therefore i f you are willing to accept hard discipline, there will be toil for you for the moment, but vou will be able to overcome the enemy and be free. (6.11.2) I n this case, the situations are closely parallel: a military leader calls for decisive action i n a moment o f crisis, stating the alternative outcomes ('whether . . . or') and calling for immediate action, as long as his hearer(s) are o f a sympathetic frame o f m i n d ('now . . . i f you'). I n this case and others where the parallels are extensive, the Homeric colouring o f Herodotus' narrative is especially strong, and for many readers may even recall a specific passage i n epic. Another example shows Herodotus' versatility i n using a familiar Homeric expression. Artabanus warns Mardonius that i f he persists i n his foolish plan to lead the Persian army to Greece, those who stay behind 14
will hear that Mardonius, haying done great harm to Persia, was torn apart by dogs and birds somewhere in the land of the Athenians or the Lacedaemonians, i f not even sooner while en route. (7.10 9 3) For Herodotus and his audience these words recall the threatening Iliadic image o f the unburied corpse, mutilated by scavenging animals on the battlefield (Iliad 1.4-5, etc.). Yet i n his ethnographic discussion o f Persian funeral customs, Herodotus reports: It is said that the body of a Persian man is not buried until it has been mauled by a bird or a dog. I know for certain that the Magi do this, because they let it happen in public; but the Persians cover corpses i n wax before burying them in the ground. (1.140) The ethnographic passage emphasizes how Persians differ from Greeks: the M a g i , at least, welcome a post-mortem fate that Greeks fear— the very fate which the Persian Artabanus foresees for Mardonius. Rather than using the Homeric tag consistently, Herodotus adopts it for two quite different effects: underlining cultural differences i n the ethnographic passage, but assuming a common human horror of mutilation by scavengers i n the warning speech o f Artabanus. Both passages, however, rely for their effect on the audience's familiarity w i t h the Homeric m o t i f o f 'dogs and birds'. 53
14
Huber (1965b) makes the point that Herodotus both unconsciously 'continues' Homeric style and deliberately alludes to or borrows from it. See further below. The image of a corpse being prey to dogs, or dogs and birds, is not restricted I:i
EPIC H E R I T A G E A N D M Y T H I C A L PATTERNS I N HERODOTUS
103
O n a larger scale too, extended sections o f the Histories bring to m i n d Homeric passages. The long 'catalogue o f ships' i n the Iliad, describing all the Greek contingents that fought at T r o y (2.494—760), finds an echo i n Herodotus' equally elaborate catalogue o f the units in Xerxes' armada—infantry, cavalry, and fleet—against mainland Greece (7.61-99)."' Equally reminiscent o f a Homeric passage (and one from the same book o f the Iliadl) is Herodotus' elaborate description o f the Dream that disastrously orders Xerxes to invade mainland Greece or suffer dire consequences (7.12-18); o f course the consequences o f Xerxes' expedition will turn out to be disastrous for the Persians. T h e Iliadic Agamemnon too is visited by a deceptive dream, which leads h i m to believe that he will be able to take the city o f T r o y o n that very day; this belief ultimately leads to prolonged fighting and a serious (though not decisive) setback for the Achaeans (//. 2.1-40). I n both these cases, Herodotus seems clearly to have based the pattern o f his narrative on the Iliad. 17
Occasionally Herodotus also echoes the rhythms o f epic. For example, he reports that when the citizens o f Delphi received an oracle before the battle o f Artemisium, directing the Greek allies to pray to the winds, they passed along the advice, and—in a perfect hexameter—'announcing this, they stored away undying gratitude' (exangeilantes kharin athanalon katethento, 7.178.2). Such a passage gives Herodotus' report a solemn epic resonance (cf. Hermogenes Id. 408 Rabe), here i n connection w i t h a rather 'heroic' theme: divine assistance and patriotic solidarity for the allied Greeks. 18
T h e striking physical resemblance to epic language, including snatches o f hexametric rhythms, may i n some instances echo a poetic account that lies behind a particular story i n Herodotus. Recently published papyrus fragments o f an extended elegy by Simonides on the Battle o f Plataea, for example, r e m i n d us that poems were U)
in pre-Herodotean literature to Homer (cf. Soph. Ant. 29-30 birds only), but it occurs there so frequently (fifteen times in the Iliad and twice in the Odyssey) that it would doubtless sound 'Homeric' to Herodotus' addressees. "' See Erbse (1992) 125 7 for discussion of Homeric influence on the catalogue of Xerxes' troops. '' On the dreams, see also Said, this volume (Ch. 6, pp. 142—4). Hornblowcr (1994a) 65-9 discusses Homeric speech and rhythms in Herodotus and Thucydides; see also Boedeker (2001) 121 "4. Ohiasson (1982) similarly looks at traces of tragic diction and meter in Herodotus (see also Ch. 6, note 6 in this volume). Cf. Boedeker (2001) 123 4. 18
lil
104
D E B O R A H BOEDEKER
composed to commemorate all the great battles o f the Persian W a r — all, at least, that were fought on (or near) the Greek mainland and described by Herodotus.'- The Plataea poem, it appears, was famous in Herodotus' time; echoes o f i t can be detected i n fifth-century poetry from Aeschylus to Timotheus (Rutherford (2001) 44, 46). I argue elsewhere that Herodotus knew this poem as well, and relied on it in certain respects in constructing his own scenario o f the decisive battle (Boedeker (2001) 121-34). Occasionally, then, echoes o f poems commemorating historical events may account for epic-like language in Herodotus. Even when that is the case, however, it is important to consider why the historian chooses to 'sound' Homeric at certain junctures. I n general, hexametric rhythms and Homeric turns of phrase are most apparent in the speeches; these passages are also hommkotata in their vivid mimetic quality. Is Herodotus most likely to use snatches o f Homeric language in his characters' speeches simply because these are points of greatest congruence with Homeric narrative technique? O r is the use o f epic-sounding language a way for Herodotus deliberately to make a character, or a section o f narrative, sound larger-than-life, more heroic, or even more archaic?'-' 0
1
Besides its echoes o f Homeric passages, great and small, the Histories shares many compositional features with Homeric epic. Like an epic poet, for example, Herodotus frequently uses ring composition or 'epic regression' as a way o f supplying background information for something discussed in the narrative. First an event is mentioned briefly, then its precedents are reviewed in reverse chronological order as far back as necessary; at that point the narrative reverses 22
2 0
Parsons (1992) 4 50 (edk'w prineeps of P. Oxy. 3965) and West (1992) fr. el. 1-22. For discussion of the 'new Simonides', see West (1993) and Boedeker and Sicler (2001). On Herodotus and archaic historical poetry, see the important essays of Lasserre (1976) and Verdin (1977). Klamp (1930) 892, for example, finds decidedly poetic style, including two examples of tmesis and a high degree of assonance, in a Herodotean passage (2.30 40) dealing with what he judges to be prehistoric magical rites; he concludes that Homeric form matches archaic content. Pearce (1981), citing Krischer (1971) 136 If. on ring composition in Homeric epic. Pearce's examples include Hist, 1.29-30 (how Solon leaves Athens and comes to Sardis), 1.65-9 (Croesus learns that Sparta gained hegemony over Tegea), and 3.1 (why Cambyses goes to war against Amasis). See also Bakker (1997a) 119 22, and Slings, this volume (Cli. 3, pp. 71-3), who discuss ring composition as an 'oral strategy*; see also de Jong, this volume (Ch. 11, pp. 260-1), who deals with ring composition as a narrative strategy. 21
2 2
EPIC H E R I T A G E AND M Y T H I C A L PATTERNS I N HERODOTUS
105
itself and moves forward in chronological order until the event i n the main narrative line is reached again. As Mabel Lang points out, Herodotus, like the epic narrator, inserts digressions right after introducing a new topic, 'where suspense is sufficient to keep the audience involved' (Lang (1984) 7 9), or directs the narrative by askingrhetorical questions—though far more often, and with a more critical attitude, than is the case i n epic. ' I n addition, as H a r t m u t Erbse ((1992) 127-31) demonstrates, the Histories closely follows epic techniques for reporting simultaneous actions i n different places. Irene cle Jong ((1999)) usefully outlines further ways in which Herodotus follows, and differs from, Homeric narratological technique. T h e Histories resembles Homeric epic not only i n structures but in attitudes as well, including a (surprising?) lack o f chauvinism. Although the Persian Wars are told from a Hellenic point o f view, with ethnic and cultural differences highlighted, Herodotus does not in general demonize the 'barbarian' enemy. Brave deeds o f Persians (and their allies) as well as Greeks are recorded, as are deliberations and decisions—some wiser or more honourable than others—on both sides. Even Xerxes can receive heroic (or is it ironic?) praise: o f all the many thousands i n his armada, no one could match h i m i n beauty or stature, to be more worthy to hold power (7.187). 2
24
Herodotus' impetus toward (relatively) non-partisan historiography is related to what Christian Meier has called his 'multi-subjective' perspective, as opposed to a record o f deeds that glorifies a single monarch or god. Meier (1987) attributes this breadth o f perspective to specific political circumstances i n fifth-century Greek culture, particularly a tendency toward democratization and a corresponding sense of the individual's role in political decision making. A t the same time, however, sympathetic portrayal o f the non-Greek enemy is a characteristic deeply embedded i n the Iliad.'-' Both a narrative model and a socio-political attitude, it seems, were available to
23
Lang (1984} 39 40: 'Unlike Homer's own questions, which seem to invoke; the authority of the Muses, [Herodotus'] actually question authority and introduce an element of debate.' Hall (1989) shows how Athenian tragedy, though contemporary with Herodotus' work, took a very different path with regard to the contrast between Greeks and barbarians. Less so the Odyssey, which tends to depict Odysseus' enemies, from the Cyclops to the Suitors, unsvmpatheticaiiv. See Strasburgcr (1972) 25; Gomme (1954) 47, 111-12. 2 4
2 3
106
D E B O R A H BOEDEKER
influence Herodotus' portrayal o f non-Greeks—along w i t h some nonelites and women—as sympathetic, intelligent, and courageous historical agents. H e r m a n n Strasburger argues for the profound influence o f H o m e r on Greek historiography; he attributes this especially to the truly historical sense o f epic, as seen i n its attempt to characterize an era different from the present—one w i t h weapons o f bronze not iron, w i t h stronger men and grand palaces."' As Susanna Stambler ((1982) 212) points out, however, the Histories, w i t h its interest i n 'first discoverers' and positive developments especially i n political institutions, displays a sense o f historical progress that is quite absent from epic. Arguably, the most important and far-reaching resemblance between Herodotus and H o m e r is the mimetic quality o f their narratives. Like Homeric epic, the Histories not only records the results o f past actions, but presents an imaginative, dramatic recreation o f how and w h y the actions took place. ' Related to this is epic's concern with verisimilitude, as seen i n its careful exposition o f cause and effect (as w i t h the chain o f events leading up to Achilles' wrath, clearly developed at the beginning o f the Iliad), and an emphasis on truthfulness and exactness in reporting: Odysseus at one point even provides a 'source' for information he could not be expected to know himself (Od. 12.389-90). One o f the most effective devices for creating this vividness is the use o f speeches to reveal the characters, motives, and fates o f historical actors, a technique i n which Herodotus is conspicuously influenced by Homer.- Another salient mimetic feature that the Histories share w i t h epic is the frequent description o f nonverbal communication—gestures, sounds, postures, expressions that richly express, as Donald Lateiner ((1987) 84) puts i t , 'states o f being beyond the report o f intentional action and conscious communication'. As Lateiner points out, for example, gestures can eloquently indicate transgressive behaviour (the suitor Antinoos throws a footstool at Odysseus the 'beggar', Od. 17.462-5; Persian emissaries fondle the breasts o f the Macedonian women at Amyntas' court, Hist. 5.18), 1
2
28
9
Strasburger (1972) 27-9. Other important discussions also in Huber (1965b), Huxley (1989), Brillante (1990) 98-102, Erbsc (1992) 122-32, Romm (1998) 16-17. Fornara (1971a) 35-6, Strasburger (1972) 38-9. Cause and effect, Strasburger (1972) 24-5; exactness of report, ibid. 21. Sec also Immerwahr (1966) 73. Waters (1966) 157-71 and (1985) 68; Asheri (1988) lx with bibliographical footnote. 2 7
2 8
3 9
EPIC H E R I T A G E A N D M Y T H I C A L PATTERNS I N HERODOTUS
107
as well as extremes o f emotion (angry Achilles throws down the sceptre, //. 1.245-6; the deposed king Demaratus wordlessly covers his head, Hist. 6.67.3). 30
H o w are we to understand the many parallels between Herodotus and Homer? Certain resemblances between epic and history maystem from a common origin rather than from imitation or borrowing. Ernst Risch has argued, for example, that Indo-European celebratory ('feierlich') prose narratives share with narrative poetry certain linguistic/stylistic features, such as the tendency to begin a sentence with a verb.' Mabel Lang, examining Herodotus' compositional techniques such as the placement o f digressions, links between passages, use o f rhetorical questions, and the like, concludes that these patterns make it easier for an audience to follow the narrative line, and thus are evidence o f Herodotus' oral style ~—in other words they are not so much influenced by as shared with Homer. Other scholars prefer to speak o f such techniques as typical of epideictic rhetoric, rather than oral origins/' 51
:?
3
I t is frequently stated or assumed that Herodotus reflects Homeric style because archaic epic was the only available model for the sustained narrative o f great events. ' This idea is supported by the impression that Herodotus' text resembles epic more obviously i n the deliberative and action-oriented parts o f the Histories and less so i n the discursive ethnographic sections. This assumption needs to be 3 1
30
Lateiner (1987) 85, 93, 103. '' Risch (1985) 8-9 (citing Wackcrnagel). Although Risch does not comment on this fact, the examples he cites usually include the verb 'to be' at the start of a new episode. See also Fornara's remark ((1971a) 68) on the force of f)v 5e for Herodotus' introduction of Themistocles (7.143) and the Iliad's of Dolon (10.314). For a linguistic (rather than stylistic) approach to this phenomenon, see Slings, this volume (Ch. 3, ad ex. (2a), p. 55). Lang (1984) 68 9 and passim; cf, also Nagy (1987), on Herodotus as a (agios or performer of tales in prose. Johnson (1994) argues against this picture of Herodotus. Huber (1965b) argues that Herodotus both 'continues' Homeric style and deliberately imitates or alludes to it. I note that although a context of oral performance is very likely the origin of Herodotus' epic-like structuring devices, it is far from their only context; ring composition, for example, is widespread even in much later ancient authors writing for highly literate audiences; for a few examples in Roman literature, see Pearce (1981) 89, nn. 4-5. De Jong (1999) 227-9; see also Thomas (2000) 257 69 and passim for arguments that Herodotus presented parts of the Histories as oral 'lectures' (and see Bakker, this volume (Ch. 1), on the differences between Nagy's and Thomas' approaches to an 'oral' Herodotus). E.g., Lateiner (1987) 84, Herington (1991b), Erbse (1992) 122 32. 8 3
108
D E B O R A H BOEDEKER
tested and refined; a comprehensive study o f where and how the Histories uses verbal echoes o f epic would illuminate both Herodotus' relationship with his most conspicuous model and the general development o f Greek prose. Oswyn M u r r a y explains Herodotus' resemblance to H o m e r not by assuming necessity or inevitability: he boldly maintains that Herodotus' many resemblances to H o m e r 'are part o f a conscious attempt to present the history o f the Persian Wars as the history o f a new Trojan W a r w o n by a new race o f heroes'. > I n some passages this is surely the case, as for example the battle over the corpse o f Leonidas at Thermopylae (7.225) w i t h its unmistakable echo o f the long fight over Patroclus (Iliad 17). Interestingly, the 'new' fragments o f Simonides' elegy on the battle o f Plataea (see above) now show that the two wars were seen as analogous significantly before Herodotus. Simonides first recalls the destruction o f T r o y and the 'undying fame' which the Danaans received from that poet who learned the truth from the Muses; then he summons his own Muse to help him adorn his song to bring 'undying fame' to 'those who marched[?] out of Sparta to w a r d off the day o f slavery' from Greece (Simonides, fr. el. 11.13-28 West). T h e parallels are astonishingly clear. 3;
Along w i t h so many similarities, however, it is important to remember that Herodotus consciously differentiates his work from e p i c * A t several junctures he criticizes poets as untrustworthy sources. T h e most salient example o f this comes i n a discussion o f what really happened during the siege o f T r o y (2.116): Herodotus declares that H o m e r knew the more plausible story that Helen was not really at T r o y but i n Egypt—yet H o m e r d i d not consider that version suitable for an epic poem. Indeed, as a number o f scholars have recently argued from very different perspectives, i n clearly recalling epic themes and language (especially i n the proem), Herodotus is not only paying homage to H o m e r but challenging his primacy. 37
Nevertheless, Herodotus deserves his ancient epithet homërikôtatos: his text again and again recalls the language, style, structure, mimetic quality, and sometimes even metre o f H o m e r i c epic. I t may be
Vj
• Murray (1988) 463. Similarly van Effcnterre (1967) 19, cited by Giraudeau (1984b) 4: 'Son histoire des guerres médiques avait forcé ment pour les Grecs une allure d'épopée. Le style de l'écrivain s'en est souvent ressenti: l'ionien même d'Hérodote est quelque peu "homerise" . Cf. Vcrdin (1977) csp. 60 1, Boecleker (2000) 103 5. E.g., Hartog (1988) 276, 315; Nagy (1987); Thomas (2000) 267. 5
3 6
3 7
EPIC H E R I T A G E A N D M Y T H I C A L PATTERNS I N HERODOTUS
109
difficult to determine where Herodotus has deliberately adopted an epic model, i n contrast to where his language unconsciously resembles epic discourse. I t is no exaggeration, however, to say that without Homeric epic's sustained narrative o f great deeds behind i t , the Histories would not exist at all; and without its variegated reflections o f epic style, it would be a very different work.
Herodo tus M y th ologos? T h e text o f Herodotus interacts frequently not only w i t h epic narrative but with myths i n general by which I mean traditional, culturally significant stories, often involving gods or heroes. For a connoisseur o f rhetoric and style such as Hermogenes, Herodotus' ubiquitous mythic quality {to muthikon) is a delightful feature, the source o f much o f his characteristic 'sweetness' (giufates,Id. 330 1, 408 Rabe). Hermogenes judges those stories to be sweetest that are truly 'mythical' (muthodes), such as Pan's epiphany to Philippides (Hist. 6.105), and somewhat less pleasing the narratives that 'share a little of the mythic quality but are more credible than myths' (330 1 Rabe). I n a very different spirit, Aristotle disparagingly refers to Herodotus as ho muthologos 'the myth-teller' (Gen. an. 3.5.755b6). T h e epithet i n this context is not a comment on Herodotus' use o f supernatural stories, however, but on his inaccuracy. I n a discussion about how fish reproduce, the philosopher blames Herodotus for passing along the silly tale (ton euethe logon) that the females o f one species conceive by swallowing the milt emitted by the males (Hist. 2.93). Herodotus himself uses the w o r d muthos only twice,* both times as a label o f disapproval directed polemically against those ('the poets' in 2.23, 'the Greeks' i n 2.45) who perpetrate implausible information. '' f o r Herodotus as for Aristotle, muthos is someone else's fabulous and incredible story.' " 5
1
There are o f course many reports i n the Histories of objects, events, and customs that, would seem implausible to Herodotus and his
Nickau (1990) 84. ·" See Marincola (1987) 128-31, Darbo-Peschanski (3987) 112, and Dewald, this volume (Ch. 12, pp. 278 -79) on the competitive character of Book Two. *' On this use of muthos by Herodotus and the way the term is used against him by later critics, see Hartog (1988) 295 6.
110
D E B O R A H BOEDEKER
addressees. The historian takes care to distance himself from such logoi with the famous disclaimer that he tells what was said but doesn't necessarily believe it (7.152.3), or sometimes by overtly stating his disbelief (as in 8.8). Occasionally he reports a supernatural tale and offers an alternative rationalizing explanation, as with the tale that Poseidon caused a ravine to appear in Thessaly. This is a credible story, Herodotus remarks, for those who attribute earthquakes to Poseidon, since it appears to h i m that the ravine was made by an earthquake (7.129). I n this story, Herodotus applies the same standards o f credibility whether an event took place recently or in the distant past. Yet occasionally, as Justus Cobet discusses in Chapter 17 o f this volume (pp. 405 ff.), he seems to make a distinction between a spatium mytliicum and a spatium historicum—especially when he distinguishes the remote era o f Minos from 'the so-called human age {geneef o f Polycrates (3.122). Scholars disagree about the degree to which Herodotus conceives o f a 'mythical' time i n which the world operated differently from 'historical' time; as w i t h many issues in Herodotus, the text allows arguments on both sides. I n general, however, time and place enjoy continuity in the Histories, as do the operating conditions o f the world. 41
12
13
More problematic for Herodotus' standing as a historian than his recording o f unveriliable events distant in time is his use o f 'historical' stories that follow narrative patterns known from myths. A particularly rich example is the tale o f how Cyrus came to power (1.107-30), told in the narrator's own persona rather than identified as 'what they say', but nevertheless replete with elements familiar from myth and folklore. ' Prophetic dreams warn K i n g Astyages that his daughter's son will depose him; Astyages orders a trusted courtier, 44
1
" See also Bakker, this volume (Ch. 1, pp. 13 19), on Herodotus' kistorie. Sec also 2.54-7: how the priestesses of Zeus came to Dodona from Egypt, and why they are called 'doves'. On the phenomenon in general, cf. How and Wells (1912) 1:32-3. Scholars arguing that Herodotus observes such a distinction include Nessclradi (1996) 276, Vandiver (1991) passim, and Shimron (1973). Among those who disagree are Nickau (1990), and Hunter (1982) 103. Brillante (1990) 102 maintains that the heroic past was continuous with the historical period, and not confused with a 'time of origins' or 'age of the gods', which was very different from the age of human beings. See also Raaflaub (Ch. 7, n. 36) and Osborne (Ch. 22, p. 799). For a discussion of these (short) stories, see Gray, in this volume (Ch. 13). For a concise discussion, sec Alv (1969) 48-51; see also Said, this volume (Ch. 6, pp. 128-29). 4 3
I !
14
11
EPIC H E R I T A G E A N D M Y T H I C A L PATTERNS IN HERODOTUS
11 1
Harpagos, to kill the dangerous baby, but Harpagos has not the heart to do so; the royal foundling is 'rescued' rather than killed by a good-hearted herdsman and his wife (and a still more fabulous variant, that the child was fostered by an animal, hides behind the wife's name, 'Bitch', cf. 1.122.3); the true nature o f the child is revealed and eventually the prophetic dreams prove true. Intertwined with the widespread legend o f the royal foundling is a m o t i f well known from the Greek myth o f Atreus and Thyestes: Astyages punishes Harpagos for not killing Cyrus in the first place, by serving h i m the cooked flesh o f his own son (1.118 19). As i n the house o f Atreus, this trick o f cannibalism brings its own revenge, for Harpagos, remembering the fate o f his son, is the one who encourages Cyrus to rise up against Astyages (1.123-4). Herodotus' stoiy o f the Spartan king Demaratus provides a second example o f a historical character linked with mythical motifs."' Demaratus' co-king Cleomencs challenged his legitimacy, on the grounds that when he was born, the alleged father, K i n g Ariston, declared that the baby could not be his, because it was born only seven months after his wife came to him from her previous husband (6.63, 65). Soon after he was unfairly deposed from his kingship, Demaratus demanded to know the truth about his birth. His mother swore to h i m that he was the son either o f Ariston or o f a local Spartan hero, Astrabacus. Astrabacus, she said, had come to her i n the guise o f her new husband and slept with her soon after her marriage to Ariston; then on the same night the king himself came to her bed and that was the night she conceived her son (6.69). This talc o f the Heraclid king Demaratus closely parallels the birth story o f his ancestor Heracles, the son o f Alcmena who was loved by Zeus and Amphitryon on the same night; it seems very likely to have been passed along by pro-Dcmaratus sources at Sparta or elsewhere. I n this case, it appears, a mythical pattern applied to a 'historical' event probably originated with Herodotus' sources and was motivated by political or familial reasons. Perhaps because the legendary elements i n the birth stories o f Cyrus or Demaratus are so transparent, there has been little temptation for scholars to try to separate factual kernels from mythical
Sec further Burkert (1965); see again Said, this volume (Ch. 6, p. 126).
112
DEBORAH BOEDEKER
47
chaff in those tales, This has not been the case, however, with other stories i n which fabulous elements blend with what appear to be historical reports. " A disturbing question arises: can stories that include mythical patterns also incorporate real historical events? A story attached to Periander, who became tyrant o f Corinth a generation or two before the accession o f Cyrus i n Persia, can serve as a test case for this question.' Periander's son Lycophron, learning that his father killed his mother, refuses to have anything to do with his father—including inheriting the tyranny o f Corinth. A t length he agrees to go to Corcyra to rule the Corinthian colony there. T h e aging Periander, still anxious to secure his family's dynasty in Corinth, later persuades Lycophron to trade places w i t h h i m ; but before Periander can arrive in Corcyra and take over the rule, the Corcyreans kill Lycophron. In revenge, Periander orders three hundred Corcyrean youths to be sent to Lydia, made into eunuchs, and sold into slavery. O n their way to Lydia, however, the boys are given asylum by the Samians, who institute a festival i n their honour (3.48, 50-3). Although historians usually assume that at least, the outline o f this tale is true,-' Christianc Sourvinou-Inwood argues forcefully that it is so pervasively based on mythical and ideological constructs, such as the consequences o f opposition between fathers and sons, that a historical core cannot be reconstructed with any degree o f certainty. 4
19
0
51
Other scholars find mythical and ideological elements within the Periander story without addressing so directly the important cjuestion of its historicity. For Michael Stahl (1983) it is a moral-political tale about the depravity o f tyranny. For Jean-Pierre Vernant, the whole tale o f the Cypselid dynasty reflects the 'crookedness' o f the tyrant, from the lameness o f Periander's ancestor Labda to his outof-balance relationship w i t h Lycophron motifs found also i n the myth o f Oedipus: 'When the father o f history recounts as fact the
47
Brelich (1958) 59-60 and passim warns against trying to reconstruct history from myths. Brillantc (1990) 108 TO provides illuminating discussion. " See How and Wells (1912) 1:35. Aly (1969) 93-5 discusses the many folktale elements in Herodotus' stories of the Cypselids. As in OCIT s.v. Periander. Sourvinou-Inwood (1988); she would allow only that the Cypselid tyranny came to an end soon after Periander's death (p. 181). 48
19
5 0
51
EPIC H E R I T A G E A N D M Y T H I C A L PATTERNS I N HERODOTUS
113
events which installed a line o f tyrants at the head of Corinth, quite "naturally" he mythologizes' (Vernant (1.982) 33). Each o f these accounts is illuminating, yet to see how mythical patterns work i n a 'historical narrative, I agree w i t h Claude Calame that we must take into account the Herodotean context the discourse o f which it is a part and the community to which it was addressed—as well as the mythical schemata that give the story its Structure. A l o n g with elements reflecting Greek familial values and social ideologies, which Sourvinou-Inwood demonstrates so effectively, it seems to me quite plausible that political or philosophical concerns (on the part o f Herodotus himself or his sources) would inform a story. Depending on the circumstances in which the tale is told, story-tellers and their audiences are not necessarily concerned only w i t h the familial and social themes so prevalent i n myths, especially the myths o f Attic tragedy. 5
y2
T h e little Periander-Lycophron tragedy is recounted as background to Herodotus' story o f an attempted coup by disaffected Samians against their tyrant Polycrates, i n the time o f Cambyses (3.39-60). Polycrates' opponents solicit help from Sparta; Corinth too is happy to assist them i n attacking Samos, because somewhat earlier the Samians had rescued the youths o f Corcyra w h o m Periander was shipping to Lydia (3.48). Herodotus comments that C o r i n t h and Corcyra had been at odds ever since C o r i n t h founded its colony at Corcyra; without those hostilities, C o r i n t h would not have joined the expedition against Samos (3.49.1). T h e grudge between Lycophron and his father Periander is reflected i n that between Corcyra and its 'parent' city Corinth (obvious i n Herodotus' time: Thuc. 1.38, etc.), and indirectly causes the hostility between Corinth and Samos. This web o f resentments, w i t h parent/child hostility at its core, now plays into the hands o f the Samians looking for support i n their insurrection against Polycrates. ' I n Herodotus, the political is always (also) personal, and the two often stand in metonymic relationship to one another.' '' T h e story o f Periander and Lycophron is revealing 33
3 1
1
5 3
Calame (1990) 281, White (1978) carries this idea further, saying that the kind of discourse (or genre) itself greatly influences the shape of the story. See SourvinouInwood (1988) 168 on mythological 'schemata . On this story, see also Ch. 6, pp. 126-27. in this volume as well as Ch. 22, p. 503. For a different perspective on such webs, see 'the reciprocity model' discussed by Gould (1989) 82-5. '•' Benardete (1969) lakes a similar approach to the relationship between personal 1
3 i
11
114
DEBORAH BOEDEKER
not only for its connections to the themes o f other myths, as SourvinouInwood and Vernant emphasize, but also for its relationship to Herodotus' central historical themes o f tyranny and the causes o f war. The problem o f historicity in such 'mythologized' accounts remains acute.''' I t is indisputable that mythical and historical materials converge in the examples discussed. This is to be expected, especially since the stories were orally transmitted; they were orally formed as narratives, for that matter, and were most likely influenced by the shape o f myths or folktales from the very beginning, as well as by Homeric and other poetic models (see above). Still, I am a little less pessimistic than Sourvinou-lnwood about the historical core that remains, partly because elements o f the story seem to be conveyed in different places (Samos and Corinth, for example). I agree with Carol Dougherty's generalization in her analysis o f Greek foundation myths: 'Since Greek colonial legends, like all narratives, are not clear, untroubled reflections o f some historical truth but rather are literary representations o f that truth, they stand in a complicated relationship to the events they relate' (Dougherty (1993) 7). There is no way around it: that relationship must be analysed for each case, bringing to bear all the kinds o f evidence that exist. Besides presenting some stories that replicate mythical patterns, Herodotus also introduces certain well-known myths (understood by his audience, to be sure, as events that really happened in the past, see Brillante (1990) 101-2) as relevant background to events in his narrative. O f course there is the sequence o f rapes between Europe and Asia, culminating in the Trojan War, which Herodotus says the Persian logioi present as the cause o f hostility between Asia and Europe (1.1-5). I n this case, myth (as ancient history) motivates—or provides the alleged justification f o r - 'history'. I n several striking instances. however, a character from the heroic past (especially the Trojan W a r era) is said by Herodotus himself, or by his informants, to cause events that occur in the narrative line. Herodotus speaks in his own persona about Talthybius (7.133-4, 137). " The herald o f the Achaeans at T r o y , Talthybius was hon:
tales and historical themes. See further Boedeker (1987} on the themes connected with Demaratus. Sebeok and Brady (1979) 12-14, taking a view almost as extreme as SourvinouInwood's, warn against reading the story of Croesus and his sons as history; they see it as 'A Myth about Communication'. " Cf. Said, this volume (Ch. 6, p. 121).
EPIC H E R I T A G E A N D M Y T H I C A L PATTERNS I N HERODOTUS
1 15
oured at Sparta as a hero and as the ancestor o f the city's official heralds. W h e n Darius sent heralds to Sparta demanding earth and water as tokens o f submission, the Spartans threw the emissaries into a well; afterwards, their sacrificial omens kept turning out unfavourably. A t last, two Spartans volunteered to be executed by Darius' successor Xerxes to atone for the wrongful deaths; they made their way to Susa, but Xerxes spared them. Nevertheless, the wrath o f Talthybius worked itself out eventually, the narrator assures us, because the sons o f those volunteers ended up being betrayed to and executed by Sparta's later enemies, the Athenians, many years after the attempted atonement.'' A t the very end o f the Histories, the wrath o f another Achaean warrior is associated w i t h the capture and execution o f a Persian (9.116-20). Artayctes, w h o m Xerxes h a d p u t i n charge o f the Chersonnese, stole treasures from the hero shrine o f Protesilaus, the first Greek to die at T r o y , and otherwise abused the hero's sanctuary. After the Persian defeat i n mainland Greece, the Athenians came to claim the Chersonnese. Artayctes tried to escape but was apprehended and brought back to the town o f Sestus for execution. Herodotus reports a story told by the Chersonnesians: on the way back to Sestos, Artayctes observed the dried fish that were beingheated for dinner, j u m p i n g i n the pan as i f alive; he exclaimed that this was a sign that Protesilaus, 'even though dead and dried', demanded vengeance from h i m . I have discussed this story at length elsewhere, arguing that Herodotus alludes to the story o f Protesilaus in the assumption that his addressees (familiar at least w i t h his epic identity: Iliad 2.695 709) will understand even more of its significance than what is spelled out i n the text. 8
39
These two examples o f 'mythical heroes' who operate on the level o f the narrative remind us again o f the close relationships drawn between the Trojan and the Persian Wars. Artayctes is even said to refer to Protesilaus as 'a Greek man who invaded [Persian] territory' (9.116), repeating the idea o f continuity between the invasions o f Achaeans against T r o y and Persians against Greece. Gregory Nagy (1987) argues that Herodotus 'subsumes' the subject matter o f epic into his own magisterial account: the Trojan War becomes just an
5 8
See the comments o f Biraschi (1989) 119 20. See Boedeker (1988) for detailed discussion. See also Fisher, this volume (Ch. 9).
116
D E B O R A H BOEDEKER
early chapter in the universal history o f Europe versus Asia. This seems an accurate description o f Herodotus' (self-interested) perspective on 'universal history', yet even so Homeric epic and its heroes retain a special cachet, to be shared occasionally with later events. 110
The stories we have just considered, from their different perspectives, all illustrate that in Herodotus' text the boundary between myth and history is a permeable one. Even beyond the examples where characters are 'shared' between two discourses (such as happens w i t h Talthybius or Protesilaus, who drop in from epic to interact with historical fifth-century characters), or where allusions seem certain (as between the birth stories o f Demaratus and Heracles), narrative patterns and concerns may converge (as with Periandcr/ Lycophron and Laius/Oedipus). For more specific patterns, such as those we have examined i n this chapter, the narratives o f myth and history can well be expected to overlap, because both are generated in the same cultural climate and reflect its categories and concerns, whether psychological, social, or political. I f succession o f power and father-son relationships are of great concern in a culture, we should not be surprised to discover them i n both mythical and historical tales or as the Greeks would probably see it, in tales o f the distant or more recent past. Even more broadly, the narrative patterns in Herodotus, Homer, and indeed o f all stoiy-tellers may participate in a master narrative, one that Henk Versnel (wiyly?) suggests can be ultimately reduced to the biological imperative 'to get"' - b u t to explore this unsurpassably reductionist possibility would take us far beyond the parameters o f the Histories. 1
On Herodotus' uses of Homer for political purposes, sec Birasclii (1989) 114-15. Versnel (1990) 60 1, following (and going beyond) Burkert (1980) with its reliance on the narrative morphology of Propp.
CHAPTER SIX
HERODOTUS AND TRAGEDY Suzanne Said
I n the Poetics (1451bl--11), Aristotle drew a clear line between poetry and history, exemplified by Herodotus and Thucydides: poetry is more concerned with the universal, that is to say, 'what a certain type o f person on a certain occasion will do or say according to probability or necessity', whereas history is more concerned with the particular and 'what Alcibiades did or had done to h i m ' (an illus tration which suggests that he had also Thucydides i n mind, cf. de Ste Croix (1992) 27). Yet many critics, ancient and modern, found this opposition inadequate and emphasized the influence o f the poetic tradition on Herodotus' Histories. Ancient authors, from Thucydides to Themistius, paid much atten tion to the parallels between Herodotus, who was fond o f myths,' and Homer, but they never made a case for a 'tragic' Herodotus. The father o f history is never praised, like Thucydides or Xenoplion, for the dramatic quality and the vividness o f his narratives, which convert the listener into a spectator, as the tragedians did (Isoc. in Mcoclem 49). T h e only traces o f a link between Herodotus, 'who followed H o m e r " and Sophocles, 'the most Homeric' of the tragic poets are to be found in the biographical tradition and the scholia: Plutarch (Moralia 785b) alludes to an epigram written by Sophocles for Herodotus and the tragic poet is said to have paraphrased the words o f Solon at the beginning o f the Trachiniae as well as at the end o f the Oedipus Rex. 2
3
1
1
T h . 1.21.1; Arise. De generations animalium 756b, DID. som. 1.69.7; Lucianiis Philopseudes 2; Them. Oratio. 33, 376c; Cic. De tegibus. 1.1.5 and Gcll. I I I . 10.11. On Herodotus in ancient criticism, see Pernot (1995). 2
D. I i . Ad Pompeium 3.11 and Ps. I .origin. On Sublimity 13.3. See also Ch. 5 in
this volume. s
Plu. Moralia 347a and D. H . On Thucydides 15 on Thucydides; Plu. Arlaxerxes
8.1 on Xenophon. ' D. H . Ad Pompeium 3.11: Όμηρου ζηλωτής. Suid. s.v. 'Polemon'. See also Arist. Poetics 1448a26; D. L. 4.20; Vita Sophoclis 20. 5
118
SUZANNE SAID
Conversely, modern scholars, starting with H . Fohl who, i n 1913, wrote a dissertation entitled Tragische Kunst bei Herodot, are prone to associate words such as 'tragic' and 'tragedy' w i t h various aspects o f Herodotus' Histories. A t the most factual level, critics have compiled a list o f words and phrases borrowed from tragedy.'' For example 'the maxim o f Solon . . .—that no one should call a man happy before his death— is repeated i n all three tragedians', as is demonstrated by Evans.' Others have stressed 'the use o f comparable and often identical material' (Walbank (1960) 237) by Herodotus and tragic poets: the Capture of Miletus, the Phoenician Women o f Phrynichus, the Persians o f Aeschylus, and the much debated Gyges deal with historical events which are narrated also by Herodotus. Conversely, Herodotus' Histories contain myths, as is demonstrated inter alia by the preface. This is no surprise, for mythical characters and events were as historical for Herodotus and his contemporaries as those belonging to 'the time of men' (that is to say those about whom Herodotus' informants have first hand information).' I t is only later that the rhetoricians will introduce a polar opposition between 'myth' (muthos or fab aid), which is neither plausible nor true, and 'history' (historid). 8
1
10
Some have emphasized that Herodotus and the tragic poets used the past—either mythical or historical - i n the same way, to 'shed light on contemporary political issues . . ., address some o f the cen tral political concerns o f [their] audience and time' (Raaflaub (1987) 231-2) and 'give historical events and characters a paradigmatic value transcending the occasion' (Hunter (1982) 82). Others focussed on Herodotus' debt to the literary techniques o f Greek tragedy." They attempted to locate the impact o f tragedy on Herodotus' 'mimetic presentation', pointing out his 'dramatization o f history' through speeches and conversations among historical characters as well as the vividness o f his descriptions—a major component,
" Aly (1921) 281-6, Schmid and Staehlin (1934) 569, n. 7; Avery (1979) and Chiasson (1982) passim. ' Evans (1991) 4. who quotes Agamemnon 928 9: Oedipus Rex 1528-30 and Andromache 100-1. " See Nesselrath (1995 6) and Ch. 5 in this volume. •' Wiseman (1979) 145 arid Shimron (1973) passim. 10
Cic. Ad Herennium 1.12, Quint, 2.42; S. E. Adversus Matheinalicos 1. 263 4 etc.
On ιστορία, see Ch. 1 in this volume. " Myres (1914) passim and (1953) 78; Egermann (1957) 38.
1 19
HERODOTUS A N D TRAGEDY
together with sensationalism, o f the so-called 'tragic' history, according to Polybius. I n the last three books o f his Histories, Herodotus is said to create 'scenes o f greatest dramatic impact' (Fornara (1971a) 61), from which he separates himself carefully, allowing his audience to form their own conclusions. H e 'visualizes episodes as i f they formed scenes o f a play' and invents 'meaningful' speeches, which, as i n tragedy, 'encapsulate the meaning of an episode' (Fornara (1983) 171-2). He also reports facts in a way inspired by messenger-speeches. Taking issue with Aristotle and his view o f history as 'chronicle', some scholars also pointed out the existence o f 'dramatic logoi, which use all the structural elements o f a staged play and 'are arranged i n such a fashion as to produce a definite tragic development' (Immerwahr (1966) 69). Most o f all, critics have discovered tragic themes i n the Histories: inescapable fate and inexorable divine forces working on characters; the tragic cycle o f rise and fall (great prosperity and olbos 'wealth' leads to koros 'surfeit', hubris 'arrogance', which in turn blinds man to danger, causing his ultimate ate 'ruin'), 'the tragic perception that man is always and everywhere vulnerable to time and chance'. " They have also found tragic motives such as ancestral curses, ambiguous dreams a n d misleading oracles, fundamental incompatibility between intent and outcome, tragic reversal sometimes followed by tragic discovery, the 'tragic adviser' and tragic: irony. *' 12
15
14
1
1
In this paper I shall attempt to assess the true impact o f tragedy on Herodotus' vision o f the working o f human life an impact which has been taken for granted by too many scholars '—identifying as precisely as possible the borrowings o f Herodotus from tragedy and their function. This is not an easy task, for the date o f Herodotus' publication is still much debated: it is usually supposed to be just 1
'Mimetic presentation': Lateiner (1987) 106; 'dramatization of history': Waters (1966); 'tragic' history: Plb. 2.56; cf. Walbank (1938), (1955), and (I960). Immerwahr (1966) 276. " Stahl (1968), Rieks (1975), Lesky (1977). '·' 'Inescapable fate': Strasburger (1982) 887-8, Kvans (1991) 33; Tragic rise; and fall': Evans (1991) 71; atf: Lang (1967/8) 81; 'time and change": Gould (1989) 132. "' Curses, dreams, and oracles: Fornara (1971a) 90 1, Herington (1991b) 6 (see also Ch. 8, this volume); intent and outcome: Immerwahr (1954) 41, Ostwald (1991) 146; tragic discovery: Gould (1989) 76; tragic adviser: Bischoff (1932) 314 19, Lattimore (1939); tragic irony: Raaflaub (1987) 239-40. E.g., Aly (1921) 279 86, Schmid and Stachlin (1934) 569 fL, Pohleuz (1937) 16 19, 213, Fornara (1971a) 61 and (1983) 171. 14
l
17
120
SUZANNE SAID
prior to the production o f the Achamians in February 425, but Fornara ((1971b, cf. Cobet (1977)) suggested a much later date, close to 414 BC. Similarly, the date o f many tragedies—as exemplified by the 'Gyges' tragedy—is much discussed. Moreover, it is sometimes hard to tell who borrows from w h o m , for we have many undisputed instances o f Sophocles' indebtedness to Herodotus. Finally, many similarities between Herodotus and the tragic poets may be explained either by their belonging to the same period or their depending on what is, after all, the acknowledged common source o f tragedy and history, that is to say the Homeric epic (F. Solmsen rightly reacted against a 'tendency to discover an influence of Aeschylus and Sophocles even for ideas or motifs which are found in the epics'). 'I n order to answer these questions, I shall first point out some isolated motives, which are also prominent in early and middle Attic tragedy, excluding those also found in Homer, such as double determination. Secondly, I shall focus on 'the tragedy o f Croesus' (Stahl (1968)) and the other stories o f the rise and fall o f barbarian kings, Greek tyrants, or Spartan leaders, that have been dubbed 'dramatic' or 'tragic', because 'they orchestrate many o f these tragic motives into a tighdy constructed narrative'. Finally, I shall compare in detail Books Seven to Nine o f Herodotus with Aeschylus' Persians. 18
1
1
20
21
Tragic motives in the Histories I n the Histories, there are characters faced w i t h a 'tragic choice' like that o f Pelasgus in the Suppliants or Agamemnon or Orestes in the Oresteia. N o doubt the best example is the wife o f Intaphrenes (3.119), who has to choose among her closest kin the one she wants to spare, and decides in favor o f her brother with an argument later echoed by Sophocles' Antigone. But in some cases the tragic issue may be 18
See Pinto (1955), Finkelberg (1995), Zellner (1997), West (1999c). Solmsen (1959) 471-3 and (1974) 7 n. 15. See also Latte (1958) 19 and Herington (1991b) 7. I t is interesting to compare the lists of tragic logoi given by Schmid and Slaehlin (1934) 569 (Croesus, Cyrus, Periander/Lycophron, Polycrates), Myres (1953) 77 (Croesus, Cyrus, Cambyses, Polycrates, Darius, Clcomenes), Immervvahr (1966) 69-71 (Gyges, Alys, Cyrus, Periander/Lycophron, Polycrates), Strasburger (1982) (Croesus, Psammenitus, Intaphrenes), and Ashcri (1988) 17 (Croesus, Cambyses, Xerxes). Dramatic: Rosenmeyer (1982) 242; tragic: Immerwahr (1966) 69. m
21
HERODOTUS AND TRAGEDY
121
successfully evaded, a fact which prevents the Histories as a whole from being tragic, as is illustrated by the story o f Pactyes (1.157.2160.1). The inhabitants of Cyme, asked by the Persians to hand over Pactyes, are initially i n the same situation as the hero o f Aeschylus' Suppliants: they have to choose between a war against a powerful adversary or the betrayal o f a suppliant. What is more, they have been deceptively advised by an oracle to surrender the suppliant to his enemies. But in the end, 'unwilling either to surrender the suppliant and come to a bad end or to keep him and be besieged by the Persians' (1.160.1), they escape the dreadful consecjuences o f this tragic choice by sending Pactyes to Mytilene. Like Aeschylus, Herodotus sometimes pictured men who had to pay for the crimes o f their ancestors, as exemplified by the story o f the brutal murder o f Darius' envoys (7.133.1-137.1). Because o f this crime, the wrath o f Agamemnon's herald, Talthybius, fell upon the Spartans who 'were unable to obtain favourable signs for their sacrifices' (7.134.2). T h e curse was allayed for some time by the two Spartans who volunteered to offer their lives in atonement for Darius' envoys and were spared by Xerxes. But long afterwards it fell upon their sons, who were put to death by the Athenians during the Peloponnesian War, clear evidence o f divine intervention, according to Herodotus (7.137.1). Yet Herodotus also stresses that the Athenians, who were as guilty as the Spartans, apparently did not suffer any harm (7.133.2), thus demonstrating that he only partially shares the Aeschylean belief. 22
23
There are also traces o f the tragic conception o f revenge i n Herodotus: the retribution exacted restores the balance by mirroring the crime even in the slightest, details, as in the Oresleia (Ag. 1318-19; Ch. 556 7, 888, 930). The abductions i n the prologue are a case in point, as is die vengeance o f Hcrmotimus (he forced the man who castrated h i m to castrate all four o f his sons before compelling the sons to castrate their father, H d t . 8.105 6). But one may also point out the story o f Pausanias, who is praised for his refusal to 'repay the like for the like' (ten homoien. apodidous, 9.78.3) by cutting off the head o f Mardonius who, together with Xerxes, had cut off the head o f Leonidas at Thermopylae. As in the tragedies o f Sophocles, there are not only isolated instances 22
2 i
Schmid and Staehlin (1934) 569; de Sic Croix (1992) 24, (1977) 146. On Talthybius, sec also Bocdckcr, this volume (Ch. 5).
122
SUZANNE SAÏD
o f neglected or misunderstood oracles i n the Histories?* but also narratives combining them i n a tragic way, like the story o f the fall o f Arcesilaus o f Gyrene and that o f the twelve kings o f Egypt. Arcesiiaus was warned beforehand by the Pythia, first, i f he found a kiln full of amphoras, not to fire them, and second, i f he d i d fire the oven, not to enter the land surrounded by water (4.163). Yet he burnt alive his opponents and 'realized only after the deed was done that this was what the oracle had meant' (4.164.3). Then he kept away from Gyrene, 'because he was afraid o f the oracle and thought it might be the land surrounded by water' (4,164.3), but he 'missed its meaning' (4.164.4), as became clear from his death i n Barca. As for the twelve kings o f Egypt, they only remembered the oracle that 'had declared that the one who should pour a libation from a bronze cup i n the temple o f Hephaestus would become master o f all Egypt' (2.147.4) after it had been accidentally fulfilled by Psammetichus. Besides, as i n Oedipus Rex, their very attempt to outwit the oracle by banishing Psammetichus to the marsh-country brought about the fated outcome: enraged by this outrage, Psammetichus planned his revenge and succeeded i n deposing the other kings (2.151-2). But deceptive oracles do not always have a tragic outcome i n the Histories, as is exemplified by the story o f the last Ethiopian ruler o f Egypt, Sabacus. L o n g ago, he had been told by an oracle 'that he had to' (hos deoi, 2.139.3) rule over Egypt for fifty years. W h e n the end o f that period came, he was sent a deceptive dream advising h i m to gather all. the priests o f Egypt and cut them i n half. But he understood that the dream was but a way o f provoking h i m to comm i t sacrilege, so that he might be harmed by either gods or men, and decided to leave Egypt 'willingly' (2.1.39.3). T h e Histories also feature 'tragic war tiers' and 'wise advisers' such as Gale has i n Ajax or Teiresias i n Antigone and Oedipus Rex, who never succeed i n preventing the disaster, for example, Solon, Croesus, Amasis, and Artabanus. Their only role i n the narrative o f Herodotus, as i n Sophocles' tragedies, is to foreshadow what is going to happen and help the reader notice the blindness o f the rulers who did not pay attention to them. As i n Greek tragedy (e.g., Ag. 468-70, Ajax 758 61), they also give expression to major truths o f human 1:>
2 4
1
E.g., the Euboeans 'who did not pay attention to the oracle of Bads (8.20.2) or the Athenians who were mistaken about the meaning of the wooden wall (8.51.5). - ' Bischoff (1932), Lattimore (1939). r
HERODOTUS A N D T R A G E D Y
123
experience, that 'before his death no one can be said to be happy, but only lucky' (1.32)*' that 'divinity is envious' (1.32.1 and 3.40.2) and 'loves to smite the great' (7.10e). But Herodotus introduces significant changes: his wise adviser is no longer a seer. H e is 'not defined any longer by supernatural information and inspired predication . . . but by a modest assumption o f probability, which is established by empirical knowledge o f man's condition' (Stahl (1975) 7). T o these tragic advisers one may add the tragic seers whose ultimate archetype is Aeschylus' Cassandra. Aware that 'there is no escape' (Ag. 1299), she bravely enters the palace to be killed. Like her, the seer Megistias, knowing his imminent death at Thermopylae, decided to stay and ' d i d not find the heart to desert the Spartan leader' (7.228). But his sending back o f his only son mitigates the tragedy. T h e story o f the anonymous Persian who, on the eve o f Plataea, told his fellow Theban o f the defeat to come (9.16.3) and walked to his death 'with a clear knowledge o f what was i n store for h i m , entangled in the net o f necessity' (9.16.3) comes closer to tragedy: the conversation o f the Persian w i t h his Greek interlocutor is modelled on the dialogue between Cassandra and the chorus i n the Agamemnon ( w . 1296-8) and his conclusion: ' i t is the worst pain for men to know much and be impotent to act' (9.16.4) precisely echoes the Aeschylean lines that underscore the bliss o f ignorance and the pain o f wisdom (Supp. 4 5 3 - 4 : Ag. 1295). I n the Histories, as in tragedy, characters are also ironically taken at their word. T h e Babylonian who jeered at the Persians' unsuccessful attempt to capture Babylon and said 'you will capture our city when mules have foals' (3.151.2), offered it as something cjuite implausible. But it happened, and the Persian Zopyrus, now convinced that the capture o f the city was fated, succeeded in devising a stratagem and sacking Babylon. I n the same way, when the Spartans, urged by an oracle, demanded reparation from Xerxes for the killing of Leonidas, the king laughed at them, 'then, pointing to Mardonius, who happened to be standing by h i m , "they will get," he said, " a l l the satisfaction they deserve from Mardonius here"' (8.114.2). T h e death o f Mardonius at Plataea (9.64) makes clear that Xerxes had unknowingly pronounced a prophetic truth.
Ag. 929-30; Track. 1-3; OT 1528-30; Andr. 100-2.
124
SUZANNE SAÏD
Herodotus' irony may also develop from a tacit dialogue with the audience. Like Sophocles, the historian, taking for granted a familiarity with his material and playing on the atidicnce's knowledge as opposed to his characters' lack of foresight, builds upon this contrast. However, to identify accurately all the occurrences of this species of 'blind irony',' ' it is crucial to define correctly the knowledge and expectations o f Herodotus' intended audience. If, as is postulated by Fornara and Raaflaub, " the Histories are addressed to contemporaries well aware o f the fall of Themistocles, the lamentable end o f Pausanias, and the 'tyranny' of Athenian imperialism (which are not directly mentioned in the Histories), one can see as 'magnificently ironic and tragic' (Fornara (1971a) 65) not only his portrayal o f Pausanias in Book Nine, but also his picture of Themistocles and his praise o f Athens' decisive contribution to saving the freedom of Greece. 2
2
T o conclude, there are obviously motives borrowed from tragedy in Herodotus. Yet our examination demonstrates that they are often transformed and do not imply a tragic vision o f human life for the Histories as a whole.
Herodotean 1 ragedies? I f the label 'tragic' is applied to any complete reversal o f fortune which is doubly determined by human motivation and by 'what had to be' (cf. Erbse (1992) 98), it is also tempting to describe as tragedies the many narratives of the falls of rulers in the Histories. But at a closer look, this statement nearly always has to be qualified. Polycrates Let us look first at the downfall of Polycrates, tyrant of Samos, as narrated in Book Three. I t is certainly possible to construe a 'tragedy of Polycrates' " by combining elements borrowed from a narrative split into two parts (3.39 60 and 120-5) and relying on the inter2
Tl
As labelled bv Rosenmcyer (1996) 504. Fornara (1971a) 59-74 and Raaflaub (1987) passim. -" Immerwahr (1966) 101, Evans (1991) 71, Chs. 13, pp. 296-7, and 23, pp. 542 8, in this volume. 2 8
125
HERODOTUS AND T R A G E D Y
pretation o f the Saurian Maeandrius, who says that 'Polycrates has fulfilled his allotted destiny' (3.142.3). But the chain o f events leading to the death o f the tyrant and his murderer is never presented as developing according to necessity or probability, as i n a good tragic plot. Indeed, there are tragic motifs. T o become the only ruler o f Samos, Polycrates behaves like the sons o f Oedipus: he kills one o f his brothers and expels the other (3.39.2). T h e 'miraculous' (3.42.4) reappearance o f the ring which he threw into the sea i n the belly o f a fish brought to h i m by a fisherman demonstrates the gods' contrivance through a series o f coincidences, as i n Sophocles' Ajax, when Tcucer points out the extraordinary relationship between the fate o f Hector, dragged to death by the same belt which Ajax had given h i m , and Ajax, who dies by a sword which was a gift o f Hector [Ajax 1028-37). A tragic discovery follows, but it is not the 'tragic' hero, Polycrates, who realizes the truth, but a friend o f his, the Egyptian Pharaoh Amasis, who understands that 'it is impossible for one m a n to rescue another from what was going to happen' (3.43.1) and therefore formally renounces Polycrates' alliance, thus escaping any tragic consequences linked to the latter's downfall. But the fall o f the tyrant, which is announced by 'the warnings of his seers and the ominous dream o f his daughter' (3.124.1), has no link w i t h his crimes. For the desire o f the satrap o f Lydia to capture and kill Polycrates has nothing to do with any serious misdeed of the Samian tyrant and is at the end left unexplained, since Herodotus leaves open the choice between two explanations which emphasize either the absurdity o f the revenge or its disproportionate character (3.120.1-122.1)/ 30
T h e true conclusion o f the story o f Polycrates is the death o f Oroetes, which is clearly presented as a punishment for the death o f Polycrates. However, among all the crimes which explain why Darius is eager to punish Oroetes—he d i d not oppose the Median usurpers, killed two distinguished Persians, and got r i d o f one o f 31
3 0
According to Herodotus, 'Oroetes had not suffered any damage or been maligned by Polycrates and did not even laid eyes on him' (3.120.1). According to Diodorus (10.16.4), Polycrates was seriously guilty, having murdered some Lydians who came to him as suppliants. H d l . 3.126.1: 'but not long afterwards, Oroetes was overtaken by the powers that avenged Polycrates' and 3.128.5: 'that was how Oroetes the Samian was overtaken by the powers that avenged Polycrates of Samos'. 31
126
SUZANNE SAÏD
Darius' couriers (3.126.1-127.1)—there is no mention o f the death o f Polycrates. So the narrative o f Polycrates' fall is not to be assimilated to a true tragedy, where, according to Aristotle 'the reversal should arise from the interna! structure o f the plot, so that what follows should be the consequence o f what happened before according to necessity or probability' (Poetics 1452a 18-20); rather, the story o f Polycrates is what is considered i n the Poetics as the worst kind o f play, that is to say 'an episodic plot, where the various episodes succeed each other without probable or necessary sequence' (Poetics 1451b34—5). Demaratus, Cleomenes, and Leoty'chides I n Book Six, the deposition o f Demaratus is to be explained by the juxtaposition o f 'what had to be' (6.64.1) and human motivations, 'the grudge harboured by Cleomenes against a fellow king who spread malicious stories about h i m . . . out o f envy and spite' (6.61.1), and the resentment felt by Leotychides towards a man who deprived h i m o f the woman to w h o m he was engaged (6.65). I n agreement w i t h Cleomenes, Leotychides swore an oath against Demaratus, declaring he had no right to the throne, because he was not the son o f the former king Ariston (6.65.3-4). W h e n the Spartans decided, at his instigation, to refer the matter to Delphi, Cleomenes secured the support o f one o f the most influential Delphians, who persuaded the Pythia to give the appropriate answer (6.66.1-2). Later on, Leotychides became the cause o f the exile o f Demaratus w h o m he outraged publicly (6.67). I n the end, Leotychides 'had to pay for what he d i d to Demaratus' (6.72.1), and Cleomenes also came to a bad end. A close look at the text demonstrates, however, as i n the case o f Polycrates, that the misfortune o f the two Spartan kings is not directly connected to what they d i d to Demaratus. Leotychides was banished from Sparta and his house demolished, only because he had later accepted a bribe and was caught red-handed (6.72.1-2). As for Cleomenes, he went m a d and c o m m i t t e d suicide. A c c o r d i n g to Herodotus (6.75.3), most Greeks explained his madness as a p u n ishment for inducing the Pythia to tell lies about Demaratus' origin. But. the punishment does not mirror the crime, as it does i n tragedy. Moreover, this is only one among the four contradictory explanations given for the death o f Cleomenes. 32
s
- On Demaratus, see also Ch. 5, in this volume.
HERODOTUS A N D T R A G E D Y
127
Cypselus and Periander T h e stories o f the Corinthian tyrants Cypselus and his son Periander have also been interpreted as a tragedy. Vernant (1982) has drawn a convincing parallel between the Oedipus legend and the birthstory o f Cypselus, which begins w i t h an obscure oracle to be understood only later, when connected to a second one (5.92(3). As in the Oedipus story, a man who has no child comes to Delphi to ask about his chances o f conceiving an heir (5.92(3). H e receives a threatening answer, which is followed by a failed attempt to avert the disaster announced by the oracle by getting r i d o f the child. W h e n the child is grown up, he goes to Delphi and as a result seizes power i n his native city. But the dissimilarities are as obvious as the similarities. T h e child is to become a threat not to his father, but to his fellow-citizens and their rulers, the Bacchiadae; and the oracle, far from being menacing, foretells his prosperity. As a matter o f fact, Cypselus, i n sharp contrast to Oedipus, ruled over Corinth for more than thirty years and died at the height o f his power (5.92Q. 53
However, the oracle had its negative side. I t announced that the Cypselids would rule over Corinth, only for two generations. Viewed from this angle, the story o f the feud between Periander and his son Lycophron, which was told before (3.49-53), retrospectively appears as the consequence o f an ancestral curse. I t is also i n itself a tragedy reminiscent o f the Oresleia or Sophocles' Electa. Periander has killed his wife. As a consequence, his youngest son, who has been informed about the murder by his grandfather, refuses to talk to him. Periander retaliates by turning his son out o f his house and forbidding anyone to receive h i m or even speak to h i m . T h e son becomes destitute and, when offered by Periander to come back home, echoes the Sophoclean Electra by turning down a life o f luxury and privilege i n the palace with an ironic answer which is reported indirect speech. Later on, Periander attempts twice to make his peace with his son. His third attempt is about to succeed (he has agreed to leave Corinth and settle i n Corcyra), when the Corcyreans murder the son to prevent the coming o f the father, an ironical ending which introduces the 'too late' motif so familiar to the readers o f Sophocles.
:ii
See also Gh. 5, pp. 113—14, in this volume.
28
SUZANNE SAÏD
Astyages and Cyrus Herodotus' account o f the birth and upbringing o f Cyrus, which is given a strikingly dramatic f o r m , also incorporates motifs which, ' i f not directly borrowed from Athenian tragedy, at least have a cousinly relationship' (Evans (1991) 53). I t is indeed a tragedy for Astyages (he is overthrown by Cyrus) and for Harpagos (his son is killed because o f the very measure taken by his father to ensure his safety). Like Laius, ' who was warned by an oracle that his son would kill h i m , Astyages is sent two ominous dreams regarding his daughter's son. As a consecjuence, he marries his daughter to a man far below her (a reaction analogous to that o f the Euripidean Aegisthus, who marries Electra to a peasant, see Erbse (1992) 34) and attempts to kill her child, who is, however, like Oedipus, saved by a herdsman. T h e identity o f Cyrus is finally uncovered i n circumstances analogous to the anagnorisis o f Oedipus Rex (by threatening the herdsman with torture), and Astyages is overthrown because o f two 'tragic' mistakes (Pelling (1996) 75-6). First, he wrongly believed that the prophecy had been fulfilled, since Cyrus had become a play king. Second and worse, after punishing Harpagos, who disobeyed his orders by not killing the child himself, and serving h i m the flesh o f his own son, a punishment which duplicates the feast o f Thyestes which was also served 'under the pretence o f happily celebrating a feast day' (Aesch. Ag. 1595), he became a victim o f ate and, 'blinded as it were by the gods' (1.127.2), placed Harpagos i n command o f the army sent to fight, against Cyrus. This tragic m o t i f is developed with a typically tragic i r o n y . Astyages' speech is as ambiguous as Clytemnestra's address to Agamemnon i n the Oresteia: 'concealing his anger' (1.118.1), he asks Harpagos to send his son to the palace, announces his intention to offer a sacrifice as a thank-offering for 34
3 1
30
34
It includes a succession of dialogues reported in direct speech between Astyages and Harpagos (1.108.5-5), Harpagos and his wife (1.109.2-4), Harpagos and the herdsman (1.110.3), the herdsman and his wife (1.111.2-112.3), Artembares, the Persian noble whose son has been beaten up by Cyrus and Astyages (1.114.5), Cyrus and Astyages (1.1 15.1-3), Astyages and Artembares (1.116.2), Astyages and Harpagos (1.117.2-118.2), Astyages and the Magi (1.120.2-6), Astyages'and Cyrus (1.121). On the Cyrus story, see also Boedckcr (Ch. 5) and Gray (Ch. 13), this volume. O n this parallel, see Evans (1991) 52. According to Burkert (1983) 108 9, 'the details of the story were probably taken from the feast of Thyestes, for we know that Herodotus was preceded by the versions in the Alkmaionis, Pherecydes and Aeschylus 'Agamemnon' and may be by Euripides' Thyestes, which may be prior to 425, according to Erbse (1992) 33. 35
:m
129
HERODOTUS A N D T R A G E D Y
Cyrus' survival and invites h i m to the feast. Besides, the contrast between the delusion o f Harpagos, who went home thinking that ' i t was a great thing to have come off so lightly' (1.119.1) and his dreadful discovery that he has eaten the flesh o f his son would not be out o f place i n a Sophoclean tragedy. T h e dialogue between Harpagos and Astyages, which closes the episode, suggests that Harpagos was no less deluded i n his revenge: by helping Cyrus to become king and enslave the Medes, he was most foolish and most unjust, 'most foolish, because, when he might have been king himself, he gave another man the power, most unjust, because merely on account o f that supper, he brought the Medes into slavery' (1.129.3). But the conclusion o f the story—at least for Astyages—is not tragic: whereas Laius was killed by his son, 'Cyrus d i d not do Astyages any h a r m and kept h i m by his side' (1.130.3). Herodotus' account o f Cyrus' life also follows a tragic pattern. T h e Cyrus who overthrew Astyages and campaigned successfully against Croesus and Babylon was a wise king, aware o f the instability o f human life (1.86.6) and protected by the gods (1.124, 126). H e is succeeded by a Gyrus w h o , i n his campaign against the Massagetae, becomes foolish and does everything w r o n g . He considers himself more than human and has to be reminded by Croesus that he is only a man (1.204.2; 207.2). As a result, he misunderstands the dream which predicts his own death and the accession o f Darius to the throne as a manifestation o f divine care for his person (1.209.1-210.1). Like Croesus before h i m (1.13; 1.33.1), 'he pays no attention' to admonitions (1.213.1), becomes 'overconfident' (1.212.2; cf. M a r g (1965) 295-7) and 'insatiate' (1.212.2, 3) because o f the magnitude o f his successes, and, i n the end, experiences a reversal whose completeness is manifested through echoes between the beginning o f the narrative and its encV I n the dream o f Astyages, a vine, growing from the genitals o f his daughter and spreading over the whole o f Asia, presaged Cyrus' rule over Asia. Wine plays a major role i n his fatal campaign against the Massagetae as well. Tomyris' son was defeated by wine and the queen, who had sworn to make Gyrus pay for his treachery by 'satiating h i m with blood (1.213.1; 214.5), cut off his head and 'put it into a wineskin' (1.214.4) filled w i t h human blood. J/
8
5
17 3 8
Avery (1972) 536-41 and Stahl (1975) 19-35. Immerwahr (1966) 165-7.
130
SUZANNE SAÏD
Cambyses T h e story o f Gyrus' successor, Cambyses, is divided into two parts: his madness and his crimes (3.1-38) and his punishment (3.61.-6). T h e first part is tragic insofar as it is a picture o f a change for the worse. I n the beginning, Cambyses behaved as a humane king towards the defeated Psammenitus, as d i d his father Cyrus towards Croesus (3,14 15; cf. Erbse (1992) 49). T h e n , contrary to the nomoi o f the Persians and the Egyptians alike, he outraged and burnt the corpse o f the Egyptian king Amasis (3.16.1-4). Disregarding the warning o f the Ethiopian king, he launched an 'unjust' (3.21.2) campaign, which ended i n disaster. H e sinned against the gods and their priests, committed the worst crimes against his o w n kin (incest and murder, 3.30-2), and outraged his most faithful servant and the noblest among the Persians (3.34-5). A l l these were 'the acts o f a madman'. Only the murder o f his brother Smerdis can be assimilated to a tragic hamartia, since Cambyses put h i m to death because he misinterpreted a dream (3.30.2 3) and feared that his brother might kill h i m and rule. 39
40
As rightly emphasized by Erbse ((1992) 55), tragic motives come to the fore i n the second part o f Cambyses' stoiy, i n a narrative interrupted by dialogues and culminating i n the great speech addressed to the leading Persians by their dying king. Cambyses' mortal wound, located ' i n the place where he himself had stabbed the god o f the Egyptians, Apis' (3.64.3), is a perfect example o f tragic retribution," followed by 'what from Aristotle we have learned to think o f as "tragic discovery" and to associate to fifth century drama' (Gould (1989) 76). I n the end, Cambyses is 'brought back to his senses' (esophronese, 3.64.5). Like Heracles i n the Trachiniae, who understands too late the meaning o f the oracles given to h i m (vv. 1159 - 6 1 , 1164 71), he grasps only then the true meaning o f previous omens. T h e Smerdis o f his dream was not his brother but the Magus, and therefore 'the murder o f his brother had been all to no purpose' (3.64.2). T h e Ecbatana where he was due to die according to the oracle at Buto, was not—as he thought—the M e d i a n Ecbatana: 'as
3 9
He burns the oracle of Zeus Ammon (3.25.3), wounds the Apis-calf and orders the Egyptian priests to be whipped (3.29.1-2). •"' Hdt 3.25. 30. 33. 34, 35. 37, 38. 61. Reinhardt (1940) 347, Gould (1989) 75. 41
HERODOTUS A N D T R A G E D Y
131
it turned out the oracle meant Ecbatana o f Syria' (3.64.4). A n d his words 'this is the place where it is assigned that Cambyses, son o f Cyrus, should die' (3.64.5) echo the exclamation o f Heracles i n the Trachiniae: 'Alas, I understand i n what a plight I a m ' (1145). Cambyses also realizes that his behaviour was wrong: he had 'acted w i t h more haste than judgment' and 'wholly mistook what was going to be' (3.65.4). This moment o f realization also involves, as in tragedy, the discovery o f a general truth regarding the human condition. T h e hero o f the Trachiniae understands at last that 'only the dead are spared pain' (1.1.73); Cambyses discovers that 'it is not after all i n the nature o f man to avert what is going to happen' (3.65.3). T h e last speech o f Cambyses has a tragic ring as well. His command to the Persians that they should take revenge o n the M a g i and 'regain their dominion 'by cunning i f the M a g i have won it by cunning, or by force i f they have achieved their purpose by force' (3.65.6), echoes the oracle telling Orestes to hunt down the murderers o f his father 'after the same fashion' (that is 'by cunning') and to 'return murder for murder' (Ckoeph. 273-4, 555-9). Last but not least, the description o f Cambyses' death, which shows a king 'bitterly lamenting the cruelty o f his lot' and Persians 'tearing their clothes and showing their sympathy by a great deal o f crying and groaning' (3.65.6 67.1) suggests an ending similar to that o f the Persians o f Aeschylus, where the king's lament is echoed and amplified by the chorus o f Persian elders. Included i n the tragedy o f Cambyses is the tragedy o f Prexaspes (Reinhardt (1940) 345--7). I n a reverse way, it parallels the story o f Harpagos, which was part o f the Astyages drama. Like Harpagos, Prexaspes was 'the most trusted' (3.30.3) o f the king's friends. But, as opposed to Harpagos, when Prexaspes was given the order to kill the king's brother, he remained faithful and carried out his duty. Yet, like Harpagos, he had his son killed by the king (3.35.1-4). But instead o f the expected betrayal and revenge, he finally decided, after the death o f Cambyses, not to side w i t h the M a g i who had taken h i m into their confidence, 'since he had been cruelly treated by Cambyses' (3.66.3). After agreeing to make a declaration that Smerdis was still alive, he 'revealed the true state o f affairs' (3.75.2) before committing suicide.
132
SUZANNE SAÏD
Croesus T h e comparison o f these two stories within a story demonstrates on a small scale how skillfully Herodotus manipulates in different ways the motifs he borrowed from tragedy. T h e same conclusion is to be drawn from the analysis o f the Grocms-logos, which is, according to most scholars, the most 'dramatic, tragic and theatrical" logos and best demonstrates the influence o f tragedy on the Histories (Stahl (1968)). I n fact, many o f the tragic motifs that, are scattered in other narratives are here put together. Yet one may be reluctant to follow Myres and read the whole Lydian logos as 'the prose scenario for a tragic "Capture o f Sardis" like the Capture of Miletus. . . . T h e sketch o f the rise o f the M e r m n a d a e stands for the prologue; the scene between Croesus and Solon is the ironic counterpart to the scene between Creon and Tiresias i n Antigone, followed by the death o f Atys, as by that o f Haemon . . . When Croesus is on the pyre . . . Apollo (comes) as deus ex machina. Between these epeuodia the digressions on Athens and Sparta fall into place as antistrophic stasima' (Myres (1953) 76 7). I would rather distinguish, with Lesky and Herington, first, a tragedy o f Gyges (1.7-13), which determines the fate o f the dynasty, second, a tragedy which involves Croesus, his son and a man who i n the past has killed his brother unwillingly and ends with the death o f the son and the suicide o f his involuntary murderer (1.34-45). 2
43
44
15
Like an Aeschylean tragedy, the story o f Gyges involves, alongside human motivation, a supernatural strand o f causation, since 'disaster had to befall Candaules' (1.8.2). T h e hero, Gyges, is placed twice in a 'truly tragic situation'." First, he 'cannot find a way out' (1.10.1), when obliged by the king to see the queen naked in her own bedroom. Second, 'forced' (1.11.4) by the queen to choose between two roads, either to kill or to be killed, he is 'forced to become against his own will the murderer o f his master' (1.11.4), a 1
2
•' Evans (1991) 45 quotes Mvres (1914). Grene (1961). Page (1962), Immerwahr (1966) 97-101. See also Chs. 9 and 13 in this volume. Lesky (1977) passim, Herington (1991b) 6-7. * On the Gyges-tragedy, see Stahl (1968) passim and Ricks (1975) 32. ' For an analysis of the Atys-story as a tragedy, see Immerwahr (1966) 7 0 - 1 , Rieks (1975) 33-7, Fornara (1983) 171-2, Erbse'(1992) 16-7, Laurot (1995) 97 102! Lesky (1977) 227 is right in thinking that this does not imply a direct borrowing from an existing Atys tragedy. Snell (1973) 201; Stahl (1975) 2. ,:i
b
1,1
HERODOTUS AND TRAGEDY
133
choice which will have tragic consequences for his descendants. The similarities between this tragic choice and that o f Aeschylean heroes faced w i t h two equally grievous alternatives, such as Pelasgus in the Suppliants, Agamemnon at Aulis i n the Agamemnon, or Orestes in the Choeplwroi, are obvious. The circumstances o f the murder also deserve attention. Gyges is supposed to attack Gandaules 'starting from the very place from where he has been shown the queen naked' (1.11.5). I n the same way, Sophocles made clear in his Electra that Aegisthus would die at the place where he killed Agamemnon (El. 1495-6). According to a definition o f responsibility which is objective and collective, as in the tragedy o f Aeschylus (see Said (1978) 265 6), this murder, though committed under compulsion, by a man who 'followed a woman's treacherous instructions' (1.9.1), as acknowledged by Apollo himself, is nevertheless a crime, since. Gyges 'has killed his master and held his office, to which he had no claim' (1.91.1). It calls for a revenge, which will come in the fifth generation: Croesus will pay for the crime of Gyges (1.13.2, 91.1). Similarly in the Seven against Thebes (743-52), the third generation, that is, the two sons o f Oedipus, had to atone for the sin o f Laius, who, overcome in the same way by the will o f a woman, disobeyed the order of Apollo and begot a son. T h e transformation o f Gyges into a tragic hero seems to be due to Herodotus, as demonstrated by a comparison with the two other extant versions of Gyges' usurpation, handed down by Plato (Rep. 359c6~360b2) arid Xanthus (FGrHist 90, 44 11 47). I n the Republic, Gyges is a lucky shepherd, who cannot resist the temptation to get hold o f the throne without risk: having discovered by chance a golden ring which makes h i m invisible, he becomes the lover o f the queen and, together with her, kills the king and seizes the throne o f Lydia. I n the Ludiaka, Gyges kills the king to escape death, because he has fallen i n love with Gandaules' wife who has told her husband about Gyges' betrayal. The publication by Lobel o f a papyrus fragment preserving parts of the speech in which the wife of Gandaules tells o f Gyges' visit to her bedroom has opened new possibilities for the interpretation o f the Herodotean account. W i t h the exception o f Lloyd-Jones (1952),
Pohlcnz (1937) 6!, Stahl (1968) 393.
134
SUZANNE SAÏD
who suggests a different possibility ('the fragment would be a part of an iambus o f Archilochus, deliberately or accidentally translated into the Attic dialect') without, however, absolutely ruling out the possibility" that it is a fragment o f a tragedy, all the scholars who have written on the fragment have unanimously assigned it to a tragedy. But relying on arguments from the metre and the vocabulary, they have reached widely different conclusions regarding the date o f the play and its relation to the Histories. For some scholars (Lobel, Page, Cataudella, and Snell), this is an early tragedy, anterior to Herodotus and to be attributed either to Phrynichus, Ion o f Chios, or, more vaguely, a pupil o f Aeschylus. According to the majority, - it is a Hellenistic tragedy. It is therefore possible to suppose either that the play depended on Herodotus or that it is the source o f the Herodotean account (given that we haive only sixteen lines from this play, it is difficult- to say the least— to assess its impact on Herodotus; besides, the example o f Aeschylus' Persians'' impact on the last books o f the Histories—on which more will be said below—seems to exclude a priori the possibility of major borrowings).' As far as I am concerned, I would rather share the scepticism o f Raubitschek (1955) and Holzberg (1973), who, after a careful examination o f all the arguments pro and contra, leave open the question o f the date. The second tragedy (1.34-45) is much closer to Sophocles. Right from the beginning, Herodotus alludes to a predetermined fate: 'the righteous anger o f a god (nemesis) took hold o f Croesus because he thought himself the most blessed o f men' (1.34.1). Yet he carefully presents this interpretation as a mere guess (hos eikasai, 1.34.1). T h e episode follows immediately after Croesus' conversation with Solon (1.30-3), which makes clear that the king is unable to pay attention to the warning o f a wise man, w h o m he wrongly abuses as a fool, a tragic irony which Stahl accurately equates with the insults hurled 48
1
1
0
Lobel (1950), Page (1950), (1951), (1962), Cataudella (1957), Snell (1973). Relying on the fragments of a hydria from Corinth published by Beazley in Hesperia 25 (1955) 305-19 and dated in all probability between 470 and 460 or 450, which represents Croesus on his pyre, but also a Greek youth playing the Hute (which suggests an actual scene of a tragedy), and combining it with the evidence of the papyri, Page suggests that there existed a trilogy on the fall of the royal house of Lydia in the first half of the fifth century. * Latte (1950), Maas (1950), Galiano (1950/1), Kakridis (1951), Cantarella (1952), Gigantc (1952), Lesky (1953), Bickel (1957), Kassel (1974), Erbse (1992) 4 5. '"' This is the conclusion reached by Lesky (1977), Evans (1985), and Erbse (1992) 5.
135
HERODOTUS A N D TRAGEDY
1
by the Sophoclean Oedipus at the seer Teiresias. ' I n fact, there are many more echoes between Oedipus Rex and the tragedy o f Croesus. Like Oedipus, Croesus, warned by the gods o f a disaster to come, does his best to prevent the fatal outcome: told by an oracular dream that one o f his sons was to die struck by an iron weapon (1.34), 'he got h i m a wife, saw to it that he no longer took the field with the Lydian soldiers whom he used to command. He also removed all the weapons, javelins, spears and so on from the men's rooms' (1.34.3). When persuaded by his son to send him to a hunt, he again took every precaution by asking Adrastus, w h o m earlier he had received as a friend and ritually purified o f a murder, to pay back his obligation by 'watching over' - his son. Nevertheless, his son is ironically--killed by the spear o f the very man w h o m his father has appointed to watch over h i m . Besides, Atys, like Oedipus, plays an active part in the decision which ultimately causes his death: he is the one who convinces a reluctant Croesus to allow h i m to participate in the hunt, by demonstrating to h i m that the dream does not say anything about a boar's tusk. Last but not least, there is Adrastus, who accidentally becomes a murderer and commits suicide, like die heroine of Sophocles' Trachiniae. He first kills his brother 'unwillingly' (1.35.3). Then, also by accident (his spear misses the boar and hits Croesus' son) and during a hunt in which he becomes involved against his wishes (1.42.1) he kills his benefactor's son. Forgiven by Croesus, who 'pities h i m ' and agrees that 'he was not guilty o f this crime' (1.45)—as does Hyllus i n the Trachiniae, when he finds out the truth about his mother (Track. 934-5, 1134-42)- , he kills himself (see Said (1978) 267-8). 1
The way in which these two narratives are organized is also reminiscent o f tragedy, as many scholars from Myres to Laurot have pointed out. M o r e precisely, they have underlined 'the masterly interweaving o f direct and indirect speech'' in these two episodes, which both, like an Attic tragedy, stage three characters Candaules, his wife, and Gyges, and Croesus, Atys, and Adrastus. 53
4
y
- Stahl (1975 ) 6 quotes OR 375; see also OR 433-6. Hdl. 1.41 (putaxtcov; 42 · cpuXdoaeiv. . . . xov ipuAiioaovTo:;. • See Myres (1953) 76-8, Immerwahr (1966) 70 1, Stahl (1968) passim, Rieks (1975) passim, Lesky (1977) 225, Foniara (1983) 171-2, Evans (1991b) 45 7, Herington (1991) 6, Laurot (1995) passim. Gould (1989) 54 and Stahl (1975) 4. w
M
136
SUZANNE SAÏD
I n the major part o f the Croesus logos (1.46-92), the formal similarities with tragedy are less obvious. As opposed to the tragic action, which occupies only a short span o f time, the events which take place extend over a long period. Besides, there are only two dialogues between Cyrus and Croesus at the very end o f the narrative. Yet, the same tragic combination o f supernatural causation and human motivation is to be found there. T h e fall o f Croesus and the capture o f Sardis, which have been repeatedly announced by a portent (1.78.1), and a series o f oracles given right at the beginning o f the expedition (1.46-58) or even long before it (1.84, 85; see Stahl (1975) 10-11), demonstrate that 'it is impossible even for a god to escape the lot assigned' (1.91.1), an idea which is not specific to Attic tragedy and may well be found i n the Iliad. But there is at least one detail which may be a direct borrowing from tragedy. I n her answer to the complaint o f Croesus, the Pythia alludes to a partially successful bargaining by Apollo: 'unable to divert the Moirai from their course' (1.91), the god nevertheless gained for Croesus three extra years o f prosperity. One is reminded o f Aeschylus' Eumenides.™ where the Erinyes reproach Apollo for beguiling the Moirai i n order to help Admetus. But some responsibility is also laid on man. I n reaction to Croesus, who after his fall accused his evil daimon and the god o f the Greeks o f having 'encouraged' h i m to eampaign against Cyrus by means o f 'deceptive' oracles (1.87.3; 90.2), the Pythia points out the mistake o f the king, who did not 'understand' the meaning o f the two oracles given to h i m by Delphi (1.91.4, 5)—an interpretation finally accepted by Croesus (1.91.6) and confirmed by a narrative which describes Croesus as deluded by 'hope' (1.54.1; 56.1; 71.1; 75.1; 77.4), 'trusting. . . ambiguous oracles', whose meaning he 'misses' (1.71.1: hamarton tou khresmou; 73.1; 75.2), and unable to listen to the advice given to h i m by the 'wise' Sandanis (1.71.2-4). 50
57
But the conclusion o f the stoiy, as Herodotus chooses to tell i t , is not tragic, since Croesus escapes death (he is miraculously rescued by Apollo) and, after learning wisdom through suffering, 58
39
723 8. CI'. Rieb (1975) 31. On the blindness of Croesus during the campaign against Cvrns, see Marg (1965) 292-3 and Stahl (1975) 8-10. ' On the other versions of the fate of Croesus after the sack of Sardis, sec Burkert (1985) passim. FA-ans (1991) 48 points out that 'the fall of Croesus is a qualified one'. " Hdt. 1.207.1. On the limits of this wisdom, sec Stahl (1975) 19-36. 3 0
J
58
137
HERODOTUS AND T R A G E D Y
00
assumes towards Cyrus and later towards his son Cambyses the role played by Solon in his own life. Besides, one has to note that the tragedy o f Croesus is but one side o f the coin. The other is the success story o f Cyrus, a success that is not to be explained only by 'the good luck' (1.87.5) o f the Persian king, but also by careful plan ning, clever stratagems and accurate observation (1.79.1; 80.4; 84.4). 61
0
Herodotus' Histories and Aeschylus' Persians " Herodotus knew and used Aeschylus' Persians, as is demonstrated by a series o f verbal echoes particularly in reported or direct speeches. ' For instance, as Broadhead, and H o w and Wells have pointed out in their commentaries," Artabanus in the Histories, as well as Atossa in the Persians, portrays a king led astray by his 'consort with bad m e n ' . What is more, the prophecy o f Bacis quoted approvingly by Herodotus (8.77) and the speech delivered by Themistocles after Salamis (8.109.2-5) interpret Xerxes' defeat in the same way as Aeschylus. Like Darius in the Persians, the oracle, after emphasizing the 'madness' o f the aggressor, attributes the Persian setback to 'divine Dike', which quenches Koros, the son o f Hubris. W h e n Themistocles says: 1 3
1
65
Indeed we did not do it. It was God and heroes, who were jealous that one man in his godless pride should be king of Asia and of Europe t o o a man who is impious and reckless, who burns and destroys the statues of the gods and dared to lash the sea with whips and bind it with fetters (8.109.3) he precisely echoes the words of the Aeschylean Darius (Pers. 745-8, 809-12). But what in the Persians was the final message o f the play has become a mere argument in the Histories. For this grand speech serves a very personal purpose. As Herodotus says (8.109.5), Themistocles wanted to prevent the Athenians from pursuing the
R
" Hdt. 1.155 6: advises Cyrus to spare the Lydians and punish only Pactyes and his followers; 207: advises Cyrus to cross the river and fight the Massagetae on their own territory by tricking them (two examples of advice followed by Cyrus: 1.208, 211); when he accompanies Cambyses in his expedition against Egypt, he warns him against reckless behaviour (3.36). Marg (1965) 294, Stahl (1975) 13 4, 20. See also Ch. 24 in this volume. Immcrwahr (1954) 28, Herington (1991b) 6. Broadhead (I960) ad Pers. 753-5 and How and Wells (1928) ad Hdt. 7.16. Persians 753: κακοΐς ομιλών άνδράσιν, Hdt. 7.16 α: ανθρώπων κακών όμιλίαι. 61
63
m
65
138
SUZANNE SAÏD
Persians, thus laying the foundation for a future claim upon Xerxes, i f he happened to get into trouble w i t h the Athenians. Besides, a close examination o f these correspondences suggests that Herodotus more often than not displaced, adapted or even significantly altered the meaning o f the phrases he borrowed. His description o f the grief o f the Persians tearing their clothes, weeping and wailing (9.99.2), which is clearly derived from the end o f the Persians, does not take place after the king's arrival, but before it. I n the Histories. it is Xerxes who tells the leading Persians that he has been thinking how not to fall short o f his predecessors and how to add as much power as they d i d to the Persian empire, while i n the Persians he was blamed for not increasing the possessions inherited from his father (Hdt. 7.8; Pers. 754-6). When Artabanus, now i n favour o f the expedition, tells Xerxes to do his best to help the god who offers h i m such an opportunity, he ironically echoes the lesson drawn by Darius from the failure o f Xerxes: 'when a man is striving, god assists h i m ' ( H d t . 7.18; Pers. 742). Yet, the best illustration o f the gap between Herodotus and Aeschylus is their opposite use o f the famous sentence 'Remember Athens'. I n the Histories (5.1.05; 6.94), Darius orders a slave to remind h i m o f the Athenians, i n order to take his revenge on them for the sack o f Sardis; i n the Persians, he asked the chorus to remember the Athenians and their victory to prevent them from sending another expedition ( w . 823-6). Such differences may warn the reader against overestimating the influence o f the Persians on the narrative o f Herodotus. A close reading o f Books Seven to Nine shows i n fact, besides similarities, great discrepancies between the two interpretations o f the second Persian War. Given that the tragic poet and the historian both wanted to picture a major reversal o f fortune, * they contrasted sharply the beginn i n g and the end o f the expedition. Like the prologue and the parodos o f the Persians, Herodotus' two descriptions o f the Persian army, the catalogue o f the troops and the calculation o f their n u m ber before the first major battles o f the war i n Book Seven, ' provide a spectacular display o f the power o f Xerxes, which only serves to bring out better the magnitude o f his disaster. T h e exodos o f the Persians, w i t h the appearance o f a king i n rags and without men 1
1 7
fi,i
67
O n the reversal in the Persians, see Said (1988). Hdt. 7.41-2, 54-5, 60-99, 184-6 and Persians 16-59, 65-87.
HERODOTUS A N D TRAGEDY
139
escorting h i m , is matched by the account o f his arrival at the Hellespont 'with hardly a fraction o f his army' (8.115.1). In the Histories as i n the Persians, the ill-fated outcome o f the war is announced by a series o f signs sent by the gods. T h e dream o f Atossa, the omen o f the eagle and the hawk which follows it, and the oracle given i n the past to Darius and alluded to i n his dialogue with Atossa (176-211, 739-41) are paralleled i n the Histories not only by the words o f the wise Artabanus, who predicts the disaster right at the beginning o f the expedition, but also by a string o f dreams, oracles, and portents. But these divine signs are sometimes used by Herodotus i n a way which is more like Sophocles than like Aeschylus. Whereas i n the Persians the queen and the chorus were well aware of their threatening character (v. 211), i n the Histories they are either misinterpreted by the M a g i as foreshadowing a catastrophe for the Greeks '" or neglected by Xerxes (7.58.1). m
1
According to Herodotus and Aeschylus alike, the expedition was doomed to fail right from the start, because it was a manifestation o f hubris ( / t o / 8 0 8 , 821; H d t . 7.16oc2; 8. 77.1). Both writers see the conquest o f Greece as the first step towards an universal empire: the paroclos o f the Persians, which pictures a king leading his troops 'against the whole world' (74), is echoed i n the Histories by the first speech o f Xerxes, who plans to make the Persian empire 'coterminous with Zeus' heaven' (7.8y2). Both agree that Xerxes violated a natural order guaranteed by the gods by bringing together two lands, Europe and Asia, which were intended to remain separate, and by enslaving people who by nature are free. I n Aeschylus, the parallelism o f these two attempts is made manifest i n the emphasis laid on the 'bridging' (in Greek 'yoking': w . 72, 722) of the Bosphorus, which is powerful and assimilated to a god (723, 746), by means o f 'fetters' (745, 747), and the recurrent simile o f the yoke o f slavery (50, 191, 196, 594). What is more, the dream o f Atossa (181 99) clearly brings together the two themes o f uniting and enslaving (the two women who were allotted two separate domains, the Greek land /t)
The prophecies announcing a failure which arc omitted by Onomacritus: 7.6; the third dream of Xerxes: 7.19.1; the eclipse of the sun when the army leaves Sardis: 7.37; the two portents which occur at Sardis and after the crossing of the Hellespont: 7.57 8. On the dreams, see also below, p. 1-14. "·' Hdt. 7.19: the third dream of Xerxes and 37.3 the eclipse. See also 7.53.2 (Xerxes) and 7.209.4 (Demaratus). 7 0
140
SUZANNE SAÏD
and that of the barbarians, are put under the same yoke). Similarly, Herodotus pictures a Xerxes who transgresses natural boundaries, not only by bridging the Bosphorus and linking the two continents,' but also by cutting a canal through Athos (7.22.1-24.2). This turning land into sea is another way of interfering with nature, as is demonstrated by the oracle warning the Cnidians against digging a canal and transforming a peninsula into an island (1.174.3-6). Like Aeschylus, Herodotus also suggests a correspondence between the bridge ('yoke') over the Bosphorus and the 'yoke' of servitude in the first speech of Xerxes (7.8(31 61). Moreover, after the first bridge was destroyed by a storm, he pictures a king commanding that a pair o f 'fetters' (7.35.1) be thrown into the sea, but, i n contrast to Aeschylus, he suggests that Xerxes may later have repented (7.54.3). T h e Persians were also guilty o f sacking and burning the temples of the Greek gods. T h e i r impiety, which was vigorously condemned by the Aeschylean Darius (Persians 809 12), is illustrated on several occasions i n the Histories? But it is mitigated by Herodotus' allusion to Xerxes' possible remorse after the burning o f the Acropolis (8.54) and his reminder that this fire was set in retaliation for the burning of the temple of Cybele by the Greeks during the sack of Sardis (5 J 02.1). As a consequence, the defeat of the Persians is explained in a slightly different way by the tragic poet, who stresses the role o f the gods, and the historian, who puts more emphasis on the part played by natural forces i n the Persian defeat. According to Aeschylus, the hubris o f Xerxes and his sins brought on a downfall which has to be explained by a supernatural intervention either by a just Zeus, as suggested by Darius (739 40, 827-88), who is the mouthpiece of the poet, or by an envious and deceitful god, as suggested by the messenger (353-4, 454-5, 495-7, 513-14), the queen (472-3), the chorus (515-16, 532-4) and Xerxes himself (909-12). Herodotus' attitude is more complex. Like Aeschylus, he may sometimes take for granted a direct intervention of the divinity: the wrecking o f the Persian fleet sailing round Euboea is to be 1
a
1
73
71
H d t 7.8pl; I Op I ; 33; 34; 36; 8.20.2; 9.120.4. Hdt. 8.32.2, 33.1: the burning and pillaging of the temples in Phocis; 35.1 2: the attempt to plunder Apollo's temple at Delphi; 8.53.2: their stripping the temple of its treasures and burning everything on the Acropolis. For a different view, see Ch. 8, pp. 193 1, in this volume. 72
,:!
;
141
HERODOTUS A N D TRAGEDY
explained by a 'god' who was doing everything to make the Persian fleet equal to the Greek and prevent it from being much superior (8.13)—an explanation which may answer the words o f the messenger, who explained the defeat o f the Persians at Salamis as due to a god who tipped the scales against the Persians by allocating them an unequal share o f luck (Persians 345 7). But Herodotus usually qualifies this type o f explanation and distances himself from i t , by placing it into a speech or by putting it in quotation marks with formulas such as 'it is said' or ' X said', as in the case o f the storm at cape Sepias, the intervention o f the two giant warriors who routed the Persians at Delphi, the miracle o f T h r i a , or the appearance before Salamis o f a phantom i n the shape of a woman/' It is only for minor incidents—the drowning o f the Persians at Paliene or the fact that they did not enter the shrine o f Demeter at Plataea that Herodotus accepts or even suggests himself a supernatural explanation (8.129.3; 9.65.2). O n the contrary, he often draws attention to the decisive intervention o f natural forces. This theme was already adumbrated i n the Persians. According to Darius, who, like Artabanus i n the Histories, often speaks on behalf of the author, the land itself is the ally o f the Greeks, by killing through starvation the mass o f the Persians (792-4), a truth already demonstrated i n the play by the description of the Persian retreat by the messenger (488-91). Artabanus goes further. He tells Xerxes that the land and the sea 'the two mightiest powers i n the world are his worst enemies': the sea, because 'there is not a harbour anywhere big enough to receive your fleet' and the land, because it will not produce enough food for such a large army and 'will starve y o u ' (7.49.2-5). T h e narrative amply validates these predictions. Herodotus alludes to the ruin o f those who had to entertain the Persians (7.118). H e mentions rivers which failed to provide enough water for their needs (7.127.2; 187.1). He describes how the troops of Xerxes, during their retreat after Salamis, had to 'eat grass where they found no grain and strip the barks and leaves of trees of all. sorts cultivated and wild because o f hunger' (8.115.2). H e tells how many among the men o f Artabazus after Plataea 'succumbed to hunger and exhaustion' (9.89.4). H e also pictures their ships wrecked by the storms because there was not enough room on the short stretch o f beach (7.188.1-3). 1
" Hdt. 7.189.1, 189.3; 8.38, 39.1, 65.1, 84.2.
142
SUZANNE SAID
U n t i l now, wc have only pointed out changes o f emphasis from Aeschylus to Herodotus. T u r n i n g to the presentation o f Xerxes' deci sion and the analysis o f the causes o f the second Persian W a r which it supposes, we shall see major discrepancies o f form as well as o f content between the Persians and the Histories. First the form. Whereas the two sets o f causation, human and supernatural, are closely entwined i n the Persians, Herodotus keeps them apart. The human motives are expressed i n the reported speech o f Mardonius and the speeches delivered during the council o f the leading Persians which follows (7.5-11); the supernatural visitations, put i n quotation marks by the formula 'as it is said by the Persians' (7.12.1), occur i n the dreams which follow and play a decisive role in Xerxes' decision (7.12-18). Second the content. I n the tragedy o f Aeschylus, the decision o f Xerxes to take 'revenge'(vv. 473-5) on Athens for the defeat o f Marathon is consistently presented as the consequence o f a passionate desire of the king (233: Ί'μειρ', 826: άλλων έρασθείς), which betrays his ignorance, his lack o f understanding,' ' or even his madness (719: έμώρανεν), a 'disease' which is sometimes explained by his temper (he is young (13, 744, 782) and rash (718, 754: θούριος)), by the intervention o f bad advisers (753-8), or a deception sent by the gods (93, 472, 831). As is demonstrated by the long speech where Darius rewrites Persian history (765-81), this decision is totally at odds w i t h the policy o f Xerxes' predecessors, beginning with Meclus, the epony mous hero o f the Medes, and Cyrus, the founder o f the Persian empire. W i t h the exception o f the usurper Marclus, they knew how to 'control their passions' (767) and had a 'sound m i n d ' (772). Therefore, they were beloved by the gods and successful (768, 772). The Aeschylean Cyrus i n particular was a wise ruler who limited his conquests to Lydia, Phrygia, and Ionia (770-1), that is, to Asian territories included i n the domain allotted to the barbarians by the gods (186-7). T h e Aeschylean Xerxes is also totally opposed to a father whose advice he has forgotten (783). For the Aeschylean Darius is a king who did not transgress the limitations assigned to the Persian 73
1
Persians 361: ού ξύνεις, δόλον 373: ού γαρ τό μέλλον έκ θεών ήπίστατο., 454: κακώς τό μέλλον Ίστορών., 744: τ ά δ ' ού κατειδώς. "' Persians 552: δυσφρόνως 725: μή φρονεΐν καλώς, 749: ουκ ευβουλία, 829: σωφρονεΐν κεχρημένον.
143
HERODOTUS A N D T R A G E D Y
77
empire by the gods (he never crossed the river Halys) and never did any harm to the Persians. O n the contrary, die Herodotean Xerxes, at the beginning o f Book Seven, did not possess any great wish to invade Greece. It is only those around h i m , Mardonius and the Peisistratidae, as well as the Aleuadae i n Thessaly, who were anxious to campaign. Among the arguments put forward privately as well as publicly by Mardonius and repeated by Xerxes, the only one which may be an echo o f Aeschylus is revenge." But it is less a cause than a pretext, as is said not only by the Greek envoys to Gelon (7.157.2), but by Herodotus himself (7.138.1). The two political arguments that appear i n the two speeches of Xerxes and seem to influence his decision are absent from the Persians. This is no surprise, for the first one, that Greece has to be con quered because it is a fertile country (7.8.a2), turns on its head the commonplace contrast between Greek poverty (7.102.1) and Persian wealth, and the second one (7.11.2), which presents the expedition as a 'pre-emptive strike' (Evans (1991) 14) and introduces the idea o f a struggle for survival and the 'them or us' attitude, 'clearly points to the period around the outbreak o f the Peloponnesian War' (Raaflaub (1987) 228). 78
7,1
0
Moreover, the argument which carries the day and appears i n the first speech o f Xerxes as well as in the dreams which are sent first to Xerxes and then to Artabanus, the iron law o f imperialist expan sionism, is foreign to Aeschylus. I n Book Seven, Xerxes opens his speech by saying that by launching a campaign against Greece, he is not establishing a new nomos, but is only following the one he inherited from his predecessors: Ί learn from our elders that we have never remained inactive (oudama ko etremisamen), since we took the sovereign power from the Medes, when Gyrus deposed Astyages.' (7.8α 1). A t Abydus, before the crossing o f the Bosporus, he again praises the undertakings o f his predecessors: ' I t was by taking risks that m y
" Persians 864 6. In the Histories (1.72) the Halys is a boundary between the Persian and the Lydian dominions, but in Isocrates {Areopagiticus 80 and Panallwiaicus 59), it is presented as a limit which has not to be transgressed by the Persian land forces. Persians 555 άβλαβης and 663, 671 άκακος, 855 άκάκας. Hdt. 7.6: έπιθυμτής, προθυμίη, προσωρέγοντο. Hdt, 7.5.3; 8.α2,β1,2; 9αΙ; 11.2,3: 7 occurrences of τιμωρός, τιμωρίη, τιμωρέειν. 79
8 0
144
SUZANNE SAÏD
ancestors brought us to where we stand today. O n l y by great risks can great results be achieved. W e are therefore acting like them . . .' (7.50.3). According to Xerxes, this nomos is sanctioned by heaven: ' I t is a god who leads us on this way (7.8a 1). This is also demonstrated by the dreams which follow and play a decisive role in the final decision (cf. Said (1981) 22-5). The god who appears diere and represents, like the god alluded to by Xerxes, the genius of the Persians, also expresses the 'inevitability' (7.17. 2: to khreon geneslhai) o f the campaign (7.17.2). As opposed to the god o f Agamemnon's dream i n Book T w o o f the Iliad—a dream w i t h which Xerxes' dream has been too quickly identified (e.g., Regenbogen (1930b) 98-9)—, he is not deceitful. I n the Iliad, the Dream was plainly lying when telling Agamemnon that the time had come to sack the city and that the Trojans were doomed (2.11-15, 28 33 = 65-70). But in the Histories the god does not say that Xerxes will be victorious, only that he is wrong to change his m i n d (7.12.2), and he warns h i m o f the consequences: 'just as i n a moment you rose to greatness and power, so in a moment you will be brought low again' (7. 14), for it is dangerous for a young king, who has just come to power, to show some weakness by changing his m i n d . I t is only Artabanus who interprets this divine impulse as a promise of disaster: 'since it is God's will and since apparently (lids eoike) heaven itself is about to send ruin upon Greece' (7.18.3) and the 'apparently' emphasizes the subjective character o f this interpretation (Kohnken (1988) 28). 1
81
It is tempting to oppose this daimon, who embodies the character of the Persians, to their moira, as it is defined in Aeschylus' Persians. I n the tragedy, the moira, assigned to the Persians from old by the gods, commanded them to fight land battles only, besieging cities and using their cavalry, thus preventing them from overstepping the boundaries between Europe and Asia and limiting their empire to Asia (Persians 94-9). O n the contrary, in the Histories, the 'god' leads the Persians to extend their empire indefinitely. The Persians' drive to ever increase their conquests goes back to Cyrus, the founder of the Persian empire. This restlessness is perceived, right at the beginning of the Histories, by the queen of Babylon and her subjects (1.185.1: auk alremizousan; 190.2: ouk atremizontd). A n d
81
As Evans (1991) 15 rightly points out, 'though Herodotus has borrowed from Homer the literary device, he has shifted the emphasis'. For the dreams, see also Ch. 5, p. 103, and Ch. 9, pp. 221-3, in this volume.
HERODOTUS A N D T R A G E D Y
145
the continuity o f Persian imperialism is brought out not only by the speeches o f Artabanus who, at the beginning o f Book Seven, compares the projected campaign against Greece with the expedition o f Darius against the Scythians (7.10a2-3, y l 2; 18.2) and other disastrous expeditions o f his predecessors, such as the campaign against the Massagetac o f Gyrus and the campaign against the Ethiopians of Cambyses (7.18.2), but also by the narrative o f Herodotus. For Cyrus never stopped enlarging his empire: after ''subduing' Croesus (1.130.3), 'enslaving' the Ionians (1.161, 169.2), 'laying waste' all the cities o f Asia M i n o r (1.177) and 'conquering' Babylon (1.201.1), 'he desired to have the Massagetae in his power' (1.201.1) and was only stopped in his conquests by death. His son and successor Cambyses was even more eager to enlarge the empire: after his campaign against Egypt, he wanted to attack the Carthaginians, the Ammonians and the long-lived Ethiopians (3.17.1), and it was only the lack of provisions and the threat o f cannibalism which put an end to this expedition. Last but not least, Darius in the Histories, far from being a wise king and the polar opposite o f his son, is similar to h i m . It would be easy to demonstrate—and it has already been done bymany scholars for the Scythian expedition —that Herodotus' narrative draws many parallels between the campaign o f Xerxes, the Scythian expedition, and the first Persian War. 02
Viewed from this angle, the campaign o f Xerxes is no longer an accident caused by the rashness o f a young king, as it was i n the Persians. It becomes the logical outcome o f the unlimited expansionism which characterized the rulers o f Asia right from the beginning. ' T h e tragedy o f Xerxes has been replaced by the tragedy of Persian imperialism, which may be read as a warning addressed by Herodotus to the contemporary representatives o f imperialism, that is the Athenians." 11 5
1
m
Evans (199!) 18 n. 34 mentions Bornitz (1968) 125-30, Wood (1972) 94-100, Hunter (1982) 206-25; Hartog (1988) 34-60. See also Said (1981) 25-7. " Fornara (1971a) 29 rightly points out that 'this theme becomes prominent and central' only in 7-9. Moles (1996) and Ch. 2 of this volume. ;l
1,1
146
SUZANNE SAÏD
Conclusion Clearly, tragedy should be numbered among the literary influences on Herodotus, I f we look for direct borrowings i n the Histories, we have to conclude, with Evans ((1991) 5), that 'it seems that Herodotus borrowed tragic elements when it suited his dramatic purposes, but they were literary devices designed to catch his audience; they d i d not inform his historical vision'. But i f we pose the question thus: Is Herodotus, like Thucydides, a 'tragic historian' (MacLeod (1983) 157)? Is there 'a tragic view o f history' (Fornara (1971a) 78) i n Herodotus? it becomes difficult to give a simple answer. I f we label as tragic a narrative which demonstrates die limitations and instability of human conditions (Stahl (1975) 1), we may say that the Histories, like Homeric epic, are a case i n point. I n the world o f Herodotus, as in the allegory o f the jars i n Book 24 o f the Iliad, there is no perfect happiness and complete self sufficiency: 'no man is able to lay his hands on everything any more than a country can produce everything it needs' (1.32.8). T h e concept o f divine jealousy, which prevents living beings from growing excessively, a concept endorsed by many Herodotean characters, is but a translation o f the same idea, into religious terms. This truth is exemplified not only by the destinies o f great kings and rulers, but also by anecdotes concerning ordinary individuals such as a certain Ameinocles: the tempest that destroyed four hundred ships i n the neighbourhood of Sepias 'made h i m a very rich man', but Herodotus adds: 'but i n other respects he proved less fortunate.For he met with a distressing disaster i n the form of the murder o f his son' (7.190). 85
A n even greater emphasis is put on the theme o f human instability i n the Histories. As Herodotus himself says i n the prologue, 'human prosperity never abides long in the same place' (1.5.4). ' This also holds good i n the case o f power: 'most of the cities which were great once are small today and those which used to be small were great i n m y own times' (1.5.4). I t is also valid for virtue. Before Plataea, the Athenians acknowledged in their speech that 'the very men who once were brave and helpful could today be cowards, and yesterday's cowards might be today's heroes' (9.27.4), a truth which 8 3
85
Hdt. 1.32.1: Solon; 3.40.2: Amasis; 7.10el, 46.4: Artabanus; 8.109.3: Themistocles. This is echoed by Solon (Hdt. 1.32.4), Croesus (1.207.2), and Artabanus (7.4). 8 6
HERODOTUS AND TRAGEDY
147
is illustrated in the Histories by the parallel transformations of Croesus, the fool who becomes wise, and Cyrus, the wise man who becomes a fool. It is precisely this pervasive instability which prevents the Herodotean world from being 'tragic', i f tragedy implies the belief i n an iron law o f history. Each fall o f a ruler is balanced by the rise o f another and all disasters have a bright side. What prevents Herodotus' Histories from being as tragic as Thucydides' History of the Peloponnes'ian war is perhaps the impartiality and the Panhellenic perspective (Fornara (1971a) 90) o f the father o f history, as opposed to the Thucydidean focus on Athens and the decline and fall o f its empire. Therefore I propose, as a paradoxical conclusion o f a paper devoted to 'Herodotus and Tragedy' that Cornford ((1907) 137-9) was right, after all, in opposing nearly a hundred years ago, an epic Herodotus to a tragic Thucydides. 87
7
Gomme (1954) 110-2 and Strasburgcr (1955) 579-80.
CHAPTER SEVEN
PHILOSOPHY, SCIENCE, POLITICS: H E R O D O T U S A N D THE I N T E L L E C T U A L TRENDS OF HIS TIME K u r t A . Raaflaub
T h e Greeks go about things i n the w r o n g way. (Mardonius, / .9(3.2)
Introduction T h e purpose o f this chapter is threefold: to survey the many ways in which Herodotus shares i n contemporary intellectual trends, that is, in ideas and theories developed by philosophers, sophists, and 'scientists' before and i n his time; to discuss his contribution to the advancement o f historical and political thought; and to explore the thesis that, despite major differences, Herodotus i n many respects is much closer to Thucydides than scholars usually allow. I thus begin, paradoxically, with Thucydides, an Athenian who spent twenty years i n exile (4.104-8; 5.26.5), presumably returned to Athens after the end o f the Peloponnesian War, and most likely died i n the m i d 3908. From the beginning o f the war he collected material for a history (1.1; 5.26) and probably composed drafts o f a narrative; large parts, however, must have been written or revised after the war. Thucydides thus traced and tried to understand one great war at 1
2
1
Translations (often with slight modifications); Waterlield (1998) for Herodotus, Strassler (1996) for Thucydides. I completed and submitted this chapter in 1999, well before the publication of Thomas (2000) which is crucial for the second section; unfortunately, at this late stage I can only acknowledge its contribution by adding references to the footnotes. I owe thanks for valuable comments to Deborah Boedeker, Carolyn Dewald, Irad Malkin, Rosaria Munson, Marek Wecovvski, and the Fellows of the Center for Hellenic Studies in 1999-2000, esp. Peter Hunt, Ted Lcndon, and John Marineola. On all this and the entire section on Thucydides. see esp. Hornblowcr (1987); (1994a) 17, 24-9; (1994b); (1996b) (with recent bibliog.); de Romilly (1963); Cawkwell (1997). Date of death: Hornblowcr (1987) 4, 151-3; see also Hunter (1977). 2
150
KURT A . RAAFLAUB
the very time when Herodotus was writing the history of another and presented some of his logoi i n 'lectures', perhaps even in Athens. Thucydides certainly knew the Histories and in his own work reacted to his most important predecessor. He shares w i t h him—long anticipated by H o m e r — a n 'overarching thematic conception, a great war', and a passion for war as the greatest challenge to human arete and most enduring source o f human glory. For my present purpose, some specific characteristics o f Thucydides' work are especially important. One is that he usually does not give us insight into the evidence or train o f thought underlying his narrative. Early on, he explains, in famous chapters (1.20 2), his methodology and then simply tells us the results o f his investigation. Second, Thucydides' writing o f history focuses almost exclusively on political events (of which warfare is a crucial part); hence it is to h i m , modern scholars conclude, that we owe 'the discovery o f political history'/ Third, his interpretation is often based on theoretical assumptions that were current i n his time, as attested by Euripides and the ' O l d Oligarch', among others, and on ideas developed by philosophers, sophists, and medical writers. ' Fourth, Thucydides offers his work as 'an everlasting possession (ktema es aid), rather than a prize composition which is heard and then forgotten' (1.22.4).' I n other words, familiarity with history is useful—presumably as a means to master future challenges. Clearly, however, history can serve this function only i f it contains a stable element i n its constant flow and infinite variety. Thucydides finds 3
4
7
1
3
In emphasizing the similarities between the two authors—an aspect still far too often ignored—I am aware of the obvious risk of making Herodotus look too much like Thucydides: this is not my intention (see below at n. 106). On Thucydides and Herodotus, see recently Stahl (1983) 219 n. 37 (end); Pelling (1991); Moles (1993) csp. 98 ff.; Scanlon (1994), and esp. Hunter (1982); Hornblower (1987) Ch. I ; (1992b); (1994a) 22 (quot), 25; (1996a) 19-38; (1996b) 1521; Rood (1999). On Herodotus and Homer, see Boedeker, this volume (Ch. 5, pp. 97-109). But see Gribble (1998) on authorial interventions in Thucydides. ' Strasburger (1954b); Momigliano (1958) 4-5 = (1966) 130-1. " Euripides: Finley (1942), (1967); de Romilly (1984). Pseudo-Xenophon: Frisch (1942) 79-87, but see de Romilly (1962). Theory: e.g., Hussey (1985); Hornblower (1987) Ch. 5; Rechenauer (1991); Price (2001) Ch. I (with bibliog.). ' Hornblower's formulation ((1991) 61). In agonisma es to parachrema akouein most scholars (e.g., Hornblower, ibid.; Fornara (1971a) 60; Gould (1989) 112) see an allusion to Herodotus' performances; cf. 1.21.1. Boedeker (1995) raises a different possibility (elegiac praise poetry on historical events, such as Simonides' elegy on Plataea: Sim. 10-8 in West (1992); see Boedeker and Sider (2001)); cf. Hornblower (1996a) 27-8, 39-40. 1
r
HERODOTUS A N D T H E I N T E L L E C T U A L TRENDS OF HIS T I M E
151
this in human nature which he considers essentially unchanging. Hence empirical data collected from history make it possible to analyse, categorize, understand, and anticipate human behaviour in comparable situations men will always act similarly—and, by extension, the course o f political developments. Thucydides' thinking here seems influenced by medical theory; his descriptions o f the plague in Athens (2.47 53) and the civil war in Corcyra (3.81-4) offer spectacular diagnoses o f socio-political illness. Logically, then, typical behaviour is attributed to communities as well: as the antithetical portrait o f Athens and Sparta illustrates (1.70-T), each has its own distinct character that prompts it to act in specific ways; yet in comparable situations they would act similarly (1.76).° Fifth, human nature is dominated by two antithetical desires for liberty and power -which determine individual and collective action; ideals or laws are unable to contain them (3.45). Hence they provide the primary categories o f historical explanation; where they fall short, individual decisions and incalculable chance (tuche) need to be taken into account. This view o f history as a constant struggle for power and domination (dunamis and arche), rooted in human nature, in which the strongest prevails without consideration for tradition, laws, or justice, originates in sophistic theories contrasting phusis and nomas, nature and human convention best known to us from Plato's Gorgias and Republic I . I t is applied most radically to historical explanation i n the Melian Dialogue (5.84-114), a set piece designed to analyse the nature o f imperialism, just as the piece on the stasis on Corcyra analyses the nature o f civil strife. I n such set pieces and i n carefully crafted speeches the historian reminds us o f his understanding o f the essential factors that drive human decisions and actions. 8
10
Sixth, Thucydides engages in a persistent effort at dcmythologizing and de-ideologizing history. Through selection, emphasis, and direct statement he reveals the truths that in everyday politics are
8
1.22.4; cf., e.g., 1.84.4; 3.82.2. See Reinhold (1985); Hornblower (1996a) 61 with bibliog. This is confirmed by Thucydides' demonstration of how Sparta too eventually turns from liberator to oppressor of the Greeks (Raallaub (1985) 248-57), an idea developed fully in Xenophon's Helknica: Tuplin (1993); Dillcry (1995); Sterling (1998). Stasis in Thucydides: Price (2001). '" Bibliog. on power and imperialism in Thucvdides is immense; it is cited in Raaflaub (1994) 105 n. 6; see also Ober (2001). Freedom: e.g., Oilier (1962). Phusis and nornos: Heinimann (1945); Guthrie (1962-9) 3, Ch. 4. Melian Dialogue: Andrewes in Gomme et al. (1970) esp. 182-8; Crane (1998) esp. Ch. 9 (links with Herodotus). !1
152
KURT A, RAAFLAUB
camouflaged by propaganda. For instance, i n the Melian Dialogue the Athenians declare that they will not use 'beautiful phrases saying, for example, that we have a right to our empire because we defeated the Persians . . ., a great mass o f words that nobody would believe' (5.89). I n reality, o f course, the Athenians d i d use such onomata kala, but the historian's intent is to show that, whatever they say, the true motives o f individuals and states are hunger for power and self-interest. Overall, then, the historian extricates from the mass o f historical data the basic forms o f political motives, actions and relations, within and between communities, that underlie all historical events and processes and that help us to cut through appearances and reach a deeper understanding. '" Keeping all this i n m i n d , we now turn to Herodotus. He was no Athenian, although he spent time i n Athens and was passionately concerned w i t h and about this city. He came from Halicarnassus, a Dorian polls w i t h strong Carian elements i n an area that was d o m inated by Ionian politics and thinking and had long served as a bridge between east and west, and he spent most o f his life away from home as an exile, traveller, and colonist. His specific background and experiences are often considered important in explaining his openness, unbiased and balanced outlook, and interest i n other cultures and in history. He is usually thought to have died around the m i d - to late-420s, a quarter-century before Thucydides, presumably shortly after his work was published. Because o f the likelihood o f extensive 'pre-publication' o f parts through recitation and other means, the concept o f 'publication' in this case now appears much more complicated and may no longer be useful as a dating device. Moreover, Charles Fornara and others have offered compelling arguments for the possibility that he was alive and still working on his Histories a few years later. However that may be, Herodotus 11
1
15
14
13
" Cf., e.g., 1.73.2, 75.3, 76.2; 6.83.2; Strasburger (1958); Raaflaub (1985) Ch. 5. Sec Hunter (1982) for Thucydides* (and Herodotus') focus on processes, especially the rise and fall of empires (arche). Strasburger (1955) (with Harvey (1966)); Ostwald (1991); Moles (1996) and this volume (Ch. 2). See also Rosier (Ch. 4). E.g., Gould (1989) 7-8; Thomas (2000) Ch. 1. See also Boedeker (1998) (on the status as critical outsider Herodotus shares with Thucydides); Symc (1962) 40 ('exile may be the making of an historian'); Hornblowcr (1987) 27-8. * Fornara (1971b), (1981); Sansone (1985). Traditional date: Jacobv (1913) 229 32: Cobet (1977); Evans (1979a); (1991) 89-90. Prepublication: below at n. 46. O n these issues, see also Moles, this volume (Ch. 2) and Rosier (Ch. 4). 12
13
14
1:
HERODOTUS A N D T H E I N T E L L E C T U A L TRENDS OF HIS T I M E
153
certainly experienced the early years o f the Peloponnesian W a r and much o f the intellectual ferment o f the Periclean and immediate post-Periclean years. We should expect these experiences to have left a mark i n his work. T h e common view holds, however, that Herodotus really belonged to an earlier generation, that he remained rooted, despite some overlaps w i t h ideas o f sophists and medical writers, i n traditional beliefs, and that he d i d not work with theoretical assumptions. ' Accordingly, until recently his relations to current intellectual trends were investigated much less thoroughly and w i t h less sophistication than is the case w i t h Thucydides. Titles one can cite i n this context are still relatively few. I t is perhaps symptomatic too that i n speaking o f 'Herodotus and his contemporaries', Robert Fowler thinks only o f historians and ethnographers; would he do the same when discussing Thucydides? ' Such assessment has, o f course, been facilitated by Herodotus' specific ways o f organizing and presenting his material, arguing his case and narrating his story. I n all these respects he is different from Thucydides, and 'different' has all too often been taken to mean not only 'earlier' but also 'more primitive'. [(
1
I n deliberate contrast to such views I propose here that Herodotus' interpretation o f history is no less influenced by theories and overarching concepts o f historical causation and dynamics than Thucyd i d e s ' - e v e n i f he does not overtly argue w i t h theory; that he is no less eager to work out the main forces that drive history and to debunk propaganda and ideologies—even i f he does this indirectly rather than directly; that he is no less concerned with political hist o r y e v e n i f he does not focus narrowly on politics; and that he offers us no less insight into his main concerns and principles—even
See the summary of this view in Thomas (2000) 6-8. Fowler (1996); by contrast, Hornblower (1987) .16 thinks, when mentioning Thucydides' contemporaries, first of 'the "pre-Socratic" thinkers... in the broadest sense (i.e., doctors and orators as well as philosophers)'. See also Hunter (1982) 274, and the di Here nee in the 'Wege der Forschung' volumes dedicated to Herodotus (Marg (1965)) and Thucydides (Heiter (1968)): theory figures prominently in the latter, not at all in the former. Recent changes: e.g., Müller (1981); Lateiner (1986), (1989); Hornblower (1987) Ch. 1 (esp. 16, referring to a statement by My res (1953) 43: 'In the collection of (acts about Man, and in the interpretation of them, Herodotus is the only "Pre-soeratic" writer who is preserved in full.'); Thomas (1993), (1997) (see 131 ~2 for the sharp contrast between Herodotus and Thucydides traditionally emphasized in scholarship), and esp. (2000). For the persistence of" traditional beliefs and explanations in Herodotus, see, e.g., Lloyd (1979) 29-32; Meier (1987) 47, 52. 17
154
KURT A. RAAFLAUB
18
i f he does not formulate them abstractly. I n this chapter, I shall discuss first correspondences between Herodotus and his intellectual predecessors and contemporaries among philosophers and scientists, then look more closely at the role o f historical and political thought i n his work, and at the end return to the question of similarities w i t h Thucyelides. I n principle, I suggest, we should think of Herodotus as interacting with rather than simply depending on contemporary intellectual trends or ideas found i n other works. T h e author o f the medical treatise on Airs, Waters, Places, preserved i n the Hippocratic corpus, probably d i d not invent the theories o f the influence of climate and environment on national character that both he and Herodotus, perhaps around the same time, applied i n characteristically different ways to their very different subjects. Just as analogies between Thucydides and Euripides, among others, indicate not that one depended on the other but that both drew on ideas and modes o f thinking that were current in their time, so too, I think, Herodotus, sophists, and medical writers, among others (including Thucydides), all drew on a large and vibrant pool o f ideas and methods that, although probably each originating w i t h one author and at one specific time, interacted w i t h one another, were advanced further by such interaction, and became part o f an intellectual koine in late fifthcentury Hellas. Such interaction probably was especially intense and productive i n Athens but certainly not limited to it. Moreover, for a Greek 'intellectual', whether thinker, writer, or artist, whether historically interested or not, Athenian or not, the domestic and imperial policies, the past and present role of Athens offered extraordinary opportunities and a special challenge which could not but deeply affect his outlook and thinking.19
0
18
I find support for these suggestions especially in the works of Hunter, Hornblower, and Thomas, cited earlier. Similarly Fowler (1996) 69. See Hunter (1982) 282-4 for the need to establish the intellectual and theoretical context in which Herodotus and Thucydides developed their interpretation and methodology of history—a need now largely met for Herodotus by Thomas (2000). Thucydides and Euripides: n. 6. Airs, Waters, Places: below n. 41. On the development of genres: Depew and Obbink (2000). Ostwald (1992); Sakellariou (1996); Boedeker and Raaflaub (1998). This is true even i f one tries to avoid Athenocentrism (see Thomas (2000) 9-16). 19
2ii
HERODOTUS A N D T H E I N T E L L E C T U A L TRENDS OF HIS T I M E
155
Philosophical and Scientific Thought I begin by mentioning some patterns o f thought or 'habits o f m i n d ' that Herodotus shares w i t h many authors. These include, most basically, an immense interest i n what is wondrous and astonishing (thômaston); such curiosity, although already visible in Homer's epics, was greatly enhanced by the expansion o f the Greek horizon especially i n the sixth and early fifth centuries. Another pattern might be labelled 'the post hoc ergo propter hoc fallacy', which dictates that what is older must be the cause or origin o f what is younger; it underlies much o f the popular belief that the Greeks imported many o f their gods, customs, and laws from Egypt. For example, 'the Egyptians were the first people i n the world to hold general festive assemblies, and religious processions and parades, and the Greeks learnt from the Egyptians. M y evidence for this suggestion is that these activities have obviously been going on i n Egypt for a very long time, whereas they have only recently started i n Greece' (2.58, cf. 104). Related w i t h this pattern is the Greek obsession w i t h the prôlos heuretes and the conviction that a specific thing or custom can have originated only in one place and at one t i m e . 21
22
23
Furthermore, Greek thought tends toward schematization: it emphasizes polarity between opposed things, antithetical patterns, symmetry and linear as well as cyclical developments. Hence, for example, the importance o f genealogies i n history as well as cosmogonie and théogonie speculation, or the symmetry in early world maps—a fallacy Herodotus fights (4.36) but succumbs to i n turn when discussing the course o f the Nile and its relation to the Danube (2.33-4), just as he over-schematizes the difference between Egyptian and foreign customs: 'almost all Egyptian customs and practices are the opposite o f those o f everywhere else' (2.35-6). Closely related is the custom o f 24
Lloyd (1975) 1.141-55; cf. 156 (quot). See below at n. 37. Barth (1968): Lloyd (1975) 1.141-7, 153-4; Bloomer (1993) (emphasizing 'Herodotus' peculiar vision . . . that sees not the average or the typical but the extreme as definitive and worthy of record' (33)). Other examples include 1.171 (Carta); 2.4, 43, 49-50, 177; 4.180 (Egypt); 4.189 (Libya): bv contrast, the Scythians do not import customs from elsewhere: 4.76-80. See Froidefond (1971); Hunter (1982) Ch. 2 and 102, 272 (Herodotus as a 'difiusionist'). Lloyd (1975) 1.49-60, 147-9 and in this volume (Ch. 18); Zhmud (1997) 57-60 discuss this fallacy and reject the historicity of many of these borrowing's and of the connected travels of famous personalities to Egypt. Prôtos fwuretês; Kleingunther (1933). Cf. 3.106-16; 4.5; 4.82 with 2.35. See generally G. Lloyd (1966); A. Lloyd n
156
KÜRT A . RAAFLAUR
thinking through comparison and analogy: they provide the means to explain and reconstruct, to progress from the known to the less known and draw inferences even on the unknown. -' Again related are two widely popular types o f argument: that from past experience (Xerxes' uncle, Artabanus, uses Darius' failure against the Scythians and the near-destruction o f the bridge over the Danube to advise against a campaign to conquer Greece (7.10)), and the argument from probability (Helen could not possibly have been in T r o y during the war because any sane ruler would have returned her to the Greeks immediately or at least after the Trojans incurred the first heavy losses (2.120.1-3))/-* A l l these patterns of thought were greatly advanced and enhanced by intellectual developments connected first with the emergence o f Ionian philosophy from the mid-sixth centuiy, then w i t h the emergence o f sophistic and scientific thinking from the mid-fifth centuiy. Although Herodotus rarely mentions them by name, it is abundantly clear that he was thoroughly familiar w i t h the ideas, theories, and modes o f thought and discourse o f the leading intellectuals, from Thales and Anaximander to his own contemporaries and that he not only applied such ideas and theories frequently, though selectively, i n his narrative and interpretation but also attempted i n various ways to participate in current debates among intellectuals or to correct and influence popular views. ' M u c h less clear, however, is whether he was inspired directly by their works or indirectly by a pool o f knowledge that had become generally available to the Greek intellectuals o f his generation. 2
2
From among many examples, I mention only a few, not least to illustrate the wide range o f issues involved. Anaximander's map o f 28
(1975) 1.149-53; Gould (1989) Ch. 5; Hartog (1988); Thomas (2000) Ch. 3. Genealogy: Fomara (1983) 4 1 2 ; théogonie poetry: West (1966) 1-16, esp. 12 ff; maps: Dilke (1985) Ch. 2. See also Greenwood and Cartledge, this volume (Ch. 15, p. 365). Analogy: explicitly stated in 2.33 ('since we may draw on the familiar to understand the unknown'); see Lloyd (1966); Hunter (1982) index s.v.; Corcella (1984). Comparison: examples abound; e.g. 2.103 5 on the Egyptian origin of the Colchians. * See Müller (1981) 307-11. ' ' For example, Herodotus is interested in some of the social, political, religious, and scientific ideas of the early philosophers but clearly not in their metaphysical speculations: Nestle (1908) 6-12; (1942) 505 8. On Herodotus' participation in current debates, see Thomas (2000) Ch. 2 and passim. For a detailed survey with full documentation, see Nestle (1908), summarized in id. 1942 503 14; see also Lloyd (1975) 141-70; Thomas (2000) (on natural philosophy, esp. Ch. 5). 2 5
2
2 8
HERODOTUS A N D THE I N T E L L E C T U A L TRENDS OF HIS T I M E
157
the earth, revised by Hecataeus, is used by Aristagoras o f Miletus in his quest to attract Spartan support for the Ionian revolt (5.49; cf. 4.36). Pythagoras' doctrine o f the transmigration o f souls is considered plagiarized from Egypt (2.123; cf. 4.95). Xenophanes' critique o f Homer's and Hesiod's stories about all too human gods and of the concept of anthropomorphic deities ( D - K 21 B l 1-16) is incorporated into the description o f Persian customs (1.131, cf. 2.53). T h e observation that much o f Egypt, now silted up, was once flooded by the sea (2.11-12) perhaps draws on Xenophancs' explanation o f fossils ( D - K 21 A33.5). Empedocles' natural explanation of dreams ( D K 31 B108) is employed in vain by Artabanus to dispell Xerxes' fear of nightly visions (7.16(3). More generally, Ionian philosophical thinking is characterized by rationalization or rationality. I t suffices to refer to Xenophanes or to the sentence with which Hecataeus opens his Genealogies: 'Thus proclaims Hecataeus o f Miletus: I write what I believe to be the truth; for many and ridiculous, so they seem to me, are the stories of the Greeks.' Rational explanation or interpretation o f myths, stories, or phenomena is prevalent in Herodotus, usually bolstered by empirical arguments. He has heard a report that the tyrant Polycrates was overthrown by a band o f Samian exiles. ' I do not think this can be r i g h t , since they w o u l d not have had to send for the Lacedaemonians, i f they were, capable of bringing Polycrates down on their own. Besides, it also does not make sense to think that someone w i t h vast numbers o f mercenaries and native archers at his disposal would have been beaten by the few returning Samians' (3.45). O r , to continue a previous example, he reasons that the Trojans would have returned Helen to the Greeks, Paris' resistance notwithstanding, not only to save their city, but also because Hector, older and more o f a man than Paris, was first in charge after Priam: 'It was Hector who would inherit the kingdom on Priam's death, and he was not the kind o f man to let his brother get away with wrongdoing. . . No, the fact is that they d i d not have Helen to give back' (2.120.4-5). This i n turn, Herodotus thinks, like so much else 20
30
51
-" Dilke (1985) 23-5. For these terms, see Hunter (1982) 107 15. On Ionian philosophy: Guthrie (1962-9) volume 1; Barnes (1979); KRS. and, for a brief survey, Hussey (1972). FCrll 1 F l (tr. Stambler (1982) 215); Fornara (1983) 5-6, however, warns against considering rationalization Hecataeus primary concern. Xenophanes: D - K 21 B l l 16, with the bibliog. cited in the previous note. 3 0
31
1
158
K U R T A . RAAFLAUB
is due to the divine (to daimonion), 'so that in their annihilation the Trojans might make it completely clear to others that the severity of a crime is matched by the severity o f the ensuing punishment at the god's hand. T h a t is m y view, at any rate' (ibid. 5 ) . T h e historian thus attributes reasonable and rational motives to divine will and human actors (both individuals and collectivities), based on arguments from experience and probability. I t is typical of such rationalization that the distant past (or different peoples) are judged from the perspective o f the here and now. As Hunter puts it, 'analogy like probability is based o n the perception o f similarities, the belief that individuals acted i n the past, or will act i n the future, much as they do i n the present, and so that behaviour i n the past can be reconstructed by using the analogy o f the present'. Hence the theory underlying Herodotus' argument, although never formulated as a principle or abstracdy by this historian, is the same as i n Thucydides: 'human nature being what i t is . . . Furthermore, Ionian philosophy is greatly concerned w i t h epistemology: the problem o f what we can know and how we can knowit. T h e extreme focus o f such concern, again, are the gods, as is attested by a wide range o f discussions and speculative theories from Xenophanes to Anaxagoras. Heraclitus, although postulating a duality o f appearance and reality, also emphasizes the importance o f empiricism, preferring things o f which opsis, akoe, mathesis are possible. Herodotus does not doubt but largely refuses to investigate the metaphysical w o r l d because i t is inaccessible to opsis, histoiie, and reason. As he explains, he does not intend to pursue ta theia, issues that 'belong to the trans-physical order o f things', because he believes 'that everyone is equal i n terms o f knowledge about divine matters', that is, no person knows or can know more about them than any other. But the anthropeia pregmata, 'all that belongs to the human sphere o f activity', are part o f the physical w o r l d and thus can be 32
33
m
32
Other examples include 1.75; 2.45, 54-7, 131, 135; 4.31, See also Fehling (1989) esp. 96-104, 109-12. On the role of the daimonion and Iheoi envisaged here, see Immerwahr (1966) 308-11; Hunter (1982) 207-9; Stambier (1982) 217-25; Lateiner (1989) 196-205. On religion in Herodotus: Huber (1965a); Gould (1994); Bichler and Rollinger (2000) 54-9, and Mikalson, this volume (Ch. 8). " See Müller (1981) 308; Hunter (1982) 111-3, on the difference between Ionian pure and Herodotus' empirical rationalism. • Thuc. 1.22.4. Hunter (1982) 112, referring tojacoby (1949) 133; cf., e.g., 3.72 which is based on a consistent and universal type of human nature. w
HERODOTUS AND T H E I N T E L L E C T U A L TRENDS OF HIS T I M E
159
?;
the objects o f rational inquiry (2.3 4). ' Similarly, at the very begin ning o f his work, Herodotus distinguishes sharply between the sphere o f what we would call myth—unverifiable contradictory accounts about a distant past—and the sphere (which we call historical) that is accessible to precise investigation and thus to knowledge (1.5). This distinction, Felix Jacoby observed, "marks the creation o f a histori cal work i n our sense, in that it limits the historical narrative to his torical time'. I n the human sphere o f activity and in historical time, where things can be known, the methods o f how to acquire and ver ify such knowledge are crucial: Herodotus' careful establishment o f a 'hierarchy o f epistemological factors', ranking autopsy (opsu) above oral reports (preferably o f eyewitnesses) and rational argument based on empirical knowledge and probability, and his constant applica tion o f source criticism need to be seen i n the tradition o f Ionian theories o f knowledge?" Another side o f the great intellectual movement o f sixth and early fifth-century Ionia is represented by geographical and ethnographic exploration, and here Herodotus' dependence on and critical inter action with his predecessors, Hecataeus foremost among them, and his contemporaries is well k n o w n . I n this sphere he often applies scientific methods and theories and displays an impressive combina tion o f observation and analytical reasoning. I mention only his acute remarks on the physical geography o f lower Egypt, 'a gift from the river' (2.5, 10 12), his involvement in the controversy about the 37
3 5
Barth (1964); Lloyd (1975) 1.157 70 and, on 2 . 3 4 , Lloyd's comm. ad toe. (quot.). Herat! D - K 22 B55; KRS 188 n. 2: 'The things of which there is seeing and hearing and perception, these do I prefer'; but such perceptions need to be checked by understanding (nous, phronesis: Β107 with the comments by KRS. ibid.). " O n mythical time vs. historical time, see also 3.122 (but see 1.171 and Thuc. 1.4); Lateiner (1989; 63-7, and generally von Leyden (1949-50); Hunter (1982) Chs. 2-3; Calame (1996); Marincola (1997a) 117-27; Romm (1998) 1-6; contra: Nickau (1990). Jacoby (1913) 335, as quoted by Hornblower (1987) 18. See also Boedeker, this volume (Ch. 5, note 43) as well as Cobel (Ch. 17, note 55) and Osborne (Ch. 22). O n 'hierarchy of epistemology': Mailer (1981); Lateiner (1986), (1989) passing Hornblower (1987) 20 1; Hartog (1988) Ch. 7; Marincola (1997a) 67 (quot), 96; see also Cartledge and Greenwood (Ch. 15) as well as Hornblower (Ch. 16). this volume. " Trudinger (1918); on Hecataeus: Jacoby (1912); von Fritz (1967) 48 76; Fornara (1983) 12-6; sec also West (1991), this volume (Ch. 19) and Karttunen, this vol ume (Ch. 20). Contemporaries: Thomas (2000) 42-74, arguing against overesti mating Hecataeus' influence and for a wide range of information available to both Herodotus and the medical writers. On Herodotus' 'anthropology': Redfield (1985); Bichler (2000): Munson (2001), and see below at n. 101 ff. J
160
KURT A . RAAFLAUB
boundary between Africa and Asia (2.15-17), and his headstrong discussion o f the causes o f the Nile's flooding (2.19-25). T h e sophists were a diverse group o f thinkers and teachers; hence generalizations tend to be misleading.' Most o f them taught rhetorical skills and explored functions and theories o f language and communication. They greatly refined the use o f various types o f arguments from probability and honed the skills o f formulating generally accepted ideas or concepts precisely and i n artful gnomai. T h e influence o f these types o f thought and expression are palpable on almost every page in Herodotus. H e shows a marked interest i n antilogy, i n eristic speeches and debates which bristle w i t h concise gnomai and general truths, and i n the meaning o f names and other linguistic phenomena. Echoes o f specific problems known to have been discussed by individual thinkers are frequent as well: thus the belief i n a divinely ordained and maintained balance in nature is demonstrated here, as i n Protagoras' myth (Plato, Prot. 321b), by the distribution o f qualities i n the animal w o r l d (3.108); the problem o f involuntary murder, discussed by Protagoras (Plut. Per. 36) and Antiphon (Tetr. 2), is explored i n the Adrastus story (1.35-45) far beyond the rational and legal aspects important to the sophist and rhetorician; Gorgias' discussion o f justified deception (e.g., Hel. 10 — I I ) reflects ethical relativism and the importance attributed to the sumpheron (advantage, interest) and is perhaps echoed i n a speech given to Darius (3.72; cf. 1.138), while Hippias' condemnation o f slander ( D - K 86 B17) perhaps underlies Artabanus' words i n 7.10c, :i!!
m
T h e sophists, much more than the Ionian philosophers, focussed their attention on human society and interaction: they analysed and conceptualized various types o f human behaviour and studied humans not as individuals and a species but as social and political beings (z&ia koinonika or politika). They were interested i n political problems stich as the nature and organization o f power, constitutional theory, the contrast between nomas (convention, law) and phusis (nature), the
;iS
On Herodotus' physical and cultural geography, see Gould (1989), Gh. 5, balancing to some extent Hartog (1988); on the division of continents, Thomas (2000) 90-6. Guthrie (1962-69) 3: pt. 1; Kerfercl (1981a), (1981b); de Romilly (1992); Wallace (1998). O n the issues raised in this and the following paragraph, see Nestle (1908) 14-34; (1942) 509-13; Dihle (1962b); Thomas (2000) Chs; 6-8.'The judgment of Eduard Meyer (1892) 202 who denied any influence of the sophists and their rhetorical teachings remains astonishing. 3 9
HERODOTUS A N D T H E I N T E L L E C T U A L TRENDS OF HIS T I M E
161
mechanisms unleashed by pleonexia (greed, desire for more) or Ophelia (self-interest, advantage), and various aspects o f 'right based on might'. Echoes i n Herodotus abound; we might think o f the speeches i n Xerxes' crown council before the Greek expedition (including, e.g., a comment on euboulia (good counsel, 7.108.2)), o f a brief digression, i n a particularly dramatic episode, on speaking the truth or lying according to what is more profitable (kerdos, 3.72), or o f Demaratus' explanation to Xerxes o f why the Greeks, especially the Spartans, will light even against vastly superior numbers: Xerxes sees them as individuals and counts numbers, thinking i n terms o f phusis, while Demaratus sees them as members o f a community, held together, transformed and enhanced by nomos (7.102-4; cf. 5.78 on the Athenians after the fall o f tyranny). The most often cited case o f sophistic influence is the 'Constitutional Debate' i n 3.80 2, which some scholars think Herodotus lifted wholesale out o f a sophistic treatise, perhaps o f Protagoras. This is quite unlikely; rather, analogies i n the works o f several o f Herodotus' contemporaries (most conspicuously i n Euripides' Suppliants) suggest that discussions o f the advantages and disadvantages o f democracy, on a more or less theoretical level, were 'a hot topic' at the time. Although Herodotus' debate is the most complex to survive, the author's own comments (3.80; 6.43) place the emphasis on democracy as well; i n addition, it serves as one o f several 'set pieces' o n the nature o f autocracy. " 4
T u r n i n g to the medical writers, several early treatises i n the Hippocratic corpus are dated roughly to the last third o f the fifth century and thus to a time near the publication date traditionally assumed for Herodotus' work. As i n the case o f the sophists, i n some instances Herodotus' familiarity w i t h their ideas seems palpable. A m o n g other examples attesting to his interest i n exceptional anatomical and physiological phenomena (1.68; 9.83), I. single out the discussion (3.12) o f the markedly different bone thickness o f the Persian and Egyptian skulls still visible on an old battle site. Herodotus concludes that the Egyptians had their heads shorn, while the Persians habitually wore felt hats. This argument, related to others that explain the human constitution and character w i t h climatic factors or social customs is close to statements typically found i n the 'Hippocratic'
,,u
Stroheker (1953/54); Gschnitzcr (1977); Bleickcn (1979); Raaliaub (1989) esp. 41-6; Lateiner (1989) Ch. 8. 'Set piece': below at n. 81,
162
K U R T A . RAAFLAUB
1
treatise, Airs, Waters, Places.* Although with specific and clearly intentional differences, Herodotus frequently applies theories, known from this essay (esp. 12, 16, 24), that a balanced mixture of seasons or a stable climate are best for human health and success, while, conversely, radical changes in climate, temperatures or humidity are detrimental to human well-being (e.g., 2.77; cf. 2.35; 3.106; 1.142), or that the richness or poverty o f a country is directly connected with the softness or toughness of the people living on and from i t . Stich theories probably originated in ethnographic thought and i n what we would call 'anthropological or comparative psychology'; the overlap between ethnographic, sophistic, and medical theories is especially noticeable here. Knowledge of such theories can be used to manipulate people: when the Lydians, 'the most courageous and warlike race in Asia' (1.79), revolt against the Persians soon after their subjection, Croesus tries to save them from extinction by suggesting to Cyrus a method of treatment that will keep them from revolting again: 'Send a message that they are forbidden to own weapons o f war, that they are to wear tunics under their coats and slippers on their feet, that they are to take up the cithara and the harp, and that they are to raise their sons to be retailers. Before long, m y lord, you will see them become women instead o f men' (1.155). Cyrus follows this adviceand the Lydians j o i n the long list of Persian subjects preferring wealth in slavery over freedom in poverty. One exception are the Persians themselves who, upon Cyrus' warning, 'chose to live in a harsh land and rule rather than to cultivate fertile plains and be others' slaves' (9.122). * The other exception are the mainland Greeks, in particular the Spartans, who resist Persian aggression because—and here Herodotus' ethical perspective transcends sober scientific theory— 42
4
'" For a modern explanation of die skulls' difference: Aldiofï (1993) 1 10, and see Kchling (1989) 28-30; Pritchett (1993) 29-32: Thomas (2000) 31-2. Airs, date: e.g., Dillcr (1934) 114 (c. 400): Pohlenz (1938) 45 (430-415); Heinimann (1945) 209 (shortly before 430); Jouanna (1999) 375 (2nd half fifth cent.); interpretation: e.g., Diller (1934); Backhaus (1976); Thomas (2000) 86-98; relation to Herodotus: Heinimann (1945) 172-80; Jouanna (1981) 11-15. Generally on Herodotus' relations to the medical writers, see Thomas (2000) Ch. 2. For a good example of'applied psychology', see 1.173. Herodotean differences: Munson (2001). For detailed discussion, see Thomas (2000) 103-14 and, on science and natural philosophy. Ch. 5. On the problem of how this passage is compatible with 1.125-6 and Herodotus' overall schema of a stark contrast between poor but tough Greeks and luxurious and soft Persians (below at n. 77), see recently Moles (1996) 274-5. 42
48
HERODOTUS AND T H E I N T E L L E C T U A L TRENDS OF HIS T I M E
163
tied into a close-knit community by a superior nomos, they overcome the restraints of poverty and the temptations o f individualism and rise to achieve indomitable arete which makes it impossible for them to accept autocracy and slavery (7.102, cf. 104). As suggested above, some scholars see such correspondences less as proof o f Herodotus' dependence on medical writers than as indication o f a 'a shared epistemological response' or o f profound familiarity w i t h ideas and theories that developed i n an atmosphere o f intense exchange and debate. Donald Lateiner, especially, argues that the comparison between the two writers can show 'that Herodotus and the medical writers shared certain ideas about methodology, what can be known, how it can be known, and the limits o f useful knowledge. They are fellows in the older, less specialized sense o f science: knowledge gained through experience. They share an attitude more than a specific subject, an ideal o f analysis rather than a specific method. They seek reliable conclusions from the available data, and from specific events (an epidemic or a war) try to discover more general patterns o f human behavior and experience'. ' 44
4
It is thus undeniable that Herodotus shares w i t h contemporary thinkers a wide range o f ideas, assumptions, and methods. Moreover, Rosalind Thomas demonstrates that he also shares with them the ways o f presenting such ideas in public: through performance and oral disputation rather than through writing. J . A . S. Evans concludes that the concept o f 'publication' in one single moment therefore seems anachronistic—although perhaps, since the work was undoubtedly published at some moment in the form in which we have it, and presumably revised or even rewritten for this purpose, one might rather say the concept seems insufficient to describe a more complex process of 'publication in stages', including readings or performances o f 'work in progress': sections, snippets, even parts that might eventually be left out. As Thomas sees it, these oral 46
M
See Dihle (1981) 59-63; Lateiner (1989) 160-1, and cf. Konstan (1987); specifically on nomos: Humphreys (1987). Sec also van Wees, this volume (Ch. 14). * Lateiner (1986); Althoff (1993); see also Rechenauer (1991); Thomas (2000). On the relation between Herodotus and the medical writers, as regards the concepts oï Historié and aide, see also Bakker, this volume (Ch. 1, p. 13). '"' Thuc. 1.21.1, 22.4 presupposes oral performances, not least by logograp/ioi; see above n. 7. See Momigliano (1978) 61-6; Hunter (1982) 294-5 ('it is an oral work committed to writing'); Lateiner (1989) 234 n. 15: Evans (1991) 89-90 and Ch. 3: Thomas (1992) 125-6, elaborated in id. (1993) esp. 228-30; (2000) 20 and Ch. 8; Hornblower (1996a) 26, while Flory (1980), Wecowski (2000) final chapter, argue 3
164
K U R T A . RAAFLAUB
performances were more stimulating, even antagonistic, than is generally envisaged. Here too, she finds many close similarities in style and mode of argument with the earliest essays o f the Hippocratic corpus; what they especially have in common 'is a mode of presentation and performance that belongs to the oral displays or contests of the early sophistic generation'. She considers such competitive oral displays an important means of intellectual inquiry and the transmission of knowledge. ' A l l this, however relevant in and by itself, is only the foundation for the next and more important task which is too large and complex to be tackled here: to determine how exactly Herodotus uses the ideas, arguments, debating techniques, rhetorical devices, and fact-finding methodologies which he shares w i t h his contemporaries, to what extent and w h y his uses differ from theirs, and what purpose they serve in each individual context and in the overall intention of his work. Great progress toward this goal has been achieved recently in Rosalind Thomas' important book (2000) which places Herodotus firmly in the context sketched here, of ethnography, science, philosophy, and rhetoric. 4
18
Historical and Political Thought Historical and political thought expresses itself in the selection of and emphasis placed upon specific historical data, their arrangement into a historical narrative, and their interpretation. I t also concerns the purpose o f writing history and the meaning the historian finds - a n d wants his audience to f i n d — i n history. Here Herodotus appears highly original, a real path breaker—none o f his predecessors' works seem to have come close i n scope, complexity, and depth of thoughtalthough he certainly did not develop his innovative view and use o f history in isolation; rather, I assume, these resulted from his close interaction with the ideas and concerns of other leading thinkers of his time.. 49
against seeing the Histories primarily as a work of oral performance. See also Bakker, this volume (Ch. 1, pp. 8-12). Thomas (1993), (1997), (2000) Ch. 8; cf. Hornblower (1987) 16, 20 1. Much should also be expected from Munson (2001) see id. (1991). Especially perhaps the Athenian tragedians (see Said this volume, Ch. 6) but the pool of 'intellectuals' was much larger and more diverse than the preserved !7
,i! i;i
HERODOTUS A N D T H E I N T E L L E C T U A L TRENDS OF HIS T I M E
165
Extreme views like that o f Ulrich von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, that Herodotus had neither political understanding nor historical sense, have long been abandoned.' Still, few have recognized fully that the storyteller in fact has an acute sense for political issues and that his understanding o f history is informed by his political insight. I n an earlier publication, I argued that Herodotus' political thinking is closely comparable to that visible in Homeric epic and fifthcentury tragedy. Like these poetic works, Herodotus' Histories is complex, dealing with many issues and serving several purposes/' One component—in my view an especially important one—is political; it addresses immediately the author's contemporaries and indirectly, I believe, all future generations. T h r o u g h occasional explicit comments but mostly through dramatic narrative, discourse between actors, and by implication and association, 'the historian o f the past frequently interacts with the present and encourages his audience to do the same . . . [He] uses the history o f the past to shed light on contemporary political issues'. Hence the Histories aims at increasing the political awareness o f the audience, to educate them, to prepare them for the great challenges o f present and future. This, I suggest, is not greatly different from Thucydides' purpose in writing history.'" 0
1
T w o examples will illustrate how implied contemporary meaning can be read i n individual stories. T h e Corinthians' opposition to Sparta's plan to reinstate Hippias as tyrant o f Athens, and Hippias' warning that the Corinthians would regret this 'when the time came, as it surely would, for them to suffer at Athenian hands', recall the Corinthians' role in 432 in urging Sparta to take up the fight against Athens, now the tyrant city oppressing the Greeks. T h e unsuccessful attempt o f the Samian Maeandrius to become the most just o f men by stepping clown from tyranny (3.142) reminds us o f debates i n ,;i
works seem to suggest; see above at n. 19. Originality: e.g., Fornara (1971a): 25 6; Hunter (1982); Fowler (1996). See further esp. Meier {1978), (1980), (1986), (1987). "'" Waters (1972) 138, referring to Wilamowitz (1905) 56. Emphasized rightly bv Roinm (1998) 8. ~ Raaflaub (1987) quot.' 231; cf. esp. Strasburger (1955); Fornara (1971a) Ch. -1. See also Waters (1972); Stahl (1983) 218; Pelting (1991) 121; Stacker (1992) 782, 784, the bibliog. cited in n. 56 and, more generally, Stahl (1987) 19 42. For possible objections to this view, see below at n. 93 ff. Hdt. 5.93, cf. explicit references also in 90-1; Time 1.67-71, 118-24. Reference to an earlier time is unlikely: Thucydides confirms that by 440 the relations between Athens and Corinth were not yet permanently soured (1.40.5, 41.2; perhaps mentioned also in the opening lines of M L 56); see Hornblower (1991) 83. 51
3 8
166
KURT A . RAAFLAUB
Athens i n 429, immortalized i n Pericles' last speech in Thucydidcs (2.63), about the dangers involved in letting go o f tyranny. Other scholars have carried this type o f study further and shown that many more stories can be read i n this way and that Herodotus' overall concern aims beyond the particular at the general and topical. I n fact, the historian seems to have structured his work consciously so as to keep his audience constantly aware o f their present, troubled as it was by disunity and constant warfare among Hellenes, imperialism, tyrannical oppression, and enslavement o f cities. As seems natural for a contemporary o f the Athenian empire and the Peloponnesian War, such topicality focuses heavily, though far from exclusively, on the political and historical role o f Athens." Skillful foreshadowing on a large and small scale, the frequent repetition o f a set o f specific motifs, and the use o f highly charged terms or arguments familiar to Herodotus' contemporaries draw attention to themes the historian considers crucial and elicit associations with the continuing importance o f these same themes far beyond the chronological limits o f the Histories. Allusions to events o f the Pentecontaetia and the early phases o f the Peloponnesian W a r as well as explicit authorial comments confirm that Herodotus was thinking along these lines and that we are permitted to do so too. One famous example, made even more poignant because Thucydides contradicts it, is the reference to an earthquake on Delos in 490, while the Persians were crossing the Aegean, a unique event 'up to my day'. 'This was an omen sent by the god, surely, to warn people o f the trouble that was to come. After all, for three successive generations . . . Greece suffered more than it had for twenty generations before Darius, partly as a result o f Persian action there, but partly because o f power struggles between the leading Greek states' (6.98). ' 31
M
: 7
Other comments or speeches are formulated or stories told in ways that make it difficult not to think o f contrasts, analogies, or later devcl-
34
7.164 offers a positive contrast. Other examples in Raaflaub (1987) 226-9. See also Forsclyke, this volume (Ch. 23). Munson (1988); Shimron (1989); Stadter (1992); Moles (1996) as well as this volume (Ch. 2): Thompson (1996); see also Immerwahr (1966) Chs. 4, 5, and conclusion; Smart (1977) 251-2 (although marred by the assumption of a far too late publication date); Hunter (1982); Nicolai (1986).' E.g., 6.91, 109; 7.7, 106-7, 235; for a more complete list and discussion of such passages, see Cobet (1971) 59-78: for the latest references, Fornara (1971b), (1981). See Thuc. 2.8.3 with Homblower (1991) ad toe: Städter (1992) 788-90. 5 5
5 0
57
HERODOTUS A N D T H E I N T E L L E C T U A L TRENDS OF HIS T I M E
167
opments that must have been uppermost in the minds o f Herodotus' audiences. Famous examples include statements about the Athenians' role in the Persian Wars. When Mardonius offers them peace and a special position o f power in Greece i f they j o i n the Persian side, they decline: there is not enough gold or fertile land in the world to prompt them to collaborate with the enemy and enslave Greece, mostly because o f 'the fact that we are all Greeks one race speaking one language, with temples to the gods and religious rites in common, and with a common way o f life. I t would not be good for Athens to betray all this shared heritage' (8.144; cf. 9.4, 6-11). Here and elsewhere the implied reading is clear: the same Athenians who declined an advantageous alliance with Persia, who for the sake o f unity yielded to Spartan claims to leadership (8.3, but see 7.160 1), and whose decision to defend Greek liberty was decisive i n saving it (7.139), later turned enslavers of Greeks and became the polls tyrannos against which the Spartans eventually rallied with their own battle cry o f freedom (Thuc. 2.8). I consider it legitimate, therefore, to read the Histories inter alia as a commentary o n political trends and developments o f Herodotus' own t i m e . Moreover, the work provides general analyses o f important political phenomena and reveals insight into what we might call laws or lessons o f history'.'' This is an important and still undervalued aspect o f Herodotus' work and a substantial contribution to the development o f political and historical thought. Since Herodotus' text offers few explicit statements, this type of inquiry has to rely largely on suggestions and implications; its results cannot strictly be proved, and the plausibility o f such results rests on the cumulative power o f many arguments pointing in the same direction. Here I limit myself to discussing two extended passages: the Croesus logos i n Book One and the description o f the debates in Xerxes' crown council in Book Seven. M
50
0
T h a t the first book has a 'programmatic' or 'paradigmatic' function
5 8
See Fomara (1971a) 84-6; ibid. 62-74 on the treatment of Pausanias and Themistocles; on the latter also Munson (1988) 99 106. For this and the following, sec also Moles, this volume (Ch. 2, p. 51). Similarly, Rood (1999) 165. To avoid misunderstandings, I repeat that 1 mean neither that this is Herodotus' only purpose nor that this purpose is prominent everywhere and equally throughout the work. For an excellent reading that focuses on entirely different aspects, see Cobet (1971). Fornara (1971a) 78-9, 87-8. m
m
168
K U R T A . RAAFLAUB
has long been recognized. Within this book, I suggest, the Croesus logos (1.5-91) serves the same function in a more condensed way: it announces programmatically many important themes that resonate throughout the Histories and far beyond.'' I begin with a brief summary. I t is Croesus w h o m Herodotus knows himself (that is, for certain) to have been 'the first to commit unjust deeds against the Hellenes' by subjecting 'some o f them to the payment o f tribute' (5-6, 27). His ancestor, Gyges, gained the kingship (7 13) by violating social norms (seeing the king's wife naked) and committing a crime (killing the king), and Croesus is destined to suffer for it (13). Other ancestors wage war frequently against Greek poleis (14 16) among which Miletus, immune against land attacks because its fleet controls the sea, ends up concluding a peace treaty and alliance w i t h the Lydian king (17 22). Croesus himself pursues an aggressive policy of imperial expansion, subjecting almost all the peoples living west o f the Halys river (28). A t the height o f his power, he is visited, among others, by Solon of Athens whose statements (29-33) emphasize inter alia the fragility of human life and the need to await the end before passing final judgments. Having risen rapidly to success and power, Croesus now experiences abrupt reversals i n both his private and public life: his son is killed accidentally (34-46), and his war against the Persian king, Cyrus, ends in disaster. Before embarking on this campaign, Croesus enters into an alliance with Sparta which he discovers to be the more powerful of the two outstanding Greek states, Dorian Sparta and Ionian Athens, the latter at the time oppressed by Peisistratid tyranny (59-64), while the former has emerged as a well-ordered and prosperous state, predominant i n the Peloponnese (65-8). Ignoring the warnings o f a wise Lydian, Sandanis (71), Croesus crosses the Halys but eventually loses 1
62
ti;!
151
First book: Fomara (1971a) 18; Evans (1991) 19; Moles (1996) 259; Lateiner (1989) 259 n. 45 ('paradigmatic function'). On Herodotus' use of the figure of Croesus, see, e.g., Immervvahr (1966) 81-8, 154-61; White (1969); Bichlcr (2000) 244-55; Moles, this volume (Ch. 2). The 'Archaeology' serves a similar function in Thucydides' work: Hunter (1982) Ch. 1. On the Croesus logos, see also Fisher, this volume (Ch. 9, pp. 218 ff.). On the problem of the accuracy of this statement, see Hcuss (1973) 388 90; Lloyd (1984); Ashed (1988) ciii civ, both with earlier bibliog. Not by chance, Gyges is the first for whom the Greeks used the word lyrannos (Archil, fr. 19 West). Transgressions against women and their revenge frame the work (1.1-5, 8-12; 9.108 13) and are typical of the 'tyrannical template': Dewald (2002) and below at n. 81; see also Blok, this volume (Ch. 10, pp. 230-1). 0 8
6 3
HERODOTUS A N D T H E I N T E L L E C T U A L TRENDS OF HIS T I M E
169
the war, is captured, put on the pyre, and saved miraculously in the last moment—to become a wise, though mostly unheeded, advisor to Cyrus and Cambyses (85 IT.). I turn now to examining in more detail some o f the issues raised in this logos completeness naturally is impossible here—and first single out allusions to two specific issues that were discussed i n Herodotus' time. I n his response to Croesus, Solon denies the possibility o f selfsufficiency (autarkeia), be it o f an individual or a country (1.32), while the Athenians, says Thucydides, thought o f their polls as autarkestate and made analogous claims for their citizens. " A m o n g Croesus' motives for attacking Persia, three (revenge, greed, and faith in oracles: 1.46, 73) occur frequently in the Histories, the fourth only here: Croesus 'began to wonder whether there might be a way for h i m to restrain the growing power o f the Persian before it became too great' (1.46); such a consideration, according to Thucydides, was the true though unavowed cause o f the Peloponnesian War.'" 64
1
m
Croesus' injustice i n subjecting formerly free Greek cities to tribute-paying slavery (1.5—6, 27) and the resulting struggle for freedom announce one o f Herodotus' leitmotifs. T h e emphasis on tribute triggers thoughts o f Athenian imperial practices. '" I n addition, the historian pointedly registers the r h y t h m o f the Ionians' enslavement, liberation, and re-enslavement; liberty regained for the second time 1
bi
Like Solon's visit (Asheri (1988) 281-3; on its reference to contemporary Athens. see Moles (1996) 262 9) and probably much else, the ending of the logos is unhistorical: Croesus was almost certainly killed by Cyrus: Burkcrt (1985); Wieschofer (1987) 116-7. On the Croesus logos, see generally Regenbogen (1930a) Hellmann (1934); Hcuss (1973); Flower (1991). For the following discussion the problem of the historicity of anything mentioned by Herodotus is immaterial: all that matters is his presentation and interpretation of events and issues. Thus, for example, the story of Democedes, the physician from Croton (3.125, 129-37), is largely unhistorical (Griffiths (1987)); what interests us here is that Herodotus presents him as one of the Greeks at the Persian court who helped motivate the king to conquer Greece (below at n. 82). On the 'tragic' aspects of the Croesus logos, see Said, this volume (Ch. 6, pp. 132-37). Thuc. 2.36.3 and esp. 41.1 with 51.3: see Macleod (1983) 151-2; Raaflaub (1985) 237-41; Loraux (1986a) 153-4; Scanlon (1994) 143 64 (with detailed interpretation and bibliog.); Moles (1996) 267-9. * On revenge: dc Romilly (1971b): Gould (1989) esp. Ch. 4; see also Bcllen (1974); Gchrkc (1987): Burnett (1998); Lendon (2000). Generally on causation: Immerwahr (1956); Lateiner (1989) Ch. 9; on war: Cobet (1986). ' Thuc. 1.23.6: cf. 88.1; Hornblower (1991) 65; Immerwahr (1956) 255. See also Hdt. 7.1 1 (below at n. 85) with Said f 1981) 21. Tribute: Stacker (1992) 795-8. Liberty: von Fritz (1965); (1967) 243ff. passim; Havelock (1972) 46-52. 6 5
1,7
6 8
170
KURT A . RAAFLAUB
in 479 is protected by the Athenians who emerge as the leaders in the fight for the freedom o f all Greeks. The audience knows, o f course, that another enslavement o f the Ionians, by those very Athenians, is not long in coming and a new war will eventually be waged not least for their liberation. Anticipating this future conflict, the historian vastly overemphasizes the polarization between Sparta and Athens as the two outstanding states in Greece already in the mid-sixth century (1.56). I n fact, as he notes himself, Athens at that time was still greatly inferior to Sparta. Athens' rise to power, triggered, as in the cases o f Sparta (1.65-8) and Miletus (5.28-30), by successful reforms (5.55-78), begins only at the end o f the sixth century and will reach its peak long after the Persian Wars. That Miletus is a naval power and thus immune against land attacks (1.17) reminds us o f late fifth-century discussions about sea power, the 'insularization' o f Athens, and Pericles' strategy i n the Peloponnesian W a r . T h e association is intended: the Lydian king's futile annual ravaging of the Milesian countryside unmistakably alludes to Peloponnesian invasions in Attica i n the Archidamian War. - More generally, Miletus' reliance on its navy recalls the crucial importance of sea power in thwarting the expansion o f eastern empires and in Greek empire building: Polycratcs aspires to control the sea but aims at ruling over all o f Greece when a Persian satrap promises h i m enough money (3.122). Based on their fleet and the financial resources 69
70
71
7
73
m
Sec 1.6, 27, 169; 2.1; 6.31-3; 9.90-2, 98, 104, 106. Cf. 5.76 on four Dorian invasions of Attica, prompting the audience to think of similar events in their own time. Stahl (1987) 57; Asheri (1988) 297; cf. Schaefer (1932) 251 -60 on Sparta as prostates les Hettados. 1.68.6 on Sparta's 'rule' in the Peloponnese {katestrammenS) almost certainly points forward to conditions of Herodotus' own time (Raaflaub (1985) 89 n. 91, 159). Parallel between Sparta and Athens: Raaflaub (1988a) 213 n. 73; between Sparta and Miletus: Gorman (2001). The return of the bones of Orestes to Sparta (1.67-8; Boedeker (1993)), will have recalled the return of the bones of Theseus to Athens (Pint. Kim. 8.5-7; Vies. 36; see Ungern-Sternberg (1986)), an episode characteristically omitted by Thuc. 1.98.2; cf. Hornblower (1991) 150 (with bibliog.). Moles (1996) 260-1. 'Insularity and sea power: e.g., Thuc. 1.143.5; 2.6212-3; Ps.-Xen. Ath. Pol. 2.14-6; Starr (1978). Pericles' strategy: 1.141.2- 144.1. Cobet (1971) 148-51 emphasizes different aspects. Munson (1986) suggests that even the brief Arion story, inserted here (1.23-4), although 'the only purely episodic insertion in the Histories', is structurally and thematicallv 'analogous to the work as a whole' (95, 98); see also u. 91 below. '·' Cf. Pansanias' desire (eras) to use his Persian connections to become tyrant over Greece (5.32). On eras in this context, see Benardete (1969) 137-8; Dewald (2002); 7(1
71
n
1
HERODOTUS AND T H E I N T E L L E C T U A L TRENDS OF HIS TIME
171
of the allies, the Athenians will do just that, and it is the Persian alliance and money that both sides will seek early in the Peloponnesian War. ' Miletus' success in establishing a special relationship as a free and allied city with Alyattes (1.22), probably Croesus, and even Cyrus (1.141, 143), while the other poleis in Asia M i n o r fight and succumb individually (1.26, 141, 169), brings up two well-known key themes in the Histories disunity and collaboration with the Persians—that will continue to trouble the Greeks after 479. Unity in leadership and purpose, Herodotus insists, makes a populous and warlike people unbeatable. I n contrast to the Thracians (5.3), Scythians (4.118-19), and Ionians (1.169-70), i n 480 those 'who had the best interests o f Greece at heart' not only impose peace among themselves but also 'try to find a way to unite the whole o f the Greek world—to get everyone to think and act i n concert' (7.145). This goal remains elusive, then as later, but among a small number o f communities it is realized—briefly but with overwhelming results. I n contrast to the Argives and Gelon of Syracuse (7.148-52, 157-63, 165), the Athenians agree to yield to Sparta's claims to leadership: 'They were right, because internal dissension is worse than a united war effort to the same degree that war is worse than peace' (8.3; cf. 1.87). Ironically, a system of conflict resolution by negotiation and arbitration, recommended by Mardonius' scathing comments on the Greeks' habit of 'going about things i n the wrong way' (7.9(5), is imposed on the Ionians by the Persians (6.42), while the free Greeks will continue to ignore arbitration agreements and to escalate their fratricidal wars. 7 1
75
In attacking the Persians, Croesus disregards a wise man's warning not to provoke war against tough men living a poor life in a rugged land; nothing is to be gained but much is to be lost (1.71). Again, two leitmotifs are announced here. That o f the wise Warner is one o f Herodotus' most successful interpretative devices. '' T h e 7
on eras in lale fifth-century political discourse, see bibliog. in Raaflaub (1994) 129-30; Monoson (1994); Wohl (1999). " Thuc. 1.82.1; 2.7.1, 67.1; 4.50.2; see Lewis (1977) 62-70 and below at n. 82. See also 5.12 15; a positive counter-example: 3.138; cf. Hunter (1982; Ch. 5. Miletus is to be contrasted with Athens (8.144, but see 9.4, 6-11). Sec generally Gillis (1979). Immerwahr (1966) Ch. 5 emphasizes disunity as the motif that binds the Greek accounts together; see 187-8 on excess of unity as the 'basic condition of Persian greatness that also causes their downfall'; see further Konstan (1987). E.g., 4.83; 7.10; see BischotF (1932); Lattimorc (1939); Shapiro (forthcoming); Said, this volume (Ch. 6). 75
70
172
K U R T A. R A A F L A U B
other concerns the contrast between poor and rich countries breeding tough and soft men that recurs throughout the work in many variations and serves especially to set Persian luxury off against Greek simplicity. Herodotus' overall conception clearly is that initial Persian toughness had long been eroded by the wealth they had acquired from their far-flung empire. Hence they were no match for the freedom-loving, poor and hardy Hellenes to w h o m , as Croesus says o f the Massagetae (about to defeat Cyrus) 'a Persian-style good life and anything approaching real luxury' were unfamiliar (1.207).' Combining all this with Croesus' insight 'that human affairs are on a wheel, and that as the wheel turns around it does not permit the same people always to prosper' (1.207; cf. 1.5; 7.18, 203), we may again extrapolate. T h e Athenians, like all mainland Greeks living i n a poor land, have proved their valour and experienced a meteoric rise to great power and wealth. They too will be corrupted by their empire and eventually fall. The first crankings o f the wheel can be heard when Themistocles uses military force to extort monetary contributions from several islands (8.111-12). Croesus is the first empire builder in the Histories. He attacks and conquers his neighbours w i t h a variety o f justifications, some serious, some trivial (1.26, 46, 73), and proves insatiable in his aggressive policy o f expansion. Bolstered by success and believing in his good fortune, he crosses the Halys, attacks a more resourceful enemyand fails. This pattern o f conquest and success, prompting overconfidence and further aggression that leads to eventual disaster is applied, as a structuring and interpretative device, to all Persian kings. Cyrus, Cambyses, Darius, and Xerxes fail at the end because they reach for the ends o f the earth, cross boundaries imposed by nature and divine order (great rivers, the Hellespont, or the desert) and are defeated by nature a n d / o r peoples that are culturally too different to be tamed by the methods with which the Persians suc7
7(i
77
E.g., 9.80-2; cf. 8.26 and 7.102, 104, 135; 8.144. The contrast (on which see above at nn. 42-4) is too schematic; see. e.g., 9.122; 9.63 with 71 and 1.136; Gould (1989) 58-60. vSee Gobet (1971) 174 6 with n. 704. Note the striking parallel between 8.111 and 9.82. Thucydides too chooses Athens' dealing with a little island, Melos, to exemplify the problem of imperialism (5.84 ff.). See also Miltiades' ill-fated expedition to Paros (6.1 32-6, also to extort money, among other reasons). On Athens and softness, see Thuc. 2.40.1 and Moles (1996) 265-6; on the Croesus logos and Athens, Moles, this volume (Ch. 2). 7 8
HERODOTUS A N D T H E I N T E L L E C T U A L TRENDS OF HIS T I M E
173
5
ceeded before/ ' M u c h o f this probably is Herodotus' free elaboration. As Aeschylus did before h i m , he stresses the boundaries between Asia and Europe, one to be ruled by the Persians, the other by the Greeks. Xerxes hubristically violates these limits, suffers defeat and loses a great army. Again we extrapolate: the Histories end with the Athenians' refusal to evacuate the Ionians from Asia M i n o r , their new alliance with some islands, and their capture o f Sestos on the Hellespont (9.106, 114-18). There will soon be a larger alliance, a change o f hegemony with a specious justification, and wars fought about the king's territory (8.3). If, however, Xerxes d i d wrong in crossing into Europe, what about the Athenians crossing into Asia?"" Finally, Herodotus introduces Croesus as tyrannos o f all the peoples west o f the Halys (1.6). This brings up the problem o f tyranny, another major topic that pervades the Histories. As Carolyn Dewald demonstrates, on various levels ranging from the use o f terminology and the development o f a 'despotic template' to the negative characterization o f most Greek tyrants and the identification o f despotic elements in Persian monarchy, Herodotus explores the nature o f autocracy and explains why it is fundamentally bad. The weaknesses he exposes, recurring repeatedly and concerning different persons, are not tied to individuals but structural: the results o f many case studies enable h i m to move from the specific to the general and to define the nature o f tyranny or despotism as such. This effort culminates in three 'set pieces', each illuminating a different aspect o f the phenomenon: the Deioces story (1.96-100), the Constitutional Debate (3.80-2), and the speech o f the Corinthian Socles (5.92)."'
'•' Such as the nomadic Scythians (esp. 4.46) or the Greeks with their love for liberty, respect for nomas, and passion for participatory government (e.g., 1.153; 7.135; 7.104). On typical and recurring patterns, see immerwahr (1966) Ch. 4; Hunter (1982) Ch. 5. See also Harrison, this volume (Ch. 24). Aesch. Persians 101-13, 739-86. Boundaries: e.g., L4; 9.116: Immerwahr (1954): Lateiner (1989) Ch. 6; Stacker (1992) 785-95, 798-801; Romm, forthcoming. Note at the end of 9.117 the hint at Athens on the move: Fornara (1971a) 81. The future change of hegemony (478/77) is announced in highly unfavourable terms (8.3); the formulation of the oath sworn by the allies reminds us of future oppression and revolts (9.106). Nor is the single reference to Pericles (6.13.1: Agariste's dream to give birth to a lion) unambiguous: Fornara (1971a) 52-6; see also ibid. 83-4 on 7462.1; Hornblowcr (1991) 346 on 3.82.4. Morrison (194!) 11-4; (1950) 76 7 on the Constitutional Debate as a critique of Pericles' monarchy goes too far: Gomme (1956) 194. On the broad range of associations elicited by the end of the Histories, see recently Boedeker (1988): Herington (1991a); Moles (1996) 27.1 -7; Dewald (1997). Dewald (2002); earlier discussions: Waters (1971), (1972); Ferrill (1978); Fiory m
174
KURT A . RAAFLAUB
Tyranny takes on an additional detrimental dimension, when Greek tyrants maintain themselves only w i t h Persian backing. Local despotism thus tends to draw i n Persian imperial despotism—just as Greeks in Persian service or Greek refugees i n Persia do not hesitate to subject fellow-Greeks to permanent Persian enslavement i n order to satisfy their individual aspirations: the list is long and will find a sad continuation much later when individuals and communities compete for Persian support not least to attain domination over Greece/' Moreover, many o f the traits which make up the 'despotic template' apply equally to Athens, the polls tymnnos that i n its rule over its allies succeeds to and i n several ways imitates the Persians. I t is ominous, therefore, that Croesus' fall from the height o f imperial power is explained by two necessities: he pays for the guilt o f his ancestor, Gyges, who assumed power (tyranny) by unjust means (1.7—13, 91) and he suffers because o f divine anger (nemesis), ' i n all likelihood for thinking that he was the most fortunate man (olbioMos) i n the w o r l d ' (1.34). Both issues, applied to Athens, were thoroughly familiar to Herodotus' contemporaries. 2
83
So much for foreshadowing of political issues i n the Croesus logos. T h e depth o f Herodotus' political thinking is perhaps gauged best in another passage. I n several scenes at the Persian court, where the crown council meets to advise Xerxes on his decision to conquer Greece, he explores the deeper motives o f Persian imperialism (7.5-18)." A m o n g other reasons brought up by various interested parties (7.5-6, 8(3, 9a), Xerxes emphasizes his obligation to prove himself and live up to the examples set by his ancestors (8a). H e presents the subjection o f Greece as merely the first step i n a sweeping conquest o f Europe that, 'will make all lands into a single land' and 'Persian territory end only at the sky. . . A n d so the innocent 4
(1987) Gh. 4; Barcelo (1993) 149-77; Christ (1994); see also Stahl (1983) 211: Socles' speech as a didactic 'Beispielrede'. See Raaflaub (1989) 41 6, for the origin of the Constitutional Debate in the context of critical analyses of democracy. See above n. 74. O n the treaties confirming the king's sovereignty over the Greeks in Asia, see Lewis (1977) 90 107. That this would be the price must have been clear to both sides much earlier than it appears from Thucydidcs. Hence Demaratus' categorical statement in 7.102.2 sounds hollow too. See also Alcibiades' cynical comments in Thuc. 8.46.3. Tyranny: Thuc. 2.63.2. Greatness and happiness: Hdt. 8.111: Thuc. 3.45.6; 7.69.2, and an allusion in 2.43.4; see also Raaflaub (1985) 241-4. See Kvans (1991) Ch. I ; Raaflaub (2002a) with further bibliog; on the differences between Herodotus and Aeschylus, see Said (1981) as well as this volume (Ch. 6). 83
m
herodotus
and
the
intellectual trends
1 75
o f his t i m e
will bear the yoke o f slavery along w i t h those who have wronged us' (8y). Mardonius carries this further: the Persians have enslaved many great peoples— not 'because they did us any wrong, but just because we wanted to increase our dominion' (9a). The Greeks will be no match for the Persians (9(3). 'Anyway, we should leave nothing untried (apeireton). Nothing comes o f its own accord (automaton); people invariably get things as a result o f their own efforts (apo pares)' (9y). Only Artabanus dares to dissent but his sane advice (10) provokes Xerxes' anger. He now sees his prestige at stake. Moreover, ' I am sure the Athenians will do something i f we do not; to judge by their past moves, they will certainly mount an expedition against our country . . . I t is impossible for either side to withdraw now . . . A n d in the end either all Persia will be i n Greek hands, or all Greece will be in Persian hands; there is no middle ground in this war' (11). Xerxes later reconsiders (13) but a repeated dream forces h i m to change his mind again and Artabanus to consent (12, 14 8). As the latter explains, o f the two options available, one 'would increase our hubris, while the other would curb it, by pointing out how wrong it is to train the mind to be constantly seeking more than it has at the moment'; he did not want the king 'to choose the more treacherous one' (16a). He has 'often seen mighty powers brought, low by inferior ones'. He knows 'what harm can come from excessive desire' (potion epithumeein) and is convinced that it would be best for the king to stay quiet (18, cf. 8a). But this does not seem to be the god's will. 83
A l l this is written from the hindsight o f Herodotus' mature years. It anticipates Athenian control o f the coast o f Asia M i n o r after 479 and strikingly echoes ideas current in the time o f the Histories' composition and highlighted in Thucydides.' I n putting the alternative %
8>
On this dream as 'une incarnation de la nécessité historique', see Said (1981) 22-5; as Herodotus' creation: Immerwahr (1954) 30-7; Bichler (1985) 140 7 (witli bibliog.). Some of the arguments mentioned above have been introduced earlier: e.g., 6.134 (proving oneself); 5.105; 6.48, 94 (revenge as pretence for large-scale conquest); 1.207 (all or nothing). Some figure already in Aeschylus' Peisians: e.g., conquest of the world (50. 65-7. 73 5, 85-92, 233-4); emulation of ancestors (753-8). ' ' ' E.g., always wanting more, being unable to stay quiet, leaving nothing untried: cf. Thuc. 1.70 with echoes in Euripides' Suppliants of the late 420s: Raaflaub (1989) 51-2; (1994). Pressure by ancestral example: e.g., Thuc. 2.36; Raaflaub (2001). Lack of knowledge about the target country, delusions, and false promises about an easy victory, use of a just pretext for an expedition that openly aims at large-scale conquest, and personal ambitions of the potential general: see Thuc. 6.1 26. Subjecting J1
176
K U R T A. R A A F L A U B
starkly as 'either them or us', Herodotus seems to think o f the polarization o f Greece and the perception, typical o f his time, that the great war between Sparta and Athens was a final contest in which the winner would take all. Moreover, all this contributes to a trenchant general characterization o f imperialism as a political phenomenon. It is nourished by pteonexia, an insatiable desire for more. Based on previous successes a n d / o r the achievements o f previous generations, it puts relentless pressure on the ruler, blinds reason, and develops its own dynamics. It knows no limit, transcends physical and mental barriers, and aims ever further, regardless o f profits or losses. Although sometimes using plausible justifications as pretexts, it is a justification in itself: conquest motivates further conquest. It is thoroughly unjust, the very essence o f hubris, because it harms guilty and innocent alike. I t ends only by overextension and strategic mistakes, engendered by the ruler's overconfidence and loss of critical judgment, which enable a weaker people to maximize their own specific resources and deal the conqueror a decisive blow. T h e entire passage is a set piece on imperialism, comparable in form and intent to similar pieces on tyranny (above at n. 81) and to much better known Thucydidean examples, such as the Mytilenian, Melian, and Sicilian debates. Just when the last and greatest Persian imperial venture is about to begin, it summarizes and deepens the analysis presented through narrative and speeches in previous books."' It is complemented, for example, by the description o f the Persian war council before the battle o f Salamis which reveals further crucial flaws in Persian decision making (8.67 9), and by a series o f discussions among the Greeks (most remarkably one at Gelon's court in Syracuse, dealing with the allies' request for assistance against the Persians) that illustrate the obstacles they face in pursuing a common purpose." 8
guilty and innocents alike: see esp. Thuc. 5.94-7. Such correspondences have been noticed, e.g., by Cornford (1907) Ch. 12; Smart (1977) 251-2 (the latter suggesting an extremely late date for the work's composition); Rood (1999). For full discussion, see Raaflaub (2002a). " See 7.20 on Xerxes' expedition as the greatest war ever; Dewald (2002) on the placement of such set pieces at moments of transition; Fornara (1971a) 87-8 on the generic nature of Xerxes' words in 7.8. * 7.153, 157-65 (cC 145, 148-52, 169-71); see Brunt (1993) 75-80. The real explanation of Gelon's unwillingness to help the Greeks (the Carthaginian threat) is mentioned as an alternative version (7.165), attributed to Sicilian sources, while no source is given for Gelon's alleged main reason: his refusal to share in the war
HERODOTUS A N D THE I N T E L L E C T U A L
TRENDS OF HIS T I M E
177
Persistent political foreshadowing and analysis, found in the two sections just examined and in many other passages, offer important clues to the reasons for Herodotus' interest in history and to his purpose in writing about it. Before he begins his historical narrative, he states programmatieally: ' I will cover m i n o r and major human cities equally, because most o f those which were important in the past have diminished in significance by now, and those which were great in my own time were small in times past. 1 will mention both equally because I know that human happiness never remains long in the same place' (1.5, cf. 207). Here we hear the Greek historian who deals equally with empires, monarchs, and cities, but addresses audiences o f Greek /wfo-citizens. He lets Solon emphasize that human life is fragile and one needs to await the end before passing final judgment on a person's happiness (1.32). Such comments define Herodotus' outlook: history consists o f a sequence o f rises and declines of great powers and powerful leaders; human happiness, success, and power are unstable and unlikely to last long; the higher a person or a state reach, the sooner will they fall; it is unjust and hubrislic to overstep one's bounds, to rob others of their land and liberty; tyrannyis innately bad and corrupts its holder; imperialism, because it is unjust and cannot be limited, will end in disaster." 0
These lessons from the past arc significant as lessons for the present and future. But which came first? Was it the past that sharpened Herodotus' awareness o f the present or vice versa? Some scholars have suggested plausibly that concerns about political conditions and developments in his own time were crucial in turning Herodotus into an historian." I f so, his historical thinking (about past history) 0
without having a share in the command; on this, see 1'ornara (1971a) 82-4. Further scenes illustrating Greek decision making and obstacles to unity: 8.49, 56 63, 74 5, 78-82, 140-4. The difficulties of establishing •defensive unity' among autonomous peoples are foreshadowed in the Scythian lotps (4.118-19); see Hunter (1982) 185-90, 197, 212-8. On the Persian war council: Munson (1988) 95-8. " See i i . 12 above. '"' Kornara (1971a) Ch. 3 (with discussion of earlier views), 86 91; Meier (1987) esp. 52 4. Meier (1978), (1980), (1986), (1987) discusses the origins of Herodotus' specific type of history. By contrast, Rood (1999) 166 acknowledges the validity of reading Herodotus' Persian War stories as political stories, but urges caution "about all easy constructions of the origins of history-writing*: 'what is not valid is to make Herodotus' story about Athenian imperialism his overriding message, the basis of his historical thought; that is, to make it central to our own stories about how he came to write history', It is not clear to me why this should not: be valid and why easy. H
178
KURT A . RAAFLAUB
was shaped a priori by his political reflection (about present conditions and problems); at the very least, both developed hand i n hand. In his final evaluation which guided the final composition o f his work, history o f the past and political developments of the present formed a continuum, unfolding under the force o f the same dynamics and propelled by the same basic human impulses: individual and communal self-interest prompting, o n the one hand, the search for power that results i n tyranny and imperialism and, on the other hand, a never-ending fight for liberty and self-assertion. Sadly, however, successful freedom fighters tend either to fall immediately under someone else's oppressive yoke (the Medes (1.95-6) or the lonians) or to turn into imperialist and tyrannical oppressors themselves (Persia, Athens)—only to be corrupted by power and luxury and destroyed by the consequences o f their pleonexia. Herodotus probably felt quite passionately about all this. Occasional remarks reveal his distaste for war and Greek disunity (1.87; 7.9(3; 8.3). We hear him speaking also through his warners, including Solon, and it seems likely that he describes his own predicament when he lets an anonymous Persian before the Battle o f Plataea say: ' A n event which has been decreed by the god cannot be averted by man, for no one is willing to believe even those who tell the truth . . . There's no more terrible pain a man can endure than to see clearly and be able to do nothing' (9.16). N o r was he alone i n being concerned about such issues. M a n y o f them were discussed by one or the other of the sophists. Athenian comedians made bitter fun o f them. Tyranny, never absent from comical satire even i n Pericles' days, re-emerged as a topic o f political polemic i n Cleon's time and o f public concern a decade later. I t pervades tragedy, and the tragedians worried immensely as well about Athens' role as a polls iyrannos?' Yet one did not need to be i n Athens to share such thoughts and worries. As suggested earlier, Herodotus drew on a large pool o f political ideas that were shared by and developed in interaction among many 91
1
91
C f Stambler (1982) 231. Solon; Chiasson (1986): Shapiro (1996) (with discussion of dissenting views); Moles (1996) 262 6, who also quotes (281 n. 26) a suggestion by Alan Griffiths that makes good sense of the story of Arion (1.23-24.6) 'as preparing the way for die wisdom figures who are to follow'. Tyranny: Berve (1967) 1.190-206. 2.625-30; McGlew (1993) Ch. 6; Henderson (2002); Seaford (2002); Raaflaub (2002b). Polls lyrannos: Raaflaub (1988c) 294-301; Rosenbloom (1995), (forthcoming). On Herodotus and tragedy: Said, this volume (Ch. 6). 9 2
HERODOTUS A N D THE I N T E L L E C T U A L TRENDS OF HIS T I M E
1 79
intellectuals throughout the Greek world. His originality lies less in these ideas themselves than i n his application of these ideas to history i n order to organize it, explain it, and make it meaningful to his present audiences and future readers. Naturally, objections can, and have been, raised against the type of interpretation presented here. I mention two o f them. One concerns Herodotus' thinking o f future readers. Charles Fornara emphasizes Thucydides' genius i n creating a self-explanatory history which by itself would suffice to secure 'perfect comprehension o f the important and universally relevant issues', while Herodotus constantly draws on the knowledge and expectations o f his audience to achieve his dramatic effects. Hence 'Thucydides wrote for the future, Herodotus for his contemporaries'. There is much truth i n this but, surely, in presenting his History as a ktema es aid, Thucydides lets the future begin with the present: his observations and insights would be important for audiences at any time, including not least his contemporaries. ' Unlike his importantly novel perspective o f offering a work o f timeless usefulness, however, concern with the present was familiar from performed poetiy since Homer's days and d i d not need to be explained; it was taken for granted. As for Herodotus, he too paid much attention to general truths that can be learned from history; hence future generations would profit as well. He need not have assumed that future audiences would lack familiarity with important events, posterior to those described i n the Histories, which would allow them to appreciate the specific interpretation and dramatic effects he was artfully presenting. He wrote for a Panhellenic audience anyway, and the purposes he mentions explicitly at the beginn i n g o f his w o r k are compatible w i t h b o t h present and future performance (or reading). Indeed, as Robert Connor suggests, we need to ask whether Herodotus 'does not treat his subject matter in a way that will make it contemporary not only to him but also to us, that is to readers o f a recurring and indeterminate present'. 93
91
05
Fornara (1971a) 59 61 and passim in chapter 4. '" This seems obvious, e.g., from 2.47.3, and all the more so i f Thucydides too presented highly polished sections in oral recitations (Hornblower (1996a) 26-7: cf. Thomas (1992)'103-4). See also Badian (1993) 128: 'Thucydides, although aiming to leave a work for eternity, was in the first instance writing for a public (and, in particular, an educated Athenian public) of his own dav.' See Raaflaub (1988b), (2000); lor tragedy id. (1988c); see also Stall! (1987) 21 and below at n. 98. ,,:>
180
K U R T A . RAAFLAUB
Connor sees as one o f the most, important challenges to Herodotean scholars the study of 'Herodotus' techniques o f breaking out o f the immediacy o f events and reaching an audience o f unknown dimensions and circumstances'.* The other objection concerns Herodotus' interaction w i t h his contemporaries. Where Fornara recognizes at least the beginnings o f a theory o f history or 'historical philosophy' and an explication o f 'laws o f history', John Gould sees no more than metaphors, 'refined common sense', 'generalizations which permit contradiction and conflicting interpretations, but at the same time . . . appeal to the comfort ol familiarity; i n some measure they serve to produce a map o f human experience. They are intelligible and they reassure'. Gould concludes that, the 'most pervasive strand o f explanation i n Herodotus' narrative . . . is the sense that historical experience is the result o f reciprocal action, the fulfilling o f debts o f gratitude and the taking o f revenge'." Here, I think, Gould, convinced that Herodotus remained rooted firmly i n the craft and horizon o f the storyteller, fails to perceive how far the historian ultimately transcends these traditional patterns o f explaining history and how frightening rather than comforting, even i f eerily familiar, the map o f human experience is which he draws up through his work. Moreover, in denying the possibility that Herodotus writes at least in part i n order to convey a message to his audiences, Gould seriously underestimates the importance o f this very aspect i n the centuries-old tradition o f Greek performed poetry with which he otherwise links Herodotus. '" Homer sings to preserve the kleos o f great heroes o f the past, but i n interpreting their actions he raises troubling social and political issues that were familiar and meaningful to his audiences. This didactic purpose, implicit in the poet's way o f shaping his narrative, is an indispensable part of the poet's craft and social function. Herodotus, I argue, extends this purpose, which perhaps lived in the tradition o f prose story7
1
%
Connor (1987) 258. Latciner (1989) 5 n. 8 (p. 230) chinks of Herodotus as addressing primarily the future. See, e.g., 1.20; 9.16 on the importance of foreknowledge for making the right decision in the present (proeidos pros to pareon (boukuesthai); reference by John Marincola). Here, too, Hunter's (1982) emphasis on Herodotus' focus on processes seems crucial. Gould (1989) 76-82; Fornara: see above n. 60. Gould (1989) 116-20 and passim esp. in Chs. 2 and 6: performed poetry: above n. 95. w
HERODOTUS A N D T H E I N T E L L E C T U A L TRENDS OF HIS T I M E
181
19
telling as well, to his prose epic.- T o put it in extreme terms: just as 'heroic epic is historical in appearance but contemporary in meaning', so too history is important less i n and o f itself than insofar as it is meaningful to the present. Herodotus differs from Thucydides i n the emphasis he places on preserving the memory o f the past but he agrees with Thucydides i n recognizing the historian's obligation to the present and future: to educate his audiences and readers through his presentation and interpretation o f history. I n all this Herodotus appears both traditional and highly original. His originality is visible also i n the relationship he establishes between history and ethnography. Scholars focussing on the mass o f geographic and ethnographic material incorporated especially in the first half o f his work have concluded that he began as a traditional Hecataeus-likc scholar and ended up being a historian; the Histories would thus reflect two or more phases i n his development, about which we know nothing but can derive much from carefully analysing his work. Yet i n its extant form this work does not contain an ethnographic first and a historical second part. Rather, the presentation of ethnographic material saves from oblivion many memorable deeds and monuments o f both Greeks and barbarians—one of the two intentions emphasized i n the preamble -and it serves an explicitly historical purpose. '' 100
10
Monuments document wealth and power; they are thus historically significant and justify extensive coverage (2.35, cf, 148-9; 3.60) although, as Thucydides (1.10; cf. H d t . 1.5) reminds us, perceptions can be deceptive. Comparison establishes contrasts and analogies which help bring out i n sharper profile both general historical patterns and specific characteristics, especially of the Greeks. Herodotus uses both sides o f this 'mirror' extensively. He understands that 102
w
A similar suggestion in Thomas (2000) 4. Quotation: Raaflaub (1997) 628. All this has, of course, considerable consequences for the question of truth and fiction in, and the historical source value of, this kind of historiography; see recently, e.g., Bichler (1985); Moles (1993), and the survey in Bichler and Rollinger (2000) 160 5. Thus, e.g., Stambler (1982) 212-7. See.Jacoby (1913) 341 11), esp. 353 ( I , for a developmental or analytical, and Pohlenz (1937) for a unitarian view, f o r surveys of the scholarship on this question, see Gobet (1971) 4 42, 188-98; Hommcl (1981) 272-7; for discussion, Fomara (1971a) Chs. 1 2 and passim. See Thomas (2000) 19-20 on the 'tyranny' of the idea of linear development, be it in literature or an author's intellectual progression. '"' Hartog (1988); Darbo-Peschansky (1987); cf Nippel (1990) 11 29: (1996) 170-2; 1110
101
182
KURT A . RAAFLAUB
people act and react i n specific ways not only because o f immediate experiences but because they are conditioned by customs, cultural traditions, environment, and previous history. Without taking these aspects seriously, their contemporaries will not know how to deal with them, and the historian and his audiences will not be able to understand historical events. Despite Artabanus' warning (4.83), Darius ignores essential facts about the Scythians who have 'come up w i t h the cleverest solution . . . to the single most important matter i n human life . . . how to prevent anyone who attacks them from escaping, and how to avoid being caught unless they want to be detected' (4.46). I n spite o f Demaratus' explanation, Xerxes disregards crucial information about the Greeks' arete and the role o f nomas i n Spartan society (7.101—5). Both kings fail not least because they are not interested i n the nomoi o f the peoples they try to conquer.' 03
Hence the more the audience knows about the lands, customs, cultures, and histories o f the peoples that ended up forming the mighty Persian empire, the better will they understand the Persian accomplishment and the more will they be able to appreciate the greatest tlioma o f all: the Greek victory over all that might—for reasons and despite great obstacles which the (naturally much shorter) presentation o f the history and customs o f the culturally and politically multi face ted Greek w o r l d illuminates. Herodotus' concept thus differs both from the peiiegesis, where history forms but one component o f the description o f foreign lands, and from later historiography, where ethnography is usually confined to relatively brief digressions. Faced with the daunting task o f making a war between two continents and two different worlds understandable, he finds ethnography, integrated into the structure o f a historical narrative, indispensable. Thucydides, writing about a war among Greeks, 104
on monuments as deeds, see Immerwahr (1960); Hornblower (1987) 30-3; (1991) 33-5. Cf. the Corinthians' efforts to explain to the Spartans what sorts of people the Athenians really are (Thuc. 1.70). I n Xerxes' case, the Persians are misled, in addition, by their experiences with the Iouians (Evans (1991) 13-14). Xerxes dismisses Demaratus with benign laughter (7.105): on the meaning of laughter in Herodotus, see Flory (1978b); Lateiner (1989) 28. See generally Lateiner (1989) Ch. 7 and the acute observations of Stambler (1982) 215-17; this seems true even i f Herodotus ethnography is unsystematic (Redfield (1985) 97) and focuses on superlatives and extremes (Bloomer (1993)). On Herodotus' ethnography and the function of nomasI nomoi in his work, see recently Thomas (2000) Ch. 4; Bichler (2000); Munson (2001). 103
1,14
1
HERODOTUS A N D T H E I N T E L L E C T U A L TRENDS OF HIS T I M E
183
excluded most o f these materials and created a purer genre o f history that focussed almost exclusively on war and politics—thereby perhaps losing as much as he gained. 10
1
Conclusion I return now to the thesis that in many important respects Herodotus is much closer to Thucydides than is usually assumed. O f course, I am far from ignoring fundamental differences: among many other aspects, religion as well as an ethical and moral perspective are prominent i n the former and almost suppressed in the latter; women play a much larger part i n Herodotus' than i n the single-sex world o f Thucydides; the authorial T is ubiquitous i n Herodotus, structuring and validating his narrative, but almost completely absorbed into Thucydides' narrative; the two authors differ radically i n dealing w i t h the difficulties posed by their sources, and Herodotus uses a complex system o f self-contained 'stories' {logoi) to construct his narrative i n writing dramatic and artistic history, while Thucydides mostly presents a smooth, strictly chronological narrative i n writingsober 'scientific history.""' Yet, despite these and other differences, the basic ideas and issues on which the two authors focus are similar. 5
For example, although Thucydides restricts his attention almost exclusively to politics and war, while Herodotus' conception o f history is much broader, he too is deeply interested in political history, and war obviously is central to his work. T o be sure, he recognizes the involvement o f forces that lie beyond human control—fate or the divine but these forces do not replace or override empirical and political causes. I n his view, history is determined largely by the decisions o f individuals; to us this seems woefully inadequate but it is perhaps not that inappropriate for archaic Greek history w i t h 107
Hornblower (1987) 30 2. '"" Religion: Horn blower (1987) 29 30; in Herodotus: see n. 32; in Thucydides: Marinatos (1981): Jordan (1986); Hornblower (1992a). Women: Hornblower (1987) 14; Gould (1989)' 129 32; cf'.' Dewald (1981); Wiedemann (1983); Bichler and Rollinger (2000) 47-50, 99-105; Blok, this volume (Ch. 10). Authorial T : Dewald (1987) and this volume (Ch. 12); Marincola (1987). Relation to sources: Fowler (1996) 78-80, cf. 84, 86; Hornblower, this volume (Ch. 16); see also Midler (1981). Narrative: Cobet (1971); Gould (1989) 111. Dramatic vs. 'scientific history: Fornara 1
(1971a) 61 and passim in Ch. 4, I W
Gould (1989) 67 81.
184
KURT A . RAAFLAUB
its multitude o f autocrats, adventurers, and ambitious individuals, it applies even to Thucydides' work to a surprising degree, and it remained an excruciatingly influential factor in later periods. "" Still, Herodotus' individuals and communities make political choices, duly i f sometimes sarcastically noted by the historian: the Athenian polemarch before Marathon and the allied admiral before Salamis have it in their hands to save or enslave those who have put them in charge (6.109; 8.60a); the Ionian tyrants at the Danube bridge choose power i n slavery (4.136-42) which the Spartan heralds refuse (7.135), and in rejecting their tyrant's offer o f equality and freedom the elite Samians 'apparently d i d not want to be free' (3.142-3). The processes by which Xerxes and the Greeks reach their decisions are complex, combining political and individual aspects. As discussed in the last section, Herodotus connects the history o f the past with the political issues troubling the present and strongly emphasizes the most important political phenomena he sees as constants i n history. He is aware o f the political debates and theories o f his time and uses some of them to interpret the past, embedding them in narrative and speeches rather than arguing with them overtly and abstractly. 1
1119
Herodotus no less than Thucydides sees history dominated by the antithetical desires for liberty and power. T h e nomos o f the Persian kings, always to expand and to leave nothing untried, clashes with the nomos o f the Spartans, never to submit. These desires determine the historic conllict between Persia and the Greeks. They are complemented by a third and equally potent force driving people's actions: self-interest. Individuals and communities constantly make decisions that serve their own ends but more often than not harm those o f their communities and peoples. Through repetition and emphasis the historian helps us recognize patterns o f typical behaviour, despite a high degree o f individualization. These patterns reflect the theory o f the sameness o f human nature, so prominent i n Thucydides, even i f Herodotus never mentions this theory explicitly. 110
Like Thucydides, Herodotus too is critical of ideologies and pro-
108
See, e.g., Strasburger (1954a); Herman (1987). Among the most troublesome consequences of this tendency is Herodotus' explanation of the Ionian Revolt: sec, e.g., Forrest (1979); Murray (1988) esp. 463 4, 474; Walter (1993); Georges (2000) (with a strong defence of the plausibility of Herodotus' presentation). Evans (1991) 35-6. A motif emphasized, as Marincola points out to me, by Gyges' choice in the very first story of the Histories. m
110
HERODOTUS A N D T H E I N T E L L E C T U A L TRENDS OF HIS T I M E
185
paganda. Again, he reveals this indirectly rather than directly, through juxtaposition, suggestion, and implication. Claims to fight a 'just war' are but useful pretexts; imperialism progresses with or without them. T h e Greek coalition spectacularly demonstrates its commitment to fighting for freedom but, i f the Persians had been smart, they might have subverted it entirely by bribing the leaders (9.2, 4 1 ; cf. 8.4-5). The Spartans, i f need be, would fight with axes for their liberty (7.135)—but mostly their own. The Athenians save Greece -as long as it serves their interests (8.3). Isonomia, 'the most beautiful w o r d ' (3.80), and demokratia are desirable—but one is imposed on the Tonians by a tyrant (5.37) and the Persians (6.43) to serve their own interests, and the other does not keep the Athenians from being fooled by a smart speaker (5.97). Isegoria (equality of speech) has enabled the Athenians to rise to a new level o f power (5.78)—but they stone to death one of their councillors who dares to dissent (9.5).' We meet a few truly admirable characters who act selflessly and justly (e.g., 3.138; 7.163-4); some rulers are not bent on expansion and are described positively," and the Athenians, after all. did save Greece; but the naked truth is that people, whatever they say, follow only one impulse: that o f self-interest. 11
2
The insights that guide Herodotus' interpretation could easily be (and occasionally almost are) formulated abstractly and theoretically. There is no equivalent to Thucydides' analysis of the stasis on Corcyra, but Herodotus uses speeches and dialogues to create analytical set pieces that highlight specific political issues (imperialism, tyranny, obstacles to Greek unity) and, although less dense and narrowly focussed, are cjuite comparable to those that have long been appreciated in Thucydides. T h e use o f political thought to interpret history and demonstrate its immediacy and relevance for present and future is one of Herodotus' crucial contributions to creating a new genre of, as Christian Meier puts i t , history as a 'multi-subjective, contingency-oriented' narrative of events that was—and remains universally meaningful. 113
111
Despite 3.80 and 5.78, Herodotus does not think highly of democracy: see 3.81-2, 5.97 (with t.59-60); see Strasburger (1955) 10--12; Fornara (1971a) 48-51; Edelmann (1975); Van der Veen (1996) Ch. 6. See also, more generally, Saxonhouse (1996). Forsdyke (1999) suggests, however, that the influence of democratic ideology might not be negligible. "-' E.g., Tomyris (1.206), the king of the Ethiopians (3.21), and even Croesus in his early years (Immerwahr (1966) 155-8). Meier (1987) 44; see above n. 49. , I J
186
KURT A . RAAFLAUB
Overall,
p e r h a p s , i t is n o t v e r y useful t o t h i n k o f H e r o d o t u s
as
the ' f a t h e r o f h i s t o r y ' w h o was q u i c k l y o v e r t a k e n a n d left f a r b e h i n d by Thucydides—although
n o one w i l l d e n y
t h a t the l a t t e r c r e a t e d
the m o d e l t h a t was t o d o m i n a t e w e s t e r n h i s t o r i o g r a p h y . A perspective seems m o r e p r o m i s i n g . D e s p i t e
the differences i n t h e i r
l i f e t i m e s a n d , a c c o r d i n g l y , the dates b y w h i c h t h e i r w o r k s their
final
shape,114
different received
a n d despite u n d e n i a b l e differences w h i c h these
w o r k s reveal i n o u t l o o k , m e t h o d o l o g y , sible t h a t H e r o d o t u s
and Thucydides
a n d n a r r a t i v e , i t seems w e r e , as H o r n b l o w e r
pos-
puts i t ,
' i n a r e a l sense c o n t e m p o r a r i e s a n d r i v a l s ' . " - ' T h e y b o t h i n t e r a c t e d w i t h a l a r g e g r o u p o f intellectuals a m o n g t h e i r c o n t e m p o r a r i e s
who
w o r k e d i n a great v a r i e t y o f genres a n d disciplines; " f > like t h e m , t h e y b o t h d r e w o n a r i c h p o o l o f ideas, t h e o r i e s , a n d concerns t h a t w e r e w i d e l y shared a n d discussed i n t h e i r t i m e , a n d t h e y were b o t h d e e p l y i n t r i g u e d b y t h e challenge o f d i s c o v e r i n g a n d c o n v e y i n g t o t h e i r listeners a n d readers n o t o n l y the course b u t also the m e a n i n g
and
c o n t i n u i n g usefulness o f h i s t o r y . W h a t t h e y d i d w i t h this interest a n d w i t h those ideas, t h e o r i e s , a n d c o n c e r n s l e d t h e m i n d i f f e r e n t d i r e c tions b u t a l o n g s i m i l a r p a t h s :
a l t h o u g h they w r o t e about different
p e r i o d s i n d i f f e r e n t w a y s , t o b o t h o f t h e m h i s t o r y consisted l a r g e l y o f r e v o l v i n g p a t t e r n s a n d processes, a n d i t was essentially c o n t e m porary history.11' To
give H e r o d o t u s
the last w o r d , at a j u n c t u r e t h a t m i g h t h a v e
c h a n g e d t h e course o f h i s t o r y , he lets the C o r i n t h i a n Socles say:
'If
y o u h a d e x p e r i e n c e o f i t , as w e d o , y o u w o u l d be able t o offer b e t ter j u d g m e n t s about i t t h a n y o u do n o w '
1 1 4
(5.92a).
See above rm. 2 and 15. Correspondences between the debates at Xerxes' court and Thucydides' Sicilian Debate (6.1-26: above n. 86) need not be tied to 415; although Thucydides concentrates these arguments in this particular debate, they may have come up in earlier discussions about Athenian expeditions to Sicily, dating to 427-4 BC (see Raaflaub (2002a)). See also Moles (1996) 276 about why his (and my) view of Herodotus' purpose makes it difficult to date the Histories later than 415 or 414. Hornblower (1992b) 141; (1996a) 27. Hunter (1982) demonstrates this impressively, without ignoring differences (286-96). Lateiner (1989) Ch. 10 discusses 'The Failures and Success of Herodotus'. '"' Hunter (1982) 287: 'the two historians worked within the same theoretical framework, on the same epistemological terrain'. " ' Connor (1987) 257: Herodotus is 'writing contemporary history'. Efforts at comparing the two authors systematically need to be continued. 1 , 5
CHAPTER E I G H T RELIGION IN HERODOTUS Jon D. Mikalson
A l t h o u g h i t is r e g u l a r l y i g n o r e d , dismissed, o r d i s p a r a g e d b y b o t h a n c i e n t a n d m o d e r n h i s t o r i a n s , H e r o d o t u s e x p l i c i t l y offers also a r e l i gious e x p l a n a t i o n o f t h e causes a n d o u t c o m e o f t h e Persian i n v a sions. 1 I n 4 9 9 B C a s m a l l f o r c e o f G r e e k s , i n c l u d i n g A t h e n i a n s , a t t a c k e d Sardis, a p r i n c i p a l city o f t h e Persian e m p i r e , a n d i n t h e course o f the attack t h e y a c c i d e n t l y b u r n e d d o w n t h e s a n c t u a r y o f the goddess G y b e b e ( 5 . 1 0 1 - 1 0 2 . 1 ) . W h e n K i n g D a r i u s first h e a r d o f i t , ' h e t o o k a b o w , f i t t e d a n a r r o w t o i t , a n d shot t h e a r r o w i n t o the
sky. A s he d i d , he p r a y e d , " Z e u s , g r a n t m e t o take vengeance
o n t h e A t h e n i a n s . . . " ' (5.105). I t was t h e b u r n i n g o f C y b e b e ' s sanc t u a r y t h a t t h e Persians t h e n used as a n excuse f o r b u r n i n g s a n c t u aries t h r o u g h o u t the lands o f hostile G r e e k cities f o r the n e x t eighteen years ( 5 . 1 0 2 . 1 ; cf. 6 . 1 0 1 . 3 a n d 7 . 8 . β ) .
2
These i n c l u d e d , after the
I o n i a n R e v o l t , A p o l l o ' s t e m p l e a n d oracle a t D i d y m a , a n d t h e sanc tuaries o f all t h e r e v o l t i n g I o n i a n cities a n d islands o f Asia
Minor
except Samos (6.19.3, 2 5 , a n d 32). L a t e r Datis o n his w a y t o M a r a t h o n i n 4 9 0 b u r n e d the sanctuaries o f N a x o s a n d E r e t r i a (6.96 a n d 101.3). A n d i n the second i n v a s i o n X e r x e s destroyed the sanctuaries i n twelve P h o c i a n cities, i n c l u d i n g A p o l l o ' s oracle at A b a e ( 8 . 3 2 . 2 ^ 3 3 ) . H a d he h a d his w a y , X e r x e s w o u l d have h a d D e l p h i destroyed too ( 8 . 3 5 - 9 ) . A n d , finally, w i t h their occupation o f Attica Xerxes a n d Mardonius fulfilled t h e vengeance
demanded by Darius.
T h e y levelled a n d
b u r n e d , so f a r as w e k n o w , a l l t h e sanctuaries o f A t h e n s a n d A t t i c a ( 7 . 8 . β a n d 140.3; 8 . 5 3 . 2 a n d 5 5 ; 9 . 1 3 . 2 ) .
1
Lateiner (1989) offers the most recent and systematic dismissal and disparage ment of religious and supernatural causation in Herodotus' Histories. For more bal anced treatments, see Harrison (2000b); Gould (1994); (1989); Lachenaud (1978): de Ste Croix (1977); de Romilly (1971b); and Immerwahr (1966). O n the discussion of the 'tragic' aspects of Xerxes' invasion, see Said, this volume (Ch. 6, pp. 137 ff.). Diodorus (10.25.1) somewhat reformulates this point: 'The Persians learned the burning of sanctuaries from the Greeks. They were repaying the same hubris to those who had first wronged them'. 2
188
JON D . MIKALSON
Herodotus
has his T h e m i s t o c l e s , surely n o t t h e least p e r c e p t i v e
observer o f X e r x e s ' i n v a s i o n , d i r e c t l y l i n k X e r x e s ' u l t i m a t e f a i l u r e to these sacrileges. I n t h e p l a n n i n g i m m e d i a t e l y after t h e v i c t o r y i n t h e Battle o f Salamis, T h e m i s t o c l e s tells his f e l l o w A t h e n i a n s ,
'Not
we
b u t the gods a n d heroes a c c o m p l i s h e d this. T h e y b e g r u d g e d
one
m a n w h o was u n h o l y a n d r a s h (atasthalori) to be k i n g o f A s i a
and
E u r o p e . H e t r e a t e d h o l y a n d p r o f a n e things alike, b u r n i n g a n d t h r o w i n g t o the g r o u n d t h e statues o f t h e gods. H e even w h i p p e d t h e sea a n d h u r l e d l e g i r o n s i n t o i t ' ( 8 . 1 0 9 . 3 ) . 3 A n d , a few m o n t h s l a t e r , the A t h e n i a n s e c h o e d these sentiments i n t h e i r response to M a r d o n i u s ' offer o f a l l i a n c e , ' W e w i l l a t t a c k h i m , t r u s t i n g i n the gods a n d heroes as o u r allies, t h e gods a n d heroes f o r w h o m X e r x e s h a d n o respect a n d w h o s e b u i l d i n g s a n d statues he b u r n e d ' ( 8 . 1 4 3 . 2 ) . T h e gods a n d heroes w h o m t h e A t h e n i a n s a n d o t h e r Greeks t r u s t e d a n d w h o b r o u g h t t h e m v i c t o r y over the Persians are those whose efforts a n d , i n p a r t i c u l a r , whose dedications after the victories Herodotus records i n his n a r r a t i v e o f the invasions: A p o l l o o f D e l p h i , Zeus o f Olympia,
Poseidon o f I s t h m i a , Zeus E l e u t h e r i o s o f Plataea,
Athena
o f A t h e n s , D e m e t e r Eleusinia o f Plataea, M y c a l e , a n d A t h e n s , A r t e m i s Agrotera and M o u n y c h i a of Athens, and Artemis of Artemision.
The
heroes i n c l u d e d t h e A t h e n i a n A j a x , the A e g i n e t a n A e a c i d a e , a n d t h e D e l p h i c Phylakos a n d A u t o n o o s . T h e s e specific gods a n d heroes a n d the gods i n g e n e r a l h e l p e d the Greeks defeat t h e i n v a d i n g Persians against o v e r w h e l m i n g odds. As H e r o d o t u s
tells i t , the ' d i v i n e ' a n d
some gods, even G r e e k gods, m a y have h e l p e d Persians a n d t h e i r predecessors i n e a r l i e r times (e.g., Croesus, Cyrus, became
1.124.1,
1.46—56.1, 8 5 - 9 1 ,
126.6, 209.4 a n d 9.122.2), b u t w h e n
s q u a r e l y b e t w e e n Persians
and
the c o n f l i c t
a n d Greeks, the Greek divine
w o r l d c o n c e i v e d o f as a w h o l e o r i n parts s t o o d c o m p l e t e l y
and
solely b e h i n d the G r e e k s . 4 T h e s e gods a n d heroes h e l p e d t h e Greeks o n l a n d a n d at sea, b y oracles a n d o m e n s , a n d b y p e r s o n a l a p p e a r ances a n d a p p a r i t i o n s . I t w a s , i n H e r o d o t u s '
own judgment,
the
A t h e n i a n s ' w h o g a t h e r e d together a l l t h e rest o f Greece a n d r e p u l s e d
3
See also Fisher, this volume (Ch. 9, p. 223). Mardonius' consultations of Trophonius, Apollo at Abae and Ptoon, and Amphiaraus at Thebes apparently proved fruitless (8.133—6), and at Plataea he eventually disregarded his Greek seer (9.33-41). The Persian sacrifices to Thetis and the Nereids at Cape Sepias may have stopped the storm off Artemision (7.191.2). For the role of the Delphic oracle in the invasion of 480 BCE, see below. 4
189
RELIGION I N HERODOTUS
King
X e r x e s ' , b u t t h e y d i d so o n l y 'second t o t h e gods' {meta ge
theous, 7 . 1 3 9 . 5 ) . T h e r e are some c h a r a c t e r i s t i c a l l y G r e e k features o f this d i v i n e h e l p . O n l y heroes, f o r e x a m p l e , a p p e a r themselves assisting the G r e e k soldiers i n b a t t l e , like Phylakos
a n d Autonoos
at D e l p h i
(8.38—39.1).
G r e e k gods d o n o t i n H o m e r i c f a s h i o n m a k e a n e p i p h a n y i n b a t t l e (or a n y w h e r e
else) i n H e r o d o t u s '
Histories, a n d t h e h i s t o r i a n labels
Pisistratus' self-serving a t t e m p t t o stage a d i v i n e e p i p h a n y n a i v e a n d silly a c t i o n ' ( 1 . 6 0 . 3 - 5 ) .
'a very
T h i s distinction—heroes occasion-
a l l y a n d p e r s o n a l l y p a r t i c i p a t i n g i n h i s t o r i c a l b a t t l e s , gods n e v e r — i s not peculiarly Herodotean.
I t is c h a r a c t e r i s t i c o f prose accounts o f
these w a r s i n a n d after t h e classical p e r i o d . 5 Secondly, Herodotus'
d i v i n e p a r t i c i p a t i o n is d e t e r m i n e d l a r g e l y b y l o c a l e . Athena,
Demeter, a n d Artemis became involved i n the
Persian W a r s because t h e i r o w n sanctuaries w e r e i n t h e field o f c o m b a t . T h e y are t h e A t h e n a o f A t h e n s , t h e D e m e t e r o f A t h e n s , and Mycale,
a n d the Artemis o f Artemision a n d Athens.
c o n f l i c t b e e n p l a y e d o u t elsewhere, i n t h e Peloponnesus
Plataea, H a d the
for exam-
p l e , w e w o u l d find q u i t e d i f f e r e n t deities i n v o l v e d , a n d a l l this is i n accord w i t h the local character o f Greek religious cult.
Recognition
o f t h e l o c a l concerns o f t h e p a r t i c i p a t i n g deities raises t h e q u e s t i o n o f m o t i v a t i o n . W h y , i n H e r o d o t u s ' v i e w , d i d these gods s u p p o r t t h e Greeks a n d oppose t h e Persians? H e r o d o t u s , u n l i k e H o m e r , does n o t p r o b e d i v i n e m o t i v a t i o n a n d n o w h e r e gives a n e x p l i c i t answer, b u t , to j u d g e f r o m his n a r r a t i v e , i t seems t h a t these gods w e r e i n t e r e s t e d p r i m a r i l y i n p r o t e c t i n g t h e i r o w n sanctuaries a n d p u n i s h i n g the Persians f o r t h e v i o l a t i o n o f those places. T h e r e is n o i n d i c a t i o n t h a t they
'were protecting' devoted worshippers o r favouring
Greeks
because t h e y w e r e G r e e k . T h e heroes Phylakos a n d A u t o n o o s
chased
the Persians
from Delphi,
t o o k vengeance
the site o f t h e i r sanctuaries.
Protesilaus
o n t h e Persian A r t a y c t e s f o r t h e d e s e c r a t i o n o f his
s a n c t u a r y (9.116—20), a n d , i n H e r o d o t u s ' v i e w , D e m e t e r E l e u s i n i a o f Plataea d e n i e d
fighting
a n d d y i n g Persians a d m i t t a n c e t o h e r sanc-
t u a r y because t h e y h a d b u r n e d h e r s a n c t u a r y i n A t t i c a ( 9 . 6 5 . 2 ) . Only
t h e p a n h e l l e n i c deities, deities a l r e a d y p a n h e l l e n i c in cult,
p a r t i c i p a t e d b e y o n d l o c a l a n d state b o u n d a r i e s . F r o m t h e spoils o f t h e i r g r e a t v i c t o r y at Plataea t h e Greeks as a g r o u p 'set aside a t i t h e
See, e.g., Dietrich (1986) 94-101 and Mikalson (1991) 21, 30-1, and 65.
190
JON
D.
MIKALSON
f o r the g o d i n D e l p h i a n d f r o m this was d e d i c a t e d the g o l d t r i p o d o n the b r o n z e t h r e e - h e a d e d snake w h i c h stands near the a l t a r . T h e y set aside a p o r t i o n also f o r the g o d i n O l y m p i a , a n d f r o m i t t h e y d e d i c a t e d a b r o n z e Z e u s , f i f t e e n feet t a l l . A n d
there was a p o r t i o n
f o r the g o d at the I s t h m u s , a n d f r o m i t came a ten a n d f o o t b r o n z e Poseidon'
one-half
(9.81.1). D e l p h i c A p o l l o , Zeus O l y m p i o s ,
and
I s t h m i a n Poseidon thus each r e c e i v e d a m a j o r d e d i c a t i o n , b u t each h a d a d i s t i n c t role w h i c h reflects a c o m p l e x b l e n d i n g o f l o c a l a n d p a n h e l l e n i c cults a n d interests. F o r the storms at A r t e m i s i o n a n d o f f E u b o e a t h a t caused so m u c h d a m a g e to the Persian fleet i n 4 8 0 B C ,
the D e l p h i a n s
had
prayed
to a n d t h e n n o d o u b t c r e d i t e d the A n e m o i ( ' W i n d s ' ) o f T h y i a , as d i d the A t h e n i a n s
t h e i r Boreas a n d O r e i t h y i a .
B u t o n this occasion
the o t h e r Greeks as a g r o u p ' p r a y e d a n d p o u r e d libations to Poseidon Soter . . . A n d f r o m t h a t t i m e t i l l n o w have n a m e d Poseidon " S o t e r " ' (7.178,
189,
and
192).
Poseidon,
b y the v e r y n a t u r e o f his r e a l m ,
transcends state b o u n d a r i e s , a n d here the n o n - D e l p h i a n ,
non-Athenian
G r e e k s , engaged i n n a v a l w a r f a r e f a r f r o m t h e i r h o m e l a n d s ,
natu-
r a l l y i n v o k e d a n d u l t i m a t e l y as a g r o u p r e w a r d e d the one P o s e i d o n panhellenic i n cult, the Poseidon o f Isthmia. H e r o d o t u s offers n o clue i n his Histories w h y
Zeus o f
Olympia
s h o u l d be r e w a r d e d after the G r e e k v i c t o r y . F o r t h a t we m u s t piece t o g e t h e r accounts i n T h u c y d i d e s P l u t a r c h (Arist. 19—21). O n
(2.71-74), Diodorus
t h e i r w a y to Plataea, the
(11.29.1),
and
Peloponnesian
c o n t i n g e n t o f Greeks h a d v o w e d t h a t ' i f t h e y w o n , the Greeks w o u l d celebrate t o g e t h e r o n t h a t d a y each y e a r the E l e u t h e r i a h o l d t h e agonistic games
and would
o f F r e e d o m (eleutheria) i n Plataea'.
After
t h e i r v i c t o r y the Greeks f u l f i l l e d t h e i r v o w , f o u n d i n g a n e w p a n h e l l e n i c c u l t f o r Zeus E l e u t h e r i o s w i t h a n a l t a r , p r e c i n c t , sacrifice, fest i v a l , a n d games. 6 T h i s Zeus E l e u t h e r i o s was surely a b y f o r m o f Zeus Olympios,
a n aspect o f Zeus w h i c h H e r o d o t u s h i m s e l f
associates w i t h ' p o l i t i c a l ' f r e e d o m
(3.142). T h e
elsewhere
h i s t o r i c a l accounts,
d e d i c a t i o n s , a n d l a t e r h i s t o r y o f this n e w p a n h e l l e n i c c u l t suggest t h a t i t was p r i m a r i l y c o m m e m o r a t i v e , 7
a new cult o f a panhellenic
deity at t h e site o f a m a j o r v i c t o r y .
6
That a new cult of Zeus Eleutherios was founded at Plataea after the victory is widely accepted, but some see the panhellenic festival and games of the Eleutheria as a fourth or third century BC innovation. See Robertson (1986) 94-5 and Etienne and Pierart (1975) 55 and 63-8. ' See, e.g., Robertson (1986).
191
R E L I G I O N I N HERODOTUS
H e r o d o t u s gives D e l p h i c A p o l l o p r i d e o f place a m o n g the three p a n h e l l e n i c gods f o r the v i c t o r y o v e r the Persians, w i t h d e d i c a t i o n s f r o m the battles o f b o t h Salamis a n d Plataea ( 8 . 1 2 1 - 2 a n d 9 . 8 1 . 1 ) . 8 B u t A p o l l o ' s role i n the h i s t o r y o f the second i n v a s i o n was As
complex.
a l o c a l g o d he p o w e r f u l l y a n d m i r a c u l o u s l y d r o v e the
f r o m his o w n
sanctuary,
' p r o t e c t i n g his o w n p r o p e r t y '
Persians
as he
had
assured the D e l p h i a n s he c o u l d ( 8 . 3 5 - 9 ) . B u t d u r i n g the w a r his o r a cles d e t e r r e d the A r g i v e s ( 7 . 1 4 8 - 5 0 ) a n d the C r e t a n s ( 7 . 1 6 9 - 7 1 ) f r o m j o i n i n g the Greek effort, a n d his oracles nearly frightened the Athenians into abandoning
the cause ( 7 . 1 3 9 . 6 - 1 4 4 ) . T h e s e oracles raise occa-
sional c o m p l a i n t s f r o m m o d e r n scholars, b u t v i e w e d f r o m the p e r spective o f the cities w h i c h sought t h e m , t h e y m i g h t w e l l have been realistic assessments t h a t , h a d the w a r e n d e d i n the w a y m o s t l i k e l y , c o u l d have saved needless s u f f e r i n g o r even t o t a l d e s t r u c t i o n . O n p o s i t i v e side, b e f o r e A r t e m i s i o n
Herodotus'
Delphic
oracle
the
urged
prayers to various w i n d a n d sea gods, a n d these prayers were answered (7.178 a n d 189). T h e d e a t h o f L e o n i d a s f u l f i l l e d , i n a w a y to the G r e e k e f f o r t , a D e l p h i c oracle ( 7 . 2 2 0 . 3 - 4 ) . T h e
favourable
Delphic
ora-
cles to A t h e n s u r g e d the strategically wise e v a c u a t i o n o f A t t i c a a n d , p r o p e r l y i n t e r p r e t e d , suggested the strategy a n d place f o r the B a t t l e of Salamis
(7.139-44).
And
the oracle b r o u g h t
the l u c k y
T e i s a m e n u s to Plataea ( 9 . 3 3 - 5 ) a n d set u p M a r d o n i u s
seer
f o r disaster
t h e r e (8.114). 9 I n h i n d s i g h t w e m i g h t , t h o u g h H e r o d o t u s does n o t , f a u l t A p o l l o ' s d i s c o u r a g i n g oracles. H i s
defence
o f his o w n
sanctuary
might
be
i m a g i n e d as a p u r e l y p a r o c h i a l e f f o r t . B u t t h a t A p o l l o ' s role i n the defeat o f the Persians was m u c h g r e a t e r , t h a t he i n fact was t h e r e l i gious f o c a l p o i n t o f the G r e e k e f f o r t , is i n d i c a t e d b y the o a t h w h i c h the a l l i e d Greeks t o o k at a n early stage i n the i n v a s i o n o f 4 8 0 'Whichever
BC:
Greeks give themselves u p to the Persians, i f t h e y have
n o t been f o r c e d a n d t h e i r s i t u a t i o n is g o o d , are to p a y a t i t h e to the god i n Delphi'
(7.132.2). H e r e H e r o d o t u s singles o u t n o t Zeus
of
O l y m p i a o r Poseidon o f the I s t h m u s b u t A p o l l o o f D e l p h i as the deity t o represent the G r e e k side. O n l y l a t e r , after the v i c t o r i e s , d i d A p o l l o share this h o n o u r w i t h Zeus o f O l y m p i a a n d P o s e i d o n o f I s t h m i a .
8
For the dedications Delphic Apollo received after the Battle of Marathon, not recorded by Herodotus, see Paus. 10.10.1-2, 11.5, 18.1, 19.4 and IGV' 1463B. Plutarch (Arist. 11.3-8) has the Delphic oracle designate the site of Plataea for batde and tell of the necessary vows and sacrifices. 9
192
JON D . MIKALSON
S u c h are the g e n e r a l o u t l i n e s a n d the m a j o r d i v i n e players i n H e r o d o t u s ' a c c o u n t o f the Persian invasions. T h e y m a y be dismissed b y historians whose p r i m a r y interests t r a d i t i o n a l l y lie elsewhere, b u t t o d o so is t o neglect a facet o f the w a r H e r o d o t u s t h o u g h t w o r t h y of inclusion. A n d
to assume t h a t Greeks w o u l d i n a religious vac-
u u m face, p r e p a r e f o r , fight, w i n , a n d r e m e m b e r a w a r t h a t t h r e a t ened t h e i r v e r y existence m a y be to m i s u n d e r s t a n d a n d o v e r s i m p l i f y classical G r e e k society. The
texts o f d e d i c a t i o n s m a d e
to the gods b y the Greeks after
t h e i r v i c t o r y celebrate the b r a v e r y a n d a c c o m p l i s h m e n t s o f the Greeks themselves, saying v i r t u a l l y n o t h i n g o f the gods' roles a n d i n n o w a y c l a i m i n g t h a t the d i v i n i t i e s s i m p l y 'gave'
the Greeks v i c t o r y . 1 0
In
Herodotus'
v i e w the r o l e o f the gods w a s , i t seems, to m a k e i t a
'fair
I n the I o n i a n R e v o l t the P h o c a e a n general
fight'.
Dionysius
p r o m i s e d the I o n i a n s v i c t o r y b y d e f a u l t o r b a t t l e i f o n l y ' t h e gods make it a fair
fight'
t h a t the A t h e n i a n s
(6.11.3). A t M a r a t h o n M i l t i a d e s was c o n f i d e n t w o u l d w i n ' i f the gods m a d e
i t a fair
fight'
(6.109.5). T h e s t o r m at A r t e m i s i o n a n d later o f f the coast o f E u b o e a led Herodotus
h i m s e l f t o c o n c l u d e t h a t ' e v e r y t h i n g was b e i n g d o n e
b y the g o d to m a k e the Persian force e q u a l i n size to the
Greek
a n d n o t m u c h l a r g e r ' (8.13). G i v e n the massive s u p e r i o r i t y o f t h e i r o p p o n e n t s i n n u m b e r s , w h a t Greeks n e e d e d f r o m t h e i r gods was a f a i r fight. T h e
Greeks themselves c o u l d h a n d l e the rest.
T h e Hutories, o f course, c o n t a i n failures as w e l l as successes, t h o u g h , g i v e n the o u t c o m e ,
m o r e failures f o r b a r b a r i a n s t h a n f o r
Greeks.
A c c o r d i n g to H e r o d o t u s , m a n y o f these failures s i m p l y ' h a d ' to h a p p e n . T h e y w e r e , i n some u n d e f i n e d w a y , ' d e s t i n e d ' . T h i n g s ' h a d ' t o t u r n o u t b a d l y f o r the L y d i a n C a n d a u l e s (1.8.2), f o r the
Egyptian
A p r i e s ( 2 . 1 6 1 . 3 ) , a n d f o r the T h r a c i a n Scyles (4.79.1). ' I t was essary' t h a t t h e N a x i a n s n o t be t a k e n b y M e g a b a t e s ' 499 B C
nec-
expedition i n
( 5 . 3 3 . 2 ) , a n d t h a t evils b e f a l l X e r x e s ' mistress a n d h e r f a m -
i l y after the w a r (9.109.2).
So too f o r Greeks. Evils ' h a d ' to s p r o u t
u p for C o r i n t h f r o m Eetion's f a m i l y (5.92.8.1),
Demaratus'
origins
h a d to be revealed a n d he lose his k i n g s h i p (6.64), M i l t i a d e s h a d t o 'die n o t w e l l ' ( 6 . 1 3 5 . 3 ) ,
a n d , m o s t s i g n i f i c a n t l y , the H e l l e s p o n t
'had
t o be y o k e d b y a Persian m a n ' (7.6.4) a n d a l l A t t i c a b e c o m e
sub-
10
E.g., Aeschines 3.116; Plut. Them. 8.2-3, Anst. 19.6, Mor. 870F and 873C; D. S. 11.14.4 and 33.2; and IG P 1463B.
193
R E L I G I O N I N HERODOTUS
j e c t to the Persians ( 8 . 5 3 . 1 ) . 1 1
Why
' i t was necessary' t h a t all these
things h a p p e n w e are n o t t o l d , b u t i t is n o t e w o r t h y t h a t each event i n its o w n c o n t e x t is a m i s f o r t u n e o r disaster. T h a t these evils ' h a d ' to h a p p e n does n o t m e a n , o f course, t h a t a l l evils i n the Histories ' h a d to h a p p e n ' .
Herodotus
shares the i n c l i n a t i o n o f m o s t
Greek
a u t h o r s t o i n t r o d u c e necessity i n some places a n d i g n o r e i t i n o t h ers. H e
uses 'necessity' to e x p l a i n evil i n m u c h the w a y t h a t l a t e r
Greeks used ' f o r t u n e ' {tuche).
12
B o t h reflect the Greeks' r e l u c t a n c e to
h o l d gods o f c u l t responsible f o r the v a r i o u s m a j o r a n d m i n o r m i s f o r t u n e s o f life. B u t m i s f o r t u n e a n d even d e a t h m i g h t also be the p u n i s h m e n t f o r i m p i e t y . I n the v i e w o f H e r o d o t u s '
T h e m i s t o c l e s , as w e have seen,
X e r x e s f a i l e d i n his e x p e d i t i o n because
he b u r n e d a n d
destroyed
sanctuaries a n d statues o f the gods. So t o o a g r o u p o f Persians d i e d for v i o l a t i n g Poseidon's sanctuary at Potidaea (8.129), as d i d Artayctes f o r desecrating the s a n c t u a r y o f Protesilaus, a n episode f e a t u r e d i n the c l o s i n g pages Herodotus
o f the Histories ( 9 . 1 1 6 - 2 1 ) .
O t h e r impieties that
has e x p l i c i t l y p u n i s h e d are the m a l t r e a t m e n t o f priests
(Cambyses, 3 . 2 9 . 2 ; C l e o m e n e s , 6.81); v i o l a t i o n o f a s y l u m 6.91; Cleomenes,
(Aeginetans,
6 . 7 5 . 3 a n d 7 9 - 8 0 ; cf. 1 . 1 5 7 - 6 0 ) ; p e r j u r y (Glaucos,
6.86); v i o l a t i o n o f xenia ( A l e x a n d e r , 2.114
a n d 120; Spartans,
5.63.2,
9 0 . 1 , a n d 9 1 . 2 - 3 ) ; k i l l i n g o f relatives (Cambyses, 3 . 6 5 . 5 ) ; a n d m a l t r e a t m e n t o f the d e a d (Cambyses, 3 . 1 6 . 2 a n d 37.1). T h e
multiple
i m p i e t i e s o f the n o t o r i o u s l y i m p i o u s such as C a m b y s e s ( 3 . 1 6 , 2 7 - 3 0 , a n d 37-38.1) a n d Cleomenes ( 5 . 7 4 - 5 ; 6.75, c a n be e x p l a i n e d o n l y as 'madness'.
The
25.3,
7 9 - 8 2 , a n d 84)
c r i m e s , the p u n i s h m e n t s ,
a n d the n a t u r e o f i m p i e t y i n H e r o d o t u s are all c o n v e n t i o n a l l y G r e e k . For
a f e w f e a t u r e d figures i n his a c c o u n t , i n p a r t i c u l a r
X e r x e s , a n d Polycrates,
Herodotus
gives a r i c h e r , m o r e
explanation o f their misfortunes.13 H e
Croesus, dramatic
describes t h e i r b e h a v i o u r
in
terms o f atasthalia, hubris, a n d d i v i n e phthonos, concepts w h i c h are c o m m o n l y f o u n d i n epic, l y r i c , a n d early t r a g e d y b u t are a l i e n t o the language o f p o p u l a r , cultic r e l i g i o n w h i c h H e r o d o t u s m o s t c o m m o n l y e m p l o y s e l s e w h e r e . 1 4 X e r x e s ' signature i m p i e t y , f o r e x a m p l e , was the
11
On these cases see Gould (1989) 68-74; Lloyd-Jones (1983) 67 8; and de Ste Croix (1977) 140-3. See Mikalson (1983) 59-62 and (1991) 18 and 22 8. See also the discussion of these stories by Said, this volume (Ch. 6). For the distinction between popular religion and 'poetic' religion as found in Athenian tragedy, see Mikalson (1991). See also Fisher, this volume (Ch. 9). 12
13
14
194
JON D . MIKALSON
w h i p p i n g , c h a i n i n g , b r a n d i n g , a n d v e r b a l abuse o f the
Hellespont
after a s t o r m d e s t r o y e d his first b r i d g e : A great storm came up and pounded to pieces and broke the bridge. W h e n Xerxes heard o f it, he thought it a terrible thing and ordered that the Hellespont receive 300 blows from a whip and that a pair o f leg irons be cast into the sea. I have heard that he also sent tattooers to b r a n d the Hellespont. A n d he ordered that, as they did the whipping, they were to say these barbaric and rash (atasthala) words: 'Bitter water, y o u r master imposes on you this punishment because you treated h i m unjustly when you have suffered no injustice from h i m . K i n g Xerxes w i l l cross you whether you wish it or not. A n d justly no human being sacrifices to you because you are a foul and brackish river.' (7.34-35.2) T h i s is n o t s i m p l y a n o t h e r order a n d presented
impiety, but an impiety of a different
i n a different manner
f r o m the impieties
of
b u r n i n g sanctuaries a n d v i o l a t i n g a s y l u m . A
key w o r d is ' r a s h ' ,
an
inadequate translation o f atasthala, w h i c h suggests links to Themistocles' l a t e r c h a r a c t e r i z a t i o n o f X e r x e s (atasthalon, 8 . 1 0 9 . 3 above) i n reference
to t h e same i n c i d e n t a n d ,
more
broadly,
to the S u i t o r s
H o m e r ' s Odyssey ( e . g . , 2 3 . 6 7 ) , to H e s i o d ' s T i t a n s (Tk. haps
more
Aeschylus'
immediately Persae w h o
relevant,
to the Xerxes a n d
are beset b y ate a n d hubris?
3
of
209), a n d , p e r Persians
of
Aeschylus'
and
H e r o d o t u s ' versions o f t h e i n c i d e n t at t h e H e l l e s p o n t d i f f e r i n i m p o r t a n t ways, b u t b o t h m a k e this c r i t i c a l event, the b r i d g i n g o f E u r o p e a n d A s i a a n d t h e first a t t e m p t b y o n e m a n t o r u l e b o t h c o n t i n e n t s , i n t o a c o n d e m n a t i o n o f the m a n . B o t h t r e a t m e n t s are p o w e r f u l i n d i c t m e n t s o f t h e i m p i e t y a n d i r r a t i o n a l i t y o f X e r x e s , a n d b o t h are f r a m e d in language
a n d concepts
o f poetic literature, not o f popular
reli-
gious t r a d i t i o n s . B u t for H e r o d o t u s atasthalia, hubris, a n d divine phthonos, like t h e 'necessity' discussed e a r l i e r , are n o t , as f o r Aeschylus,
a the-
o l o g i c a l m a t r i x t h a t structures t h e w h o l e . H e r o d o t u s i n t r o d u c e s t h e m o n l y f o r a f e w l a r g e r t h a n life i n d i v i d u a l s to w h o m
he w a n t e d
to
give special t r e a t m e n t . Herodotus'
Histories is filled w i t h oracles, o m e n s , manteis, a n d
dreams,
a n d is t h e m o s t c o m p r e h e n s i v e a n d best single source for G r e e k d i v -
15
E.g., 96-100, 800-31, and 1005-7. For the link of atasthalia with hubris in Herodotus, see 3.80.3-4.
195
R E L I G I O N I N HERODOTUS
i n a t i o n i n the classical p e r i o d . 1 6 H i s
oracles, o m e n s ,
mantels, a n d
d r e a m s are s i m i l a r i n t h a t t h e y give m o r t a l s i n f o r m a t i o n o r at least indications o f w h a t lies i n the f u t u r e , b u t there are significant differences a m o n g t h e m . O n l y oracles have a n a m e d d i v i n e agent, like t h a t o f A p o l l o o f D e l p h i , w h o i n his sanctuary t h r o u g h his c u l t officials a n d rituals gives p r e d i c t i o n s i n his n a m e .
Prophecies
f r o m omens
and
d r e a m s m i g h t be c r e d i t e d to 'the gods' o r 'the d i v i n e ' (e.g., 6 . 2 7 . 1 - 3 , 7.12—18), b u t o f t e n i n v o l v e n o deity. For
omens
the l o c a t i o n
and
circumstances m i g h t offer a clue ( D e m e t e r near Eleusis? 8.65) as m i g h t the f o r m (Zeus f o r a l i g h t n i n g bolt? 4 . 7 9 . 2 ) , b u t even here we, not Herodotus,
m a k e the c o n n e c t i o n . T h e
different methods
of
d i v i n a t i o n also t r e a t d i f f e r e n t topics, w i t h o n l y rare o v e r l a p . O r a c l e s establish n e w
cults a n d r i t u a l s (e.g.,
H e r o d o t u s a t t r i b u t e s to o n l y one (2.49.2);
1 . 1 6 7 . 1 - 2 , 5.114), a n a c t i v i t y
mantis, the l e g e n d a r y
Melampus
oracles offer expiations a n d solutions f o r religious c r i m e s
(e.g., 1 . 1 9 - 2 2 , 6 . 1 3 2 - 6 ) , a n d o n l y t h e y c a n give d e t a i l e d i n s t r u c t i o n s t h a t m i g h t shape a society o r g o v e r n m e n t (e.g., 1.65, 4.161). Mantels a n d omens give i n f o r m a t i o n p r i m a r i l y a b o u t results o f p l a n n e d
and
c u r r e n t activities (e.g., 8 . 6 4 ; 9 . 3 6 - 8 ) , b u t oracles c a n c o m m a n d
new
a c t i o n as w e l l (e.g., 4 . 1 5 5 . 3 - 1 5 7 , 7 . 1 3 9 . 6 - 1 4 4 ) . O r a c l e s , mantels, a n d omens
usually give t i m e l y w a r n i n g s t h a t , i f h e e d e d ,
escape disaster, 1 7 b u t H e r o d o t u s '
a l l o w one
d r e a m s seem r a t h e r to
to
announce,
literally o r s y m b o l i c a l l y , a n inescapable f u t u r e (e.g., 1 . 3 4 - 4 5 ; 3 . 1 2 4 - 5 ) . M o s t i m p o r t a n t l y , v i r t u a l l y a l l oracles, o m e n s , mantels, a n d dreams prove accurate.18 Oracles i n particular m i g h t appear misleading a n d be so i n i t i a l l y , b u t i n the m o s t f l a g r a n t such cases H e r o d o t u s takes pains to have the recipients themselves u l t i m a t e l y a c k n o w l e d g e oracle's correctness (e.g., 1 . 9 1 . 4 - 6 , 6 . 7 6 . 1 a n d 80). M o d e r n
the
readers
a r e , o f course, d i s i n c l i n e d t o accept t h a t the m a j o r G r e e k i n s t r u m e n t s o f d i v i n a t i o n p r o v e d accurate o n a l l occasions, a n d to e x p l a i n t h e i r i n f a l l i b i l i t y i n t h e Histories m o s t assume t h a t H e r o d o t u s
16
chose
Harrison (2000b) 122-57, Crahay (1956), and Kirchberg (1965) treat specifically Herodotean oracles, and Frisch (1968) the dreams in the Histories. Individual Herodotean oracles are discussed in the fuller accounts of the Delphic oracle by Fontenrose (1978) and Parke and Wormell (1956). On the relationship of oracles to 'what has to happen' or 'what will happen' and on how individuals succeed or fail in their efforts in this regard, see Kirchberg (1965). Interpreters of oracles and dreams, whether Greek chresmologoi or Persian priests, however, are often in error. See, e.g., 1.128.2 and 7.142.3. 17
18
196
JON D . MIKALSON
to record only the successful instances or shaped or created occasions o f divination to make them appear successful. I myself do not accept that Herodotus created oracles or other instances o f divination out o f nothing, with no warrant from his sources. I rather think that the uniform success o f divination may be owed to two mutually supportive trends: the first, that the traditions from w h i c h Herodotus drew—some emanating from oracular sanctuaries—tended to 'remember' better the successful cases or to reinterpret problematic incidents retrospectively; and the second, that the poetic convention—most demonstrable in tragedy— that oracles, omens, mantels, and dreams always give the truth has affected Herodotus' narrative art. Both trends would lead to the same result. Since all oracles, omens, mantels, and dreams will prove true, those who ignore, forget, misinterpret, or reject them are, as i n tragedy, from that moment marked for destruction and suffering. A n d this fundamentally poetic feature is one o f Herodotus' favourite devices for foreshadowing and, i n some instances, for explaining the suffering of his historical figures, whether it be Croesus (1.34-45) or Xerxes (7.37 and 57-58.1), Polycrates (3.124-5) or Hipparchus (5.55-6). I t is then not surprising that in his account of the Greek victory over the Persians it is the Persians Xerxes and Mardonius who disregard or misinterpret 'signs' at critical moments (e.g., 7.37, 57—58.1; 8.114; 9.36-8, 41.4-43). 19
20
Herodotus occasionally delves into the early history of Greek religion, not systematically but i n response to parallels he finds i n foreign cultures. The details appear sporadically in the Histories but seem to derive from a single comprehensive and coherent view o f the beginnings o f Greek religion on mainland Greece. The pre-Greek Pelasgians there originally worshipped nameless gods through only sacrifice and prayer. These Pelasgians, with the encouragement of the oracle at Dodona, gave Egyptian names to their gods (2.50 and 52). O n their arrival the Greeks took over these Pelasgian gods with Egyptian names and themselves enriched their repertoire of worship by adopting the Egyptian practices o f giving to the gods altars, statues, temples, festivals, processions, and 'offering bringings' (prosago-
19 2
On the possible nature of these sources, see Evans (1991) 89-146. " Mikalson (1991) 87-114, 129, 207-8.
197
R E L I G I O N I N HERODOTUS
gias) (2.4.2 a n d 58). T h e Greeks also i m p o r t e d f r o m E g y p t the occasional n e w d e i t y o r names f o r n e w deities, n o t a b l y D i o n y s u s 145-6), Pan
(2.49,
( 2 . 1 4 5 - 6 ) , a n d H e r a c l e s ( 2 . 4 3 - 4 ) . A n d , j u s t 4 0 0 years
before Herodotus'
o w n t i m e , Hesiod and H o m e r 'created a divine
genealogy f o r G r e e k s , gave epithets t o t h e gods, d i s t r i b u t e d t h e i r "offices" a n d "crafts", and m a r k e d out their o u t w a r d
appearances'
(2.53). S u c h is o n l y the broadest o u t l i n e o f d e v e l o p m e n t s f o r w h i c h Herodotus
offers n u m e r o u s
and varied arguments and i m p o r t a n t
exceptions a n d nuances, b u t the outline shows that H e r o d o t u s accounts f o r , r i g h t l y o r w r o n g l y , m a j o r features o f G r e e k r e l i g i o n as i t was p r a c t i s e d i n his o w n t i m e . H e r o d o t u s ' interest i n r e l i g i o u s t o p i c s , o f course, ranges f a r b e y o n d G r e e k r e l i g i o n . S t a n d a r d features o f his m a n y e t h n o l o g i c a l surveys o f n o n - G r e e k peoples are descriptions o f the gods they w o r s h i p p e d , t h e i r m a j o r sanctuaries, a n d u n u s u a l cultic o r b u r i a l practices, a l l usually n o t e d because o f their variance f r o m the Greek. T h e
Ethiopians
at M e r o e , f o r e x a m p l e , w o r s h i p p e d o n l y Zeus a n d D i o n y s u s (2.29.7), the T h r a c i a n s
only Dionysus,
Artemis,
a n d A r e s (5.7).
Herodotus
lingers l o n g o n a d e s c r i p t i o n o f t h e c o m p l e x s a n c t u a r y o f Zeus Belos at B a b y l o n
(1.181—3). H e
describes at some
length the
un-Greek
practices o f t h e Persians, t h a t t h e y ' d o n o t have t h e c u s t o m o f erecti n g statues a n d temples a n d altars. . . . T h e y d o n o t m a k e altars o r l i g h t fires w h e n t h e y i n t e n d to sacrifice, a n d t h e y d o n o t use l i b a tions, a flute, garlands, o r barley-corns' ( 1 . 1 3 1 - 1 3 2 . 1 ) . T h e
Massagetai,
he tells us, s a c r i f i c e d a n d ate t h e i r e l d e r l y ( 1 . 2 1 6 . 2 - 3 ) , a n d
the
Issedones ate a l l b u t the heads o f t h e i r d e a d m a l e relatives (4.26). For
the Persians a n d the E g y p t i a n s i t was u n h o l y to c r e m a t e the
dead. T o
t h e Persians
fire
was a g o d , a n d i t was n o t j u s t to give
the corpse o f a h u m a n b e i n g to a g o d . T o
the E g y p t i a n s fire was
a l i v i n g creature w h i c h w o u l d die i f i t c o n s u m e d h u m a n flesh (3.16.3). Herodotus
offers dozens o f such r e l i g i o u s practices o f
non-Greeks,
b u t o n l y r a r e l y , as i n o u r last e x a m p l e , puts t h e m i n t o the c o n t e x t o f t h a t society's system o f religious beliefs. 2 1 T h i s is p a r t i c u l a r l y a p p a r ent i n his l o n g a c c o u n t (nearly 3 0 chapters) o f the E g y p t i a n gods, w h e r e he w r i t e s m u c h o f t h e i r n a m e s , t h e i r sanctuaries, a n d t h e i r festivals, b u t a l m o s t n o t h i n g o f w h a t the E g y p t i a n s believed t h e i r
On this, see Gould (1994) and Burkert (1990).
198
JON D . MIKALSON
gods did (in a cultic sense) or had done (in mythological terms). Herodotus warns us that this will be so i n his account of Egypt (2.3.2 and 65.2), but i t seems his general inclination, no doubt increased by difficulties o f language and sources, when he deals with foreign peoples. Herodotus likewise does not describe, a la Homer, the Greek gods 'in action', but that certainly should not lead us to conclude that he therefore thought the gods did not contribute to Greek life or to the Greek effort against the Persians. I n his Histories Herodotus employed cultic rather than poetic thought, with prayers, vows, and sacrifices directed to the gods to achieve a given purpose, and, after that purpose was accomplished, with memorials and expressions o f gratitude through dedications. W i t h the exception o f the occasional storm or phantom, the Greek worshipper and historian could not determine what specific actions the divinity had taken, but the success itself was the answer to prayers and sacrifices, and that success was then to be marked by a gift to the gods. I t is this popular, cultic thought that can be traced throughout Herodotus' Histories, with, as we have seen, the occasional admixture o f elements from the poetic tradition.
CHAPTER N I N E POPULAR MORALITY IN Nick
HERODOTUS
Fisher
Introduction: footychides and Glaucus, Croesus and Solon I n Book Six, Herodotus
describes h o w , s h o r t l y before D a r i u s '
inva-
sion o f m a i n l a n d G r e e c e , K i n g L e o t y c h i d e s of" S p a r t a sought t o p e r suade t h e A t h e n i a n s t o s u r r e n d e r t e n A e g i n e t a n hostages w h o m he a n d t h e n o w disgraced K i n g
C l e o m e n e s h a d left w i t h t h e m . H i s
r h e t o r i c a l strategy was t o tell a s t o r y w i t h a s t r o n g m o r a l : 1 a S p a r t a n c a l l e d G l a u c u s , w i t h a n e x c e p t i o n a l r e p u t a t i o n f o r j u s t i c e , agreed t o h o l d o n t r u s t a large s u m o f m o n e y rized
from a Milesian, b u t tempo-
w h e n asked f o r its r e t u r n b y his sons, a n d e n q u i r e d o f A p o l l o ' s
oracle a t D e l p h i w h e t h e r he m i g h t p e r j u r e h i m s e l f i n o r d e r t o keep the m o n e y . T h e oracle responded t h a t even i f Glaucus h i m s e l f p r o f i t e d f r o m his p e r j u r y , his descendants w o u l d p a y i n t h e e n d . G l a u c u s i m m e d i a t e l y asked f o r forgiveness f o r even asking the q u e s t i o n o f the g o d , a n d r e t u r n e d the m o n e y ; b u t the priestess' p r o m i s e t h a t i t was t o o late w a s f u l f i l l e d . G l a u c u s h a d n o descendant o r h e a r t h left i n S p a r t a , a n d his f a m i l y was w i p e d o u t r o o t a n d b r a n c h , so t h a t t h e m o r a l was t h a t ' i t is g o o d n o t even t o c o n t e m p l a t e a n y o t h e r course c o n c e r n i n g a n e n t r u s t e d p r o p e r t y (paratheke) t h a n t o r e t u r n i t w h e n i t is d e m a n d e d ' A
number
Herodotean
(6.86).
o f p o i n t s arise f r o m this c h a r a c t e r i s t i c e x a m p l e
of
s t o r y t e l l i n g . C e n t r a l t o j u s t i c e a n d g o o d b e h a v i o u r are
k e e p i n g one's w o r d , r e t u r n i n g objects o n t r u s t , a n d n o t s w e a r i n g falsely b y t h e gods; a p r i m a r y s a n c t i o n f o r observance o f m o r a l p r i n ciples was t h e fear o f p u n i s h m e n t f r o m t h e gods, w h i c h m i g h t p r e serve its c r e d i b i l i t y b y t h e a r g u m e n t t h a t i t o f t e n o p e r a t e d over a
1
Herodotus is of course following Homeric models in employing this technique of argument by lengthy storytelling (see also de Jong, this volume, pp. 262-3). Its application to political debates would have already seemed archaic to Thucydides: see e.g., Gould (1989) 40-1. On Herodotus' moralizing use of Greek and Eastern folk-tale motifs, see esp. Aly (1921), Murray (1987), Pelling (1996), Griffiths (1999).
200
NICK FISHER
v e r y l o n g time-scale; a n d the D e l p h i c o r a c l e , as A p o l l o ' s m o u t h p i e c e , was t h o u g h t to have a role i n u p h o l d i n g such basic m o r a l tenets. 2 H o w e v e r , the i m p r e s s i o n the passage m a y give o f a s i m p l e m o r a l i z i n g designed t o have a s t r a i g h t f o r w a r d effect o n its hearers readers is p a r t i a l l y u n d e r m i n e d b y the b r o a d e r context. T h e
or
Athenians
p a y the story n o a t t e n t i o n , a n d the i m p r e s s i o n is given t h a t t h e y a l r e a d y r e g a r d i t as a n o l d - f a s h i o n e d r h e t o r i c a l strategy.' does n o t c o m m e n t here t h a t the A t h e n i a n s
Herodotus
suffered later f o r t h e i r
refusal to c o m p l y o n g r o u n d s o f p o l i t i c a l e x p e d i e n c y i n r e l a t i o n to t h e i r q u a r r e l w i t h A e g i n a ; b u t , as we shall see, h i n t s o f such f u t u r e p r o b l e m s f o r A t h e n s d o exist. 4 H e r o d o t u s
has also, n o t l o n g b e f o r e ,
revealed t h a t Leotychides was later to y i e l d to t e m p t a t i o n , m o r e d e c i sively t h a n G l a u c u s , a n d was exiled after b e i n g discovered s u r r o u n d e d b y b r i b e s ; his house was d e m o l i s h e d ( 6 . 7 2 ) . ° Herodotus'
text is f u l l o f events, speeches, a n d n a r r a t o r i a l c o m -
m e n t s w h i c h o f f e r j u d g m e n t s i n t e r m s o f g e n e r a l l y accepted G r e e k m o r a l p r i n c i p l e s , a n d o f r e t r i b u t i o n d e l i v e r e d to those w h o against t h e m .
6
The
offend
i n t e r n a l coherence o f these p r i n c i p l e s , h o w e v e r ,
the i n e v i t a b i l i t y w i t h w h i c h H e r o d o t u s
supposes t h e y are u p h e l d b y
d i v i n e p o w e r s , t h e extent to w h i c h h u m a n r e t a l i a t i o n i n response to m o r a l o u t r a g e c a n be p r o b l e m a t i c i n itself, a n d the i m p o r t a n c e
of
such m o r a l ideas i n his o v e r a l l p a t t e r n s o f e x p l a n a t i o n , are all the subject o f m u c h debate a m o n g his m o d e r n i n t e r p r e t e r s . T h i s
chap-
ter discusses a selection o f cases w h i c h raise such general p r o b l e m s . I
shall suggest t h a t the h i s t o r i a n is i n d e e d c e n t r a l l y c o n c e r n e d
to
e x p l o r e m a j o r issues such as d i v i n e p u n i s h m e n t f o r i n j u s t i c e , excessive revenge o r o v e r c o n f i d e n c e i n p r o s p e r i t y , o r the contrast b e t w e e n t y r a n n i c a l a n d l u x u r i o u s E a s t e r n E m p i r e s a n d leaner, f r e e d o m - l o v i n g G r e e k states; b u t t h a t w e d o n o t find simple o r consistent messages o r contrasts, b u t r a t h e r a subtle a n d
2
flexible
set o f i n t e r c o n n e c t e d
On which see the minimalist account of Davies (1997); on the Glaucus story, also Immerwahr (1966) 213-15, Harrison (2000b) 117-19. See also Missiou (1998), arguing that the Athenians are presented consistently in Herodotus and Thueydides as less responsive to arguments from reciprocity. See esp. Immerwahr (1966) 214-18, Fornara (1971a) 80-6, Momigliano (1979) 148-9, Konstan (1987) 72-3, Raaflaub (1987), Moles (1996), Harrison (2000b) 117-18. - On this further penalty, Connor (1985), esp. 199. Leotychides, like Cleomenes, is in Herodotus' view (6.84) paying the penalty for the manipulation of the deposition of Demaratus; see Boedeker (1987) 190-1. E.g., Pohlenz (1937) 91-5, Immerwahr (1966) 308-9. 3
4
1
6
201
POPULAR M O R A L I T Y I N HERODOTUS
themes,
h i n t s , a n d e x p l a n a t i o n s , w h i c h are d e l i v e r e d v a r i o u s l y i n
speeches, i n n a r r a t o r i a l c o m m e n t s , a n d b y the t h e m a t i c o r g a n i z a t i o n o f his m a t e r i a l . ' I shall also occasionally consider the e q u a l l y fascin a t i n g q u e s t i o n o f h o w f a r H e r o d o t u s is d r a w n b y his e t h n o g r a p h i c analyses o f the m o r a l i t i e s o f o t h e r peoples to cast d o u b t o n those o f his
own. V e r y close to the start o f t h e Histories is p l a c e d the e n i g m a t i c c o n -
v e r s a t i o n b e t w e e n the L y d i a n K i n g Croesus a n d the A t h e n i a n legal r e f o r m e r a n d p o e t S o l o n (1.29—34).8 T h e
c o n v e r s a t i o n establishes a
n u m b e r o f basic values w h i c h resonate p o w e r f u l l y t h r o u g h the rest o f the w o r k . 9 T h e
issue b e t w e e n S o l o n a n d Croesus concerns w h a t
i t takes f o r h u m a n happiness; S o l o n rejects the i d e a t h a t great w e a l t h a n d p r o s p e r i t y (here c a l l e d eudaimonie) c a n be e n o u g h i n themselves to call a m a n ' h a p p y ' (olbios). H i s p r i m a r y reason is t h a t life is u n p r e d i c t a b l e a n d changeable
( ' e v e r y t h i n g is c h a n c e ' ) , a n d the d i v i n e is
a l t o g e t h e r j e a l o u s a n d d i s r u p t i v e (phthoneron a n d tarakhodes); hence one c a n n o t j u d g e a m a n h a p p y u n t i l he has d i e d a g o o d d e a t h , r e c o g n i z e d b y his c o m m u n i t y , This
w h i l e still e n j o y i n g m o d e r a t e
establishes at t h e s t a r t t w o f u n d a m e n t a l
prosperity.
themes w h i c h
t h r o u g h the w o r k . First there is a c o n t r a s t b e t w e e n the
run
over-valua-
t i o n o f w e a l t h , l u x u r y , a n d p o w e r , w h i c h is associated above a l l , b u t n o t exclusively, w i t h a succession o f Eastern kings, a n d the t o u g h ness a n d austerity o f o t h e r peoples, such as, f o r e x a m p l e , the Persians w e r e o r i g i n a l l y , a n d the Greeks s h o w e d themselves still to be at the t i m e o f the Persian W a r s .
Second,
there is a f u n d a m e n t a l
aware-
ness, w h i c h is f o u n d t h r o u g h o u t G r e e k literature f r o m H o m e r onwards, o f the u n c e r t a i n t y o f h u m a n
life a n d the u n p r e d i c t a b i l i t y o f the
d i v i n e , a n d c o n c o m i t a n d y , a persistent c o n t r a s t b e t w e e n those whose
' For complexities of modes of suggestions and viewpoints in the Histories, see, e.g., Marincola (1987), Boedeker (1987), Dewald (1987), Gould (1989) 78-81. On the chronological problems and doubtful historicity of this conversation, see, e.g., Duplouy (1999). On Solon and Croesus, see also Chs. 6 and 7 in this volume. See also 1.27, 1.29 and 6.125 for other 'sophists' and aristocrats who allegedly visited the Lydian court, in these cases with an eye on its riches, thus subverting the contrast between Eastern wealth and Greek contentment with austerity: see, e.g., Konstan (1987) 70-2, Pelling (1997b) 4. On the Croesus-Solon meeting, and the figure of Solon as a 'Herodotean' wise man providing a philosophical and moral framework for much of the Histories, see e.g., Regenbogen (1961) 80-2, Lattimore (1939) 30-1, Immerwahr (1966) 154-61, Fornara (1971a) 18-21, Stahl (1975), Raaflaub (1987) 248, and the most recent discussions by Shapiro (1996) and Harrison (2000b) 38-41. 8
9
202
N I C K FISHER
acts reveal this awareness,
a n d those, especially the p o w e r f u l ,
who
c o m e to g r i e f i n p a r t t h r o u g h t h e i r f a i l u r e to take this i n t o a c c o u n t .
Principles of Community, Family and Sexual Morality The Herodotean
Solon's e l a b o r a t i o n o f lives to w h i c h he w i l l ascribe
the c o v e t e d l a b e l 'olbios' reveals f u r t h e r f u n d a m e n t a l m o r a l
values
l i n k e d closely to t r a d i t i o n a l G r e e k t h i n k i n g (not least, ideas t o be f o u n d i n w h a t r e m a i n s o f the r e a l Solon's p o e t r y ) . 1 0 First place goes to the A t h e n i a n
Tellus. He
d i e d g l o r i o u s l y i n the most t r a d i t i o n a l
sense, p l a y i n g a decisive r o l e i n r o u t i n g the e n e m y i n a b o r d e r w a r at Eleusis, a n d r e c e i v i n g a p u b l i c b u r i a l a n d great h o n o u r s . "
Warfare
f o r H e r o d o t u s , as f o r H o m e r , A e s c h y l u s , o r T h u c y d i d e s , is p r e s e n t e d a m b i v a l e n t l y . 1 2 I t o f t e n appears as a r e g r e t t a b l e fact o f life w h i c h n o sane p e r s o n w o u l d w e l c o m e .
I n his o w n v o i c e , he c o m m e n d s
the
A t h e n i a n d e t e r m i n a t i o n to value u n i t y a m o n g the allies over disputes over the h e g e m o n y ,
as l o n g as the m a i n Persian t h r e a t c o n t i n u e d ,
a n d adds the t r a d i t i o n a l m o r a l t h a t ' i n t e r n a l stasis is as m u c h w o r s e t h a n w a r w a g e d b y a h a r m o n i o u s g r o u p as w a r is worse t h a n peace' ( 8 . 2 - 3 ) ; 1 3 the start o f the I o n i a n R e v o l t is signalled w i t h the o m i n o u s , H o m e r i c , r e m a r k t h a t i t was 'the b e g i n n i n g o f evils f o r Greeks and barbarians' (5.97).14
Croesus h i m s e l f , after his defeat at G y r u s '
h a n d s , becomes m o r e a w a r e o f t h e h o r r o r s o f w a r , a n d denies, i m p l a u s i b l y , his o w n r e s p o n s i b i l i t y f o r s t a r t i n g one: o n l y fools start w a r s , i n w h i c h fathers b u r y t h e i r sons (1.87). B u t the o p e n i n g o f his Histories (1.1)
10
also recalls the epic w i t h the
See esp. Chiasson (1986). Most probably Herodotus was referring to a battle at Eleusis in the war between Athens and neighbouring Megara (see e.g., Asheri ad loc). Tellus' name seems to carry the implication of 'fulfilment', whether or not it was his real name; Immerwahr (1966) 156-7. On this, see Cobet (1986). On stasis in Herodotus, see also Fisher (2000) 103-6. Herodotus' next comment, on how the Athenians seized the opportunity to take the leadership of the Greek forces, which led directly to the Dehan League, on the excuse of the alleged outrageous behaviour (hubris) of Pausanias the Regent, suggests his awareness of the charges brought against Athens of serious disruption of the Greek world after 479 (cf. also 6.98.2). See esp. Konstan (1987) 72-3, Raaflaub (1987) 237-9, Moles (1996). Pelling (1997b), with modifications in Gould (1989) 117-20. '-' Homer, Iliad 5.63, 11.603, Cobet (1986)' 7-8. See also Ch. 14, note 58 and Ch. 24 in this volume. 11
12
13
203
POPULAR M O R A L I T Y I N HERODOTUS
emphasis o n the f a m e (kleos) t h r o u g h w h i c h the a c h i e v e m e n t s o f i n d i viduals a n d states deserve to be r e m e m b e r e d ; this f a m e f o r H e r o d o t u s as f o r H o m e r is w o n above a l l t h r o u g h w a r f a r e . I n H e r o d o t u s ' battle a c c o u n t s , as i n those i n the Iliad, b o t h h e r o i s m a n d b r u t a l i t y are strongly present.15 T h e
m o r e e g a l i t a r i a n ideologies o f h o p l i t e a n d
n a v a l w a r f a r e m a y have restricted the p r e s e n t a t i o n o f i n d i v i d u a l deeds o f exceptional valour, of dreadful h o r r o r , or other remarkable occurrences o n the b a t t l e f i e l d ; b u t they are b y n o means e x c l u d e d a l t o g e t h e r . 1 0 T h e readiness to f i g h t bravely a n d to die f o r one's c o m m u n i t y as p a r t o f G r e e k (male) i d e o l o g y is a constant t h e m e , as is H e r o d o t u s ' interest i n p r e s e n t i n g his o w n a n d o t h e r people's c h a r a c t e r i z a t i o n s o f the collective c o u r a g e o r l a c k o f i t o f d i f f e r e n t g r o u p s , b o t h G r e e k a n d n o n - G r e e k . Arete, t h e m o s t g e n e r a l t e r m i n G r e e k f o r goodness
o r v i r t u e ( a n d used i n t h a t b r o a d sense e . g . , at
7 . 2 3 7 ) , " is used i n m a n y instances (16) b y H e r o d o t u s
(as b y
human 1.134, many
o t h e r authors) specifically o f the m i l i t a r y prowess o r the display o f bravery i n war.18 Especially n o t e w o r t h y is the c o n t r a s t b e t w e e n t w o Persian debates: at 3 . 1 2 0 , t w o Persian satraps O r o e t e s a n d M i t r o b a t e s h a d a v i o l e n t a r g u m e n t ' c o n t e s t i n g over arete', i n w h i c h M i t r o b a t e s q u e s t i o n e d t h e o t h e r ' s c l a i m to be i n t h e lists o f ' m e n ' , because he h a d f a i l e d to a d d to t h e king's possessions, a n d i n p a r t i c u l a r h a d neglected to c o n q u e r t h e soft t o u c h o f the i s l a n d o f Samos. O n
the o t h e r h a n d after
the b a t t l e o f A r t e m i s i o n , t h e Persians l e a r n t t h a t t h e Greeks w e r e c e l e b r a t i n g the O l y m p i c games, w i t h t h e i r prizes o f olive-leaf w r e a t h s . T r i t a n t a e c h m e s , the son o f A r t a b a n u s ( X e r x e s ' c o u s i n a n d the m a n
13
For all this, see Gould (1989) 60 2, and Chs. 1 and 5 in this volume. See e.g., 6.114, 117 (Marathon), 7.180-2 (Artemision), 7.224 7 (Thermopylae), 8.92-5 (Salamis) and 9.64-75 (Plataea). In the last example, notice the minor details at 9.75 of the subsequent death ('proving himself a good man', andra genomenon agatlum) of the great Athenian warrior Sophanes of Decelea, fighting as joint commander with Leagrus against the Edonians in Thrace (in the mid 460s? cf. Thuc. 1.100.3); he died 'fighting over the gold mines at Daton', which seems to be a further typically brief yet pointed allusion to the greed which the Athenians displayed immediately after the Persian invasions. Or even more broadly, e.g., of quality of textiles at 3.106, or of land at 4.198, 7.5, 8.144. See Immerwahr (1966) 309-10. See 1.176 (Lydians of Xanthus), 5.49 (Spartans), 7.102 (attributed by Demaratus, to Greeks generally, and especially Spartans), 7.154 (Gelon), 7.181 (Aeginetans), 7.225-6 (Spartans and Thespians), 8.1 (Plataeans), 8.92, 9.21, 9.28 (Tegeates), 9.40 (Persian and Mede cavalry), 9.70 and 71 (the skill and courage of the Athenians and the Spartans at Plataea). 16
17
18
204
NICK FISHER
who had advised Xerxes against the expedition, as stated at 7.82) expressed his surprise at their enemies, men who competed in such games 'not for money . . . but for arete' (8.26). Arete here seems to indicate both the prize—a honorific crown—offered at the games for the exercise o f competitive skill and valour, and the valour itself, in that the implication o f the admiration is that Greek free citizens and warriors will risk danger and even death for the sake o f proving themselves real m e n . Elsewhere too there is a marked contrast between the Greeks' courage, stemming from their love o f freedom, and the Persians and their subjects, rewarded by money or material gifts, and compelled to fight rather through fear o f the K i n g and the whip (e.g., the debate between Xerxes and Demaratus). I n fact, however, despite this ideology, great financial rewards as well as honours from their own cities were often available to the victors at the Panhellenic games, and athletic victors at the local city games could enjoy substantial prizes (see Y o u n g (1984)). Herodotus may well expect readers to take this point, as i n many other instances he seems concerned to warn Greek readers by deconstructing over-easy contrasts between the peoples on these issues. M o r e serious recognition that individual Greeks and (democratic) states could be strongly influenced by desire for money rather than honour and virtue may be seen i n the consistent presentation of Themistocles (esp. 8.109-12, see also below p. 224), and the success Aristagoras achieved, i n part by emphasizing the wealth to be gained, i n inducing the Athenians to aid the Ionian revolt (5.95). 19
20
4'ellus deserved to be called happy also because the continuity o f his line was assured with flourishing sons and grandsons (as opposed to the uprooted hearth o f Glaucus); the achievement of those w h o m Solon placed second i n happiness, the Argive young men Cleobis and Biton, was to use their strength to satisfy their mother's wish to play her part i n the festival o f Hera, which led to their deaths. 21
19
See on this passage esp. Konstan (1987) 61-3, von Reden (1995) 98-9. On its connection with the third deceitful dream, of the olive crown, which encouraged Xerxes to take his decision, Köhnken (1988) 32-4. 7.101-4; 7.209-10, 7.234; on Persian use of the whip, also 3.16, 3.157, 7.22, 7.54, 7.56, 7.223. See e.g., Konstan (1987) 64-5, Lateiner (1987) 91-3. See on this example also Lloyd (1987) and Shapiro (1996) 351. They are placed second to Tellus, because their lives were less complete and they had no children; nonetheless they died a noble death just after demonstrating spectacularly an important element of aretê. 2,1
21
POPULAR M O R A L I T Y I N HERODOTUS
205
H o n o u r i n g one's close f a m i l y , a n d e x p e c t i n g g o o d a n d g r a t e f u l t r e a t m e n t i n r e t u r n , w e r e p r i n c i p l e s h e l d deeply b y the Greeks as b y m o s t peoples; they are f u l l y r e c o g n i z e d i n H e r o d o t u s ' h i s t o r y , b o t h i n o b s e r v i n g spectacular examples o f g o o d a n d ( m o r e usually) b a d p r a c t i c e i n stories o f G r e e k a n d Eastern f a m i l i e s , a n d i n n o t i n g v a r i ations o n these themes o f f a m i l y r e l a t i o n s h i p s , values, a n d structures i n his e t h n o g r a p h y . 2 2 T h e d e a t h o f one's first o r f a v o u r i t e son is thus one o f the w o r s t tragedies w h i c h c a n b e f a l l o n e . Croesus' first p u n i s h m e n t , a p p a r e n t l y because o f ' i n d i g n a t i o n ' (nemesis) o f the ' d i v i n e ' a t his c o n f i d e n c e i n his o w n p r o s p e r i t y (see b e l o w p . 218), was t h e loss o f his o n l y fit son A t y s , k i l l e d b y his f r i e n d A d r a s t u s i n the t e r r i b l e h u n t i n g a c c i d e n t (1.34—8). 23 T h e
story fits G r e e k tragic p a t t e r n s a l l too n e a t l y ,
a n d the names o f the characters are also a l l t o o a p p r o p r i a t e : A t y s is
first
a n a n c i e n t L y d i a n n a m e (1.7), second recalls t h e d o o m e d
y o u n g g o d o f the East, A t y s o r A t t i s , a n d t h i r d echoes the
Greek
c o n c e p t (ate) w h i c h spans d e l u s i o n , e r r o r , a n d disaster, w h i l e Adrastus recalls Adrasteia, a G r e e k t e r m for the p e r s o n i f i c a t i o n o f Fate. 2 4 H e n c e it is generally agreed t h a t H e r o d o t u s o r his G r e e k sources have d e v e l o p e d a m o r a l tale a c c o r d i n g t o established G r e e k m y t h i c a l p a t t e r n s , t o emphasize the h o r r o r o f the loss o f Croesus' g o o d son, even before he lost his k i n g d o m . 2 5 A t t e m p t s b y grandees o f the Persian e m p i r e to p r o t e c t t h e i r sons
22
See also in general on the closeness and tensions of father and son relationships, Dover (1974) 273-8, Blundell (1989) 40-2, and see also Herodotus 3.50.2, with van der Veen (1996) 24-5. On the story see Stahl (1975) and Konstan (1987) 64; as Kxmstan observes, Croesus' over-protective fear for his son shows an over-valuation of life as opposed to the display of arete, contrary to the views of 'Solon'. This Adrastus was allegedly a descendant of Midas the famous king of Phrygia (1.35, 46); conceivably Herodotus hints at a long-standing guilt in this royal family, comparable to that begun in the Lydian house by Gyges (cf. also 1.14, another connection between Midas and Gyges), which might mitigate the apparent injustice somewhat here too. On the names, Immerwahr (1966) 157-8. On the theme of two sons, one fit, who is killed, and one defective, see also Harrison (2000b) 40-1. See also Fornara (1999) 34 6 and Ch. 6 in this volume. There is also the interesting case of Ameinocles of Magnesia (7.190); he became suddenly extremely rich by windfall discoveries of Persian treasure, but, like so many others in Herodotus, was not fortunate in all respects, because 'he too was affected by a distressing, unreciprocal, child-killing accident'. In this case at least, i f the disaster was the result of divine envy or nemesis, there is no sign of any specific fault, but rather the idea that no mortal can expect or deserve uninterrupted good fortune—the disaster was explicitly akharis, not in recompense for anything. Does the 'too' here (kai) mean 'like Croesus'? 23
24
25
206
NICK
FISHER
p r o d u c e d f u r t h e r disastrous consequences. T w o d o t i n g fathers i n successive g e n e r a t i o n s each t r i e d to save a son f r o m the against Scythia
campaigns
a n d Greece respectively, to f i n d each k i n g , p r e v i -
ously generous, r e s p o n d w i t h ruthless c r u e l t y : O e o b a z u s ' t h r e e sons h a d t h e i r t h r o a t s c u t o n D a r i u s ' o r d e r s , a n d X e r x e s h a d his a r m y m a r c h t h r o u g h the d i v i d e d halves o f the eldest son o f P y t h i u s , o f Atys, o f Lydia (4.84, 7 . 2 6 - 9 , 3 8 - 4 0 ) . t h e r associations, as this Pythius descendant,
a n d hence
26
The
son
second case has f u r -
m u s t be supposed to be
the f a m i l y was still g r i p p e d b y
Croesus' disaster.27
O t h e r stories b u i l t o n the closeness o f the f a t h e r - s o n r e l a t i o n s h i p a n d the h o r r o r s o f revenges w h i c h target i t are the s e r v i n g o f H a r p a g o s ' c h i l d r e n to h i m b y Astyages ( 1 . 1 1 7 - 1 9 ) a n d the e n f o r c e d emasculat i o n i m p o s e d o n the e u n u c h m a k e r P a n i o n i u s a n d his f o u r sons b y Hermotimus
(8.104—6; see also b e l o w p .
215).
E q u a l l y d r e a d f u l m i g h t be the b r e a k d o w n
o f relations
between
father a n d s o n . 2 8 W h a t e v e r h i s t o r i c a l basis m a y u n d e r l i e the stories c o n c e r n i n g the h o s t i l i t y b e t w e e n P e r i a n d e r
o f C o r i n t h a n d his son
has b e e n r a d i c a l l y t r a n s f o r m e d to fit m y t h i c a l p a t t e r n s a n d The
complex
sequence
themes.
o f events i n v o l v i n g these i n d i v i d u a l s ,
C o r i n t h ' s relations w i t h C o r c y r a
and
a n d S a m o s , was m o d e l l e d o n i n i -
t i a t o r y rites a n d c u l t practices; t h e y also d i s p l a y a n a p p r o p r i a t e p u n i s h m e n t f o r a b r u t a l G r e e k t y r a n t , w h o was supposedly g u i l t y o f the m u r d e r o f his w i f e a n d n e c r o p h i l i a w i t h h e r b o d y . H e lost the love a n d s u p p o r t o f his s o n , 2 9 a n d t h e n , w h e n he was a b o u t to be reco n c i l e d , saw h i m f o u l l y k i l l e d
(3.44-53).30
A s a n e t h n o g r a p h e r H e r o d o t u s is especially alive to the i m p o r t a n c e f o r social s t a b i l i t y o f a r r a n g e m e n t s f o r r e p r o d u c t i o n a n d the c o n t r o l o f sexuality, a n d to the v a r i e t y o f means d i f f e r e n t c o m m u n i t i e s have a d o p t e d f o r a c h i e v i n g t h i s . 3 1 H i s sense o f w o n d e r at the alleged cust o m s o f the m o r e 'savage' peoples o f the Balkans, C e n t r a l A s i a ,
and
N o r t h A f r i c a , a n d his schematic e x a g g e r a t i o n o f such customs based
26
Underlying this treatment may be a Persian purification ritual tradition: Evans (1988). On these associations, see Lewis (1998). For such themes in tragedy, cf. Belfiore (2000) and Ch. 6 in this volume. As with Croesus, his other son was not an adequate replacement, being rather stupid (3.53). See Sourvinou-Inwood (1991) 244-84, Gould (1989) 51-3 and Chs. 5 and 6 in this volume. See esp. Hartog (1988), Rossellini and Said (1978), Redfield (1985), Cartledge (1990), and Ch. 20 in this volume. 27
23
29
30
31
207
POPULAR M O R A L I T Y I N HERODOTUS
o n g e o g r a p h i c a l distance f r o m the G r e e k w o r l d , are n a t u r a l l y m a p p e d against G r e e k n o r m s ; so is his p o r t r a y a l o f the exotic jealousies a n d b r u t a l i t i e s at t h e courts o f his Eastern kings. S u c h n o r m s i n c l u d e monogamy,
t h e p r o t e c t i o n o f c i t i z e n w o m e n , legal penalties f o r those
w h o d i s r u p t m a r r i a g e s , a n d m o d i f i e d t o l e r a n c e f o r the m a l e use o f p r o s t i t u t e s , courtesans, a n d , w i t h i n c e r t a i n r e s t r i c t i o n s , e n g a g e m e n t i n h o m o s e x u a l , especially p é d é r a s t i e , r e l a t i o n s h i p s . : w H e r o d o t u s ' presentation o f alternatives t o these n o r m s c a n n o n e t h e less be r e m a r k a b l y diverse a n d o p e n - m i n d e d . 3 3 Some m o r e cultures (at the g e o g r a p h i c a l extremities) are a p p a r e n t l y
extreme dismissed
f a i r l y r a p i d l y f o r p e r m i t t i n g (e.g.) r a n d o m c o p u l a t i o n i n p u b l i c like animals (1.203, 3 . 1 0 1 , 4.180), b u t t h r o u g h most o f the ethnographic sections, h e is as o f t e n c o n c e r n e d t o a t t e m p t t o e x p l a i n t h e c o h e r ence a n d r e g u l a r i t y o f the practices a n d t h e i r c o n t r i b u t i o n t o t h e o v e r a l l s t a b i l i t y o f t h e p e o p l e . 3 4 A g o o d e x a m p l e is p r o v i d e d b y his t r e a t m e n t o f a p p a r e n t l y b i z a r r e customs o f m a r r i a g e auctions a n d sacred p r o s t i t u t i o n a m o n g the B a b y l o n i a n s . 3 ' I t is also n o t a b l e h o w f a r H e r o d o t u s
is f r o m s i m p l e appeals to
t r a d i t i o n a l G r e e k m a l e fear o f p o w e r f u l w o m e n ,
individual or col-
lective. T h e t r a d i t i o n a l representatives o f female p o w e r , the A m a z o n s , a p p e a r , b u t t h e story w h i c h develops, t h e origins o f the S a u r o m a t a e f r o m the a m u s i n g l y described u n i o n s o f f u g i t i v e A m a z o n s a n d y o u n g Scythians, emphasizes
h o w t h e r e s u l t i n g society a c h i e v e d a h a r m o -
nious c o m b i n a t i o n o f t h e t w o c u l t u r a l t r a d i t i o n s , a n d allows f o r t h e p r e s e r v a t i o n o f some degree o f A m a z o n i a n female w a r r i o r customs ( w h i c h m a y reflect some g e n u i n e features o f S a r m a t i a n c u l t u r e ) . 3 b I n d i v i d u a l w o m e n , w h e t h e r a t t h e Persian c o u r t , i n t h e G r e e k w o r l d , o r even
i n 'savage'
c u l t u r e s , t y p i c a l l y d e f e n d , o f t e n i n devious o r
m a n i p u l a t i v e ways, the values o f t h e i r d i f f e r e n t societies; a n d o n occasions such p o w e r f u l w o m e n c a n m a t c h m e n i n b r u t a l acts o f sexual j e a l o u s y o r revenge. the Massagetai
32
P r i m e examples
(1.211-14), Pheretime
are t h e stories o f T o m y r i s
of
o f C y r e n e ( 4 . 2 0 5 , see b e l o w
See, e.g., Dover (1974) 205 16, (1978) passim, Winkler (1990), Cohen (1991). Rosselini and Said (1978), Dewald (1981), Gould (1989) 129 32. Well argued by Redfield (1985), and see also Gould (1989) 95-109. On his treatment of these practices, Pembroke (1967), Beard and Henderson (1997), Kurke (1999) 227-46, Harrison (2000b) 216-17, and Chs. 20 and 21 in this volume. See Dewald (1981) 99-101, Gould (1989) 131, Lateiner (1985) 93-6; for archaeological evidence, Gerschevitch (1985), 185-99; see also Chs. 10 and 19 in this volume. 33 M
b
36
208
N I C K FISHER
p. x x ) , a n d the passions a n d jealousies o f X e r x e s a n d his w i f e Amestris t o w a r d s his b r o t h e r Masistes, a n d his w i f e a n d d a u g h t e r ( 9 . 1 0 8 - 1 3 ) . 3 7 M a n y o t h e r E a s t e r n kings gave greater p r i o r i t y t o the seizure
of
p o w e r , o r a d e m o n s t r a t i o n o f its absolute n a t u r e , t h a n to the d e m a n d s o f sexual m o r a l i t y a n d f a m i l y ties. T w o Candaules,
examples
may
be g i v e n .
the last H e r a c l i d k i n g o f L y d i a , ' w h o was destined to
e n d b a d l y ' (1.8), b r o u g h t a b o u t his d o w n f a l l t h r o u g h excessive sexu a l love f o r his o w n w i f e , a n d the i n a p p r o p r i a t e need to have
her
b e a u t y a p p r e c i a t e d b y his f a v o u r i t e Gyges (described as b e i n g c o n t r a r y to w h a t is p r o p e r , la kala, a n d t o nomos). H i s wife's s t r o n g sense o f shame (aidos, aiskhune) at b e i n g seen u n v e i l e d a n d n a k e d b y a n o t h e r m a n i m p e l l e d h e r to seek revenge t h r o u g h m u r d e r ; H e r o d o t u s
com-
m e n t s t h a t this sense o f disgrace was even m o r e t y p i c a l o f b a r b a r i a n peoples t h a n (by i m p l i c a t i o n ) Greeks, whose males at least exercised n a k e d . 3 8 Gyges' readiness to acceed t o the wife's desire f o r revenge a n d t h e i r j o i n t seizure o f p o w e r , w o u l d , a c c o r d i n g to t h e
Delphic
o r a c l e , l e a d to r e t r i b u t i o n f a l l i n g o n his descendants i n the fifth g e n e r a t i o n ( 1 . 1 3 , 91). Astyages' preparedness t o h a v e his d a u g h t e r m a r r i e d to a m a n o f a lesser e t h n i c g r o u p , a n d t h e n , m o r e d r e a d f u l l y , to have h e r s o n , his g r a n d s o n C y r u s k i l l e d r a t h e r t h a n see h i m succeed to his i m p e r i a l p o s i t i o n , has as its a p p a r e n t l y n a t u r a l consequence a yet f o u l e r d e e d against the values o f f a m i l y f e e l i n g a n d succession; a n d r e t r i b u t i o n f o l l o w e d , as his act o f revenge against H a r p a g u s
in
s e r v i n g u p his s o n t o h i m at a feast m e t w i t h r e t a l i a t i o n w h e n Harpagus
37
i n s p i r e d C y r u s t o l e a d t h e Persians i n r e v o l t (1.107—30). 3 9
On the Masistes story, see also Gould (1991) 10-11 and Chs. 10, pp. 230-1 and 13, pp. 310 13 in this volume; on the moral and political theme of the decline of the Persian monarchy, and its significant placing here, see Dewald ('1997), esp. 68-70. On aidas, see above all Cairns (1993), and on this passage Gould (1980) 53-4, Kilmer (1993) 161 2, and Cairns (1996). There is another case of women's shame in relation to exposure of their own bodies at 3.133. On the thematic connections linking the stories of Candaules' and Masistes' wives, and their contribution to the complex modes of closure of the work, see also Wolff (1964), Herington (1991a) 152-3, and below, pp. 215-16. Recent analyses of this episode in van der Veen (1996) Ch. 3 and Pelling (1996), though van der Veen undervalues the importance in such standard folktales of the failure to kill babies fated to become kings or leaders, because of the natural difficulty even tough men find in killing smiling babies; on these motifs (found in 5.92, as well as in many other traditions), see Binder (1964), Lewis (1980) and Asheri (1988) on 1.113. 38
39
209
POPULAR M O R A L I T Y I N HERODOTUS
Helping Friends and Harming Enemies: Reciprocity and Revenge I n a d d i t i o n to the o b l i g a t i o n s , e m o t i o n s ,
a n d conflicts i n h e r e n t i n
f a m i l y relations across cultures, H e r o d o t u s b u i l d s the r e c i p r o c a l o b l i g ations o f f r i e n d s a n d guest-friends
firmly
i n t o the s t r u c t u r e o f his
n a r r a t i v e , w h e r e s t r o n g values o f f r i e n d s h i p a n d e n m i t y are assumed throughout.40 A
s t a n d a r d v i e w o f m a n y G r e e k s , w h i c h appears
the s t a r t i n g p o i n t o f Plato's Republic, was t h a t j u s t i c e m e a n t friends a n d h a r m i n g enemies'.
The
t e r m ' f r i e n d s ' (philoi)
k i n , close p e r s o n a l friends (as i n o u r c o m m o n e s t
as
'helping included
sense o f the t e r m ) ,
a n d m o r e loosely perhaps f e l l o w - m e m b e r s o f social o r p o l i t i c a l groups (at t i m e s i n c l u d i n g one's c i t y o r c o u n t r y ) w i t h w h o m one feels c o m m o n i d e n t i t y a n d interests. Inside the c o m m u n i t y , philoi s h o u l d a i d a n d e n t e r t a i n each o t h e r , a c c o r d i n g to r e c i p r o c a l rules o f kharis, o f r e c i p r o c a l g i f t - g i v i n g a n d s u p p o r t . W h e r e e n m i t y exists, o r replaces f r i e n d s h i p , rules o f 'negative r e c i p r o c i t y ' o r revenge take over. O u t s i d e the c o m m u n i t y elaborate p r o t o c o l s o f h o s p i t a l i t y a n d m u t u a l g i f t - g i v i n g (Greek xenia, 'guest-' o r ' r i t u a l i z e d - f r i e n d s h i p ' ) w e r e available to f o r m lasting co-operative relationships; as is clear f r o m H o m e r onwards, a host w h o entertains a guest f r o m a b r o a d , a n d gives h i m presents, expects a l a s t i n g , possibly h e r e d i t a r y , r e c i p r o c a l r e l a t i o n s h i p t o be established. 4 1 M a n y narratives i n H e r o d o t u s p l a y o n the
problems
such relationships can present, especially w h e r e they become
enmeshed
i n p o l i t i c s , w h e t h e r w h a t is i n v o l v e d is relations b e t w e e n i n d i v i d u a l s , b e t w e e n i n d i v i d u a l s a n d states, o r b e t w e e n states. 4 2 W h a t is o f p a r t i c u l a r interest to H e r o d o t u s , the unstable b o u n d a r y
as i n H o m e r a n d A t h e n i a n t r a g e d y , is
between
l e g i t i m a t e a n d excessive
forms
of
b o t h generosity a n d revenge; w h e r e the protocols o f such relationships
*" On the importance of this theme, see especially Gould (1989) 82 5, (1991). " See especially Blundell (1989), Mitchell (1997), Ch. 1. The story of Syloson and Darius is especially rich for the values and language of gifts and kharis; van der Veen (1995) 53-8, Kurke (1999) 122-5. On the political aspects of xenia or 'ritualized friendship', see above all Herman (1987). It is of course true that elites possess greater wealth than the rest, often in the form of splendid individual items such as bowls, goblets, or cloaks (which may be described as 'heirlooms', keimelia, or objects of shining/symbolic value, agalmata); hence they will be able to engage in splendid acts of gift-exchange on their own or their state's behalf. But both Herman (1987) and Kurke (1999) err, it seems to me, in presenting the underlying values of gift-exchange and reciprocity as inherently elitist or aristocratic, and individual instances of conflict between such values and other ideals such as justice or humane restraint as necessarily a clash between elitist and 'middling' or democratic ideologies. 42
210
NICK
are left u n c l e a r (in B r a u n d ' s
FISHER
t e r m , ' u n d e r n e g o t i a t e d ' ) , o r there are
clashes o f c u l t u r a l t r a d i t i o n s , a gruesome i n t e n s i t y o f e m o t i o n s a n d actions r e s u l t s . 4 ' G r e e k tyrants regularly f o r m e d networks o f guest-friendship alliances w i t h f e l l o w - t y r a n t s a n d w i t h aristocrats; such relationships are p r e sented as e q u a l a n d m u t u a l l y s u p p o r t i v e , b u t o f t e n w i t h destructive consequences f o r t h e i r societies, t h o u g h there is o f t e n disagreement over the degree o f m o r a l d i s a p p r o v a l w h i c h m a y be f o u n d , e x p l i c i t l y o r i m p l i c i t l y , i n the accounts. T h e first G r e e k t y r a n t to be m e n tioned, Thrasybulus
of Miletus, when
u n d e r siege f r o m
o f L y d i a , b e n e f i t e d f r o m his close r e l a t i o n o f xenia w i t h
Alyattes Periander,
son o f Cypselus o f C o r i n t h (1.19-20); P e r i a n d e r passed o n v a l u a b l e inside i n f o r m a t i o n a b o u t a D e l p h i c oracle g i v e n to A l y a t t e s . 4 4
The
m o r e sinister side to the r e l a t i o n s h i p is revealed i n the C o r i n t h i a n spokesman's later a c c o u n t o f the t e r r i b l e deeds o f the dynasty (5.92). The
t r a n s i t i o n to a m u c h m o r e b r u t a l r e g i m e is t h e r e a t t r i b u t e d t o
Thrasybulus'
f a m o u s wordless advice to P e r i a n d e r ' s
messenger,
to
l o p o f f a l l the tallest ears o f w h e a t ; 4 ' the C o r i n t h i a n t y r a n t ' s b r u t a l i t y t h e n e x t e n d e d b e y o n d the killings a n d b a n i s h i n g o f the m o s t p o w e r f u l a n d t h r e a t e n i n g o f his f e l l o w - c i t i z e n s to e n f o r c e d c o n f i s c a t i o n o f the clothes o f a l l the city's w o m e n . 4 1 '
O t h e r examples
o f such
t y r a n n i c a l xeniai i n c l u d e Peisistratus' useful f r i e n d s h i p a n d alliance w i t h L y g d a m i s o f N a x o s (1.61-4), w h i c h h e l p e d b o t h t o get established i n p o w e r ; ' 1 7
the f r i e n d s h i p a n d m a r r i a g e c o n n e c t i o n s w h i c h
brought together Anaxilaos
43
of Rhegion,
Terillus of H i m e r a
and
Braund (1998). Gould (1989) 49, 55-6. Periander may be seen here as usurping the practice of the gods in attacking the highest trees etc., as described by Artabanus (7.lO.e), and this perhaps foreshadows his later troubles; van der Veen (1996) 8 2 3 , Harrison (2000b) 57, 163. Waters (1971) 13-15, 18-20 observes that the Corinthian speaker Soclees, apparently condemning Periander, spends more time on the more exotic tales of ghosts, necrophilia and confiscation of women's clothes, and suggests that his selection of the material reflects Herodotus' interests in telling varied tales, not in expressing his anti-tyrannical bias; but variation and even some humour is nonetheless compatible with a general hostility in principle to tyranny's normal acts. See also van der Veen (1996) 81-2, emphasizing that in the necrophilia story Periander is treating free people as slaves, and in general on Herodotus' attitudes to tyrants, see Ferrill (1978), Lateiner (1984). " Lygdamis supposedly also had a friendship with Polycrates (Polyaenus 1.23); similarly Theagenes the earlier tyrant of Megara had, according to Thuc. 1.126 (but not mentioned at Hdt. 5.71), encouraged his son-in-law Cylon in his attempt at a tyranny in Athens. 4 4
15
46
211
POPULAR M O R A L I T Y I N HERODOTUS
Hamilcar
o f Carthage and helped lead to t u r m o i l and
w a r f a r e (7.163—4); 4 H a n d m o s t f a m o u s l y the elaborate
large-scale
entertainments
a n d contests o f f e r e d b y the t y r a n t Cleisthenes o f S i c y o n f o r the suitors o f his d a u g h t e r A g a r i s t e As T h r a s y b u l u s '
(6.126—31).
advice suggests, relations o f tyrants w i t h the elite
m e m b e r s o f t h e i r o w n states are c h a r a c t e r i z e d b y tensions, l a t e n t o r active hostilities, a n d swift a n d v i o l e n t t r a n s i t i o n s . As O t a n e s puts i t i n the ' C o n s t i t u t i o n a l D e b a t e ' (3.80), the typical tyrant w i t h his u n c o n t r o l l e d p o w e r is d r i v e n above a l l b y hubris a n d phthonos
Vi
to 'possess
every wickedness'; he c o m m i t s the m o s t serious offences, the overt h r o w o f all ancestral laws a n d customs (nomaia), rapes o f a n d executions
w i t h o u t trial.''" Friendships
women,
and intermarriage
can
s w i f t l y be r e p l a c e d b y d i v o r c e , p l o t s , exiles, a n d k i l l i n g s ; this is excellently demonstrated
b y the c o m p l e x
relations b e t w e e n
Peisistratus
a n d his sons i n A t h e n s a n d o t h e r elite families such as the A l c m a e o n i d a e ( 1 . 5 9 - 6 4 , 5 . 6 6 - 7 , 6 9 - 7 3 , 6 . 1 2 1 - 3 1 ) a n d the l i n k e d families o f Miltiades and C i m o n ( 6 . 3 4 - 4 1 ,
6.103-4).
Similar motifs of hospitality, guest-friendship, power and conflict p e r v a d e the stories o f Polycrates o f Samos a n d the f u r t h e r catastrophes t h a t affected t h a t i s l a n d after his m u r d e r Herodotus'
(3.39-60,
120-7).
versions m a y reflect i n p a r t the n e e d f o r his S a m i a n f e l -
l o w - c i t i z e n s , elite a n d n o n - e l i t e , t o b l a c k e n the n a m e o f the
tyrant
after his fall a n d t o distance themselves; b u t t o g e t h e r t h e y f o r m c o m p l e x chains o f events w h e r e m a n y o f those w h o choose t o b r e a k the p a t t e r n s o f r e c i p r o c i t y a n d those w h o t r i e d to act j u s t l y came alike to grief, often i n u n e x p e c t e d ways. 5 1 A m b i v a l e n c e surrounds Polycrates f r o m the b e g i n n i n g o f the n a r r a t i v e . A f t e r seizing p o w e r , i n i t i a l l y he a t t e m p t e d to share p o w e r w i t h his t w o b r o t h e r s , b t i t t h e n , d e c i d i n g t h a t he p r e f e r r e d sole r u l e , he k i l l e d one b r o t h e r a n d e x i l e d the o t h e r , Syloson. H e r o d o t u s '
selection o f stories o f Polycrates i n p o w e r
48
Their opponents, other Sicilian tyrants, Gelon o f Gela and Syracuse and Theron of Acragas, also intermarried (see Asheri, CAH TV' , 786). On human phthonos as a constant feature leading to disunity and preventing stable absolutism in human societies, see also 3.52, 7.236-7, 8.124-5, and Immerwahr (1966) 313 4. See, e.g., Ferrill (1978), Lateiner (1984), Fisher (1992) 346 9. The role of the unexpected, and the importance of waiting to see how events turn out in the end, are emphasised by van der Veen (1996) Ch. 6. The importance of the juxtapositions and interconnections o f stories o f the Greek tyrant and the Persian king in this book are analysed by (e.g.,) Immerwahr (1956-57), Kurke (1999) 101-29. See also Ch. 6 in this volume/ 2
4 9
511
51
212
N I C K FISHER
balances the p r o p e r a n d advantageous guest-friendship alliance, secured w i t h lavish r e c i p r o c a l gifts, w i t h A m a s i s the k i n g o f E g y p t , 3 2 against the c a l c u l a t e d l y t y r a n n i c a l a n d self-interested ' e x t e n s i o n ' (or p e r h a p s i n a n o t h e r sense ' i n v e r s i o n ' ) o f the rules o f r e c i p r o c i t y w h i c h a c c o m p a n i e d his successful career as a large-scale ' p i r a t e ' : he
plundered
f r o m everyone i n c l u d i n g his ' f r i e n d s ' , o n the a r g u m e n t t h a t he w o u l d create m o r e g r a t i t u d e (mallon kharidzesthai) i n a f r i e n d to w h o m
he
r e t u r n e d w h a t he h a d t a k e n t h a n i f he h a d never t a k e n i t i n the first place ( 3 . 3 9 . 4 ) . 5 3 The
s e n t i m e n t sets the tone f o r some o f the e x p l a n a t i o n s o f f e r e d
f o r the Spartans' a n d C o r i n t h i a n s ' decision to a i d the S a m i a n exiles, w h o m Polycrates h a d m a l i c i o u s l y sent to a i d Cambyses i n his i n v a sion o f E g y p t , a n d w h o
h a d escaped. T h e
Spartans
claimed that
t h e y w e r e a n x i o u s to avenge the t h e f t o f the m i x i n g - b o w l h a d b e e n s e n d i n g t o Croesus, sent to t h e m
(3.47). Despite
(/crater)
they
a n d the corselet w h i c h A m a s i s
had
the c h r o n o l o g i c a l p r o b l e m s o f w h i c h
H e r o d o t u s seems at least p a r t l y a w a r e (3.148), the i m p l i c a t i o n seems to be t h a t the first t w o thefts at least reflect Polycrates'
plundering
f r o m his friends w i t h serious consequences f o r his r u l e i n the l o n g r u n . T h e C o r i n t h i a n g r i e v a n c e - - S a m i a n assistance to C o r c y r e a n
boys
b e i n g e x p o r t e d to Alyattes o f L y d i a — s e e m s m o r e distanced b y H e r o dotus f r o m a d i r e c t c o n n e c t i o n w i t h Polycrates' d i s d a i n f o r r e c i p r o cal r u l e s . 3 4 I n o t h e r ways t o o , Polycrates displays the ruthless b r u t a l i t y o f the t y r a n t (e.g., 3.45); yet he is also seen i n places as the l a v i s h a n d generous r u l e r a n d h o l d e r o f a s p l e n d i d c o u r t (and p a t r o n poets such as A n a c r e o n ,
52
of
3.121), a n d one w h o k n o w s the e t i q u e t t e
See also Hdt. 2.182, where Amasis' xenia gifts to Polycrates, two wooden statues of himself, are mentioned. See Gould (1991) 7-8, 17-19, Kurke (1999) 102 4, though her claim is disputable that the emphasis on the breaches of the rules of kharis in these sequences suggest it was exclusively disgruntled Samian aristocrats who presented this picture of Polycrates' thalassocracy rather than a more general tradition. One should not take Theognis' word for it that non-elites (his kakoi and deiloi) had little understanding of or concern for the values of reciprocal favours: see van Wees (2000) especially 62 7. On this, see above, p. 211. Against Kurke (1999) 103, who sees this as another instance of 'violated exchange', one might observe that the sending of the boys was not a mere sending of a gift, but an act of savage revenge committed by Periander on the Corcyreans for their killing of his estranged son Lycophron, and that Herodotus feels the need for a further explanation for the Corinthians' continued resentment at the Samians. On the theme of the castration of Greek boys, see below, p. 215 on Hermotimus. 33
54
213
POPULAR M O R A L I T Y I N HERODOTUS
o f r e c i p r o c i t y {kharis).
33
I n the elaborate a c c o u n t o f the rediscovery
o f his j e t t i s o n e d r i n g i n the b o d y humble labouring
fisherman
o f the great fish, he treats the
w i t h p r o p e r g r a t i t u d e a n d respect (a
d o u b l e kharis is d u e f o r his gift a n d his w o r d s ) , a n d treats h i m to a d i n n e r ( i n c l u d i n g the
fish?).:*
A f t e r Polycrates' foreseen yet ' u n w o r t h y ' e n d at O r o e t e s ' (3.125),
:>/
hands
o t h e r actors i n relations b e t w e e n Samos a n d t h e Persians
saw a t t e m p t s to a d h e r e to the values o f the r e c i p r o c a l gift a n d
of
j u s t i c e f o u n d e r i n r e l a t i o n to the pressures o f p o w e r a n d the needs o f the m a j o r e m p i r e . Polycrates' e x i l e d b r o t h e r Syloson
first
found
t h a t a gratuitous a n d a p p a r e n t l y foolish act o f generosity led to o p p o r t u n i t i e s f o r t h e r e c o v e r y o f his h o m e l a n d a n d p o w e r ; g i v i n g , r a t h e r t h a n selling, a fine r e d cloak to a m a n ( D a r i u s ) w h o at t h a t t i m e was m e r e l y a m e m b e r o f the Persian g u a r d i n E g y p t , b u t w h o later b e c a m e k i n g . O n b e i n g r e m i n d e d o f the gift t h e k i n g o f f e r e d Syloson as m u c h g o l d a n d silver as he w i s h e d , 5 " b u t instead he chose p o w e r i n Samos, o n c o n d i t i o n ( t r y i n g to a v o i d the c r i m e s o f his b r o t h e r ) t h a t n o S a m i a n was k i l l e d o r enslaved. B u t this p l a n f o u n d e r e d i n a c o m p l e x i n t e r p l a y w i t h t h e a t t e m p t o f Polycrates' s t e w a r d a n d successor i n S a m o s , M a e a n d r i u s , also a m a n w i t h t w o b r o t h e r s , to a v o i d Polycrates' t y r a n n i c a l r u l e . H i s a p p a r e n t l y g e n u i n e desire to be ' m o s t
On this complex portrait, see also Waters (1971) 28-9. * Herodotus' Amasis acts in this narrative as the voice of 'Solonian' concern for a long-term view of 'success' and fear of the gods' disruptiveness through jealousy (phthonos); he does not link this fear to a moral distaste for Polycrates methods of gaining wealth and power, but it is possible to hold that Amasis is to be supposed to be alarmed on both moral and prudential grounds—at the indiscriminate nature of Polycrates' greed (see also 3.122-3), likely to arouse opposition from gods and/or men, which it would not be appropriate to express to Polycrates in his letter. 1 would not follow Kurke (1999) 109 1 1 in seeing further reflections of aristocratic discourse, condemnatory of the tyrant, in Polycrates' readiness to acknowledge gratitude to the humble fisherman. Rather the scrupulously polite correctness of the tyrant's response underscored the irony of the alarming discovery of the gods' rejection of the voluntary sacrifice of the object of high value (which also helps to account for the high number of occurrences of terms of value and worth (axios/a). 'Unworthy of himself and his high thoughts' (phronemata) may come as a surprise after the enumeration of Polycrates' greed, unscrupulousness, and brutality; it seems above all a response to his 'megaloprepeia', that is the extent and greatness of his rule and its lasting memorials: see Fisher (1992) 361-3. " Despite his general reputation as a 'huckster' (kapelos), intent on establishing a coinage and maximizing his revenues, on which see Kurke (1999) 68-89, Herodotus' Darius like the other kings could also at times display extravagant generosity; though usually to those he hoped to bind to his service. 37
J
214
NICK FISHER
just' and to surrender power to some form o f democracy and isorwmup collapsed, when aristocrats objected to his position o f limited privilege, and he had them arrested. The apathetic people offered no effective support; one brother resorted to execution when Maeandrius fell i l l , the other brother urged resistance when Syloson and the Persians under Otanes turned up. Otanes (who himself, by another twist o f irony, had advocated 'democracy'; for the Persians at the 'Constitutional Debate', 3.80-2) took the city by ruthless force and made the Samians all 'equal' by the imposition o f a 'dragnet' policy o f extermination. So Syloson took control of an empty city until a genital disease and consequent dream persuaded Otanes to make amends for his ruthlessness by repopulating it. These stories, which may originate from varied types o f sources among the Samians, among w h o m Herodotus clearly had many contacts, have been recast into linked narratives which display many o f the historian's characteristic preoccupations: his perception that the powerful usually failed to keep their relationships based on moral reciprocity free from the more political drive for wealth, power, and fame; his recognition of the impossibility for Greek states or their rulers to form friendships or alliances with Persian kings or their satraps without losing their freedom and often coming to unpleasant and unworthy ends; and his preference for identifying 'causal' connections between chains of aggressive or hubristic acts, revenge and further retaliation. Herodotus is as alive as many other Greek writers to the danger that revenges frequently become morally excessive, and that precise judgments on the moment o f transition are very difficult. Three varied stories o f such terrible revenges, w i t h apparently contrasting morals, may be considered to conclude this section. A t the end o f Book Four (202-5), the Battiad queen Pheretime o f Cyrene showed no mercy to the people o f Barka for killing her son Arcesilaus I I I , when they were delivered into her hands by her allies the Persians. 60
61
s s
See, e.g., Mitchell (1975) 85-6, Shipley (1981) 103-5, Roisman (1985). " Against the view that all his sources were aristocrats, as argued by Mitchell (1975) 75 9, Kurke (1999) 122-9, seeks- but perhaps over-precisely to distinguish aristocratic and more middling versions, e.g., those which present Maeandrius and his attempt at isonomia with some favour. See also Ch. 23 in this volume. On the weight given by Herodotus to retaliation and revenge in his explanations of wars and conflicts, see the minimizing account in de Romilly (1971b), (1977) and, rightly taking them more seriously, Gould (1989) 43-4, 82 5 and Lendon (2000) esp. 1-3, 13 18. There are 69 instances of timoria- words in the text. See also Ch. 6, p. 121 in this volume. l>
61
215
POPULAR M O R A L I T Y I N HERODOTUS
She i m p a l e d the m e n m o s t i n v o l v e d i n the m u r d e r o n stakes r o u n d t h e w a l l , a d d e d the breasts o f t h e i r wives, a n d let the Persian a r m y pillage a n d enslave the rest. S u b s e q u e n t l y she d i e d f o u l l y , c o n s u m e d by worms, and Herodotus'
e x p l a n a t o r y c o m m e n t is that ' f o r m e n
excessively p o w e r f u l revenges are causes o f e n v y (epiphthonoi) a m o n g t h e g o d s ' , t h e o n l y case w h e r e he endorses i n his o w n voice t h e i d e a o f d i v i n e phthonos, a p p a r e n t l y i n a m o r a l i z e d f o r m . ' ' 2 N e x t , w h a t H e r o d o t u s calls the 'greatest revenge for a m a n w r o n g e d o f a l l those w e k n o w o f
was a c h i e v e d b y H e r m o t i m u s o f Pedasos
o n Panionius o f Chios (8.104-6). Panionius, a slave-trader w h o specialized i n castrating attractive boys a n d selling t h e m as eunuchs, eventually f e l l i n t o the p o w e r o f one o f his v i c t i m s , w h e n H e r m o t i m u s h a d risen t o the post o f X e r x e s ' c h i e f e u n u c h . T h e revenge was t h a t P a n i o n i u s was f o r c e d to c u t o f f the genitals o f his f o u r sons, w h o t h e n d i d the same to h i m . T h e
story is t o l d i n a w a y w h i c h invites us to agree
w i t h H e r m o t i m u s t h a t t h e gods have w o r k e d to d e l i v e r P a n i o n i u s i n t o his h a n d s , a n d t h a t this, like the result o f the T r o j a n W a r , is a case w h e r e (as H e r o d o t u s h i m s e l f emphasizes) the gods have e n g i n e e r e d i t t h a t 'great injustices m e e t great revenges' (2.120).
03
The
revenge itself, h o w e v e r , is described o n l y w i t h the m o r e a m b i g u o u s t e r m 'greatest' (megistos), a n d n o f u r t h e r recompense affects H e r m o t i m u s ; the r e a d e r is a p p a r e n t l y left free t o see this e i t h e r as an a p p r o p r i a t e , albeit h o r r i f y i n g , f o r m o f d i v i n e l y b a c k e d r e t r i b u t i o n , o r as a n o t h e r case w h e r e t h e revenge, a g a i n i n v o l v i n g m u t i l a t i o n , is itself 'excessive', a n d the q u e s t i o n o f subsequent p u n i s h m e n t is left o p e n . ' ' 4 F i n a l l y , the last event o f G r e e k - P e r s i a n c o n f l i c t i n the Histories (just after t h e story o f the excessive, also m u t i l a t o r y , revenges o f X e r x e s a n d his w i f e o n Masistes a n d his wife) is the c a p t u r e o f Sestus, a n d
02
On mutilations in Herodotus, see also Lateiner (1987) 92 3. It is possible that the point is that the gods feel phthonos here because they reserve excessive vengeance to themselves: so e.g., Mossman (1995) 174-6. But one might think that the emphasis on the brutality of the impalings suggests rather the gods too are here supposed to be applying a moral judgment on the excessive acts, as Immerwahr (1966) 313, Harrison (2000b) 111. « See e.g., Vandiver (1991) 130, 227, Harrison (2000b) 108-10; other cases include 1.118-29, 3.49 53, 7.137, and esp. 5.55, the dream which, fruitlessly, appeared to Hipparchus before his death, warning him that 'no mortal does not pay the retribution for his unjust deeds'. See e.g., Lateiner (1985) 99 (Herodotus 'does not disapprove'). Braund (1998) 166-7 and Lendon (2000) 18 see it as probably more problematic. Clearly excessive, yet not directly linked to retaliation, is the story of Xerxes' and Amestris' killings and mutilations, 9.108 13. 6 4
216
N I C K FISHER
the astonishingly r i c h a n d a m b i g u o u s c l o s i n g n a r r a t i v e here i n c l u d e s a p p r o p r i a t e p u n i s h m e n t s o r revenges m e t e d o u t to t w o (9.114-22).
One,
Persians
a n o t h e r O e o b a z u s , ' " w h o h a d s t o r e d the cables
used to b r i d g e the H e l l e s p o n t , escaped, o n l y to be r i t u a l l y sacrificed b y some T h r a c i a n s , a n d the cables w e r e r e c o v e r e d , to be d e d i c a t e d b a c k at A t h e n s .
The
other, the devious, greedy,
a n d sacrilegious
Persian g o v e r n o r o f the H e l l e s p o n t r e g i o n , A r t a y c t e s , h a d a p p r o p r i ated f o r h i m s e l f the w e a l t h o f the h e r o - s h r i n e at Elaious o f Protesilaus (the
first
G r e e k to die i n the T r o j a n W a r ) ,
t u r n e d the s a n c t u a r y
enclosure over to a g r i c u l t u r e , a n d h a d sex w i t h w o m e n i n t h e i n n e r s a n c t u a r y ; he was c a p t u r e d a n d p r o m i n e n t l y c r u c i f i e d o n a h e a d l a n d n e a r t h e s h r i n e , o n the o r d e r o f the A t h e n i a n
commander
X a n t h i p p u s (the f a t h e r o f Pericles), i n o r d e r to satisfy the desire f o r a p p r o p r i a t e revenge o f the p e o p l e o f Elaious. T h e s e offences e n c a p sulate m a n y o f t h e themes o f excess w h i c h p e r v a d e X e r x e s ' e x p e d i t i o n , t h e b r i d g i n g o f the H e l l e s p o n t , the desecration o f temples a n d sanctuaries, i m p a l i n g s o f defeated enemies, a n d its r e l a t i o n t o the Trojan War.
The
a p p a r e n t l y r a n d o m k i l l i n g o f O e o b a z u s gives a
sense o f a n a p p r o p r i a t e l y i r o n i c d i v i n e p u n i s h m e n t ; b u t the c r u c i f i x i o n o f A r t a y c t e s , * w h i l e i t is n o t e x p l i c i t l y c o n d e m n e d (as H e r m o t i m u s ' g e n i t a l m u t i l a t i o n s w e r e n o t ) , carries the p o s s i b i l i t y t h a t the G r e e k s , a n d specifically the n e w A t h e n i a n - l e d alliance, w e r e themselves b e g i n n i n g to behave 'excessively'. T h e
c o n t r a s t is t e l l i n g w i t h the rejec-
t i o n b y Pausanias after t h e battle o f Plataea o f t h e ' m o s t i m p i o u s ' proposal made b y L a m p o n , that Xerxes' uncharacteristic i m p a l i n g o f Leonidas' head be m a t c h e d b y the retaliatory i m p a l i n g o f M a r d o n i u s (7.238, 8.78-9).67
83
H e r e , as i n m a n y o t h e r instances, H e r o d o t u s uses
There seems no reason to suppose that this is the same Oeobazus whose sons were killed by Darius (4.83-4). '* The little story of the salt fish coming alive and jumping about on the coals, as interpreted by Artayctes (9.120), takes us back to Cyrus' fable, told to the lonians when rejecting their belated offer of a settlement, that they had lost their chance to dance freely to his tune (1.141), and offers yet another form of appropriate closure, as the lonians regained their freedom and took revenge: see Boedeker (1988) 40-1, Herington (1991a) 153, and Ceccarelli (1993). See esp. Bischoff (1932) 78-83, Boedeker (1988), Vandiver (1991) 223-7, Herington (1991a), Pelling (1998), Dewald (1998), Hartog (1999) 192. As Harrison points out, (2000b) 111, that the crucifixion was evidently a 'rational' decision taken by Xanthippus after consultation, need not exclude the idea that the gods had done their bit to bring this about, in a manner similar to Hermotimus' revenge, by delivering the wrongdoer to the victim. 67
217
POPULAR M O R A L I T Y I N HERODOTUS
traditional moral justifications and problematics concerning revenge both to bring out Persian and other barbarian cruelties and to question any easy confidence that Greeks were always their superiors. 1,8
Pride, hubris, aggression, and imperialism This brings us finally to the use o f moral language in the discussion of the causes o f these conflicts. Arguably the most debated area of 'popular morality' i n Herodotus concerns its role i n his analysis of the major decisions o f the leading states and his complex categories of historical explanation. I n his opening sentences Herodotus makes it clear that he sees it as his business to explain why major conflicts start, and to record how cities as well as individuals rise and fall, fall and rise, in changing patterns o f human mutability. The question for this final section is to assess the function, in his explanations o f these patterns, o f moral terms such as justice, reciprocity and truth-telling, revenge or retaliation (tisis, timoria), greed and graspingness (pleonexid), dishonouring aggression (hubris), and desire for empire, and finally over-confidence or pride (mega phroneein etc.). Many different categories or modes o f explanation (not mutually exclusive, but not necessarily easily compatible either) have been plausibly identified as operating i n his work;' while there is much disagreement, it is clear that in his text the moral, the religious and the political are constantly and inextricably intertwined.' 09
0
1
I have space to consider just two of the narratives o f the leadingEastern kings, through whose wars with various Greek peoples the development o f the main structure o f the Histories is articulated. A l l
m
Sec esp. Braund (1998). There are thus connections with these central themes of his work, considered in Chs. 7, 8, 14, 24 in this volume. Full and convenient discussions of Herodotean modes of explanation are provided by Laleiner (1989) Ch. 9, and Harrison (2000b) passim, though Lateiner is more concerned to argue that Herodotus does not need to, and does not in fact, choose between types of explanation, but is more interested in human modes, and Harrison that the religious explanations need to be taken very seriously (and see also Gould (1994)), but not seen as part of a coherent 'system' (as argued e.g., by Fornara (1999)). Many have seen parallels between the complexity of Herodotus' moral, religious, and political patterns and similar subtle patterns in Athenian tragedy, especially Sophocles: see. e.g., Lachenaud (1978) 498 500, Raaflaub (1987) 228, 247, Asheri Book I , xliv xlv, Ostwald (1991), Fisher (1992) 347-8, and Ch. 6 in this volume. 89
711
71
218
NICK FISHER
the leading kings make mistakes o f judgment, commit acts o f brutality at the level o f individual relationships, and engage in acts o f imperialistic aggression against other states; throughout, issues o f fate, and divine justice or jealousy, are prominent. Croesus, the first to commit injustice against Greek states (1.6), is appropriately the first complex case. His overvaluation o f his own prosperity, and failure to realize that, in Solon's words, the divine was a 'jealous and disruptive thing' (phihoneron and tarakhodes), aroused, Herodotus thinks it probable (hos eikasai), the 'indignation' (nemesis) o f 'a god' (1.34) which then apparently took the form o f the coincidental yet tragically appropriate circumstances o f the 'accidental' killing o f his son Atys by his suppliant and guest-friend Adrastus.' Croesus' failure to understand the changeable conditions o f human life should not, in my view, be seen as a serious religious offence (like, say, destroying temples or bridging the Hellespont), nor is there sufficient reason to label it, as so many have, hubris, as it did not involve either an intention to insult or shame, nor had that as its effect.' The 'divinity's' response hence seems, initially at least, disproportionate to any 'offence' the mortal may have given by expressing the view that he was the most fortunate o f men, however that is labelled. 12
3
4
75
The following narrative, however, presents Croesus' decision and preparations for a pre-emptive strike against Cyrus' new Persian empire. His motives were varied: originally the aim was to stop the growing power o f Persia (1.46), then expanded to imperialism, the 'desire for land, to acquire more i n addition to his own share', confidence in the Delphic oracle (based on a misunderstanding o f which 'empire' he would destroy), and a desire to avenge his brotherin-law and former ally Astyages (1.73). Here a similar overconfidence
72
On this phrase, see Gould (1994) 95. " O n die reciprocal gift-giving and its dangers in this story, see Gould (1991) 8-9. '* Those who call it hubris have included Regenbogen (1961) 80-2 (= 1962, 84-6), de Romilly (1971b) 315, Stahl (1975) 5; for the contrary view, see Gould (1989) 79—80, Fisher (1992) 357-60. Contrary to much received opinion explicit connections between nemesis and hubris are not in fact very frequent in Greek literature. ' Cairns' response to my book on Hybris (1992) suggests, rightly, that there is felt to be an offence to the gods in so thinking one's prosperity could be lasting, as this fails to observe mortal limits, concludes cautiously, but still incorrectly in my view, that in such an offence 'all the signs of hubris are there' ((1996) 18-19). But if it could be construed as a form of insult to the gods in general, it would be one committed in foolish ignorance rather than wilful insolence; thus in my view not 'all' the signs of hubris are present, as the offence lacks the necessary intent to insult. 7;
219
POPULAR M O R A L I T Y I N HERODOTUS
i n his success, his o v e r - v a l u a t i o n o f w e a l t h , a n d his r e l u c t a n c e to ask the m o r e cautious q u e s t i o n s , 7 6 c o m b i n e d w i t h the e x p l i c i t a m b i t i o n f o r m o r e e m p i r e , as w e l l as a (less c o n v i n c i n g ) case f o r revenge, l e d t o his s t a r t i n g the w a r ; the i n i t i a l l y successful moves i n c l u d e d a u n i l a t e r a l crossing o f the significant r i v e r - b o r d e r o f the H a l y s , 7 ' a n d the enslavement o f the Syrians (1.76). T h e
first
is thus s h o w n — i n m o r e abstract terms-
Eastern i m p e r i a l i s t k i n g
as c l e a r l y g u i l t y o f t e r r i t o -
r i a l g r e e d (pleonexia), a n d , at this stage, i f n o t b e f o r e , his desire f o r even m o r e w e a l t h a n d p o w e r c a n c e r t a i n l y be said t o have b e c o m e hubris, i n the f o r m o f t h e aggressive crossing o f b o u n d a r i e s a n d i m position o f political slavery.'8 T h e t h i r d e l e m e n t o f m o r a l e x p l a n a t i o n o f Croesus' fall is revealed w h e n Croesus, defeated a n d a b o u t to be b u r n e d o n a p y r e b y C y r u s , w o n his release b y s h o u t i n g o u t e n i g m a t i c a l l y ' S o l o n ' a n d p e r s u a d i n g C y r u s o f the A t h e n i a n sage's message o f w a i t i n g f o r d e a t h , a n d r e s p e c t i n g the m u t a b i l i t y o f a l l t h i n g s . A f t e r s w i f t l y d e m o n s t r a t i n g his value w i t h his n e w 'wise adviser' status' 9 b y c h e c k i n g the excessive l o o t i n g o f the c i t y o f Sardis, he was g r a n t e d the r e w a r d o f asking the D e l p h i c A p o l l o w h e t h e r he was n o t a s h a m e d to have deceived the m a n w h o h a d s h o w n h i m so m u c h h o n o u r , s h o w n h i m kharis i n r e t u r n . T h e
Pythia,
a n d n o t to have
the god's
representative,
carefully distinguished b e t w e e n the charges; she f o r b o r e f r o m b l a m i n g Croesus f o r his recent aggression, a n d instead i n t r o d u c e d the t r a d i t i o n a l idea o f i n h e r i t e d g u i l t over g e n e r a t i o n s , a n d thus j u s t i f i e d his loss o f the k i n g d o m b y the o r i g i n a l c r i m e o f Gyges. 8 " O n
the o t h e r
h a n d , she c l a i m e d t h a t the g o d h a d s h o w n g r a t i t u d e , w h i c h h a d c o n sisted i n his h a v i n g delayed the disaster f o r three years, a n d
Apollo
was absolved o f deceit b y the a m b i g u i t y o f the oracles; as b e f o r e ,
7
" On this, see esp. Christ (1994) 189-93. On the moral and religious significance of crossing rivers in Herodotus, see e.g., Immerwahr (1966) 162-7, 293-4, Flory (1987) 54 8, Fisher (1992) 352-60; excessive scepticism in Waters (1971) 51. The warnings given before the Battle of Plataea against crossing die Asopus river (9.36) seem to have been prominent in Simonides' elegy of the battle (el. 14), and something similar may be going on in Pind. Paean 2.73-5 in relation to a war between Abdera and the Paeonians. See esp. Stahl (1975), Raaflaub (1987) 241 4, Fisher (1992) 359 6. On this Herodotean role. Bischoff (1932), Lattimore (1939), Dewald (1985) 52-3, Raaflaub (1987) 242. On this idea elsewhere, cf. e.g., Solon 13 West, Theognis 731-52, Aesch. 750-81, and in Herodotus, see Fornara (1999) 40 2, Harrison'(2000b) 112-13. On the idea of kharis between gods and men, and the defence of a god on a charge of ingratitude, see Parker (1998) esp. 114-15. 11
78
79
8,1
220
N I C K FISHER
81
Croesus lacked the self-doubt to ask the right questions (1.86-91). As he has already indicated (1.13), Herodotus accepted that the Heraclids achieved revenge (tisis) for Gyges' offence by this loss o f the Lydian kingdom, but it may be left open whether he fully commits himself, or his audience, to the privileging o f this long-term explanation over the other two reasons offered, Croesus' overconfidence and aggression, or the military reasons for Cyrus' victory. M y second case is Xerxes' decision to invade mainland Greece, the most elaborately deployed, important, and over-determined decision i n the Histories. The invasion is seen first as retaliation, as the next escalation in the chain of retaliations between Persians (and before that Lydians) and Greeks. Darius had, i n the immediate anger on hearing o f M a r a t h o n , begun to plan his revenge, but delays because o f his death, the succession problem, and the Egyptian revolt meant the new K i n g had to take the decision afresh, and Herodotus built this up into a complex pattern o f motives and divine impulsion. The ideas o f revenge and retaliation (timmia and tisis) run strongly through Mardonius' and Xerxes' speeches (7.5, 7.8.b, 7.9.a), but overall a set o f imperialist motives concerned with the desire for conquest and wider empires predominates. Mardonius and Xerxes are presented as more concerned to increase power and rule other peoples, whether they have deserved 'revenge' or 'punishment' or not (7.8.a, 7.8.C, 7.9.a); Mardonios had also his own personal motives (7.6). A l l critics agree on the presence o f different elements i n the account, such as their associations o f political subjection, contempt for other peoples and their gods, and the overconfident refusal to 82
93
84
81
See Christ (1994) 189-93, and also Kurke (1999) 160-3, on a distinction between two types of discourse, to do with gift-exchange and with intellectual understanding. See Cobet (1986) 8-10, Gould (1989) 67 8, 121 2, Lateiner (1989) 208-9. On this passage, see also Ch. 7, pp. 174-6. Similar analyses are of course appropriate for the over-confidence, failure to take advice, aggressive acts, invasions, boundary-crossings, treacheries, and cruelties of other kings, especially Cyrus and Darius: see various accounts, e.g., for Cyrus, Lattimore (1939) 29, Immerwahr 11966) 165-7, Waters (1971), 51-2, Avers' (1972), Flory (1987) 95-6, Raaflaub (1987) 244-5, Paven (1991), Fisher (1992) 352-7, Pelling (1996); for Darius, Immerwahr (1966) 169-76, Waters (1971) 58-64, Lateiner (1984) 260, Hartog (1988) 32-9, Fisher (1992) 382 4. On the significance of this emphasis on Persian admission of their committing of injustice in the pursuit of empire (with the possibility of implications for fifthcentury Athenian imperialism), see e.g., Pohlenz (1937) 121-35, Raaflaub (1987) 228-9, 241-2. 8 2
83
84
221
POPULAR M O R A L I T Y I N HERODOTUS
recognize human limits, but there remain many disagreements on the appropriate use o f Greek terms to describe them, on whether the focus is on the King's individual faults or on broader cultural traditions, and on the role Herodotus attributes to the divine. The debated issue o f how the loaded value term hubris is used i n this prolonged debate takes in all these motifs. Elsewhere in Herodotus, the term is often used to denounce the intention behind individual verbal or physical insults, and most frequently it is used i n claims by states seeking revenge to denounce the acts o f aggression and humiliation o f other states; i n a more abstract political analysis, as we saw previously, it is one of the two main stimuli to the crimes committed by tyrants or kings (3.80). I t is used only twice in relation to Xerxes' expedition and only once i n this section, i n the second of Artabanus' explorations o f why he holds the invasion o f Greece to be dangerous. I n the first, i n the public debate, Artabanus responds to the ambitiously expansive and confident plans o f Mardonius and Xerxes with his fears o f a possible reverse, i n part based on past Greek successes, and then more generally on the tendency o f 'the god' to cut down the greatest buildings, the tallest trees and the greatest armies, because his envy (phthonos) does not allow anyone other than himself to show pride, mega phroneein (7.10e). Later, when alone with Xerxes, and agreeing to test out the allegedly divine dream, he said, referring back to the previous speech, 'what caused me pain was not so much hearing abuse from you, as that when there were two motions for action placed before the Persians, one of which was tending to increase hubris and the other to diminish it, by saying that it is a bad thing to teach the soul always to have more than what is i n front o f one, you chose the one likely to be more dangerous for yourself and the Persians' (7.16a—b). I t has commonly been argued that the hubris i n the second speech is essentially identical with the mega phroneein i n the first, the over-confident pride which ignores the limits set to mankind by the gods. ' I n my view, what is being described in general i n both these passages is the complex o f drives and conquests which link together the Persians' past advances and their present ambitions, and include Xerxes' own aims 85
81
8 5
See esp. Fisher (1992) 343-57 and (2000) 103-6; briefly Giraudeau (1984a) 73-7. E.g., Regenbogen (1961) 97-102. Pohlenz (1937) 125 9. Immerwahr (1966), 177-8, de Romilly (1977) 42-6, Dickie (1984) 104-9, Redfield (1985) 113. 8 6
222
N I C K FISHER
and feelings, responding to the pressures to gain honour, wealth, and empire. ' Mega phroneein, hubris and always wanting to have more than one has (evidently a periphrasis for pkonexiaf are all ways o f expressing aspects o f imperialist aggression which might be offensive to the gods as well as to their human victims. But the three terms or phrases differ significantly i n their rhetorical force, here as also in other comparable cases. I n the open debate, Artabanus' language offers only hints of moral offensiveness; terms like mega phronein are morally ambiguous, and the view that the gods i n their envy (phthonos) choose to bring low the highest trees and the greatest powers is compatible either with the view that the gods dislike moral excess, and with the view expressed by Solon that they will not permit any mortal to match their levels of power. These ambiguities seem designed to protect Artabanus against retaliation by a shamed and angry Xerxes (as we have seen, many stories of often savage punishments indicate the need for such caution). Alone later with the K i n g , he puts his argument more bluntly and uses the stronger terms hubris and (in effect) pleonexia, which carry the ideas o f serious moral outrage as well as that o f excessive overconfidence and pride. Hubris, I would argue, adds the idea o f enslaving other peoples, and 'pleonexia' that o f a relentless drive for imperial expansion, both placed i n the context o f the traditional patterns o f imperialism found i n all Persian reigns since that of Gyrus, and already acknowledged i n the speeches o f Mardonius and Xerxes. Thus these moral terms, and above all hubris, have as much to say about the effects o f Persian expansion as on the presence o f prosperity, pride and over-confidence i n the Persians or their kings; the full statement o f Artabanus' views suggest that the gods may object to b o t h . 8
a
89
90
The divinely sent dreams which forced the two to agree after all
87
Most fully expressed in Fisher (1992) 368-74; Cairns (1996), esp. 13-22, takes partial issue with my views. In some respects our views are closer than he realizes, but differences remain. See e.g., Pohlenz (1937) 123, Raaflaub (1987) 229. See also e.g., Lateiner (1987) 92-3; on the atmosphere of fear at the court, also Pelling (1991) 130-6. This emphasis on Persian traditions rather than on individual error is given strong, though perhaps excessive, weight by Evans (1961), and also by Immerwahr (1966) 321-2, Gould (1989) 114 16, and Fisher (1992) 369-74. It compels a qualification to Momigliano's otherwise penetrating critique (1979; esp. 146 8) of Herodotus' allegedly over-personalized presentation of" Persian motives. 88 89
911
223
POPULAR M O R A L I T Y I N HERODOTUS
t o go a h e a d w i t h the i n v a s i o n seem best i n t e r p r e t e d as a n o r i g i n a l Persian m o t i f w h i c h have b e e n p r o f o u n d l y m o d i f i e d to fit G r e e k p a t terns. T h e d r e a m s o f the n o b l e figure i n s i s t i n g o n the e x p e d i t i o n are m o d e l l e d above a l l o n Z e u s ' false d r e a m to A g a m e m n o n i n the seco n d b o o k o f the Iliad; i n v i e w o f the o u t c o m e , t h e y s h o u l d be r e a d as a deliberate d e c e p t i o n designed to c o m p e l the i n v a s i o n , a n d hence a sign t h a t the j e a l o u s ' d i v i n i t y ' h a d d e c i d e d t h a t Persian
expansion
a n d hubris s h o u l d suffer a n o t h e r m a j o r reverse. 9 1 I n this w a y ,
then,
t r a d i t i o n a l m o r a l beliefs c o n c e r n i n g the c o n n e c t i o n s b e t w e e n
over-
c o n f i d e n c e a n d aggression are i n t e g r a t e d w i t h sophisticated p o l i t i c a l analysis o f i m p e r i a l i s t i c t r a d i t i o n s a n d o f the pressures o n successive kings, a n d t h e n o v e r - d e t e r m i n e d b y the m o r a l l y - g r o u n d e d i n t e r v e n t i o n o f the d i v i n e ; 9 2 the reader m a y
thus c o n c l u d e t h a t
Herodotus
c o n t e m p l a t e s ' d i v i n e phtkonos' as o p e r a t i n g here i n a m o r e w a y t h a n he has A r t a b a n u s
use i t d u r i n g the d e b a t e .
moralized
93
T h e details o f the e x p e d i t i o n f u l l y r e i n f o r c e this p i c t u r e . T h e
moral
language a n d the idea t h a t d i v i n e assistance s i g n i f i c a n t l y h e l p e d the Greeks to w i n r e c u r o f t e n . X e r x e s ' changes o f m i n d , his occasional signs o f c a u t i o n , a n d his flashes o f generosity, p i t y a n d
humanity,
d o c o m p l i c a t e the p i c t u r e a n d present a m o r e i n t e r e s t i n g figure i n the f r a m e w o r k
of human
u n c e r t a i n t y (7.13, 2 8 - 9 , 4 4 - 7 ,
101
5).91
B u t g r e a t e r emphasis is p l a c e d o n the king's a r r o g a n c e , g r a t u i t o u s c r u e l t y a n d i m p i e t y . T h e n a r r a t i v e h i g h l i g h t s the t r e a t m e n t o f Pythius the L y d i a n ( 7 . 2 7 - 9 , 3 8 - 4 0 ) , the m a r k i n g o f the b o r d e r - c r o s s i n g b y the b r i d g i n g , a n d t h e n the
flogging,
o f the H e l l e s p o n t (7.33
the t a m i n g o f A t h o s b y means o f the c a n a l (7.22
6 , 53—6),
6 , 1 1 7 - 2 2 ) , the
b u r n i n g o f temples a n d shrines (8.32 9 , 5 4 - 5 ) , a n d the k i l l i n g a n d i m p a l i n g o f defeated Greeks, (e.g., 7 . 2 3 8 , 8 . 5 3 - 4 ) . H e n c e
Herodotus'
o w n q u i e t statement t h a t 'after the g o d ' i t was the A t h e n i a n s
who
d i d m o s t t o defeat the Persians (7.139) is p l a u s i b l y e x p a n d e d b y the t w o l a t e r passages,
91
the e x p l i c i t ' o r a c l e o f B a c i s ' ,
whose
t r u t h is
On these dreams, see van Lieshout (1970), Gärtner (1983), Fornara (1999) 36 7, 42 5, Harrison (2000b) 132 7, and especially on the third dream of the olive crown, Köhnken (1988). See also Chs. 5 and 6 in this volume. There is thus no need, as does e.g., de Romilly (1977) 42-6, to make a distinction between 'religious' (as here in Herodotus) and 'political' hubris (as in Thucydides). On this point 1 agree with Cairns (1996) 15, 18. See e.g., Immerwahr (1966) 181 3, Waters (1971), 75 9, Gould (1989) 133-4; and see also Sancisi, Ch. 25, in this volume. 92
93
91
224
NICK
endorsed
by
FISHER
the h i s t o r i a n (8.77), w h i c h p r e d i c t e d t h a t at
Salamis
'Justice w i l l q u e n c h m i g h t y Excess (Koros), the c h i l d o f Hubris',
and
9i
b y the m o r a l i z e d v e r s i o n o f the e n v y o f the gods w h i c h is p r e s e n t e d p o w e r f u l l y by
Themistocles,
when
discussing G r e e k strategy
after
Salamis (8.109): ' I t was n o t w e w h o a c h i e v e d this, b u t the gods a n d the heroes, w h o
were
envious
(phthonein) t h a t one m a n
k i n g over A s i a a n d E u r o p e , a m a n w h o is i m p i o u s a n d
should
be
outrageous
(atasthalos), w h o t r e a t e d sacred a n d p r i v a t e things i n the same
way,
b u r n i n g a n d c a s t i n g d o w n the statues o f the gods, a n d w h o a c t u a l l y lashed the sea a n d b o u n d i t w i t h c h a i n s . ' W e m a y w e l l suppose t h a t H e r o d o t u s does endorse these j u d g m e n t s a n d this m o r a l i z e d v e r s i o n o f d i v i n e phthonos, t h o u g h w i t h o u t e n d o r s i n g the p o l i t i c i a n ' s m o c k modest
understatement
o f the G r e e k s ' o w n
c o n t r i b u t i o n . I t is,
of
course, o n l y a n o t h e r o f this h i s t o r i a n ' s c u n n i n g i r o n i e s t h a t this neat s u m m i n g u p o f X e r x e s ' m o r a l p u n i s h m e n t is d e l i v e r e d by the cleverest a n d m o s t m o r a l l y a m b i g u o u s o f his G r e e k characters, w h o a c c o r d i n g to H e r o d o t u s was already p l a n n i n g a possible escape r o u t e t o the c o u r t o f this same i m p i o u s a n d outrageous
Xerxes, who
con-
stantly d i s p l a y e d his g r e e d , a n d w h o was s o o n to p l a y a l e a d i n g role i n the earliest stages o f A t h e n i a n this w a y ,
precisely w h e r e w e m a y
i m p e r i a l i s m (8.112; cf. 8 . 3 ) . %
In
be c o n f i d e n t t h a t H e r o d o t u s is
a p p r o v i n g a m o r a l i z i n g j u d g m e n t w h i c h explains the v i c t o r y o f the Greeks i n t e r m s o f the i m p e r i a l i s t aggression a n d b l a s p h e m y o f t h e i r enemies, h e offers the reader the h i n t t h a t such m o r a l a n d p o l i t i c a l contrasts are as subject t o constant, yet u n p r e d i c t a b l e , change as are the p r o s p e r i t y o r sufferings o f i n d i v i d u a l s a n d the rise a n d f a l l states (1.5,
95
of
1.32).'"
On which see Immerwahr (1966) 278-9, Darbo-Peschanski (1987) 79 83, Gould (1989) 122-5, Harrison (2000b) 130-2. See, e.g., Immerwahr (1966) 199-200, 223-5, Fornara (1971a) 66-74. Dewald (1985) 53, Konstan (1987) 70-3, Raailaub (1987) 242, Gould (1989) 117-18. See especially Gould (1989) 76 82, Dewald (1998) 80-2. 9 6
97
CHAPTER T E N W O M E N IN HERODOTUS'
HISTORIES
Josine B l o k
Introduction: the importance of women in the H i s t o r i e s Herodotus'
Histories offer the reader a v i e w o f a w i d e - r a n g i n g his-
t o r i c a l process w h i c h i n v o l v e d n e a r l y t h e w h o l e i n h a b i t e d w o r l d . B y s i t u a t i n g the G r e c o - P e r s i a n w a r i n this c o n t e x t , H e r o d o t u s c o n f e r r e d a special m e a n i n g o n the i m m e n s e c o n f l i c t t h a t still g o v e r n e d
the
a c t u a l p o l i t i c a l c o n d i t i o n s o f the eastern M e d i t e r r a n e a n a n d deeply i n f l u e n c e d t h e G r e e k s ' p e r c e p t i o n s o f themselves a n d
the w o r l d .
W o m e n p l a y a salient role i n the h i s t o r i c a l w o r l d as H e r o d o t u s trays i t . T h e y p a r t a k e i n all activities t h a t f o r m the b o d y
por-
of the
Histories: t h e y rule k i n g d o m s , p r o d u c e o r n u r t u r e r o y a l c h i l d r e n , take v i t a l decisions, f o u n d oracles, serve i n s i m p l e j o b s , fall v i c t i m to w a r , take revenge, a n d p a r t i c i p a t e i n w a r f a r e . W o m e n p e r f o r m some
of
these activities o n a smaller scale t h a n m e n , n o t a b l y i n the fields o f politics a n d m i l i t a r y a c t i o n ; i n others t h e y o u t d o t h e m e n ' s
contri-
b u t i o n , p a r t i c u l a r l y w h e n t a k i n g r e s p o n s i b i l i t y f o r r e l i g i o u s observance a n d t h e p r e s e r v a t i o n o f social stability. I n t h e w o r d s o f J o h n Gould, (. . .) what is most striking throughout is what I w o u l d call the visibility of women i n the w o r l d as Herodotus presents i t , and their often paramount role i n determining what happens; this is i n stark contrast to the way i n which the public w o r l d of political action appears elsewhere i n Greek literature. (Gould (1989) 130-1) W o m e n ' s p a r t i c i p a t i o n i n t h e n a r r a t e d h i s t o r i c a l events is t h o r o u g h l y i n t e r t w i n e d w i t h a l l o t h e r aspects o f t h e Histories. H e r o d o t u s '
work
strikes t h e m o d e r n reader as holistic i n the s t r o n g i n t e r d e p e n d e n c e o f its subject m a t t e r , sources, selection, synthesis, e x p l a n a t i o n ,
and
p r e s e n t a t i o n — t h e elements t h a t c o n s t i t u t e a n y m a j o r h i s t o r i c a l w o r k . A m o n g the m u c h - d e b a t e d questions evoked b y the Histories a n d the craft o f t h e i r a u t h o r , t h e r e are f e w themes t h a t are n o t i n some w a y
226
JOSINE BLÖK
c o n n e c t e d w i t h the role o f w o m e n as a g r o u p w i t h distinct f u n c t i o n s i n society, o r w i t h g e n d e r as a f u n d a m e n t a l c a t e g o r y o f h i s t o r i c a l understanding. T h e significance o f w o m e n i n the historical n a r r a t i v e o f the Histories is o f t e n d e m o n s t r a t e d b y e n u m e r a t i n g w h e n a n d h o w w o m e n
are
m e n t i o n e d , notably b y contrast to T h u c y d i d e s ' History of the Peloponnesian War. D e w a l d ( 1 9 8 1 : 92) notes 375 references to w o m e n i n H e r o d o t u s (Cartledge
(1993) 128
m e n t i o n s 381),
as against L a t e i n e r ' s
o n l y six i n T h u c y d i d e s ((1989) 2 6 5 ; cf. G o u l d (1989) 1 2 9 - 3 0 ) . six are t h e o n l y i n d i v i d u a l w o m e n
w h o are m e n t i o n e d b y
L o r a u x counts a b o u t t w e n t y instances w h e r e T h u c y d i d e s ' w o m e n a n d c h i l d r e n ' or other anonymous w o m e n ( L o r a u x (1995)). O f history here.
findingThese name;1
mentions
collectives t h a t i n c l u d e d
course, n u m b e r s reflect c o n c e p t i o n s o f
I n w r i t i n g the history o f the Peloponnesian
T h u c y d i d e s b e s t o w e d u p o n w a r the q u a l i t y o f b e i n g -
War,
o r revealing—
the essence o f h i s t o r y , s i m u l t a n e o u s l y p r e s e n t i n g this v i e w as the objective t r u t h ( L o r a u x (1986a);
Hornblower
(1991 2 ) 5 9 - 6 6 ) . As
a
consequence, he c o n s i d e r e d t h e m o r e o r less r a t i o n a l b e h a v i o u r a n d decisions o f those w h o w e r e p o l i t i c a l l y a n d strategically responsible to be t h e decisive factors i n the h i s t o r i c a l process a n d hence
the
t h i n g s really w o r t h k n o w i n g . H i s a p p r o a c h i n e v i t a b l y p r o d u c e d a hist o r i o g r a p h y i n w h i c h w o m e n c o u l d n o t be e x p e c t e d to figure as hist o r i c a l agents. I n s t e a d they w e r e c o n c e i v e d o f as b e i n g subject t o t h e i r f e m i n i n e n a t u r e (phusis) w h i c h , b y r e p r e s e n t i n g the v u l n e r a b l e oikos side o f the w a r r i n g states, c o u l d o n l y feature as a b a c k d r o p t o w h a t was historically significant ( L o r a u x (1995); cf. W i e d e m a n n H a r v e y (1985); C a r t l e d g e (1993)). M o r e o v e r ,
(1983);
i n dealing w i t h a war
t h a t was f o u g h t a m o n g t h e Greeks themselves, T h u c y d i d e s was n o t c o m p e l l e d to take i n t o a c c o u n t c u l t u r a l d i f f e r e n c e - one o f the f o r m a t i v e factors i n H e r o d o t u s '
h i s t o r i o g r a p h y t h a t i n d u c e d the l a t t e r
to recognize w o m e n as i m p o r t a n t agents. H o w e v e r , t h e differences b e t w e e n t h e i r conceptions o f h i s t o r y o b v i ously c a n n o t be r e d u c e d to the d e m a n d s i n h e r e n t i n the subject m a t t e r o f t h e i r respective w o r k s . N e i t h e r
1
w i l l i t d o to assume
their
The priestess of Argos, Chrysis, and her successor Phaeinis (2.2.1 and 4.133.2-3, both serving chronological purposes): Archedice and Myrrhine, the daughter and wife of Hippias (6.59.3, 55.1); the mythical Procne (2.29.3), and the savage Thracian Brauro, who took part in killing her husband, the Edonian king (4.107.3); see Lateiner (1989) 265.
WOMEN I N HERODOTUS'
HISTORIES
227
thoroughly distinct social environments as an explanation o f these differences. Whatever the reasons for his particular standpoint, Herodotus presents a view of the world i n which women played a central role i n all cultural and social relations. Like Thucydides, he often mentions circumstances in which it was necessary for the men to bring 'the women and children' o f a community into a state o f safety, but the context o f the Histories gives a different meaning to the same kind of event. Herodotus never attributes the characteristics o f people as a group to nature (phusis). Instead, his emphasis on nomas (a custom o f such impact as to function as a natural law within a community) as the governing force i n people's behaviour is articulated i n an ethnography in which gender-relations, and women's activities i n particular, are among the cardinal criteria of description and evaluation (Rossellini and Said (1978)). For instance, Herodotus indicates the topsy-turvy nature of the Egyptian world by observations to the effect that i n Egypt the roles o f men and women were exactly the reverse o f those of the Greeks (2.35); and the successful resistance o f the Scythians against the Persian kings is set against the background o f their nomoi, a nomad way o f life, while in the case o f tribes such as the Massagetae and the Sauromatae the women are shown to be as valiant and independent as the men (1.205-16; 4.110-17). Although he can only use Greek practices as a norm, often implicitly, his aim is clearly to demonstrate that what is considered normal varies from one society to another. 2
3
4
W o m e n represent a kind o f seismograph o f the general condition of a civilization or society. They are essential indicators o f normality (Lateiner (1989) 135, 140) and, consequently, o f transgressions o f that normality. The notion of normality includes a moral aspect and an idea of tradition; it refers to nomas i n its practical and i n its prescriptive sense. I n the Histories, women who act in a positive way often defend the nomas against irresponsible transgressions by men,
2
Fehling (1989) 243-5 thinks that Herodotus was not at all the upper-class figure he is usually taken to have been. I do not think that this argument is of any help in understanding the structure of the Histories; a dependence on different kinds of literary genre seems to be more to the point. E.g., 1.164; 3.45; 3.97; 4.121; 4.145.2; 4.202; 5.15; 5.98; 6.16; 6.19; 6.32; 6.137; 7.114.1; 8.33; 8.36; 8.40; 8.142; cf. Dewald (1981) 121. * I have argued elsewhere that Herodotus uses the Greek myth of the Amazons to explain the nomoi of the Sauromatae, rather than to identify the Scythians as the origin of the Amazons, which is the usual interpretation of this passage (Blok (1995) 86-9). Sec also Ch. 9 in this volume. 3
228
JOSINE B L O K
as when Cyno the servant woman saves the royal child Cyrus from destruction by his own grandfather (1.110—13). Cyno's role in fact provides an example o f Herodotus' tendency to illuminate important people and events by focussing on small and apparently insignificant ones (van der Veen (1996) 23—52). Conversely, women whose agency is destructive, or who are cast in a negative light, indicate that something is rotten i n the society to which they belong (Pheretime fulfulling a long tradition o f strife and murder i n Cyrene and Barce, 4.160—2, 202-5, and the unpredictable power o f the Persian queens, a component o f dynastic autocracy; cf. Lateiner (1989) 139). The individuals who take fundamental decisions in the Histories are situated within this cultural context, moulded by Herodotus' understanding o f it. This assessment of the historical perspective created in the Histories forms one strand o f this essay. The published contributions that I shall discuss are mainly those that take this structural coherence o f Herodotus' historiography as a starting point. M y aim is to elucidate what the analysis o f women's role in Herodotus' work has contributed to our understanding of the Histories. The debate on the relationship between narrative and historical 'reality' in the Histories, which seems to have become the overarching question in Herodotean scholarship^ has been stimulated by discussions on the representations o f women. A m o n g the factors contributing to this interest are Herodotus' stories about the power and sexual freedom o f women in faraway societies. These stories have fanned the imagination of readers from antiquity to the present, but, simultaneously, they have recurrently evoked doubts, and hence questions, about the truth o f it all. Since Herodotus' account o f Babylon—the Babylonian queens Semiramis and Nitocris (1.184—5), and the practice in the same city of selling and prostituting the daughters o f citizens (1.196)—is clearly unreliable/' why should one believe his narrative about the battle o f Salamis? Another such factor is the discrepancy between Herodotus' 7
5
In the Arethusa volume on Herodotus (1987), the emphasis has shifted almost entirely towards the narrative side of the Histories. The contributors to the volume discuss specific episodes using cautionary phrases such as 'whatever may really have happened, Herodotus tells that. . .'. Yet any assessment of historical narrative is ultimately concerned with a narrative about something, an assumption which is implicitly taken for granted in much of the Arethusa volume. '' Rollinger (1993); Beard and Henderson (1997); from a different point of view Lloyd (1976) 289-91. ' See also Ch. 15 in this volume.
W O M E N I N HERODOTUS'
229
HISTORIES
views o n w o m e n ' s p r o m i n e n c e a n d w h a t is generally c o n s i d e r e d t o have b e e n the m o r e c o m m o n noted by
Gould.
What
p r a c t i c e i n Greece at t h e t i m e , as
made
Herodotus
d i f f e r e n t l y f r o m his c o n t e m p o r a r i e s ? A n d different? A n
describe the w o r l d
so
w h a t exactly is i t t h a t is
assessment o f the range o f positions t a k e n b y scholars
o n questions d e a l i n g w i t h n a r r a t i o n a n d h i s t o r i c a l process t h e r e f o r e f o r m s the second s t r a n d o f this c h a p t e r .
Approaching the theme: fact and fiction in the Histories Since t h e r e is ' n o single f o r m u l a w h i c h covers the role o f w o m e n i n H e r o d o t u s ' ( G o u l d (1989) 130), there is n o single i n t e r p r e t a t i v e f r a m e work w h i c h may accommodate subject. T h e
a l l , o r m o s t , s c h o l a r l y w o r k o n the
v a r i o u s approaches r a t h e r reflect the p r o b l e m s raised
b y the c h a r a c t e r o f H e r o d o t u s ' w o r k itself. T h e Histories seem to m e t o pose a n e x t r e m e case o f a generic q u e s t i o n a b o u t a l l h i s t o r i c a l w r i t i n g : h o w are w e to u n d e r s t a n d the r e l a t i o n s h i p b e t w e e n h i s t o r i o g r a p h y as n a r r a t i o n a n d the events i t claims to describe a n d explain? This
q u e s t i o n is b o t h m o r e
intractable and more
m i g h t appear at first glance. F o r
important
than
instance, w h e n d i s t i n g u i s h i n g the
elements t h a t t o g e t h e r m a k e u p the Histories, I m m e r w a h r
concludes
t h a t ' h i s t o r i c a l k n o w l e d g e i n H e r o d o t u s moves o n three levels: events, t r a d i t i o n s a b o u t events, a n d the h i s t o r i c a l w o r k w h i c h i n t e r p r e t s these traditions' ( I m m e r w a h r
(1966) 6). T h i s analysis gives a fine i n s i g h t
i n t o the w a y a r e a d e r experiences H e r o d o t u s '
t e x t , b u t the
under-
l y i n g p r o b l e m surfaces a g a i n i n the c h o i c e o f p r i o r i t y . E i t h e r proceeds f r o m the ' h i s t o r i c a l events a n d the t r a d i t i o n s a b o u t
one
them',
o r one ascribes the decisive role to ' t h e h i s t o r i c a l w o r k w h i c h i n t e r prets these t r a d i t i o n s ' . I n the first case, the i m p a c t o f the i n t e r p r e t a t i v e l e v e l is n o t b e l i t t l e d , b u t i t is r e g a r d e d
u l t i m a t e l y as t h e
kaleidoscope t h r o u g h w h i c h the reader is presented w i t h h i s t o r i c a l events, h o w e v e r c o l o u r e d a n d r e a r r a n g e d . C r i t i c s w h o adhere t o this position regard Herodotus
first
a n d last as a n h i s t o r i a n — p e r h a p s a
h i g h l y i m a g i n a t i v e a n d c e r t a i n l y a h i g h l y creative o n e , b u t n o n e t h e less one w h o is m a i n l y c o n c e r n e d w i t h u n d e r s t a n d i n g w h a t h a d h a p pened i n the w o r l d a r o u n d h i m , w h e n a n d w h y . T h e y value H e r o d o t u s ' n a r r a t i v e qua r h e t o r i c a l d i s c o u r s e — f o r e x a m p l e q u o t a t i o n s a n d d i r e c t speech—as
his use o f source-
a l e g i t i m a t e vehicle f o r the c o n -
veyance o f a h i s t o r i a n ' s v i e w o f h i s t o r y . O f the critics discussed h e r e ,
230
JOSINE B L O K
Tourraix
(1976), D e w a l d (1981), a n d L a t e i n e r
(1989) fall i n t o this
category. I n t h e second case, t h e emphasis shifts t o w a r d s t h e t e x t t o t h e Histories as a n a c c o u n t ( p r o b a b l y o r a l i n o r i g i n , l a t e r c o m m i t t e d t o w r i t i n g ) t h a t is essentially t h e c r e a t i o n o f a G r e e k a u t h o r . Here, Herodotus
h i m s e l f is seen first a n d last as a w r i t e r — a story-
teller. F r o m this perspective, t h e r e l a t i o n s h i p b e t w e e n his t e x t a n d the h i s t o r i c a l , outside w o r l d is m o r e
o r less i n c i d e n t a l - - a m a t t e r
r e q u i r i n g a separate, altogether d i f f e r e n t k i n d o f j u d g m e n t .
Although
the critics b e l o n g i n g t o this l a t t e r g r o u p w i l l n o t d e n y t h a t some references to r e a l , h i s t o r i c a l events w e r e i n c l u d e d i n t h e Histories, they consider this h a r d l y relevant to w h a t they see as the core o f H e r o d o t u s ' c r e a t i o n . T h i s p o s i t i o n , t h o u g h based o n w i d e l y d i f f e r i n g t h e o r e t i c a l p o i n t s o f v i e w , is here represented b y P e m b r o k e (1967), R o s s e l l i n i a n d S a i d (1978), a n d G r a y (1995) o n t h e o n e h a n d a n d , o c c a s i o n a l l y , F e h l i n g (1989 ) o n t h e o t h e r . 2
The
t w o p o s i t i o n s , a t least i n t h e i r m o s t r a d i c a l v e r s i o n s , a r e
d i f f i c u l t t o r e c o n c i l e . T h e y seem each t o b e d e f e n d e d b y critics w h o focus p r e d o m i n a n t l y o n t h e e t h n o g r a p h y / c u l t u r a l h i s t o r y c o n t a i n e d i n t h e first five books o f t h e Histories, w i t h a n occasional reference to t h e last p a r t . Scholars focussing o n single episodes, p a r t i c u l a r l y i n the last three books (here represented b y M u n s o n (1988)), appear t o be l i t t l e t r o u b l e d b y a p u l l t o w a r d s e i t h e r e x t r e m e . U l t i m a t e l y , t h e common
a i m o f m o s t critics is t o l o o k f o r a balance b e t w e e n
text
a n d e v e n t — f o r a means t o c o n n e c t H e r o d o t u s ' role as c r e a t o r o f his narrative w i t h the historical events t h a t he considered w o r t h r e c o r d i n g .
From narrative to historical agency The
recognition o f women's
central role i n the narrative structure
o f the Histories was m o r e o r less i n i t i a t e d b y E r w i n W o l f f (1964; M a r g (1965) 668^78). I n his a r t i c l e , he p o i n t s o u t t h a t H e r o d o t u s
marks
the b e g i n n i n g a n d t h e e n d o f his m a i n t h e m e — t h e c o l l i s i o n b e t w e e n the G r e e k a n d N e a r - E a s t e r n w o r l d s — w i t h p a r a l l e l stories: the episode o f t h e L y d i a n k i n g G a n d a u l e s , w h o s h o w e d his w i f e n a k e d t o his advisor a n d later successor Gyges (1.8—13), a n d t h e episode o f X e r x e s ' i n f a t u a t i o n w i t h first t h e w i f e a n d t h e n t h e d a u g h t e r o f his b r o t h e r Masistes (9.108-13). I n b o t h stories, a queen's response t o h e r h u s 8
8
For the Masistes story, see also Chs. 9, pp. 207-8 and 13, pp. 310-13 i n this volume.
W O M E N I N HERODOTUS'
231
HISTORIES
b a n d ' s irresponsible b e h a v i o u r triggers o f f a series o f disastrous events. W h a t i n d u c e d H e r o d o t u s to select precisely these stories to flank his history? W o l f f i n fact w o n d e r e d h o w a n d w h y H e r o d o t u s h a d m a d e a choice b e t w e e n d i f f e r e n t versions o f the same story. T h e
existence
o f v a r i a n t s was c e r t a i n i n the case o f the L y d i a n episode, b u t h i g h l y u n l i k e l y i n t h e case o f t h e M a s i s t e s Reinhardt's
observations
story.
Linking
his v i e w s
c o n c e r n i n g the Gyges story (1940;
to
1960;
1965), W o l f f argues t h a t the Masistes story p r o v i d e d the clue to the choice o f the Gyges v e r s i o n . I n the Persian episode, X e r x e s ' t r a n s gression o f m a r i t a l fidelity a n d the subsequent revenge o f the q u e e n o n the one w h o m
she c o n s i d e r e d the o r i g i n a l danger
to h e r
own
p o s i t i o n — M a s i s t e s ' i n n o c e n t w i f e — w o u l d u l t i m a t e l y lead to his o w n d o w n f a l l (465 BC), a finale n o t i n c l u d e d i n the Histories themselves b u t f o r e s h a d o w e d b y H e r o d o t u s a n d k n o w n t o the w h o l e w o r l d w h e n he was w r i t i n g . T h i s p a t t e r n o f events at the Persian directed Herodotus' He
royal court
selection f r o m a m o n g the v a r i o u s Gyges stories.
chose one w h i c h e n a b l e d h i m to represent the s i t u a t i o n a l o n g
s i m i l a r lines: the L y d i a n king's b e t r a y a l o f the t r u s t o f his w i f e p l a c i n g h e r i n a s i t u a t i o n close to e n f o r c e d i n f i d e l i t y , h e r
by
subsequent
insistence t h a t revenge be t a k e n against the r e a l offender a n d , after Gyges' decision t h a t C a n d a u l e s was t o b l a m e , the d o w n f a l l o f the latter a n d the succession o f Gyges. Since, a c c o r d i n g to
Herodotus.
Gyges' descendant Croesus was the first t o b e g i n ' b a r b a r i a n ' agression t o w a r d s the Greeks, the L y d i a n episode was the first i n a c h a i n o f conflicts t h a t w o u l d o n l y e n d w i t h the defeat o f X e r x e s . T h e canvas o f the G r e e k - b a r b a r i a n
vast
c o n f r o n t a t i o n thus becomes t h e c e n -
t r a l p a r t o f a t r i p t y c h , w i t h the w i n g s p o r t r a y i n g queens t a k i n g d e c i sions f a t a l to t h e i r r u l i n g b u t e r r i n g husbands. W o l f f i n t e r p r e t s these stories as narratives t h a t , as a series o f situ a t i o n s , lead to a m o r a l o f w i d e r significance: kings w h o
destroy
themselves a n d t h e i r k i n g d o m s b e g i n b y d e s t r o y i n g t h e i r o w n households. T h u s he breaks a w a y f r o m a l o n g - s t a n d i n g t r a d i t i o n w h i c h p e r c e i v e d w o m e n ' s agency i n H e r o d o t u s as s y m p t o m a t i c o f the hist o r i a n ' s f a t a l i n c l i n a t i o n t o w a r d the a n e c d o t a l . I n s t e a d he shows t h a t the l a r g e r p r o j e c t o f the Histories is represented even i n stories he h i m s e l f classifies as ' h a r e m - l o v e
stories' ( W o l f f (1965) 673).
Wolff
makes n o e x p l i c i t statements, h o w e v e r , a b o u t the c o n n e c t i o n o f these stories t o h i s t o r i c a l r e a l i t y . W h e t h e r and dramatized
H e r o d o t u s gives a H e l l e n i z e d
a c c o u n t o f s t r u c t u r a l tensions e x i s t i n g w i t h i n the
Persian r u l i n g f a m i l i e s , as a specialist o n Persian h i s t o r y has a r g u e d (Sancisi-Weerdenburg
(1983) 2 7 - 3 1 ) , o r j u s t passes o n a story t h a t
232
JOSINE B L O K
suited his fancies about Xerxes, is not a question W o l f f wants to discuss. His approach to the stories o f these royal women helps to reveal the structural coherence o f the Histories as a narrative; that is, to our understanding of Herodotus' views and the ways i n which he has moulded his material accordingly. Although Wolff's article was apparently unknown to h i m , Alexandre Tourraix (1976) was equally struck by the queen's agency i n the Candaules story, but he expanded the argument i n several ways. First, he connects the Lydian story not only to its counterpart concerning Xerxes and his queen, but also to about fifty other stories in the Histories which reveal a similar pattern. According to Tourraix, episodes such as those o f the Athenian tyrant Pisistratus marrying the daughter o f Megacles (1.60), the Corinthian tyrant Periander keeping alive the memory of his dead wife Melissa (5.92), the succession o f Cyrus to the royal throne through his mother (the Median princess Mandane, 1.107-8), Cambyses gaining power over Egypt through the daughter o f pharaoh Apries (3.1—3), and, negatively, the male Babylonians losing power through the killing o f the women o f their city (3.150), demonstrate that i n monarchical societies power exercised by men is only legitimate and lasting i f it includes the feminine and is transferred through it. The feminine may be represented by a goddess (see for instance Athena's protection o f Peisistratus at Pallene, 1.62) or another kind of feminine power, but most often it is incorporated in the wife, sister, or daughter o f the predecessor. There is a strong tie, implicit but effective, between the person o f the queen and royal power itself (Tourraix (1976) 370—1). By acting as the indispensable intercessors between men's generations, women were to perform a role that was at once dynamic and consolidating. Woman, or femininity, is the guarantee, mortal or immortal, of the solidity of Power, particularly in its monarchical forms: she thus fulfils two complementary and fundamental functions, by simultaneously assuring both the transmission and the permanence of Power. (Tourraix (1976) 369, tr. J. B.). Thus T o u r r a i x perceives not only a common structure i n the opening and closing scenes, as W o l f f had done, but also an intermittent series o f similarly structured events throughout the Histories. The recurrence o f this pattern again demonstrates the strong compositional coherence o f the Histories. Episodes such as the ones on royal succession should be understood, not as digressions, but as instances signifying the meaning of the whole.
W O M E N I N HERODOTUS'
The
second w a y i n w h i c h T o u r r a i x
233
HISTORIES
expanded the a r g u m e n t
was
b y a s c r i b i n g to this p a t t e r n a w i d e r m e a n i n g t h a n W o l f f , w h o
had
l i m i t e d his i n t e r p r e t a t i o n to the level o f n a r r a t i v e i n the strict sense. According
to T o u r r a i x ,
the r e c u r r e n c e o f the p a t t e r n i n b o t h
the
G r e e k a n d O r i e n t a l societies exemplifies H e r o d o t u s ' v i e w t h a t b e h i n d c u l t u r a l differences some h i s t o r i c a l c o n d i t i o n s c o m m o n to a l l m a n k i n d m a n i f e s t themselves. O n e between
monarchy
such feature is the f u n d a m e n t a l difference
and democracy
(or, i n a w e a k e r
sense, a r i s t o c -
racy). T h i s d i f f e r e n c e overrides the d i s t i n c t i o n s b e t w e e n , say, a n d G r e e k i n t h e i r effects o n t h e vicissitudes o f p o w e r . G r e e k t y r a n t s i n t h e same c a t e g o r y
9
Persian
Placing the
as t h e N e a r - E a s t e r n
kings,
classification b y the y a r d s t i c k o f m o n a r c h y puts ' b e i n g G r e e k ' as the alleged n o r m o f c i v i l i z a t i o n i n t o perspective. M o r e o v e r , t h e p a t t e r n i m p l i e s a n i d e a o f m a t r i l i n e a r succession as a p r e r e q u i s i t e to p a t r i l i n e a r succession, hence p r e c e d i n g i t e i t h e r i n t i m e o r i n f o r c e . M a n y generations o f a n c i e n t historians have a r g u e d t h a t the m a n i f e s t c o n n e c t i o n s b e t w e e n (Eastern) m o n a r c h y a n d f e m i n i n e p o w e r i n the Histories was a clear sign, i n the eyes o f the a n c i e n t Greeks a n d weakness
of modern
scholars e q u a l l y ,
of that monarchy's
a n d inclination towards capricious tyranny;
see S a n c i s i - W e e r d e n b u r g that Herodotus'
(1983). I n c o n t r a s t , T o u r r a i x
for
fatal
examples,
now
argues
i d e a o f the f e m i n i n e basis o f m o n a r c h i c a l
represents a w i d e l y h e l d v i e w o n essential connections between
power women
a n d the h i s t o r i c a l change o f p o l i t i c a l systems. T o u r r a i x is c a r e f u l n o t to c o m m i t h i m s e l f to a j u d g m e n t
as t o w h a t r e a l l y h a p p e n e d ,
he insists t h a t H e r o d o t u s conveys a n o t i o n i n w h i c h n a t i o n s East a n d
West strongly believed,
and
which
thus h a d
but both
gradually
become part of the Greek perception of history. T h r o u g h o u t the Histories Herodotus applies a mythical scheme w i t h an aetiological value, which he derived from a common fund o f Greek ideas and w h i c h echoed a mental structure [that was partly related to] I n d o - I r a n i a n cosmologies. (Tourraix (1976) 380; tr. J. B.).
'•' In this context the Constitutional Debate (3.80 2) is a fine example of the notion that political patterns are universal; compare Herodotus' comment that those who would not believe that Otanes, a Persian, had advocated democracy in this Debate would be astonished to learn that Mardonius founded democracies in various cities on the Ionian coast (6.43).
234
JOSINE B L O K
T h e i n t e r a c t i o n b e t w e e n m a t r i l i n e a r a n d p a t r i l i n e a r pressures i n the t r a n s m i s s i o n o f p o w e r , as T o u r r a i x
sees i t , recalls the o l d e r h y p o t h -
esis o f m a t r i a r c h y . Since the s c h o l a r l y e x c o m m u n i c a t i o n
o f its m o s t
i n f l u e n t i a l spokesman, J . J . B a c h o f e n (Das Mutterrecht, 1861), the t h e m e o f m a t r i a r c h y has b e e n c o n s i d e r e d a t r i c k y affair a m o n g a n c i e n t hist o r i a n s ( B l o k (1995) 6 3 - 1 1 2 ) . A t the t i m e o f T o u r r a i x ' s a r t i c l e , h o w ever, m a t r i a r c h y was b e c o m i n g fashionable a g a i n i n some f e m i n i s t circles, a n d this interest d i d n o t escape the n o t i c e o f professional hist o r i a n s . T o u r r a i x ' s p a p e r was p u b l i s h e d i n the Dialogues d'histoire ancienne, w h i c h , t r u e to its n a m e , i n c l u d e d a c r i t i c a l response, a n d Jacques Annequin,
who
responded
to T o u r r a i x ,
i m m e d i a t e l y raised o b j e c -
tions w h i c h clearly a i m e d at e r a d i c a t i n g a n y m a t r i a r c h a l i m p l i c a t i o n . Tourraix,
t h o u g h d e f e n d i n g his a r g u m e n t , hastened to
acknowledge
t h a t his use o f the terms ' m a t r i a r c h a l society' a n d ' m a t r i l i n e a r h a d been i m p r u d e n t ( T o u r r a i x
(1976) 3 8 9 ) .
brought f o r w a r d by A n n e q u i n
c o n c e r n e d the r e l a t i o n s h i p
10
One
filiation'
o f the objections
n a r r a t i v e a n d r e a l i t y . W h a t d i d H e r o d o t u s really k n o w
between
about
the
practices a n d t r a d i t i o n s w h i c h lay b e h i n d the stories t o l d h i m b y his Near-Eastern informants? H o w
c o u l d we k n o w t h a t the p a t t e r n
of
b e l i e f i n t h e f e m i n i n e basis o f m o n a r c h i c a l p o w e r was t r u l y as w i d e s p r e a d as T o u r r a i x
c l a i m e d i t to be? W a s
it not just a
H e r o d o t e a n i d e a p r o j e c t e d o n t o the outside w o r l d ? W a s
Greek/ not
the
s t o r y - p a t t e r n o f the p o w e r f u l q u e e n used t o conceal a social r e a l i t y in which w o m e n Tourraix
were
i n fact the objects o f m a r r i a g e
exchange?
r e p l i e d t h a t o n e s h o u l d l o o k at p o l i t i c a l relationships n o t
o n l y f r o m the outside, b u t also f r o m inside the society itself. M o r e o v e r , a l t h o u g h c u t t i n g l'histoire des mentalités o f f social h i s t o r y m i g h t be a risky step, i t was sometimes necessary to start w i t h a n analysis historical 'mentalities' ( T o u r r a i x An
of
(1976) 3 8 9 - 9 0 ) .
a d d i t i o n a l c o n c l u s i o n m i g h t be t h a t this i d e a o f the h i s t o r i c a l -
p o l i t i c a l role o f w o m e n represents a v i e w o f the w o r l d t h a t was n o t u n i q u e to H e r o d o t u s b u t one t h a t he shared w i t h the w h o l e o f the ancient w o r l d . Thus it w o u l d women's
n o t be H e r o d o t u s '
of
h i s t o r i c a l i m p o r t a n c e , b u t r a t h e r the h i s t o r i o g r a p h i c a l t r a -
dition beginning w i t h Thucydides
that needed explanation. Such an
i n f e r e n c e is close to the c o n c l u s i o n s d r a w n
10
presentation
by
Carolyn
Dewald,
The use made of Tourraix's article is interesting: Dewald (1981) 114, Munson (1988) 92, and Lateiner (1989) mention it but use it less than would suit their respective arguments; Gray (1995) does not refer to it at all.
W O M E N I N HERODOTUS'
235
HISTORIES
d e f e n d i n g d i e most positive v i e w o f H e r o d o t u s ' description o f w o m e n ' s historical p r o m i n e n c e to date ( D e w a l d (1981)). O f course she a c k n o w l edges a difference b e t w e e n n a r r a t i v e a n d r e a l i t y , b u t t h e s t r u c t u r e o f h e r a r t i c l e d r a w s all o u r a t t e n t i o n to the w o r l d as i t m a y
have
existed b e y o n d H e r o d o t u s ' text: ' [ a ] real effort is m a d e . . . to describe w o m e n as t h e y w e r e , o r at least as H e r o d o t u s t h i n k s they m u s t have b e e n ' ( D e w a l d (1981) 92). D e w a l d classifies H e r o d o t u s '
descriptions
o f ' w o m e n as t h e y w e r e ' a c c o r d i n g to t h e k i n d s o f agency t h e y disp l a y i n the Histories, a d d i n g the n u m b e r o f occasions o n w h i c h each occurs. T h u s she argues t h a t ' w o m e n
who
d o n o t act' (128
occa-
sions) b u t passively p a r t i c i p a t e i n events (e.g., b e i n g u n a b l e to bear c h i l d r e n , b e i n g g i v e n a w a y i n m a r r i a g e , o r b e i n g w a r victims) 'become a m o t i f r e p e a t e d l y e m p h a s i z i n g the t h i n l i n e t h a t i n a n c i e n t societies separated c u l t u r a l s u r v i v a l f r o m c u l t u r a l e x t i n c t i o n . ' ( D e w a l d (1981) 9 3 ; cf. L a t e i n e r o n ' n o r m a l i t y ' above). ' W o m e n w h o act' (212
cases),
either i n groups o r i n d i v i d u a l l y , c a r r y o u t a l l k i n d s o f actions i n c o m p l e m e n t a r y balance w i t h t h e i r m e n ' s
a c t i o n s , c o n f o r m i n g w i t h the
expectations o f the same c u l t u r e , t h o u g h i n a d i f f e r e n t m o d e .
They
are, first a n d f o r e m o s t , the ones w h o m a i n t a i n the nomas; c h i l d r e n usually take after t h e i r m o t h e r s i n m a t t e r s o f c u l t u r e ( C a r i a n
women
m a r r i e d t o I o n i a n s , 1.146; A t t i c w o m e n m a r r i e d to L e m n i a n s , 6 . 1 3 8 ; the S a u r o m a t a e l i v i n g m o r e like A m a z o n s , 4.117). T h e
individual
w o m e n w h o act i n the p u b l i c sphere (22 cases) ' f r e q u e n t l y . . . a r t i c ulate the social values t h a t u n d e r l i e t h e i r actions' ( D e w a l d 108), thus r e i n f o r c i n g the t r a d i t i o n a l n o r m s w h i c h m a y have to be at risk at t h a t p a r t i c u l a r m o m e n t .
The
(1981) come
62 w o m e n w h o act as
priestesses a n d f o u n d e r s o f religious cults are representatives o f the d i v i n e o r d e r i m p o s e d o n m a n k i n d a n d are t h e r e f o r e n o t ble to the f o r m e r D e w a l d ((1981)
compara-
group. 111)
perceives
in Herodotus'
r e n d e r i n g o f exis-
tence d i s t i n c t b u t c o n n e c t e d spheres o f a c t i v i t y — n a t u r e , society a n d c u l t u r e , d i v i n i t y . She
does n o t relate these spheres to a
temporal
s t r u c t u r e , a l t h o u g h she recognizes t h a t the female c u l t - f o u n d e r s a n d priestesses recall m y t h i c a l times ( D e w a l d (1981) 118, n . 27; cf. V a n d i v e r (1991)). Y e t the reader o f the Histories senses t h a t the patterns o f c u l t u r e u n d e r l y i n g the events o n the surface o f h i s t o r y h a d b e e n c r e ated l o n g b e f o r e , 1 1 a n d are
1
firmly
f o u n d e d i n religious n o t i o n s t h a t
Cf. Lateiner (1989) 186: '. . . social structure determines a nation's political fate,
236
JOSINE BLOK
define the l i m i t s o f h u m a n b e h a v i o u r .
Women
g u a r d this t r a d i t i o n ( D e w a l d (1981) 119
n . 30), a n d L a t e i n e r
are the ones
who (1989)
does j u s t i c e t o these r e l a t i o n s h i p s b y p l a c i n g ' t h e subject o f w o m e n ' b e t w e e n ' l i m i t , transgression, a n d r e l a t e d m e t a p h o r s ' a n d ' m o r a l p r i n ciples i n h i s t o r y ' . T h e s e are i n fact G r e e k i d e a s ; 1 - i n this c o n t e x t i t is o n l y
fitting
that in Herodotus'
Egypt,
the alleged opposite
of
G r e e c e , ' w o m e n are n o t d e d i c a t e d t o the service o f a n y g o d o r g o d dess' ( 2 . 3 5 ) . 1 3 B u t H e r o d o t u s seems to have f o r g o t t e n a b o u t this w h e n a p p l y i n g the same scheme ( r e l i g i o n = v e r y a n c i e n t = w o m e n ' s first p r i o r i t y ) t o several G r e e k oracles a n d cults: t h e y o r i g i n a t e d i n v e r y ancient Egypt a n d w i t h Egyptian 2.51-8;
14
cf. L e t o ' s o r a c l e , 2 . 1 5 2 ,
w o m e n (e.g., D o d o n a a n d 155;
the T h e s m o p h o r i a e ,
Siwa, 2.171;
t e m p l e o f A t h e n a at L i n d u s , 2 . 1 8 2 ) . Nevertheless, w o m e n , b e i n g the e m b o d i m e n t o f social a n d r e l i g i o u s t r a d i t i o n , t h u s transfer h i s t o r i c a l c u l t u r e i n t o the a c t u a l events. T h i s c o n n e c t i o n b e t w e e n t h e past a n d t h e p r e s e n t is p a r t i c u l a r l y e x e m p l i f i e d b y ' w o m e n w h o act' t h r o u g h o u t the G r e e k a n d b a r b a r i a n w o r l d . H e r o d o t u s ' r e n d e r i n g o f w o m e n ' s h i s t o r i c a l agency, a c c o r d i n g t o D e w a l d ,
is due t o the f a c t t h a t his
descriptions are n o t yet d e f i n e d b y the conventions o f a genre ( D e w a l d (1981) 91). H o w e v e r , o t h e r critics o f H e r o d o t u s ' t e x t argue t h a t the v e r y o p p o s i t e is the c a s e — a n a r g u m e n t t o w h i c h I shall n o w
turn.
From historical agency to narrative W h i l e w o m e n p a r t i c i p a t e o n the l e v e l o f n a r r a t i v e p r o p e r , a c t i n g e i t h e r i n g r o u p s o r i n d i v i d u a l l y , t h i s n a r r a t i v e is s i t u a t e d w i t h i n Herodotus' Here,
w o r l d - v i e w , o f w h i c h his e t h n o g r a p h y is a m a j o r p a r t .
even m o r e t a n t a l i z i n g t h a n i n the case o f m o r e s t r i c t l y 'his-
t o r i c a l ' episodes, i t is o f t e n d i f f i c u l t t o assess t h e r e l a t i o n s h i p b e t w e e n H e r o d o t u s ' a c c o u n t a n d the w o r l d he describes. A r e ' t r u t h ' a n d its
although Herodotus has not yet found the theoretical and abstract terminology to express it so concisely'. On the Greekness of the idea of women's influence 'long ago', see Pembroke (1967) and below, pp. 237-9. As hiratai gym oudemia is translated by A. D. Goldey (Loeb-ed.). According to Lloyd (1976, ad toe), Herodotus means to say that in Egypt women could not perform the functions of a Greek hiereie: sacrifice and various tasks concerning the conditions of and around the temple. Cf. Zografou (1995); Lloyd (1976) ad be; compare Fehling (1989 ) 65-70, who points out the implausibility of this passage. 12
13
14
2
W O M E N I N HERODOTUS'
237
HISTORIES
opposite ' f i c t i o n ' adequate terms by w h i c h t o j u d g e H e r o d o t u s ' descriptions o f societies t h a t w e r e far r e m o v e d space?
O f t e n the b o r d e r l i n e b e t w e e n
f r o m his o w n i n t i m e
ethnography
events is h a r d l y d i s c e r n i b l e , as i n the case o f T o m y r i s ,
or
and historical the
Scythian
q u e e n w h o defeated C y r u s (1.205—16). W h a t m i g h t the a c t i o n o f this v a l i a n t q u e e n have to d o w i t h the p r o m i s c u i t y h e r society was r e p u t e d to practise? I n a n a r t i c l e t h a t s t i m u l a t e d a n e w a p p r o a c h to H e r o d o t e a n s t u d ies, S i m o n P e m b r o k e (1967) first makes a c a r e f u l d i s t i n c t i o n b e t w e e n Bachofen's
theories a n d the evidence
o n w h i c h they were
based.
A l t h o u g h H e r o d o t u s h a d c e r t a i n l y n o t b e e n B a c h o f e n ' s o n l y source, the Histories o c c u p y the m o s t p r o m i n e n t place i n the e t h n o - h i s t o r i c a l c o r p u s , o f t e n c o m p r i s i n g the m o s t extensive a c c o u n t , the oldest c o m plete a c c o u n t o r even t h e o n l y e x t a n t a c c o u n t o f a g i v e n people o r event.
In a number
Herodotus'
o f representative
cases, P e m b r o k e
compares
v e r s i o n w i t h o t h e r descriptions o f the same s i t u a t i o n , f o r
instance the r e p u t e d m a t r i l i n y o f t h e L y c i a n s (1.173; f o r a f u l l assessment
o f this case, see P e m b r o k e (1965)). T h e
decisive
b e t w e e n his o w n v i e w a n d t h a t o f B a c h o f e n is t h a t , i n a
difference metaphor
f r o m b i o l o g i c a l research, B a c h o f e n t h o u g h t he h a d f o u n d fossils w h i l e P e m b r o k e sees the same evidence as descriptions o f fossils ( P e m b r o k e (1967) 8). T h i s o b s e r v a t i o n changes the n a t u r e o f the evidence
from
i n d i c a t i o n s o f a h i s t o r i c a l r e a l i t y i n t o elements b e l o n g i n g to a discourse. M a t r i a r c h y , m a t r i l i n y , p r o m i s c u i t y , a n d s i m i l a r p h e n o m e n a — ' a n c i e n t descriptions c a n n o t s i m p l y be s u b s u m e d u n d e r the categories of modern examples
anthropology'
( P e m b r o k e (1967) 2 3 ) — a l l a p p e a r to be
o f societies whose
r e p u t e d existence
served t o
represent
alternatives to G r e e k j&o&-life as H e r o d o t u s a n d his c o n t e m p o r a r i e s k n e w i t . T h e s e alternatives i n c l u d e d situations b o t h i n Greece
and
outside i t — f o r instance w o m e n ' s p o l i t i c a l r i g h t s i n A t h e n s w h e n the strife b e t w e e n A t h e n a a n d P o s e i d o n for o v e r l o r d s h i p o f the c i t y was n o t yet d e c i d e d , o r m a t r i l i n y i n L y c i a . T h e value a t t r i b u t e d to these alternatives c o u l d be p o s i t i v e , r e c a l l i n g the g o l d e n times o f C r o n u s , o r negative, i n d i c a t i n g chaos u n d e r a r u l e o f w o m e n , b u t m o s t o f t e n consisted o f a m i x t u r e o f the t w o . As t o t h e i r l o c a t i o n i n t i m e , the alternatives w e r e usually h e l d to be deep i n the past i n the case o f G r e e c e , b u t still to be p a r t o f the present i n the case o f societies elsewhere i n the w o r l d . I n this respect some c o n g r u i t y seems t o have existed b e t w e e n H e r o d o t u s ' v i e w o f time a n d space a n d t h a t o f scholars o f the e i g h t e e n t h a n d n i n e t e e n t h c e n t u r i e s — i n c l u d i n g J .
Lafitau
238
JOSINE B L O K
and Lewis H .
Morgan,
a n d o t h e r evolutionists such as B a c h o f e n (see
also P e m b r o k e (1977)). C o m p a r i s o n between Pembroke's views a n d those o f T o u r r a i x (who does n o t refer t o h i m ) c l e a r l y shows
how
the a r g u m e n t s
d i f f e r e n t d i r e c t i o n s . B o t h critics agree t h a t the alleged
point in
prominence
o f w o m e n i n k i n s h i p a n d p o l i t i c s — a n d Pembroke's discussion includes v a r i o u s kinds a n d degrees o f sexual licence as w e l l — i n the past a n d elsewhere exists first o f a l l i n the eye o f the b e h o l d e r ; t h a t is, i n the eye o f H e r o d o t u s a n d his c o n t e m p o r a r y Greeks. W h a t T o u r r a i x calls 'a m y t h i c a l s c h e m e
w i t h an
aetiological value'
is v e r y close
to
P e m b r o k e ' s ' s t r u c t u r e o f alternatives'. T h e n a r r a t e d relations b e t w e e n t h e sexes represent a n i m a g i n e d s o c i o - c u l t u r a l s t r u c t u r e , w h i c h the Greeks c o n s i d e r e d to be effective i n b o t h G r e e k a n d n o n - G r e e k societies. T h i s s t r u c t u r e is d e f i n e d b y T o u r r a i x as a religious e l e m e n t
of
politics a n d b y P e m b r o k e as a m a t r i x to give t i m e a n d space a p o l i t ical m e a n i n g . H o w e v e r , t h e i r ways p a r t i n the m e a n i n g they a t t r i b u t e to 'reality'; the difference m a y seem slight, b u t i t is i m p o r t a n t . T o u r r a i x argues t h a t H e r o d o t u s ' ' m y t h i c a l scheme' m a y derive u l t i m a t e l y f r o m a religious t r a d i t i o n c o m m o n Mediterranean practices. T h e comparable
to the N e a r East a n d t h e
w h i c h m u s t have b o r n e p a t t e r n revealed i n the
eastern
some r e l a t i o n to h i s t o r i c a l fifty-odd
stories reflects some
reality, however indirect, twisted and changed
have b e c o m e t h r o u g h the p r i s m o f m y t h .
it
P e m b r o k e , o n the
may other
h a n d , makes a n essential d i s t i n c t i o n b e t w e e n the m y t h i c a l p a t t e r n s o f m a t r i a r c h y a n d the r e a l i t y t h a t the stories c l a i m to reflect. points out that the models
o f ' a l t e r n a t i v e societies' are f a r
He
more
schematic t h a n the h i s t o r i c a l practices to w h i c h t h e y profess t o refer: ' [ n o ] c o h e r e n t r e l a t i o n c a n b e established b e t w e e n the p a t t e r n o f fact a n d the p a t t e r n o f t r a d i t i o n ' ( P e m b r o k e (1967) 35). So n o single type of reality may
be assumed t o be reflected i n a s i m i l a r instance
of
' m y t h i c a l ' r e p r e s e n t a t i o n , a n d ' i t is i n every case the precise n a t u r e o f the r e l a t i o n b e t w e e n
fact a n d d e s c r i p t i o n w h i c h m u s t be
ascer-
t a i n e d ' ( P e m b r o k e (1967) 23). I n s u m , P e m b r o k e is the first to call f u n d a m e n t a l l y i n t o question the r e l a t i o n s h i p b e t w e e n H e r o d o t u s ' n a r r a t i v e a n d the w o r l d he claims to p o r t r a y , n o t because o f H e r o d o t u s ' alleged ' l y i n g ' a b o u t
the w o r l d (cf. F e h l i n g (1989 2 ) b u t because
of
the i n t e r n a l r e f e r e n t i a l i t y o f his text as p a r t o f w h a t a m o u n t e d
to
general G r e e k values. Relations
between
Herodotus' world-view
and historical reality
have dissolved a l m o s t e n t i r e l y i n a n u m b e r o f p u b l i c a t i o n s t h a t elab-
W O M E N I N HERODOTUS'
239
HISTORIES
orate t h e idea o f ' t h e a l t e r n a t i v e ' . 1 ' 1 M i c h è l e Rossellini a n d S u z a n n e S a i d (1978) analyse Herodotus' demonstrate monogamy,
t h e m o d e l o f a l t e r n a t i v e societies u n d e r l y i n g
ethnography
o n a w i d e r scale t h a n P e m b r o k e .
t h a t t h e 'uses o f w o m e n ' polygamy
They
( m e a n i n g t h e degrees
of
to promiscuity) were linked w i t h patterns o f
b e h a v i o u r i n o t h e r codes, n o t a b l y diet (vegetarian, m i l k - d r i n k i n g , c a n n i b a l i s m ) , sacrifice, a n d b u r i a l . M o r e o v e r ,
t h e f u r t h e r t h e society i n
q u e s t i o n was r e m o v e d f r o m t h e c i v i l i z e d c e n t r e , t h e m o r e t h e Greeks' u n d e r s t a n d i n g o f t h e rules g o v e r n i n g such codes t e n d e d t o be c o n fused o r i n v e r s e d , o r t o disappear altogether. I n this w a y a m e n t a l m a p c o u l d be d r a w n t o designate t h e w a y i n w h i c h H e r o d o t u s
would
describe a n d estimate t h e c u l t u r e o f a p e o p l e , a c c o r d i n g t o its area o f residence. H e r o d o t u s '
d e s c r i p t i o n has a c e r t a i n l o g i c , a sense a n d
a m e a n i n g , b u t u l t i m a t e l y has n o t h i n g t o d o w i t h r e a l i t y (Rossellini a n d S a i d (1978) 1 0 0 3 - 4 ) . T h e t h e o r e t i c a l c o n c e p t o f ' a l t e r i t y ' o r ' o t h erness', w h i c h holds t h a t t h e u n d e r s t a n d i n g o f the ' o t h e r ' is b o u n d b y necessity t o use o n l y t e r m s t h a t refer t o oneself—a t h e o r y w h i c h was to g a i n m o m e n t u m a f e w years after R o s s e l l i n i a n d Said's p u b l i c a t i o n 1 0 — i s o n l y h i n t e d at at t h e v e r y
end o f their article. T h e
a u t h o r s ' views are m o r e representative o f t h e Parisian a p p r o a c h t o m y t h (Rossellini a n d Said (1978) 9 5 0 - 3 ) . T h i s includes a n a w a r e ness o f m y t h ' s a b i l i t y t o subsume a great v a r i e t y o f p h e n o m e n a i n its structures, thus g i v i n g m e a n i n g t o t h e w o r l d , r a t h e r t h a n the o t h e r way
r o u n d , a n d a p p l y i n g this m e a n i n g t o a w i d e r area t h a n t h e
themes o f t h e m y t h i c a l n a r r a t i v e itself. A l t h o u g h they refer t o P e m b r o k e ' s views, Rossellini a n d S a i d m o v e in a somewhat
different direction. O n
the one h a n d ,
our under-
s t a n d i n g o f w o m e n ' s roles i n H e r o d o t u s ' e t h n o g r a p h y is e n r i c h e d b y t h e i r r e v e a l i n g t h e systematic c o n n e c t i o n s w i t h o t h e r c u l t u r a l codes. The
m e a n i n g o f gender i n the larger historiographical context c a n
thus be e x p l o r e d ; c o m p a r e f o r instance L a t e i n e r (1989) o n ' e t h n o g r a p h y as access t o h i s t o r y ' a n d ' h i s t o r i o g r a p h i c a l p a t t e r n i n g ' . O n t h e other hand,
this w i d e r v i e w o f c u l t u r a l space goes h a n d i n h a n d
w i t h a d i m i n i s h i n g v i e w o f t h e d y n a m i c s o f t i m e ; i n t h e perspective o f R o s s e l l i n i a n d Said's a r g u m e n t , there seems t o be h a r d l y a n y h i s t o r y left i n t h e Histories. I n d e e d , H e r o d o t u s '
|D
w o r l d - v i e w appears also
See also Ch. 15, pp. 365-7, in this volume. "' The best-known example of this approach in the case of Herodotus, is Hartog (1980).
240
JOSINE
BLOK
to be e n t i r e l y H e l l e n o c e n t r i c , the opposite o f w h a t h a d been
sup-
posed b e f o r e . Because H e r o d o t u s defines all f o r m s o f ' b a r b a r i a n ' c u l t u r e b y the n a t u r e a n d extent o f t h e i r b e i n g n o n - G r e e k , t a k i n g the a d u l t , m a l e G r e e k c i t i z e n f o r a n o r m a n d t h e r e b y sustaining a G r e e k barbarian/male-female polarity, any similarities between Greek a n d n o n - G r e e k societies as represented i n the Histories have n o t h i n g t o d o w i t h any u n d e r l y i n g , h i s t o r i c a l c o n g r u e n c e , b u t are o n l y the result o f a n essentially H e l l e n o c e n t r i c r e p r e s e n t a t i o n o f the w o r l d . Although
a i d i n g impressively o u r u n d e r s t a n d i n g o f the ways
which Herodotus
in
was c o n s t r a i n e d b y the l i m i t a t i o n s o f his k n o w l -
edge w h e n a p p r o a c h i n g o t h e r s , the c o n c e p t o f ' a l t e r i t y ' as a m o d e l , a n d its c o n c o m i t a n t methods, also poses severe limitations. Theoretically, a n d taken to an e x t r e m e degree, t o insist o n the u l t i m a t e self-referentiality o f Herodotus'
w o r l d - v i e w — a charge t h a t c o u l d be l e v e l l e d
at a n y text-—renders the w h o l e enterprise o f w r i t i n g h i s t o r y r a t h e r pointless. O n
a m o r e p r a c t i c a l l e v e l , the 'discourse o n the O t h e r ' is
liable to be a p p l i e d t o o s c h e m a t i c a l l y . W i t h the overt p u r p o s e c r i t i c i z e such p r a c t i c e s , V i v i e n n e
G r a y analyses some o f the
to
more
f a m o u s stories ( i n c l u d i n g the story o f the w i f e o f C a n d a u l e s , a n d t h a t o f X e r x e s a n d Masistes' wife) i n o r d e r to d e m o n s t r a t e t h a t the o p p o s i t i o n G r e e k - b a r b a r i a n , m a n - w o m a n was t o o simplistic ( G r a y (1995)). G r a y c o n c l u d e s t h a t the n a r r a t i v e m o d e l o f the ' v e n g e f u l
queen'
requires the i n c l u s i o n o f the ' v e n g e f u l k i n g ' a n d ' v e n g e f u l
servant'
as w e l l . T h i s
narrative m o d e l exemplifies an u n d e r l y i n g political
m o d e l w h i c h complicates a
Greek/democratic—barbarian/monar-
chic p o l a r i t y b y a d d i n g a b a r b a r i a n - m a s t e r / b a r b a r i a n - s u b j e c t p o l a r i t y ( G r a y (1995) 201). A l t h o u g h G r a y a t t e m p t s t o m i t i g a t e the discourse o n p o l a r i t y b y d r a w i n g D e w a l d ' s a p p r o a c h i n t o the discsussion, t h e o u t c o m e still strikes t h e reader as b e i n g q u i t e schematic. A
m o r e satisfactory w a y
o f u s i n g the p o l a r i t y - m o d e l f o r subtler
ends h a d been c r e a t e d a f e w years e a r l i e r b y R o s a r i a M u n s o n
(1988;
n o t m e n t i o n e d b y G r a y ) . I n a n a d m i r a b l e discussion o f A r t e m i s i a , the female t y r a n t o f Halicarnassus a n d h e r roles as X e r x e s ' a n d as c o m b a t t a n t i n the B a t t l e o f Salamis, M u n s o n
advisor
shows the r e -
c u r r e n t s h i f t i n g o f p o s i t i o n s , w h i c h destabilizes a n y fixed m e a n i n g o f ' s e l f a n d 'other', a n d definitely u n d e r m i n e s a polarized view. A r t e m i s i a is b o t h
female
and masculine,
Greek and
enemy,
cunning
and
victorious; she fights o n X e r x e s ' side b u t is almost a double o f T h e m i s tocles. I n d e e d ,
although Artemisia
tified w i t h a topsy-turvy
does e v e n t u a l l y b e c o m e
w o r l d , threatening to Hellas,
iden-
that w o r l d
W O M E N I N HERODOTUS'
241
HISTORIES
resembles Athens more than it does Persia (Munson (1988) 94). Arguing that Artemisia shows a remarkable similarity to Athens, Munson demonstrates that the Athenian political ideal o f isegoria encourages people to pursue their own interests, on the grounds that this is likely to benefit the whole community. I n problematic circumstances, however, individuals clearly give up the community to serve their own ends, as indeed 'fhemistocles considered doing i f the Greeks failed to resist Xerxes at Salamis. The very same attitude marks Athenian policy after Salamis and the city's subsequent pursuit of its own interests, ultimately at the cost of the community of allied cities. Artemisia also exemplifies the moral-political insight that the use of one's gnome (intelligence) brings greater benefits than enjoying tuche (good fortune). This view draws attention to possible connections between Herodotus and the sophists, and, with greater certainty, to critical judgments of the political attitude of Athens during the 430s and 420s (Munson (1988) 102-5). Munson thus infers that Herodotus' audience was expected to see the Artemisia story in the light of the later consequences of Salamis, just as W o l f f concluded that the story of Masistes and his wife (and the wife of Gandaules) were to be seen in the light of Xerxes' later death. It is impossible to say how much of Herodotus' account of Artemisia is his own invention. This remains true of anything he reports for which there is no other source available. Artemisia does not belong to the category of ethnography, but neither is she unequivocally historical. She must have been a famous figure, but obviously Herodotus could not know anything about her secret advice to Xerxes (8.68-9; 101-2), and Fehling gives little credit to the way in which the account of Artemisia's role at Salamis is introduced (Fehling (1989 ) 127). From this perspective, Munson's discussion remains firmly on the 'narrative' side. Yet it is her careful analysis of the wider political and philosophical issues at stake in the Artemisia episode that allows a connection to be made between Herodotus the creative story-teller and the historical world in which he lived. 2
Conclusion Quite early in Book Five, a small story is inserted on the situation in Miletus some time before the Ionian revolt. Ridden with stasis, the Milesians ask the Parians to create peace among them. The
242
JOSINE B L O K
P a r i a n envoys visit t h e w h o l e t e r r i t o r y o f M i l e t u s , h n c l i n g m o s t oikoi c o m p l e t e l y w a s t e d b u t c o l l e c t i n g the names o f those whose lands are w e l l t i l l e d . H a v i n g r e t u r n e d to the c i t y , the Parians a p p o i n t the o w n ers o f the w e l l - t i l l e d lands to be the n e w rulers o f M i l e t u s because, they say, these p e o p l e w o u l d p r o b a b l y take as m u c h care o f p u b l i c affairs as they d i d o f t h e i r o w n (5.29). T h i s v i e w seems to have been a c o m m o n one i n the G r e e k w o r l d ; i n A t h e n s i t was v o i c e d o n t h e stage b y C r e o n , speaking to his son H a e m o n , i n Sophocles' Antigone: ' T h e m a n w h o acts r i g h t l y i n f a m i l y m a t t e r s w i l l be seen to be r i g h t eous i n the city as w e l l ' ( 6 6 1 - 2 ) . "
T h e r e is h a r d l y a p o l i t i c a l t h e o r y
i n classical A t h e n s t h a t does n o t take t h e oikos as a p o i n t o f d e p a r t u r e f o r u n d e r s t a n d i n g t h e polis as a c o m m u n i t y a n d a state. I t seems t h a t H e r o d o t u s m o d e l f o r t h e polis w h e n
used this perspective o n the oikos as a s h a p i n g his h i s t o r y . T h e
n o v e l t y o f his
a p p r o a c h m a y be f o u n d i n his a p p l i c a t i o n t o h i s t o r y o f a m o d e l t h a t was b e i n g s c r u t i n i z e d , d e b a t e d , p a r o d i e d , a n d a p p l i e d i n m a n y o t h e r contexts a n d genres. T h e
m o d e l i n c l u d e d m u c h to guide his selec-
t i o n o f e t h n o g r a p h i c a l features: genealogy (of peoples a n d i n d i v i d u als), m a n n e r s
of livelihood, burial,
s a c r i f i c e , sexual c u s t o m s ,
and
g e n d e r e d d i v i s i o n o f l a b o u r . I t e n a b l e d h i m to u n d e r s t a n d the r e l a tions b e t w e e n m e n a n d w o m e n as m u t u a l l y d e p e n d e n t , even t h o u g h each sex h a d p r i o r i t i e s a n d weaknesses
o f its o w n . I t l e d h i m
to
expect t h a t the m o s t i n f l u e n t i a l i n t e r v i e w s w o u l d take place b e h i n d closed d o o r s . I t even p r o v i d e d h i m w i t h a g o o d e n t r y i n t o t h e l a r g e r t h e m e o f the Persian W a r s w h i c h , because i t was i n s p i r e d b y H o m e r ' s epic tale o f T r o y , i n c l u d e d d o m e s t i c r e l a t i o n s h i p s . H e
a p p l i e d this
m o d e l w i d e l y i n his h i s t o r y , a n d t h e efforts o f m o d e r n critics to disc e r n w h e r e a n d h o w he d i d so b e a r t e s t i m o n y to his v e r s a t i l i t y . F e w historians f o l l o w e d his e x a m p l e i n a n t i q u i t y , b u t his audience p r o b a b l y f o u n d his w r i t i n g s n o t o n l y e x c i t i n g a n d e n j o y a b l e , b u t p e r f e c t l y comprehensible.
17
On the influence of dramatic styles in Herodotus, see Lateiner (1989) 20-34 and Ch. 6 in this volume.
T H E HISTORIES
AS
NARRATIVE
CHAPTER ELEVEN
NARRATIVE UNITY A N D UNITS Irene J. F. de Jong
Introduction: 'harmonious body' versus 'the work of scissors' I n the first century BC the literary critic Dionysius of Halicarnassus enthusiastically concludes that Herodotus τάς πολλάς και ουδέν έοικυίας υποθέσεις προελομένφ σύμφωνον έν σώμα πεποιηκέναι.
having chosen a number of subjects which are in no way alike has made them into one harmonious 'body'. 1
Some twenty centuries later the German scholar Jacoby reaches a totally different verdict: After he had taken up the plan to write the work and had devised the structure which he wanted to impose on the material he had gath ered, he apparently did not make major changes to his manuscripts, but tried to use his collection of lectures as much as possible as it stood . . . The distribution over the work of the Greek login which deal with the times before the Persian Wars also appears to be essentially the work of scissors.These quotations illustrate the two positions which divide the liter ary scholarship on Herodotus. According to some, Herodotus has managed to create a unified work regardless of the exact way in which his work came about, by piecing together old material or by gradually collecting and processing an ever-expanding body of material. 3
1
Letter to Gnaeus Pompeius, 3. (1913) 361: 'Offenbar hat er (Herodotus), nachdem er einmal den Gedanken an das Werk gefasst und den Plan gefunden hatte, dem er sein gesammeltes Material unterwerfen wollte, . . ., an seinen Manuskripten größere Veränderungen nicht vorgenommen, sondern sich bestrebt, seinen Bestand an Vorträgen möglichst in der vorhandenen Form zu verwerten . . . Auch die Verteilung der hellenischen Logoi, soweit sie vorpersische Geschichte gaben, über das Werk hin, erscheint wesentlich als Arbeit mit der Schere.' AH translations are mine, unless otherwise indicated. For an overview of the debate on the genesis of the text, see Fornara (1971a), 2
3
246
IRENE J. F. DE JONG
A c c o r d i n g to others, he has f a i l e d a n d the sheer q u a n t i t y o f his m a t e r i a l has got the better o f h i m . A f t e r J a c o b y ' s fiercely negative assess m e n t at the b e g i n n i n g o f this c e n t u r y , the p e n d u l u m has s w u n g b a c k a g a i n , a n d scholars have d e m o n s t r a t e d H e r o d o t u s ' t h o u g h t f u l arrange m e n t o f his m a t e r i a l , w h i c h has r e s u l t e d i n , i f n o t 'one
harmonious
b o d y ' , at least some f o r m o f u n i t y . I n the first p a r t o f this c h a p t e r I w i l l give a h i s t o r i c a l o v e r v i e w o f the ways i n w h i c h scholars have defended Herodotus'
unity, concentrating o n f o r m a l rather than the
m a t i c a r g u m e n t s . 4 I n the second p a r t I w i l l discuss the various devices w h i c h H e r o d o t u s e m p l o y s to create u n i t y . I n the last p a r t I w i l l s h o w the w o r k i n g o f such devices in a specific passage. B e f o r e e m b a r k i n g o n the discussion p r o p e r , I w a n t to m a k e one p o i n t . M a n y m o d e r n discussions o f a n c i e n t w o r k s i a b o u r u n d e r anachronistic, nineteenth-century,
concept o f unity. W h i l e I
an
would
n o t go as far as H e a t h (1989), w h o argues t h a t a n c i e n t poetics a n d poetical practice adopt a centrifugal rather than a centripetal con c e p t i o n o f u n i t y , I w o u l d stress t h a t a n c i e n t l i t e r a r y taste does
show
a greater tolerance t o w a r d s — i n d e e d a n a p p r e c i a t i o n o f — t h e episodic, ecphrastic, a n d d i g r e s s i o n a l . 3 I t is absolutely c r u c i a l to keep this i n m i n d w h e n discussing the u n i t y , o r lack o f i t , i n H e r o d o t u s '
Histories.
Herodotus' unity: the arguments T h i s section m u s t b e g i n w i t h J a c o b y , w h o has set the agenda f o r a l l scholars t o c o m e .
T h i s a g e n d a consists m a i n l y o f t w o i t e m s :
Histories lack (i) a u n i f y i n g subject a n d (ii) a u n i f y i n g s t r u c t u r e . (i). I n his p r o e m H e r o d o t u s announces c o n f r o n t a t i o n b e t w e e n Persians
the Ad
t h a t his subject w i l l be the
a n d G r e e k s , b u t this subject is v i r
t u a l l y absent i n the first f o u r b o o k s , w h i c h deal almost
exclusively
w i t h the c o n f r o n t a t i o n b e t w e e n Persians a n d o t h e r b a r b a r i a n s ((1913) 3 3 3 - 4 1 ) . Ad (ii). I n the first five books the m a i n story (the g r o w t h
who rightly stresses (pp. 6-7) that the unity or 'coherence' of a work as we have it, need not say anything about the manner of its origin. Exponents of this second type of defence are Regenbogen (1930b) and Schadewaldt ((1934) 1960). See also Ch. 1 in this volume. A central notion, which recurs often in ancient discussions of Herodotus, is ποικιλία, 'variation'. Cf., e.g., Dionysius, LMkr to Pompeius, 3: ποικίλην έβουλήθη ποιήσαι την γραφήν. It is this variation which allows the author to insert a great deal of digressional material. 1
5
247
N A R A T I V E U N I T Y A N D UNITS
o f Persian p o w e r ) is c o n t i n u o u s l y i n t e r r u p t e d b y Exkurse. T h i s struct u r e is a weakness: the digressions 'slow d o w n ' o r ' d i s r u p t ' the m a i n story, p o p
u p at s u r p r i s i n g m o m e n t s ,
H e r o d o t u s was n o t able to present
and contain material w h i c h
at the ' r i g h t ' m o m e n t
((1913)
379-92). One
o f the first to d e f e n d H e r o d o t u s '
i n the folktale elements
u n i t y was A l y .
H i s interest
i n H e r o d o t u s l e d h i m to p u t f o r w a r d
o r i g i n a l suggestion as to the s t r u c t u r e o f the Histories: the
first
an five
books are a f r a m e n a r r a t i v e (Rahmenerzählung), a f o r m w h i c h H e r o d o t u s d e r i v e d f r o m o r i e n t a l , folktale l i t e r a t u r e . 6 T h i s idea even p r o m p t e d the p r o v o c a t i v e thesis t h a t , as u s u a l , the f r a m e d narratives (Jacoby's d i s r u p t i v e digressions) are m o r e i m p o r t a n t t h a n the f r a m e itself. The
i d e a o f t h e Histories as a f r a m e n a r r a t i v e was
independently
p r o p o s e d b y H o w a l d , w h o also f o u n d evidence o f this structure i n the later b o o k s . ' T h e r e the f r a m e is m o r e i m p o r t a n t t h a n (überwuchert) the f r a m e d n a r r a t i v e s . T h i s idea p u t f o r w a r d b y A l y a n d H o w a l d is n e i t h e r c o n v i n c i n g 8 - -tin a real f r a m e n a r r a t i v e , the f r a m e is sketchy a n d the f r a m e d narratives are i n d e p e n d e n t stories, peopled b y different characters t h a n those o f the f r a m e - n o r p a r t i c u l a r l y h e l p f u l . I n fact, t h e y consider i t a m e r e e x p e d i e n t f o r the h i s t o r i a n to i n c o r p o r a t e as m u c h m a t e r i a l as possible, o r , i n H o w a l d ' s w o r d s , as 'a loose, r a n d o m f r a m e , w h i c h is n o t o r g a n i c a l l y related to w h a t is r e c o u n t e d , i n w h i c h H e r o d o t u s c o u l d place 'his m a n i f o l d m a t e r i a l ' ((1923)
128).
W h e r e J a c o b y saw H e r o d o t u s as a hasty a n d n o t too p r o f i c i e n t e d i t o r o f his o w n w o r k , A l y a n d H o w a l d present h i m as a naive storyteller w h o is c a r r i e d a w a y b y his o w n stories. 5 A n o t h e r dubious Frankel.
He
defence
of Herodotus'
suggests t h a t H e r o d o t u s '
s t r u c t u r e comes
from
m a n y digressions s h o u l d
seen i n the l i g h t o f his t i m e : early G r e e k m a n
be
t e n d e d to l o o k at
things i n i s o l a t i o n , a n d was n o t interested in l a r g e r causal o r l o g i cal r e l a t i o n s , b u t o n l y i n d i r e c t c o n n e c t i o n s ( ( 1 9 2 4 - 6 0 ) 82 3). T h i s m e n t a l i t y is reflected i n the ' s t r u n g - a l o n g style' o r Xefyq etpouevn, already Frankel,
described by A r i s t o t l e (Rhetoric I I I . 9 ) , w h i c h , a c c o r d i n g
to
d e t e r m i n e s n o t o n l y the s t r u c t u r e o f sentences b u t o f the
w o r k as a w h o l e :
" (1921) 260-2. 297 8; (1929) 66. (1923) 128-30; (1945) 42. 7
8
Cf. the criticism o f I m m e r w a h r (1966) 13.
9
See, in particular, Aly (1921) 262 and H o w a l d (1945) 41 3.
248
IRENE J. F. DE JONG
I f the people of this age really liked to see and represent things i n such a way, that every element counts as complete i n itself and, irrespective o f its place w i t h i n the structure, displays the independent value of its free and stable existence, . . . then the overall structure of the work of art must aim at the pleasure of fullness and colourfulness, quantity and variety . . . l u W h i l e this i n f l u e n t i a l thesis o f H e r o d o t u s ' p a r a t a c t i c s t r u c t u r e appears to be a step f o r w a r d , i n t h a t i t tries to u n d e r s t a n d the Histories i n t e r m s o f early G r e e k t h o u g h t a n d l i t e r a r y t a s t e , 1 1 i t still p a i n t s a p i c ture o f H e r o d o t u s
randomly
i n s e r t i n g digressions w h i c h are
s u p e r f i c i a l l y c o n n e c t e d to his m a i n
story.
only
12
A n a m b i g u o u s c o n t r i b u t i o n to the ' u n i t y ' debate comes f r o m Focke. He
v i g o r o u s l y denies t h a t H e r o d o t u s was j u s t a s t o r y - t e l l e r ,
whose
o n l y a i m was to keep his audience a m u s e d (the p o s i t i o n o f A l y Howald):
'he has p r i n c i p a l l y n o t h i n g i n c o m m o n
G r e e k n a r r a t o r s ' ((1927) 52).
He
and
w i t h o r i e n t a l or
is a n h i s t o r i a n , w h o
employs
the
succession o f five o r i e n t a l despots as t h e m a i n s t r u c t u r e o f his Histories. H o w e v e r , w h a t Focke gives w i t h one h a n d (structure), he takes w i t h the other: 'The
five
great o r i e n t a l kings h a v e b e c o m e the m a i n f o r -
m a l carriers o f all o f H e r o d o t u s '
m a t e r i a l , reservoirs, i n t o w h i c h the
s t u f f o f n a r r a t i v e has b e e n p o u r e d i n such q u a n t i t i e s t h a t i t spills o v e r o n a l l sides.' 1 3 A
new metaphor,
t u r e as d r a w n b y A l y
and H o w a l d and their frame
Not
b u t essentially the same p i c narrative.
u n t i l we c o m e to P o h l e n z d o we see a t u r n i n g p o i n t i n the
debate. H e
i d e n t i f i e s a u n i f y i n g subject (the c o n f r o n t a t i o n s
between
Greeks a n d b a r b a r i a n s ) , a n d argues t h a t t h e first f o u r books n o t o n l y serve this subject ( i n t h a t t h e y set o u t h o w
10
the m a i n o p p o n e n t
of
'Wenn wirklich die Menschen dieser Zeit die Dinge so zu sehen und darzustellen liebten, daß jedes für sich voll gilt und unabhängig von seiner Einordnung den eigenen Wert seines freien und festen Daseins ausstrahlt, . . . so muß der Gesamtaufbau eines Kunstwerks auf den Reiz von Fülle und Buntheit, von Masse und Wechsel gestellt sein . . .' " Fränkel's 'the pleasure of fullness and colourfulness, quantity and variety' reflects the concept of ποικιλία (see note 5). At times, Frankel does not entirely succeed in suppressing his own—modern—taste, e.g., on pp. 85, 88 ('Und doch hat auch der Herodot des grossen Perserkriegs die Darstellung gewaltiger Ereignisse mit klein lichen Anekdoten in einer Weise gespickt, die uns zuwider ist und zuwider sein darf', my italics), 95. Frankel ((1924) 1960) 86. I n this context the idea of the frame narrative pre sents itself again, see Frankel ((1924) 1960) 87. (1927) 25: 'Die fünf großen Asiaten sind jetzt die formalen Hauptträger des gesamten herodotischen Materials, Sammelbecken, in die der Stoff in solchen Massen hineingeschüttet ist, daß er nach allen Seiten über ihre Ränder quillt.' 12
13
249
NARATIVE UNITY A N D UNITS
the G r e e k s , the Persians, a t t a i n e d t h e i r p o s i t i o n o f p o w e r ) , b u t also c o n t a i n e n o u g h r e m i n d e r s t o keep t h a t subject i n the f o r e f r o n t the reader's m i n d ((1937) 9-21). H e
is also t h e first to stress t h a t
r a t h e r t h a n d r o w n i n g helplessly i n his m a t e r i a l , H e r o d o t u s selects i t , p a s s i n g o v e r w h a t
of
consciously
is n o t r e l e v a n t t o his subject ((1937)
2 9 , 31 ) . ' * As f o r the digressions, P o h l e n z argues t h a t t h e i r p u r p o s e is t o e x p l a i n t h e m a i n story ((1937) 39, 42), a n d t h a t t h e y are n o t i n s e r t e d at r a n d o m , b u t at p o i n t s w h e r e the m a i n story needs t h e m , i . e . , w h e n a n e w p e r s o n , p e o p l e , o r l o c a t i o n has t o be i n t r o d u c e d ((1937) 6 8 - 7 3 ) . An 5.55
example Herodotus
w i l l illustrate the progression made b y Pohlenz. i n t e r r u p t s his tale o f A r i s t a g o r a s '
visit t o
w h i c h t o o k place i n 4 9 9 a n d w h i c h was a i m e d at p e r s u a d i n g Athenians
to j o i n the I o n i a n r e v o l t , f o r a ' d i g r e s s i o n ' o n
h i s t o r y (chapters 55-96), w h i c h covers the years 5 1 0 - 4 9 9 B C . i n g t o J a c o b y ((1913) 383) typical example
a n d F r a n k e l (((1924) 1960)
o f the w a y H e r o d o t u s
Herodotus
Accord-
86), this is a
uses a w e a k m o t i v e ('a his-
Herodotus
mate-
contends t h a t this is one o f the places w h e r e
inserts a h i s t o r i c a l digression w h e n
' i n the fifth book
the
Athenian
torical meeting') i n order to include thematically independent rial. Pohlenz, however,
At
Athens,
the a c t i o n needs i t :
i t is l o g i c a l f r o m a h i s t o r i c a l p o i n t o f v i e w t h a t
i n f o r m s his readers a b o u t
the p o l i t i c a l s i t u a t i o n w h i c h
Aristagoras finds i n A t h e n s ' ((1937) 41). I n d e e d , b y the t i m e H e r o d o t u s picks u p his m a i n story, the digression has m a d e
i t clear w h y
the
A t h e n i a n s — i n c o n t r a s t t o t h e S p a r t a n s — w i l l be p r e p a r e d t o j o i n t h e I o n i a n s a n d fight the Persians ((1937) 38). P o h l e n z sums u p his i d e a o f H e r o d o t u s '
narrative procedure
as
follows: He is a traveller who knows exactly where he wants to go, who has exactly plotted the main stages of his voyage and keeps to them, but who also allows himself the time to look at all beautiful and interesti n g things w h i c h the road offers, and needs not even be afraid to make long detours to this end, because he knows that he will eventually rejoin the m a i n road at the right p o i n t . ' 1 11
This point is later worked out by Lateiner (1989) 59 75. (1937) 43: 'Er ist der Wanderer, der genau weiß, wohin er schließlich kommen will, auch genau die Hauptstationen seines Weges vorher festgelegt hat und innehält, der sich aber dabei Zeit laßt, um alles Schöne und Interessante, das die Gegend bietet, zu betrachten, und selbst lange Seitenwege zu diesem Zwecke nicht zu scheuen braucht, da er weiß, daß er die Hauptstraße am richtigen Punkte wieder erreichen wird.' 15
250
IRENE J. F. DE JONG
This metaphor of Herodotus the traveller seems to do him and the Histories more justice than any previous label (story-teller, frame narrative) or metaphor (reservoir). A somewhat curious interlude i n the 'unity' debate is the study by Myres. In his view, Herodotus' structure is not problematic at all. The plan of the whole work is 'simple', in that the Histories consist o f two parts: 'a narrative of the struggle between Persians and Greeks, from the Ionian Revolt to the defeat of Xerxes' invasion (5.28-9), preceded by a retrospect o f the origin o f the quarrel between East and West, and the Rise o f the Persian empire and the leadingGreek states, Athens and Sparta (1-5.27)' ((1953) 60). W i t h i n these parts two structural principles are at work: the 'antistrophic' principle, which means that we find two parallel narratives (e.g., the Athenian and Spartan histories at 1.59-64 and 65-8, or the longaccounts o f Scythia, 4.1-144, and Libya, 4.145-205), and the 'pedimental' principle, which means that we find a climax in the centre, preceded and followed by episodes which prepare for it and reveal its consequences (e.g., at 1.65-8, where Lycurgus' meeting with the Pythia is the prologue, the meeting between Lichas and the blacksmith o f Tegea the epilogue, and the military confrontation between Sparta and Tegea the centre)."' The problem with this kind of structural analysis is that it is highly subjective. Often the structure is there only i n the eye of the beholder; at 1.65-8 why not make the scene o f Lichas and the blacksmith the climax?" I t is also ultimately unhelpful; i n comparison with Pohlenz's analysis, the observation that 'the visits o f Aristagoras to Sparta, 5.39-54, and to Athens, 5.55-97, serve as the frame for explanatory retrospects of both cities' ((1953) 78) is a regression. T h e second turning point (after Pohlenz) is Immerwahr. He detects both a subject ('the history o f Persian power and aggressiveness i n a well-defined period in which aggression affected the Greeks') and a structure (the Histories consists o f a series o f logoi, narrative units which are usually demarcated by ring-composition, which vary i n
"' For the 'antistrophic' principle, see Myres (1953) 62, 78; for the 'pedimcntal' principle (1953) 62, 81-8. " The following remark by Myres is in fact revealing: 'This peclimental structure, deep-seated and all-embracing though it is, has escaped the notice even of literary critics, probably because the literary skill of Herodotus has so completely united the substance of history with its form' ((1953) 86-7, my italics).
251
N A R A T I V E U N I T Y A N D UNITS
l e n g t h a n d w h i c h m a y themselves consist o f smaller logoi).
18
The
over-
all s t r u c t u r e o f the logoi is p a r a t a c t i c , yet they d o f o r m a u n i t y i n t h a t t h e y share n a r r a t i v e patterns (there are d r a m a t i c a n d c i r c u l a r 19
logoi)
a n d t h o u g h t p a t t e r n s ( ' t h o u g h t a n d a c t i o n ' , 'rise a n d fall
a ruler', etc.).20 I n Immerwahr's
analysis,
the p a r a t a c t i c style
of has
g a i n e d i n p o w e r ; i t is n o t the p r o d u c t o f a n i n q u i s i t i v e b u t u n s t r u c t u r e d m e n t a l i t y (Franker), b u t r a t h e r a sophisticated l i t e r a r y a n d historiographical instrument. T h e years t h a t f o l l o w e d saw the p u b l i c a t i o n o f t w o studies o n the digressions, w h i c h b o t h e x p a n d a n d r e f i n e Pohlenz's defence o f these passages. T h e
first
is B o r n i t z , w h o sets o u t to s h o w t h a t the histor-
ical digressions ( n o t a b l y those o n G r e e k h i s t o r y i n Books O n e ,
Five,
a n d Six) are closely c o n n e c t e d t o one a n o t h e r a n d to the m a i n story. With
r e g a r d t o passage 5.55
seamlessly
97,
he notes ((1968)
106
9) h o w
it
c o n t i n u e s t h e h i s t o r y o f A t h e n s , w h i c h was s t a r t e d at
1 . 5 9 - 6 4 (there we h e a r d a b o u t A t h e n s b e c o m i n g a t y r a n n y Peisistratus, here H e r o d o t u s recounts h o w
under
this t y r a n n y was p u t to
a n end); h o w this episode m a r k s the b e g i n n i n g o f the r i v a l r y hostilities b e t w e e n
Athens and
Sparta,
w h i c h will determine
behaviour i n the ensuing Persian W a r s ; a n d h o w A t h e n s ' b r i e f
and their
flirtation
w i t h Persia (5.73) casts a d u b i o u s l i g h t o n t h e i r later pious o a t h t h a t t h e i r m e n t a l i t y is such t h a t they w o u l d never consider s i d i n g w i t h the Persians The
(8.144).
second study is by C o b e t , w h o argues t h a t the
(ethnograph-
ical a n d geographical) digressions n o t o n l y serve to e x p l a i n the m a i n story, b u t also e n r i c h i t , i n t h a t t h e y c o n t a i n m a t e r i a l w h i c h is itself o f interest. H e r o d o t u s s i m p l y cast his net w i d e , i n a n effort to i n c l u d e e v e r y t h i n g he c o u l d find a b o u t the k n o w n w o r l d : thus Herodotus introduces the large logoi not only i n order to make clear w h i c h people caused certain events, but m u c h more simply, because events draw attention to something that i n itself deserves our interest—because the context points to i t , not because the context demands i t . 2 1
"' For the structure, see Immerwahr (1966) 17-45 (quotation from p. 44). for the subject (1966) 14 15. Immerwahr (1966) 46-72. Immerwahr (1966) 72-8. (1971) 156 7: 'Und so führt Herodot die großen Logoi nicht allein dafür ein, um verständlich zu machen, welches Volk solches Geschehen möglich machte, sondern viel einfacher lenkt das Geschehen den Blick auf etwas, das selbst Aufmerksamkeit 19
20
21
252
IRENE J. F. DE JONG
A n e n t i r e l y d i f f e r e n t d i r e c t i o n was i n d i c a t e d b y W a t e r s . H e stresses t h a t t h e Histories is a n a r r a t i v e ( w h i c h means t h a t the historical digressions m a y be seen as
flashbacks;
a n i m p r o v e m e n t over Exkurse)
and
p o i n t s to the H o m e r i c epics as a n i m p o r t a n t m o d e l for H e r o d o t u s ' structure: [the Odyssey] presents a model o f ingenious construction w i t h its double thread and its elaborate flash-back technique. These structural methods, together w i t h the range o f the Odyssey, its time-span o f twenty years, its geographical extent, its ethnology (e.g., Cyclops!) and gallery of OwuaaTcc, make i t an obvious comparison with the history and certainly a source o f suggestions as to narrative structure. 22
A l t h o u g h H e r o d o t u s ' dependence o n H o m e r m e n t i o n e d i n passing b y s c h o l a r s ,
23
h a d previously been
this was t h e first t i m e i t was used
to get a b e t t e r g r i p o n H e r o d o t u s ' h a n d l i n g o f his m a t e r i a l .
Unfor-
t u n a t e l y , W a t e r s spoils t h e effect o f this n e w a p p r o a c h b y r e t a i n i n g the o l d i d e a o f H e r o d o t u s as the i n v e t e r a t e story-teller: [ T h e tales o f Tellus and Clcobis and Biton are inserted because] Herodotus perhaps thought he could tell [them] better than the current market-place retailers. Artists tend to do what they like doing, especially i f they get paid for it, and Herodotus likes to tell tales. ((1974) 6-7) A n o t h e r i m p o r t a n t c o n t r i b u t i o n is a small article by C a r b o n e l l , w h i c h has n o t r e c e i v e d t h e a t t e n t i o n i t deserves. H i s thesis is t h a t t h e struct u r i z i n g p r i n c i p l e i n H e r o d o t u s is t i m e : I t is not space w h i c h orders and organises the Histories. I t is time which turns it into a rigorously chronological work, even i f that rigour requires some apparent disorder. 24
At
first
g l a n c e , this is h a r d l y a r e v o l u t i o n a r y i d e a , 2 ' b u t w h e n we
r e v i e w t h e s c h o l a r s h i p s u m m a r i z e d so f a r , w e see t h a t i t h a d n o t
beansprucht, sicherlich weil der Zusammenhang darauf führt, aber nicht, weil der Zusammenhang es verlangt.' (1974) 3, and cf. (1985) 61-70. For example, Jacoby (1913) 377, 380, Aly (1921) 266, and Thomson (1935) 224-7. See also Ch. 5 in this volume. (1985) 145: 'Ce n'est pas l'espace qui ordonne et organise les Histoires. C'est le temps qui en fait une oeuvre rigoureusement chronologique, même si cette rigueur exige un apparent désordre.' Clearly, Carbonell, who does not place his own contribution within the context of the 'unity' debate, is himself unaware of the contentious nature of his thesis. 22
23
24
25
N A R A T I V E U N I T Y A N D UNITS
253
previously been proposed. Indeed, Frankel h a d emphatically rejected t i m e as a s t r u c t u r i z i n g p r i n c i p l e : As regards Herodotus, i n his w o r k time is completely lacking as a means of connecting the many things from many countries about which he has something to say. This is surprising in a historian, but as has
often been observed, he simply has no interest in chronology. One could even say that he and the archaic period to which he still partly
belongs has no sense at all of the ceaseless march of time . . . Herodotus does not hesitate to stop time: he reports on completely different things, describes, say, a country and its inhabitants in many, many pages, and only when he is quite finished w i l l he let time roll on. N o r is he afraid of reversing the chronological order. 2 6 Elsewhere (de J o n g (1999) 2 3 0 - 4 1 , (2001)) I suggest t h a t H e r o d o t u s ' r e l a t i v e disinterest i n r e a l , e x t r a - t e x t u a l c h r o n o l o g y m a y have caused scholars t o close t h e i r eyes to t i m e as a n i n t r a - t e x t u a l p r i n c i p l e . I n the case o f F r a n k e l , i t also seems t h a t his f i r m ideas a b o u t the m i n d o f a r c h a i c m a n have d e t e r m i n e d his p o s i t i o n . E x p a n d i n g the suggestions o f W a t e r s a n d C a r b o n e l l , I p r o p o s e to call H e r o d o t u s ' struct u r e ' a n a c h r o n i c a l ' : like H o m e r , he has r e s t r i c t e d the t i m e span
of
his m a i n story, b u t has i n c l u d e d a m u c h l a r g e r p e r i o d i n the f o r m o f a n a c h r o n i e s : analepses (flashbacks) a n d prolepses ( f l a s h f o r w a r d s ) . 2 7 H e has developed this technique b y c h a n g i n g its scale a n d c o m p l e x i t y . T h u s he includes m a n y m o r e a n d , above a l l , m u c h longer anachronies, a n d c o m p l i c a t e s t h e m b y p u t t i n g t h e m i n the m o u t h s o f b o t h n a r r a t o r a n d characters (whereas i n H o m e r t h e y t e n d to be v o i c e d o n l y b y the characters). T h i s Herodotus'
thesis c o n s i d e r a b l y m o d i f i e s t h e i d e a
of
s t r u c t u r e b e i n g p a r a t a c t i c ; the elements o f his story d o
n o t f o l l o w each o t h e r like beads o n a s t r i n g b u t are p l a c e d i n a
26
((1924) 1960) 85: 'Was zunächst Herodot betrifft, so fehlt bei ihm fast ganz, als Bindemittel zwischen den vielen Dingen die er aus vielen Ländern zu berichten weiß, die Zeit. Bei einem Historiker nimmt das wunder; aber er hat nun einmal für Chronologie, wie das schon oft ausgesprochen ist, kein Interesse. Man kann sogar sagen, daß ihm, und der archaischen Epoche zu der er halb nocht gehört, der Sinn für die rastlos fortschreitende Zeit überhaupt abgeht... Es kostet Herodot keine Überwindung die Zeit anzuhalten: er berichtet von ganz anderen Dingen, schildert z.B. ein Land und seine Geschichte auf vielen, vielen Seiten unserer Bücher, und erst wenn er damit fertig ist, läßt er sie weiterrollen. Und er kennt auch keine Scheu vor der Umkehrung der Zeitenfolge.' Cf. also Lateiner (1989) 114. The term 'anachronies' derives from Genette (1980) 35-6: 'the various types of discordance between the two orderings of story [= the events in their chronological order] and narrative [= the events in the order we read them in the text]'. 27
254
IRENE J, F. DE JONG
t e m p o r a l perspective, the past a n d f u t u r e i l l u m i n a t i n g the p r e s e n t . 2 8 T h e c o n c e p t o f ' a n a c h r o n i c a l s t r u c t u r e ' o n l y accounts f o r the hist o r i c a l digressions. W h a t a b o u t the e t h n o g r a p h i c a l a n d g e o g r a p h i c a l ones? O n c e a g a i n , the fact t h a t the Histories is a n a r r a t i v e a n d is m o d e l l e d o n the H o m e r i c
epics is o f p r i m e i m p o r t a n c e . A l l n a r r a -
tives c o n t a i n d e s c r i p t i o n s , even t h o u g h , as H a m o n ((1993) 9- 36) shows, l i t e r a r y critics have always h a d a p r o b l e m w i t h this 'strange' e l e m e n t . I n fact, H a m o n ' s c h a r a c t e r i z a t i o n o f the t y p i c a l descripteur, suits H e r o d o t u s
perfectly:
He is a voyager, a tourist, an explorer, someone w i t h a scientific mission or who travels i n order to learn or to fill i n a gap i n institutionalized knowledge. 2 9 Specifically, there is the p r e c e d e n t o f descriptions i n H o m e r
(e.g.,
A c h i l l e s ' shield i n II. 1 8 . 4 7 8 - 6 0 8 , o r Calypso's cave i n Od. 5 . 6 3 - 7 5 ) . Erbse (1992: 157 -79) suggests—convincingly—that H e r o d o t u s
'derived
f r o m the H o m e r i c ekphraseis the r i g h t t o discuss g e o g r a p h i c a l questions i n the c o n t e x t o f a n a r r a t i v e , t h a t is t o say o f a h i s t o r i c a l n a r rative' ((1992) 157). 3 ( l H e also shows h o w i n most cases the i n f o r m a t i o n o f a g e o g r a p h i c a l or e t h n o g r a p h i c a l d e s c r i p t i o n is relevant to w h a t follows. T h u s the l e n g t h y d e s c r i p t i o n o f S c y t h i a ( 4 . 5 - 3 1 ) w i l l a l l o w the narratees to u n d e r s t a n d w h y D a r i u s ' e x p e d i t i o n against this p e o ple fails. I c o n c l u d e t h a t a p p r o a c h i n g the Histories as a n a r r a t i v e a n d l o o k i n g at the H o m e r i c epics as a m o d e l has m u c h e n h a n c e d o u r a p p r e c i a t i o n o f its s t r u c t u r e . H e r o d o t u s has a d o p t e d the m o d e l o f a m a i n story e x p a n d e d b y analepses, prolepses, a n d descriptions, a n d enlarged its scale. T h e
analepses a n d prolepses i n t r o d u c e the necessary b a c k -
g r o u n d i n f o r m a t i o n o n people a n d places, w h i l e the descriptions set the stage o n w h i c h the events o f the m a i n story w i l l be p l a y e d o u t o r p r o v i d e the narratees w i t h the i n f o r m a t i o n w h i c h t h e y n e e d t o appreciate w h a t follows. Before t u r n i n g t o the next p a r t — a n d i n the spirit o f
Herodotus
h i m s e l f — I w o u l d like to insert a digression o n the terms a d o p t e d b y scholars w h e n t a l k i n g a b o u t n a r r a t i v e units w i t h i n the Histories.
2 8
For further examples, see Ch. 22, pp. 501-4 in this volume. (1993) 38: 'c'est un voyageur, un touriste, un explorateur, quelqu'un d'investi d'une mission scientifique ou qui voyage pour apprendre ou pour combler une case vide du savoir institutionnalisé.' See also Ch. 18, pp. 415-16 in this volume. 29
3(1
255
N A R A T I V E U N I T Y A N D UNITS
Narrative units: the terminology T h e r e are three t e r m s w h i c h are r e g u l a r l y used i n the scholarship o n H e r o d o t u s to refer to n a r r a t i v e u n i t s w i t h i n the Histories: logos, digression (Exkurs), a n d n o v e l l a . A n d
yet each o f the three terms is
problematic. I n the case o f logos, we m u s t d i s t i n g u i s h b e t w e e n the use o f the t e r m b y H e r o d o t u s (a section i n his w o r k w h i c h m a y be o f v a r y i n g length) a n d by scholars themselves, w h o o f t e n f a i l to m a r k the dis t i n c t i o n : the i n d e p e n d e n t texts w h i c h H e r o d o t u s pasted t o g e t h e r to f o r m the Histories ( J a c o b y (1913) 282), folktales i n prose (Aly
(1921)
18, T h o m s o n (1935) 32); prose texts w h i c h collect a n d c o m b i n e m a t e r i a l a c c o r d i n g to r a t i o n a l c r i t e r i a ( P o h l e n z (1937) 5 4 - 5 ) ; 'prose texts w h i c h a t t e m p t to describe a n d e x p l a i n the n a t u r a l w o r l d o r some aspect o f i t . T h e y m a y b e r i t u a l o r religious m y t h s , h i s t o r i c a l l e g ends a b o u t p a r t i c u l a r persons o r occasions, f a b l e s . . . o r m e r e f o l k tales' ( M y r e s (1953) 7 0 - 3 ) ; 'a series o f i t e m s , w h i c h are
themselves
smaller logoi, h e l d t o g e t h e r b y c e r t a i n f o r m a l elements s i g n i f y i n g i n t u r n a selection (but never the t o t a l i t y ) o f u n i f y i n g themes w h i c h o t h e r elements are left i n t a c t ' ( I m m e r w a h r
(1966) 14
beside 15);
or
i n d i r e c t a n d d i r e c t speeches by characters (as o p p o s e d t o erga, the events as r e c o u n t e d b y the n a r r a t o r ) ( H u n t e r (1982) passim). 3 1 F a c e d w i t h this b e w i l d e r i n g series, I c a n o n l y c o n c l u d e t h a t a n
in-depth
study o f the t e r m logos, b o t h inside the Histories a n d i n the l i t e r a t u r e o f his t i m e is a d e s i d e r a t u m . A t first g l a n c e , the use o f the t e r m digressions o r Exkurse seems w a r r a n t e d b y the fact t h a t H e r o d o t u s h i m s e l f occasionally speaks
of
π ρ ο σ θ ή κ η , ' a d d i t i o n ' (4.30), a n d π α ρ ε ν θ ή κ η , ' i n s e r t i o n ' (7.171). B u t at least f r o m J a c o b y o n w a r d s ,
the c o n c e p t o f the H e r o d o t e a n
Exkurs
b e g a n to live a life o f its o w n . J a c o b y h i m s e l f lists n o fewer three types o f Exkurse: (1) n o t r e a l ones:
than
'those w h i c h c l e a r l y o n l y
serve to insert m a t e r i a l t h a t c o u l d n o t be p l a c e d s o m e w h e r e
i n the
m a i n story' ((1913) 381), (2) r e a l ones: 'short digressions, w h i c h c a n easily be missed a n d w h i c h cause n o o r h a r d l y any d i s r u p t i o n ' ((1913) 384), a n d those w h i c h (3) ' a f t e r w a r d s a d d i m p o r t a n t , v e r y i m p o r t a n t
31
Immerwahr explicitly states that his logoi do not necessarily coincide with those of Herodotus. For one thing, Herodotus does not systematically label parts of his work a logos, whereas Immerwahr's analysis of the Histories in logoi ((1966) 79 147) covers the whole text.
256
IRENE J. F. DE JONG
m a t e r i a l w h i c h H e r o d o t u s c o u l d n o t present i n t h e i r p r o p e r p l a c e ' (386). I t is clear f r o m his analysis o f the s t r u c t u r e o f the Histones ((1913) 2 8 3 - 3 2 6 ) t h a t , i n his v i e w , this w o r k consists m a i n l y o f Exkurse a n d Exkurse w i t h i n Exkurse. J a c o b y ' s great o p p o n e n t P o h l e n z , n o t o n l y demonstrates the e x p l a n a t o r y f u n c t i o n o f m a n y digressions (see the above section), b u t also contends t h a t c e r t a i n passages s h o u l d n o t be c o n s i d e r e d digressions at a l l : [ T h e logoi on Greek history] were for h i m a necessary part of his sub ject matter, whether they paint the political situation of the motherland i n a certain period or recount events w h i c h are either relevant to the Asiatic situation of the moment or w i l l become important later on. : ' 2 Immerwahr
opts f o r a m o r e r a d i c a l a p p r o a c h , r e j e c t i n g the n o t i o n
o f digression altogether: '. . . c o n t r a r y t o m a n y scholars, I believe t h a t the few places w h e r e H e r o d o t u s speaks o f a d d i t i o n s to his w o r k are n o t o f a n y r e a l i m p o r t a n c e f o r the u n d e r s t a n d i n g o f its s t r u c t u r e ' ((1966) 14, n . 34). As we have seen i n the p r e v i o u s section, he prefers to see the Histories as a series o f logoi. H i s suggestion t h a t i t w o u l d be b e t t e r to a b o l i s h the t e r m digression has n o t been f o l l o w e d Cobet, who
insists o n using the w o r d Exkurs,
by
a l t h o u g h he is w e l l
a w a r e t h a t i t is n o t exactly the same as H e r o d o t u s '
προσθήκη and
π α ρ ε ν θ ή κ η o r logoi: the term 'Exkurs' is entirely a construction of and for ourselves, w h i c h covers everything that i n our view seems to lead away f r o m the main context. ((1971) 82) He
distinguishes three types o f Exkurse: (1) e t h n o g r a p h i c a l a n d
g r a p h i c a l digressions, (2) novellas, a n d (3) places w h e r e
geo
Herodotus
goes b e y o n d the t e m p o r a l b o u n d a r i e s o f his story by r e l a t i n g events w h i c h t o o k place after 479
BC.
As w e saw i n the p r e v i o u s s e c t i o n ,
C o b e t i n fact manages to m a k e clear the f u n c t i o n o f m o s t o f these Exkurse, a n d f o r this reason i t is all the m o r e regrettable t h a t he d i d n o t choose a n o t h e r t e r m , w h i c h does n o t have the c o n n o t a t i o n
of
disconnectedness.
32
(1937) 42: '[Die logoi über die griechische Geschichte] gehören für ihn notwendig zur Sache, mögen sie nun die politische Lage des Mutterlandes in einer bestimmten Zeit schildern oder Ereignisse erzählen, die entweder gegenwärtig mit der asiatischen Handlung in Zusammenhang stehen oder für die spätere Entwicklung Bedeutung gewinnen.'
N A R A T I V E U N I T Y A N D UNITS
257
The suggestion to give up the notion of digression can also be read between the lines i n Hartog: What I would question are the grounds for making a separation between one Herodotus, who is the historian of the Persian wars, and another or, rather Herodotus' other self. I t is perfectly possible to see the 'ethnographic' part and the 'historical' part with the same eye and to read both with the same voice . . . To separate one from the other, making one come before the other, or hiding one behind the other, is after all to fall victim to Thucydides . . . ((1980) 319; I quote the translation by Janet Lloyd) After Immerwahr disposed o f the notion o f digression/Exkurs for the Anglo-Saxon scholars, Hartog for the French, it is a pity that Erbse did not do the same for the German one, especially since he comes so close. I n his introduction he speaks o f sogenannte Exkursen and at the opening of his section on Exkurse he states that the common term 'Exkurs' as a reservoir of random, not seldom fabulous notes is not of great use for the interpretation o f Herodotus, indeed perhaps misleading. ((1992) 121) As we have seen, Erbse rightly linked the ethnographical and geographical digressions to Homeric descriptions. I n his analyses he consistently speaks of Beschreibungen or Beobachtungen (instead o f Exkurse), yet he has not taken the final i n my view, necessary—step, o f dropping the word Exkurs altogether. Perhaps the most enigmatic type o f narrative unit is the novella. Here we are on even thinner ice than i n the previous two cases, since the word is not used by Herodotus. Indeed, it was only coined in fourteenth-century Italy. But even i f we accept the use o f such a modern term to refer to ancient texts—after all, we do the same i n the case o f the ancient novel--there remain two problems: (1) whether there were 'novellae' i n the time o f Herodotus, and (2) whether his Histories contain such 'novellae' (or i n any case the vestiges o f this genre). Most German Herodotusscholars agree that the answer to both questions is 'yes'. AJy, Regenbogen, Heni, Cobet, and Erbse all confidently refer passim to the typically Ionian genre o f novellae: short and entertaining stories about real people, situated in a certain place and at a certain time (in contrast to the folktale), and including a great deal o f direct speech. 33
There is one non-German adherent to the novella theory: Trenkner (1958) 24.
258 The
IRENE J. F. DE JONG
u l t i m a t e source o f this t h e o r y o n the I o n i a n n o v e l l a is Ercl-
m a n n s d o r f f e r (1870). I n a b r o c h u r e , e n t i t l e d ' D i e Zeitalter d e r N o v e l l e i n H e l l a s ' , this scholar claims t h a t i n m a n y respects the p e r i o d
of
the tyrants i n Greece resembles the f o u r t e e n t h - c e n t u r y
of
Italy
B o c c a c c i o (the i n v e n t o r o f the n o v e l l a ) , a n d t h a t hence w e m a y postulate the existence o f this genre i n Greece as w e l l .
Unfortunately,
n o one has yet been able to p r o d u c e a s p e c i m e n o f such a n o v e l l a . Aly's argument
t h a t we are d e a l i n g w i t h u n w r i t t e n l i t e r a t u r e a n d
t h a t hence by definition n o s p e c i m e n is left ((1921) 5 - 6 ) is clever b u t i n the e n d e silentio. O f course, there w i l l have b e e n short o r a l prose n a r r a t i v e s (alongside the l o n g p o e t i c ones o f epic), b u t I d o n o t t h i n k t h a t these w e r e a n exclusively I o n i a n a f f a i r , o r t h a t i n the
absence
o f a n y s p e c i m i n a , i t is s o u n d to p o s i t a specific genre o f novellae. So m u c h for p o i n t 1. E v e n a s s u m i n g t h a t there w e r e such I o n i a n n o v e l l a e , there is still the p r o b l e m o f i d e n t i f y i n g t h e m i n t h e Histories. I f w e take C o b e t ((1971) 1 4 0 - 5 7 ) o r Erbse (1992), for e x a m p l e ,
we
see t h a t t h e y s i m p l y call every passage w i t h a n e c d o t a l o r folktale c o n t e n t a n d a great d e a l o f speech a n o v e l l a : n o t o n l y the 'Gyges a n d Candaules'
story at 1 . 8 - 1 3 , b u t also X e r x e s ' decision to attack
G r e e c e at 7 . 5 - 1 9 , essence, h o w e v e r ,
a n d the 'False S m e r d i s '
s t o r y at 3 . 3 0 - 6 6 .
In
these passages d o n o t d i f f e r f r o m the rest o f the
Histories; they are all examples o f the same n a r r a t i v e art. I n m y v i e w , w e w o u l d d o b e t t e r t o get r i d o f t h e t e r m n o v e l l a a n d i n s t e a d call the passages w h i c h have b e e n l a b e l l e d as such 'scenes' (in the n a r r a t o l o g i c a l sense o f the w o r d ) . 3 * L i k e a n y n a r r a t o r , H e r o d o t u s
has
the possibility to present his story as a series o f events a n d actions (e.g., A l y a t t e s ' w a r against T h r a s y b u l u s a n d the M i l e s i a n s at 1 . 1 7 - 2 2 ) o r as a scene, w h i c h means t h a t he slows d o w n the pace o f n a r r a t i o n , so as t o a p p r o a c h the l e n g t h o f t i m e o f the events a n d actions, g i v i n g us details a b o u t scenery o r the characters (their gestures, facial expressions, etc.) a n d q u o t i n g t h e i r w o r d s .
The fact that her book is based on a Polish dissertation may be relevant here. Thus the secondary literature listed by her is almost exclusively German. See Genette (1980) 95, 109 12 and Bal (1985) 71, 73 5. 34
259
N A R A T I V E U N I T Y A N D UNITS
Herodotus' unity: the means In this section I will discuss the narrative devices which the Herodotean narrator employs to create unity, on the level o f the parts o f his work as well as on that o f the work as a whole. I will proceed from small to large and from explicit to implicit. (1) Repetition of words. I n the course of a story or section the narrator repeats a word which is central to that story or section. A n example is the root συμφορ- i n the Adrastus' story at 1.34-45, which recurs i n 35.1.4, 41.1, 42.1, and 45.3. O f course, not every recur ring w o r d is an example o f significant word repetition. Long (1987), who pays much attention to w o r d repetition i n his analysis o f Herodotus' short stories, is, in my view, much too ready to desig nate a repetition as significant. Thus in that same Adrastus' story, I take issue with him for giving so much weight to the repetition of μεγάλη (34.1), μέγα (36.1), and μέγιστος (36.2). A detailed study o f w o r d repetition i n the Histories, including a thorough theoretical dis cussion o f what makes a repetition significant, is a desideratum. ' (2) Presentation markers o f the type 'as follows' (pointing forward) and 'thus' (pointing backward), for example: 35
36
3
38
39
Κατ' αυτόν δέ Κροΐσον τάδε έγίνετο. (1.85)
With Croesus himself the following happened, κατά μεν νυν τον κρητήρα οΰτω έσχε. (1.70.1)
This was what happened to the bowl. Presentation markers often occur as part of headlines (see below 3) or ring-compositions (see below 4). (3) Headlines and conclusions. The narrator announces before hand what a story or section will be about or concludes afterwards what it has been about, for example: 40
3
-' As in section 1, I concentrate on the formal devices, leaving out of account the motifs and story patterns, which on the level of the content lend unity. I also leave aside linguistic devices, such as the use of tenses, for which see Rijksbaron (1988). For other examples, see van der Veen (1996) 6-22. Fehling's study on figures of repetition (1969) contains a great deal of mater ial, but provides no interpretative evaluation of that material. See also Ch. 1, pp. 19-20 on hecle in the proem. Frankel ((1924) 1960) 65 6, Pohlenz (1937) 87, Immerwahr (1966) 52-3, and Muller (1980) 51-8, 69-70. Immerwahr (1966) 53 and Lang (1984) 2-5. 56
37
38
m
260
IRENE J. F. DE JONG
τ φ δή λ έ γ ο υ σ ι Κ ο ρ ί ν θ ι ο ι . . . θ ώ μ α μέγιστον π α ρ α σ τ ή ν α ι , Ά ρ ί ο ν α τον Μηθυμναΐον έπί δελφίνος έξενειχθέντα έπί Ταίναρον. (1.23) The Corinthians tell that there happened to h i m [Periander] a very great marvel, the transport of A r i o n o f M e t h y m n a to Taenarus o n a dolphin. H e a d l i n e s a n d conclusions
can also be e x p a n d e d i n t o
narratorial
i n t e r v e n t i o n s , i . e . , w i t h t h e n a r r a t o r r e f e r r i n g t o his o w n a c t i v i t y , f o r example: Έ π ι δ ί ζ η τ α ι δέ δή τό ένθεΰτεν ήμΐν 6 λόγος τόν τε Κϋρον δστις έών την Κροίσου αρχήν κατεΐλε, και τους Πέρσας δτεφ τρόπω ήγήσαντο της Ά σ ί η ς . (1.95) But it is next the business o f my history to set out who this Cyrus was who brought down the power o f Croesus and how the Persians came to be rulers o f Asia. (4) R i n g - c o m p o s i t i o n .
At
the e n d o f a section the n a r r a t o r
the w o r d s w i t h w h i c h he b e g a n , 4 1
repeats
for example:
. . . τό μεν Άττικόν κατεχόμενόν τε και διεσπασμένον έπυνθάνετο ό Κροίσος υπό Π ε ι σ ι σ τ ρ ά τ ο υ τοΰ Ί π π ο κ ρ ά τ ε ο ς τοΰτον τόν χρύνον τ υ ρ α ν ν ε ύ ο ν τ ο ς Α θ η ν α ί ω ν . (1.59) . . . Croesus learnt that the Attic people was held in subjection and divided into factions by Peisistratus, son of Hippocrates, who at that time was tyrant of Athens. Τούς μεν νυν Αθηναίους τοιαΰτα τόν χρόνον τοΰτον έπυνθάνετο ό Κροίσος κατέχοντα . . . (1.65) About the Athenians Croesus learnt that at that time such things were occupying them . . . T h i s device m a r k s o f f analepses, prolepses, a n d descriptions, b u t also sections o f the m a i n story. T h e
e l e m e n t w h i c h is repeated
signals
either the e n d o f t h e analepsis, etc., or the r e s u m p t i o n o f the m a i n story. I n the l a t t e r case, the r i n g - c o m p o s i t i o n can also be i n terms o f a n epanalepsis. R i n g - c o m p o s i t i o n s
described
often consist o f a c o m
bination o f headline a n d conclusion, a n d contain
presentation-mark
ers, f o r e x a m p l e :
" Frankel ((1924)1960) 71-2. Immerwahr (1966) 12, 54 8, Pohlenz (1937) 63, Beck (1971), Lang (1984) 5-6, and Bakker (1997a) 115-21. See also Ch. 3, p. 000 (nu 16 ff.) in this volume.
261
N A R A T I V E U N I T Y A N D UNITS
Σάρδιες δέ ήλωσαν ώδε . . . οϋτω δή Σάρδιές τε ήλώκεσαν και παν τδ άστυ έπορθέετο. (1.84.1, 5) Sarcles was taken in the following way . . . Thus Sardes had been taken and the whole city was being destroyed. (5) G r o s s - r e f e r e n c e s . T h e n a r r a t o r recounted
something
remarks
earlier i n his w o r k
that
he has already-
o r w i l l d o so l a t e r , 4 2 f o r
example: Τοΰτον δή ών τον Άστυάγεα Κΰρος έόντα έωυτοΰ μητροπάτορα καταστρεψάμενος εσχε δ ι ' αίτίην τήν έγώ έν τοΐσι οπίσω λόγοισι σημανέω · (1.75.1, the narrator will fulfill his promise at 1.124) This Astyages then was Cyrus' mother's father, and was made subject to him for a reason which I will set out in a later section. . . . Κροΐσον ϋστερον τούτων ά ρ ξ α ν τ α άδικίης κατεστρέψατο, ώς- εϊρηται μοι πρότερον. (1.130.3, the narrator refers back to 1.79-85) . . . later he subdued Croesus, who had started being unjust, as I have already told before. (6) R e p e a t i n g prolepses a n d analepses. Instead o f m a k i n g an e x p l i c i t cross-reference
( as i n 5), t h e n a r r a t o r m e r e l y repeats s o m e t h i n g he
has already related o r reveals s o m e t h i n g h e w i l l later r e c o u n t i n f u l l , for example: . . . "Αρπαγος κατέβη διάδοχος της στρατηγίης, . . ., τον ό Μήδων βασιλεύς Αστυάγης άνόμω τραπέζη εδαισε, ό τω Κύρφ τήν βασιληίην συγκατεργασάμενος (1.162.1, analepsis of 119, 123-9) .. Harpagus came to succeed him as commander,. . ., the same whom Astyages, king of the Medes, had entertained with an unholy meal, and who had helped Cyrus to get the kingship. . . . τδ σκηπτόμενοι ot Πέρσαι ϋστερον άντενεπίμπρασαν τά έν "Ελλησι ίρά. Using this [the burning of Sardes by the Greeks] as a pretext, they later set fire to temples in Greece. (5.102.1, prolepsis of 6.19, 96, 101; 8.33, 53) (7) I n t e r a c t i o n o f speech a n d n a r r a t o r - t e x t . 4 3 take d i f f e r e n t f o r m s .
T h e narrator
This interaction can
can prepare
f o r a speech, f o r
e x a m p l e : Coes' speech a b o u t t h e Scythians (4.97), i n w h i c h he w a r n s D a r i u s t h a t h e is a b o u t t o ' m a r c h against a c o u n t r y w h e r e y o u w i l l 42 43
Jacoby (1913) 282, 327 and Pohlenz (1937) 87. For more examples, see de Jong (1999) 254-8.
262 find
IRENE J. F. DE JONG
n e i t h e r t i l l e d l a n d s n o r i n h a b i t e d c i t i e s ' , is p r e p a r e d
4.46.2-3,
w h e r e the n a r r a t o r tells the narratees t h a t the
f o r at
Scythians
'have n o established c i t i e s . . . a n d live n o t b y t i l l i n g the s o i l . . .'. The
n a r r a t o r c a n react to a speech, f o r e x a m p l e :
at
1.209.3-5
C y r u s sets o u t a n i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f his d r e a m , w h i c h is c o r r e c t e d by the n a r r a t o r at 2 1 0 . 1 . S o m e speeches c o n t a i n analepses o f events already r e c o u n t e d
by
the n a r r a t o r . T h u s at 7.10.a.2 A r t a b a n u s uses the example o f D a r i u s ' unsuccessful e x p e d i t i o n against the Scythians, r e c o u n t e d b y the n a r r a t o r at 4 . 8 3 - 1 4 4 , i n a n a t t e m p t to dissuade X e r x e s f r o m m a r c h i n g against the Greeks. T h e
f r e q u e n c y w i t h w h i c h characters use
the
past as a n a r g u m e n t i n t h e i r speeches lends the device o f the a c t o r i a l analepsis 4 4 a n e x t r a , t h e m a t i c f u n c t i o n , i n a d d i t i o n to its f o r m a l , u n i f y i n g f u n c t i o n : i t shows the narratees t h a t h i s t o r y is n o t o n l y about p r e s e r v i n g the kleos o f great deeds a n d m e n f r o m the past, b u t also a b o u t d e a l i n g w i t h one's o w n present s i t u a t i o n . T h e r e are also speeches
t h a t c o n t a i n prolepses o f events to
later r e c o u n t e d b y the n a r r a t o r .
43
Croesus at 1.207
be
advises C y r u s t o
cross the A r a x e s , m a r c h i n t o the t e r r i t o r y o f the Massagetae,
pre-
p a r e a festive m e a l , a n d t h e n w i t h d r a w to the r i v e r a g a i n . H e a n t i c ipates t h a t t h e Massagetae w i l l start feasting a n d t h e r e b y
become
easy p r e y f o r the Persian a r m y . C y r u s follows his advice a n d t h i n g happens ever,
events
exactly as foreseen (1.211). M u c h evolve
very
differently from
the way
characters h a d foreseen, h o p e d , o r f e a r e d . O n e
every-
more often,
how-
in which
the
need o n l y t h i n k o f
D a r i u s ' a n d X e r x e s ' oft-expressed i n t e n t i o n s o f c o n q u e r i n g G r e e c e . A c t o r i a l prolepses, i n w h i c h the Histories a b o u n d , a c t o r i a l analepses,
t h e r e b y , like the
acquire an extra, thematic function: they
allow
t h e narratees to d i s t i n g u i s h b e t w e e n wise characters, w h o are able t o foresee the f u t u r e , a n d b l i n d characters (the m a j o r i t y ) , w h o
over-
estimate t h e i r o w n possibilities, forget t h e i r l i m i t s as m o r t a l s
and,
above a l l , d o n o t take to h e a r t the H e r o d o t e a n m o t t o t h a t
'human
p r o s p e r i t y is never stable' (1.5). (8) N a r r a t i v e i n t e g r a t i o n o f d e s c r i p t i o n s . T h i s c a n be a c h i e v e d by h a v i n g a c h a r a c t e r l o o k at scenery (e.g., 4 . 8 5 - 6 , w h e r e D a r i u s looks at the Pontus), visit sites (e.g., X e r x e s at 7.26,
4 4
3 0 , 4 3 , 5 9 , 108,
109,
A n actorial analepsis is one made by a character, while a narratorial analepsis is one made by the narrator. Cf. Hunter (1982) 190-6. 45
263
N A R A T I V E U N I T Y A N D UNITS
197), o r i n f o r m a n o t h e r c h a r a c t e r a b o u t a c o u n t r y (e.g., 7 . 1 3 0 , w h e r e G r e e k guides i n f o r m X e r x e s a b o u t
Thessaly). 4 6
B y w a y o f c o n c l u s i o n I w o u l d like to note t h a t as regards t e c h niques 3, 4 , 6, 7, a n d 8 , H e r o d o t u s once a g a i n h a d H o m e r as his model.
Narrative unity: an example To
s h o w t h e w o r k i n g o f some o f the n a r r a t i v e devices listed i n t h e
p r e v i o u s section, I w i l l analyse i n d e t a i l the passage 5 . 5 5 - 9 7 , w h i c h has a l r e a d y f e a t u r e d several times i n the h i s t o r i c a l o v e r v i e w
pre-
sented i n the first p a r t o f this c h a p t e r . 55-96.2: a chunk of Athenian
history ( 5 1 4 - 4 9 9 BC).
This narrato-
r i a l analepsis as a w h o l e is enclosed b y r i n g - c o m p o s i t i o n : ' B e i n g c o m p e l l e d to leave S p a r t a , Aristagoras w e n t to A t h e n s ' (55) = . . . at this moment,
Aristagoras the M i l e s i a n , d r i v e n f r o m S p a r t a , . . . came to
A t h e n s ' (97.1). 55—65.5: A t h e n s frees itself f r o m its tyrants H i p p a r c h u s
(514
and Hippias
ring-com-
(510
BC).
T h i s section is m a r k e d o f f b y
BC)
p o s i t i o n , w h i c h is a c o m b i n a t i o n o f a h e a d l i n e a n d a c o n c l u s i o n , b o t h of w h i c h c o n t a i n p r e s e n t a t i o n m a r k e r s : '(Athens) w h i c h h a d b e e n f r e e d f r o m its r u l i n g despots i n the f o l l o w i n g m a n n e r ' ~ ' T h u s the A t h e n i a n s 56: H i p p a r c h u s
(55)
got r i d o f t h e i r t y r a n t s ' (65.5).
has a d r e a m b e f o r e he is m u r d e r e d (514
T h i s n a r r a t o r i a l analepsis is t r i g g e r e d by ' W h e n H i p p a r c h u s
BC). had
been slain . . . after seeing in a dream a very clear picture of the evil that befell him" (55). I t is i n t r o d u c e d b y a h e a d l i n e , w h i c h c o n tains a p r e s e n t a t i o n m a r k e r : ' T h e
d r e a m o f H i p p a r c h u s was as
follows'. 57—61: the G e p h y r e a n c l a n comes f r o m P h o e n i c i a
to
Boeotia
t o A t h e n s (c. 1 2 0 0 - 1 1 0 0 B C ) . 4 ' T h i s n a r r a t o r i a l analepsis is t r i g gered b y ' W h e n H i p p a r c h u s . . . h a d been s l a i n . . . b y Aristogeiton and Harmodius,
40
men of Gephyrean descent. . .' (55).
Jacoby (1913) 383, 390; he regards these forms of integration as 'artificial'. '' This date and the others which follow make no claims to exact accuracy; they will merely serve to place the analepses in some form of chronological order.
264
IRENE J. F. DE JONG
6 2 . 1 : a n a r r a t o r i a l i n t e r v e n t i o n , w h i c h caps t h e analepses o f 5 6 a n d 5 7 - 6 1 a n d announces
i n the f o r m o f a renewed
headline
the c o n t i n u a t i o n o f t h e section 5 5 - 6 5 : ' I have s h o w n w h a t was the v i s i o n o f H i p p a r c h u s '
dream
and what
t h e first o r i g i n o f
the G e p h y r e a n s , o f w h o m w e r e t h e slayers o f H i p p a r c h u s ; n o w I m u s t g o f u r t h e r a n d r e t u r n t o t h e story w h i c h I b e g a n t o t e l l , namely h o w the Athenians were freed f r o m their tyrants.' 6 2 . 2 ^ 6 5 . 5 : A t h e n s frees itself f r o m its tyrants ( c o n t . j . 6 5 . 5 - 9 6 . 2 : h i s t o r y o f A t h e n s after i t has f r e e d itself ( 5 1 0 - 4 9 9 B G ) . T h i s section is i n t r o d u c e d b y a h e a d l i n e i n t h e f o r m o f a n a r r a t o r i a l i n t e r v e n t i o n : ' A l l the n o t e w o r t h y
things that they d i d o r
e n d u r e d , after t h e y w e r e f r e e d a n d before f o n i a r e v o l t e d against D a r i u s a n d Aristagoras o f M i l e t u s c a m e t o A t h e n s t o ask t h e h e l p o f its p e o p l e , these I w i l l n o w first relate' (65.5). 6 7 . 1 - 6 9 . 1 : Gleisthenes rules S i c y o n ( 6 0 0 - 5 7 0 B C ) . T h i s n a r r a t o r i a l analepsis is m a r k e d o f f b y r i n g - c o m p o s i t i o n : ' I n this respect, i t seems t o m e , this Cleisthenes i m i t a t e d his o w n m o t h e r ' s father, Cleisthenes t h e despot o f S i c y o n . ' (67.1) ~ '. . . a n d t h e A t h e n i a n Cleisthenes, w h o w a s t h e son o f t h a t Sicyonian's d a u g h t e r a n d bore h i s n a m e ,
d i d to m y t h i n k i n g i m i t a t e his namesake . . . '
(69.1). 7 1 : t h e A c c u r s e d get t h e i r n a m e [c. 6 3 0 B C ) . T h i s n a r r a t o r i a l analepsis is t r i g g e r e d b y ' C l e o m e n e s d e m a n d e d the b a n i s h m e n t o f Cleisthenes a n d m a n y o t h e r A t h e n i a n s , the Accursed, as he called therri (70), a n d is i n t r o d u c e d b y a h e a d l i n e , w h i c h contains a p r e s e n t a t i o n m a r k e r : ' T h e A c c u r s e d g o t t h e i r n a m e as f o l l o w s . ' 76: t h e f o u r D o r i a n invasions o f A t t i c a (c. 1 2 0 0 - 5 0 5 B C ) . T h i s n a r r a t o r i a l analepsis is m a r k e d o f f b y
ring-composition,
which
c o m b i n e s a h e a d l i n e a n d c o n c l u s i o n , w h i c h contains a p r e s e n t a t i o n m a r k e r : ' T h i s was t h e f o u r t h t i m e t h a t D o r i a n s h a d c o m e into Attica'
~ ' t h u s this w a s t h e f o u r t h D o r i a n
invasion
of
Athens'. 8 2 . 1 - 8 9 . 1 : the o r i g i n o f t h e A e g i n e t a n s ' l o n g - s t a n d i n g h a t r e d o f the A t h e n i a n s (c. 7 0 0 - 5 0 0 B C ) . T h i s n a r r a t o r i a l analepsis is t r i g g e r e d b y ' B u t t h e A e g i n e t a n s . . . h a d i n m i n d an ancient feud with Athens' (81.2) a n d is m a r k e d o f f b y a
ring-composition,
which
c o m b i n e s a h e a d l i n e , w h i c h contains a p r e s e n t a t i o n m a r k e r , a n d a c o n c l u s i o n , w h i c h takes t h e f o r m o f a n a r r a t o r i a l i n t e r v e n t i o n : ' N o w this w a s t h e b e g i n n i n g o f t h e A e g i n e t a n s ' i n g e n m i t y against t h e A t h e n i a n s '
long-stand-
(82.1) = ' a n d t h e e n m i t y o f
265
NARATIVE UNITY A N D UNITS
t h e A t h e n i a n s against the Aeginetans began as I have t o l d ' (89.1). 92.(3.1—n.4: t y r a n t s r u l e C o r i n t h [c. 6 5 0 - 5 8 5 B C ) .
This actorial
analepsis is t r i g g e r e d b y ' y o u p r e p a r e t o i n t r o d u c e tyrannism i n the cities, t h e m o s t u n r i g h t e o u s a n d b l o o d y i n s t i t u t i o n t h e r e is' (92.o.l). 94.1—95.2; S i g e u m
comes u n d e r A t h e n i a n
r u l e (600 B C ) .
The
n a r r a t o r i a l analepsis is t r i g g e r e d b y ' H i p p i a s w i t h d r e w t o Sigeum'. I t is c a p p e d marker:
by
a conclusion, w h i c h contains a presentation
'thus then Sigeum
came
t o be u n d e r A t h e n i a n
rule'
(95.2). W h a t I h o p e this analysis has m a d e
clear is t h a t , yes, at first sight
H e r o d o t u s ' n a r r a t i v e , w i t h its r e p e a t e d i n t e r r u p t i o n s o f t h e story l i n e , seems t o be a m u d d l e . H o w e v e r , i f w e w o u l d place the analepses i n t h e i r c h r o n o l o g i c a l o r d e r , the f o l l o w i n g p i c t u r e w o u l d emerge: four D o r i a n Phoenicia
invasions o f A t t i c a - - t h e G e p h y r e a n c l a n comes
to B o e o t i a to A t h e n s
the A e g i n e t a n s Accursed
and
-the o r i g i n o f the e n m i t y
the A t h e n i a n s — t h e
get t h e i r n a m e -
Cleisthenes rules S i c y o n -
Sigeum
the from
between
tyrants rule C o r i n t h - -the
comes
under
Athenian
rule -
H i p p a r c h u s has a d r e a m b e f o r e he is m u r -
d e r e d . I n o t h e r w o r d s , this w o u l d result i n the r a n d o m h i s t o r i o g r a p h y w h i c h A r i s t o t l e — d i s p a r a g i n g l y — d e s c r i b e s i n his Poetics: h i s t o r i o g r a p h y w h i c h l u m p s t o g e t h e r 'events t h a t have a m e r e l y casual r e l a t i o n t o each o t h e r ' ( 2 3 , cf. 9). W h e n w e r e t u r n t o H e r o d o t u s '
anachron-
i c a l s t r u c t u r e a n d e x a m i n e i t m o r e closely, we discover i t t o be h i g h l y effective. T h e
analepses are c l e a r l y m a r k e d off, t r i g g e r e d by a n ear-
l i e r e l e m e n t i n the t e x t , a n d are u s u a l l y r e l e v a n t t o the c o n t e x t . 4 8 I n some cases, t h e y m o t i v a t e a n a c t i o n b y characters (the h a t r e d o f the A t h e n i a n s
explains w h y
story a b o u t the t y r a n t s w h o
Aeginetans'
t h e y d o n o t help t h e m ;
r u l e d C o r i n t h is designed t o
the
dissuade
the A t h e n i a n s f r o m r e c a l l i n g H i p p i a s ; 4 9 the A t h e n i a n r u l e o f S i g e u m e x p l a i n s w h y H i p p i a s goes t h e r e i n s t e a d o f a c c e p t i n g the h o s p i t a l i t y offered to h i m i n M a c e d o n i a
18
o r Thessaly; the w h o l e analepsis
on
For a—largely convincing—analysis of 5.55-97 in these terms, see Legrand (1942) 43-9. Here 1 disagree with Legrand, who claims that the story of Gypselus' childhood has no argumentative function and is merely inserted by Herodotus here because he could find no better place and did not want to leave a good story untold ((1942) 48). For the relevance of the passage, see van der Veen (1996) 86-9. 4 9
266
IRENE J. F. DE JONG
A t h e n i a n h i s t o r y explains b o t h w h y the A t h e n i a n s are p r e p a r e d to j o i n the l o n i a n s against the Persians a n d w h y Aristagoras comes t o A t h e n s i n the first place). I n o t h e r cases, t h e y p r o v i d e the narratees w i t h b a c k g r o u n d i n f o r m a t i o n w h i c h a m o d e r n t e x t w o u l d give i n a f o o t n o t e (the e x p l a n a t i o n o f t h e n i c k n a m e ' A c c u r s e d ' , t h e f o u r i n v a sions o f the D o r i a n s ) . I n yet o t h e r cases, t h e y e n r i c h the c o n t e x t (Gleisthenes'
r e f o r m s i n C o r i n t h p r o v i d e a n i n t e r e s t i n g p a r a l l e l to
those o f Gleisthenes i n A t h e n s ; 5 0
t h e story o f H i p p a r c h u s '
dream
makes clear h o w H i p p a r c h u s chooses n o t to h e e d this w a r n i n g , a f a v o u r i t e H e r o d o t e a n m o t i f ) . 5 1 O n l y i n the case o f t h e analepsis o n the G e p h y r e a n c l a n , w h i c h is i n f a c t a vehicle f o r a section o n t h e P h o e n i c i a n a l p h a b e t , I a m f o r c e d to a d m i t t h a t I c a n find n o d i r e c t contextual relevance.02 I
c o n c l u d e t h a t , i n the hands o f H e r o d o t u s ,
teller's device o f t h e
flashback
t h e a g e - o l d story-
o r analepsis has b e c o m e a p o w e r f u l
instrument of historical n a r r a t i o n . ' 3
so j j I again disagree with Legrand, who finds the parallel superficial, introduced by Herodotus in order to make a transition to information he wanted to include ((1942) 47). Legrand's qualification of this analepsis as an 'hors-d'ceuvre' ((1942) 47) does not do justice to its relevance. For a suggestion, see Ch. 14, p. 326. I wish to thank the members of the Hellenistenclub for their comments, Mrs B. Fasting for her correction of my English, Hans van Wees for invaluable help with the- - last minute—translation of the many German quotations in my text. e r e
01
52
53
CHAPTER T W E L V E 'I D I D N ' T G I V E M Y O W N GENEALOGY': AND
THE AUTHORIAL Carolyn
HERODOTUS
PERSONA
Dewald
I n t h e course o f B o o k T w o , w h e r e
Herodotus
is s o m e w h a t
more
f o r t h c o m i n g t h a n usual a b o u t h i s o w n i n v e s t i g a t o r y p r a c t i c e s , he m e n t i o n s t h a t he r e p e a t e d t h e visit t h a t H e c a t a e u s h a d m a d e
sev-
e r a l generations e a r l i e r , t o see t h e priests l i n e d u p i n t h e i r austere r o w s i n t h e t e m p l e o f A m o n - r e a t K a r n a k (Thebes). H e c o m m e n t s t h a t H e c a t a e u s h a d t o l d t h e E g y p t i a n s t h a t he w a s t h e s i x t e e n t h g e n e r a t i o n descendant o f a g o d , a n d t h a t t h e priests i n response h a d s h o w n H e c a t a e u s 345 statues, l i n e d u p i n a r o w , o f priests descended f r o m earlier p r i e s t s — e a c h o f t h e m a piromis, E g y p t i a n f o r s o m e t h i n g like n o b l e m a n , b u t h a r d l y a g o d . T h e n H e r o d o t u s ,
i n one o f the
m o s t spontaneous m o m e n t s o f self-expression i n t h e w h o l e Histories, says, ' a n d t h e y s h o w e d t h e same t h i n g t o m e , emoi ou geneelogesanti emeouton, a l t h o u g h I d i d n ' t give m y o w n genealogy'
(2.143.1).
I n d e e d , h e does n o t . A l t h o u g h his a u t h o r i a l , first-person voice plays a p r o m i n e n t p a r t i n t h e Histories, H e r o d o t u s
does n o t tell us a n y -
t h i n g a b o u t his f a m i l y o r his e t h n i c a f f i l i a t i o n s . 1 A r m e d w i t h scraps o f ancient gossip, w e c a n choose t o i n t e r p r e t as significant o u r i m p r e s sion that H e r o d o t u s
h i m s e l f is less t h a n d a z z l e d b y m o s t o f t h e
I o n i a n s (except possibly t h e Samians),
t h a t he is interested i n a n d
respectful o f C a r i a n a c c o m p l i s h m e n t , t h a t he has a soft spot f o r t h e v a l i a n t H a l i c a r n a s s i a n q u e e n A r t e m i s i a , a n d t h a t h e c e r t a i n l y seems to k n o w
a l o t o f l o c a l details f r o m t h e area o f t h e A e g e a n coast
a r o u n d Halicarnassus.' 2 B u t he does n o t encourage us t o d r a w c o n -
1
I f Jacoby (1956) 225 is right, that Herodotus wrote 'Herodotus of Thurii' in his first sentence (Aristode's version of the proem, Rhet. 1409a), nothing in the text would make explicit that he was a Dorian from Halicarnassus. For a discussion of 2.143 in terms of Herodotus' possible dependence on Hecataeus, see Lloyd (1988a) 107-8; cf. the scepticism of West (1991) 147-51. E.g., Ionians: 1.143, 4.142, 5.69, 5.97, 6.13; Samians: 3.60, but see 6.13; Carians and Pedasa: 1.171.1, 1.175-6, 2.152, 5.118-19, 6.20, 8.104-5; Artemisia: 7.99, 8.68, 2
268
CAROLYN DEWALD
elusions from these impressions; quite the contrary, the narrator or T o f the narrative who tells the Histories tacitly situates himself as a professional outsider, someone who knows many things about many peoples, not just Greeks but barbarians as well. Although many times he interjects himself as an T into the narrative, he does so in what is at base a profoundly non-autobiographical voice that does not depict the author himself as a person with local ties and an insider's attachment to the immediate context under consideration. It is instead an early version o f the 'Expert's Persona'—a voice that owes much of its credibility to the fact that it is detached, austere, non-personal in its intellectual engagement with the material it narrates. This fact has both bad and good consequences for us. Unfortunately, it means that Herodotus leaves us guessing at much about the inception o f the genre he began that we would very much like to know. What d i d he have in m i n d to do, when he started to write? What literary antecedents or ethnic traditions shaped his attitudes to the world, and to the text he wanted to produce? I f we knew some o f these answers, we could begin to formulate answers to the more basic questions they raise i n turn: did he intend his work to be at base a constructed and thus implicitly persuasive form o f narrative, with all the (rhetorical) possibilities for invention that entails? O r was it instead his intent to produce a neutral, impartial, and, as much as possible, transparent account of past human social realities? Unlike Thucydides (1.21—2), Herodotus does not tell us. 3
4
8.87, 8.93, 8.101; Halicarnassus: 1.144, 3.7, 9.107. Cf. his references to Pedasa (above); Cnidus: 1.174; Cos: 7.163-4, 9.76; Labraunda: 5.119. On Artemisia, see also Blok, this volume (Ch. 10, pp. 240-41). For possible generic antecedents and connections for this authorial voice, see de Jong (1987) 97, and (1999) 223. 227-9, Détienne (1967) 81-143, Nagy (1990) 224-35, Calame (1995) 77-96, Fowler (1996), Boedeker (2000). For some of the fifth-century intellectual and political contexts possibly relevant to Herodotus' biography, see e.g., Forrest (1984), Raaflaub (1987), Ostwald (1991), Stadter (1992), Thomas (1993), Moles (1996). Thomas (2000) appeared after this article was largely complete; she explores what I have here called Herodotus' 'expert's persona' in the context of the intellectual presuppositions and epideictic stylistic conventions of the first sophistic and contemporary scientific debate. See also Fowler (1996) 79 n. 118 and Cartledge and Greenwood, this volume (Ch. 15). These issues continue to occupy historiographers today. For what might be entailed by a 'serious, impartial and responsible account,' see, e.g., Veyne (1971), Mink (1987), White (1978), (1987), Appleby, Hunt, and Jacob (1994), Berkhofer (1995), and the scholarly exchange about historical narrative in the journal Past and Present in 1991 and 1992 by P.Joyce, C. Kelly, L. Stone, and G. Spiegel. Berkhofer (p. 3) sums up the form of the question as it is posed in contemporary postmod3
4
s
' I D I D N ' T GIVE M Y O W N GENEALOGY'
269
O n the other hand, on the positive side, i f we look closely at his persona, the presentation i n the text o f the authorial, expert T , we see elements i n it suggesting that both strategies—the Histories as an overtly constructed account, the Histories as the transmission o f relatively neutral and trustworthy information—are present and even necessarily commingled i n this first historical text. Each is necessary to the implicit narrative contract that Herodotus establishes with us, his readers, from the outset. H o w the tension between them is established and sustained—even, why it is necessary—is something we can investigate by looking at how the authorial T i n Herodotus' text works in action. T o begin at the beginning: i n the first sentence, an impersonal (unidentified) voice states that hede (a deictic, pointing to the work before us) is the apodexis ('demonstration', 'publication') o f the historic ('investigation') o f Herodotus. This initial declarative statement is immediately followed by a couple o f purpose clauses setting out the aims o f this work: the preservation and celebration o f the human past and its astounding achievements, including i n particular why Greeks and barbarians went to war with one another (1.1). What follows is not, however, what we or even Thucydides might call a conventionally historical, straightforward, and avowedly trustworthy version o f past events. Instead, the narrator (presumably Herodotus, but still unidentified i n the second sentence as an T ) sets up a division between what he knows and says i n his own voice because he knows it, and the logoi or stories o f others. First he recounts what Persian logioi or 'experts' say about the origins o f Greco-barbarian conflict i n the very distant past, concerning the abduction o f four mythic heroines, Io, Europa, Medea, and Helen, Greek women by barbarians and barbarian women by Greeks; after this, he adds an alternative, Phoenician, version o f the abduction o f Io. Only after recounting what Persian logioi and Phoenicians have said about these distant and dubious doings does he conclude his proem with its first overtly first-person statement: 3
ernist criticism: 'To what extent can historians combine the two meanings of history as actual past and modern representation when all we know of language seemingly subverts that very goal?' For Herodotus as the fashioner of a rhetoric of history, see Hartog (1980/88), and a helpful overview of the larger debate begun by Fehling (1971) in Boedeker (2000). On these terms, the deictic, and on the Proem in general, see Bakker, this volume (Ch. 1), esp. pp. 29-30. 5
270
CAROLYN D E W A L D
But I am not going to say about these matters that they occurred one way or the other, but the man I know (oidd) first began unjust deeds against the Greeks, indicating h i m I w i l l proceed farther into the logos, going alike through small and big communities of humankind. For what was before big has mostly become small, and what was big i n my time was earlier small. So knowing that human happiness never stays i n the same place, I will recount both alike.' 1 T h i s i n i t i a l n a r r a t i v e strategy has o f t e n b e e n r e a d as an i m p l i c i t reassurance to the reader t h a t here at the b e g i n n i n g o f the w o r k
the
a u t h o r is t h i n k i n g h i s t o r i c a l l y , because i t t a c i t l y declares t h a t he dismisses o l d m y t h s o f d u b i o u s value a n d i n t e n d s t o start his a c c o u n t i n s t e a d i n the spatium historicum, the t i m e i n the relatively recent past for w h i c h one c a n say o n e k n o w s things w i t h c e r t a i n t y . ' C e r t a i n l y , i f the T
o f the n a r r a t i v e h a d
of rhetorical praeterition
firmly
firmly
gone o n f r o m this first m o v e
t o a b j u r e all a n c i e n t , m y t h i c logol
a n d to i n d i c a t e t h a t the n a r r a t i v e to f o l l o w w o u l d have m a g n i t u d e , a n d comprehensiveness
accuracy,
as its goals, H e r o d o t u s '
as i t stands w o u l d be u n e x c e p t i o n a b l y
proem
h i s t o r i c a l . 8 B u t t h a t is n o t
w h a t he does, e i t h e r i n t h e o r y o r i n p r a c t i c e . W h a t seems to m a k e the Persian
and Phoenician
stories suspect i n c o n t e x t is n o t t h e i r
e x t r e m e a n t i q u i t y , the oddness o f t h e i r causal e x p l a n a t i o n s , o r t h e i r d u b i o u s h i s t o r i c a l status as r a t i o n a l i z e d m y t h s . W h a t
the n a r r a t i v e
h i g h l i g h t s b y l a b e l l i n g t h e m v a r i a n t versions o f the same story, w i t h the (unspoken) G r e e k m y t h s l o o m i n g f a i n t l y visible b e h i n d t h e m , is r a t h e r t h a t they are o v e r t l y b o t h p a r t i a l a n d p a r t i s a n : Persians
tell
a v e r s i o n o f the d i s t a n t past designed to e x o n e r a t e Persians f r o m the responsibility for b e g i n n i n g the e n m i t y between Phoenicians a d d o n l y a d e t a i l t h a t exonerates Thus what
emerges
Fiast a n d
West;
Phoenicians."
as t h e first n a r r a t i v e m o v e i n
Herodotus'
Histories is less the a r t i c u l a t i o n o f a c o n v e n t i o n a l l y ' h i s t o r i c a l ' t i m e
6
1.5; translations of Herodotus throughout this chapter are my own. Von Leyden (1949-50) 95 cites Jacoby (1956) 99 for this idea; cf. Dewald (1999) 229 n. 16 and Marincola (1999) 285 n. 13. See also Boedeker, this volume (Ch. 5 n. 43) as well as Raaflaub (Ch. 7, n. 36), Cobet (Ch. 17, n. 55), and Osborne (Ch. 22). Berkhofer (1995) 50-1 cites Cronon's (1992) 1371 list: depth, breadth, elegance, inclusiveness, coherence, and, most important, accuracy. Cf. what Appleby, Hunt, and Jacob (1994) 247—61 call the objectivity of a 'practical realism'. Moreover, Herodotus begins his next narrative not with Croesus himself but with another romantic story from the distant past, this time about Croesus' distant ancestor Gyges. The narratological implications are developed more fully in Dewald (1999) 224-33; cf. Fowler (1996) 84-6 for the possibility that Herodotus was reporting real sources. 7
8
9
271
' I D I D N ' T GIVE M Y O W N GENEALOGY'
or subject matter than the creation o f an initial binary division between two different voices. The first is the narrator himself, someone who knows things and in (re)telling stories tacitly notes but stands apart from partisanship. Also present, constituting a second and quite different kind of voice, is the series o f tacitly focalized logoi of his informants, retold by Herodotus i n all their vivid and perhaps partisan particularity. Even as he retells the stories from the distant past told by foreign experts, the first move o f Herodotus as the authorial T o f the text indicates to us that he will not necessarily believe that such logoi tell the truth, because they are quite likely to be tendentious and self-serving. This is a rhetorical stance implicitly sustained throughout the narrative to come. Herodotus will go to some lengths to tell the best version possible o f the logoi he has heard (or read; he does not distinguish the two), but he will not abandon the initial rhetorical distinction drawn between his own voice and that o f the material he retells from others." This strong demarcation o f his own voice as qualitatively different from what he has got from others lay behind my decision, i n the mid-1980s, to investigate the authorial T in Herodotus. I began by trying to see the range o f the expressions Herodotus uses to articulate his own authorial presence i n the narrative, cataloguing 1,086 first-person comments according to four different ways i n which I saw Herodotus interacting with his material: as a bystander, as a investigator, as a critic, and as a narrator. The basic image I used in 1987 was o f Herodotus as a Menelaus-like figure struggling with the 'Protean' logoi, forcing them to reveal what truths they contained. The four ways i n which he engaged with the logoi I discussed as four different kinds o f handholds used to subdue the logoi to his will. This approach still has something to recommend it, especially i n its recognition o f the sharp distinction that Herodotus often makes separating his own voice from that o f his sources, and the variety of different 10
12
111
Dewald (1999) 229-33 discusses the difficulty of knowing in any passage precisely where the voice of Herodotus as narrator gives way to the localization of a narrated logos. See Lateiner (1989) 101-2 for Herodotus' (possible) written sources and West (1985) for his use of epigraphy; for his own statements about writing, see Hartog (1988) 277-89 and Edmunds (1993) 835 (comparing him to Thucydides). De Jong (1999) points out that, although writing is referred to (e.g., 2.123), most of Herodotus' comments as a narrator are those of 'un narrateur qui parle plutôt qu'un narrateur qui écrit'. Dewald (1987) 147-70. 11
12
272
CAROLYN D E W A L D
j u d g m e n t s he makes as a n a u t h o r i a l p e r s o n a i n the text.
However,
i t n o l o n g e r seems to m e adequately to s u m u p H e r o d o t u s ' engagem e n t as a n T
w i t h his t e x t , precisely because i t takes at face value
the b i n a r y division between n a r r a t o r a n d n a r r a t e d logoi that H e r o d o t u s as n a r r a t o r o f t e n insists u p o n . " B u t i f one i n s t e a d b r o a d e n s the n o t i o n o f a u t h o r i a l presence t o i n c l u d e n o t o n l y the o v e r t
first-person
p r o n o u n s a n d verbs b u t also
all o f the places w h e r e the a u t h o r i a l T
is effectively present as a
tacit register o f a u t h o r i t a t i v e c o n t r o l o v e r w h a t is b e i n g r e c o u n t e d , as n a r r a t o l o g y has t a u g h t us n o w to d o , the p i c t u r e one f o r m s o f H e r o d o t u s ' a u t h o r i a l i n t e r v e n t i o n s is m o r e c o m p l e x t h a n this i n i t i a l b i n a r y s e p a r a t i o n i n t o n a r r a t o r a n d f o c a l i z e d logoi suggests. 1 4
For
a l t h o u g h H e r o d o t u s goes t o c o n s i d e r a b l e pains to establish t h e i d e a t h a t the text s t r a i g h t f o r w a r d l y alternates b e t w e e n his o w n v o i c e a n d j u d g m e n t a n d t h e n a r r a t i o n o f stories he has h e a r d , s i m u l t a n e o u s l y a d i f f e r e n t a n d m o r e c o m p l i c a t e d set o f n a r r a t i v e relations b e t w e e n a u t h o r a n d t e x t is also present. I f w e l o o k closely, H e r o d o t u s engages w i t h t h e text n o t o n l y as a n a r r a t o r a n d c r i t i c o f t h e logoi o f o t h e r s , b u t also as a n a u t h o r , c o n s t r u c t i n g a n a r r a t i v e o f his o w n o f a n e w a n d different k i n d . I n this chapter I w i l l (at the risk o f some a n a c h r o n ism) reserve the use o f t h e t e r m histor f o r this second k i n d o f a u t h o r i a l e n g a g e m e n t as a n T B o t h registers, the T
i n the text.13 o f t h e n a r r a t o r a n d the ' I ' o f the histor, are
c r u c i a l to t h e w a y t h e genre o f h i s t o r y itself l a t e r develops, a l t h o u g h
13
It is much clearer to me now than it was a decade ago that this material is highly labile and will order itself in any number of different legitimate configurations, depending on the scholarly questions uppermost in the investigator's mind. Other important studies of Herodotus' authorial first person include Hartog (1980), DarboPeschanski (1987), Lateiner (1989), Marincola (1987) and (1999), Fowler (1996), de Jong (1999), Thomas (2000), and Munson (2001). For some of the more important narratological studies, including in particular those analysing ancient historical narratives, see Dewald (1999) 223 n. 4. Calame (1995) 78 96, Bakker (1997d), Gribble (1998), and de Jong (1999) should be added to the list of authors cited there. In Dewald (1987) 153 I used the term histor to signify the whole of Herodotus' authorial persona. I use it here more narrowly, to signify the register of the authorial voice that conveys and tests information about the world; this is the part of Herodotus' authorial ' I ' that Thucydides and other historians after him will adopt as the basis of their own authorial personas as historians (cf. n. 28 below). Cf. Evans (1990) 94-5, who doubts the usefulness of the term histor altogether, but see also Nagy (1990) 250-73, Connor (1993) 3 n. 5, and Darbo-Peschanski (1995) 179-81. The term is technically anachronistic for Herodotus, but useful in that it points toward (but is not identical to) the later more developed persona of the 'historian'. Further discussion of histor in Bakker, this volume (Ch. 1, pp. 14-16). 14
15
' I D I D N ' T GIVE MY O W N GENEALOGY'
273
i n quite different ways. Both establish quite far-reaching interpretive connections within the ongoing text o f the Histories, affecting our readerly understanding o f the third-person narrative, and together they anticipate the epistemological and ethical complexities raised by the status o f history as a human science discussed above. As we have already seen in considering the Histories' proem, the narrator's initial T on the one hand articulates the narrative structure to come as a binary one: material initially received from others is told and to a certain extent arranged and critiqued by Herodotus himself. The histor's ' 1 , ' however, engages us as readers with a quite different set o f concerns: it criticizes bits o f information as data, but it also communicates, supplements, and ultimately interprets the narrated content o f the logoi as a responsible, straightforward, and ongoingrepresentation o f ta anthropeia pregmata, the human world (2.4.1). When Herodotus uses this second authorial register, he treats the contents of the Histories not as a set o f stories drawn from a variety o f different and contestable sources, but rather as parts o f a continuous narrative that has become in effect Herodotus' own account o f a real, lived human past. The two modes or authorial registers overlap to some degree, of course, but they are also fairly easy to distinguish from each other conceptually. Herodotus asks us as readers to attend simultaneously to both registers: to confront the contents o f the Histories as narrated logoi taken from outside sources, arranged and critiqued by Herodotus himself, but at the same time to read the text as a whole as his own ongoing, seriously investigated account o f the cultures and events that produced the Persian Wars. Here we shall briefly explore each register o f the authorial T i n turn (for the sake o f simplicity I will call them two voices, narrator and histor) and then attempt to put them back together, acknowledging that, after all, the same ' I ' speaks for them both. As we shall see, paradoxically it is the voice o f the narrator, overtly distancing himself from the logoi he has gathered, that makes possible the responsible authority o f the histor, it is the histor's voice, on the other hand, that makes us see the narrator's efforts as ultimately more than mere entertainment, because the logoi he retells also become, within the ongoing framework established by the histor, important data that together comprise an ongoing account about real human communities told by Herodotus himself.
274
CAROLYN
DEWALD
Herodotus as .Narrator: Managing the Logoi Herodotus' basic move as a first-person presence i n his text is to articulate for the reader the rudiments o f how he sees his role as a narrator o f logoi gathered from others. I n hundreds o f metanarrative statements scattered throughout the Histories he confirms what we have already gathered from the proem, that he has heard many logoi from others and that he is i n charge o f deciding which logoi to include and how to retell them. A n almost random sample drawn from all nine books gives some idea of the range o f expressions that affirm one or both o f these functions: ' [n] ow as some of the Persians say, those not wanting to glorify the Cyrus account but to tell the real story, this is the version I will write, although I also know how to say three other paths o f story concerning Cyrus' (1.95); 'but o f the other Heracles, w h o m the Greeks know, I was unable to hear anywhere from an Egyptian' (2.43.1); 'but this logos too is told, to me not trustworthy, that some one o f the Persian women came visiting the wives o f C y r u s . . .' (3.3); '[t]he vision o f the dream of Hipparchus and the origins o f the Gephuraei, the family o f the slayers o f Hipparchus, have been told by me. But it is necessary in addition to these things still to return to the logos I set out to tell at the outset, how the Athenians were freed from tyranny' (5.62); ' I write according to what the rest o f the Greeks say' (6.53); 'although I have to say what is said, I am not at all obliged to believe it, and this declaration on my part is to hold for the whole narrative (es panta logon)' (7.152.3), ' [ h ] o w Artabazus was aided by Timoxenus the Scionian g e n e r a l . . . I can't say (for it is not reported), but finally such things happened' (8.128). Such comments indicate how Herodotus wants us to understand his own fundamental function i n the text: he retells logoi he has heard. He acknowledges the existence o f sources and both their strengths and their limitations as purveyors o f information throughout the text, although admittedly on a sporadic basis (e.g., 1.214.5, 4.16.2, 8.135.1, 9.16.1). He also informs us i n passing about various kinds o f editorial control he exerts upon what he recounts. He tells us that he chooses to end one logos and begin another, he cuts 16
lb
Fowler (1996) 77 suggests that the citation of sources may be an innovation of Herodotus' own, judging from the surviving fragments of other early writers like Hecataeus, Acusilaus, and Pherecydes.
1 DIDN'T GIVE M Y O W N GENEALOGY
275
logoi short, or lengthens them, sometimes telling us why (2.117, 2.135.6, 3.60.1, 4.14.1, 7.100). He briefly and usually quite generally judges the quality of what he retells as information, sometimes stating that something must be said or, on the contrary, can be bypassed (2.86.2, 5.62.1, 7.96.1, 7.187, 8.85.3). He includes variant versions of the same story (3.9.2, 4.11.1, 8.119, 9.74), and acknowledges cross-references, places in his text where something being narrated is relevant to an earlier or later passage (2.161.3, 5.36, 9.32.2), or states that he is returning to an earlier topic (4.82, 5.62, 7.137, 7.171). ' Occasionally he views the logoi he retells as having a m i n d of their own, that heads the ongoing narrative off in a particular direction (1.95, 4.30). However, he pointedly omits heuresis, invention, from this repertoire o f narrative moves but rather emphasizes again and again that what follows has been told to h i m by others (9.84). He expresses this idea not only in the overt first-person comments, but also through other, less obtrusive metanarrative expressions as well. There is an enormous additional amount of metanarrative comment spread throughout all nine books that is not explicitly added by the first-person narrator per se, but nonetheless confirms and extends the idea that his principal function is to act as a hearer and reteller of the logoi o f others. 200 times a narrative segment begins or is allowed to continue by the simple expedient o f announcing that someone says something ('the Athenians say . . .', 'the Corinthians say . . .', 'the Ammonians say . . .', 'the Carthaginians say . . .'). Another 111 times the passive legetai, 'it is said' is similarly used, generally to extend or amplify an ongoing narrative. Each time this metanarrative move occurs, the reader has again tacitly encountered Herodotus as narrator, although here in a self-effacing mode, implicitly reminding us that he retells logoi gathered from elsewhere. 1
18
For the future of the genre he begins, it is important to see that this is not just a move exonerating Herodotus from responsibility (although this is apparently how Plutarch later reads it i n the de Herodoti malignitate, Mor. 856c). For Herodotus makes clear his belief
" Alternate or variant versions of the same account often involve the authorial voice as a narrator of logoi but simultaneously as a histdr assessing (logoi as) data as well; cf. n. 25 below and esp. Lateiner (1989) 82-90. Thus de Jong (1999) 220-3 describes this narrator as heterodiegetic (following the terminology of Genette and Bal). Cf. Dcwald (1999) 224 n. 7. See also Ch. 11 of this volume. On the question of sources, see also Hornblower (Ch. 16), this volume. 18
276
CAROLYN DEWALD
t h a t there are l i m i t s to w h a t he c a n say, l i m i t s t h a t the logoi t h e m selves define. T h a t is, the logoi o f others t h a t p r o v i d e the basic n a r r a t i v e c o n t e n t o f the Histories are p r e s e n t e d b y t h e i r n a r r a t o r - a u t h o r , Herodotus,
as things o u t i n the w o r l d . T o
use B a k h t i n ' s t e r m , this
is a p r o f o u n d l y d i a l o g i c m o v e : i t makes c e n t r a l t o the Histories the otherness o f H e r o d o t u s '
m u l t i p l e i n f o r m a n t s as voices he has listened
to a n d is t r a n s m i t t i n g i n t u r n to us. I n H e r o d o t u s '
n a r r a t i v e w e are
a p p a r e n t l y e n c o u n t e r i n g the p o l y v o c a l i s m o f the w o r l d itself. 1 '' T h e s e r a t h e r simple r h e t o r i c a l m o v e s r e p e a t e d l y d i s t i n g u i s h i n g the n a r r a t o r f r o m w h a t he claims to r e t e l l also c u m u l a t i v e l y a r t i c u l a t e h o w H e r o d o t u s w a n t s us as readers t o perceive the Histories' f u n d a m e n t a l n a r r a t i v e s t r u c t u r e . As
Immerwahr
s h o w e d us almost
years ago, the Histories is o v e r t l y a r t i c u l a t e d as a c o n t i n u o u s
forty parat-
actic sequence o f n a r r a t i v e u n i t s , each i n t r o d u c e d a n d c o n c l u d e d b y a quasi-formular
sentence whose
c h i e f f u n c t i o n is to m a r k t h a t
a
n e w u n i t (or s u b - u n i t w i t h i n a u n i t ) is b e g i n n i n g o r e n d i n g ; R o s a r i a M u n s o n has d e m o n s t r a t e d t h a t e a c h n a r r a t i v e u n i t contains a f o r m u l a i c i n t r o d u c t o r y o r c o n c l u d i n g sentence t h a t acts as a
metanar-
r a t i v e gloss r e c o n f i r m i n g the b i n a r y d i v i s i o n b e t w e e n the voice
of
the n a r r a t o r a n d t h a t o f the logoi t h a t w e have b e e n e x p l o r i n g h e r e . 2 0 By
announcing
to us t h a t yet a n o t h e r
n a r r a t i v e segment
is e i t h e r
b e g i n n i n g o r e n d i n g , the f o r m u l a r i n t r o d u c t o r y a n d c o n c l u d i n g sentences o f the v a r i o u s n a r r a t i v e u n i t s also t a c i t l y c o n f i r m the presence o f H e r o d o t u s as a h e l p f u l guide to the o n g o i n g chain o f narratives he retells. H e i n t r u d e s at the e n d o f one segment a n d the b e g i n n i n g o f the n e x t w i t h c o m m e n t s to help us as readers to m a k e sense
of
w h a t w e r e a d , as w e p r o c e e d a l o n g the logon hodos (1.95.1), a n d t o trust t h a t there is a discursive shape i n w h a t m i g h t otherwise be a p u z z l i n g , a m o r p h o u s j u m b l e o f disparate stories. T h u s the n a r r a t o r ' s T
has t w o i m p o r t a n t f u n c t i o n s . First, i t allows
the n o t i o n to emerge o f the logoi o f others as objects, themselves p a r t
19
Dewald (1999) 247. For the importance of this move to the invention of history as a genre, see Meier's (1987) 45 description of the Histories as a 'multi-subjective account'. Cf. Berkhofer (1995) 28-31, 36-40 on the related problem of 'reconstructing the plenitude of the Great Story'. On 'dialogism' in Herodotus' historié, see also Bakker, this volume (Ch. 1, p. 18). Immerwahr (1966); Munson (1983) and (2001). See also de Jong (Ch. 11, this volume). Herodotus, however, rarely specifies that the logoi demarcated by formular beginning and ending sentences are precisely the same thing as the logoi he has heard from others and is narrating in his text. Presumably the nature of logos itself, in an oral world, discourages clear attribution of ownership. See also n. 10 above. 20
277
' I DIDN'T GIVE M Y O W N GENEALOGY'
o f the p h e n o m e n a l w o r l d , t h a t c a n be r e t o l d b u t also e x a m i n e d
and
c o m m e n t e d u p o n as objects w o r t h y o f a t t e n t i o n . S e c o n d , i t p r o v i d e s us w i t h a w a y t o u n d e r s t a n d the w i l d l y heterogeneous
collection of
m a t e r i a l i n t h e Histories as a r o u g h l y s e q u e n t i a l c h a i n o f c o n t i n u o u s logoi, a r r a n g e d f o r us b y H e r o d o t u s h i m s e l f , b u t n o t i n v e n t e d b y h i m .
Herodotus as H i s t 5 r : Representation of Data Herodotus'
voice as a histm- has a f u n c t i o n i n the t e x t q u i t e d i f f e r e n t
f r o m t h a t o f t h e n a r r a t o r . I n 1987 ial T
I d i v i d e d t h e cluster o f a u t h o r -
c o m m e n t s I a m n o w c a l l i n g t h e histor i n t o t h r e e separate
and
d i s t i n c t categories (the i n v e s t i g a t o r , the c r i t i c , the b y s t a n d e r ) ; n a r r a t o l o g i c a l tools i n w i d e use t o d a y , h o w e v e r ,
h e l p us see a l l o f these
f u n c t i o n s i n s t e a d as i n t e r l i n k e d a n d m u t u a l l y d e p e n d e n t
parts o f a
single a u t h o r i a l register o r v o i c e . W h e n he uses i t , H e r o d o t u s
is n o t
a c t i n g as a n a r r a t o r , t h a t is, a r r a n g e r , c r i t i c , a n d reteller o f logoi o t h ers have g i v e n h i m , b u t is r a t h e r a h e l p f u l assessor/expositor o f facts a b o u t the w o r l d t h a t , t o g e t h e r w i t h t h e logoi he retells, g r i d f o r the reader the p h e n o m e n a t h a t are b e i n g d e s c r i b e d i n the o n g o i n g n a r r a t i v e as d i f f e r e n t aspects o f a single i n t e r l o c k i n g w h o l e . 2 1 At
its simplest, this is a p e r s o n a t h a t is w e l l k n o w n i n the genre
o f o r a l storytelling. T o cite a c o n t e m p o r a r y e x a m p l e , R i c h a r d B a u m a n , the A m e r i c a n
ethnographer
a n d f o l k l o r i s t , describes t h e
extensive
changes t h a t o c c u r r e d i n one w e l l k n o w n A m e r i c a n story-teller's p e r f o r m a n c e s b e t w e e n 1967 a n d 1 9 8 2 . 2 2 D u r i n g this t i m e the story-teller i n question, Ed
B e l l , c o n t i n u e d t o tell t h e l o c a l l y - b a s e d t a l l tales he
h a d i n i t i a l l y t o l d t o his clients a n d n e i g h b o u r s at his
fishing
camp
at I n d i a n o l a , b u t i n the l a t e r versions t e l l i n g t h e m at substantially g r e a t e r l e n g t h . W h e n B a u m a n c a u g h t u p w i t h h i m after m o r e t h a n fifteen
years as a n o t e d p e r f o r m e r at u r b a n f o l k festivals, a n d f o u n d
t h e stories m u c h
longer t h a n they
had
originally been,
e x p l a i n e d , ' j c f j o w n o n the coast, e v e r y b o d y
Ed
Bell
k n e w a l l this stuff, so I
d i d n ' t h a v e t o describe i t i n d e t a i l . I go i n t o m o r e d e t a i l , n o w ,
21
to
Good descriptions of this integrating authorial imagination are found in Immerwahr (1966) 306 26; Hartog (1988) 341-60; Gould (1989). Bauman (1986) 78 I l l , esp. 103. See also Städter (1997) 7, who very suggestively compares the Jack tales of the North Carolina oral narrative tradition to Herodotus' 'pan-Hellenic account which could speak to a variety of persons'. 22
278
CAROLYN D E W A L D
be sure'. Bauman consequently entitled one o f his chapters, describing a narratorial mode much like a simplified form of Herodotus' histofs persona, ' I go into more detail now, to be sure.' Stripped to its essentials, this voice can be characterized as one of helpful supplementation of the narrative, fleshing it out, making it more comprehensible to the reader. Herodotus' quasi-autobiographical comments about his own efforts as an investigator provide his most explicitly personal and engaged expressions as a histor. I n Book T w o especially, Herodotus presents himself i n his own text almost as an actor, certainly as the initiator, guide, and discoverer o f information. He expressly tells us in 2.99 that his general procedure is to rely on sight (apsis), reasoning (gnome) and inquiry (historié). As John Marincola comments, in Book T w o , '[h]e has gone to great pains to find the sources o f the Nile (2.19), checked to see i f the various reports o f priests agree with one another (2.3), asked about the origin of the god Heracles (2.44) and heard from the priests themselves of the antiquity o f Egypt and her rulers (2.99). I n Book T w o Herodotus explicitly states and places before our eyes his participation i n the process o f inquiry. The impression of a conversation is at times further achieved by the quotation o f long passages o f the stories o f the priests in indirect discourse'. 23
Marincola argues that this very personal, assertive, quasi-autobiographical persona is heavily polemical, often or even usually in evidence where Herodotus is correcting or improving a specific prior account. T h a t may well be right; it is certainly true that this particular version o f the investigating, supplemental histoYs voice occurs most frequently i n Book T w o , where Herodotus seems frequently to abandon structuring his account as a sequence o f logoi, providing instead his own enormous ethnographic survey of the land, flora, fauna, and customs o f the Egyptians. I would add only to Marincola's observations about the controversial, combative flavour o f Herodotus' quasi-autobiographical investigatory observations that there is also something o f an air o f paradox about many of them. Frequently Herodotus says that he himself went somewhere, or saw something, in order to provide us the assurance that something odd or unexpected is nonetheless to be taken seriously, because he himself has
23
Marincola (1987) 127-8; see also Fornara (1971a) 18-23, Dewald (1987) 155-9, and n. 25 below.
279
' I DIDN'T GIVE M Y O W N GENEALOGY'
seen it. Sometimes opsis and interview are used together to destroy an inadequate set o f previous assumptions, without themselves generating a correct answer i n its place (2.131, 2.143). The quasi-autobiographical T that appears i n the early parts of Book T w o is often found linked w i t h a second and much more pervasive aspect o f Herodotus' voice as a histor- -one i n which he discusses data and arguments critically. O f all the kinds o f authorial intervention we are looking at here, this one is closest to and perhaps even responsible for the later development o f the generically conventional historian's persona: the investigator who tests data before including it i n his or her own historical account. We should note that this part o f Herodotus' authorial voice, the critical histor, often cannot be completely separated from his voice as a narrator, editing and assessing logoi. The critical histor, however, emphasizes facts and arguments about data rather than his own engagement in the reporting and assessing o f logoi, and the construction o f his own account out of logoif 24
1
A t least superficially, Herodotus' critical comments about the truth or likelihood o f some phenomenon provide an authorial rhetoric of assurance, authority, and control over data. O n a handful of occasions he says he knows something. But much more common than expressions o f certainty are various forms o f opinion, ranging from qualified belief to outright disbelief. As a histor Herodotus does not assess or argue the probability o f large stretches of narrative (as we have seen, these he fundamentally defines as material he is reporting, and he controls them as a narrator), but he does speculate about and provisionally judge individual details: the Persian conspirators really did debate establishing a democratic government (3.80.1, 6.43.3), a silver bowl at Delphi might well have been made by Theodoras (1.51), Scyllias probably did not swim to Artemisium (8.8.2); Anacharsis definitely did not praise the moderation of Spartan speech (4.77). M a n y o f the longer discussions o f this type occur i n Books T w o and Four and concern details of natural history or ethnography. Beyond Book Four, he more frequently questions the motive an individual
2 4
Dcwald (1987) 158. Cf. Dewald (1993) 59, 67-70. See Lateiner (1989) 78-90 for Herodotean source criticism. When undertaking 'source criticism' Herodotus is often expressing himself as both narrator and histor simultaneously. See Fowler (1996) 80 6 for a good assessment of Fehling's (1989) analysis of Herodotus' sources and source criticism as largely invented. See also Hornblower, this volume (Ch. 16). 23
280
CAROLYN DEWALD
m i g h t have h a d t o d o s o m e t h i n g , t h e c o r r e c t c a l c u l a t i o n o f n u m bers, o r m a t t e r s o f r e l i g i o n o r g n o m i c j u d g m e n t . 2 6 B o t h D o n a l d L a t e i n e r a n d C a t h e r i n e D a r b o - P e s c h a n s k i have s t u d i e d the i m p l i c a t i o n s o f this aspect o f H e r o d o t u s ' a u t h o r i a l T
i n some
d e t a i l , b u t t h e y place d i f f e r e n t emphases o n w h a t t h e y have seen. L a t e i n e r has c o n s i d e r e d i n p a r t i c u l a r the passages w h e r e H e r o d o t u s says he c a n n o t ascertain s o m e t h i n g , o r has to c o n j e c t u r e because h a r d d a t a was m i s s i n g , o r is d i s i n c l i n e d t o treat s o m e t h i n g t r i v i a l o r o f a religious n a t u r e . A s we have seen, he also focuses o n a l t e r n a tive versions o f t h e same story, i n p a r t i c u l a r w h e r e H e r o d o t u s discusses the v a l i d i t y o f v a r i o u s sources o f i n f o r m a t i o n , some o f t h e m probably w r i t t e n . 2 ' For
L a t e i n e r , such statements m a k e
Herodotus
t h e q u i n t e s s e n t i a l h i s t o r i a n , because t h e y p r o v i d e t h e e t h i c a l reassurance t h a t allows the r e a d e r to trust t h a t w h a t has b e e n n a r r a t e d was a r r i v e d at b y serious, sober research a n d n o t d i v i n e i n s p i r a t i o n o r novelistic flights o f f a n c y . 2 8 Catherine Darbo-Peschanski,
o n the other h a n d , builds o n the
w o r k o f H a r t o g b u t expands the scope o f his structuralist i n q u i r y i n t o H e r o d o t u s ' l a n g u a g e b y i n t e r p r e t i n g i t as the language o f a q u a s i - p h i l o s o p h i c a l , even sophistic, r h e t o r i c . She uses v i r t u a l l y t h e same m a t e r i a l as L a t e i n e r t o emphasize t h a t w i t h his c r i t i c a l c o m m e n t s as a histor H e r o d o t u s is d e s i g n i n g a p e r s o n a t h a t eschews cert i t u d e as s o m e t h i n g n o t available i n the h u m a n w o r l d . She discusses h o w H e r o d o t u s uses a r g u m e n t s f r o m signs, a r g u m e n t s f r o m a n a l o g y , a n d d e d u c t i v e a r g u m e n t s f r o m h y p o t h e t i c a l p r o p o s i t i o n s t o get a t w h a t is, i n his o p i n i o n , m o s t l i k e l y i n a n y g i v e n i n s t a n c e . 2 9 B u t she
26
Lateiner (1989) 55-75. Cf. Verdin (1971), Weber (1976), Strasburger (1982a) 838-81, Packman (1991) 359-408, Thomas (1997) and (2000) 168-212. Connor (1993) 9 argues that Herodotus' critical authorial role is comparable to that of the archaic histor or legal arbitrator. For statements of knowledge, see Lateiner (1989) 71. Cf. Darbo-Peschanski (1987) 165-84, Dewald (1989) 160-1. Lateiner (1989) 69 75; cf. n. 17 above. 'For historians the ethical core of their professional commitment has always been a belief that their arduous, often tedious labour yields some authentic knowledge of the dead "other", a knowledge admittedly shaped by the historian's own perceptions and biases, but nonetheless retaining a degree of autonomy, in the sense that it cannot (putatively) be made entirely to bend to the historian's will,' Spiegel (1992) 196. Cf. Berkhofer (1995) 66-70, but see also Appleby, Hunt, and Jacob (1994) 254-61. For the importance of the historian's character in the ancient world, see Marincola (1997) 128-74. Darbo-Peschanski (1987) 137-53; the category of 'refutations' is also interesting in this context, p. 154. 27
28
29
281
' I DIDN'T GIVE M Y O W N GENEALOGY'
stresses t h a t this l a t t e r q u a l i f i c a t i o n is c r u c i a l l y i m p o r t a n t . T h a t is, H e r o d o t u s constructs a n a r r a t i v e i n w h i c h his c o n c l u s i o n w i l l r e m a i n , in
each p a r t i c u l a r passage,
one,
moreover,
t h a t holds o n l y f o r t h e i m m e d i a t e discussion at h a n d . N o
individual
argument
is e x t e n d e d
Thucydides
o n l y his o p i n i o n — a n d
to become
more
broadly
applicable,
c l a i m s w i l l be the case f o r his o w n t h o u g h t
Herodotus
as
processes.
refuses a u n i v e r s a l system o f r e a s o n i n g , a p p l i c a b l e i n a l l
cases, a n d , m o r e b r o a d l y , he r e n o u n c e s , i n his c r i t i c a l p e r s o n a as a histor, a h o l d o n t r u t h , a n c h o r i n g his w o r k i n s t e a d i n t h e ' r e a l m o f opinion'.30 So f a r , w e have c o n s i d e r e d t w o o f H e r o d o t u s ' o f data,
stances as a histor
those I e a r l i e r l a b e l l e d ' i n v e s t i g a t o r ' a n d
Peschanski's
take o n the histor's c o m m e n t s
'critic'.
t h i n k i n i n t e r e s t i n g ways a b o u t a t h i r d a n d m o r e a m o r p h o u s of
first-person
Darbo-
as a c r i t i c allows us t o group
a u t h o r i a l c o m m e n t s , those w h e r e he reacts as a n i n t e r -
ested a n d v a g u e l y responsive b y s t a n d e r t o s o m e t h i n g t h e t h i r d - p e r son n a r r a t i v e r e p o r t s . I f D a r b o - P e s c h a n s k i is r i g h t , a n d comments
as a histor o f d a t a are n o t m e a n t
Herodotus'
p r i m a r i l y t o increase
a c c u r a c y a n d p r e c i s i o n , a n d hence o u r t r u s t i n the f a c t u a l t r u t h
of
w h a t he r e c o u n t s , b u t r a t h e r to r e m i n d us t h a t he is p u t t i n g his o w n j u d g m e n t o u t es meson, a l o n g w i t h those o f his i n f o r m a n t s a n d his readers, t h e n this g r o u p o f r e l a t i v e l y u n o b t r u s i v e c o m m e n t s ,
respon-
sive r a t h e r t h a n c r i t i c a l , are some o f the m o s t i m p o r t a n t o f a l l ; t h e y serve t o a n c h o r H e r o d o t u s '
first-person
generalized a n d modest alert-
ness as a histor f a r d o w n w i t h i n t h e f a b r i c o f t h e o n g o i n g n a r r a t e d text. F o u r groups o f spontaneous a u t h o r i a l c o m m e n t o c c u r w i t h some frequency:
ton hemeis iclmen w i t h a c o r r e l a t i v e o r s u p e r l a t i v e , es erne,
statements o f w o n d e r , Herodotus
a n d statements o f praise a n d b l a m e . 3 1
uses a c o r r e l a t i v e o r a superlative w i t h ton hemeis idmen
i n o r d e r t o say t h a t s o m e t h i n g is e x t r a o r d i n a r y , the first o r best o r m o s t e x t r e m e i n some w a y : Croesus is 'the first b a r b a r i a n o f w h o m we know'
to subdue
G r e e k cities (1.5); t h e E t h i o p i a n
Troglodytes,
whose language sounds like the squeak o f a b a t , are the fastest m e n
3 0
Darbo-Peschanski (1987) 164 88, esp. 184-8. Thomas (1993, 2000) stresses the similarities between Herodotus and the early Hippocratic writers and suggests that their eristic discourse represented the way serious scientific inquiry worked in the fifth century BC. To the bibliography in Dewald (1987) 155 nn. 20-1 add Hartog (1988) 230-7, Redfield (1985), Bloomer (1993) 30 50 (on superlatives), Rosier (1991), Thomas (2000) 138-53. 31
282
CAROLYN D E W A L D
in the world 'of w h o m we have heard by report' (4.183); Themistocles was the only man ' o f w h o m we know' to receive an honorary escort from the Spartans (8.124); the crocodile of all animals we know o f grows from the smallest beginnings into the largest size (2.68.2). Such comments, although relatively insignificant individually, have a cumulative effect that is important. They again show that the authorial judgment i n play is one that is secular and social, not obtained as part of an unshakable tradition or by divine fiat. These superlatives express i n an abbreviated form the diffidence that Herodotus insists on as a critic, in passages like 2.34, 4.192, or 4.197: 'to the greatest extent to which we in our investigations have been able to come'. The same points can be made o f his expressions o f praise and blame, wonder, and 'to my time'. Praise and blame are, as Plutarch later complains, liberally bestowed on people for their actions i n the Histories, but in the context o f the ongoing narrative, not usually in Herodotus' own voice as a histor}' When Herodotus overtly praises or blames something in the narrative i n his own voice, it almost always concerns an intellectual accomplishment. Twelve of the fifteen most striking instances o f praise concern intellectual or cultural achievement: particularly worthy laws, Egyptian judgment, Scythian cleverness i n their modes of self-defence. Sixteen of the eighteen overt instances o f authorial blame also concern an intellectual or cultural exploit: the Lacedaemonians are w r o n g to claim the bowl inscribed for them at Delphi (1.51). Ionians think inaccurately about Egypt (2.16), or want to become known for their cleverness (2.20, 24); the Greeks tell a silly logos about Heracles (2.45), an inaccurate one about Rhodopis (2.134) and about. Polycrates (3.45). Herodotus laughs outright at the absurd efforts o f map makers (4.36). 1
Herodotus promises i n his proem to report things that are thometsta, wonderful. He uses expressions o f wonder to discuss things he himself believes exceptional; he justifies the length o f his accounts o f Egypt and Polycrates' Samos by pointing to the numbers o f wonders these countries contain (2.35, 3.60); he notes the absence of wonders worth mentioning in Lydia and Scythia (1.93, 4.82). Wonder itself, however, includes a variety o f different authorial attitudes within
32
Plutarch, Mm. 856c-863; see Marincola (1994) 201-3. Thomas (2000) 242 8 rightly stresses that when one does not look specifically for the first person, but rather for the authorial register of the histor, his polemical reach becomes much more extensive and combative in a way that resembles early Hippocratic texts.
283
' I DIDN'T GIVE M Y O W N GENEALOGY
it; Herodotus wonders at spectacular achievements, at things he considers real but probably cannot explain, at portents and other supernatural manifestations, and, finally, at reports or logoi that he flatly disbelieves. Finally, over one hundred times Herodotus remarks that some phenomenon mentioned in the narrative survives ep'eme or es erne, 'to my own day', or that something exists nun, now. His mentions of his own time both connect Herodotus' own narrative present, the present o f the onlooker, to the past that forms the subject matter of the Histories, and sharply distinguish it as separate. Traces o f the past continue to exist i n the present: statues, tombs, temples, temple dedications, forts, and roads survive to Herodotus' own day, giving implicit testimony about the reality of the past events i n which they were created. Similarly, festivals, habits of dress, and details o f sacrifice, tribute, law, language, and culture survive i n the present as the ritualized or formalized commemoration o f some event i n the past that gave them b i r t h . But Herodotus also recognizes that such traces of the past i n the present can prove deceptive: the lurid story of paternal rape told of Mycerinus, king o f Egypt, was the work o f phluereontes, babblers, because the statues lacking hands that were supposedly evidence o f this ancient monstrosity were still to be seen i n Herodotus' own day, with their hands merely broken off, lying i n the sand at the statues' feet (2.131). 33
34
35
We have seen that as a narrator Herodotus eschews any claim of heuresis, invention o f material. But i f we really look closely at almost any extended passage in the Histories, a tacit extension o f his histoYs voice can be found on almost every page, that throws this basic claim o f his narrator's voice into doubt. For i f we acknowledge the extent and quality of helpful, sometimes critical, authorial supplementation to the narrative, it begins to look at many points as though the narrative itself is no longer definable as a series o f logoi that
In his wonder at incredible login, we are again venturing rjuite close to the register of his voice as narrator. See Munson (2001) for wonder as a basic Herodotean historiographic principle. Rosier (1991) argues that Herodotus locates his own time as that of a 'historical' past in relation to the time of his readers, and thus tacitly makes some of the claims for the permanence of his work that Thucydides after him does. See also Ch. 4, this volume, pp. 91-2. Kurt Raaflaub rightly points out to me that in this way they do implicitly testify to the fact that the events of which they are traces are still important and meaningful in shaping both the present and our understanding of it. 34
33
284
CAROLYN DEWALD
H e r o d o t u s narrates a n d looks at; i t also, s o m e h o w , has b e c o m e his o w n l a r g e r o n g o i n g a c c o u n t . T h i s is because, as a histor, H e r o d o t u s presides over l e t t i n g t h e m a t e r i a l h e narrates t o us m a k e sense. T h i s voice appears m o s t p r o m i n e n t l y as a n T
i n the ethnogra-
p h i e s , p a r t i c u l a r l y at t h e b e g i n n i n g s o f Books T w o o r F o u r , b u t n o t o n l y t h e r e . L a t e r i n t h e t e x t , i n p a r t b u i l d i n g o n its earlier p r o m i nence i n t h e e t h n o g r a p h i e s , a n i m p l i c i t a u t h o r i a l register o f this sort also suggests its presence, at least as a ' d e v i a n t f o c a l i z a t i o n ' ,
when-
ever t h e o n g o i n g n a r r a t i v e includes t h i r d - p e r s o n statements o f declarative helpfulness whose filling
a u t h o r i t y is n o t i n t e n d e d t o be contested,
i n t h e blanks a n d h e l p i n g us as readers u n d e r s t a n d w h a t is
g o i n g o n a n d h o w to t h i n k a b o u t
it.36
C o n s i d e r , f o r i n s t a n c e , t h e f o l l o w i n g t w o passages, d r a w n at r a n d o m f r o m t h e n a r r a t i v e o f events.
Neither
of them
almost contains
a n e x t e n d e d expression o f a u t h o r i a l i n t r u s i o n as a n T , b u t each o f t h e m c o n t a i n s t h e t o n e o f c o m m u n i c a t i v e expansiveness t h a t is f o u n d i n the register o f the author-as-fe/or, s u p p l e m e n t i n g t h e t h i r d - p e r s o n n a r r a t i v e o f events w i t h a d d i t i o n a l i n f o r m a t i o n . T h e first passage occurs i n B o o k F o u r ; t h e list-like i n f o r m a t i o n t h a t begins a n d ends the passage is d i r e c t e d b y t h e histor
to the reader
as p a r t o f a n
e x t e n d e d d e s c r i p t i o n o f t h e l a n d a n d people o f L i b y a , p r i o r t o t h e n a r r a t i o n o f t h e logos a b o u t t h e Persian a t t e m p t e d conquest o f t h a t r e g i o n d u r i n g t h e r e i g n o f D a r i u s . T h e i t a l i c i z e d parts are those t h a t m o s t clearly ( t h o u g h tacitly) c o n t a i n t h e h e l p f u l voice o f t h e histor, w i t h i n the third-person account. The Psylloi are the neighbours of the Nasamones. These died out in the following way: the south w i n d blowing dried up their water reservoirs, and their whole land, lying within the Syrtis, was without water. But they taking counsel i n a joint discussion marched on the south w i n d ( I say what the Libyans say), and when they got to the sand, the south wind blowing buried them. Since they have all perished the Nasamones hold their land. And below these to the south in the country of the wild animals live the Garamantes, who flee humankind and the acquaintance of anybody. . . . (4.173—4)
36
This part of the argument initially profited greatly from discussion with D. Fowler. See Fowler's (1990) discussion of deviant focalization, as well as la 'voix off' of Darbo-Peschanski (1987) 114-15; cf. Gribble (1998) 58 61 for Thucydidean 'deviant focalization'. f. de Jong, however, has pointed out to me that strictly speaking focalization should not be used of the authorial voice at all; that is why 1 have described it here in terms of 'register'. The subject clearly requires further discussion; cf. Rood (1998) 294-6.
285
' I D I D N ' T G I V E M Y O W N GENEALOGY'
L a t e r i n t h e Histories, such m a t e r i a l tends t o o c c u r i n passing, inside the n a r r a t i v e o f events: But when Megabazus had taken the Paeonians, he sent seven Persian men as messengers to Macedonia, who after himself were the most respected i n the army. A n d these were sent to Amyntas to request earth and water for Darius the king. There is from the Prasiad lake a very
direct way into Macedonia; for first right near the lake is the mine from which later- came a talent of silver each day for Alexander, and after the mine [it is possible for] one crossing the mountain called Dusoron to be in Macedonia. So when these Persians arrived, coming into the sight o f Amyntas, they requested earth and water for Darius the king. (5.17-18) E a r l i e r w e saw t h a t w h e n he is u s i n g his n a r r a t o r ' s v o i c e ,
Herodotus
persuades us t o t h i n k o f t h e Histories as m a t e r i a l r e t o l d f r o m others (as i n t h e c o m m e n t ' I say w h a t t h e L i b y a n s say', i n 4.173). A n d y e t , i n b o t h t h e above passages, t h e actual c o n t e n t o f t h e o n g o i n g n a r r a t i v e i n c l u d e s a great d e a l o f i m p l i c i t m a t e r i a l a d d e d b y H e r o d o t u s as histm, so extensively s u p p l e m e n t i n g t h e bones o f t h e stories (the fate o f the Psylloi; the entry o f the Persian ambassadors i n t o Macedonia) t h a t i t becomes a q u a l i t a t i v e l y d i f f e r e n t k i n d o f t h i n g a l t o g e t h e r — a n a r r a t i v e n o w w r i t t e n , i n effect, b y H e r o d o t u s
himself. T h e
com-
ments t h a t he adds o f this sort, n o t obviously m a r k e d w i t h the a u t h o r ial T
b u t i m p a r t i n g its h e l p f u l , s u p p l e m e n t a l a n d fact-based
flavour
to t h e o n g o i n g n a r r a t i v e nonetheless, severely m o d i f i e s t h e n a r r a t o r ' s insistence t h a t H e r o d o t u s - t h e - a u t h o r
is m e r e l y at base r e t e l l i n g the
hgoi o f others. I t is n o t clear t h a t H e r o d o t u s
a n d his i m m e d i a t e
contemporaries
(his o r i g i n a l audiences, f o r instance) w o u l d have h e a r d t w o distinct registers i n his a u t h o r i a l voice. Perhaps i n H e r o d o t u s '
o w n d a y his
c o m m e n t s as a histor w i t h i n t h e n a r r a t i v e w e r e seen o n l y as a set o f h e l p f u l p a r e n t h e t i c a l r e m a r k s - - m a k i n g t h e n a r r a t i v e , like E d
Bell's
t a l l stories, 'a little l o n g e r ' , i n o r d e r t o fill o u t f o r t h e p a r t i c u l a r a u d i ence details a b o u t t h e events a n d people n a r r a t e d t h a t w o u l d have r e m a i n e d i n c o m p r e h e n s i b l e w i t h o u t these a d d e n d a . 3 7 O n e c o u l d i m a g ine H e r o d o t u s t r a v e l l i n g a r o u n d t h e G r e e k w o r l d , audience as he w e n t i n his histofs
filling
i n f o r each
voice t h e m a t e r i a l t h a t
would
enable t h e m to u n d e r s t a n d a n d i n t e g r a t e i n t o t h e i r l o c a l k n o w l e d g e the parts o f his logoi f o r e i g n t o t h e i r o w n experience. T h i s is c e r t a i n l y
37
Cf. n. 21 and Nagy (1990) 306-7 on the Panhellenism of the huidr. Cf. Dionysius of Halicarnassus, de Thuc. 5.
286
CAROLYN DEWALD
i m p o r t a n t ; the c o m m u n i c a t i v e s u p p l e m e n t a r i t y o f this voice has m a d e m u c h i n f o r m a t i o n available to us, his later readers, t h a t m i g h t h a v e r e m a i n e d i n c o m p r e h e n s i b l e , h a d H e r o d o t u s w r i t t e n o n l y f o r insiders w h o k n e w w h a t he was t a l k i n g a b o u t . I t m a y w e l l be a large p a r t of why,
o u t o f a l l o f the o l d I o n i a n w r i t e r s , H e r o d o t u s alone
has
been preserved f o r us. B u t its m a j o r i m p o r t a n c e was f o r the genre he b e g a n ,
since the f a s h i o n i n g o f a n a r r a t i v e t h a t
unobtrusively
explains the b a c k g r o u n d details a n d causal connections u n d e r l y i n g events as i t goes a l o n g lies at the h e a r t o f w h a t T h u c y d i d e s a n d o t h ers after H e r o d o t u s w e n t o n to develop as the a u t h o r i a l voice o f h i s torical narrative. T h i s chapter began b y n o t i n g Herodotus' genealogy, a n d w i t h t h e i d e a t h a t i n his
refusal to tell his
first-person
own
authorial voice
he f a s h i o n e d a n 'expert's p e r s o n a ' t h a t o w e d its a u t h o r i t y to the fact t h a t the a u t h o r / n a r r a t o r r e m a i n s a n o u t s i d e r to the text p r o p e r - — i n i m p o r t a n t w a y s , he insists i t is n o t 'his' b u t his r e - e d i t i n g o f logoi he has h e a r d . T h i s is a m o v e a b a n d o n e d
by Thucydides
and
nar-
r a t i v e historians t h e r e a f t e r , w h o c o n s t r u c t instead one a u t h o r i t a t i v e voice t h a t presents the a u t h o r s i m u l t a n e o u s l y as c r i t i c a l n a r r a t o r a n d histor o f his o w n n a r r a t i v e . Herodotus'
authorial persona remains an anomaly, therefore, but
one w i t h a c e r t a i n o d d spaciousness a n d i d i o s y n c r a t i c i n t e g r i t y . H e r o d o t u s ' p r o c e d u r e s as a n T
For
i n his o w n t e x t show t h a t the ques-
t i o n c e n t r a l to h i s t o r i o g r a p h y raised at the b e g i n n i n g o f the c h a p t e r — h i s t o r y as r h e t o r i c , h i s t o r y as h u m a n science—has been there f r o m the v e r y b e g i n n i n g o f the g e n r e , since i t is i m p l i c i t i n b o t h k i n d s o f f o c a l i z a t i o n t h a t H e r o d o t u s uses his a u t h o r i a l ' I ' to c o m m u n i c a t e . I have t r i e d to show t h a t b o t h the ' n a r r a t o r ' a n d the 'Airfor' are c r u c i a l to the w a y the later genre o f h i s t o r y w r i t i n g develops, b u t perhaps i n ways n o t obvious f r o m one's i n i t i a l c o n c e p t i o n these roles. T h e
of
obvious d i v i s i o n b e t w e e n the t w o voices o f course
w o u l d place the n a r r a t o r ' s voice as the r h e t o r i c a l o n e , a n d the histdYs, voice as the one t h a t p a t i e n t l y collects a n d supplements i t w i t h d a t a a n d also w i t h a c r i t i c a l e x a m i n a t i o n o f details c o n t a i n e d i n the n a r r a t i v e . B u t w e have seen t h a t i n one q u i t e i m p o r t a n t respect the roles o f the t w o voices are reversed. F o r
i t is w h e n he is speaking
as a n a r r a t o r t h a t H e r o d o t u s encodes i n t o his t e x t the sense o f d i a l o g i s m t h a t is essential to the i n v e n t i o n o f h i s t o r y as a h u m a n
sci-
e n c e — i n s i s t i n g t h a t the stories he recounts h a v e been l e a r n e d f r o m
287
' I D I D N ' T G I V E M Y O W N GENEALOGY'
others a n d t h a t t h e i r c o n t e n t is n o t a m a t t e r o f his o w n i n v e n t i o n , b u t o n e t h a t c a n be e x a m i n e d c r i t i c a l l y b y h i m s e l f , a n d b y us t o o . A n d a l t h o u g h T h u c y d i d e s , X e n o p h o n , a n d others a b a n d o n this n a r rator's p e r s o n a , c o l l a p s i n g the o v e r t d i s t i n c t i o n b e t w e e n t h e i r o w n voices a n d those o f t h e i r sources, the t a c i t assurance
nonetheless
r e m a i n s t h a t w h a t w e are r e a d i n g i n the Histories is n o t a single story but
a composite account d r a w n f r o m m a n y previous narrators o f
events t h a t have b e e n c o m m u n a l l y l i v e d t h r o u g h a n d r e m e m b e r e d ; i t c o n t i n u e s t o be the n a r r a t o r ' s T t h a t has t a c i t l y selected the parts o f t h e i r c o m p o s i t e story w o r t h r e t e l l i n g . The
voice o f the n a r r a t o r is also w h a t makes possible the sup-
p l e m e n t a l helpfulness o f H e r o d o t u s ' times he intervenes as a n T
histo/s v o i c e - - t h e h u n d r e d s o f
n o t t o talk a b o u t the c o m p o s i t i o n o f
the n a r r a t i v e as a c o l l e c t i o n o f r e t o l d logoi b u t t o r e s p o n d as i f some p a r t o f the c o n t e n t o f t h e p a r t i c u l a r logos u n d e r w a y has serious claims to o u r a t t e n t i o n as a reasonably v e r i d i c a l a c c o u n t , a n d o n e t h a t is i m p l i c i t l y p a r t o f a l a r g e r , o n g o i n g story t h a t H e r o d o t u s h i m s e l f p r e sents. H e r e , t o b o r r o w a l e a f f r o m H e r o d o t u s ' o w n n o t e b o o k , 1 a m n o t g o i n g t o choose b e t w e e n t h e a r g u m e n t s o f L a t e i n e r a n d D a r b o Peschanski, b u t t o r e g a r d t h e m instead as v a r i a n t versions, each o f w h i c h has a g o o d deal t o r e c o m m e n d i t . D a r b o - P e s c h a n s k i gets r i g h t , I
t h i n k , the n o t i o n t h a t H e r o d o t u s
has f a s h i o n e d a histor's persona
for h i m s e l f m u c h o f whose a u t h o r i t y consists i n the fact that i t remains modest:
secular, p r o v i s i o n a l , c a u t i o u s i n its t r u t h c l a i m s . W e are
i n c l i n e d t o trust this voice because i t is so o p e n i n its o w n f i r m decl a r a t i o n o f tentative p r o v i s i o n a l i t y — a n d b o t h halves o f this o x y m o r o n are necessary, f o r us t o a c c o r d i t o u r t r u s t . 3 8 O n the o t h e r h a n d , w h a t L a t e i n e r ' s analysis captures is, u l t i m a t e l y , even m o r e i m p o r t a n t . I have a r g u e d t h a t t h e preface o f the Histories does n o t necessarily create a c o n v e n t i o n a l spatium historicum—a c h r o n o logical t i m e , say the r e i g n o f Croesus, at w h i c h serious H i s t o r i e s , as opposed to m y t h o r l e g e n d , begins. B u t w h a t H e r o d o t u s
has u l t i -
m a t e l y d o n e w i t h his a u t h o r i a l v o i c e , both c r i t i c a l l y r e t e l l i n g logoi and assessing, i n t e r p r e t i n g t h e m a t e r i a l he recounts as d a t a , is t o create for us w i t h i n the text the presence o f his o w n alert a n d c r i t i c a l a u t h o r i a l consciousness as a spatium historicum i n itself. T h e sense i t makes
3a
Momigliano (1966) argues that it was not trusted until the era of European exploration, in the early modern period; see also Bowersock (1989).
288
CAROLYN DEWALD
does n o t y e t lie as i t does for T h u c y d i d e s
i n patterns o f quasi-
p r e d i c t a b l e h u m a n b e h a v i o u r t o be i m p e r s o n a l l y d e d u c e d f r o m d a t a at h a n d . I n s t e a d , i n h u n d r e d s o f a u t h o r i a l gestures—themselves supported by a body o f third-person supplemental information brought b y the histor t o t h e logoi—Herodotus
allows his o w n alert a u t h o r i a l
p e r s o n a t o act as the i n t e r p r e t i v e f r a m e w i t h i n w h i c h the logoi, c o l l e c t e d f r o m a l l o v e r t h e E a s t e r n M e d i t e r r a n e a n w o r l d , f r o m t h e early sixth c e n t u r y d o w n t o his o w n d a y , fall i n t o a m e a n i n g f u l a n d c o h e r ent set o f relationships w i t h one a n o t h e r , so t h a t significant causal c o n n e c t i o n s b e t w e e n o n e set o f events a n d a n o t h e r c a n be d r a w n . U l t i m a t e l y , as T h u c y d i d e s
a n d l a t e r h i s t o r i a n s after h i m saw, this
p e r m i t s t h e histor h i m s e l f t o b e c o m e n a r r a t o r o f a n a c c o u n t t h a t in toto is p r o f o u n d l y d i f f e r e n t i n q u a l i t y f r o m the m a t e r i a l f r o m w h i c h it o r i g i n a l l y has b e e n f a s h i o n e d , w h e t h e r w e t h i n k o f i t as r e t o l d logoi, as i n d i v i d u a l pieces o f m o r e o r less believable d a t a , o r as a b l e n d o f the t w o , as H e r o d o t u s
h i m s e l f seems t o have d o n e .
T h u s h i s t o r y , i n t h e hands o f H e r o d o t u s
its first p r a c t i t i o n e r , is
resolutely b i n o c u l a r : b o t h n a r r a t i v e a n d c r i t i q u e o f n a r r a t i v e , b o t h the voice o f m a n y others a n d the v o i c e o f t h e histor h i m s e l f i n h e l p f u l s u p p l e m e n t a t i o n . T h i s i n t u r n reveals a m o r e basic t r u t h h i s t o r y w r i t i n g as a g e n r e , at least as H e r o d o t u s
about
p e r c e i v e d i t . I t is
clear f r o m t h e w a y he handles t h e m , b o t h as a n a r r a t o r a n d as a histor, t h a t H e r o d o t u s t h i n k s logoi m a t t e r , because t h e y are one o f the best tools w e have b e e n g i v e n f o r u n d e r s t a n d i n g the w o r l d o f ta anthropaa pregmata. A n d despite the c h a r m , t h e s p o n t a n e i t y a n d a p p a r ent delightfulness o f m u c h o f t h e c o n t e n t o f the Histories, the u l t i m a t e o b j e c t i v e o f its a u t h o r ,
this expert's p e r s o n a w i t h w h i c h w e
b e g a n , is serious: to u n d e r s t a n d the h u m a n w o r l d , i n a l l its d i m e n sions. T h r o u g h o u t
the Histories, p e o p l e w h o take the t r o u b l e t o be
a l e r t to t h e i r s u r r o u n d i n g s , t o find t h i n g s o u t , a n d t o listen c a r e f u l l y t o t h e logoi o f o t h e r s , fare b e t t e r t h a n those w h o go a b o u t t h e w o r l d n o t n o t i c i n g w h a t i t is l i k e , o r t h e realities o f t h e i r o w n place i n i t . Herodotus' authorial T
models a s i m i l a r l y i n t e l l i g e n t b e h a v i o u r ; w h a t
he has g i v e n us finally is a n o n g o i n g a c c o u n t i n w h i c h his o w n c o n sciousness as a n alert a n d secular T
constructs f o r us a f i e l d w i t h i n
w h i c h logoi m o r e o r less m a k e sense, causal c o n n e c t i o n s w o r k , i n f o r m a t i o n is u s e f u l , a n d c r i t i c a l i n t e l l i g e n c e c o u n t s , b o t h his o w n a n d t h a t o f actors inside t h e n a r r a t i v e . 3 9 A s a n a u t h o r i a l T
Christ (1994) 169-82.
i n his t e x t ,
' I D I D N ' T GIVE M Y O W N GENEALOGY'
289
b o t h n a r r a t o r a n d histor, he persuades us t h a t t h e doubleness o f his overt a u t h o r i a l persona reflects his o w n efforts i n the service o f k n o w l edge; i n d o i n g so he also models f o r us t h e doubleness o f w h a t t h i n k i n g historically m i g h t m e a n . 4 0
4 0
This chapter was written and initially delivered at the Center for Hellenic Studies in Washington D.C., in the fall of 1999; I would like to thank the Center's fellows and its directors, Deborah Boedeker and Kurt Raaflaub, for their generous and incisive comments, f would like to thank as well the departments of Classics at Columbia University and Barnard College, the University of Chicago, the University of Pennsylvania, and the University of California at Berkeley, for opportunities to further sharpen my ideas. Special thanks are due to Egbert Bakker, Nancy Felson, Helene Foley, Irene de Jong, John Marincola, Susanne Said, Seth Schein, and Laura Slatkin.
CHAPTER T H I R T E E N
S H O R T STORIES I N H E R O D O T U S ' Vivienne
HISTORIES
Gray
Problems of Definition To
survey s h o r t stories i n H e r o d o t u s is to survey his entire n a r r a -
t i v e , since s h o r t stories e x h i b i t its m o r e g e n e r a l features a n d are p a r t o f its s t r u c t u r e . 1 T h e r e is a n e e d t h e r e f o r e to focus o n t h e i r m o r e d i s t i n c t i v e qualities. Y e t
t h e i r d e f i n i t i o n is p r o b l e m a t i c . 2 H e r o d o t u s
does n o t have a specialized w o r d f o r his s h o r t e r n a r r a t i v e s , b u t c o m m o n l y describes t h e m i n t e r m s o f t h e i r a c t i o n s . 3 N o r d o scholars use a systematic t e r m i n o l o g y . 4 S o m e call t h e m logoi, b u t these i n c l u d e m a n y o t h e r types o f n a r r a t i v e . ' O t h e r s call t h e m ' s h o r t stories', o r 'novellas' after E u r o p e a n
practice.6 T h e
a n c i e n t n o v e l l a has been
d e f i n e d as a c h a n g e o f f o r t u n e o r c h a r a c t e r i s t i c b e h a v i o u r , i n r e a l life a n d
fixed
i n t i m e , a n d o f a l e n g t h sufficient to r o u n d o u t the
a c t i o n . 7 B u t r e m a r k s o n the m o d e r n s h o r t story p r o v i d e a b e t t e r d e f i n i t i o n t h a n these. H e r o d o t u s '
1
examples indeed make a m o r e
Many scholars use the short story to exemplify general features, but Thomson (1935), Long (1987), Cobet (1971), Erbse (1981, 1991, 1992) alone focus on it. Long (1987) 7 demurs. But Trenkner (1958) xiii defines 'novella' (below). 'A very great wonder': 1.23.1; 'the greatest revenge for injustice of those we know': 8.105.1; 'the man who won the tyranny in the following way': 8.137.1; 'the lust of Xerxes and the death of Masistes': 9.113.2; 'what happened about a deposit in Sparta' 6.86a. 1. See also Ch. 11, pp. 255-8. •' Many refer to them as 'passages', 'episodes'. Thomson (1935) uses logos for the short story as well as other types of narrative. Immerwahr (1966) uses logoi for all types, calling short stories 'minor' logoi. Herodotus calls both stories and arguments logoi in reference to subject matter, as Immerwahr (1966), 14 n. 34 indicates. He sometimes calls a short story a 'logos', in addition to the description of its action: 6.86a. 1, d; or an epos for a story of a wise saying: 7.226.1 2. For more specialized ancient terms, which Herodotus does not use: Trenkner (1958) 5. '' Trenkner (1958): 'novella'. Long (1987): 'short story' as well as 'novella'. Erbse (1991, 1992): 'Novellen' for longer and 'Anekdoten' for shorter stories. ' Trenkner (1958) xiii-xiv, 11, 24. But Herodotus' reliance on oral traditions means that his stories are not 'imaginary' in Trenkner's fictitious sense. 2 3
1
292
V I V I E N N E GRAY
8
coherent corpus for definition than the still-evolving modern form. The one major difference is that the modern short story stands in isolation, whereas Herodotus incorporates his short stories into a larger narrative. This raises the question o f their organization within the work and their thematic relationships to their immediate contexts and the larger narrative. Some seem to 'drift free' o f their contexts, while others seem to comment directly on them. Some seem to interact with other parts o f the work. The three short stories that come at the end o f the work have seemed to achieve thematic as well as structural closure. I leave their organization and relationships in the meantime and first focus on their definition. The short story is rather obviously defined by its length. T i m e limits on ancient oral performance or w o r d limits on modern publication in print could explain this. But the construction o f a modern short story also differs from that o f a longer one in that the writer grasps the totality before writing a single line o f it: 'a distinctive form with its own methods o f construction'. There is an art which strives for concentration, singleness and wroughtness, a powerful and exacting form in which every w o r d counts toward closure. The modern short story amasses its whole weight toward the ending, and the closure or denouement is more concentrated than the anticipation or dilemma that precedes it. This distinctive narrative 'shape' makes a short story distinct from a story that happens to be short. '' 9
10
11
12
1
This shape also defines Herodotus' short stories. Herodotus' moment u m toward closure usually involves a crisis. Relevant to the notion of crisis is the concept o f the 'functional' event which involves confrontation, opens a choice between two possibilities and produces changes involving either improvement or deterioration for the main character. The famous musician A r i o n is the main character o f a 14
8
See Reid (1977) 1-4, 10-14, 16; Shaw (1983) 20-1, who concludes: 'a firm definition of the (modern) short story is impossible'. Shaw substitutes die question: 'What can a short story do particularly well because it is short?'. For a range of views: Gould (1989) 50-8; and on the closure n. 54 below. Shaw (1983) 7. But some of Herodotus' shorter stories are less than 300 words. It is hard to imagine an oral performance as restrictive as this. Shaw (1983) 3. Shaw (1983) 3, quoting Chekov; May (1995) 116. Shaw (1983) 9. Bal (1997) 182-93, esp. 182, 184, 185 f., 192 f., in relation to the fabuk. 9
10
11
12
13
14
SHORT STORIES I N HERODOTUS'
293
HISTORIES
t i g h t l y - f o c u s s e d d o u b l e crisis short story ( 1 . 2 3 - 4 ) . T h e
c r e w o f the
ship t h a t carries h i m b a c k t o the c o u r t o f his p a t r o n P e r i a n d e r
the
t y r a n t o f C o r i n t h t u r n p i r a t e , take the w e a l t h he has e a r n e d i n the W e s t , a n d force h i m t o m a k e a c h o i c e t h a t appears to be n o c h o i c e , b e t w e e n d e a t h o n b o a r d the ship a n d b u r i a l , o r d e a t h
overboard
a n d a w a t e r y grave. I n this crisis he p r o m i s e s t o k i l l h i m s e l f , asking o n l y f o r p e r m i s s i o n to give a w h i c h he is f a m o u s . H e
final
performance
o f the m u s i c
then throws himself overboard,
for
apparently
m a k i n g the worse c h o i c e , b u t a d o l p h i n picks h i m u p a n d carries him
t o l a n d at T a e n a r u m .
This
denouement
occupies a b r i e f l i n e
o r t w o , c o n t r a s t i n g w i t h the c o m p a r a t i v e l y d e t a i l e d a n t i c i p a t i o n o f it. T h e
m i r a c u l o u s rescue t h e n leads t o the second crisis, i n w h i c h
A r i o n reaches C o r i n t h a n d tells P e r i a n d e r his story. P e r i a n d e r disbelieves h i m , detains h i m a n d waits to i n t e r r o g a t e the c r e w o n t h e i r r e t u r n . T h e y assert t h a t t h e y left h i m safe a n d s o u n d i n T a r a s , b u t A r i o n appears, to refute t h e i r story. T h e
d e n o u e m e n t is a g a i n b r i e f
a n d r a p i d i n c o m p a r i s o n w i t h the a n t i c i p a t i o n . C a n d a u l e s , i n a n o t h e r short story o f tightly-focussed d o u b l e crisis ( 1 . 8 - 1 2 ) , wants Gyges to see his w i f e n a k e d i n o r d e r to m a k e h i m a p p r e c i a t e h e r b e a u t y ,
and
c o n f r o n t s h i m w i t h a choice t h a t is n o choice (as A r i o n ) : to disobey his k i n g o r c o m m i t the i n d i s c r e t i o n . Gyges chooses the i n d i s c r e t i o n a n d resolves the first crisis. T h e consequence o f this r e s o l u t i o n is t h a t the w i f e w a n t s to resoive h e r shame a n d offers Gyges a n o t h e r choice t h a t is n o choice: to disobey his q u e e n o r k i l l the k i n g (second c r i sis). Gyges kills the k i n g a n d takes his q u e e n . A g a i n a n t i c i p a t i o n is m u c h m o r e extensive t h a n o u t c o m e i n b o t h parts o f the story. The
a c t i o n o f the s h o r t story n e e d n o t be as p h y s i c a l as i n the
stories o f A r i o n a n d C a n d a u l e s .
Croesus'
refusal o f the wise advice
t h a t S o l o n gives h i m is also a s h o r t story ( 1 . 2 9 - 3 3 ) . 1 5 S o l o n
comes
to Croesus' c o u r t a n d three times answers the question a b o u t h a p piness t h a t Croesus puts to h i m , each t i m e m o r e e x p l i c i t l y t h a n the last. Croesus b r i e f l y rejects h i m three times, each t i m e s h o w i n g greater ignorance.
Solon's
advice is a f u n c t i o n a l event t h a t offers c h o i c e ,
there is c o n f r o n t a t i o n , the d e f i c i e n c y is the i g n o r a n c e o f
Croesus,
a n d his c h o i c e leads to i m m e d i a t e d e t e r i o r a t i o n (the loss o f his son). Croesus' r e a c t i o n to the advice he receives f r o m oracles ( 1 . 5 3 - 6 ) a n d d r e a m s ( 1 . 1 0 7 - 8 ) i n v o l v e the same f u n c t i o n a l event. T r i p l i c a t i o n is
15
This is a well-recognized pattern: Dewald (1987) 20: on Bischoff (1932), Lattimore (1939).
294
VIVIENNE GRAY
a basic m o t i f o f t h e t r a d i t i o n a l tale, b u t also o f the m o d e r n story, w h e r e
short
i t has b e e n r e l a t e d t o t h e story shape, w h i c h has a
beginning, middle, and end.16 T h i s f o r m a l , artistic d e f i n i t i o n o f s h o r t stories distinguishes t h e m f r o m H e r o d o t u s ' o t h e r shorter n a r r a t i v e s , such as his g e o g r a p h i c a n d e t h n o g r a p h i c excursuses, his descriptions o f d e d i c a t i o n s , etc. (except w h e r e t h e y themselves c o n t a i n stories). B u t t h e r e has also b e e n a desire t o define s h o r t stories f r o m t h e i r c o n t e n t . T h e y are n o t u n i q u e i n t h e i r focus o n h u m a n
achievement,"
or their 'spirit',18 o r their
sensational subject m a t t e r (lust, p i r a c y , c a s t r a t i o n c o m e t o m i n d ) w h i c h are w i d e s p r e a d t h r o u g h o u t t h e rest o f the n a r r a t i v e . H o w e v e r , t h e y d o e x h i b i t stereotyped characters a n d patterns o f a c t i o n . P r o p p classified t h e p a t t e r n s o f stories i n f o l k l o r e a c c o r d i n g t o t h e i r d o m i n a n t actions as expressed t h r o u g h t h e f u n c t i o n s o f t h e i r dramatis personae. S u c h classification is p r o m i s i n g f o r H e r o d o t u s a n d comes close 19
to d e f i n i n g c o n t e n t . 2 0 Patterns
c a n be i d e n t i f i e d w h e n
they
occur
m o r e t h a n o n c e , a n d t h e i r c o m p a r i s o n o f t e n reveals t h e i r sometimes less t h a n t r a n s p a r e n t m e a n i n g s . 2 1 T h e p a t t e r n s seem t o c o m e
from
the o r a l t r a d i t i o n w h i c h H e r o d o t u s c o n s t a n t l y acknowledges, p a r t o f w h i c h seems t o have b e e n t h e t r a d i t i o n a l short s t o r y . 2 2 T h e r e are f e w w r i t t e n precedents e x t a n t , 2 3 b u t H o m e r uses patterns t h a t sometimes constitute stories (the m e e t i n g w i t h t h e king's d a u g h t e r , etc.) 2 ' 1 a n d his techniques c o u l d usefully be c o m p a r e d w i t h those o f H e r o d o t u s .
Shaw (1983) 217. The proem's promise to deliver the 'achievements of mankind' applies to the whole narrative. Erbse (1981) 268-9 sees two themes (the restoration of order and the celebration of human talent) and two spirits: the tragic condition and the positive achievement of men. Both 'spirits' are found in the careers of eastern kings. Amasis is exceptionally free of the disaster that most others meet: 2.172 82, 3.10. Aly ((1921) 1969 was a landmark in the identification of traditional patterns in Herodotus. Propp ((1928) 1968) ch. 2 categorized them according to their dominant patterns, rejecting previous categorizations: 5-11. -" For work on patterns i n Herodotus, see Stern (1991), who identifies 'scapegoat narratives' in stories of exiled tyrants, and Flory (t978a), who identifies Arion's leap with other brave gestures in Herodotus. Great care needs to be taken in establishing parallels that are tight enough to convince. Dewald (1987) 10 rightly sees archaic oral thought as 'largely inaccessible to our ways of thinking and feeling'. Aly ((1929) 1987) 63-9 defines the style of the Ionian 'Volkserzahlung'. Dewald (1987) 14 refers to Trenkner (1958). Hecataeus FGH 1. fr. 1 may refer to the traditional short story when he calls the lospi of the Greeks 'many and laughable'. See Bowra (1972) 124-5. 17
18
19
21
22
23
24
SHORT STORIES I N HERODOTUS'
295
HISTORIES
I t has been h e l d t h a t m o d e r n s h o r t stories are also a d a p t a t i o n s
of
t r a d i t i o n r a t h e r t h a n n e w c r e a t i o n s , a n d t h a t t h e i r c o m p r e s s i o n lends itself p a r t i c u l a r l y to f o r m u l a i c t r e a t m e n t . 2 : > T h e Herodotus'
oral background
of
Histories perhaps just makes this f o r m u l a i c i m p e r a t i v e
of
the f o r m m o r e pressing. Herodotus'
use o f stereotyped elements creates r e c u r r e n t plots i n
his stories. T h i s is also t r u e o f the m o d e r n s h o r t story: T h e
same
f e w p l o t s , I a m s o r r y to say, h a v e p u r s u e d m e d o w n t h r o u g h
the
y e a r s . ' * T h e p a t t e r n , f o r e x a m p l e , i n w h i c h a r u l e r expresses
exces-
sive a n d inconsistent kindness a n d c r u e l t y t o w a r d a subject,
shapes
t w o s h o r t stories a b o u t X e r x e s t h a t f r a m e
his e x p e d i t i o n
against
Greece. T h e first is the story o f Pythius the L y d i a n . X e r x e s r e w a r d e d Pythius h a n d s o m e l y
f o r v o l u n t a r i l y s u p p o r t i n g his large a r m y o n its
m a r c h against Greece ( 7 . 2 7 - 9 ) . B u t w h e n Pythius asked f o r his eldest son to r e m a i n at h o m e , X e r x e s split h i m i n t w o a n d p u t the halves o n e i t h e r side o f the m a r c h i n g r o u t e ( 7 . 3 8 - 9 ) . T h e s t o r y is also split, p l a c e d o n e i t h e r side o f the i n t e r v e n i n g n a r r a t i v e , w i t h the excessive kindness after X e r x e s ' crossing i n t o P h r y g i a a n d excessive c r u e l t y at Sardis before the m a r c h to the Hellespont a n d the crossing to E u r o p e . The
same p a t t e r n is used i n the story o f h o w the c a p t a i n o f the
ship c a r r y i n g X e r x e s back to A s i a f r o m Greece after his defeat at Salamis, who
recommended,
crowded
i n a t h r e a t e n i n g s t o r m , t h a t the
the deck be t h r o w n o v e r b o a r d
Persians
to ensure the k i n g ' s
safety (8.118). X e r x e s asked f o r v o l u n t e e r s ; they leaped to t h e i r d e a t h , a n d he l a n d e d safely. W h e r e u p o n
he r e w a r d e d the c a p t a i n
gener-
ously f o r saving his l i f e , a n d c u t o f f his h e a d f o r causing the d e a t h o f so m a n y Persians: characteristic b e h a v i o u r ,
a n d a change o f f o r -
t u n e , even i f n o t f o r the m a i n character! T h e
story o f D a r i u s '
t i o n t o a s i m i l a r request t o leave
t h r e e sons o u t o f his
reac-
Scythian
e x p e d i t i o n shows o n l y the u n k i n d p a r t o f the p a t t e r n (4.84)-
he left
t h e m a l l b e h i n d , d e a d , b u t the k i n d p a r t is expressed i n the father's e x p e c t a t i o n o f f r i e n d l y t r e a t m e n t . T h e s e p a t t e r n s c a n be r e d u c e d f u r t h e r i n t o m o t i f s , b u t this c h a p t e r is c o n s i d e r i n g actions t h a t c o n s t i tute a story r a t h e r t h a n j u s t p a r t o f one. The
f o r m u l a i c s h o u l d n o t be confused w i t h the t r i t e a n d
ingless, since patterns are l i k e l y to c o n v e y m e a n i n g o f human
2 5
26
importance.
X e r x e s ' p a t t e r n a b o v e conveys
Shaw (1983) 19. Shaw (1983) 19, quoting Borges.
mean-
momentous
the w h i m s i c a l
296
VIVIENNE G R A Y
n a t u r e o f absolute p o w e r — n o
t r i t e r e v e l a t i o n . I t seems n o a c c i d e n t
t h a t the t w o stories f o r m a f r a m e at the b e g i n n i n g a n d e n d o f X e r x e s ' expedition. The
reader w h o notices this c a n enhance t h e i r i n d i v i d -
ual meaning w i t h interpretation of their placement. The
d i f f i c u l t y i n the d e f i n i t i o n based e n t i r e l y o n patterns is t h a t
the m a i n story develops the patterns o f s h o r t stories i n t o m u c h l o n g e r o n e s . 2 7 E v e n a m o d e r n short story c a n be a condensed v e r s i o n o f a longer one.28 T h e even m o r e
d i s t i n g u i s h i n g feature o f the short story
clearly its a v o i d a n c e
penchant for concentration and
o f unfocussed
becomes
complexity
a n d its
compression.
T h r e e examples o f stories o f rise a n d f a l l , w h i c h is the
common-
est p a t t e r n i n t h e Histories, d e m o n s t r a t e this. T h e p a t t e r n shows t h a t the r a p i d a c c u m u l a t i o n o f w e a l t h leads d i r e c t l y o r i n d i r e c t l y to disaster. A m i n o c l e s o f M a g n e s i a (7.190) acquires w e a l t h f r o m the s h i p wrecks a r o u n d A r t e m i s i o n , b u t t h o u g h r i c h , was ' u n l u c k y ' i n the rest o f his l i f e : ' T h e r e was i n this case t o o a c e r t a i n unpleasant
child-
k i l l i n g disaster t h a t g r i e v e d h i m . ' T h i s v e r y s h o r t a c c o u n t has bare f r a m e w o r k
o f the first phase
the
o f the rise a n d fall o f C r o e s u s ,
w h o loses his c h i l d after r e j e c t i n g Solon's advice t h a t the w e a l t h he h a d a c q u i r e d was n o g u a r a n t e e o f p e r m a n e n t happiness. Its a v o i d ance o f d e t a i l a n d o f c o m p l e x i t y a l m o s t b r i n g s its status as a s h o r t story i n t o question.
I t has nevertheless
w e i g h t t o w a r d t h e e n d i n g . Polycrates'
the r e q u i r e d a m a s s i n g rise ( 3 . 3 9 - 4 3 )
of
a n d his f a l l
( 3 . 1 2 0 - 5 ) is a l o n g e r v e r s i o n o f the p a t t e r n , separated o u t i n t o its t w o phases t o accentuate its p o l a r i t y , w i t h w e i g h t o n the e n d i n g b o t h p a r t s , b u t p a r t i c u l a r l y the l a t t e r . 2 9 I n the first p a r t
of
Polycrates'
rise t o w e a l t h a n d f a m e is r a p i d (3.39). H i s story is t h e n e x p a n d e d b y the i n s e r t i o n o f wise advice f r o m A m a s i s a b o u t the dangers i n h e r e n t i n his great ' l u c k ' , w h i c h he is u n a b l e to h e e d ( 3 . 4 0 - 3 ) . I n the second p a r t , a m i d s t f u r t h e r w a r n i n g s , he meets his death (3.124—5). Croesus offers a f u l l d e v e l o p m e n t
o f the p a t t e r n . 3 " H e
experiences
t w o phases
first
rapid
27
o f rise a n d f a l l . H i s
rise is n o m o r e
than
See Immerwahr (1966) eh. 4 for the patterns of rise and fall behind the careers of the eastern kings. Herodotus also uses patterned campaign narratives not found in his short stories: Immerwahr (1966) ch. 6. Immerwahr also refers to general patterns in what he calls minor logoi: 73-5 'thought and action', 75-8 'rise and fall', and 244: 'the old epic and folklore story of the duel'. Shaw (1983) 21. See also Ch. 6, pp. 124-6 and 23, pp. 156-7 in this volume. See also Ch. 6, pp. 132-7 in this volume. 2 8
29
SHORT STORIES I N HERODOTUS' Polycrates'
297
HISTORIES
( 1 . 2 6 - 8 ) , b u t gains early c o m p l e x i t y
t h r o u g h the inser-
t i o n o f the story o f the wise a d v i c e o f B i a s / P i t t a c u s i n t o t h e m i d d l e o f i t (1.27; a story i n its o w n r i g h t ) . Solon's advice to C r o e s u s , w h i c h f o l l o w s , is also m o r e elaborate t h a n A m a s i s ' to Polycrates
(1.29-33).
Croesus' i n a b i l i t y to h e e d i t leads to his first disaster i n the loss o f his son (1.34—46). H e t h e n plans a second phase o f rise against C y r u s (1.46—85). T h i s is m u c h e x p a n d e d b y his c o u r t i n g a n d m i s i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f the wise advice o f the o r a c l e , the a c q u i s i t i o n o f G r e e k allies a n d so o n . T h e final
w h o l e c u l m i n a t e s i n his final disaster, a n
elaborate
scene, a s h o r t story i n its o w n r i g h t , i n w h i c h he is m a d e wise
t h r o u g h suffering (1.86-91). The
d i s t i n c t i o n b e t w e e n the s h o r t e r a n d t h e l o n g e r v e r s i o n o f t h e
p a t t e r n lies i n the presence o r absence o f a d d i t i o n s , w h i c h c a n t h e m selves take the f o r m o f s h o r t stories, such as t h a t o f t h e wise a d v i sor. H e r o d o t u s sometimes tells stories i n fewer t h a n 3 0 0 w o r d s . is nevertheless f o n d o f c o m p l e x i t y .
He
He
achieves i t t h r o u g h the c o n -
nected a n d u n i f i e d d o u b l e crisis i n A r i o n ' s s t o r y , w h i c h connects the m i r a c l e a n d the i n q u i r y i n t o i t ( 1 . 2 3 - 4 ) , a n d a g a i n i n t h e tion of crime and punishment
in Hermotimus'
connec-
and Artayctes'
sto-
ries, b e l o w p p . 3 0 8 - 1 0 , 3 1 3 - 1 4 . H e likes the i n c r e m e n t a l t r i p l e , w h i c h repeats t h e basic p a t t e r n f o r i n c r e a s i n g i m p a c t , as i n Croesus' t r i p l e r e j e c t i o n o f Solon's advice o r X e r x e s ' t r i p l e reversal, b e l o w p p . 3 1 0 ™ 13. H e c a n d i v i d e a single p a t t e r n o f rise a n d fall i n t o its t w o phases, as i n the story o f Polycrates, o r insert one p a t t e r n (the wise advisor) into another
one
(rise a n d fall). H e
produces
even m o r e
complex
stories o u t o f a b a l a n c e d i n t e r w e a v i n g o f separate p a t t e r n s . T h e
stoiy
o f the rise o f C y r u s c o m b i n e s the revenge p a t t e r n as e x e m p l i f i e d b y Alexander (5.18-20), Hermotimus 120),
( 8 . 1 0 4 - 7 ) , and Artayctes
(9.116,
w i t h the p a t t e r n o f t h e rise o f the t y r a n t as e x e m p l i f i e d
Peisistratus ( 1 . 5 9 - 6 4 ) , D e i o c e s ( 1 . 9 6 - 1 0 0 ) , a n d Perdiccas
by
(8.137-9),
a n d is replete w i t h insertions o f v a r i o u s types w h i c h e x p a n d i t o u t to o v e r 3 , 0 0 0 w o r d s . 3 1 T h i s reaches t h e l o w e r l i m i t o f the
modern
s t o r y , w h i c h is o f t e n 2 , 0 0 0 t o 1 0 , 0 0 0 w o r d s o r l o n g e r . 3 2 T h e
point
at w h i c h such a n a r r a t i v e forfeits t h e d i s t i n c t i v e qualities o f t h e s h o r t story is a m a t t e r o f artistic j u d g m e n t . C y r u s ' story does seem to possess t h a t c o n c e n t r a t i o n a n d m o m e n t u m
31
32
t o w a r d closure t h a t defines
Long (1987) 126-75 for Cyrus; Gray (1997) for the rise of the tyrant. Shaw (1983) 7, 8, 11.
298
VIVIENNE GRAY
the s h o r t story. I t is m o r e d i f f i c u l t to d e f i n e the difference
between
this n a r r a t i v e a n d the rise a n d f a l l o f Croesus. I t c o u l d o n l y rest i n the less o r g a n i c c o n t r i b u t i o n t h a t some o f the insertions i n Croesus' story m a k e to the d e v e l o p m e n t The
reasons w h y
o f the w h o l e .
H e r o d o t u s chooses
t o present m a t e r i a l i n the
f o r m o f a shorter r a t h e r t h a n a l o n g e r n a r r a t i v e c o n c e r n the w h o l e design o f the w o r k a n d c a n n o t be d o n e j u s t i c e to here. I t is t r u e t h a t w h i l e the m a i n story addresses the e x p a n s i o n o f eastern p o w e r , Greeks o f t e n a p p e a r i n 'short stories' ( A r i o n ,
Bias/Pittacus,
Peisistratus o f A t h e n s a n d S p a r t a , Polycrates, H e r m o t i m u s ) ,
Solon, but that
w h e n the tide t u r n s n e a r the e n d o f the Histories, Persians o f t e n take over this role (Artayctes, X e r x e s a n d Masistes, Cyrus). A m i n o c l e s ' story is also a n i n s e r t i o n i n t o a n a c c o u n t m a i n l y d e v o t e d t o a s t o r m b r i n g i n g h a v o c to the Persian fleet. Y e t this r u l e is n o t w i t h o u t e x c e p t i o n . Short
stories are c r e d i t e d w i t h c l a r i t y , s i m p l i c i t y , e c o n o m y ,
and
v i v i d n e s s . 5 3 T h i s i m p r e s s i o n is a result o f t h e i r n a r r a t i v e a r t , b u t also o f their context. T h e
advice o f Bias/Pittacus
looks v i v i d because i t
is set i n t o a n annalistic a c c o u n t o f Croesus' rise d e v o i d o f such features ( 1 . 2 6 - 8 ) , a n d even w i t h i n the story o f Solon's advice, his p h i l o sophical lecture on the c o m p u t a t i o n comparison Cleobis
of a man's
life is d u l l
w i t h his clear, v i v i d , s i m p l e a n d e c o n o m i c a l story
and Biton. Nor
byof
is the alleged m a i n story d e v o i d o f these
effects; thus the story o f Z o p y r u s ' c a p t u r e o f B a b y l o n shows a l l these features (3.150—60).
Arion's
story possesses t h e m , b u t n o t i n m u c h
greater degree t h a n the story o f A l y a t t e s ' escape f r o m illness (1.19: Alyattes'
d i l e m m a a n d p r o p o s e d r e s o l u t i o n ; 1 . 2 0 - 1 : he is deceived
i n t o f a i l i n g his first a t t e m p t a t a r e s o l u t i o n , b u t 1.22: his second s o l u t i o n w o r k s ) . N e i t h e r has d i r e c t speech, b o t h are clear, s i m p l e , e c o n o m i c a l accounts o f A l y a t t e s ' f r o m death. T h e
escape f r o m disease, a n d
and
Arion's
deceptive sight o f t h e M i l e s i a n s d r i n k i n g a n d eat-
i n g f r o m t h e i r large heap o f stores is p a r t i c u l a r l y v i v i d . T h e r e is n o u n i f o r m n a r r a t i v e m o d e t h a t c a n define short stories. B o n h e i m (1982) distinguishes f o u r n a r r a t i v e modes: description, r e p o r t , speech, a n d c o m m e n t .
H e r o d o t u s w r i t e s s h o r t stories i n the
third
p e r s o n o f n a r r a t i v e r e p o r t except w h e r e speech intervenes, b u t this is characteristic o f m u c h o f his n a r r a t i v e . T h e balance o f r e p o r t a n d speech is n o t u n i f o r m , even i n short stories o f c o m m o n
Thomson (1935).
t y p e , such
SHORT STORIES I N HERODOTUS'
299
HISTORIES
as those o f X e r x e s ' excessive kindness a n d c r u e l t y (7.27-9, 38-9
and
8.118, above p. 000), w h e r e his i n t e r v i e w w i t h Pythius uses d i r e c t speech almost exclusively, w h i l e his sea voyage is a r e p o r t , w i t h d i r e c t speech o n l y to h i g h l i g h t the captain's advice a n d X e r x e s '
request.
S i m i l a r l y , t h o u g h the wise advisor stories are usually i n speech, some v a r i a t i o n s are reports (3.14, 119: b e l o w p. 000). A r i o n ' s s t o i y is even a n e x c e p t i o n to the a p p a r e n t r u l e t h a t stories m a i n l y i n n a r r a t i v e m a r k t h e i r crises i n d i r e c t speech (the revenge o f H e r m o t i m u s ,
the
revenge o n A r t a y c t e s , a n d m a n y others). T h o s e few descriptions t h a t o c c u r c o n f o r m to the artistic r e q u i r e m e n t s o f the short story, w h i c h o n l y a d m i t s m a t e r i a l t h a t c o n t r i b u t e s to i n t e r p r e t i n g the a c t i o n (e.g., the wildernesses i n t o w h i c h p o t e n t i a l t y r a n t s retreat: C y r u s 1.110.2, Perdiccas 8.138.2-3). T h e r e are f r e q u e n t n a r r a t o r i a l c o m m e n t s , p a r t i c u l a r l y o n the sources o r the c r e d i b i l i t y o f the stories ( A r i o n
1.23,
X e r x e s 8.119; i n t r u s i o n s also m a k e o t h e r p o i n t s at 1.119.7, 8.137.2), b u t such c o m m e n t s also grace the m a i n story. I n c o n c l u s i o n , short stories i n H e r o d o t u s
c a n be best d e f i n e d b y
t h e i r p r e s e n t a t i o n o f stereotyped patterns o f a c t i o n o f l i m i t e d comp l e x i t y w h i c h are c o n c e n t r a t e d a n d h i g h l y w r o u g h t ,
amass
their
w e i g h t t o w a r d t h e i r endings i n a r e s o l u t i o n o f crisis, a n d can
be
grasped w h o l e .
Pattern and Variation T h e t r a d i t i o n a l tale has a t w o f o l d q u a l i t y : 'its a m a z i n g m u l t i f o r m i t y , picturesqueness a n d c o l o r a n d o n the o t h e r h a n d its n o less s t r i k i n g u n i f o r m i t y , its r e p e t i t i o n ' . 3 4 H e r o d o t u s
i n fact varies his p a t t e r n s i n
v e r y sophisticated ways. I h a v e a l r e a d y b r i e f l y described v a r i a t i o n s i n the stories o f kindness a n d c r u e l t y , rise a n d f a l l , a n d the wise advisor. T h e p a t t e r n o f the wise advisor merits a closer l o o k , i n o r d e r to appreciate its t y p i c a l f u l l range o f v a r i a t i o n s . T h e characters f o r a start are n o t always the p l a i n wise m a n
and
r u l e r . Bias/Pittacus (1.27), S o l o n ( 1 . 2 9 - 3 3 ) , d r e a m s (1.34), A p o l l o of D e l p h i (1.47-56) a n d p o r t e n t s (1.78) v a r i o u s l y advise Croesus. characters c a n also change places. A
34
deposed Croesus, m a d e
The wise
Propp ((1928) 1968) 21. Schwabl (1969), working on analogies, though not exclusively on short stories, concluded, 272: 'Geschichte führt bei Herodot immer wieder zum selben'; but variety is also essential.
300
V I V I E N N E GRAY
t h r o u g h s u f f e r i n g the loss o f his r u l e , advises G y r u s ( 1 . 8 8 - 9 ,
207)
a n d , u n d e r constant threat o f menaces, Cambyses ( 3 . 3 4 - 6 ) . D e m a r a t u s , a n o t h e r deposed k i n g m a d e wise t h r o u g h s u f f e r i n g a n d e x i l e , advises X e r x e s , once i n c o m p e t i t i o n w i t h A c h a e m e n e s ( 7 . 1 0 1 - 4 , 2 0 9 , 234—7). E v e n those still i n possession o f p o w e r p r o v e wiser t h a n t h e i r subj e c t s i n t i m e s o f success (Pausanias'
refusal o f L a m p o n ' s
advice:
9 . 7 8 - 9 ; G y r u s ' refusal o f A r t e m b a r e s ' : 9.122). T h e r e are n o b a r r i e r s o f age o r sex. T h e c h i l d G o r g o competes w i t h ambassador Aristagoras i n a d v i s i n g h e r f a t h e r Cleomenes (5.49—51). X e r x e s favours t h e advice o f a n a d u l t w o m a n A r t e m i s i a over t h e m o r e c a l c u l a t i n g M a r d o n i u s even t h o u g h he does n o t always act o n i t ( 8 . 6 8 - 9 , 1 0 1 - 3 ) . T h e r u l e r c a n take the i n i t i a t i v e i n seeking a d v i c e , pro forma or o t h e r w i s e , o r c a n receive i t u n a s k e d ; he c a n h a v e the w i t to see i t o r n o t , act o n it o r n o t , take offence at i t o r l a u g h at i t . H e
c a n even test i t
first,
as Croesus tests t h e oracles o f A p o l l o a n d A m p h i a r a u s (1.47—9).
The
advisor is usually i n d i r e c t h o w e v e r (the oracles are a n e x t r e m e case, b u t even r u l i n g kings d o n o t f o r c e t h e i r advice o n t h e i r p e o p l e : 9 . 1 2 2 ) , a n d w a r y o f a hostile response ( 1 . 8 8 , 7 . 1 0 1 ; A r t e m i s i a is an exception). T h e f o r m o f t h e advice c a n also be v a r i e d . B i a s ' / P i t t a c u s '
advice
t o Croesus (1.27) p r o d u c e s a b r i e f d i a l o g u e , A m a s i s gives his advice to Polycrates ( 3 . 4 0 - 3 ) i n a letter. Solon's advice ( 1 . 2 9 - 3 3 ) is e x p a n d e d i n t o the i n c r e m e n t a l t r i p l e t h a t u n d e r l i n e s Croesus' greater resistance to w i s d o m ; the advice itself consists o f t w o s h o r t stories ( 1 . 3 0 . 4 - 5 , 31)
and a long lecture (1.32-3). Demaratus,
i n another variation,
advises X e r x e s o n three separate occasions, a n d each o f these is f o r m a l l y v a r i e d . T h e first develops t h e i n c r e m e n t a l t r i p l e : t h r e e requests f o r advice f r o m X e r x e s a n d three responses f r o m D e m a r a t u s ,
each
one l o n g e r t h a n the last, w i t h final dismissal ( 7 . 1 0 1 - 4 , i n c l u d i n g the m o t i f i n w h i c h t h e wise m a n w a r i l y asks w h e t h e r he s h o u l d speak to please o r t r u l y advise: 7.101). T h e second consists o f t w o requests a n d t w o responses, t h e first s h o r t e r t h a n t h e second, w i t h
final
dis-
missal (7.209). T h e t h i r d also has t w o pairs o f request a n d response, b u t i n c l u d e s the advice o f A c h a e m e n e s ,
who
opposes
Demaratus,
a n d is answered b y X e r x e s ( 7 . 2 3 4 - 7 ) . B y means o f this k i n d o f e x p a n sion the p a t t e r n even generates w h o l e debates. T w o
wise advisors,
r e p r e s e n t i n g t h e p o l a r i t i e s o f speaking to please a n d s p e a k i n g the t r u t h , a r e a g a i n i n c o m p e t i t i o n i n t h e debate o f 7.8—18. X e r x e s deconstructs the p a t t e r n even w h i l e p e r f o r m i n g w i t h i n i t , w h e n
he
calls his advisors to assent to his schemes r a t h e r t h a n give t r u e advice
SHORT STORIES I N HERODOTUS'
(7.8d). M a r d o n i u s
flatters
301
HISTORIES
unvvisely w h i l e A r t a b a n u s
tells the
truth,
w i t h X e r x e s h a v i n g a series o f r e a c t i o n s t o w h a t h e hears.
The
speeches o f 8 . 1 4 0 - 4 also i n v o l v e t h r e e speakers, w i t h the
Spartans
a n d A l e x a n d e r o f f e r i n g o p p o s i n g advice to t h e A t h e n i a n s
and
the
A t h e n i a n s r e s p o n d i n g t o e a c h . T h e s e speeches also e x h i b i t r e p e a t e d m o t i f s , such as t h e c o u r t e o u s b u t f i r m dismissal o f a d v i c e cf. 9 . 7 9 . 2 ) .
(8.143.3,
35
Sometimes
t h e p a t t e r n is n o t easy to detect at first r e a d i n g . I n a
v a r i a t i o n o f the wise a d v i s o r s t o r y , t h e Persian K i n g C a m b y s e s 'tries the soul' o f the E g y p t i a n K i n g Psammetichus, w h o turns out to have g a i n e d w i s d o m t h r o u g h s u f f e r i n g (3.14). C a m b y s e s parades i n f r o n t o f t h e i r defeated f a t h e r first the enslaved princess, h u m i l i a t e d a l o n g w i t h the o t h e r n o b l e g i r l s , t h e n t h e d o o m e d p r i n c e , a b r i d l e o n his m o u t h , a rope around
his n e c k , i n the m i d s t o f his f e l l o w s .
The
E g y p t i a n shows n o e m o t i o n . B u t t h e n a t h i r d a n d a c c i d e n t a l spectacle p r o v o k e s ion,
his m o s t severe distress; a n o l d e r
drinking-compan-
u n r e l a t e d t o h i m , b u t f a l l e n f r o m p r o s p e r i t y , w h o is b e g g i n g f o r
w h a t he c a n get f r o m t h e soldiers. C a m b y s e s fails t o
understand.
T h e E g y p t i a n explains t h a t his o w n f a m i l y ' s s u f f e r i n g surpasses tears, b u t n o t his o l d f r i e n d ' s . C a m b y s e s recognizes
t h a t his e n e m y
has
w i s d o m i n s u f f e r i n g . H e even feels p i t y . C r o e s u s , present at the testing
o f t h e E g y p t i a n , cries also at t h e o l d f r i e n d ' s f a l l f r o m f o r t u n e ,
so like his o w n . T h e
t h r e e c l i m a c t i c tests o f the E g y p t i a n ' s soul (the
d a u g h t e r , the son, the f r i e n d ) m a t c h Solon's t r i p l e advice t o Croesus i n speech, b u t are presented m a i n l y i n n a r r a t i v e f o r m . Speeches m a r k o n l y the crisis, w h i c h is t h e exchange
o f messengers,
t w o k i n g s , i n w h i c h t r u t h is r e v e a l e d (3.14.9—10). T h e
between
the
use o f c o n -
trast is a n a d d i t i o n a l f e a t u r e , w e l l suited t o b r i n g a n e x t r a
dimen-
sion o f m e a n i n g t o the compressed f o r m . C a m b y s e s ' c o u r t i e r s reveal t h e i r o w n l a c k o f w i s d o m w h e n t h e y w e e p f o r t h e i r o w n sons
and
daughters, paraded along w i t h the royal c h i l d r e n , b u t n o t for their old friend. The
story o f the w i f e o f I n t a p h e r n e s
(3.119) is a v a r i a t i o n i n a
s i m i l a r v e i n , a g a i n m a i n l y p r e s e n t e d as n a r r a t i v e r e p o r t w i t h the c l i m a x i n speech. H a v i n g a r r e s t e d h e r h u s b a n d f o r d i s l o y a l t y a n d b e i n g
35
According to Lang (1984) 36, these patterns are of an oral rather than a rhetorical origin; for one exception, see Lang (1984) 138 ff. For arguments against the influence of formal tragedy: Long (1987) 1 7 9 - 9 2 , Evans ( 1 9 9 1 ) 4 - 5 , and
6 in this volume.
see
Ch.
302
V I V I E N N E GRAY
a b o u t to e l i m i n a t e t h e rest o f h e r k i n as w e l l , D a r i u s offers h e r t h e c h o i c e o f saving just o n e r e l a t i v e . She reveals u n e x p e c t e d w i s d o m b y c h o o s i n g her b r o t h e r r a t h e r t h a n h e r h u s b a n d o r sons, e x p l a i n i n g t o D a r i u s t h a t she c a n n o t get a n o t h e r b r o t h e r , b u t m i g h t get another husband and children. T h e s e stories characterize the early parts o f Cambyses' a n d D a r i u s ' reigns. T h e
p a t t e r n o f t e n i n c o r p o r a t e s t h e m o t i f o f kings a d m i r i n g
the w i s d o m they receive; t h e n c e f o r t h , C a m b y s e s keeps the defeated Egyptian Croesus
k i n g at his side (3.15.1), i n the same w a y as C y r u s (1.88.1) a n d C y r u s
k e p t t h e d e f e a t e d Astyages
when
kept he
s h o w e d p o l i t i c a l w i s d o m (1.130.3). The
final
w o r d belongs to a n a n o n y m o u s
Persian, w h o
decon-
structs the p a t t e r n f r o m the p o i n t o f v i e w o f the wise m a n , as X e r x e s d e c o n s t r u c t e d i t f r o m the ruler's p o i n t o f v i e w . H e advises the G r e e k Thersander
a b o u t the disaster c o m i n g to the Persians. H i s
reason
f o r i n f o r m i n g the G r e e k r a t h e r t h a n his o w n h i g h c o m m a n d ,
who
are alone i n a p o s i t i o n to d o s o m e t h i n g a b o u t i t , is, as he says, t h a t disaster c a n n o t be a v o i d e d , the wise advisor is never h e e d e d ,
and
he is u n d e r o r d e r s to f o l l o w ; the w o r s t p a i n is to k n o w m u c h
and
c o n t r o l n o t h i n g (9.16). S o m e o f these v a r i a t i o n s s i m p l y reflect t h e characters i n v o l v e d , b u t others m a y have greater s i g n i f i c a n c e , just as v a r i a t i o n i n H o m e r is sometimes the key to his m e a n i n g . T h i s makes H e r o d o t u s ' v a r i a tions as w o r t h y o f i n v e s t i g a t i o n as t h e patterns themselves.
Organization and Function The
Histories as a w h o l e are s t r u c t u r e d as a series o f u n i t s m a r k e d
b y f r a m i n g sentences o r t h e i r e q u i v a l e n t , set i n sequence, one g i v i n g rise to the n e x t . 3 6 These are said to i m i t a t e the units o f H e r o d o t u s ' p a r e n t h e t i c kai- sentence s t r u c t u r e s . 3 7 H i s c o m m e n t a b o u t t h e i n a b i l -
* Immerwahr (1966) 7, 11-16 on general structure, 52-8 on framed units. These units (15), are of'every conceivable length' and there is 'no hierarchy of major and minor'; (61): nothing should be labelled 'digression' since this implies lack of importance; it is impossible to say that the alleged digression is more or less important than other units; only 'From the purely formal point of view, we can make a distinction between shorter and larger units.' See also Ch. 11 in this volume. " Immerwahr (1966) 47-51: kai- elements enhance the autonomy and separateness of each unit. Long (1987) 11-14: all ideas are presented as equally important, there is little subordination and a lot of conjunction. :
*
SHORT STORIES I N HERODOTUS'
HISTORIES
303
ity to breed mules in Elis (4.30), which he calls an 'addition', actually describes his sequential habit. The comment arises as an exception to his previous comment that mules generally tolerate temperate climes. This makes the structure o f the work as a whole completely different from that o f the short story, even though short stories are one o f the many forms o f unit found in the sequence. The short story is organic, like Aristotelian poiesis, with a clear beginning, middle, and end, short enough to be focussed on the ending, and grasped in one view. I n contrast, the work as a whole has an inorganic, archaic structure, a series of units o f more or less equal weight, which cannot be grasped all at once. The ending is merely the last i n the series. A form of ring composition could link it to the beginning, but it would be difficult to say that it carries the weight of the whole. Short stories are nevertheless organized within the larger narrative according to this sequential habit. They usually have an obvious mechanical connection to the preceding narrative. They can involve a character o f the main story (e.g., stories o f advice). The connection is often personal i n other cases as w e l l . Perdiccas' story (8.137-9), Euenius' story (9.92.2), and Artembares' story (9.122) arise out of the stories o f their descendants: Alexander, Deiphonus, and Artayctes respectively. Arion's story (1.23-4) arises out o f the mendon o f Periander, his patron, i n the previous story o f the siege o f Alyattes (1.20, 23-4). Hermotimus is mentioned in the main story only in order to tell his own story (8.104-7). 38
39
The sequential impulse is strong. Even those stories out o f chronological sequence are i n structural sequence. Herodotus says that he is returning to an earlier point i n his narrative when, after completing the campaign o f Thermopylae, he tells how Demaratus first warned the Greeks o f the invasion and how the wife of Leonidas interpreted his message (7.239). Yet it is linked to the previous unit through the immediately preceding reference to Demaratus as advisor o f Xerxes (7.237) and to the dead Leonidas (7.238). Stories structure the main story i n various ways. They mark the completion o f stages i n the larger careers o f the eastern rulers,
38
Cobet (1971) 45-59 discusses 'additions', which Immerwahr (1966) 14 n. 34 would see merely as further logoi in sequence. Immerwahr (1966) 40 sees action and counter-action as the link between major units. Gould (1989) 42 points to the importance of personal connections in relating one unit to the next. See also the way in which Homer introduces characters: Richardson (1990) 36-50. 39
304
V I V I E N N E GRAY
operating in a similar fashion to sections on ethnography and customs. Hermotimus' story marks the end of the campaign o f Salamis (8.104-7). Perdiccas' story marks the Persian offer of terms to the Athenians (8.137-9). Stories about diviners mark pauses before battles (8.33-7, 9.93—4). Stories o f aristeia cluster after battles (9.71-83). Artembares' story marks the work's final pause (9.122). Short stories also frame larger units o f narrative. The two stories o f Xerxes' excessive kindness and cruelty link the beginning and end of his invasion (7.27-8, 38-9, 8.118). Demaratus' story (7.239) marks the end o f the campaign of Thermopylae and refers back to its beginning. T h e three stories o f Xerxes and Masistes, Artayctes and Protesilaus, and Artembares and Cyrus at the end o f the Histories echo stories from the beginning (below pp. 310—15). The thematic relation o f short stories to their contexts is more controversial. Stories are often thematic 'digressions' in that they do not directly advance the chronological progress o f the mainstream narrative, but the removal o f the stories from Croesus' career would leave the merest skeleton o f a narrative— no longer the full-fleshed and organic account o f the human condition that the short stories make it. There are other ways besides i n which short stories relate thematically to the main story. Those that arise directly from the subject matter often comment on it as a result o f their placement. The advice o f Bias/Pittacus (1.27) divides Croesus' conquest o f the Greeks i n Asia from those Greeks and other nations within the River Halys. It is placed here to explain Croesus' friendship with the Ionian islands, the one area o f relations with Greeks i n which he departs from the war-like conquest that surrounds it, and it thus confirms by exception his identity as 'the first who harmed the Greeks'. Solon's advice, which marks the completion of Croesus' rise to power and heralds the loss o f his son, his first disaster i n his unbroken happiness, is also o f immediate as well as far-reaching thematic relevance because Solon focusses on sons as an ingredient o f happiness (the sons and grandsons o f Tellos, Cleobis and Biton, the sons o f the priestess). Similarly, the twin logoi of Athens and Sparta (1.59-68) that herald Croesus' aggression against Cyrus and explain why Croesus chose to make alliance with Sparta as the most powerful o f the Greeks, develop political thought about the constitutional sources o f the m i l 10
Immerwahr (1966) 61 f.
<
SHORT
STORIES
IN HERODOTUS'
HISTORIES
305
41
itary power he seeks. Even Demaratus' story (7.239) has a thematic function. Herodotus says that his warning provoked the Spartan request for the oracle of 7.220. This predicted the death o f Leonidas, which is the focus o f the immediately preceding narrative (7.237-8). Some stories that do not obviously contribute to the subject matter o f the main story have seemed to drift free of their original connection, to develop their own unrelated themes. Those stories that have an overt persuasive function within speeches are an interesting case. According to the rules o f rhetoric, Leotychides and Socles should shape their short stories o f Glaucon (6.86) and Cypselus/ Periander (5.92) to prove their point. A n d Leotychides does tell a story of failure to return a deposit held on trust that clearly instructs his audience to return the hostages that they also hold on trust. But the smile o f the baby tyrant Cypselus has suggested that his story does not entirely prove the thesis that Socles is making about the blood-thirsty nature o f tyranny. T h a t may seem unlikely when Solon and Bias so neatly tailor their material to their persuasive purpose. But the Homeric simile, as it is sometimes understood, might offer a parallel for this 'drift'. 12
43
44
45
The other view is that the context alone can explain why Herodotus tells a particular story i n a particular place, so that there should be a relation to the context that goes beyond the merely personal or accidental starting-point. After all, stories arising through personal connections do not arise for all individuals, nor, where they do, at their first appearance. Herodotus promises to tell the story o f Alexander's lineage at his first appearance (5.22), but, in spite o f further appearances, he delays the story until Alexander's appearance as intermediary between the Persians and Athenians (8.137-9). The reason for the delay could be that the story is more appropriate to that particular context. Finally, one of the possible relations between short story and context is analogy. This requires resemblances, e.g., of patterns, between 46
11
Gray (1997). Gould (1989) 53: some stories have a 'power and scale and weight' out of all proportion with their alleged explanatory function; also 50-8. Cobet (1972) 140-55 sees the 'Novelle' as integrated into the whole in quite sophisticated ways. This use of the short story is Homeric: Gould (1989) 55 6. Contrast Gray (1996). Bowra (1972) 6 1 2 . Schwabl (1969) 261, 265 on analogy. 12
4 3 4 4
45
4 6
306
V I V I E N N E GRAY
the n a r r a t i v e s . S h o r t stories i n w h i c h the p a t t e r n s resemble those o f the s u r r o u n d i n g n a r r a t i v e m a y act as ' m i r r o r texts', w h i c h i n d i c a t e how
t o r e a d the m a i n t e x t . T h e y at least c o n v e y
a
generalizing
significance, such as ' P r o s p e r i t y always leads to r u i n . ' T h e d i f f i c u l t y in Herodotus
is t h a t resemblances are f o u n d t h r o u g h o u t his s h o r t
stories a n d his m a i n story because o f his w i d e s p r e a d use o f p a t t e r n s . T h e r e is a q u e s t i o n w h e t h e r similarities b e t w e e n w i d e l y
separated
parts o f the w o r k c o n v e y a n y greater significance t h a n the suggest i o n o f the g e n e r a l r u l e i n the p a r t i c u l a r case. T h e contrasts b e t w e e n such stories. B u t
same applies to
analogies o r contrasts
between
s h o r t stories a n d t h e i r contexts are a n o t h e r m a t t e r , m o r e l i k e l y t o have specific l o c a l significance.
Meaning The
d e f i n i t i o n o f s h o r t stories p u r s u e d i n this c h a p t e r suggests
a
t e c h n i q u e f o r the analysis o f m e a n i n g : t o i d e n t i f y the p a t t e r n t h r o u g h c o m p a r i s o n w i t h s i m i l a r p a t t e r n s , to consider the n a r r a t i v e
shape,
p a r t i c u l a r l y a n t i c i p a t i o n a n d d e n o u e m e n t t o assess w h e r e the m e a n i n g lies, a n d t h r o u g h this to p u r s u e the q u e s t i o n o f t h e i r r e l a t i o n t o t h e i r c o n t e x t s — a n d w h a t follows is the e x p e r i m e n t a l a p p l i c a t i o n o f the t e c h n i q u e , focussing o n these m a t t e r s . 4 7
The story of Anon 1.23—4 The
story has b e e n d e s c r i b e d e a r l i e r . A r i o n ' s escape f r o m d a n g e r is
a story i n its o w n r i g h t , b u t the i n q u i r y i n t o i t makes i t p a r t o f the larger story o f double
crisis. P e r i a n d e r
is t h e focus o f a t t e n t i o n
t h r o u g h o u t since the m i r a c l e is r e p o r t e d to h i m a n d he c o n d u c t s the inquiry into it. T h e hero's escape f r o m d a n g e r is a c o m m o n p a t t e r n . S o m e heroes use i n g e n u i t y a n d c o u r a g e . Hegesistratus, the seer o f Plataea,
escapes
f r o m d a n g e r b y a c q u i r i n g a k n i f e a n d a m p u t a t i n g his o w n foot w h i l e i m p r i s o n e d i n the S p a r t a n n u i t y to s u m m o n
stocks (9.37). A r i o n seems to use inge-
a g o d t o help h i m escape w h e n he asks p e r m i s -
sion to give a final p e r f o r m a n c e . H i s d e d i c a t i o n at Poseidon's sanctuary
' Vansina (1985) 144-6 has guidelines for the interpretation of patterns.
SHORT STORIES I N HERODOTUS'
307
HISTORIES
at C a p e T a e n a r u m (1.24.8) suggests t h a t he at least t h o u g h t t h a t he was saved b y d i v i n e p o w e r . T h e d o l p h i n is t h e n a d i v i n e agent.
This
makes his escape a d i v i n e s a l v a t i o n , w h i c h has its o w n special p a t t e r n w i t h i n stories o f escape f r o m danger. M o r e
e x p l i c i t l y , Croesus
shouts o u t a n appeal t o A p o l l o t o save h i m f r o m d e a t h a n d is resc u e d f r o m his b u r n i n g p y r e t h r o u g h the agency s t o r m because similar manner,
o f Apollo's
rain-
he h a d pleased t h e g o d w i t h his gifts (1.87). I n a A r i o n p e r f o r m s a song w h i c h pleases his g o d a n d
is s i m i l a r l y rescued t h r o u g h t h e d i v i n e agency o f the d o l p h i n . H i s performance
explains his rescue, as a n t i c i p a t i o n precedes
denoue-
m e n t . A p o l l o o f D e l p h i w o u l d be a suitable rescuing g o d f o r a p o e t u n d e r his p r o t e c t i o n , a n d m u c h c a n be m a d e o f his c o n n e c t i o n w i t h d o l p h i n s , b u t i t is i n Poseidon's s a n c t u a r y t h a t A r i o n sets u p his d e d i c a t i o n , a n d his c o n n e c t i o n w i t h d o l p h i n s is m o r e o b v i o u s . The h y m n or prayer,
f o l l o w e d b y t h e casting o f a n o f f e r i n g i n t o t h e sea, is
f o u n d i n o t h e r appeals t o t h e gods o f t h e sea f o r p r o t e c t i o n f r o m harm.48 Periander's i n q u i r y also follows a p a t t e r n , w h i c h models
Herodotean
i n q u i r y a n d m a y have a g e n e r a l i z i n g significance. Astyages also questions t h e h e r d s m a n , as P e r i a n d e r questions t h e c r e w , a n d t h e herdsm a n ' s presence at t h e c o u r t makes
H a r p a g u s tell t h e t r u t h a b o u t
C y r u s f o r fear o f r e f u t a t i o n , w h i c h is t h e effect t h a t t h e appearance o f A r i o n also has o n the c r e w (1.117.1—2). L i k e P e r i a n d e r , questions P a r i s / A l e x a n d e r a b o u t
Proteus
his possession o f H e l e n a n d h e r
treasure. Paris' p r e v a r i c a t i o n s are r e f u t e d b y the witness o f his r u n a w a y slaves (2.115), as the i n f o r m a t i o n g i v e n b y t h e c r e w is r e f u t e d by Arion's
appearance.
A r i o n ' s story arises f r o m t h e m e n t i o n o f P e r i a n d e r
i n the p r e v i -
ous m a i n s t r e a m story o f A l y a t t e s ' siege o f M i l e t u s (1.20). 4 9 T h i s l i n k is s t r o n g because o f the i n q u i r i n g i d e n t i t y t h a t P e r i a n d e r has i n b o t h stories. H i s i n v e s t i g a t i o n o f A r i o n ' s
story is p a r a l l e l t o his ' f i n d i n g
o u t ' a n d r e l a y i n g t o T h r a s y b u l u s t h e i n f o r m a t i o n t h a t allows h i m t o deceive A l y a t t e s i n t o g i v i n g u p t h e siege. T h e m o r e i m p o r t a n t c o n n e c t i o n is t h r o u g h a w i d e r analogy. H e r o d o t u s presents t h e story o f the siege e n t i r e l y i n terms o f A l y a t t e s ' d i v i n e salvation f r o m disease
1,1
Polycrates: 3.41; the various appeals to gods of the sea during the storms around Euboea: 7.191, 192. Long (1987) 52 3 and Munson (1986) survey the many different interpretations of this story and its context; most recently Erbse (1992) 153 6. Mine is a summary of what appears in fuller form in Gray (2001). 4 9
308
VIVIENNE GRAY
(1.19; 1.22.4) j u s t as he presents A r i o n ' s story i n terms o f his d i v i n e salvation f r o m d e a t h at sea. 5 0 T h e
t h e m a t i c significance (that m e n
suffer f r o m a c c i d e n t a n d disease, a n d pirates a n d a w a t e r y
grave,
a n d t h a t the gods a l o n e c a n give s a l v a t i o n f r o m these ills) is o f i m m e n s e m o r a l significance for the Histories as a w h o l e , as serious as the advice o f S o l o n a b o u t the h u m a n c o n d i t i o n . T h e stories h e r a l d the e n t r y i n t o h i s t o r y o f Croesus ( 1 . 2 6 . 1 ) — a n d b y a n a l o g y p r e f i g u r e his d i v i n e s a l v a t i o n f r o m a d i f f e r e n t range
of
the disasters t h a t afflict m e n . T h e i r
in
hand
p l a c e m e n t here goes h a n d
w i t h their thematic significance. Herodotus
Alyattes'
also
postpones
d e d i c a t i o n i n thanks f o r his escape f r o m disease
(1.25.2),
w h i c h m i g h t have c o m p l e t e d his story at 1 . 2 2 . 4 , u n t i l after the c o m pletion of Arion's
story, w h i c h ends w i t h his d e d i c a t i o n i n thanks
f o r his escape f r o m d e a t h (1.24.8). T h e j u x t a p o s i t i o n o f t h e i r d e d i cations reinforces the p a r a l l e l o f t h e i r d i v i n e salvation.
Herodotus
makes A l y a t t e s '
s a l v a t i o n the o n l y r e a l focus o f his w h o l e
w h i c h spanned
57
years.
He
career,
m e n t i o n s o t h e r w a r s (1.16), b u t
the
siege o f M i l e t u s w h i c h he i n h e r i t e d f r o m his f a t h e r at the v e r y b e g i n n i n g o f his r u l e , is the sole focus because o f the salvation t h a t ensued. T h i s , a l o n g w i t h the d e v e l o p m e n t o f t h e a n a l o g y w i t h A r i o n , proves Herodotus'
o w n artistic role i n s h a p i n g his n a r r a t i v e .
The revenge of Hermotimus The
8.103-7
story heralds X e r x e s ' w i t h d r a w a l f r o m G r e e c e . H e r m o t i m u s is
m e n t i o n e d as secondary escort to X e r x e s ' c h i l d r e n o n l y i n o r d e r to t e l l his story. H e r o d o t u s
indicates at b e g i n n i n g a n d e n d (8.103 a n d
107.1) t h a t the p r i m a r y escort was A r t e m i s i a . The
story follows the p a t t e r n o f the revenge o f Astyages (1.119),
Alexander ( 5 . 1 9 - 2 1 ) , a n d A r t a y c t e s
(9.116,
120)
a n d endorses
the
i n e v i t a b i l i t y o f p u n i s h m e n t f o r i n j u s t i c e , b u t is u n i q u e l y the ' g r e a t est revenge f o r i n j u s t i c e o f those t h a t w e k n o w o f ' . 5 1 that Hermotimus
suffers a n d the revenge
t h a t he
T h e injustice
exacts take
the
p a r t i c u l a r f o r m o f c a s t r a t i o n , w h i c h destroys the r e p r o d u c t i v e capacity. Castrated
as a c h i l d , H e r m o t i m u s
becomes
Xerxes'
a n d t r u s t e d c o u r t e u n u c h . L i f e is n o t all u n f o r t u n a t e ! O n
30
honoured business
Schwabl (1969) 256-60 notes the parallel. Long (1987) 126-75, esp. 161 ft. on the patterns of Astyages' revenge. See also Ch. 9 in this volume. 51
HISTORIES
309
his castrator.
Astyagesdike,
SHORT STORIES I N HERODOTUS' one d a y i n A t a r n e u s ,
Hermotimus
finds
A l e x a n d e r - l i k e , w i t h a s t r o n g v a r i a t i o n o n the i r o n y t h a t belongs t o the m o t i f , he invites his oppressor's f a m i l y to receive t h e i r dues f o r m a k i n g h i m such a n h o n o u r e d e u n u c h . W h e n t h e y a r r i v e , he accuses his castrator o f m a k i n g h i m a ' n o t h i n g ' . H e
says t h a t the gods have
d e l i v e r e d h i m i n t o his hands a n d he forces his v i c t i m to cut his f o u r sons, w h o t h e n c u t h i m . T h e r e are t w o p o t e n t i a l crises (crime a n d p u n i s h m e n t ) b u t the first is n o t d e v e l o p e d ,
a n d the emphasis,
with
a t t e n d a n t a n t i c i p a t i o n , falls h e a v i l y o n the p u n i s h m e n t - — a l t h o u g h the t w o foci d o c o n t r a s t the Persian v i e w o f e u n u c h s (trusty a n d
hon-
o u r e d ) , a n d the e u n u c h ' s o w n G r e e k v i e w (I a m a n o t h i n g ) . ' 2 Herodotus
tells this story here because i t offers a n a n a l o g y
that
c o m m e n t s o n the c o n t e x t . 1 3 X e r x e s has b u r n e d A t t i c a i n revenge f o r t h e i r b u r n i n g o f Sardis (8.99.1), b u t is n o w i n p e r s o n a l d a n g e r after his defeat at Salamis ( 8 . 9 9 . 2 ) . M a r d o n i u s offers to c o n t i n u e the
fight
w h i l e X e r x e s w i t h d r a w s . A r t e m i s i a agrees, insisting t h a t X e r x e s a n d his household must survive a n d continue to threaten Greece (8.102.2-3). P a n i o n i u s a n d X e r x e s are o f the same c h a r a c t e r a n d s i t u a t i o n . T h e y are b o t h d e s c r i b e d as ' u n h o l y ' ,
the c a s t r a t o r i n the n a t u r e o f his
business ( 8 . 1 0 5 , 106.3), t h e k i n g f o r his d e s e c r a t i o n o f G r e e k shrines (8.109.3).
X e r x e s is c o n c e r n e d f o r the s u r v i v a l o f h i m s e l f , his sons,
a n d his h o u s e h o l d , w h i c h the Greeks m i g h t t h r e a t e n . P a n i o n i u s his f o u r sons a n d h o u s e h o l d are also t h r e a t e n e d . B u t
the
and
analogy
f r o m this p o i n t is s i g n i f i c a n t l y i m p e r f e c t a n d i n t r o d u c e s a c o n t r a s t . The
gods
hands
have n o t d e l i v e r e d X e r x e s a n d
o f the Greeks,
as t h e y
his h o u s e h o l d
delivered Panionius'
into
household
the to
H e r m o t i m u s f o r e x t e r m i n a t i o n (8.106.3). T h e A t h e n i a n s w a n t to p u r sue, b u t the L a c e d a e m o n i a n s refuse, o n the g r o u n d s t h a t X e r x e s w i l l c o n t i n u e t o t h r e a t e n t h e m i f he r e m a i n s i n G r e e c e , b u t w i l l
even-
t u a l l y have t o fight f o r his o w n l a n d i f he retreats. T h e m i s t o c l e s , i n p u r s u i t o f his o w n
interests, tells the d i s a p p o i n t e d A t h e n i a n s
that
t h e i r achievements have so far been the w o r k o f the gods a n d heroes, w h o refused t o let one such i m p i o u s m a n r u l e b o t h E u r o p e a n d A s i a (8.108-9).
32
The
gods have a l l o w e d his defeat, b u t d o n o t a l l o w the
His description as a 'gift' confirms that he is a 'thing': 8.105.2. See Dewald (1987) 23-5 on 'otherness'.' Immerwahr (1966) 284-5 believes that the analogy is with Xerxes' revenge on Athens, but he notes Xerxes' fear for his sons. Cf. Erbse (1992) 94 f: he enters into history to illustrate the Herodotean principle of balance. ,:i
310
V I V I E N N E GRAY
elimination o f his household and the end of his rule of Asia. The concept of limit is o f course central to the thought o f the Histories.
Xerxes/ Arlayctes/Artembares
9.107-22
The three stories mark pauses and conclude the various parts o f the main story. Herodotus leaves the Greeks sailing for the Hellespont bridge after Mycale and follows the Persians retreating to Sardis. H e highlights one incident. The king's brother Masistes is attacked when he castigates the commander of Mycale for ruining 'the king's house'. He is saved by a Greek (9.107), w h o m Xerxes rewards with the province o f Cilicia. The mention o f Xerxes' gratitude for the preservation of the brother who is so concerned for the royal household, and o f the arrival of the army i n Sardis, gives rise to the first story, set i n Sardis, of Xerxes' own destruction of this same brother and his household (9.108-13). Herodotus then returns to the Greeks, who find the Hellespont bridge destroyed. Their subsequent siege of Sestus involves the governor o f the region, Artayctes, who gives rise to the second story, which begins with his crime i n robbing and desecrating the 'house' of Protesilaus (9.116). The story of his punishment ends the siege (9.120). T h e n the Greeks return to Greece and after the close o f events for that year, Artayctes' story gives rise to the final story o f his ancestor Artembares, which closes the Histories. Analogies have been found to suggest thematic connections between these closing stories and the beginning o f the Histories, and to create a structural frame around the entire work or substantial parts o f i t . '
4
Xerxes and Masistes Herodotus calls this story 'the lust (eras) o f Xerxes and the death o f Masistes' (9.113). Xerxes was last seen fleeing the destruction o f his household. Here he destroys his brother's household through his lust, which frames the story (9.108.1, 113.2). There is a directional marker confirming the movement (9.109.2: Masistes' daughter was doomed to bring ruin to her and her whole house). Xerxes' murder of the brother 5j
:,+
Moles (1996) 271-84 gives a good recent reading of all three stories. See also: Ayo (1984), Boedeker (1988), Herington (1991a), Erbse (1992), Dcwald (1997) and Ch. 24 in this volume. But there is always more to say . . . See also Chs. 9, pp. 207-8 and 10, pp. 230 2 in this volume. :rj
SHORT STORIES I N HERODOTUS'
HISTORIES
311
for whose preservation he gave reward i n the preceding story makes it a pattern o f reversal, like those that afflict Croesus and Adrastus and many others. This main reversal is the result o f other reversals: Xerxes does not use violence (bid) against Masistes' wife because he respects Masistes, and she knows that she can resist Xerxes without fear o f violence for the same reason (9.108.1), but due to a sequence of unexpected outcomes she receives the most monstrous violence from Xerxes' wife (9.112). The patterned action that produces the reversal is the unwelcome obligation, caused by lust and creating a rift between two bonded men. It also shapes the story of Ariston's lust (eras) for his friend's wife (6.62). Ariston has his friend swear an oath that they will give each other anything they want. He meets his friend's request, then demands his friend's wife, and he is bound to give her because he is under oath. Sometimes the eras is latent. Democedes makes Queen Atossa swear an oath to give h i m in return for his medical treatment whatever he asks, but adds that this will not make her blush (3.133). His proviso suggests that eras was the usual driving force in the pattern. He lusts himself for his home in Croton, and his rift is with K i n g Darius. Xerxes' story uses this pattern to create an incremental triple series of crises, where each is linked to the next through the unexpected outcomes o f his gift-giving, which was part of the normal royal Persian protocol (9.107.3, 9.116.2), and the ultimate crisis is the break between the brothers. In the first two crises Xerxes is bound to give two women whatever they want. H e has to give his mistress Artaynte the cloak because he has sworn on oath to give her whatever she wants as repayment for her services (9.109.2). This leads Amestris to detect his infidelity. He then has to give Masistes' wife to Amestris because o f the requirement o f custom (the equivalent o f the pattern's more usual oath) to meet all requests on the royal feast-day (9.110.2111.1). Amestris will mutilate her i n revenge and her mutilation will lead Masistes to rebel. I n the third and ultimate crisis, which varies the m o t i f and puts the unwanted obligation back on his brother, Xerxes tries to force Masistes to accept the gift o f another wife (his daughter) that will save his house, but fails, making h i m declare that he will teach Masistes 'how to accept gifts' and leading to the destruction o f Masistes, his sons, and his army i n civil war. Direct speech underlines this major crisis, the confrontation with his brother, and the anticipation has been long indeed. The earlier crises are marked by mixtures o f direct and indirect speech.
312
VIVIENNE GRAY
4"he o t h e r p a t t e r n i n the story is t h e c o n t r a v e n t i o n o f nomos t h r o u g h lust, f o u n d also i n t h e story o f G a n d a u l e s at t h e b e g i n n i n g o f t h e work.
Xerxes contravenes
t h e laws o f m a r r i a g e ,
first
t h r o u g h his
i n f i d e l i t y , t h e n i n o r g a n i z i n g his son's m a r r i a g e to give h i m access to w o m e n ,
t h e n i n b e i n g o b l i g e d t o request a f u r t h e r c o n t r a v e n t i o n
i n t h e f o r m o f Masistes' d i v o r c e f r o m a v i r t u o u s wife a n d m o t h e r ( 9 . 1 0 8 . 1 , 1 1 1 . 2 - 4 ) . H e struggles against t h e o u t c o m e s o f these t r a n s gressions, as does Masistes, here t a k i n g o n t h e role o f Gyges i n t h e earlier story, b u t t h e r u i n is u n a v o i d a b l e . T h e story generalizes t h e h u m a n c o n d i t i o n , i n w h i c h m e n achieve the opposite o f w h a t they i n t e n d , b u t this p a r t i c u l a r reversal is a n a p p r o p r i a t e final i m a g e o f X e r x e s at t h e e n d o f the Histories, because it offers a domestic reversal t o p a r a l l e l his reversal i n m i l i t a r y affairs, a b o u t w h i c h t h e reader has b e e n r e m i n d e d i n t h e i n t r o d u c t i o n t o the story, i n t h e m e n t i o n o f the r e t r e a t f r o m Salamis (9.107.3). H i s c o n c e r n w i t h t h e s u r v i v a l o f his h o u s e h o l d d u r i n g t h a t e a r l i e r w i t h d r a w a l prefigures his c o n c e r n f o r his b r o t h e r t h a t also i n t r o d u c e s this story. T h e o t h e r p a t t e r n s m a y suggest o t h e r analogies. T h e a n a l o g y o f t h e c o n t r a v e n t i o n o f nomos t h r o u g h lust i n C a n d a u l e s ' story c o u l d l i n k t h e e n d o f t h e w o r k t o its e a r l i e r p a r t s . Y e t t h e s i m i l a r i t y o f t h e p a t t e r n o f the u n w e l c o m e o b l i g a t i o n i n A r i s t o n ' s story has p r o v o k e d no s i m i l a r l i n k . T h e s e analogies m a y show n o t h i n g m o r e t h a n t h e generalizing
tendency
at w o r k .
T h e story o f Cyrus w h i c h
subse-
q u e n t l y endorses t h e v i r t u e o f t h e h a r d life o f leadership c o u l d be c o m m e n t i n g o n X e r x e s ' decline f r o m this s t a n d a r d , as seen p e r h a p s i n his slavish s u b j e c t i o n t o w o m e n .
H i s m o t h e r already h a d ' e n t i r e
p o w e r ' t o i n f l u e n c e his o r i g i n a l a p p o i n t m e n t as k i n g i n t h e struggle between
t w o sets o f r o y a l b r o t h e r s ( 7 . 2 - 3 ) . B u t t h e decline is n o t
a p p a r e n t i n Masistes. H e is f a i t h f u l t o his w i f e , a g o o d f a t h e r , a successful s o l d i e r a n d l e a d e r w h o m
the Bactrians
a n d Sacians
love
(9.113.2). X e r x e s recognizes his virtues (9.111.2). T h e c o n t i n u i n g existence o f this m o r a l Persian reduces t h e p o w e r o f the c o n n e c t i o n w i t h the story o f C y r u s . I t is n o t a b l e t o o t h a t , t h o u g h they stem
from
lust, X e r x e s achieves his disastrous o u t c o m e s t h r o u g h t h e p e r f e c t l y h o n o u r a b l e r o y a l c u s t o m o f r e p a y i n g service a n d b e s t o w i n g w h i c h Darius
Z o p y r u s ( 3 . 1 4 0 , 160).
-
favour,
h a d o p e r a t e d t o such g o o d effect w i t h Syloson a n d
SHORT STORIES I N HERODOTUS'
313
HISTORIES
Artayctes and Protesilaus The
story
follows
the p a t t e r n o f revenge f o r c o n t r a v e n t i o n o f nomos,
t o l d i n t w o p a r t s w i t h i n the siege o f Sestus: c r i m e (9.116) a n d p u n i s h m e n t (9.120). The
c r i m e a n d the p u n i s h m e n t are m a r k e d b y passages o f d i r e c t
speech, p r e c e d i n g r a p i d a n d b r i e f d e n o u e m e n t .
Artayctes
deceives
X e r x e s i n t o g i v i n g h i m t h e shrine o f the h e r o Protesilaus, o n
the
g r o u n d s t h a t i t is the m e r e house o f a m e r e m a n w h o was p u t t o d e a t h j u s t l y f o r c a m p a i g n i n g against A s i a . H e w i l l deter others (cf. 7.5.2). H e
argues t h a t its seizure
t h e n takes t h e s h r i n e , p l u n d e r s its
treasures, a n d uses i t as a house, s o w i n g the fields, h a v i n g sex i n i t . He
suffers m i l i t a r y defeat a n d , i n t h e m a i n crisis, i n chains he rec-
ognizes t h a t the d e a d h e r o has p o w e r
from beyond
p u n i s h his transgression. H e
to persuade
is u n a b l e
accept r e s t o r a t i o n o r r e c o m p e n s e
the grave
to
the Greeks
to
i n spite o f his speech o f a p p e a l .
T h e y c r u c i f y h i m a n d k i l l his son. The
story shows a g a i n t h a t the gods d e l i v e r w r o n g d o e r s i n t o the
hands
o f t h e i r enemies i n o r d e r t o p u n i s h i n j u s t i c e . O t h e r stories
also s h o w t h a t some c r i m e s d o n o t a l l o w r e s t o r a t i o n o r tion.
compensa-
G l a u c o n deceives his c r e d i t o r s , a n d is p u n i s h e d b y t h e
god
whose o a t h he swore i n spite o f r e s t o r a t i o n (6.86). X e r x e s desecrated A t h e n i a n shrines a n d t h e n o f f e r e d r e s t o r a t i o n a n d c o m p e n s a t i o n .
The
A t h e n i a n s p r e f e r r e d t h e n , as X a n t h i p p u s a n d the Greeks p r e f e r n o w , to avenge the heroes r a t h e r t h a n agree w i t h the desecrator ( 8 . 1 4 0 - 4 ) . The
story has analogies t h r o u g h o u t the w o r k , b u t i n the c o n t e x t
o f the f i n a l act o f c o u n t e r - h o s t i l i t i e s against the Persians,
this
par-
t i c u l a r v e r s i o n suggests, even as the w o r k finds its closure, t h a t the c o n f l i c t w h i c h has b e e n its t h e m e w i l l n o t find c l o s u r e , because the crimes c o m m i t t e d c a n never be r e c o m p e n s e d . T h e r e m a y be a n a n a l o g y w i t h the b e g i n n i n g o f the w o r k . T h e revenge t h a t the A t h e n i a n s a n d t h e i r allies take is f o r the d e s e c r a t i o n o f the shrine o f Protesilaus, w h o first c a m p a i g n e d against A s i a i n t h e earliest stage o f the c o n f l i c t . The
early c o n f l i c t was m a r k e d b y the t h e f t o f w o m e n
a n d refusals
to restore o r compensate f o r t h e m ( 1 . 1 - 4 ) . I n the first crisis, Artayctes' story replaces t h e t h e f t o f w o m e n
w i t h the t h e f t o f the
o f a shrine f r o m a h e r o o f t h a t e a r l i e r p e r i o d . A n d
crisis, t h o u g h he n o w tries t o restore a n d c o m p e n s a t e took,
t h e G r e e k s refuse i t , as t h e y a n d
proem.
The
story m i g h t also s h o w
treasures
i n the
t h e i r enemies
second
for w h a t
he
did in
the
the further decline o f
Persian
314
VIVIENNE GRAY
m o r a l i t y , i n c o n t r a s t to t h e i d e a l t h a t C y r u s is s h o r t l y to offer i n his story (see b e l o w ) . I t c e r t a i n l y resolves the t h e m e o f g e o g r a p h i c t r a n s gression. A r t a y c t e s c o m m i t s the c r i m e as X e r x e s marches o n A t h e n s a n d is c r u c i f i e d at the place o f his crossing o f the H e l l e s p o n t .
In
w h a t m a y also be a n i m p l i c i t a n a l o g y , the revenge t a k e n i n a l l i e d t e r r i t o r y f o r a l l i e d gods foreshadows the D e l i a n League's c a m p a i g n o f revenge against Persia.
Artembares and Cyrus Herodotus
closes his w o r k w i t h a wise advisor story, the last i n a
l o n g sequence. A r t e m b a r e s gives advice to the Persians w h o pass i t o n to C y r u s , the a r c h i t e c t o f t h e i r first a n d perhaps greatest e x p a n sion. T h e
story arises f r o m the p r e v i o u s story o f his
descendant,
A r t a y c t e s . C y r u s is an u n d e f e a t e d a n d v i c t o r i o u s k i n g w h o t u r n s o u t to be a wise m a n , a n d A r t e m b a r e s The
a n d the Persians p r o v e
unwise.
p a r a l l e l is the advice o f the f o o l i s h L a m p o n o f A e g i n a to the
wise S p a r t a n
regent Pausanias (9.79). T h e
unwise advisors i n b o t h
stories praise the v i c t o r i o u s k i n g a n d suggest h o w this praise c a n be increased. L a m p o n says t h a t m u t i l a t i o n o f M a r d o n i u s w i l l increase the a l r e a d y great g l o r y o f Pausanias;
Artembares
advises t h a t the
possession o f a finer l a n d w o u l d make the Persians even m o r e a d m i r e d . J u s t as Pausanias sees t h a t this w o u l d e x t i n g u i s h even his present r e p u t a t i o n , so C y r u s sees t h a t w o u l d e x t i n g u i s h t h e i r present p o w e r . The
epilogue c o n t r a d i c t s the earlier story i n w h i c h C y r u s puts a
choice i n f r o n t o f his Persians- -to w o r k the l a n d all t h e i r lives o r feast i n l u x u r y (1.126). H e uses t h e i r preference f o r the soft life there to m o t i v a t e t h e m to rise against the M e d e s a n d set o u t o n the p a t h to e m p i r e . Perhaps he c h e a t e d t h e m . C e r t a i n l y , this episode serves a d i f f e r e n t p u r p o s e a n d p o i n t s to the i m p o r t a n c e o f c o n t e x t i n shapi n g short stories i n g e n e r a l . 1 ( 1 The
p a t t e r n o f the wise advisor has always b e e n a b o u t
choice.
H e r e C y r u s offers his Persians a free choice t h a t is n o c h o i c e : to live i n a f a i r a n d p r o d u c t i v e l a n d a n d be subjected a n d enslaved b y
):<> Herodotus has no qualms about consistency. His stories are strongly contextual. Thomson (1935) 199-207 notes that Herodotus' amalgamation of originally distinct stories produces inconsistencies of character. Edmunds (1997) 421 f. explains Homer's two different versions of Hephaestus' fall in terms of context.
SHORT STORIES I N HERODOTUS'
315
HISTORIES
o t h e r s , o r t o live i n a r o u g h a n d u n p r o d u c t i v e l a n d as w a r r i o r r u l e r s o f others. T h e
Persians
m a k e the r i g h t c h o i c e . T h e y
accept
that
empires rise f r o m r o u g h lands because o f n e e d f o r the p r o d u c t s
of
others, a n d conquer
to
those w h o
are too busy w o r k i n g the l a n d
p r a c t i c e t h e lives o f s o l d i e r s . " T h e
story c o u l d c o n t r a s t t h e i r o r i g i -
n a l wise choice w i t h the characters a n d b e h a v i o u r s s h o w n b y X e r x e s a n d Artayctes
i n the o t h e r t w o stories. B u t
followed Cyrus never d i d really a b a n d o n story m a y w a r n i m p e r i a l A t h e n i a n s , 3 9
the Persian kings
this o r i g i n a l c h o i c e . ' 8
b u t this p o l i t i c a l advice
the r u l e r w h o first d e v e l o p e d the E a s t e r n E m p i r e , is a n comment
The from
appropriate
o n its p r i m a r y c o n t e x t , w h i c h is as a n e n d i n g f o r a w o r k
t h a t has w r i t t e n the h i s t o r y o f this e m p i r e a n d c o n f i r m e d analogies t h e issues w h i c h are here The
who
meanings
through
addressed. 6 0
a n d f u n c t i o n s o f s h o r t stories i n H e r o d o t u s
need
c a r e f u l analysis. T h e y s t r u c t u r e the w o r k a n d address serious t h e m e s , both i n their o w n
r i g h t a n d i n r e l a t i o n to o t h e r n a r r a t i v e s ,
they interpret. T h e i r variations o n patterns c o m b i n e
the
which
universal
w i t h the p a r t i c u l a r i n h i s t o r y .
Transmission and Truth O n c e u p o n a t i m e , short stories w e r e d i s c a r d e d f r o m the Histories as e n t e r t a i n i n g digressions d e v o i d o f h i s t o r i c a l t r u t h . 0 1 B u t A r i o n ' s d i v i n e salvation is a t r u t h o f a d i f f e r e n t k i n d , a n d n o m o r e fabulous
57
than
Evans (1991) 38 f.: the original imperial impulse or nomas of Persia. The Persians do acquire wealth: 7.190. Feasting becomes part of their life: 9.82. Yet they do not apparently abandon their 'rough land': 1.71. The course of the Persian Wars shows that they do not abandon the warrior life or become slaves to others. Mardonius still prefers fighting to soft-living 'diplomacy': 9.41. Xerxes still honours good warriors: 7.238. For this approach to Herodotus, see Raaflaub (1987) and Moles (1996). ''" For example, Solon asserts with Cyrus that the one land cannot produce all goods: 1.32.8. Demaratus asserts that poverty is likely to turn people toward military skill as the only means to ward off poverty and enslavement: 7.102.1. Subsequently, Thucydides' Corinthians emphasize the importance of toil in the imperial ethos of constant achievement of the Athenians: 1.70.8. Pericles emphasizes toil as the price that they must pay for the honour of rule: 2.63.1. Mure (1853) 457, 461 for the old view, stories as amusements for those readers who had no heart for the graver realities of political history and as relief of the main narrative. De Ste. Croix (1977) 135 (and Erbse (1992) 92) quote Gibbon, that Herodotus writes sometimes for children, sometimes for philosophers. 58
3 9
61
316
V I V I E N N E GRAY
Croesus' salvation i n the ' m a i n s t r e a m ' .
O n c e u p o n a t i m e t o o , the
' h i s t o r i c a l ' core w i t h i n the short story was separated o u t f r o m t h e ' f o l k t a l e ' elements. T h e
s e p a r a t i o n is still t e m p t i n g w h e r e stories are
the earliest evidence f o r i m p o r t a n t e v e n t s — s u c h as the rise o f Peisistratus to t y r a n n i c a l p o w e r . B u t these are p a t t e r n e d i n the same w a y as the m o r e f a b u l o u s , i n d e t a i l as w e l l as i n the r o u n d , a n d makes the i s o l a t i o n o f 'facts' impossible.*' 2 T h e
that
same applies to p a t -
terns i n the m a i n s t r e a m o f the Histories. S h o r t stories have since b e e n accepted i n t h e i r e n t i r e t y as t r a d i tional truths about
the past o f t h e c u l t u r e s i n w h i c h t h e y
were
shaped. 6 3 O r the t r u t h s t h a t H e r o d o t u s shaped, as Geschichtsschreiber rather than G e s c h i c h t e n - E r z ä h l e r . 6 4 O r
the lies he t o l d . 6 5 T h e r e is a
n e e d f o r m o r e analysis o f the r e l a t i o n s h i p b e t w e e n his t r a d i t i o n s .
66
the w r i t e r a n d
I t is characteristic o f o r a l t r a d i t i o n t h a t i t develops
existing stories to reflect c o n t e m p o r a r y
concerns. ' I m p r o v i s a t i o n
on
a n e x i s t i n g stock o f images a n d f o r m s is the h a l l m a r k o f f i c t i o n a l narrative o f all sorts."" 'The
o l d fables reassemble a b o u t some n e w
p o i n t o f a t t r a c t i o n . . . ' 6 8 S u c h a d a p t a t i o n is also characteristic o f the w r i t t e n h i s t o r i c a l r e c o r d a n d o f s h o r t stories i n H e r o d o t u s . T h e
ques-
t i o n o f the extent o f his a d a p t a t i o n r e m a i n s o p e n , t h o u g h the study o f o r a l t r a d i t i o n s i n o t h e r societies i l l u m i n a t e s the task, as does the study o f the m o d e r n s h o r t story. T h e m o s t a t t r a c t i v e a n d positive assessment o f the s t o r y t e l l i n g style o f h i s t o r y as i t n o w
stands i n H e r o d o t u s '
t e x t is t h a t i t is m o r e
t h o u g h t - p r o v o k i n g t h a n n i n e t e e n t h c e n t u r y analysis: ' H e r o d o t u s '
con-
c e p t i o n o f h i s t o r i c a l t h o u g h t as e m b o d i e d i n t r a d i t i o n a l stories "raises (rather t h a n lowers) the level o f r e a s o n i n g [ r e q u i r e d o f the r e a d e r ] " . ' 6 9
62
Gray (1997) on the history behind the story of the rise of Peisistratus. In general for this problem, see Ch. 5, pp. 110-16 in this volume. Arion's story could be accepted for example as the genuine traditions of the Lesbians and Corinthians: 1.23. Thomson (1935) saw that audiences determined the content of stories. Erbse (1992) vii and passim. Schwabl (1969). Fehling (1971) 1989 believed that Herodotus falsified his traditions. Erbse (1991) and Fowler (1996) partially accept his thesis, Erbse as a device to distance Herodotus from 'the unbelievable', Fowler as the product of his mentality. Thomas (1989, 1996). Vansina (1985) 12. Thomson (1935) 167; also 20. Gould (1989) 41 paraphrases Redfield in Arethusa (1987) 252. Ibid., ch. 6 on the business of the story-teller and reactions to it. 6 3
61
65
6 6
67
68
69
SHORT STORIES I N HERODOTUS'
HISTORIES
317
The continuing debate about the meaning o f Herodotus' short stories proves that this view is correct. The technique o f analysis here proposed, i n terms o f story patterns and narrative art, is a systematic way o f revealing their meaning.
THE HISTORICAL
METHOD
CHAPTER FOURTEEN
H E R O D O T U S A N D T H E PAST Hans van Wees
Herodotus' interest in the past knew no limits. His investigations went back to the first known human, M i n , who ruled Egypt some 11,500 years before the Persian W a r (2.142.U3), and beyond h i m to the birth o f the oldest gods another 5,500 years earlier (2.43.4, 145.2). They extended to the furthest boundaries o f the known world, taking i n the origins and achievements o f all major nations along the way. Some readers see these accounts as mere digressions, entertaining but barely relevant, from the 'real' subject o f the Histories, the Persian War. This badly underestimates the scope of Herodotus' ambitions, as set out i n his preface: Herodotus of Halicarnassus hereby makes public the result of his investigations, so that the achievements of mankind may not be wiped out by time, and so that great and astounding deeds, some accomplished by Greeks, some by barbarians, may not be without fame—among other things, the reason why they waged war against one another. His record o f 'the achievements o f mankind' (la genomena ex anlhropon: 'the things brought about by human beings') included all of mankind and all o f the past. The war between Greeks and barbarians was the end, not the whole, o f this story. Since Herodotus artfully strung together histories and ethnographies of the world's nations along the thread provided by the story o f the origins o f this great war, his accounts o f Egyptians, Scythians, and many other peoples did indeed take the form of digressions—but i n substance they were an integral part o f what the Histories were intended to be: a universal history o f the human race. 1
1
So Lateiner (1989) 14-15, 217; Waters (1985) 23 (contra 47, 55); Fornara (1971a) 1, 32-5. More often, it is assumed that the Histories were essentially a history of the Persian empire, which 'swelled into a universal history' (Fornara (1983) 32), not by design, but as a side-effect of tracing the empire's expansion: so e.g., Myres (1953) 60-1; Immerwahr (1966) 17 45; 'Cobet (1971); Gould (1989) 1,'86; Luce
322
HANS V A N WEES
Herodotus' sheer ambition extended not only to the scope o f his work but also to its intended audience. The wish expressed in the preface, that the events o f the past should 'not be wiped out by time', implies that this work o f history was compiled for posterity, not just for the entertainment or education o f contemporary audiences. Herodotus' frequent use of the phrase 'until my time' (es erne), instead o f simply 'until now', confirms that he was writing with an eye on later generations. He sought to create 'a possession for all time', just as Thucydides did, although presumably he would have rejected Thucydides' opinion that this mission was incompatible with storytelling and 'competition for an immediate audience'. The main purpose of the Histories was, still according to the preface, to record great achievements and bestow fame. Herodotus here made himself sound more like an epic poet glorifying the deeds o f heroes than a historian reconstructing and analysing the past. Yet he advertised his knowledge of the past as derived from 'investigation' (historié), aligning himself with contemporary intellectuals rather than traditional poets whose knowledge was supposedly divinely inspired. Herodotus is admittedly willing to tell stories regardless o f their reliability, which may seem at odds with the insistence o f historians from Thucydides onwards on finding out 'what really happened', but the contrast should not be overstated. Herodotus dealt mostly with oral traditions at least a generation old and extending into the realm o f myth, so that he often felt unable to establish the facts and could do no better than repeat what he had been told, while keeping his critical distance—he concluded his first story with the words: ' I am not going to say whether these things happened i n this way or i n some other manner' (1.5). Whenever he felt that his evidence was reliable enough, however, Herodotus, no less than 2
(1997) 15-18; Romm (1998) 26. Although the Histories were organized around the history of die Persian empire, the preface and the sheer scale of the 'digressions' show that they were, not intended merely as a history of the Persian empire. For the debate about the 'unity' of the Histories, see also Ch. 11, this volume; for a detailed analysis of Herodotus' preface, see Ch. 1, this volume. Thuc. 1.22.4. See also Ch. 4, pp. 91-4; Ch. 12, p. 283, this volume. Moles (1996) 278 9, notes the address to a future audience in Herodotus' remark about cities 'which were great in my day' (1.5.4); Fowler (1996) notes that there is no evidence for es erne in the work of Herodotus' contemporaries (73; cf. 76-7); also Bichler and Rollinger (2000) 15. Fornara (1971a) 60- 1, 66, Gould (1989) 119-20, and Thomas (2000) 249-69, all stress the role of the immediate audience. 2
HERODOTUS A N D T H E PAST
a n y o f his successors, t r i e d to find the ' t r u t h ' a b o u t the past. : i T h e r e m a y have b e e n a g o o d deal o f the p o e t a n d story-teller i n h i m , b u t H e r o d o t u s was above all a h i s t o r i a n insofar as his m a i n c o n c e r n was to m a k e his r e c o r d o f the past as accurate as possible. 4 N o t e v e r y t h i n g t h a t h a p p e n e d i n the past was equally w o r t h p u t t i n g on record. Herodotus
s k i p p e d w h o l e stretches o f the past
deemed
i n s u f f i c i e n t l y 'great a n d a s t o u n d i n g ' , i n c l u d i n g m o s t o f G y r u s ' c a m paigns o f conquest (1.177) a n d the first 11,000 years o f E g y p t i a n hist o r y (2.101.1). H e
m a d e special note o f such things as the w o r l d ' s
greatest m o n u m e n t after the p y r a m i d s a n d ziggurats (Alyattes' t o m b , 1.93.2), 'the m i g h t i e s t b a t t l e b e t w e e n b a r b a r i a n s ' (Persians a n d M a s sagetai,
1.214.1), a n d the longest-ever siege (of A s h d o d ,
29 years,
2.157). A m o n g the m o r e s u r p r i s i n g entries were c a s t r a t i o n o f a m a n a n d his f o u r sons as ' t h e greatest o f all k n o w n acts o f vengeance' (8.105.1) a n d c u t t i n g o f f one's o w n f o o t as 'the greatest o f a l l k n o w n deeds o f b r a v e r y ' (9.37.2). H e r o d o t u s p u l l e d o u t all the stops f o r the c u l m i n a t i o n o f his story: the Persian a r m y o f r e c o r d - b r e a k i n g p r o p o r t i o n s w h i c h m a r c h e d against G r e e c e . This was by far the greatest o f all known military expeditions, so much so that by comparison the expeditions of Darius against the Scythians, or the Scythians i n pursuit o f the Cimmerians . . ., or the sons of Atreus against Troy, or the Mysians and Teucrians before the Trojan War. . . were nothing. All these expeditions and all the others that took place put together were still not equal to this single one. (7.20.2'21.1) V e r y m u c h i n the same v e i n , T h u c y d i d e s
felt the n e e d to argue at
l e n g t h t h a t 'his' w a r i n t u r n was s u p e r i o r to the Persian W a r
and
all t h a t h a d g o n e b e f o r e . By the n e x t g e n e r a t i o n , 'great e x p e n d i t u r e s a n d great dangers' h a d b e c o m e c a n o n i c a l c r i t e r i a o f h i s t o r i c a l i m p o r t a n c e , to the p o i n t t h a t a h i s t o r i a n m i g h t feel the need to apologize
3
Dewald (1987) 151, 173: on 41 occasions Herodotus denied the truth of what he reported: 'much of his energy as a critic goes into emphasizing the serious limitations of his data'. See also Ch. 15, this volume, and Thomas (2000) 228-35. Intellectual context: Ch. 7, this volume. Herodotus displays a 'dizzy combination of narrative, storytelling and the use of deductive proof: Thomas (2000) 175; also ibid., 168 75, 190-200, 217 18, 267 71; Lateiner (1989); Hunter (1982); see also Ch. 1, pp. 13-19, this volume. As is often pointed out, there is a great difference between ancient and modern standards of proof, plausibility, and acceptable invention, but this does not affect the essential point that Herodotus strove for accuracy by the standards of his time. 4
324
HANS V A N WEES
for i n c l u d i n g m a t e r i a l t h a t d i d n o t q u i t e m e e t these standards ( X e n o p h o n , Hellenica 5.1.4)."' The
Histories,
however,
were m u c h m o r e
t h a n a list o f w o r l d
records. H e r o d o t u s ' generous d e f i n i t i o n o f his subject as 'the achievem e n t s o f m a n k i n d ' a l l o w e d h i m to r a n g e e x c e p t i o n a l l y w i d e l y i n past a n d present. T h r e e historical topics stand o u t as o f special significance to h i m : t h e o r i g i n s o f c o m m u n i t i e s a n d customs, t h e rise a n d f a l l o f p o w e r s , a n d the causes o f w a r s .
Deep roots: the question of origins A n interest i n o r i g i n s is p e r h a p s t h e m o s t obvious m o t i v e f o r invest i g a t i n g the d i s t a n t past, a n d Greeks h a d b e e n r e c i t i n g genealogies a n d t e l l i n g m i g r a t i o n stories l o n g b e f o r e H e r o d o t u s . 6
I t is n o t sur-
p r i s i n g , t h e n , t h a t the Histories o f t e n e l a b o r a t e d o n the descent o r g e o g r a p h i c a l o r i g i n s o f i n d i v i d u a l s a n d n a t i o n s . T h e v e r y first b i t o f h i s t o r i c a l i n f o r m a t i o n o f f e r e d b y H e r o d o t u s was, as i t h a p p e n s , t h a t the Phoenicians w e r e m i g r a n t s ' f r o m the so-called R e d Sea'
(1.1.1).
H i s c o n c e r n s , h o w e v e r , w e n t b e y o n d c o m p i l i n g f o l k histories o f o r i gins. M u c h o f his m a t e r i a l seems c a l c u l a t e d to challenge the sort o f ideas a b o u t the Greeks' c o m m o n roots a n d i d e n t i t y expressed i n the Histories b y a n A t h e n i a n w h o defines 'Greekness' as ' h a v i n g t h e same b l o o d a n d t h e same language a n d c o m m o n
shrines a n d sacrifices,
as w e l l as s i m i l a r c u s t o m s ' . ' Taking
' s i m i l a r customs'
first,
the a u d i e n c e was soon
disabused
o f a n y n o t i o n t h a t these were o r i g i n a l l y o r exclusively G r e e k . T r a d i n g i n t h e m a r k e t - p l a c e was t h o u g h t o f as a t y p i c a l G r e e k a c t i v i t y ( 1 . 1 5 3 . 1 - 2 ) , b u t i t was the L y d i a n s w h o w e r e 'the first o f a l l people w e k n o w to strike a n d use g o l d a n d silver c o i n s , a n d also t h e first to b e c o m e r e t a i l traders' (1.94.1). T h e Greeks w e r e p a r t i c u l a r l y p r o u d
5
Of. Xenophon, Hellenica 2.3.56, 2.4.27. Thueydides' (implicit) use of these criteria: 1.1 - 21. See esp. Fornara (1983) 4-23; Hornblower (1994) 9-15. 8.144.2; as Harrison (2000b) 212-15 points out, the speaker here claims only distinctive common religious rites for the Greeks, but other passages make clear that there are supposed to be distinctive Greek gods also (4.108.2; 5.49.3, 92.tp; 9.90.2). Greek 'ethnic identity': Hall (1997). Herodotus' questioning attitude: Thomas (2000) 102 34; Hunter (1982) 74-92. 6
7
325
HERODOTUS A N D T H E PAST
o f t h e i r characteristic a r m o u r , w e a p o n s , a n d tactics, yet n o t o n l y was the i n v e n t i o n o f shields a n d h e l m e t s a t t r i b u t e d to the ( 4 . 1 8 0 . 4 ) , b u t some o f the t h i n g s t h a t m a d e
Egyptians
Greek military equip-
m e n t d i s t i n c t i v e — h e l m e t crests, shield e m b l e m s a n d shield h a n d l e s — w e r e c r e d i t e d to the C a r i a n s
(1.171.4). T h e
first to d i v i d e armies
i n t o h e a v y i n f a n t r y , l i g h t i n f a n t r y , a n d c a v a l r y i n the classical G r e e k m a n n e r was a k i n g o f the M e d e s (1.103.1). A l l b u t one o f the games p l a y e d b y the Greeks were b o r r o w e d f r o m L y d i a ( 1 . 9 4 . 2 - 3 ) , w h i l e the f o u r - h o r s e c h a r i o t , used i n the m o s t prestigious o f G r e e k sporti n g c o m p e t i t i o n s , c a m e f r o m L i b y a (4.189.3).
Herodotus
a r g u e d at
l e n g t h t h a t w r i t i n g was i n t r o d u c e d i n t o G r e e c e b y P h o e n i c i a n i m m i grants, a l o n g w i t h ' m a n y f o r m s o f l e a r n i n g ' ( 5 . 5 8 - 6 1 ) ; i n this l i g h t , his e a r l i e r r e m a r k t h a t one o f t h e S e v e n Sages, T h a j e s ,
was
'a
P h o e n i c i a n b y d i s t a n t descent' (1.170.3) emerges as m o r e significant t h a n i t m a y seem. H e
n o t e d t h a t astrology a n d g e o m e t r y a n d the
a r t o f s i n g i n g all o r i g i n a t e d i n E g y p t ( 2 . 7 9 , 8 2 . 1 , 109.3). T h e
Greek
system o f m e a s u r i n g t i m e w a s d e v i s e d b y E g y p t i a n s ( 2 . 4 . 1 ) Babylonians
and
(2.109.3).
Customs p e c u l i a r to the m a j o r G r e e k cities were revealed as equally unoriginal. The
' I o n i a n ' style o f dress a d o p t e d b y A t h e n i a n
women
was i n fact C a r i a n (5.88.1), w h i l e the dress a n d aegis w o r n b y A t h e n s ' p a t r o n goddess w e r e L i b y a n ( 4 . 1 8 9 . 1 - 2 ) . T h e A t h e n i a n s m i g h t p r i d e themselves o n b e i n g ' t h e first o f t h e Greeks' to represent the g o d H e r m e s w i t h erect p h a l l u s , b u t u l t i m a t e l y t h e y w e r e o n l y c o p y i n g the Pelasgians (2.51.1). M o r e s i g n i f i c a n t l y , the Persians seriously c o n sidered the i n s t i t u t i o n o f d e m o c r a c y , Cleisthenes i n t r o d u c e d i t i n A t h e n s
m o r e t h a n a decade
before
( 3 . 8 0 - 2 ; cf. 6 . 4 3 . 3 ) . N o t
even
Sparta's customs were u n i q u e : some w e r e shared w i t h Persians (6.59), others w i t h E g y p t i a n s (6.60), a n d the spectacular r o y a l f u n e r a l rites h a d parallels a m o n g m o s t ' b a r b a r i a n s i n A s i a ' (6.58.2). Herodotus
d e m o l i s h e d a n y suggestion t h a t the ' c o m m o n
a n d sacrifices' o f the Greeks w e r e n a t i v e . H e
shrines
a r g u e d t h a t the i d e n -
tities o f a l l G r e e k gods w e r e l e a r n t f r o m b a r b a r i a n s , p r i m a r i l y f r o m the E g y p t i a n s (2.50.1), a n d t h a t i t was at m o s t 4 0 0 years ago t h a t the Greeks h a d a c q u i r e d d e t a i l e d k n o w l e d g e o f the p a n t h e o n — l i k e 'yesterday o r t h e d a y b e f o r e ' ( 2 . 5 3 . 1 ) . A l t a r s , t e m p l e s , statues, images c a r v e d i n stone (2.4.2), religious festivals a n d processions (2.58), the taboo o n sex i n sanctuaries ( 2 . 6 4 . 1 ) , a n d the d o c t r i n e o f r e i n c a r n a t i o n (2.123.2-3) were all invented by the Egyptians.
E v e n the cries
326
HANS V A N WEES
u t t e r e d at sacrifices were n o t spontaneous b u t a c u s t o m l e a r n t a b r o a d , f r o m the L i b y a n s ( 4 . 1 8 9 . 3 ) . 8 As f o r the G r e e k language, i t h a d develo p e d f r o m a ' b a r b a r i a n t o n g u e ' spoken b y the G r e e k s ' ancestors (1.57) a n d even t h e l a t t e r was n o t t h e earliest k n o w n l a n g u a g e . T h i s , research h a d s h o w n , was P h r y g i a n
(2.2).
M o s t r e m a r k a b l e p e r h a p s was H e r o d o t u s '
attitude towards
'hav-
i n g the same b l o o d ' . H e seized several o p p o r t u n i t i e s to d e m o n s t r a t e t h a t p r o m i n e n t G r e e k families a n d e n t i r e ' e t h n i c ' groups w e r e
of
n o n - G r e e k descent. A l l o f G r e e c e , he n o t e d r e p e a t e d l y , was o r i g i n a l l y i n h a b i t e d b y a b a r b a r i a n people called the Pelasgians, a n d those G r e e k nations w h o p r i d e d themselves o n always h a v i n g l i v e d i n the same p l a c e - - t h e A t h e n i a n s
and Arcadians,
above
all- -were
thus
d i r e c t descendants o f these b a r b a r i a n s . T h e Pelasgian i n h a b i t a n t s o f 9
Athens
were
originally called Granaans, a n d only later
'Athenians', then
finally
became
' I o n i a n s ' (8.44.2). I t was n o t u n t i l this last
stage t h a t t h e y 'split o f f f r o m the Pelasgians, a d o p t e d a n e w i d e n t i t y a n d l a n g u a g e , a n d first b e c a m e Greeks (1.57.3). E v e n t h e n some Pelasgians w i t h i n A t h e n i a n t e r r i t o r y c o n t i n u e d to m a i n t a i n t h e i r o r i g i n a l e t h n i c i d e n t i t y , u n t i l e v e n t u a l l y they w e r e f o r c e d to e m i g r a t e . 1 0 N o less s t r i k i n g was H e r o d o t u s ' take o n the e t h n i c o r i g i n s o f A t h e n s ' m o s t c e l e b r a t e d p o l i t i c a l heroes, the tyrant-slayers H a r m o d i u s
and
A r i s t o g e i t o n , w h o b e l o n g e d to a c l a n c a l l e d the G e p h y r a e a n s .
He
w e n t so far as to reject o u t o f h a n d the clan's o w n story t h a t t h e y were of Eretrian
origin:
'as I have
f o u n d by i n q u i r y , they
were
P h o e n i c i a n s ' (5.57.1). T h e r e was n o such u n c e r t a i n t y a b o u t t h e Spartans a n d the o t h e r D o r i a n s w h o h a d b e e n 'a G r e e k p e o p l e ' f r o m the start (1.56.2),
and
H e r o d o t u s t r a c e d the ancestry o f the S p a r t a n kings b a c k t o H e r a c l e s , the greatest G r e e k h e r o , as was c o n v e n t i o n a l ( 7 . 2 0 4 , 2 0 8 . 1 , 8.131.2). Yet
i n a n e x t r a o r d i n a r y passage he a n n o u n c e d t h a t , g o i n g f u r t h e r
b a c k i n t i m e , ' t h e kings o f the D o r i a n s ' h a d b e e n Greeks o n l y ' u p t o Perseus, son o f D a n a e ' , r u l e r o f A r g o s : I said 'up to Perseus', and did not take it further back for the following reason: no name is known for a mortal father for Perseus . . .
8
See further Harrison (2000b) 208-22, 251-64; see also Chs. 8 and 18, this volume. 1.56-8, 2.51-2, 2.171, 6.136 8, 8,44; cf. 8.73. Hall (1997) 51, 72; Thomas (2000) 117 22. 1.57, 2.51, 6.137 8; cf. 4.145. 9
10
327
HERODOTUS A N D T H E PAST
Thus I used the right phrase and correctly said 'up to Perseus'. I f one lists the paternal ancestors of Danae, daughter of Acrisius, one will find that the leaders of the Dorians are Egyptians by direct descent. . . . Why and how, as Egyptians, they acquired the kingships of the Dorians, I will leave o u t . " To
c o m p l i c a t e m a t t e r s , he also c i t e d the Persian b e l i e f t h a t Perseus
was o r i g i n a l l y an A s s y r i a n ,
n o t a n E g y p t i a n , a n d t h a t his son was
the ancestor o f the Persian people ( 6 . 5 4 , 7 . 1 5 0 . 2 ) . I f such c o m m e n t s t e n d e d to raise questions a b o u t the significance of Greek 'blood', Herodotus
was o p e n l y s c a t h i n g a b o u t the
f o o l i s h ' claims o f c e r t a i n cities i n A s i a M i n o r to be o f ' n o b l e r '
'very and
p u r e r I o n i a n descent t h a n others. A large p r o p o r t i o n o f the o r i g i n a l settlers, he s a i d , i n fact consisted o f o t h e r G r e e k a n d
non-Greek
g r o u p s , a n d even the I o n i a n s a m o n g t h e m h a d taken b a r b a r i a n wives a n d b a r b a r i a n kings (1.146—7). A little l a t e r , he m o c k e d the h a b i t o f the Greeks o f t r a c i n g t h e i r ancestry b a c k to a g o d o r h e r o over as f e w as sixteen generations, w h e n i n E g y p t there h a d been 345 h u m a n generations w i t h o u t any
d i v i n e o r h e r o i c c o n n e c t i o n (2.143).
The
audience was surely m e a n t to i n f e r t h a t the Greeks' u l t i m a t e origins were not only more m i x e d but lay m u c h further back t h a n they h a d realized. Contemporary
audiences w e r e almost c e r t a i n l y m o r e o p e n t o w a r d s
such ideas t h a n some o f H e r o d o t u s ' later critics p r o v e d to be: P l u t a r c h was a l m o s t a p o p l e c t i c w h e n he r e p e a t e d some o f the above p o i n t s i n his treatise On The Malice of Herodotus (esp.
1315,
23). B u t
even
b r o a d - m i n d e d intellectuals o f t h e late fifth c e n t u r y a p p a r e n d y refused to believe t h a t the Persians h a d c o n t e m p l a t e d a d e m o c r a t i c g o v e r n m e n t b e f o r e the A t h e n i a n s
d i d ( 3 . 8 0 . 1 ; 6 . 4 3 . 3 ) , a n d we s h o u l d n o t
u n d e r e s t i m a t e j u s t h o w r a d i c a l some o f H e r o d o t u s '
ideas w e r e . 1 2
T h e Histories w e r e c e r t a i n l y n o t always so c r i t i c a l . H e r o d o t u s o f t e n e n o u g h appears to have s i m p l y r e p e a t e d the genealogies,
founding
legends, a n d stories o f o r i g i n s t h a t w e r e presented to h i m , w i t h o u t m a k i n g a p o i n t o f c h a l l e n g i n g t h e i r v a l i d i t y . B u t the c u m u l a t i v e effect o f the m a n y passages w h i c h a t t r i b u t e n o n - G r e e k origins to G r e e k
" 6.53, 55. This is a particularly striking claim because Herodotus elsewhere accepts the more conventional idea that these Egyptian rulers imposed themselves on pre-Dorian, Pelasgian populations: 2.171. (Lateiner (1989) 100 suggests that Herodotus is mocking the genealogy.) See Chs. 1 and 15, this volume, for Herodotus' self-consciously polemic pose. 12
328
HANS V A N WEES
c o m m u n i t i e s , customs a n d heroes, c o m b i n e d w i t h a n occasional o u t spoken p o l e m i c , leaves little d o u b t t h a t one o f H e r o d o t u s '
aims i n
investigating origins was t o p r o v e a p o i n t w h i c h he m a d e i n his o p e n i n g discussion o f t h e Greeks as a n a t i o n : t h a t they w e r e once ' w e a k ' and grew i n numbers
and power
o n l y because
t h e i r ranks
were
swelled b y 'Pelasgians a n d n u m e r o u s o t h e r b a r b a r i a n peoples' (1.58).
Lost empires: the me and fall of powers The
c h a n g e a b i l i t y o f f o r t u n e was a f a v o u r i t e t o p i c o f G r e e k m o r a l
discourse, a n d i t has a p r o m i n e n t place i n t h e Histories, m o s t f a m o u s l y i n t h e i r l e n g t h y r e - t e l l i n g o f the p o p u l a r stories o f h o w K i n g
Croesus
o f L y d i a a n d the t y r a n t Polycrates o f Samos fell f r o m grace. H e r o d o t u s e x t e n d e d this interest t o t h e c h a n g i n g fortunes o f entire p o l i t i c a l c o m m u n i t i e s , w h i c h he felt was a n i m p o r t a n t e n o u g h t h e m e i n his w o r k to be h i g h l i g h t e d at the outset: I shall move o n w i t h m y story, touching equally upon small and great cities o f mankind. For those which were great i n the old days have i n most cases become small, and those w h i c h were great i n m y day had been small i n the past. (1.5.3-4) The
Histories h a p p i l y d r e w m o r a l lessons o n t h e subject, sometimes
b l a t a n t l y , as i n t h e stories already c i t e d , a n d sometimes m o r e subt l y . 1 3 T h e observation that the 'notable' Egyptian city A n t h y l l a h a d ever since t h e Persian c o n q u e s t b e e n r e d u c e d t o p a y i n g f o r ' t h e f o o t w e a r o f the w i f e o f w h o e v e r rules E g y p t at the t i m e ' (2.98.1) was immediately followed b y an account o f the country's l o n g a n d glorious h i s t o r y ; t h e p o i g n a n t j u x t a p o s i t i o n was n o d o u b t d e l i b e r a t e . Herodotus,
however,
went beyond mere moralizing a n d made an
effort t o establish t h e precise extent a n d d u r a t i o n o f t h e ' l e a d e r s h i p ' (arkhe o r hegemonid) o f t h e great p o w e r s o f t h e p a s t . 1 4
See Ch. 9, pp. 217 24; Ch. 13, pp. 296 8; Ch. 23, pp. 524 8 and Ch. 24, pp. 553-9 (Persian empire), this volume. '* Evans (1991) 144: Herodotus was 'the first historian to articulate die succession of empires'. The modern distinction between arkhe as hegemonia as 'hegemony' is not made by Herodotus, who uses the onyms: e.g., Persian 'rule' is hegemonia in 3.65.6, arkhe in 3.73.1.-2. n. 44.
(Polycrates); the idea of 'empire' and terms as synSee also below,
329
HERODOTUS A N D T H E PAST
Tabic: Herodotus' chronology of the rise and fall of empires Egypt
Lower Asia (west of R. Halys)
Upper Asia (east of R. Halys)
Modern dates
Greece
Births of Dionysus and Heracles, 1,000 and 900 years, respectively, before 1 lerodotus (2,145)
330 generations (2.100), 11,000 years Id. 2.142), from Min to Moeris, 'less than 900 years' ago f2.13)
until c. 1300 B C
Sesostris (2.103 10): conquest of Ethiopia, Asia, and Scythia Pheros (2.1 I I ) Proteus (2.112)
Heraclid dynasty of 22
Assyrian
rule
for 520 years venerations, 505' (1.95) yrs. (1.7) Rhampsinitus (2.121) Cheops (50 yrs., 2.127) Chephren (56 yrs. 2.127) Mycerinus (2.129) Asycliis (2.136) Anysis (2.137) Sabacos (50 yrs. 2.137) Scthos (2.141) [Suite]
from c. 1225 B C
Hesiod & Homer 'no more than 400 years' before Herodotus (2.53)
f. 825 B C
1
Rulers include: Sardanap alius (2.150)
Sanacheribus (2.141) Mermnad dynasty
dynasty
Trojan war: '800 years before my time (2.145)
Median
ride
145 years]
for 4 generations. [5 generations, 128 years* 170 years] (1.130)
Psannnetichus, 54 (2.157)
Gyges, 38 (1.15 )
Nccos, 16 (2.159)
Ardys, 49 (1.15 1 Phraortes, 22 (1.102)
Psammis, 6 (2.161)
Sadyattcs, 12 (1.16)
Cyaxares, 40 (1.106)
Cypsclus, 30 years (5.92)
Apries, 25 (2.161)
Alyattes, 57 (1.25)
Astyages, 35 (1.130)
Thrasybulus of Miletus, Periander of Corinth (1.20)
Amasis, 44 years (3.10), and ' Psammenitus, 6 months (3.14)
Croesus, 14 (1.86)
Persian rule Gyrus, 29 (L. 126-130, 214)
Anaxandrides and Ariston, kings of Sparta (1.67)
Dcioees, 53 (1.102)
from f. 700 B C Arehiloehus (1.12)
Pisistratid dynasty, Persian rule over all Asia Athens, 36 years Conquest of Lydia by Cyrus (1.130) Cambyses, 7 y rs,, 5 months (3.66) (1,59 64: 5.65)
Persian rule over all Asia and Egypt (3,10 16) Conquest of Egypt by Cambyses
from 525 B C 522
Persian invasion of Attica, 'in the archonship of Calliades' (8.51)
from 486
522-486
Darius. 36 years (7.
1
from 546 B C
Polyerates of Samos (3.44)
Smerdis, 7 months (3.67)
Xerxes (7.4)
c. 560 B C
480 BC
Noi including' the interruption by 'Scythian rule lor 28 \ears (1.104, 106, 130; 4.1; the figures do not add up).
330
HANS V A N WEES
H i s special interest i n ' l e a d e r s h i p ' is i m m e d i a t e l y obvious f r o m his t r e a t m e n t o f t h e story o f Croesus. A l t h o u g h t h e r e h a d been
much
earlier contact a n d conflict between Greeks a n d barbarians, the Histories started w i t h t h e r e i g n o f Croesus, because he h a d b e e n t h e first b a r b a r i a n to 'subject' Greeks a n d i m p o s e ' t r i b u t e ' (phoros; 1 . 6 . 2 , 27.1), t h a t is, he was t h e first to i n c o r p o r a t e Greeks i n t o w h a t w e w o u l d call an ' e m p i r e ' . 1 5 H e r o d o t u s
d e f i n e d the precise e x t e n t
of
Croesus' conquests w i t h a list o f t e n b a r b a r i a n a n d three G r e e k subj e c t p o p u l a t i o n s (1.28) a n d stories a b o u t t h e n a t u r a l b o u n d a r i e s
of
his e m p i r e i n the west (1.27) a n d east ( 1 . 2 8 , 7 2 . 2 - 3 ) . H e was uniquelyspecific a b o u t t h e age at w h i c h Croesus
c a m e to p o w e r ,
35,
and
n o t e d t h a t his r u l e lasted 14 years, e n d i n g w i t h t h e f a l l o f Sardis after a siege o f 14 days ( 1 . 2 6 . 1 , 8 4 . 1 , 86.1). I n d e e d , H e r o d o t u s w e n t b a c k to the b e g i n n i n g o f Croesus' d y n a s t y , l i s t i n g the exact lengths o f the reigns o f his predecessors, a n d f u r t h e r b a c k still, t o the p r e vious dynasty w h i c h ' r u l e d f o r 22 g e n e r a t i o n s , 505 years' (1.7.4; see T a b l e , p p . 329). S o m e o f this i n f o r m a t i o n h e l p e d to b r i n g h o m e the m o r a l o f Croesus' story as H e r o d o t u s t o l d i t , b u t its a p p a r e n t p r e cision is r e m a r k a b l e . T h e exact figures w e r e h a r d l y a n a r r a t i v e necess i t y , a n d t h e i r p r o f u s i o n h e r e is s u r p r i s i n g g i v e n t h e i r r a r i t y i n H e r o d o t u s ' accounts o f Greek history.16 We
find
the same p a t t e r n i n subsequent t r e a t m e n t s o f t h e ' r u l e '
o f the M e d e s , Scythians, Assyrians, E g y p t i a n s , a n d Persians: the terr i t o r i a l e x t e n t , p o l i t i c a l n a t u r e , a n d c h r o n o l o g i c a l span o f each w e r e set o u t i n n o t a b l e d e t a i l . T h e
g r o w t h o f the p o w e r o f t h e
Medes
was t r a c e d step-by-step, f r o m the u n i f i c a t i o n o f the six M e d i a n p e o ples (all listed, 1.101), v i a t h e i r first f o r e i g n c o n q u e s t (of the Persians, 102.1), to t h e i r s u b j e c t i o n o f a l l A s i a east o f the R i v e r H a l y s i n c l u d i n g Assyria
' e x c e p t t h e B a b y l o n i a n p a r t ' (106.2).
(103),
Herodotus
briefly explained the curious ranked structure o f M e d i a n rule, w h i c h p l a c e d the M e d e s themselves i n d i r e c t c o n t r o l o f t h e i r n e i g h b o u r s , b u t a l l o w e d these n e i g h b o u r s to c o n t r o l t h e i r o w n n e i g h b o u r s i n
15
As Stacker (1992) 795-8 points out, the Athenian 'empire' and its tribute were taken as the model of 'leadership'; more on the implications for Herodotus' message below, p. 343, n. 47. The contrast between the precision of chronological indications for barbarian empires and their vagueness for Greek history may help explain why some scholars feel that Herodotus was keenly interested in chronology (so Fowler (1996) 75-6; Strasburger (1956)) wdiile others think that his interest in the subject was limited (see Chs. 17 and 22. pp. 500-4, this volume). 16
331
HERODOTUS A N D T H E PAST
t u r n , a n d so o n , to the b o r d e r s o f the e m p i r e ( L I 3 4 . 3 ) . H e gave the l e n g t h o f each k i n g ' s r e i g n , a n d t o t t e d u p the figures to s h o w t h a t M e d i a n r u l e i n U p p e r Asia lasted 128 years ( 1 . 1 3 0 . 1 ) . 1 7 A Scythian invasion of U p p e r Asia had interrupted M e d i a n
dom-
i n a n c e : 'the Scythians r u l e d Asia f o r 28 years, a n d they created chaos w i t h t h e i r aggression a n d a r r o g a n c e ' (1.106.1). A p a r t f r o m r e i t e r a t i n g the length o f their rule (4.1.2; cf. 1.130.1), H e r o d o t u s also r e c o r d e d j u s t h o w far t h e i r p o w e r reached: ' t h e y g o v e r n e d almost all o f U p p e r Asia'
(7.20.2) a n d came as far as A s c a l o n i n Palestine (1.105).
By
c o n t r a s t , he p r o v i d e d n o such d e t a i l f o r the c o n t e m p o r a r y , ostensibly similar C i m m e r i a n
invasion of L o w e r Asia,
a l t h o u g h this
h a d a m u c h greater i m p a c t o n m a n y G r e e k cities a n d h a d n e a r - p r o v e r b i a l i n early G r e e k p o e t r y . T h e
had
become
reason f o r this d i f f e r e n t
t r e a t m e n t was e v i d e n t l y t h a t the Scythians raised ' t r i b u t e ' w h e r e v e r they w e n t (1.106.1), whereas the C i m m e r i a n s m e r e l y r a i d e d (1.6.3). The
S c y t h i a n presence, f o r all the chaos i t p r o d u c e d , thus q u a l i f i e d
as a p e r i o d o f l e a d e r s h i p , whereas the C i m m e r i a n presence d i d n o t . The
fact t h a t H e r o d o t u s
p a i d m o r e a t t e n t i o n to a s h o r t - l i v e d a n d
probably unhistorical18 empire i n remote
U p p e r A s i a t h a n to the
n o t o r i o u s d e s t r u c t i o n o f G r e e k cities close to h o m e is t e s t i m o n y to his special interest i n the rise a n d f a l l o f great p o w e r s . I t m a y have been the same interest t h a t e n c o u r a g e d h i m to p l a n a d e t a i l e d a c c o u n t o f A s s y r i a n h i s t o r y , i n c l u d i n g a list o f the kings o f B a b y l o n (1.184) a n d the final sack o f the c a p i t a l N i n e v e h (1.106.2). H e r o d o t u s ' r e m a r k t h a t 'the Assyrians h a d r u l e d U p p e r A s i a f o r 520 years' before the M e d e s t o o k over (1.95.2) c e r t a i n l y fits the p a t t e r n , b u t since n o f u r t h e r a c c o u n t a c t u a l l y appears i n the Histories, we c a n o n l y speculate a b o u t w h a t m i g h t have b e e n . The
earliest a n d greatest p o w e r o f all was the E g y p t i a n e m p i r e
c r e a t e d b y the conquests o f Sesostris. T h i s
t o o k shape a b o u t
two
generations b e f o r e Assyria a n d L y d i a e m e r g e d as m a j o r p o w e r s (see Table,
p . 329) a n d e x t e n d e d n o t o n l y to all o f A s i a , b y l a n d a n d
b y sea as f a r as ships c o u l d sail, b u t also t o the Scythians Thracians
i n E u r o p e , a n d the E t h i o p i a n s
i n Africa (2.102-10).
this case w e are n o t t o l d h o w the e m p i r e was g o v e r n e d ,
or
and In how
l o n g i t l a s t e d - - t h e n a r r a t i v e gives the i m p r e s s i o n t h a t i t d i d n o t
" The figures do not add up correctly; attempts to make them tally (see How and Wells, Appendix III.6) are unconvincing. See Ch. 19, p. 437, n. 4, this volume. 18
332
HANS V A N WEES
o u t l i v e Sesostris h i m s e l f — b u t H e r o d o t u s w e n t to e x c e p t i o n a l lengths to p r o v e t h a t i t d i d exist. H e c i t e d t w o k i n d s o f i n s c r i p t i o n as p r o o f o f t h e extent o f Sesostris' c o n q u e s t s 1 9 a n d r e s o r t e d to e t h n o g r a p h i c evidence to d e m o n s t r a t e t h a t some o f Sesostris' soldiers h a d settled as far a w a y as the B l a c k Sea: t h e natives h e r e , he c l a i m e d , s h a r e d the E g y p t i a n s '
dark skin a n d 'woolly' hair, their weaving technique
a n d t h e i r p r a c t i c e o f c i r c u m c i s i o n ( 2 . 1 0 3 . 2 - 105). T h e i m p o r t a n t p o i n t f o r H e r o d o t u s was t h a t this a n c i e n t e m p i r e h a d i n c l u d e d e v e r y t h i n g t h a t was later to b e c o m e p a r t o f t h e Persian e m p i r e — a n d m o r e , because t h e Persians n e v e r c o n q u e r e d t h e Scythians (2.110.2—3). 2 0 I n subsequent g e n e r a t i o n s , the p o w e r o f E g y p t d e c l i n e d so f a r t h a t the c o u n t r y was c o n q u e r e d b y E t h i o p i a n s ( 2 . 1 3 7 - 9 ) a n d a l m o s t b y Assyrians as w e l l (2.141). Its f o r t u n e s w e r e r e v i v e d b y P s a m m e t i c h u s , whose c a m p a i g n s i n c l u d e d the longest-ever siege (2.157). H i s cessor Necos b u i l t a fleet o f t r i r e m e s ( 2 . 1 5 9 . 1 ) , Psammis
suc-
attacked
E t h i o p i a (2.161.1), A p r i e s c a m p a i g n e d as far n o r t h as P h o e n i c i a , a n d h a d a n a r m y o f 3 0 , 0 0 0 mercenaries ( 2 . 1 6 1 . 2 - 1 6 3 . 1 ) , a n d finally t h e r e was a p e a k o f p r o s p e r i t y u n d e r A m a s i s (2.177.1), w h o was said t o have b e e n ' t h e first h u m a n b e i n g to c a p t u r e C y p r u s a n d subject i t to t h e p a y m e n t o f t r i b u t e ' (2.182.2). F o r
the p e r i o d of Egypt's
rise
to p o w e r , H e r o d o t u s r e c o r d e d the l e n g t h o f each king's r e i g n , whereas f o r earlier rulers he h a d g i v e n h a r d l y a n y dates at a l l . 2 1 T h e m o s t d e t a i l e d i n v e s t i g a t i o n o f a n y p o w e r was o f course d e v o t e d to the Persian E m p i r e .
The
stages o f its e x p a n s i o n w e r e c l e a r l y
m a r k e d : C y r u s ' r e b e l l i o n against the M e d e s m a d e t h e Persians rulers o f U p p e r Asia,
his v i c t o r y over Croesus
put Lower Asia i n their
h a n d s (1.130), a n d his f u r t h e r c a m p a i g n s subjected 'every n a t i o n ' i n
19
2.102.4-103.1, 106; actually Ramesside stelae and Hittite reliefs: West (1985) 298-302. As the Persian King Darius himself is said to have acknowledged (ibid.); compare the later emphasis on the lack of Persian authority beyond the Colchians and the Caucasus (3.97.4), i.e., beyond the northern boundary of Asia and Europe (4.45.2). For a probable (remote) historical model for Sesostris, see Ch. 18, pp. 000-00, this volume. This investigation, and the rest of the long account of Egyptian history, confirms that Book Two was not an overgrown digression, but a major part of the universal history in its own right (cf. Hunter (1982), esp. 92). The exceptions are listed in the Table, p. 329, and are easily explained: Sabacos' 50 years in effect mark another mini-empire, when the Ethiopians ruled Egypt (2.137), and were predicted by an oracle; Cheops' 50 and Chephren's 56 years were required to explain why their pious successor came to a bad end: an oracle had predicted 150 years of misery for Egypt and after the combined 106 years of Cheops and Chephrcn time simply was not yet up (2.127, 129). 20
21
333
HERODOTUS A N D T H E PAST
U p p e r A s i a ' w i t h o u t m i s s i n g a single o n e ' (1.177, Cyrus,
190.2),
a m o n g o t h e r t h i n g s , the first m a n ever to c a p t u r e
making Babylon
(191.6). H i s son Cambyses a d d e d E g y p t , L i b y a , Phoenicia, a n d C y p r u s ( 3 . 1 3 . 3 , 19.3), a n d i n d o i n g so t r a n s f o r m e d the Persians f r o m a strictly l a n d - b a s e d p o w e r (1.143.1) i n t o a n a v a l p o w e r as w e l l . T h e
Persians
p r o c l a i m e d Cambyses a ' b e t t e r ' m a n t h a n his f a t h e r , because he h a d m a i n t a i n e d c o n t r o l over a l l earlier conquests a n d ' h a d w o n i n a d d i t i o n E g y p t and the sea' (3.34.4). I n the n e x t g e n e r a t i o n , the i s l a n d o f S a m o s was D a r i u s '
very
first
conquest (3.139.1), followed b y
the
I n d i a n s (4.44.3) a n d T h r a c i a n s ( 5 . 1 - 2 ) , the t w o most p o p u l o u s nations i n the w o r l d ( 3 . 9 4 . 2 , 5.3.1). A f t e r t h a t , o n l y the Greeks stood b e t w e e n the Persians a n d t o t a l c o n t r o l over the rest o f E u r o p e ( 7 . 5 0 . 4 , 53.2) a n d thus w o r l d d o m i n a t i o n (7.8y2). H e r o d o t u s Megara
c a r e f u l l y signposted
as the ' f u r t h e s t p o i n t i n E u r o p e t o w a r d s the setting s u n '
reached b y a Persian force before t h e i r a m b i t i o n s w e r e finally t h w a r t e d (9.14). 2 2 T h e t r i b u t e raised b y t h e Persian e m p i r e was a m a t t e r o f so m u c h interest to H e r o d o t u s t h a t he c o m p i l e d , o r r e p r o d u c e d , 2 3 a list o f t h e precise a n n u a l a m o u n t s c o n t r i b u t e d b y each o f t h e t w e n t y p r o v i n c e s o f t h e e m p i r e , a d d i n g u p t o t h e e q u i v a l e n t o f 14,560 E u b o e a n t a l ents o f silver, p l u s 360 w h i t e horses, 5 0 0 e u n u c h s , 120,000 measures of grain (3.89-95). O n
t o p o f this, t h e p r o v i n c e s w e r e o b l i g e d to
p r o v i d e supplies w h e n e v e r a n a r m y was raised (1.192.1), the fish tax f r o m L a k e M o e r i s b r o u g h t i n a n average 40 m i n a e o f silver a d a y (2.149.5) a n d i n one u n f o r t u n a t e r e g i o n the locals were m a d e to p a y ' a l o t o f m o n e y i n a d d i t i o n to t h e t r i b u t e ' f o r access t o v i t a l w a t e r supplies (3.117). A t
the e x t r e m e ends o f the e m p i r e , some nations
p r o d u c e d 'gifts' r a t h e r t h a n t r i b u t e , a n d t h e i r e b o n y logs, e l e p h a n t tusks, a n d talents o f f r a n k i n c e n s e w e r e d u t i f u l l y a d d e d to the list (3.97).
Almost
as r e m a r k a b l e as t h e d e t a i l e d c a t a l o g u i n g o f these
sums are t h e u n u s u a l l y e l a b o r a t e c a l c u l a t i o n s b y w h i c h t h e y w e r e c o n v e r t e d i n t o s t a n d a r d measures o f silver ( 3 . 8 9 . 2 , 95).
Herodotus
c o u l d n o t have d o n e m u c h m o r e to impress u p o n his a u d i e n c e the vast scale o f resources raised b y the Persian e m p i r e ' u n t i l m y
22
day'
Compare an earlier marking of the furthest point west reached by a Persian army in North Africa: 'the furthest part of Libya reached by this Persian army was Euesperides' (4.204). For the rise of the Persian empire, see also Ch. 24, pp. 553-9, this volume. For a sceptical view of the origins of this information, see Armayor (1978a). 23
334
HANS V A N WEES
(3.97.3; 6.42.2), but for good measure he threw in an anecdote about Cambyses angrily picking up and scattering to his troops Cyrene's gift o f 50,000 drachmas, a hefty sum by Greek standards, 'because it was so little, I believe' (3.13.4). The lifespan o f the empire was measured, as ever, by giving the length o f each king's reign. The apex o f its power—when it assembled the greatest army i n world history (7.20 1), shown by another lengthy series o f calculations to have consisted o f 5,283,220 men, accompanied by cooks and concubines, eunuchs, beasts o f burden and dogs (7.184-7)—was marked by the only absolute date recorded i n the Histories ('the archonship o f Calliades', 480 BC, 8.51.1). It almost goes without saying that, for all its apparent precision, much o f Herodotus' information about the great powers o f the past is unreliable, and indeed demonstrably false. His history o f Egypt before the Saite dynasty, for example, bears little relation to known reigns and events, and is not even internally plausible since it has only eight generations o f kings to cover a span o f more than 500 years (see Table, p. 329). M o r e remarkable than the mistakes, however, are Herodotus' willingness and ability to reconstruct and synchronize—so far as we know from scratch- any sort o f world history at all, let alone one which was roughly accurate for the last 300 years or so, and dared to reach back more than eight centuries. ' Measuring the dimensions of past empires in this way must have required an intense research effort. 24
25
26
2
Herodotus' explanation o f the rise and fall of the great powers, although presented in an unsystematic manner, was quite comprehensive. Beyond the simple observation that it took divine support " and large numbers o f brave fighters to w i n power, he remarked 2
29
24
Herodotus is inconsistent in claiming that before Darius subjects offered only 'gifts', no 'tribute' (3.89.3), yet elsewhere mentioning tribute paid to Cambyses (3.13.3, 67.3; 4.165.2). See for this, and many other points of chronology, Ch. 17, this volume. See Chs. 18 (Egypt), 19 (Scythian 'empire'), 21 (Babylon and Assyria), this volume. Medes: Sancisi-Weerdenburg (1988b, 1994). Persians: Baker (1987). Herodotus' contemporary Hellanicus may also have had 'universal' aspirations: his chronicle of the Priestesses of Hera at Argos included events in Macedon, Phrygia, and Italy (FGrH 4 F 74-84). Against the common view that Herodotus drew a clear line between historical time and mythical time: Hunter (1982) 86-7; and Chs. 17, 22, pp. 497-8, this volume. For explanations at the supernatural level, see Chs. 8 and 9, pp. 217-24, this volume. Bravery of Lydians: 1.79.3; of Persians: 9.62.3. Large manpower reserves: 4.1.1. 2 3
26
2/
28
29
335
HERODOTUS A N D T H E PAST
on the importance of unity among the conquerors. I f the numerous and warlike Thracians 'were ruled by a single man or were able to unite, they would be invincible and by far the most powerful o f all nations, i n my opinion. But they have no way, no means, to achieve this, and it will never happen; and that is why they are weak' (5.3.1). A detailed and probably fanciful account of the unification of the Medes prior to their conquests pointed the same m o r a l . Another prerequisite for power was 'great wealth' to support one's armies, attributed to the Lydians (1.29.1, 32.5), Persians (4.1.1), and, implicitly, Assyrians (1.192.1). Those who enjoyed all these assets could be expected to put them to use i n wars of conquest. Herodotus credited a king and queen o f Persia with the sentiment that i f a ruler w i t h great power and wealth were to 'sit still, without acquiring another nation or power', he would not be 'a man' (3.134.2, 4). T h e limits of imperial expansion were dictated simultaneously by the gods and by logistics. Croesus' ambition to conquer the Greek islands was stifled because he simply did not have the necessary naval resources (1.27); his eastward expansion failed because the gods and fate conspired against h i m , and, at the human level, because his army was too small (1.77.1). Herodotus blamed a lack of logistical support for the disastrous outcome o f Cambyses' attempt to subject Ethiopia (3.25) and praised scorched-earth tactics as 'the single greatest, cleverest of all human inventions' (4.46.2), responsible for the failure o f Darius' invasion of Scythia (4.83.1, 130). A wise advisor warned that a similar fate awaited Xerxes' expedition against Greece because suitable harbours and sufficient supplies were lacking, so that 'the two greatest things o f all'- -land and sea—'are your worst enemies' (7.47.2, 49). As for the inability o f Xerxes' army to defeat heavily outnumbered Greek forces i n the decisive battles, Herodotus' clear-cut explanation was that the Persians lost because the Greeks had, not greater courage, but superior military skills and equipment. 30
31
32
33
T w o obvious causes o f the fall o f empires, other than divine intervention, were defeat by even more powerful rivals and rebellion by
30
1.96-101; on its unreliability, see Sancisi, as cited in n. 26, above. See further below, p. 336, and Ch. 24, pp. 566-9, this volume. See Ch. 9, pp. 217-20, this volume. 7.10a.3 ('the best men both at sea and on land'), 8.68a. 1 ('at sea as much better than your men as men are better than women'). Skill and equipment at Plataea: 9.62.3. Inferiority of Persian equipment: 5.49.3, 97.1. See also Hunter (1982) 176 201, and Ch. 24, pp. 564-6, this volume. 31
32
33
336
HANS V A N WEES
discontented subjects. The Medes were simply overthrown by 'the great army o f the Scythians' which Herodotus reckoned among the largest of all time (1.103.3; 7.20.2). His accounts o f the fall o f Lydia and Egypt concentrated on moral lessons, rather than causes, but he did explain that the defeat o f the Lydians was due to the scale, speed, and cunning o f the Persian attack (1.79-80, 84). The Assyrian, Scythian, and revived Median empires were overthrown by their own subjects, who resented the 'slavery' to which they had been reduced and sought to regain their 'freedom'. Herodotus assumed that the impulse to resist, like the impulse to rule, was the mark o f a 'man'. Thus he had Croesus say that the only way to keep his 'manly and brave' Lydians (1.79.3) from rebelling, short o f destroying them, was to deprive them o f weapons, force them to wear luxurious clothes and to divide their time between leisurely entertainments and retail trade, 'and soon you will see them turned from men into women, and they will be no danger to you' (1.155.4). The full significance o f this observation only emerges in the last lines of the Histories, where Herodotus flashes back to the crucial decision made by the Persians when they first came to power to stay in their 'small and rough' homeland. Migrating to a 'better' part of their empire, Cyrus had told them, would mean 'no longer ruling but being ruled, for soft territories tend to breed soft men, because the same soil cannot produce both spectacular crops and good fighting men'. So 'they chose to live i n a barren land and rule, rather than spread their seed in rich plains and become other men's slaves' (9.122). T h e fundamental threat to imperial power- and political freedom— was thus a loss o f masculinity as a result of living a life o f ease. I n concluding his work on this note, Herodotus was implicitly formulating a historical theory about the rise and fall of empires, which sent a clear message to his audience concerning the best way to retain the freedom and power the Greeks had won for themselves. 34
35
30
34
1.95.2-96.1 (Assyrians), 1.126-127.1, 3.65.6-7 (Persians). The Medes overthrew Scythian rule because it was arbitrary and violent: 1.106.1. Conflict within the ruling elite was supposed to have been a contributory factor in the fall of the Medes (1.123-4), and to have brought the end of the Heraclid dynasty in Lydia (1.8 13). 'Retail trade' was seen as the epitome of an undignified pursuit of wealth because it was thought to be concerned with nothing but profit-making and to involve deliberate deceit (cf. 1.153.1—2). In its way it was regarded as no less inimical to masculinity and martial valour than a life of excessive leisure and luxury was (cf. Aristotle, Politics 1258a39-b8, !319a20-32). See further below, p. 343, n. 47; and Ch. 2, pp. 35-6, this volume. 3:>
3 6
HERODOTUS A N D T H E PAST
337
'From small beginnings': the slow rise of Greek power When the Histories turned their attention to the Greeks, their surprising emphasis was not only on the remote barbarian ancestry of the people and their customs, but also on the Greeks' humble beginnings and recent rise, i n contrast to the great old empires of Asia and Egypt, When the Greeks first separated themselves from the Pelasgians, they were 'weak' (1.58), and for centuries this was how they stayed: even at the time o f the Persian conquest of Lower Asia 'the entire Greek race was weak' (1.143.2). Herodotus did note repeatedly that the Greeks managed to muster a large army against Troy, as long as 800 years ago, but never without indicating his scepticism about the reliability of the tradition. Similarly, he dismissed Minos' thalassocracy, the other high point o f the Greek heroic age, as not belonging to 'the human generation': it did not really count. Herodotus went out o f his way to minimize the significance o f this thalassocracy, which might have been cited as an early peak o f Greek power, roughly contemporary with the conquests o f Sesostris. H e acknowledged that Minos had subjected the Leleges who lived i n the islands, but insisted that 'they paid no tribute, so far as I am able to tell from oral tradition'. Minos' naval power was thus not a true empire; moreover, his ships were manned by the Leleges so that they, rather than the Greeks, were 'far and away the most famous of all nations at that time' (1.171.2—3). 37
W h e n the Persians arrived on the scene, the two most powerful Greek states, by their own feeble standards, were Sparta and Athens (1.56.2). The power o f Athens, however, was impaired because the city was 'controlled and torn apart' by a dynasty o f tyrants (1.59.1) who kept the Athenians 'weak' and effectively i n subjection to Sparta (5.91.1-2). N o t until the last tyrant was expelled almost 40 years later did Athens begin to be a real force: 'while the Athenians were under tyrants, they were no better than any o f their neighbours, but when they were r i d o f the tyrants, they became by far the foremost state' (5.78; cf. 66.1). Cleisthenes' reform o f the Athenian tribes was explained, characteristically i f implausibly, as a symptom o f this
37
Scale of Trojan War (and doubts about reliability): 1.4.3 (cf. 1.5.3); 2.118.2 (cf. 'whether the Greeks tell an empty talc about what happened at Troy or not'); 7.20.2 ('according to the stories'). Minos not of'so-called human generation': 3.122.2; cf. above, p. 334 with n. 27.
338
HANS V A N WEES
g r o w t h i n p o w e r : the A t h e n i a n s n o w w i s h e d to set themselves a p a r t f r o m the o t h e r I o n i a n s (5.69.1), n a t i o n s ' (1.143.2). H e r o d o t u s
w h o w e r e ' b y far the weakest
k n e w o f A t h e n i a n overseas
of
expansion
u n d e r , a n d b e f o r e , t h e reigns o f t h e t y r a n t s , b u t he chose t o p l a y this d o w n
a n d present A t h e n s
as a v e r y late a r r i v a l o n the i n t e r -
n a t i o n a l scene. 3 8 The
power
o f Sparta,
o n the o t h e r h a n d , was w e l l established
w h e n the Persians m a d e their appearance: 'the b u l k o f the Peloponnese was a l r e a d y s u b j e c t e d to t h e m ' (1.68.6). h i g h l i g h t e d weaknesses. A
flashback
Yet
even here
Herodotus
i n f o r m e d t h e audience t h a t t h e
Spartans h a d b e e n 'just a b o u t t h e w o r s t - g o v e r n e d o f a l l Greeks a n d the m o s t isolated f r o m outsiders' u n t i l the r e f o r m s o f L y c u r g u s , eleven generations earlier ( 1 . 6 5 . 2 - 4 ; 7.204). A f t e r w a r d s , 'since they h a d g o o d l a n d a n d a large n u m b e r o f m e n , they q u i c k l y w e n t u p i n the w o r l d a n d f l o u r i s h e d ' (1.66.1). H o w e v e r , instead o f a n a c c o u n t o f Sparta's e a r l y successes, i n c l u d i n g t h e enslavement o f Messenia (of w h i c h he was w e l l a w a r e , 3.47.1), H e r o d o t u s
o f f e r e d the stories o f its unsuc-
cesful a t t e m p t , o n l y a g e n e r a t i o n before the emergence o f the Persian t h r e a t , to c o n q u e r A r c a d i a
( 1 . 6 5 . 1 , 6 6 ) , its recent n a r r o w
'escape
f r o m great t r o u b l e s ' i n a w a r against T e g e a ( 1 . 6 5 . 1 , 6 7 - 8 ) , a n d its m o s t r e c e n t success i n k e e p i n g h o l d o f t e r r i t o r y taken f r o m A r g o s (1.82). S p a r t a n h i s t o r y c e r t a i n l y c o u l d have b e e n given a m o r e positive gloss. H e r o d o t u s ' version seems designed to reinforce the scathing p i c t u r e d r a w n l a t e r in the Histories, a c c o r d i n g t o w h i c h even
this
m o s t p o w e r f u l o f G r e e k states m e r e l y f o u g h t 'battles over s m a l l pieces o f n o t very g o o d l a n d a n d t i n y boundaries . . . against equally m a t c h e d Messenians,
Arcadians,
and Argives'
(5.49.8). Sparta,
like
Athens,
was as yet u n k n o w n to the Persians. 3 9 T h e same p a t t e r n m a y be d e t e c t e d in H e r o d o t u s ' t r e a t m e n t o f the early h i s t o r y o f o t h e r G r e e k states, p a r t i c u l a r l y w h e n c o m p a r e d to T h u c y d i d e s ' b r i e f a c c o u n t o f the same p e r i o d . T h u c y d i d e s also stressed the 'weakness
o f t h e a n c i e n t s ' ( 1 . 3 . 1 ) , w h i c h he d e m o n s t r a t e d at
l e n g t h ( 1 . 1 . 3 - 8 . 1 ) , b u t d a t e d t h e rise o f the Greeks m u c h earlier: t h e
38
Earlier expansion: 5.94-5, 6.36-9. See Chs. 22 and 23, this volume, for different perspectives on Herodotus' treatment of archaic Athens, Sparta, and Greece at large, focussing on the extent to which it was shaped by his sources' selectivity and his own political beliefs. 1.153.1 2 (cf. for Athens 5.73.2, 105.1). For different perspectives on Herodotus' treatment of Sparta, see Vannicelli (1993) 21-96; Levy (1999). 39
If
339
HERODOTUS A N D T H E PAST
thalassocracy o f M i n o s was a first t u r n i n g p o i n t ( 1 . 8 . 2 - 3 ) a n d b y the t i m e o f the T r o j a n W a r A g a m e m n o n a l r e a d y h a d great p o w e r a large fleet, even i f he was short o f m o n e y (1.8.4—11.2). For
and
Thucy-
dides, the n e x t leap f o r w a r d c a m e w i t h the emergence o f C o r i n t h as a sea p o w e r , a b o u t 300 years ago ( 1 . 1 3 . 2 - 5 ) , t h a t is, r o u g h l y the era to w h i c h H e r o d o t u s d a t e d the rise o f the L y d i a n s a n d the M e d e s a n d the r e v i v a l o f Egypt. By c o n t r a s t , H e r o d o t u s
never even h i n t e d
t h a t C o r i n t h h a d at the t i m e b e e n a great n a v a l p o w e r ,
although
he h a d a g o o d deal to say a b o u t e a r l y C o r i n t h i a n h i s t o r y a n d was aware o f the n a v a l r i v a l r y b e t w e e n C o r i n t h a n d C o r c y r a
cited by
Thucydides.4" Second i n Thucydides'
list o f 'the m o s t p o w e r f u l
fleets'
(1.14.1)
was the n a v y o f the l o n i a n s , 'whose p o s i t i o n was m o v i n g
towards
great t h i n g s ' a n d ' f o r a w h i l e d u r i n g t h e i r w a r against C y r u s r u l e d the sea i n t h e i r area' ( 1 . 1 3 . 6 , 16). H e r o d o t u s p i c t u r e d the l o n i a n s at this t i m e as ' b y far the weakest o f n a t i o n s ' (1.143.2), w h o
despite
brave attempts to resist stood n o chance against C y r u s ' armies (1.169). E v e n M i l e t u s , 'at its highest peak a n d the j e w e l o f I o n i a ' , h a d
no
h o p e o f b e c o m i n g r u l e r o f the waves w i t h o u t t a k i n g the desperate step o f c o n f i s c a t i n g the sacred treasure o f B r a n c h i d a e , because p o w e r o f the M i l e s i a n s was w e a k ' ( 5 . 2 8 ,
'the
36.2-3).
I n the n e x t g e n e r a t i o n , Polycrates o f Samos ' m a d e o t h e r islands subject to h i m s e l f to b e c o m e T h u c y d i d e s ' t h i r d thalassocrat (1.13.6). Herodotus
saw things d i f f e r e n t l y :
Polycrates is the first Greek k n o w n to us w h o conceived the ambition to rule the sea—other than Minos o f Knossos or anyone else who may have ruled the sea before h i m . Polycrates was the first o f the so-called human g e n e r a t i o n . . . (3.122.2) Thucydides'
f o u r t h e n t r y i n the list, the Phocaeans (1.13.6),
elevated by
Herodotus
were
to ' t h e first Greeks to sail l o n g distances'
(1.63.1). T h e lack o f resources w h i c h p l a g u e d M i l e t u s affected even Herodotus'
first
two
naval powers:
Phocaea owed
its i m p r e s s i v e
fortifications to a f o r e i g n benefactor, the k i n g o f Tartessus ( 1 . 1 6 3 . 3 - 4 ) , a n d Polycrates was l u r e d to his d e a t h b y a false p r o m i s e o f
financial
help f r o m a Persian satrap, w h o h a d t o l d h i m : ' I hear t h a t y o u are
"' Herodotus on Corinth: 1.23-4, 3.48-53; 5.92(3-ii; cf. his near-silence about the Lelantine War (5.99.1) which for Thucydides was among the greatest ever (1.15.3).
340
HANS V A N WEES
p l a n n i n g great t h i n g s , b u t d o n o t have t h e resources t o m a t c h y o u r ambitions' (3.122.3).41 S t a r t i n g w i t h t h e first thalassocracy w h i c h he recognized,
Herodotus
b e g a n t o offer a f e w i n d i c a t i o n s o f t h e resources o f G r e e k states. Polycrates h a d 100 p e n t e k o n t e r s , a n d l a t e r 4 0 t r i r e m e s , as w e l l as 1,000 citizen-archers a n d m a n y mercenaries ( 3 . 3 9 . 3 , 4 4 . 2 , 4 5 . 3 ) . T h e Spartans h a d a b o u t 8 , 0 0 0 citizen-soldiers (7.234.2) a n d kept Polycrates u n d e r siege f o r 4 0 days (3.56.1). A r o u n d 5 0 0 B C , N a x o s h a d 8 , 0 0 0 hoplites a n d m a n y
warships ( 5 . 3 0 . 4 ) , T h a s o s h a d a n n u a l
revenues
f r o m its g o l d m i n e s o f u p t o 3 0 0 talents, used t o b u i l d warships a n d f o r t i f i c a t i o n s ( 6 . 4 6 . 2 - 3 ) , a n d A e g i n a h a d 70 pentekonters (6.92.1). A t the t i m e , t h e A t h e n i a n s
h a d h a d o n l y 5 0 p e n t e k o n t e r s ; they later
b o u g h t a n o t h e r 2 0 , a n d m a n a g e d to l a y siege t o Paros f o r 26 days; t h e n a s u d d e n i n f l u x o f 'great w e a l t h ' f r o m t h e i r silver m i n e s a l l o w e d t h e m to b u i l d 2 0 0 t r i r e m e s ( 6 . 8 9 , 1 3 2 - 1 3 5 . 1 ; 7.144.1). 4 2 T h e n u m bers o f G r e e k ships a n d m e n r a n g e d against t h e Persians d u r i n g t h e I o n i a n Revolt a n d Xerxes' invasion were carefully l i s t e d . " H e r o d o t u s , like T h u c y d i d e s , b e l i e v e d t h a t t h e p o w e r o f the Greeks h a d g r o w n ' f r o m s m a l l b e g i n n i n g s ' (1.58), a n d m e a s u r e d its g r o w t h i n t e r m s o f w a r s h i p s , f o r t i f i c a t i o n w a l l s , a n d revenues i n g o l d a n d silver. I n his Histories, h o w e v e r ,
he i n t e r p r e t e d this d e v e l o p m e n t as
even m o r e recent a n d m o r e l i m i t e d t h a n T h u c y d i d e s m a d e i t appear i n his Archaeology. I n d o i n g so, H e r o d o t u s created t h e starkest possible contrast b e t w e e n t h e cities o f Greece a n d t h e empires o f A s i a , w h i c h he so p a i n s t a k i n g l y s h o w e d t o b e m u c h o l d e r a n d vasdy m o r e powerful. T h i s v i s i o n o f h i s t o r y i m p l i e d t h a t t h e Greeks h a d little h o p e o f resisting i n c o r p o r a t i o n i n t o a b a r b a r i a n e m p i r e unless t h e y p o o l e d t h e i r g r o w i n g b u t still l i m i t e d resources. T h e d e t r i m e n t a l effects o f d i v i s i o n a n d t h e benefits o f u n i t y w e r e a c c o r d i n g l y a p r o m i n e n t t h e m e
41
Note however, Herodotus' reference to the Aeginetans as 'thalassocrats' at an unspecified but early time: 5.83.1-2. On the tradition of thalassocracy lists, see de Souza (1998) 277-88. Note the contrast with the Siphnians, whose mining revenues were distributed amongst the citizens and used to decorate public buildings with marble (3.57), rather than converted into ships and fortifications, and who were easily overrun by the Samians. Lade: 6.8; Thermopylae: 7.202-203.1; Artemisium: 8.1; Salamis: 8.43-8; Plataea: 9.28-30; cf. Mycale: 8.131.1. The inclusion of greater detail was of course not only a matter of choice for Herodotus, but also a reflection of his more detailed sources for events after c. 525-BC. 42
43
3 I I
HERODOTUS A N D T H E PAST
in Herodotus. The lonians, he said, might have remained free men i f they had taken the advice of their Sages and adopted at an early stage the 'good idea' that their twelve cities should form a single political unit, or, later, when the Persians had already conquered Ionia, the 'extremely good idea' that they should all j o i n forces and settle i n a single new city in Sardinia, where they would not only be free but 'rule over others' (1.170). The main obstacle to unity was that the Greeks fought among themselves for 'leadership', just as the barbarians did: 44
In the three consecutive generations of the reigns of" Darius, Xerxes, and Artoxerxes [522-424 BC] . . . more bad things happened to Greece than in the twenty generations before Darius—some inflicted on her by the Persians and others inflicted by the leading states themselves as they waged war over the leadership [arkhe]. (6.98.2) The consequences of this competition to lead took centre stage in Herodotus' account o f the negotiations to form a general Greek alliance against the Persians. The Argives offered to j o i n on condition that they could share the leadership fifty-fifty with the Spartans; when offered only a third share o f command, they pulled out and said that 'they would rather be ruled by barbarians' (7.148.4- 149). Gelon o f Syracuse promised a spectacular 200 triremes, 20,000 heavy infantry, 2,000 each o f cavalry, archers, slingers, and other lightarmed, and supplies for the duration o f the war, but withdrew his offer when the allies refused to let him have supreme command or command o f the fleet alone (7.158-61). His reply drew the moral of the story: ' I t seems that you have the leaders but will not have anyone to be led' (7.162.1). Herodotus made the Spartans the villains o f this episode, having them approach potential allies i n the most abrupt and peremptory manner. He allowed the Argives to reply that 'the naked ambition [pleonexia] of the Spartans was intolerable' (7.149.3) and Gelon to remark on their 'verbal display o f arrogant aggression [hybrismataY (7.160.1, cf. 158.1). His condemnation o f their uncompromising insistence on being recognized as leaders is implied also by the contrast 45
14
Again, Herodotus did not distinguish between 'hegemony' and 'empire' (see n. 14 above): thus, Argive 'hegemony' is hegemonia in 7.148.4, 149.2, but arkhe in 7.150.3. *' He also made apologies for the Argives (7.152) and listed as mitigating circumstances for their refusal the recent loss of 6,000 casualties to Sparta and a discouraging oracle (7.148.1-3).
342
HANS V A N WEES
w i t h the A t h e n i a n s , w i l l i n g to cede n a v a l c o m m a n d to Sparta despite the vast s u p e r i o r i t y o f t h e i r o w n fleet (161.2). T h e i r a t t i t u d e was singled o u t f o r e x p l i c i t praise: the Athenians gave i n , putting the survival of Greece first, aware that Greece would be destroyed i f they were to fight over the leadership \hegemonia].... So they yielded, but only for as long as they were badly needed -as they made clear, for when they had driven back the Persian, . . . they cited the aggressive arrogance of [the Spartan regent] Pausanias as their reason for taking the leadership away f r o m the Spartans. (8.3) Herodotus
also l a i d m u c h stress o n the i n t e r n a l u n i t y o f
w h e r e f a c t i o n a n d p e r s o n a l e n m i t y w e r e set aside i n the
Athens, common
interest, a n d he e x p l o r e d the f a c t i o n a l divisions elsewhere w h i c h o f t e n gave the Persians a n excuse, a n d the m e a n s , to attack a n d subject G r e e k states.' 6 I n w r i t i n g a h i s t o r y c o n c e r n e d w i t h the weaknesses o f the G r e e k city-states at least as m u c h as t h e i r strengths, H e r o d o t u s
presumably
i n t e n d e d to give his audience a l o n g v i e w o f t h e i r small a n d m o d est role i n w o r l d h i s t o r y u n t i l r e c e n t l y a n d o f t h e i r still p r e c a r i o u s p o s i t i o n i n the c o n t e m p o r a r y w o r l d - a n i n t e l l e c t u a l b r o a d e n i n g
of
h o r i z o n s o f t h e k i n d he a t t e m p t e d i n his i n v e s t i g a t i o n o f o r i g i n s . A t the same t i m e , G r e e k v i c t o r y over the Persian e m p i r e c o u l d o n l y seem a l l the m o r e a s t o u n d i n g f r o m such a perspective, a feat a c c o m p l i s h e d against the tide o f h i s t o r y . A b o v e a l l , H e r o d o t u s ' w a y o f l o o k i n g at the past sent a message to the a u d i e n c e a b o u t h o w to r e t a i n their freedom and gain power. T h e
Greeks' l i m i t e d resources c o u l d
be seen as a positive advantage, since t h e y ensured the sort o f austere a n d t o u g h w a y o f life w h i c h h a d b r o u g h t the Persians first freed o m a n d t h e n d o m i n a t i o n over
Asia:
Poverty has always been w i t h Greece, but our excellence is imported; it was w o n by our wisdom and powerful law, and by resorting to it Greece keeps poverty at bay and prevents subjection to a master. (7.102.1; cf. 9.82) P r o v i d e d the Greeks m a i n t a i n e d this t r a d i t i o n a n d steered clear o f b o t h the l u x u r i o u s , leisurely lifestyle a n d the u n d i g n i f i e d p u r s u i t o f
Internal unity in Athens: 6.109 10 (generals co-operate), 121-4 (no treason); 8.79—80. Internal faction elsewhere: pp. 345~6, and Ch. 23, this volume; also Raaflaub (1987) 230-41.
343
HERODOTUS A N D THE PAST
profit which had turned the powerful Lydians 'from men into women', they might be able to emulate the Persians' success. After all, unlike the warlike llrracians who were potentially the most powerful nation i n the world but as a result o f internal division had not been able to stand up to the Persians, the Greeks had managed to j o i n forces to preserve their independence. I f they continued to put the comm o n good first, they might prove capable of establishing an empire to rival the greatest i n history.*'
'The beginning of evils': causes of war Herodotus' preface advertised his work as a w o r l d history with special reference to the causes o f the war between Greeks and barbarians. Tracing the causes o f conflict not only served as a narrative device, a theme around which the disparate histories o f nations and empires could be organized, but was a serious historical pursuit for Herodotus. I f his explanations often seem less than adequate to the modern reader, this is mainly because he tended to concentrate on what we would call immediate causes- -in his view usually insults and injuries which called for revenge or punishment-
although
he
was aware of, and often alluded to, underlying causes such as expansionism, acquisitiveness, and old rivalries. Moreover, Herodotus did not think of 'underlying' causes as inherently more important and true, nor o f immediate causes as mere pretexts, but allowed for the significance o f all kinds o f causes, which might be delicately balanced. We may compare Thucydides, who, assessing the causes o f the Peloponnesian War, cited a series o f specific grievances but declared that the 'truest' cause was Athenian expansionism (1.23.6; cf. 6.6.1). He did not say that the latter was the real or underlyingcause as opposed to pretexts or immediate causes: it was merely the 'truest', most significant, in a hierarchy of causes, all o f which were true. The reader who bears i n m i n d these peculiarities of Herodotus'
4 /
Although Herodotus warned against the dangers of excessive expansion (see Chs. 9 and 24) and competition for leadership, he evidently approved of the ambition to 'rule over others' as such (1.170; 9.122). His message was thus not only that the contemporary Athenian empire might collapse (so e.g., Moles (1996) 277-8, Stadter (1992) 807-9, Meier (1987) 53), but more positively and more generally that the Greeks--if they lived and behaved appropriately--might maintain and expand their power (cf. Raaflaub (1987) 247-8, Jouanna (1981) 7 11).
344
HANS V A N WEES
analysis o f the causes o f war will find it quite comprehensive and sophisticated. A simple and plausible explanation for the Persian invasions o f Greece might have been that for two generations the empire had been expanding i n all directions and that Greece's turn had come. " Herodotus frequently commented on the Persians' imperialist motives with regard to Greece. I n 500 B C , a Persian commander tried to conquer Naxos for the sake o f its 'great wealth and many slaves' and its strategic location as a springboard to Euboea, 'a large and prosperous island, as large as Cyprus, and very easy to capture' (5.31.1-3). I n 492 and 490 BC, expeditions set out 'with the intention o f subjecting as many Greeks cities as they could' (6.44.1; cf. 94.1), while the great expedition of 480 BC marched not only against 'all Greece', but against the whole continent of Europe.' As the Persians themselves were made to say, 'We have subjected and made slaves of the Sacae, the Indians, the Ethiopians, the Assyrians, and many other great nations, although they had done the Persians no wrong—just because we wanted to extend our power' (7.9.2; cf. 7.8y). Yet Herodotus took every opportunity to show that the Persian War had not been inevitable. W orking our way backwards, we find that Xerxes was 'not at all keen' to march against Greece (7.5.1) and took a great deal o f persuading by human and divine agency before changing his m i n d (7.6-18). His father Darius had initially been equally uninterested in moving against Greece; even when he eventually agreed to send out a reconnaissance party, he failed to follow up on it (3.131—8). Indeed, the Persians might never have reached even the Greek cities i n Asia i f they had not been provoked. It was Croesus who 'committed the first injustice' by attacking some of the Persians' 'innocent' subjects (1.76.2; 1.130.3); until then it had never occurred to the Persians to expand into Lower Asia.' The 48
4
0
r
1
48
Causation in Herodotus: Hunter (1982) 201-4, 326 31; Gould (1989) 63-85; contra Evans (1991) 15 23, Hart (1993) 109-12, who claim that for Herodotus imperialism is the only 'real' cause, and Sealey (1957) 1-8 who claims that Herodotus acknowledged only the 'chain of grievances' constituting immediate causes. For the revenge motive, see Lendon (2000). For Herodotus' use of the concept of ailié, see further Ch. 1, pp. 17-19, this volume. But this is clearly not Herodotus' view, pace Evans (1991) 3, 29-33. Greece: 7.138.1. Europe: 7.5, 7.8B.1, 7.50.4; cf. 7.8a.2 ('a territory as good and as large as we already possess'), 7.157.3 (Persians will move against Sicily). '' Croesus' advisor Sandanis says: ' I thank the gods for not giving the Persians 49
5,1
I
345
HERODOTUS A N D T H E PAST
Histories p u r s u e d this t h e m e back to m y t h i c a l times i n its o p e n i n g story, a c c o r d i n g to w h i c h the Persians c l a i m e d t h a t the people A s i a h a d been
r e l u c t a n t l y d r a g g e d i n t o ' e n m i t y w i t h the
of
Greeks'
(1.5.1). First, the Greeks chose to retaliate r a t h e r t h a n negotiate w h e n a w o m a n was a b d u c t e d f r o m A r g o s .
L a t e r , i t was the Greeks
who
started t r o u b l e b y a b d u c t i n g a w o m a n f r o m C o l c h i s a n d r e f u s i n g to negotiate for h e r release. F i n a l l y ,
when
the q u e e n o f S p a r t a
was
t a k e n , the Greeks d i d n o t c o n f i n e themselves to m e r e c o u n t e r - a b d u c t i o n , b u t m u s t e r e d a vast a r m y a n d i n v a d e d Asia. F o r this decisive e s c a l a t i o n , the Persians (1.4.1).»
said, the Greeks were
'greatly to
blame'
'
Persian i m p e r i a l i s m was thus n o t a sufficient e x p l a n a t i o n for the Persian W a r s . H e r o d o t u s assigned m u c h o f t h e r e s p o n s i b i l i t y to the Greeks themselves. I n his v i e w , D a r i u s was r e l u c t a n t l y d r a w n i n t o G r e e k affairs b y Greeks p u r s u i n g t h e i r o w n p r i v a t e interests.
The
reconnaissance p a r t y o f 'the first Persians w h o c a m e f r o m A s i a to Greece' (3.138.4) was sent as a result o f the m a c h i n a t i o n s o f the court physician Democedes, his ticket h o m e . ' 3 D a r i u s favour
a G r e e k f r o m C r o t o n , w h o saw i t as
u n d e r t o o k his first G r e e k conquest as a
to his G r e e k f r i e n d Syloson,
who
sought to w i n back
the
t y r a n n y over Samos w h i c h his b r o t h e r Polycrates h a d h e l d ( 3 . 1 3 9 - 4 0 ) . The
self-interest o f r i c h a n d p o w e r f u l Greeks was also b e h i n d the
p u n i t i v e e x p e d i t i o n against B a r c a
(4.166—7), t h e f a i l e d e x p e d i t i o n
against N a x o s (5.30), a n d above a l l the Persian invasions o f 490 a n d 480 B C
at the u r g i n g o f t h e r u l i n g f a m i l i e s o f Thessaly,
and
sons o f Pisistratus, still h o p i n g to r e t u r n to p o w e r i n A t h e n s . '
the 1
A
notable e x c e p t i o n was Gillus o f T a r a s , w h o was o f f e r e d Persian b a c k i n g f o r his r e t u r n f r o m exile, b u t t u r n e d i t d o w n 'so t h a t he m i g h t n o t b r i n g chaos to G r e e c e ' , a n d r e l i e d o n the h e l p o f f e l l o w - G r e e k s instead. H e r o d o t u s a d m i t t e d t h a t this a d m i r a b l e a l t e r n a t i v e strategy
the idea of marching against the Lydians' (1.71.4); cf. 3.21.2 3 and Ch. 24, pp. 555-6, this volume. Herodotus questioned the historicity of this story, but its message was surely serious: the audience was invited to consider the possibility that the Greeks might bear some responsibility. 3.132-7. This story is often cited as an example of the frivolity of Herodotus' explanations (Derow (1994) 76; Fornara (1971a) 30), but he did not present it as a direct cause of war. Peisistratids: 5.96.1, 6.94.1, 102, 107.1; 7.6.2-5; rulers of Thessaly: 7.6.2, 5, 130.3, 172.1. In 480, the personal ambitions of the Persian commander Mardonius also became an issue: 7.6.1. 3-2
53
54
346
HANS V A N WEES
actually failed: the Tarentines ignored Gillus' Greek friends, who 'were unable to apply force' (3d 38.3). Most crucial in bringing about the Persian invasions was the burning o f Sardis, including 'the sanctuary o f the local goddess Cybebe' (5.102.1), by Ionian rebels supported by Athens and Eretria. Darius' allegedly prayed that he might 'punish the Athenians' for this and instructed a servant to remind h i m o f this duty three times a day; the 'overt reason' (proskhema, prophasis) for his two campaigns o f conquest against Greece was accordingly to punish Athens and Eretria.' The failure o f both expeditions meant that the Persians still had a score to settle almost twenty years later, and Herodotus had Xerxes and his advisors constantly cite the need to punish the Greeks for 'being the first to commit an injustice'. What is more, Herodotus stated as his own view that it was the Ionian Revolt and Athens' involvement which were 'the beginning o f bad things for Greeks and barbarians', i.e., the chief cause o f the Persian Wars (5.97.3). ' I t was probably this assessment of the revolt which led Herodotus to dismiss it as motivated by the self-interest o f a couple o f Ionian tyrants (5.28—38) who managed to embroil the gullible Athenians by 'deceit' (5.97.2); he might easily have presented it as a heroic war of liberation instead. H e even went so far as to accept that the burning o f the sanctuary o f Cybebe gave the Persians a reason for burning Greek temples.' No historian could have done more to assign a share o f responsibility for war to the Greeks. Herodotus' only concession was to acknowledge the driving role of imperialism i n Persia and especially in Lydia. N o t only had Croesus' eastward expansion provoked the 55
16
37
: 8
9
Syloson attempted to minimize Persian use of force, but this too failed: 3.140.5, 147. 56
5.105.2, 6.43.4-44.1, 6.94, 6.119, and 7.1.1, adding revenge for defeat at Marathon. 7.5.2, 7.8«x.2-p.3, 7.9, 7.11, also 8.102.3 and 142.2 (Athens as main and original objective); 8.76.2, 8.100.1-2, and 9.58.4, adding revenge for resistance at Artemisium and Thermopylae. Cf. 5.28, 30.1 (new beginning o f ' b a d things'); 8.22.2 (lonians reminded that 'initially our enmity witii the barbarians stemmed from you'). 5.102; 7.8(3.3. It was probably because Herodotus accepted that the burning of Athens and its temples were punishment for burning the sanctuary at Sardis that he felt forced to conclude that this fate could not also have been punishment for murdering Persian heralds (7.133.2). See also Ch. 8, pp. 187-8, this volume, for the burning of the temple of Cybebe, and Ch. 23, pp. 528-31, for Herodotus' treatment of the revolt. 57
58
M
347
HERODOTUS A N D T H E PAST
Persians, but he had 'been the first to commit unjust deeds against the Greeks' (1.5.3), often attacking without any valid reason at all: 'where he was able to find great causes, he accused them o f something great, but against others he could only adduce feeble causes' (1.26.3). Greek motives for waging war, i n turn, were as mixed as those of their enemies. The appeals to j o i n the Ionian Revolt which persuaded Athens, and nearly persuaded Sparta, mentioned saving fellow-Greeks from slavery (5.49.2-3, 97.2), but, as Herodotus told the story, they were mainly effective because they stressed the prospect of vast amounts o f easy booty (5.49.4-7, 97.1), and even the possibility o f the Greeks 'ruling over all Asia' (5.49.8). Sparta's conquests in the Peloponnese were, so far as Herodotus was concerned, motivated by greed (see above, pp. 338, 341 2). The Athenians were prepared to send out their entire fleet on the basis o f a promise of 'a limitless amount of gold' i n booty, without even knowing who their enemy would be (6.132); on this occasion Herodotus clearly deemed false the official justification that this was a punitive expedition for collaboration with the Persians (6.133.1). A t other times, however, the main causes o f war had been of a less material nature: old enmities flaring up, revenge or punishment being exacted, old friendships being honoured. There were even occasions when Greek armies turned down a chance o f profit. Despite an offer of money the allied forces persisted in a 20-day siege o f Thebes in order to punish those who had collaborated with the Persians (9.87—8). The Athenians twice resisted temptation. First Xerxes made them an offer o f freedom, as much land as they wanted, and restoration o f all destroyed sanctuaries, i n exchange for an alliance (8.140a.2, 9.7a. 1), which they rejected or several altruistic reasons, 'first and foremost the statues and the temples o f the gods, burnt and ravaged, for which we must at all costs exact the greatest possible punishment' (8.144.2; cf. 9.7a.2). I n the very last action o f the Histories, they are shown meeting this promise in the capture o f Sestos. fts governor Artayctes had desecrated a Greek shrine, but promised both to restore the stolen sacred 60
61
1,0
Another factor was the commander's private interest. Cf. 8.111-12, 121.1 (Themistocles). Enmities: 5.81 9, 8.27-30. Friendships: 5.99.1, 1.18.3, 3.47.1. Revenge: e.g., 3.47-9. 61
348
HANS V A N WEES
treasure a n d to p a y a 2 0 0 - t a l e n t r a n s o m f o r his o w n a n d his son's life. 4'he A t h e n i a n s refused a n d i n s t e a d c r u c i f i e d t h e g o v e r n o r
and
s t o n e d to d e a t h his son before his eyes ( 9 . 1 2 0 . 3 - 4 ) . G r u e s o m e as this episode m a y seem, i t was c l e a r l y m e a n t to s h o w t h a t at this c r u cial t i m e the A t h e n i a n s were m o t i v a t e d b y concerns other, a n d h i g h e r , t h a n b o o t y a n d conquest. I n t h e i r f i g h t against X e r x e s , i f n o t always b e f o r e , t h e y l i v e d u p to the ideal o f Greeks w h o ' c o n t e n d , n o t f o r w e a l t h , b u t f o r excellence' ( 8 , 2 6 . 3 ) . 6 2 Herodotus'
e x p l a n a t i o n o f w h a t caused t h e P e r s i a n W a r s
scrupulously balanced and
was
u n p a r t i s a n to a r e m a r k a b l e degree.
A
seemingly naive f o r m — t a l e s f r o m legend a n d folklore, i n v e n t e d speeches a n d dialogues, as w e l l as scattered a u t h o r i a l
comment—
b e l i e d a s o p h i s t i c a t e d c o n t e n t , i n his analysis o f causation as i n t h e Histories at l a r g e .
Conclusion I f H e r o d o t u s emerges as a suspiciously ' m o d e r n ' h i s t o r i a n , there are o f course deeply u n m o d e r n m o r a l a n d religious dimensions to his w o r k , e x p l o r e d elsewhere i n this v o l u m e b u t b a r e l y m e n t i o n e d h e r e . The
rise a n d f a l l o f e m p i r e s , the o u t b r e a k o f w a r s , a n d j u s t a b o u t
every o t h e r h i s t o r i c a l event c a n , a n d o f t e n is, e x p l a i n e d at a supern a t u r a l level as w e l l as i n secular t e r m s . I m p e r i a l e x p a n s i o n
comes
to a h a l t w h e n logistics f a i l o r enemies p r e v a i l , b u t also w h e n the gods decide t h a t a c o n q u e r o r is a b o u t to exceed his 'share'.
Wars
b r e a k o u t w h e n expansionist d r i v e s , p o l i t i c a l interests, a n d l e g i t i m a t e grievances coincide, b u t also w h e n the gods w i s h i t . Some o f H e r o d o t u s ' h i s t o r i c a l e x p l a n a t i o n s are even c o u c h e d primarily i n religious t e r m s : the suicide o f C l e o m e n e s a n d the d e a t h i n exile a n d disgrace
of
L e o t y c h i d e s w e r e d i v i n e p u n i s h m e n t f o r w h a t these t w o S p a r t a n kings h a d d o n e to t h e i r r i v a l Their
Demaratus.63
s t r o n g r e l i g i o u s e l e m e n t makes t h e Histories seem
conven-
t i o n a l (especially i n c o m p a r i s o n w i t h t h e m o r e l i m i t e d role o f r e l i -
62
Gf. Boedeker (1988) 42; contra the idea that the episode hints at future 'barbaric' excesses of Athenian imperialism: Moles (1996) 276-7 and Ch. 2, pp. 48-9, this volume. See also Ch. 9, 215-17, and Ch. 24, p. 553, this volume. 6.72 (Leotychides), 6.75.3, 84.3 (Cleomenes). See for the supernatural dimensions of these matters Chs. 8, 9, and 24, this volume; and in detail Harrison (2000b).
.51«)
HERODOTUS AND T H E PAST
g i o n i n the w o r k o f T h u c y d i d e s )
a n d t h e i r m o r a l values are r e m i -
niscent o f c o m m o n p l a c e s i n a r c h a i c G r e e k p o e t r y . B u t
Herodotus'
beliefs a n d values are n o t to be c o n f u s e d w i t h his a p p r o a c h to t h e study o f h i s t o r y , w h i c h was a n y t h i n g b u t t r a d i t i o n a l . H e
lived i n a
t i m e w h e n intellectuals w e r e c h a l l e n g i n g the v a l i d i t y o f all f o r m s o f k n o w l e d g e , a n d he a p p l i e d t h e r a d i c a l l y c r i t i c a l a t t i t u d e o f his c o n t e m p o r a r i e s to his chosen f i e l d o f study: the past. I t is thus, after a l l , n o cause f o r suspicion o r surprise i f H e r o d o t u s ' as ' m o d e r n ' i n some ways.
For
work
emerges
all their peculiarities o f f o r m
and
c o n t e n t , the Histories p r o v i d e t h e essential m o d e l for t h e w o r k o f a l l later h i s t o r i a n s , a n c i e n t a n d m o d e r n : t h e y w e r e the first to m a k e disp a r a t e recollections a n d records a subject o f systematic c r i t i c a l invest i g a t i o n . I t is H e r o d o t u s ' history.
a c h i e v e m e n t to have t u r n e d the past i n t o
CHAPTER FIFTEEN H E R O D O T U S AS A TRUTH,
FICTION,
CRITIC: POLARITY
Paul Cartledge a n d E m i l y
Greenwood
H e r o d o t u s ' Histories c o n t a i n n u m e r o u s episodes i n w h i c h t h e k n o w l edge o f t r u t h is o v e r w h e l m e d b y p o w e r a n d a u t h o r i t y . A succession o f advisors, p r o p h e t s , soothsayers, a n d oracles a l l 'speak t r u t h t o p o w e r ' , a n d , all t o o o f t e n , p o w e r is seen t o p r e v a i l over t r u t h . 1 H e n c e , i n B o o k N i n e o f the Histories a n u n n a m e d Persian d i g n i t a r y confides to the T h e b a n T h e r s a n d e r a t a b a n q u e t t h a t , 'this is t h e w o r s t p a i n a m a n c a n have: t o k n o w m u c h a n d h a v e n o p o w e r t o a c t ' (9.16.5). As i f t o c o n f i r m t h a t t r u t h is i m p o t e n t unless spoken f r o m a posit i o n o f p o w e r (kratos), H e r o d o t u s r e p o r t s t h e proceedings o f a Persian debate i n w h i c h the o p i n i o n o f M a r d o n i u s , the c o m m a n d e r a p p o i n t e d b y X e r x e s , prevails [ekratee) because he has p o w e r , whereas t h e m o r e p r u d e n t course o f a c t i o n suggested b y A r t a b a z u s is rejected (9.42.1). H o w e v e r , w h i l e t r u t h s e l d o m influences m i l i t a r y strategy a n d p o l i c y i n t h e Histories, i t is present as a c o u n t e r - d i s c o u r s e t h a t f r e q u e n t l y serves as a c o m m e n t a r y o n t h e vagaries o f p o w e r . H e n c e i n B o o k One,
S o l o n , t h e A t h e n i a n sage a n d l a w g i v e r , speaks his m i n d t o
Croesus, r e f u s i n g t o be c o w e d b y t h e spectacle o f p o w e r a n d w e a l t h t h a t t h e L y d i a n k i n g stages. T h e r e is surely a p o l i t i c a l d i m e n s i o n t o Solon's stance: i n c o m m o n w i t h t h e S p a r t a n envoys w h o refuse t o
' The phrase 'speaking truth to power' is used by Edward Said to explore the question of how the modem intellectual confronts issues of power and authority (Said (1994) ch. 5). Examples of 'speaking truth to power' in the Histories include: the Pythia's predictions for Croesus (1.47; 1.53, 55); the Median Magi who tell Astyages that it is in their interests for their interpretations of his dreams to keep him in power, because his rule guarantees their safety and authority (1.120); the royal judges of the Persian King Cambyses who have to strike the right balance between upholding justice and keeping Cambyses happy (3.31,4); Prexaspes, one of Cambyses' courtiers, who forfeits his son as a result of speaking truthfully to Cambyses (3.34-5); the soothsayers of the King of Scythia who are put to death i f the consensus of the soothsaying community goes against them (4.68); and Artabanus, Xerxes' uncle, who dares to contradict the king's proposal during a conference
352
PAUL CARTLEDGE A N D EMILY GREENWOOD
prostrate themselves before Xerxes (7.136), as a free Greek Herodotus' Solon stands up for what he believes to be true. However, there is also an intellectual dimension to Solon's stance, i n that he refuses to pass judgment on Croesus' prosperity until the latter dies, thereby asserting a long-term view such as that espoused i n the introduction to the Histories (1.5.4). We begin with the idea of 'speaking truth to power' because, as a freelance inquirer, Herodotus faced countless pressures. He had to establish authority for himself and, i n many respects, to create the criteria according to which he wanted his work to be judged. Herodotus is sensitive to the popularity of epic poetry, the widespread influence of oracles and the balance o f political power i n Greece i n his time. I n the history o f the reception o f Herodotus' Histories, there has been a tendency to consider these different influences unworthy o f the historian, but we hold the view that they serve to inform us about Herodotus' vision o f the genre that we now call History. Before we can pose questions about his reliability, we need to consider the nature o f Herodotus' intellectual enterprise. A l l too often scholars have lost sight of the fact that the debate about Herodotus' reliability as an historian is itself envisaged and indeed invited by the Histories. Herodotus has much to say about competing claims to authority across different disciplines and the credibility o f these conflicting claims. He expounds the criterion that any rigorous account o f an inquiry should submit to elenkhos, scrutiny (cf. Thomas (2000) 168, 208, n. 94). As he argues i n his polemical review o f Egyptian geography, the author who has written a tale (muthos) about the ocean takes refuge i n obscurity (es aphanes), and consequently his account is inscrutable (ouk ekhei elenkhon, 2.23). However reliable or fallible one finds Herodotus' methodology, he argues stridently for its scrutability and transparency. A m o n g the promising developments to emerge i n recent scholarship on Herodotu! are those that seek to explore Herodotus' critical persona and tc chart the rhetoric o f his history writing (or his 'voiceprint', to us< Robert Fowler's phrase). 2
3
4
~ In 1.86, several years after his encounter with Solon, Croesus acknowledge belatedly, the truth of Solon's judgment. Momigliano (1966a) offers an overview of the reception of the Histories in t l Western historiographical tradition. Cf. Verdin (1975) and Evans ( 1968) for shif ing perceptions of Herodotus' reliability as an historian; see also Ch. 1, pp. 4-: this volume. Fowler (1996) passim; see also Ch. 12, this volume. For a recent example of 3
4
HERODOTUS AS A CRITIC: TRUTH, FICTION, POLARITY
353
I n the first half of this chapter we shall try to relate the debate about Herodotus' reliability to issues o f truth and fiction as they arise in the Histories. We argue that Herodotus' conception o f his role and the way i n which different critics have conceived o f this role must be central to the process o f establishing appropriate conceptions o f truth for the work.' I n the second half o f the chapter, we shall consider the limitations of Herodotus' outlook and the cultural constraints on his reliability.
Truth and or fiction? One o f the works which has made the strongest and most sustained case against the 'historical' accuracy of the Histories i n recent decades is Detlev Fehling's Herodotus and his Sources.'' Scholars have been quick to point out that Fehling's portrait of Herodotus as a pseudo-historian imports latter-day categories into the work;' indeed, Fehling himself ((1989) 253) furnishes this very objection: As for the pious assumption of modern scholars that the man who first thought of writing history must, if he had so much as an average sense of moral responsibility, have pursued an idea of strictly truthful narrative, that appears anything but natural to me. On the contrary it seems more natural to me that historiography should begin as a mixture of truth and poetry and should use the resources of poetry to present the truth. Fehling finds fault with the generations of scholarship which have taken Herodotus on trust (though it is worth stressing that, i n many instances, Herodotus' word has served historians very well). However,
study that examines Herodotus' scientific, geographical, and ethnographical claims to knowledge in the context of contemporary debates and terminology, see Thomas (2000). For a recent overview of Herodotus' conception of his role cf. Darbo-Peschanski (1998), esp. 143 54, offering a good discussion of the resistance of ancient Greek history writers to modern criteria for defining history. On the gulf between ancient and contemporary history writing, cf. Shrimpton (1997) 80 227. German original 1971. Cf. Armayor (1978 b,c) and (1985). Fehling's work has, in its turn, provoked a counter-study by Pritchett (1993) on the 'Liar School of Herodotus' -his term for the school of Herodotean criticism which focuses on the shortcomings of the Histories as an historical source. For a recent review of the debate on the status of Herodotus' sources and the work's historical accuracy, cf. Fowler (1996) 80-7 with n. 125. Cf. Dewald (1987) 31-2; also Darbo-Peschanski (1987) 87. 3
6
7
354
PAUL CARTLEDGE AND EMILY GREENWOOD
it is o f t e n the a p p a r e n t failings o f t h e w o r k as a n h i s t o r i c a l source w h i c h reveal the n a t u r e o f t h e intellectual p r o j e c t i n w h i c h H e r o d o t u s was engaged. T o take one instance c i t e d b y F e h l i n g , H e r o d o t u s c o n tends t h a t 'the names o f n e a r l y a l l t h e gods c a m e to Greece f r o m Egypt' (2.50.1).8 A.
B. L l o y d , i n his I n t r o d u c t i o n to his c o m m e n t a r y
o n t h e second b o o k o f the Histories a t t r i b u t e s H e r o d o t u s ' e r r o r to t h e l o g i c o f 'post hoc ergo propter hoc' ((1975) 148, w i t h 50—1). W e w o u l d like t o stress the possible m o t i v a t i o n b e h i n d H e r o d o t u s ' c l a i m . As suggested b y T h o m a s H a r r i s o n , a n i m p o r t a n t c o n t e n t i o n b e h i n d H e r o d o t u s ' a r g u m e n t f o r t h e p r o v e n a n c e o f the names o f the G r e e k gods is to p u t G r e e k h i s t o r y , c u l t u r e , a n d r e l i g i o n i n a b r o a d e r c o n t e x t . H e r o d o t u s c a n p u t the Greeks i n t h e i r place as 'late starters i n the k n o w l e d g e o f the gods' ( 2 . 5 3 . 1 ) . 9 I n 2 . 5 0 . 1 , H e r o d o t u s c l a i m s , 'as to t h e f a c t t h a t t h e y c o m e f r o m f o r e i g n peoples [ek ton barbaron], h a v i n g m a d e m y i n q u i r i e s I find t h e f o l l o w i n g to be the case [eon]', H e r o d o t u s is e x p l i c i t i n m a k i n g G r e e k religious p r a c t i c e d e r i v e f r o m b a r b a r i a n p r a c t i c e a n d u n d e r w r i t e s this statement w i t h a c o n f i d e n t t r u t h - c l a i m (the n e u t e r p a r t i c i p l e eon denotes w h a t exists i n a c t u a l fact). T h i s ' E g y p t i f i c a t i o n ' o f Greece (cf. R o m m (1998) 101)
informs
us a b o u t H e r o d o t u s ' p r o v o c a t i v e p o s i t i o n i n g o f h i m s e l f i n r e l a t i o n to his a u d i e n c e a n d , w h i l e i t m i g h t n o t score m a n y p o i n t s f o r a c c u r a c y , suggests a n i n d e p e n d e n t a t t i t u d e w h i c h was t o b e c o m e one o f the d e f i n i n g traits o f the h i s t o r i a n . 1 0 This
sense o f i n d e p e n d e n c e
account o f Egypt (Book T w o
is stressed t h r o u g h o u t
Herodotus'
o f the Histories) as he takes issue w i t h
a r a n g e o f a u t h o r i t i e s f r o m disparate fields. As R o s a l i n d T h o m a s has a r g u e d ((1993) 241), i n this p o l e m i c a l section o f his w o r k ,
Herodotus
is e n g a g i n g i n c u r r e n t i n t e l l e c t u a l debates: ' W h a t w e are seeing h e r e is . . . a n emphasis o n the a c c u r a c y , d e t e r m i n a t i o n , a n d insistence a n d achievements
o f the a u t h o r a n d i n q u i r e r
a n d t h e r e f o r e his
s u p e r i o r i t y to o t h e r s . ' I n a d d i t i o n to c o r r e c t i n g a n o n y m o u s
Greeks
o n t h e causes b e h i n d the f l o o d i n g o f the N i l e ( 2 . 2 0 - 3 ) , i n B o o k
Two
H e r o d o t u s also supplements H o m e r ' s a c c o u n t o f Helen's w h e r e a b o u t s
8
Fehling (1989) 243: 'an astounding failure'. Harrison (2000b) 220, although Harrison also points out that Herodotus metes out the same treatment to other cultures. For instance, he exposes the insularity of the Ausaeans, who misguidedly think that their divinity (who corresponds to Athena) is unique to them (4.180.2) (ibid). For the motif of the historian's cultural, political, and geographical independence, cf. Lucian's On How to Write History 41. 9
111
355
HERODOTUS AS A CRITIC! T R U T H , F I C T I O N , P O L A R I T Y
d u r i n g the T r o j a n W a r w i t h i n i b r m a t i o n g l e a n e d f r o m t h e priests at T h e b e s i n E g y p t . 1 1 T h e n a r r a t i v e o f H e l e n ' s stay i n E g y p t , i n w h i c h H e r o d o t u s shifts b e t w e e n alleged certainties a n d the stuff o f m y t h , is e m b e d d e d w i t h i n a series o f claims t h a t l i m i t H e r o d o t u s ' l i a b i l i t y f o r the stories w h i c h he mediates. A t 2 . 2 9 . 1 - 2 , H e r o d o t u s states t h a t he c a n v o u c h f o r his a c c o u n t o f the t e r r i t o r y as far as E l e p h a n t i n e , o n the basis o f autopsy (autoptes elthon); h o w e v e r , S o u t h o f this p o i n t , he was reliant o n hearsay a n d i n q u i r y (akoei historeori). A g a i n at 2 . 9 9 . 1 - 2 , we are i n f o r m e d t h a t ' u p to this p o i n t ' ,
his a c c o u n t has h a d
the
benefit o f f i r s t - h a n d personal experience, whereas w h a t follows derives f r o m Ejgyptian i n f o r m a n t s : U p to this point I have confined what I have written to the results of my own direct observation and research, and the views I have formed f r o m d i e m ; but f r o m now on the basis of m y story w i l l be the accounts given to me by the Egyptians themselves—though here, too, I shall put i n one or two things which I have seen w i t h my own eyes.' 2 I t is n o t e w o r t h y not vouch,
t h a t , even i n r e l a t i o n to stories f o r w h i c h he c a n -
H e r o d o t u s does n o t r e l i n q u i s h his a u t h o r i a l
guarantee
altogether. W h e n w e c o m e to the section a b o u t H e l e n ' s a b d u c t i o n , H e r o d o t u s reviews the poetic accounts ( 2 . 1 1 6 - 1 7 ) a n d concludes t h a t
Homer
was f a m i l i a r w i t h the t r u e a c c o u n t , b u t t h a t he was b o u n d b y generic considerations (the s u i t a b i l i t y o f the d i f f e r e n t versions f o r epic (epopoiien)—2.116.1).
As f o r the a u t h o r i t y o f the a c c o u n t , the priests c l a i m
u n e r r i n g k n o w l e d g e (atrekeos epistamenoif''' f o r the events t h a t t o o k place i n t h e i r r e g i o n (2.119.3). T h e succession of qualifications a n d c o u n t e r q u a l i f i c a t i o n s m i g h t n o t m a k e f o r consistency, b u t it gives the i m p r e s sion o f a c i r c u m s p e c t i n q u i r y whose t r u t h s are c o n d i t i o n e d b y shades o f u n c e r t a i n t y a n d whose m y t h i c a l elements are analysed to y i e l d an e x p l a n a t i o n f o r the processes w h i c h w e n t i n t o t h e i r m a k i n g . As J o h n M a r i n c o l a c o m m e n t s , ' W h a t these people or nations " s a y " , together w i t h H e r o d o t u s ' r e a c t i o n to it, is itself the v a l i d a t i o n presented H e r o d o t u s f o r w i n n i n g the reader's b e l i e f ((1997a)
11
by
100).
2.113-20. On critical reflection on myth and myth criticism in poetry and early historiography, cf. Brillante (1990); also Ch. 7, n. 29, this volume. Trans. De Selincourt/Marincola (1996) 119. A l l sizeable English quotations of Herodotus are from this work, unless otherwise stated. See also Ch. 1, pp. 15 19, this volume. On the terminology cf. pp. 357-6.3 below. 12
13
356
PAUL CARTLEDGE A N D E M I L Y GREENWOOD
Furthermore,
Herodotus' personal
flourish
is t h e lesson w h i c h h e
d r a w s f r o m t h e i n c i d e n t : t h e Greeks refused to believe t h e T r o j a n s w h e n t h e y t r u t h f u l l y c l a i m e d t h a t t h e y d i d n o t have H e l e n (legousi ten alitheien), because o f t h e c o n t r i v a n c e o f a d i v i n e p o w e r
which
w a n t e d t o illustrate the harshness w i t h w h i c h t h e G o d s p u n i s h h u m a n transgressions ( 2 . 1 2 0 . 5 ) .
B y c o n c l u d i n g t h e episode i n this w a y ,
H e r o d o t u s a p p r o p r i a t e s o r a c u l a r a u t h o r i t y f o r himself: w i t h t h e w o r d s γ ν ώ μ η ν α π ο φ α ί ν ο μ α ι ('ί w i l l reveal t h e r a t i o n a l e ' ) he reveals to his audience t h e design b e h i n d d i v i n e r e v e l a t i o n . H e r e w e see H e r o d o t u s i n t h e act o f c o m p e t i n g w i t h t h e a l l u r e o f epic, w h i l e p a y i n g l i p service t o the standards o f r i g o r o u s i n q u i r y a n d , f o r g o o d m e a s u r e , v e n t u r i n g a religious i n s i g h t . 1 4 Herodotus
f r e q u e n t l y displays a ' c r é d u l i t é c r i t i q u e ' w h i c h has
seemed paradoxical to m a n y o f his m o d e r n readers. A helpful a p p r o a c h is t h a t suggested b y P a u l V e y n e , w h o has e x p l o r e d t h e attitudes o f l e a r n e d Greeks t o w a r d s t h e i r c u l t u r a l ' m y t h s ' : ' c r i t i c i z i n g m y t h s d i d n o t m e a n p r o v i n g t h a t t h e y w e r e false b u t r e d i s c o v e r i n g t h e i r t r u t h f u l basis' ((1988) 5 9 ) . F i c t i o n , t h a t i s , f u r n i s h e d endless m a t e r i a l f o r critical r e d a c t i o n . T h i s is o n l y one o f the m a n y strategies w h i c h enable H e r o d o t u s to c o m p e t e w i t h o t h e r sources o f c u l t u r a l a u t h o r i t y , 1 0 a n d to d o w n g r a d e t h e i n t e l l e c t u a l c r e d i b i l i t y o f those sources. As J a m e s R o m m has o b s e r v e d , a n c i e n t geographers f a c e d t h e challenge o f reco n c i l i n g t h e i r audience's expectations o f strangeness a n d n o v e l t y w i t h the c o m m i t m e n t t o r e p r e s e n t i n g r e a l peoples a n d places ((1992) 173). He
posits a n o p p o s i t i o n b e t w e e n t h e p o e t , f o r w h o m w o n d e r s are
an 'artistic r e s o u r c e ' , a n d t h e g e o g r a p h e r - c r i t i c f o r w h o m
they a r e
a n 'investigative obstacle'. H e r o d o t u s appears t o h a v e i t b o t h w a y s , j u x t a p o s i n g ' a r t i s t i c resources' a n d i n t i m a t i o n s o f c r i t i c a l distance f r o m these v e r y resources (cf. M o l e s (1993) 96). A c o m m o n s o l u t i o n , w h i c h w e e n c o u n t e r i n t h e Histories, was t o suspend b e l i e f a n d c l a i m (merely) t o ' r e p o r t w h a t was said'- -legein ta legomena (7.152.3; cf. 2 . 1 2 3 . 1 , 2 . 1 3 0 . 2 - 1 3 1 . 1 , 4 . 1 9 5 . 2 a n d 6.137.1). A t 7 . 1 5 2 . 3 H e r o d o t u s
actually
claims suspension o f b e l i e f as a feature o f t h e w o r k as a w h o l e . 1 5
14
Cf. Lateiner (1989) 63: 'The logic is unsatisfactory, but the polemical point and method are noteworthy: the truth about past events can be found by argument. Circumspection about knowledge of the past can lead to trustworthy results.' Cf. Finley (1975) 14: 'one kind of retelling of the past was being measured against another'. For an excellent inventory of the different gradations of Herodotus' knowledgeclaims about various phenomena, cf. Lateiner (1989) 69-72. Headings include 16
li
HERODOTUS AS A C R I T I C : T R U T H , F I C T I O N , P O L A R I T Y
357
I n t h e d i f f e r e n t societies d e p i c t e d i n t h e Histories, k n o w l e d g e a n d access to i n f o r m a t i o n are v i t a l c o m p o n e n t s i n t h e struggle f o r p o w e r . I n t h e early stages o f t h e n a r r a t i v e , Croesus expands his e m p i r e a n d is subsequendy
defeated b y C y r u s . T h i s q u i c k i n t e r c h a n g e o f p o w e r
is p u n c t u a t e d b y Croesus' e n c o u n t e r w i t h t h e G r e e k sage S o l o n , w h o refuses t o flatter t h e k i n g a n d speaks t h e t r u t h (to eonti khresamenos— 1.30.3). Croesus disdains Solon's insights, b u t is subsequently
com-
p e l l e d t o a d m i t t h e i r truthfulness w h e n he suffers a c o m p l e t e reversal o f f o r t u n e a n d p r o c l a i m s t h a t he w o u l d r e c o m m e n d t o a l l kings c o n v e r s a t i o n w i t h S o l o n i n preference t o vast a m o u n t s o f m o n e y (1.86,4). Solon's
insight into the changeability o f h u m a n
Herodotus'
fortunes
echoes
statement i n t h e p r o e m (1.5) to the Histories t h a t h u m a n
p r o s p e r i t y is fickle. B y a l i g n i n g his p o s i t i o n w i t h t h a t o f a r e n o w n e d sage a n d a c o n t e m p o r a r y source o f a u t h o r i t y , a n d b y b e g i n n i n g t h e Histories w i t h a sequence t h a t bears o u t his forecast, H e r o d o t u s asserts the v a l u e o f his w o r k over t r a d i t i o n a l , m o r e o b v i o u s f o r m s o f p o w e r . T h o s e i n p o w e r are c o n t i n u a l l y p o r t r a y e d as t r y i n g to secure r e l i able i n f o r m a t i o n f r o m oracles, a n d t h e o b s c u r i t y o f t h e i r dealings a n d t h e n a t u r e o f o r a c u l a r r e v e l a t i o n f u n c t i o n , as a c o u n t e r - e x a m p l e to t h e scrutable t r u t h s w h i c h H e r o d o t u s c l a i m s t o dispense. A t 6 . 8 0 , C l e o m e n e s protests t h a t t h e D e l p h i c oracle has m i s l e d h i m over the c a p t u r e o f A r g o s . W h e n s u m m o n e d b a c k t o S p a r t a he e x p l a i n e d his c o n f u s i o n over t h e oracle a n d his decision t o seek f u r t h e r c l a r i f i c a t i o n f r o m t h e gods ( 6 . 8 2 . 1 - 2 ) . A t this p o i n t H e r o d o t u s
interjects t h a t he
c a n n o t c o m m e n t o n t h e t r u t h o f C l e o m e n e s ' a c c o u n t t o t h e Spartans (oute ei pseudomenos oute ei alethea legon, 6 . 8 2 . 1 ) . C l e o m e n e s c l a i m e d t h a t he l e a r n t t h e c e r t a i n t y o f t h e m a t t e r (ten atrekeian) b y t h e fire signal w h i c h shot o u t o f t h e breast ( n o t the head) o f t h e c u l t statue o f H e r a (6.82.2). H e r e v o c a b u l a r y t h a t H e r o d o t u s
usually applies to his o w n
research is e m p l o y e d i n c o n n e c t i o n w i t h a n i n s c r u t a b l e scenario, as related by an acknowledged
madman.
W h i l e H e r o d o t u s refrains f r o m c o m m e n t i n g o n the v e r a c i t y o f t h e oracle r e c e i v e d b y C l e o m e n e s a n d t h e d e t a i l a b o u t H e r a ' s signal, he devotes m u c h a t t e n t i o n t o a n a l y s i n g t h e causes a n d s y m p t o m s Cleomenes'
of
madness, w h i c h he u l t i m a t e l y a t t r i b u t e s to d i v i n e r e t r i -
b u t i o n f o r the latter's injustice towards his c o - k i n g D e m a r a t u s Thus Herodotus
(6.84.3).
claims to be able t o i n f e r d i v i n e i n v o l v e m e n t i n
'Ignorance Universal', 'Certainty Impossible', 'Certainty Explicitly Achieved', and 'Responsibility Disclaimed'. See also Ch. 1, n. 40, this volume.
358
PAUL CARTLEDGE AND EMILY GREENWOOD
human events, but he achieves these inferences through a process of independent inquiry based on the realm of human knowledge. I n a carefully weighed statement i n Book Eight, Herodotus claims that he is unable to refute (antilegein) the truth o f oracles, i n light of a particularly explicit prediction from the oracle o f Bacis. Herodotus remarks that it is impossible to contradict an oracle that explicitly predicts what came to pass: 'enargeos legeiri (8.77.1). After quoting the oracle, Herodotus reaffirms that he himself will neither dare to make refutations (antilogias) o f oracles, nor accept them from others, given the clarity o f this oracle: once again he uses the phrase enargeos legeiri (8.77.2). However, the fact that Herodotus singles out this oracle for its clarity acknowledges implicitly that oracles are often obscure and hard to hold to account. By contrast, Herodotus' principles of accountability, which show to the reader the reasoning behind his conclusions, reflect the complexity o f the known world. There is scope for oracles i n the Histories, and indeed Herodotus is aware of their authority, but where their testimony is included, it is supplementary to the process o f research. Hence, after presenting a closely-argued discussion o f the geographical boundaries of Egypt, Herodotus remarks that the Egyptian oracle o f A m m o n supports his position: 17
An oracle delivered from the shrine of Ammon, which came to my notice after I had formed my own conclusions, is a witness for the opinion that I have expressed about the extent of Egypt. 18
Before this, Herodotus has considered the question of the geology of Egypt from several different angles, adducing (and rejecting) the theories espoused by the Greeks—and the Ionians i n particular(2.15-17). W h e n he concurs with a particular school of thought, he is at pains to emphasize that he has reached the same conclusion independently: So not only do I believe the people who gave me this account of Egypt, but my own conclusions strongly support what they said. 1 have observed for myself (idori) that Egypt at the Nile delta projects into the sea beyond the coast on either side and the shells which are visible •••..··..•'. .- "ii
I I P
lull . .
_' I _'. I
" On antilosiai in the works of Herodotus' (near-)contemporaries, cf. Thomas (2000) 250, 252-3, 264-7. 2.18.1-2. For the heavy accent placed on the first person as a way of highlighting a (polemical) assertion of proof, cf. Thomas (2000) 243. 18
HERODOTUS AS A CRITIC: TRUTH, FICTION, POLARITY
359
Herodotus' concern to appear representative and trustworthy in his review o f the debate invokes ideals o f judicial procedure, and the motif o f the judge who weighs up conflicting claims contributes to Herodotus' self-depiction as a reliable narrator. I n the section on Egyptian geography, he employs the verb marturein and the noun marturion (respectively 'to testify/bear witness' and 'proof/testimony') to underwrite the judicial metaphor. A t 2.18.1, the oracle from A m m o n 'martime? (testifies) to Herodotus' judgment, and at 2.22.2, the w a r m winds are the strongest proof [marturion) that the floods in the Nile basin are not caused by melting snow. We have seen how Herodotus insulates his field of inquiry from the domain o f oracles and the supernatural which are present in his account. A similar tension and potential problem for critical research arise i n the case o f seemingly incredible phenomena. The category of thomata, or things which are axiotheata (worthy to behold), permits the inclusion o f the sensational without compromising Herodotus' intellectual posture. O n the one hand, he retains the credibility o f the Odyssean narrator who offers his audience novel and astounding reports from the ends o f the earth, yet at the same time he is not implicated in the more dubious aspects o f these tales. A typical example o f the historian's negotiation of thomata is the account of Scyllias' desertion to the Greeks (from the Persian forces) which involved crossing from Aphetae, on the Pelion peninsula, to Artemisium on Euboea—a distance o f about ten miles (8.8). Herodotus reports the claim (legetai—it is said/reputed) that Scyllias made the crossing underwater, without coming up for air. The language of the passage is 19
20
21
22
19 Cf. JVlarincola (1997a) 164 on the strategy o f citing various versions o f events to suggest i m p a r t i a l i t y ; m o r e generally, see his c h . 3 f o r a discussion o f ' T h e Historian's Character', o f which ' I m p a r t i a l i t y ' is a sub-section. Cf. R o m m (1992) 183 4 o n the importance o f the character of the narrator for the believability o f the account i n H o m e r i c poetry. 20 O n marturion, cf. Thomas (2000) 184 and 191-2. T h o m a s argues that while rooted i n the lawcourts, this w o r d was part o f the language o f p r o o f i n ancient science. 41 For the m o t i f o f the historian as j u d g e i n Herodotus, Thucydides and Polybius, cf. Darbo-Peschanski (1998). For a historiographical survey o f this metaphor, cf. G i n z b u r g (1991). For the \h\utor as a possible model for Herodotus' status as judge i n such passages, cf. C o n n o r (1993) (for m o r e on the [h\istor, cf. also Floyd (1990)). Giraudeau (1984a) provides a discussion o f the j u r i d i c a l terminology employed i n the Histories. See also C h . 1, n. 30, this volume. 22 For a nuanced discussion o f Ihoma i n the Histories, cf. Hunzinger (1995), also Packman (1991) and Barth (1968).
360
PAUL CARTLEDGE AND EMILY GREENWOOD
informative for Herodotus' self-positioning in relation to the realm of the fantastic: As to the means by which he reached the Greeks from that position, I am unable to give a certain account (ouk ekho eipein atrekeos), but I would be amazed (thomazo de) if the reports (ta legomend) are true. I t is claimed that, after submerging himself into the sea at Aphetae, he did not emerge until he came to Artemisium, swimming about eighty stades through the sea to this place. About this man many other seeminglyfalse (pseudesi ikeldj tales are told and some true ones (alethed) as well. However, concerning this matter, note my opinion that he reached Artemisium by boat. Herodotus states that he cannot account for Scyllias' crossing to Artemisium with any authority, but distances himself from the fabulous report o f the crossing, labelling it a thoma (by employing the verb thomazo). The phrase 'pseudesi ifala\ whereby Herodotus dismisses the validity o f many o f the reports which have clustered around this man, evokes the already well-established debate in Greek literature on how to establish the veracity o f a narrative and echoes the passage at the beginning o f Hesiod's Theogony (27) where the muses claim that they can speak fictions ipseudea) which pass for truths (etumoisin omoici). Thus he scores veridical points by exposing the improbability o f accepted accounts. As Hunzinger notes, Texpression 8co(id^co e t . . ., quand i l s'agit d'un etonnement d'ordre intellectuel, suffit pour capter l'intelligence qui desire une explication.' 23
As with his handling of oracles, i n the case of thomata, Herodotus does not forgo the mythical dimension, which they can import into his narrative. Instead he circumscribes them with his own truth conditions. Herodotus points to his own 'good practice' by highlighting the gulf between the uncritical nature o f popular lore in comparison to his more critical approach to the past. One area o f the Histories which has been particularly slighted by some modern critics is that o f Herodotus' geographical researches. As R o m m observes, in Herodotus' narrative the distinction between what can be known atrekeos (unerringly) and that which cannot maps onto the boundary-line between regions o f the earth that have been seen or explored and those about which only wild rumours are told. 24
23
(1995) 62. Translation: 'The expression 9co|id^co et, when it relates to astonishment of an intellectual kind, is sufficient to intrigue the kind of intellect that desires an explanation.' Cf. the works by Fehling and Armayor cited in n. 6 above. 2 1
t
HERODOTUS AS A C R I T I C : T R U T H , F I C T I O N , P O L A R I T Y
361
W h e n t h e e x t e n t o f t h e lands w h i c h he is w r i t i n g a b o u t exceeds t h e e x t e n t o f his travels (or i n d e e d o f t h e travels o f a n y o n e w h o m he has m e t o r h e a r d o f ) , H e r o d o t u s o f t e n ventures t o say t h e unsayable. The
result is a ' m y t h i c a l ' o r ' f a n t a s t i c a l ' g e o g r a p h y w h i c h uses a l l
o f t h e resources available t o H e r o d o t u s '
c u l t u r e a n d surpasses t h e
h o r i z o n s o f this v e r y c u l t u r e i n a t t e m p t i n g t o represent t h e u n k n o w n . I n his a c c o u n t o f S c y t h i a n g e o g r a p h y (the area a r o u n d the B l a c k Sea), H e r o d o t u s
m e n t i o n s a n epic p o e m c a l l e d t h e The Tale of the
Arimaspians, w h i c h he a t t r i b u t e s t o Aristeas o f Proconnesus. T h i s reference t h e n occasions t h e story o f Aristeas' u n u s u a l life a n d w o r k s . O n c e a g a i n i t is i n s t r u c t i v e t o n o t e h o w H e r o d o t u s brackets o f f t h e d i f f e r e n t levels o f his n a r r a t i v e . F i r s t l y , Aristeas' a c c o u n t is design a t e d as p o e t r y (4.13.1) - a genre w i t h its o w n conventions (cf. 2 . 1 1 6 . 1 , p . 355 above). H e t h e n offers a story a b o u t Aristeas f r o m hearsay, a n d the sign-post Hegousf ('they say', 4.14.1) acts as a c r e d i b i l i t y shield. W i t h i n this t a l e - w i t h i n - a - t a l e , H e r o d o t u s i n t r o d u c e s some o f his o w n research, as i t w e r e . A f t e r Aristeas' alleged d i s a p p e a r a n c e , t h e M e t a p o n t i a n s c l a i m e d t h a t he a p p e a r e d t o t h e m i n M e t a p o n t u m (in S o u t h e r n I t a l y ) . H e r o d o t u s proceeds t o offer a c h r o n o l o g y f o r t h e events related by the Metapontians: As to what the cities themselves say, I know (oida) that these events occurred two hundred and forty years after the second disappearance o f Aristeas, as I discovered by inference (sumbaliomenos. . . heuriskon) i n Proconnesus and Metapontum. (4.15.1-2) A l t h o u g h strictly H e r o d o t u s
is m a k i n g a specific c l a i m o n l y
about
the t i m e at w h i c h these events h a p p e n e d , t h e verbs oida, sumbaliomenos a n d heuriskon l e n d c r e d i b i l i t y to t h e tale i n w h i c h t h e y are i m p l a n t e d . O n c e a g a i n , w e c a n observe H e r o d o t u s
'redeeming'
fictional
matter
f o r his h i s t o r i c a l purposes. S i m i l a r subtleties a r e i n p l a y i n t h e subsequent c h a p t e r , w h e r e H e r o d o t u s
admits that nobody knows w i t h
a n y c e r t a i n t y (oudeis olde atrekeds, 4.16.1) a b o u t w h a t lies b e y o n d t h e r e g i o n w h i c h he has b e e n discussing, b u t he t h e n reassures his a u d i ence t h a t he w i l l relate, t o t h e fullest e x t e n t , w h a t h e has been able to establish c e r t a i n l y (atrekeds) b y hearsay. Herodotus
o f i n c o n s i s t e n c y , b u t t o observe
This
is n o t t o accuse
the delicate balance
b e t w e e n w h a t is a n d is n o t k n o w n a n d t h e o n g o i n g process o f extracti n g the f o r m e r f r o m the latter. The
terms w h i c h Herodotus
uses t o signal t h e v e r a c i t y o f his
a c c o u n t reveal a b r o a d e r p r e o c c u p a t i o n t h a n t h a t w i t h m e r e a c c u r a c y o r fact. I n t h e above passage he t w i c e uses t h e a d v e r b atrekeds
362
PAUL
CARTLEDGE
AND
EMILY
GREENWOOD
( u n e r r i n g l y ) , to m a r k o u t reliable i n f o r m a t i o n f r o m vague r e p o r t . n o u n atrekeia (certainty) a n d the a d v e r b o c c u r Histories a n d a l i g n H e r o d o t u s ' poetry. 2 - 1 T h e
fifty-one
The
times i n the
discourse o f t r u t h w i t h t h a t o f a r c h a i c
etymology w h i c h Chantraine
((1968) 135) suggests f o r
the adjective atrekes emphasizes the idea o f ' b e i n g o n t r a c k ' , as opposed to m i s l e a d i n g i n f o r m a t i o n , w h i c h strays f r o m t h e p a t h o f t r u t h . Herodotus'
p r e d i l e c t i o n f o r atrekeia—and n o t e w o r t h y a v o i d a n c e
aletheia/alethes w h e n
s t a k i n g his o w n
claims to truth—suggest
i m a g e o f the 'logon hodos\ the r o u t e o f the logoi w h i c h
of the
Herodotus
traces i n the course o f his a c c o u n t (cf. 1 . 9 5 . 1 , 1.117.2, 2.20.1).
As
C a r o l y n D e w a l d has r e m a r k e d , the m e t a p h o r o f the r o a d c o n t r i b u t e s to the sense o f strain a n d e x e r t i o n b e h i n d H e r o d o t u s ' h i s t o r i o g r a p h i c a l p r o j e c t ((1987) 149,
165-6).
H e n c e the choice o f atrekeia/atrekeos evokes the p o t e n t i a l f o r l o s i n g one's w a y amidst the m a n y , heterogeneous, c o m p e t i n g claims to t r u t h a b o u t the past a n d a b o u t distant lands. A t tures a c o m m e n t
1.140, H e r o d o t u s
ven-
a b o u t Persian b u r i a l p r a c t i c e . I n contrast to the
p r e c e d i n g Persian i n s t i t u t i o n s a b o u t w h i c h he c o u l d speak w i t h cert a i n t y (atrekeos) t h r o u g h k n o w l e d g e
(eidos), H e r o d o t u s
concedes
that
r e p o r t s a b o u t t h e etiquette o f m a l e b u r i a l are obscure a n d as i f a secret (1.140.1). B y c o n t r a s t , he u n w a v e r i n g l y attributes (atrekeos oida) the b u r i a l p r a c t i c e i n q u e s t i o n to the M e d i a n priestly caste o f the Magi,
since t h e y practise i t o p e n l y (emphaneds). H e
t h e n concludes
this s e c t i o n — a b r i e f discussion o f P e r s i a n nornoi p r e f a c e d w i t h a c o n f i d e n t c l a i m t o k n o w l e d g e (oida)—by s i g n a l l i n g his r e t u r n to his p r e v i o u s a c c o u n t (aneimi de epi ton proteron logon, 1.140.3). T h e v e r b o f m o t i o n aneimi i m p l i e s t h a t , h a v i n g n e g o t i a t e d several details d o w n a n obscure b y w a y , he w i l l resume the m o r e s t r a i g h t f o r w a r d e x p o s i t i o n (the h i g h w a y , as i t were) o f his p r i m a r y n a r r a t i v e . I t is w o r t h recalling that, as w e l l as c o m i n g to terms w i t h H e r o d o t u s ' p a r t i c u l a r a p p r o a c h to c r i t i c a l , historical research, there are also p r a c tical considerations w h i c h s h o u l d be b r o u g h t t o b e a r o n the r e l i a b i l i t y debate. I n d e e d , the i n t e l l e c t u a l a n d the p r a c t i c a l considerations are i n t e r r e l a t e d . J o c e l y n S m a l l has given a c o n v i n c i n g a c c o u n t o f the t e c h n o l o g y available to historians i n the a n c i e n t G r e e k a n d R o m a n w o r l d s , s h o w i n g h o w the l i m i t a t i o n s o f the w r i t i n g materials w h i c h
25
For a recent suggestive study, see Crane (1996) 50-65: 'Herodotus' atrekeia versus Thucydidean akribeia: from knowledge to expertise'.
HERODOTUS AS A CRITIC: TRUTH, FICTION, POLARITY
363
they used and the written sources to which they had access influenced their cognitive approach to history-writing. Small suggests that the concept or standard o f 'accuracy as gist' is better suited to this technological environment than current notions o f historical accuracy ((1997) 192). Each generation of scholars will cast Herodotus in their own image. From the vantage point o f current criticism there are new directions to be taken. One way o f opening up the 'truth/fiction' debate is that developed by Pascal Payen (1997), who relates Herodotus' criteria for assessing true knowledge and insight to the ethnographical content o f the Histories. Payen has concluded that the peoples who dominate i n the power stakes are undermined by the powerless who outwit them by bringing counter-knowledge into play. This inversion reflects the position o f the historical narrator, whose innovative research sometimes cuts across or directly contradicts the received assumptions o f his Greek audience. I n one sense the Histories raise the question as to who has the prerogative over the truth: the present, the past, one's native culture or foreign lands?
Polarity 'History is as much about the obviously other as it is about the seemingly familiar' (R. Evans (1997) 214). One seemingly obvious mode of 'othering' is the intellectual device o f polarity or polarization. I n practice, though, this proves to be not quite as obvious as it may at first sight appear. For, on the one hand, 'other' is not, and should not be used merely as, a fashionable synonym for different; ' and, on the other hand, 'polarity' may be applied in rather different meanings. T o make absolutely clear where we stand from the start, polarity or polarization i n the rest o f this chapter will be understood, in its ideal construction or as an ideal type, as the both logical and rhetorical figure o f the binary opposition of same or self to its polar opposite, expressed in such a way that the two parts o f the 20
2
28
* Cartledge (1997a) uses othering in the form of polarity as an exploratory framework for investigating Greek conceptions of self-identity; cf. Darbo-Peschanski (1985). For an application of (mere) difference in late classical and Hellenistic Greek philosophy, see Follinger (1996). Compare and contrast, e.g., Gimelli-Martin (1990) and Taussig (1993). 27
28
364
PAUL CARTLEDGE AND E M I L Y GREENWOOD
o p p o s i t i o n are b o t h a n t i t h e t i c a l a n d m u t u a l l y exclusive a n d j o i n t l y exhaustive
of t h e c a t e g o r y t h e y t o g e t h e r represent o r
designate.29
T h u s , to take t h e m o s t r e l e v a n t e x a m p l e o f a l l f o r the purposes of this c h a p t e r : Greeks vs B a r b a r i a n s constitutes a p o l a r i t y i n o u r sense, i n t h a t t h e t w o g r o u p s b o t h are m u t u a l l y exclusive a n d a n t i t h e t i c a l (a B a r b a r i a n is precisely a n o t - G r e e k
a n d vice versa) a n d are j o i n t l y
exhaustive (of the b r o a d e r c a t e g o r y H u m a n Beings). 3 0 H o w e v e r , there was i n a n c i e n t G r e e c e , as there is t o d a y , a r h e t o r i c as w e l l as a strict l o g i c o f p o l a r i t y o r p o l a r i z a t i o n , w h e r e b y
(mere)
differences t h a t are n o t l o g i c a l l y p o l a r o r b i n a r y are e m p l o y e d as if t h e y are, i n o r d e r precisely to c o n s t r u c t , t h a t is i n v e n t i d e o l o g i c a l l y , a supposedly b i n a r y o p p o s i t i o n , o r , m o r e p o l e m i c a l l y , p o l a r a n t a g o n i s m . A n e x a m p l e w o u l d be ' M e n a n d W o m e n ' , since a l t h o u g h there are i r r e d u c i b l e , a n a t o m i c a l differences b e t w e e n m e n
and
women,
o b j e c t i v e l y speaking, yet a h u m a n b e i n g c a n be m o r e o r less m a l e o r f e m a l e , i n d e e d at t h e l i m i t s u f f i c i e n t l y b o t h m a l e and f e m a l e to j u s t i f y o r r e q u i r e t h e use o f a t h i r d classificatory t e r m ( h e r m a p h r o dite).31
Conversely,
w h e n i t suits the p o l i t i c a l o r o t h e r p u r p o s e
or
subtext o f a w r i t e r , w h e t h e r a n c i e n t o r m o d e r n , a — l o g i c a l — p o l a r i t y such as ' G r e e k vs B a r b a r i a n ' m a y be o p p o r t u n i s t i c a l l y m o d u l a t e d o r m o d e r a t e d , i n such a w a y t h a t the n o t i o n o f degrees o f e i t h e r Greekness o r B a r b a r i a n n e s s c a n be b r o u g h t strategically i n t o p l a y . 3 2 T h e s e t w o are j u s t the m o s t o b v i o u s l y f u n d a m e n t a l p o l a r i t i e s t h a t Herodotus
c o u l d have dealt w i t h ; others i n c l u d e d C i t i z e n vs
C i t i z e n , Free vs U n f r e e ,
Non-
G o d s vs M o r t a l s , O l d vs Y o u n g , R i c h vs
P o o r , etc. H o w t h e n does the device o f p o l a r i z a t i o n fit i n t o his l a r g e r scheme o f p e r s u a d i n g the reader to give credence to his a c c o u n t o f the logoi relevant to e x p l a i n i n g relations between Greeks a n d Barbarians, a n d especially w h y t h e y c a m e to fight each other? W h a t are ' w e ' — t h a t is H e r o d o t u s ' s
readers, w h e n e v e r
and wherever
and
however
these i d e a l readers are taken to be s i t u a t e d — t o m a k e o f i t all? F r o m considerations o f space, w e shall restrict ourselves here t o j u s t a s m a l l
29
Lloyd (1966) pt I is an exemplary discussion from a philosophical standpoint. Cartledge (1997a) ch. 3 (with further reading cited pp. 188-90). Cartledge (1997a) ch. 4 (with further reading cited pp. 190-2). For various ways of 'inventing' the Barbarian in classical Greece, see, besides op. cit. (n. 30), Laurot (1981); Georges (1994); Hartog (1988); Hall (1989); Miller (1995). flartog (1988), for instance, brilliantly shows how Herodotus' Persians become less 'Barbarian', i.e., more Greek, as they come into conflict with Herodotus' Scythians. 30
31
32
HERODOTUS AS A C R I T I C : T R U T H , F I C T I O N , P O L A R I T Y
365
selection o f examples o f some o f these o p p o s i t i o n s i n o r d e r to illustrate the p o t e n t i a l range o f i n t e l l e c t u a l d e p l o y m e n t o f p o l a r i t y as a s t r u c t u r i n g o r i n t e r p r e t a t i v e device i n H e r o d o t u s '
historiography.
Greeks versus Barbarians I t is w i t h a n e x a m p l e o f p o l a r i z a t i o n at its p u r e s t t h a t w e m a y usefully begin. Book T w o ,
the E g y p t i a n book,
m e t h o d o l o g i c a l . I n i t , t h a t is, H e r o d o t u s
is i n i m p o r t a n t p a r t
stakes his c l a i m v i g o r o u s l y
to b e i n g a n u p - t o - t h e - m i n u t e c r i t i c a l t h i n k e r , i n a n u m b e r o f d i f f e r e n t ways.33 T h e
reason he gives f o r s p e n d i n g so l o n g o n E g y p t a n d the
E g y p t i a n s , h o w e v e r , is r a t h e r d i f f e r e n t : h e r e , he says, he f o u n d m o r e ' w o n d r o u s t h i n g s ' (thomasid) a n d m o r e n a r r a t i o n - w o r t h y (ergd) t h a n a n y w h e r e
monuments
else (2.35.1). S p e c i f i c a l l y , he goes o n i m m e d i -
ately t o list i n a tour de force o f s u m m a t i v e c o m p a r i s o n the n o fewer t h a n eighteen ways i n w h i c h the customs a n d practices o f the Egyptians (ethea, nomoi; cf. Aiguptia ethea, 2 . 3 0 . 5 ) e x a c t l y reverse o r i n v e r t those o f the rest o f m a n k i n d (by w h i c h he r e a l l y means the Greeks). T h e s e specific inversions are all set w i t h i n a c o n c e p t u a l a n d g e o g r a p h i c a l f r a m e t h a t is precisely one o f p o l a r o p p o s i t i o n :
In keeping with the idiosyncratic climate which prevails there and the fact that their river [the Nile] behaves differently from any other river, almost all Egyptian customs and practices are the opposite of those of everywhere else. 34
As Francois
H a r t o g has r e m a r k e d i n a n o t h e r c o n t e x t , ' t h e interest-
i n g t h i n g is t h a t this space, w h i c h p u r p o r t s to be s i m p l y " s p a c e " , is i n r e a l i t y a G r e e k space o f s h a r e d
knowledge'.33
N e x t , consider h o w i n the first B o o k H e r o d o t u s
chooses to m o d -
ulate, r a t h e r t h a n s t r a i g h t f o r w a r d l y (re)present, the G r e e k vs B a r b a r i a n p o l a r i t y w i t h r e g a r d to the Persians. F o r H e r o d o t u s first asserts, w i t h apparently privileged certainty, that the core components Persian
e d u c a t i o n a l system are h o r s e m a n s h i p ,
archery and
t e l l i n g (alethizesthai); t h e n , w i t h i n t w e n t y chapters o f the same
o f the truthbook,
he represents the m o s t e m i n e n t Persian i m a g i n a b l e , C y r u s the G r e a t ,
33
34
35
A. B. Lloyd (1975); Thomas (1997): Vannicelli (2001). 2.35.2. Tr. Waterfield (1998). Hartog (1988) 350; cf. Jacob (1991); Payen (1997).
366
PAUL CARTLEDGE AND EMILY GREENWOOD
founder of die Achaemenid r a t h e r , as H e r o d o t u s
Persian
e m p i r e , as c h a r a c t e r i z i n g — o r
is at pains to e x p l a i n , d e n i g r a t i n g — a l l Greeks
as liars a n d cheats (the specific r e f e r e n c e is t o t h e i r ' n a t i o n a l ' p r a c t i c e o f b u y i n g a n d selling i n a n agora).
36
supposedly Here, there-
f o r e , w e are p r e s e n t e d w i t h o t h e r i n g i n t h e f o r m o f negative p o l a r i z a t i o n o r s t e r e o t y p i n g o n a g r a n d scale
but f r o m a Barbarian not
a G r e e k p o i n t o f v i e w , a n d n o t t h e r e f o r e , ostensibly, f r o m t h e v i e w point o f the author. Consider
f u r t h e r a f a m o u s instance i n w h i c h H e r o d o t u s
at
first
c o m p l i c a t e s t h e process o f e t h n i c c o m p a r i s o n a n d contrast y e t m o r e . At
3 . 3 8 he has a n o t h e r Persian k i n g , D a r i u s ,
institute at his c o u r t
i n Susa a sort o f m o r a l contest b e t w e e n (some) Greeks a n d a p a r t i c u l a r g r o u p o f B a r b a r i a n s , i n o r d e r a p p a r e n t l y t o set h i m s e l f u p i n j u d g m e n t over t h e m b o t h . T h e issue, o r r a t h e r t h e nomos, at stake is t h a t o f t h e t w o peoples' respective f u n e r a r y customs, surely the m o s t sensitive m a r k e r o f e t h n i c i d e n t i t y . T h u s , so H e r o d o t u s '
story
goes, D a r i u s is supposed once u p o n a t i m e t o have s u m m o n e d
some
Greeks a n d some C a l l a t i a n I n d i a n s to his presence a n d asked each o f t h e m respectively h o w m u c h m o n e y
( i n bribes) i t w o u l d r e q u i r e
to persuade t h e m t o d o t h e opposite o f w h a t they n o r m a l l y a n d n o r m a t i v e l y d i d t o t h e i r k i n d r e d d e a d — t h a t i s , t o eat t h e m i n t h e case o f t h e (allegedly) c r e m a t i n g Greeks o r t o c r e m a t e t h e m i n t h e case o f the (allegedly) c a n n i b a l i s t i c C a l l a t i a n s . Perhaps H e r o d o t u s was also u s i n g the scenario to illustrate t h e m e r c e n a r y q u a l i t y o f Darius's g e n eral o u t l o o k a n d a t d t u d e (cf. 3 . 8 9 — t h e
Persian
equivalent o f the
G r e e k f o r ' r e t a i l m e r c h a n t ' , kapelos, was allegedly t h e Persians' o w n tag for Darius;
cf. K u r k e
(1995) 5 4 - 5 ) ; b u t t h a t was n o t w h a t he
c l a i m e d , b y w a y o f i n t r o d u c t i o n , t o be his main p o i n t . T h i s was r a t h e r to illustrate a g e n e r a l i z a t i o n t h a t he states t o be a p p l i c a b l e t o a l l h u m a n societies, G r e e k a n d B a r b a r i a n , h o w e v e r ' c i v i l i z e d ' (by G r e e k standards)
or otherwise:
namely,
the quasi-law that 'each
group
regards its o w n nomoi as b y f a r the best', t h a t i s , the best absolutely speaking. I n the s t o r y , b o t h t h e Greeks a n d t h e Callatians
indig-
n a n t l y reject t h e v e r y suggestion t h a t t h e y m i g h t a b a n d o n , l e t alone reverse, t h e i r c u s t o m a r y n o r m s . H e r o d o t u s , h o w e v e r , is so i m p a t i e n t t o get t o t h e m o r a l o f t h e story t h a t he does n o t a l l o w his D a r i u s to express
a view o n their rejection b u t proceeds
1.136.2, 1.153.2; cf. Cartledge (1997a) 6 0 - 2 .
directly to a n
367
HERODOTUS AS A C R I T I C : T R U T H , F I C T I O N , P O L A R I T Y
expression o f his o w n v i e w , o r r a t h e r a r e p e t i t i o n o f his i n t r o d u c t o r y p o i n t a b o u t the r e l a t i v i t y (as he saw i t , f r o m the o u t s i d e , i n an observer's n o t a n actor's view) o f c u s t o m : 'So these practices have b e c o m e e n s h r i n e d as customs j u s t as t h e y are, a n d I think P i n d a r was r i g h t to have said i n his p o e m t h a t " c u s t o m is k i n g o f a l l ' " (our emphasis). 3 '
Men versus Women T h a t c o m m e n t , as H e r o d o t u s h i m s e l f said o f another r e m a r k
(7.152.3),
c o u l d be t a k e n to a p p l y to the w o r k as a w h o l e . W e shall t u r n n e x t to M e n vs W o m e n , w h i c h , to r e p e a t , is a n i d e o l o g i c a l l y c o n s t r u c t e d r a t h e r t h a n a n a t u r a l l y g i v e n p o l a r i t y . H e r o d o t u s ' t e x t , as a F r e n c h ' s t r u c t u r a l i s t r e a d i n g ' has so b r i l l i a n t l y d e m o n s t r a t e d , explores
the
p o l a r i t y i n a n u m b e r o f ways, m o s t c o n s p i c u o u s l y t h r o u g h his i t e m izing o f the customary
'uses o f w o m e n '
b y d i f f e r e n t cultures a n d
societies, G r e e k a n d n o n - G r e e k . 3 8 H e n c e i t emerges t h a t t h e i d e a l p o l a r i t y M e n vs W o m e n
is s o m e t h i n g o f a gross s i m p l i f i c a t i o n : l o r
here w e find n o t just M e n vs W o m e n b u t also G r e e k M e n vs G r e e k Women,
Greek M e n
Barbarian W o m e n ,
vs B a r b a r i a n
Women,
Barbarian
Free G r e e k M e n vs U n f r e e B a r b a r i a n
Men
vs
Women,
a n d so o n . Nevertheless, at one e n d o f H e r o d o t u s ' s p e c t r u m , serving to struct u r e t h e m a n y d i f f e r e n t i n d i v i d u a l a c c o u n t s , is the n o r m a t i v e G r e e k society p r a c t i s i n g m o n o g a m o u s m a r r i a g e , w h i l e at the o t h e r (and also ' o t h e r ' ) e n d is t h e m o s t b a r b a r o u s a n d b a r b a r i c o f b a r b a r i a n societies, t h a t o f the A n d r o p h a g o i any conception of R i g h t
('Cannibals')
w h o do not
(dike, 4 . 1 0 6 ; cf. G i r a u d e a u
recognize
(1984a)).
The
G r e e k w a y w i t h w o m e n , one m i g h t reasonably w a n t to i n f e r , is t h e r e fore i n H e r o d o t u s ' eyes g o o d n o t o n l y f o r G r e e k s , a c c o r d i n g to t h e i r p u r e l y subjective j u d g m e n t based p e r h a p s o n n o t h i n g better t h a n u n r e f l e c t i v e t r a d i t i o n , b u t g o o d a b s o l u t e l y — o r at a n y rate s u p e r i o r to a n y B a r b a r i a n w a y . Y e t i t is a m a r k o f H e r o d o t u s '
ethnographic
f l e x i b i l i t y a n d i n t e l l e c t u a l subtlety t h a t even t h e G r e e k n o r m is capable o f d e c o n s t r u c t i o n b y h i m , b o t h n e g a t i v e l y a n d positively.
37
Cartledge (1997a) 69 70 (with further reading cited p. 189). Rossellini and Said (1978); further reading cited in Cartledge (1997a) 191. Setalso Ch. 10, this volume. 38
368
PAUL CARTLEDGE AND EMILY GREENWOOD
Positively, i n a c o m p l e x dialectic i n v o l v i n g relations between X e r x e s and
his v a r i o u s s u b - c o m m a n d e r s
Herodotus
G r e e k as w e l l as
non-Greek,
is p r e p a r e d to v i o l a t e G r e e k n o r m s o f evaluative
termi-
n o l o g y b y a p p l y i n g o x y m o r o n i c a l l y to a w o m a n — a d m i t t e d l y ,
the
G r e e k q u e e n o f his o w n native Halicarnassus, A r t e m i s i a — t h e descriptive-cum-evaluative 'manliness' (7.99.1).
t e r m for bravery, 39
On
andreia, t h a t l i t e r a l l y
meant
the negative side, he presents his (Greek)
addressee w i t h Greeks w h o behave o n occasion i n a suspiciously ' u n G r e e k ' m a n n e r (the C o r i n t h i a n t y r a n t P e r i a n d e r c o p u l a t i n g w i t h t h e corpse o f his w i d o w is a n i n every sense spectacular i l l u s t r a t i o n , 5.92n.2-3),
a n d even w i t h a w h o l e G r e e k society, n a m e l y
Sparta,
w h e r e the n o r m seems at t h e least u n s t a b l y established, at a n y rate among
t h e r o y a l f a m i l i e s : here w e f i n d a k i n g p r a c t i s i n g b i g a m y
(5.40.2), another wife-swapping (6.61-62),
a n o t h e r (royal) m a r r i a g e
h a p p e n i n g b y c a p t u r e ( 6 . 6 5 . 2 ) , a q u e e n r e l a t i n g to h e r son a f a n c y tale (in the guise o f a ' t r u e story') o f e x t r a - m a r i t a l c o p u l a t i o n w i t h a h e r o i c a p p a r i t i o n (6.69), a slave p l a y i n g a key r o l e i n d e t e r m i n i n g seniority i n t h e r o y a l succession b y o b s e r v i n g t h e n u r s i n g b e h a v i o u r o f a m o t h e r o f r o y a l t w i n s (6.52.5—6), a n d so o n . 4 0 Nevertheless, i n the c o n t e x t o f the M e n vs W o m e n p o l a r i t y w h a t is surely c r u c i a l f o r t h e i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f H e r o d o t u s ' o v e r a l l a u t h o r i a l i n t e n t i o n is t h a t he (almost) begins a n d ends his w o r k as a w h o l e w i t h e x e m p l a r y tales o f B a r b a r i a n M e n vs B a r b a r i a n W o m e n .
This,
he i m p l i e s , is w h a t B a r b a r i a n s c a n a n d , t y p i c a l l y , d o practise amongst themselves: a C a n d a u l e s
o f L y d i a c a n b r e a c h the etiquette o f m a r -
i t a l p r i v a c y a n d f e m i n i n e modesty to the extent o f r e v e a l i n g his q u e e n i n a l l h e r nakedness i n h e r b e d c h a m b e r to his
right-hand
m a n , the
c a p t a i n o f his g u a r d ( 1 . 8 - 1 2 ) ; a X e r x e s o f Persia c a n so abuse the absolute p o w e r o f f a m i l i a l disposal vested i n a n o r i e n t a l despot b y the h a r e m system t h a t he c a n seek to v i o l a t e b o t h the w i f e o f a b r o t h e r a n d a d a u g h t e r - i n - l a w a n d c a n t h e r e b y d r i v e his o w n p r i n cipal w i f e to extremes o f ' o r i e n t a l ' m u t i l a t i o n ( 9 . 1 0 8 - 1 3 ) . 4 1 Correlatively,
39
Cartledge (1997a) 82-4 (with further reading cited p. 191). '"' For insight into the inverted representation of Spartan sexual mores (by no means only by Herodotus), we are indebted to Ellen Greenstein Millender, the reworked book of whose 1997 University of Pennsylvania Ph.D. thesis, 'The Teacher of Hellas—Athenian Democratic Ideology and the 'Barbarization' of Sparta in fifthcentury Greek Thought', is forthcoming. Meanwhile, see briefly Cartledge (1997a) 80-2. " Cartledge (1997a) 84-5 (with further reading cited p. 192); see also Ch. 9, pp. 206-8, this volume.
369
HERODOTUS AS A CRITIC! TRUTH, FICTION, POLARITY
i t is i m p l i e d , these are the sorts o f a b o m i n a t i o n s t h a t Greeks m u s t at a l l costs a v o i d .
Gods versus Mortals However, important to Herodotus
t h o u g h t h e G r e e k vs B a r b a r i a n
a n d M e n vs W o m e n p o l a r i t i e s u n d o u b t e d l y w e r e , a r g u a b l y t h e m o s t i m p o r t a n t o i all-—as i t was t o , say, his c o n t e m p o r a r y his f r i e n d ) S o p h o c l e s — w a s
( a n d possibly
t h a t o f G o d s vs M o r t a l s . 4 2 T h e p o l a r i z e d
religious f r a m e o f t h e w o r k as a w h o l e is set early o n : ' t h e d i v i n e (to theion) is e n t i r e l y jealous [ o f m o r t a l s ' p r o s p e r i t y ] a n d a source o f c o n f u s i o n ' , says wise G r e e k adviser S o l o n t o o r i e n t a l despot Croesus (1.32.1), whereas
' m a n ' (in the generic
sense,
anthropos) is c o r r e -
s p o n d i n g l y ' e n t i r e l y a m a t t e r o f f o r t u n e ' ( 1 . 3 2 . 4 , u s i n g sumphora, a w o r d w h i c h c o u l d also r e g u l a r l y m e a n disaster, i . e . , m i s - f o r t u n e , b u t n o t g o o d f o r t u n e ) . ' C a l l n o m a n t r u l y blessed, b u t o n l y f o r t u n a t e , before he (or she) is d e a d ' , S o l o n c o n t i n u e s , ' . . . l o o k t o t h e e n d o f e v e r y t h i n g t o see h o w i t t u r n s o u t : f o r m a n y are t h e y w h o m t h e gods have d e p r i v e d o f p r o s p e r i t y a n d d e s t r o y e d r o o t a n d b r a n c h ' ( 1 . 3 2 . 7 , 9 ) . Croesus' o w n c o n f u s i o n , i n m i s i n t e r p r e t i n g t h e w o r d s o f Apollo's
Delphic
o r a c l e , is p r o v e d t o be as c o m p r e h e n s i v e l y
disas-
t r o u s as c o u l d b e , a n d his e n d was v e r y f a r f r o m w h a t he h a d p r e d i c t e d f o r h i m s e l f . As f o r G r e a t K i n g
X e r x e s , t h e history's homme
fatal (cf. 8 . 1 0 9 . 3 , i n a speech p l a c e d i n t h e m o u t h o f ' T h e m i s t o c l e s ' , w h o echoes t h e j u d g m e n t o f ' S o l o n ' at 1.32.1), he m a d e t h e c a r d i nal error o f t h i n k i n g himself not only the equal b u t the superior o f a g o d (the H e l l e s p o n t : 7.54.3). Contrast
7.35; note H e r o d o t u s '
the Greek Spartans,
o w n pious
comment,
w h o — l i k e a l l (good)
Greeks,
o n l y m o r e so—sagely 'rate t h e t h i n g s o f t h e gods as m o r e estimable t h a n t h e t h i n g s o f m o r t a l m e n ' ( 5 . 6 3 . 2 ; cf. 9.7.1). Y e t i t is n o t always w h a t H e r o d o t u s chose t o say b u t r a t h e r w h a t he chose not to say t h a t c a n be r e v e a l i n g o f his deeper F o r a p p a r e n t l y n o t a l l Spartans doctrine
to the letter. B o t h
always o b e y e d
at h o m e
Spartan regent w h o h a d c o m m a n d e d
a n d abroad at Plataea,
purposes.
their o w n religious Pausanias, the
was j u d g e d g u i l t y
o f o v e r s t e p p i n g t h e m a r k i n a r r o g a t i n g t o h i m s e l f sole c r e d i t f o r t h a t
4 2
Cartledge (1997a) ch. 7, esp. pp. 159-62 (with further reading cited p. 196); cf. more generally, on Greek attitudes to foreign religions, Rudhardt (1992).
370
PAUL CARTLEDGE A N D EMILY
GREENWOOD
v i c t o r y a n d i n a d v e r t i s i n g h i m s e l f as 'first leader' (arkhegos) n o t o n l y of t h e Spartans b u t o f a l l t h e Greeks ( M L p . 60). Y e t y o u w i l l n o t find a m e n t i o n o f t h a t p e r s o n a l , q u a s i - t y r a n n i c a l excess i n H e r o d o t u s , w h o is g e n e r a l l y s y m p a t h e t i c t o Pausanias
a n d made i n his favour
a n e x c e p t i o n t o his stated r u l e o f ' t e l l i n g t h a t w h i c h is said' (7.152.3). T h e story is t o be f o u n d r a t h e r i n T h u c y d i d e s (1.132.2), w h o in a n i n v e r s i o n o f a d i s t i n c t l y H e r o d o t e a n m a n n e r presents Pausanias as a p a r a d i g m , b u t a largely negative o n e . I n line w i t h T h u c y d i d e s '
brief
a c c o u n t , t h e praise-poet S i m o n i d e s h a d w a r n e d Pausanias t o r e m e m b e r t h a t h e was m e r e l y a m o r t a l , a w a r n i n g a l l t h e m o r e r e v e a l i n g in that Simonides
h a d earlier been prepared to h y m n
'[great
C l e o j m b r o t u s ' m o s t n o b l e [ s o n ] ' a l o n g w i t h t h e rest o f t h e S p a r t a n heroes o f Plataea i n p r o t o - H e r o d o t e a n
Homeric
terms.43
H e r o d o t u s ' l a p s i n g i n t o silence h e r e — n o t t o be confused w i t h t h e religious silence t h a t h e e x p l i c i t i y p r a c t i s e d elsewhere (e.g., 1.51.4)— w o u l d seem t o b e t r a y a larger, p r o p e r l y p o l i t i c a l a g e n d a . " F o r h a d he i n c l u d e d t h a t c r i t i c i s m o f t h e S p a r t a n regent, at such a c l i m a c tic m o m e n t , his w o r k ' s t w o f o l d message- -to a l l Greeks to live u p to the highest H e l l e n i c ideals, a n d to t h e m u t u a l l y antagonistic A t h e n i a n s a n d Spartans specifically t o place H e l l e n i c homonoia above selfish c i t y state p r i d e a n d p a r t i c u l a r i s m — w o u l d have been s i g n i f i c a n t l y m u t e d (Cartledge
(1990)).
T h a t message was a k i n d of ' t r u t h ' w h i c h - - t o
b o r r o w t h e t e r m s o f his o w n ' c u s t o m is k i n g ' anecdote-
he c o u l d
n o t have been p e r s u a d e d t o f o r g o at a n y p r i c e .
Envoi I t is p e r h a p s
c o n t e s t a b l e w h e t h e r p o l a r i t y i n o u r sense was i n -
d e e d a master t r o p e o f ' G r e e k ' t h o u g h t , a n d c e r t a i n l y i t is c r u c i a l t h a t w e n o t o n l y s h o u l d be constantly o n t h e l o o k o u t f o r exceptions o r m a r g i n a l cases, b u t also s h o u l d n o t a p p l y a n y c r u d e version o f i t to t h e t h o u g h t o f a w r i t e r as s u b t l e a n d p o s s i b l y subversive as H e r o d o t u s . O n the other h a n d , i n the hands o f a w r i t e r like H e r o d o t u s p o l a r i z a t i o n c o u l d be another f o r m i d a b l e w e a p o n armoury,
43
i n the critical
t o be w i e l d e d against o u t - o f - l i n e , off-message Greeks n o
Warning: Simonides ap. Aelian, VH 9.41, with Huxley (1978) 245. Plataea elegy: Simonides el. 11, trs. M . West, Greek lyric Poetry (Oxford, 1994) 169. The case for a political Herodotus is interestingly made anew in Thompson (1996); see already Hartog (1988) passim. 44
HERODOTUS AS A C R I T I C : T R U T H , F I C T I O N , P O L A R I T Y
less t h a n c o n g e n i t a l l y disabled B a r b a r i a n s ;
i n favour
371
of exception-
ally e n d o w e d G r e e k w o m e n as w e l l as against stereotypically a d v a n taged G r e e k m e n ; a n d always o n the side o f the Gods (capital G) against m e r e
m o r t a l s (lower-case
readers c o u l d r e l y .
m). O n
t h a t , his h e a r e r s
and
CHAPTER HERODOTUS AND
HIS SOURCES OF Simon
The
SIXTEEN INFORMATION
Hornblower
study o f sources, f o r w h i c h t h e w o r d Quellenforschung has estab-
l i s h e d i t s e l f i n languages
o t h e r t h a n its n a t i v e
G e r m a n , is n o t a
fashionable a c t i v i t y a t t h e b e g i n n i n g o f the t w e n t y - f i r s t c e n t u r y A D . Quellenforschung was r i g o r o u s , a t times excessively so, i n t h a t i t t e n d e d to assume c o m p l e t e r a t i o n a l i t y a n d a m o d e r n scientific a t t i t u d e (preference f o r t h e earlier a n d 'better' o v e r t h e l a t e r a n d m o r e
deriva-
tive source, a n d so f o r t h ) o n t h e p a r t o f the a n c i e n t authors i t s t u d i e d . I t assumed,
i n fact, that ancient authors w i t h their u n w i e l d y a n d
a r b i t r a r y collections o f p a p y r u s rolls o p e r a t e d like m o d e r n
scholars
in their libraries, w h o read a n d write i n rooms furnished floor-toc e i l i n g w i t h shelves w h i c h c o n t a i n g o o d a n d i n s t a n t l y accessible texts, a n d w h o are a r m e d w i t h a u t h o r - s p e c i f i c l e x i c a a n d (nowadays) w i t h e l e c t r o n i c data-bases w h i c h enable t h e m t o chase l i n g u i s t i c parallels i n a f e w seconds o f t i m e (see H o r n b l o w e r
(1994a) 71 f ) . T h e present
c h a p t e r is a n a t t e m p t at t h e looser r a t h e r t h a n t h e stricter enterprise; i t is c o n c e r n e d w i t h w h a t is n o w k n o w n as ' i n t e r t e x t u a l i t y ' r a t h e r t h a n Quellenforschung. i n fact, w i t h H e r o d o t u s '
r e l a t i o n s h i p t o his l i t -
e r a r y sources (the r e l a t i o n s h i p o f his t e x t t o o t h e r texts) a n d t o his o r a l sources (one aspect o f the r e l a t i o n s h i p o f his text t o t h e w o r l d ) . How
d i d he h a n d l e his sources? H o w d i d he a c q u i r e a n d select
his m a t e r i a l ? W h y d i d he sometimes o f f e r c r i t i c a l j u d g m e n t s o n his sources b u t a t o t h e r times refuse t o d o so? W h a t c r i t e r i a d i d he apply i n m a k i n g critical j u d g m e n t s , a n d t o w h a t extent was he prep a r e d t o e x t r a p o l a t e a n d generalize o n t h e basis o f his sources? These are some o f t h e topics I address i n t h e present chapter. S o m e are o f course very h a r d t o answer except b y t h e historical novelist: n o b o d y after 2,500 years c a n easily say why H e r o d o t u s f o l l o w e d a p a r t i c u l a r course o f a c t i o n o n some occasions b u t d e c l i n e d t o f o l l o w i t o n others. A t m o s t w e c a n t r y , a t t h e level o f d e t a i l , t o i d e n t i f y p a t terns o f choice a n d suggest h o w those p a t t e r n s m i g h t be c o m p a t i b l e w i t h b r o a d e r l i t e r a r y strategies (the p a t t e r n i n t h e c a r p e t , as H e n r y
374
SIMON H O R N B L O W E R
J a m e s called i t ) . T h e r e is n o g u a r a n t e e t h a t the h i s t o r i c a l H e r o d o t u s w o u l d accept o u r i n t e r p r e t a t i o n even i f i t c o u l d be e x p l a i n e d t o h i m . T h e present c h a p t e r does n o t accept the results o f Fehling's a t t e m p t (by n o means the first b u t the m o s t i n g e n i o u s a n d
thorough-going
so far) to show t h a t H e r o d o t u s ' source-citations are i m a g i n a r y . 1 S o m e o f Fehling's views w i l l be discussed b e l o w . The
n o t i o n o f 'sources' is easy f o r us to grasp a n d to s u b d i v i d e :
o r a l sources a n d w r i t t e n sources, i n d i v i d u a l o r a l i n f o r m a n t s generic o r a l c i t a t i o n s ; d o c u m e n t a r y a n d n o n - d o c u m e n t a r y
and
(poetical,
h i s t o r i c a l , etc.) w r i t t e n sources. T h e s e ideas a n d categories are ours; t h e r e is n o single a n d s i m p l e G r e e k w o r d even f o r 'source'. T h i s is one d i f f i c u l t y . W e
w o u l d w a n t to say t h a t H e r o d o t u s
uses all the
types o f source I have j u s t m e n t i o n e d , a l t h o u g h his specific c i t a t i o n s o f i n d i v i d u a l n a m e d G r e e k i n f o r m a n t s are j u s t t w o i n n u m b e r : A r c h i a s o f S p a r t a at 3.55 a n d T h e r s a n d e r o f (Boeotian) O r c h o m e n u s at 9 . 1 6 . 2 He
also cites s i m u l t a n e o u s l y three n a m e d priestesses at D o d o n a at
2.55.3 (Promeneia,
Timarete, Nicandra),
a r a t h e r special case;
and
he cites one n o n - G r e e k , T y m n e s agent o f Ariapeithes (4.76.6). Precisely the r a r i t y o f such i n d i v i d u a l a t t r i b u t i o n s shows t h a t he d i d n o t r e g a r d a c i r c u m s t a n t i a l ' I got this f r o m X ' c l a i m , w h e r e X is a n a m e d i n d i v i d u a l , as c o n f e r r i n g any special a u t h o r i t y . G e n e r a l l y , H e r o d o t u s
does
n o t a r r a n g e the types o f source, w h i c h I have g i v e n above, i n a n y sort o f h i e r a r c h y . W e
c e r t a i n l y c a n n o t assume t h a t he w o u l d have
g i v e n a u t o m a t i c p r i o r i t y to w r i t t e n over
o r a l sources: i t has
said r e c e n t l y ( S h r i m p t o n (1997) 119 f , cf. 118) t h a t ' H e r o d o t u s
been quotes
c e r t a i n i n s c r i b e d texts m o r e f o r c e l e b r a t i o n t h a n f o r p r o o f .
But
e q u a l l y w e are n o t e n t i t l e d to t h i n k he w o u l d have r a t e d o r a l sources h i g h e r t h a n w r i t t e n ones. N o r
c a n o r s h o u l d w e assume
t h a t he
r e g a r d e d a n a p p e a l to the a u t h o r i t y o f a source as superior to the exercise o f his o w n i n t e l l i g e n c e , o r to a n a r g u m e n t f r o m a n a l o g y . I t has b e e n p o i n t e d o u t ( L u r a g h i (2001) 142) t h a t he defends his c l a i m t h a t a Persian a d v o c a t e d d e m o c r a c y n o t b y a source-reference
but
b y p o i n t i n g o u t t h a t M a r d o n i u s i n s t a l l e d democracies i n A s i a M i n o r some decades later ( 6 . 4 3 , r e f e r r i n g b a c k to 3.80 f f . ) .
' Periling (1989). The most recent account and list of Herodotus' source-citations is by Shrimpton and Gillis in Shrimpton (1997) 229-65 = Appendix 1, with list at 249-65; see 231 for the claim that Fehling's examination 'lacks statistical rigour', and (earlier in the page) their conclusion that 'there is no compelling reason to regard items of information attributed to sources as Herodotean fictions'. Whose name is given wrongly as Thrasybulus in Fehling (1989) 117. 2
375
HERODOTUS A N D HIS SOURCES OF I N F O R M A T I O N
A second d i f f i c u l t y is t h a t H e r o d o t u s ,
unlike Thucydides,
has n o
i n i t i a l l y - p l a c e d p r o g r a m m a t i c s t a t e m e n t a b o u t h o w he has used his sources. T h e r e l e v a n t c h a p t e r o f T h u c y d i d e s (1.22) is so f a m o u s t h a t i t is h a r d t o grasp h o w o r i g i n a l i t m u s t h a v e b e e n , i n some o f its aspects, w h e n first f o r m u l a t e d . T h u c y d i d e s distinguishes b e t w e e n n a r rative a n d speeches, a n o b v i o u s d i s t i n c t i o n once m a d e , b u t there is no comparable
e x p l i c i t statement o f this awareness i n H e r o d o t u s .
T h u c y d i d e s says i t was h a r d f o r b o t h h i m s e l f and for his informants t o r e m e m b e r w h a t was said (there f o l l o w s his c e l e b r a t e d c l a i m t o have c o m p r o m i s e d between
r e p o r t i n g t h e essence o f w h a t was a c t u a l l y
said, a n d g i v i n g w h a t was r h e t o r i c a l l y a p p r o p r i a t e ) . T h a t he treats speeches before n a r r a t i v e m a y be i n t e r e s t i n g i n itself f o r its i m p l i cations a b o u t p r i o r i t i e s , u n c o n g e n i a l t h o u g h those i m p l i c a t i o n s m a y be f o r us, w h o like t o t h i n k t h a t T h u c y d i d e s w a s m o r e p r e o c c u p i e d w i t h the demands
o f his r i g o r o u s n a r r a t i v e t h a n w i t h t h e r h e t o r i -
cally e l a b o r a t e speeches o f w h i c h his H i s t o r y is so f u l l . H e goes o n to state his p r i n c i p l e s a b o u t n a r r a t i v e : he has n o t d e r i v e d his accounts o f events f r o m chance informants, n o r p u t d o w n his o w n o p i n i o n , i . e . , o f f e r e d r e c o n s t r u c t i o n s a c c o r d i n g t o ideas o f his o w n , b u t has subj e c t e d to close s c r u t i n y b o t h the events he h i m s e l f witnessed a n d those he l e a r n t a b o u t f r o m others. Bias a n d f a u l t y m e m o r i e s o f w i t nesses, l e a d i n g t o inconsistent a c c o u n t s , m a d e this a h a r d j o b . H e r e , p e r h a p s , w e have m o r e t h a n a personal statement; we have the first c r i t i q u e o f H e r o d o t u s ( n o t f o r g e t t i n g T h u c y d i d e s ' o t h e r p r e decessors, n o t e t h e s w e e p i n g ' a l l m y predecessors' at 1.97.2). T h e expression ' n o t f r o m chance i n f o r m a n t s o r m y o w n r e c o n s t r u c t i o n ' is a n e x a m p l e o f w h a t students o f n a r r a t i v e f n a r r a t o l o g i s t s ' ) call ' p r e sentation t h r o u g h n e g a t i o n ' . 3 T h e negative f o r m u l a t i o n i m p l i e s ' n o t , as is usually d o n e ' , o r even ' n o t , as m y predecessors have d o n e ' . I f Herodotus
is t h e m a i n target h e r e , o r even o n e o f t h e targets, i t
seems t h a t T h u c y d i d e s d i d n o t t h i n k m u c h o f t h e i n f o r m a n t s he t o o k H e r o d o t u s t o have used, n o r d i d h e like t h e w a y H e r o d o t u s i n t r u d e d his o w n r e a s o n i n g , as i n t h e Persian d e m o c r a c y e x a m p l e m e n t i o n e d above.
B u t i t is n o t e w o r t h y t h a t even T h u c y d i d e s ,
Herodotus
though unlike
he cites r a w d o c u m e n t s , i n c l u d i n g t w o i n d i a l e c t , does
n o t m e n t i o n d o c u m e n t s i n this m e t h o d o l o g i c a l c h a p t e r
(Shrimpton
(1997) 101), t h o u g h t o o u r w a y o f t h i n k i n g , use o f d o c u m e n t s w o u l d be a n o b v i o u s w a y o f asserting his o w n s u p e r i o r i t y t o H e r o d o t u s .
De Jong (1987) 61-8; Hornblowcr (1994b) 152-8.
376
SIMON HORNBLOWER
How
far was T h u c y d i d e s ' c r i t i c i s m o f H e r o d o t u s - - i f t h a t is w h a t
it is—justified? I f Thucydides
m e a n t t h a t H e r o d o t u s was u n c r i t i c a l
i n his choice o f sources, the c r i t i c i s m was as w e shall see v e r y u n f a i r . B u t H e r o d o t u s l a i d h i m s e l f o p e n to i t i n t w o ways: first b y n o t s e t t i n g o u t his m e t h o d f u l l y a n d i n i t i a l l y , as T h u c y d i d e s l a t e r d i d , a n d seco n d l y b y saying o n t w o separate occasions t h a t he r e g a r d e d i t as his j o b , t h r o u g h o u t his w o r k , s i m p l y to r e c o r d w h a t each i n f o r m a n t said to h i m (see 2 . 1 2 3 d a n d 7 . 1 5 2 . 3 , w h e r e he adds t h a t he is n o t o b l i g e d to believe e v e r y t h i n g he reports). I t is easy to see h o w this h o s p i t a b l e a t t i t u d e c o u l d be m i s i n t e r p r e t e d as naive a n d u n c r i t i c a l . D i d Herodotus
r e a l l y t a l k to j u s t a n y b o d y ?
Certainly not; i f we
are i n t e r e s t e d i n the attitudes a n d b e h a v i o u r o f people o t h e r t h a n elites (a p r o b l e m f a c i n g all i n q u i r y i n t o a n c i e n t history) w e c a n n o t l o o k to H e r o d o t u s f o r h e l p . A n t h r o p o l o g i s t s speak o f the 'social surface' o f the t r a d i t i o n s p r e s e r v e d . 4 T h a t is a n expression for the g r o u p f r o m w h i c h the t r a d i t i o n stems, a n d w h i c h believes i t to be t r u e . The
social surface o f the t r a d i t i o n s i n H e r o d o t u s
is c o n s t i t u t e d b y
a n i n t e l l e c t u a l a n d social elite, w h o e v e r exactly he w a n t s us t o u n d e r stand b y the logioi w h o m he quotes e x p l i c i t l y three times ( 1 . 1 . 1 , w h e r e t h e y are Persians,
2.3.1
a n d 2 . 7 7 . 1 w h e r e t h e y are E g y p t i a n s ;
also 4 . 4 6 . 1 o f A n a c h a r s i s the S c y t h i a n ) . T h e
cf.
w o r d logioi means (so
G o u l d (1989) 27) 'those w i t h s o m e t h i n g to say', 'those w i t h a story to t e l l ' , a n d , i n the t h i r d instance, 'those w h o m a d e a p r a c t i c e o f the m e m o r y o f the p a s t ' . 0 F o r N a g y ((1987) 181),
H e r o d o t u s is h i m -
self b y i m p l i c a t i o n p r e s e n t e d at the v e r y b e g i n n i n g o f his Histories as one i n a l o n g line o f logioi. H o w e v e r this m a y b e — a n d L a n g ((1987) 204) reasonably objects t h a t H e r o d o t u s
uses the w o r d o n l y o f f o r -
eigners, w h i c h i f i t expresses a p r i n c i p l e w o u l d d i s q u a l i f y h i m s e l f — it is clear that the appeal to logioi is n o t an appeal to chance i n f o r m a n t s . T h a t is c e r t a i n l y t r u e b o t h o f A r c h i a s o f S p a r t a , a m e m b e r o f a dist i n g u i s h e d f a m i l y , one o f whose m e m b e r s was h o n o u r e d w i t h p u b lic b u r i a l at Samos (an o u t s t a n d i n g h o n o u r , otherwise w e l l attested o n l y at A t h e n s ) ;
and of Thersander
of Orchomenus,
w h o was a
p a r t i c i p a n t at a v e r y g r a n d b a n q u e t , a n d i n d e e d is expressly called one o f t h e m o s t logimoi m e n i n O r c h o m e n u s
4
(i.e., 'distinguished',
Luraghi (2001b) 159; Giangiulio (2001) 135, drawing on the Africanist Moniot (1970) 134 f. ·' Nagy (1987) adds more speculatively that the function of logioi is to confer kleos, 'glory', and suggests that they are thus assimilated to aoidoi (poets, singers); on Nagy's approach, see also Ch. 1, pp. 10-12, this volume.
t
377
HERODOTUS AND HIS SOURCES OF I N F O R M A T I O N
' i m p o r t a n t ' ; n o t the same w o r d as logios t h o u g h e t y m o l o g i c a l l y related to i t ) . B u t n e i t h e r the h a n d f u l o f e x p l i c i t references to logioi, n o r the t w o named informants Archias and Thersander,
get us far e n o u g h .
We
need to l o o k at evidence i n b u l k . Before w e d o so, h o w e v e r ,
we
s h o u l d n o t e i n fairness to H e r o d o t u s
t h a t w h e n i t comes to a c t u a l
p r a c t i c e , as o p p o s e d to statements o f m e t h o d , T h u c y d i d e s
gets us
even less far: t h e r e are i n his H i s t o r y absolutely n o citations o f i n d i v i d u a l n a m e d sources, t h o u g h n a t u r a l l y inferences c a n be
drawn,
especially w h e n he names a n i n d i v i d u a l ; ' ' thus T h u c y d i d e s once (2.5.6) reports a discrepancy b e t w e e n w h a t the Plataeans a n d T h e b a n s say a b o u t some p r i s o n e r s , a n d he repeats a n o t h e r b e t w e e n the A t h e n i a n s Scione was c a p t u r e d (4.122.6). O n
the
second occasion he adjudicates m a g i s t e r i a l l y b e t w e e n t h e t w o
a n d Spartans
about when
ver-
sions: 'the t r u t h was m o r e o n the A t h e n i a n side'. L e t us r e t u r n t o the H e r o d o t e a n evidence i n b u l k . T h e r e are t w o m a i n categories:
first,
those passages w h e r e n o source is stated b u t
w h e r e i t is possible to i n f e r the i d e n t i t y o f t h e source ( n a t u r a l l y this m e t h o d also takes a c c o u n t of, b u t is n o t t h e p r i s o n e r of, e x p l i c i t source-citations w h e r e t h e y o c c u r e m b e d d e d i n t h e section o f n a r rative i n question); a n d second, those passages i n t r o d u c e d , c o n c l u d e d , o r f r a m e d b y e x p l i c i t source-citations (9.82 is a n e x a m p l e o f such ' f r a m i n g ' , w h e r e a passage is b o t h i n t r o d u c e d a n d c o n c l u d e d b y a n ' i t is said' f o r m u l a w h i c h t u r n s i t i n t o a s i m p l e c o m p o s i t i o n a l ' r i n g ' ; see S h r i m p t o n a n d G i l l i s i n S h r i m p t o n (1997) 234). The
job of identifying Herodotus'
u n s t a t e d sources b y i n f e r e n c e
was c a r r i e d o u t b y the t r a d i t i o n a l a n d e v e n t u a l l y v e r y sophisticated techniques o f Quellenforschung, always a l e r t t o the e v i d e n t i a l w e i g h t o f bias; the h i g h - w a t e r m a r k o f this t e c h n i q u e was J a c o b y (1913) cols. 419—67, ' Q u e l l e n a n a l y s e des W e r k e s ' . A f t e r J a c o b y , as after a n y p a t i e n t genius, things c o u l d n o t be d o n e b e t t e r , they c o u l d o n l y be d o n e d i f f e r e n t l y . M o d e r n scholarship has lost interest i n i d e n t i f y i n g u n s p e c i f i e d sources, b u t i t r e m a i n s t r u e t h a t f o r l a r g e t r a c t s
of
H e r o d o t u s , J a c o b y ' s l o n g a n d systematic analysis, b o o k b y b o o k , is usually t h e best place to discover w h e r e H e r o d o t u s p r o b a b l y g o t i t
6
His practice over naming is nearly twice as sparing as Herodotus, so that Thucydidean naming is arguably and occasionally a way of flagging a source, see Hornblower (2000). Even group citations are very few (Hornblower (1994b) 136).
378
SIMON HORNBLOWER
7
from. The central Greek sanctuary o f Delphi featured extensively as the location o f informants i n Jacoby's tabulated treatment (with occasional reservations, see Jacoby (1913) col. 402, where he suggests that the Delphian element i n the Lydian logos or ethnographic section i n Book One was added only quite late as part o f an 'Umarbeitung' or reworking). This stress on Delphi as a source for Herodotus i f anything became more pronounced i n the course o f the twentieth century (see e.g., Flower (1991)), as the study of Greek religion moved from the margins to the centre o f the scholarly stage (Davies (1997) 31). 'The Delphians' are explicitly named as a source very early i n the History (1.20, on which see however Fehling (1989) 91), but their evidence is far more pervasive than the explicit citations would suggest. Colonization, for instance, is a theme which recurs all over the History, and it is likely that Herodotus derived much knowledge i n this area from the servants o f Apollo at Delphi, whose role i n the founding o f overseas settlements was so large. Progress has also been made, since Jacoby's time, i n identifying Herodotus' unstated Persian informants: Lewis (1985), followed by M u r r a y (1987) 110, suggested that one o f Herodotus' sources for Persia was the Greek element i n the Persian bureaucracy. N o w for our second category, the explicit source-citations—a much more fashionable object o f study i n the early twenty-first century. They are governed by two principles; it is an odd fact that though they were established or most clearly and pithily formulated by the sceptical Fehling, they are accepted as valid account of Herodotus' working method even by those scholars (Shrimpton and Gillis in Shrimpton (1997) 231; Luraghi (2001b) 148) who disagree with the negative conclusions which Fehling draws from them. The principles are: (1) the principle of citing the obvious source, and (2) the principle o f regard for party bias. Clearly, these principles might be followed by a writer o f plausible fiction, but also by an honest writer who did interrogate his sources. 8
' 'Usually', not 'always'. For a powerful but curiously understudied (because repellent?) section of Herodotus, see Hornblower [forthcoming], an analysis of the story (involving castration and possibly worse) of Hermotimus and Panionius at 8.104 6; Jacoby (1913) fastidiously ignores it. Forrest (1957); Malkin'(1987); Murray (1987) 105. 8
HERODOTUS A N D HIS SOURCES OF INFORMATION
379
The first principle ('the basic rule on which everything else is founded': Fehling (1989) 88) assumes that Herodotus distributed his source-citations 'according to the usual principle o f considering who can be supposed to know what' (Fehling (1989) 92). The 'obvious source' is usually an 'epichoric' or regional source. The statement that the Libyans say that cauterizing their children makes them the healthiest of mankind (4.87) is said by Fehling to be an example o f Greek theory, falsely attributed to the Libyans because they are the appropriate people to say it. But Fehling's critics observe that this sort o f attribution is sometimes best understood not as palpable fabrication or fraud but as a statement about the social surface (see above), the social dimension, o f the material reported: 'people are simply made to say, think or report what he supposes any reasonable person would expect them to do' (Shrimpton (1997) 109, quoted by Luraghi (2001) 148 n. 27). I n any case, Herodotus may sometimes attribute an item to a source, not i n order to verify the information but precisely in order to distance himself from it (Shrimpton (1997) 112; see further below). Divided source-attributions, i.e., instances where part o f a story is attributed to one group, part to another, are explained by Fehling on similar lines, thus the main report o f the miraculous appearance of two superhuman figures at Delphi (8.36—7) is assigned to the Persians, but the names o f the figures are assigned to the Delphians, who alone could reasonably be expected to 'know' them; but the attributions must—we are told- be false because the whole story assumes that there really was such an event, which in the real world there was not (Fehling (1989) 12-17). Therefore the story has not two origins but one—inside Herodotus' head. This line of approach takes for granted a modern (or Thucydidean) attitude to divine epiphanies: obviously, they did not really happen. Herodotus is not so sure or so dogmatic (see below, pp. 381-2, on Pan, for the care he takes to distance himself by invoking what other people said or believed), and his contemporaries are more likely to have shared his attitide than Thucydides', or ours. Another 'divided' story, the death o f Miltiades, illustrates principle no. 2: regard for 'party bias' (Fehling (1989) 106 f t ) . The people o f Paros diverge from the story told by the rest o f the Greeks in that the Parians say Miltiades died because o f an impiety committed on Paros. Is this 'unrealistic' so as to 'give rise to doubts'
380
SMON HORNBLOWER
( F e h l i n g (1989) 106)?
On
the c o n t r a r y , the l o c a l stress o n the l o c a l
aspect is e n t i r e l y n a t u r a l a n d p l a u s i b l e , a n d a n y G r e e k w o u l d have f o u n d i t so (on p a r t y bias, see L u r a g h i (2001) 148). 9 I t is, h o w e v e r , unsatisfactory to discuss H e r o d o t u s '
use o f sources
as i f i t w e r e u n i f o r m t h r o u g h o u t t h e w h o l e o f his e n o r m o u s t e x t , o r u n i f o r m f r o m t o p i c to t o p i c . I shall n o w t r y to i d e n t i f y some o f the differences i n the w a y he handles his m a t e r i a l o n d i f f e r e n t occasions. L e t us first l o o k at his d i f f e r e n t b e h a v i o u r i n d i f f e r e n t parts o f the work. One
o b v i o u s w a y o f d e c l i n i n g to offer a c r i t i c a l j u d g m e n t o n
his sources is b y p r e s e n t i n g his m a t e r i a l w i t h n o s o u r c e - a t t r i b u t i o n at a l l , thus i m p l y i n g t h a t he accepts the deliverances o f his sources o r else t h a t he has m a d e
a choice b e t w e e n t h e m , o r else t h a t he
has c o m b i n e d t h e m i n some undisclosed w a y ; b u t i n any case he is h a p p y w i t h the result. T h i s , we m a y say, is the seamless,
Thucydidean,
a p p r o a c h . I n a n e w a n d massively w e l l - d o c u m e n t e d study i t has b e e n shown ( S h r i m p t o n a n d Gillis i n S h r i m p t o n (1997) 2 3 2 - 4 9 ) t h a t sourcecitations preponderate
i n the e a r l i e r b o o k s ,
especially Books
Two
( E g y p t ) , T h r e e (Persia) a n d F o u r (Scythia; L i b y a ) . B o o k N i n e b y c o n trast, w h i c h deals w i t h events m u c h closer to H e r o d o t u s '
own time,
a n d is m a i n l y a b o u t G r e e c e , e x h i b i t s a v e r y s m a l l n u m b e r o f sourcecitations. T h e statistical tables are impressive, a n d show that H e r o d o t u s is r e a d i e r to give c i t a t i o n s w h e n d e a l i n g w i t h events r e m o t e i n t i m e , g e o g r a p h y , o r c u l t u r e . ' T h e i n f e r e n c e is clear: w h e n H e r o d o t u s feels t h a t the i t e m is r e l i a b l e k n o w l e d g e , n o source c i t a t i o n is r e q u i r e d , b u t a n otherwise i d e n t i c a l i t e m t h a t c a n n o t be c o n f i d e n t l y a d v a n c e d as k n o w l e d g e is a t t r i b u t e d to a source' ( S h r i m p t o n (1997) 245 f ; cf. M a r i n c o l a (1987) 133:
'after B o o k I I he does n o t d e t a i l his travels
a n d the p e o p l e w i t h w h o m he c a m e i n t o c o n t a c t ' ; see also 132
and
134, discussing the d i f f e r e n t a p p r o a c h i n Books Five to N i n e ) . H e r o d o t u s varies his t e c h n i q u e n o t j u s t progressively t h r o u g h the work but when
h a n d l i n g c e r t a i n specially sensitive t o p i c s . I shall
c o n f i n e m y s e l f to t w o , r e l i g i o n a n d A t h e n i a n p r e - P e r s i a n - W a r
poli-
tics. T w o f a i r l y recent t r e a t m e n t s , b y G o u l d (1994) a n d B a d i a n (1994), are c o n c e r n e d w i t h d i f f e r e n t aspects o f H e r o d o t u s ,
the religious a n d
the p o l i t i c a l , b u t b o t h use the w o r d ' r e t i c e n c e ' to describe the p r o b lems t h e y have i d e n t i f i e d . 1 0
9
Note in any case that a Delphic source probably lies alongside the Parian, see Jacoby (1913) col. 445. Gould (1994) 92, citing Lateiner (1989) 64 ff.; Badian (1994) 127, 'Herodotus' reticence about unpalatable facts'. 10
381
HERODOTUS A N D HIS SOURCES OF I N F O R M A T I O N
G o u l d has s h o w n t h a t one area w h e r e H e r o d o t u s
was specially
sensitive, even embarrassed, was r e l i g i o n , a n d t h a t this coyness extends to his a t t i t u d e to his sources f o r i t — n o t w i t h s t a n d i n g his i m p o r t a n t l i n e o f c o m m u n i c a t i o n to D e l p h i (above): Herodotus sometimes feels that he requires additional weight o f evidence, that i t is or may be impossible to identify the power concerned or be certain of its motive, and that such reports may be better distanced from the rest o f the surrounding narrative by being given i n oratio obliqua [indirect speech]. (Gould (1994) 96) Gould
offers a g o o d e x a m p l e ,
t h e s t o r y o f A r i s t o d i c u s at
Cyme
( 1 . 1 5 3 - d 60). A n o t h e r e x a m p l e , w h i c h I have discussed i n a d i f f e r e n t c o n n e c t i o n elsewhere ( H o r n b l o w e r (2001)) is t h e e p i p h a n y o r d i v i n e appearance o f P a n
(6.105-6).
The
A r c a d i a n g o d was supposed to
have
a p p e a r e d to the r u n n e r P h i l i p p i d e s , o n his w a y f r o m A t h e n s to Sparta to appeal f o r h e l p just before t h e B a t t l e o f M a r a t h o n i n 4 9 0 .
'As
P h i l i p p i d e s h i m s e l f used to say a n d as he t o l d t h e A t h e n i a n s ' — n o t e t h a t this f o r m u l a t i o n does n o t necessarily i m p l y t h a t H e r o d o t u s p e r sonally spoke to h i m — h e h a d a n e n c o u n t e r w i t h P a n i n A r c a d i a , a n d P a n r e p r o a c h e d the A t h e n i a n s f o r n o t h o n o u r i n g h i m w i t h c u l t because he was favourably disposed to the Athenians, had been useful to them i n the past and w o u l d be useful again. After the battle, when the Athenians' affairs had turned out well, they believed that what Philippides had said was true and built a shrine to h i m . . . But on this occasion [in 490] he was sent out on the mission on which he said he had seen Pan. T h i s c h a p t e r is f u l l o f interest. T h e d i s t a n c i n g devices are p l a i n : 'as he used to say', h a d seen P a n ' .
'as he t o l d the A t h e n i a n s ' , But a doubt remains. T h e
' o n w h i c h he said he c r y p t i c a l l y vague refer-
ence t o t h e A t h e n i a n s ' affairs ' t u r n i n g o u t w e l l ' has b e e n i n t e r p r e t e d as a n a c k n o w l e d g m e n t b y H e r o d o t u s t h a t P a n a c t u a l l y sent h e l p d u r i n g the B a t t l e o f M a r a t h o n i n t h e f o r m o f a p a n i c (Pan-ic) a t t a c k i n f l i c t e d o n the Persian a r m y . 1 1 I f H e r o d o t u s does m e a n to i m p l y t h a t there was a Pan-sent p a n i c i n t h e Persian a r m y d u r i n g the b a t t l e ,
11
Though this is not agreed: some scholars say that Pan sent panics only to armies at rest, for instance at night. See Borgeaud (1988) 136; Parker (1996) 164 and n. 36, who is more favourable than is Borgeaud to the idea that Pan might have sent his own panic attack.
382
SIMON HORNBLOWER
in other words that there was a second and more public epiphany o f Pan, it is surprising that he makes no mention of any such thing i n his actual battle-description a few chapters later. However, this could be just another instance of Herodotean reticence. The first epiphany is given as something claimed by Philippides, and believed by the Athenians -but only after the second epiphany had provided corroboration for the first. The reporting o f the sources is very carefully and unobtrusively managed, and it leaves the issue of Herodotus' own belief strictly unresolved. But there is i n the course of the chapter a gathering sense that the epiphany o f Pan (perhaps only auditory not visual, see Versnel (1987) 49) was more than a touch of the midday sun. Religion was not the only area calling for occasional obliqueness and selectivity (a topic I shall address more fully i n a moment) i n the handling o f source-material. Certain political issues were almost equally sensitive and for the same reason. 'Herodotus took great care not to give offence to the powerful, or those who might be: the gods of course, Egyptian no less than G r e e k . . . ' (Badian (1994) 120)." We can accept that i n the normal run o f cases, Herodotus cheerfully transmitted 'party bias' (see above) by recording versions in the form 'x is what the people o f y say', where x is to the advantage of y (or where x is disobliging to z, who are the enemies o f y). But it has been ingeniously shown (Badian (1994), a study i n 'subtle silences') that Herodotus hints very delicately indeed at the reasons why Alexander I , king o f Macedon was honoured at Athens. N o t just for providing ship-building timber, but for mediating the Athenian submission to the Great K i n g o f Persia i n the late sixth century BC, a submission which looked bad in the period after the Persian Wars of 490-479 BC when the Athenians were the saviours o f Greece, at least i n Herodotus' presentation (7.139). The facts are there, above all at the end o f the crucial chapter (5.73) when Herodotus says that the Athenian ambassadors who made an alliance with the Persian king were 'held i n great blame' on their return; what he does not say (although modern scholars have incautiously taken h i m to be saying it) is that the Athenians repudiated the alliance. They d i d not. 'The fact that he does not say so, but uses a vague phrase about 1
12
See further below p. 384, citing Harrison. He then proceeds to list some powerful human individuals and groups whom Herodotus was also careful not to offend. 13
HERODOTUS A N D HIS SOURCES OF I N F O R M A T I O N
383
blaming the envoys, once more reveals his technique when he has something to hide' (Badian (1994) 126). His sources left him i n no doubt o f the truth, but he could not be explicit. ('It is surely inconceivable that Herodotus was told that Alexander was euergetes [benefactor] of Athens, but not told why . . . We are forced to conclude that Herodotus deliberately chose to withhold the information' (Badian (1994), 122). T o o much was at stake, i n the m i d fifth century when Athenian heroism against the Persians had become a national myth, so for the moment Herodotus lays aside his normally transparent and ebullient manner. Explicitly critical discussion o f and judgment on his sources was i n this area, as i n some aspects of religion, completely out o f place. Finally, how did Herodotus select his material, and how far was he prepared to generalize on the strength of the selections he had made? Usually, the first part o f this question ('how did he select. . .?') is unanswerable, because selection means leaving certain things out, and there are limits to what we can say about what is not there. I f we had a full tradition apart from Herodotus, we would be in a better position to say 'he did not record event x or custom y' but that would not tell us whether he consciously omitted x or y unless we knew for certain that he was aware o f x or y. Sometimes we can feel confident that when dealing with a particular complex of traditons, he has under-reported or rejected elements of which he was well aware. Thus his account or rather accounts o f the the foundation by the Theran Battus of Gyrene in N o r t h Africa ( 4 . 1 4 5 - 5 9 , a narrative which includes the story o f Cyrene's mother-city Thera) both resemble, and diverge from, the material i n Pindar's Fourth and Ninth Pythian Odes. For example, the n y m p h Cyrene (for whom see Pindar Ninth Pythian) does not feature i n Herodotus; she is not quite a foundress, as Malkin (1994) 173 rightly insists, but he agrees that she is extremely important as 'foreshadowing the "political" foundation/colonization by Battos'. N o r does Herodotus spell out the story of Battus' ancestor Euphemus the Argonaut, who was given a clod o f earth by a son o f Poseidon, to legitimate his possession o f Cyrene (Pindar, Fourth Pythian). Herodotus does, however, plainly show his awareness o f this story by his casual description o f Battus as 'Euphemides', 'descendant of Euphemus' (4.150, part of the Theran version of events). 14
Dougherty (1993) 136 56; Malkin (1994) 169-79; Giangiulio (2001).
384
SIMON HORNBLOWER
Elsewhere, i t is v e r y h a r d to a p p l y controls to H e r o d o t u s ' Thucydides,
accounts.
as I have t r i e d to show elsewhere ( H o r n b l o w e r
(1996a)
129—34) is, i n the speeches w h i c h he p u t s i n t o his agents'
mouths,
d e p e n d e n t to a r e m a r k a b l e a n d almost exclusive degree o n H e r o d o t u s f o r his ' a n c i e n t h i s t o r y ' i . e . , f o r events earlier t h a n the Persian W a r s . I n his narrative, T h u c y d i d e s is m o r e w i l l i n g to d r a w o n
non-Herodotean
t r a d i t i o n s , b u t even here there is conspicuous reluctance to m o v e outside the H e r o d o t e a n War,
g r o o v e . A g o o d e x a m p l e is the First
allegedly f o u g h t i n t h e early s i x t h c e n t u r y B C
Sacred
f o r possession
of D e l p h i by a coalition o f Greek powers; b u t not mentioned Herodotus BC.
As
by
o r (in effect) a n y source e a r l i e r t h a n the f o u r t h c e n t u r y
a m u l t i - s t a t e c o n f l i c t , i t w o u l d have b e e n v e r y r e l e v a n t to
T h u c y d i d e s ' i n i t i a l discussion o f wars e a r l i e r t h a n the
Peloponnesian
(1.1—20, w h e r e he seeks t o show t h a t such w a r s w e r e less great t h a n B u t he o m i t s i t , surely because H e r o d o t u s
had
also o m i t t e d i t . B y c o n t r a s t , T h u c y d i d e s includes the L e l a n t i n e
the Peloponnesian).
War
f o u g h t o n E u b o e a b u t w i t h i n t e r n a t i o n a l allies—because d i d m e n t i o n i t ( T h u c . 1.15; Herodotus
(or T h u c y d i d e s )
Hdt.
Herodotus
5.99). Before w e c a n say w h e t h e r
o m i t t e d the First Sacred W a r
we
need
t o b e sure t h a t the w a r was h i s t o r i c a l , a n d was n o t a n i n v e n t i o n o f the age o f P h i l i p I I o f M a c e d o n ; D a v i e s (1994b) 2 0 6 cautiously c o n cludes t h a t the h i s t o r i c i t y o f the w a r is 'a p l a u s i b l e hypothesis, b u t n o m o r e ' . I f the w a r d i d h a p p e n , we have a n example o f a H e r o d o t e a n o m i s s i o n n o t r e c t i f i e d except b y some scrappy l a t e r evidence. T h e reasons f o r such omissions are i n s c r u t a b l e , b u t one c a n m a k e guesses: A p o l l o g i v i n g a n oracle a b o u t the f o u n d a t i o n o f C y r e n e was one t h i n g , A p o l l o
r a p i n g the n y m p h
C y r e n e was a n o t h e r ,
was the c l o d o f e a r t h g i v e n to E u p h e m u s b y the son o f
a n d so
Poseidon.
T h a t is, H e r o d o t u s s h r a n k f r o m i n c l u d i n g d i r e c t as o p p o s e d to m e d i ated intervention by
a god.
(On
this t o p i c see H a r r i s o n
(2000b)
8 2 - 9 2 , a n d cf. above p. 382). As for the First Sacred W a r , its absence f r o m Herodotus
is j u s t a r e m i n d e r t h a t he was n o t w r i t i n g a c o m -
prehensive h i s t o r y o f a r c h a i c Greece (for the q u e s t i o n o f unevenness in Herodotus'
coverage
o f events b e f o r e the sixth c e n t u r y , a t o p i c
w h i c h c a n n o t be discussed h e r e , see the r a t h e r d i f f e r e n t perspectives o f M u r r a y (1987) a n d o f T h o m a s (2001)). Generalization
and extrapolation in Herodotus
there c e r t a i n l y is.
S o m e o f i t is ' g n o m i c ' i n c h a r a c t e r , t h a t is, i t offers p r o v e r b i a l l y expressed s u m m i n g s - u p
o f some facet o f h u m a n experience.
Gould
((1989) 8 1 f.) r i g h t l y insists t h a t such r e m a r k s are generalizations o n l y
HERODOTUS
AND
HIS SOURCES
385
OF INFORMATION
i n a special a n d p a r t i a l sense: this sort o f u t t e r a n c e does n o t ' r e q u i r e all subsequent experience t o b e a r i t o u t ' . W e c a n a d d t h a t i t is n o t p a r t i c u l a r l y closely r e l a t e d to a n y 'source' except i n the l i m i t e d sense t h a t the generalization i n H e r o d o t u s m a y take the f o r m o f an endorsem e n t o f someone else's v i e w , thus ' P i n d a r was right to say t h a t " c u s t o m is k i n g o f a l l ' " (3.38). O t h e r g e n e r a l i z a t i o n s , like t h a t a b o u t the s u p e r i o r i t y o f d e m o c r a c y t o t y r a n n y (5.78), l o o k like expressions
of
p o l i t i c a l o p i n i o n m a s k e d as g e n e r a l i z a t i o n . B u t some o f t h e genera l i z a t i o n is m o r e specific a n d a p p a r e n t l y s o u r c e - d e r i v e d . T a k e three m a i n city-states o f o l d G r e e c e , the A t h e n i a n s , the Spartans, a n d the C o r i n t h i a n s . E a c h is t h e subject o f a b o l d a n d celeb r a t e d g e n e r a l i z i n g j u d g m e n t : the A t h e n i a n s are t h e cleverest o f t h e Greeks w h o are themselves cleverer t h a n the b a r b a r i a n s (1.60), the Spartans value t h e things o f the gods m o r e t h a n the things o f m e n ( 5 . 6 3 , surely a H e r o d o t e a n o r possibly a n A t h e n i a n v i e w , b u t n o t a Spartan
one), a n d the C o r i n t h i a n s despise c r a f t s m e n less t h a n
do
other Greeks (2.167). T h e second a n d t h i r d o f these, at least, are m u c h c i t e d b y students o f G r e e k r e l i g i o n a n d G r e e k economics respectively, a n d i t w o u l d be g o o d to be sure t h a t t h e y have some i n d u c t i v e v a l i d i t y . B u t i t is n o t easy to say w h e t h e r these a n d s i m i l a r g e n eralizations are o f f e r e d o n the s t r e n g t h o f a c c u m u l a t e d t e s t i m o n y o f his sources, the communis opinio o f t h e logioi Greeks he h a d spoken t o , a n d t h a t he h a d spoken to e n o u g h ( a n d to e n o u g h n o n - S p a r t a n s
Spartans
and
Corinthians
a n d n o n - C o r i n t h i a n s ) to give w e i g h t
t o his j u d g m e n t s ; o r w h e t h e r they m e r e l y represent his o w n p r e j u dices, casually a n d i m p r e s s i o n i s t i c a l l y a r r i v e d at. T h e
cleverness
of
the A t h e n i a n s looks m o r e s t r a i g h t f o r w a r d at first sight: n o l o n g t r a i n i n g i n a n c i e n t G r e e k h i s t o r y is needed to s h o w t h a t there w e r e p l e n t y o f clever
fifth-century
Athenians for Herodotus
to t a l k t o . B u t the
g e n e r a l i z a t i o n m u s t be c o n t e x t u a l i z e d . I t features i n a story a b o u t a n u n c h a r a c t e r i s t i c piece o f A t h e n i a n c r e d u l i t y as H e r o d o t u s saw i t . A n d these same A t h e n i a n s are elsewhere (5.97) used to s u p p o r t the p a r a d o x t h a t i t is easier to f o o l 3 0 , 0 0 0 p e o p l e t h a n one m a n , because K i n g C l e o m e n e s o f S p a r t a refused h e l p to A r i s t a g o r a s the I o n i a n whereas the A t h e n i a n d e m o c r a c y g r a n t e d i t a n d so b r o u g h t o n itself the w r a t h o f t h e Persian k i n g . T h e
r e l a t i o n o f sources to g e n e r a l -
i z a t i o n r e m a i n s elusive. As M o m i g l i a n o once f a m o u s l y said o f H e r o dotus: 'the secrets o f his w o r k s h o p are n o t yet a l l o u t ' ((1966)
130).
F o r instance, m u c h m o r e w o r k needs to be done o n H e r o d o t u s ' relat i o n to o t h e r types o f c o n t e m p o r a r y l i t e r a r y a n d scientific a c t i v i t y ;
380
SIMON H O R N B L O W E R
thus i t has r e c e n t l y b e e n suggested t h a t some o f H e r o d o t u s '
Scythian
m a t e r i a l has been passed t h r o u g h a ' H i p p o c r a t i c f i l t e r ' . T h a t is, there is some sort o f d e b t to c o n t e m p o r a r y m e d i c a l i n q u i r y ( T h o m a s (2000) 60,
a very guarded formulation). Something
s i m i l a r c a n be s a i d
( T h o m a s (2000) 1 6 2 - 2 0 0 ) a b o u t the language o f p r o o f i n H e r o d o t u s , w h i c h shows clear analogies w i t h n o n - h i s t o r i c a l w r i t i n g o f the p e r i o d . B u t i n a l l this i t is v e r y d i f f i c u l t (as T h o m a s ' g u a r d e d use o f the 'filter' m e t a p h o r Herodotus'
shows) t o k n o w
w h e r e i t is p r o p e r to speak
of
'use o f [specific, possibly i d e n t i f i a b l e ] sources o f i n f o r -
m a t i o n ' a n d at w h a t p o i n t we s h o u l d stop t a l k i n g o f 'sources' a n d t a l k instead o f g e n e r a l o c c u p a n c y o f a s h a r e d i n t e l l e c t u a l The
milieu.15
same is t r u e i n m a n y ways o f T h u c y d i d e s as w e l l , b u t t h o u g h
t h e r e is a little e t h n o g r a p h y i n T h u c y d i d e s , a n d t h o u g h t h e r e is a n interest i n things m e d i c a l o n the p a r t o f a m a n w h o c a u g h t the great Plague b u t r e c o v e r e d f r o m i t ( T h u c . 2 . 4 8 . 3 ) , nevertheless H e r o d o t u s ' c h e e r f u l m a r c h across the i n t e l l e c t u a l disciplines takes h i m across a w i d e r t e r r i t o r y a n d his f o o t p r i n t s are t h a t m u c h h a r d e r to t r a c e .
See also Chs. 1 and 7, this volume.
CHAPTER SEVENTEEN THE
ORGANIZATION
OF T I M E I N THE
HISTORIES
Justus G o b e t
Introduction to the Subject R u r a l societies experienced t i m e as b e i n g set b y nature. T h e y observed h e r r e g u l a r r h y t h m as t h e fig trees s p r o u t , t h e swallows f l y , a n d t h e planets show p a r t i c u l a r c o n f i g u r a t i o n s . 1 T h e E g y p t i a n s , o n t h e o t h e r h a n d , actively c o u n t e d . ' T h e y i n v e n t e d t h e year' (exeurein ton eniauton) a n d l e a r n e d h o w t o cope w i t h t h e difference b e t w e e n t h e solar a n d the l u n a r year, t o t h e effect t h a t c o n t r a r y t o t h e Greeks ' t h e i r seasonal cycle comes r o u n d t o t h e same p o i n t i n t h e i r calendar each time'.2 Ancient
societies registered t h e sequence
o f time b y kings'
r e i g n s , p r i e s t h o o d s , a n d magistracies. T o measure l o n g e r spaces o f t i m e , t h e y t o o k a b e g i n n i n g as reference p o i n t , such as t h e exodus f r o m E g y p t , t h e f o u n d i n g o f a dynasty, founding of Rome.
t h e first O l y m p i c s ,
B u t a r e a l l y absolute c h r o n o l o g y ,
or the
which tran-
scended c u l t u r a l f r o n t i e r s o r h i s t o r i c a l p e r i o d s , came i n t o existence o n l y t h r o u g h t h e a l m o s t u n i v e r s a l usage o f the C h r i s t i a n e r a . I n n a t u r e , things appear t o r e c u r , b u t t h e i n d i v i d u a l experience o f life a n d d e a t h teaches us t h a t t i m e is n o t reversible. D i f f e r e n t hist o r i c a l times a r e e x p e r i e n c e d n o t o n l y b y i n d i v i d u a l s b u t also b y g r o u p s a n d over a t i m e span o f several generations. A c c o r d i n g l y , t h e irreversible n a t u r e o f t i m e changes f r o m a n a t u r a l i n t o a c u l t u r a l experience o f a g i v e n story o r h i s t o r y , a l t h o u g h such stories c a n be a n d have been i n t e r p r e t e d as a n a t u r a l cycle, f o r e x a m p l e , o n e o f g r o w i n g a n d decaying empires. T i m e measured i n a f r a m e o f absolute c h r o n o l ogy such as t h e secularized C h r i s t i a n era becomes a q u a n t i t y abstracti n g f r o m specific experiences, i n t e r p r e t a t i o n s , a n d m e a n i n g . A t t h e
1
Hesiod, W&D 382; 567 8; 679 81. Both quotations Hdt. 2.4. Quotations without author will refer to Herodotus throughout this chapter. For verbatim quotations I use the English translation of Waterfield (1998). 2
388
JUSTUS
COBET
same t i m e , such a c h r o n o l o g y enables us to c o n n e c t v a r i o u s h i s t o ries a n d c u l t u r a l constructs o f d i f f e r e n t g r o u p s a n d to c o m b i n e t h e m i n t o a new a n d m o r e general history. A n y
such c o n s t r u c t w i l l reveal
its h i s t o r i a n ' s specific h i s t o r i c a l perspective a n d the specific t r a d i t i o n she o r he is w o r k i n g i n , w h i c h yields t h e i n t e r e s t i n g t o p i c o f h i s t o r ical p e r i o d i z a t i o n (See C o b e t (2000)). Herodotus'
w o r k belongs to the b e g i n n i n g o f this story. Perhaps
c o m p a r a b l e to the O l d T e s t a m e n t , i t c r e a t e d the m o d e l f o r a n o r g a n i z a t i o n o f t i m e w h i c h transcends c u l t u r a l b o u n d a r i e s . T h e r e was n o absolute c h r o n o l o g y o n w h i c h he c o u l d b u i l d t o present a c o h e r e n t story consisting o f d i s p a r a t e , causally u n r e l a t e d events. T h e r e f o r e , legem ta legomena ' t o r e p o r t w h a t is t o l d ' (2.123) involves first o f all the o r g a n i z a t i o n o f t i m e within a p a r t i c u l a r logos, as f o r e x a m p l e i n the case o f the L y d i a n kings. As W . Geschichte
d e n B o e r p u t i t : ' W e n n i h m eine
o d e r etwas anderes w i c h t i g o d e r n ü t z l i c h e r s c h i e n , so
ü b e r n a h m er sie, z u s a m m e n m i t d e m c h r o n o l o g i s c h e n R a h m e n , i n d e n sie sein G e w ä h r s m a n n gestellt h a t t e ' . 3 On
this basis, H e r o d o t u s
o r g a n i z e d t i m e a n d space as the basic
d i m e n s i o n s i n w h i c h h i s t o r i o g r a p h y has t o d e v e l o p
meaning.
To
a r r a n g e the heterogeneous m a t e r i a l he e n c o u n t e r e d i n t o a continuum o f t i m e was a p r a c t i c a l q u e s t i o n , b u t also a m a t t e r o f i n t e r p r e t a t i o n : the c o n s t r u c t i o n o f a p a r t i c u l a r h i s t o r i c a l t e m p o r a l space t h a t was m e a n i n g f u l t o the readers he h a d i n m i n d . H e
is so to speak
the
f u n n e l t h r o u g h w h i c h heterogeneous t r a d i t i o n s a b o u t d i f f e r e n t t i m e s a n d places change i n t o a n o t h e r f r a m e o f p e r c e p t i o n , so t h a t o u t o f past a n d p r e s e n t , o u t o f the c o m p l e x i t i e s o f h i s t o r i c a l t i m e s , a c o n t i n u o u s t i m e space is c r e a t e d t h a t c a n r i g h t l y be called the h i s t o r y
o f the Oikoumene. Before the rise o f h i s t o r i o g r a p h y i n G r e e k l i t e r a t u r e , there w e r e t w o m o d e l s t o relate ' a n c i e n t h i s t o r y ' t o one's o w n t i m e : H o m e r a n d H e s i o d . I n the Iliad, H e l e n speaks to H e c t o r a b o u t h e r b e i n g g u i l t y o f the o n g o i n g w a r .
She
concludes w i t h a reference to the
poem
w i t h i n the p o e m : the present events ' w i l l b e c o m e subject o f song f o r future generations' 6.357-8. 'The
(opissö anthropoid pelömeth' aoidimoi essomenoisi) II.
f a v o u r i t e i l l u s t r a t i o n o f this [ i . e . , a h e r o i c age l o n g
since passed] is p e r h a p s the poet's reference (//. 12.447) to a hero's
3
Den Boer (1967) 38. See also Dux (1989) 278: '. . . war auch die Chronologie nicht die Chronologie eines Weltgeschehens, sondern die des Handlungsfeldes, in dem die Ereignisse einem festgehaltenen Handlungslauf angegeliedert wurden'.
THE
ORGANIZATION
OF TIME
IN T H E
389
HISTORIES
t h r o w i n g a stone " w h i c h t w o m e n o f t o d a y [hoioi nun brotoi els']
could
scarcely have l i f t e d ' " (Snodgrass (1971) 2). Before his d u e l w i t h A i a s , H e c t o r proposes to the Achaeans t h a t i n case he is victorious a t u m u lus f o r his slain o p p o n e n t be e r e c t e d , t o be seen b y e v e r y b o d y w h o passes the H e l l e s p o n t (II. 7 . 6 7 - 9 1 ) . ' A n d
someone o f the l a t e r b o r n
m e n ' (kai pote tis. . . opsigonon anthropon), as he envisages, w i l l 'some day' (pote) relate w h a t h a p p e n e d , saying: ' T h i s is the t o m b o f a m a n who
d i e d a l o n g t i m e ago' [andros men lode sema palai katatethneotos,
7.87).
4
T h e p o e t separates the n a r r a t e d t i m e o f the heroes f r o m his
o w n a n d his audience's b y a distance t h a t is n o t m e a s u r e d i n t e m p o r a l units. The
events o f this ' a n c i e n t h i s t o r y ' far a w a y are n o t o n l y present
t h r o u g h the actual p e r f o r m a n c e o f the epic poems (see Bakker (1999b); (1999c)) b u t also t h r o u g h the visible evidence o f the t u m u l i i n the T r o a d a n d the r u i n s o f T r o y ' s w a l l s , t h e v e r y s y m b o l o f w h a t w h o l e story is a b o u t . ' H e s i o d ,
the
e n d o w e d w i t h the skill o f the M u s e s ,
w h o k n o w t o t e l l ' a b o u t the past, t h e present, a n d the f u t u r e ' (eirousai ta t' eonta ta t'essomena pro t'eonta, Th. the w o r l d (W&D
38), speaks o f five ages o f
1 0 6 - 2 0 1 ) . I n this c o n c e p t i o n , t h e t i m e o f the
H o m e r i c heroes separates the g o l d e n , silver a n d b r o n z e age
from
the present, i r o n age: a p r i m e v a l c o n d i t i o n o f p a r a d i s i a c a l bliss has d e t e r i o r a t e d i n f o u r steps to the m i s e r y o f the e m p i r i c a l w o r l d . N e i t h e r i n H o m e r n o r i n H e s i o d is there a c o n t i n u u m i n t i m e a n d h i s t o r y . T h e c o n c e p t i o n is r a t h e r one o f layers o f d i f f e r e n t q u a l i t y , a n d i f w e call the m o s t recent one
' h i s t o r y ' , d e f i n e d b y later
authors as spatium historicum, t h e r e are d i f f e r e n t p r o j e c t i o n s f r o m i t r e a c h i n g i n t o a n o t h e r state o f t h i n g s , c a l l e d spatium mythicum b y the same a u t h o r s .
I n o r d e r t o have access to b o t h spatia o f t i m e , the
poets h a d to i n v o k e
the M u s e s ,
'who
know
everything, who
are
e v e r y w h e r e ' (pareste te iste te panta, II. 2 . 4 8 5 ) . 6 H e r o d o t u s , b y c o n t r a s t , h a d t o establish a u t h o r i t y f o r his n a r r a t i v e i n his o w n n a m e ,
1
through
See Bakker (1997b) 12: 'the idea of the past as something near and re-created in the context of the performance yet at the same time something distant', and, referring to 77. 7.87-91, 33: 'the future of an event, instead of being something inherent in that event, is the kleos of that event, its representation in the poetry of the future'. Cf. also Patzek (1992a) 162 f. and passim. Patzek (1992b). On the visibility of the Bronze Age walls in Homer's time, see Hertel (1991); Korfmann (1993) 19. See also Darbo-Peschanski (1987) 23-4. 5
6
390
JUSTUS COBET
his p e r s o n a l research i n t o the c o n t i n u u m o f the e m p i r i c a l w o r l d : his-
tories apodexis.' After
Herodotus,
Thucydides
i n his Archaeology ( 1 . 2 - 1 9 )
recon-
s t r u c t e d a l l o f ' a n c i e n t h i s t o r y ' as a c o n t i n u o u s d e v e l o p m e n t l e a d i n g u p to his p r o p e r subject, the Peloponnesian
War,
w h i c h t o o k place
i n his o w n l i f e t i m e . ' A n c i e n t h i s t o r y ' became the i m m e d i a t e p r e h i s t o r y o f the present. I n this w a y , spatium mythicum a n d spatium historicum have been
amalgamated
i n t o o n e c o n t i n u o u s h i s t o r y (cf.
Hunter
(1982) 103—4). H i s n a r r a t i v e i n the Archaeology is t h o r o u g h l y o c e n t r i c , t o the p o i n t t h a t scholars are i n d o u b t a b o u t
Hellen-
Thucydides'
i m p l i c i t p r e t e n s i o n o f the universal value o f its c o n t e n t ( H u n t e r (1982) 101).
The
o b v i o u s difference w i t h H e r o d o t u s
i n h o w to c o n s t r u c t a
h i s t o r i c a l c o n t i n u u m is t h a t the Histories i n t e g r a t e various h i s t o r i c a l subjects w i t h t h e i r d i s t i n c t histories. I n this respect, H e r o d o t u s ' is m o r e
work
i n t e r e s t i n g a n d also p r o d u c e d t h e m o d e l f o r the f u t u r e .
T h u c y d i d e s ' n a r r a t i v e presupposes the m a t e r i a l o f H o m e r a n d H e r o dotus. T h e p a r a d i g m a t i c t r a n s i t i o n to h i s t o r y as a c o n t i n u u m o f t i m e happened i n between H o m e r a n d
Thucydides.8
Introduction to the Author Mosshammer's
study o f ' T h e Chronicle o f Eusebius' (1979) has G r e e k
interest i n h i s t o r i c a l c h r o n o l o g y b e g i n w i t h H e r o d o t u s ,
whom
he
places i n b e t w e e n genealogy as a s i m p l e m e t h o d o f relative c h r o n o l ogy (e.g., Hecataeus a n d Pherecydes)
and chronography
(e.g.,
Hel-
lanicus), w h i c h records ' h i s t o r i c a l events precisely d a t e d b y reference to
an absolute
chronological system'.9
But
Mosshammer
rejects
a s i m p l i s t i c e v o l u t i o n a r y m o d e l : ' W h a t we shall f i n d , h o w e v e r , is n o t c o n f i r m a t i o n o f the e v o l u t i o n a r y hypothesis, w h i c h moves f r o m genealogy to c h r o n o g r a p h y . I n s t e a d , we shall find p r o o f t h a t G r e e k c h r o n o l o g i c a l t r a d i t i o n rests o n a w o n d e r f u l m i x t u r e o f i n g r e d i e n t s , n o o n e o f w h i c h can be distilled o u t w i t h o u t destroying the rest'
7
(Mosshammer
On this term and its significance for Herodotus' work, see Bakker, this volume (Ch. 1). For a narcological discussion of the temporal framework of the Histories, see de Jong, this volume, Ch. 11. Mosshammer (1979) 85. On Hecataeus FGrH 1 F 1-35, see Meyer (1892); on Pherecydes FGrH 3, see Ruschenbusch (1995), (1999), (2000); on Hellanicus FGrH 4 F 74-86, see Jacobv (1912) 114-27. 8
9
•
T H E O R G A N I Z A T I O N OF T I M E I N T H E
HISTORIES
391
(1979) 105). Herodotus' narrative reflects the different 'historical times' inherent in the various cultural traditions he draws on. I t is not the least part of his achievement to have constructed out of these a new continuum of space and time. Herodotus started the journey which Eusebius and Hieronymus completed. The tradition of research i n the field o f Herodotus' organization of time started with Eduard Meyer's influential article 'Herodots Chronologie der Sagengeschichte' (1892). Meyer did not allow for any interest i n chronology on Herodotus' part, either as regards the spatium mythicum, or, as he remarked in a later publication, as regards the spatium hisloricum. As Walter Burkert ((1995) 144) remarks: 'What Eduard Meyer the historian overlooked was that the question is not about historical fact, but about traditions.' Meyer's negative judgment was followed for a long time, for example by H o w and Wells and Felix Jacoby's substantial article i n Pauiy-Wissowa's supplement 2." A thorough study on early Greek genealogical chronology was conducted by Prakken (1943). Prakken worked along the lines of Meyer but he reached the opposite conclusion that Herodotus 'had a definite system of chronology and that this system was founded on genealogical principles'. Mitchel's (1956) examination of Herodotus' use o f genealogical chronology, using but not appreciating Prakken, modified Meyer's judgment only slightly. He makes an exception for the more recent past, but concludes for the remote past that, though it is a vague, misleading, arbitrary, and artificial method, counting by generations is the only way to arrange things. He clears up the terminological confusion by distinguishing between genealogy, mythography, mythical historiography, and genealogical chronology as part of historiography, all of these being genres that had developed in this order before Herodotus. As he sees this development mirrored in various examples i n Herodotus, Mitchel ((1956) 60) states that on the whole Herodotus was 'not concerned with establishing a consistent chronology for the mythical history'. 10
12
13
10
Meyer (1892) 185; Meyer (1937) 210 (Bouvier (2000) 123 n. 25 wrongly declares this reference of Strasburger (1956) 129 'fautive'). How and Wells (1928) I : 437-42; Jacoby (1913) 484. Further references in Strasburger (1956) 129-31; (1962) 678 80. See also Frankel (1960) 85 6; de Jong (1999) 233 5; Bichler and Rollinger (2000) 31-42. Prakken (1943) 18-48; quotation 47. I pass over the rather artificial 'marriage of historiography and arithmetic' of Miller (1965) 109. 11
12
13
392
JUSTUS
COBET
E r n s t B a d i a n w r i t e s ((1996) 58 n . 7) t h a t ' f o r study o f the n o n chronological nature of Herodotus' b e y o n d J o h n L. V'.14
Badian's
Myres'
o r g a n i z a t i o n one need n o t l o o k
classic Herodotus, Father of History, 1953
is the m o s t recent statement o n o u r subject I
ch.
know
of. I t does n o t take n o t i c e , h o w e v e r , o f Strasburger's t h o r o u g h invest i g a t i o n o f the c h r o n o l o g i c a l g r i d b e h i n d the spatium historicum i n the Histories. U n d e r t h e u n p r e t e n t i o u s title ' H e r o d o t s
Zeitrechnung',
his
a c c o u n t a p p e a r e d i n the same year as M i t c h e l ' s 'genealogical c h r o n o l o g y , ' a n d r e f e r r e d to a late positive statement o f J a c o b y ' s ((1949) 382 n.
10): ' H e r o d o t o s '
interest i n c h r o n o l o g y is obvious i n all parts o f
his w o r k , n o t f o r m y t h i c a l times o n l y , b u t f o r h i s t o r i c a l t i m e s , f o r w h i c h he gives epochs a n d dates o f reigns f o r the kings. I f he gives o n l y i s o l a t e d dates f o r G r e e k events t h a t c a n n o t be d a t e d b y Persian o r L y d i a n k i n g s , t h e o n l y possible i n f e r e n c e is t h a t he h a d n o m o r e to g i v e . ' Strasburger ((1956) 132;
(1962): 682) c o n c l u d e d : 'Er
d o c h der Erste, d e r M a n n , der [. . .] aus d e m C h a o s v o n
ist j a
Greisenge-
s c h w ä t z d e n K o s m o s d e r Geschichte geschaffen h a t ' . T h i s c o n c l u s i o n was contested b y d e n B o e r (1967), a l t h o u g h the c o n t r o v e r s y he raises seems t o be p r i m a r i l y a m a t t e r o f t e r m i n o l o g y . I f w e take d e n Boer's t e r m s s t r i c t l y , even o u r C h r i s t i a n era w o u l d n o t q u a l i f y f o r w h a t he calls 'absolute c h r o n o l o g y ' (den B o e r (1967) 30-5).
Den
B o e r offers a p o s i t i v e assessment
o f the m e t h o d
of
g e n e a l o g i c a l c h r o n o l o g y ( w h i c h he considers nevertheless i m p r e c i s e ) , b u t stresses the inconsistencies i n H e r o d o t u s '
a c c o u n t t h a t are d u e
to his sources (e.g., r o y a l lists), whose s y n c h r o n i s m s he f a i l e d to h a r monize.
H i s c o n c l u s i o n is t h a t H e r o d o t u s
d i d the best he c o u l d d o :
'Sein o r d n e n d e r Geist h a t die i h m z u r V e r f ü g u n g stehenden
man-
gelhaften M i t t e l i n ü b e r z e u g e n d e r A r t
Kurt
u n d Weise
benutzt."3
v o n F r i t z , i n his Griechische Geschichtsschreibung, dedicates a l o n g c h a p ter to the subject a l o n g the lines o f S t r a s b u r g e r , 1 6 a n d A .
B. L l o y d ' s
assessment e x p l i c i t l y rejects d e n Boer's i n t e r v e n t i o n : ' T h e r e c a n , i n fact, be n o d o u b t t h a t w h e n he set h i m s e l f d o w n to w r i t e the w o r k w h i c h w e k n o w he h a d d e v e l o p e d a c o h e r e n t a n d systematic scheme
14
Myres actually neither inquires into the topic nor advances an opinion on it. Lateiner (1989) 114 starts his chapter on chronology as follows: 'Chronological order provides the obvious principle of organization for most historians, but not for Herodotus.' Cf. Darbo-Peschanski (1987) 30-2. Den Boer (1967) 49; see also Prakken (1943). Von Fritz (1967) 364-406 (text); 2, 173-99 (notes). 15
16
THE
ORGANIZATION
OF TIME
IN T H E
393
HISTORIES
to serve as the f r a m e w o r k f o r his m o n u m e n t a l study' ( L l o y d (1975) 171;
172
n . 4).
T o m e i t is n o t as c o m p e l l i n g as i t is t o L l o y d t o i n f e r t h a t H e r o dotus c o n s t r u c t e d 'a g r i d o n w h i c h to base his h i s t o r i c a l n a r r a t i v e before even b e g i n n i n g the serious c o m p o s i t i o n o f his w o r k ' . 1 7 B u t there seems to be a g e n e r a l consensus to f o l l o w Strasburger i n a s s u m i n g that Herodotus
k n e w w h a t he was d o i n g w h e n he t r i e d t o c o o r d i -
nate the dates he c o u l d collect i n c o n n e c t i o n w i t h his n a r r a t i v e m a t e r i a l . T h e i n t e n t i o n o f the present chapter is to analyse a n d to i n t e r p r e t H e r o d o t u s ' o v e r a l l o r g a n i z a t i o n o f t i m e w i t h o u t s e p a r a t i n g the m y t h i c a l a n d the h i s t o r i c a l sections o f the Histories.
lii
I n o r d e r to facilitate
the e x p o s i t i o n o f the subject, I offer a n abstract g r i d w h i c h i n t e grates the m o r e
overt indications o f
time
Herodotus
gives i n the
course o f his n a r r a t i v e . A n t i c i p a t i n g m y analysis, I e x p l a i n the h i e r a r c h y o f c r i t e r i a I used i n c o n s t r u c t i n g this g r i d . I a m w e l l a w a r e o f the fact t h a t v a r i o u s intervals i n t i m e d o n o t c o r r e s p o n d w i t h each o t h e r v e r y w e l l ; b u t the g r i d helps t o see t h a t t o o . T h e g r i d is based o n the f o l l o w i n g i n d i c a t i o n s o f t i m e : 1. absolute figures i n d i c a t i n g i n t e r v a l s : 1.1 time;
es erne, t o H e r o d o t u s '
life-
1.2 o f r e g n a l years, a d d i n g u p t o the t i m e span o f a p a r -
t i c u l a r dynasty. 2. intervals o f t i m e m e a s u r e d b y c o u n t i n g generations: 2.1 as a m e r e indication of their number;
2.2 as a list o f names.
3. s y n c h r o n i s m s : 3.1 b e t w e e n specific h i s t o r i c a l events; 3.2
between
actors; 3.3 b e t w e e n generations. T h e r e also are some h a r m o n i z i n g c o m p r o m i s e s b e t w e e n these c r i t e r i a to be d e t e c t e d . I t m a y n o t be b y chance t h a t the g r i d I
finally
a r r i v e d at somewhat resembles w h a t H e l m reconstructed for Eusebius. 1 9
" Lloyd (1975) 194; on a possible distinction between Herodotus' gathering of knowledge and the actual composition of the Histories, see Rosier, this volume (Ch. 4). ' Cf. Burkert (1985) 15: 'Herodot als Historiker von Traditionen, nicht als Ausgräber von Fakten zu verstehen, ist eine Aufgabe, an der Historiker wie Philologen noch zu arbeiten haben.' Helm (1984). A first version is offered in Cobet (1999) 604 5; see also Asheri (1988) C X I I f. Helpful genealogical tabulations in Ruschenbusch (1995); D. Feil in Bichler (2000) 403-6. 18
19
394
JUSTUS
GOBET
T H E ORGANIZATION OF T I M E I N T H E
395
HISTORIES
Defining the Extension oj Time I n his first sentence, Herodotus announces a specific topic, the Persian Wars, which happened within his parents' lifetime. I n an unspecific way this event is embedded in a large open space of time, in which everything can happen, as he once says explicitly (5.9.3). I n the same general way, Greeks as well as barbarians, i n fact all the inhab itants of the Oikoumene, arc the general subject o f reference i n the Histories. Herodotus starts off his specific topic with an artificial construc tion, which distils from traditional Greek myths an argument about war guilt (1.1-5). This argument organizes time within the spatium mythicum through a significant chain of events. The turning point is the Trojan War, interpreted as an overreaction o f the Greeks to the abduction o f women by the barbarians. The chain o f abductions is a model o f how to create new meaning by arranging different sto ries in a specific order o f time. Yet he quotes it merely as a version of the prehistory o f the Persian Wars, only to put it aside i n favour of making a start with the Lydian K i n g Croesus (1.5 £). Only starting from Croesus does Herodotus begin to organize the threads o f his narrative and to count the years. For Herodotus, Croesus is an empirically well-documented point o f departure, both temporally and i n terms of the meaningful historical process which leads up to the only anchor date he offers at a particularly significant moment i n the course o f the events he wants to save from oblivion. The moment Xerxes took and destroyed Athens is the turning point of the story, which is designated with the remark that 'Calliades was Arkhon in Athens' (and qualified by the indication that it happened 'three months after he had crossed the Hellespont': the symbol o f Persian hubris in crossing over from Asia to Europe (8.51)). As Strasburger noted, every Greek could convert this date without further ado to his own time reckoning. The Athenocentric chronology is empha sized later on with Herodotus' remark that Athens had been cap tured for a second time 'nine months later' (dekarnenos egeneto, 9.3). 20
21
20
γένοιτο δ' αν παν έν τω μακρω χρόνφ (the Sigynnae may derive from the Medes). Cf. the notion of 'the whole time': 9.27 έν τω παντί χρόνφ: 9.73 ές τον πάντα χρόνον. Cf. Soph. Phil. 236: πολλά γαρ τάδε έν τφ μακρφ χρόνφ γένοιτ'αν άνδρώπων χρόνφ. See de Romilly (1971a) 87. Strasburger (1956) 136 (= (1962) 688): 'Jeder Grieche konnte dieses Datum ohne weiteres in seine Zeitrechnung umsetzen.' The harsh criticism of den Boer 21
396
JUSTUS COBET
Thucydides would later do the same thing, not, as Herodotus did, towards the end o f the historical process he studied, but at its very beginning, because he analysed the war, as he pretended (1.1), from its outset. I n meticulously synchronizing the Arkhon of Athens with the priestess o f Hera at Argos and the Spartan Ephorus (Thuc. 2.2), he did it i n a more elaborate way. Speaking o f the Athenian archon list first published i n the 420s, Mosshammer ((1979) 91 f.) points out that 'The publication o f such a list made historical chronology possible, while the scene o f history that Herodotus had brought to the Greek world made such work desirable.' The expansion, first of Croesus' empire, and subsequently that o f the Persian kings, is interpreted as a meaningfully coherent process. It provides a context for events, and so creates historical time. As this process proceeds, it begins to function as an abstract frame, i n connecting a great many different stories, each of which contains in a specific way its intrinsic economy o f time. O n the whole, Herodotus' text gives the impression o f having systematically paced and measured 'the large space of time' (5.9.3). Its dimensions reach back far beyond the 345 generations since the time o f the first human king in Egypt (2.143) and to the time, 17,000 years ago, when the gods around the Egyptian Heracles mingled as kings with men (2.43; 144 f ) . The rhythm o f nature differs from the rhythm of history. I n the long interval o f 11,340 years between the kings M i n and Sethos, the sun, as Herodotus reports, changed direction four times. But 'nothing i n Egypt was altered at these times—nothing growing i n the earth or living i n the river was any different, and there was no change i n the course o f diseases or i n the ways people died' (2.142). In another context Herodotus nevertheless reckons with a history o f nature. He empirically confirms the notion that the river Nile had built up the delta 'only recently' (neosti has logoi eipeiri); man had followed up north along with the growing land (2.15). Herodotus does not speculate about the origins o f man, and there is, of course, no 22
(1967) 32 f.) is mere word play; his own interpretation, it seems to me, concurs with what Strasburger wants to say: 'Das Invasionsjahr wurde in der mündlichen Tradition als 'das Jahr des Kalliades' bezeichnet.' Vannicelli (1993) 10-13 is in agreement with Strasburger. Lloyd (1975) 183 f. interprets this as the only weak point of Herodotus' organization of time; even more so Hunter (1982) 332. But compare Solon at 1.32.9: 'With everything you have to look at how it comes to an end' σκοπέειν δε χρη 22
παντός χρήματος την τελευτην κί) άποβήσεται.
•
T H E O R G A N I Z A T I O N OF T I M E I N T H E HISTORIES
myth o f creation to be found i n he mentions that at some time tence. ' The idea that they always continuum o f time includes the 2
397
his work. I t is only in passing that men have had to come into exis have been there prevails. Herodotus' gods. 24
Horizons of Memory and Beyond 'When working, as Herodotus worked, with neither an era nor reli able documents, one must obviously begin with his own time and work backwards. The closer to the present, the greater the com pleteness and accuracy o f the account' (Mitchel (1956) 48). Thucydides looks back briefly to 'ancient history' and in somewhat more detail to the recent past, but he wrote about the present, progressing as things happened, being eyewitness himself and inquiring with his contemporaries (1-22). Herodotus wrote on the recent past and on events further back, beyond the confines o f his personal memory. He could inquire personally into the memory o f those who lived in the generations o f his parents and grandparents, but beyond that horizon he depended on other cultural techniques to preserve or to imagine some memory o f the past. ' U p to my own time' (es erne) is in various contextual functions the most common way i n which Herodotus talks about some point in the past with respect to his own and his audience's present; the expression constitutes so to speak the chronological base line o f the Histories.' 'Even now' (alia kai nun) many Ionians are ashamed of their name remembering their subjection by Cyrus (1.143); Xerxes in 480 BC could not subjugate the Thracian tribe o f the Satrae (7.111): they are 'still free until my time' (to mekhri emeu aiei eontes eleutheroi); K i n g Amasis o f Egypt installed a law to enforce the declaration o f yearly income which Solon introduced to Athens, where it is 'still in use' (toi ekeinoi es aiei khredntai, 2.177). 25
T h e interval between his topic, the Persian Wars, and his own lifetime, is most clearly expressed w i t h i n the context o f Xerxes'
23
έξ ού άνβρώπων γένος έγένετο, 2.15. Against Darbo-Peschanski (1987) 25-38. Powell (1938) 146 quotes this or the like expression 32 times. More than fifty references of this type in Schmid and Staehlin (1934) 590 n. 9; cf. Cobet (1971) 53 f; 59 f; Rosier, this volume (Ch. 4), 91-92. 24
25
398
JUSTUS
COBET
approaching the Greek heartland (7.137 f.). Asking about the final retaliation for the sacrilege o f killing Persian envoys i n Sparta i n 490 BC (6.48), Herodotus finds the answer i n the death o f their sons Sperthias and Boulis, who had ottered satisfaction to Xerxes: this happened 'much later' (khronoi de metepeita polloi), at the time o f the war between the Peloponnesians and the Athenians' (7.137.1). But only with the help o f Thucydides are we able to call it the year 430 BC (Thuc. 2.67). I n other words, the time at which Herodotus was working on the Histoiies and the present of his immediate audience is not related to the time o f his main theme in any more precise way than by the distance o f that one generation. Consequently, 'up to my own time' refers to the personal memory o f his own generation of, say, the 450s to the early 420s. Beginning with the Ionian revolt o f 499 B C , halfway through the Histories (at 5.28 if.), Herodotus relates i n close sequence, arranging events almost year by year, i n the end even counting months and days, from the destruction o f Miletus and the Persian defeat at Marathon up to Salamis 480 BC (with the 'anchor date' 8.51) and Plataea 479 B C . ' Greek and oriental history are i n close interaction, and so there is need for explicit synchronization only i n a few cases, for example to connect the western Greeks with the main events (7.166). O f course, both sides do not remember the same story, and Herodotus takes care to arrange his narrative i n such a way as to keep this difference i n the reader's mind. O f course, he adopts the Greek perspective, as he opposes the Persian king to Demaratus the Spartan i n conversation (7.101-5; 209), or Greek and Persian aristocrats at the symposium o f Attaginus (9.15 f ) . A participant i n the latter event was one o f Herodotus' informants. The Persian (and Phoenician) interpretation of the Persian-Greek conflict which he had presented i n the introductory chapters (1.1-5) may derive from a similar social situation. 26
2
Knowledge through personal testimony reaches back three generations, a distance which Herodotus equates with one hundred years (2.142), ' i l suo campo storico' (Vannicelli), Bichler's and Rollinger's
26
The elate of his akmë (444 BC) is deduced from Apollodorus FGrH 244 F 7; see also Jacoby (1913) 230. Strasburger (1956) 151-6; (1962) 710 17. Cf. Bouvier (2000) 123 f.; 131. It is on the level of the smaller units of time that Bouvier inquires into Herodotus' 'procedures de connexion' between 'le temps cosmique' and 'le temps discursif. 21
T H E O R G A N I Z A T I O N OF T I M E I N T H E
399
HISTORIES
'Erzahlzeit' from Croesus to Xerxes, or simply 'the recent past' (Vansina), He consulted Archias, son of Samius, grandson of Archias, about the expedition of Sparta against Samos of c. 525 B C , during which the grandfather fought at Samos with great bravery (3.55). I n Athens Herodotus may have talked to Zopyrus, son of Megabyzus, son o f Zopyrus, who had played an important role i n Darius' reconquest o f Babylon in 521 BC. His son Megabyzus came to Greece with Xerxes in 480 BC (7.82; 121) and fought against the Athenians in Egypt about 455 B C , but the grandson j o i n e d the Athenians towards 440 BC (3.160). The recapturing of Babylon at the beginning of Darius' reign is synchronized with the end of Polycrates of Samos. Since the pluriform nature of Greek oral tradition, with its focus on aristocratic families and disparate poleis, does not allow for any grid of chronology even within the three generations' span of time, orientation has to come from the oriental kingdoms: 'The tales of the Greeks are many and absurd', that is, contradictory. Further back in time, beyond the reconquest of Babylon of 521 BC, one reaches the destruction o f Sardes of c. 547 BC, a date that is not exactly fixed within the reign of Cyrus, but that can be extrapolated fairly plausibly from various synchronisms in the Histories. I t is certainly a major chronological orientation point in his narrative, and also probably the earliest one within the horizon of orally transmitted memory available to Herodotus. Xenophanes of Colophon, who lived up to the generation of our author's parents, took this event as a particular point of reference in the memory o f his peers: ' I n winter, at the fire place, small talk may begin with the question: 28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
30
28
Vannicelli (1993) 14 f.; Bichler and Rollinger (2000) 31 f.; Vansina (1985) 23 f.; 168f. Cf. Schott (1968); Thomas (1989) 108-23; 186; Ruschenbusch (1992). According to Herodotus at the same time as Cambyses' campaign against Egypt (3.44) and not a long time before Polycrates' death (3.120-5). Herodotus rarely gave the name of a personal informant he talked to: 2.55; 4.76; 9.16. How and Wells (1928) ad toe. Hdt. 3.150; cf. 140; 133: 127; 126; 120. Thomas (1989) 108-23; 155-95.; Raaflaub (1988a); Cobet (1988a). Bouvier (2000) 120-2. Strasburger (1956) 134 f; 151; (1962) 686; 710 f. Hacataeus, FGrH 1 F 1; Thomas (1989) 183. Strasburger (1962) 684 n. 27; 693. The external confirmation of 547 BC by the chronicle of Nabonid unfortunately depends on a conjecture: Rollinger (1993) excursus 1; Cobet (1997) 259 n. 104. 29
30
31
32
33
34
35
:il>
400
JUSTUS
COBET
" W h e r e d o y o u c o m e f r o m ? T e l l m e y o u r age. H o w
old were you
w h e n the M e d e c a m e (pelikos esth' hoth' ho Medos aphiketo)?" " r
With
Peisistratus o f A t h e n s g a i n i n g t y r a n n y f o r t h e first t i m e a r o u n d 5 6 0 BC
( 1 . 5 9 - 6 5 ) , w e are o b v i o u s l y at t h e v e r y edge o f the o r a l h o r i -
z o n ( R u s c h e n b u s c h (1992)), because w e c a n n o t u n e q u i v o c a l l y insert i n t o his t i m e g r i d the t h i r t y - s i x years o f his a n d his sons' t y r a n n y o f w h i c h H e r o d o t u s speaks (5.67). 3 8 B e y o n d this h o r i z o n there are the s y n c h r o n i s m s b e t w e e n Croesus a n d the wise m e n S o l o n T h a l e s (1.75), Pittacus (1.27), a n d Bias (ibid.).
29
(1.29-33),
T h e r e is C y l o n 'before
the t i m e o f Peisistratus' (5.71), b u t n o D r a c o . B e y o n d the t h r e e g e n e r a t i o n s ' t h r e s h o l d a r o u n d t h e m i d d l e o f the sixth century BC
t h e r e is a n o t h e r h o r i z o n o f m o r e o r less c o h e r e n t
t r a d i t i o n n o t d e p e n d i n g o n p e r s o n a l m e m o r i e s b u t o n some k i n d o f w r i t t e n sources. I t is r e p r e s e n t e d b y the dynastic sequence o f t h e L y d i a n s , the M e d e s , a n d the Persians (rather t h a n o f the Assyrians a n d B a b y l o n i a n s ) , 4 0 a n d o f t h e Saitic kings i n E g y p t : M a n e t h o ' s 2 6 t h d y n a s t y , b a c k t o a r o u n d 700
BC.
Das chronologische R ü c k g r a t des gesamten Werkes, bzw. der Teile, die literarisch als H a u p t e r z ä h l u n g zu betrachten sind, bildet also die Reihe der medisch-persischen K ö n i g e m i t ihren lückenlos verzeichneten R e g i e r u n g s l ä n g e n , vor welche für die Zeit vor Kyros die ungefähr gleichzeitige Reihe der lydischen Herrscher kompositioneil vorgelagert w i r d , weil die lydische Geschichte, i m Gegensatz zu der medischen, zahlreiche B e r ü h r u n g s p u n k t e m i t der griechischen Geschichte aufweist und damit zugleich eine Reihe loser Einzelzüge aus letzterer zeitlich einzuordnen erlaubte. 41
T h i s h o r i z o n reaches i n fact b a c k t o the t i m e o f H o m e r a n d H e s i o d , b u t this was u n k n o w n t o H e r o d o t u s a n d the Greeks, w h o p u t t h e m b e y o n d t h a t l i n e (2.53). T h e y w e r e u n a b l e t o s y n c h r o n i z e t h e i r early a r c h a i c p e r i o d w i t h t h e o r i e n t a l kings w i t h a n y p r e c i s i o n , t h o u g h a r o u n d 600 BC
37
the b r o t h e r o f Alcaeus w e n t t o M e s o p o t a m i a (Ale.
Xenophanes fr. 18 Diehl = 22 D - K ; cf. Drews (1973) 7. Strasburger (1962) 693 n. 36; Den Boer (1967) 57 f. Fehling (1985) 78-104. The epoch-making destruction of (Assur and) Nineveh about 612 BC is mentioned and can be attributed to the time of the Mede Cyaxares (1.103; 106). Herodotus does not keep his promise to tell more about it (1.106; 184, see also Bakker,, this volume, Ch. 1, n. 25 and Rosier, Ch. 4, n. 17). Cf. Phocylides fr. 4 Diehl; the prophet Nahum in the Old Testament. Strasburger (1956) 150; (1962) 710 f. Cf. Drews (1969); Burkert (1995) 140 f. 38 39
40
41
401
T H E O R G A N I Z A T I O N OF T I M E I N T H E HISTORIES
fr. 50 Diehl = 350 L—P), and Greek mercenaries under Psammetichus fought i n Egypt (Hdt. 2.154; Syll. 1). The earlier generations of the older tyranny i n Greece are notoriously difficult to reconcile with chronology. The oriental dynasties are connected with each other at least through the Persian expansion as they are all incorporated into the Persian empire at various dates. Nevertheless, none o f those can be securely attributed to a certain year on the basis o f Herodotus' narrative alone, and the date o f the battle o f M a y 28, 585 B C between the Lydians and the Medes i n Herodotus' time grid does not match the dates o f both kings in question (1.74; 103). Beyond 700 B C , there are genealogical constructions—and o f course there is Egypt, with its additional, now rather episodical row of kings which stretches back to Moeris, which is followed by speculations involving fantastic figures leading back to an undefined beginning. These are dimensions which Hecataeus and the Greeks could hardly imagine (2.143). T h e Phoenicians, who founded Tyre 2,300 years before Herodotus, occupy an intermediate position (2.44). Within Egyptian temporal dimensions he remarks that the Delta had come into existence 'just recently' (neosti 2.15), which translates into twenty or rather ten thousand years (2.11). I n Greek dimensions he speaks of neosti about Cadmus, his earliest point o f reference for Greek genealogical constructions (2.49). H o m e r and Hesiod lived, as he guessed, no more than four hundred years ago, which is like 'only yesterday or the day before so to speak' (proen te kai khthes hos eipein logdi, 2.53). W i t h the Egyptians Herodotus could make up his m i n d about definitions o f time and history. ' ' O f all men I happened to come across they exercise memory most and have the most to tell' (mnemen anthropon ponton epaskeontes malista logiotatoi eisi makroi ton ego es diapeiran apikomen, 2.77). Throughout Book T w o , Herodotus reports on architecture and monuments which bear testimony to an ancient culture. The Egyptians invented the calender to measure the rhythm of the years (2.4). What Herodotus systematizes as the progress i n time, to be sure, involves construction, rather than memory. The 3
42
43
44
4
18
It is a matter of taste to admire how much Herodotus' time grid is in agreement with modern reconstruction (Strasburger) or to stress its inconsistencies (den Boer). Den Boer (1967) 42; 52 f. Lloyd (1975) 185-94 and commentary (1976); Brown (1962) 260-3. Cobet (1971) 127 37; Hunter (1982) 50 92. 43
4 4
45
402
JUSTUS
COBET
whole scheme nevertheless explores time as the comprehensive space of history. Its beginning is undetermined beyond seventeen thousand years (2.145). A t its other end it runs into the grid of oriental dynasties. The quality of Herodotus' scheme as a statement about Egyptian history is moulded by his informants. I t primarily involves the organization of time. This has been effected by characteristically distinct means. The sequence of its sections mirrors a difference in knowledge, a difference in the quality of memory and traditions as they congealed somewhere on the way between, say, Egyptian priests and inquiring Ionians. The Sake dynasty is plausibly described as a realistic sequence (2.151—3.15). T o Herodotus this is due to the knowledge of the Greeks i n Egypt (1.147; 154). Going back in time, the section from Sethos to Moeris, attributed to Egyptian priests (2.142), is no longer a dynastic sequence. I t includes fragments of different dynasties and bridges time through abstract arithmetics, that is, genealogy without names (2.142). This is even more true of the adjacent section, which does not provide any name besides the cornerstones Moeris and M i n (2.99—101). M i n stands at the beginning o f the human race (anlhropon geneas, 2.142). He is supposed to have been the first human being to become king of Egypt (basileusai de proton Aiguptou anthropon elegon Mina, 2.4). Before M i n , the kings were gods, but there were Egyptians already, who 'existed as long as man existed' (aiei te anai ex hou anlhropon genos egeneto, 2.15), and there is a continu u m in time and even a rhythm of three sequences of gods (2.144 f ) . Herodotus inquired about beginnings with the priests in Heliopolis, who are supposed to be 'the most knowledgeable i n logoi, things to tell' (logiotatoi, 2.3). But as far as things divine are concerned, Herodotus wouid not write down what he heard, because 'all men are equal in not knowing about such things' (nomizon pantas antkropous ison pen auton [sc. ta tkeia] epistasthai, 2.3). 46
Etkne and Historical Time W i t h ethne, tribes or nations, as described by Herodotus in the Histories, the status of historical time is very different from that of empires,
4 6
I n essence it accords to what we now know from Egyptian sources: Lloyd (1975) 191 3.
THE
ORGANIZATION
OF TIME
IN T H E
HISTORIES
403
dynasties, or Greek cities. The Scythians are introduced as the youngest o f all nations, the opposite of the Egyptians (4.5). The Scythians extended i n space as the Egyptians extended i n time. The way i n which they use the vast open spaces, which are structured by an elaborate system o f rivers is even thought to be to their credit (4.46 £). Ethne have no history and time makes no difference for their culture and way of life. This seems to be also true for the Massagetae (1.201-4; 215 f.), the Aethiopians (3.17 24), the Indians (3.98-105) as well as for the Libyans, who are the subject o f an extended logos (4.168-99); even the Psyllians are part of the tableau, though they had had their time and i n that sense are history (4.173). There are other splinters o f history: for example, the Libyans are part o f history through Greek colonization (4.178 f.), and the tribe of the Maxyes because they were immigrants from T r o y (4.191). Such contacts with 'history' are especially relevant i n the case of the Thracians, who in spite o f their static ethnology (5.3-10; 16) lived close to the scene o f the Persian Wars and their antecedents (Asheri (1990)). They had been the object o f the expedition o f the Egyptian king Sesostris, who can be found i n the time grid two generations before the Trojan W a r (2.103). Explicitly 'before the Trojan War' (pro ton Troikon genomenon, 7.20) is Herodotus' date for the deportation of some Thracians to Bithynia (7.20; 75). The same has to be assumed for the immigration o f Thracian Paeonians from the Troas to the Strymon (5.13)." The immigration o f the Thracian Sigynnae has to be dated within the horizon of Herodotus' oriental dynasties, say, to the generations of Phraortes, Cyaxares, and Astyages, though our author confesses to having no idea about the circumstances or the date. I n connection with this detail, he quotes what sounds like a proverb: ' I n the long span o f time everything may happen' (5.9.3). The Paeonians conquered Perinthus some time 'before' Darius' Scythian and Megabazus' Thracian expedition (ta men proteron genomena . . . tote de. . ., 5.1 f ) . Some tribes o f the Paeonians were deported to Asia M i n o r by Megabazus not long after his Thracian expedition, as can be deduced from the narrative sequence (5.12-15; 23; 98). There are several Thracian involvements w i t h Athenian and Persian politics i n the decades before M a r a t h o n (6.33-41), and some more events directly connected with Xerxes' expedition o f 480 B C
7
Asheri (1990) 153 f.: to be connected with //. 2.844 f.
404
JUSTUS
COBET
(e.g., 7.75; 110, see A s h e r i (1990) 156 f f . ) . F i n a l l y , i n a f e w instances H e r o d o t u s m e n t i o n s i n c i d e n t s b e l o n g i n g t o t h e t i m e after t h e Persian W a r s , b u t he gives n o exact dates. Expressions like 'later' (9.75) o r ' m a n y years l a t e r ' (4.78) d o n o t r e f e r , say, t o 4 8 0 B C
but to the
respective c o n t e x t . T h e sons o f the Spartans Sperthias a n d Bulis w e r e seized b y t h e T h r a c i a n K i n g Sitalces t o be d e l i v e r e d to the A t h e n i a n s ' m u c h later [sc. t h a n X e r x e s ' e x p e d i t i o n ] , i n t h e t i m e o f t h e w a r b e t w e e n t h e Peloponnesians a n d t h e A t h e n i a n s ' (7.137). Several o f the e a r l i e r T h r a c i a n i n v o l v e m e n t s i n h i s t o r y like Sesostris' e x p e d i t i o n are r e l a t e d t o H e r o d o t u s ' t h e m e o f A s i a versus E u r o p e . 4 8 T h e r e are also i n d i c a t i o n s o f a n o t h e r m a j o r subject: ethnos versus e m p i r e . W i t h c e r t a i n Paeonians (5.16) a n d w i t h the Satrae (7.110 f.) t h e c u l t u r a l i n n o c e n c e o f p r i m i t i v e life is a s t r e n g t h t h e Persian c o u l d n o t cope w i t h .
empire
I n this case t h e t w o sides f u n c t i o n w i t h i n
different notions o f time. I f ethne have a h i s t o r y o f t h e i r o w n a t a l l , i t is stories a b o u t b e g i n nings. T h e r e a r e t w o stereotypes w h i c h e x p l a i n w h y p e o p l e c a m e t o be w h e r e they l i v e d . E i t h e r they have always been there as ' a u t o c h thons',
c
Ureinwohner\
or they came
there a l o n g time ago. Both
possibilities are c o n s i d e r e d w i t h t h e G a r i a n s , G a u n i a n s , a n d L y c i a n s (1.171-3). Herodotus
summarizes
the L y b i a n
logos as follows: T w o
n a t i o n s , t h e Greeks a n d t h e P h o e n i c i a n s , c a m e t o L y b i a as i m m i grants, b u t the Libyans
a n d A e t h i o p i a n s w e r e ' a b o r i g i n e s ' (4.197).
I n t h e case o f t h e S c y t h i a n s , m o r e space is g i v e n to b e g i n n i n g s . Herodotus
gives t h r e e v e r s i o n s . T h e S c y t h i a n v e r s i o n b u i l d s o n
a u t o c h t h o n y ( 4 . 5 - 7 ) . T h e first m a n i n t h e still u n i n h a b i t e d c o u n t r y was b o r n f r o m Zeus a n d a d a u g h t e r o f t h e R i v e r Borysthenes. T h e S c y t h i a n s , a s s u m i n g t h a t t h e y are t h e y o u n g e s t o f a l l p e o p l e , i m a g i n e t h a t this h a p p e n e d o n e t h o u s a n d years before D a r i u s '
expedi-
t i o n . A c c o r d i n g t o t h e G r e e k v e r s i o n , i t started w i t h Scythes b o r n f r o m a m a i d h a l f snake, l i v i n g i n the e m p t y c o u n t r y i n a cave, w h o j o i n e d i n love w i t h Heracles ( 4 . 8 - 1 0 ) . T h i s makes t h e Scythians still a f e w generations y o u n g e r , as appears f r o m t h e t i m e g r i d .
Herodotus
h i m s e l f prefers t o have t h e m i m m i g r a t e d f r o m A s i a ( 4 . 1 1 - 1 3 ) . ' L o n g a g o ' (to palaiori) t h e c o u n t r y h a d been i n h a b i t e d b y t h e C i m m e r i a n s , w h o f o r t h e i r p a r t left t h e c o u n t r y e m p t y w h e n they e m i g r a t e d t o A s i a , w h e r e they are m e n t i o n e d i n c o n n e c t i o n w i t h t h e t i m e o f t h e
48
Asheri (1990) 151 ff.; 162.
T H E O R G A N I Z A T I O N OF T I M E I N T H E
L y d i a n K i n g A r d y s (1.6; Egyptian
405
HISTORIES
15), C y a x a r e s , k i n g o f d i e M e d e s , a n d the
P s a m m e t i c h u s (1.103; 4 . 1 ; 7.20), a t i m e span o f t w o g e n -
erations ( H a r m a t t a
(1990)).
W i t h the ethne, space, t i m e , a n d m e a n i n g c o n v e r g e i n t o a special j u n c t i o n . O f t e n the ethne are i n t e g r a t e d i n t o H e r o d o t u s ' o f t i m e a n d space b y c o n t i n g e n c y . T h e
continuum
c u l t u r e o f 'alterité'
(Hartog
1980) is s t u d i e d alongside the course b y w h i c h the histoire événementielle a c c o m p a n i e s the reader t h r o u g h t i m e a n d space, t h a t is, the Lydian
a n d Persian e x p a n s i o n . Ethne, w h i c h are ' p r i m i t i v e ' i n t h e
sense o f l i v i n g close to n a t u r e , a n d w h i c h c e r t a i n l y d o n o t f o r m an e m p i r e , c o n s t i t u t e i n H e r o d o t u s ' n a r r a t i v e a f u n d a m e n t a l antithesis to i m p e r i a l g o v e r n m e n t : ' O t h e r n e s s ' creates a special m e a n i n g i n the Histories i n c o n n e c t i o n w i t h t h e Persian e x p a n s i o n . T h e Persian k i n g is n o t a 'just m a n (anêr dikaios), o t h e r w i s e he w o u l d n o t l o n g f o r l a n d b e l o n g i n g to someone else', as H e r o d o t u s r e s p o n d t o t h e P e r s i a n envoys
has the A e t h i o p i a n k i n g
(3.21). H i s
narrative explains the
Persian failures p a r t i c u l a r l y i n c o n n e c t i o n w i t h t h e conflicts w i t h t h e Massagetae
(Cyrus),
A e t h i o p i a n s (Cambyses),
Scythians
(Darius)—
a n d t h e G r e e k s , w h o also are h a p p y w i t h t h e i r f r e e d o m t h o u g h l i v i n g i n a p o o r c o u n t r y (7.102). 4 9 I n the e n c o u n t e r o f ethne w i t h hist o r y , t w o d i f f e r e n t m o d i o f h i s t o r i c a l t i m e are c o n f r o n t e d w i t h each o t h e r . I n o r d e r f o r the Greeks to be e x c l u d e d f r o m this i n t e r p r e t a t i o n , t h e ' p r i m i t i v e ' ethnë i n this n o t i o n fill o u t space r a t h e r t h a n t i m e . T h i s o p p o s i t i o n r e m i n d s us o f H o m e r ' s C y c l o p e a n society (Od. 9 . 1 0 5 - 1 5 ) a n d exemplifies 'the coexistence o f d i f f e r e n t t i m e s ' . 5 0 T h i s n o t i o n is p a r t o f H e r o d o t u s ' c o n c e p t o f ' h i s t o r i c a l t i m e ' .
S p a t i u m H i s t o r i c u m , S p a t i u m M y t h i c u m , and the Floating Gap Strasburger (1956) c o n f i n e d his i n v e s t i g a t i o n t o the o r i e n t a l dynasties. H e e x p l i c i t l y e x c l u d e d ' S a g e n c h r o n o l o g i e ' as the spatium mythicum, set aside b y H e r o d o t u s '
4
'Abschiedsgeste a n d e n M y t h o s ' . T h i s was
" Cobet (1971) 101 flf.; 107-20. 'Gleichzeitigkeit des Ungleichzeidgen': Kosellcck (1979) 222 f.; 32 ff. Cf. Kracauer (1973) 166 ff. Locus classicus is Thucydides' Archaeology (1.6): 'It could be shown by many examples, how the Greeks of old lived the same customs as the barbarians today.' Cf. John Locke, Two treatises of government (1690) I I : 5. O f property § 49: 'Thus in the beginning all the world was America [. . . ] ; for no such thing as money was anywhere known.' 50
406
JUSTUS
GOBET
his i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f the phrase s e p a r a t i n g t h e sequence o f m y t h i c a l abductions o f w o m e n
f r o m the definite starting point o f the histor-
ical n a r r a t i v e , Croesus' rise t o p o w e r
(1.5f.). 5 1 T h i s accords t o t h e
conventional w o r k i n g definition o f the ancient writers c o m m u n i c a t e d b y C e n s o r i n u s , based o n t h e experience o f a specific historia perpétua, o f w h i c h H e r o d o t u s is o n l y t h e b e g i n n i n g : A n d i f the origin of the w o r l d had come to the knowledge of man. we w o u l d take the outset f r o m there. But now I will treat that span of time (intewallum temporis), which V a r r o called historical [ιστορικόν). H e transmits that there are three distinctive times (tria discrimina temporum): 1) f r o m the first men to the first flood, w h i c h because of ignorance is called imperceptible (αδηλον); 2} f r o m the first flood to the first Olympics, which, because m u c h i n it is related fabulously (quia multa in eo fabulosa referuntur), is named mythical (μυθικόν); 3) f r o m the first Olympics to our time (ad nos), which is denominated historical (ιστορικόν), because it contains events and deeds based on real histories (quia res in eo ges 1
tae vais historiis continentur)?'
T h i s is a p e r i o d i z a t i o n , w h i c h i m p l i e s i n p r i n c i p l e a c o n t i n u i t y o f history. T h e criterion o n w h i c h different periods o f historical time are d i s t i n g u i s h e d is k n o w l e d g e ,
as is also t r u e f o r H e r o d o t u s ( v o n
Leyden (1949/50) 9 4 - 6 ) . At
first sight, H e r o d o t u s '
spatium historicum is the h o r i z o n
o f the
o r i e n t a l dynasties, at least as f a r as E g y p t i a n h i s t o r y is c o n c e r n e d . Because o f t h e contacts b e t w e e n K i n g Psammetichus
the lonians a n d Carians
(whom
h a d called t o settle i n E g y p t ) o n the one h a n d
a n d t h e Greeks o n t h e o t h e r , ' w e k n o w e v e r y t h i n g t h a t i n Egypt f r o m the time o f K i n g Psammetichus
happened
o n w a r d s w i t h cer
t a i n t y ' (atrekeos, 2 . 1 5 4 ) . T h e section o n o l d e r E g y p t i a n h i s t o r y is set a p a r t f r o m t h e Saitic dynasty because o f t h e use o f o t h e r i n f o r m a n t s ( i . e . , t h e E g y p t i a n priests: 2.142) a n d b y g e n e r a l considerations o n the d i m e n s i o n s o f t i m e i n h i s t o r y ( 2 . 1 4 2 - 6 ) . B u t n o t o n l y is c o n t i n u i t y o f h i s t o r y t h e p o i n t he o b v i o u s l y i n t e n d s t o c l a r i f y , b u t he even refers t o w r i t t e n sources w h i c h attest t h e 3 3 0 E g y p t i a n kings start i n g w i t h M i n (2.100).53 Der Mythos w i r d nicht von innen heraus kritisiert, sondern i h m eine andere T r a d i t i o n entgegengesetzt; u n d indem die reale Kenntnis der
Strasburger (1956) 134; (1962) 685 f.; (1982) 841 f.; 871 f.; 913. Censorinus, De die natali 21.1 (ed. Sallmann). Hunter (1982) 63 f.; Hampl (1979) 116-22.
THE
ORGANIZATION
O F TIME
IN THE
407
HISTORIES
Vergangenheit weiter i n diese hineinzuleuchten scheint, weicht das Mythische einfach i n die fernere Vergangenheit z u r ü c k . ' 4
T h e b e g i n n i n g s o f h u m a n h i s t o r y are i n t e r w o v e n w i t h t h e presence o n e a r t h o f gods: t h e t i m e b e f o r e M i n i n E g y p t , a n d the generations a b o u t D i o n y s u s , Heracles, a n d P a n i n Greece (2.145). H e r o d o t u s started t h e E g y p t i a n logos w i t h t h e q u e s t i o n w h o o f a l l h u m a n beings w e r e ' t h e first' (prötous genesthai pardon anthröpön, 2 . 2 ) , o r , i n o u r term i n o l o g y , ' i n h i s t o r y ' . I n q u i r i n g f u r t h e r a b o u t b e g i n n i n g s , he makes the r e m a r k a b o u t l e a v i n g aside ' d i v i n e questions' (ta theia, 2.3) q u o t e d a b o v e , t o start the section o n E g y p t i a n
culture i n the next chapter:
'As f a r as h u m a n m a t t e r s are c o n c e r n e d . ' . . . ihosa de anthröpeia preg-
mata . , . 2.4). S p e a k i n g a b o u t Polycrates a n d M i n o s i n t e r m s o f 'thalassocratia' (sea p o w e r ) , H e r o d o t u s distinguishes the f o r m e r f r o m the latter (3.122): 'Polycrates r e a l l y is the first o f t h e Greeks w e k n o w o f (prvtos ton hemeis idmen Ellenon) w h o r u l e d over t h e sea- - e x c e p t f o r t h e Gnossian M i n o s o r i f someone else before h i m (proteros toutou) r u l e d over the sea.' B u t Polycrates was t h e first ' w i t h i n t h e so-called h u m a n g e n e r a t i o n ' (tes de anthrbpeies legomenes genees). T h i s passage is t h e locus classicus f o r a d i s t i n c t i o n i n H e r o d o t u s b e t w e e n a temps des dieux a n d a temps des hommes, o r t h e s e p a r a t i o n o f m y t h f r o m h i s t o r y . 0 5 A b o u t t h e ' t i m e o f t h e gods' H e r o d o t u s d i d n o t w a n t t o talk; as f a r as c h r o n o l ogy is c o n c e r n e d , i t occupies n o absolute p o s i t i o n . T h e t i m e o f t h e (Greek) heroes is d i f f e r e n t f o r H e r o d o t u s . H e reflects o n their influence o n h u m a n affairs, j u s t as he does w i t h t h e gods (2.45; 8.109).
Heroes
are n o t c o m p l e t e l y s u p e r h u m a n (2.45), b u t t h e bones o f Orestes are o f s o m e w h a t l a r g e r size t h a n m e n o f t o d a y (1.67 f . ) . V a n d i v e r (1991) takes t h e heroes i n H e r o d o t u s the same Herodotus
time:
t o represent t w o k i n d s o f r e a l i t y at
that o f traditional m y t h
a n d that o f history. As
exemplifies w i t h H e r a c l e s (2.44), t h e t i m e o f t h e heroes
is d i f f e r e n t f r o m t h e t i m e o f t h e gods. 0 '' H e r o e s
54
do represent a
Von Fritz (1967) I : 183. Vidal-Naquet (1960); Finley (1975); Darbo-Peschanski (1987) 25-38. More references Hunter (1982) 104 n. 9; see also, in this volume, Bocdeker (Gh. 5, p. 110), Raaflaub (Ch. 7, n. 36), and Osborne (Ch. 22, p. 499). Hesiod's age of the heroes (Op. 156-73) is strictly separated from the 'iron age', which we may call the spatium historicum. They are 'a divine kin called halfgods, who lived before us on the boundless earth' (άνδρων ηρώων θείον γένος, o'i καλέονται ημίθεοι, πρότερη γενεή κατά άπείρονα γαϊαν 159 f.). They fought at Thebes and at Troy; after Troy the gods separated from living with men (fr. 204). 55
36
408
JUSTUS
COBET
distinctive p e r i o d w i t h i n the t i m e g r i d . T h e generation o f the T r o j a n W a r a n d m o r e so the g e n e r a t i o n o f Heracles'" are the m a j o r dates o f reference w i t h i n the spatium mylhicum, w h i c h extends n i n e
gener-
ations, o r a b o u t t h r e e h u n d r e d years, f r o m C a d m u s (2.145; 4 . 1 4 7 ; 5 . 5 8 f.) to Orestes. I f T h u c y d i d e s i n the A r c h a e o l o g y c o m p l e t e l y levelled the difference b e t w e e n the t i m e o f the heroes a n d t h a t o f later p e r i o d s , a c c o r d i n g to H u n t e r ((1982) 9 3 - 1 1 5 ) H e r o d o t u s himself pointed out,
'Er
behandelt
d i d the same. As
Strasburger
die m e n s c h l i c h e n F i g u r e n
M y t h o s w e i t e r als h i s t o r i s c h e . ' M i n o s is a g o o d e x a m p l e ( 1 . 1 7 1 ;
des 173).
Strasburger's c o n c l u s i o n is a m b i g u o u s : ' U n d d o c h zieht er a u c h zwischen d e m entgötterten bzw. Geschichte
rationalisierten Mythos
noch u n d
der
[. . . ] , w i e w o h l e r es n i r g e n d s s c h a r f u n d p r i n z i p i e l l
ausspricht, e i n e n d e u d i c h e n T r e n n u n g s s t r i c h . ' 5 8 ' L o n g ago (to pahion) the Carians
w e r e subjects o f M i n o s '
(1.171). A t
the battlefield o f
Plataea, the A t h e n i a n s d i s p u t e d the T e g e a n s ' c l a i m o f p r i o r i t y , u s i n g 'recent' as o p p o s e d to ' a n c i e n t h i s t o r y ' as a n a r g u m e n t , b o t h sides ' p u t t i n g f o r t h b o t h recent a n d a n c i e n t a c c o m p l i s h m e n t s ' (kai kaina kai palaia parapherontes erga, 9.26). M a r a t h o n represented recent t i m e , the past events w e r e 'the w a r against T h e b e s ' , 'a c a m p a i g n against the A m a z o n s ' , the T r o j a n W a r ,
a n d ' t h e r e t u r n o f the H e r a c l i d a e ' .
On
the o t h e r h a n d , to palaion c o u l d also refer to the t i m e o f Polycrates (3.58), a n d the usage o f ta palaia kai kaina does n o t represent a strict terminology of periodization. W h e n Herodotus
believes t h a t he has m o r e substantial i n f o r m a -
t i o n a b o u t events o f t h e m y t h i c a l past, he subjects these to the same c r i t i c a l s c r u t i n y as m o r e r e c e n t events ( v o n L e y d e n ( 1 9 4 9 / 5 0 ) 95 f . ) . The
best e x a m p l e is his c r i t i c a l raisonnement a b o u t w h a t r e a l l y h a p -
p e n e d at T r o y (2.120). A l t h o u g h he seems to distance h i m s e l f r a t h e r e m p h a t i c a l l y f r o m the m y t h i c a l c o n s t r u c t i o n s a r o u n d the T r o j a n
War
r i g h t f r o m the b e g i n n i n g ( 1 . 1 - 5 ) , he o n the o t h e r h a n d integrates this event w i t h o n l y a slight r e s e r v a t i o n i n t o the s h o r t
historical
abstract he gives o n the occasion o f X e r x e s ' e x p e d i t i o n against Greece (7.20). T h i s is supposed to be ' b y far the largest e x p e d i t i o n we k n o w
o f (stolön gar tön hemeis idrnen pollöi de megistos houtos egeneto) i n c o m p a r i s o n to D a r i u s '
e x p e d i t i o n against the S c y t h i a n s ,
the
Scythian
" Prakken (1943) 19 and passim; Mitchel (1956) 52; Drews (1969) 6 f.; Burkert (1995); Giovannini (1995) 140-8. Strasburger (1982) 871 f. with more examples. 5 8
T H E O R G A N I Z A T I O N OF T I M E I N T H E
HISTORIES
409
i n v a s i o n o f M e d i a , a n d ' w h a t is t o l d o f (fa legomena) t h e e x p e d i t i o n o f t h e A t r i d a e against T r o y a n d t h e i n v a s i o n o f t h e M y s i a n s a n d T e u c r i a n s i n t o T h r a c i a , ' b e f o r e t h e T r o j a n W a r ' (to pro ton Troikon genomenon). A t the e n d o f the Histories, he integrates the hero Protesilaus M
a n d t h e events o f t h e T r o j a n W a r Persian W a r s
firmly
i n t o his a c c o u n t o f t h e
(9.116-20).fi0
T h e t i m e g r i d t h a t c a n be a b s t r a c t e d f r o m t h e Histories c o m b i n e s h o r i z o n t a l a n d v e r t i c a l linkages. S y n c h r o n i s m s i n H e r o d o t u s
are a
r e g u l a r device f o r l i n k i n g d i f f e r e n t scenes o f a c t i o n . 6 1 S o m e t i m e s t h e y serve a f a c t u a l c o n t e x t , m o s t o f t e n i n t h e second h a l f o f t h e Histories, B u t o f t e n a s y n c h r o n i s m s i m p l y organizes t h e m a t e r i a l i n t i m e , like C a m b y s e s c o n q u e r i n g E g y p t a t t h e same m o m e n t as t h e Spartans a t t a c k e d Samos (3.39). F r e q u e n t l y t h e r e a r e inconsistencies i n d e t a i l w h i c h r e v e a l t h e difficulties i n i m p o s i n g c h r o n o l o g i c a l o r d e r o n such a mass o f disparate m a t e r i a l . 0 2 I n o t h e r cases h e w a s disposed t o o m u c h t o keep close t o his v a r i o u s sources. 6 3 F o r t h e l o n g e r distances b a c k i n t o t h e past, E g y p t p r o v i d e s t h e b a c k b o n e
(Hunter
(1982)
5 0 - 9 2 ) . T h e date f o r the e n d o f t h e Saitic dynasty c a n be determ i n e d b y c o n n e c t i n g i t w i t h t h e Persian kings r a t h e r closely t o a b o u t 525 B C . 6 4 A m a s i s is s y n c h r o n i z e d w i t h S o l o n , Croesus (1.30),
Cyrus
(1.77), a n d Polycrates (2.182; 3 . 3 9 - 4 3 ) , t h e latter also w i t h Cambyses (3.39; 44). A t t h e o t h e r e n d o f t h e t i m e scale, K i n g Proteus attaches the E g y p t i a n
sequence t o t h e T r o j a n W a r (2.112—120), a n d K i n g
M o i r i s is s y n c h r o n i z e d w i t h H e r a c l e s (2.13; 145). An
o b v i o u s feature o f t h e v e r t i c a l s t r u c t u r e o f t h e t i m e g r i d is
w h a t e t h n o l o g y calls t h e f l o a t i n g g a p ' : t h e p r e s e n t a n d t h e recent past a r e a n c h o r e d i n t h e r e m o t e past, f a r a w a y i n time; a b o u t t h e time i n b e t w e e n n o t m u c h is k n o w n . 6 ' W i t h i n classical studies, G i l b e r t M u r r a y has r e m a r k e d t h a t ' T h e r e is a f a r - o f f i s l a n d o f k n o w l e d g e , o r a p p a r e n t k n o w l e d g e ; t h e n darkness; t h e n t h e b e g i n n i n g s o f c o n t i n u o u s h i s t o r y . ' 6 6 T h e Scythians p r o v i d e t h e clearest e x a m p l e f o r
59
Cf. Vandiver (1991) Ch. 5. Boedeker (1988) and this volume (Ch. 5, p. 115); Vandiver (1991) 223-9. Strasburger (1956) 157-60; (1962) 719-23. 'There was no Herodotus before Herodotus' is a basso continue) with Strasburger (1956). This is a main point with Mitchel (1956). Strasburger (1956) 138; (1962) 690 f. Vansina (1985) 23 f; 168 f; Cobet (1988) 229; Bichler (2000) 35 42. Murray (1907) 29, quoted as the opening sentence in Snodgrass (1971) 1. 60 61
62
63
64
m
6 6
410
JUSTUS
COBET
this w i t h the v a r i o u s versions o f t h e i r o r i g i n . H e r o d o t u s ' G r e e k hist o r y basically testifies to the same s t r u c t u r e . T h e the T r o j a n W a r
generations a b o u t
a n d Heracles m i r r o r the o r g a n i z a t i o n i n t i m e
of
G r e e k saga as a n elaborate version o f G r e e k beginnings. F u r t h e r m o r e , these stories are c o n n e c t e d w i t h o r i e n t a l h i s t o r y b y means o f G r e e k devices; t h e y reveal n o k n o w l e d g e o f b r o n z e age history. T h e
Lydian
a n d A s s y r o - B a b y l o n i a n h i s t o r y is c o n n e c t e d w i t h the distant past over a l o n g gap w i t h o u t a n y n a m e o r event. T h e E g y p t i a n sequence c o n sists o f three stages o f such a gap. B e t w e e n Sethos a n d M o e r i s there are n o t e n o u g h names a n d events t o really cover the distance, between M o e r i s a n d M i n there are n o n e . M i n is i d e n t i f i e d as a start, b u t there are still m o r e stages o f ' h i s t o r y ' b a c k t h r o u g h e m p t y spaces o f t i m e . To
o r g a n i z e a n d measure all these distances, H e r o d o t u s uses lists
o f kings w i t h the years o f t h e i r reigns. W h e r e t h e y are m i s s i n g , he enumerates names r e p r e s e n t i n g generations; the p r o t o t y p e f o r this is the S p a r t a n k i n g list (7.204; 8.131).
67
A still m o r e abstract p r o c e d u r e
is to c o u n t b y generations w i t h o u t g i v i n g names, short o f j u s t givi n g bare
figures,
as he does several t i m e s . H e
once explains a pos-
sible base o f c o u n t i n g : three generations c a n be taken as one h u n d r e d years (2.142), w h i c h fits i n f o r e x a m p l e w i t h t h e Persian kings (6.98). T h o s e w h o c r i t i c i z e E d u a r d M e y e r ' s t h e o r y t h a t t h e r e is also a f o r t y years c o u n t f o r o n e g e n e r a t i o n b e h i n d the genealogical c o n s t r u c t i o n s found in Herodotus,
w h i c h M e y e r based o n the S p a r t a n k i n g list,
m u s t be r i g h t , since there w o u l d still be m o r e variants i f w e also take i n t o a c c o u n t the examples o f the L y d i a n , A s s y r i a n , a n d E g y p t i a n sequences." 8 H e r o d o t u s counts b a c k 4 0 0 , 8 0 0 , 9 0 0 , 1,000 a n d 2,300 years f r o m his o w n t i m e (2.13; 44; 53; 145 f . ) . M U n f o r t u n a t e l y there are t o o few (Egypt) a n d i n o t h e r cases t o o m a n y (1.7) f o r the g i v e n t i m e span. B u r k e r t a n d G i o v a n n i n i
generations
rightly point out
t h a t i f w e take j u s t the genealogies as a d a t i n g c r i t e r i o n , the c o n texts H e r o d o t u s
r e p o r t s o n at the f a r t h e r e n d o f the once
gap w o u l d have to be p u t at m u c h l o w e r dates: the T r o j a n
1,7
floating War,
In this respect it does not matter whether these two lists ate meant to be Leonidas' and Leotychides' pedigrees or real king lists: Cartledge (1979) 341-6: Vanicelli (1993) 35-8. Mitchel (1956) 64 f.; Ball (1979); Mosshammer (1979) 105-10; Burkert (1995) 143f. Giving more credit to Meyer: Prakken (1943) 18 48. One thousand instead of 1,600 years for the Greek Dionysus is Wilamowitz' conjecture, convincing to me for the genealogical context: Prakken (1943) 33 n. 74; 41;'Burkert (1995) 141 n. 22. Contra Mitchel (1956) 60; den Boer (1967); DarboPeschanski (1987) 31. 68
1,9
THE
O R G A N I Z A T I O N OF T I M E I N T H E
411
HISTORIES
f o r e x a m p l e , w o u l d have to be d a t e d a b o u t 910 BC.'° I n the h i s t o riographic The
process o f fixing a t r a d i t i o n i n t i m e the gap is still
floating.
distance separating the t i m e o f H o m e r ' s n a r r a t i v e f r o m his
o w n a n d his audience's lifetime has been closed. T h e r e f o r e the t w o f o l d d i v i s i o n o f m y t h i c a l a n d h i s t o r i c a l t i m e does Herodotus.
not really apply
I n s t e a d , I recognize three d i s t i n c t i v e periods b e y o n d
spatium 'adelon', the t i m e n o b o d y c a n k n o w of:
1) the
to the
complex
sto-
ries a b o u t b e g i n n i n g s , the age o f the G r e e k poets' gods a n d heroes, t r a d i t i o n a l l y the m y t h i c a l p e r i o d ; 2) the m e a g r e l y gap o r ' D a r k A g e ' ;
filled
i n 'floating'
3) the spatium historicum i n t h e p r o p e r sense,
be d i v i d e d i n t o the h o r i z o n
o f the o r i e n t a l kings a n d the
to
'recent
past' o f the three generations. T h i s last difference v a n i s h e d as hist o r i o g r a p h y became a c o n t i n u o u s h a b i t w i t h the ancients, T h i s develo p m e n t resulted i n a historia continua i n a g r o w i n g l i b r a r y to w h i c h Eusebius operation
finally
c o u l d refer. T o
of historicization by
sources. T h e
fill
the once
antiquarian
floating means
m o d e r n concept o f a ' D a r k Age'
gap was with
an
doubtful
c e r t a i n l y reflects the
structure o f a n c i e n t t r a d i t i o n a b o u t the past as w e find i t r e p r o d u c e d a n d systematized
in Herodotus'
Kyklos, Herodotus'
organization
of time.'1
Process, and Contingency
sentence o n 'the cycle o f h u m a n affairs' (Croesus speak-
i n g to C y r u s , 1.207) a n d his p r o g r a m m a t i c d e c l a r a t i o n a b o u t the rise a n d f a l l o f cities t h r o u g h t i m e (1.5) are o f t e n t a k e n as evidence
for
a cyclic n o t i o n o f h i s t o r y as o p p o s e d to the n o t i o n o f a o n e - w a y l i n ear process. ' I n seiner A u f f a s s u n g der Geschichte h a t die Z e i t z a h l u n g keine g r u n d l e g e n d e W i c h t i g k e i t . ' 7 2 I n d e e d , d i v i n e i n t e r v e n t i o n , hubris, circumstances o f the conditio humana, topoi like the wise advisor o r the p u n i s h m e n t b y the gods o f the crossing o f n a t u r a l b o u n d a r i e s
such
as the H e l l e s p o n t c o n v e y the i m p r e s s i o n o f r e p e t i t i v e patterns w h i c h t u r n t i m e i n t o a m e r e secondary d i m e n s i o n o f w h a t is t o l d . ' 3 T h i s i n a sense is even t r u e o f the w h o l e sequence o f the o r i e n t a l kings
70
Burkert (1995) 141: Giovannini (1995) 140-8. Snodgrass (1971) 1-2; Morris (1997). Strasburger (1954) 400 f.; (1968) 422 4; cf. Cobet (1971) 178 f. Against the thesis of a general cyclic orientation of ancient historiography, going back to Augustine's verdict against the Platonic conception of time, Momigliano (1966); Cobet (2000) 10 16. " 'General causes' with Vansina (1985) 132 ff. 71
72
412
JUSTUS
f r o m Croesus to X e r x e s , O n
COBET
the o t h e r h a n d , besides the topoi a n d
the r e p e t i t i v e elements o f each u n i t there is a n ascending l i n e starti n g w i t h the Croesus logos as a p r e l i m i n a r y t o the Persian
sequence:
the n a r r a t i v e units f r o m Croesus to D a r i u s t a k e n together p r e p a r e the c l i m a x w i t h X e r x e s ( C o b e t (1971) 1 5 8 - 7 1 ) . I t is, o f course, the e v e n t o f t h e Persian W a r s
that instigated such a n approach.
Herodotus'
the e x p a n d i n g
contemporaries,
Persian
empire
To
opened
u p a u n i v e r s a l perspective o n h i s t o r y . ' * I n this m a j o r process w h i c h H e r o d o t u s ' n a r r a t i v e p o r t r a y s , c o n t i n g e n c y , the c o i n c i d e n c e o f events i n space a n d t i m e , is a characteristic feature o f the Histories ( M e i e r (1978)). T h e n o t i o n o f ' o t h e r n e s s ' a n d 'coexistence o f d i f f e r e n t t i m e s ' is a clear i l l u s t r a t i o n o f this. O u t
of a multitude of traditions w i t h
t h e i r specific c h r o n o l o g i e s , H e r o d o t u s c r e a t e d a n a r r a t i v e c o n t i n u u m o f h i s t o r i c a l t i m e o r g a n i z i n g the oldest c h r o n o l o g y t r a n s c e n d i n g v a r ious c u l t u r a l t r a d i t i o n s . L o o k i n g at o u r t o p i c f r o m far a w a y , B o r s t ((1990) 11)
summarized
about
Arno
Herodotus:
Er verglich grundverschiedene Zeitbegriffe und Geschichtsbilder miteinander [. . .] Die Sterblichen auf der vielgestaltigen Welt hatten nur eines gemeinsam: Zeitgenossenschaft. W o sie handelnd und reagierend aufeinandertrafen, vollzog sich Geschichte, u n d durch ihre relative Gleichzeitigkeit datierte sie Herodot. The
n a r r a t i v e o f the Histories as a w h o l e organizes
a n d integrates
different horizons o f m e m o r y into an unequivocal and unconvertible sequence, a t t r i b u t i n g to 'the w i d e o p e n space o f t i m e , i n w h i c h everyt h i n g is possible' (5.9.3), a definite s t r u c t u r e . A l t h o u g h this s t r u c t u r e is abstract i n the sense t h a t i t is o p e n to contingencies a n d capable o f r e c e i v i n g m o r e stories, i t conveys a n u n m i s t a k a b l e i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f h i s t o r i c a l t i m e . I t a c t u a l l y represents the b e g i n n i n g o f t r a d i t i o n to be c o n t i n u e d b y T h u c y d i d e s i n general. A general m a y
Western
and ancient historiography
cyclic v i e w o n the u n c e r t a i n t i e s o f h u m a n h i s t o r y i n represent H e r o d o t u s '
s o p h i c a l o u t l o o k . Nevertheless,
personal theological and philo-
t w o features especially, the sequence
o f e m p i r e s ' 3 a n d processuality, progress i n t o the f u t u r e , give m o m e n t u m t o a historia perpetua w h i c h later was to be r e i n f o r c e d b y A l e x a n d e r a n d the u n i v e r s a l success o f the R o m a n e m p i r e .
74
'Handlungszeit' moves towards 'Weltzeit', to speak with Dux (1989) 278; cf, the quotation in note 4 above. In Herodotus the Assyrians, the Medes, and the Persians (1.95; 102 ff.; 130). Cf. Alonso-Nunez (1988). /:>
HISTORY AND ETHNOGRAPHY
CHAPTER E I G H T E E N EGYPT A l a n B.
Lloyd
A n interest i n things e t h n o g r a p h i c a l was n o t n e w i n H e r o d o t u s ' A l r e a d y i n H o m e r w e see n u m e r o u s n o n - G r e e k peoples, real o r
fictional,1
examples
time.
of a concern
with
a n d the s u r v i v i n g f r a g m e n t s
Hecataeus o f M i l e t u s p r o v i d e a m p l e evidence o f this
of
phenomenon.2
I t is clear a n d n a t u r a l t h a t these e t h n o g r a p h i c interests w e r e closely l i n k e d to g e o g r a p h i c a l s p e c u l a t i o n . T h i s is m o s t o b v i o u s l y the case i n the p a r a l l e l i s m b e t w e e n the early G r e e k d i v i s i o n o f the e a r t h i n t o t w o c o n t i n e n t s , i . e . , Europe a n d Asie, to each o f w h i c h is allocated an archetypal 'barbarian' people,
the Scythians
i n Europe a n d
the
E g y p t i a n s i n Asie. T h i s neat m a p p i n g o f the w o r l d is slightly i m p a i r e d f o r H e r o d o t u s b y the i n t r o d u c t i o n o f Libye (Africa) as a t h i r d c o n t i n e n t , 5 b u t its i n f l u e n c e is still p a t e n t i n the fact t h a t the t w o longest a n d most searching o f all Herodotus' those d e a l i n g w i t h E g y p t i n B o o k T w o The
e t h n o g r a p h i c a l excursuses
are
a n d Scythia i n Book Four.4
o r i g i n s o f these e t h n o g r a p h i c a l p r e o c c u p a t i o n s are n o t far to
seek. A t the m o s t basic level t h e y are p a r t o f a m a p p i n g process b y w h i c h a n y c u l t u r e defines the p h y s i c a l w o r l d i n w h i c h i t finds itself, b u t t h e r e is also a deeper
p s y c h o l o g i c a l i m p e r a t i v e at w o r k .
Self-
d e f i n i t i o n is a f u n d a m e n t a l r e q u i r e m e n t i f a n y i n d i v i d u a l , social g r o u p , o r society is to be able to locate ' s e l f p s y c h o l o g i c a l l y i n its w o r l d , negotiate t e r m s w i t h t h a t w o r l d , a n d t h e r e b y m a k e i t t r a c t a b l e .
An
essential p a r t o f this process o f s e l f - d e f i n i t i o n is d e f i n i n g ' s e l f i n r e l a t i o n to o t h e r h u m a n beings. E v i d e n t l y , 'others' c a n present themselves basically i n t w o f o r m s : (a) 'others' w i t h w h o m there is a p e r c e i v e d
1
E.g., the Egyptians, Ethiopians, Lotus-eaters, Carians, Lycians, and Phoenicians; see Wace and Stubbings (1962) 283 ff., for a convenient survey. For the fragments see Jacoby (1923) I . See Lloyd (1975) 126 ff; (1976) 82 ff. Much has been written on Herodotus' ethnographical interests: Grassl (1904); Triidinger (1918); von Fritz (1967) 128 ff; Müller (1972); Rossellini and Said (1978) 949 ff; Hartog (1980); Mora (1986) 60 ff. 2
:i
4
416
ALAN B. LLOYD
Egypt. Adapted from W. G. Waddell, Herodotus Book I I (London 1939), 16.
EGYPT
417
identity and sense of solidarity; (b) 'others' who are regarded as disparate. The first group may include a wide range of categories: those who are perceived to be biologically linked with the individual, e.g., the family, lineage, or clan; units defined by shared functions, interests, or geography, such as clubs, groups of colleagues, churches, or towns; politically defined structures such as the state; and possibly, though not universally, groups defined by genetically determined physical characteristics. Group (b), on the other hand, will comprise all those with w h o m no such sense of corporate solidarity is recognized. The perception o f such differences will have two major effects. Most obviously, it defines disparate entities which must be conceptually located i n one's world. Less conspicuously, by the very act of recognizing 'otherness' the consciousness is defining more precisely a sense o f 'selfness'. Herodotus' Histories are explicitly presented at their very beginning as the commemoration o f the achievements o f Greeks and nonGreeks, but it is more than that. The work becomes an exploration of the very nature o f what were, to Greeks, the two major categories of human being and, ipso facto, o f humanity as a whole. I t is, therefore, raising, exploring, and meditating upon the critical questions: 'What is it to be Greek?'; 'What is it to be a non-Greek?'—and it is doing this i n a historical context where these questions had been posed in an unnervingly stark and immediate manner by the great confrontation between the Persian empire and Greece. Herodotus is, therefore, engaged i n nothing less than responding to the intense challenge to define 'self and 'alien' which the experience of that war presented. 5
W i t h i n an account o f the clash between Greece and the Persian empire some discussion o f Egypt has a natural place: the incorporation o f Egypt into the Persian empire made it one of the many major military and economic forces ranged against the Greeks; the fact that the Persians could conquer such a great and wealthy nation said much for the capacities o f the Empire; the conquest also formed part o f an inexorable dynamic o f western movement which reached its crescendo (at least to Greek observers) i n the clash between the states o f mainland Greece and the armies of Darius and Xerxes; and, finally, an analysis of Egyptian civilization contributed much to the characterization o f the non-Greek, the 'barbarian', the deadly
5
In general see Hartog (1980); Hall (1989).
418
ALAN B. LLOYD
foe w h i c h the Greeks h a d to c o n f r o n t a n d o v e r c o m e
i f they
were
to survive. Easy t h o u g h
i t is to i d e n t i f y the l o g i c f o r the i n c l u s i o n o f
an
E g y p t i a n section i n the n a r r a t i v e , i t m u s t be c o n c e d e d t h a t H e r o d o t u s has i n d u l g e d h i m s e l f m i g h t i l y i n his E g y p t i a n excursus a n d p r o d u c e d a discussion w h i c h is seriously o u t o f scale. I t has f r e q u e n t l y
been
a r g u e d , w i t h considerable p l a u s i b i l i t y , t h a t i t was o r i g i n a l l y a separate piece w r i t t e n as a n i n d e p e n d e n t e t h n o g r a p h i c i n q u i r y a n d subsequently i m p o r t e d i n t o the a c c o u n t o f the Persian W a r s w h e n relevance o f such a discussion b e c a m e c l e a r . b O n
the
the o t h e r h a n d , i t
m i g h t be the case t h a t , once H e r o d o t u s h a d got started, the discussion g r e w
and that no opportunity
or i n c l i n a t i o n
subsequently
i n t e r v e n e d t o e d i t i t d o w n to a n a p p r o p r i a t e scale. I t is possible t o d e t e c t a n u m b e r
o f factors d e t e r m i n i n g
what
H e r o d o t u s discussed a n d the presuppositions w h i c h he b r o u g h t
to
b e a r . T h e r e is, o f course, n o a t t e m p t to p r o v i d e a c l i n i c a l a n d objective v i e w o f E g y p t . G r e e k f o c i o f interest are a l l - p o w e r f u l , w h e t h e r i t be E g y p t ' s i m p a c t o n G r e e k h i s t o r y , its i n f l u e n c e o n G r e e k c u l t u r e , s t r i d e n t differences between G r e e k a n d E g y p t i a n ways o f d o i n g t h i n g s , o r the real o r i m a g i n e d m o r a l lessons t h a t m i g h t be l e a r n e d b y Greeks f r o m E g y p t i a n h i s t o r i c a l experience. are also i n evidence i n the pervasive
G r e e k perspectives
i n f l u e n c e o f to thomasion, ' t h e
m a r v e l l o u s ' (i.e., t o a G r e e k ) , a p o i n t w h i c h H e r o d o t u s e x p l i c i t l y c o n cedes i n his f a m o u s sentence, ' I shall speak at some l e n g t h o f E g y p t because b e y o n d a l l lands i t possesses v e r y m a n y w o n d e r s a n d vels w h i c h pass a l l p o w e r to describe' ( 2 . 3 5 . 1 ) . O n s i m i l a r i t i e s , real o r i m a g i n a r y , b e t w e e n
the o t h e r
marhand,
E g y p t a n d Greece c a n act
like a m a g n e t to d r a w h i m i n t o r a m p a n t c u l t u r a l d i f f u s i o n i s m , a n d G r e e k religious i n h i b i t i o n s c a n l e a d h i m to a v o i d discussing c e r t a i n aspects o f E g y p t i a n belief. H e r o d o t u s '
t h i n k i n g o n a l l these m a t t e r s
shows the m a r k e d i n f l u e n c e o f c o n t e m p o r a r y
ethnographic
theory:
Pindar's r e l a t i v i s m is strongly e n d o r s e d — ' c u s t o m is k i n g i n all t h i n g s ' , a n d c u l t u r a l practices m u s t be t r e a t e d as v a l i d c u l t u r e b y
culture
(3.38.4); the o p e r a t i o n o f the w i d e l y c u r r e n t c u s t o m / n a t u r e p o l a r i t y is clearly v i s i b l e ; ' a n d he is c o n v i n c e d o f the pervasive i n f l u e n c e
of
e n v i r o n m e n t i n creating E g y p t i a n customs.8
6
7
8
On this issue, see Jacoby (1913) 330 ft".; Fornara (1971a) 1 ff.; Lloyd (1975) 66 ff. 2.45.2-3. See further Hunter (1982) 264 ff.; Corcella (1984) 74 if. See below, p. 433.
419
EGYPT
A
striking feature o f Herodotus'
n a r r a t i v e o f the Persian W a r s is
his w i l l i n g n e s s t o i n d i c a t e sources, a n d B o o k T w o
is a p a r t i c u l a r l y
r e m a r k a b l e e x a m p l e o f t h a t t r a i t . A t the v e r y b e g i n n i n g o f the Histories he describes the w o r k as a n historié, ' i n q u i r y , i n v e s t i g a t i o n ' , 9 a n d this ' i n q u i r y ' he pursues i n E g y p t u s i n g t h r e e stated m e t h o d s :
autopsy
(opsis), ' o p i n i o n ' , i . e . , a n expression o f p e r s o n a l o p i n i o n based
on
evaluation o f data (gnômë), a n d i n q u i r y o r hearsay (historié, akoê) ( 2 . 2 9 . 1 , 99.1,
123.1,
147.1). F o r
o u r c o n t e x t the first is v e r y p r o m i n e n t i n
his discussion o f g e o g r a p h y , geology, b o t a n y , z o o l o g y , customs,
and
sites, b o t h a r c h a e o l o g i c a l a n d i n h a b i t e d . ' O p i n i o n '
and
is w i d e l y
e x p l i c i t l y present i n m a t t e r s o f r e l i g i o n a n d t r a d i t i o n w h i l s t hearsay evidence is v e r y m u c h his s t o c k - i n - t r a d e f o r h i s t o r y a n d t r a d i t i o n s : i n the e a r l i e r p a r t o f the Aigyptios logos he i n q u i r e s a n d 'hears' m a i n l y f r o m t h e priests a n d ' o t h e r E g y p t i a n s ' , b u t i n h i s t o r i c a l discussions f r o m the r e i g n o f Psammetichus I o n w a r d s his o r a l sources are mainlyG r e e k (2.154.4). T h a t these sources y i e l d e d d a t a o f v a r i a b l e
value
he k n e w f u l l w e l l , a n d he issues a clear w a r n i n g to t h a t effect:
'Now
as f o r the claims o f the E g y p t i a n s , p e o p l e c a n use w h a t e v e r
they
find
c r e d i b l e . As f o r m e , i t is m y p o l i c y t h r o u g h o u t m y n a r r a t i v e to
r e c o r d w h a t each g r o u p says as I h e a r d i t ' ( 2 . 1 2 3 . 1 , cf. 7 . 1 5 2 . 3 ) . I n a d d i t i o n to these stated sources he was also i n f l u e n c e d deeply b y the Greek tradition on Egypt. This
began w i t h H o m e r w h o played a
m a j o r r o l e i n d e f i n i n g a n d d i s s e m i n a t i n g the G r e e k i m a g e o f E g y p t , b u t he also d r e w m u c h f r o m a n d r e a c t e d s t r o n g l y against the geog r a p h i c a l a n d e t h n o g r a p h i c a l t r a d i t i o n d e v e l o p e d b y the t w o great Ionians A n a x i m a n d e r and Hecataeus o f M i l e t u s . 1 0 L e t us n o w consider h o w all this w o r k s o u t i n p r a c t i c e .
Political and Social Structure H e r o d o t u s h a d available a clear d e f i n i t i o n o f w h a t a n E g y p t i a n was: ' E g y p t is the area w h i c h the N i l e i n u n d a t e s w h e n i t rises, a n d those people are E g y p t i a n s w h o live b e l o w the c i t y o f E l e p h a n t i n e
9
and
The word can be used to denote 'inquiry, investigation', whatever the method, or to refer to specifically oral inquiry. In the first line of the Hutories it is the former sense which is at issue (Lloyd (1975) 81 f.). On the sources for Book Two, see Lloyd (1975) 77 f t ; (1988b) 23 ffi; Fehling (1989); and Pritchett (1993). 10
420
ALAN B. L L O Y D
d r i n k f r o m this r i v e r ' ( 2 d 8 . 3 ) , a d e f i n i t i o n w h i c h n o a n c i e n t E g y p t i a n w o u l d have h a d a n y d i f f i c u l t y i n a c c e p t i n g . H i s c o m m e n t s o n t h e i r physical appearance are, at first sight, p u z z l i n g : at 2.104.2 he describes t h e m as ' d a r k - s k i n n e d a n d c u r l y - h a i r e d ' , w h i c h c e r t a i n l y describes m a n y a n E g y p t i a n (cf. 2 . 5 7 . 2 ) , b u t b o t h i n a n c i e n t a n d m o d e r n times the range
o f p h y s i c a l types goes w e l l b e y o n d
that. However,
we
s h o u l d n o t m a k e too m u c h o f this. C l e a r l y we m u s t a l l o w here f o r a G r e e k c o n c e p t o f the ' s y m b o l i c ' E g y p t i a n , i . e . , i f a spot-check w e r e taken amongst
Greeks to n a m e t w o E g y p t i a n characteristics ' d a r k -
s k i n n e d ' a n d ' c u r l y - h a i r e d ' w o u l d be the l i k e l y result, a n d , i f a n artist o f any k i n d r e q u i r e d a p h y s i c a l l y i d e n t i f i a b l e E g y p t i a n , 1 1 he
would
w o r k w i t h these descriptors. W i t h i n this b o d y o f p e o p l e H e r o d o t u s p e r c e i v e d a society d o m i n a t e d b y k i n g s h i p a n d d i v i d e d i n t o seven d i s t i n c t classes (genea) w h i c h w e r e d e f i n e d b y t h e i r 'crafts'. T h e s e are e n u m e r a t e d at 2 . 1 6 4 . 1 as the priests (hirees), the w a r r i o r s (makhimoi), the c o w h e r d s (boukoloi), the swineherds (subotai), the i n l a n d - t r a d e r s (kapeloi), the i n t e r p r e t e r s (hermenees), a n d the p i l o t s (kybernetai). Elsewhere he also talks o f craftsmen,
fishermen,
a n d the p e a s a n t r y , b u t t h e y clearly d i d n o t present
themselves to h i m as groups w h i c h c o u l d be d e f i n e d b y t h e i r 'crafts' i n the same w a y as the seven classes listed a b o v e , perhaps t h e y l a c k e d the t i g h t c o r p o r a t e u n i t y w h i c h he p r o b a b l y i n the genea.
12
find
because perceived
B i r d c a t c h e r s , t h o u g h f r e q u e n t i n the E g y p t i a n r e c o r d ,
n o place i n his n a r r a t i v e , despite the f a c t t h a t H e r o d o t u s was
w e l l a w a r e o f the E g y p t i a n p r e d i l e c t i o n f o r e a t i n g birds i n a v a r i e t y o f f o r m s (2.77.5). K i n g s o c c u p y a d o m i n a n t place i n H e r o d o t u s '
a c c o u n t , a n d i t is
t h r o u g h t h e m that the historical narrative unfolds.13 T h e power
o f this i n s t i t u t i o n is, o f course, a m a j o r area o f
political
divergence
f r o m the eleutherie o r ' f r e e d o m ' w h i c h is so o f t e n p r a i s e d as a dist i n c t i v e feature o f the G r e e k w o r l d (cf. 2 . 1 7 2 . 5 ) . H e r o d o t u s is c l e a r l y aware
t h a t the m a i n p r i n c i p l e o f succession was h e r e d i t y , b u t
he
k n o w s p e r f e c t l y w e l l t h a t o t h e r factors c a n i n t e r v e n e , e . g . , he speaks
" Making 'Egyptians' even remotely genuinely Egyptian could well be surplus to requirements. The 'Egyptian' context of Euripides' Helen dispenses completely with anything that could be called Egyptian local colour! Note that the swineherds are stated to practise exclusive intermarriage (2.47.1). Herodotus' account of Egyptian history is studied in depth by von Fritz (1967) I , 158 f t ; Drews (1973) 56 ffi; and Lloyd (1988b). 12
13
421
EGYPT
o f a priest o f H e p h a e s t u s ( E g y p t i a n Ptah) b e c o m i n g k i n g at 2 . 1 4 1 . 1 , b y a c o n v e r s i o n o f ecclesiastical i n t o r o y a l p o w e r w h i c h is easily p a r alleled i n E g y p t i a n h i s t o r y . H e
is also a w a r e t h a t the p o l i t i c a l c o u p
b r i n g i n g a usurper to the t h r o n e was n o t u n k n o w n i n E g y p t (2.162.2). Divine
assistance was available t o k i n g s , a n d H e r o d o t u s
mentions
several cases o f t h e m r e c e i v i n g messages t h r o u g h oracles a n d dreams ( M y c e r i n u s , 2 . 1 3 3 . 1 ; Sethos, 2 . 1 4 1 . 3 - 4 ; Psammetichus, 2.152.3). These rulers are c o r r e c d y described as r u l i n g o v e r a c o u n t r y d i v i d e d i n t o nomes
( a d m i n i s t r a t i v e districts c o m p a r a b l e
Herodotus
to a n E n g l i s h
county).
m e n t i o n s eighteen o f these (less t h a n h a l f ) , all b u t
i n the D e l t a ,
one
a fact w h i c h reflects n o t h i n g m o r e t h a n the general
D e l t a bias o f his n a r r a t i v e . Herodotus
was w e l l a w a r e o f the E g y p t i a n t r a d i t i o n t h a t E g y p t
h a d i n i t i a l l y been r u l e d b y dynasties o f gods (2.144.2), the first ' h u m a n ' k i n g being M i n . For
h i m the sequence o f n a t i v e kings e n d e d w i t h
Psammenitus (Psammetichus I I I ) w h o was deposed i n 525 b y Gambyses a n d subsequentiy e x e c u t e d . M o s t
o f the t e x t f r o m 2 . 9 9 t o 3 . 6 4 is
d e v o t e d t o the d e s c r i p t i o n o f r o y a l a c t i o n s , t h o u g h f o r o u r purposes C a m b y s e s w i l l be left o u t o f c o n s i d e r a t i o n . 1 4 T h e
astonishing t i m e -
span over w h i c h this h u m a n h i s t o r y u n f o l d e d was one o f the m o s t e x t r a o r d i n a r y features o f E g y p t i a n h i s t o r y a n d received m u c h caref u l c o n s i d e r a t i o n , n o t least because i t gave the lie to received G r e e k w i s d o m o n the past o f Greece itself, a n d p r o v i d e d H e r o d o t u s
with
the p e r f e c t basis f o r the o p e r a t i o n o f the post hoc ergo propter hoc p r i n ciple i n a r g u i n g f o r the E g y p t i a n o r i g i n o f m u c h o f G r e e k c u l t u r e . T h e first p a r t o f this h i s t o r i c a l n a r r a t i v e covers the reigns o f kings from M i n
to the D o d e c a r c h s
(2.99-141).15 T o
the E g y p t o l o g i s t
its
m o s t s t r i k i n g deficiency is the eccentric c h r o n o l o g y w h i c h seriously displaces the P y r a m i d B u i l d e r s , b u t i t does i n c l u d e discussion o f r e p resentatives o f a l l the m a j o r p e r i o d s r e c o g n i z e d b y m o d e r n E g y p t o logists: T h i n i t e ( M i n ) , O l d K i n g d o m ( C h e o p s , C h e p h r e n ,
Mycerinus,
Nitocris), M i d d l e K i n g d o m (Sesostris, M o e r i s ) , N e w K n g d o m ( R h a m p sinitus), t h e L i b y a n P e r i o d (Sabacos, Sethos,
14
(Asychis,
the D o d e c a r c h s ) ,
Anysis),
the N u b i a n
Period
a n d the Saite P e r i o d ( N e c h o I ,
On the Cambyses tradition, see Posener (1936); Klasens (1944—8) 339 ft".; Schwartz (1948) 65 ft; Kienitz (1953); Otto (1954): Bresciani (1958) 167 ff.; Gyles (1959); Drioton and Vandier (1962) 600 ft'.; Porten ((968); Kraeling (1969); Waters (1971), 53-6; Lloyd (1982) 166 ff.; Brown (1982) 387-403; Lloyd (1988a). For detailed commentary on this section, see Hoyd (1988c) 1 ff. 15
422
ALAN B. L L O Y D
Psammetichus I , N e c h o I I , Psammetichus I I (Psammis), Apries, Amasis, P s a m m e t i c h u s I I I (Psammenitus). unhistorical—Pheros, who
O n l y t w o o f his kings are p a t e n t l y
is a c o m p l e t e f a b r i c a t i o n , a n d
w h o was i m p o r t e d f r o m G r e e k l e g e n d . The
Proteus,
16
actions a t t r i b u t e d to this first b a t c h o f rulers are o f v a r y i n g
historical credibility. T h e y include imperialist
expansion—Sesostris
c a m p a i g n s on the R e d Sea C o a s t , in A s i a , a n d i n E u r o p e (!), b r i n g i n g b a c k prisoners w h o w e r e used f o r b u i l d i n g a n d c i v i l - e n g i n e e r i n g purposes. H e also c o n q u e r e d N u b i a w h i c h he is alleged, quite w r o n g l y , t o have b e e n the o n l y k i n g to subdue. A r e c u r r e n t a c t i v i t y is t e m p l e b u i l d i n g a n d e m b e l l i s h m e n t — M i n founds the temple of Hephaestus at M e m p h i s ,
M o e r i s b u i l d s its n o r t h p y l o n ; Sesostris erects obelisks
a n d statues i n M e m p h i s ;
P h e r o s d e d i c a t e d statues at
Heliopolis;
Proteus was responsible f o r a t e m p l e enclosure at M e m p h i s ;
Rhamp-
sinitus b u i l t the west p y l o n o f the t e m p l e o f H e p h a e s t u s at M e m p h i s a n d set u p statues i n the same s h r i n e ; a n d Asychis c o n s t r u c t e d the east p y l o n at M e m p h i s . ( M u c h o f this has some t r u t h i n i t . ) " I r r i g a t i o n w o r k s such as c a n a l - d i g g i n g a n d d y k e - b u i l d i n g are also m e n t i o n e d : M i n is alleged to have d i v e r t e d the N i l e a r o u n d M e m p h i s ,
almost
c e r t a i n l y w r o n g l y ; Sesostris is c l a i m e d to have been responsible f o r E g y p t ' s c a n a l system, despite the fact t h a t i t m u s t have b e e n
much
o l d e r , a n d his alleged m o t i v a t i o n is d i s t i n c t l y o d d ; a n d M o e r i s is c l a i m e d , q u i t e i n c o r r e c t l y , t o have b e e n responsible for the c r e a t i o n o f L a k e M o e r i s . K i n g s c a n also f o u n d cities: M i n is asserted t o have been responsible for the f o u n d a t i o n o f M e m p h i s after he h a d r e c l a i m e d the requisite l a n d ; a n d kings also engage i n spectacular t o m b - b u i l d i n g ( 2 . 1 2 4 - 3 6 ) . I n a l l these enterprises H e r o d o t u s
rarely mentions
the existence o f a d m i n i s t r a t o r s o r agents a c t i n g o n P h a r a o h ' s behalf. Sesostris is d e s c r i b e d as u s i n g his b r o t h e r as regent at 2 . 1 0 7 . 1 ,
and
T h o n i s holds the office o f ' G u a r d i a n o f the C a n o p i c M o u t h o f t h e N i l e ' ( 2 . 1 1 3 . 3 ) , b u t o t h e r w i s e rulers operate i n isolated o m n i p o t e n c e . T h i s a l m o s t exclusive c o n c e n t r a t i o n o n r o y a l a c t i o n m a y s i m p l y arise f r o m a n a r r a t i v e d y n a m i c w h i c h insists o n a sharp a n d
16
exclusive
Pheros' name is clearly based on the Egyptian title per-aa, the origin of the English Pharaoh, but he was clearly identified in later tradition with Amenemhet I I of the Twelfth Dynasty (Lloyd (1988c) 38 f£). Proteus is an import from Homeric tradition (Hoyd (1988c) 43 ff.). Herodotus' accounts of Egyptian buildings have been discussed in detail by Lloyd (1995) 273-300. 17
423
EGYPT
focus o n t h e p r o t a g o n i s t , b u t i t is p e r f e c t l y possible t h a t i t owes s o m e t h i n g t o E g y p t i a n t r a d i t i o n f o r w h i c h such exclusivity is n o r m a l . W i t h t h e b e g i n n i n g o f the a c c o u n t o f t h e Saite D y n a s t y i n 6 6 4 (2.147 ff.) t h e n a r r a t i v e moves m o r e
firmly
into the w o r l d o f history,
b u t a great deal o f w h a t w e have i d e n t i f i e d i n t h e earlier h i s t o r i c a l n a r r a t i v e is still i n evidence. F a m i l i a r rialistic e x p a n s i o n
fields
o f a c t i v i t y recur: impe-
is ascribed to P s a m m e t i c h u s ,
who c a m p a i g n s i n
Asia, t h o u g h t h e r e m a r k a b l e extent o f these operations escapes H e r o dotus c o m p l e t e l y ;
conquests
are also a t t r i b u t e d t o N e c h o I I w h o
operates i n A s i a a n d the R e d Sea, t h e latter's a m b i t i o n s f u r t h e r e d , i t is c l a i m e d , b y t h e e n h a n c e m e n t
o f the Egyptian navy. H o w e v e r ,
w e hear n o t h i n g o f his c a m p a i g n i n t o N u b i a ; Psammis is described as i n v a d i n g N u b i a ( E t h i o p i a ) , b u t there is n o reference t o his k n o w n interest i n Asia; a n d Apries Phoenician
engages i n n a v a l
operations
against
city-states as well sis i n a disastrous invasion of Libya.
F i n a l l y , A m a s i s is c l a i m e d to have subdued C y p r u s . Allied to all this are c a l c u l a t e d d i p l o m a t i c activities such as gifts to Greek shrines ascribed to N e c h o a n d Amasis and Amasis' relationship with Polycrates o f Samos. T e m p l e - b u i l d i n g
continues t o be a m a j o r r o y a l activity:
the D o d e c a r c h s are stated ( w r o n g l y ) t o h a v e b u i l t t h e L a b y r i n t h , a n d Psammetichus
later b u i l t a p y l o n a t t h e t e m p l e o f H e p h a e s t u s a n d
a c o u r t f o r t h e A p i s b u l l . A m a s i s c o n s t r u c t e d a p y l o n i n Sais as w e l l as colossal statues a n d large sphinxes; he also a t t e m p t e d to set u p an allegedly m o n o l i t h i c shrine, erected colossal statues at and built a t e m p l e o f Isis there.
18
Memphis,
Whilst every i t e m i n this catalogue
cannot be c o n f i r m e d a r c h a e o l o g i c a l l y , t h e r e is n o t h i n g i n t r i n s i c a l l y i m p l a u s i b l e here. T o m b - b u i l d i n g is less i n evidence, though we d o h e a r of the r o y a l necropolis at Sais, b u t this d i s p a r i t y s i m p l y reflects the fact t h a t t h e c o n s t r u c t i o n o f r o y a l b u r i a l i n s t a l l a t i o n s o n t h e g r a n d scale w a s v e r y m u c h a t h i n g o f t h e past. H e r o d o t u s , h o w e v e r , goes m u c h f u r t h e r i n his h i s t o r y o f E g y p t than a t t e m p t i n g t o l a y d o w n a h i s t o r i c a l f r a m e w o r k
and e x p l i c i t l y
or i m p l i c i t l y ascribes c h a r a c t e r and m o t i v a t i o n t o these kings: ambition to excel is h i g h l i g h t e d i n the case o f Asychis; benevolence features i n t h e accounts o f Sesostris, M y c e r i n u s , and
18
a n d Sabacos; Pheros
Sethos are s h o w n as pious a n d M y c e r i n u s as just; arrogance is
This Isis temple cannot be identified, but Amasis' interest in this goddess is gratifyingly confirmed by his temple constructed in her honour at Philae (Haeny (1985) 197 ff.).
424
A L A N B.
LLOYD
ascribed to Sesostris, Pheros, C h e o p s , Sethos,
and Mycerinus,
and
vengefulness to N i t o c r i s , Sesostris, a n d Proteus; a streak o f ruthlessness emerges i n N i t o c r i s , Sesostris, Pheros, C h e o p s , a n d
Chephren,
a n d the trickster i n N i t o c r i s , R h a m p s i n i t u s , a n d M y c e r i n u s ; n i m i t y features i n the b e h a v i o u r
of Rhampsinitus,
magna-
a n d Proteus
is
described as m a i n t a i n i n g the m o r a l o r d e r . W h e t h e r these m o t i v e s o r c h a r a c t e r traits w e r e i n h e r i t e d i n m a t e r i a l f r o m E g y p t i a n i n f o r m a n t s or i m p o r t e d by Herodotus
c a n n o t be d e f i n i t i v e l y resolved,
though
the c o i n c i d e n c e o f this b o d y o f m o t i v e s w i t h those o c c u r r i n g elsewhere i n Herodotus' owe
Histories justifies the s t r o n g suspicion t h a t t h e y
m u c h t o his s t a n d a r d n a r r a t i v e apparatus
(see L l o y d
(1988c)
I ft). T h e c h a r a c t e r i z a t i o n o f the Saite rulers is v e r y m u c h i n l i n e w i t h w h a t we are t o l d o f these earlier E g y p t i a n kings. T h e p r o a c t i v e , d o m i n a n t r u l e r is m u c h to the f o r e : i t is
omniscient,
Psammetichus
the significance o f the oracle a n d acts a t 2 . 1 5 2 . 5 ,
w h o recognizes
a n d i t is he w h o consolidates r e l a t i o n s w i t h Greeks f o r the b e n e f i t o f the k i n g d o m ; i t is P s a m m e t i c h u s w h o is alleged (inconceivably) t o have a t t e m p t e d to establish the sources o f the N i l e , a n d i t is N e c h o I I w h o is b e h i n d the alleged c i r c u m n a v i g a t i o n o f A f r i c a ; s i m i l a r p r o b l e m - s o l v i n g expertise is assumed
i n t h e case o f P s a m m i s w h o
is
r e q u i r e d to u n r a v e l a d i f f i c u l t y i n w h i c h the Eleans f o u n d themselves; A m a s i s ' alleged f o u n d a t i o n o f N a u c r a t i s p r o v i d e s yet a n o t h e r
exam-
ple o f the p r o a c t i v e r u l e r ; benevolence features i n the b e h a v i o u r the D o d e c a r c h s ,
as also i n A m a s i s '
treatment o f Apries;
of
arrogance
as w e l l as ruthlessness are a t t r i b u t e d to A p r i e s , a n d vengefulness to Psammetichus.
N e c h o c a n s h o w acquiescence i n the d i v i n e w i l l , b u t
m u c h o f Amasis' b e h a v i o u r is c h a r a c t e r i z e d b y i r r e v e r e n c e . H o w e v e r , i n his r e l a t i o n s h i p w i t h Polycrates he is described as s h o w i n g a grasp o f the w o r k i n g s o f the d i v i n e o r d e r ,
even
firm
i f t h a t o r d e r is
u n e q u i v o c a l l y Greek. Some rulers can also appear as tricksters, Amasis i n a d i d a c t i c c o n t e x t a n d i n r e l a t i o n to C a m b y s e s a n d
Psammenitus
w i t h l e t h a l consequences to h i m s e l f after his c a p t u r e b y the Persians. H e r o d o t u s is e x p l i c i t o n his sources f o r E g y p t i a n h i s t o r y . T o
begin
w i t h t h e r e is a v e r y h e a v y emphasis o n E g y p t i a n t r a d i t i o n ( u n d e r w h i c h h e a d i n g he p r i o r i t i z e s the priests) 1 9 s u p p l e m e n t e d b y a u t o p s y , 2 0
For the character of Herodotus' priestly tradition, see Lloyd (1975) 89 ff. On autopsy, see Lloyd (1975) 84 ff.
425
EGYPT
b u t f r o m 2,147
they are r e i n f o r c e d b y n o n - E g y p t i a n sources, p r e -
eminently Greeks21 w h o had acquired direct knowledge of Egyptian h i s t o r y f r o m t h e i r p a r t i c i p a t i o n i n m a k i n g i t . As a result H e r o d o t u s is j u s t i f i a b l y c o n v i n c e d t h a t his a c c o u n t o f the X X V I t h D y n a s t y is v e r y m u c h m o r e accurate t h a n w h a t precedes. T h e m a i n , i f n o t the o n l y , source o f i n f o r m a t i o n accessed t h r o u g h these i n f o r m a n t s
was
o r a l t r a d i t i o n w h i c h h a d e v o l v e d o v e r m a n y centuries i n the case o f pre-Saite kings. T h e r e is some h i s t o r i c a l f o u n d a t i o n f o r m u c h o f w h a t he says, b u t o r a l t r a d i t i o n is i n t r i n s i c a l l y fluid a n d retains o n l y w h a t is needed o r c o n s i d e r e d r e l e v a n t t o a g i v e n g e n e r a t i o n . T h e
past is
there f o r the benefit o f the present a n d is far f r o m b e i n g a sacrosanct set o f d a t a . T r a d i t i o n s m a y , arranged,
t h e r e f o r e , be s u p p l e m e n t e d ,
t r i m m e d , often radically customized,
re-
depending
entirely
o n c u r r e n t social, p o l i t i c a l , or c o n c e p t u a l i m p e r a t i v e s . T h e
histori-
cally specific is, t h e r e f o r e , g r a d u a l l y lost, a n d situations a n d i n d i v i d uals are progressively
assimilated to a r c h e t y p e s . 2 2
They would,
in
a d d i t i o n , have assimilated or been affected by such influences as folklore, political and cultural propaganda, u m e n t s o r features o f m o n u m e n t s ,
m y t h , tales e x p l a i n i n g m o n -
m y t h , a n d even r i t u a l p r a c t i c e .
Nevertheless, the general t r e n d o f the accounts o f these rulers reflects the classic activities o f E g y p t i a n kings. S u c h actions a p p e a r i n the t r a d i t i o n s r e c o r d e d b y H e r o d o t u s , even w h e n t h e y are n o t h i s t o r i c a l , because t h e y are p a r t o f the agenda o f E g y p t i a n k i n g s h i p , i . e . , the k i n d o f things w h i c h E g y p t i a n s expected a k i n g to d o .
Therefore,
the c h a r a c t e r o f this t r a d i t i o n indicates t h a t a n a u t h e n t i c i m a g e
of
E g y p t i a n k i n g s h i p was g e t t i n g t h r o u g h to H e r o d o t u s , even i f v e r y little genuine
history frequently came
w i t h i t . I t follows t h a t the
p a t e n t h i s t o r i c a l i n a d e q u a c y o f so m u c h o f 2 . 9 9 - 1 4 1 s h o u l d n o t be t a k e n as p r o o f t h a t the n a r r a t i v e d i d n o t e m a n a t e , at least i n some measure, f r o m E g y p t i a n sources, h o w e v e r m u c h i t m a y have been contaminated in transition. O n c e i n G r e e k hands, the process o f e v o l u t i o n o f these t r a d i t i o n s was i n f l u e n c e d b y n e w factors: t h e i n t r o d u c t i o n o f elements Greek tradition, chronological misunderstandings,
from
over-schematiza-
t i o n , analogies w i t h things G r e e k w h i c h m a y t h e n be i m p o r t e d i n t o E g y p t i a n accounts, a n emphasis o n things o f relevance a n d interest
21
See Lloyd (1975) 1 16 fit. Usually Herodotus simply refers to them as Hellenes, but references to Ionians and Cyreneans do occur. See Lloyd (1988a) 60 ff.; (1988b) 39 ff. 22
426
ALAN B. L L O Y D
to a Greek audience, and the pervasive predilection for the marvellous. T o all this we must add the Herodotean agenda. We have already described the contemporary-relevance principle applied to tradition i n oral societies, and that principle still exercised a profound influence on Herodotus' writing, but Herodotus belonged to what was, at least i n part, a literate society, and the advent of literacy induced a progressive reorientation, though this was neither immediate nor indeed complete. The capacity to record 'facts' i n writing has the effect o f exteriorizing and objectivizing them. T o a much greater extent than i n oral society these data are, and their reality must be accepted and respected. T o Herodotus certain phenomena i n which he is interested and on which he focuses existed/took place i n space and time. They are realities which form a matrix o f fact, but the important thing about such realities is their significance to his Greek audience, and he worked on the basis that he had complete freedom to use whatever narrative techniques he felt necessary to put over their perceived significance to his readers. Therefore, the modern rigorous distinction between fiction and non-fiction is not appropriate to the reading of Herodotus, or, for that matter, to historical writers o f the ancient world in general. Put simply, he clearly felt justified i n editing, supplementing, or highlighting received historical tradition as he thought fit, and, i f this involved departing from what we call history or even adding non-historical elements, he felt at complete liberty to do so. Thus it is that, underpinning the account o f Egyptian history and explaining it, we find a Greek moral universe. Egyptian history is used to illustrate and confirm fundamental Greek perceptions o f the way the world works: the punishment o f Pheros (2.111), the moral disquisition at 2.120, the concept o f divine punishment at 2.139, the rewards o f piety at 2.141, the fall o f Apries from unparalleled good fortune (2.161.2; 169), Psammenitus' recognition o f the pathos that can arise from the transitory nature o f human well-being (3.14), and, most telling o f all, the quintessentially Greek moral thinking driving the narrative o f the relationship between Amasis and Polycrates and the latter's disastrous end (3.39-43). This remarkable episode reveals with complete clarity the relationship between historical matrix and customization. The basis is evidently an alliance concluded between Polycrates and Amasis for strategic reasons i n the face o f the growing threat o f Persia. This alliance was terminated, probably by Amasis and probably because Polycrates had become more o f a liability than
427
EGYPT
an asset. T h i s
s i t u a t i o n is t h e n p i c k e d u p by H e r o d o t u s ,
together
w i t h l e g e n d a r y m a t e r i a l to p r o d u c e a ' n o v e l l a ' , a l i t e r a r y f o r m a p t l y described b y G e o r g e Coates: A novella is a creative construction by the author, designed to meet the author's distinctive goals. The author presents not simply what happened long ago and far away, but rather what happened and continues to happen so that the traditions carried by plot structure capture each new audience. Historical figures and events are caught up into an imaginative fabric produced by the creative activity of the author. Its concern is not to report historical events . . P O n e final p o i n t should be m a d e before leaving H e r o d o t u s o n E g y p t i a n k i n g s h i p . T h e a u t h o r shows n o awareness i n his h i s t o r i c a l n a r r a t i v e , o r a n y w h e r e else, o f the E g y p t i a n i d e o l o g y o f d i v i n e k i n g s h i p , i.e.. t h a t the k i n g was conceptualized as a g o d i n c a r n a t e , the l i v i n g e m b o d i m e n t o f the g o d H o r u s . H e does i n d i c a t e t h a t gods c o u l d c o m m u nicate w i t h h i m b y d r e a m s a n d oracles, t h o u g h these w e r e
media
w h i c h w e r e available to a n y o n e , a n d he does describe i n the case o f R h a m p s i n i t u s a c a p a c i t y to b r e a k outside the n o r m a l b o u n d a r i e s o f h u m a n a c t i o n (2.122), b u t t h a t is as close as he gets. I n t r i g u i n g l y , n o classical w r i t e r does any b e t t e r , despite the fact t h a t there w e r e Greeks w h o got v e r y close i n d e e d t o E g y p t i a n Pharaohs i n the L a t e P e r i o d . W e c a n o n l y c o n c l u d e t h a t , w h a t e v e r t h e o r y said, the d i v i n i t y o f P h a r a o h d i d n o t impress itself o n G r e e k observers i n p r a c t i cal contexts a n d was v e r y far f r o m b e i n g evident. E g y p t i a n priests are f r e q u e n t l y m e n t i o n e d b y H e r o d o t u s , p a r t i c u l a r l y those o f the m a j o r centres o f H e l i o p o l i s , M e m p h i s , a n d T h e b e s . The
H e l i o p o l i t a n s are said to be the m o s t l e a r n e d , b u t priests i n
g e n e r a l are r e g a r d e d as a m a j o r source o f h i s t o r i c a l i n f o r m a t i o n . T h e priests were a t o p i c o f considerable interest to H e r o d o t u s because a dedicated priestly class was a n u n f a m i l i a r p h e n o m e n o n i n the G r e e k world. He
also c o m m e n t s o n the o d d p r a c t i c e w h e r e b y there was
n o t one priest p e r d e i t y b u t a w h o l e g r o u p p r e s i d e d over b y a h i g h priest (2.37.5). H e recognizes t h e i r p o t e n t i a l to achieve p o l i t i c a l p o w e r w h e n he i n f o r m s us t h a t P h a r a o h Sethos h a d o r i g i n a l l y b e e n a priest o f Hephaestus.
H e is aware t h a t the p r i e s t h o o d was i n his t i m e an
h e r e d i t a r y office a n d has m u c h t o say a b o u t t h e i r p e r s o n a l habits.
23
(1992) 980. On the applicability of the term 'novella' where Herodotus' work is concerned, see also Ch. 11, pp. 257-8, this volume.
428
A L A N B. L L O Y D
I n all this we can see both similarities to and contrasts with Greek practice directing Herodotus' attention to aspects of this important group, and much of what he says amply qualified to a Greek as 'marvels'. Well informed though he is, however, Herodotus shows no knowledge of the theory behind the institution of priesthood, i.e., that the chief officiant is the substitute for Pharaoh i n temple ritual, and his function is to maintain deities which have the potential to die i f they are not properly tended. According to Herodotus the Warriors were a large proportion of the population. They were a hereditary class made up of two groups, the Kalasiries (250,000 strong) and the Hermotybies (160,000 strong). They were based almost exclusively in the Delta, and each was given 12 arourai (8 acres) of land free of tax. They were required to devote themselves entirely to war, and he is particularly emphatic on their exclusion from all forms of banausic, 'handicraft'. Their weaponry, at least in marine mode, is described as formidable, and they were well protected by helmets, shields, and breastplates (7.89.3). Every year the two groups had to provide a thousand men each to act as a royal bodyguard, and i n return for this they received generous rations over and above their land-allotments, ft is clear, though far from explicit, that Herodotus' description of this class is pervaded by contamination from his or his sources' knowledge of the Spartan elite warrior class, and that we must allow for severe distortion i n this account from that influence. We should edit out anything here which smacks too much of Sparta. Cowherds were certainly numerous, particularly i n the Delta area, and played a major part i n the Egyptian economy, but Herodotus felt under no obligation to linger over them. The same held true of the swineherds and the inland traders. The interpreters interested h i m rather more since they were allegedly created by Psammetichus I to facilitate communication with Greeks. Finally, he talks of the pilots, a select group within those who plied the waters of the Nile who were expert i n dealing with navigational hazards and are comparable to the elite corps of river pilots still to be found i n Middle Egypt. 24
23
}A
" Sauneron (1957) 27 f£; Homung (1983), 151 ff.; and Silverman in Shafer (ed.) (1991) 29, 64, 66-7. Froidefond (1971); Lloyd (1988a), 184 ff. It is a matter of some considerable doubt whether these late Pharaonic Makhimoi are the ancestors of the Ptolemaic class of the same name (Goudriaan (1988), 121 ff.). 2:1
429
EGYPT
Ine Economy Herodotus' knowledge o f the Egyptian economy is partial. He knows of the importance of agriculture and the contribution of irrigation to its success. He is also aware o f the phenomenon o f sedimentation. However, some o f his comments betray a limited understanding and considerable inaccuracy: K i n g M i n is claimed to have engaged in land-reclamation works at the site o f fifth-century Memphis, which was certainly untrue; Sesostris is asserted, quite wrongly, to have devised the Egyptian canal system; and K i n g Moeris is said to have been responsible for Lake Moeris, which he was not. ' There are frequent references elsewhere to royal water direction or canal-digging: Nitocris (2.100.3), Cheops (2.127.2), and Necho II's abortive Red Sea Canal (2.158). True or not, however, there is no doubt that these traditions reflect an Egyptian perception that a critical function o f the king lay in guaranteeing the workings o f the irrigation system, a point made emphatically at the very beginning o f Egyptian history by the mace-head o f K i n g Scorpion. Since Herodotus was highly aware o f the importance of irrigation, it is a little surprising that he can say at 2.14.2 that Egyptian agriculture was easier than anywhere else. Here he is evidently focusing entirely on the fact that little, i f any, ploughing would be needed, unlike in Greece, and that sowing the seed was a relatively easy task. However, he leaves out of account completely the enormous amount of labour required to keep the irrigation system up and running. 26
2
28
Herodotus refers to raw materials, mentioning the acquisition o f stone from the quarries at T u r a on several occasions and the transportation o f granite from Elephantine. Beyond that he does not go. Metals he mentions, gold, copper, silver, and iron all featuring at some point, but there is no awareness o f sources of supply or the
* Recent excavations strongly indicate that the settlement of Memphis moved gradually southwards during its long history, and that the site of 'Min's' Memphis lay to the north of the fifth-century site (Giddy. Jeffreys, and Malek (1990) 13; Giddy and Jeffreys (1991) 6; and Giddy and Jeffreys (199 The Fayum basin is a natural formation created by wind erosion. The lake was created when an offshoot of the Nile, now known as the Bahr Yusuf, broke through the western cliffs and flooded the lower part of the basin (Lloyd (1988c) 126). This monument dates from the late prehistoric period and shows the king wielding a hoe to create a canal (Spencer (1993) 56, fig. 36). 21
38
430
ALAN B. L L O Y D
ease or difficulty with which Egyptian requirements might be met. dffiere is nothing on the Egyptian timber problem, though he does mention the use of acacia in boat-building. He fails to grasp the enormous value o f papyrus as, amongst other things, a timber substitute, but he does recognize that it had its uses in boat-building (though not, oddly enough, to construct the hulls of boats), the weaving of ropes, and also in the making of sandals. Manufacturing, in particular technology, does come i n for some discussion. He can speak o f craftsmen (2.141.4) as an identifiable group, even though he does not recognize them as a genos. He is aware of the use of the vertical double-beamed loom in Egypt and contrasts its technique of beating-in with that customary on the more primitive Greek warp-weighted loom; his discussion of Egyptian boatb u i l d i n g is most remarkable and corresponds closely to k n o w n Pharaonic practice; building technology also attracts his attention, and he has much to say on the construction of pyramids and on the movement of large masses, not all of it as accurate as one would wish. As for trade, he knew of the existence o f inland traders (see above), the role of Naucratis as a Greek trading post (2.178-9), anc a large-scale wine trade with Greek and Phoenician sources of sup ply (3.6), but there is also some awareness in the account of Naucrati and the wine trade that a high degree of centralization existed. There are, then, strengths i n what Herodotus has to say, but th( strengths lie in detail. There is little evidence of insight into the way economic institutions worked i n Pharaonic Egypt. Above all the critical role o f storage and redistribution centres, such as palaces, temples, and large estates, finds no place in his account. 29
30
31
1
The Egyptian Belief System Herodotus' choice o f material for discussion in this area is partly determined by the conviction that much o f Greek religion had an Egyptian origin and partly by 'the marvellous dimension' which attached to so much Egyptian religious practice (Lloyd (1975) 141 ff.).
29
On the Egyptian use of papyrus, see Lucas and Harris (1962) index, s.v. On this intriguing account, see the studies of Morrison in Greenhill (1976) 161 ft'.; Lloyd 11979); and Haldane and Shelmerdine (1990). See the analysis of Lloyd (1988c) 63 f t ; (1995) 274 ff. 30
31
-
EGYPT
431
The information is marked by a profound reticence in discussing what he had learned about the character and actions o f the gods (i.e., myth and theology). This reticence is founded on the conviction that it was impossible to gain reliable knowledge on such topics (2.3). The concept o f Fate appears at 2.133.3, but only as part of a tradition acquired from Egyptian priests which may have its distant origins i n the Egyptian concept o f say, 'the predestined'. Xhe gods preoccupy h i m greatly, but he treads very carefully. He comments on an Egyptian opinion on the orders o f gods at 2.46, but this does not break his rule because it is presented simply as a doctrine held by the Mendesians. O f consuming concern is the issue of the interrelationship between Greek and Egyptian deities, a preoccupation which leads h i m into pervasive interpretatio graeca culminating i n the insistence that the vast majority o f Greek deities are of Egyptian origin. Evidently Herodotus felt that his inhibitions need not extend to discussing this historical issue because it did not commit h i m to making statements about the nature of the gods on his own behalf; he was simply expounding his considered opinion on the origins o f Greek concepts o f divine beings. T o h i m there were two main phases i n the development o f these concepts, the Pelasgian and the Hellenic. Pelasgian beliefs evolved i n two phases: at first, the objects o f cult i n Greece were undifferentiated and unnamed gods. Subsequently, the ounomata o f the gods, i.e., 'their names and personalities', came from Egypt and were taken up by the Pelasgians, not necessarily at one and the same time. These included the ounomata o f all the classic Greek deities, with the exception o f Poseidon (who allegedly came from Libya) and the Dioscuri, Hera, Hestia, Themis, the Charites, and the Nereids who were supposedly 'named' by the Pelasgians. Other religious material was also acquired from Egypt i n this process. The Greeks subsequently took all this over, sharpened it up and and fleshed it out, a process in which Homer and Hesiod played a crucial part. This ingenious but entirely erroneous construction means that, when Herodotus refers to the Egyptian A m u n as Zeus or W i l l i as Athene, he is not using the Greek names as a matter o f convenience for the sake o f his readers. O n the con32
33
32
This interesting passage is discussed in detail by Lloyd (1988c) 81 ff. On the Egyptian concept of fate, see Grumach-Shirun in Helck and Otto (1984) 598 ff. See further Lloyd (1976) 232 ff.; Mora (1986) 189 ff. 33
432
ALAN B. L L O Y D
trary, he is reflecting a profound conviction that the Greek and Egyptian deities are one and the same thing. The same issue o f transference o f doctrines arises at 2.123, where he insists, quite wrongly, that the Egyptians were the source o f the Greek doctrine of metempsychosis. Given his reticence on matters o f belief, it is not surprising to find Herodotus concentrating much attention on observable phenomena. H e speaks o f iconography, and festivals occupy a great deal o f attention: he distinguishes between different types and describes those of Artemis at Bubastis (2.60), Isis at Busiris (2.61), Athene at Sais (2.62), and Ares at Papremis (2.63), as well as those o f Dionysus (2.48) and Demeter (2.122). He also speaks o f the games of Perseus at Chemmis (2.91), which he evidently believed to be o f a thoroughly Greek character. Methods o f communication between man and god are equally exempt from Herodotus' inhibitions since they too are observable phenomena. He speaks o f portents and portent books, dreams, and oracles, all o f the latter given by the gods, though methods could differ. He also has much to say on methods o f sacrifice and the requirement for purity i n temples. He devotes a substantial amount of space to sacred animal cults which had particular value as a 'marvel', but here again he concentrates on observable aspects such as the animals which were worshipped, the penalties for killing them, their maintenance, and their mode o f burial. Egyptian mortuary practices are also a focus o f much attention, particularly mummification which he discusses to good effect, clearly because o f its status as a 'marvel'. He also speaks of repositories for the dead which he describes as 'sepulchral chambers'. What, then, is our verdict on Herodotus' portrayal o f Egyptian religion? Typically, although he knew a great deal o f correct or largely correct detail, particularly on cult practice, he lacks any grasp of the concepts underpinning belief or ritual; he shows no awareness o f the Egyptian concept o f gods potentially subject to mortality who must be maintained by priestly action; i n his account of animal cults there is no awareness o f the thinking underlying these practices; and i n his account of mummification he betrays no knowledge o f w h y it was practised, though 2.122 shows that he knew something o f the Egyptian concept o f the underworld, and 2.78 reveals an awareness of the Egyptian preoccupation with mortality.
EGYPT
433
Daily Life I n discussing daily life Herodotus makes a distinction between those Egyptians who dwelt i n the arable part o f Egypt and those who inhabited the marsh area, i.e., the northern part o f the Delta, but most o f what he says is intended to be valid for the entire country, and it is only at 2.92 ff., that he addresses the peculiarities o f the northerners. His dominant theme is the differences between Egyptian practices and those occurring elsewhere, above all divergence from Greek custom. His explanation for differences is the current Greek doctrine o f environmental determinism, a concept which is virtually explicitly stated at 2.35.2, and at 2.77.3 he is unequivocal on the point when he insists that the reason w h y the Egyptians, after the Libyans, are the healthiest o f men is the absence o f change i n the seasons. Once established, this thesis is developed at some length and to excess: he speaks o f contrasts i n shopping practices, weaving, transporting burdens, urination and defecation, organization o f the priesthood, care for the elderly, coiffure and practice related thereto, living arrangements with animals, bread-making, the kneading o f dough and mud, circumcision, habits o f dress, sail-making, and writing; the Egyptians are also described as the most pious o f men who lay particular emphasis on ritual purity. A t 2.77 ff. he specifically addresses the customs o f the Egyptians who lived in the arable part o f Egypt and are claimed to be the most learned i n traditions o f all men: they purge themselves for three days consecutively each month, believing that food is the source o f all illnesses (certainly an Egyptian idea but also a view widely held i n Hippocratic circles); they ate loaves of emmer wheat (as distinct from common Greek practice o f using barley or naked wheat); they made 'wine' from barley (another contrast); they also consumed fish dried i n the sun or salted and birds prepared i n a variety o f ways; they observed a macabre practice o f displaying the image o f a corpse at dinner parties to remind the guests o f their mortality and encourage them to enjoy themselves. They do not import customs from elsewhere but follow home-grown practices only, though similarities with Greek practices are identified, e.g., i n the Maneros/Linos song, i n the extreme reverence for the aged (shared with the Spartans), and their wool taboo (shared with 34
See the Hippocratic Airs, Waters, Places and, e.g., Snovvden (1971) 172 ff.
434
ALAN B. LLOYD
such groups as the O r p h i c s ) . T h e y w o r e t h e i r l i n e n tunics l o n g w i t h tassels at the h e m (whereas G r e e k t u n i c s w e r e o f w o o l ) , b u t t h e y d i d wear woollen garments
over t h e m . M e d i c i n e
i n E g y p t was
highly
specialized, u n l i k e the s i t u a t i o n i n G r e e c e . The
m a r s h dwellers p r o v i d e contrasts b o t h w i t h the rest o f the
c o u n t r y a n d w i t h Greece: u n l i k e o t h e r E g y p t i a n s b u t like the Greeks t h e y o n l y have one w i f e 3 5 a n d e x p l o i t c h e a p f o o d resources p r o v i d e d b y the seeds o f the rose lotus a n d p a p y r u s stalks, t h o u g h m a n y l i v e d exclusively f r o m s u n - d r i e d
fish;
t h e y m a d e o i l f r o m the c a s t o r - o i l
p l a n t w h i c h , u n l i k e G r e e k s , t h e y c u l t i v a t e d ; a n d t h e y h a d also develo p e d a n i n g e n i o u s m e t h o d o f c o m b a t t i n g mosquitoes b y u s i n g t h e i r fishing
nets as m o s q u i t o c u r t a i n s ( i . e . , 'a m a r v e l ' ) .
W h a t is o u r
final
v e r d i c t o n a l l this? T h e
ethnography
is c h a r a c -
t e r i z e d b y a w i d e range o f k n o w l e d g e w h i c h has a s o u n d basis i n f a c t , b u t its focus is d e t e r m i n e d b y G r e e k interests, i n p a r t i c u l a r the focus o n clear p o i n t s o f s i m i l a r i t y a n d difference to G r e e k c u l t u r e . T h i s c a n lead t o omissions a n d
to serious d i s t o r t i o n o f the
truth.
D i s t o r t i o n s can. be aggravated b y t w o a d d i t i o n a l faults, o v e r - s c h e m a t i z a t i o n a n d the t o o r e a d y a p p l i c a t i o n o f the post hoc ergo propter hoc fallacy. T h e
h i s t o r i c a l m a t e r i a l i n the e a r l i e r section o f B o o k
Two
a m o u n t s largely to a series o f tales w h i c h arc closer to E g y p t i a n stories a n d p r o p a g a n d a texts t h a n recognizable history, t h o u g h H e r o d o t u s makes the m o s t o f t h e i r n a r r a t i v e possibilities to spin a g o o d
yarn
a n d , w h e r e o p p o r t u n i t i e s present themselves, he exploits t h e i r d i d a c tic p o t e n t i a l for the benefit o f his G r e e k a u d i e n c e . T h e Saite h i s t o r y is e v i d e n d y m u c h m o r e
firmly
based o n h i s t o r i c a l events, b u t here
a g a i n i t is i m p o s s i b l e t o a l l a y the suspicion t h a t events w e r e chosen f o r discussion because they w e r e o f interest to Greeks, i n d e e d f r e q u e n t l y i n v o l v e d Greeks. W e
are n o t c o n f r o n t e d w i t h a n y t h i n g like
a c o n s i d e r e d assessment o f w h a t r e a l l y m a t t e r e d i n the Saite p e r i o d , t h o u g h historians are t o o o f t e n r e a d y to w o r k o n t h a t a s s u m p t i o n . T h i s s e c t i o n , h o w e v e r , offers H e r o d o t u s considerable p o t e n t i a l f o r t e a c h i n g his m o r a l lessons, a n d the r e l a t i o n s h i p b e t w e e n A m a s i s a n d Polycrates p r o v i d e s a superb e x a m p l e o f the use o f the 'novella' w h i c h is f u n d a m e n t a l
to H e r o d o t u s '
approach
to the w r i t i n g o f ' h i s t o r y '
35 A curious thing to say since the Egyptians were, in practice, almost entirely monogamous, whatever might be permitted in theory.
435
EGYPT
t h r o u g h o u t his w o r k . B u t be w a r n e d . T h e s e caveats o n a n d h i s t o r y d o n o t absolve
ethnography
us f r o m c o n f r o n t i n g his n a r r a t i v e w i t h
E g y p t i a n d a t a , a n d t h a t exercise f r e q u e n t l y reveals a w e a l t h o f a c c u rate d a t a , even i f , u l t i m a t e l y , H e r o d o t u s m u s t be c o n v i c t e d o f d o i n g n o m o r e t h a n s k a t i n g o v e r the surface o f E g y p t i a n c i v i l i z a t i o n . A l l is n o t surface, h o w e v e r . D e p t h lies elsewhere i n this e x t r a o r d i n a r y n a r r a t i v e , i . e . , i n the f u n d a m e n t a l
tension a n d r e s o l u t i o n o f
t h a t t e n s i o n w h i c h permeates the w h o l e o f the Histories. O n
the one
h a n d , t h e r e is a n insistence o n difference w h i c h reflects the agenda o f defining Greek a n d n o n - G r e e k . O n
broad
the o t h e r , there is a
p r o f o u n d willingness to tie E g y p t i a n h i s t o r y i n t o t h a t o f Greece to the extent t h a t the Egyptians are c l a i m e d to be the ancestors o f the K i n g s o f the D o r i a n s
a n d m u c h t h a t is f u n d a m e n t a l to G r e e k c u l -
t u r e is alleged t o have been i m p o r t e d f r o m E g y p t . E v e n the kings o f E g y p t are presented as i n h a b i t i n g w h a t is essentially a G r e e k m o r a l a n d i n t e l l e c t u a l universe. T h e r e f o r e ,
the c e n t r i f u g a l t e n d e n c y o f the
G r e e k / n o n - G r e e k d u a l i s m is c o u n t e r b a l a n c e d
and mitigated by
a
c e n t r i p e t a l i m p e r a t i v e to create a u n i t y o u t o f this d u a l i t y a n d t h e r e b y fuse the b i n a r y h u m a n w o r l d i n t o a coherent, intelligible, a n d tractable whole.
CHAPTER N I N E T E E N SCYTHIANS Stephanie
The
West
Scythians e n j o y a place o f h o n o u r i n H e r o d o t u s ' w o r k b y rea-
son o f t h e i r success i n t h w a r t i n g Persian expansionism. 1 D a r i u s ' unsuccessful b i d to e x t e n d Persian sovereignty n o r t h o f the D a n u b e f o r m s the c o n t e x t f o r a n a c c o u n t o f the N o r t h P o n t i c r e g i o n 2 a n d its p e o ples ( 4 . 1 - 1 4 4 ) , j u s t as Cambyses'
c o n q u e s t o f E g y p t p r o v i d e s a set-
t i n g f o r the b e t t e r o r d e r e d E g y p t i a n e t h n o g r a p h y i n B o o k T w o .
The
g r o u n d has been w e l l p r e p a r e d . T h e m i l i t a r y effectiveness o f S c y t h i a n m o u n t e d archers has been established e a r l y i n the Histories b y
Hero-
dotus' a c c o u n t o f a n i n v a s i o n w h i c h r e s u l t e d i n t h e i r d o m i n a t i o n o f W e s t e r n A s i a (i.e., f r o m the S c y t h i a n p o i n t o f v i e w , the greater p a r t o f the k n o w n w o r l d ) f o r t w e n t y - e i g h t years 3 ( 1 . 1 0 3 - 6 ; 130).
Darius'
c a m p a i g n is presented as r e t a l i a t i o n f o r t h a t historically d u b i o u s i n c u r sion a c e n t u r y e a r l i e r ( 4 . 1 . 2 , 4 . 4 , 4.118
1
f., 7 . 2 0 . 2 ) . * T h e m o t i v a t i o n is
To avoid cluttering the footnotes, I may note here a few works relevant to the whole of this chapter. Minns (1913) (a masterly study which has retained its value quite remarkably) and Rostovtzeff (1922) are of fundamental importance. The very full bibliography provided by Sulimirski and Taylor (1991) usefully supplements Rolle's invaluable introduction (though it is a pity that Rolle (1989) was not updated when translated from Rolle (1980), and the translator should have been more careful about the transliteration of Russian proper names). Bichler (2000) 15-110 offers a judicious and well-informed survey. On Herodotus Book Four Macau (1895), though somewhat dated, should not be overlooked; there is much of value in Dovatur et al. (1982). Corcella and Medaglia (1993) ad loc. is invariably helpful; likewise, on Books One and Three, Asheri (1988), (1990). I have been very sparing with references to publications in Russian, believing that this information will seldom be directly useful to readers of this chapter. A cumbersome phrase, but the older designation 'South Russia' long ceased to fit the region concerned. The curiously precise figure should probably be taken to represent a generation. While raids from the northern steppe were a persistent danger for the settled civilizations of Western Asia, and a raiding expedition lasting many years not in itself improbable, Near Eastern sources do not support the notion of a period of stable Scythian rule (arkhe). Does this strangely exaggerated picture reflect Scythian dreams of what they had once been and might be again? See further Ivantchik (1999). 2
3
4
SCYTHIANS
439
highly characteristic o f H e r o d o t u s , for w h o m reciprocity is an immensely i m p o r t a n t e x p l a n a t o r y p r i n c i p l e , 3 b u t can h a r d l y be relevant to D a r i u s ' m i l i t a r y aims w h i c h , like m u c h else a b o u t this c a m p a i g n , r e m a i n m y s t e r i o u s . 6 H e r o d o t u s , t h o u g h e v i d e n t l y a t t a c h i n g i m p o r t a n c e to the e x p e d i t i o n , is vague as to its d a t e , o f f e r i n g s i m p l y a terminus post quern, 'after the c a p t u r e o f B a b y l o n ' (4.1.1.). E t h n o g r a p h y here takes prece7
dence over h i s t o r y , b u t this section is spiced b y the appeal o f a narrative t u r n i n g o n the d i s c o m f i t u r e o f a p o w e r f u l aggressor at the hands o f a t o u g h , self-sufficient people d e t e r m i n e d t o defend t h e i r i n d e p e n d e n c e . I n the m a n n e r o f t h e i r resistance the Scythians
to
some extent p r e f i g u r e the A t h e n i a n r o l e i n the defeat o f X e r x e s ; b u t H e r o d o t u s does n o t alert us to this p a r t i a l p a r a l l e l , a n d there is a danger o f o v e r - e m p h a s i z i n g its i m p o r t a n c e f o r his t h o u g h t . O r d i n a r y G r e e k (and later L a t i n ) usage c o u l d designate as S c y t h i a n any n o r t h e r n b a r b a r i a n f r o m the general area o f the E u r a s i a n steppe, the v i r t u a l l y treeless c o r r i d o r o f d r o u g h t - r e s i s t a n t p e r e n n i a l grassland e x t e n d i n g f r o m the D a n u b e to M a n c h u r i a . 8 H e r o d o t u s seeks greater p r e c i s i o n , a n d this essay is focussed o n his Scythians, w h o b e l o n g to the N o r t h P o n t i c steppe; t h e i r t e r r i t o r y is d e f i n e d as the area stretchi n g n o r t h w a r d s f r o m the coast f o r t w e n t y days' j o u r n e y b e t w e e n the D a n u b e (Istros) a n d the D o n ( T a n a i s ) , e x c l u d i n g t h e t e r r i t o r y o f the T a u r i i n the m o u n t a i n s o f the C r i m e a a n d the coast o f the Sea A z o v (Lacus M a e o t i s ) (16-21; 4 7 - 5 8 ; 99-101). T h i s is m u c h
of too
schematic, a n d H e r o d o t u s h i m s e l f is n o t consistent i n his d e m a r c a t i o n o f Scythia; w e note t h a t he m e n t i o n s as a r e g u l a r o c c u r r e n c e Scythians crossing the Straits o f K e r c h ( C i m m e r i a n Bosporus) f r o m w h a t ( a c c o r d i n g to his account) is the t e r r i t o r y o f the T a u r i to the t e r r i t o r y o f the S i n d i (28.1), w h i l e t o the west Scythians, T h r a c i a n s , a n d Getae w e r e e v i d e n t l y closely i n t e r c o n n e c t e d . N o t a l l the groups
5
See Gould (1989) 42-85, and Ch. 9, pp. 000-00, this volume. Herodotus makes no attempt to accommodate these episodes (or Sesostris' invasion of Europe (2.102 10)) to his introductory theme of hostility between Europe and Asia (1.1 5). " Gardiner-Garden (1987) persuasively argues that Herodotus has conflated information relating to two campaigns, one between 520 and 514 against tribes just north of the Caucasus (to be distinguished from the expedition against the Saka Tigraxauda, recorded in the Behistun inscription) and a second across the Danube but short of the Dniester (cf. Strabo 7.3.14), sometime between 514 and 512. Hereafter no book number will be given in references to Book Four. Just as Achaemenid inscriptions use the term Saka for all the nomad tribes to their north, from the Danube to the Syr-darya. Modern works on the Scythians generally cover archaeological discoveries from the whole area of the steppe culture. 7
8
440
STEPHANIE
WEST
d w e l l i n g w i t h i n this r e g i o n were (in his view) p r o p e r l y called S c y t h i a n . He
reveals a serious p r o b l e m a b o u t t h e e t h n i c ' s d e n o t a t i o n at
81.1,
w h e n he says t h a t he h a d h e a r d v e r y d i f f e r e n t accounts o f t h e i r n u m b e r s , b o t h t h a t t h e y w e r e v e r y m a n y a n d t h a t true Scyths w e r e few. These true Scyths seems to be those w h o m he calls R o y a l Scyths, t h a t is, t h e g r o u p w h o c l a i m e d h e g e m o n y ( 2 0 . 2 , 2 2 . 3 , 5 6 , 5 7 , 71.2,
59.1,
cf. 20.1), a p p a r e n t l y w a r r i o r - p a s t o r a l i s t s . I t is generally a g r e e d ,
f r o m w h a t we k n o w o f t h e i r names, t h a t these were people o f I r a n i a n stock (Zgusta (1955)) t h o u g h the p o p u l a t i o n v e r y likely i n c l u d e d speakers o f d i f f e r e n t dialects. B u t H e r o d o t u s also recognizes n o m a d Scyths w h o are distinct f r o m t h e R o y a l Scyths (56, cf. 19 f.) a n d a g r i c u l t u r a l Scyths, r a t h e r o d d l y d i f f e r e n t i a t e d as aroteres (farmers) a n d georgoi (cultivators) ( 1 7 . 2 , 18.1). 9 T h e C a l l i p p i d a e , w h o are ( t a n t a l i z i n g l y ) d e s c r i b e d as H e l l e n e Scyths ( 1 7 . 1 ; cf. the people o f G e l o n u s (108)), are also a g r i c u l t u r a l i s t s . O t h e r g r o u p s f r o m this area m a y
have
S c y t h i a n customs a n d dress, b u t are n o t , i n his v i e w , Scythians (e.g., 17.1). T h e f l u i d i t y o f the t e r m even i n his o w n usage is e v i d e n t w h e n he later says t h a t the Persians call a l l t h e Scythians Sacae ( 7 . 6 4 . 2 ) , w h i c h extends t h e t e r m m u c h f u r t h e r east. I t is n o t clear h o w he t h o u g h t t h e Scythians d i f f e r e d f r o m t h e people w h o m
he believes they d i s p l a c e d , f t s h o u l d be n o t e d t h a t ,
t h o u g h his i d e n t i f i c a t i o n o f the p r e - S c y t h i a n p o p u l a t i o n as C i m m e r i a n s (1.2) has b e c o m e a firmly established a r c h a e o l o g i c a l c o n v e n t i o n , there are n o solid g r o u n d s f o r associating w i t h the N o r t h P o n t i c steppe t h e Gimmirri o f N e a r Eastern texts, w h o caused havoc i n Assyria a n d L y d i a d u r i n g t h e late e i g h t h a n d seventh centuries a n d w h o m the I o n i a n G r e e k s , o n the s t r e n g t h o f the s i m i l a r i t y o f t h e n o r t h e r n e r s '
own
n a m e f o r themselves, i d e n t i f i e d w i t h t h e m y t h i c a l Cimmerii f r o m t h e far west f a m i l i a r f r o m the Odyssey ( 1 1 . 1 4 - 1 9 : see H e u b e c k ad
be.).
10
I t is o b v i o u s l y futile for us t o a t t e m p t to c l a r i f y the r e l a t i o n s h i p b e t w e e n the v a r i o u s e t h n i c g r o u p s ; i t looks as i f the n a m e Scythes was e x t e n d e d f r o m one d o m i n a n t g r o u p o f I r a n i a n stock to e n c o m pass a large n u m b e r o f c u l t u r a l l y s i m i l a r t r i b e s , some o f w h o m mayhave been F i n n o - U g r i a n
9
or Proto-Baltic."
Herodotus'
reference to
It has been suggested that georgoi is an adaptation of a non-Greek name. On whom see Ivantchik (1993a, 1997). The savage Tauri (99-103) in the southern Crimea may well have been an unassimilated pre-Scythian remnant. ' The problems presented by shifts in the denotation of the ethnonym Kirghiz offer an instructive parallel: see further Hatto (1980) 300-1. 1(1
1
441
SCYTHIANS
trade w i t h the n e i g h b o u r i n g Argippaei
'conducted
through
seven
i n t e r p r e t e r s ' (24) n o d o u b t reflects t h e story-teller's p e n c h a n t f o r a significant n u m b e r , b u t p r o b a b l y gives a f a i r i m p r e s s i o n o f the p r e v a l e n t linguistic diversity. T h u c y d i d e s ' c o m m e n t (2.79) o n S c y t h i a n d i v i siveness w a r n s us against a s s u m i n g t h a t t h e r e g i o n f r o m t h e D a n u b e t o t h e D o n w a s p o l i t i c a l l y u n i t e d u n d e r a single c h i e f o r c l a n . 1 2 T h e p o p u l a t i o n was c e r t a i n l y less h o m o g e n e o u s
t h a n H e r o d o t u s supposed
a n d i t is clear f r o m t h e a r c h a e o l o g i c a l r e c o r d t h a t there were changes b e t w e e n t h e t i m e o f D a r i u s ' c a m p a i g n c. 5 1 3 a n d t h e m i d - f i f t h c e n t u r y , t h o u g h t h e differences seem n o t t o have struck t h e Greeks. T h e h i s t o r y o f the steppe has b e e n c h a r a c t e r i z e d b y successive waves o f invaders f r o m t h e east, w h o i n t h e course o f t i m e a r e assimilated m o r e o r less c o m p l e t e l y b y t h e e a r l i e r p o p u l a t i o n s b u t whose a r r i v a l i n e v i t a b l y b r i n g s changes
i n the power
relations between
ethnic
g r o u p s . 1 3 T h e G r e e k colonies c l e a r l y h a d some i m p a c t o n t h e p e o ples o f t h e h i n t e r l a n d , s t i m u l a t i n g a taste f o r w i n e a n d p r o v i d i n g immense
commercial opportunities; whether
w e t h i n k i n terms o f
s t r a i g h t f o r w a r d t r a d e o r o f p r o t e c t i o n rackets, S c y t h i a n chiefs w e r e growing wealthy. The
r i v e r system p r o v i d e s
a topographical grid for Herodotus'
f o c a t i o n o f d i f f e r e n t g r o u p s ; t h e p r i n c i p l e is s o u n d , b u t his c o n c e p t i o n is i m p l a u s i b l y s c h e m a t i c , w i t h rivers r e g u l a r l y r u n n i n g d o w n at r i g h t angles t o t h e coast, a n d t h e a t t e m p t t o i d e n t i f y obscure streams is w a s t e d l a b o u r . H i s o r i e n t a t i o n is c o n f u s e d a n d his c o n c e p t i o n o f S c y t h i a c a n h a r d l y be r e c o n c i l e d w i t h o u r m a p s ; b e t t e r g e o g r a p h i cal k n o w l e d g e w o u l d surely have l e d h i m t o see t h e i m p r o b a b i l i t y o f his view o f D a r i u s ' e x p e d i t i o n (cf. M i n n s (1913) 116 f ) . H i s d i f f i c u l t y i n m a s t e r i n g his sources is i n d i c a t e d b y h i s t h r e e f o l d e x p o s i t i o n o f g e o g r a p h i c a l relationships ( 1 7 - 2 7 ; 4 7 - 5 8 ; 9 9 - 1 1 7 ) (cf. his t h r e e f o l d t r e a t m e n t o f S c y t h i a n o r i g i n s ( 5 - 1 3 ) , a series o f Marchen-mouk strungt o g e t h e r i n sad contrast t o t h e selectivity o f his a c c o u n t o f C y r u s ' origins (1.95.1)). T h i s p a r t o f his w o r k is i m p o r t a n t f o r o u r evalua t i o n o f t h e level o f G r e e k g e o g r a p h i c a l k n o w l e d g e
i n the mid-fifth
c e n t u r y , b u t , unsatisfactory as w e m a y f i n d i t , w e m u s t
remember
t h a t n o o n e a t this date h a d , o r a s p i r e d t o , t h e b i r d ' s eye v i e w o f t o p o g r a p h i c a l relationships t o w h i c h c a r t o g r a p h i c c o n v e n t i o n s
12
have
Care needs to be taken over the translation of βασιλεύς in Book Four: 'chief, 'prince', or 'lord', rather than 'king'. See further Taylor (1994) 394, Bokovenko (1996). 13
442
STEPHANIE
WEST
a c c u s t o m e d us. T r a v e l l e r s (most c o m m o n l y t r a d e r s ) 1 4 r e c k o n e d dis tances b y t h e stages o f a j o u r n e y , n o r m a l l y in t e r m s o f w h a t m i g h t be c o v e r e d i n a day. P r o b l e m s o f n o m e n c l a t u r e m u s t have b e e n f r e q u e n t , w i t h d i f f e r e n t g r o u p s u s i n g d i f f e r e n t names f o r the same place (as w i t h B y z a n t i u m / C o n s t a n t i n o p l e / M i c k l e g a r d / I s t a n b u l ) (compare G e r m a n , Deutsch, A l l e m a n d , Tedesco,
or people
Niemecki).
I n his m u c h better o r g a n i z e d a c c o u n t o f E g y p t H e r o d o t u s ' repeated references t o his o w n observations a n d i n q u i r i e s m a k e i t i m p o s s i b l e t o d o u b t t h a t he h a d v i s i t e d the c o u n t r y w i t h o u t c a l l i n g i n t o ques t i o n his g o o d f a i t h o r at least r e g a r d i n g his
first-person
references as
a k i n d o f l i t e r a r y p e r s o n a , a p r o t o t y p e f o r the w i d e l y t r a v e l l e d Sir J o h n M a n d e v i l l e . T h i s is n o t the case w i t h his t r e a t m e n t o f S c y t h i a . A t a n early p o i n t i n his w o r k ( 1 . 1 0 5 . 4 ) , he appears to distance h i m self f r o m those w h o have v i s i t e d the r e g i o n . R e l a t i n g the t e r r i b l e h e r e d i t a r y m a l a d y i n f l i c t e d o n t h e E n a r e e s , 1 3 descendants o f t h e Scythians g u i l t y o f sacrilege against A p h r o d i t e d u r i n g t h e i r seventhc e n t u r y i n v a s i o n o f W e s t e r n A s i a , he says t h a t ' t h e Scythians
say
t h a t those w h o c o m e to S c y t h i a see f o r themselves the c o n d i t i o n ' o f the v i c t i m s o f the goddess' w r a t h . Unless the t e x t is m o r e seriously c o r r u p t t h a n a n y o n e appears to have supposed, H e r o d o t u s does n o t e n c o u r a g e us to believe t h a t he h i m s e l f h a d h a d t h e o p p o r t u n i t y to observe the a f f l i c t e d at first h a n d . 1 6 T h e o n l y p o i n t w h e r e he is g e n erally t h o u g h t to l a y c l a i m to
first-hand
o b s e r v a t i o n comes a l m o s t
at t h e e n d o f his S c y t h i a n e t h n o g r a p h y . C o n f e s s i n g to u n c e r t a i n t y about population
figures,
he says t h a t he was i n v i t e d to d r a w his
o w n conclusions f r o m a n i m m e n s e b r o n z e c a u l d r o n at E x a m p a e u s (81),"
a l l e g e d l y e m b o d y i n g t h e results o f a census c o n d u c t e d
by
A r i a n t a s w h o , w i s h i n g to k n o w the n u m b e r o f his p e o p l e , o r d e r e d every S c y t h i a n t o b r i n g a n a r r o w - h e a d ; f r o m the m a t e r i a l thus c o l l e c t e d was m a d e a n e n o r m o u s vessel, o f w h i c h H e r o d o t u s gives the d i m e n s i o n s . I take the c r u c i a l phrase tooovSe . . . djxecpatvov uot ec, o\|/tv to m e a n ' t h e y i n d i c a t e d this m u c h to m e b y w a y
of illustration',
r a t h e r t h a n ' t h e y s h o w e d (or o f f e r e d t o show) m e ' , as i t is u s u a l l y u n d e r s t o o d . O f course H e r o d o t u s was p r o b a b l y n o t averse to u s i n g
14
Polybius (4.39.11) terms εμπορικά διηγήματα (merchants' tales) what we should call 'travellers' tales'. On whom see further below, pp. 449-50. See further West (2000) 18 f. From 52.3 we learn that this lay somewhere between the Borysthenes (Dnieper) and the Hypanis (Bug/Sinyukha). 15
16
17
r
113
SCYTHIANS
an expression which might suggest autopsy but fell short of an explicit claim to have visited the area, I n any case, we should not underestimate the problems of travel to the N o r t h Pontic coast; Polybius (4.38.11) regarded even Byzantium as lying outside those parts o f the world generally visited. I f Herodotus went anywhere i n this region, he surely visited the city known to us as Olbia, though he himself preferred to call it the trading post or town o f the Borysthenites (17.1; 78.3; 79.2). The city's centrality i n his account corresponds to its peculiar importance among the N o r t h Pontic colonies; i f he had not himself been there, he must have been confident i n the information provided by others who had. His description of the climate (28), suggesting the Arctic Circle rather than the Ukraine, argues against first-hand observation; certainly it rules out a prolonged stay. Away from the resort strip the reality was, as Aristotle knew (Problems 25.6), the 'continentality effect', the cold winters and hot summers characteristic o f Inner Asia. I t is significant that Herodotus fails to realize that conditions of near-perpetual winter would have prevented keeping the herds o f cattle and horses on which the Scythian lifestyle depended as well as the cultivation o f grain vital for Greek trade with the area. While this chilly misconception, destined to become a cliche (cf. Hippocrates, Airs, Waters, Places 19.2-4, O v i d , Epistulae ex Ponto 1.3.53 ff.), might result from confusion with reports o f conditions further north, Herodotus would not have supposed that cold made it difficult for animals to grow horns (29) i f he had ever heard o f reindeer. His appeal to the Odyssey\ reference (4.85) to 'Libya, where lambs straightaway have horns' to support his theory o f the importance of heat for this development suggests that the charm o f an emphatic contrast distorted the picture. I n general we need to be alert to the 18
19
20
21
22
18
See further West (2000). For a thoroughly sceptical approach to Herodotus' northern travels, see Armayor (1978b). " The circumstances in which the city received its new name on the authority of Apollo of Didyrna are reflected in a bone plaque from Berezan dated to the third quarter of the sixth century; see further SEG 36.694; 40.611: Vinogradov (1994) 63 f, Dubois (1996) 146-54, esp. 148 f. On Olbia, see further Vinogradov and Kryzickij (1995). See further Backhaus (1976) esp. 179 81. It has also been suggested that the Greeks were over impressed by the tendency of the Straits of Kerch to freeze, as they believed that salt water would freeze only if the cold were extreme. 19
2
21
22
444
STEPHANIE
WEST
a t t r a c t i o n s , f o r o t h e r Greeks besides H e r o d o t u s , o f a sharp a n t i t h e sis b e t w e e n S c y t h i a a n d A f r i c a (and p a r t i c u l a r l y E g y p t ) . 2 3 W h e t h e r o r n o t H e r o d o t u s h a d h i m s e l f t r a v e l l e d to the n o r t h e r n coast o f the B l a c k Sea, w h a t he retails a b o u t the Scythians s h o u l d be treated as a synthesis o f i n f o r m a t i o n d e r i v e d f r o m various sources. 2 4 G r e e k contacts w i t h the peoples o f this r e g i o n are i n evidence already i n the Iliad
(first h a l f o f the seventh c e n t u r y ) . T h e
North
Pontic
n o m a d s e n t e r G r e e k l i t e r a t u r e as ' n o b l e m i l k e r s o f m a r e s , l i v i n g o n m i l k ' a n d are associated w i t h the A b i i , 'the m o s t decent o f m e n ' (Iliad 13.5 £ ) . K n o w l e d g e o f the i n d i g e n o u s peoples steadily increased w i t h the f o u n d a t i o n o f the G r e e k c o l o n i e s , 2 0 b u t the dangers o f the B l a c k Sea t e n d e d to isolate the G r e e k c o m m u n i t i e s o n its n o r t h e r n shore. T h e n a m e Skythes is first attested i n the f r a g m e n t a r y Catalogue of Women (F
150.15;
151),
ascribed to H e s i o d b u t p r o b a b l y t o be
d a t e d to the p e r i o d 5 8 0 - 5 2 0 . T h e r e the e p o n y m o u s Scythes is the son o f Z e u s , a n d the m a r e - m i l k i n g Scythians are described (together w i t h the E t h i o p i a n s a n d L i b y a n s ) as a p e o p l e 'whose m i n d is o v e r t h e i r t o n g u e ' , a p h r a s e p r o b a b l y t o be i n t e r p r e t e d as e x p r e s s i n g a p p r o v a l o f p r u d e n t reserve ( m a t c h i n g the praise o f S p a r t a n l a c o n i s m w h i c h H e r o d o t u s attributes t o the S c y t h i a n sage Anacharsis (77)). T h e d i s t i n c t i v e features o f the steppe lifestyle are encapsulated i n a single line (F 151), 'the l a n d o f those w h o live o n m i l k a n d have w a g ons as t h e i r h o m e s ' . F o r H e r o d o t u s a n d his c o n t e m p o r a r i e s , H o m e r a n d H e s i o d w e r e the classics, the a u t h o r i t y o f t h e i r w o r d s e n h a n c e d b y a n overestimate o f t h e i r a n t i q u i t y ; 2 6 t h e i r e v i d e n t a p p r o v a l set a firm
f o u n d a t i o n f o r a n i d e a l i z e d i m a g e o f the N o r t h P o n t i c n o m a d s .
F u l l e r , a n d m o r e i m a g i n a t i v e , t r e a t m e n t was g i v e n to the steppe peoples i n the lost epic Arimaspeia o f Aristeas o f Proconnesus, w h i c h H e r o d o t u s t w i c e cites (13.1; 16.1); t h o u g h he e v i d e n t l y saw n o p r o b l e m i n a n early s e v e n t h - c e n t u r y date f o r Aristeas, the Suda is m o r e likely to be r i g h t i n m a k i n g Aristeas c o n t e m p o r a r y w i t h Croesus a n d C y r u s , i . e . , w i t h the fall o f Sardis, c. 5 4 5 . 2 7 Some e t h n o g r a p h i c sophist i c a t i o n is i n d i c a t e d b y t h e m o s t substantial f r a g m e n t (11
23
Bernabe,
On the 'central opposition between Egypt and Scythia'. see further Redfield (1985) 106-9. Levy (1981) is very relevant; see also Shaw (1982/3). See further Ehrhardt (1983). Herodotus believed Horner and Hesiod lived some 400 years 'and not more' before his own time (2.53.2). See further Bolton (1962), Ivantchik (1993b), West [forthcoming]. 24
25 26
27
445
SCYTHIANS
1 Davies), w h i c h represents someone expressing a m a z e m e n t
at the
i d e a o f seafaring. I t is n o t clear h o w m u c h H e r o d o t u s o w e d to this mysterious p o e m ; the fact t h a t i t takes its title f r o m the
one-eyed
A r i m a s p i a n s , w h o m Aristeas d i d n o t c l a i m to have r e a c h e d (13) a n d i n w h o m H e r o d o t u s does n o t believe (3.116), is n o t the o n l y feature i n d i c a t i n g t h a t i t was n o t p r i m a r i l y a h e x a m e t r i c t r a v e l o g u e . N o r is it clear h o w w i d e l y k n o w n i t was, t h o u g h i t appears to have sufficiently impressed the a u t h o r o f the Prometheus Vinctus
28
for h i m to d r a w o n
i t i n d e v i s i n g t h e e x t r a o r d i n a r y i t i n e r a r y i n f l i c t e d o n I o (707—35, 790-807). M o r e severely f a c t u a l i n f o r m a t i o n was o f f e r e d b y H e r o d o t u s ' great predecessor, Hecataeus
o f M i l e t u s (FGrH
1) i n his Periegesis/Periodos
Ges (Description of the World). Its n u m e r o u s b u t exiguous f r a g m e n t s discourage the s u p p o s i t i o n t h a t Hecataeus
said m u c h a b o u t the cus-
t o m s o r h i s t o r y o f the peoples he m e n t i o n e d ; the w o r k seems r a t h e r t o have consisted o f a series o f i t i n e r a r i e s e n l i v e n e d b y occasional items o f interest. T h e
few f r a g m e n t s r e f e r r i n g to the N o r t h
Pontic
area (F 184—90; see J a c o b y ad loci) are q u i t e u n r e w a r d i n g . H o w e v e r , w e l e a r n t h a t Hecataeus t r i b e (F
classified the M e l a n c h l a e n i as a S c y t h i a n
185), whereas H e r o d o t u s says specifically t h a t t h e y are n o t
S c y t h i a n (20.2); so, t h o u g h H e r o d o t u s m u s t have digested the Periegesis, he d i d n o t f o l l o w i t b l i n d l y . M o r e c o n t r o v e r s i a l is the r e l a t i o n s h i p b e t w e e n H e r o d o t u s ' a c c o u n t a n d t h a t g i v e n i n the H i p p o c r a t i c Airs, Waters, Places ( 1 7 - 2 2 ) . W h e t h e r o r n o t this is r e a l l y the w o r k o f H i p p o c r a t e s is i r r e l e v a n t h e r e ; b u t a l m o s t c e r t a i n l y i t is to be d a t e d to the l a t t e r h a l f o f the f i f t h century.29 The
antithetical climatic conditions of Egypt and
Scythia
(Greece b e i n g a m e a n b e t w e e n these extremes) p r o v i d e the o r g a n i z i n g p r i n c i p l e f o r a discussion o f the effects o f e n v i r o n m e n t h u m a n development. T h e
on
a u t h o r is n o t a systematic e t h n o g r a p h e r ,
a n d the d i s t i n c t i v e , t r a d i t i o n a l steppe life-style h a r d l y interests h i m . R e a c t i n g against b o t h the i d e a l i z i n g i m a g e o f the n o m a d s a n d a realistic nervousness (cf. [ A e s c h y l u s ] , Prometheus Vinctus 709—12), h e is i n d i f f e r e n t alike to the e n d u r a n c e a n d skills e n t a i l e d b y t h e i r w a y o f life a n d to the tactical advantages a r i s i n g f r o m i n d e p e n d e n c e o f a fixed
28
base. S c y t h i a n customs a n d p h y s i o l o g y i n c u r his c o n t e m p t , a n d
More likely Aeschylus' talented son Euphorion than Aeschylus himself: see further M . L. West (1990) 51-72. See further Jouanna (1996a) 82, (1996b) 274. 29
446
STEPHANIE
WEST
making no attempt at a general survey he concentrates on what he thinks he can explain by reference to his scientific principles. Thus aetiology governs his selection o f material, and theory far outruns his empirical data. Notwithstanding the appeal o f the image of the physician as traveller and observer, we should not suppose that he had actually visited the area. I t seems most likely that he and Herodotus had some sources i n common but were independent o f each other; the work can usefully supplement Herodotus, but its author's prejudice against riding and life i n wagons distorts his account and his status as a scientific observer should not pass unquestioned. The loss o f so much earlier literature falsifies our perspective, and makes us overestimate the extent to which Herodotus was offering new information. Aristophanes' parody (Birds 941—3) has preserved for us Pindar's insight into the plight o f the impoverished warriorpastoralist forced by lack o f transportation to abandon the traditional way of life (F 105, from a hyporkhana addressed to Hieron I , com posed sometime between 476 and 467): A m o n g the Scythian nomads the man who lacks a wagon-borne home wanders an outcast from the host, and goes his way without fame.' This appreciation o f the underlying social and economic realities goes far beyond the fasci nation which the nomads' wagons continued to exercise until their supersession by the completely demountable yurt, which could be loaded on pack-animals. For Pindar's Sicilian audience the essentials of the steppe lifestyle were evidently a commonplace. 30
31
O f course, what Herodotus and other fifth-century Greeks knew about the Scythians was not limited to what they might discover on the spot or learn from books. Merchants involved i n the trade which brought to Greece grain (cf. 7.147) and slaves must have carried home reports of life i n the hinterland of the Greek colonies. Herodotus' tantalizing references to mixed Hellene/ Scythian groups (the Callippidae (17.1), the town o f Gelonus (108)) and to the Greek mother o f the unfortunately hellenophil Scyles (78.1) indicate some social contact, though we might doubt whether Greeks had much opportunity to experience the hospitality o f a nomad camp. Slaves of Scythian prove nance (like the archers who provided the Athenian equivalent o f a police-force, unflatteringly depicted i n Aristophanes' ITiesmophoiiazoitsai ' ) 3 2
See further West (1999b). I doubt if στρατών 'from the host' is sound. See further Hall (1989), Vos (1963).
SCYTHIANS
447
should not be overlooked as a source o f information. Hippocrates' reference (Airs, Waters, Places 21.3) to the ease with which Scythian slave-girls conceive is significant. But, even i f we disregard linguistic obstacles to communication, the majority o f slaves from this area sold to the Greeks are likely to have belonged to groups conquered by the nomads and may well themselves have been strangers to the true steppe culture. I n attempting to supplement Herodotus' account, to supply its deficiencies (which may sometimes be a matter of what he assumes we know already, as with his omission of any details of Scythian appearance or dress) and to identify its biases, we have two main, and to some extent overlapping, resources, ethnography and archaeology. Though we need to bear i n m i n d the dangers o f a synthesis combining details from vastly separated times and places, it would be absurd to neglect the insight which both can provide into the realities underlying Herodotus' account. The vast stretches o f the Eurasian steppe are favourable only to extensive animal husbandry, and its distinctive culture evolved early. The need to find natural pasture requires mobility, and this dictated virtually every aspect o f the nomads' lives, not only the structure o f their dwellings but also the style o f their clothes and their method of cookery. This culture was based on a self-sufficient economy; its own resources could provide its essentials, and its mainstay, the horse, could be used either to barter peacefully for other commodities and services (including the skills of carpenter and wheelwright essential for the construction of wagons) or to allow a form o f warfare in which the nomads were almost irresistible until the invention o f firearms. T o their victims their incursions seemed like a natural disaster, to be interpreted as a sign o f God's wrath against a sinful people (cf. Isaiah 5.26-8). The extent o f the raids by which the Scythians could supply their wants and satisfy a taste for portable luxuries is. 33
34
30
3t>
s> Formally this sentence is ambiguous, as it could refer to slave-girls serving the Scythians; but a reference to girls sold into service in Greece better suits his argument. ' See further Rostovzeff (1922) 212, Finley (1962), Braund and Tsetskhladze (1989). See further Sinor (1990) 1-18. * Herodotus was surely mistaken in supposing that animal bones were normally used as fuel (61); the nomads should not have lacked dried dung, l i r e detail may reflect a religious ritual. : 4
33
448
STEPHANIE
WEST
i n d i c a t e d b y t h e o c c u r r e n c e o f t h e i r d i s t i n c t i v e b r o n z e a r r o w heads i n M e s o p o t a m i a , E g y p t , a n d S y r i a , p a r t i c u l a r l y i n the walls o f t o w n s , t h o u g h w e c a n n o t always tell w h e t h e r these are evidence o f freelance forays o r o f assaults u n d e r t a k e n i n the service o f N e a r E a s t e r n rulers/" Herodotus,
w h o concentrates o n a n isolated 28-year
cam-
p a i g n o f c o n q u e s t e x t e n d i n g to Palestine a n d otherwise reduces the m i l i t a r y effectiveness o f the m o u n t e d w a r r i o r s to a p u r e l y defensive f u n c t i o n ( 4 6 . 2 , 3), has u n d e r e s t i m a t e d t h e i m p o r t a n c e o f w a r as a n a t i o n a l i n d u s t r y . W h a t e v e r h i s t o r i c a l r e a l i t y lies b e h i n d his a c c o u n t o f D a r i u s ' c a m p a i g n , the Persian k i n g m u s t have been c o n c e r n e d at the t h r e a t w h i c h t h e n o m a d s c o u l d pose to the settied peoples the Achaemenid The
of
empire.
c o n t i n u i t y o f steppe c u s t o m makes i t p r o f i t a b l e t o
w h a t we k n o w o f later groups,
38
compare
a n d t h e accounts o f m e d i a e v a l t r a v -
ellers are m o s t i l l u m i n a t i n g . T h e
limitations of Herodotus'
account
o f S c y t h i a n customs b e c o m e b l a t a n t l y o b v i o u s w h e n we c o m p a r e t h e r e p o r t o n his m i s s i o n t o the G r e a t K h a n at K a r a k o r u m
composed
i n the m i d - t h i r t e e n t h c e n t u r y b y the t o u g h a n d i n t r e p i d F r a n c i s c a n friar W i l l i a m of Rubruck
(Jackson and M o r g a n
(1990)).
'On
the
t h i r d d a y after w e left Soldaia w e e n c o u n t e r e d t h e T a r t a r s ; a n d w h e n I c a m e a m o n g t h e m I r e a l l y felt as i f I w e r e e n t e r i n g some o t h e r world'
(1.14): t h u s he r e c a l l e d t h e b e g i n n i n g o f his j o u r n e y .
His
detailed, sober, a n d f a i r - m i n d e d r e p o r t b r i n g s h o m e to us h o w strange the c u l t u r e o f the steppe peoples m u s t have seemed to t h e Greeks. Herodotus
c o u l d present E g y p t as T o p s y - t u r v y d o m
(2.35 f.) ( r a t h e r
as E u r o p e a n s c a m e to v i e w J a p a n ) ; his analysis is e m b a r r a s s i n g l y s u p e r f i c i a l , b u t at least conveys the idea t h a t c o n t a c t w i t h the a n c i e n t civilization o f the N i l e valley m i g h t provide a standard o f c o m p a r i son f o r w h a t i t m e a n t to be a H e l l e n e . T h e
steppe c u l t u r e was t o o
a l i e n t o a l l o w s u c h a n exercise i n s e l f - d e f i n i t i o n . 3 9 W i l l i a m ' s j o u r n e y w o u l d have been impossible w i t h o u t official assist a n c e . T h e e x e m p l a r y efficiency o f the M o n g o l e m p i r e was p e r f e c t l y c o m p a t i b l e w i t h the n o m a d i c w a y o f l i f e , to w h i c h the e s t a b l i s h m e n t
37
This is not the place to speculate about the effects of such exposure to Near Eastern art and luxury. Cf. Minns (1913) 47 f. and Morgan (1986) on Mongols; Matthews (1989) 332-55 on Huns and Alans. Hartog (1988) esp. 35-60, who stresses Herodotus' exposition of Scythian 'otherness' as directed towards establishing what it meant to be Greek, underestimates this incommensurability. See further Dewald (1990). 38
39
449
SCYTHIANS
o f t h e c a p i t a l at K a r a k o r u m
p o s e d n o t h r e a t . M o b i l e a n i m a l hus
b a n d r y calls f o r agreements o v e r g r a z i n g r i g h t s ; n o m a d s m a y r a n g e w i d e l y i n t h e course o f a n a n n u a l c i r c u i t , b u t they d o n o t
wander
at w h i m . H e r o d o t u s r a t h e r t a n t a l i z i n g l y reveals a glimpse o f S c y t h i a n a d m i n i s t r a t i o n , ( p r e s u m a b l y p r i m a r i l y t h e c o n t r o l o f g r a z i n g rights) i n a l l u d i n g to a n n u a l ceremonies p e r f o r m e d b y each nomarkhos ( w h i c h may
be t r a n s l a t e d ' d i s t r i c t g o v e r n o r ' ) i n his o w n
area (66). + 0
The
Scythian r e p u t a t i o n for a w e l l - o r d e r e d existence (cf. Aeschylus, Eumenides 700-3; F
198 R a d t ) is p e r f e c t l y consistent w i t h customs w h i c h seem
t o t h e sedentary p r i m i t i v e a n d
savage.
C o n t e m p o r a r y o b s e r v a t i o n d e m o n s t r a t e s t h a t there are varieties o f m o b i l e p a s t o r a l i s m . " M a n y households m a y
combine it with
agri
c u l t u r e o r h u n t i n g o r f i s h i n g , a n d those w h o spend t h e s u m m e r i n tents m a y r e t u r n to solid houses i n w i n t e r . H e r o d o t u s n o t o n l y k n o w s o f a g r i c u l t u r a l Scythians (17.2; 18.1), b u t includes p l o u g h a n d y o k e a m o n g the g o l d e n gifts f a l l e n f r o m h e a v e n i n t h e S c y t h i a n m y t h o f t h e i r o r i g i n s ( 5 . 3 ) , 4 2 i m p l y i n g t h a t t h e r e was n o t h i n g
un-Scythian
about farming;. I t is n o t so s t r a i g h t f o r w a r d to e x t r a p o l a t e insights i n religious m a t ters. K a r l M e u l i i n his f a m o u s ' S c y t h i c a ' 4 3 has l o n g b e e n t h o u g h t to h a v e e l u c i d a t e d the p r o b l e m s p r e s e n t e d b y the a n d r o g y n o u s Enarees, v i c t i m s (in H e r o d o t u s '
view) o f the ' f e m a l e disease' ( θ ή λ ε α ν ο ΰ σ ο ς ) ,
the i n h e r i t e d p u n i s h m e n t f o r t h e sacrilege c o m m i t t e d b y t h e i r ances tors at the t e m p l e o f A p h r o d i t e (i.e. A s t a r t e o r Atargatis) (67; Herodotus
1.105).
tells us t h a t t h e y a t t r i b u t e d to the goddess t h e i r exper
tize i n a p e c u l i a r f o r m o f d i v i n a t i o n , w i t h the bast o f the l i n d e n tree. H i p p o c r a t e s (Airs, Waters, Places 22), w h o connects the c o n d i t i o n w i t h incessant r i d i n g , gives a f u l l e r p i c t u r e , o u t l i n i n g the p h y s i c a l d e t e r i o r a t i o n w h i c h leads t h e v i c t i m s t o a d o p t w o m e n ' s clothes, w o r k , a n d m a n n e r o f speech; he adds t h a t t h e natives, seeing a d i v i n e cause f o r this c o n d i t i o n , h o l d such m e n i n awe a n d reverence, a significant detail not f o u n d i n Herodotus.
M e u l i , c o m b i n i n g this evidence f o r
a p e c u l i a r r e l i g i o u s status w i t h r e p o r t s o f o c c a s i o n a l transvestism
40
Significantly (in view of the importance of the Egypt/Scythia antithesis) the only other instance of this term in Herodotus comes in his account of Egypt (2.177.2). See further Vainshtein (1980), Levi (1989). Plough and yoke really constitute a unit; some have seen in these gifts the symbols of the Dumezilian three functions structuring Indo-European society. Meuli (1935); see also Halliday (1910-11), Margreth (1993), Taylor (1996) 210-14. 41
42
4 3
450
STEPHANIE
a m o n g Siberian shamans,
WEST
has seemed t o m a n y t o have
f o r this mysterious g r o u p . W h a t to H e r o d o t u s
accounted
and Hippocrates
ap-
p e a r e d to be a m e d i c a l p r o b l e m is thus to be i n t e r p r e t e d as the o u t w a r d manifestation o f a religous calling. M e u l i ' s views always c o m m a n d respect, b u t a reversal o f g e n d e r roles is u n u s u a l a m o n g the shamans o f n o r t h e r n E u r a s i a , 4 4 a n d seems g e n e r a l l y to be r e g a r d e d as a n o d d i t y , even i f n o o d d e r t h a n o t h e r r e q u i r e m e n t s w h i c h the
shaman's
spirits m i g h t i m p o s e . M o r e o v e r ,
observed
shamanizing
as n o r m a l l y
makes h e a v y p h y s i c a l d e m a n d s o n the p r a c t i t i o n e r , inconsistent w i t h the enfeebled c o n d i t i o n w h i c h H i p p o c r a t e s a t t e m p t s to e x p l a i n .
We
m i g h t a d d t h a t , i f M e u l i ' s a p p r o a c h is r i g h t , i t implies a l a r m i n g l y s u p e r f i c i a l o b s e r v a t i o n a n d m i s c o n c e p t i o n o n the p a r t o f the Greeks to w h o m Herodotus m a n s are
figures
a n d Hippocrates o w e d their i n f o r m a t i o n . Sha-
o f great a u t h o r i t y a n d prestige w i t h i n t h e i r c o m -
m u n i t i e s , c o m b i n i n g the role o f p r o p h e t s , 4 0 healers, weather-controllers, poets, a n d g e n e r a l advisers. I t m a y be b e t t e r to postulate a genetic abnormality.40 We
really do not k n o w
enough
about Scythian
r e l i g i o n to say
w h e t h e r i t c a n p r o p e r l y be called s h a m a n i s t i c , t h o u g h M e u l i ((1935) 121—7) saw impressive similarities b e t w e e n the p r o c e d u r e used Siberian
shamans
to escort souls to t h e w o r l d o f the d e a d
by and
H e r o d o t u s ' d e s c r i p t i o n , likewise as the c o n c l u s i o n o f f u n e r a r y r i t u a l , o f Scythian
h e m p - i n h a l i n g (73—5; c o n t r a s t the reference to p u r e l y
r e c r e a t i o n a l p o t - s m o k i n g a m o n g the Massagetae (1.202.2)).
Herodotus'
a c c o u n t c a n be n i c e l y i l l u s t r a t e d b y the sets o f h e m p - s m o k i n g e q u i p m e n t f o u n d , far to the east, i n the f r o z e n t o m b s o f P a z y r y k i n the A l t a i , 4 ' t h o u g h the a r c h a e o l o g i c a l c o n t e x t does n o t setde w h e t h e r its f u n c t i o n was sacred o r secular. H e r o d o t u s ,
indefatigably interested
i n r i t u a l ( 6 0 - 2 ) b u t i n d i f f e r e n t to t h e o l o g y , believed that the Scythians w o r s h i p p e d d i v i n i t i e s w h o c o u l d be e q u a t e d w i t h H e s t i a , Z e u s ,
Ge,
A p o l l o , A p h r o d i t e , P o s e i d o n , A r e s , a n d H e r a c l e s (59); these i d e n t i f i cations are i n a c c o r d a n c e w i t h the n o r m a l G r e e k a p p r o a c h to the problems of comparative
4 4
r e l i g i o n , t h o u g h a t h e o l o g i c a l system i n
I have no idea whether it is commoner in Greenland and North America. We should not expect them to have to compete with other specialists in divination, as the Enarees apparently do (67). See further Lieber (1996), West (1999b). " See Rolle (1989) 93 5, Corcella and Medaglia (1993) plate 59. On Pazyryk see further Rudenko (1970), Jettmar (1967) 82-140. 43
4 6
451
SCYTHIANS
w h i c h H e s t i a was p r e - e m i n e n t m i g h t be t h o u g h t to call i n t o quest i o n the v a l i d i t y o f such e q u a t i o n s (see B u r k e r t (1990)).
I t seems a
safe guess t h a t the religious beliefs o f the v a r i o u s N o r t h P o n t i c p e o ples w e r e a n i m i s t i c , w i t h p l e n t y o f l o c a l p e c u l i a r i t i e s a n d a n u n d o g m a t i c c a p a c i t y to absorb f o r e i g n elements. Some scholars have a t t a c h e d i m p o r t a n c e to the Ossetes' k i n s h i p w i t h the Scythians; u n l i k e l y to p r o v e
b u t study o f Ossetic f o l k l o r e a n d t r a d i t i o n s is
r e w a r d i n g f o r o u r purposes.
S t i l l , the v e r y
exis-
tence o f t h e i r h e r o i c epic, c e l e b r a t i n g the N a r t s , insatiable i n t h e i r a p p e t i t e f o r d r i n k a n d w a r , 4 8 s h o u l d m a k e us w o n d e r w h e t h e r legend of Scythian
the
descent f r o m t h e t h r e e sons o f T a r g i t a u s
or
I d a n t h y r s u s ' resistance to A c h a e m e n i d aggression h a d been celebrated b y S c y t h i a n b a r d s . O r a l p o e t r y does n o t , after a l l , r e q u i r e c u m b e r some e q u i p m e n t a n d has c e r t a i n l y Inner
Asia.
flourished
a m o n g the n o m a d s
of
49
Archaeology
has spectacularly s u p p l e m e n t e d H e r o d o t u s '
account,
b u t w e m u s t resist the t e m p t a t i o n to d o v e t a i l the results o f excavation w i t h Herodotus'
text. E v e r y year i t becomes
e v i d e n t t h a t the
p i c t u r e was far m o r e c o m p l e x a n d v a r i e d t h a n i t p r e v i o u s l y a p p e a r e d , a n d the greater accessibility o f p u b l i c a t i o n s r e l a t i n g to this r e g i o n is cause for p r o f o u n d satisfaction. 5 0 T h e frozen b u r i a l m o u n d s o f Pazyryk. w h i c h have preserved perishable m a t e r i a l s , have w o n d e r f u l l y e n l a r g e d o u r c o n c e p t i o n o f the range o f c r a f t s m a n s h i p c o m m a n d e d
by
the
steppe peoples. M o r e r e c e n t l y t h e r e have been sensational discoveries at A r z h a n a n d I s s y k , ' 1
likewise f a r t o the east o f
Herodotus'
S c y t h i a b u t c u l t u r a l l y closely r e l a t e d . l o m b s are p a r t i c u l a r l y i m p o r t a n t f o r the study o f n o m a d i c
cul-
t u r e , since the lifestyle leaves f e w r e m a i n s f o r the archaeologist; even today
concentration on a few,
easily p o r t a b l e possessions,
among
w h i c h a c a u l d r o n f o r c o o k i n g m e a t is l i k e l y to be the m o s t b u l k y , m a y give the outsider a m i s l e a d i n g impression o f poverty. T h e burial mounds
o f the E u r a s i a n steppe have preserved
and extraordinary
48
artifacts; the i m p o r t a n c e
grander
magnificent
o f this m a t e r i a l was
See further Dumézil (1930), (1978), Bailey (1980). See further Hatto (1980). For a representation of a Scythian minstrel playing the lyre see Rolle (1989) 95. Marchenko and Vinogradov (1989) is a valuable early example of this welcome trend, which brought the inauguration (in 1994) of a very relevant new journal, Ancient Civilizations from Scythia to Siberia. See further Rolle (1989) 38-44, 46-51. 49
51
452
STEPHANIE
WEST
r e c o g n i z e d a l r e a d y b y Peter the G r e a t , w h o t o o k steps to insure the p r o t e c t i o n o f a n t i q u i t i e s a n d thus l a i d the f o u n d a t i o n o f the vellous collections o f the H e r m i t a g e .
mar-
B u t spectacular artifacts, r e p -
52
r e s e n t i n g b o t h the i n d i g e n o u s style o f the steppe a n d , l a t e r , the w o r k o f Greek craftsmen, contribute only a small part o f what we learn f r o m the m o s t impressive t u m u l i . T h e i r v e r y scale i m p l i e s the o r g a n i z a t i o n ( a n d feeding) o f a considerable l a b o u r f o r c e , a n i n d i c a t i o n o f the
firm
a d m i n i s t r a t i o n w h i c h u n d e r l a y the a p p a r e n t f r e e d o m
the steppe peoples.
Systematic
excavation
of
(as opposed t o g l o r i f i e d
t r e a s u r e - h u n t i n g ) has revealed the skill i n v o l v e d i n t h e i r e r e c t i o n a n d the e x t e n t t o w h i c h m a t e r i a l was t r a n s p o r t e d f r o m elsewhere t o c o n s t r u c t the m o n u m e n t .
O f course, r i c h grave m o u n d s were a t t r a c t i v e
to r o b b e r s , a n d the e n o r m o u s l a b o u r - f o r c e r e q u i r e d m e a n t t h a t t o o m a n y people k n e w the l a y o u t ; m a n y t u m u l i w e r e p l u n d e r e d q u i t e soon after t h e i r e r e c t i o n . B u t the evidence r e m a i n s f o r
extravagant
slaughter o f livestock; occasionally, t o o , a few h u m a n victims are f o u n d , w h o m a y o r m a y n o t have chosen t o lie w i t h t h e i r d e a d master. I t is n a t u r a l to c o m p a r e H e r o d o t u s ' f u n e r a l a n d grave
mound
(70
account o f a Scythian royal
f.). T h e
variety evident a m o n g
the
t u m u l i so f a r e x c a v a t e d shows t h a t he was w r o n g i n supposing p r a c tice t o be u n i f o r m ; n o d o u b t he g e n e r a l i z e d f r o m w h a t he c o u l d l e a r n o f the last such i n t e r m e n t . A
close m a t c h f o r his d e s c r i p t i o n
has n o t b e e n f o u n d , b u t the graves o f the n o m a d princes o f the s i x t h a n d earlier fifth centuries still a w a i t discovery, to bridge a gap b e t w e e n the r i c h t u m u l i o f the K u b a n ( n o r t h e r n f o o t h i l l s o f the Caucasus) a n d the f o u r t h - c e n t u r y elite graves o f the U k r a i n e , above all A l e x a n d ropol, Chertomlyk,
and Tolstaya Mogila.
R e n e w e d e x c a v a t i o n o f the C h e r t o m l y k
b a r r o w (21 m . h i g h ) has
revealed t h e e x t r a o r d i n a r y skill i n v o l v e d i n its c o n s t r u c t i o n ; the erect i o n o f this h u g e m o u n d ,
i n v o l v i n g m o r e t h a n 7,500 c u b i c metres
o f soil, was n o t s i m p l y a m a t t e r o f enthusiastic s p a d e w o r k might rather think f r o m Herodotus'
(as one
r e p o r t (71.5)). M o r e o v e r ,
the
stones used i n its c o n s t r u c t i o n , some as m u c h as 2.5 m . h i g h , w e r e b r o u g h t f r o m a distance o f 2 8 -
k m . E x c a v a t i o n has b r o u g h t p a r t i a l
c o n f i r m a t i o n o f the m o s t m e m o r a b l e feature o f H e r o d o t u s '
descrip-
t i o n (72), 'a circle o f fifty i m p a l e d y o u n g m e n u p o n i m p a l e d horses
52
For excellent illustrations combined with some account of the development of Scythian archaeology, see Jettmar (1967), Artamonov (1969), Rolle (1979), From the Lands of the Scythians, Rolle (1989), Rolle et al. (1991), Schütz (1994).
453
SCYTHIANS
s t a n d i n g o n ghastly g u a r d a b o u t a Prince's t o m b ' ( M i n n s (1913) 88). B y the f o u n d a t i o n o f the fence w e r e f o u n d the bones o f n i n e horses, pieces o f harness a n d some h u m a n bones ( C h e r n e n k o (1994) 47). W e m u s t resist the t e m p t a t i o n to speculate a b o u t the beliefs i m p l i e d b y S c y t h i a n b u r i a l practices. B u t the artifacts c o n s i g n e d to the t o m b s o f f o u r t h - c e n t u r y chieftains are n o t i r r e l e v a n t to H e r o d o t u s ' The
account.
w o r k o f G r e e k c r a f t s m e n i n g o l d a n d silver (metals n o t to be
f o u n d i n the steppe region) show t h a t S c y t h i a n magnates w e r e g r o w i n g w e a l t h y , n o d o u b t f r o m the a l m o s t limitless c o m m e r c i a l outlets o p e n e d u p b y the G r e e k colonies. T h e the K u l ' O b a
m u c h r e p r o d u c e d vase f r o m
k u r g a n , d i s c o v e r e d i n 1830,
53
revealed w h a t
l o o k e d like ( c o n t e m p o r a r i e s saw a r e s e m b l a n c e to the D o n a n d w h a t m e n w o r e . ( W o m e n ' s everyday
Scythians cossacks) 1 4
dress is m o r e mysterious.)
M a l e j e w e l l e r y at its grandest, the m a r v e l l o u s g o l d p e c t o r a l f r o m the T o l s t a y a M o g i l a 5 5 c o m b i n e s a n u p p e r frieze o f scenes f r o m p a s t o r a l life w i t h a l o w e r frieze o f p r e d a t o r y a n i m a l s ( i n c l u d i n g griffins) a n d t h e i r v i c t i m s , the l a t t e r a strange a p p l i c a t i o n o f G r e e k c r a f t m a n s h i p to themes characteristic o f the i n d i g e n o u s ' a n i m a l style'. M o r e m o d e s t graves c o n t r i b u t e s o l i d l y to o u r v i e w o f the S c y t h i a n w o r l d . A m o n g the t u m u l i so g r o u p e d
together that they can
d e s c r i b e d as cemeteries, t h e r e is sufficient v a r i a t i o n i n
be
grave-goods
to i n d i c a t e d i v e r s i t y i n status a n d w e a l t h . N o t o n l y m e n w e r e b u r i e d w i t h the s t a n d a r d m i l i t a r y e q u i p m e n t o f b o w , spears, a n d s w o r d ; the presence
o f weapons
quiver, and
arrows,
(along w i t h spindles,
mirrors, a n d jewellery) i n an increasing n u m b e r o f women's i n the S c y t h i a n Sauromatian
r e g i o n ( a n d a n even
graves
higher proportion f r o m
area t o the east o f the D o n )
the
has revealed w h a t l e d to
t h e l o c a t i o n o f t h e m y t h i c a l A m a z o n s i n t h i s a r e a (cf.
110-17,
H i p p o c r a t e s Airs, Waters, Places 17). T h e s e ' A m a z o n ' graves raise i n t e r esting questions, b u t w e s h o u l d e m p h a s i z e the p r a c t i c a l v a l u e o f such skills i n defence o f a n i m a l s a n d f a m i l y , p a r t i c u l a r l y v a l u a b l e
M
when
See Minns (1913) 200-2, figs. 93, 94, Artamonov (1969) 69, plates 226-9, 232-3, From the Lands of the Scythians plates 17, 18, Rolle (1989) 66-8, plate 22, Corcella (1993) plates 24-6 Schütz (1994) 169-72, plates 124-27. Alexander Blok was behind the times when he described them as Asiatics with greedy eyes slanting' (The Scythians). See From the Lands of the Scythians plates 31-3, Rolle (1989) plates 14-18, Corcella and Medaglia (1993) plates 33-4; Schütz (1994) 12 f., 60 f., 63, 68, 194-203, plates 145-8. 31
35
454
STEPHANIE
the m e n o f a g r o u p w e r e absent,
WEST
r a i d i n g o r r o u n d i n g u p beasts;'"'
b e t t e r t o a r m w o m e n t h a n slaves. S o m e l i g h t has p e r h a p s
been t h r o w n o n t h e mysterious c i t y o f
G e l o n u s w h i c h H e r o d o t u s (108) describes as s i t u a t e d i n t h e forest steppe r e g i o n towards the north-east, a n d s u r r o u n d e d b y h i g h w o o d e n walls n e a r l y f o u r miles l o n g each w a y ; its b u i l d i n g s w e r e
wooden,
a n d i t c o n t a i n e d altars a n d temples t o t h e G r e e k gods c o n s t r u c t e d i n a Greek manner;
its i n h a b i t a n t s , w h o spoke a m i x t u r e o f G r e e k
a n d S c y t h i a n , w e r e descended f r o m Greeks w h o h a d come f r o m t h e t r a d i n g stations (by w h i c h H e r o d o t u s m u s t m e a n t h e settlements f r o m w h i c h the colonies developed). known
M a n y f o r t i f i e d settlements are n o w
f r o m t h e forest steppe r e g i o n ; o u t s t a n d i n g a m o n g
t h a t o f Bel'sk o n t h e R i v e r V o r s k l a . 5 7
t h e m is
Its r a m p a r t s are 2 0 . 5 miles
l o n g , a n d t h e oldest b u i l d i n g phase goes b a c k t o t h e seventh o r s i x t h c e n t u r y . I t s i d e n t i f i c a t i o n w i t h G e l o n u s c a n b e r e g a r d e d as n o m o r e t h a n s p e c u l a t i o n , b u t G r e e k c o n n e c t i o n s are i n d i c a t e d b y t h e a b u n dance o f G r e e k p o t t e i y f o u n d there (over 10,000 pieces), t w o v e r y Greek-style gems, o n e o f w h i c h bears a G r e e k i n s c r i p t i o n o f w h i c h o n l y three letters s u r v i v e , a n d a spindle w i t h G r e e k g r a f f i t i . I t w a s the first site o f a s k u l l - c u p w o r k s h o p (cf. 65) t o be discovered. O l b i a is c e n t r a l t o H e r o d o t u s '
assemblage o f i n f o r m a t i o n , a n d w e
m i g h t expect t h a t t h e city's r e l a t i o n s h i p t o t h e s u r r o u n d i n g p o p u l a tion
has c o l o u r e d his a c c o u n t . H e does n o t m u c h a d m i r e
Scythian
customs (46.2), a n d his curious d e s c r i p t i o n o f the processing o f mare's m i l k (see W e s t (1999a)) involves a p r a c t i c e o f u n a c c o u n t a b l e b r u t a l i t y , t h e b l i n d i n g o f t h e slaves e m p l o y e d i n this task (2), w h i c h strikes a d i s t u r b i n g k e y n o t e (cf. 1.73). T h e v i c t i m s o f S c y t h i a n a r r o w s f r o m the e a r l y
fifth
c e n t u r y i n t e r r e d i n t h e necropoleis o f B e r e z a n a n d
O l b i a are o n e i n d i c a t i o n o f S c y t h i a n pressure o n t h e c i t y , as is t h e r e t r e a t o f t h e p o p u l a t i o n at this p e r i o d f r o m the khora ( a g r i c u l t u r a l t e r r i t o r y ) t o greater security i n , o r close t o , t h e c i t y , w h i c h h a d , i t seems, f o r a t i m e t o a c k n o w l e d g e
a barbarian protectorate;38 H e r o -
dotus cites t h e S c y t h i a n r u l e r ' s agent (epitropos), T y m n e s , f o r i n f o r m a -
5 6
See Rolle (1989) 86-91, Melyukova (1990) 106. On the general all-round competence of women among the nomads see Minns (1913) 84; among twentieth-century Mongols: Cable and French (1950) 169 (possibly somewhat starry-eyed). See. further Shramko (1987) esp. 121-6, 160-3, 174-9, Rolle (1989) 117-19, Tsetskhladze (1998) 50, 54 f. See Vinogradov and Kryzickij (1995) 130-3. 57
58
455
SCYTHIANS
t i o n a b o u t A n a c h a r s i s . 3 9 T h e city's a t t r a c t i o n s l e d to the d o w n f a l l o f the p h i l h e l l e n i c S c y t h i a n p r i n c e Scyles, t o be d a t e d a p p a r e n t l y to the
first
h a l f o f the
fifth
century (78-80);
the d i s c o v e r y , some six
miles f r o m I s t r i a , o f a r i n g b e a r i n g his n a m e i n G r e e k script (tog e t h e r w i t h a n i n s c r i p t i o n o n its b a n d w h i c h s h o u l d p e r h a p s
be
taken as a n a t t e m p t to r e n d e r S c y t h i a n i n G r e e k letters) 6 0 adds v i v i d ness t o H e r o d o t u s ' story, a n d , i n p a r t i c u l a r , to t h e d e t a i l t h a t Scyles' m o t h e r , herself G r e e k , h a d t a u g h t h i m to r e a d . 6 1 I t is cause for regret t h a t i t was n o t the c u s t o m a m o n g the S c y t h i a n n o b i l i t y to l a b e l t h e i r possessions. We
c a n n o t strictly say t h a t the
Scythians w e r e i l l i t e r a t e , t h o u g h s u r v i v i n g examples o f t h e i r use o f script are v e r y f e w . 6 2 I d a n t h y r s u s ' s y m b o l i c message o f a b i r d ,
a
m o u s e , a f r o g , a n d five a r r o w s ( 1 3 1 - 2 ) s h o u l d n o t be c o n s t r u e d as evidence o f i l l i t e r a c y ; the objects c o n v e y e d his m e a n i n g u n i m p e d e d b y a n y l a n g u a g e b a r r i e r , a n d this t y p e o f code e n j o y e d a l o n g life i n I n n e r A s i a . 6 3 B u t c e r t a i n l y a d e a r t h o f texts leaves us i n d o u b t h o w to i n t e r p r e t m u c h t h a t e x c a v a t i o n has r e v e a l e d , a n d there is a risk
o f c i r c u l a r i t y i n r e l a t i n g a r c h a e o l o g i c a l evidence to
a c c o u n t . We
Herodotus'
s h o u l d b e a r i n m i n d the w a r n i n g o f a n archaeologist
w e l l a w a r e o f t h a t danger: ' W e t h i n k we k n o w a l o t a b o u t S c y t h i a n l i f e , b u t m o s t comes t h r o u g h G r e e k eyes a n d texts. T h e finds
Greek-style
a n d H e r o d o t u s are g i v e n p r o m i n e n c e , b u t the m a j o r i t y o f the
sites a n d t o m b s tell a d i f f e r e n t s t o r y , o f a p e o p l e i m m u n e to most M e d i t e r r a n e a n ways o f life a n d p r o b a b l y m o r e l i k e l y to e x p l o i t t h a n t o be e x p l o i t e d b y t h e n e w c o m e r s f r o m t h e s o u t h ' ( B o a r d m a n (1994) 216 f ) . A h u n d r e d years e a r l i e r , R. W . M a c a n , i n t h e i n t r o d u c t i o n to his c o m m e n t a r y o n Books F o u r t o Six, e m p h a s i z e d the d i f f i c u l t y o f f o r m u l a t i n g a n y g e n e r a l assessment o f H e r o d o t u s ' a c c o u n t : ' t h e r e is n o page o n w h i c h fact a n d f i c t i o n - — i f so c r u d e a d i s t i n c t i o n m a y
be
a d m i t t e d f o r the sake o f a r g u m e n t — a r e n o t to be f o u n d l y i n g side b y side, o r i n d i s s o l u b l y i n t e r p e n e t r a t e d , m u t u a l l y affected, n o t as o i l
* In view of Herodotus' Carian connections it may be significant that Tymncs has a Carian name. It should not be assumed that Olbia was the only place where Herodotus could have conversed with him. See further Rolle (1989) 123-7, Vinogradov (1997) 613-33, Tafel 39. On the importance of the bilingual offspring of mixed unions in the transmission of alphabetic literacy, see Coldstream (1993). See further Harmatta (1990). (1992); SEG 42 (1992) no. 681. See further West (1988). 6 0
61
6 2 m
456
STEPHANIE
WEST
a n d v i n e g a r , b u t as w a t e r a n d w i n e ' ((1895) x x v i i ) . A n air o f a u t h o r i t y suggesting f i r s t - h a n d o b s e r v a t i o n o r i n f o r m a n t s o f u n i m p e a c h a b l e credentials is i n t e g r a l to H e r o d o t u s '
n a r r a t i v e style. B u t ,
however
d e t e r m i n e d w e m a y b e t o u p h o l d his basic g o o d f a i t h , a n d to insist t h a t w h a t e v e r elements o f
fiction
m a y be f o u n d i n his w o r k d o n o t
result f r o m his o w n conscious i n v e n t i o n , w e have to a l l o w t h a t he m u s t o f t e n have b e e n u n c e r t a i n a b o u t t h e p r o v e n a n c e a n d r e l i a b i l i t y o f items o f c u r i o u s i n f o r m a t i o n a c c u m u l a t e d over the years f r o m hearsay a n d across language b a r r i e r s . W e c a n n o t h o p e to trace t h e e x t e n t t o w h i c h h e h i m s e l f tacitly r a t i o n a l i z e d (or exaggerated)
the
i m p r o b a b l e o r s u p p l i e d links b e t w e e n d a t a w h i c h w e r e i n r e a l i t y u n c o n n e c t e d o r c o n n e c t e d i n q u i t e a d i f f e r e n t w a y . As D a r i u s ' ture into Europe brings the menace
o f Persian e x p a n s i o n i s m
vensig-
n i f i c a n t l y closer t o m a i n l a n d G r e e c e , S c y t h i a n e t h n o g r a p h y f o r m s a b r i d g e b e t w e e n t h e t w o halves o f H e r o d o t u s ' w o r k , a n d i t w o u l d be s u r p r i s i n g i f his p r e s e n t a t i o n was n o t affected b y k n o w l e d g e o f w h a t was to c o m e . M a c a n ' s
advice r e m a i n s s o u n d : 'every separate s t o r y ,
every i n d i v i d u a l statement is to be t r i e d o n its o w n m e r i t s ' ((1895) xiii).
CHAPTER T W E N T Y THE
ETHNOGRAPHY Klaus
OF T H E
FRINGES
Karttunen
Herodotus and the nms of the world H e r o d o t u s h a d t w o ways o f d i v i d i n g the i n h a b i t e d w o r l d (oikoumene/ οικουμένη), geographical a n d ethnographical. T h e geographical divi sion, w h i c h is, mutatis mutandis, still used, is given i n 4 . 3 6 ~ 4 5 .
Dismissing
the earlier view o f a circular earth fringed b y the O c e a n , the R i v e r O c e a n u s , a n d d i v i d e d i n t w o e q u a l halves,
E u r o p e a n d A s i a , 1 he
i n t r o d u c e d a n e w system w i t h t h r e e c o n t i n e n t s o f d i f f e r e n t size: E u r o p e , A s i a , a n d L i b y a (Africa). I n several passages he m a d e clear t h a t i n his o p i n i o n the O c e a n was p u r e l y m y t h i c ( 2 . 2 3 , 4 . 8 , 3 6 , cf. 3 . 1 1 5 , 4.45).
I n his e t h n o g r a p h i c a l t h i n k i n g , h o w e v e r , there w a s a t h r e e
f o l d p a t t e r n w h i c h was a p p l i e d t o a l l three c o n t i n e n t s : the o r d e r l y a n d f a m i l i a r c e n t r e , t h e i n t e r m e d i a t e r e g i o n , a n d t h e fringes (eskhatiail έσχατιαί). T h e m e t h o d s a n d the types o f source c r i t i c i s m used b y H e r o d o t u s i n ethnographical matters were ethnography
t h e same as i n h i s t o r y — a f t e r a l l ,
w a s f o r h i m o n l y a subgenre o f h i s t o r y . H e m a d e his
o w n observations, collected l o c a l i n f o r m a t i o n , checked e x i s t i n g l i t e r a r y sources a n d analysed a l l these i n t h e l i g h t o f his o w n r a t i o n a l t h i n k i n g . 2 H e r a r e l y gave exact r e f e r e n c e s — t h e
normal
technique
b e i n g t o n a m e the source o n l y w h e n one was c r i t i c i z i n g i t — b u t care f u l l y d i s t i n g u i s h e d t h e type o f i n f o r m a t i o n he w a s r e l y i n g o n a n d said w h e t h e r h e f o u n d i t r e l i a b l e o r n o t . H o w e v e r , i n t h e case o f the fringes h e r a r e l y h a d a choice o f source. H i s o w n travels (see J a c o b y (1913) 247 f f . ) , t h o u g h extensive, never w e n t b e y o n d the f a m i l i a r c e n t r a l parts o f the oikoumene. F o r the f r i n g e regions, h e d e p e n d e d
1
On this earlier view, probably still followed by Hecataeus, see Romm (1992) 20 ff, 32 ff. See further the long discussion by Hartog (1988) 260 ff. 2
THE
ETHNOGRAPHY
459
OF T H E FRINGES
o n a few travellers' tales a n d his o n l y w a y o f c h e c k i n g was o f t e n his own rational m i n d . W h i l e the l a r g e r e t h n o g r a p h i c a l logoi o r excursuses h a d a w e l l d e f i n e d place i n the scope o f his great h i s t o r y — c o u n t r i e s such as E g y p t , S c y t h i a , a n d L i b y a w e r e d e s c r i b e d w h e n they
first
emerged
i n the h i s t o r y o f the Persian e m p i r e — t h e fringes w e r e j u s t dices. T h e y w e r e n o t necessary,
appen-
but certainly entertaining.3
The
fringes were different, completely d i f f e r e n t , w h i c h fascinated H e r o d o t u s a n d p r o b a b l y his readers, t o o . A n
o f t e n - r e t u r n i n g t h e m e is the r e l -
a t i v i t y o f m a n n e r s (see D i h l e (1981) 196 i f . ) , discussed i n a w a y sometimes c a l l e d inverse e t h n o c e n t r i s m . T h e m a i n interest f o r
Herodotus
i n e t h n o g r a p h y was the nomas, a n d the d i f f e r e n c e i n nomoi, a n d he m a d e a serious a t t e m p t to accept every c u l t u r e w i t h its o w n values. T h e emphasis is o f t e n o n those features t h a t d i f f e r m o s t clearly f r o m G r e e c e , t h o u g h a d i f f u s i o n i s t v i e w p o i n t makes
h i m also n o t e
the
similarities. For i f anyone, no matter who, were given the opportunity o f choosing from amongst all the nations i n the w o r l d the set o f beliefs which he thought best, he w o u l d inevitably, after careful consideration of their relative merits, choose that o f his o w n country. (3.38; t r l . De Selincourt) Special p r o m i n e n c e was g i v e n to rites because these w e r e t h o u g h t to be a n c i e n t a n d u n c h a n g e d a n d thus to p r o v i d e evidence f o r the origins o f n a t i o n s . H e r e t h e d i f f u s i o n i s m was i m p o r t a n t a n d larities i n ceremonies l e d H e r o d o t u s
simi-
to derive, for instance, Greek
r i t u a l customs f r o m L i b y a (4.189) a n d L i b y a n f r o m Greece (4.180). The
p r o b l e m is, o f course, t h a t G r e e k m y t h o l o g y a n d m y t h i c p r e -
h i s t o r y w e r e t a k e n for g r a n t e d a n d e v e r y t h i n g was
fitted
i n t o i t (in
m u c h t h e same w a y t h a t classical a n d o t h e r m y t h i c a n d early histories w e r e later fitted i n t o t h e B i b l e ) . 4 L i k e m o s t a u t h o r s , H e r o d o t u s w r o t e w h a t he t h o u g h t was i n t e r esting f o r his audience a n d , like e v e r y b o d y else, he i n t e r p r e t e d w h a t he l e a r n e d i n the l i g h t o f w h a t was f a m i l i a r t o h i m . 0 C o n s c i o u s
3
or
See, however, Ch. 15, above, pp. 321-2. The same tendency runs through the Greek ethnological literature: see Bickermann (1952). In the case of Herodotus this meant interpretatio graeca, but when, for instance, a Scythian was explaining Greeks to his compatriots, the Scythian was certainly using interpretatio scythica. 4
:>
460
KLAUS
KARTTUNEN
unconscious selection a n d s i m p l i f i c a t i o n was also inevitable, a n a t t e m p t to sift o u t w h a t seemed essential a n d leave o u t w h a t seemed ondary.
More
t h a n t w o m i l l e n n i a l a t e r , the results d o n o t
sec-
always
satisfy us, b u t this is h a r d l y a reason to c r i t i c i z e h i m . T h e r e are t w o approaches to the study o f classical e t h n o g r a p h y a n d b o t h have t h e i r uses a n d s t r o n g p o i n t s . T h e
first
c o m p a r e s the
d i f f e r e n t accounts o f the d i s t a n t regions o f t h e i n h a b i t e d w o r l d t o each o t h e r a n d analyses t h e m i n the l i g h t o f G r e e k l i t e r a r y t r a d i t i o n , also t a k i n g the possible sources a n d later i n f l u e n c e i n t o a c c o u n t . T h e second is m o r e i n t e r e s t e d i n the p a r t i c u l a r regions discussed b y Herodotus,
s i f t i n g his m a t e r i a l i n o r d e r to find i n f o r m a t i o n w h i c h is
t h e n c o m p a r e d t o o t h e r available sources o f i n f o r m a t i o n such as the (often later) l i t e r a r y sources a n d a r c h a e o l o g i c a l evidence. B o t h m e t h ods are j u s t i f i a b l e a n d p r o b l e m s arise o n l y w h e n one is used i n a w a y t h a t c o m p l e t e l y ignores the o t h e r .
General patterns in Herodotean etiinography I n a f a s c i n a t i n g a r t i c l e M i c h è l e R o s s e l l i n i a n d Suzanne S a i d (1978) have d e f i n e d a conspicuous p a t t e r n i n H e r o d o t e a n e t h n o g r a p h y .
They
have t r a c e d a system o f three c o n c e n t r i c circles: the c e n t r e , w i t h G r e e c e , contains the sphere o f o r d e r e d , ' n o r m a l ' life, w i t h a l l the h a r d s h i p s o f the p r e v a i l i n g I r o n A g e .
A r o u n d i t is the i n t e r m e d i a t e
r e g i o n i n h a b i t e d b y the v a r i o u s tribes o f n o m a d s .
The
o u t e r circle
c o n t a i n s the fringes o f the i n h a b i t e d w o r l d p e o p l e d b y savages, at the same t i m e still a b o u n d i n g w i t h the benefits o f the Age.
The
differences b e t w e e n
but
Golden
these circles c a n be seen i n
every
aspect o f e c o n o m i c a n d social life: i n r e l i g i o n a n d f u n e r a l c u s t o m s , love a n d m a r r i a g e , f o o d a n d d r i n k , h a b i t a t i o n a n d means o f l i v i n g . The
p a t t e r n was n o t i n v e n t e d b y H e r o d o t u s — s o m e
traces o f i t are
a l r e a d y seen i n H o m e r a n d later i t c a n be seen e . g . , i n Gtesias a n d to some extent also i n S t r a b o — b u t its details are best i l l u s t r a t e d i n his w o r k , b e i n g the o n l y c o m p l e t e l y preserved e x a m p l e o f early G r e e k ethnography. I n each case the series goes f r o m the o r d e r l y a n d c o m p l i c a t e d syst e m o f the c e n t r a l r e g i o n , especially G r e e c e , t h r o u g h the s i m p l e , b u t still r e l a t e d ways
o f the n o m a d s ,
to the p r i m i t i v e a n a r c h y
o f the
fringes. T h u s the diversified r e l i g i o n o f the Greeks, w i t h so m a n y gods a n d heroes a n d cults, w i t h temples a n d h o l y places, is c o n t r a s t e d to
THE
ETHNOGRAPHY
OF T H E FRINGES
461
the simple religion of the nomads with only one or two gods and to the savages living completely without religion. The Massagetan religion is simple, the sun being their only god. The Arabians had two gods, Dionysus and Urania (3.8), while in Ethiopian Meroe only Zeus and Dionysus were worshipped (2.29). The majority of Libyans only sacrifice to the sun and the moon (4.188). The Thracians honour Ares, Dionysus, and Artemis (5.7). T h e Scythians know several gods, but Herodotus emphasized that their number is rather small (4.59). Beside the elaborate funerals of the Greeks and the simple burials of the nomads are seen the exposure o f corpses or cannibalism of the savages. Cannibalism was perhaps the most repulsive form of human behaviour known to the Greeks (and it has remained so in Europe ever since). As such, it belonged only to hoary antiquity and to the fringes of the world. A type o f ritual cannibalism is mentioned by Herodotus in connection with the Massagetae (1.216) and Issedones (4.26). These two people held an intermediate position and accordingly we read that their cannibalism was considered a sacrifice. The victim was slaughtered together w i t h cattle, which represented the normal kind of sacrifice for the Greeks. When somebody died of an illness, he was considered unsuitable for sacrifice and buried. The Indian Padaei (3.99 f.) practise cannibalism on sick and old members of their tribe, while among their neighbours, a man who becomes i l l goes to the desert to die there without burial. I n another passage (3.38) the eating of parents is ascribed to Indian Callatiae. The idea of primitive cannibalism (as seen e.g., in the legend of Cronus) still preserved on the fringes was much older than Herodotus: the first examples were the Laestrygonians and Cyclopes of Homer (Burkert (1990) 9). I n the sphere of family life, marriage i n Greece was conducted according to elaborate rules involving the families in question and defining rights and duties. A m o n g the nomads marriage was a simple affair, but still easily recognized as the institution of marriage, while the savages generally lived i n a primitive state of promiscuity. Thus the Massagetae (1.216) have marriage, but they hold their wives in common and the simple rule o f hanging a quiver on the front of a wagon shows that the other men are supposed to keep away. The Libyan Nasamones have a similar custom (4.172), and the Scythian Agathyrsi strengthen their brotherhood with common wives (4.104). The Libyan Adyrmachidae practise the ius primae noctis (4.168). Among
462
KLAUS
ΚΛΚΙΊΓΜΛ
the L i b y a n G i n d a n e s , a w o m a n is esteemed a c c o r d i n g to h o w m a n y lovers she has h a d (4.176) a n d the M a c h l y e s (or Auses) have n o m a r riage at a l l , b u t casual i n t e r c o u r s e like a n i m a l s (4.180). T h e
most
distant I n d i a n t r i b e s , t o o , have i n t e r c o u r s e i n p u b l i c (3.101), a n d the same is stated a b o u t the i n h a b i t a n t s o f the Caucasus (1.203). The
basis o f life i n Greece was a g r i c u l t u r e a n d a c c o r d i n g l y , the
basis o f the d i e t w e r e its p r o d u c t s : b r e a d a n d w i n e . T h e
nomads
wandered around w i t h their animals, eating meat a n d d r i n k i n g m i l k . 6 I n the case o f the savages there w e r e t w o d i f f e r i n g views. O n one h a n d
they still e n j o y e d
the p r i m e v a l , G o l d e n Age
fertility
n a t u r e , w h i c h gave its f r u i t s w i t h o u t a n y n e e d t o w o r k . O n
the of
the o t h e r
h a n d , b e i n g savages, t h e y d i d n o t k n o w h o w to p r e p a r e f o o d ,
but
ate r a w m e a t , i n c l u d i n g h u m a n , a n d u n c o o k e d f r u i t s a n d vegetables. E v e n the Massagetae a n d Issedones, w h o h o l d a n i n t e r m e d i a t e p o s i t i o n — t h e y d o n o t sow, b u t live o n m e a t a n d fish a n d m i l k — s l a u g h ter t h e i r elderly relatives a n d eat t h e m ( 1 . 2 1 6 , 4 . 2 6 ) . T h e
nomadic
Scythians d o n o t t i l l a n d sow (4.19), a n d the Thyssagetae a n d I y r c a e live b y h u n t i n g (4.22). T h e
L i b y a n N a s a m o n e s are n o m a d s a n d eat
w i l d dates a n d locusts (4.172). T h e
L i b y a n s i n g e n e r a l are
w h o eat m e a t a n d d r i n k m i l k (4.186). T h e
nomads
I n d i a n Padaei (3.99) eat
r a w m e a t a n d practise c a n n i b a l i s m , w h i l e t h e i r n e i g h b o u r s d o sow o r h u n t , b u t eat a k i n d o f w i l d cereal (3.100). A
not
t h i r d t r i b e is
c o n t e n t w i t h r a w fish (3.98). T h e S c y t h i a n A r g i p p a e i live o n the fruits o f the tree c a l l e d p o n t i c u m (4.23) a n d the L i b y a n L o t o p h a g i o n the l o t u s f r u i t (4.177). B e y o n d a S c y t h i a n Androphagi
(4.18,
106). T h e
ots the savage T r o g l o d y t e s ,
desert live the
man-eating
Garamantes h u n t i n four-horse chari w h o themselves eat snakes a n d
lizards
(4.183). I n one case H e r o d o t u s h i m s e l f rationalizes a w a y the p r i m i tive w a y o f f e e d i n g . T h e
l o n g - l i v e d E t h i o p i a n s (3.18) eat e v e r y day
f r o m the table o f the s u n , b e l i e v i n g t h a t i t is every n i g h t
filled
by
t h e e a r t h itself, b u t H e r o d o t u s suggests t h a t i t is secretly r e p l e n i s h e d by
magistrates. Rosseliini a n d Said ((1978) 962) p o i n t o u t t h a t these f o o d differences
are also seen i n the subsequent stages o f Gambyses' i l l - f a t e d E t h i o p i a n
6
A parallel to the Herodotean nomads in later sources are the primitive fisheating Ichthyophagi on the coasts of the Red Sea and the Arabian Sea. Such tribes were also mentioned in passing by Herodotus, e.g., in 1.200 (preparing fish for eat ing), 1.202 and 3.98 (eating raw fish), and 5.16 (Thracian lake-dwellers). The very name Ichthyophagi is mentioned in 3.19 ff.
THE
ETHNOGRAPHY
463
OF T H E FRINGES
e x p e d i t i o n (3.25). W h e n the o r d i n a r y f o o d h a d been eaten, the soldiers first ate t h e i r p a c k a n i m a l s , t h e n some w i l d vegetables, a n d i n the e n d even some o f t h e i r o w n c o m p a n i o n s selected b y l o t . W h i l e this can be seen as a n a t u r a l ' p r o g r e s s i o n ' i n a s i t u a t i o n o f e x t r e m e f a m i n e , i t corresponds to the g r o w i n g ' b a r b a r i z a t i o n ' o f f o o d habits n o t e d above.
I n this w a y
duced i n Ethiopia,
the t h e m e o f c a n n i b a l i s m is even
t h o u g h the E t h i o p i a n s
intro-
themselves are o r d i n a r y
meat-eaters (3.18). T h e Greeks a n d o t h e r peoples o f the c e n t r a l r e g i o n l i v e d i n houses, w h i l e the n o m a d s w i t h t h e i r w a n d e r i n g w a y o f life w e r e c o n t e n t w i t h tents o r c o v e r e d w a g o n s , b u t the savages j u s t lay d o w n u n d e r trees a n d slept. T h u s the Massagetae
(1.216 b r i e f l y ) l i v e d i n wagons.
Scythians i n g e n e r a l , as horse n o m a d s ,
also l i v e d i n wagons
The
(4.46).
I n the n o r t h o f S c y t h i a , the b a l d - h e a d e d A r g i p p a e i l i v e d u n d e r trees, w h i c h i n w i n t e r were p r o t e c t e d w i t h felt (4.23). A n has n o houses (3.100).
A
I n d i a n people
L i b y a n t r i b e i n a rainless c o u n t r y b u i l d s
huts o f salt-blocks (4.185), w h i l e o t h e r L i b y a n s have p o r t a b l e huts o f t w i s t e d reeds (4.190). T h e r e are some possible f u r t h e r variables i n v o l v e d , t h o u g h n o t so clearly i n d i c a t e d b y H e r o d o t u s .
Rossellini a n d S a i d ((1978) 979 ff.)
discuss the i n v e r s i o n o f sexes. A n o t h e r e l e m e n t is the f o r m o f gove r n m e n t . I n G r e e c e , the g o v e r n m e n t is d e f i n e d b y elaborate w r i t t e n laws, w h i l e the n o m a d s c h y a n d f e w laws. T h e
have t r i b a l societies w i t h a s i m p l e
monar-
savages e i t h e r live i n a state o f a n a r c h y
have a n extremely simple leadership. T h e l o n g - l i v e d Ethiopians as t h e i r k i n g the m a n w h o
seems to be the tallest a n d
or
choose
strongest
a m o n g t h e m ( 3 . 2 0 ) . 7 T h e T h r a c i a n s , b e i n g the m o s t n u m e r o u s
peo-
ple after the I n d i a n s , w o u l d also be the m o s t p o w e r f u l n a t i o n i f they c o u l d p u t a w a y t h e i r t r i b a l divisions a n d be u n i t e d u n d e r a single r u l e r (5.3). I n the same w a y the L i b y a n a n d S c y t h i a n n o m a d s
are
d i v i d e d i n t o m a n y tribes. I n t e r n a l d i v i s i o n , h o w e v e r , is n o t restricted to p r i m i t i v e peoples; H e r o d o t u s
also m e n t i o n s i t as a m a j o r h a n d i -
cap o f the Greeks i n the face o f Persian i n v a s i o n . " T h e d o u b l e idea o f the fringes b e i n g p r i m i t i v e b u t also still e n j o y i n g the c o n d i t i o n s o f the G o l d e n A g e r e s u l t e d i n a t w o f o l d c o n c e p t i o n o f the p e o p l e l i v i n g t h e r e . O n
7
the o n e h a n d they w e r e
savages
In the literature on Alexander it was claimed that the Indian Cathaei choose as their king the most handsome man among them (Onesicritus F 21). See further above, Ch. 15, pp. 335, 340-3, and below, Ch. 24, pp. 566-9. 8
464
KLAUS
KARTTUNEN
practising cannibalism (cf. Rankin (1969)), on the other hand they were just and peaceful, 'noble savages'. A n early example (in the Odyssey) are the godless man-eating Cyclopes and the peaceful Phaeacians who honour Poseidon. Rossellini and Said explain the second type as a primitive kind of righteousness, originating in nature rather than i n higher moral ideas. Therefore, this righteousness is often mentioned as a simple statement quite unrelated to the account of local nomoi. T o kill nothing living (the Indian people in 3.100 and the Libyan Atlantes in 4.184) is both righteous and primitive. The Scythian Argippaei have no weapons and are asked by their neighbours to act as peacemakers (4.23). The Garamantes of southern Libya avoid all contact with other people and have no weapons of war (4.174). Even the Issedones who eat their parents are characterized as just (4.26). The long-lived Ethiopians and their moral condemnation of Persian customs are a major example of the relativity of manners (3.21f., cf. R o m m (1992) 53 If.). A n important part of the conception of the fringes, especially i n w a r m climates, is the immense fertility of nature and its many marvels. Therefore, the primitive fringe-dwellers were able to survive without work, as nature gave its gifts freely to them. The most famous examples of the exceptional riches of the fringes are perhaps the gold of India (3.94, 98, 102 ff., 106) and the aromatics of Arabia (3.106, 107 ff.). As befits the Golden Age conditions, gold seems to be common everywhere on the fringes: in Libya (4.195), i n Ethiopia (3.114), in India (3.106), and i n Scythia (3.116). I n India animals and birds are much larger than elsewhere and w i l d trees yield cotton (3.106). The long-lived Ethiopians reach the age of 120 years and sometimes even more (3.23). They are said to be the tallest, best-looking, and longest-living people (3.114). The Libyans are the healthiest of all men (2.77 and 4.187). Southernmost Libya abounds with fantastic animals and w i l d tribes (4.191). Herodotus and his contemporaries took it for granted that this extraordinary fertility o f nature with its marvels was something that existed on the fringes. Attempts at a scientific explanation came only with the Hippocratic Airs, Waters, Places and Hellenistic ethnography (see Dihle (1962a)). 9
10
9
The classic study on this is Dihle (1962). See further Rossellini and Said (1978) 963 f f , and Romm (1992) 38 f. An early example is the island of the Cyclopes in the Odyssey 9.106 ff. The Cyclopes do not till and sow, hut the soil by itself produces wheat and barley and grapes. 10
THE
ETHNOGRAPHY
OF T H E FRINGES
465
A further common feature o f the fringes are deserts as boundaries between nomads and savages or as the outer boundary o f the world (Edelmann (1970), also R o m m (1992) 35 ff.). This is easy to understand as it is generalized from real examples. There really is the vastness o f the Sahara to the south o f civilized Libya (2.32 and 4.185), and also south and west o f Egypt (2.25-6). I n the same way, the Arabian desert (3.4-7, 9) most certainly exists. The desert east of India (3.98, and 4.40) can perhaps be identified as the T h a r desert of western Rajasthan—India being mostly the Indus Valley—but it is also exactly where a desert is supposed to be. The desert where the gold-digging ants live (3.102) points rather to Central Asia. For Herodotus, deserts were found everywhere on the fringes. Thus Scythia, too, is bounded by deserts. Beyond the Neuri in the northwest there is an uninhabited desert (4.17). O n the eastern side of the Borysthenes (Dnieper) the Androphagi, themselves living beyond a desert, are the northernmost people, beyond w h o m there is only desert (4.18). Further to the east, beyond the Melanchlaeni there is again an uninhabited desert (4.20). The rugged and stony country beyond the Budini also seems to be desert (4.23), and another Scythian desert is mentioned at 4.53 and 4.123 f. I n Europe, the country beyond Thracia and the Ister is desert (5.9). T o these may be added the uninhabitable winter wastes o f the extreme north (4.31). I n addition to deserts, high mountains are occasionally met as boundaries. Southernmost Libya is mountainous (4.191). Cinnamon is obtained by Arabians from high mountains situated i n the land where Dionysus grew up (3.111). Insurmountable mountains separate the Scythian Argippeans from the far north (4.25). I t is somewhat surprising that Herodotus mentions no mountains i n India, though they were reported already by Scylax and had an important place in the Indica of Ctesias. M y own contribution to the ethnography o f the fringes is to have noted the theme of the expedition to the end of the world (Karttunen (1988)). The fringe-dwellers are often too primitive to exploit effectively the riches o f their countries, which are coveted by their more civilized neighbours. Idiere are many examples o f expeditions made to exploit these riches. The Indians went with camels to fetch ant-gold (3.102 ff.) and the Arimaspians fetched gold from the griffins (3.116, 4.13, 427)." The Arabians face dangers and difficulties to obtain " in Ctesias, too, the griffin-gold is obtained by a long expedition.
466
KLAUS
KARTTUNEN
l i b a n o t u s , cassia, a n d c i n n a m o n ( 3 d 0 7 , 11 Of.). T h e L i b y a n Nasamones m a k e a s u m m e r e x p e d i t i o n to the oasis o f A u g i l a (4.172, 182). is f o u n d o n a n i s l a n d i n w e s t e r n L i b y a (4.195). A ill-fated Ethiopian
special case is the
e x p e d i t i o n o f C a m b y s e s (3.25). I n one i n s t a n c e ,
the f r i n g e - d w e l l e r s v i s i t the c e n t r e : the H y p e r b o r e a n s ' D e l o s (4.33
ff.j. A
Gold
k i n d of unrealized
c o m i n g to
e x p e d i t i o n was perhaps
the
I o n i a n p l a n to c o l o n i z e S a r d i n i a (1.170). I n m a n y cases these e x p e d i tions
are a n n u a l a n d c a n be c o n n e c t e d w i t h the y e a r l y w a n d e r i n g s
o f m a n y n o m a d i c peoples, b u t t h e y also have a d e f i n i t e b a c k g r o u n d i n G r e e k t r a d i t i o n , w i t h the travels o f H e r a c l e s , J a s o n , a n d Aristeas o f Proconnesus.
Odysseus,
T h e passage to the fringes is a c h i e v e d
t h r o u g h deserts o r m o u n t a i n s , o r o n the sea a d r i f t i n a s t o r m , a n d the riches b e y o n d are o f t e n g u a r d e d b y dangerous beasts o r savages. W h i l e the u n d e n i a b l e o u t c o m e o f a l l this is t h a t H e r o d o t u s
was
p u t t i n g his m a t e r i a l o n the P r o c r u s t e a n b e d o f his t h e o r e t i c a l f r a m e w o r k , i t is n o less t r u e t h a t he was i n d u s t r i o u s l y c o l l e c t i n g i n f o r m a t i o n . T h o u g h analogous to each o t h e r , the fringes w e r e t o his m i n d b y n o means i d e n t i c a l . T h e p a t t e r n is t h e r e , b u t i t is at least p a r t l y f o u n d e d o n o b s e r v a t i o n , as i n the case o f the m o v a b l e homes o f the nomads;
the p a t t e r n g u i d e d the a c c o u n t , n o t necessarily to i n v e n -
t i o n , b u t to r a t i o n a l selection. W h a t was seen to be c o m p a t i b l e w i t h the p a t t e r n was s i m p l y f o u n d m o r e r e l e v a n t t h a n deviations.
The Extremes: the Ethiopian South Herodotus'
account of Ethiopia
is f o u n d i n 3 . 1 7 - 2 5 ( w i t h f u r t h e r
notes i n 2.29 a n d 3.114). I n this p a r t i c u l a r area he c o u l d r e l y o n v e r y o l d t r a d i t i o n s i n G r e e k l i t e r a t u r e , 1 2 t h o u g h he a t t e m p t e d
to
m a i n t a i n a c r i t i c a l distance f r o m his predecessors. T h u s , the c o m m o n c o n f u s i o n b e t w e e n E t h i o p i a a n d I n d i a , s t a r t i n g before h i m a n d lasting i n t o late a n t i q u i t y , is n o t really seen i n H e r o d o t u s (cf. K a r t t u n e n (1989) 134 f t . ) . Its b e g i n n i n g s l a y w i t h H o m e r a n d his a c c o u n t the t w o kinds o f E t h i o p i a n s .
Herodotus'
Eastern Ethiopians
of
(3.94,
7.70), l i v i n g s o m e w h e r e i n M a k r a n o r B a l u c h i s t a n , w e r e c e r t a i n l y n o l o n g e r the same p e o p l e as the E a s t e r n E t h i o p i a n s o f H o m e r (Odyssey
12
The word Aithiops was already known in the Mycenaean period (see Dihle (1994) 8 f.) and used as an ethnic name since Homer.
THE
1.22
ff.,
ETHNOGRAPHY
467
OF T H E FRINGES
cf. L e s k y (1959) 29 ff.). I n l a t e r t i m e s , w i t h the w i d e n i n g
w o r l d - v i e w , these Eastern E t h i o p i a n s w e r e m o v e d still f u r t h e r to the east (to Southeast
Asia).
Probably
ground for identification; Herodotus Ethiopians
the b l a c k skin was a sufficient h i m s e l f k n e w t h a t the Eastern
w e r e s t r a i g h t - h a i r e d , w h i l e the S o u t h e r n h a d c u r l y h a i r
(7.70). T h e i r languages w e r e d i f f e r e n t , t o o . E t h i o p i a itself, the c o u n t r y s o u t h o f E g y p t , was f a m i l i a r f r o m m y t h a n d l e g e n d , b u t was passed o v e r b y H e r o d o t u s
i n r e l a t i v e l y few-
w o r d s . I t is e v i d e n t t h a t the E t h i o p i a n s , as t h e i r n a m e (aithi-ops) i n d i cates, w e r e b l a c k - s k i n n e d , a feature c o m m o n l y e x p l a i n e d b y the nearness o f the s u n , b u t this is n o t m e n t i o n e d b y H e r o d o t u s 3.101
o n an I n d i a n t r i b e ) . T h e
(but see
q u e s t i o n o f the H y p e r n o t i i is b r i e f l y
m e n t i o n e d (4.36), b u t the p a r a l l e l i s m b e t w e e n the e x t r e m e n o r t h a n d south a l r e a d y m e t i n a r c h a i c p o e t r y is n o t e l a b o r a t e d b y Ethiopia
Herodotus.
c o n t a i n e d b o t h the i n t e r m e d i a t e r e g i o n a n d the fringes.
Those l i v i n g near the E g y p t i a n b o r d e r were vassals o f the Achaemenids, s e n d i n g r i c h presents to D a r i u s (3.97) a n d s e r v i n g i n X e r x e s ' i n v a sion a r m y (7.69 f ) . T h e y i n c l u d e the n o m a d i c E t h i o p i a n s haps also the i n h a b i t a n t s o f the c i t y o f M e r o e
and per-
(2.29).
Some o l d m o t i f s appear o n the fringes. T h e table o f the S u n (3.18) probably where
belongs to the same
t r a d i t i o n as the H o m e r i c
account,
the gods all go to p a r t a k e o f a feast i n E t h i o p i a . 1 3
In
the
a r c h a i c w o r l d , the p h y s i c a l presence o f gods was one o f the G o l d e n A g e features o f t h e fringes. I n a w o r l d n o l o n g e r a r c h a i c , i g n o r e d the gods a n d o f f e r e d a r a t i o n a l s o l u t i o n f o r the
Herodotus appearance
o f f o o d o n the t a b l e , b u t the table was p o p u l a r e n o u g h f o r h i m to make
a special p o i n t o f r e p r e s e n t i n g C a m b y s e s seeking the t r u t h
about it. As t r u e f r i n g e - d w e l l e r s , the E t h i o p i a n T r o g l o d y t e s (4.183) have n o l a n g u a g e , b u t squeak like bats. T h e y w e r e a l r e a d y m e n t i o n e d i n a f r a g m e n t o f Hecataeus a n d b e c a m e v e r y p o p u l a r i n later l i t e r a t u r e o n E t h i o p i a . A n o t h e r o l d a n d p o p u l a r m o t i f , the Pygmies a n d t h e i r w a r against cranes, was c o m p l e t e l y i g n o r e d b y
13
Iliad 1.423 f., cf. Lesky (1959) 27 if. " See Iliad 3.3 ff., and Karttunen (1989) 128 ff.
Herodotus.14
468
KLAUS
KARTTUNEN
The Extremes: the Libyan Southwest E x t r e m e L i b y a is described b y H e r o d o t u s i n 4 J 8 1 - 9 6 as p a r t o f the general account o f L i b y a ( 4 . 1 4 5 - 2 0 5 ) , w h i c h includes all three regions, s t a r t i n g w i t h the c i v i l i z e d coastal r e g i o n w i t h G r e e k colonies, t h e n d e a l i n g w i t h the m a n y tribes o f n o m a d s l i v i n g n o r t h o f the S a h a r a , a n d i n the e n d r e t u r n i n g t o the h i s t o r y . T h e r e is a f u r t h e r a c c o u n t o f the e x p l o r a t i o n ( c i r c u m n a v i g a t i o n ) o f A f r i c a i n 4.42 f., a n d the N a s a m o n e s w i t h t h e i r S a h a r a n e x p l o r a t i o n are dealt w i t h i n 2.32 f . 1 5 I n a comprehensive
sense, L i b y a was the n a m e
o f the
African
c o n t i n e n t , i n c l u d i n g E g y p t i n the northeast a n d E t h i o p i a i n the southeast, b u t the m a i n a c c o u n t concentrates o n lands to the west o f these regions. H o w e v e r , a c o n n e c t i o n b e t w e e n L i b y a p r o p e r a n d was m a i n t a i n e d . T h e
N i l e was supposed to be
flowing
Ethiopia
from Libya
to E t h i o p i a (2.33), t h o u g h its w e s t e r n course was p r o b a b l y the N i g e r seen b y the N a s a m o n e s . 1 6 f n a d d i t i o n t o the f r i n g e features tioned
men-
a b o v e , the L i b y a n A t a r a n t e s have n o i n d i v i d u a l names (4.184).
I n 4.191
Herodotus
summarizes
his a c c o u n t o f the L i b y a n fringes
w i t h a n u n c h a r a c t e r i s t i c list, perhaps g o i n g b a c k to Hecataeus,
men-
t i o n i n g a n u m b e r o f L i b y a n marvels w i t h o u t e l a b o r a t i n g o n t h e m at all (cf. R o m m (1992) 91 f . ) .
The Extremes: the Arabian Southeast A r a b i a as a c o u n t r y o n the fringes is discussed i n H e r o d o t u s
3.107-13,
w h i l e the A s i a n e x p l o r a t i o n a c c o u n t i n 4 . 4 4 does n o t say m u c h a b o u t Arabia.
I t seems t h a t there was n o traveller's a c c o u n t available for
A r a b i a , as there is n o g e o g r a p h y a n d the b u l k o f the d e s c r i p t i o n is a fantastic a c c o u n t o f n a t u r e a n d t h e w a y o f o b t a i n i n g t h e p r e c i o u s aromatics for w h i c h A r a b i a
was t h e n a l r e a d y f a m o u s . I n the t i m e
o f D a r i u s f r a n k i n c e n s e was sent as a gift to Persia (3.97) a n d the i n v a s i o n a r m y o f X e r x e s c o n t a i n e d A r a b i a n c a m e l riders (7.86).
15
For a more detailed discussion and further references see Lloyd (1990), who claims that as a whole the Libyan logos stands up well to scrutiny, though there is some exaggeration and over-simplification (237 f.). For his arguments against the historicity of the circumnavigation of Africa, see p. 251. Sec also Romm (1992) 49 If. The question of the sources of the Nile fascinated many later authors, too. See Romm (1992) 149 If. 16
THE
ETHNOGRAPHY
469
OF T H E FRINGES
I t has b e e n suggested t h a t w h i l e parts o f A r a b i a (and I n d i a ) h a d b e e n subject to D a r i u s , this was l o n g a g o , a n d b y H e r o d o t u s '
time
b o t h c o u n t r i e s h a d c o m p l e t e l y r e t u r n e d t o b e i n g parts o f the lege n d a r y fringes ( D i h l e (1990) 45). O r the Greeks. T h e countries.
Gtesias saw
Achaemenid
so i t seemed to H e r o d o t u s
and
Persians m a n a g e d to keep some c o n t a c t w i t h b o t h an I n d i a n embassy
b r i n g i n g gifts to
c o u r t . D a r i u s G o d o m a n n u s was still able to use
the some
I n d i a n troops a n d a f e w I n d i a n elephants against A l e x a n d e r ( A r r i a n ,
Anabasis 3.8)
a n d the A c h a e m e n i d c o m m a n d a n t o f G a z a h a d A r a b i a n
mercenaries ( A r r i a n ,
Anabasis
2.25.4).
A r a b i a is a large area, c o n t a i n i n g b o t h f a m i l i a r a n d d i s t a n t p a r t s . D i h l e has p o i n t e d o u t t h a t the occasional notes o n n o r t h e r n
Arabia
i n H e r o d o t u s ( 1 . 1 3 1 , 198; 2 . 3 0 , 141; 3 . 4 , 7 - 9 , 8 8 , 97) are m o r e r e a l istic t h a n the a c c o u n t o f the a r o m a t i c s c o u n t r y . H o w e v e r , this seems to be a r e f l e c t i o n o f d i f f e r e n t sources; to H e r o d o t u s
himself,
Arabia
was a single w h o l e . I n 3 . 1 0 7 - 1 3 A r a b i a is a t r u e p a r t o f the fringes. The
first
instance o f the c i n n a m o n b i r d t o p o s , the story o f a g i a n t
b i r d b u i l d i n g its nest o f c i n n a m o n sticks, is f o u n d here (3.111). L a t e r i t is f o u n d i n a d i f f e r e n t f o r m i n A r i s t o t l e a n d t h e n i n m a n y o t h e r a u t h o r s , a n d also i n I n d i a n a n d I s l a m i c l i t e r a t u r e . For
Herodotus,
snakes o f A r a b i a India."
Arabia
was the c o u n t r y o f snakes.
(3.107, cf. 2.75)
The
winged
w e r e l a t e r d e s c r i b e d as l i v i n g i n
O r i g i n a l l y , the story was p e r h a p s f o u n d e d o n a n
observa-
t i o n o f m i g r a t i n g locusts. T h e r e are perhaps m o r e a r t h r o p o d s i n v o l v e d : it is n o t t r u e f o r snakes t h a t the female eats the m a l e i m m e d i a t e l y after c o p u l a t i o n (3.109), b u t such b e h a v i o u r is observed a m o n g some spiders, s c o r p i o n s , a n d m a n t o i d s . The
a c c o u n t o f the f a t - t a i l e d sheep (3.113) is a g a i n f o u n d e d o n a
t r u e a c c o u n t , b u t exaggerated i n a w a y s u i t e d to the fringes.
The
race itself is a n c i e n t : f a t - t a i l e d sheep w e r e d e p i c t e d b o t h i n S u m e r i a n art and i n Central A r a b i a n
rock engravings
(perhaps
a different
breed). I n Ctesias the same sheep (plus s i m i l a r goats) are f o u n d i n I n d i a ( K a r t t u n e n (1989) 167
17
f.).
Megasthenes F 21, cf. Karttunen (1997) 280 f.
470
KLAUS
KARTTUNEN
The Extremes: the Indian East The
Herodotean
a c c o u n t o f I n d i a is f o u n d at 3 . 9 8 - 1 0 6 ( w i t h a d d i -
t i o n a l notes i n 3.38). I n d i a is the easternmost o f all countries (4.40) a n d I n d i a n s the m o s t n u m e r o u s o f a l l peoples (5.3). T h e
exploration
o f A s i a i n 4 . 4 4 also starts f r o m I n d i a . I n d i a n s (7.65 a n d 7.83) their neighbours
s u c h as t h e G a n d a r a e
(7.66) a n d the
and
Eastern
E t h i o p i a n s (7.70) served i n the a r m y o f X e r x e s . A d i s t i n c t i o n b e t w e e n the n e a r I n d i a r u l e d b y
the A c h a e m e n i d s
a n d the d i s t a n t I n d i a
b e y o n d i t is n o t e d (3.101), b u t n o t m a i n t a i n e d . I t is l i k e l y t h a t I n d i a , a l t h o u g h p a r t l y f a m i l i a r t o his sources, was to H e r o d o t u s
himself
e n t i r e l y a p a r t o f the fringes. As o n o t h e r fringes, the fact t h a t some o f the m a r v e l s w e r e o r i g i n a l l y f o u n d e d o n a t r u e a c c o u n t m a d e t h e m n o less m a r v e l s . T h e I n d i a n g o l d , t h o u g h a c c o m p a n i e d b y f a b u l o u s tales, was real (but evidently n o t as a b u n d a n t as c l a i m e d b y H e r o d o t u s i n 3.94). E v e n the n a m e ' a n t - g o l d ' is f o u n d i n I n d i a n sources. I have s h o w n elsew h e r e t h a t the a n t - g o l d was p r o b a b l y r e l a t e d to the S c y t h i a n a c c o u n t o f g r i f f i n - g o l d (see b e l o w ) , b o t h g o i n g b a c k to C e n t r a l A s i a n l e g e n d s . 1 8 The
vegetarian tribe i n 3.100
is h a r d l y a n a c c o u n t o f I n d i a n
ascetics, t h o u g h o f t e n presented as s u c h , b u t o f savages (1989)
125
(Karttunen
n . 26). A n o t h e r v e g e t a r i a n t r i b e i n H e r o d o t u s
are the
L i b y a n A t l a n t e s (4.184), also a people l i v i n g o n o r near the fringes. But
while Herodotus
introduced a number
o f t n d i a n marvels
to
G r e e k l i t e r a t u r e , he was silent a b o u t the f a b u l o u s peoples a p p a r e n t l y m e n t i o n e d b y S c y l a x ( k n o w n to H e r o d o t u s i n 4.44) a n d t h e n a c o m m o n p a r t o f m y t h i c I n d i a i n classical l i t e r a t u r e (see K a r t t u n e n (1989) 127 f t . ) .
The Extremes: the European Northwest I n 3.115
f. H e r o d o t u s briefly m e n t i o n s the E u r o p e a n northwest a m o n g
t h e f r i n g e s . 1 9 Stories deemed
13
and
sources w e r e
them untrustworthy.
He
available, but
Herodotus
b r i e f l y stated his suspicion as to
Karttunen (1989) 171 ff. Indian sources for 'ant-gold': Mahdbhdrata 2.48.4, Mamnathapurani 2.239.21. A l l geographical and ethnographical material on Europe (other than Greece) in Herodotus is listed and discussed by Nenci (1990). 19
THE
ETHNOGRAPHY
OF T H E
w h e t h e r the n o r t h - f l o w i n g r i v e r Ericlanus
471
FRINGES
(as the source o f
amber,
b y others v a r i o u s l y i d e n t i f i e d as t h e R h o n e or the Po) a n d the f a b ulous T i n
Islands (Gassiterides,
probably
the B r i t i s h Isles) actually
existed, t h o u g h he k n e w t h a t b o t h a m b e r a n d t i n a r r i v e d f r o m somewhere
o n the E u r o p e a n fringes. I n 4 . 4 5
he repeats his
c o n c e r n i n g the distant parts o f E u r o p e . T h e
of the Ister ( D a n u b e ) are b r i e f l y discussed i n 2.33 4.48 f ) . T h e
ignorance
sources a n d the course (and a g a i n
in
question of w h e t h e r E u r o p e is c i r c l e d b y the O c e a n ,
is e m p h a t i c a l l y left o p e n ,
as s o m e t h i n g c o n c e r n i n g w h i c h r e l i a b l e
i n f o r m a t i o n (as opposed to p o e t r y ) is n o t available (3.115 a n d 4.45). H e r o d o t u s d i d n o t believe the T h r a c i a n c l a i m t h a t the lands
beyond
t h e Ister are i m p e n e t r a b l e because o f n u m e r o u s bees; r a t h e r , i t was due to the c o l d (5.10). H o w e v e r , a lack o f i n f o r m a t i o n is n o t sufficient e x p l a n a t i o n t h e sceptical t a c i t u r n i t y o f H e r o d o t u s . T h e India and Arabia,
for
i n f o r m a t i o n available f o r
f o r instance, was c e r t a i n l y n o t m u c h better
or
m o r e reliable t h a n t h a t a b o u t the E u r o p e a n fringes. I n m a n y passages H e r o d o t u s was w i l l i n g to give a l e n g t h y a c c o u n t , t h o u g h himself deemed
the m a t t e r r a t h e r u n t r u s t w o r t h y .
G r e e k colonies- -themselves
The
q u i t e f a m i l i a r to a n d o f t e n
b y H e r o d o t u s ( N e n c i (1990) 304) distant parts o f E u r o p e . I n 1.163 rations b y the Phocaeans is m a d e .
he
flourishingmentioned
certainly had information
about
an a c t u a l reference to the e x p l o B u t f o r H e r o d o t u s the focus
the h i s t o r y lay i n the east a n d his m a n y excursuses
of
on individual
countries a n d peoples were inserted w h e n they became i n v o l v e d w i t h the m a i n
h i s t o r y , w i t h the g r o w t h o f the Persian
empire. I n
this
schema, the E u r o p e a n eskhatiai h a d n o p l a c e at a l l . W i t h the help o f t h e T h r a c i a n excursus ( 5 . 3 - 1 0 ) , it is possible to see the c o m m o n
threefold pattern in Europe, too. T h e
Black
Sea
coast w i t h G r e e k colonies belongs to the centre, w h i l e the i n l a n d T h r a cians represent the i n t e r m e d i a t e stage, a n d the fringes spread b e y o n d the Ister. T h r a c i a n s
are n o n o m a d s ,
t r u e , b u t they
out
despise
a g r i c u l t u r a l l a b o u r (5.6), practise p r e m a r i t a l p r o s t i t u t i o n (5.6), have o n l y a few gods (5.4).
20
The
(5.7)
and entertain curious notions about
lake-dwellers (5.16) w i t h t h e i r curious villages a n d
sided diet o f fish are already close to the fringes. T h e
death one-
real fringes
start beyond the Ister. T h e only Trans-Istrian people k n o w n to Herodotus
20
The same custom is also ascribed to Lydians (1.93, cf. also 1.199 on Babylonian sacred prostitution).
472
KLAUS
KARTTUNEN
are the Sigynnae, w h o have M e d i a n - s t y l e dress a n d small, l o n g - h a i r e d horses. T h e i r area extends a l m o s t to t h a t o f the E n e t i , i . e . , V e n e t i on
the A d r i a t i c ( 5 . 9 ) . 2 1 I n a n o t h e r passage (1.196) i t is stated t h a t
the V e n e t i practise a n a u c t i o n o f b r i d e s s i m i l a r to t h a t i n B a b y l o n i a .
The Extremes: the Scythian Northeast T h e m a i n a c c o u n t o f e x t r e m e S c y t h i a is f o u n d i n H e r o d o t u s 4.25—36 (inserted i n the g e n e r a l a c c o u n t o f S c y t h i a i n 4 . 1 - 1 4 3 ) . 2 2 A
parallel
to this is the a c c o u n t o f the Massagetae i n 1 . 2 0 1 - 1 6 . T h e y live i n the east b e y o n d the r i v e r A r a x e s ,
opposite t o the Issedones (1.201),
w h o m t h e y m u c h resemble i n customs. L i k e L i b y a , Scythia c o n t a i n s all t h r e e regions: G r e e k colonies a n d a g r i c u l t u r e n e a r the B l a c k Sea, the
intermediate nomads,
a n d t h e savages o f t h e f r i n g e . A
clear
d i s t i n c t i o n is m a d e between a g r i c u l t u r a l Scythians a n d n o m a d i c S c y t h i a n s , w h i l e some o f the f r i n g e - d w e l l e r s are specially said t o be n o n S c y t h i a n . T h e r e is n o clear b o u n d a r y b e t w e e n m o r e western E u r o p e a n d S c y t h i a , w h i c h as a w h o l e is i n c l u d e d i n E u r o p e .
Herodotus
a c t u a l l y counts the Ister as the w e s t e r n m o s t o f S c y t h i a n rivers (4.51). T h e Issedones (4.26) are l o c a t e d i n t h e d i s t a n t northeast.
Beyond
t h e m w e r e the o n e - e y e d A r i m a s p i a n s a n d the g o l d - g u a r d i n g griffins (4.13 a n d 27), w h i c h Ctesias puts i n a place r e a c h e d b y a n e x p e d i tion
f r o m I n d i a o r B a c t r i a . I n 3.116
H e r o d o t u s locates the A r i m a s p i a n s
a n d the g o l d - g u a r d i n g griffins i n n o r t h e r n E u r o p e , b u t is seems t h a t his E u r o p e e x t e n d e d n o r t h o f A s i a . I n this he was c e r t a i n l y b e t t e r i n f o r m e d t h a n m a n y later a u t h o r s , k n o w i n g t h a t the C a s p i a n a n i n l a n d sea (1.202 f.) a n d n o t a n i n l e t o f the N o r t h e r n
was
Ocean.
M u c h l a t e r , i n the Geography o f P t o l e m y ( 6 . 1 6 . 5 ) , the Issedones are f o u n d i n C e n t r a l A s i a . As n o t e d a b o v e , the griffins m a y go b a c k to a C e n t r a l A s i a n story ( K a r t t u n e n (1989) 177 fif.). I n I n d i a , H e r o d o t u s s w a l l o w e d t h e story o f the g o l d - d i g g i n g ants; here he d o u b t s t h e existence o f t h e o n e - e y e d A r i m a s p i a n s a n d g o l d - g u a r d i n g g r i f f i n s , b u t a d m i t s t h a t t h e g o l d is real. Despite his c r i t i c i s m , h o w e v e r ,
Herodotus
has t a k e n e n o u g h f r o m the Arimaspeia to give us some i d e a o f this lost w o r k a n d o f its a u t h o r , Aristeas o f Proconnesus. 2 3
21
Qn the Sigynnae see Nenci (1990) 312 See in more detail above, Ch. 19; also dealing with Scythian history, see Harmatta In addition to the classic monograph by 22
n
ff. Romm (1992) 45 ff. For the passages (1990) 122 ff. Bolton (1962) see Romm (1992) 69 ff.
THE
ETHNOGRAPHY
OF
473
THE FRINGES
I n the n o r t h t h e b a l d - h e a d e d A r g i p p a e i are the last k n o w n
peo-
p l e , b e y o n d t h e m there are tales o f g o a t - f o o t e d p e o p l e a n d , still f u r t h e r i n t h e n o r t h , o f m e n w h o sleep for six m o n t h s of the year (4.25), T h i s is n o t t r u e , b u t the
p e r i o d o f six m o n t h s does c o r r e s p o n d to
the sunless w i n t e r t i m e i n the e x t r e m e n o r t h . T h e n follows a n a c c o u n t o f the w i n t e r i n Scythia (4.28). 2 4 T h e f o r t u n a t e H y p e r b o r e a n s
(4.32-36,
cf. R o m m (1992) 60 ff.) are at t h e same t i m e f r i n g e - d w e l l e r s a n d a p a r t o f G r e e k t r a d i t i o n . A c c o r d i n g to Aristeas, t h e y l i v e d b e y o n d t h e Arimaspians
(4.14). T h e y w e r e early presented as i n h a b i t i n g a dis-
tant Utopia, b u t this aspect is d e l i b e r a t e l y suppressed b y
Herodotus,
w h o is c o n t e n t to discuss such accounts w h i c h to h i m seem m o s t like h i s t o r y .
Before and after Herodotus I t was c u s t o m a r y i n G r e e k l i t e r a t u r e i n t h e t i m e s o f H e r o d o t u s
(and
l o n g afterwards) to start e v e r y t h i n g w i t h H o m e r a n d always take t h e possible H o m e r i c evidence i n t o a c c o u n t . 2 ' 1 F o r H e r o d o t u s ,
however,
H o m e r was n o source f o r the f r i n g e s , t h o u g h he is occasionally m e n t i o n e d a n d accepted as a source o f h i s t o r y . A c c o r d i n g to H e r o d o t u s , H o m e r a n d o t h e r a r c h a i c poets w e r e i n v e n t i n g things a n d t h e n p r e s e n t i n g t h e m as t r u e , as i n t h e cases o f t h e r i v e r O c e a n u s (2.23) a n d the H y p e r b o r e a n s
(4.32). T h e m y s t e r i o u s epic o f Aristeas o f P r o c o n -
nesus, t h e Arimaspeia, was used (4.13
ff.) as the o n l y source f o r the
far S c y t h i a n fringes, t h o u g h w i t h m u c h scepticism. O f t e n his c r i t i c i s m seems to i n c l u d e the Periegesis o f Hecataeus o f M i l e t u s , a l t h o u g h this is n o t c l e a r l y stated. The
name o f Hecataeus26
by Herodotus,
is a c t u a l l y m e n t i o n e d o n l y a f e w times
b u t there is h a r d l y a n y d o u b t t h a t the Periegesis was
m u c h used i n e t h n o g r a p h i c a l passages. Since i t was n o t c u s t o m a r y to n a m e one's sources save i n a f e w cases o f c r i t i c i s m , 'the I o n i a n s say' p r o b a b l y refers to Hecataeus. T h e r e was a t i m e w h e n scholars w e r e keen to see e v e r y t h i n g i n H e r o d o t u s
as d e r i v e d f r o m earlier w r i t -
t e n sources (see e . g . , Reese (1914)), b u t h o w c o u l d a n e x p e r i e n c e d
24
The continental climate makes winter rather hard even in Southern Russia. This was known early to the Greeks: see the Cimmerian passage in the Odyssey 11.13 ff. See, e.g., the long discussions of Homeric geography in the first book of Strabo. His relation to Herodotus is fully discussed in Karttunen (1989) 65 ff. and again by Dihle (1994) 24 ff. Jacoby (1913) 392 ff. is also still worth reading. &
2I>
474
KLAUS
KARTTUNEN
traveller and collector o f information such as Herodotus have kept himself from adding to these? According to Lloyd, the geographical and ethnographical parts of the Libyan account more or less followed the lines laid by Hecataeus, but Herodotus also used other sources, often oral, and applied his own reason to all (Lloyd (1990) 239 £). The same is probably true for other fringes. Hecataeus was important, but Herodotus searched for other information, too, and kept a critical distance from his predecessor. The unquestionable fragments of Hecataeus (most easily found i n the edition o f Nenci) are so terse and uninformative that without the hypothesis that Herodotus uncritically compiled from him (and he was critical), our idea of the Periegesis remains poor. I n later times Herodotus was given the undeserved stamp o f being a liar. Nevertheless, as M u r r a y (1972) showed, he was much read, especially i n the early Hellenistic period. Aristotle criticized but also used him often. Ephorus and Theopompus owed much to him. There are many examples relating to less remote parts o f the world (e.g., in the descriptions of Egypt), but where the fringes are concerned, too, his influence is conspicuous. Nearchus (F 8) and Megasthenes (F 23) knew the gold-digging ants of fndia and Nearchus even claimed to have seen their skins. There are further Herodotean elements i n Nearchus (Murray (1972) 205 f.). W h e n Herodotus said that the inhabitants of the Caucasus west o f the Caspian had intercourse i n public like animals (1.203), Megasthenes said the same i n a passage probably dealing w i t h the Indian Caucasus, i.e., the Hindukush (F 27b). The description of Arabia i n Arrian (Anabasis 7.20) uses Herodotus. However, there is danger i n reconstructing literary reminiscenses on the basis o f only a single point. Were there not several independent accounts o f Indian widows dying with their dead husbands and even competing for this honour- -and strong parallel evidence i n Indian sources—it would be easy to claim that the account was founded on the Herodotean passage describing a similar custom i n Thrace (5.5). Herodotus was not only the father of history, but also the father of ethnography. While his predecessors remained shadowy figures rarely quoted or even mentioned, Herodotus' own work became the model for future generations describing distant lands. ' 2
11
Margot Whiting has kindly checked and corrected my English.
CHAPTER T W E N T Y - O N E
BABYLON Amélie K u h r t
Introduction Herodotus composed his work after the middle of the fifth century BC, by which time Babylonia had been part o f the Achaemenid empire for nearly a hundred years. I n his description o f the country, centred on the city of Babylon, he evokes the shortlived NeoBabylonian imperial period (626-539 BG), preceding Persian rule (1.178—86), i n order to set the scene for Gyrus' conquest in 539 (1.189—91). This is followed by a rapid and highly selective survey of Babylonia's resources and customs (1.192—200). Only very occasionally does Herodotus remark on changes that have taken place in Babylonia result o f Persian rule (e.g., 1.196.5). What picture of Babylon and Babylonians do we take away from Herodotus? First, Babylon was an Assyrian city, the greatest after the fall of Nineveh. I t was perfectiy square, bisected by the Euphrates, with the palace i n the western half, temples i n the eastern half. The massive walls, surmounted by small buildings and broad enough to accommodate a four-horse chariot, enclosed an area more than 91 km. i n circumference. They were protected by a moat and pierced by a hundred bronze gates. For construction, mudbricks and locally available bitumen were used; large buildings were strengthened with reed-mats layered between the courses. There were two temples: one was an eight-staged tower; ascent was by a spiral stair to reach a shrine at the top where, according to the 'Chaldaeans', a divinely chosen woman was visited by the god Bel (i.e., the Babylonian god Marduk)—a similar custom being known i n Egyptian Thebes and Lycia. The second temple was lower and contained a gigantic gold cult-statue o f Zeus (by which Herodotus probably means Bel); outside were massive altars for sacrifice, and there had been another statue here, o f a man, plundered by Xerxes.
476
AMÉLIE
KUHRT
Babylon. Adapted from J. Goodnick Westenholz (ed.), Royal Cities of the Biblical World (Jerusalem 1996), 196 fig. 1.
477
BABYLON
Herodotus
t h e n t u r n s to B a b y l o n ' s
history: Semiramis,
a
queen
w h o l i v e d p e r h a p s three h u n d r e d years e a r l i e r , h a d b u i l t a system o f dykes to c o n t r o l the r i v e r . B u t i t was a n o t h e r q u e e n , N i t o c r i s
(150
years before H e r o d o t u s ) , w h o d i d some o f the m o s t impressive w o r k — d i v e r t i n g the E u p h r a t e s to stem its flow a n d c o n s t r u c t massive
quay
w a l l s , a n d b u i l d i n g a b r i d g e to l i n k the t w o halves o f t h e city.
She
was b u r i e d i n a t o m b set over one o f B a b y l o n ' s gates; its i n s c r i p tion promised money opened it. T h e
to future Babylonian
kings i n n e e d , i f t h e y
Persian k i n g D a r i u s I (522-486) e v e n t u a l l y d i d so,
m a i n l y because he w a n t e d to be able t o use t h e gate; a l l he f o u n d inside was a s c o r n f u l note c o n d e m n i n g his g r e e d . I t was N i t o c r i s ' son, L a b y n e t o s , w h o f o u g h t against C y r u s . 1
First he was successful,
t h e n defeated. B a b y l o n was p l a c e d u n d e r siege, w h i c h d r a g g e d o n because the city was so w e l l p r o v i s i o n e d a n d f o r t i f i e d .
Eventually,
C y r u s d i v e r t e d the E u p h r a t e s to a l l o w his a r m y to enter the c i t y ; t h e B a b y l o n i a n s d i d n o t n o t i c e t h e fall o f t h e i r city because i t was so h u g e a n d t h e y w e r e a l l c e l e b r a t i n g a festival at the o t h e r e n d . 2 After
t h a t we get a t h u m b n a i l sketch o f t h e i r r i g a t i o n
Babylonia's
system,
e x t r a o r d i n a r y f e r t i l i t y , the c u l t i v a t i o n o f the date p a l m
a n d t h e use o f sesame o i l . N e x t comes a c u r i o u s tale o f c i r c u l a r boats, t r a v e l l i n g r e g u l a r l y d o w n the T i g r i s f r o m A r m e n i a w i t h cargoes o f w i n e a n d donkeys as ballast; they w e r e d i s m a n t l e d after d e l i v e r y , p a c k e d o n the backs o f t h e donkeys a n d t a k e n b a c k to A r m e n i a o v e r l a n d . T h e n we h e a r a b i t a b o u t B a b y l o n i a n dress, a l a u d a b l e system o f a u c t i o n i n g m a r r i a g e a b l e girls i n o r d e r to p r o v i d e d o w r i e s f o r a l l (a p r a c t i c e t h a t has ' n o w ' ceased, w i t h t h e p o o r p r o s t i t u t i n g t h e i r daughters), t r e a t m e n t o f t h e i l l i n the p u b l i c square,
burial,
m a r r i e d sex, a n d a r i t u a l b y w h i c h a l l w o m e n m u s t , once i n t h e i r l i f e t i m e , have sex w i t h a s t r a n g e r — a c u s t o m also k n o w n i n C y p r u s . W i t h a short r e m a r k a b o u t t h e fact t h a t three B a b y l o n i a n tribes eat
1
Earlier on, another Labynetos appears as mediator resolving the conflict between Cyaxares and Alyattes on the Halys (1.74). Herodotus digresses here to mention the Persian king's practice of having water from the Choaspes transported for his consumption when on the move (1.188; cf. Briant (1994)). He also describes Cyrus dividing the Gyndes river into channels as punishment for drowning one of the sacred white horses, before moving to Babylon. Herodotus says that this was the first time Babylon was taken, pointing forward to his elaborate tale, 'The ruse of Zopyrus', when Babylon fell to Darius I (3.150-60). He continues with a description of Babylonian contributions to the satrapal and royal coffers, over and above the regular tribute. At 3.92, he lists its annual tribute as 1,000 talents of silver and 500 boys to be made into eunuchs. 2
478
AMÉLIE
KUHRT
nothing but dried fish, pounded up and made into cakes or bread, Herodotus moves on to Cyrus' campaign i n Central Asia where he was killed. Archaeological investigation has recovered texts and building remains, which allow us to look at Babylonia from the inside, as it were, and compare the emerging picture o f its history and society with Herodotus' sketch. That raises questions about Herodotus' focus, sources, and conceptual structuring o f the world. T o try and clarify this complicated interplay, I shall, after a discussion of Herodotus' sources, assess the evidence, sketch a picture o f Babylonian history, society, and its great capital, Babylon, in the sixth and fifth centuries, as it appears from the Mesopotamian sources.
Herodotus' sources H o w did Herodotus acquire his information? I t has been plausibly argued that the manner i n which he presents his work fits well with the philosophical and scientific modes o f Ionian debate o f the later fifth century (Thomas (2000)). Several passages suggest that Herodotus rehearsed at least part o f his findings to a live, critical audience. I n such a context, he needed to demonstrate the trustworthiness of his research (historié). A n obvious way to persuade his listeners o f his reliability was to point to the fact that he had travelled to the relevant regions, seen things himself and spoken to the local inhabitants. W h a t does he say, or imply, about his sources o f information on Babylonia? The anecdote of Nitocris' tomb (1.187) ends with the words: 'That is the kind o f queen she is said to have been,' implying a story in general circulation. O n three occasions, he refers to Chaldaean informants (1.181; 1.182; 1.183), 'who are priests of this god' (sc. Bel; 1.181.5). Although he reports 'what they say', he does not necessarily accept it uncritically. I n one case (concerning the chastity o f the woman who annually is visted by Bel), he emphasizes that he does not believe them (1.182); in another (description of a statue stolen by Xerxes, 1.183), that he only has their word for it and has not been able to verify it with his own eyes. A couple o f times he refers to travelling to Babylonia, which could indicate that he has visited the country himself. However, both references are oblique. Thus, at 1.185, he simply says that 'those who travel from our sea to Babylonia', will see how the river bends around the v i l -
479
BABYLON
lage o f A r d e r i c c a as a result o f N i t o c r i s ' w a t e r d i v e r s i o n . T h e seco n d , f a m o u s statement is at 1.193, w h e r e he declines to say a n y m o r e a b o u t t h e g i a n t size o f B a b y l o n i a ' s c r o p s , 'because those w h o have never b e e n t o B a b y l o n w i l l n o t believe w h a t I have
already
said'. F o r t h e rest, H e r o d o t u s r e m a i n s unspecific. H e picks o u t w h a t he d e e m s
t o b e t h e m o s t m a r v e l l o u s t h i n g (to thoma megiston) i n
B a b y l o n i a (the r o u n d boats, 1.194), w h i c h h e t h i n k s is t h e best cust o m (nomas: t h e m a r r i a g e m a r k e t , 1.196) a n d w h i c h t h e w o r s t ( r i t u a l p r o s t i t u t i o n , 1.199), a n d he r e m a r k s t h a t several habits are p r a c t i s e d elsewhere, t o o (1.182, 196, 198, 199). S o , o u r i m p r e s s i o n o n r e a d i n g H e r o d o t u s ' d e s c r i p t i o n is t h a t he has b e e n t h e r e , m a d e i n f o r m e d c o m p a r i s o n s , seen t h i n g s , t a l k e d w i t h t h e locals a n d h e a r d t h e i r stories. So h e is i n a p o s i t i o n t o p r o v e t o his a u d i e n c e t h a t w h a t h e says is t r u e because he c a n v o u c h f o r i t f r o m p e r s o n a l e x p e r i e n c e — a type o f a r g u m e n t c r u c i a l i n c o n t e m p o r a r y debates ( T h o m a s (2000) 200).
B u t is t h a t i m p r e s s i o n r i g h t ?
First, w h o w e r e t h e G h a l d a e a n priests, f r o m w h o m H e r o d o t u s garn e r e d some o f his i n f o r m a t i o n ? A
distinct element o f Babylonia's
p o p u l a t i o n i n t h e first h a l f o f t h e first m i l l e n n i u m BC was l a b e l l e d C h a l d a e a n , a l t h o u g h i t is d i f f i c u l t t o define precisely h o w t h e y d i f f e r e d f r o m t h e i n h a b i t a n t s o f t h e o l d c i t y - c e n t r e s . W e can o n l y grasp t h e i r mode
o f existence v e r y p a r t i a l l y t h r o u g h t h e eyes o f u r b a n elites,
w h e n t h e t w o groups c a m e i n t o c o n f l i c t . T h e y seem to have
been
p r o s p e r o u s , d i v i d e d i n t o several g r o u p s d e r i v i n g t h e i r identities f r o m an eponymous
ancestor, a n d t h e i r m a i n settlements were
concen-
t r a t e d i n t h e m a r s h y , e x t r e m e s o u t h o f I r a q . 3 B y t h e e n d o f t h e seventh century, w h e n the Neo-Babylonian
e m p i r e c a m e i n t o existence,
a large p r o p o r t i o n o f these g r o u p s seem t o have b e e n a b s o r b e d i n t o the d o m i n a n t f a b r i c o f B a b y l o n i a ' s p o l i t i c a l life. M a n y later classical w r i t e r s , t o o , like H e r o d o t u s ,
refer t o ' C h a l d a e a n s '
as c u l t i c experts;
a l t e r n a t i v e l y , i t comes t o be a g e n e r a l d e s i g n a t i o n f o r B a b y l o n i a n s . 4 B u t f o r S t r a b o (16.8) t h e Chaldaeans are still a people l i v i n g i n s o u t h ern Babylonia
a r o u n d t h e Persian G u l f . So there is n o u n a n i m i t y
a b o u t w h o t h e y really w e r e . W h a t
is c e r t a i n is t h a t n o g r o u p o f
scholars o r t e m p l e - p e r s o n n e l i n B a b y l o n i a w e r e ever c a l l e d this i n the s u r v i v i n g d o c u m e n t a t i o n f r o m
Mesopotamia.
Ili'iiikimin (1968), 11!)84). For a discussion of the problems involved in defining Chaldeans, and a critique of the idea that they were 'tribal', see von Dassow (1999). Edzard (1975); Kuhrt (1982). 4
480
AMÉLIE
The
KUFIRT
second q u e s t i o n concerns H e r o d o t u s '
p e r s o n a l presence
in
B a b y l o n i a , T h e r e was c e r t a i n l y little to p r e v e n t h i m j o u r n e y i n g w i t h i n the Persian e m p i r e , so there is n o t h i n g i n h e r e n t l y i n c r e d i b l e i n his c o n d u c t i n g his i n q u i r i e s o n the spot. M a n y , w h e t h e r he d i d . T h e tion in Babylonia
nevertheless,
question
issue has b e e n c o n t e n t i o u s ever since
showed that Herodotus'
excava-
p i c t u r e does n o t r e a l l y
t a l l y w i t h the s u r v i v i n g r e m a i n s o r texts ( B o i y (2000) 8 1 - 2 ) . T h i s has led scholars to f o r m u l a t e a range o f d i f f e r e n t approaches. A ard
stand-
one f o r m a n y years, a n d still g o i n g s t r o n g (e.g., D r e w s (1997)),
has b e e n to argue t h a t the B a b y l o n H e r o d o t u s
saw h a d b e e n dev-
astated b y the Persians, so t h a t he was d e s c r i b i n g a city w h i c h h a d v a n i s h e d — a v i e w n o l o n g e r sustainable (see b e l o w , p p . 4 8 8 - 9 0 ) .
To
this w e c a n a d d the w i d e s p r e a d idea t h a t H e r o d o t u s was the v i c t i m o f ' o r i e n t a l d r a g o m a n s ' (the ' G h a l d a e a n s ' ) , o n w h o m he h a d to r e l y because he d i d n o t speak the language. T h e y exaggerated a n d i n v e n t e d i n o r d e r to impress the f o r e i g n t r a v e l l e r , w h o f a i t h f u l l y r e p o r t e d t h e i r a b s u r d stories as f a c t — a n a p p r o a c h w h i c h t u r n s H e r o d o t u s naive f o o l . S o m e t r y to 'save' H e r o d o t u s
into a
b y d r a w i n g u p a balance
sheet o f t h i n g s he gets r i g h t a n d the ones he gets w r o n g . 3 As
some
things are u n d o u b t e d l y c o r r e c t — s u c h as the Euphrates flowing t h r o u g h B a b y l o n , the b r i d g e across i t , i r r i g a t i o n c h a n n e l s , the existence o f a ziggurat
a n d l o w e r t e m p l e , great w a l l s , sesame,
date-palms,
mud-
b r i c k , e t c . — t h e balance is i n f a v o u r o f H e r o d o t u s g i v i n g us a descript i o n w h i c h is b r o a d l y r e l i a b l e . 6 B u t i t is precisely the fact t h a t the b r o a d strokes o f the d e s c r i p t i o n get m a t t e r s r o u g h l y r i g h t , w h i l e a m u l t i t u d e o f details c o u l d n o t be m o r e w r o n g , t h a t raises the suspicion t h a t H e r o d o t u s
operated
w i t h a n i m a g e o f B a b y l o n a l r e a d y f a m i l i a r to his audience. T h i s he e l a b o r a t e d to f i t his o v e r a l l c o n c e p t i o n o f the w o r l d , w h i c h is m a r k e d b y a s t r o n g sense o f s y m m e t r y ,
by a vision whereby
the f u r t h e r a
place is f r o m the G r e e k c e n t r e , the m o r e expected n o r m s ( p a r t i c u l a r l y g e n d e r roles, sex, b u r i a l ) w i l l be s u b v e r t e d , a n d b y a d y n a m i c i n t e r p l a y o f 'soft' a n d ' h a r d ' c u l t u r e s , w i t h Greece r e p r e s e n t i n g (at the m o m e n t )
a p e r f e c t balance o f the t w o , w h i l e B a b y l o n i a
e x a m p l e o f softness.' T h i s creates the g r i d t h r o u g h w h i c h
5
Herodotus
E.g., MacGinnis (1986); cf. Dalley (1994). For detailed criticism of these approaches, see Rollinger (1993), (1998). ' Redfield (1985); Rosselini and Said (1978).
6
is a n
481
BABYLON
views his material and filters his perceptions; and it is this which determines the structuring o f his material. Some scholars, moreover, have demonstrated that certain stories in the Babylonian logos come from a Greek milieu, such as the 'marriage-market' and the anecdote o f Nitocris' tomb, which suggests that Herodotus placed them here to startle his audience, by finding odd, albeit familiar elements i n an exotic place. Conversely, when he says that he has seen, or been told by locals about, some particularly bizarre custom, he confirms the expectations o f his listeners by such apparently reliable testimony from someone 'who has seen it for himself. Taking such an approach would help to explain many o f Herodotus' omissions, factual errors, and some of the peculiar practices imputed to Babylonia. I t works particularly well with the 'sacred prostitution' episode, o f which no real trace can be found in the dense Babylonian evidence. This was seen as a quintessentially 'eastern' practice (note that Herodotus says it was also practised i n Cyprus), a perversion o f regular, female behaviour, which helps to underscore Babylonia's otherness i n contrast to normative Greek behaviour (Beard and Henderson (1997)). None o f this, of course, need mean that Herodotus did not visit Babylon, but it does suggest that, like many travellers, he is not necessarily a particularly reliable source o f information, as he is of necessity fitting what he may have seen and heard into an established framework o f expectations and current knowledge. Such a view assumes, of course, that he drew on all kinds o f stories and material about Babylonia already i n circulation. Their existence should not surprise us: people from western Turkey worked i n the palace at Babylon i n the sixth century; soldiers from the Aegean fought for Neo-Babylonian kings and were rewarded; many people from the north-western edges o f the Achaemenid empire were i n the employ of the Persian royal family who owned extensive tracts of land i n Babylonia; there are many reported instances o f Greek embassies visiting the court at Susa, travelling along a road that touched northern Babylonia. I n other words, there is a long history o f diverse contact and interaction between the Greek and Babylonian worlds. What 8
9
10
I ...MI.I 9
1'·::·'
;;·•. | ; „ 1,1, ,
,,„1 l<. .111 •.-_-. ,
_'
'"
.1
MacNeal (1988); Dillery (1992). See, e.g., Dyson (1971), for a discussion of the odd reports by British travellers in India in the late eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. 1(1
482
AMÉLIE
KUHRT
Herodotus did, brilliantly, was to structure this existing, albeit sketchy, knowledge in accordance with contemporary philosophical concepts and deploy it within a coherent system for understanding the world. I n this creative effort, Babylon played a key role, foreshadowing that other, much more elaborately depicted, exemplar of'softness', Egypt."
The Babylonian sources The written sources available for reconstructing Babylonia's history i n the time o f the Neo-Babylonian rulers and then under the Achaemenids are extensive and diverse, although their distribution is uneven in time and space. There are, first, a substantial number of royal inscriptions, commemorating the immense building programmes undertaken by Babylonian kings. I t is in the nature of these texts that they dwell at length on the royal piety reflected by such work; mentions of military and political events are exceptional. W h e n they occur, they are highly biased i n favour of the commissioning ruler, as one would expect. The Persian kings, save Cyrus, are represented by very few, badly damaged inscriptions only. Despite these limitations, such texts illuminate Babylonian kingship ideals, which created a framework within which the defeated Babylonians and the victorious Persian king could reach an accommodation. A second important source is the Babylonian chronicles. I n their original state, they presented a dispassionate, virtually year-by-year account of political events, as they affected Babylonia, from 744 into the late Seleucid period. But only a handful of fragments have survived, covering (in the timespan relevant for this book) the years 627-594, 557, 555-538, and even these tablets are badly damaged in places. Moreover, where legible, the chronicle information is frequently rather laconic. Nevertheless, where the texts are usable, their information can be invaluable, as it seems to have been drawn from near-contemporary, neutral records. Additional information can be gleaned from king lists and notices in astronomical texts. 12
13
14
13
16
11
12
13 14
15 16
Redfield (1985) 109-12; Rollinger (1993) 182. Langdon (1912); Berger (1973). Cf. Beaulieu (1989): Kuhrt (1983), (1990c). Kuhrt (1983), (1990a) 180-1, (1987), (1990b); van der Spek (1983). Grayson (1975); Glassner (1993). Kuhrt (1990a) 179 80; Sachs and Hunger (1988); Stolper (1988): Walker (1997).
483
BABYLON
The bulk o f documentation comes from the archives o f temples in Sippar and Uruk. Their number is exceptionally large—tens o f thousands, with many still awaiting publication. Chronologically they span, roughly, the period from the late seventh to the early fifth centuries. W h y the archives come to an end is debated; suggestions range from changes in administrative procedures to the increasing use o f Aramaic, widely used by the Achaemenid regime and written on perishable materials such as parchment. I t is also worthwhile remembering that the mass of documentation surviving from sixth century Babylonia is unusual; only one other period in Mesopotamia's long history, 1500 years earlier, has left us such quantities (Joannes (1995), (1997)). The downside of this wealth o f material is that, while it affords us detailed insight into how these great institutions administered their properties and ran their staff and dependents, it tells us virtually nothing about the rest of the population, nor the central administration. About both o f these crucial aspects, we are poorly informed. A set of documents, specifying rations to be given to people resident at, or working for, the palace in Babylon at the time of Nebuchadnezzar I I (605-562), is the sole and tiny remnant o f the immense Neo-Babylonian royal archives to have survived. From the Persian period, texts relating to the business enterprises o f a governor of Babylonia i n the late fifth century have been found in the Babylon citadel; it seems that records o f some private transactions, from approximately the same date, were also stored there. 17
18
19
Numerous texts reflect the diverse activities o f Babylonian families and individuals. They come from several sites, including Babylon, " Many aspects of the rich Uruk archives (which seem to cease in the early years of Darius I) have been, and continue to be, studied, and more texts published (cf. Kessler (1991) for survey; for the end of the archive: van Driel (1998)). The most recent substantial studies (with bibliography) of the Sippar material, which comes to an end in the early years of Xerxes, are: Bongenaar (1997): Jursa (1995); MacGinnis (1995). Weidner (1939); cf. Pedersen (1998) 183 4. That they certainly did exist is clear from occasional references in other texts to directives received from the king, and by analogy with the enormous documentation surviving from the Assyrian state archives, now being published in full in the series State Archives of Assyria, Helsinki 1987-. So far, fifteen volumes of texts with translations have appeared, plus twelve books in the companion monograph series {Slate Archives of Assyria Studies). Discussions of Assyrian history and society linked to the project appear regularly in the biannual journal, State Archives of Assyria Bulletin. The archive of the governor, who, unusually, was a Babylonian appointed by the Persian regime, is being published and analysed by Stolper (1987), (1990), (1995). 18
1!i
484
AMÉLIE
KUHRT
a n d offer the o p p o r t u n i t y t o g a i n a clearer u n d e r s t a n d i n g o f the socioe c o n o m i c c o n t e x t . B u t there are p r o b l e m s i n t r y i n g to r e c o n s t r u c t society a n d e c o n o m y f r o m such r a n d o m l y p r e s e r v e d 'business Two
files'.20
collections are p a r t i c u l a r l y i m p o r t a n t : several t h o u s a n d tablets
r e c o r d the m a r r i a g e s , i n h e r i t a n c e s , purchases, leases, a d o p t i o n s , loans a n d investments o f five generations o f the p r o m i n e n t E g i b i f a m i l y ( 6 0 2 - 4 8 2 ) . T h e y w e r e resident i n B a b y l o n , b u t t h e i r c o m m e r c i a l t e n tacles r e a c h e d w e l l b e y o n d
Babylonia's
f r o n t i e r s . 2 1 O v e r 700
texts
attest the enterprises o f the M u r a s h u f a m i l y ' f i r m ' o f N i p p u r i n t h e second h a l f o f the fifth century.
T h e y managed
owned
as w e l l as 'fiefs' assigned b y
b y h i g h - r a n k i n g Persians,
agricultural land the
a d m i n i s t r a t i o n to i n d i v i d u a l s ( i n c l u d i n g f o r e i g n settlers) a n d i n s t i t u t i o n s , i n r e t u r n f o r w h i c h the c r o w n d e m a n d e d services a n d / o r Finally,
a considerable n u m b e r
a r l y texts date f r o m the s i x t h a n d
o f B a b y l o n i a n l i t e r a r y a n d scholfifth
the age-old traditions o f Mesopotamian fostered i n Babylonia's
tax.22
centuries, w h i c h s h o w
that
learning survived a n d were
cities b o t h i n the N e o - B a b y l o n i a n
and
A c h a e m e n i d periods ( H u n g e r (1968)). A m o n g the most s t r i k i n g recent finds
o f such m a t e r i a l are o v e r 1,500 tablets f o u n d b y I r a q i a r c h a e -
ologists i n the N a b u sa hare t e m p l e i n B a b y l o n .
The
publication of
selected i t e m s shows t h e m t o be extracts f r o m the long-established corpus o f M e s o p o t a m i a n
l i t e r a t u r e , used i n the t r a i n i n g o f scholars
( C a v i g n e a u x (1981)). I n 1 9 8 5 - 6 , a t e m p l e l i b r a r y w i t h b r i c k shelvi n g , a b o u t h a l f still c o n t a i n i n g n e a t l y a r r a n g e d tablets, was u n e a r t h e d at S i p p a r . T h e
l i b r a r y was c e r t a i n l y still f u n c t i o n i n g i n t h e r e i g n o f
C a m b y s e s ( 5 3 0 - 5 2 2 ) . So f a r , o n l y a s m a l l selection o f the 8 0 0 texts have b e e n p u b l i s h e d , b u t reports o f the find i n d i c a t e t h a t the l i b r a r y c o n t a i n e d v i r t u a l l y the e n t i r e range o f M e s o p o t a m i a n
literature and
l e a r n i n g , i n c l u d i n g a c o l l e c t i o n o f copies o f e a r l i e r r o y a l i n s c r i p t i o n s , m a t h e m a t i c a l a n d a s t r o n o m i c a l t e x t s . 2 3 W i t h i n this c o n t e x t o f c u l t u r a l c o n t i n u i t y , there w e r e also n e w d e v e l o p m e n t s , the m o s t r e m a r k able o f w h i c h — i n the field o f a s t r o n o m y — o c c u r r e d w h e n was u n d e r Persian
20
domination.
Babylonia
24
For survey of findspots and publications: Pedersen (1998) 186-9, 198-9, 203-4, 210-12. Cf. Pedersen (1998) 187-9, n. 73, for publications; add now Wunsch (2000). Cardascia (1951); Stolper (1985); Donbaz and Stolper (1997). For full references to reports, and publications, of the Sippar library, see Pedersen (1998) 197, n. 85. Sachs (1948), (1952); Rochberg-Ffalton (1984), (1991). 21
22
23
24
485
BABYLON
T h i s is t h e m a t e r i a l at o u r disposal for w r i t i n g a h i s t o r y o f p o l i t i c a l events a n d r e c o n s t r u c t i n g the s o c i o - e c o n o m i c f r a m e w o r k .
I t is
very h a r d to do m o r e w i t h i t t h a n describe the expansion o f B a b y l o n i a , its fall to the Persians, the succession o f k i n g s , a n d some aspects o f Babylonian
society. T h e r e is n o
Babylonian
Herodotus;
no
text
recounts B a b y l o n i a ' s h i s t o r y i n n a r r a t i v e f o r m o r discusses the social a n d p o l i t i c a l f r a m e w o r k . I n some respects, t h a t is a n advantage
in
t h a t w e d o n o t have to cope w i t h the d i s t o r t i n g effects o f l i t e r a r y s t r u c t u r i n g a n d i d e a l i z e d a b s t r a c t i o n . O n t h e o t h e r h a n d , the sources are f r a g m e n t a r y
and uneven.
The
apparently objective chronicles
h i g h l i g h t o n l y select events. R a n d o m s u r v i v a l a n d i n c o m p l e t e excav a t i o n i n t r o d u c e t h e i r o w n d i s t o r t i o n s o f w h i c h w e have to b e w a r e i n r e c r e a t i n g B a b y l o n i a ' s h i s t o r y . M a n y aspects o f B a b y l o n i a n society w i l l always r e m a i n obscure because t h e y d o n o t surface i n the w r i t t e n or archaeological record.
Historical Outline Babylonia
was, f r o m a r o u n d
1500
BG
onwards,
the n a m e
o f the
t e r r i t o r y s t r e t c h i n g south f r o m B a g h d a d to the A r a b - P e r s i a n
Gulf,
its c h i e f r o y a l c i t y a n d religious centre at B a b y l o n . Before t h a t , f r o m the late f o u r t h m i l l e n n i u m o n , the r e g i o n h a d been one o f c o m p e t i n g city-states, w i t h a h i g h l y d e v e l o p e d ,
sophisticated, literate civi-
l i z a t i o n , w h i c h later B a b y l o n i a n s i n h e r i t e d , g u a r d e d , a n d reshaped. the n o r t h lay Assyria,
c e n t r e d o n the m o d e r n cities o f M o s u l
To and
E r b i l , i n I r a q . Despite s t r o n g links w i t h the s o u t h , Assyria h a d q u i t e distinctive p o l i t i c a l , l i n g u i s t i c a n d c u l t u r a l characteristics. I n the early second m i l l e n n i u m , Assyria was n o m o r e t h a n the m o d e s t ,
though
c o m m e r c i a l l y p r o s p e r o u s , city-state o f A s h u r o n the T i g r i s . 2 ' B u t i n the late
fifteenth
c e n t u r y , r e a c t i n g to p o l i t i c a l pressures, i t b e g a n to
d e v e l o p i n t o a substantial expansionist p o w e r :
i n the west, i t p u t
m u c h o f the area east o f the E u p h r a t e s u n d e r p r o v i n c i a l c o n t r o l ; i n the s o u t h , i t clashed repeatedly w i t h B a b y l o n i a i t b r i e f l y . Assyria's
and
dominated
growth did not proceed unchallenged, and it
u n d e r w e n t several p e r i o d s o f c o n t r a c t i o n a n d relative weakness.
But,
f r o m the n i n t h c e n t u r y o n , its kings l a u n c h e d r e p e a t e d , f a r - r e a c h i n g
Larsen (1976); Veenhof (1995).
486
AMÉLIE
KUHRT
campaigns until, by the end of the eighth century, Assyria controlled, directly and indirectly, the entire territory from the G u l f to the Egyptian frontier, from southern Turkey to the foot hills leading to the Iranian plateau, including Babylonia. But, i n the 620s, the Babylonians revolted against the Assyrians, which eventually led to the establishment of the Neo-Babylonian empire, dominating the former Assyrian territory. I t is undoubtedly the great, pervasive power of Assyria that led Herodotus to visualize it as the imperial predecessor of the Medes and Persians (1.95), and to think of Babylonia (rather uneasily, K u h r t (1982)) as a part of Assyria. I n 626, a previously unknown Babylonian, Nabopolassar, ' began a series of attacks on Assyria, which may have been already weakened by internal problems. Between 616 and 610/9, Nabopolassar fought the Assyrians beyond the confines o f Babylonia; i n this, he was supported by the Medes, living on and beyond the edges of the Assyrian empire in the east. The majority of Assyria's great royal cities fell to the allies during this period, although it was Nabopolassar who established solid political control over most of the former Assyrian centres. By the time of his death in 605, Babylonian control extended into N o r t h Syria, west of the Euphrates. T h e rest o f the Levant, as far as Egypt, was added by Nebuchadnezzar I I , Nabopolassar's son, over the next twenty years. Nebuchadnezzar's son, Amel-Marduk, was deposed after a mere two years (562-560) by his brother-in-law, Ncriglissar (560-556), who campaigned in Cilicia Aspera, along the Lydian frontier. W h e n he died, his small son fell victim to a coup, which brought Nabonidus (556-539), unrelated to the royal family as far as we know, to the throne. Herodotus' Babylonian king, Labynetos, seems to be a rendering of Nabonidus' name, used by him, indeed, as a portmanteau name for all Babylonian kings (see above, n. 1). Some scholars have argued that Herodotus' Nitocris was, in fact, Nabonidus' long-lived mother, Adda-guppi (Rollig (1969)), although reduplication of the same-named Egyptian queen seems more likely ( K u h r t (1982)). After campaigns i n Syria and Cilicia, 26
2
28
2
" Lanfranchi (2000) has argued that by the early seventh century some Greeks were settled as subjects inside the Assyrian empire. It is often assumed that Nabopolassar belonged to the powerful Chaldaean tribe, who lived in the extreme south of Iraq (see Brinkman (1968), (1984)), but this is debatable (Kuhrt (1995a) 621, n. 4). See the important evidence from ancient Dur Katlimmu, Kühne et al. (1993); cf. Kuhrt (1995b). 21
28
It
487
BABYLON
Nabonidus mounted a major expedition into the Arabian desert, where he set up a base at the great oasis o f Teima, a nodal point in the rich, trans-Arabian caravan trade. I n September 539, Cyrus (II) o f Persia, penetrated the Babylonian frontier. Persian and Babylonian armies met i n a fierce battle at Opis, just east o f the Tigris, i n which the Babylonians were defeated. Cyrus followed up his victory by looting Opis and massacring the inhabitants. O n 10 October, Sippar, on the Euphrates, surrendered and Cyrus waited there, while his forces invested Babylon to the south, which he entered, amidst a carefully orchestrated ceremony of public rejoicing, on 12 October. Nabonidus was taken prisoner and, according to a later Babylonian source, provided with the revenues o f an estate i n eastern Iran, which implies that he spent the remainder of his life as a pensioner o f the Persian king. The Babylonian empire was undoubtedly the largest, most highly evolved and complex polity conquered by Cyrus. Strategically, it was hugely important, dominating all the routes running east to west and north to south. Without controlling this territory, the Persian empire could not have existed. Consolidating the Achaemenid hold was crucial, but we know very little about how i t was achieved. There are some hints: first, it is clear that many members o f the local elite, who had served the Neo-Babylonian kings, retained their posts, at least initially. They provided the essential know-how for the Persian rulers and mediated between the Babylonian population and the new regime. Yet their own position depended on showing the Persians that they could be trusted, so that they needed to demonstrate their unswerving devotion and make Persian interests their own. Another indicator o f how important secure control o f Babylonia was is the fact that, almost immediately after the conquest, Cyrus installed his crown-prince, Cambyses, as king of Babylonia. He seems to have presided over the great public ceremony of investiture in Babylon in person ( K u h r t (1997)), thus driving home the point that, while Cambyses might appear to be acting in the manner of a Babylonian ruler, the centre o f power now lay elsewhere. For reasons we do not understand, Cambyses held the sub-kingship o f Babylon for only one year. By 535, Cyrus had appointed the Persian Gobryas 29
Full discussion of Mesopotamia!! history in Kuhrt (1995a) chs. 1-2, 7, 9, 11; details of Cyrus' conquest, Kuhrt (1983), (1988); Nabonidus provided with revenues, Briant (1985). 29
188
AMÉLIE
KUHRT
as g o v e r n o r o f a l l the t e r r i t o r i e s w h i c h h a d o r i g i n a l l y c o n s t i t u t e d the Neo-Babylonian ally m a n a g e d
empire. H o w
such a n i m m e n s e p r o v i n c e was a c t u -
we do not know;
a r o u n d the beginning o f Xerxes'
r e i g n , i t was d i v i d e d i n t o t w o separate satrapies, ' B a b y l o n i a ' ( i n c l u d i n g the t e r r i t o r y o f Assyria), a n d t h e p r o v i n c e ' B e y o n d the
River',
i.e. d i e L e v a n t , west o f the Euphrates, to the E g y p t i a n f r o n t i e r (Stolper
(1989)). T h e r e is n o h i n t i n w h a t w e have o f a n y resistance to the Persian take-over.
The
m a t e r i a l at o u r disposal gives the i m p r e s s i o n t h a t
B a b y l o n i a r e m a i n e d t r a n q u i l t h r o u g h o u t t h e rest o f G y r u s ' r e i g n a n d t h a t o f his successor, C a m b y s e s (530- 522). B a b y l o n i a n s a p p e a r also t o have accepted c a l m l y the seizure o f the Persian t h r o n e b y Cambyses' y o u n g e r b r o t h e r , B a r d i y a ( H e r o d o t u s ' Smerdis), i n t h e s p r i n g o f 522 (Hdt.
3.61—79). B u t o n l y f o u r days after D a r i u s ' m u r d e r o f B a r d i y a
(late S e p t e m b e r man
5 2 2 ) , B a b y l o n i a r e b e l l e d u n d e r the leadership o f a
c l a i m i n g t o be a son o f N a b o n i d u s ,
grammatic name
who
assumed t h e p r o -
N e b u c h a d n e z z a r . B u t t h e r e v o l t was s h o r t - l i v e d :
the rebels w e r e defeated i n t w o battles b y D a r i u s i n
mid-December,
B a b y l o n was t a k e n , t h e r i n g l e a d e r a n d his supporters p u b l i c l y executed. A l t h o u g h some scholars have expressed d o u b t ( R o l l i n g e r (1998)), m o s t accept D a r i u s '
statement t h a t yet a n o t h e r B a b y l o n i a n
revolt
b r o k e o u t , u n d e r a leader l a y i n g c l a i m to the same i d e n t i t y , i n A u g u s t 5 2 1 , w h i c h was scotched b y D a r i u s ' close associate, I n t a p h e r n e s . course o f these revolts is d e s c r i b e d i n D a r i u s
The
I's l o n g i n s c r i p t i o n
c a r v e d i n t o the rockface at B e h i s t u n , j u s t i f y i n g his seizure o f t h e Persian t h r o n e . T h e o n l y t a n g i b l e r e f l e c t i o n o f t h e m i n B a b y l o n i a is t h a t several d o c u m e n t s are d a t e d b y the p r e t e n d e r s . 3 0 Two
m o r e rebels are attested b y B a b y l o n i a n
b u t , apart f r o m their names, we k n o w
dated
documents,
nothing about them.
The
revolts w e r e s h o r t l i v e d — n o t m u c h m o r e t h a n t w o weeks a n d three m o n t h s , r e s p e c t i v e l y — a n d i t is q u i t e u n c l e a r w h e n they t o o k p l a c e . F o r m a n y decades i t has b e e n assumed t h a t t h e y s h o u l d be p l a c e d i n X e r x e s ' second a n d f o u r t h r e g n a l years (484 a n d 4 8 2 ) , b u t this was based o n the m i s r e a d i n g o f a passage i n H e r o d o t u s ' d e s c r i p t i o n o f a t e m p l e i n B a b y l o n (1.183), c o m b i n e d w i t h a deep-seated
idea
t h a t X e r x e s was a p s y c h o l o g i c a l l y unstable a n d sacrilegious despot
30
The most important analyses of Darius' usurpation are Dandamaev (1976); Briant (1996) 109-39. For discussion of Herodotus' account of Darius' accession and its relationship to the Behistun inscription, see Balcer (1987).
48!)
BABYLON
d e r i v e d f r o m G r e e k l i t e r a r y sources, b a c k e d u p b y the a t t r i b u t i o n o f a false significance to t h e titles a p p l i e d t o Persian kings i n B a b y l o n i a n d o c u m e n t s . L e t us e x a m i n e this q u e s t i o n m o r e closely, as i t is i m p o r t a n t t o h o w w e v i e w the s i t u a t i o n i n B a b y l o n i a w h e n H e r o d o t u s
was
writing. T h e t r a d i t i o n a l a r g u m e n t , w i d e l y a c c e p t e d , runs like this: at 1.183, H e r o d o t u s tells us t h a t X e r x e s r e m o v e d the cult-statue o f c h i e f g o d o f the p a n t h e o n , all-important New
from Babylon.
Y e a r Festival,
k i n g s , c o u l d n o t be p e r f o r m e d . remove
serving to legitimize The
Babylonian
fact that Xerxes d i d
the statue, as p u n i s h m e n t f o r B a b y l o n i a ' s
so r e d u c e d its status, is s h o w n
Bel-Marduk,
W i t h o u t this statue, the indeed
t w o revolts,
and
b y the f a c t t h a t , u n t i l 4 8 2 , he was
always g i v e n the title ' k i n g o f B a b y l o n ,
k i n g o f lands' i n the date
f o r m u l a e o f d o c u m e n t s . B u t after 4 8 2 he o n l y has the title ' k i n g o f lands', Festival
as d o
a l l his successors, w h i c h shows
t h a t the N e w
Year
ceased w i t h t h e r e m o v a l o f the c u l t - s t a t u e a n d X e r x e s was
no longer accepted by Babylonians
as a l e g i t i m a t e r u l e r . T h e
'fact'
o f X e r x e s ' change o f t i t u l a r y also helps t o date the B a b y l o n i a n revolts to 4 8 4 a n d 4 8 2
respectively.
E v e r y single p o i n t o f this a r g u m e n t s examination, account
fails t o s t a n d u p
beginning w i t h the Herodotus
immense,
golden
itself. I n his
he describes
the
c u l t - s t a t u e (agalma) o f Z e u s (i.e., B e l - M a r d u k )
b e i n g i n place w e l l after X e r x e s ' d e a t h . H e golden
passage
o f the m a i n , l o w e r t e m p l e o f B a b y l o n ,
to closer
statue o f a m a n
then mentions
(andrias), o u t s i d e t h e t e m p l e , w h i c h
r e m o v e d b y X e r x e s , so t h a t he has o n l y h e a r d a b o u t i t f r o m
as
another was
'Chal-
daeans'. T h e use o f t w o d i f f e r e n t t e r m s f o r t h e statues is s i g n i f i c a n t , 3 1 a n d makes q u i t e clear t h a t , w h a t e v e r H e r o d o t u s
m a y have t h o u g h t
a b o u t X e r x e s , he d i d n o t envisage h i m r o b b i n g B a b y l o n ' s t e m p l e o f its m o s t i m p o r t a n t c u l t - i m a g e . T h e r e is, t h e r e f o r e , n o reason t o c r e d i t Xerxes w i t h any disruption o f i m p o r t a n t rituals i n Babylon. o n d p o i n t is t h a t the N e w
Y e a r Festival
A
sec-
d i d n o t f u n c t i o n t o legit-
i m i z e kings. I t was a n i m p o r t a n t o c c a s i o n , i n w h i c h i d e a l l y the k i n g p a r t i c i p a t e d , an occasion o n w h i c h he d i s p l a y e d spoils f r o m his c o n quests, m a d e gifts to temples a n d o b t a i n e d g o o d o m e n s f o r t h e f o l l o w i n g y e a r , b u t he was n o t necessarily p e r s o n a l l y present a n d
he
d i d n o t cease t o be a c c e p t e d as k i n g w h e n he was u n a b l e t o take
K u h n and Sherwin-White (1987) 71 2; Briant (1998) 217-19, 224.
490
AMÉLIE
KUHRT
p a r t . I t c o u l d still be p e r f o r m e d , a l b e i t i n a less spectacular f a s h i o n (Kuhrt
(1987)). M o r e o v e r ,
w e h a v e n o evidence
that any
o f the
Persian k i n g s , a p a r t f r o m Gambyses as r e g e n t , after the conquest Babylon
i n 5 3 8 , ever p e r f o r m e d this festival p e r s o n a l l y . I t
of
would
have b e e n , o f course, impossible f o r Gambyses w h i l e i n E g y p t to d o so, f o r e x a m p l e . Y e t , a l l o f X e r x e s ' predecessors have the title ' k i n g of Babylon'.
C l e a r l y r o y a l festival p a r t i c i p a t i o n a n d l e g i t i m a c y d i d
n o t go h a n d i n h a n d . F i n a l l y , the p a t t e r n o f X e r x e s ' titles d e r i v e d f r o m business d o c u m e n t s is n o l o n g e r v a l i d . M o r e B a b y l o n i a n
doc-
u m e n t s f r o m his r e i g n have b e e n p u b l i s h e d r e c e n t l y (see R o l l i n g e r (1999) f o r a n u p - t o - d a t e list). I t is n o w q u i t e p l a i n t h a t n o t o n l y is he g i v e n the title ' k i n g o f B a b y l o n ' r i g h t t h r o u g h his r e i g n , his successor, A r t a x e r x e s
I , also used i t . 3 2 A d m i t t e d l y , the title is used w i t h
decreasing frequency
a n d eventually
dropped
altogether, but
we
s h o u l d p r o b a b l y seek e x p l a n a t i o n s f o r this i n the fact t h a t , as the e m p i r e d e v e l o p e d a n d stabilized, i t b e c a m e a n ever m o r e i n t e g r a t e d p o l i t i c a l u n i t , a n d emphasis o n the discrete entities t h a t c o n s t i t u t e d it b e c a m e less signficant. One
result o f this is t h a t i t leaves us w i t h o u t a w a y o f d a t i n g the
revolts; w e c a n n o t even be c e r t a i n t h a t t h e y o c c u r r e d i n X e r x e s ' r e i g n , a l t h o u g h t h a t is a p o s s i b i l i t y . 3 3 A n o t h e r i m p o r t a n t p o i n t t o note is t h a t the d e s t r u c t i o n o f the t r a d i t i o n a l a r g u m e n t suggests t h a t n o drastic changes
or d i m i n u t i o n of Babylonian
cults were
intro-
d u c e d b y a n y o f the Persian kings. T h a t fits r a t h e r w e l l w i t h the t e x t u a l m a t e r i a l , w h i c h reflects the c o n t i n u i t y o f t r a d i t i o n a l t e m p l e activities (Stolper (1994)). C o n t r a r y to w h a t is f r e q u e n t l y asserted b y archaeologists, 3 ' 1 there is n o evidence at B a b y l o n o f t e m p l e destructions datable t o the A c h a e m e n i d p e r i o d , even less to X e r x e s ( R o l l i n g e r (1993),
32
(1998)).
Rollinger (1998) stresses, rightly, that we do not know precisely which Artaxerxes had these titles (it could be either I , I I or III). Attributing the documents (there are so far only three) to Artaxerxes I is based on the assumption that there is an evolution in the titulary. Briant (1992); Kuhrt (1997); Rollinger (1998). Haerinck (1990), (1997); Schmid (1981), (1995). 33
31
491
BABYLON
Babylon T h e city o f B a b y l o n rose to p r o m i n e n c e i n the r e i g n o f H a m m u r a b i ( 1 7 9 2 - 1 7 5 0 B C ) ; i t was an i m p o r t a n t cultic centre subsequently u n d e r the Kassites (c. 1550-1155). Its role as the p r i m e c e r e m o n i a l a n d r o y a l c a p i t a l g r e w as its c h i e f g o d , B e l - M a r d u k ,
b e c a m e h e a d o f the
B a b y l o n i a n p a n t h e o n a n d was closely l i n k e d t o B a b y l o n i a n k i n g s h i p ( L a m b e r t (1963)). B u t t h e B a b y l o n o f l e g e n d was essentially the c r e a t i o n o f N e b u c h a d n e z z a r I I , w h o used the w e a l t h a c q u i r e d b y e m p i r e to l a y o u t a n e w
the c i t y , w h i c h h a d u n d o u b t e d l y suffered i n the
struggles against Assyria, a n d e q u i p p e d i t w i t h m a g n i f i c e n t b u i l d i n g s . T h i s is the city excavated b y t h e D e u t s c h e O r i e n t Gesellschaft f r o m
1899 to 1916.
35
B a b y l o n f o r m e d a r e c t a n g l e , s u r r o u n d e d b y a massive a n d c o m p l e x , t u r r e t e d w a l l , p i e r c e d b y e i g h t gates a n d l a p p e d b y a w a t e r filled
m o a t . T h e Euphrates flowed t h r o u g h the city, its banks p r o t e c t e d
b y great q u a y - w a l l s , a n d c o u l d be crossed b y a solidly b u i l t b r i d g e . V i r t u a l l y a l l the i m p o r t a n t p u b l i c b u i l d i n g s — t e m p l e s a n d palacew e r e l o c a t e d i n the l a r g e r , eastern section o f the city. A n o t h e r
wall
r a n outside the m o a t e d f o r t i f i c a t i o n o f the eastern c i t y , e n c l o s i n g a n o t h e r possible palace l o c a t e d 2 k m . to t h e n o r t h , w h i c h the excavators t h o u g h t was used as a r o y a l s u m m e r residence. T h i s w a l l was some
7.5
outer
k m . l o n g ; w i t h the E u p h r a t e s to the west, i t
f o r m e d a t r i a n g l e m e a s u r i n g c. 12.5
k m . i n circumference. Straight
streets r a n f r o m the city-gates t o the c e n t r e , d i v i d i n g the u r b a n terr a i n i n t o r e g u l a r sectors. The
m a i n t e m p l e s , h o m e o f the c i t y - g o d M a r d u k ,
c e n t r a l l y a n d enclosed b y w a l l s . T o rat, Etemenanki
were located
the n o r t h rose the great z i g g u -
('House o f t h e B o n d o f H e a v e n a n d E a r t h ' ) ,
with
p r o b a b l y seven stages, each one p a i n t e d a d i f f e r e n t c o l o u r a n d surm o u n t e d b y a s m a l l s h r i n e . 3 6 Access was a l m o s t c e r t a i n l y b y a straight c e n t r a l staircase, a n d p e r h a p s t w o sets o f (1990)). T h e
flanking
stairs (cf. S c h m i d
precise f u n c t i o n o f ziggurats is u n k n o w n :
the
upper
shrine may have b e e n used f o r a sacred m a r r i a g e c e r e m o n y , b u t w h a t
35
Koldewey (1990); linger (1928). Precise height is not known, as all that survives at Babylon is a badly denuded stump. The ziggurat at Ur [c. 2100 BC) was originally c. 12 m. high; the thirteenthcentury one at Choga Zanbil was 100 m. square and c. 48 m. high. Only at Khorsabad in Assyria (eighth-century) is there a trace of spiral access. 36
492
AMÉLIE
KUHRT
3
this was precisely is hotly debated. ' Another important aspect of the ziggurat is that it 'entombed' earlier sacred buildings inside its core, thus preserving and protecting them (Stone (1997)). Directly next to it was the great lower temple o f M a r d u k , Esangil ('Lofty House'). From these two structures, considered the most sacred and oldest, led the Processional W a y (to the east), decorated with brilliantly coloured, glazed, moulded bricks showing bulls, dragons (the animal sacred to Marduk), and lions. The street passed another temple to the north, where the royal investiture took place (Pongratz-Leisten (1994) 103), and led on past the walls o f the palace and through the immense, identically decorated Ishtar gate. The central section of the street was paved with white limestone slabs, red breccia paving on either side creating the effect o f a modern street. I t was along this street that the king led the procession o f cult-statues, temple attendants, citizenry, followed by displays o f booty from royal campaigns (living and material) on the occasion o f the New Year Festival (Berger (1970)). A further feature is that the processional way gradually sloped upwards on both sides o f the city wall, so that the Ishtar gate and the royal palace, on its raised platform, were elevated above other dwellings, forming a lower, but marked, elevation to balance the immense height o f the ziggurat. The large royal residence rode on the inner city-wall, extending beyond it to the north, j u t t i n g west to the river and surrounded by walls to form a prominent citadel. Parts o f it were decorated w i t h glazed bricks, depicting lions and floral motifs, using the same colours as the Ishtar gate. Other temples were located throughout the city. The urban space was densely inhabited, houses crowding together along twisted streets within the regular pattern o f rectangular segments created by the main streets. 38
31
Two distinct rituals are dubbed 'sacred marriage': one is the marriage of two gods, represented by their statues; the other a ceremony during which the goddess of erotic love, Inanna/Ishtar (represented by a priestess?), and the king in the guise of her mythical lover, Dumuzi, had intercourse. How this latter was enacted precisely is enigmatic as, apart from literary allusions, no descriptions survive. Scholars are, therefore, divided on what it involved. For arguments denying its performance, see Leick (1994) 111-38; for acceptance, Frymer-Kensky (1992) 50-7. Best recent assessments of ritual, Cooper (1993); Goodnick-Westenholz (1995). The topography of Babylon is re-examined, using the literary texts known as 'The Description of Babylon' and more recent examinations of the city's terrain, in George (1992), (1993), (1997); this supersedes, in many important respects, the earlier study by Linger (1931). 33
BABYLON
493
As we saw, there is no evidence that the Persians modified Babylon's layout or buildings substantially. One addition was that at least one, possibly more, copies of Darius' Behistun inscription, i n Accadian, and surmounted by an over life-size relief of the king triumphant over the rebels, was set up along the palace wall fronting the Processional Way (Seidl (1976), (1999)). T h e message of Babylon's definitive defeat and subjection was driven home i n no uncertain manner, the inscription claiming Babylon's own god, Marduk, as supporter of Darius' action. A beautiful small Persian palace was built in the westernmost courtyard of the south part of Nebuchadnezzar's citadel by Artaxerxes I I (405-359), decorated with brick reliefs of the kind known from Susa. But this did not happen until 39
M
ilIII-
I 1 1 ' I . 1 1 11 N
.1 111
|
||l
| t I I 11 11 I | v
Babylonian society Despite the political turmoil experienced by Babylonia between the late seventh and fifth centuries, social and economic structures present an image of continuity. This probably masks all sorts of shifts and changes, which are hard for modern scholars to pin down, but it also reflects a real constancy i n the basic framework. The mode of production of staples, such as barley and sesame (dependent on irrigation), dates (requiring artificial pollination, cf. Hdt. 1.193.4—5), and wool did not change in any fundamental respects. Basic forms of landholding and exploitation were unchanged. Some transformations can be observed: for example, more land began to be worked in the late Assyrian period, a trend which intensified under the NeoBabylonian and early Persian rulers (Cocquerillat (1968)); the system of granting land to individuals i n return for service and tax, was definitively tightened and extended in the early Persian period (Stolper (1977)). But these were modifications of existing systems, not drastic changes. The same is true of the Babylonian cities, where the great temples retained their long-established forms o f cult, involving many oi the free citizens ( K u h r t (1995a) 610-21), although they seem to have been drawn into the network of service and tax demands by the
Vallat (1989); Haerinck (1990), (1997).
494
AMÉLIE
KUHRT
Persian r e g i m e , a n d c e r t a i n l y received less spectacular r o y a l
dona-
tions (Joannes (1990)). I t is also possible t h a t some o f the large cities s h r a n k i n size i n the course o f the A c h a e m e n i d p e r i o d , a n d
there
was a c o n c o m i t a n t increase i n r u r a l , ' m a n o r i a l ' settlement, a l t h o u g h the evidence is c h r o n o l o g i c a l l y i m p r e c i s e (Joannes (1997) 283).
But
the o v e r r i d i n g i m p r e s s i o n is o f c o n t i n u i t y : j u r i d i c a l l y free citizens, c l a i m i n g c e r t a i n r i g h t s vis-a-vis the r o y a l a u t h o r i t y , f o r m e d the l e a d i n g segment o f the u r b a n p o p u l a t i o n : they s u p p l i e d the l o c a l a d m i n istrators, w e r e closely i n v o l v e d i n the t e m p l e o r g a n i z a t i o n , fields
i n the r u r a l h i n t e r l a n d a n d engaged i n a v a r i e t y o f
owned commer-
cial enterprises. M a n y o f the B a b y l o n i a n elite o w n e d substantial n u m b e r s o f slaves ( D a n d a m a e v (1984)); the E g i b i f a m i l y seems to have
concentrated
m u c h o f its business o n slave-dealing. T e m p l e s also o w n e d
slaves,
w h i c h c o u l d n o t be s o l d , a n d a p p e a r to have l i v e d i n f a m i l y u n i t s . R o y a l slaves, t o o , seem n o t to have b e e n subject to sale,
although
w e k n o w l i t t l e a b o u t t h e i r status. A l l categories o f slaves c o u l d a c c u m u l a t e considerable p r o p e r t y , a n d w e r e o f t e n a p p r e n t i c e d to p a r t i c u l a r trades b y t h e i r masters; b u t i t looks as t h o u g h o n l y p r i v a t e slaves c o u l d be m a n u m i t t e d . S o m e p r i v a t e a n d t e m p l e slaves w o r k e d f o r t h e i r o w n e r s i n the sex-trade, alongside non-slave prostitutes. A t t i t u d e s to p r o s t i t u t i o n i n Mesopotamia
are h a r d to d e f i n e , as the r a t h e r a m b i g u o u s
evidence
seems to reflect b o t h c o n t e m p t a n d a p p r o v a l . 4 0 M a r r i a g e
practices
a n d h o u s e h o l d structures are m a i n l y k n o w n f r o m
dowiy-agreements
b e t w e e n p r o m i n e n t B a b y l o n i a n families ( R o t h (1987), (1989)). N e i t h e r Herodotus'
p o p u l a r d e s c r i p t i o n o f the B a b y l o n i a n
(1.196), n o r his a c c o u n t o f c o m p u l s o r y
ritual
marriage-market
i n t e r c o u r s e as p a r t
of
t h e c u l t o f a love-goddess (1.199), appear a n y w h e r e i n M e s o p o t a m i a n sources. N o t i o n s
a b o u t sexuality d i f f e r e d p r o f o u n d l y f r o m o u r s , b u t
t h a t does n o t c o n f i r m his sensational stories. T h e p o p u l a t i o n o f B a b y l o n i a , i n the s i x t h a n d fifth centuries, was cosmopolitan. The
w e a l t h a n d p o w e r o f the N e o - B a b y l o n i a n kings
attracted c r a f t s m e n , p o l i t i c a l fugitives, m e r c h a n t s a n d soldiers; hostages f r o m n e w l y i n c o r p o r a t e d c o m m u n i t i e s were h e l d at c o u r t ; d e p o r t a t i o n policies l e d to the settlement o f f a m i l i e s f r o m defeated
com-
m u n i t i e s . W e k n o w o f Greeks, C a r i a n s , L y d i a n s , C i l i c i a n s , E g y p t i a n s ,
Kuhrt (1989), Leick (1994).
495
BABYLON
people from the coastal cities o f the Levant, Jews, Medes, Persians and Elamites. I n the Persian period, yet more non-Babylonian groups surface i n the texts, some o f them soldiers settled on land on which they owed military service (Stolper (1985)). A n important function they performed was to underpin Persia's physical control of Babylonia's territory. O f course, the relative balance o f power and, hence, proportion of foreigners shifted in the Achaemenid period. The Persian satrap represented a quasi-regal power in the judicial sphere; he received substantial incomes from the province (Hdt. 1.192), held estates and controlled a staff, which was partly made up o f Iranians. The king, queen, and members o f the royal family all held substantial stretches of land i n Babylonia (Stolper (1985)). The estates o f a treasurer with an Iranian name, of an franian titled 'chamberlain' (Joannes and Lemaire (1996)) and of a Mardonius (Stolper (1992)) appear in texts from the reign o f Darius I and Xerxes respectively. Such lands must have been confiscated from the defeated Nabonidus and his retinue. But Iranians also appear at lower, even the lowest, levels o f society, intermingling with Babylonians (Stolper (1994) 255). Members o f the Babylonian urban elites appear working in the administration and managing the estates of Persian nobles. Artaxerxes I is said to have had three Babylonian concubines. His successor, Darius I I Ochus, and Ochus' queen, Parysatis, were the offspring o f these liaisons, indicating that some Babylonian families were in a position to forge close links with the very heart of imperial power. Artaxerxes IPs building of a Persian-style palace within Nebuchadnezzar's great residence suggests that Babylonia may have occupied a relatively favoured place within the Persian empire. 41
Conclusion The picture o f Babylonia and its capital which we can disengage from the sources differs in many fundamentals from that of Herodotus. Babylon was not an Assyrian city, although it had been subject to the Assyrians, which may account for the confusion, and Herodotus,
41
For a full, recent discussion of Babylonia under Persian rule, see Wiesehdfer (1999).
496
AMÉLIE
KUHRT
remarkably and unlike later writers, gave space to the Neo-Babylonian empire. Babylon was never ruled by a queen: Nitocris cannot be accommodated into our fairly full picture o f Babylonia's history, although his brief mention o f the legendary Semiramis evokes the Assyrian queen-regent, Shammuramat, active i n the late eighth century, which fits his chronological scheme. The palace of Babylon lay fairly close to the central temples, not on the other side o f the river; the city was enormous (c. 850 ha.), but nowhere near the size envisaged by Herodotus; it had eight gates not a hundred; the ziggurat did not have a spiral ascent; i l l people were not displayed in public squares; girls were neither auctioned off nor prostituted to earn their dowries; nowhere i n the quite dense documentation do we hear of women being compelled to have intercourse with random passersby as part o f a cult. The two images—Herodotean and Babylonian— cannot easily be harmonized, and attempts to do so remain methodologically questionable. A tribute to Herodotus' skill as a writer is that, despite the enormous volume o f local material now available, his sketch o f the country and its inhabitants continues to play a potent role in contemporary ideas about Babylonia (Rollinger (1993)). 42
42
For analysis of Herodotus' ideas about Assyrian and Babylonian history (and that of later classical writers), see Kuhrt (1982), (1995c).
1
CHAPTER T W E N T Y - T W O ARCHAIC GREEK
HISTORY
R o b i n Osborne
The beginning and end of archaic Greek history Herodotus
traces b a c k past generations f o r as l o n g as he c a n
be
c o n f i d e n t t h a t the l i n e is a h u m a n l i n e . A t 6.53 he stops the line o f D o r i a n kings w i t h Perseus o n the g r o u n d s t h a t Perseus was n o t h e l d to have a h u m a n father. H e r o d o t u s
e x p l i c i t l y contrasts Perseus w i t h
H e r a c l e s , w h o i n A m p h i t r y o n h a d a h u m a n f a t h e r , a n d w i t h the possibility o f f o l l o w i n g the ancestry o f Perseus' m o t h e r D a n a e b a c k n o t j u s t to h e r father Acrisius b u t t h r o u g h h i m to the Egyptians. T h e i m p o r tance o f m a k i n g such a d i v i s i o n b e t w e e n t h e generations o f gods to the generations o f m e n was d e b a t e d , b u t H e r o d o t u s i n m a k i n g i t : at 2.143
was n o t alone
he tells h o w the priests at E g y p t i a n T h e b e s
refused to accept t h a t a m a n c o u l d be descended f r o m a g o d ,
and
so c o n s t r u c t e d f o r Hecataeus a n a l t e r n a t i v e genealogy w h i c h d i d n o t i n v o l v e his ancestry h a v i n g b e e n d i v i n e sixteen generations b e f o r e . L i k e his T e g e a n i n f o r m a n t s (9.26), H e r o d o t u s
does n o t , o n
the
o t h e r h a n d , d i s t i n g u i s h the w o r l d o f m e n f r o m the w o r l d o f heroes. M e n descend f r o m heroes ( 6 . 6 9 . 4 ) , a n d t h e y b e c o m e heroes ( 5 . 4 7 . 2 , 5 . 1 1 4 . 2 ; cf. 6 . 3 8 . 1 , 7.167.2) w i t h equal ease. For as l o n g as there have b e e n m e n , Greece has h a d a h i s t o r y : the a b d u c t i o n s o f I o , E u r o p a , M e d e a , o r H e l e n (1.1—3) have p o t e n t i a l l y the same role i n h i s t o r i cal causation as the A e g i n e t a n a b d u c t i o n o f statues f r o m E p i d a u r u s (5.82-4). W h e n Herodotus
recounts h o w the c h i l d r e n o f the c h i l d -
r e n o f the A r g o n a u t s established themselves o n T a y g e t u s a n d c l a i m e d ancestral rights at S p a r t a , he is h a p p y to use i n f o r m a t i o n a b o u t p r a c tice at S p a r t a i n his o w n t i m e ( j u d i c i a l executions are always carr i e d o u t at n i g h t ) i n o r d e r to m a k e c r e d i b l e the story a b o u t
what
t h e n h a p p e n e d t o t h e m ( 4 . 1 4 5 - 9 ) . Events o f the distant past d o n o t d e m a n d d i f f e r e n t sorts o f e x p l a n a t i o n f r o m events o f the recent past. 1
1
On Herodotus and mythology, see Détienne ("1986) 48-52, Shimron (1989) ch. 3, Lateiner (1989) 63-7.
498
ROBIN
OSBORNE
Greece. Adapted from A . M . Snodgrass, Archaic Greece: The Age of (London 1980), 16-17 fig. 1.
Experiment
ARCHAIC
GREEK
HISTORY
499
Yet not all the past is equally knowable for Herodotus. The Cretans can be persuaded not to take part i n Greek resistance to Persia by a Delphic oracle reminding them of the consequences o f Minos' anger at their participation i n the Trojan W a r (7.169-71). Herodotus also records the Cretans' story that the Carians once lived on the islands o f the Aegean and were ruled by Minos before they were expelled by Dorians and lonians, even though the Carians themselves deny that (1.171). I n telling this story, Herodotus admits of doubt ('as far as I have been able to gather from my inquiries') only as to whether the Carians paid tribute. When, however, he discusses the power of the Samian tyrant Polycrates, Herodotus does allow that Minos has a rather different historical status: 'Polycrates is the first of the Greeks of w h o m we know who formed the plan of ruling the seas, except for Minos of Knossos and any before h i m who ruled the sea. Polycrates is the first o f what is called the human generation and he had hopes o f ruling Ionia and the islands' (3.122.2). Likewise Herodotus refuses to commit himself to the historicity of the abductions listed in 1.1—3, distinguishing them from 'what I know' (1.5.3). Later, i n reckoning the Persian invasion of 480 BC to be 'by far the greatest expedition of those known to us', Herodotus qualifies the Trojan expedition and Teucer's Mysian expedition by 'according to legend' (kata ta legomend) (7.20.2). I n the case o f Egyptian history Herodotus distinguishes what he has learned from Egyptian priests from the 'infallible knowledge' that he has o f the period after the Greeks themselves settled i n Egypt (2.154.4). For Greek history, as for Persian (see 1.140.1), there is no such chronological watershed. Attempts by scholars to foist upon Herodotus a firm distinction between mythical and historical times are mistaken: it is not time alone that determines whether Herodotus thinks he has reliable knowledge of particular events. When at 4.152.3 Herodotus says that, after Sostratos son o f Laodamas the Aeginetan, Kolaios of Santos made the greatest profit from trade o f all Greeks 'of whom we know securely' the opposition is not to putative mythical traders but to traders whose fame simply had not reached Herodotus. 2
I f archaic Greek history has a shadowy and shifting beginning i n Herodotus, it has a more definite end. This end is supplied not by 2
For claims that the Trojan Wars act as a watershed, see von Leyden (1949-50), and, generally, Lateiner (1989) ch. 5.
500
ROBIN
OSBORNE
a change in epistemological status but by the organization of Herodotus' work. Herodotus' work is not a history o f Greece, it is a history o f the Persian empire and of Greek interaction with it. All that Herodotus tells us about events that happened i n the Greek world prior to 499 BC we learn i n digressions which serve variously to explain or to parallel episodes i n the history o f the Persian empire or i n the history o f Greek resistance to Persia after 499. Herodotus informs us rather more richly about events i n Sparta after the accession o f Cleomenes i n 520 BC and i n Athens after the murder of Hipparchus in 514 BC, but the year 520 marks no major change in Herodotus' method or coverage. While it is true that from the last quarter o f the sixth century onwards events fell within the living memory of Herodotus' informants (cf. Archias o f Pitana, 3.55), the distinction between this chapter and the next remains largely one o f convenience, enabling the separate treatment o f two particularly interesting sets o f stories. 3
The chronology of archaic Greek history Herodotus has little interest i n absolute dates. His dating o f H o m e r and Hesiod is as much a (tendentious) claim about their distance from their subject matter as an attempt to place them at a defined point i n the past: the statement that they lived four hundred years ago (2.53), made i n connection w i t h their creation o f a theogony for the Greeks, has to be seen i n relation to his claim that even the youngest o f the gods is reckoned i n Egypt to have originated more than 15,000 years before the present whereas the Greeks reckon the youngest o f their gods, Pan, more recent than the Trojan War, 800 years ago (2.145). 4
Herodotus is not interested i n constructing a time-line. He provides lists of the kings of Sparta (7.204 and 8.131), but few events, even in Spartan history, are keyed i n to those lists; the one action by a figure other than a king that is tied i n to the king lists is Lycurgus' reform, and that is provided with two alternative, and very
3
Cf. Vannicelli (1993) who argues that Herodotus' focus is on the three generations prior to the Persians Wars: 520 falls right in the middle of that trigenerational period. See on this question Graziosi (2002). 4
ARCHAIC
GREEK
501
HISTORY
different, correlations. Later writers are able to provide accounts of early Spartan history that are closely linked to those king lists (see especially Pausanias 3.2-3, 4.4-7). I n the case o f the M e r m n a d and Persian rulers Herodotus indicates the length of time that each ruled (1.15, 16, 25, 86; 1.130, 214, 3.66-7, 7.4, 7.7, 7.20), but he provides no such indication for the kings o f Sparta. A t 2.142 Herodotus offers a translation between generations and years (three generations to one hundred years), and as far as we know he was the earliest Greek writer to attempt this; however, i n view of the limited use Herodotus makes o f the technique elsewhere, this innovation seems better interpreted as a rough and ready method o f estimating the scale of human history i n Egypt, rather than as an indication of how to convert any generational date into a date before present. Other equivalents o f generations i n years which Herodotus gives do not conform to the same scheme (cf. 1.7 where 22 generations correspond to 505 years). For Xerxes' invasion Herodotus provides an Athenian archon date (8.51.1), but he does so for no earlier event. He neither tells the reader that Solon was an archon nor refers to Isagoras' holding the archonship i n his account o f the events between the fall o f Hippias and Cleisthenes' reforms; and he never provides any list of Athenian archons. Herodotus knows how long the Peisistratids ruled, the length of time that Peisistratus was i n exile after his second expulsion, and how long Hippias continued to rule after the murder of Hipparchus, but he tells us these figures i n separate places and makes no attempt to work out the whole chronology o f the Peisistradd tyranny. Similarly, Herodotus' figure for the length of Gypselus' rule as tyrant at Corinth is an isolated one (5.92C1). 5
6
A l l o f this suggests that Herodotus made no attempt to provide an integrated chronology of the past. I f generations or years were part o f a story told to h i m then he might repeat them, i f he thought that they made some contribution to the story, and might convert them to a passage o f years, i f argument required that to be clarified.
5
Alternatively, some have considered that Herodotus did regard three generations to a century as a basic rule, but that he failed to apply the rule universally: cf. Fowler (1996) 74-5, who thinks Herodotus was keenly interested in chronography; see also Chs. 14, pp. 328-34, and 17, this volume. For chronological issues more generally, see Mosshammer (1979). 1.62.1, 5.55, 5.65.3; contrast [Aristotle] Ath. Pol. 14-19, with Rhodes (1981) 191-2. 6
502 But
ROBIN
he is r e m a r k a b l y
OSBORNE
l o t h to give g e n e a l o g i c a l details (3.55
and
6 . 1 2 6 - 7 stand o u t ) , a n d there is n o sign t h a t he r e g a r d e d establishi n g the absolute date at w h i c h an event h a p p e n e d , o r m a k i n g possible s y n c h r o n i z a t i o n s , as any p a r t o f his task. H e r o d o t u s does r e c o r d the b a t t l e at H i m e r a h a v i n g o c c u r r e d o n the same day as the b a t de at Salamis, as s o m e t h i n g t h a t ' t h e Sicilians say' (7.166.1), b u t i n general he does n o t seem to consider the m e r e fact o f events h a v i n g o c c u r r e d at the same t i m e sufficiently i n t e r e s t i n g to m e r i t any e f f o r t to establish i t . I f Herodotus
is little i n t e r e s t e d i n dates for t h e i r o w n sake, he is
interested i n c h r o n o l o g i c a l relationships w h e n they c a n c o n t r i b u t e to e x p l a i n i n g events. O n
occasion he d r a w s a t t e n t i o n to suggestive j u x -
tapositions at the same t i m e as d e n y i n g a s i m p l e causal r e l a t i o n s h i p b e t w e e n the events j u x t a p o s e d . T h e S p a r t a n c o n f l i c t w i t h A r g o s l e a d i n g to the battle o f the C h a m p i o n s was at the same t i m e as Croesus' a p p e a l to S p a r t a f o r h e l p (1.82.1), b u t the S p a r t a n decision to act was despite r a t h e r t h a n because o f this (1.83.1). T h e
Samians p r e -
v e n t e d the C o r i n t h i a n s t a k i n g 300 C o r c y r e a n boys t o Alyattes to be castrated at the same t i m e as they stole a b o w l w h i c h the
Spartans
w e r e sending to Croesus (3.48.1) a n d a g e n e r a t i o n before the S p a r t a n e x p e d i t i o n against Samos i n w h i c h the C o r i n t h i a n s p a r t i c i p a t e d , b u t Herodotus (3.49.1). O n
denies t h a t the f o r m e r s u f f i c i e n t l y e x p l a i n s the l a t t e r o t h e r occasions H e r o d o t u s
makes n o e x p l i c i t c o m m e n t
o n the significance o f the c o i n c i d e n c e to w h i c h he d r a w s a t t e n t i o n . M i l e t u s a n d N a x o s w e r e b o t h at a peak o f p r o s p e r i t y i n 4 9 9 at the same t i m e (5.28). B u t at 6.27
he asserts as a g e n e r a l rule t h a t there
are usually w a r n i n g signs i n advance w h e n s o m e t h i n g t e r r i b l e is a b o u t to h a p p e n to a c i t y o r people b e f o r e t e l l i n g o f a series o f disasters t h a t h a p p e n e d to C h i a n s at the same t i m e (98 o r 100 boys sent as a c h o r u s to D e l p h i d y i n g f r o m p l a g u e , 119 o u t o f 120 c h i l d r e n k i l l e d w h e n the r o o f o f a school fell in) to presage the Battle o f L a d e (6.27). W h e n , i n B o o k O n e ( 5 9 - 6 8 ) , H e r o d o t u s tells o f the h i s t o r y o f S p a r t a a n d A t h e n s i n o r d e r to illustrate the p r o p o s i t i o n t h a t they w e r e the p r e - e m i n e n t cities o f Greece at the t i m e t h a t Croesus was l o o k i n g f o r allies against Persia, the events to w h i c h he refers b o t h stretch b a c k w e l l before the t i m e o f Croesus (in the case o f S p a r t a ,
where
c o n d i t i o n s h e l d to have b e e n established i n the d i s t a n t past
still
o b t a i n e d ) a n d e x t e n d l a t e r (in the case o f A t h e n s , w h e r e i t is recent events t h a t have m o s t d e t e r m i n e d the
1
fifth-century
state);
Herodotus
ARCHAIC
GREEK
503
HISTORY
picks o u t those events i n his a c c o u n t o f S p a r t a n h i s t o r y t h a t are c o n t e m p o r a r y w i t h Croesus
(1.67,1).
I n d i c a t i n g c o n t e m p o r a n e i t y is a means b y w h i c h H e r o d o t u s
intro-
duces m a t e r i a l w h i c h w o u l d n o t o t h e r w i s e appear at t h a t p o i n t i n his a c c o u n t b u t w h i c h suggests t o the r e a d e r a f r a m e w o r k o f i n t e r p r e t a t i o n . A fine e x a m p l e o f this is H e r o d o t u s ' a c c o u n t o f Polycrates in Book Three. Spartan
Herodotus
t u r n s to Polycrates i n n o t i n g t h a t the
c a m p a i g n against Samos h a p p e n e d
Cambyses' c a m p a i g n against E g y p t (3.39.1).
at the same t i m e as The
account that fol-
lows treats n o t o n l y Polycrates' relationships w i t h Amasis o f E g y p t , the Spartans a n d the C o r i n t h i a n s , a n d P e r i a n d e r o f C o r i n t h ' s relat i o n s h i p w i t h C o r c y r a (as a w a y o f e x p l a i n i n g w h y the C o r i n t h i a n s t o o k p a r t i n the S p a r t a n e x p e d i t i o n against Samos), b u t also t h a t 'first c a m p a i g n t h a t the D o r i a n Spartans m a d e against A s i a ' (3.56). A t the c o n c l u s i o n o f his a c c o u n t (3.60), h o w e v e r , H e r o d o t u s t h a t he has spent a l o n g t i m e o n the Samians
remarks
because they w e r e
responsible f o r the three greatest e n g i n e e r i n g achievements (exergasmend)—Eupalinus'
t u n n e l , the h a r b o u r m o l e a n d R h o i k o s ' t e m p l e (cf.
2 . 1 4 8 ) — t h a t is, he links his t r e a t m e n t e x p l i c i t l y to his c o n c e r n for erga. S o m e t h i n g n o t dissimilar occurs w i t h the story o f Polycrates' d e a t h a n d its consequences o n Samos. T h e
d e a t h is i n t r o d u c e d as
m o r e o r less c o n t e m p o r a r y w i t h the sickness o f Cambyses (3.120.1), b u t its place i n the scheme o f the histories is i n d i c a t e d to be t h a t 'Samos was the first c i t y , G r e e k o r b a r b a r i a n , t h a t D a r i u s c a p t u r e d ' (3.139.1), a c a p t u r e consequent u p o n the troubles i n Samos t h a t foll o w e d Polycrates' d e a t h . 3.139 does, h o w e v e r , also suggest a f u r t h e r reason w h y H e r o d o t u s
l o c a t e d Polycrates' d e a t h i n r e l a t i o n to the
d e a t h o f Cambyses: D a r i u s h a d m e t Syloson, the m a n w h o calls h i m i n t o Samos, w h e n b o t h w e r e i n E g y p t d u r i n g Cambyses' c a m p a i g n . As
many
Herodotus
o f these examples
a l r e a d y i l l u s t r a t e , one reason
why
is interested i n the o r d e r o f events is t h a t o r d e r is c r u -
c i a l to causation. I n c i d e n t s f r o m e a r l y G r e e k h i s t o r y are r e l a t e d p r i m a r i l y i n o r d e r to e x p l a i n later events:' the story o f relations between A t h e n s a n d A e g i n a is t o l d i n o r d e r to e x p l a i n h o w t h e y came to be hostile to each o t h e r at the e n d o f the sixth c e n t u r y ; b e y o n d
the
fact t h a t t h e events n a r r a t e d m u s t be before t h e n , n o o t h e r c h r o n o l o g i c a l i n d i c a t i o n s are g i v e n ( 5 . 8 2 - 8 9 . 1 ) .
' See also Ch. 11, pp. 263 6, this volume.
W e hear o f Cleisthenes
of
504
ROBIN
OSBORNE
Sicyon's tribal reforms (5.67-8) as an explanation of the tribal reforms of his grandson, Gleisthenes, at Athens. We hear o f the competition for the hand o f Agariste daughter o f Cleisthenes o f Sicyon because it illustrates the glorious past history of the Alcmaeonidae and helps prove that they could not have acted as traitors to Athens i n 490 (6.121-31). I n other cases the sequential relationship between incidents seems to be indicated because a later incident explains something about an earlier one: so the not at all helpful remark that the unsuccessful coup of Cylon at Athens was 'before the time of Peisistratus' (5.71). As that case reminds us, explanation may be a matter of perceiving a pattern o f activities which is made clearer in a later and unrelated event and not simply o f understanding the antecedents. Herodotus' indications o f sequence or contemporaneity often tease the reader by leaving it open whether it is a causal sequence or a parallel pattern that is primarily being offered.
Herodotus and the traditions of Greek history I n using earlier history to throw light on later history Herodotus was reproducing the very mechanism by which fifth-century Greeks passed on knowledge o f their past. I n many cases Herodotus says explicitly that he is passing on the stories that a certain person or people told. Herodotus is interested both in what people say about what happened i n the past and in whether what they say is true. He is willing to record alternative versions of past events, noting where different informants agree or disagree; a good example o f this is provided by Herodotus' telling both what the Spartans say ('consonant with nothing any poet says') about the origins o f their dual kingship and what the Greeks say (6.52-3). This willingness to note alternatives extends to written sources: at 6.137 he records both what the Athenians say about their relations with the Pelasgians, and what Hecataeus said, leaving their different accounts side by side with no further comment. From time to time Herodotus indicates what he himself believes or finds incredible. His grounds for rejecting claims as false are generally that the claim is simply impossible (so Scyllias ten-mile swim 8
8
On the recording of alternative sources, see Drexler (1972) 57-60, Lateiner (1989) 76-90, Shimron (1989) ch. 2, and Ch. 16, this volume.
ARCHAIC
u n d e r w a t e r (8.8)). H e
GREEK
505
HISTORY
e x p l i c i t l y d r a w s t h e reader's a t t e n t i o n to his
b e l i e f t h a t he has a d u t y to r e c o r d w h a t p e o p l e say, w h e t h e r o r n o t he h i m s e l f believes i t . F o r
H e r o d o t u s w h a t is s a i d , as w e l l as w h a t
a c t u a l l y h a p p e n s , is i m p o r t a n t . A t
3 . 9 . 2 he declares a story to be
' m o r e p l a u s i b l e ' b u t t h e n insists t h a t t h e less plausible v e r s i o n be t o l d also 'since i n d e e d i t is said' ( c o m p a r e 4 . 1 9 5 . 2 ) . T h e m o s t e x p l i c i t a p p l i c a t i o n o f this to historical events concerns the reasons w h y A r g o s d i d n o t j o i n the Greeks w h o a c t i v e l y resisted the Persians:
Herodotus
tells t w o d i f f e r e n t accounts ( w h a t the A r g i v e s say a n d ' a n o t h e r story t o l d a l l over Greece') a n d t h e n says ' I a m d u t y - b o u n d to tell w h a t is said, b u t I a m n o t at a l l b o u n d to believe i t — a n d let this sentence a p p l y to the w h o l e o f m y a c c o u n t ' (7.152.3); he t h e n gives yet a n o t h e r e x p l a n a t i o n saying 'this t o o is t o l d ' . P r o v i d e d we t h i n k t h a t we c a n trust H e r o d o t u s ' source c i t a t i o n s , 9 his willingness to reveal w h o h a d t o l d h i m w h a t is w h a t m o s t r e n ders H e r o d o t u s o f value f o r the study o f a r c h a i c G r e e k h i s t o r y a n d a l m o s t c e r t a i n l y m a r k e d h i m o u t f r o m his predecessors (as w e l l as f r o m m a n y successors). T o k n o w w h a t (some p e o p l e in) a g i v e n c o m m u n i t y said a b o u t t h e i r past is o f considerable value t o us, w h e t h e r o r n o t we t h i n k t h e i r claims reflected w h a t h a d i n d e e d h a p p e n e d . To
be t o l d t h a t already i n the
fifth
century different communities
t o l d d i f f e r e n t accounts o f the 'same' past events is a f u n d a m e n t a l r e m i n d e r o f t h e t e n d e n t i o u s n a t u r e o f t r a d i t i o n s a b o u t t h e past, a n d o f the i n a p p r o p r i a t e n e s s o f a m o d e r n scholar's r e p e a t i n g ' w h a t p e o ple say' as i f i t is a s t r a i g h t f o r w a r d a c c o u n t o f ' w h a t a c t u a l l y h a p p e n e d ' . Since H e r o d o t u s m a y excerpt p a r t i c u l a r episodes f r o m a longer a n d m o r e i n v o l v e d discourse, we c a n n o t always be sure o f the c o n text i n w h i c h a story was o r i g i n a l l y t o l d i n t h e c o m m u n i t y
from
w h o m H e r o d o t u s cites i t . Nevertheless, H e r o d o t u s ' o w n a c c o u n t c a n f r e q u e n t i y be seen to preserve the c o n t e x t o f t e l l i n g as w e l l as t h e a c c o u n t o f the p a r t i c u l a r i n c i d e n t , a n d i n d o i n g so i t enables us to see h o w a r c h a i c G r e e k h i s t o r y was b e i n g used i n t h e The
fifth
century.
m o s t f a m o u s case o f e x t e n d e d i n c o m p a t i b l e versions o f t h e
same past event comes i n t h e a c c o u n t o f t h e settlement o f C y r e n e
9
The case against Herodotus' source citations has been most vociferously stated by Fehling (1989) (and equally vociferously responded to by Pritchett (1993)). The most important general critique is provided by Fowler (1996) 80-6. None of Fehling's 'demonstrably false source-citations' (his ch. 1) concern what we would call 'archaic Greek history'.
506
ROBIN
b y the T h e r a n s .
OSBORNE
T h a t a c c o u n t is p a r t o f a l o n g story t o l d i n o r d e r
to p r o v i d e the b a c k g r o u n d f o r the Persian e x p e d i t i o n against L i b y a . T h a t story is i n t r o d u c e d b y one o f H e r o d o t u s ' c h r o n o l o g i c a l c o i n c i dences, r e c o r d e d because t h e g r o w t h o f the Persian e m p i r e is his c e n t r a l interest a n d o f f e r i n g a n e x t r e m e i l l u s t r a t i o n o f Persia's e x p a n sionist d r i v e : t h e Persian e x p e d i t i o n to L i b y a was at the same t i m e as D a r i u s '
Scythian campaign
(4.145.1). T h e
background
to t h e
L i b y a n e x p e d i t i o n starts w i t h the f o u n d a t i o n o f T h e r a , a b o u t w h i c h H e r o d o t u s c l a i m s t h a t t h e Spartans a n d the T h e r a n s t o l d the same story ( 4 . 1 5 0 . 1 ) . 1 0 H e r o d o t u s
t h e n c o n t i n u e s w i t h w h a t the
Therans
say a b o u t t h e i r i n i t i a l settlement i n L i b y a ( 4 . 1 5 0 - 3 ) a n d t h e n w i t h w h a t the G y r e n a e a n s say a b o u t those same i n i t i a l actions ( 4 . 1 5 4 - 6 ) ' f o r the C y r e n a e a n s
i n n o w a y agree w i t h the T h e r a n s as concerns
B a t t o s ' , a l t h o u g h t h e y agree o n the subsequent events. T h e differences b e t w e e n t h e t w o accounts c o n c e r n b o t h the m o t i v a t i o n a n d t h e r e s p o n s i b i l i t y for the settlement. T h e T h e r a n a c c o u n t has G r i n n o s ,
basileus o f T h e r a ,
g o i n g to D e l p h i
a b o u t some
other
m a t t e r , b e i n g t o l d to f o u n d a city i n L i b y a , a n d selecting one Battos, a Theran
o f M i n y a n descent, f o r t h e task. I t t h e n has the
Therans
i g n o r e the i n s t r u c t i o n u n t i l seven years o f d r o u g h t leave o n l y
one
tree still alive o n t h e i s l a n d a n d t h e oracle repeats its c o m m a n d . T h e T h e r a n s c o n s e q u e n t l y seek k n o w l e d g e o f L i b y a f r o m C r e t e , a n d , w i t h a C r e t a n p u r p l e - f i s h e r g u i d i n g t h e m , send o u t first a n advancep a r t y a n d t h e n t w o p e n t e k o n t e r s o f settlers, chosen f r o m each f a m i l y a n d f r o m each o f t h e villages o f T h e r a . T h i s is a story o f r e l u c t a n t T h e r a n s e t t l e m e n t , o f c a r e f u l oflficiai p l a n n i n g , a n d o f f a i r selection o f settlers. T h e
C y r e n a e a n a c c o u n t , b y c o n t r a s t , centres the w h o l e
f o u n d a t i o n o n Battos: f o r t h e m he was the g r a n d s o n o f a
Cretan
k i n g , whose m o t h e r P h r o n i m e ('wise w o m a n ' ) n a r r o w l y escaped d e a t h because o f the i n f l u e n c e o f h e r s t e p m o t h e r , was rescued b y a m e r c h a n t n a m e d T h e m i s o n ('the m a n w h o does r i g h t ' ? ) a n d b o r e Battos t o a T h e r a n n a m e d Polymnestos ('the m a n w h o woos m u c h ' ) . Battos c o n s u l t e d D e l p h i a b o u t his s t a m m e r a n d was o r d e r e d to f o u n d a c i t y i n L i b y a b u t f a i l e d to act o n this. T h e
Therans
suffer i l l f o r -
t u n e , consult D e l p h i , a n d are t o l d to f o u n d G y r e n e i n L i b y a a l o n g w i t h Battos. Battos a n d t w o p e n t e k o n t e r s set off, get to L i b y a ,
10
do
On the foundation of Thera see Malkin (1994) 89-95, 106-11. For what follows on Gyrene, compare Davies (1984), Calame (1988), (1990), Vannicelli (1993) 123-48, Osborne (1996) 8-17.
ARCHAIC
GREEK
507
HISTORY
n o t k n o w w h a t to d o , t r y to r e t u r n to T h e r a , are d r i v e n a w a y , a n d settle at Platea. I n this v e r s i o n t h e r e is n o T h e r a n p l a n n i n g ,
and
r a t h e r t h a n Battos b e i n g selected as leader f o r the
Theran expedi-
t i o n , T h e r a n s are selected as m a n p o w e r
expedition.
f o r Battos'
E v i d e n c e outside H e r o d o t u s b o t h increases the p r o b a b i l i t y t h a t he d i d indeed hear his two versions, f r o m the T h e r a n s a n d the Cyrenaeans respectively, a n d shows w h y
the t w o parties w e r e t e l l i n g d i f f e r e n t
stories. T h e use o f the f o u n d a t i o n story to the T h e r a n s is m a d e v e r y clear by the s u r v i v a l o f a f o u r t h - c e n t u r y C y r e n e a n i n s c r i p t i o n . T h i s r e c o r d s a T h e r a n embassy t o C y r e n e w h i c h c l a i m s the r i g h t
of
T h e r a n s to j o i n the c i t y o f C y r e n e o n the basis o f a n o a t h taken at the t i m e C y r e n e was f o u n d e d , a n d i t i n c l u d e s the c l a i m e d o a t h n o . 5). B y e m p h a s i z i n g
(ML
i n the w a y t h e y tell the story o f the f o u n -
d a t i o n t h a t t h e y h a d b e h a v e d responsibly, the T h e r a n s stake a c l a i m t o p r i v i l e g e d t r e a t m e n t by C y r e n e t h a t w i l l ensure t h a t C y r e n e c o n tinues to be a possible place f o r T h e r a n s to e m i g r a t e to i n t i m e o f trouble. The
uses o f the C y r e n e a n s ' v e r s i o n o f t h e i r f o u n d a t i o n c a n
also be i l l u s t r a t e d f r o m a n o t h e r
text: P i n d a r ' s
Pythian Ode 5, cele-
b r a t i n g a v i c t o r y b y Arcesilaus, k i n g o f C y r e n e , i n the c h a r i o t race at the P y t h i a n and
G a m e s o f 4 6 2 , makes
Battos' f o u n d i n g o f the c i t y
o f the r o y a l l i n e its c e n t r a l t h e m e .
As
l o n g as the
Battiads
r e m a i n e d i n p o w e r at C y r e n e a story o f the f o u n d a t i o n w h i c h m a d e the figure o f Battos c r u c i a l served to l e g i t i m a t e t h e i r r u l e . One
episode
i n the T h e r a n v e r s i o n does n o t seem t o be
ade-
q u a t e l y a c c o u n t e d f o r by this e x p l a n a t i o n . T h e T h e r a n v e r s i o n holds t h a t after the advance p a r t y h a d d i s c o v e r e d the i s l a n d o f Platea, the T h e r a n s left t h e i r C r e t a n g u i d e o n the i s l a n d w h i l e t h e y r e t u r n e d to collect the m a i n g r o u p o f settlers. T h e
themselves
guide was
about
to r u n o u t o f supplies w h e n K o l a i o s , a S a m i a n m e r c h a n t o n his w a y to E g y p t , a r r i v e d a n d p r o v i d e d h i m w i t h f o o d . O n
departing f r o m
Platea the S a m i a n was b l o w n t h r o u g h the Pillars o f Heracles (Straits o f G i b r a l t a r ) a n d e n d e d u p at Tartessos i n S p a i n , w h e r e he m a d e a p r o f i t so e n o r m o u s t h a t o n r e t u r n to Samos he d e d i c a t e d a b r o n z e k r a t e r w i t h g r i f f i n protomai at the H e r a i o n .
H e r o d o t u s states t h a t the
Samians trace t h e i r great f r i e n d s h i p w i t h the T h e r a n s a n d Cyrenaeans to this episode. T h e
f a v o u r r e l a t e d i n this story is e n t i r e l y f r o m the
Samians t o the C r e t a n
fisherman,
a n d b o t h o n g r o u n d s o f self-inter-
est a n d o n g r o u n d s o f the existence o f a p h y s i c a l m e m o r i a l to w h i c h the story c o u l d be a t t a c h e d , i t is easier to see h o w
and why
the
Samians t o l d this tale t h a n t h a t either the T h e r a n s o r the Cyrenaeans
508
ROBIN
OSBORNE
w o u l d be likely to d o so (but note Arcesilaus' r e c r u i t m e n t f r o m Samos, discussed b e l o w ) . I n the case o f t h e f o u n d a t i o n o f C y r e n e i t is clear t h a t b o t h t h e interested parties c o n t i n u e d t o t e l l t h e story o f its f o u n d a t i o n , e v e n i f t h e y t o l d i t i n t h e i r o w n w a y a n d the n a r r a t i v e was also l a t c h e d o n t o b y others f o r t h e i r o w n purposes. I n o t h e r cases
Herodotus
seems to have h e a r d o f m a j o r events o n l y because those w i t h a m a r g i n a l interest c o n t i n u e d to tell t h e tale. T w o
instances o f this c o n -
c e r n the earliest 'events' o f archaic G r e e k history: the (first) M e s s e n i a n W a r a n d the L e l a n t i n e
War.
H e r o d o t u s preserves n o a c c o u n t o f w a r against the Messenians i n his discussion o f e a r l y S p a r t a n h i s t o r y . I n t h a t discussion he refers o n l y t o the Spartans h a v i n g , b y t h e t i m e o f Croesus, f l e d f r o m g r e a t t r o u b l e s a n d t r a n s f o r m e d themselves f r o m t h e w o r s t r u l e d p e o p l e t o a p e o p l e e n j o y i n g g o o d r u l e (eunomia) (1.65.1—2). T h e o n l y m e n t i o n s o f the Messenian W a r
c o m e i n t h e a c c o u n t o f troubles i n Samos
a n d i n the speech o f Aristagoras at S p a r t a . H e r o d o t u s records t h a t the Samians a c c o u n t f o r S p a r t a n a g r e e m e n t to h e l p the S a m i a n exiles b y reference to the Spartans r e p a y i n g t h e e a r l i e r S a m i a n f a v o u r g i v i n g n a v a l h e l p against the Messenians, b u t t h a t the Spartans
of
deny
this a n d say t h a t t h e y i n t e r v e n e d i n revenge f o r t h e earlier S a m i a n snatching o f the m i x i n g b o w l t h a t was b e i n g taken to Croesus (3.47.1). H e l a t e r has A r i s t a g o r a s tell the Spartans t o suspend hostilities w i t h the Messenians, the rewards o f
Arcadians, fighting
and Argives
over scraps o f l a n d , since
Persia are so m u c h greater (5.49.8).
H e r o d o t u s r e p e a t l y cites w h a t ' t h e L a c e d a e m o n i a n s '
say, a n d t h e
absence o f a n y S p a r t a n a c c o u n t o f the M e s s e n i a n W a r s is u n l i k e l y to be a m a t t e r o f c h a n c e . T h e
e x t r a v a g a n t h i s t o r y o f those w a r s i n
Pausanias' Description of Greece comes f r o m the Messenians; t h e
fifth-
c e n t u r y Spartans are surely l i k e l y to have t o l d some story a b o u t t h e i r conqest o f M e s s e n i a
( i f o n l y to e x p l a i n allusions i n the p o e t r y
of
T y r t a e u s ) , b u t i t w i l l h a r d l y have l o o k e d like t h a t . T h e t h r u s t o f t h e Spartans' Herodotus
o w n a c c o u n t o f t h e i r m o r e d i s t a n t past as r e c o r d e d
the conquest o f A m y c l a e , Pausanias
by
focuses o n a l l i a n c e , n o t conquest: he has n o m e n t i o n o f o f Helos, or of Phigaleia, all k n o w n f r o m
( 3 . 2 . 6 - 7 , 8 . 3 9 . 3 - 5 ) , or o f the battle o f Hysiae
(Pausanias
2 . 2 4 . 7 ) , o r o f S p a r t a n struggle f o r the c o n t r o l o f t h e O l y m p i c k n o w n f r o m E p h o r n s (FGrH
70 F
games,
115).
I n the case o f the L e l a n t i n e W a r ,
t h e o n l y h i n t comes, as w i t h
the M e s s e n i a n W a r , i n a passage a t t e m p t i n g t o e x p l a i n later a c t i o n .
ARCHAIC
GREEK
509
HISTORY
E r e t r i a n assistance f o r the I o n i a n s i n t h e i r r e v o l t is said to have b e e n g i v e n ' n o t f o r t h e sake o f the A t h e n i a n s
b u t for the sake o f the
M i l e s i a n s themselves, p a y i n g b a c k a d e b t t h a t was o w e d t o t h e m , f o r the M i l e s i a n s i n earlier times j o i n e d i n w a r o n the side o f t h e Eretrians
against t h e C h a l c i d i a n s , w h e n
the Samians
h e l p e d the
G h a l c i d i a n s against the E r e t r i a n s a n d M i l e s i a n s ' ( 5 . 9 9 d ) . O n c e m o r e w e see here t h e story o f a n early c o n f l i c t b e i n g t o l d n o t b y the c e n t r a l p a r t i c i p a n t s b u t b y a n outside p a r t y k e e n to keep alive the r e c o r d o f a d e b t o f g r a t i t u d e t h a t they c o n s i d e r e d to be o w e d to themselves. Herodotus
m a y have b e e n p a r t i c u l a r l y sensitive to a n d m i n d f u l o f
such stories, f o r his w h o l e v i s i o n o f h i s t o r y is d o m i n a t e d b y the sett l i n g o f o l d debts a n d o l d s c o r e s . " Herodotus
d r e w his i n f o r m a n t s f r o m a large n u m b e r
of Greek
cities, b u t t h e r e are m a n y cities t h a t are never c i t e d as the source f o r a n y s t o r y . 1 2 T h e s e 'silent cities' i n c l u d e C h a l c i s a n d E r e t r i a ,
and
the absence o f a n a c c o u n t o f t h e L e l a n t i n e W a r m a y be a p r o d u c t o f H e r o d o t u s ' never h a v i n g been i n a p o s i t i o n to a c q u i r e a E u b o e a n v e r s i o n ; i t is to be n o t e d t h a t n e i t h e r i n t h e case o f the battle b e t w e e n the A t h e n i a n s a n d C h a l c i d i a n s i n c. 507 n o r i n t h a t o f the sack o f E r e t r i a b y the Persians i n 4 9 0 does H e r o d o t u s offer a n a c c o u n t f r o m the E u b o e a n side. W h a t e v e r
d e t e r m i n e d the l i m i t s o f
Herodotus'
o w n i n q u i r i e s — a n d the p r a c t i c a l i m p o s s i b i l i t y o f v i s i t i n g every G r e e k c i t y m i g h t be c o m b i n e d w i t h d i f f e r e n t i a l e n t h u s i a s m f o r e x p e r i e n c i n g different p o l i t i c a l r e g i m e s — w e s h o u l d n o t underestimate the extent to w h i c h the shape a n d t e n o r o f H e r o d o t u s '
a c c o u n t was affected
b y w h o s e stories he d i d a n d whose stories he d i d n o t hear.
11
Gould (1991), (1989) 42-7; see also Ch. 9, pp. 209 17, this volume. Jacoby (1913) 398-9 lists the following Greek sources of logoi (asterisks indicate that citation 15 for a single logos): 'Greeks', Peloponnesians, Lacedaemonians/ Spartiates, Argives, *Eleians, Arcadians, Corinthians, Aeginetans, Athenians, Delphians, *Thebans, *Thessalians, Dodonaeans, Macedonians, *Poteidaeans, *Abderans, *Chersonesites, *Proconnesians and Cyzicenes, Delians, *Parians, *Cretans, *Praisians, Therans, *Lesbians, *Ionians, Samians, "Milesians, *Cnidians, Cyreneans, *Sybarites, *Crotoniates, *Metapontines, *Syracusans. I n addition he cites 'locals' to the regions of Thermopylae, *the Magnesian coast and *Plataea, and Greek residents of Pontus, *Sc,ythia, and *Borysthenes. 12
510
ROBIN
OSBORNE
Herodotus' neglect of written sources H e r o d o t u s names o n l y one w r i t e r o f prose i n the course o f his histories—Hecataeus w h o figures b o t h as a w r i t e r (logopoios) (2.143, 6 . 1 3 7 , see above), a n d as a p o l i t i c a l A m o n g poets he n a m e s Alcaeus,
Sappho, Solon,
figure
i n his o w n r i g h t ( 5 . 3 6 ,
(as poets) H o m e r , O l e n , Simonides,
Hesiod,
Pindar,
125). 1 3
Archilochus,
Phrynichus
and
Aeskhylus, a n d at o t h e r times he refers to ' t h e p o e t s ' . 1 4 A r c h i l o c h u s m a y have b e e n m e n t i o n e d (some editors delete t h e reference as a m a r g i n a l gloss) as h a v i n g r e f e r r e d t o Gyges (1.12). Alcaeus r a n a w a y i n a b a t t l e b e t w e e n the M y t i l e n e a n s a n d the A t h e n i a n s at S i g e i o n , l e a v i n g his a r m s b e h i n d t o be d e d i c a t e d b y the A t h e n i a n s a n d w r i t i n g u p the i n c i d e n t i n a p o e m (6.95). S a p p h o abused h e r b r o t h e r G h a r a x u s f o r his r e l a t i o n s h i p to R h o d o p i s (2.135). S o l o n w r o t e p o e t r y i n praise o f P h i l o c y p r u s (5.113). O l e n f r o m L y c i a is the a u t h o r h y m n s sung at D e l o s
of
(4.35). S i m o n i d e s is the a u t h o r of the T h e r -
m o p y l a e e p i g r a m s (7.228), a n d p r a i s e d i n p o e t r y t h e E r e t r i a n a t h lete a n d general Eualcides
w h o was k i l l e d i n t h e b a t t l e
Persians a n d Greeks w h i c h f o l l o w e d t h e b u r n i n g o f Sardis
between (5.102.3).
P i n d a r c a l l e d nomos ' k i n g o f a l l ' (3.38). P h r y n i c h u s was f i n e d over his p l a y o n the Capture of Miletus (6.21.2), Aeschylus is c i t e d f o r a v i e w a b o u t the r e l a t i o n s h i p b e t w e e n t h e gods
(2.156).
I t is notable t h a t H e r o d o t u s makes n o use o f the p o e t r y o f T y r t a e u s a n d effectively n o n e
o f the p o e t r y o f S o l o n ,
b o t h of w h o m
were
extensively q u a r r i e d f o r h i s t o r i c a l allusions b y l a t e r w r i t e r s , a n d t h a t he fails to m a k e m o r e systematic use o f Alcaeus. I t is impossible t o be c e r t a i n w h i c h p o e t i c texts H e r o d o t u s
w o u l d have h a d to h a n d ,
b u t A r i s t o p h a n e s seems to expect f a m i l i a r i t y w i t h a w i d e range a r c h a i c poets. H e r o d o t u s
of
h i m s e l f c l e a r l y expects the reader to be
f a m i l i a r w i t h t h e n a m e s o f the poets t h a t he n a m e s , b u t m a n y
of
the m e n t i o n s seem to be casual notes, w h e t h e r his o w n o r those o f his i n f o r m a n t s , a n d at n o p o i n t does he seem to have gone searchi n g i n l i t e r a r y texts f o r h i s t o r i c a l i n f o r m a t i o n . H e r o d o t u s '
f a i l u r e is
best i n t e r p r e t e d i n the l i g h t o f his p a r a l l e l f a i l u r e t o m a k e
use
of
e p i g r a p h i c evidence.
13
For further discussion of Herodotus' use of written sources, see Lateiner (1989) ch. 4. 2.23, 3.115, 6.52; cf. 5.67. H
ARCHAIC
Herodotus
GREEK
511
HISTORY
m e n t i o n s i n s c r i p t i o n s o n some
19 occasions.
Outside
Greece Sesostris r e c o r d e d his m i l i t a r y exploits o n stelai ( 2 . 1 0 2 , 106), Croesus set u p a n i n s c r i b e d b o u n d a r y stone at C y d r a r a
103, (7.30),
N i t o c r i s ' t o m b at B a b y l o n h a d a n i n s c r i p t i o n o n the outside a n d a f u r t h e r w r i t t e n message o n t h e i n s i d e , a n d D a r i u s p u t a n i n s c r i p t i o n o n his o w n e q u e s t r i a n statue (3.88), r e c o r d e d i n G r e e k a n d A s s y r i a n the
names o f a l l the e t h n i c c o n t i n g e n t s t h a t m a d e
u p his e x p e d i -
t i o n a r y force t o S c y t h i a a n d setting these u p at the Bosporus (4.87), a n d also r e c o r d e d his a c h i e v e m e n t i n a r r i v i n g at the R i v e r T e a m s (4.91); i t is n o t clear t h a t H e r o d o t u s h a d seen a n y o f these i n s c r i p tions.
Herodotus
does, h o w e v e r ,
n o t e t h e c o n t i n u e d existence
A l y a t t e s ' t o m b , o n w h i c h letters w e r e i n s c r i b e d (1.93),
which
of
may
be a sign o f autopsy, a n d e x p l i c i t l y c l a i m s t h a t a n i n t e r p r e t e r r e a d for h i m t h e i n s c r i p t i o n o n C h e o p s ' p y r a m i d (2.125), t h o u g h he makes n o such c l a i m a b o u t the i n s c r i p t i o n o n t h e p y r a m i d o f Asychis (2.136) o r the statue o f Sethos (2.141). I n the G r e e k w o r l d he records t h a t the Samians listed the names o f the c o m m a n d e r s o f the eleven S a m i a n ships t h a t stayed to fight at L a d e a n d his m e n t i o n t h a t this i n s c r i p t i o n is i n the a g o r a suggests t h a t he m a y
have seen i t (6.14);
he
quotes the text o f M a n d r o c l e s ' d e d i c a t i o n at t h e S a m i a n H e r a i o n to celebrate his b r i d g i n g the Bosporus (4.88) a n d he records t h e i n s c r i p t i o n o f the T h e r m o p y l a e
e p i g r a m s (7.228); he quotes the e p i g r a m
o n the c h a r i o t d e d i c a t i o n celebrating the A t h e n i a n v i c t o r y over Chalcis a n d B o e o t i a a n d tells us w h e r e the d e d i c a t i o n stood (5.77); 1 5 he quotes three i n s c r i p t i o n s p u t u p at T h e r m o p y l a e
(7.228) a n d the
message
to the I o n i a n s i n s c r i b e d b y T h e m i s t o c l e s at A r t e m i s i o n (8.22),
and
he m e n t i o n s the a d d i t i o n o f t h e n a m e o f the T e n i a n s to the Serpent c o l u m n at D e l p h i (8.82). H e
also c l a i m s t o have seen, i n the t e m -
ple o f I s m e n i a n A p o l l o at T h e b e s , i n s c r i p t i o n s i n C a d m e i a n letters d a t i n g to the t i m e o f O e d i p u s a n d the f o l l o w i n g g e n e r a t i o n s , w h i c h he quotes ( 5 . 5 9 - 6 1 ) ,
a n d to k n o w the n a m e o f t h e D e l p h i a n
a d d e d a n i n s c r i p t i o n to a d e d i c a t i o n m a d e b y Croesus t h a t d e d i c a t i o n was m a d e b y t h e Spartans In
15
to say t h a t
(1.51).
every case the i n s c r i b e d o b j e c t acts to c o n f i r m the
Herodotus
who
account
has g i v e n . I n m a n y cases t h e i n s c r i p t i o n was p a r t o f a
Some have found Herodotus' description of the site of the chariot inconsistent with the other evidence for its location (West (1985) 284—5), but i f 'entering the Propylaea' is understood to mean 'passing through the Propylaea' his description is entirely accurate.
512
ROBIN
OSBORNE
story, i n others i t seems likely t h a t the teller o f a story p o i n t e d t o a n i n s c r i p t i o n to l e n d p l a u s i b i l i t y to the claims t h a t w e r e b e i n g m a d e , o r , i n the case o f the f o r g e d i n s c r i p t i o n , to d e m o l i s h evidence c o n t r a d i c t e d the c l a i m t h a t was b e i n g m a d e . M o d e r n
that
scholars rea-
s o n a b l y o b j e c t t h a t close s c r u t i n y o f the stories or o f the i n s c r i p t i o n s w o u l d i n m a n y cases have given H e r o d o t u s s t r o n g grounds f o r d o u b t i n g the t r u t h o f w h a t was c l a i m e d . 1 ( 1 T h e
relatively uncritical con-
f i r m a t o r y use o f i n s c r i p t i o n s is exactly p a r a l l e l t o the w a y i n w h i c h H e r o d o t u s uses u n i n s c r i b e d objects (the b r o n z e o f a m a n o n a d o l p h i n t o c o n f i r m the
story o f A r i o n (1.24); the
fetters in t h e t e m p l e
o f A t h e n a A l e a at T e g e a to c o n f i r m the story o f the battle (1.66); the d e d i c a t i o n o f the k r a t e r t h a t c o n f i r m s the story o f K o l a i o s
the
S a m i a n (4.152); t h e r e are m a n y m o r e examples). J u s t as i n all these cases the u n i n s c r i b e d o b j e c t falls s h o r t o f p r o v i n g H e r o d o t u s ' c o r r e c t , so t o o w i t h i n s c r i b e d objects, it is sufficient for t h a t t h e y have b e e n c i t e d to p r o v e whether
Herodotus
a case, he does n o t
o r n o t the p r o o f is g o o d . N o r
story
does H e r o d o t u s
consider scrutinize
i n s c r i p t i o n s i n o r d e r to deduce f r o m t h e m the events o f the past: i f t h e r e is n o story a t t a c h e d b y his i n f o r m a n t s to a n i n s c r i b e d o b j e c t there is n o sign t h a t H e r o d o t u s w i l l be
interested i n i t .
Plutarch
17
(On the Malice of Herodotus 870c) o b j e c t e d to H e r o d o t u s '
f a i l u r e to
m a k e f u l l use o f the i n s c r i p t i o n o n the S e r p e n t C o l u m n o v e r such m a t t e r s as the c o n t r i b u t i o n o f the C o r i n t h i a n s to the v i c t o r y .
How-
ever, H e r o d o t u s ' c o r r o b o r a t i v e use o f t e x t u a l evidence, using t h a t e v i dence w h e n evidence and
i t fits a l i n e o f a r g u m e n t
evidence in the H i p p o c r a t i c w r i t i n g s . To
but not starting f r o m
the
asking w h a t i t m e a n s , is closely p a r a l l e l to the use
understand
Herodotus'
of
18
neglect of p o t e n t i a l p o e t i c a n d
epi-
g r a p h i c evidence w e n e e d also to u n d e r s t a n d t w o f u r t h e r features o f his w o r k . T h e
first
past is used in the
is t h a t he is p r i m a r i l y interested i n the w a y present. P a r a d o x i c a l l y ,
i n v i e w of the
the
concern
expressed i n his preface to p r e v e n t great a n d r e m a r k a b l e t h i n g s f a d i n g , he shows n o interest i n d i s c o v e r i n g a b o u t the past as such. e x p l a n a t i o n f o r this p a r a d o x
lies i n the e x p l a n a t o r y
power
The
o f the
past. H e r o d o t u s wishes the story o f G r e e k relations w i t h Persia to
16
So, especially, West (1985). Marincola (1997a) 103-4. Compare G. E. R. Lloyd (1979) 168-9, (1987) 118-19, 123, 263-4, and, more generally on Herodotus and the Hippocratics, Thomas (2000). 17
18
ARCHAIC
GREEK
HISTORY
513
be understood because it will explain the situation i n which his contemporaries find themselves; events from the archaic period that have been forgotten do not offer the same explanatory power with regard to the fifth-century situation. Indeed, one might argue that to resurrect forgotten events might actually mislead, i f it led to events of which an actor was ignorant being used to explain the actor's actions. The second feature that is closely related to Herodotus' neglect of poetic and epigraphic writing as a source is his limiting arguments to a single stage. Objects which themselves directly witness to the truth o f a tale are one thing, texts which imply something about a past situation that then has further implications are another. Herodotus himself notes from time to time that the stories people tell raise issues which they do not themselves answer (e.g., 1.49, 7.60): even when there is scope for using written sources to fill the gaps in oral sources or settle a debate, there is no sign that Herodotus made any attempt to do so (no sign, for instance, that he trawled through Alcaesus' poetry to see i f it shed light on whether Bias or Pittacus was the man who answered Croesus' request for news from Greece (1.27)). There is no Herodotean parallel to the epigraphic detective work o f Thucydides on the Peisistratids (6.54-5).
Herodotus and the study of archaic Greek history Herodotus is an invaluable source for, but no sort o f guide to, archaic Greek history. The individual stories that he tells offer vivid illumination o f the nature o f archaic Greek life, but even for Athens it is clear that Sir John Myres' claim that 'Herodotus knows all the principal crises i n the long early history' is wishful thinking ((1953) 177). Herodotus tells us a minimal story about Cylon, never mentions Dracon, and although knowing that Solon was a lawgiver (1.29, 2.177) gives us no insight either into Solon's laws or into any crisis that led to his appointment. His account o f Peisistratus and his sons is very strongly weighted towards Peisistratus the deceiver and to the end o f the tyranny, and his analysis o f the factors that led to Peisistratus' success and his sons' failure is i n narrowly personal terms. 19
19
Compare above all the account of the marriage of Agariste, 6.126-30; see Murray (1993) 212-14.
514
ROBIN
OSBORNE
D e s p i t e his interest i n the effects o f d e m o c r a c y o n A t h e n s ' s t r e n g t h , H e r o d o t u s displays n o interest i n the e a r l i e r c o n s t i t u t i o n a l a r r a n g e m e n t s at A t h e n s . Herodotus'
a c c o u n t surely reflects the A t h e n i a n s '
o w n attitudes i n
the m i d d l e o f the f i f t h c e n t u r y . A l l the signs are t h a t there was l i t tle interest i n Solon's c o n s t i t u t i o n a l a r r a n g e m e n t s u n t i l dissatisfaction w i t h r a d i c a l d e m o c r a c y i n the last q u a r t e r o f the c e n t u r y l e d to a n attempt to promote
the ancestral c o n s t i t u t i o n as a n a l t e r n a t i v e , at
w h i c h p o i n t w h a t S o l o n d i d , o r w h a t he c o u l d be h e l d to have d o n e , b e c a m e i m p o r t a n t (cf. H a n s e n (1990)). S o m e d o c u m e n t a r y seems t o have b e e n c a r r i e d o u t i n the late
fifth
research
c e n t u r y a n d i t is
likely that this, a n d the related r e - i n s c r i p t i o n o f the l a w code, increased the consciousness t h a t c e r t a i n laws w e r e S o l o n i a n , w h i c h is first visible i n A r i s t o p h a n e s
Birds 1660. H e r o d o t u s '
A t h e n s was the A t h e n s
o f Pericles' F u n e r a l Speech, p r o u d o f its present c o n d i t i o n a n d n o t m u c h c o n c e r n e d w i t h the details o f its past c o n d i t i o n . I n as far as early A t h e n i a n
h i s t o r y was a l t e r e d after
Herodotus,
it was b y d o c u m e n t a r y research. S o m e o f this research was o n m a t e r i a l d a t i n g b a c k to the archaic p e r i o d , b u t m u c h o f i t i n v o l v e d u n c o v e r i n g claims about early history m a d e i n the context o f late or fourth-century argument.20 The
fifth-century
a c c o u n t t h a t [ A r i s t o t l e ] gives i n
the Athenaion Politeia reflects the activities o f earlier
Atthidographers
(see R h o d e s (1981) 2 0 - 3 0 ) . Solon's p o e t r y was searched f o r h i s t o r i cal allusions (Ath. Pol. 12), a n d his laws f o r patterns to his l e g i s l a t i o n (Ath. Pol. 9); i n s c r i p t i o n s y i e l d e d evidence f o r S o l o n i a n census classes (Ath. Pol. 7.4) a n d p e r h a p s a n a n n o t a t e d a r c h o n list ( b e h i n d e . g . ,
Ath.
Pol. 13.1-2?). B u t the A r i s t o t e l i a n Athenaion Politeia also derives i t e m s m o r e o r less d i r e c t l y f r o m H e r o d o t u s ,
adding only an interpretation,
shaped b y f o u r t h - c e n t u r y ideas, o f h o w politics w o r k e d , a n d
where
this is the case m o d e r n scholars' preference f o r the A r i s t o t e l i a n v e r sion
seems
perverse.21
Atthidographers
were
Although
t h e i r studies m e a n t
technically better equipped
t h e i r h i s t o r i c a l u n d e r s t a n d i n g was
than
that
the
Herodotus,
n o t necessarily s u p e r i o r ,
partly
because m a n y o f the sorts o f a d d i t i o n a l i n f o r m a t i o n available to t h e m d i d n o t c o n t r i b u t e d i r e c t i y to a n u n d e r s t a n d i n g o f w h y events pened. T h e
20
hap-
h i s t o r y o f Pisistratus a n d his sons is a g o o d i n d i c a t i o n
So e.g., the 'Constitution of Dracon' in Athenaion Politeia 4; see Rhodes (1981) 84-8. For a recent example, see Gouschin (1999). 21
ARCHAIC
GREEK
HISTORY
515
of this: Athenaion Politeia adds a number o f anecdotes about the character o f Pisistratus (ch. 16) and a divergent version of his family line (ch. 17), but the account continues to revolve around the inception and destruction o f the tyranny and the 'factual' basis for historical judgment available to the author is much the same as was available to Herodotus. I n the case o f Sparta, Herodotus does show constitutional interest, but this is largely because the Spartans claimed that the fifthcentury constitutional arrangements, to which Herodotus uniquely devotes considerable space (6.56—60), had been long established. He knows also about Lycurgus' reforms, about the long struggle with Tegea and about the crisis over K i n g Anaxandridas' failure to produce the requisite son and heir (5.39). T h e ephor Chilon makes an appearance giving advice to Peisistratus' father at Olympia (1.59) and observing the problematic position o f Cythera (7.235) but plays no role in formulating Spartan policy. Herodotus' knowledge can be explained in terms of Spartan fifth-century interests: they have an interest in claiming their constitution to have been long unchanged, and hence tell about Lycurgus; they have an interest i n maintaining that they had renounced subjugation o f the rest of the Peloponnese and that they shared interests with the other Peloponnesian states, and hence they told the story o f the struggle with Tegea i n which the Battle o f the Fetters was succeeded by the Bones o f Orestes. Other incidents they tell o f in as far as they act as good exempla: hence the story of the 'Battle o f the Champions' (1.82). The density of Spartan history gets much greater with the accession o f Cleomenes: his reign lay within living memory, the events o f the reign were still having repercussions in the period o f the Persian Wars themselves, and his story offered an autocratic template which helped to explain others' behaviour and its consequences. 22
23
24
Subsequent writers were not able m u c h to enrich Herodotus' account o f archaic Spartan history. The explosion o f material on Lycurgus that enabled Plutarch to write a Life included but little genuine archaic material (although it did invaluably include the Great
22
See, briefly, Osborne (1996) 283-5. For which see Vannicelli (1993) 21-98. As an interpretation of sixth-century events, this classic modern interpretation is righdy criticized by Boedeker (1993), but as an interpretation of Spartan telling of the stories it retains its power. 23
24
516
ROBIN
OSBORNE
Rhetra, which item, at least, was the fruit o f fourth-century Aristotelian research). Pausanias was able to include massive accounts o f the Messenian Wars, but these are almost certainly fictions created in the newly independent Messenian state (Starr (1965)). He also has stories related to the formation o f the Peloponnesian League which may be genuine long-lived oral traditions preserved in cities which Herodotus never visited (e.g., the story o f the bones o f Teisamenus, Pausanias 7.1.7-8). The best example o f a continuous city history in Herodotus is i n fact Cyrene. Cyrene owes its special treatment to the fact that it had a history of contact with Persia quite separate from that o f mainland Greece and Ionia, and the explanation o f that separate history demanded that events there be traced i n some detail. Thus we learn not only of its foundation (see above), but o f subsequent discord leading to the appointment o f Demonax o f Mantineia as lawgiver, and of Arcesilaus, Pheretime, and the events leading up to the Persian expedition to Libya. The richness o f the tradition here, in which the partial suppression o f the 'democratic' reforms recommended by Demonax leads to a period o f intense civil strife and to Persian intervention, may result from there being an ongoing struggle in Cyrene up until the time o f the final overthrow o f the Battiads, and to the availability to Herodotus o f a 'popular' tradition. Subsequent writing on Cyrene adds very litde to Herodotus' account. 23
I n the case o f Corinth we learn about how Cypselus got power, how his son Periander behaved when i n power, and i n particular the relations between Periander and his own son (5.92; 3.48-53). Both these stories are told to explain incidents i n other stories: we learn about Cypselus and Periander from the speech of Socles to the Peloponnesians as he dissuades them from restoring Hippias to power i n Athens; we learn about Periander and his son as a way of explaining why the Corinthians took part in the Spartan expedition against Samos. Herodotus has little interest i n Corinth herself, but these incidents both promote understanding o f histories which he does think are important, and offer portraits o f tyrannical power that help to form his particular presentation o f autocracy. ' 25
2
2 5
On Cyrene, see Chamoux, (1953), Vannicelli (1993) 123-48. Both these stories have been much discussed. For recent discussions, see McGlew (1993) 61-72, Sourvinou-Inwood (1991) 244-84. Herodotus' attitudes to tyranny and autocracy have been much discussed; see Dewald (2002), Lateiner (1989) 169-75, Ferrill (1978), Waters (1971). 26
2 /
:
ARCHAIC
GREEK
HISTORY
517
Although Herodotus justifies his account o f Samos i n part by reference to her engineering achievements (see above), the opportunity to show autocracy i n action (and the difficulties arising on liberation from autocracy) is important here too. Herodotus tells us about Polycrates' relationships with Amasis o f Egypt and Oroetes the hyparkhos of Sardis, about the Spartan expedition against h i m , and about what happened i n Samos at his death. H e also, however, tells us about the Samian Kolaios' role i n the foundation o f Cyrene and about Arcesilaus o f Gyrene using Samos as a base from which to recruit an army with which to effect his own restoration (4.152, 163-4). Both these incidents are presented seamlessly within the Gyrenean account o f their own history, but Samians are likely to have been even keener than Cyreneans to keep these stories alive i n the interests o f maintaining and reinforcing a claim to good relations between the cities. For no other city does Herodotus show any knowledge of events before 520 except for particular incidents—Cleisthenes o f Sicyon's tribal reforms and daughter's marriage (5.67-8; 6.126-30), Pheidon of Argos' reform of measures and highly hybristic actions (not specified) (6.127.3), the beginnings o f the struggle between Aegina and Athens (5.82-9). T h e Cleisthenes stories are both embedded i n episodes o f Athenian history, and there is no sign o f a Sicyonian source; the Aeginetan story also involves Athens but here Herodotus does claim to know the Aeginetan version. Later historians will know more about Sicyon, and a little more about Pheidon, but were not able to supplement Herodotus' version o f Aeginetan history. Herodotus tells us about those events in archaic Greek history where his interests and the interests o f his informants can be made to intersect. Herodotus will have experienced what regularly frustrates ancient historians today, that the sources o f information available are not interested in answering the questions the historian wants to ask. There is no doubt that he has selected from amongst the stories he was told and so has shaped the way i n which we see archaic Greek history, as well as what we see; but it is also the case that the stories o f archaic Greece played a part i n shaping Herodotus' view o f the world. 28
so this volume. F
o
r
m
o
r
e
o
n
p i 0
y c r a t e s >
s e e
Osborne (1996) 272-80 and Ch. 23, pp. 524-8,
518
ROBIN
OSBORNE
What did the history of archaic Greece contribute to Herodotus? H e r o d o t u s p l u n g e d i n t o the G r e e k past i n o r d e r t o e x p l a i n h o w the clash w i t h Persia h a p p e n e d a n d w h y it t u r n e d o u t as i t d i d . G i v e n the o p i n i o n t h a t he h a d f o r m e d as t o t h e i m p o r t a n c e of t h e p o l i t i cal c o n s t i t u t i o n ( l a w , f r e e d o m , t h e role o f t h e p e o p l e , cf. 5.78, 7.102, 104) i n m a i n l a n d G r e e k resistance to a n d v i c t o r y o v e r Persia, i t is n o t s u r p r i s i n g t h a t issues o f p o l i t i c a l p o w e r
figure
l a r g e l y i n his
a c c o u n t . N o r is i t s u r p r i s i n g , i n v i e w o f t h e f a i l u r e of t h e I o n i a n r e v o l t a n d o f t h e i r subsequent histories, t h a t a s i m i l a r sequence
of
events o n Samos a n d at A t h e n s ( r e m o v a l o f t y r a n t b y e x t e r n a l a c t i o n , r i v a l r y a m o n g s t t h e p o l i t i c a l elite as t o w h a t s h o u l d h a p p e n
next,
b i d b y o n e p a r t y t o o p e n u p p o l i t i c a l p o w e r t o t h e people) s h o u l d be p o r t r a y e d i n v e r y d i f f e r e n t ways. A r c h a i c
Greek history offered
H e r o d o t u s a n u m b e r o f d i f f e r e n t t e m p l a t e s , a n d i n d i f f e r e n t contexts he o f f e r e d u p d i f f e r e n t templates t o t h e reader's a t t e n t i o n . I t is i m p o r t a n t t h a t a r c h a i c G r e e k h i s t o r y o f f e r e d a d y n a m i c , n o t a static, t e m p l a t e f o r H e r o d o t u s t o use. People t o l d stories a b o u t t h e past t o e x p l a i n w h e r e they h a d c o m e f r o m a n d h o w they h a d a r r i v e d w h e r e t h e y w e r e . T h o s e stories e x p l a i n e d c h a n g e , t h e y d i d n o t s i m p l y r e c o u n t t h e c u r r e n t s i t u a t i o n . So t o o , H e r o d o t u s
is i n g e n e r a l
n o t keen t o describe t h e c o n t e m p o r a r y w o r k i n g s o f a G r e e k c i t y : he tells us t h e bare m i n i m u m w e n e e d t o k n o w i n o r d e r to a p p r e c i a t e t h a t Cleisthenes at A t h e n s c h a n g e d the established o r d e r t o p u t m o r e p o w e r i n t h e h a n d s o f t h e p e o p l e , b u t he does n o t e x p l a i n h o w t h e new order w o r k e d . Even the implications o f the reforms f o r a r m y o r g a n i z a t i o n are left t o be teased o u t f r o m t h e discussion o f m i l i t a r y a u t h o r i t y at M a r a t h o n
(6.109-10).
A r c h a i c G r e e k h i s t o r y o f f e r e d t o H e r o d o t u s stories o f b o t h t h e rise a n d the fall o f a u t o c r a t s , b u t i t o f f e r e d o n l y t h e story o f t h e rise o f good government. arrangements,
Autocrats
replaced a variety o f constitutional
b u t t h e stories t h a t H e r o d o t u s
retells s h o w e d
interest i n t h e i r v i r t u e s o r vices, m e r e l y casting a m o m e n t a r y
little glance
at t h e i r weakness—the i n b r e d Bacchiads (5.92(3-7) o r t h e f a c t i o n - r i v e n Athenians
(1.59). T h e stories w e r e i n t e r e s t e d i n h o w autocrats g o t
p o w e r , a n d H e r o d o t u s reflects this, even t h o u g h t h e g a i n i n g o f a u t o cratic p o w e r h a d l i t t l e role i n his story ( H e r o d o t u s ' n a r r a t i v e repeate d l y stresses t h e r o l e o f a u t o c r a t i c deceit:
1.59-64, 5.67-8,
5.92;
c o m p a r e 3.84-7). T h o s e stories w e r e i m p o r t a n t f o r H e r o d o t u s l a r g e l y as t h e b a c k g r o u n d t o t h e p r o b l e m s faced b y a u t o c r a t i c rulers a n d
P
ARCHAIC
GREEK
519
HISTORY
t o t h e i r d o w n f a l l . T h e m o s t i m p o r t a n t f a c t a b o u t autocrats was t h a t t h e y w e r e n o n e o f t h e m g o o d : even P h e i d o n , i n his c a m e o
appear-
ance, is i n t r o d u c e d as h y b r i s t i c . B y c o n t r a s t the m o s t i m p o r t a n t fact a b o u t the w e l l - o r d e r e d c i t y was its e n d u r a n c e . T h e
S p a r t a n interest
i n l a y i n g c l a i m to a c o n s t i t u t i o n u n c h a n g e d since i t was set u p
by
L y c u r g u s m a t c h e d his o w n j u d g m e n t o f t h e positive p o w e r s o f g o o d r u l e , a n d i t is n o t s u r p r i s i n g t h a t the a l t e r n a t i v e v e r s i o n , i n w h i c h the e p h o r a t e was a later m o d i f i c a t i o n (Aristotle Politics 1313a), i f i t existed before the late fifth c e n t u r y , does n o t get r e c o r d e d b y h i m . The
'ethnographic'
t r e a t m e n t o f S p a r t a (6.56-60), u n i q u e
among
G r e e k states, is perhaps best e x p l a i n e d b y the n e e d H e r o d o t u s
felt
to d e m o n s t r a t e t h a t S p a r t a n k i n g s h i p was n o t a m a t t e r o f a u t o c r a c y . The
c o n t i n u a t i o n o f f a c t i o n a l disputes i n A t h e n s after the i n t r o d u c -
tion
o f d e m o c r a c y gets n o coverage: o s t r a c i s m o n l y gets m e n t i o n e d
(and then not explained) w h e n
A r i s t e i d e s offers g o o d
advice
to
T h e m i s t o c l e s despite t h e i r e n m i t y (8.79). B u t the i g n o r i n g o f d e m o cratic r e f o r m s at C y r e n e t h a t b r i n g s o n l y disaster is r e c o u n t e d at length. T h e a b i l i t y o f the Greeks to resist the Persians w h e n they clashed w i t h t h e m i n the early fifth c e n t u r y B G
was a p r o d u c t o f t h e i r past
h i s t o r y . H a d H e r o d o t u s n o t established w h a t i t is to w r i t e a b o u t the Persian W a r s ,
any h i s t o r i a n t o d a y t r y i n g to a c c o u n t f o r w h a t
p e n e d w o u l d w a n t to take close account o f G r e e k m e t h o d s o f
hap-
fighting,
the e c o n o m i c base o f the G r e e k c i t y , the G r e e k sense o f i d e n t i t y , G r e e k attitudes to c o - o p e r a t i o n a n d a u t h o r i t y , G r e e k modes o f m a k i n g decisions— tin other w o r d s , o u r o w n versions o f m a n y o f H e r o d o t u s ' questions. D o i n g t h a t w o u l d i n v o l v e d e l v i n g b a c k i n t o the h i s t o r i c a l events o f t h e s i x t h c e n t u r y , as H e r o d o t u s not re-write Herodotus'
delves b a c k , b u t i t w o u l d
Histories. J u s t as o u r questions w o u l d
i n f l u e n c e d b y the p a t t e r n s o f histories a c c o u n t i n g for the course o t h e r w a r s i n h i s t o r y , so H e r o d o t u s '
be of
a c c o u n t was i n f l u e n c e d b y the
shape o f the stories he was t o l d . H e r o d o t u s ' a c c o u n t o f archaic G r e e k h i s t o r y necessarily itself r e f l e c t e d the shape i m p o s e d b y his i n f o r m a n t s u p o n the stories h a n d e d d o w n to t h e m . T h i s shape was n o t fixed,
f o r i t was seen t h r o u g h the c h a n g i n g lens o f present develop-
m e n t s , b o t h p o l i t i c a l a n d i n t e l l e c t u a l . 2 9 T h a t lens, t h r o u g h w h i c h the
Compare again the use of current Spartan execution practices as criteria of past behaviour at 4.146.
520
ROBIN
OSBORNE
course o f t h e Persian W a r s themselves w e r e p r e s e n t e d , b e c a m e t h e shape o f h i s t o r y . W h a t e v e r the talk was i n the days a n d m o n t h s after the battles, w h e n m i l i t a r y m a n o e u v r e s a n d i n d i v i d u a l acts o f m a r t i a l skill a n d b r a v e r y m a y w e l l have p l a y e d a large p a r t , b y t h e t i m e H e r o d o t u s c a m e to q u e s t i o n Greeks a b o u t t h e i r past the politics o f G r e e k success i n t h e Persian W a r s h a d b e c o m e t h e most p r o m i n e n t aspect o f t h e d i s c u s s i o n . P o l i t i c a l events d o m i n a t e d f i f t h - c e n t u r y accounts o f earlier history a n d were h e l d to have m a d e most difference to the p r o s p e r i t y o f a G r e e k city because i t was politics w h i c h those w h o t o l d stories o f the past c o u l d hope direcdy to influence. H e r o d o t u s ' last w o r d is t h a t even w h e n i t comes t o m a t t e r s o f conquest a n d the effects o f c o n q u e s t , the decision t h a t d e t e r m i n e s e c o n o m i c c o n d i t i o n s is a p o l i t i c a l decision (9.122). 3 0
30
I am grateful to Sara Forsdyke, Hans van Wees, and, in particular, Christopher Pelling for stimulating comments on an earlier draft of this chapter.
CHAPTER T W E N T Y - T H R E E GREEK H I S T O R Y
c. 525-480 BC
Sara Forsdyke
Introduction H e r o d o t u s defines t h e subject o f his h i s t o r y as ' t h e affairs o f m e n ' , 'great a n d w o n d r o u s Yet
deeds',
a n d ' t h e cause o f the w a r ' (Preface).
t h e events t h a t he narrates u n d e r these r u b r i c s are o f t e n q u i t e
d i f f e r e n t f r o m w h a t m o d e r n historians w o u l d w r i t e a b o u t . F o r this reason,
historians have o f t e n c h i d e d H e r o d o t u s f o r n o t r e c o r d i n g
w h a t they t h i n k is i m p o r t a n t . R e c e n t l y , h o w e v e r , scholars have a p proached H e r o d o t u s m o r e productively b y focussing o n w h a t H e r o d o t u s does say a n d w h a t this indicates a b o u t t h e n a t u r e o f his sources a n d his m e t h o d s o f c o m p o s i t i o n . I t is o n l y b y g a i n i n g greater i n s i g h t i n t o these features o f H e r o d o t e a n h i s t o r i o g r a p h y t h a t m o d e r n
historians
m a y better u n d e r s t a n d w h a t his accounts c a n tell us a b o u t
archaic
a n d classical G r e e k h i s t o r y . The
r e c o g n i t i o n t h a t H e r o d o t u s g a t h e r e d his m a t e r i a l f r o m o r a l
t r a d i t i o n s is f u n d a m e n t a l tory.1 Although
t o e v a l u a t i n g his accounts o f G r e e k his-
some d o c u m e n t a r y
a n d l i t e r a r y sources w e r e a v a i l -
able, i t is generally agreed t h a t h e r e l i e d p r i m a r i l y o n i n f o r m a n t s who
reported the oral traditions o f communities
( e . g . , poleis) a n d
groups w i t h i n c o m m u n i t i e s (e.g., families) as w e l l as p a n h e l l e n i c t r a ditions. T h e latter w o u l d have been t r a n s m i t t e d a t m e e t i n g places such as o r a c u l a r shrines, a t games, a n d b y t r a v e l l i n g poets a n d ' l o g o g r a phers'
such as H e r o d o t u s .
Recently a more
sophisticated
under-
s t a n d i n g o f the n a t u r e o f o r a l t r a d i t i o n s a n d t h e factors w h i c h affect t h e i r h i s t o r i c a l r e l i a b i l i t y has l e d t o s i g n i f i c a n t advances i n o u r u n d e r s t a n d i n g o f w h a t H e r o d o t u s c a n tell us a b o u t G r e e k h i s t o r y . 2 W h i l e a basic d i s t i n c t i o n b e t w e e n d i f f e r e n t types o f t r a d i t i o n is essential t o d e t e r m i n i n g t h e influences o n t h e shape o f t r a d i t i o n s a b o u t t h e past,
' Argued by Jacoby (1913) 413 ff. and (1949). See Thomas (1989); Murray (1987); Evans (1991); Raaflaub (1988a).
2
522
SARA
FORSDYKE
nevertheless, it has also been recognized that these traditions cannot be wholly separated since they tend to influence one another. Thus, while polis traditions can often be detected as underlying some o f Herodotus' narratives, i n some cases their form i n Herodotus' Histories reveals that they have been adapted to suit the needs of a Panhellenic audience. Panhellenic traditions, likewise, can be adopted into polis traditions and adapted to fit local needs. W i t h i n the category o f polis tradition, moreover, we may distinguish popular polis traditions, which tend to emphasize the moral and religious aspects o f the past, from official polis traditions, which emphasize the justice and injustice of different political actors i n the past. Yet moralizing or religious themes are often present i n official polis traditions, while popular traditions may be focussed on political actors. The recognition of the variety of types o f traditions and the ways that they relate and adapt to each other and to changing historical circumstances, nevertheless, has been one significant advance in Herodotean scholarship. Focus has also shifted from the simple recognition o f bias to an interest i n what the oral traditions i n Herodotus' narratives can tell us about fifth-century Greek values, ideologies, and self-perception. Historians have often castigated Herodotus for focussing on the motives and actions of individuals rather than the larger social, political, and economic forces that modern historians tend to cite as explanations for historical change. Yet the study o f oral traditions has allowed scholars to recognize that this is a narrative technique which is a feature o f the oral traditions and oral society in which he was writing. Moreover, although the focus on individual motivations and acts (particularly the ideas o f reciprocity and retribution) provides a convenient narrative device for Herodotus and the traditions on which he relies, Herodotus reveals on many occasions that 3
4
0
6
3
Raaflaub (1988a) 218; Thomas (1989) 238-51; Lavelie (1993) 94. In Forsdyke (2001) and below, pp. 545-6, for example, I argue that the Demaratus-logos in 7.101-4, may have begun as a Spartan tradition extolling the Spartan military ethic, but has adopted elements of Athenian anti-tyrannical tradition, and finally, has been adapted to fit a panhellenic perspective by which general Greek values are contrasted to non-Greek, specifically Persian values. For example, as I argue in Forsdyke (1999) and below, pp. 544-5, panhellenic traditions about the Cypselid tyranny were adapted to fit the needs of the Athenian democracy. See for example Hartog (1980), Euben (1986), Raaflaub (1987), Georges (1994) 115-66, Cartledge (1995). 4
;>
6
GREEK
HISTORY
c.
525-480
523
BC
he is aware of larger historical forces.' Thus i n discussing Herodotus' understanding of Greek history i n these years, it is important to be sensitive to how his narratives reveal an awareness o f the deeper historical forces as well as the immediate causes which ostensibly motivate his narratives. As important as the role of oral tradition i n shaping his accounts is Herodotus' own 'literary personality', by which I mean the role of his own aesthetic, moral, and conceptual framework. I t is clear, for instance, that Herodotus' conception of the inevitable rise and fall o f individuals and communities shapes his presentation o f events. Yet it is often difficult to separate the formative role o f Herodotus' own conceptual framework from that o f his oral sources. Oswyn M u r r a y has argued that the moral patterning o f rise to greatness, hubris and ultimate downfall was central to East Greek oral traditions yet also was characteristic o f Herodotus' historical framework precisely because he was a product o f these traditions. A second example o f this overlap is the importance o f political freedom i n Greek polls traditions and i n Herodotus' own value system. The exact mixture o f Herodotus' own conceptual framework and that o f the traditions from which he drew is a matter of debate between historians and literary critics, and is one o f the most fertile areas for future research. I shall follow the narrative sequence o f Herodotus i n my analysis of Herodotus' treatment of Greek history i n the period 525-480 B C . This modus operandi leads to a somewhat disjointed presentation o f 8
9
111
' On the narrative pattern of act and counteract cf. Lang (1984) 12, 79 and Gould (1989) 63-85. Gould, however, disputes the idea that this pattern is merely a narrative device and argues that it has a more fundamental role in Herodotus' understanding of why things happen. I would argue that the pattern can be both a narrative device characteristic of oral traditions and reflective of these traditions' historical understanding. I owe the phrase 'literary personality' to Murray (1987) 97. Murray (1987) 105-7 (and see also Ch. 13, pp. 296 8, this volume). Although Murray also notes the importance of this moral patterning in traditions of the shrine at Delphi, he argues that East Greek traditions differ from Greek mainland traditions in that they are shaped by moral not political aims. 1 am not so sure that moral patterning is absent from mainland traditions or political aims from Delphic and Eastern traditions. Nevertheless, the recognition that some of the traditions which Herodotus uses have a moral function and others a political function, regardless of geography, is valid and extremely important in determining the kinds of distortion that Herodotus' historical accounts have undergone. The essays in Boedeker (1987) are particularly good in showing Herodotus' role in shaping his material. See also Immerwahr (1966) and Lateiner (1989). 8
9
10
524
SARA
FORSDYKE
G r e e k h i s t o r y since H e r o d o t u s ' m e t h o d o f n a r r a t i o n does n o t f o l l o w strict c h r o n o l o g i c a l o r d e r o r p r o v i d e a c o m p r e h e n s i v e a c c o u n t , as has a l r e a d y b e e n n o t e d . Nevertheless, this o r d e r o f p r e s e n t a t i o n best illustrates h o w H e r o d o t u s a n d his sources r e m e m b e r e d the past a n d allows m e t o focus o n w h a t t h e y chose to r e m e m b e r a n d w h y r a t h e r t h a n w h a t t h e y left o u t . "
Polycrates of Samos and the Spartans The
first episode o f G r e e k h i s t o r y o f o u r p e r i o d w h i c h
Herodotus
narrates is the S p a r t a n e x p e d i t i o n against the t y r a n t Polycrates S a m o s , c. 523 ( 3 . 3 9 - 6 0 ) .
12
of
H e r o d o t u s tells us t h a t the Spartans w e r e
s u m m o n e d b y some exiles f r o m Samos, w h o asked t h e m to overt h r o w Polycrates a n d restore t h e m to p o w e r . These exiles h a d b e e n t r i c k e d i n t o l e a v i n g Samos b y Polycrates ( 3 . 4 4 - 5 ) .
Polycrates
had
secretly sent a message t o Cambyses asking t h a t he request a S a m i a n force f o r his E g y p t i a n c a m p a i g n . Cambyses c o m p l i e d a n d Polycrates t h e n selected those o f the S a m i a n citizens w h o m he m o s t suspected o f dissent a n d sent t h e m o n f o r t y t r i r e m e s t o E g y p t , i n s t r u c t i n g Cambyses n o t to send t h e m back. T h e m e n o n the ships soon r e a l i z e d w h a t h a d h a p p e n e d a n d d e c i d e d to r e t u r n to attack Polycrates. H e r o d o t u s t h e n breaks i n t o his n a r r a t i v e to register his d i s a g r e e m e n t w i t h those w h o say t h a t the exiles defeated Polycrates b y themselves. W h y , he asks, w o u l d t h e y have subsequently requested a i d f r o m the Spartans? F u r t h e r m o r e , H e r o d o t u s asserts t h a t i t is u n l i k e l y t h a t so f e w exiles c o u l d have defeated Polycrates since he was s u p p o r t e d b y m a n y m e r c e n a r i e s a n d n a t i v e archers. I n a d d i t i o n , H e r o d o t u s notes, Polycrates h a d the wives a n d c h i l d r e n o f the citizens w h o r e m a i n e d i n Samos i m p r i s o n e d i n ship-sheds a n d t h r e a t e n e d to b u r n t h e m i f the citizens b e t r a y e d h i m to the exiles. Since several elements o f this a c c o u n t are c o m m o n t o o t h e r t y r a n t stories i n the Histories a n d G r e e k l i t e r a t u r e i n g e n e r a l , i t is likely t h a t Herodotus'
a c c o u n t o f Polycrates is i n f l u e n c e d b y w i d e s p r e a d a n t i -
t y r a n n i c a l t r a d i t i o n s . W h i l e negative representations o f t y r a n n y
may
h a v e o r i g i n a t e d i n the t r a d i t i o n s t o l d b y a r i s t o c r a t i c factions a b o u t
" For a standard narrative of Greek history 525-479, see Boardman et al. (1988). For Polycrates, see further Chs. 6, pp. 124-6, and 22, p. 503, this volume. 12
GREEK
their opponents, polis-wide
b y the
HISTORY
fifth
c
525-480
525
BC
c e n t u r y t h e y h a d been a d o p t e d i n t o
t r a d i t i o n s , b o t h p o p u l a r a n d o f f i c i a l t r a d i t i o n s . T h u s the
e x i l e d S a m i a n aristocrats m a y have been the o r i g i n a l source o f t r a d i t i o n s a b o u t Polycrates, b u t H e r o d o t u s
p r o b a b l y i n c o r p o r a t e s ele-
ments o f w h a t h a d become the p o p u l a r a n d official S a m i a n
version
o f the t y r a n n y , w h i c h i n t u r n was i n f l u e n c e d b y the t r a d i t i o n s o f o t h e r a n t i - t y r a n n i c a l poleis.
13
The
clever t r i c k b y w h i c h
Polycrates
gets r i d o f his p o l i t i c a l o p p o n e n t s , for i n s t a n c e , was a s t a n d a r d feat u r e o f the r e p r e s e n t a t i o n o f t y r a n n y in the fifth c e n t u r y a n d served to v a l i d a t e n o n - t y r a n n i c a l p o l i t i c a l systems b y c h a r a c t e r i z i n g tyrants as b o t h deceptive a n d b r u t a l t o w a r d s t h e i r s u b j e c t s . 1 4 T r i c k e r y
and
b r u t a l i t y feature most p r o m i n e n t l y in the stories o f Peisistratus
of
A t h e n s a n d Cypselus a n d P e r i a n d e r o f C o r i n t h . 1 0 T h e p a r t i c u l a r t r i c k as w e l l as the language o f the Polycrates story, h o w e v e r , m o s t closely resemble H e r o d o t u s ' a c c o u n t o f K i n g A p r i e s o f Egypt. T h e Egyptians w e r e l e d t o r e v o l t , a c c o r d i n g to H e r o d o t u s ,
because t h e y b e l i e v e d
t h a t A p r i e s d e l i b e r a t e l y sent t h e m against C y r e n e in o r d e r t h a t they m i g h t p e r i s h a n d he m i g h t r u l e the rest o f the E g y p t i a n s securely ( 2 . 1 6 1 . 4 , cf. The
4.159.6).
more
16
i m p r i s o n m e n t o f the c h i l d r e n a n d wives o f the S a m i a n
zens a n d P o l y c r a t e s ' Herodotus'
threat to b u r n t h e m
citi-
a l i v e is p a r a l l e l e d i n
a c c o u n t o f the t y r a n n i e s o f Peisistratus a n d
Periander.
Peisistratus t o o k hostages f r o m the c h i l d r e n o f the A t h e n i a n s d i d n o t go i n t o exile f r o m his r e g i m e (1.64.1) a n d P e r i a n d e r
who
burned
the clothes o f a l l the w o m e n o f C o r i n t h t o p r o p i t i a t e his wife's ghost (5.92t|.3). These accounts o f t y r a n n i c a l b r u t a l i t y w o u l d have h e l p e d
13
See Mitchell (1975) for the view that the Samian exiles were the source for Herodotus' account. For a demonstration of how an archaic anti-tyrannical aristocratic tradition can be adopted and adapted by a fifth-century anti-tyrannical polls tradition, see Forsdyke (1999). For the representation of tyranny in Greek literature, cf. n. 53 below. For the view that Herodotus' tyrants conform to a fifth-century pattern in which they are negative exempla for the political values of fifth-century Greeks, see Lateiner (1989) 163-86. Each of Peisistratus' three attempts at tyranny involve trickery (1.59-64). His final and most successful attempt results in the death and exile of Athenians as well as the taking of children as hostages (1.64). For Cypselus see Hdt. 5.92e,2 and Nicolaus of Damascus FGrH 90 F 57. For Periander, see Hdt. 5.92C2, with the discussion below, pp. 542-5. "' Note also that Cypselus was said to have sent his political opponents off to colonies 'in order that he might rule the rest more easily' (Nicolaus of Damascus FGrH 90 F 57) and Periander is said to have asked 'how he might govern his city best and most securely' and is told to 'get rid o f his rivals (5.92C2). 14
10
526
SARA
FORSDYKE
to excuse the citizenry i n the hfth century for their failure to resist the tyrant i n the archaic period. Herodotus' own account o f the de fence o f Samos against the Spartans, however, suggests that Polycrates had widespread popular support, as was the case for the other tyrants about w h o m anti-tyrannical polls traditions arose i n the fifth century. Modern historians accept that the Spartan mission against Polycrates was prompted by exiled aristocrats who had guest-friendship ties with Spartan aristocrats. Aristocratic factions often appealed to their for eign allies for help i n their domestic political struggles and archeological evidence confirms strong ties between Sparta and Samos i n this period. Whether the Samian aristocrats were compelled to leave Samos by Polycrates or whether they went o f fiheir own accord to Sparta to seek aid is not ultimately knowable. I t is likely, how ever, that the political tradition i n which this story was preserved elaborated in ideologically pointed ways on the historical fact o f an appeal by Samian aristocrats to Sparta for assistance i n overthrow ing Polycrates. The next part o f Herodotus' narrative suggests several different types of tradition. W h e n the Samian exiles reached Sparta they made a long speech begging for aid before the ephors. W h e n they finished speaking, the ephors said they had forgotten what they had said at the beginning o f the speech and d i d not understand what they had said at the end o f it (3.46). O n a second appearance, the Samians brought a bag and said the bag needed grain. The Spartans then said that the bag was superfluous, but agreed to help them. The Spartans sent a large force and besieged Samos, with the help o f 17
18
19
20
17
Cf. the aid of 'many of the Samians themselves' (αυτών Σαμίων συχνοί) at 3.54.2. These ties may date back at least as far as the Messenian Wars, since the Samians themselves apparently explained Spartan aid against Polycrates as a return for Samian help to the Spartans against the Messenians (3.47.1). The Spartan claim that their expedition against Polycrates was retribution for an ancient theft (3.47.1), makes little historical sense and, as Nino Luraghi has argued in an unpublished paper, can be explained by Sparta's need to obscure its special relationship with Samos and its willingness to help Samos in 441 against Athens in violation of the Thirty Years' Peace. On the use of guest-lfiendship ties to acquire foreign troops for an aristocrat's domestic political struggles, see Herman (1987) 97-105. On aristocratic ties between Sparta and Samos at this time, see Cartledge (1982). Shipley (1987) 97 suggests that the exiles were given the opportunity to leave and gladly took it up. 18
19
20
GREEK
HISTORY
c.
525-480
527
BC
the Corinthians (3.48, 54). The Spartans were driven back by Polycrates' mercenaries and the Samians themselves, as well as Polycrates himself (3.54). T w o Spartans, Archias and Lycopes, performed especially bravely but the siege was unsuccessful. The Spartans left after forty days. Herodotus reports a story that he doesn't believe, namely that Polycrates made fake coins and bribed the Spartans to leave (3.56.2). The Samian exiles then gave up and decided to settle elsewhere. They first extracted money from the Siphnians by force, then bought an island off the Peloponnese and handed it over to the Troezenians. They then founded a city i n Crete but were later driven out by the Aeginetans and the Cretans. The Aeginetans sawed off the prows of the captured Samian ships and dedicated them i n the temple o f Athena on Aegina (3.57—9). The story o f the Samian exiles' encounter with the Spartan ephors is in accord with the pattern o f representation of Sparta as being hostole to speechmaking. Representations o f Spartan laconism probably reflect the disciplined and authoritarian nature o f the Spartan social and political system. Yet, as Ellen Millender (2001) argues, this feature is probably sharpened i n this and other anecdotes to emphasize the contrast between democratic Athens and oligarchic Sparta, and hence the anecdote may be influenced by democratic ideology. The only historically secure element of the story is that the Spartans did i n fact agree to help the Samians. The stories o f individual bravery o f Spartans during the siege o f Sparta, furthermore, are derived from family traditions which Herodotus heard at Sparta, as Herodotus explicitly mentions i n the case o f Archias (3.55.2). The story o f Polycrates' bribery may be a tradition invented to explain the gilded lead coins which archaeologists have discovered. I t is not uncommon for traditions to be invented i n order to explain artefacts and practices whose origins are no longer remembered. Finally, Herodotus' account of the later wandering o f the Samian exiles incorporates information which he must have gathered from Delphi (concerning the Siphnians) and from Aegina (concerning the Samian 21
22
23
21
See Cartlertge (1978) 34: 'it is extremely doubtful whether there was ever much debate in the Spartan Assembly'. This tradition, furthermore, neatly dovetails with the other traditions representing tyrannical trickery. For the coins, see Barron (1966) 17. Cf. Stahl (1987) 22-3. 22
23
528
SARA FORSDYKE
colonization o f Crete). I t is noteworthy that, in contrast to the ear lier narrative which represented the Samian exiles as innocent vic tims o f a tyrant, here the exiles are represented negatively as extorting money from the Siphnians and violently driving people out o f their lands. This unflattering portrait is in accord with non-Samian sources, such as Delphic and Aeginetan traditions.Herodotus' narrative o f the Spartan expedition against Samos pro vides a case study i n his historical methods. Herodotus utilizes many diflerent traditions to construct his account, including family, popu lar, and official polls traditions. He sometimes records multiple ver sions o f the same event and occasionally questions versions which he judges implausible (e.g., the exiles were too few in number to defeat Polycrates alone). Affinities between Herodotus' account o f Polycrates and stories about other tyrants, moreover, arc most likely a result o f the influence o f the traditions o f diflerent poleis on one another. Herodotus himself may have further sharpened such par allels in order to create vivid examples o f the unaccountability o f tyranny as theorized i n his 'Constitutional Debate' (ανεύθυνος, 3.80). 1
The Ionian Revolt The next important event Greek history narrated by Herodotus is the Ionian Revolt (499 -494), when the Eastern Greeks tried unsuc cessfully to throw off the yoke o f Persia and were aided by Athens and Eretria. The relevance o f this episode to Herodotus' history is explicitly stated: the Ionian Revolt was one o f the immediate causes of the subsequent invasions launched by Persia against Greece. Specifically, Athens' participation in the burning o f Sardis caused first Darius and then Xerxes to turn his attention to mainland Greece (5.97.3; 5.105; 7.5.2; 7.8β). O f utmost importance for Greek histo rians, however, is that Herodotus uses the appeal of the Ionian Greeks for help from the mainland Greeks as an occasion to recount the history o f Sparta and Athens i n the years leading up to the revolt. Thus, within the narrative of the Ionian Revolt, we get capsule his-
The geographical locations of the successive settlements as well as the evident concern of the Aeginetans over the actions of the Samians suggest that these set tlements were strategically placed to control trading routes. See Figucira (1985) 53.
GREEK
HISTORY
c.
525-480
529
BC
tories o f what Herodotus and his sources thought important about this period o f mainland Greek history; these will be discussed later. Herodotus' account o f the Ionian Revolt presents a difficult problem for historians. Scholars agree that the desire for freedom from Persia and internal political freedom (democracy) in the East Greek cities were fundamental factors in the revolt. These were causes o f which Herodotus approved and which he should have been glad to emphasize. Yet instead, Herodotus focuses on the personal motives of the leaders o f the revolt, Aristagoras and Histiaeus o f Miletus. Modern historians believe that this focus distorts his account of the causes and course o f the revolt to an unacceptable degree. Instead of criticizing Herodotus, however, it is more useful to ask w h y Herodotus chose this emphasis. M o r e precisely, did he choose this emphasis or were these critical traditions the only ones available? I f the latter, then we must explain why there were no traditions which emphasized the heroism o f the Eastern Greek cities i n revolting against the mighty Persian empire. The answer is probably that the failure o f the revolt influenced the nature o f the traditions about i t . Rather than producing an account o f unified action i n defence o f Greek freedom, the traditions o f the cities and individuals involved were concerned to defend themselves and blame others for the defeat. There was, however, some common ground i n these traditions. AH Ionians, it seems, could agree that Aristagoras, Histiaeus, and the other Ionian tyrants had acted i n their own self-interest, and were not truly interested the cause o f Greek freedom. I t was from these critical traditions that Herodotus constructed his account. 23
2,>
27
Modern historians believe that the underlying causes o f the revolt probably included the increasing demands on the East Greeks for military service and tribute as well as declining economic prosperity due to the disruption o f trade by Persian expansionism. Herodotus does not cite these issues as causes o f the revolt although it is from his account that we can infer that these must have been significant 28
25
See the analyses of Tozzi (1978) and Murray (1988). * With this absence of positive traditions about the Ionian Revolt we might compare the traditions about the Phocaeans and the Teans who in 546 refused to submit to the Persians and instead migrated to the West. Herodotus calls these men agathoi and cxplictly praises them for their desire for freedom (1.169). ' Lang (1968) 24; Murray (1988) 471. Tozzi (1978) 114-76 and Murray (1988). 2 7
28
530
SARA
FORSDYKE
factors. H e does record the immediate cause o f the revolt: the appeal of some exiled Naxian aristocrats for aid to Aristagoras, the acting tyrant o f Miletus. Aristagoras agreed to help because he thought that he might add Naxos to his dominion (5.30.3). He then appealed to the Persians for help, pointing out to them that Naxos was the key to conquest o f the Cyclades and Euboea (5.31.2-3). As many have recognized, in this speech o f Aristagoras, Herodotus shows awareness o f the imperial aims o f Persia and provides a plausible explanation o f Persian actions at this time, namely, that Darius seized the opportunity o f civic stasis to conquer Naxos and begin expansion towards Greece. Herodotus, however, keeps his narrative focus on Aristagoras in a way which is consistent both with oral techniques o f narration and with his sources' desire for a scapegoat. When the siege o f Naxos failed, Aristagoras was left in an awkward position: he was unable to fulfil his promises to the Persians, he owed a lot of money to the army, and he feared he would be deposed at Miletus as a consequence (5.35.1-2). H e decided, therefore, to become leader o f a revolt against Persia. Herodotus emphasizes both here (5.37.1) and later (5.98.1), that Aristagoras' motive was not to help Ionia, but to maintain his own position and harm Darius. It is quite likely that after the failure o f the Naxian expedition, Aristagoras did indeed find his position as puppet tyrant untenable and was driven to revolt mainly by this fact. However, his establishment o f isonomia at Miletus and his overthrow o f tyrants i n other Ionian cities i n order gain popular favour (5.37.2) show that there was widespread hostility to the Persian-backed tyrants and a desire for a more egalitarian political system. The establishment o f democracies in the Ionian cities by Mardonius in 492 (6.43), moreover, attests to the demand for political reform in Ionia in the 490s. Herodotus' accounts o f the activities o f the other leader o f the revolt, Histiaeus, the former tyrant o f Miletus, are somewhat puzzling. I t is noteworthy that nowhere i n Herodotus' account are Histiaeus' actions really important to the outcome o f events. H e is merely a fellow-instigator, a slippery advisor to Darius and ultimately a failed rebel who acts largely on his own. Furthermore, the only real consistency i n the narratives is Histiaeus' cleverness. These two features o f the Histiaeus story suggest that Herodotus' account derives from popular traditions which were mainly concerned to illustrate Greek cleverness (metis; M u r r a y (1988) 486). Thus we get the story of the message tattooed into a slave's skull (5.35.3) as well as Histiaeus'
•
GREEK
HISTORY
c.
525-480
BC
531
deception o f Darius (5.106—7) and of the Ionians themselves (6.3). The failure o f the revolt may explain the lack o f a consistent political position i n Histiaeus' character as well as the inconsequentiality of the Histiaeus narratives; all that is remembered i n the tradition (or invented to fit the needs o f the tellers) are stories illustrating Greek cleverness, particularly Greek cleverness exercised against Persia. Herodotus' account o f the final sea battle at Lade reveals its origins i n the oral traditions o f the defeated Ionian cities. Herodotus himself comments that he is unable to give a good account o f the battle, because all the reports are confused and everyone blames everyone else (7.14.1). M a n y historians, however, have pointed to Samian sources for Herodotus' account since Herodotus explicitly mentions the eleven Samian ships which were honoured for not defecting (6.14.2-3). He also mentions the dislike o f some Samian aristocrats for the behaviour o f their generals at Lade and the consequent departure o f these aristocrats on a colonizing enterprise i n order not to become subject to the Persians (6.22.1). I t may be that the story o f the Phocaean general Dionysius, who unsuccessfully attempted to put the Ionians through rigorous training for battle, may be a post-defeat adaptation designed to excuse the Samians for their departure (Murray (1988) 488). Herodotus' report o f the bravery o f the Chians and their unfortunate fate (6.15-16), on the other hand, is likely derived from an apologetic Chian tradition. Finally, although the Persians were undoubtedly helped by the Ionian tyrants who had fled to Persia after their deposition, their infiltration of the Ionian army and the way that they threaten the Ionians with typical oriental punishments help to excuse the Ionians for deserting and thus may originate in Ionian polls traditions. 29
Spartan History c.
525-499
I n his quest for external support for the revolt, Aristagoras first appealed to Sparta. Aristagoras' appeal provides Herodotus with the opportunity for his second digression on Sparta i n his Histories (5.39-54). Herodotus picks up Spartan history with the accession 30
29
Cf. 6.32, where the Persians fulfil their threats, castrating the Ionian boys and sending the girls to the king, while burning the Ionian cities and temples. For the first digression, see Ch. 22, esp. pp. 515-16, this volume. 30
532
SARA
FORSDYKE
o f C l e o m e n e s t o t h e S p a r t a n t h r o n e c. 520 a n d provides some dynastic h i s t o r y . T h e story o f C l e o m e n e s ' r e i g n is c o n t i n u e d i n H e r o d o t u s ' a c c o u n t o f affairs i n A e g i n a i m m e d i a t e l y before D a r i u s i n v a s i o n i n 4 9 0 (see b e l o w ) . Since t h e n a r r a t i v e s o n C l e o m e n e s i n c l u d e b o t h p o s i t i v e a n d negative elements, some historians believe t h a t H e r o d o t u s ' sources m u s t h a v e b e e n t h e r i v a l r o y a l f a m i l i e s ; others t h i n k t h a t these stories give a n o f f i c i a l polls v i e w . 3 1 I f we accept the m o r e recent v i e w t h a t f a m i l y t r a d i t i o n need n o t be o p p o s e d t o official o r p o p u l a r polls t r a d i t i o n , b u t instead the t w o types o f t r a d i t i o n m a y i n f l u e n c e a n d i n c o r p o r a t e elements f r o m each o t h e r , t h e n the a m b i g u i t i e s i n the t r a d i t i o n are easier to e x p l a i n . M o r e o v e r , it is likely that H e r o d o t u s d i d n o t r e l y o n a single source b u t h a d access to f a m i l y , o f f i c i a l polls a n d , p a r t i c u l a r l y i n the a c c o u n t o f C l e o m e n e s , gruesome d e a t h , p o p u l a r polls t r a d i t i o n s . T h e
ways t h a t these d i f f e r e n t t r a d i t i o n s relate
a n d a d a p t t o one a n o t h e r , as w e l l as h o w H e r o d o t u s
shapes t h e m
to t h e needs o f his n a r r a t i v e are some o f the m o s t significant areas f o r f u t u r e research. Cleomenes'
e n c o u n t e r w i t h A r i s t a g o r a s bears all the m a r k s o f a
G r e e k m o r a l i z i n g t r a d i t i o n a n d also appears to have b e e n by Herodotus'
shaped
o w n conceptual framework. After a brief appeal to
the n o t i o n s o f f r e e d o m a n d k i n s h i p , A r i s t a g o r a s tries to t e m p t t h e S p a r t a n k i n g b y d e s c r i b i n g the i n f e r i o r i t y o f t h e Persian a r m y
and
the w e a l t h o f t h e Eastern lands (5.49.2—8). W h y s h o u l d t h e Spartans fight
against t h e i r f o r m i d a b l e P e l o p o n n e s i a n adversaries over a s m a l l
a n d i n f e r t i l e l a n d w h e n Persia is r i c h a n d easily conquered? I f they c o n q u e r Susa, t h e y w i l l ' r i v a l Zeus i n w e a l t h ' (5.49.7). A r i s t a g o r a s is thus m a d e to a p p e a l to desires w h i c h are e x t r e m e l y dangerous
in
S p a r t a n a n d G r e e k value systems. A c c o r d i n g to G r e e k beliefs, a fertile landscape causes softness i n its i n h a b i t a n t s a n d is associated w i t h a servile s p i r i t . 3 2 F u r t h e r m o r e ,
t h e a t t e m p t to r i v a l the gods always
meets w i t h disaster. 3 3 G i v e n the p r o m i n e n c e o f these values i n the Histories a n d i n G r e e k t h o u g h t i n g e n e r a l , i t is d i f f i c u l t to d e t e r m i n e
31
For the former view see Jeffery (1988) and Evans (1991) 125. In a variation on this view see Cartledge (1979) 143. For the view that Herodotus' aecount of Cleomenes' reign derives from a polis tradition, see Murray (1987) 104 w4io writes 'Spartan tradition, even in so far as it relates to the kings, seems to be unconnected with families, but rather to give an official polis view of the past which it would be easier to attribute to a group aware of the need for social cohesion.' See 7.102.1 and 9.122.3-4; Democritus F 251 D K ; Hippocrates Airs, Waters, 32
Places 24. 33
See below, ch. 24, pp. 560 1, this volume.
GREEK
HISTORY
525-480
c.
w h e t h e r t h e i r expression here is due to H e r o d o t u s One
m i g h t t h i n k that Cleomenes'
533
BC
o r his sources.
r e j e c t i o n o f A r i s t a g o r a s ' suit i n d i -
cates a pro-Cleomenes t r a d i t i o n . Yet Cleomenes only rejects Aristagoras on learning how
far Susa was f r o m t h e sea (5.50).
Furthermore,
w h e n Aristagoras tries to b r i b e Cleomenes w i t h fifty talents, Cleomenes has to be p r o m p t e d b y his y o u n g d a u g h t e r G o r g o to go away (5.51.2). T h i s last e l e m e n t suggests a p o p u l a r t r a d i t i o n w h i c h was n o t p a r t o f the r o y a l f a m i l y t r a d i t i o n . W e may
surmise t h a t this p o p u l a r t r a d i -
t i o n e l a b o r a t e d i n m o r a l l y p o i n t e d ways u p o n the h i s t o r i c a l fact t h a t S p a r t a d i d n o t p a r t i c i p a t e in the
I o n i a n r e v o l t . L i k e the t r a d i t i o n s
f r o m w h i c h he d r a w s , h o w e v e r , H e r o d o t u s h i m s e l f is c o n c e r n e d w i t h the
contrast b e t w e e n soft a n d h a r d c u l t u r e s , as w e l l as the d i s t i n c -
t i o n b e t w e e n d i v i n e a n d m o r t a l . 3 1 The
resonances b e t w e e n this pas-
sage a n d o t h e r passages i n the Histories s h o w t h a t the m o r a l t o n e of this n a r r a t i v e is n o t due solely to H e r o d o t u s ' sources, b u t is p o i n t e d u p i n his n a r r a t i v e to evoke some of the m a j o r themes o f his w o r k . Modern
h i s t o r i a n s , o n the o t h e r h a n d , e x p l a i n Sparta's
f a i l u r e to
help w i t h the I o n i a n R e v o l t b y its t r o u b l e s w i t h its allies i n 5 0 6 a n d its c o n t i n u i n g r i v a l r y w i t h
Argos.
Athenian History
514-499
A r i s t a g o r a s ' appeal was m o r e successful i n A t h e n s t h a n i t h a d b e e n in Sparta.
C r u c i a l factors i n A t h e n s '
decision to h e l p the l o n i a n s
were p r o b a b l y A t h e n s ' k i n s h i p ties w i t h t h e l o n i a n s ( m e n t i o n e d briefly by Aristagoras,
5.97.2),
as w e l l as A t h e n s '
s u p p o r t f o r isonomia.
H e r o d o t u s , h o w e v e r , has A r i s t a g o r a s m a k e the same a r g u m e n t s t h a t he m a d e at S p a r t a , n a m e l y the g o o d t h i n g s t h a t A s i a c o u l d offer i f c o n q u e r e d a n d the ease w i t h w h i c h the Persians c o u l d be (5.97.1). A l t h o u g h H e r o d o t u s
does n o t d i r e c t l y praise the
beaten Spartans
f o r t h e i r r e j e c t i o n o f A r i s t a g o r a s ' suit, H e r o d o t u s feels c o m p e l l e d to c o m m e n t o n A t h e n s ' a g r e e m e n t to h e l p . H e concludes t h a t i t seems to be easier to deceive (8tcd3dA,A,£iv) m a n y m e n t h a n one, since A r i s tagoras h a d n o t been able to deceive C l e o m e n e s
b u t was able to
deceive t h i r t y t h o u s a n d A t h e n i a n s (5.97.2). M a n y c o m m e n t a t o r s have taken this passage as a n i n d i c a t i o n o f H e r o d o t u s ' c r i t i c a l v i e w o f t h e
" On soft and hard cultures, see Gould (1989) 58 60. On divine and mortal see Ghs. 8 and 9, pp. 220 4, this volume.
534 Athenian
SARA
democracy.
sions o f A t h e n i a n democracy
Yet,
FORSDYKE
as w e shall see, H e r o d o t u s
records ver-
h i s t o r y w h i c h c o n f i r m the b e n e f i c i a l effects
on Athens.
This
c o n t r a d i c t i o n is p r o b a b l y
of
due t o the
d i f f e r e n t t r a d i t i o n s t h a t H e r o d o t u s depends u p o n . T h e negative v i e w reflects a c r i t i c a l v i e w o f the I o n i a n r e v o l t a n d its s u p p o r t e r s , i n c l u d i n g A r i s t a g o r a s a n d the A t h e n i a n s ; the positive v i e w o f the A t h e n i a n d e m o c r a c y , o n the o t h e r h a n d , reflects the l e g i t i m i z i n g t r a d i t i o n s o f the A t h e n i a n
democracy.
Herodotus
h i m s e l f , o f course, m u s t have
b e e n a w a r e o f this c o n t r a d i c t i o n i n his sources a b o u t the value
of
the A t h e n i a n d e m o c r a c y . As is clear f r o m the ' C o n s t i t u t i o n a l D e b a t e ' ( 3 . 8 0 - 2 ) as w e l l as his accounts o f kings a n d t y r a n t s , H e r o d o t u s
was
n o t a n u n c r i t i c a l p r o p a g a n d i s t f o r a p a r t i c u l a r p o l i t i c a l system, b u t r a t h e r was c o n c e r n e d to use his h i s t o r i c a l i n q u i r i e s to e x p l o r e the strengths a n d weaknesses o f systems o f p o l i t i c a l o r g a n i z a t i o n . 3 0 H e r o d o t u s ' a c c o u n t o f A t h e n s at the t i m e o f A r i s t a g o r a s '
embassy
includes key m o m e n t s i n A t h e n s ' recent p o l i t i c a l d e v e l o p m e n t (notably the e s t a b l i s h m e n t o f a d e m o c r a c y ) a n d a n a c c o u n t o f A t h e n s ' relations w i t h o t h e r G r e e k states (in p a r t i c u l a r , S p a r t a a n d O n c e a g a i n , a key q u e s t i o n is h o w reflects H e r o d o t u s '
recent Aegina).
f a r this selection o f m a t e r i a l
choices o r the choices o f the t r a d i t i o n s available
t o h i m . O n c e a g a i n , t h e answer is p r o b a b l y b o t h . S o m e elements o f Herodotus'
a c c o u n t c a n be s h o w n to reflect the A t h e n i a n s '
under-
s t a n d i n g o f the i m p o r t a n c e o f t h e i r p o l i t i c a l system t o t h e i r h i s t o r y ; o t h e r elements suggest the i n f l u e n c e o f H e r o d o t u s '
o w n v i e w o f the
value o f p o l i t i c a l f r e e d o m . U n t i l r e c e n t l y , scholars accepted the v i e w o f J a c o b y t h a t H e r o d o t u s r e l i e d p r i m a r i l y o n the f a m i l y t r a d i t i o n s o f the A l c m e o n i d a e a c c o u n t o f the o v e r t h r o w o f the t y r a n n y
and Athenian
f o r his
history i n
g e n e r a l ( J a c o b y (1913), (1949)). M o r e r e c e n t l y , scholars have b e g u n to argue f o r the presence o f a m o r e Herodotus' account.
36
complex
set o f t r a d i t i o n s i n
N o t o n l y are a r i s t o c r a t i c f a m i l y t r a d i t i o n s p r e -
sent, i t is a r g u e d , b u t b r o a d e r polls t r a d i t i o n s . T h i s n e w perspective on Herodotus'
o r a l sources is based p a r t l y o n the r e c o g n i t i o n t h a t
f a m i l y a n d polls t r a d i t i o n s are n o t m u t u a l l y exclusive, a n d p a r t l y o n the o b s e r v a t i o n t h a t parts o f H e r o d o t u s ' a c c o u n t are n o t at a l l c o m -
33
For Herodotus as a political theorist, see Saxonhouse (1996) and Thompson (1996). See especially Thomas (1989) 238-82 and Lavelle (1993) 74-108; also Develin (1985). 36
GREEK
HISTORY
c.
525-480
535
BC
plimentary to the Alcmeonid family and therefore would have been dropped from the tradition i f it were preserved solely by that family. Although most scholars would not go so far, I would argue that the Athenians' collective belief i n the value o f their democratic political system has influenced Herodotus' version o f Athens' history and hence that specifically democratic polls traditions lie behind his account. Herodotus begins with an account o f how Athens was liberated from the tyranny o f the sons o f Pisistratus (5.55). A t the time o f the overthrow o f the tyranny, Herodotus explains, Hippias was tyrant. His brother, Hipparchus, had recently been killed and this had affected the manner o f Hippias' rule. Herodotus does not delve into details o f Hipparchus' death or the motivations o f Hipparchus' killers. He simply notes that after the death o f Hipparchus, the Athenians were ruled for four more years by Hippias, who ruled more tyrannically after the murder than before. I t is clear from Thucydides' vehement refutation o f popular Athenian views o f the tyrannicides as liberators o f Athens (Time. 6.54-9), that Hipparchus' murderers were credited with the overthrow o f the tyranny i n some traditions. ' This is not surprising since it is a common feature o f oral traditions to collapse two distinct historical events into one. Yet it is evident from Herodotus' account that there were other versions o f the end of the tyranny and, in particular, that the crucial role of the Spartans was not forgotten by some. Herodotus rejects the simplified version in which Harmodius and Aristogeiton are liberators (cf. 6.123) and accepts another version, namely that the Alcmeonidae bribed the Delphic oracle to persuade the Spartans to overthrow the tyrants (5.63). When the Spartans gave i n to the repeated requests o f the oracle, they, along with some Athenians, drove the tyrants from Athens (5.63-5). Since Herodotus gives all credit to the Alcmeonidae and the Spartans (cf. 6.123), it has been thought that Herodotus relied on the family tradition of the Alcmeonidae. I n fact, both the tyrannicides-as-liberators and the Spartans/Alcmeonids-as-liberators versions may have been polls traditions. As Thomas has shown ((1989) 250-1), oral societies can have multiple, even contradictoty, versions 3
38
" The idea that the tyrannicides-as-liberators version was promoted by an antiAlcmeonid faction and specifically Themistocles' faction is no longer considered plausible (Thomas (1989) 238-51; Raaflaub (1988a) 200). See Thomas (1989) 133-5, 138-44, 224-6 and Raaflaub (1988a) 202, 222 on this feature of oral traditions. 311
SARA
FORSDYKE
of a given historical tradition. As long as the two versions are told on different occasions, the contradiction is not considered important. As Thomas has pointed out, although the Alcmeonid family tradition no doubt preserved the memory o f its role in these events, it is unlikely that their version would have highlighted so prominently the dishonourable fact o f their bribery of the Delphic oracle. I t is likely that the detail o f bribery would have been de-emphasized and eventually dropped from their version o f events. In Herodotus' version, however, this is the only deed that the Alcmeonidae are explicitly credited with, apart from their unsuccessful earlier attempts to overthrow the tyrants.' Even though the Alcmeonidae probably led the Athenian force which helped the Spartans overthrow the tyranny (5.64.2), they are not mentioned by name. Instead, Herodotus designates the Athenian force as 'those Athenians who wished to be free'. T h e anonymity o f this phrase recalls other instances under the Athenian democracy where individual achievements are subsumed under the anonymous collective label 'the Athenians'." These features o f Herodotus' version diminish the role o f the Alcmeonidae and emphasize collective action by the Athenians. - This suggests that Herodotus' version contains elements o f a wider polls tradition. The role o f the Spartans and the Alcmeonidae in the overthrow o f the tyranny was presumably historical and remembered by too many people to be covered u p . Nevertheless, the tradition does what it can to show the Athenians acting against the tyrants and is not particularly concerned to note Alcmeonid leadership. 39
10
4
43
Herodotus' account o f the establishment o f the democracy i n Athens similarly seems to derive from a polls tradition. The nature of the tradition is suggested by the remarks which frame Herodotus' account: Athens, although it was a great city even before, became even greater when it was liberated from the tyrants. (5.66.1)
71
Thomas (1989) 24850; Evans (1991) 126; although see Develin (1985) 128. 5.62.2 63.1; 5.66.1; 6.123. For their earlier unsuccessful efforts: 5.62.2. " For example, in the epigram on the bronze chariot which commemorated the victory over the Boeotians and Chalcidians (5.77.4). The emphasis on collective Athenian action is even more prominent in fourthcentury versions, see Thomas (1989) 196-237, 251-7. " Aristophanes gives all the credit to the Spartans in what appears to be a popular tradition about the overthrow of the tyrants in Lysxstraia 1150-6 (see Thomas (1989) 245-7). Herodotus also mentions the tomb of Anchimolius (Spartan com111
GREEK
HISTORY
c.
525-480
537
BC
I t is clear that democracy (icrnyopvn) is an excellent thing not just in one aspect but in every way. For the Athenians, when ruled by tyrants, were not better than any o f their neighbours in war, but when they had r i d themselves o f the tyrants, they were first by far. This shows, therefore, that when they were held down by a tyrant they were cow ardly, on the grounds that they were w o r k i n g for a master, but when they had been liberated (e^evOepcoOevTcov) each m a n was eager to work for himself. (5.78) 44
A l t h o u g h t h e l a t t e r r e m a r k is c l e a r l y m a d e i n H e r o d o t u s ' o w n v o i c e , t h e idea t h a t p o l i t i c a l f r e e d o m , a n d specifically d e m o c r a t i c f r e e d o m , h a d a b e n e f i c i a l effect o n A t h e n s is e c h o e d t h r o u g h o u t Athenian
n a r r a t i v e as w e l l as i n o t h e r A t h e n i a n
Herodotus'
sources (Forsdyke
(2001)). F o r this reason w e m a y surmise that H e r o d o t u s '
account
derives at least i n p a r t f r o m o f f i c i a l a n d p o p u l a r polls t r a d i t i o n s w h i c h sought t o l e g i t i m a t e d e m o c r a t i c g o v e r n m e n t
by using Athens'
past
to show the benefits o f d e m o c r a t i c r u l e . Nevertheless, the association between p o l i t i c a l f r e e d o m a n d civic strength is also p a r t o f H e r o d o t u s ' o w n c o n c e p t u a l f r a m e w o r k a n d once a g a i n it is d i f f i c u l t t o separate Herodotus'
s h a p i n g o f t h e t r a d i t i o n f r o m t h a t o f his sources. 4 3
T o argue t h a t H e r o d o t u s ' a c c o u n t is i n f l u e n c e d b y d e m o c r a t i c polls t r a d i t i o n s is n o t t o say t h a t H e r o d o t u s '
a c c o u n t is p u r e j i n g o i s t i c
i d e o l o g y . H e r o d o t u s a n d his sources w o r k e d w i t h g e n u i n e h i s t o r i c a l m e m o r i e s o f this p e r i o d . M a n y aspects o f his a c c o u n t , m o r e o v e r , fit w i t h w h a t w e k n o w o f t h e p o l i t i c a l c o n d i t i o n s o f a r c h a i c Greece. I n particular,
Herodotus'
a c c o u n t o f t h e i m m e d i a t e a f t e r m a t h o f the
o v e r t h r o w o f the t y r a n n y is believable i n t e r m s o f w h a t w e k n o w o f the p o l i t i c a l s t r u c t u r e a n d h i s t o r y o f the a r c h a i c G r e e k states. I n A t h e n s , as w e l l as o t h e r poleis, there was a c o n s t a n t struggle f o r d o m i n a n c e a m o n g r i v a l groups o f aristocrats i n the seventh a n d s i x t h
mander of the first expedition against the tyrants) in a deme where Alcmeonids resided (5.63.4), a monument which may have helped to preserve the memory of the role of the Spartans and the Alcmeonids. Herodotus uses the term ίσηγορίη (isêgoriê, 'equal right to speak') to denote the Athenian democracy by synecdoche. I n the context, it is clear that Herodotus is speaking of the Athenian democracy. Herodotus rarely uses the term δημοκρατίη (demokratië). He uses it only once of the Athenian democracy (6.131.4), and once more of the establishment of democracies in the cities of Ionia after the Ionian revolt (6.43.3, cf. his use of the verb δημοκρατέεσθαι at 6.43.3 and 4.137.2). Herodotus uses other terms to denote democracy such as ίσονομίη (isonomië, 3.80.6, 3.142.3) and/or circumlocutions such as πάντα . . . ές μέσον τω δήμφ εθηκε (4.161.3) and ές μέσον την αρχήν τιθείς (3.142.3). On relation between civic strength and political freedom in the Histories see Gray (1997). 11
b
538
SARA
centuries. T h e
FORSDYKE
leaders o f successful factions o f t e n b e c a m e
tyrants;
unsuccessful factions e i t h e r s u b m i t t e d to t h e r u l e o f the t y r a n t o r w e n t i n t o exile to g a t h e r forces f o r t h e i r r e t u r n . 4 6 H e r o d o t u s records such a s i t u a t i o n o f v i o l e n c e b e t w e e n r i v a l aris t o c r a t i c f a c t i o n s after t h e o v e r t h r o w o f t h e t y r a n n y .
So
m u c h is
agreed b y m o d e r n scholars. T h e rest o f his a c c o u n t is d i s p u t e d . S o m e scholars believe t h a t H e r o d o t u s ' v e r s i o n is so v i t i a t e d b y t h e effects o f o r a l t r a d i t i o n t h a t the h i s t o r y o f the t r a n s i t i o n to d e m o c r a c y is n o t r e c o v e r a b l e (see R a a f l a u b
(1998b)
87-8).
M o s t scholars take a
m o r e m o d e r a t e p o s i t i o n : H e r o d o t u s does i n d e e d preserve s o m e t h i n g o f the h i s t o r i c a l events, b u t e x t r e m e care m u s t be t a k e n to c o m p e n sate f o r the effects o f the o r a l t r a d i t i o n s w h i c h w e r e his sources. issues have d o m i n a t e d recent w o r k o n H e r o d o t u s ' events o f 5 0 8 / 7 B C .
Two
account o f the
First is the q u e s t i o n o f w h a t types o f o r a l t r a
d i t i o n s lie b e h i n d H e r o d o t u s '
a c c o u n t a n d hence w h a t sorts o f dis
t o r t i o n s t h e a c c o u n t has u n d e r g o n e . S e c o n d , a n e w debate has arisen over w h a t H e r o d o t u s '
a c c o u n t i m p l i e s a b o u t the roles o f elites a n d
masses i n the t r a n s i t i o n to d e m o c r a c y . L e t us b e g i n w i t h a s u m m a r y . Cleisthenes
o f the f a m i l y o f the A l c m e o n i d a e
a n d Isagoras
of
a n o t h e r l e a d i n g a r i s t o c r a t i c f a m i l y f o u g h t over p o w e r after the over t h r o w o f the t y r a n t s . Cleisthenes was b e i n g w o r s t e d i n the struggle a n d ' t o o k t h e p e o p l e i n t o his f a c t i o n ' (τον δ ή μ ο ν π ρ ο σ ε τ α ι ρ ί ζ ε τ α ι ) . W i t h the s u p p o r t o f the p e o p l e , Cleisthenes w o n p o w e r over Isagoras. He
t h e n c h a n g e d the tribes f r o m f o u r to t e n ( i . e . , passed d e m o c r a
tic r e f o r m s , cf. 6.131.1). Cleisthenes c h a n g e d the names o f the tribes i n i m i t a t i o n o f his u n c l e Cleisthenes o f S i c y o n w h o s i m i l a r l y c h a n g e d the names o f some tribes i n his city. N e x t Isagoras c a l l e d o n his S p a r t a n g u e s t - f r i e n d Cleomenes to h e l p h i m r e g a i n p o w e r . sent a h e r a l d to A t h e n s
Cleomenes
d e m a n d i n g t h a t Cleisthenes a n d his sup
p o r t e r s go i n t o exile o n the g r o u n d s t h a t t h e y w e r e p o l l u t e d as a result o f t h e i r m u r d e r o f t h e adherents o f C y l o n
during a similar
b o u t o f a r i s t o c r a t i c i n f i g h t i n g i n t h e late seventh c e n t u r y . Cleisthenes t h e n left A t h e n s .
When
Cleomenes
arrived i n Athens w i t h a small
force he d r o v e o u t a n a d d i t i o n a l 700 families a n d a t t e m p t e d to dis solve the C o u n c i l a n d give p o w e r to Isagoras a n d three h u n d r e d o f his s u p p o r t e r s . T h e
C o u n c i l resisted a n d , i n response,
a n d Isagoras r e t r e a t e d to t h e a c r o p o l i s . T h e
4,1
rest o f the
Cleomenes Athenians
On aristocratic stasis in the archaic Greek poleis and its relation to the develop ment of democracy at Athens, see Forsdyke (2000).
GREEK
HISTORY
525-480
c'
539
BC
( Α θ η ν α ί ω ν ο ι λ ο ι π ο ί ) , t h i n k i n g the same t h i n g (τα α υ τ ά φ ρ ο ν ή σ α ν τ ε ς ) , besieged the Spartans a n d Isagoras o n t h e a c r o p o l i s f o r t w o days. O n the t h i r d d a y , the Spartans left A t h e n s u n d e r a t r u c e . T h e
Athe
nians c o n d e m n e d Isagoras' supporters to d e a t h a n d recalled Cleisthenes a n d the o t h e r e x i l e d families. R e a l i z i n g t h a t the Spartans w o u l d r e t a l i a t e , t h e A t h e n i a n s d e c i d e d to send envoys
to Persia to m a k e
an
alliance. A r t a p h e r n e s , the Persian g o v e r n o r at Sardis, d e m a n d e d t h a t A t h e n s s u r r e n d e r h e r a u t o n o m y to Persia i n r e t u r n f o r a n a l l i a n c e . T h e envoys gave tokens o f submission a n d w e r e severely b l a m e d f o r this w h e n t h e y r e t u r n e d t o A t h e n s This
a c c o u n t has raised m a n y
(5.66-73). questions. T h e
traditional inter
p r e t a t i o n o f H e r o d o t u s ' n a r r a t i v e is t h a t t h e d e m o c r a c y was b r o u g h t a b o u t b y self-interested aristocrats as a n e w tactic t h e i r o n - g o i n g p o l i t i c a l struggles, a n d t h a t Cleisthenes c l e v e r l y e x p l o i t e d p o p u l a r f a v o u r to defeat his elite r i v a l . 4 7 O n
this i n t e r p r e t a t i o n , the A t h e n i a n
p e o p l e gave o n l y passive s u p p o r t to Cleisthenes i n the assembly w h e n he p r o p o s e d his r e f o r m s . 4 8 F u r t h e r m o r e , i t is n o t e d t h a t the p e o p l e d i d n o t resist the e x p u l s i o n o f Cleisthenes as t h e y m i g h t have d o n e i f t h e y h a d h a d a n active desire f o r d e m o c r a t i c r e f o r m . I t was o n l y w h e n C l e o m e n e s t r i e d to d i s b a n d t h e C o u n c i l t h a t resistance b e g a n , a n d this has b e e n t a k e n as a n i n d i c a t i o n t h a t i t was a r i s t o c r a t i c l e a d ers o n the C o u n c i l w h o d i r e c t e d ' t h e rest o f t h e A t h e n i a n s ' i n the subsequent siege o f Isagoras a n d C l e o m e n e s o n the a c r o p o l i s . S u p p o r t e r s o f this v i e w o f the events o f 5 0 8 / 7 argue t h a t o n l y the h o p l i t e class lies b e h i n d H e r o d o t u s ' t e r m ' t h e rest o f the A t h e n i a n s ' a n d t h a t therefore Herodotus'
a c c o u n t does n o t suggest w i d e s p r e a d p o l i t i c a l
consciousness a m o n g the A t h e n i a n masses. M o r e o v e r , the A t h e n i a n p e o p l e h a d n o t resisted the t y r a n n y o f Peisistratus (despite the claims o f later t r a d i t i o n s ) a n d there is n o evidence t h a t t h e y w o u l d have o b j e c t e d to Isagoras' r u l e h a d i t n o t b e e n f o r Cleisthenes a n d o t h e r aristocratic leaders. I n a c r i t i q u e o f this i n t e r p r e t a t i o n , J o s i a h O b e r has p o i n t e d to the key r o l e o f the demos i n H e r o d o t u s '
a c c o u n t a n d a r g u e d t h a t this
reflects the r o l e o f the citizens as a w h o l e , i n c l u d i n g t h e lowest social classes, i n the e s t a b l i s h m e n t o f the d e m o c r a c y . 4 9 A f t e r n o t i n g t h a t
47
See Raaflaub (1998a, b) and Eder (1998) for recent statements of this view. For a reconstruction of the legislative procedures of the reform, see Andrewes (1977). Originally argued in Ober (1993); restated in Ober (1998). 48
49
540
SARA
FORSDYKE
Cleisthenes must have proposed his reforms to an assembly which was aware o f the potential of the reforms to 'provide them with the institutional means to express more fully their growing sense o f themselves as citizens' ((1993) 218), Ober makes two central arguments based on Herodotus' account. First, he notes that Isagoras' aristocratic rivals had been driven into exile by the time o f the resistance to Isagoras and the Spartans and thus could not have led the revolt. T h e expulsion o f Cleisthenes and 700 families had been carefully planned by Isagoras so as to get r i d o f all the likely leaders o f resistance to his coup (5.70.2, 72.1). Second, Ober notes that it was the corporate entities o f the Council and the 'rest o f the Athenians' who resisted Isagoras and the Spartans and caused the recall o f Cleisthenes and his supporters. O n this basis, he argues that the subsequent establishment o f the Athenian democracy was 'the product of collective decision, action and self-definition on the part o f the demos itself ((1993) 216). Although the political consciousness o f the Athenian demos had been developing throughout the sixth century, Ober argues that it crystallized in the crisis o f the Spartan invasion engineered by Isagoras. A key issue in deciding between these two interpretations is the nature o f the traditions on which Herodotus' account is based as well as Herodotus' own narrative aims. Would Herodotus and his sources have tended to emphasize either aristocratic or democratic action? Ober accepts the traditional view that much o f Herodotus' account must come from aristocratic family tradition; he argues on this basis that such traditions would have remembered aristocratic leadership i f there had been any ((1993) 221). Yet as we have seen, many scholars have begun to question Herodotus' dependence on aristocratic family traditions. The framing comments to Herodotus' narrative suggest that a democratic polls tradition lies behind Herodotus' account; moreover, Herodotus' own valuation o f political freedom would have led h i m to accept elements of the tradition with emphasized the effectiveness of democratic action. I f we discard the idea that Herodotus relies on aristocratic tradition, and instead posit a polls tradition as Herodotus' source then the fact that his account does not indicate aristocratic leadership may be attributable to his sources' aims (the validation of democratic power) and not to history. Several other features of Herodotus' account contribute to the impression that he relied on polls traditions and not aristocratic family traditions. First o f all it is significant that Cleisthenes does not
•
GREEK
HISTORY
c. 525
480
BC
541
play a particularly heroic role (cf. Lavelle (1993) 101). He engages in aristocratic factionalism and only appeals to the people when it is clear that he is losing. When Cleomenes demands Cleisthenes' expulsion, Cleisthenes withdraws. There is no mention o f an attempt by Cleisthenes to gather forces for a counter-attack. Instead, it is only after the anonymous Council and 'rest o f the Athenians' act, that Cleomenes is defeated and Cleisthenes and his supporters are allowed to return. Ober is thus correct to draw attention to the emphasis on collective action by the Athenian masses in Herodotus' account. However, i f Herodotus' account is, or includes elements of, a polls tradition, then the role o f the demos may be exaggerated i n accordance with fifth-century hostility to tyranny and valuation of the political power o f the demos: We must, therefore, be cautious about inferring anything about the political consciousness and role of the people as a whole in the late sixth century. Subsequent episodes of Herodotus' narrative do suggest a democratic polls tradition in which individual leadership and accomplishment is forgotten and collective accomplishment is emphasized. The Athenians resoundingly defeat a three-pronged attack engineered by the Spartans, and, as we have seen, their success is attributed to their new political system. Polls pride in this victory was marked by four-horse bronze chariot with dedicatory inscription celebrating the victory o f 'the sons of the Athenians' (5.74 78). I f the anonymity o f the revolution is indeed attributable to the needs o f a polls tradition, then the historical role o f individual elites on the Council and among the Athenians may have been lost. Yet this view does not fully counter the argument that the role o f the people in the establishment of the democracy was remembered because this is what actually happened. The people may have emphasized their role in the revolution both because it actually was important and because it suited their current political values. Furthermore, unlike previous instances o f aristocratic factionalism, the events o f 508/7 actually resulted in the reorganization o f political power on a wholly new basis. I t is a reasonable assumption that something must have been different about this instance o f aristocratic in-fighting and Herodotus' own account indicates that that something was the role o f a politically self-conscious and active demos. A self-directed, self-defining 10
'The role of the demos is emphasized also in Aristophanes' Lysislrala 273 82, which presumably reflects official and popular polis traditions. 511
542
SARA
FORSDYKE
p o p u l a r r e v o l u t i o n , t h e r e f o r e , is one w a y ordinary phenomenon
o f explaining the extra-
o f the c r e a t i o n o f d e m o c r a c y at the e n d
of
the s i x t h c e n t u r y ( O b e r (1998) 73). Although Herodotus
m e n t i o n s the n e w tribes a n d the r e d i s t r i b u -
t i o n o f t h e demes w i t h i n t h e m ( 5 . 6 9 . 2 ) , he does n o t discuss the i n s t i t u t i o n a l details o f the r e f o r m s o r Gleisthenes' i n t e n t i o n s i n p r o p o s i n g the r e f o r m s . T h e
lack o f c o n s t i t u t i o n a l d e t a i l as w e l l as the c l a i m
t h a t Gleisthenes was i m i t a t i n g his g r a n d f a t h e r Gleisthenes o f S i c y o n , has l e d historians to r i d i c u l e his p o l i t i c a l u n d e r s t a n d i n g . R e c e n t s c h o l a r s h i p has s h o w n m o r e respect f o r H e r o d o t u s ' p o l i t i c a l i n s i g h t , a n d has r i g h t l y focussed o n w h a t H e r o d o t u s ' omissions a n d emphasis tell us a b o u t his o w n
a n d his sources' aims. I n s t e a d o f c o n s t i t u t i o n a l
d e t a i l , H e r o d o t u s ' focus is the effect o f p o l i t i c a l f r e e d o m o n A t h e n s ' sub-se-quent h i s t o r y . T h i s suggests t h a t H e r o d o t u s was w o r k i n g f r o m d e m o c r a t i c polls t r a d i t i o n s w h i c h w e r e p r i m a r i l y c o n c e r n e d to l e g i t i m a t e A t h e n s ' c o n t e m p o r a r y p o l i t i c a l system. H e r o d o t u s '
own valu-
a t i o n o f p o l i t i c a l f r e e d o m w o u l d have l e d h i m to accept a n d i n d e e d to emphasize these aspects o f the t r a d i t i o n f r o m w h i c h he d r e w his account. The
Spartans
subsequently [c. 506) m a d e
a n a t t e m p t to restore
the t y r a n n y to A t h e n s . T h i s episode, t h e g r a n d finale to H e r o d o t u s ' a c c o u n t o f A t h e n s at the t i m e o f t h e I o n i a n R e v o l t , shows i n its l a n guage a n d themes t h a t i t derives f r o m A t h e n i a n polls t r a d i t i o n s a n d , I w o u l d argue, A t h e n i a n official a n d popular democratic traditions in particular. A
p r o m i n e n t feature is a debate b e t w e e n S p a r t a
and
h e r allies w h i c h is i n essence a discussion o f p o l i t i c a l systems, j u s t as is the C o n s t i t u t i o n a l D e b a t e i n B o o k T h r e e . T h i s debate,
however,
is n o t c o n d u c t e d i n abstract t e r m s , b u t t h r o u g h a n h i s t o r i c a l e x a m ple:
the t y r a n n y
of the Cypselids
at C o r i n t h
(mythologized
as
the a c c o u n t g i v e n o f i t m a y be). F u r t h e r m o r e , this debate is n o t o p e n e n d e d b u t r a t h e r results i n the v i n d i c a t i o n o f d e m o c r a c y over t y r a n n y . A l t h o u g h H e r o d o t u s ' a c c o u n t is u l t i m a t e l y shaped to fit t h e p o l i t i c a l ideals o f t h e A t h e n i a n s , A t h e n i a n d e m o c r a t i c t r a d i t i o n s are n o t the o n l y source f o r this c o m p l e x a n d f a s c i n a t i n g n a r r a t i v e . T h e
nar-
r a t i v e c o n t a i n s t r a d i t i o n s o f the C o r i n t h i a n s , i n its a c c o u n t o f t h e rise a n d r u l e o f Cypselus, as w e l l as w h a t is p r o b a b l y a w i d e s p r e a d , even P a n h e l l e n i c t r a d i t i o n a b o u t the dangers o f t y r a n n y , i n its anecdote a b o u t T h r a s y b u l u s ' advice to P e r i a n d e r . 3 1 I n d e e d i t is o n l y t h e
Murray (1987) 104 concludes that Delphi is probably the source of the tradition.
GREEK
HISTORY
c,
525—480
543
BG
l a r g e r f r a m e o f these t r a d i t i o n s — t h e defeat o f a S p a r t a n a t t e m p t to restore the t y r a n n y to A t h e n s — w h i c h seems t o c o m e d i r e c t l y f r o m A t h e n i a n d e m o c r a t i c polls t r a d i t i o n s . L e t us b e g i n w i t h the f r a m e . H e r o d o t u s p r o v i d e s t w o j u s t i f i c a t i o n s o f the Spartans, d e c i s i o n to t r y to restore the t y r a n n y , each o f w h i c h resonates against his f a m o u s statement a b o u t the association b e t w e e n d e m o c r a c y a n d civic strength q u o t e d above.
First the Spartans d i s c o v e r e d t h a t the
Alcmeonidae
h a d b r i b e d t h e D e l p h i c oracle w h i c h c o m m a n d e d t h e m to expel the Peisistratids. T h e
Spartans
were aggrieved that they h a d
harmed
t h e i r guest-friends, a n d , m o r e o v e r , h a d w o n n o g r a t i t u d e f r o m the A t h e n i a n s f o r i t . S e c o n d l y , the Spartans h a d l e a r n e d f r o m o r a c u l a r w r i t i n g s k e p t o n the A t h e n i a n acropolis t h a t t h e y w e r e d e s t i n e d to suffer h a r m f r o m the A t h e n i a n s . H e r o d o t u s elaborates o n these alleged S p a r t a n fears i n the f o l l o w i n g w a y : T h e Spartans . . . saw that the Athenians were growing greater and were not prepared to obey them. They recognized that the Attic race, i f free, w o u l d be equal i n power to them, but, i f held down by a tyrant, w o u l d be powerless and ready to obey. (5.91.1) "Agitated by false oracles, we expelled from their own country men who were close guest-friends to us and who undertook to keep Athens subservient. I n doing this, we handed over the city to an ungrateful people, who, when they had been liberated by us, tossed up their heads and arrogantly drove us and our king out o f their country. A n d now that they have established a reputation, they are g r o w i n g i n strength, as their neighbours, the Boeotians and Chalcideans have learned, and anyone else who wrongs them w i l l quickly learn." (5.91.2) This
j u s t i f i c a t i o n bears s t r i k i n g r e s e m b l a n c e to T h u c y d i d e s '
claim
t h a t Sparta's r e a l reason f o r s t a r t i n g the P e l o p o n n e s i a n W a r i n 431 was 'its fear o f t h e f u r t h e r g r o w t h o f A t h e n s , t h a t a l r e a d y t h e greater p a r t o f H e l l a s
seeing, as they d i d ,
was u n d e r the c o n t r o l o f
A t h e n s ' (1.88). T h u s this m o t i v e i n H e r o d o t u s seems to be i n f l u e n c e d b y later S p a r t a n concerns. Y e t the passages q u o t e d above also express v e r y c l e a r l y the c o n n e c t i o n b e t w e e n civic strength a n d
democracy
w h i c h s t r u c t u r e d H e r o d o t u s ' e a r l i e r n a r r a t i v e a n d t h e r e f o r e m a y be similarly derived f r o m A t h e n i a n democratic traditions. T h e
Spartans
are m a d e to c o n c u r t o o s t r o n g l y w i t h A t h e n i a n claims a b o u t the v a l u e o f t h e i r d e m o c r a c y f o r these passages to reflect a c t u a l S p a r t a n views at the t i m e . H i s t o r i c a l l y , t h e Spartans w e r e p r o b a b l y eager to put
A t h e n s i n t h e h a n d s o f H i p p i a s w h o c o u l d be c o u n t e d o n to
co-operate.
544
SARA
FORSDYKE
Sparta's allies had been unsympathetic to an earlier attempt to restore Isagoras, and they were no more convinced by Sparta on this occasion. The Corinthian delegate made the case against Sparta's proposal. His speech takes up almost five pages o f Herodotus' text and seems to be derived from multiple types of traditions. The essence of his argument is that the tyrant Cypselus and his son Periander secured their rule over the Corinthians through murder, banishments, and confiscations o f property, among other acts o f injustice against innocent Corinthians (5.92e.2—ipl). Yet Socles begins with an account of Cypselus' birth which contains many details irrelevant to this argument. This part of the account may reflect popularized versions of what was once a Cypselid family tradition since it credits Cypselus w i t h getting r i d o f the unjust Bacchiad family which ruled Corinth before the tyranny of Cypselus (5.92(3.1 - e . l ) . The centrepiece o f Socles' political argument is the story o f Periander's encounter with the tyrant Thrasybulus o f Miletus (5.92.1/n) which he uses to illustrate the brutality o f Periander's reign: the tyrant cut down innocent citizens just as Thrasybulus cut down the ears of grain in a wheat field. I t is this anecdote, as well as the story o f Periander's ill treatment o f his own wife and the women o f Corinth, which are Socles' prime examples o f the injustice o f tyranny. Socles' description o f Cypselus and Periander corresponds w i t h the theoretical critique o f tyranny in the Constitutional Debate. A tyrant is 'not accountable and can do whatever he likes; he transgresses the established customs; he commits many terrible deeds due to hubris and envy; he overturns ancestral customs and rapes women and puts men to death without trial' (3.80.3-5). These characteristics of tyranny are also paralleled i n other Greek literature, and especially Athenian tragedy. Herodotus and the traditions which were his sources, therefore, seem to be drawing on widespread Greek ideas about the nature o f tyranny. 52
53
Nevertheless, it is important to note that Socles' speech is made in order to prevent the Spartans from attempting to overthrow the >2
The story of Cypselus' birth contains elements found in folklore traditions worldwide (cf. Murray (1987) 104 and 110 ft.). Herodotus' narratives of the births of Cyrus (1.108-16) and Pisistratus (1.59.1-3) share the pattern of divine portant preceding the birth of a powerful individual. The second oracle concerning Cypselus' birth (5.92(3.3), however, is in accord with the general anti-tyrant theme of the speech as a whole, since it suggests that Cypselus will be responsible for the deaths of many Corinthians. See Lanza (1977) and Georgini (1993). 53
GREEK
HISTORY
c.
525-480
BC
545
newly established democracy at Athens. Thus the Athenian democracy is the point of contrast and ultimate beneficiary o f this diatribe against tyranny. This suggests that Athenian polis traditions may have coopted Corinthian polls traditions or even Panhellenic anti-tyrannical traditions for their own democratic purposes. We have already seen that the Spartan justifications o f their proposal betray traces o f Athenian democratic polls traditions. Likewise Socles' arguments serve the interests o f the Athenian democracy and it is likely that they derive from similar sources. :>+
Greek History
494-480
The final books o f Herodotus' Histories are concerned with the Persian invasions o f Greece. W i t h i n this narrative o f the Persian Wars, however, Herodotus has reason to mention a few episodes o f Greek history in the period 494-480 which are only tangentially related to the larger narrative. First o f all, the Persian campaigns on the European side o f the Hellespont give rise to a brief history of how the Athenian family of the Philaids under the leadership of Miltiades the Elder gained control of and ultimately were expelled from the Chersonnesus (6.33 41). T h e family o f the Philaids is generally believed to be behind the version o f events that Herodotus presents, since the account appears to be apologetic. The trials of Miltiades the Younger c. 492 (for tyranny i n the Chersonnesus) and i n 489 (for deception o f the demos after his failed Parian campaign), both mentioned by Herodotus, are thought to be the context i n which such a tradition may have been formulated and disseminated. 55
Darius' demand for earth and water from the Greek cities, c. 492, leads to a digression on the Spartan kingship, since Aegina's medism at this time was the occasion for the perpetuation o f the conflict between the two Spartan kings, Cleomenes and Demaratus. I n this account, we can detect some positive elements i n the traditions about
14
For a discussion of the ideological influences on the Thrasybulus anecdote in Herodotus, see Forsdyke (1999). " In particular, the claim that Miltiades was invited by the Dolonci to rule in the Chersonnesus (6.34-5), that Miltiades left Athens out of hatred for the tyranny of Pisistratus (6.35.3), and that Miltiades tried to persuade the Ionian tyrants to destroy the bridge during Darius' Scythian campaign (4.136) appear designed to defend him against charges of tyrannical inclinations.
546
SARA
Cleomenes,
FORSDYKE
w h o acts p r o m p t l y t o p r e v e n t A e g i n a ' s m e d i s m a n d is
t h w a r t e d by Demaratus. Herodotus comments that while Cleomenes was w o r k i n g f o r t h e g o o d o f G r e e c e , D e m a r a t u s was at h o m e slandering Cleomenes Cleomenes
(6.61.1). H e r o d o t u s
also r e c o r d s , h o w e v e r ,
b r i b e d t h e D e l p h i c oracle t o declare D e m a r a t u s
m a t e a n d thus caused D e m a r a t u s portrait of Demaratus
that
illegiti-
t o flee to Persia (6.66-70).
The
i n t h e rest o f the Histories is q u i t e c o m p l i -
m e n t a r y , c o n s i d e r i n g t h a t he was essentially a t r a i t o r to Greece.
De-
m a r a t u s gives X e r x e s g o o d advice f o r his i n v a s i o n o f Greece (7.235), y e t also sends a message to S p a r t a w a r n i n g o f the i m m a n e n t i n v a sion (7.239). D e m a r a t u s , m o r e o v e r , serves as a spokesman f o r G r e e k a n d especially S p a r t a n values i n t h e c o n t e x t o f b a r b a r i a n Persia. T h i s a m b i g u o u s t r a d i t i o n seems t o d e r i v e f r o m t h e m u l t i p l e needs o f its tellers. First t h e r e was t h e n e e d o f t h e S p a r t a n r o y a l houses t o d e f e n d t h e i r ancestors. S e c o n d l y , there was the need o f t h e S p a r t a n polis t o l e g i t i m a t e c o m m u n a l values, p r i m a r i l y the S p a r t a n F i n a l l y t h e r e are H e r o d o t u s ' Demaratus
figure
o w n l i t e r a r y aims. F o r
military ethic. Herodotus,
p r e s e n t a t i o n o f G r e e k values t h r o u g h c o n t r a s t to the Persian ple.
As
many
the
c l e a r l y is a c o n v e n i e n t c h a r a c t e r f o r t h e d r a m a t i c
students o f H e r o d o t u s
exam-
have n o t i c e d , D e m a r a t u s
the p a t t e r n o f t h e 'wise adviser' w h i c h H e r o d o t u s
fits
uses t h r o u g h o u t
the Histories to give expression to G r e e k v a l u e s . 0 6 I n c l u d e d i n this t h i r d episode o f S p a r t a n h i s t o r y is a b r i e f m e n t i o n o f a n i m p o r t a n t v i c t o r y o f S p a r t a over h e r p e r p e t u a l A r g o s [c. 494). T h e
enemy,
d e v a s t a t i n g effect o f this w a r o n A r g o s is m e n -
tioned again i n the context o f the appeal o f the Greek confederacy to A r g o s i n 4 8 1 (7.148). I n each case, the w a r is n o t m e n t i o n e d f o r its o w n sake as a n i m p o r t a n t event, n o r is its significance f o r t h e b a l a n c e o f p o w e r i n the Peloponnese
discussed. R a t h e r ,
is c o n c e r n e d w i t h the r e l a t i o n s h i p o f C l e o m e n e s ' against t h e A r g i v e s
t o his g r u e s o m e
Herodotus
acts o f sacrilege
d e a t h , as w e l l as t h e conse-
quences o f A r g o s ' loss f o r its role i n t h e Persian W a r s . I t is a p p a r ent
that Herodotus
a n d his sources have r e m e m b e r e d a n d
shaped
the C l e o m e n e s m a t e r i a l f o r its m o r a l i m p l i c a t i o n s , w h i l e A r g o s '
dev-
astating loss is also r e m e m b e r e d as a p a r t i a l e x p l a n a t i o n f o r the city's
56
On the figure of the wise advisor, see Bischoff (1932) and Lattimore (1939). For an argument that the Demaratus episode is influenced not simply by Panhellenic Greek values but also specifically by Athenian democratic values, see Forsdyke (2001).
GREEK
HISTORY
c.
525-480
547
BC
neutrality in the Persian Wars. M o d e r n historians consider Sparta's victory over Argos to be of great importance in its own right. Sparta's victory consolidated her position o f dominance in the Peloponnese and shows that, despite the claim o f some of Herodotus' sources that Cleomenes was 'not quite right in his head' (5.42.1), Cleomenes was in fact a capable and strong king (Griffiths (1989)). Moreover, despite Herodotus' assertion that Cleomenes ruled for only a short time, his own narrative shows that Cleomenes was a driving force in Spartan policy from the 520s through the 490s. Herodotus, however, concentrates on the personal fate of Cleomenes, finishing off his 'biography' with the discovery of Cleomenes' bribery of the Delphic oracle, Cleomenes' flight first to Thessaly and then to Arcadia, and finally Cleomenes' recall to Sparta, madness and gruesome death (6.74—5). This selection o f material must be partly due to the rival traditions of royal families, but also to popular and official polls traditions, as well as panhellenic traditions. These latter sources are indicated by Herodotus himself, as he attributes different explanations of Cleomenes' demise to 'most Greeks', 'the Athenians', and 'the Argives' (6.75). Aegina's medism also provides an opportunity for a further instalment of the history of the conflict between Athens and Aegina (6.85-93). It is likely that these events were remembered i n the polls traditions of Athens and Aegina partly as the 'ancient history' of their ongoing conflict in the later fifth century. The ultimate significance o f these events for Herodotus' narrative, on the other hand, is mentioned in a later narrative: hostilities between Athens and Aegina in these years led the Athenians, on the advice o f Themistocles, to use public funds to build a fleet which was ultimately used against Persia (7.144). The decision to build a fleet (c. 482) is one o f the few details o f Athenian social and political history that Herodotus provides. Although Herodotus does mention the suspicions about the Alcmeonids after Marathon (6.121), the internal politics o f Athens o f the 490s and 480s do not fit his mandate o f recording 'great deeds' and explaining the causes of the war with the Persians. Yet evidence from other sources suggests that these years were a particularly tumultuous period in the young democracy's history. From Thucydides' history we learn a few more details about Themistocles' career and policies, and from ostraka we get some names of leading political figures. The Athenalon 37
57
Thuc. 1.89-93, 134-8. For the ostraka, see Lang (1990) and Brenne (2000) and (2001).
548
SARA FORSDYKE
Polileia's r e c o r d o f five ostracisms i n t h e 480s (the first t i m e the i n s t i t u t i o n was used) a n d o f a r e f o r m o f t h e m e t h o d f o r selecting a r c h o n s p i q u e h i s t o r i a n s ' c u r i o s i t y , yet o n l y c o n f i r m h o w Athens'
d o m e s t i c h i s t o r y i n this p e r i o d . '
Plataean a i d to A t h e n s brief account of h o w
little w e k n o w
of
8
at M a r a t h o n p r o v i d e s t h e occasion for a
Plataea's
alliance w i t h A t h e n s
was the result
o f the i n t e r v e n t i o n b y the m a j o r G r e e k p o w e r s (Sparta, C o r i n t h , a n d A t h e n s ) i n the B o e o t i a n L e a g u e c. 5 1 9 (6.108). H e r o d o t u s e x p l a i n the reasons f o r C l e o m e n e s '
does n o t
presence i n C e n t r a l G r e e c e at
this t i m e , a l t h o u g h he does give a g l i m p s e o f i n t e r n a l tensions w i t h i n the B o e o t i a n
L e a g u e as w e l l as t h e roles t h a t t h e m a j o r
powers
p l a y e d i n s e t d i n g disputes b e t w e e n states. I t is clear f r o m T h u c y d i d e s ' s t a t e m e n t t h a t the d e s t r u c t i o n o f Plataea
i n 427
b y the
Spartans
o c c u r r e d i n the 9 3 r d year o f the alliance b e t w e e n A t h e n s a n d Plataea, t h a t this alliance d i d i n d e e d date back t o the incidents that H e r o d o t u s describes (3.68.5). F i n a l l y ,
the appeal o f the G r e e k c o n f e d e r a c y
to
t h e t y r a n t G e l o n leads to a digression o n S i c i l i a n h i s t o r y i n these years (7.153). H e r o d o t u s '
a c c o u n t covers the m a j o r i n c i d e n t s l e a d -
i n g t o G e l o n ' s seizure o f p o w e r first i n G e l a a n d t h e n i n
Syracuse.
G e l o n ' s v i c t o r y against the C a r t h a g i n i a n s at H i m e r a i n 4 8 0 is also mentioned. W e
m a y surmise t h a t H e r o d o t u s
g a t h e r e d the i n f o r m a -
t i o n f o r his a c c o u n t o f S i c i l i a n affairs f r o m polls t r a d i t i o n s o f the W e s t e r n G r e e k poleis w h i l e he l i v e d i n T h u r i i i n S o u t h e r n I t a l y .
Conclusion The
examination of Herodotus'
t r e a t m e n t o f G r e e k h i s t o r y shows
h o w s k i l f u l l y he c o l l e c t e d , c o m p a r e d , a n d c o n n e c t e d the o r a l t r a d i tions o f families a n d Moreover,
c o m m u n i t i e s to f o r m a coherent
account.
w e have seen h o w t h e d i f f e r e n t types o f t r a d i t i o n s w h i c h
constituted Herodotus' t h e i r specific
sources each s h a p e d t h e past a c c o r d i n g t o
fifth-century
needs. T h e s e needs i n c l u d e the l e g i t i m a -
t i o n o f c o n t e m p o r a r y social a n d p o l i t i c a l values a n d the defence
of
past c o n d u c t . F i n a l l y , a n d p e r h a p s m o s t i m p o r t a n t l y , we have seen
5,1
Alh. Pol. 22. Herodotus does comment (6.109.2) that Callimachus, the polemarch at Marathon, had been chosen 'by the bean' (i.e., by lot), a statement which contradicts the testimony of the Ath. Pol. and has fuelled discussion of how archonship functioned in the 490s.
GREEK H I S T O R Y c.
525-480
549
BC
how Herodotus himself selects and organizes his material according to the aims o f his history, his interests, and values. Central to Herodotus' aims are the demonstration o f the causes o f the rise and fall of individuals and communities and the use of the past to illustrate, the value o f political freedom. The contemporary significance o f the former aim with regard to the Athenian empire and later with regard to the Athenian democracy has often been noted. Herodotus' Histories record fifth-century Greeks' understanding of their past and thus give us access to their ways o f seeing the world, and not solely to the views o f an elite Greek intellectual. While these perceptions often do not reveal the past that they purport to recall, they do provide a window into the Greeks' self-understanding which is unique among the literature that we possess from this time. 59
r 9
' Fornara (1971a) 37-58 and 75-91; Raaflaub (1987), Stadter (1992) and Moles (1996).
CHAPTER T W E N T Y - F O U R
T H E PERSIAN INVASIONS Thomas Harrison
I f we may say of Thucydides that he 'wrote the Peloponnesian war' (Loraux (1986a)), it is no less true to say o f his predecessor that the unsuccessful Persian invasions o f Greece in the early fifth century are his own creation. A t the same time, it is clear that the Persian Wars are the centrepiece, the culmination o f his Histories, as the words o f his Proem make clear: 'the great and marvellous deeds, both o f Greeks and barbarians, and especially through what cause they made war with one another'. Clearly the 'great and marvellous deeds' are made up o f much that has only the most tenuous link to the build-up to the Persians' expedition to Greece. The unity o f any literary work, as Charles Fornara has written ((1971a) ch. 1), is relative, and the Histories present themselves, at least initially, as no more than a loosely unified structure, one that pushes to the margins o f human experience, which in its course takes in such wonderful-but-true stories as that o f the Pedasian priestess who grew a beard whenever trouble brewed (1.175, 8.104). Nevertheless, one o f the most significant advances i n scholarship on Herodotus has been to show the subtle ways in which Herodotus' narrative is. structured. The Persian invasion o f Xerxes, though it is marked off from the rest o f the Histories by the episode of the dreams that come to the king and to Artabanus at the beginning o f Book Seven, is at the same time immaculately prepared i n earlier books, implicit in Herodotus' structure is his explanation o f the war's causes. 1
See e.g., the i n t r o d u c t i o n of D e w a l d (1998).
THE
The The
PERSIAN
Persian
553
INVASIONS
Wars in
the H i s t o r i e s
beginning and end of Herodotus'
w o r k i m p l i c i t l y place the
Persian W a r s i n a series o f conflicts b e t w e e n A s i a a n d E u r o p e . story o f r e c i p r o c a l w i f e - s t e a l i n g w i t h w h i c h H e r o d o t u s
Histories
The
opens his
is one w h i c h — i n g e n u o u s l y o r n o t - d i e ascribes to l e a r n e d
Persians (1.1
5). These Persians d e e m e d t h a t t h e i r e n m i t y w i t h the
Greeks b e g a n w i t h the f o o l i s h o v e r r e a c t i o n o f the Greeks to the theft of Helen.
'For
the Persians c l a i m A s i a a n d the b a r b a r i a n peoples
t h a t i n h a b i t i t as t h e i r o w n a n d consider E u r o p e a n d the people o f Greece as d i s t i n c t ' (1.4.4). T h i s v i e w o f the Persian W a r s as r o o t e d i n a cycle o f conflicts is c o n f i r m e d by the e n d o f the
Histories.2
The
Persian c l a i m to a l l A s i a is r e p e a t e d (9.116.3) i n the course o f the story o f t h e Persian g o v e r n o r A r t a y c t e s
a n d his sacrilege against
the G r e e k h e r o Protesilaus (9.11620). T h r o u g h Protesilaus, the first G r e e k to die i n the course o f the T r o j a n w a r , a n d X a n t h i p p u s ,
the
father o f Pericles, the episode equates the n o w drastically chastened Persian e m p i r e b o t h w i t h the G r e e k c a m p a i g n t o T r o y a n d to t h e A t h e n i a n e x p a n s i o n i s m o f the fifth c e n t u r y . 3 T h e r e are s i m i l a r overtones to the final c h a p t e r o f the the Persians'
Histories.4
A t the c r i t i c a l j u n c t u r e o f
conquest o f the l u x u r i o u s M e d e s ,
C y r u s enjoins the
Persians t h a t i t is better 'to live i n a b a r r e n c o u n t r y a n d rule t h a n to live i n fertile p l a i n s a n d be t h e slaves o f o t h e r s ' (9.122). T h r o u g h the chapter's allusion to a n earlier s i m p l i c i t y , a n d t h r o u g h the i d e n tity o f C y r u s ' i n t e r l o c u t o r — A r t e m b a r e s , whose son C y r u s h a d chastized as a p l a y g r o u n d ' k i n g ' before his i n n a t e m o n a r c h y h a d been realized (1.114)'—Herodotus appeals back to the outset o f the Persian e m p i r e at the m o m e n t o f its eclipse b y a y o u n g e r p o w e r . J u s t as Sandanis Persians
h a d w a r n e d Croesus
(1.71; cf. 1.126)
o f the f o l l y o f m a k i n g w a r o n the
w h o w o r e leather trousers, d r a n k w a t e r ,
a n d i n h a b i t e d a b a r r e n c o u n t r y , b u t w o u l d q u i c k l y develop a taste f o r finer
t h i n g s - -so Pausanias after Plataea d e m o n s t r a t e d the a b s u r d i t y
- Sec esp. ISoeileker .1988), Druald : 1997 . For the argument, however, thai the opening of the Wnlmes implies a linn distinction of mvth and lii-ti>r\ ^as espoused by e.g. Momigliano (1960) 14 15), sec Nickau (1990),'Harrison (2000b) 196-207, and Ch. 22, pp. 497-9, this volume. See, more generally, Fornara (1971a), Stadter (1992), Moles (1996). See esp. Redfield (1985) 114. For the significance in Greek of Cyrus' name, see Harrison (2000b) 262. 3 4 5
554
THOMAS
HARRISON
o f the Persian desire f o r Greece b y setting Persian a n d S p a r t a n meals alongside o n e a n o t h e r (9.82). Herodotus'
B o o k O n e i n large p a r t tells t h e s t o r y o f C r o e s u s '
r e p l a c e m e n t b y C y r u s as t h e G r e e k s ' b a r b a r i a n b o g e y m a n . L y d i a n k i n g Croesus,
The
' t h e first m a n w e k n o w t o have b e g u n u n j u s t
deeds against t h e G r e e k s ' , f o o l i s h l y supposed t h a t he c o u l d c o n q u e r the
fledgling
empire o f Cyrus (1.46.1,
185.1), a n d so b y his defeat
b r o u g h t t h e Persians a n d t h e Greeks face t o face f o r t h e first t i m e . Croesus h a d b r o u g h t a b o u t t h e first s u b j u g a t i o n o f I o n i a (1.92.1); n o w , t h r o u g h C y r u s , I o n i a was enslaved f o r a second t i m e (1.169.2). The
rest o f B o o k O n e sees t h e c o m p l e t i o n o f the Persians'
conquest
o f Asia. C y r u s , as his m o t h e r ' s d r e a m s h a d f o r e b o d e d , h a d b e e n dest i n e d t o r u l e a l l o f A s i a ( 1 . 1 0 8 ; cf. 1.209); t h r o u g h his defeat o f Astyages, a n d the finishing t o u c h o f his conquest o f Assyria (1.177-8.1), the d r e a m was f u l f i l l e d . T h e r u l e o f A s i a is seen repeatedly as a single, d i s t i n c t prize.'' F r o m this p o i n t i n t h e Histories, t w o m a i n m o v e m e n t s o c c u r . T h e first
is t h e Persians' c o n t i n u e d e x p a n s i o n b e y o n d t h e i r a l l o t t e d ter-
ritory. As Xerxes later noted i n proposing the expedition
against
G r e e c e , these e a r l i e r conquests f o r m e d a p a t t e r n : M e n o f Persia, I shall not be the first to introduce this custom among you, b u t shall adopt i t , having received i t from m y forefathers. For as I learn from older men, we have never remained inactive since we wrested the sovereign power from the Medes, and Cyrus overthrew Astyages: b u t the deity leads the way, and to us w h o follow his guidance many things result to our advantage. W h a t deeds Cyrus and Cambyses and m y father Darius have achieved, and what nations they have added to our empire, no one need mention to you w h o know them well. (7.8a. 1; cf. V e r d i n (1982)) X e r x e s ' secondary a u d i e n c e ( o f readers) m a y also appreciate o t h e r patterns, however.
T h o u g h o t h e r m o r e successful c a m p a i g n s go r e l -
atively u n h e r a l d e d , C y r u s ' e x p e d i t i o n against t h e Massagetai (an exped i t i o n w h i c h e n d e d i n his d e a t h ,
1 . 2 0 1 - 1 4 ) , C a m b y s e s ' against t h e
E t h i o p i a n s ( 3 . 2 5 - 6 ) , o r D a r i u s ' against t h e Scythians ( 4 . 8 3 - 1 4 4 ) , are all e x p e d i t i o n s t o o f a r , e x p e d i t i o n s w h i c h exceeded t h e n a t u r a l l i m its t o t h e Persian e m p i r e ( L a t e i n e r
(1989) c h . 6), a n d o n w h i c h t h e
q u e s t i o n o f t h e Persians' safe r e t u r n t o t h e i r h e a r t l a n d l o o m s l a r g e .
" Cf. 3.88.1, 4.1, 4.4, 7.1.2.
THE
The
Scythian
PERSIAN
555
INVASIONS
c a m p a i g n presents a n a n a l o g u e
to the later
Persian
i n v a s i o n o f Greece i n a n u m b e r o f o t h e r w a y s : 7 the Scythians,
for
e x a m p l e , o n l y u n i t e against t h e Persian t h r e a t w h e n i t is p r o v e d to t h e m that they
are a l l the objects o f D a r i u s '
revenge
campaign
(4 J 1 8 - 1 9 ) . The
Persians' g r a d u a l e x p a n s i o n p r o v i d e s the n a r r a t i v e h o o k
which Herodotus
on
hangs the descriptions o f the customs o r nomoi o f
f o r e i g n peoples w h i c h fill m u c h o f the e a r l y books o f the Histories.
8
H i s d e s c r i p t i o n o f the Persians' o w n customs f o l l o w s t h e i r a r r i v a l as the masters o f A s i a (1.130). T h e I o n i a n s ' offer o f submission to C y r u s leads to discussion o f the history o f the Ionians a n d Aeolians ( L 1 4 2 - 5 1 ) . T h e l e n g t h y ' d i g r e s s i o n ' o n the h i s t o r y a n d customs o f E g y p t takes its start f r o m the conquest o f E g y p t b y C a m b y s e s (2.1). T h i s
pat-
t e r n o f n a r r a t i v e f r a m i n g e t h n o g r a p h y is m o s t c l e a r l y revealed b y a n e x c e p t i o n : after his d e s c r i p t i o n o f the peoples o f L i b y a ,
Herodotus
notes t h a t m o s t o f these L i b y a n tribes h a d p a i d little a t t e n t i o n to the k i n g o f the M e d e s (4.197.2). H e r o d o t u s also reinforces this impression o f the Persians' a c c u m u l a t i o n o f p o w e r b y p e r i o d i c reviews: the accession o f Cambyses, a n d his decision to l a u n c h a c a m p a i g n against E g y p t , are the o p p o r t u n i t y for his observation t h a t C y r u s ' son regarded the I o n i a n s a n d A e o l i a n s w h o m he t o o k o n this c a m p a i g n as ' h e r e d i t a r y slaves' (2.1). T h e
succession o f D a r i u s leads t o a s u m m a r y
of
all the peoples o f the e m p i r e a n d o f the t r i b u t e t h a t t h e y b r i n g h i m (3.90-7).
Like Herodotus'
l a t e r reviews o f the peoples at X e r x e s '
c o m m a n d i n his e x p e d i t i o n against Greece ( 7 . 6 1 - 9 9 ) , such techniques all a d d to the i m p r e s s i o n o f the relentless a c c u m u l a t i o n o f p o w e r , so setting the scene, a n d p i l i n g u p the stakes, f o r the n a r r a t i v e
of
invasion.9 T h e o t h e r m a i n m o v e m e n t t h r o u g h the early books o f the Histories is the g r a d u a l a c c u m u l a t i o n o f t h e causes o f w a r . 1 0 A t the outset, i t appears t h a t w e are i n a w o r l d o f discrete p o p u l a t i o n s . T h e
Phoenician
ship t h a t wends its w a y f r o m the R e d Sea t h r o u g h the M e d i t e r r a n e a n to A r g o s , w h e r e the a b d u c t i o n o r e l o p e m e n t o f l o triggers a cycle
7
See Hartog (1988) e.g., 51; from a different perspective Fol and Hammond (1988) 234. Contrast e.g., Murray's emphasis, (1988) 261-3, on two distinct 'elements' in the Histories: the 'collection of logoi' and the history of events; see also Ch. 14, p. 321, this volume. Harrison (2000a) ch. 8, (2000c); see also Ch. 14, pp. 328-361, this volume. Contrast Sealey (1957) 8, positing a break between two chains of grievances. 8
9
10
556
THOMAS
HARRISON
o f w a r b e t w e e n Greeks a n d b a r b a r i a n s , is represented as b e i n g the first c o n t a c t b e t w e e n these peoples (1.1). T h e
possibility o f p o p u l a -
tions r e m a i n i n g discrete is m a i n t a i n e d i n a n u m b e r o f l a t e r passages o f the Histories, N i t o c r i s ' c o n s t r u c t i o n o f isolationist b a r r i e r s b e t w e e n herself a n d the 'great a n d restless e m p i r e o f the M e d e s '
(1.185-6),
the advice o f Bias o r o f Sandanis to Croesus n o t to t h i n k o f attacki n g the G r e e k islands o r the Persians (1.27, 71),
o r the p r o u d mes-
sage o f the k i n g o f the E t h i o p i a n s to the spies o f Cambyses (3.21.2—3): T h e king o f the Ethiopians advises the king o f the Persians, when the Persians can thus easily draw a bow o f this size, then to make war on the M a c r o b i a n Ethiopians w i t h more numerous forces, but until that time to let h i m thank the gods who have not inspired the sons of the Ethiopians w i t h a desire to add another land to their own. The
E t h i o p i a n s are clearly u n l i k e the Persians i n h a v i n g n o desire
t o r u l e o v e r others. S u c h passages seem also, h o w e v e r , to i m p l y the futility of any
a t t e m p t t o h o l d b a c k such expansionist
powers.
m i g h t be b e t t e r i f peoples w e r e able to r e m a i n a p a r t i n peace,
It but
c o n t a c t is i n e v i t a b l e — a n d , j u s t as i n e v i t a b l y , c o n t a c t leads to w a r . T h a t is also the i m p l i c i t m o r a l o f a g r o w i n g
flood
of individual
contacts b e t w e e n Greeks a n d Persians, a l l o f w h i c h have d i s p r o p o r t i o n a t e consequences. T h e Persian g o v e r n o r O r o e t e s ' personal grudge against Polycrates
b r o u g h t the S a m i a n t y r a n t to his d e a t h , b y
har-
nessing his g r e e d f o r w e a l t h a n d l u r i n g h i m w i t h the false p r o m i s e o f the means w i t h w h i c h to realize his a m b i t i o n s (3.120 5). T h e
des-
p e r a t i o n o f D e m o c e d e s (see G r i f f i t h s (1987)), the G r e e k d o c t o r discovered a m o n g s t the spoils o f Oroetes a n d t a k e n to the Persian c o u r t , to escape f r o m the g i l d e d cage o f Susa a n d r e t u r n t o his h o m e c i t y o f C r o t o n leads to his b e i n g sent o n a f a c t - f i n d i n g mission to Greece (3.129-38), preparatory
to l a t e r c o n q u e s t : 1 1
'these w e r e
the
first
Persians to c o m e f r o m A s i a to G r e e c e ' ( 3 . 1 3 8 . 4 ) , H e r o d o t u s observes. The
chance m e e t i n g o f D a r i u s a n d the S a m i a n Syloson leads b y a
c i r c u i t o u s r o u t e to the d e s t r u c t i o n o f Samos, its b e i n g h a n d e d
over
to Syloson e m p t y o f its i n h a b i t a n t s (3.139—49). S i m i l a r l y the eagerness f o r t y r a n n y
o f the t w o Paeonians Pigres
( t h r o u g h the s t u n t , staged before D a r i u s ,
a n d Mastyes results
o f t h e i r h a r d - w o r k i n g sis-
ter) i n the P a e o n i a n s ' f o r c e d t r a n s p o r t a t i o n to A s i a ( 5 . 1 2 - 4 4 ) .
A Persian policy according to Martin (1952).
THE
PERSIAN
557
INVASIONS
M o s t f a t e f u l o f a l l , h o w e v e r , is the a p p e a l to Aristagoras o f M i l e t u s by a g r o u p o f N a x i a n exiles f o r s u p p o r t i n t h e i r restoration (5.30 Aristagoras appeals i n t u r n to his ' f r i e n d ' A r t a p h e r n e s .
6).
By d w e l l i n g
o n the w e a l t h o f N a x o s , a n d p o r t r a y i n g the i s l a n d as a s t e p p i n g stone to the Cyclades a n d Euboea, Aristagoras ensures that Artaphernes gives his h e l p , b u t his q u a r r e l w i t h A r t a p h e r n e s '
a p p o i n t e d general
M e g a b a t e s means t h a t the a t t e m p t o n N a x o s fails; this, c o u p l e d w i t h the costs o f the e x p e d i t i o n , a n d a t i m e l y message f r o m Histiaeus o f M i l e t u s — a g a i n , like D e m o c e d e s ,
m o t i v a t e d b y the desire t o escape
f r o m Susa to his h o m e (cf. 5.106-7)- - e n c o u r a g e A r i s t a g o r a s to i n i tiate the I o n i a n r e v o l t against Persia, d'he r e v o l t is c o u n t e r - p r o d u c tive: A r i s t a g o r a s ' o w n c i t y o f M i l e t u s is razed to the g r o u n d ; I o n i a , H e r o d o t u s adds i n reference to B o o k O n e ,
is enslaved f o r the t h i r d
time (6.32)—only to be l i b e r a t e d w i t h t h e i r second r e v o l t at the close o f the Histories, at the t i m e o f the battle o f M y c a l e (9.104). B u t the r e v o l t has l a r g e r consequences
insofar as i t e m b r o i l s the
Greeks o f the m a i n l a n d i n the struggle w i t h Persian a u t h o r i t y . J u s t as he h a d t e m p t e d the Persians w i t h the i m a g e o f the w e a l t h
of
N a x o s a n d the G r e e k i s l a n d s — a n d j u s t as Histiaeus persuaded D a r i u s to release h i m w i t h the p r o m i s e , p r e d i c t a b l y b r o k e n , t h a t he w o u l d n o t change his clothes till he h a d m a d e
S a r d i n i a t r i b u t a r y to the
k i n g (5.106.6, 6.2.1)- -so Aristagoras hooks the A t h e n i a n s w i t h tales o f the fabulous w e a l t h o f the peoples o f A s i a , a n d o f t h e i r weakness t o resist i n v a s i o n ( 5 . 9 7 ; cf. 5 . 4 9 ) . T h e Athenians
t w e n t y ships l e n t b y
the
to the r e v o l t w e r e , i n H e r o d o t u s ' j u d g m e n t , 'the b e g i n -
n i n g o f evils f o r b o t h Greeks a n d B a r b a r i a n s ' (5.97.3) sarily a c o m m e n t o n the m o r a l i t y o r g o o d sense o f the
-not necesAthenians'
a c t i o n b u t s i m p l y a n o b s e r v a t i o n o f the f a t e f u l i n s t a n t at w h i c h the fuse f o r the Persian i n v a s i o n o f the G r e e k m a i n l a n d was l i t ( 5 . 1 0 5 ) : 1 2 I t is said that as soon as he discovered these things, taking no account of the Ionians, as he well knew that these w o u l d not go unpunished i n their revolt, he asked: 'who are these Athenians?' and being told he called for his bow and, placing an arrow on it, he released it up into the sky, and as he shot it into the air said: ' O Zeus, grant me my revenge against the Athenians'. A n d after saying these things he instructed one of his servants, whenever dinner was laid before h i m , to say three times: ' O master, remember the Athenians!'
12
Harrison (2000b) 242; contrast e.g., Momigliano (1960) 16.
558
THOMAS
HARRISON
C o u p l e d w i t h the e n c o u r a g e m e n t o f the Pisistratids a n d t h e p r e t e x t o f the A t h e n i a n s ' refusal o f e a r t h a n d w a t e r , his d a i l y r e m i n d e r e v e n t u a l l y p r o v o k e d D a r i u s to a p p o i n t D a t i s a n d A r t a p h e r n e s w i t h orders to enslave A t h e n s a n d b r i n g b a c k those enslaved to A s i a (6.94). T h e i r subsequent defeat at M a r a t h o n m a d e D a r i u s , still incensed over the fate o f Sardis, even m o r e eager to subdue Greece ( 7 . I d ) ,
a double
m o t i v e t h e n i n h e r i t e d b y his son X e r x e s (7.8<x.2—(3, 138.1). H e r o d o t u s ' a c c u m u l a t i o n o f causes m i g h t seem at first sight t o be m e r e l y the absence o f h i s t o r i c a l e x p l a n a t i o n a n d analysis: 1 3 r a t h e r t h a n c h o o s i n g b e t w e e n a l t e r n a t i v e causes f o r t h e w a r s , he s i m p l y amasses t h e m i n a n u n d d y c h a i n reaction o f cause a n d effect. H o w e v e r , the care taken b y H e r o d o t u s
to keep d i f f e r e n t causes ' i n p l a y ' sug-
gests t h a t this d o m i n o - p a t t e r n reflects a m o r e c o n s i d e r e d v i e w
of
c a u s a t i o n , one w h i c h he has i m p l e m e n t e d systematically (contrast M o m i g l i a n o (1960) 15). H e r o d o t u s ' emphasis o n the role o f the i n d i v i d u a l m a y reflect a w o r l d - v i e w ( i f n o t a w o r l d ) i n w h i c h the i n d i v i d u a l was m o r e i m p o r t a n t (Forrest (1979)). T h e c o m i n g t o g e t h e r o f causes i n the case o f A r i s t a g o r a s ' decision to r e v o l t m a y reflect a fatalistic c o n c e p t i o n o f h i s t o r y : c o i n c i d e n c e s , o r p a t t e r n s o f h u m a n a c t i o n t h a t seem to leave n o choice to the i n d i v i d u a l , are f r e q u e n t l y interpreted by Herodotus
as evidence o f the d i v i n e h a n d i n events
( H a r r i s o n (2000b) 2 3 4 - 4 0 ) .
The
emphases o n the first m o m e n t
of
c o n t a c t b e t w e e n adversaries a n d o n the a c c u m u l a t i o n o f grievances are b o t h , m o r e o v e r , characteristics s h a r e d b y t h e w o r k o f H e r o d o t u s ' successor, T h u c y d i d e s . H i s a c c o u n t o f the B a t t l e o f Sybota, for e x a m p l e , highlights i n s l o w - m o t i o n detail the instant at w h i c h the A t h e n i a n s t u r n f r o m the defensive to the offensive ( T h u c . 1.49). W i t h T h u c y d i d e s even m o r e t h a n w i t h H e r o d o t u s ,
m o d e r n critics have m i s t a k e n this
focus o n 'first c o n t a c t ' f o r t h e s i m p l i s t i c desire to allocate b l a m e .
If
t h a t h a d b e e n e i t h e r h i s t o r i a n ' s a i m , i t is one t h a t they c o u l d have a c h i e v e d w i t h m u c h greater ease a n d c l a r i t y : r a t h e r , i n b o t h cases, t h e i r p u r p o s e is to b r i n g o u t the f u l l c o m p l e x i t y o f the w a r ' s causes. The
seriousness o f H e r o d o t u s '
strategy i n t h e early books o f his
Histories is e m p h a s i z e d also b y the w a y i n w h i c h m a n y o f t h e themes
13
See e.g., Murray's characterization of Herodotean causation, (1988) 463-4, as 'limited to two main areas, the explanation of events in terms of personalities, and belief in the inevitability of the rise and fall of states'; 'it is hard to find fault', he continues, 'with [Herodotus'] general view that the only adequate explanation for the Persian Wars must be a complete account of relations between the two peoples since the conquest of the Ionian cities in 545 B C . Contrast Rood (1998) 213.
-
THE
PERSIAN
INVASIONS
559
and techniques o f those books recur i n the 'debate' on the expedition at the beginning of Book Seven. Like Aristagoras and Histiaeus before h i m , Mardonius encouraged Xerxes with the promise of the fertility o f Greece 'worthy to be possessed by the king of all mortals' (7.5.3)—for Mardonius had an ambition to be the governor o f Greece (7.6.1). He was supported then by a host o f coincidences: the invitation of the Thessalian Aleuadae, the pressure of the Peisistratid exiles of Athens and, in their entourage, the oracle-monger Onomacritus with carefully tailored prophecies from the collection o f Musaeus (7.6.2). As we have seen, Xerxes is motivated also by the desire to maintain the 'custom' of continuing expansion established by his predecessors (7.8a. 1); he would not be the son o f Darius, the son of Hystaspes (and so on), i f he d i d not exact vengeance on those who had torched Sardis (7.11.2). A t the same time, Persian expansion is hardly morally discriminating. It would be a terrible thing, Mardonius professes, i f the Sacae and the Indians were subdued when they had committed no injustice and the Greeks were not when they had (7.9a. 1). Similarly, though the pretext o f avenging Sardis is feebly maintained, Xerxes' real goal, it is repeatedly emphasized, is much greater: no less than to unite Asia and Europe, to create an empire 'bordering the aither of Zeus' (7.8",). The causes o f the expedition's ruin, however, are visible as soon as it is launched. The size and magnificence o f the Persian force, the confidence o f Xerxes i n the Persians' good fortune, and the good sense o f Artabanus i n recognizing the jealousy o f the divine all point to a reversal. The dreams that come to Xerxes and Artabanus are clearly intended to deceive. Even i f (as i n the case o f Croesus, 1.91) we may judge Xerxes somehow as 'responsible' for his failure to recognize such divine deception, Herodotus' narrative clearly emphasizes the inevitability o f the action (Harrison (2000b) 231): Xerxes' and Artabanus' m a u d l i n re-examination o f their dreams (7.49), Herodotus' reference forward to the fate o f Artayctes at the end o f the Histories (7.33), or any o f a series o f glaringly misinterpreted dreams and o m e n s " ' a l l these point to a clear conclusion. 14
15
14
15
16
Cf. 1.209.1, 6.48, 7.19.1, 32, 54.2. 138.1. 8.53.2, 109.3, Aeschylus Persae 189-99. Harrison (2000b) 136 7; contrast West (1987) 264 5. Cf. 7.19, 37.2, 57-58.1.
560
THOMAS
HARRISON
The invasion narrative The onset of Xerxes' campaign brings with it a new direction and force in Herodotus' narrative. Digressions from the main thread of Persian progress such as the catalogue o f the peoples in Xerxes' army, their commanders and armour (7.61-99)—are generally much briefer than in the earlier books. Moreover, the number o f crossreferences introduced by Herodotus—sometimes double cross-references"—suggest again a considered and successful attempt to marshal his material effectively. A number of consistent concerns run across Herodotus' narrative of the war. I n its criteria of inclusion, however, Herodotus' 'account' of the war differs fundamentally from our assumed conception of a historical war narrative. The detailed narrative of Xerxes' itinerary through Europe digresses to include not only details of the towns and rivers passed by the Persians, but a whole range of curiosities: a town named merely A g o r a ' (7.58.2), how lions devoured the Persian supply camels (7.125), the king's admiration at the Peneius gorge (7.128—30). Xerxes' own interest in what he passes offers the ostensible justification for many o f Herodotus' excursuses: Herodotus' lengthy review of Xerxes' forces is prompted, for example, by that of the king himself; Xerxes' wonder at the Peneius gorge introduces Herodotus' geological theorizings; the king's guides similarly told h i m (as Herodotus tells us) of the myth of the punishment of Athamas, whose descendants' house the king then revered (7.197). The emphasis i n this final example on cults and aetiological myths tied to the localities passed by the Persians is also a consistent one, and one which may have a broader message: stories such as of how Thetis was stolen away at Cape Sepias (told to the Persians by the Ionians, 7.191), or of Aphetai where Heracles was 'left behind' by Jason and the Argonauts (7.193), reinforce a sense of the divine possession of the Greek landscape, of an undercurrent that pulls against the Persians in their attempt to appropriate Greece. " This sense is strengthened yet further on those occasions on which Xerxes and the Persians choose to propitiate Greek gods. Propitiation of Athena 1
15
7.184.3, 217.2, 8.50.1 (cf. 8.34-5), 82.2, 85.2. 7.58.2, 176.3, 189.3, 192.2, 198.2, 200.2. For the relationship of landscape and myth, see Buxton (1994) ch. 6. For the Persians' attempted appropriation of natural phenomena, cf. 1.189, 3.117, 4.91, 7.27.2, 35, with Harrison (2000b) 238 9. 18
THE
PERSIAN
561
INVASIONS
Ilias and the heroes o f T r o y meets apparently with divine displeasure through a panic, attack that comes over his men (7.43.2); the sacrifices ordered by Xerxes on the (ravaged) Athenian acropolis result i n the sudden sprouting o f the sacred olive tree, a symbol o f Athenian revival (8.54-5); Cape Sepias, where the Persians propitiate Thetis and the Nereids, was perhaps not accidentally the site o f the subsequent destruction o f a large part o f the Persian fleet. This pattern of divine opposition to the Persians, and divine favour towards the Greeks, is another consistent strand o f the Persian W a r narrative. ' The storms that level the Greek and Persian fleets i n advance of Artemisium (8.13; cf. 6.44), the succession of miracles that meet the Persians on their approach to Delphi (8.35 9), the apparition of the Eleusinian procession, forecasting the Persians' defeat at sea rather than on land (8.65), the sudden floodtide at Potidaea which swept away those Persians who had earlier committed sacrilege against Poseidon (8.129), the extraordinary distribution o f Persian corpses around but not within the sanctuary o f Demeter (9.65), or the multiple coincidences between the Battles o f Plataea and Mycale (9.100), all these overlapping signs of divine favour i n the war suggest what Idiemistocles makes explicit (8.109.3), that it was not the Greeks themselves who achieved their eventual victory i n the war but the 'gods and heroes, who begrudged any one man to be king of both Asia and Europe, a man unholy and impious'. This is not to say that Herodotus excludes from his account, or that he consequently downplays, the achievements or plans o f men. As Themistocles also asserts (8.60y), divinity is more likely to promote human plans i f they are reasonable, fndeed, although Herodotus refrains, as we have seen in his account o f the causes o f the war, from any simplistic allocation of responsibility, the recording for posterity o f brave or ignoble deeds is an important priority for him. He is concerned always to count the dead i n battle, to discover the bravest and the most cowardly lighters, and to describe their memorials (7.225-6), to name traitors such as Ephialtes who led the Persians around the pass at Thermopylae (7.213—14),' or equally to record 1 1
20
21
22
19
Contrast e.g., Murray (1988) 261. on the Histories as the 'first non-religious historical narrative'; against such formulations, see Harrison (2000b) ch. 1. Contrast Gould's emphasis on Herodotus' 'debt to the past' (1989) 119 20. 6.114, 7.223 32, 8.17, 85, 87-8, 93-5, 9.70-5. See also 6.101.2, 9.84, 85.3. Contrast, however, 1.51.4, 4.43 in which Herodotus 21
22
562
THOMAS
those w h o
HARRISON
s t o o d o u t against c o l l a b o r a t i o n : the f e w b r a v e
Greeks,
A n t i d o r u s o f Lesbos o r Panaetius o f T e n o s , w h o deserted f r o m the Persian fleet to t h a t o f the Greeks (Sri 1.3, 82.1), o r the r a r e islanders w h o refused X e r x e s ' d e m a n d f o r e a r t h a n d w a t e r
(8.46.4).
T h e r e is o f t e n , o f course, a b r a v a d o q u a l i t y to his claims o f d e t a i l e d k n o w l e d g e : t h o u g h there is n o reason to d o u b t the a c c u r a c y o f the names he does r e c o r d , c o u l d he r e a l l y (as he claims) have
named
the n a t i v e guides o f X e r x e s (7.96.2), a l l t h r e e h u n d r e d o f the S p a r t a n dead of Thermopylae
(7.224.1), o r m o r e ( t h a n t h e t w o S a m i a n s
he
does m e n t i o n ) o f those i n the Persian fleet at Salamis w h o c a p t u r e d G r e e k ships (8.85.2-3)? I t is clear also t h a t those classified w i t h such seemingly o b j e c t i v e c l a r i t y as the bravest o r m o s t excellent (aristos) o f the Greeks c o r r e s p o n d u n c a n n i l y w i t h those to w h o m e x t r a o r d i n a r y anecdotes h a d c l u n g : Dieneces,
w h o left 'as m e m o r i a l s ' such
w i t t i c i s m s as t h e r e m a r k t h a t t h e Persians' c l o u d o f a r r o w s a l l o w e d the Greeks to fight i n the shade, is c i t e d as the bravest o f t h e Spartans at T h e r m o p y l a e (7.226); A m o m p h a r e t u s ,
whose actions at Plataea—
at least, as d e s c r i b e d b y H e r o d o t u s — m i g h t r a t h e r have b r o u g h t h i m i n t o d i s f a v o u r , is c r e d i t e d nonetheless as one o f t h e bravest Spartans at the b a t t l e (9.71.2); Sophanes o f D e c e l e a , said to have c a r r i e d a n i r o n a n c h o r i n t o b a t t l e (in a c t u a l fact a n e m b l e m o n his shield) w h i c h he t h r e w d o w n w h e r e he s t o o d
firm
to
bravest o f t h e A t h e n i a n s (9.74). H e r o d o t u s
fight,
is r e c o r d e d as t h e
has a p p a r e n t l y
assumed
t h a t t h e scraps o f o r a l t r a d i t i o n t h a t have c o m e d o w n t o h i m are representative o f the full t e x t u r e o f a g i v e n b a t t l e . O f course, i t m i g h t be c o u n t e r e d t h a t such tales w o u l d n a t u r a l l y adhere to those a c k n o w l edged as the bravest. A m o m p h a r e t u s figures
who
Callicrates
is m e n t i o n e d alongside o t h e r
are o t h e r w i s e u n k n o w n — P o s e i d o n i u s ,
Philocyon,
and
as w e l l as A r i s t o d e m u s , eager to m a k e a m e n d s f o r his
fortuitous survival at T h e r m o p y l a e (9.71.2-72). As H e r o d o t u s ' account o f their b u r i a l testifies, however, w h a t m a r k e d this g r o u p o f ' u n k n o w n s ' o u t was t h e i r p a r t i c u l a r s t a t u s — e i t h e r as S p a r t a n eirens o r as priests (9.85).
23
I n t h e case o f C a l l i c r a t e s , m o r e o v e r , w h o d i e d after b e i n g
is unwilling to blacken a man's reputation by naming him; at 3.125.3, his reluctance is to report the unfitting death of Polycrates. * Depending on one's interpretation of the text and of e.g., the status of Spartan priests: for recent discussion, see now Hodkinson (2000) 258, Gilula (2002), Makres forthcoming. For a correlation also between Persian commanders and the brave, cf. 8.89.1, 9.71.1. :i
1
THE
563
PERSIAN INVASIONS
s t r u c k b y a n a r r o w b e f o r e t h e b a t t l e h a d even b e g u n , t h e o n l y a c t i o n t h a t c o u l d j u s t i f y his c i t a t i o n is his r e m a r k o f regret at n o t t a k i n g p a r t i n the b a t t l e (9.72). H i s r e a l q u a l i f i c a t i o n appears to have been his h e r o i c l o o k s : 2 4 as the G r e e k terms f o r b r a v e r y suggest, the l i n e between
acknowledged
courage
a n d a r i s t o c r a t i c r e p u t a t i o n was
a
grey o n e . I t is n o t o n l y insofar as he seeks to c o m m e m o r a t e b a d deeds o f m e n t h a t H e r o d o t u s
the g o o d a n d
relies o n such a n e c d o t a l
tradi-
tions. T h e w i t t i c i s m s o f the S p a r t a n Dieneces are c h a r a c t e r i s t i c o f a b r a n d o f s m a r t repartee t h a t r u n s t h r o u g h H e r o d o t u s ' the w a r .
'Themistocles',
the C o r i n t h i a n A d e i m a n t u s
account
warns,
of
'those
w h o i n races j u m p the g u n are w h i p p e d ' ; ' b u t those w h o are left b e h i n d ' , Themistocles Megacreon
r e t o r t s , ' w i n n o prizes'
( 8 . 5 9 ; cf. 8 . 6 1 ,
o f A b d e r a s i m i l a r l y advised the A b d e r i t e s ,
125).
crippled by
the costs o f f e e d i n g X e r x e s ' forces, to give thanks to the gods t h a t Xerxes demanded
o n l y one m e a l a day (7.120). T h e
king's d i n n e r
is o n e o f a n u m b e r o f subjects a r o u n d w h i c h o r a l t r a d i t i o n s a p p e a r to have clustered a n d w h i c h H e r o d o t u s tive ( 7 . 2 7 - 9 , 3 2 ,
116,
1 18.3,
t h e n b u i l d s i n t o his n a r r a -
1 1 8 - 2 0 ) ; 2 5 i t seems also to have p r o -
v i d e d f o o d f o r G r e e k c u r i o s i t y even i n t o the f o u r t h c e n t u r y . such r e p e a t e d m o t i f s i n c l u d e the e n o r m o u s
Other
fortunes m a d e b y
non-
Persians f r o m the scraps o f Persian w e a l t h , 2 6 the p r o m i n e n c e at c o u r t o f Persian w o m e n , 2 ' c u n n i n g messages such as that b y w h i c h Demaratus w a r n e d the Spartans o f the i m p e n d i n g Persian i n v a s i o n ( 7 . 2 3 9 ) , 2 8 o r the 'news o f Persian successes a n d v i c t o r i e s r e a c h i n g Susa, o r
the
tales o f the r a g g e d r e t u r n o f the Persian forces f r o m E u r o p e . 2 9 To
note H e r o d o t u s '
stress o n the a n e c d o t a l , h o w e v e r ,
is n o t to
deny that he is equally c o n c e r n e d w i t h 'nuts-and-bolts' m i l i t a r y details. H e r o d o t u s p r o v i d e s , f o r e x a m p l e , sufficiently d e t a i l e d i n f o r m a t i o n o n the Persians' e n g i n e e r i n g projectsthe H e l l e s p o n t
24
in p a r t i c u l a r o n the b r i d g e across
(7.33-7)- -to allow for their m o d e r n
reconstruction
For beauty as a heroic characteristic, see Visser (1982) 410, Harrison (2000b) 139, 162-3, 257. See Lewis (1987), Briant (1989), (1996) 297-306. 7.190, 4.43.7, 8.8.1, 9.80.3, Plutarch Aristides 5.7-8; cf. Miller (1997) 30-1; cf. also the alleged Lydian origins of Alcmeonid wealth, 6.125. Harrison (2000a) ch. 3; contrast Sancisi-Weerdenburg (1983), Brosius (1996). Cf. 1.123.4, 5.35.2, 8.128, with S. Lewis (1996) 145-6. Harrison (2000a) ch. 4. We cannot, of course, rule out the possibility of the truth of all such 'roving anecdotes'—the phrase is Hornblower's (1987) 22-3, used of false wealth at 3.123.2, Thuc. 6.46. See e.g., S. Lewis (1996) 189 n. 90. 25
26
27
28
29
564
THOMAS
HARRISON
30
(on paper, at least). H e also reveals a consistent interest in the numbers o f Greek and Persian forces (6.115-17, 7.184—7, 8.1-2.1), taking trouble to ensure that his numbers add up, that round numbers remain round by the making up o f losses (8.13, 62.2-3, 82.2, 9.32.2). Such consistency clearly may have been bought at the expense o f a scrupulous concern with accuracy. Moreover, Herodotus' concern with such details may be dramatic as much as historical: the absurd weight o f Persian numbers, as the discussions between Xerxes and Artabanus (or parallel dialogues i n Aeschylus' Persians) reveal, play an important role i n building up the scale o f the Persians' expedition and o f their impending failure. Stories o f the huge demand placed on cities by the Persian forces, o f rivers drunk dry, or the king's observation that Greek grain ships at Abydos were bringing h i m supplies (7.147.2—3), may suggest an awareness o f the need for supplies and logistical planning. But it is not a concern that is sustained or which—except for the important theme o f the rejection o f the Persians by Greek 'land and sea', a corollary to the gods' opposition (Harrison (2000a) ch. 7)—is offered as any form of explanation for Persian defeat. Herodotus' accounts o f battles are necessarily stylized. The line between battle narrative and post-mortem is a grey one. Which city or people holds which wing (6.111.1, 8.85.1, 9.26-30, 46-7)? W h i c h city began the battle (8.84)? W h o fought bravely? D i d the Corinthians, for example, flee from Salamis as the Athenians claimed but they denied (8.94, cf. 9.105)? The reason for this focus, o f course, is the partisan nature o f Herodotus' sources. Herodotus also ascribes a limited range o f tactical choices to any commander: the decision to fight a battle i n a confined space (a 'tactic' employed with success 31
32
33
30
See esp. Hammond (1988b) 527-32, Hammond and Roscman (1996). Herodotus' explanation of Xerxes' motivation for ordering another engineering project, the Athos canal—that he wanted to display his power and leave a memorial of himself (7.24)—may also not be far off the mark: cf. Kent (1953) DSf The numbers of troops and ships can be brought to reasonable levels by, e.g., estimates of the number of men that a given territory might support, standard sizes of Persian navies, and the drastic but perhaps justifiable expedient of removing noughts from many of Herodotus' figures: see e.g.. Lazenby (1993) 90-6, Hammond (1988b) 5.32-5, 549, Young (1980). See Hammond's comments on 7.121.3; (1988b) 537. Cf. 7.112, 158, 187. Cf. Herodotus' judgement on the impossibility of assessing who fought bravely at the Batde of Lade, 6.14.1. See also e.g., de Jong (1999) 262-71, for a detailed literary analysis of the battle of Salamis, and Ch. 23, pp. 528- 31, this volume. 31
32
33
p
THE
PERSIAN
565
INVASIONS
by the Greeks at Artemisium, Thermopylae, and at Salamis, 7.175—7, 8.16, 60a-d3) or i n a location suitable for cavalry (6.102; cf. 5.63.4). Though the moving o f men along the Greek lines at Plataea (9.46—7) or the refusal o f Amompharetus to retreat from his forward position (9.53) may reflect a degree o f planning inaccessible to HerodotusAmompharetus, it has been suggested, was left i n advance of the line intentionally to cover their tactical retreat Herodotus maintains that the rearrangements o f the battle lines were prompted merely by the Spartans' sense o f their own inexperience o f the Persians, and that Amompharetus was motivated simply by Spartan obduracy. Though scraps o f more detailed information are preserved (Darius' garrison against the Scythians, for example, 7.59.1), and though there is evidence of relative tactical expertise (in references to the inability o f Megarians to cope w i t h cavalry, 9.21, or the Athenians' superior -knowledge o f siege warfare, 9.70.2), the extent to which Herodotus' account may provide the basis for modern rationalizations is often questionable. 31
W h e n we move on to inquire into the causes of the Persians' defeat, strictly military explanations are again few and far between. The Persians, we are told, died i n such numbers at Salamis because of their being unable to swim (8.89). A small rash o f such minimalist explanations appear i n the much more complex narrative o f the battle of Plataea: the Persians' forces were insufficiently well armoured (9.63.2); when the elite Persians fled, the rest o f the Persian line disintegrated (9.68). I n general, however, i f we were to judge die importance o f any explanation by the space given to it in the pages of the Histories, it would be hard to avoid another conclusion: that the Greeks' victory was the result simply o f their superiority over their enemies (whether that superiority be the result o f nature or nurture). That, at least, is the implicit moral o f a series o f dialogues between Persians and Greeks: the lecture on freedom given by the Spartan heralds to the Persian Hydarnes (7.133-6), the report that the Greeks were competing in games at Olympia- deading the Persian IVitantaechmcs to observe that they were fighting against men who 3.
3(>
34
Lazenby (1993) 239-40; Barron, (1988) 607, suggests an Athenian source. See the comparison of Herodotus and Hippocrates of Jouanna (1981). "' The encounter with Xerxes has a sting in its tail, 7.136: the king delivers a lecture on the 'universal customs of men' contravened by the Spartans in killing a herald.
566
THOMAS
HARRISON
competed for virtue rather than wealth ( 8 . 2 6 ) - o r Demaratus' homily on Greek poverty and virtue and the constraining influence o f nomos (7.101-4). These dialogues stress repeatedly the link between the Greeks' freedom and their military valour. Xerxes, for example, is unable to comprehend the composed fashion in which the Spartans at Thermopylae prepared for their own death (7.209.1); only i n the light of the battle is he able to acknowledge that he has at his command 'many people but few men' (7.210.2; cf. 8.88.3). I n many ways, however, this stark contrast is subverted. The Persian fleet at Salamis fights m u c h more courageously than at Artemisium for fear o f the king (sitting on high recording their actions, 8.86). The Persians at Plataea fought no less bravely than the Greeks, but they were let down by their lack o f skill and discipline and by their armour (9.62.3). There are frequent glimpses also o f a strong ethos o f loyalty among the king's lieutenants- -and o f a tradition o f the king's reward for such loyalty - -and o f a heroic ideal o f excellence among the Persians: Xerxes, Herodotus notes surprisingly, was deserving o f his rule over so many men because o f his beauty and height .7.187 2 A" The Greeks, on the other hand, were not uniformly united by high ideals. The Phocians, Herodotus observes, only fought for the Greeks because o f their hostility to the Thessalians (8.30); i f the Thessalians had not medized, he speculates, the Phocians would themselves have done so. The certainty and Panhellenic zeal with which the Athenians dismiss all thought o f an alliance w i t h the Persians (8.143-4) is immediately undermined by Herodotus' account of the Athenians' actions. The impression o f the Athenians' visceral opposition to the idea o f an alliance is reinforced by the story o f the spontaneous stoning o f Lycidas and his family for the suggestion that the Persian offer should be put to the people (9.5), yet it is only by using the threat of such an alliance that the Athenians succeed in galvanizing the Spartans into action (9.6-9). Herodotus shows some puzzlement at the contradictory nature o f his material (9.8.2): why were the Spartans so nonchalant now when they had earlier shown such anxiety at the prospect o f an Athenian alliance with Persia? Perhaps, now that the Isthmus wall was more advanced, they 37
3.160,4.143,6-30,7.8.5, 27-9, 38-9, 106-7, 117 with Harrison (2000b) ch. 8. 1.139, 4.91.2, 7.187.2, 9.25.1, 96.2 with Briant (1996) 237-9.
T H E PERSIAN INVASIONS
567
did not consider the threat so great? A t any rate, it was only by virtue of a stiff reminder o f the joint power o f Athens and Persia and o f the inadequacy o f the Isthmus wall from the Tegean Chileos (9.9) that the Athenians avoided making their threat a reality. Already i n the w a r m afterglow of victory at Plataea, moreover, the seeds o f the Greeks' own excesses are evident. Even in the midst of Herodotus' catalogue o f the brave, there are a number of passing references to later Greek deaths at each other's hands (9.73.3, 75, 76; Fornara (1981)). T h o u g h Pausanias refrains from stooping to the Persian level by mutilating the corpse o f Mardonius (9.78), the recommendation that he should do so, from the prominent Aeginetan Lampon, is significant. Pausanias' chivalrous treatment of a Goan lady prisoner (9.76), or his ostentatiously Spartan taste i n food (9.82), hint at his later degeneration into tyrannical excess: his adoption o f Persian dress and a 'Persian table' (Thuc. 1.130.1; Fornara (197la) 62 if.). Similarly the barbaric punishment of Artayctes meted out by the Athenian Xanthippus at the end o f the Histories points forward to the excesses o f the Athenian imperialism of his son, Pericles. Moreover, though the Greeks engineer a seemingly resolute unity in the face of battle (8.86), this unity is, i n the broader canvas o f the war and the Histories, at best tenuous. The theme o f the tension between the two leading cities o f Greece, Athens and Sparta, is one that runs throughout the Histories. I t is reflected, for example, in the very organization of the work, with the early histories o f Athens and Sparta introduced i n pairs (through the device o f the search for alliances o f first Croesus and then Aristagoras, 1.56-68, 5.38.2-97). War exposes this tension. As Miltiades observes before Marathon, the battle against the Persians is also a battle for Greece: i f Athens wins through, she will become the first of the cities of Greece (6.109.3). The battle of Mycale sees Athenians and Spartans actually scrambling to gain the greatest share o f the credit for the liberation o f Ionia (9.102.2). 39
The differences of interest between the Greek states are also, o f course, reflected i n the proposed strategies for repelling the Persians. The Spartans and Peloponnesians had no desire to fight for the Greeks who lived north o f the fsthmus (8.49, 70.2, 74). Just as Themistocles devised a cunning ploy whereby to break off the Greeks
See above, nn. 2 3.
568
THOMAS
o f Asia M i n o r
f r o m the Persian
HARRISON
fleet
confidence i n his G r e e k t r o o p s , 8 . 1 9 ,
(or t o u n d e r m i n e
Xerxes'
22), he also ensured t h a t the
Greek alliance h e l d together b y threatening the allies that the Athenians w o u l d desert to f o u n d a c o l o n y at Siris i n I t a l y (8.62.2), a t h r e a t t h a t is said to have been v i t a l i n p e r s u a d i n g the allies to stay p u t at Salamis (8.63). W h e n P e l o p o n n e s i a n d i s c o n t e n t b r o k e o u t i n t o the o p e n (8.74), T h e m i s t o c l e s resorted t o still m o r e devious m e a n s , sendi n g S i c i n n u s t o the Persian c a m p to r e p o r t t h a t the Greeks w e r e at loggerheads, w i t h m a n y i n c l i n i n g to the K i n g , a n d t h a t t h e y w e r e p l a n n i n g to b r e a k o u t i n flight f r o m Salamis ( 8 . 7 5 . 2 3 ) . W h i l e m i s r e p r e s e n t i n g the real cause o f d i v i s i o n , T h e m i s t o c l e s uses the Greeks' d i s u n i t y to i m p o s e his o w n v i e w u p o n t h e m . T h e
fleeting
Salamis is i n some senses t h e n a c t u a l l y t h e p r o d u c t o f the
unity of Greeks'
p o l i t i c a l disunity. When
this sequence o f events is p u t t o g e t h e r w i t h
Herodotus'
' u n p o p u l a r v e r d i c t ' o f the p i v o t a l c o n t r i b u t i o n o f the A t h e n i a n s to G r e e k v i c t o r y - -his forecast that the Spartans w o u l d have
been
b e t r a y e d b y t h e i r allies, a n d e i t h e r d i e d n o b l e deaths o r c o m e to some settlement w i t h the Persians (7.139.3 4)- - i t is clear t h a t he a t t a c h e s a n e n o r m o u s w e i g h t t o t h e acts o f t r i c k e r y b y w h i c h T h e m i s t o c l e s e n g i n e e r e d b a t t l e at Salamis, a n d t o his advice to b u i l d a fleet f r o m the w i n d f a l l at L a u r i o n (7.144). Nonetheless, G r e e k v i c t o r y is n o t solely d u e to the A t h e n i a n s . T h e Persians consistently fail to take advantage o f G r e e k d i s u n i t y , o r to d r i v e wedges i n the G r e e k camp. Demaratus'
advice to o c c u p y G y t h e r a
a n d so to p r o v o k e a
c i v i l w a r i n the Peloponnese i n o r d e r to isolate the Spartans
(7.235)
is r e j e c t e d b y the k i n g i n f a v o u r o f A c h a e m e n e s ' to keep the Persian forces t o g e t h e r (7.236—7).
40
Artemisia similarly recommends that any
b a t t l e at Salamis s h o u l d be a v o i d e d (8.68); instead the fleet s h o u l d p r o c e e d i n p a r a l l e l w i t h the a r m y to the Peloponnese, w i t h the result t h a t the king's enemies w o u l d scatter; the Peloponnesians, she adds ( e c h o i n g H e r o d o t u s ' consistent r e p o r t o f Peloponnesian m i s g i v i n g s , 8 . 4 9 , 70.2, 74), w o u l d have n o s t o m a c h to fight o n b e h a l f o f A t h e n s .
111
It is possible that it is through this advice that Demaratus' earlier response to Leutychidas (that his taunt would be the 'beginning either of great evil or great good fortune for the Lacedaemonians', 6.67.3) is fulfilled. I f his advice had been taken, it would have been a great misfortune for the Spartans. Demaratus' other potentially significant intervention was his role in the succession of Xerxes (7.2 3), but Herodotus ascribes the main role there to the king's mother, Atossa (7.3.4).
THE
PERSIAN INVASIONS
569
Even after Salamis, Herodotus presents the Persians with one last chance to break up their enemies: the The bans offer Mardonius a strategy whereby they might 'subdue the whole of Greece without a fight' (9.2): 'While the Greeks continue to be firmly o f one m i n d . . . it would be difficult for all mankind to overcome them. But i f you do what we advise', they continued, 'you will without difficulty frustrate their plans: send money to the most powerful men in the cities, and by sending it you will divide Greece into factions; then, w i t h the support o f those in your faction, you will easily subdue those who are not o f your mind.'
Whereas Themistocles, however, uses fair means and foul to attain his ends Taking money from the Euboeans, and passing a part o f it on to Eurybiades to encourage him not to retreat to the Isthmus (8.4-5)—Mardonius refrains from bribery, overcome by the desire to sack Athens for a second time and to report the news to his king (9.3.1). In all these instances, the consequences o f the rejected strategies would have been exactly those postulated by Herodotus as the result if the Athenians had not stood firm at Salamis (7.139.3 4). The only occasion on which the Persians do intervene to take advantage o f Greek disunity, however, is at Salamis. This persistent stress on the potential for the Persians to take advantage o f Greek divisions is perhaps the key interpretative theme o f the Persian W a r narrative. The Persians' repeated failure to grasp their opportunities itself demands explanation, however. Essentially the Persians are trapped within their national stereotype." A corollary o f the Persians' time-hallowed monarchy (3.82.5) is an almost complete lack o f effective counsel. So, for example, Xerxes summons his elders at the beginning o f Book Seven 'so as to learn their opinions and inform them all o f his wishes' or (in his own words) 'so that I may not seem to follow my own counsel' (7,8, 7.85.2); the king is furious at the opposition o f Artabanus (7.10-1 l j . " Artemisia's frank advice after Salamis- -that Xerxes should leave the conduct o f the campaign to Mardonius is accepted for the reason
" For Herodotus' assumption of consistent national characteristics, revealed e.g., at 7.238, see Harrison (2000b) 237 8, 240 1. Contrast Xerxes' pacific response to Artemisia, 8.69. Other examples of* the failure of consultation: 7.101-4, 209, 234-7, 8.67 9. Sec further Harrison (2000a) ch. 8. 12
570
THOMAS
HARRISON
t h a t i t coincides w i t h t h e king's p r e f e r e n c e (8.103). As a consequence o f this ' d e m o c r a t i c d e f i c i t ' , there are s i m p l y n o brakes o n c o n t i n u e d Persian e x p a n s i o n . D e s p i t e t h e i r d e l i g h t a n d r e l i e f a t t h e m o m e n t a r y c a n c e l l a t i o n o f t h e e x p e d i t i o n ( 7 . 1 3 . 3 ) , X e r x e s was s u r r o u n d e d b y those w h o e n c o u r a g e d h i m , t e l l i n g h i m w h a t he w a n t e d to h e a r (7.13.2,
16<x. 1). A f t e r t h e defeat at Salamis, M a r d o n i u s
h i m s e l f to t h e c o m m a n d
committed
o f t h e c a m p a i g n f o r fear t h a t he w o u l d
otherwise be h e l d responsible f o r defeat (8.99- 100); at the same t i m e he t r i e d t o shift t h e b l a m e f o r defeat o n t o t h e Phoenicians a n d o t h e r n o n - P e r s i a n forces. H i s desire to sack A t h e n s f o r a second t i m e , a n d to send t h e r e p o r t o f this a c h i e v e m e n t to X e r x e s i n Sardis, destroys any
chance, however
slight, o f his f o r g i n g a n alliance w i t h t h e
A t h e n i a n s , a n d so o f v i c t o r y (9.3). W h e n f r a n k counsel is a v a i l a b l e , m o r e o v e r , t h e advice is p r e d i c t a b l y i g n o r e d (e.g., 8 . 6 8 ; cf. 8 . 1 0 2 . 3 ) . Two
o t h e r Persian characteristics c o m p o u n d t h e i r defeat.
Their
reliance o n n u m b e r s — a nomas o f t h e Persians, a c c o r d i n g to H e r o d o t u s (1.136.1), b u t also a p p a r e n t l y a p a t h o l o g i c a l obsession o f X e r x e s is r e p e a t e d l y a n d devastatingly c o u n t e r - p r o d u c t i v e ( H a r r i s o n (2000a) c h . 7). T h e l a n d a n d the sea, as A r t a b a n u s w a r n s X e r x e s , w i l l be all t h e m o r e hostile f o r t h e n u m b e r o f his ships (7.49.1)
-a prophecy
d u l y f u l f i l l e d b y t h e series o f storms t h a t b a t t e r the Persian fleet. A t Thermopylae,
A r t e m i s i u m a n d at Salamis,
the n u m b e r
o f Persian
m e n s i m p l y enhances t h e advantage t o t h e Greeks o f fighting i n a c o n f i n e d space a n d c o n t r i b u t e s t o t h e n u m b e r o f Persian casualties (7.177, 2 1 1 . 3 , 8 . 1 6 , 6 0 a - B ) . The
second Persian c h a r a c t e r i s t i c t o c o n t r i b u t e t o t h e i r defeat is
t h e i r f a i l u r e t o h e e d t h e lessons d e r i v e d f r o m t h e gods. I t w a s , H e r o d o t u s tells us, i n accordance w i t h a Persian nomos that M a r d o n i u s chose to i n i t i a t e t h e b a t t l e o f Plataea i n c o n t r a d i c t i o n o f t h e o m e n s t h a t he h a d r e c e i v e d (9.41.4). T h i s c a n be c o n t r a s t e d w i t h t h e p r o p e r ( a n d a p p a r e n t l y well-received) r i t u a l observations o f t h e Greeks. T h e Greeks' progress t o w a r d s Plataea,
b y contrast t o t h e Persians'
ear-
lier a r r i v a l , seems at times like a procession f r o m shrine t o shrine (9.19). I n t h e b a t t l e itself, t h e Greeks' o b e d i e n c e t o the o m e n s f a v o u r a b l e f o r defence, b u t u n f a v o u r a b l e f o r attack-
eventually saw
them rewarded (9.61.3-62.1): T h e Spartans being hard-pressed and the victims being unfavourable, Pausanias, looking towards the Heraion o f the Plataeans, called upon the goddess, requesting that they might not be disappointed of their hopes. While he was calling upon her, the Tegeans, starting f o r w a r d ,
THE
PERSIAN
571
INVASIONS
attacked the barbarians, and immediate!) after the prayer of Pausanias the victims became favourable to the Lacedaemonians as they sacrificed. T h i s episode f o r m s p a r t o f a l a r g e r contrast.' 1 3 W h e r e a s the Greeks make
a p r i o r i t y o f c o n s u l t i n g t h e o r a c l e at D e l p h i , 4 1 X e r x e s sees
D e l p h i o n l y as a source o f p l u n d e r ( 8 . 3 5 - 9 ) . I t is o n l y
Mardonius
w h o gives a n y place to oracles i n his p l a n n i n g b y s e n d i n g M y s E u r o p u s o n a t o u r o f o r a c u l a r shrines ( 8 . 1 3 3 - 5 ) .
of
I t is o n the basis
o f t h e oracles o b t a i n e d b y M y s t h a t M a r d o n i u s a t t e m p t s to forge a n alliance w i t h the A t h e n i a n s ( 8 . 1 3 6 ,
140
4). T h e
advice o f the o r a -
cles tallies closely w i t h H e r o d o t u s '
persistent stress o n the
Persian
need t o d r i v e a wedge i n the G r e e k a l l i a n c e . Y e t a g a i n G r e e k d i v i sion a n d defeat w e r e averted b y a w h i s k e r .
Veracity and bias W e t u r n f i n a l l y to issues o f v e r a c i t y . T h e first d i f f i c u l t y t h a t we m u s t a d m i t is the lack o f a n y o t h e r sustained accounts b y w h i c h to assess Herodotus'
account o f the w a r .
The
e p i t o m i z e d narrative o f the
f o u r t h - c e n t u r y Gtesias, t h o u g h i t m a y c o n t a i n echoes o f l a t e r Persian e l a b o r a t i o n s o n t h e Persian W a r s , 4 5 is n o t o r i o u s f o r its failings, m o s t d r a m a t i c a l l y f o r its reversal o f Salamis a n d Plataea. give plausible s u p p l e m e n t a r y details
i n v o l v e m e n t i n the q u a r r e l o f C o r c y r a (Themistocles 24; cf. 32), m a y
Plutarch
may-
his reference to T h e m i s t o c l e s ' w i t h C o r i n t h , for
offer a c o n t e x t f o r the
example
Corcyraeans'
offer o f ships to the G r e e k fleet (7.168.3)- - b u t his w o r k is also replete w i t h s e c o n d - g e n e r a t i o n (or still later) e m b e l l i s h m e n t : i t is at the v e r y least o p e n to q u e s t i o n , for i n s t a n c e , w h e t h e r we m a y give credence to t h e sophisticated strategy a s c r i b e d to T h e m i s t o c l e s at Salamis, his l e a r n i n g the lesson o f A r t e m i s i u m a n d t a k i n g advantage o f a d a w n swell t o d i s r u p t t h e Persian l i n e (Themistocles 14.2). 4 6 Aeschylus' Persae has often b e e n discussed o n the a s s u m p t i o n t h a t the p l a y w r i g h t , w r i t i n g o n l y seven years after the events at Salamis, felt h o n o u r - b o u n d to p r o v i d e a n accurate h i s t o r i c a l r e c o r d ; a l t e r n a t i v e l y , h i s t o r i a n s have fallen b a c k o n the a r g u m e n t t h a t
4 4
11
45
1,1
Aeschylus
For a similar contrast in Aeschylus' Persae, sec Harrison (2000a) ch. 9. Contrast, however, the Eubocans' failure to heed the prophecy of Bacis, 8.20. See Lenfant (1996); cf. Bigwood (1978). As Hammond (1988b) 575-6, 578; cf. Lazenby (1993) 186.
572
THOMAS
HARRISON
could not have diverged from the true course o f events without provoking the outrage o f his audience o f fellow-veterans. The first o f these lines is unfounded, however, and the second- that of the historical constraint represented by his audience- -arguably offers little comfort.*' Aeschylus 'account' o f Salamis is short on detailed information -the tendentious detail that the Athenian ships were the first to break into Persian view is a rare exception (399-401). As a result of this, Aeschylus can offer litde historical control: the suggestion, for example, that the Herodotean version of a hoplite skirmish on the island o f Psyttaleia is the fabrication o f an anti-Themistoclean tradition (see e.g., Fornara (1966)) is not one which Aeschylus can help us to quash. Other constraints, moreover the need to generate a recognizably stereotyped representation o f the Persians, or to develop the play's political and ideological arguments- would surely have outweighed any, even residual, historical duty. The emphasis, for example, laid by Aeschylus (and Herodotus) on the orderliness of the Greek fleet, by contrast to the chaotic jumble o f the Persian navy (Persae 399-400; cf. 8.86), can be explained simply i n terms of the play's theme o f individual Greek submission to the collective; " to take such a detail at face value may be to be deceived by the Athenians' own recreation o f their past (contrast Lazenby (1993) 190-1). Where the Persae is arguably most useful is in its ideology rather than its narrative o f events. By providing close parallels to the ideology implicit in Herodotus' narrative -in its representation o f the prominence o f Persian women, for example, or o f the Greeks as plucky u n d e r d o g s t h e play helps us to reconstruct the impetus that lay behind the distortion o f the history of events (Harrison (2000a) ch. 3). Persian expressions o f interest i n things Greek -seen, for example, i n the questions 'who are the Athenians?' or 'who are the Spartans?' (5.105, 1.153; cf. Aesch. Persae 230-45), or in more extended fashion i n the interviews o f Xerxes and Demaratus -are revealed to be a regular m o t i f of Greek traditions on Persia and a convenient vehicle for highlighting, through 'a kind of "oratio obliqua"', Greek virtues rather than knowledge o f the Persian court. 4
49
47
See further Harrison (2000a) ch. 1; Pelting (1997a); and Ch. 6, pp. 137-45, this volume. See esp. Goldhill (1988), Harrison (2000a) chs. 8 9. Craig (1924) 99; see further Harrison (2000a) chs. 3-4. 48
THE
PERSIAN
573
INVASIONS
O t h e r pieces o f evidence c o m e w i t h t h e i r o w n
difficulties.
The
c o n t r o v e r s i a l ' T h e m i s t o c l e s decree' m a y shed i m p o r t a n t l i g h t o n t h e Athenian
e v a c u a t i o n , suggesting a m o r e p l a n n e d w i t h d r a w a l — i f i t
i n d e e d derives f r o m a n a u t h e n t i c d e c r e e . 3 0 T h e
near-contemporary
m u r a l o f the Stoa Poikile m i g h t have p r o v i d e d a n a l t e r n a t i v e i m p r e s sion o f M a r a t h o n , i f i t h a d s u r v i v e d t h r o u g h m o r e t h a n a n c i e n t testimonies.3' T h e
G r e e k landscape has b e e n the subject o f c o n t i n u i n g
battles o n t h e t o p o g r a p h y o f each o f t h e battles o f the w a r : t h e e f f o r t to d e c i d e , f o r e x a m p l e , w h e t h e r a n c i e n t Psyttaleia was m o d e r n A y i o s Y e o r y i o s o r L i p s o k o u t a l i (a q u e s t i o n w i t h huge i m p l i c a t i o n s f o r t h e shape o f the B a t t l e o f Salamis) is one m a d e m o r e d i f f i c u l t b o t h b y the disappearance o f a n c i e n t place n a m e s , a n d b y changes i n the landscape itself. 3 2 On
this a n d o t h e r q u e s t i o n s t h e n w e
can expect
no historio-
g r a p h i c a l s h o r t c u t s o n t h e basis o f o t h e r sources o f evidence.
In
a t t e m p t i n g to i n t e r p r e t H e r o d o t u s ' a c c o u n t , m o r e o v e r , we m u s t n e g o tiate n o t o n l y suspicions o f a c y n i c a l bias
allegations, f o r e x a m p l e .
t h a t H e r o d o t u s w r o t e his w o r k as a p a e a n o f praise to A t h e n s o r as a n a p o l o g y f o r D e l p h i - -but also a w h o l e r a n g e o f m o r e subtle f o r m s o f ' d e f o r m a t i o n ' ( M u r r a y (1987)
102).
Accusations o f a cynical bias- - f r o m a n t i q u i t y to the present day 5 3 have i n v a r i a b l y been exaggerated. T h e i m p e r a t i v e o f p r e s e n t i n g the w a r as a struggle b e t w e e n free m e n a n d slaves m a y l e a d H e r o d o t u s , f o r e x a m p l e , to d o w n p l a y the presence o f slaves i n the G r e e k forces, b u t he also p r o v i d e s m u c h o f the evidence to c o u n t e r this r e w r i t i n g of history.34 T h e
c o m m o n view o f a Herodotean
bias i n f a v o u r
the A t h e n i a n A l c m e o n i d c l a n is also u n f o u n d e d . 3 3 T h e
of
loyal family
r e t a i n e r m i g h t dismiss w h a t he considers a l i b e l against his p a t r o n s — as H e r o d o t u s dismisses the story o f A l c m e o n i d t r e a c h e i y at M a r a t h o n (6.115, 121~31)- -but he w o u l d n o t be t h a n k e d f o r r e p e a t i n g at l e n g t h the substance o f t h a t l i b e l . 3 * r Fhe c o m p l i m e n t p a i d b y H e r o d o t u s
to
* Sec Hammond (1988b) 558 63; cf. Lazenby (1993) 102-4. See e.g., Hammond (1968) 26-31, Harrison (1972), Francis and Victors (1985). See esp. Hammond. Pritchett, and Burn as cited by Hammond (1988b). Lazenby (1993). See esp. Plutarch, de malignitate Herodoti, Moralia 854-74. "" Hammond (1988b) 549, 563 n. 79, Hunt (1998) chs. 2-3. For Alcmeonid traditions, see esp. Thomas (1989) ch. 5; also Chs. 2, pp. 37 42, and 22, p. 504, this volume. * See n. 22 above for Herodotus' unwillingness to blacken reputations. 51
52
53
574
THOMAS
HARRISON
Aristides, 'the most excellent and just of the Athenians' (8.79.1), is never paralleled by any tribute to an Alcmeonid. The fact that Aristides' reputation for justice was proverbial, moreover, may suggest that Herodotus had no privileged access to Athenian family tradition (Fehling (1989) 243-5). The charge that his account o f the war covers over the medism of the Delphic oracle is one which fails completely to consider the mechanisms by which belief in oracles was maintained. Herodotus can hardly have been alone in highlighting the 'eternal gratitude' (7.178) earned by the god rather than his judicious caution.' Herodotus' statement of the pivotal role of Athens is accompanied by an acknowledgment of the unpopularity of such a verdict (7.139.1): this is not the manner of an unthinking apologist; indeed Herodotus seems implicitly to accept the validity of others' resentment of Athens. Herodotus may give space to the Athenians' stirring rejection of an alliance with the Mede (7.144), but he then, as we have seen, suggests that this situation would have become inevitable- -had the Athenians not succeeded in stiffening Spartan resolve by indicating that such an alliance was a possibility (cf. Barron (1988) 596). I f Herodotus is guilty of an Athenian bias, it is in his acceptance of Athenian claims at face value: in his report, for example, o f the Athenians' noble suppression of their desire for a share in the command (8.3). The material from which Herodotus drew is frequently, as we have seen, anecdotal and partisan. He is often, of course, capable of rejecting material on precisely these grounds: the story that the Corinthians fled from Salamis he dismisses as an Athenian slander (8.94). O n other occasions, however, partisanship slips through the net. M a n y o f the traditions surrounding Themistocles, most notably his alleged medism, may be the products o f his later history: his expulsion from Athens and eventual flight to Persia. A t the same time, however, the tradition that his political enemy Aristides appealed to h i m before Salamis to compete for the good of the city (8.79.2—3) originates in a patriotic, democratic tradition that predates his retrospective demonization: Aeschylus' Persae significantly portrays their achievements at Salamis as balancing one another.' 7
8
Herodotus' claim that Athens' contribution to the war was crucial is clearly a considered judgment (7.139); the same conclusion, 7
' See esp. Parker (1985), Elayl (1978), (1979), Harrison (2000b) ch. 5. See further Harrison (2000a) chs. 2, 9. 18
THE
PERSIAN
INVASIONS
575
h o w e v e r , is i m p l i c i t i n a n u m b e r o f o t h e r episodes: i n T h e m i s t o c l e s ' insistence t h a t t h e f r e e d o m o f Greece depends u p o n the decision to r e m a i n a t Salamis (8.62.1), o r M a r d o n i u s ' r e a l i z a t i o n o f the n e e d t o c o m e t o terms w i t h the A t h e n i a n s (8.136.2—3). C l e a r l y i t is possible that H e r o d o t u s , i n T h u c y d i d e a n f a s h i o n , ' 9 has k n o w i n g l y p l a n t e d this i m p l i c a t i o n i n c o n f i r m a t i o n o f his earlier j u d g m e n t ; but it is also possible t h a t such a n i m p l i c a t i o n w a s , i n p a r t at least, e m b e d d e d i n such logoi as t h e y came to h i m , a n d t h a t H e r o d o t u s ' v e r d i c t at 7 . 1 3 9 d e r i v e d i n p a r t from such stories. T h i s p h e n o m e n o n o f e m b e d d e d bias c a n be m o r e clearly s h o w n b y a n e x a m p l e t h a t c o n t r a d i c t s his j u d g m e n t o f A t h e n s ' r o l e , w h e n D e m a r a t u s makes a s i m i l a r c l a i m o n b e h a l f o f t h e Spartans (7.209.4):
' U n d e r s t a n d this. I f y o u c o n -
q u e r these m e n a n d those t h a t w a i t i n S p a r t a , n o o t h e r p e o p l e o f m e n r e m a i n , k i n g , w h o w i l l raise t h e i r hands to y o u . ' T h e battle over whose c o n t r i b u t i o n t o t h e w a r was m o s t v i t a l — o n e w h i c h o r i g i n a t e d i m m e d i a t e l y i n t h e a f t e r m a t h o f t h e w a r -has spilled o v e r , i t seems, o n t o t h e pages o f t h e Histories. '
1 0
W e can well understand,
against this b a c k d r o p , w h y H e r o d o t u s s h o w e d some a n x i e t y i n d e l i v e r i n g his v e r d i c t . T h e d e f o r m a t i o n o f H e r o d o t u s ' sources n e e d n o t , h o w e v e r , i n all cases b e m o t i v a t e d b y p a r t i s a n s h i p . I t is d i c t a t e d also b y a desire f o r o r d e r : t h e desire t h a t creates s e m i - m y t h i c a l analogues f o r X e r x e s ' i n v a s i o n o f Greece i n earlier Persian e x p e d i t i o n s , w h i c h sees n a t i o n a l c h a r a c t e r o r nomoi r i g i d l y r e p e a t e d , o r t h e f a t a l i s m w h i c h looks f o r the signs o f t h e e n d o f t h e e x p e d i t i o n a t its outset. I t is p e r h a p s t h e same d r i v e f o r o r d e r w h i c h m o t i v a t e s H e r o d o t u s to ensure t h a t n u m bers r e m a i n r o u n d , o r w h i c h ( o n t h e p a r t o f his sources) has spiri t e d t h e precise synchronisms o f A r t e m i s i u m a n d T h e r m o p y l a e (8.15), Plataea a n d M y c a l e (9.100.2), o r H i m e r a w i t h Salamis o r T h e r m o p y l a e ( 7 . 1 6 6 , D i o d . Sic. 11.24.1). 6 1
59
E.g., Thucydides' emphasis on the growth of Athenian power and Spartan fear in the course of his narrative of die Pentakontaetia. For a defence of the Pentakontaetia. see Rood (1998) ch. 10. See further West (1970), Harrison (2000a) ch. 6; contrast Murray (1988) 471 2, emphasizing the coalescence of different versions of the co-operative Persian wars by comparison with the Ionian Revolt; for the Panhellenic tone of Simonides' Plataea elegy, and for its relationship with the Histories, see e.g., Boedeker (1995), (1996), Rutherford (1996) 175 (though contrast Aloni (1994)). For further discussion of Herodotus' attitude towards Athens, see Ch. 2, this volume. See further Gauthier (1966), Rood (1999), Harrison (2000c). 61
576
THOMAS
HARRISON
We must also contend with the falling away o f many o f the details that we would consider most valuable. The mystery o f the nonappearance of the Persian cavalry at Marathon can only be answered by guess-work (e.g., Lazenby (1993) 59—61). I n other cases, Herodotus' account may disguise more prosaic alternatives. Xerxes' construction o f a mole at Salamis is seen by Herodotus only as a bluff' to conceal his planned retreat: modern historians suggest plausibly that the mole may have been designed for a more positive role, that its construction may in part have predated Salamis, and that the King's decision to retreat was made in a more reasoned and calm fashion.'' Similarly various attempts have been made to find a sober, strategic reason for Leonidas' self-sacrifice at Thermopylae.'' Reconstruction, however, can quickly become fanciful. I n a useful recent corrective, it has been suggested that the absence o f detailed strategic considerations in Herodotus' narrative may only reflect the lack of detailed strategy on the part o f the war's commanders (Lazenby (1993) e.g., 14, 38-9, 79). The reconstruction o f Persian history presents especial difficulties. Though Demaratus' interviews with Xerxes on the virtues o f the Spartans may simply be the product o f Greek imagination, and though what may have been no more than a 'modest superiority' in Persian numbers has been monstrously inflated (Young (1980) 237), there is clearly plenty o f material in the Histories that originates i n near-eastern tradition. The stories o f Xerxes' army marching through the dissected corpse of the son o f Pythius (7.39.3) or o f the punishment o f the Hellespont (7.35) both represent in distorted fashion near-eastern rituals.'' M a n y o f the names o f individual commanders find corroboration i n the clay tablets o f Persepolis (Lewis (1985)); Herodotus' catalogue o f the many different contingents in the Persian army is also likely to originate in Persian material (Armayor (1978a)). 2
3
4
The constraints on the elaboration o f such material clearly are less than in the case o f Herodotus' Greek sources. I n some instances,
62
Hammond (1988b), Lazenby (1993) 163-5, 198. Grant (1961), Lazenby (1993) 144-7. Similarly, Eurybiades' failure to remove to the Isthmus at 8.4 is ascribed to Themistoclcs' bribery, when simple strategic considerations the desire not to leave Leonidas at Thermopylae stranded—may have explained it more adequately: Hammond (1988b) 552. Masson (1950), West (1987) 265-6, Pcrdrizet (1912); cf. Keaveney (1996). 63
61
THE
PERSIAN INVASIONS
577
a kernel of fact appears to have been wilfully misunderstood. The Persian custom of offering proskynesis to their king is falsely represented as constituting a form o f worship (e.g., 7 . 1 3 6 . 1 ) t h i s despite Herodotus' report that the Persians offered proskynesis also to men of higher status w h o m they met on the streets (1.134.l). Similarly, the history o f Persian respect for the gods of foreign peoples is either erased (see e.g., K u h r t and Sherwin-White (1987)) or, as in the case of the Persian invasion o f Greece, presented in such a fashion that rare instances of piety seem inexplicable (Harrison (2000b) 218). The story, at the end of Book Nine, o f the descent o f the Persian court into lust and degeneracy (9.108-114) though it reveals some traces of near-eastern folktale motifs, and o f Persian administrative practice (Sancisi-Weerdenburg (1988))—by virtue o f its position in the Histories has been taken to imply that the defeat in Greece marked the beginning o f the end o f the Persian empire.'* Moreover, beyond the image o f the king's lust for revenge and world dominion both actual features o f Persian court ideology "- -Herodotus can provide us with little idea of the Persians' strategic aims: he gives little sense, for example, o f military activity in the east o f the empire." However, any attempt to reconstruct such a long-term strategy seems inevitably to fall back on the material he provides. A recent 'reassessment' o f the history o f the Persian Wars by a historian o f Persia, for example, seeks to replace the 'Herodotean' model—whereby Persian hybris and despotism are defeated by Greek (or Athenian) democracy- by an interpretation which emphasizes how (in Thucydides' verdict, 1.69.5) the Persians were defeated by their own errors: i f the Persians had been able to avoid battle at Salamis, the Greek alliance would have fractured (Baker (1989)). The 'Herodotean' version of the war here is no more than a caricature, however; Thucydides' judgment indeed might justifiably be described as an accurate paraphrase of Herodotus' account o f the war. to
1
8
This failed reassessment might be taken, finally, as a parable o f our dependence on Herodotus, and of the consistent underestimation of his account by modern readers. It would be wrong, however, to
65
See Bickcrmann (1963), Harrison (2000a) eh. 8. '"' Sancisi-Weerdenburg (1989) reprinted as Gh. 25 in this volume, Briant (1989); contrast Young (1988) 71, 77-8. Young (1988) 69; cf. Kent (1953) DB. Though contrast 1.153.3. 1)8
578
THOMAS
HARRISON
conclude even on this note o f qualified approval- -to applaud the complexity o f Herodotus' presentation o f causation, or his relative lack o f partisanship. For, ultimately, this would be to judge Herodotus by too mean a measure. His purpose is greater: the celebration o f human achievement and diversity—of the 'great and marvellous deeds of Greeks and barbarians'- -and o f the reversals in human fortune that reveal the influence o f the divine i n history. The greatest o f these reversals was the Persian expedition to Greece. 69
See Harrison (2000b) eh. 2, esp. 62 3.
CHAPTER TWENTY-FIVE
T H E PERSONALITY OF XERXES, K I N G OF KINGS* Heleen Sancisi-Weerdenburg
To Louis Vanden Berghe, with warm gratitude A first glance at the current manuals on Persian history would suggest that we are well acquainted with the personality o f Xerxes, king of the Achaemenid empire from his accession i n 486 till his murder i n 465. Born the son o f Atossa, the daughter o f Gyrus the Great, during the kingship o f his father Darius he was raised mostly in the harem (Plato Leges 694D). His father nominated h i m as his successor ( X P f 30-32, H d t . 7.1-2) either for dynastic reasons or because of the influence o f his mother at court. Soon after his accession to the throne he had to cope with rebellions in Egypt and Babylonia. The Babylonian revolt i n particular was the prelude to a new policy towards subject populations: Xerxes did not attempt to continue the well-known Achaemenid policy o f respecting national and religious feelings reflected i n titles such as 'king of Babylon, king o f lands', but henceforth called himself merely 'king o f lands', thus showing overt disregard for Babylonian national pride most clearly demonstrated by the removal o f the cult-statue of M a r d u k from its sanctuary (Hdt. 1.183). A few years later he ventured on an expedition against Greece at the head o f an enormous army that was brought together after three years o f preparations. Notwithstanding the huge expedition-force and a few initial successes, Xerxes' fleet was defeated at Salamis and the king departed hastily from Greek soil, leaving behind his general Mardonius and a number o f picked troops. Mardonius did not fare better than his master and i n 479 the remainder o f the Persian army was destroyed at Plataea. Back i n his own territory Xerxes apparently gave up
* This chapter was originally published in L. de Meyer and E. Haerinck (eds.) Archaeologia Iramca el Orientals Miscellanea in Honorem Louis Vanden Berghe Peeters, Gent, 1989, 549-560.
5 BO
HELEEN
SANCISI-WEERDENBURG
plans for a conquest o f Greece and devoted his time to two matters: building and women. O n this second matter, we are apparently 'well-informed': apart from Herodotus' mention o f the intervention of Atossa in the succession to the throne (7.3), and another reference to the behaviour o f Amestris, Xerxes' wife, who had sacrificed in old age seven young Persian men and seven girls to the god o f the underworld as a substitute for herself (Hdt. 7.1 14), we have the famous episode o f Xerxes' infatuation with his niece Artaynte, a dramatic story that resulted i n the death o f Xerxes' full brother Masistes and his whole family (9.108-113). Xerxes' building-activities are very well known, both from the extant remains and from a number o f inscriptions. M u c h o f what is now still visible at Persepolis, was completed or constructed during Xerxes' reign, i n particular the most impressive palace, the Apadana, was finished by h i m . His portrait once adorned the central and most conspicuous place on the reliefs but was removed to the Treasury at some point after his death, possibly as a result o f the confused situation at court after the palaceconspiracy to which not only Xerxes, but also his designated successor and eldest son Darius fell victim.
The Sources These biographical outlines are based on a variety o f sources: the most important and most elaborate being Herodotus' description of Xerxes' campaign i n books six to nine o f the Histories. Evidence from other sources, royal inscriptions, Babylonian documents and archeological evidence complements or confirms the picture. As a result, our conclusions on the personality of Xerxes, his character and psychological demeanor seem well established: he was a bigot, passionate and a neurasthenic (Dunlop 1912: 74), he was self-righteous (Cook 1983: 122), he was very much i n the shadow of, and under the influence o f his father (Frye 1983: 126), a sovereign o f indolent nature (Arborio Mella 1979: 72), no easy master (Burn 1985: 331), a womaniser whose most impressive construction was the harembuilding (Nyberg 1954: 98), a creature motivated by passion rather than by reason (Immerwahr 1966: 177). I n short, Xerxes was a weak personality whose faults showed mostly i n his religious fanaticism, in his aesthetic enjoyment o f beautiful surroundings and he wasted his time on women o f pernicious influence at the cost o f state-affairs.
T H E PERSONALITY OF XERXES, K I N G OF KINGS
581
These statements on Xerxes' character are taken from both scholarly and more popular discussions o f the Persian empire. It is not difficult to expand this randomly chosen small collection o f samples: There seems to be almost general agreement as to history's verdict on Xerxes: a second rate personality and not really worthy of the throne o f his father. It is remarkable that this picture of Xerxes, based for the larger part on Greek sources, whose hellenocentric bias was recognised long ago, underwent no changes after the discovery o f inscriptions by Xerxes himself, the Daiva and the Harem-inscription in 1935 and X P 1 i n 1967. O n the contrary, these new documents seemed to confirm the judgment of religious intolerance and o f inadequacy in comparison to his father Darius. Taking together all the evidence it seems as i f there are few monarchs in the ancient world whose personality and psychological motivations are so well known to us as Xerxes. I n recent years some criticism has been proffered o f this traditional, virtually unchanging portrait of Xerxes. The evidence for a change of religious policy in Xerxes' reign is far less firm than has been concluded generally: the famous passage o f Herodotus on the removal o f the cult-statue o f M a r d u k has been misread (Kuhrt & Sherwin-White 1987: 71 f ) , there is (new as well as overlooked) evidence that the titulary i n Babylon did not change i n as drastic a way as has often been assumed (ibid.: 72 f ) , the famous Daiva-inscription is not a complete novum but an elaboration of statements already formulated in D B V (Sancisi-Weerdenburg 1980: 16 ff.). I n other respects too, similar criticisms may be made. This could result in some small corrections o f the prevailing ideas on Xerxes' character but it may be more appropriate to investigate how this image originated, on what sources it is based and what kind o f reliable information these sources are likely to yield. This is a question that is equally relevant to much other information on the Persian empire. For many chronological and factual data we have to rely on Greek sources. Knowledge handed down from antiquity has acquired the sanctioning o f tradition: the Greeks had been there, had observed and had come into close contact with the Persians. Their reports are treated as primary evidence, while neglecting one o f the most 1
1
Cf. Sancisi-Weerdenburg 1980: 33 for further examples.
582
HELEEN
SANCISI-WEERDENBURG
f u n d a m e n t a l h i s t o r i c a l rules o f d e a l i n g w i t h sources. I n the case
of
X e r x e s the usual p r o c e d u r e is as f o l l o w s : c o r r o b o r a t i o n is sought i n Persian sources f o r w h a t we k n o w f r o m H e r o d o t u s t h a t X e r x e s m u s t have b e e n l i k e , a n d n o t the o t h e r w a y r o u n d . I f w e k n o w f r o m a (clearly novelistic) tale i n the Histories t h a t X e r x e s h a d a l o v e - a f f a i r (and so w h a t : are there a n y m o n a r c h s w h o have n e v e r used t h e i r e x a l t e d p o s i t i o n i n o r d e r to seduce a b e a u t i f u l girl?) this ' f a c t ' c a n be used to i n t e r p r e t X e r x e s ' b u i l d i n g p o l i c y w h i c h leads f u r t h e r m o r e t o the ' c o n c l u s i o n ' t h a t is u n d e r s t a n d a b l e
that the ' H a r e m '
was
X e r x e s ' m o s t impressive b u i l d i n g ( i f the usually so-called b u i l d i n g was i n d e e d a h a r e m , cf. D e
F r a n c o v i c h 1966:
209).
T h i s type o f r e a s o n i n g consists o f a n u m b e r o f d o u b t f u l links. First, it is b y n o means c e r t a i n i f G r e e k descriptions o f X e r x e s p r o v i d e us w i t h h a r d facts a b o u t t h e king's c h a r a c t e r . O n
the c o n t r a r y , there is
sufficient reason to t h i n k , as I w i l l discuss b e l o w , t h a t this is n o t the case. S e c o n d l y , the b u i l d i n g o f a r o y a l residence is the result o f a great n u m b e r o f factors, i n c l u d i n g a n c i e n t c u l t u r a l t r a d i t i o n s , n e w l y i n t r o d u c e d elements f r o m s u r r o u n d i n g c u l t u r e s , the a v a i l a b i l i t y
of
m o d e l s , m a t e r i a l a n d c r a f t s m e n , a d m i n i s t r a t i v e , b u r e a u c r a t i c , b u t also i d e o l o g i c a l a n d l e g i t i m i s i n g needs. I n s h o r t , a k i n g c a n express his wishes o r even i m p o s e his w h i m s , b u t this is h a r d l y m o r e t h a n one f a c t o r i n a v e r y c o m p l e x system a n d r a r e l y the d e t e r m i n i n g o n e .
In
the s u p e r f i c i a l c o n n e c t i o n , t r a d i t i o n a l l y m a d e b e t w e e n the p e r s o n a l i t y o f X e r x e s a n d the d o c u m e n t s f r o m the h e a r t l a n d o f the e m p i r e , the state is usually r e g a r d e d as a o n e - m a n - s h o w a n d the forces a n d momentum
o f the I r a n i a n a n d M e s o p o t a m i a n
t r a d i t i o n s are
often
c o m p l e t e l y o v e r l o o k e d . T h i s t h i r d p o i n t violates one o f the m o s t f u n d a m e n t a l h i s t o r i c a l r u l e s , n a m e l y t h a t each source s h o u l d p r i m a r i l y be e v a l u a t e d o n its o w n m e r i t s a n d w i t h i n its c u l t u r a l s u r r o u n d i n g s . The
case o f X e r x e s is p a r t i c u l a r l y i l l u m i n a t i n g as i t
demonstrates
h o w pervasive the o f t e n m e n t i o n e d h e l l e n o c e n t r i c bias i n o u r views o f a n c i e n t Persia r e a l l y is. T h e
psychological portrait of Xerxes i n
H e r o d o t u s is used as a c o l l e c t i o n o f established facts w h i c h
more-
o v e r are squeezed far b e y o n d t h e i r o r i g i n a l extent. W h a t is essentially a Greek p i c t u r e o f a n o r i e n t a l m o n a r c h is t r a n s f o r m e d , b y r e a d i n g i n t o the Persian evidence this p r e v i o u s ' k n o w l e d g e ' , i n t o a d e s c r i p t i o n o f a Persian k i n g . I t is a p p r o p r i a t e to q u e s t i o n the w h o l e p r o c e d u r e a n d to a t t e m p t to assess w h a t o u r sources are w o r t h . As I w i l l argue i n this p a p e r , although Herodotus'
p o r t r a y a l o f X e r x e s is persuasive
and beauti-
THE
PERSONALITY
OF XERXES,
KING
OF
583
KINGS
f u l l y e l a b o r a t e d , i t contains v e r y little t h a t a h i s t o r i a n c o u l d use as h a r d evidence f o r the character o f the k i n g a n d i t s h o u l d t h e r e f o r e n o t be used t o elucidate e n i g m a t i c p o i n t s i n the Persian
sources.
Elsewhere I have discussed X e r x e s ' i n s c r i p t i o n s ( S a n c i s i - W e e r d e n b u r g 1980, c h . 1). I n this p a p e r I w i l l c o n c e n t r a t e o n the G r e e k side o f t h e story.
Herodotus H e r o d o t u s , o n whose i n f o r m a t i o n we are mosdy dependent for X e r x e s ' r e i g n , was h a r d l y a c o n t e m p o r a r y o f the G r e a t K i n g . H e
collected
his i n f o r m a t i o n i n the p e r i o d after t h e Persian w a r s a n d
probably
after the d e a t h o f X e r x e s as w e l l . I t s h o u l d be stressed t h a t there is every reason to agree w i t h M o m i g l i a n o ' s j u d g m e n t (1979: Herodotus
150)
of
as a h i s t o r i a n w i t h far m o r e ' i n t e l l e c t u a l generosity' t h a n
a n y o f his l a t e r f e l l o w - G r e e k s .
Complete
i m p a r t i a l i t y is b e y o n d
any
h i s t o r i a n , b u t H e r o d o t u s at least m a d e a v e r y serious a t t e m p t to give d i e Persians a f a i r deal. H e
was, h o w e v e r ,
a h i s t o r i a n a n d h a d to
tell his story: he c o l l e c t e d , o r g a n i s e d a n d a r r a n g e d his m a t e r i a l . I f one realises the c o n d i t i o n s u n d e r w h i c h he a c c o m p l i s h e d this task, one c a n n o t b u t a d m i r e the impressive results. S t i l l , as i n a n y w o r k o f h i s t o r i o g r a p h y , the w a y i n w h i c h i n f o r m a t i o n is chosen, e l a b o r a t e d a n d i n s e r t e d affects the r e l i a b i l i t y the evidence. H e r o d o t u s
is b y n o means the teller o f a n
of
unorgan-
ised n u m b e r o f stories a n d the i n d i s c r i m i n a t i n g r e p o r t e r o f a c o n secutive series o f hearsay
accounts. H i s
clearly evident t h r o u g h o u t markedly
his w o r k ,
presence
even
so t h a n i n others ( I m m e r w a h r
as a n a r r a t o r is
i f i n some p a r t s
more
1977;
1987;
Marincola
D e w a l d 1987). I n the light o f the initial question w i t h w h i c h H e r o d o t u s opens his w o r k " t o preserve the m e m o r y o f the past b y p u t t i n g o n r e c o r d the a s t o n i s h i n g achievements
b o t h o f o u r o w n a n d o f the
A s i a t i c peoples; secondly a n d m o r e p a r t i c u l a r l y , to show h o w t w o races came i n t o c o n f l i c t " ( H d t .
1.1),
the
the k i n g o f Persia w h o a c t u -
ally l e d his a r m y t o the battle w i t h the Greeks is g i v e n a n i m p o r t a n t place i n the story. Herodotus,
however,
is f a r m o r e
cautious t h a n some
o f his
m o d e r n c o m m e n t a t o r s : X e r x e s is n o t the o n l y p e r s o n responsible f o r the c a m p a i g n ; the course o f h i s t o r y is n o t d e t e r m i n e d b y p e r s o n a l decisions o r i n d i v i d u a l actions alone. A l t h o u g h
some persons
may
584
HELEEN
SANCISI-WEERDENBURG
have m o r e i n f l u e n c e o n w h a t is g o i n g to h a p p e n t h a n o t h e r s , m u c h a t t e n t i o n is p a i d to factors t h a t are b e y o n d the grasp o f i n d i v i d u a l h u m a n beings. I n the discussion b e t w e e n X e r x e s a n d his c o u n c i l l o r s o n the plans f o r the c a m p a i g n against G r e e c e , i t is d i v i n e i n t e r v e n t i o n i n the f o r m o f a d r e a m w h i c h
finally
convinces X e r x e s to act
(7.18). S t i l l , because o f his exalted p o s i t i o n , the k i n g o f Persia has greater f r e e d o m o f a c t i o n t h a n a n y o f the o t h e r personalities. T h i s , it s h o u l d be realised, is H e r o d o t u s '
v i s i o n : X e r x e s , like the
characters i n the Histories, are pieces o n H e r o d o t u s '
other
chessboard t h a t
he moves a c c o r d i n g t o the rules, b u t the r e s u l t i n g g a m e is H e r o d o t u s ' own. T o
e x t e n d this m e t a p h o r , we m i g h t ask w h i c h are
Herodotus'
pieces, w h a t are the rules o f the g a m e a n d w h a t moves he
makes
to o b t a i n the desired result. M u c h a t t e n t i o n has been p a i d to H e r o d o t u s '
sources. T h e r e is n o
n e e d to discuss this p r o b l e m here i n d e t a i l . J u d g e d b y the w a y i n which Herodotus roughly
presents his i n f o r m a t i o n , i t c a n be d i v i d e d i n t o
t h r e e k i n d s : a) c o m p l e t e
Herodotus
tales w h i c h p r o b a b l y
reached
as such (e.g. the Pythios story a n d the Masistes-tale), b)
actions o f X e r x e s based o n hearsay
o r o n reports o f
eyewitnesses
(e.g. X e r x e s ' b e h a v i o u r at A b y d o s , at T h e r m o p y l a e a n d d u r i n g the battle o f Salamis) a n d c) discussions o f X e r x e s w i t h his advisers such as A r t a b a n u s ,
Demaratus,
A r t e m i s i a etc. I f o u r interest is m a i n l y i n
X e r x e s ' p e r s o n a l i t y , the value o f these d i f f e r e n t types o f i n f o r m a t i o n is r a t h e r v a r i a b l e . W h a t , f o r instance does a novelistic tale say a b o u t the real c h a r a c t e r o f one o f its m a i n actors? H o w
well were
the
Greeks able to d i s t i n g u i s h b e t w e e n the role o f a n eastern m o n a r c h , far m o r e s u r r o u n d e d b y r i t u a l a n d c e r e m o n i a l p r e s c r i p t i o n s t h a n t h e y w e r e a c c u s t o m e d t o i n t h e i r o w n s u r r o u n d i n g s , a n d the p e r s o n a l i t y o f the i n c u m b e n t o f the office? D o e s the fact t h a t X e r x e s witnessed the sea-battle at Salamis seated o n his c h a i r a n d n o t actively engaged i n c o m b a t as a G r e e k c o m m a n d e r m i g h t b e , say a n y t h i n g a b o u t his c h a r a c t e r o r does i t r a t h e r reveal s o m e t h i n g o f the role a
Persian
k i n g was e x p e c t e d to p e r f o r m ? As to the discussions b e t w e e n X e r x e s a n d his c h i e f c o u n c i l l o r s , i t is clear t h a t i f eye-witnesses h a d b e e n present at a l l , the r e p o r t t h e y m i g h t have g i v e n w o u l d have b e c o m e r a t h e r d i s t o r t e d i n the course o f the fifty years b e t w e e n the Persian w a r s a n d the c o m p o s i t i o n the Histories. I n these cases especially i t is m o s t l i k e l y t h a t d i r e c t l y r e m o u l d e d o r recreated his m a t e r i a l . T h e
of
Herodotus
Greek informa-
t i o n w e have o f X e r x e s ' c h a r a c t e r thus consists o f eye-witness r e p o r t s
THE
PERSONALITY
OF XERXES,
KING
OF
585
KINGS
w h i c h in all p r o b a b i l i t y c o n t a i n a n e t h n o c e n t r i c bias: i t is h a r d e n o u g h to j u d g e the c h a r a c t e r a n d p e r s o n a l i t y o f someone i n office w i t h i n one c u l t u r e , b u t i t is n e a r l y impossible to m a k e s i m i l a r evaluations i f one does n o t have a solid grasp o f the c u l t u r a l codes a n d the i n s t i tutionalised behaviour required i n an entirely different culture. The
f a m o u s episode o f X e r x e s chastising the H e l l e s p o n t has u s u -
ally b e e n i n t e r p r e t e d as p r o o f o f X e r x e s ' v i o l e n t a n d irascible t e m p e r : o u r k n o w l e d g e of ritual a n d religious b e h a v i o u r of Persian kings is so l i m i t e d t h a t the a s s u m p t i o n o f X e r x e s a c t i n g o u t his p e r s o n a l a n g e r is h a z a r d o u s , even i f H e r o d o t u s
c l e a r l y describes X e r x e s act-
i n g in such t e r m s . B u t even w h e n H e r o d o t u s
explicitly mentions a
Persian c u s t o m , i t is o f t e n i n t e r p r e t e d as a p e r s o n a l a c t i o n as, f o r e x a m p l e , i n the case o f the h u m a n sacrifice o f A m e s t r i s i n 7 . 1 1 4 . 2
Xerxes and women T h e ' s h o r t stories' i n the Histories i n w h i c h X e r x e s figures are e q u a l l y p r o b l e m a t i c sources f o r the person o f the k i n g : they p r o b a b l y
orig-
i n a t e d in a p o p u l a r n a r r a t i v e t r a d i t i o n a n d t h e r e is n o reason suppose t h a t t h e y c o n t a i n m u c h s o l i d evidence. I t has been
to
argued
f o r o t h e r s i m i l a r stories t h a t the p a t t e r n was m u c h o l d e r t h a n the figures
n a m e d i n i t ( L o r d 1970:
27;
see also c h . 13, this v o l u m e . ) .
I n a n o t h e r c o n t e x t , the t e r m g e n e - p o o l o f s t o r y - m o t i f s has b e e n used ( G r i f f i t h s 1987:
37). Some o f these tales c o n t a i n a n u m b e r o f m o t i f s
t h a t c a n be f o u n d i n s i m i l a r stories a b o u t o t h e r persons. T h e
famous
story o f X e r x e s ' love f o r his niece A r t a y n t e has some parallels i n the B o o k o f Esther (cf. S a n c i s i - W e e r d e n b u r g i n g p a r a l l e l i n the story o f H e r o d i a s
1980: 63) a n d a v e r y strik-
(Matthew
14,
1-12). I t is this
tale t h a t is responsible f o r X e r x e s ' r e p u t a t i o n as a sensual p e r s o n , easily c a r r i e d a w a y b y his passions a n d above a l l a w o m a n i s e r was
unable
to c o n t r o l his e n t o u r a g e
firmly" (Hignett
H i s t o r y j u d g e s easily, a l t h o u g h i t s h o u l d be n o t e d t h a t is m o r e
1963:
"who 89).
Herodotus
p r u d e n t t h a n m a n y o f his l a t e r colleagues. H i s
portrait
o f X e r x e s is far r e m o v e d f r o m the simplistic d e p i c t i o n o f a t y r a n t ( G a m m i e 1986:
2
183). H e r o d o t u s
shows h o w the k i n g is c a u g h t in a
Cf. Legrand, comm. on Hdt. 9.109: "Amestris faire preuve d'une impitoyable cruauté".
devait jusqu'à ses vieux jours
586
HELEEN
SANCISI-WEERDENBURG
tragic e n t a n g l e m e n t b e t w e e n the p r e s c r i p t i o n s o f his o f f i c e , the l a w t h a t the k i n g s h o u l d give w h a t e v e r
he is asked f o r , a n d the p a r t l y
unforeseen consequences o f the f u l f i l m e n t o f this r u l e . O n e t h a t X e r x e s ' generosity to his niece i n this tale is too
c o u l d say unreserved,
b u t there is, as far as I c a n see, n o e l e m e n t i n the story w h i c h w a r rants a j u d g m e n t o f the k i n g as a n abuser o f his r o y a l p o w e r seduce w o m e n .
On
to
the c o n t r a r y , i n the p r o l o g u e t o the m o s t d r a -
m a t i c p a r t o f the story, X e r x e s ' i n f a t u a t i o n w i t h A r t a y n t e
a n d its
subsequent disastrous results, the k i n g uses n e i t h e r threats n o r v i o lence b u t a p p a r e n t l y accepts his r e j e c t i o n b y his s i s t e r - i n - l a w , w h o o r i g i n a l l y was the o b j e c t o f X e r x e s ' love. T h i s story a n d this story alone has e a r n e d X e r x e s the r e p u t a t i o n o f b e i n g a w e a k l i n g
who
was c o n t r o l l e d b y the w o m e n a r o u n d h i m . E v e n i f the tale c o u l d be d e m o n s t r a t e d to be a piece o f h i s t o r i o g r a p h y i t seems a b i t h a r s h to base a b a d r e p u t a t i o n o n a single i n c i d e n t a n d f u r t h e r m o r e to define i t as the cause o f the g r a d u a l decline o f a w h o l e e m p i r e . T h e r e are three o t h e r i n c i d e n t s i n v o l v i n g w o m e n i n the r e c o r d e d events o f X e r x e s ' life: one involves his m o t h e r , t w o his w i f e . T h u s , his accession to the t h r o n e is supposed to be due to the i n f l u e n c e o f Atossa, his m o t h e r . Y e t ,
nowhere
else does H e r o d o t u s
mention
Atossa as still alive d u r i n g the l a t e r p a r t o f X e r x e s ' life a n d he gives no clue as to the r e l a t i o n s h i p b e t w e e n m o t h e r a n d son. T h e r e is e q u a l l y n o trace i n the Histories o f the i n f l u e n c e o f q u e e n o n h e r h u s b a n d . R a t h e r the opposite: i n the A r t a y n t e
Amestris
episode
she
has to w a i t f o r a f o r m a l occasion to o b t a i n the revenge she desires. P r o o f o f h e r v i n d i c t i v e n a t u r e is r a t h e r p o o r : sacrifice, h o w e v e r
abhorrent they may
motives for
human
seem t o us, are m o r e
fre-
q u e n t l y the result o f r e l i g i o u s codes t h a n p e r s o n a l feelings o f v a n i t y a n d c r u e l t y . X e r x e s ' relations w i t h w o m e n , as r e p o r t e d b y
Herodotus,
is m u c h m o r e a t r a g i c story o f a k i n g c a u g h t b e t w e e n d u t y a n d fate, t h a n o f the lecherous m o n a r c h m o d e r n c o m m e n t a t o r s i n the A r t a y n t e - s t o r y .
have
found
I n the s i t u a t i o n d e s c r i b e d i t is n o t so m u c h
the seductive p o w e r s o f w o m e n w h i c h place X e r x e s i n a d i f f i c u l t situ a t i o n , b u t the o b l i g a t i o n t o adhere to his r o y a l d u t y a n d n o t t o go b a c k o n his p r o m i s e . 3
Flory's conclusion that Xerxes "is even less intelligent than Candaules for he
THE
PERSONALITY
OF XERXES, KING
OF
587
KINGS
Xerxes' personality in Herodotus Although Herodotus'
sources c l e a r l y d i d n o t p r o v i d e reliable m a t e
r i a l to analyse X e r x e s ' p s y c h o l o g i c a l d e v e l o p m e n t , i t is very m u c h a p e r s o n a l i t y w h i c h we m e e t o n the pages o f the Histories. W h i l e i t is a m a t t e r o f debate w h e t h e r the elements o f X e r x e s ' b e h a v i o u r t a k e n t o g e t h e r represent a g r a d u a l c h a r a c t e r - e v o l u t i o n , i t seems d o u b t t h a t i n his t e x t H e r o d o t u s
beyond
has m o d e l l e d a n d s c u l p t u r e d the
p e r s o n o f X e r x e s . L a u g h t e r at w h a t w e k n o w f r o m h i n d s i g h t to be inappropriate moments
m a r k s f o r instance those t r a g i c situations
w h e r e X e r x e s underestimates the p o t e n t i a l consequences o f his actions o r orders. As L a t e i n e r has a r g u e d : " f e w laughs are r e c o r d e d f o r pos t e r i t y . T h e y are m o s t o f t e n s u b - h i s t o r i c a l n o n - e v e n t s "
(1977:
175).
The
m a i n f u n c t i o n o f such l a u g h s , w h i c h u n a v o i d a b l y signal disas
ter,
is to create a p a t t e r n w h i c h "helps the a c c o u n t c a r r y a n o n -
e x p l i c i t i n t e r p r e t a t i o n " (ibid.: 182). I n o t h e r w o r d s , l a u g h t e r a n d o t h e r n o n - v e r b a l f o r m s o f c o m m u n i c a t i o n are H e r o d o t u s '
means o f c o n
s t r u c t i n g the t e x t i n o r d e r to f o r m a c o m p r e h e n s i b l e e x p l a n a t i o n
of
w h a t h a d h a p p e n e d w h i l e at the same t i m e c r e a t i n g tension b e t w e e n the p a r t i c i p a n t s ' o b s e r v a t i o n o f the events i n the i m m e d i a t e f u t u r e a n d historical knowledge o f w h a t really h a p p e n e d . A t c e r t a i n m o m e n t s this t e n s i o n is m a d e m o r e d r a m a t i c b y e x p l i c i t p r e d i c t i o n s o f d o o m as e.g. i n the A r t a y n t e - s t o r y : to a b a d e n d " (9.109).
" h e r w h o l e f a m i l y was b o u n d t o c o m e
Whatever Artaynte
does, w h a t e v e r
Xerxes
replies, disaster is forecast a n d i n e v i t a b l e . W e e p i n g m a y also serve to enhance the d i s c r e p a n c y b e t w e e n helpless i n a c t i o n a n d the course the events are t o take: w h e n X e r x e s bursts i n t o tears after his i n s p e c t i o n o f the a r m y a n d fleet at A b y d o s (7.45), H e r o d o t u s ' t i o n o f the event a n d the subsequent Artabanus
signals less the h y b r i s t i c m o n a r c h
p r e p a r e d to take reasonable risks a n d
descrip
c o n v e r s a t i o n w i t h his u n c l e follow
t h a n a m a n w h o is i n the
footsteps
o f his
predecessors o n · the Persian t h r o n e (7.8). Fate ( δ α ι μ ο ν ί η τ ι ς γ ί ν ε τ α ι ο ρ μ ή ) , as A r t a b a n u s
says, 7.18)
m e a n w h i l e has d e c i d e d t h a t things
w i l l h a p p e n d i f f e r e n t l y f r o m w h a t c o u l d be foreseen. I t is o n l y w i t h
twice makes dangerous promises and is unable to learn from the unfortunate results not to make the second" (1978: 152) underestimates the fact that the occasion of Amestris' request was a customary one (9.111) and that Xerxes was compelled by law (ύπό τοΰ νόμου έξεργόμενος). He not only could not have refused, even avoid ance of the occasion was beyond his power, as Herodotus recognises.
588
HELEEN
SANCISI-WEERDENBURG
h i n d s i g h t t h a t w e k n o w his c a l c u l a t i o n s w e r e w r o n g ; even a n u m b e r o f G r e e k cities at the t i m e o f X e r x e s ' c a m p a i g n w e r e n o t p a r t i c u l a r l y c o n f i d e n t o f G r e e k v i c t o r y . T h i s is n o t the r i g h t place to discuss the elements o f X e r x e s ' c h a r a c t e r i s a t i o n i n H e r o d o t u s ' text. V e r y often the emphasis has been p u t o n the Persian king's hybristic behaviour. T h e r e are, however, several factors i n his p o r t r a i t u r e by
Herodotus
w h i c h a d d u p to a t r a g i c X e r x e s , a m a n u n a b l e to escape fate.
A
f u r t h e r analysis o f the text a n d a close s c r u t i n y o f the r e l e v a n t passages m a y result i n a b e t t e r u n d e r s t a n d i n g o f H e r o d o t u s ' i n s i g h t i n t o the i n t e r r e l a t i o n b e t w e e n the destined course o f events a n d
human
i n t e r f e r e n c e i n h i s t o r y . H e r e i t is o n l y necessary to note t h a t the X e r x e s o f the Histories is as m u c h a p r o d u c t o f H e r o d o t u s '
sources
as o f the a u t h o r ' s conscious c o n s t r u c t i o n o f his n a r r a t i v e . I f w e are discussing the p s y c h o l o g y o f X e r x e s i n H e r o d o t u s '
a c c o u n t , w e are
i n fact d e a l i n g w i t h H e r o d o t u s ' h i s t o r i c a l u n d e r s t a n d i n g a n d w i t h his t e c h n i q u e s f o r w r i t i n g u p the results o f his investigations. T h e r e are at least several layers b e t w e e n the p e r s o n a l i t y o f X e r x e s , as k i n g o f Persia a n d as c o m m a n d e r tion. The
o f his armies d u r i n g the G r e e k e x p e d i -
u p p e r m o s t o f these layers is H e r o d o t u s '
careful and con-
v i n c i n g r e p r e s e n t a t i o n , w h i c h makes us feel as i f w e are e n c o u n t e r i n g a real life p e r s o n a l i t y . B u t w e s h o u l d be w a r n e d t h a t w h a t w e r e a d is " n e i t h e r f a c t n o r
1987: 103).
fiction
but 'transfigured t r a d i t i o n ' "
(Lateiner
4
The sources from Persia T h e persuasiveness o f H e r o d o t u s ' p o r t r a i t plus the fact t h a t centuries o f h i s t o r i o g r a p h y o n the Persian e m p i r e w e r e based o n the G r e e k sources is p r o b a b l y
responsible f o r the strange s i t u a t i o n t h a t
G r e e k evidence is used t o e x p l a i n puzzles i n the Persian
the
sources,
w h i c h , i f s t u d i e d o n t h e i r o w n m e r i t s , w o u l d n o t have b e e n p u z z l i n g at a l l . T h i s is m o s t s t r i k i n g l y so i n the case o f X e r x e s ' i n s c r i p t i o n s w h i c h have b e e n s t u d i e d , analysed a n d c o m p l e m e n t e d i n the cert a i n t y t h a t the G r e e k sources c o n t a i n e d 'established facts'. T h e
Daiva-
i n s c r i p t i o n r e a d i n this l i g h t thus p r e s e n t e d c o n f i r m a t i o n o f the fact
4
Lateiner adds: "interpretation and reconstruction structure the amorphous data of every historical investigation" (Ibid.)
THE
PERSONALITY
OF XERXES,
that Xerxes w h o , i n Herodotus'
KING
OF KINGS
589
a c c o u n t , c a r e f u l l y listens to his r e l i -
gious advisers, as, i t s h o u l d be n o t e d , a k i n g o u g h t , was a religious fanatic a n d b i g o t , w h o d e v i a t e d f r o m the f a m o u s religious tolerance p r a c t i s e d b y his predecessors.
S t u d i e d o n its o w n m e r i t s the Daiva-
i n s c r i p t i o n shows a s t r i k i n g c o n t i n u i t y w i t h especially the last c o l u m n o f 1)11: one m i g h t c o n c l u d e t h a t instead o f d e v i a t i n g , X e r x e s ' p o l i c y was a f u r t h e r a r t i c u l a t i o n o f the p r o g r a m m e father (Sancisi-Weerdenburg
1980:
35). O n
set o u t b y his
the w h o l e , the f o r m u l a i c
c h a r a c t e r o f t h e i n s c r i p t i o n s has b e e n u n d e r v a l u e d . T o o
o f t e n they
are r e a d as the p e r s o n a l statements o f i n d i v i d u a l s , u n d e r e s t i m a t i n g the forces o f a t r a d i t i o n , be i t a w r i t t e n o r a n o r a l l i t e r a r y o n e , w h i c h set c e r t a i n l i m i t s to p e r s o n a l ideas o f kings w h o , as seems to be generally agreed, w e r e themselves i l l i t e r a t e a n d h a d at least to dictate to scribes w h o k n e w the a p p r o p r i a t e w o r d s a n d phrases. A p a r t f r o m the i n f l u e n c e o f o u r h e l l e n o c e n t r i c bias, the i m p o r t a n c e o f r i t u a l s u r r o u n d i n g the k i n g ' s office is u n d e r e s t i m a t e d : kings are kings i n a t r a d i t i o n , t h e i r office is based o n c o n t i n u i t y , t h e i r sayings
are
n o t expressions o f t h e i r p a r t i c u l a r state o f m i n d o n a specific occasion b u t r o y a l declarations o f the state o f affairs. W h e n X e r x e s repeats the same lines i n the i n s c r i p t i o n f o u n d i n 1967 i n Persepolis as D a r i u s d i d i n the i n s c r i p t i o n o n his t o m b , the o n l y possible c o n c l u s i o n is: this is w h a t a Persian k i n g o u g h t t o say, this is w h a t Persian k i n g s h i p — a n d n o t the i n c i d e n t a l h o l d e r o f the o f f i c e — s h o u l d l o o k like/' B e f o r e a s s u m i n g t h a t t w o d i f f e r e n t types o f evidence c o n f i r m each o t h e r , i t s h o u l d be analysed w h e t h e r i n fact they d o c o n t a i n the same k i n d o f i n f o r m a t i o n . I n the case o f the X e r x e s o f the i n s c r i p tions a n d the X e r x e s o f H e r o d o t u s ,
there is n o j u s t i f i c a t i o n i n using
Cf. Cook 1983: 69 on the inscriptions: " O f all the kings Darius I was much the most loquacious in his inscriptions, indeed he was even introspective. Xerxes came second to him; but a long text of his found near Persepolis in 1967 repeats
in his own name what his father had said in a very personal vein about himself at Naqsh-i Rustam (DNb), so it may not be entirely cynical to wonder whether even his celebrated 'daiwa inscription' may not also turn out to be less original than has been supposed (ital. H.S.-W.). It is not at all cynical: a new copy of XPh, in the name of Xerxes or Darius would only be a missing part in the development of a royal ideology, for which, at present we have only evidence from early in Darius' reign and from Xerxes' reign. Cook's verdict stems from a mistaken belief in the individual character of the texts, which in turn depends on the fact that the Greek sources portray the kings as individual human beings. Even an Iranist such as Fryc (1983: 121) thus comes to the following statement on XPh: "Only Xerxes among die Achaemenid kings showed strong feelings about religion".
590
HELEEN
SANCISI-WEERDENBURG
the d a t a as c o m p l e m e n t a r y
t o each o t h e r . T h e i n s c r i p t i o n s p r o v i d e
i n f o r m a t i o n o n t h e r o y a l i d e o l o g y , the Histories give i n s i g h t i n t o t h e G r e e k v i s i o n o f a n eastern m o n a r c h . I n Persian s u r r o u n d i n g s w e d o n o t f i n d a n y evidence
t h a t c a n b e used f o r c o n s t r u c t i n g a p s y c h o -
l o g i c a l p o r t r a i t o f X e r x e s , o r o f a n y o f the o t h e r rulers o f the A c h a e m e n i d e m p i r e . T h i s is m o s t clearly i l l u s t r a t e d b y the Persepolis a n d the N a q s - i R u s t a m reliefs a n d t h e p r o b l e m s caused i n t r y i n g t o i d e n t i f y t h e kings s c u l p t u r e d i n various positions a n d i n various If not by an accompanying
places.
i n s c r i p t i o n o r b y t h e headgear t h e y are
w e a r i n g , i t is impossible t o i d e n t i f y w h i c h k i n g is d e p i c t e d . 6 T h i s c a n h a r d l y be d u e to i n a b i l i t y o f the sculptors, w h o i n a l l l i k e l i h o o d w e r e capable
o f g i v i n g some i n d i v i d u a l i t y t o a p o r t r a i t i f necessary
or
r e q u i r e d . A g a i n , t h e c o n c l u s i o n is j u s t i f i e d t h a t , i f i n d i v i d u a l kings are i n d e e d p o r t r a y e d , i t is above all t h e u n c h a n g i n g t r a d i t i o n a l aspects o f k i n g s h i p t h a t w e r e emphasised a n d expressed. I f w e w a n t t o study t h e A c h a e m e n i d e m p i r e o n its o w n t e r m s , i t s h o u l d be a p p r o a c h e d f r o m this angle: h o w are t r a d i t i o n a n d i n n o vation
reflected i n the extant
processes,
documentation?
w h i c h h a d their o w n m o m e n t u m ,
Before
connecting
w i t h the i n t e r f e r e n c e
(or lack o f action) o f specific kings, i t s h o u l d be realised t h a t m a n y o f the questions w e have been asking s h o w t h e same h e l l e n o - c e n t r i c bias as o u r results. Seen f r o m a Persian p o i n t o f v i e w , t h e r e i g n o f X e r x e s m a y w e l l t u r n o u t t o be t h e glorious h i g h p o i n t o f A c h a e m e n i d history a n d n o t the m o m e n t
6
at w h i c h decline set i n .
As e.g. in the ease of the Treasury-reliefs. Porada (1985: 816-9) sees Darius as the enthroned king, mainly for stylistic reasons, against Von Gall (1974: 148 If.) who has pointed out that the king on the throne does not have the crown with crenelations which is characteristic for Darius.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Note: abbreviations for journal titles are according to L'année philologique. Aarne, Α., and S. Thompson. (1961). 'Lie Types of the Folktale. Helsinki. Aloni, A. (1994). 'L'elcgia di Simonide dedicata alia battaglia di Platea (Sim. frr. 10 18 W2) e l'occasione della sua performance'. fPE 102: 9-22. Alonso-Nufiez, J. M . (1988). 'Herodotus' Ideas about World Empires'. AncSoc 19: 125-33. AlthofI, J. (1993). 'Herodot und die griechische Medizin'. In Antike Naturwissenschaft und ihre Rezeption, ed. K. Döring and G. Wöhrle, 1-16. Bamberg. Aly, W. (1921). Volksmärchen, Sage und Novelle bei Herodot, und seinen Zeitgenossen. Eine Untersuchung über die volkstümlichen Elemente der allgriechischen Prosaerzählung. Göttingen. (1969). 2d cd. Göttingen. (1929). Formprobleme der frühen griechischen Prosa. Philologus Suppl. 21. Leipzig. (1987). 2d ed. New York. Andrewes, A. (1977). 'Kleisthenes' Reform Bill'. CQ 27: 241-8. Annequin, J. (1976). Comment on Tourraix (1976). DHA 2: 386 9. Appleby, J., L. Hunt, and M.Jacob. (1994). Telling the Truth About History. New York. Arborio Mella, F. A. (1979). L'impero persiano. Da Giro il Grande alia conquista araba. Milan. Armayor, O. K. (1978a). 'Herodotus' Catalogue of the Persian Empire'. TAPhA 108: 1-9. - . (1978b). 'Did Herodotus Ever Go to the Black Sea?' HSPh 82: 45 62. - --. (1978c). 'Did Herodotus ever go to Egypt?' journal of the American Research Center in ELgypt 15: 59-73. (1985). Herodotus' Autopsy of the Fayounv Lake Moeris and the Labyrinth of Egypt. Amsterdam. Artamonov, M . I . (1969). Treasures from Scythian Tombs in the Hermitage Museum, Leningrad. London. Asheri, D. (1988). Erodoto, L ; Storie. Libro 1: La Lidia e la Persia. Introduzione, lesio, commenta. Milan. -. (1990). 'Herodotus on Thracian Society and History'. In Hérodote et les peuples non grecs, Entretiens Hardt 35, 131-69. Geneva. ••-. (1997). 'Lotte per l'egemonia e l'indipendenza nel V e I V secolo a. C . In I Grea. Sloria, cullura, arte, sociela II 2, cd. S. Settis, 163-89. Turin. Asheri, D., and S. M . Medaglia. (1990). Erodoto, !..£ Stone. Libro üi: La Persia. Rome. Austin, T. R. (1984). Language Crafted: A Linguistic Theory of Poetic Syntax. Bloomington. <\very, H. C. (1972). 'Herodotus' Picture of Cyrus'. AJPh 93: 529-46. -. (1979). Ά Poetic Word in Herodotus'. Elermes 107: 1-9. \yo, N . (1984). 'Prolog and Epilog: Mythical History in Herodotus'. Ramus 13: 31 47. (Saba, K. (1990). 'The Macedonian/Thracian Coastland and the Greeks in the Sixth and Fifth Centuries B.C.' Kodai 1: 1 23. Backhaus, W. (1976). 'Der Hellenen-Barbaren-Gegensatz und die hippokratische Schrift Peri aerôn hydatôn lopôri. Historia 25: 1 70 85. Badian, E. (1993). From Plalaea to Potidaea: Studies in the History and Historiography of the Penleconlaetia. Baltimore. -. (1994). 'Herodotus on Alexander I of Macedon: A Study in Some Subtle Silences'. In Greek Historiography, ed. S. Hornblower, 107 30. Oxford.
592
BIBLIOGRAPHY
—. (1996). 'Phrynichus and Adieus' οικεία κακά'. SCI Ιό: a5-60. Bailey, Sir H . (1980). Ossetic'. In Traditions of Heroic and Epic Poetry, ed. A. T. Hatto, 236 67. London. Bakker, E.J. (1993). 'Topics, Boundaries, and the Structure of Discourse: An Inves tigation of the Particle Di. Studies in Language 17: 275-311. . (1997a). Poetry in Speech: Orality and Homeric Discourse. Ithaca and London. (1997b). 'Storytelling in the Future: Truth, Time, and Tense in Homeric Epic'. In Written Voices, Spoken Signs: Tradition, Performance, and the Epic Text, ed. E. J. Bakker and A. Kahane, 11-36. Cambridge, M A . —. (1997c). 'The Study of Homeric Discourse'. In A Mew Companion to Homer, ed. I . Morris and B. Powell, 284 304. Leiden. —. (1997d). 'Verbal Aspect and Mimetic Description in Thucydides'. In Grammar as Interpretation: Greek Literature in its Linguistic Contexts, ed. E.J. Bakker, 7-54. Leiden. -, ed. (1997e). Grammar as Interpretation: Greek Literature in its Linguistic Contexts. Leiden. -. (1999a). 'How Oral is Oral Composition?' In .Signs of Orality, ed. A. Mackay, 29-47. Leiden. (1999b). 'Homeric ΟΥΤΟΣ and the Poetics of Debris'. CPh 94: 1 19. -. (1999c). 'Pointing to the Past: Verbal Augment and Temporal Dcixis in Homer'. In Euphrosyne. Studies in Honor of D. .N. Maroniiis, ed. J. N. Kazazis and A. Rengakos, 50 65. Stuttgart. Bai, M . (1985). .Narratology: Introduction to the Theory of '.Nanative. Toronto. (1997). 2d ed. Balcer, J. M . (1987). Herodotus and Bisitun: Problems in Ancient Persian Historiography. Historia Einzelschriften 49. Stuttgart. (1989). 'The Persian Wars against Greece: A Reassessment'. Historia 38: 127 43. Ball, R. (1979). 'Generation Dating in Hcrodotos'. CQ, 29: 276-81. Barcelo, P. (1993). Basikia. Monorchia, Tyrannis: Untersuchungen zur Entwicklung und Beurteilung von Alleinherrschaft im vorhellenislischen Griechenland. Historia Einzelschriften 79. Stuttgart. Barnes, J. (1979). The Presocratic Philosophers. 2 vols. London. Barron, J. P. (1966). The Siher Coins of Samos. London. . (1988). 'The Liberation of Greece'. In Tlie Cambridge Ancient History, vol. 4, cd. J. Boardman, Ν. G. L. Hammond, D. Μ. Lewis, and VI. Ostwald, 592-622. 2d ed. Cambridge. Barth, H . (1964). 'Einwirkungen der vorsokratischen Philosophie auf die Herausbildung der historiographischcn Methoden Herodots'. In Neue Beiträge zur Geschichte der Alten Well 1: Aller Orient und Griechenland, ed. E. C. Welskopf, 173-83. Berlin. —. (1965). 'Das Verhalten des Themistokles gegenüber dem Gelde'. Klio 45: 30 7. —. (1968). 'Zur Bewertung und Auswahl des Stolfes durch Herodot (Die Begriffe thSma, thömazß, thSmasios, und thomastos)'. Klio 50: 93-110. Bauman, R. (1986). Story, Performance, and Event: Contextual Studies of Oral Narrative. Cambridge Studies in Oral and Literate Culture 10. Cambridge. Beard, M . , and J. Henderson. (1997). 'With This Body I Thee Worship: Sacred Prostitution in Antiquity'. Gender and History 9: 480-503. Beaulieu, P. A. (1989). The Reign of Nabonidus, King of Babylon, 556-539 B.C. Yale Near Eastern Researches. New Haven. Beck, I . (1971). Die Ringkomposition hei Herodot und ihre Bedeutung für die Beweistechnik. Hildesheim. Belfiore, E. (2000). Murder among Friends: Violation of Philia in Greek 'Tragedy. Oxford. Bellen, Η. (1974). 'Der Rachegedanke in der griechisch-persischen Auseinandersetzung'. Chiron 4: 43-67. (1997). Reprint. H . Bellen, Politik -Recht Gesellschaft: Studien zur Allen Geschichte, Historia Einzelschriften 115, 1 24. Stuttgart. Benardete, S. (1969). Herodolean Inquiries. The Hague. Berger, P.-R. (1970). 'Das Neujahrsfest nach den Königsinschriften des ausgehen-
•
BIBLIOGRAPHY
593
den babylonischen Reiches'. In Actes de la XVII" Rencontre Assyriologique Internationale: Universite Libre de ßruxelles, 30 juin-4 juillet, 1969, ed. A. Einet, 155-59. Ham-surHeure. (1973). Die rumbabylonischen Königsinschriften. Königsinschriften des ausgehenden babylonischen Reiches (626-539 a. Chr.). Alter Orient und Alles Testament, Vol. 4 / 1 . Neukirchen-Vluyn. Berkhofer, R. (1995). Beyond the Great Story: History as Text and Discourse. Cambridge. MA. Berve, H. (1967). Die Tyrannis bei den Griechen. 2 vols. Munich. Bichler, R. (1985). 'Die 'Rcichsträume' Herodots. Eine Studie zu Herodots schöpferischer Leistung und ihrer quellcnkritischcn Konsequenz'. Chiron 15: 125-47. —. (2000). Herodots Well. Der Aufbau der 'Historie' am Bild der fremden Lander und Volker, ihrer Zivilisation und ihrer Geschichte. Berlin. Bichler, R., and R. Rollinger. (2000). Herodot. Olms Studienbücher Antike 3. Hildesheim. Dickel. E. (1957). 'Rekonstruktionsversuch einer hellenistischen Gyges-Nysia-Tragödie'. R/M 100: 141 52. Bickermann, E. J. (1952). 'Origines Gentium'. CPh 47: 65-81. (1963). ' A propos d'un passage de Chares de Mytilene'. PP 18: 241-55. Bicknell, P. J. (1982). 'Thernistocles' Father and Mother'. Hislona 31: 161 73. Bigwood, J. VI. (1978). 'Ctesias as Historian of the Persian Wars'. Phoenix 32: 1 9 4 1 . Binder, G. (1964). Die Aussetzung des Königskindes: Kyros und Romulus. Meisenheim am Glan. Biraschi, A . - M . (1989). Tradizioni epiche e sloriogrqfia. Studi su Erodoto e Tucidide. Perugia. Bischoff, Fl. (1932). Der Warner bei Herodot. Borna-Leipzig. (1962). Reprint (extracts). In Herodot. Eine Auswahl aus der neueren Forschung. Wege der Forschung 26, cd. W. Marg. Munich. (1965). 2d ed. Munich. (1982). 3d ed. Darmstadt/ Bleicken, J. (1979). 'Zur Entstehung der Verfassungstypologie im 5. Jahrhundert v. Chr'. Hislona 28: 148 72. Blok, J. H . (1995). The Early Amazons: Modern and Ancient Perspectives on a Persistent Myth. Leiden. Bloomer, W. M . (1993). 'The Superlative Nomoi of Herodotus's Histories'. ClAnl 12: 30 50. Blundell, M . W. (1989). Helping Friends and Making Enemies: A Study in Sophocles and Greek Ethics. Cambridge. Boardman, Sir J. (1994). Hie Diffusion if Classical Art in Antiquity. London. Boardman, J., N . G. L. Hammond, D. M . Lewis, and M . Ostwald, eds. (1988). Persia, Greece and the Western. Mediterranean, c. 525-479 B.C. Cambridge Ancient History, vol. 4, 2d ed. Cambridge. Boedeker, D. (1987). 'The Two Faces of Demaratus'. In Herodotus and die Invention of History, Arethusa 20, cd. D. Boedeker and J. Peradotto, 185-201. Buffalo. -. (1988). 'Protesilaus and the End of Herodotus' Histories'. ClAnl 7: 30-48. -. (1993). 'Hero Cult and Politics in Herodotus: The Bones of Orestes'. In Cultural Poetics in Archaic Greece: Cull, Peiformance, Politics, ed. C. Dougherty and L. Kurke, 164-77. Cambridge, M A . ·-. (1995). 'Simonidcs on Plataea: Narrative Elegy, Mythodic History'. 2fPE 107: 217-29. (1996). 'Heroic Historiography: Simonides and Herodotus on Plataea'. Arethusa 29: 223-42. (1998). 'Presenting the Past in Fifth-Century Athens'. In Democracy, Empire, and the Arts in Fifth-Century Athens. Center for Hellenic, Studies Colloquia 2, ed. D. Boedeker and K. Raaflaub, 185-202. Cambridge, M A . —. (2000). 'Herodotus's Genre(s)'. In Matrices of Genre. Authors, Canons, and Society, ed. iVI. Depew and D. Obbink, 97-114. Cambridge, M A .
594
BIBLIOGRAPHY
-. (2001). 'Heroic Historiography: Simonides and Herodotus on Plataea'. In The Mew Simonides: Contexts of Praise and Desire, ed. D. Bocdeker and D. Sider, 120 34. Oxford and New York. Boedeker, D., and J. Peradotto, eds. (1987). Herodotus and die Invention of History. Arethusa 20. Buffalo. Boedeker, D., and K . Raaflaub, eds. (1998). Democracy, Empire, and the Arts in FifthCentury Athens. Center for Hellenic Studies Colloquia. 2. Cambridge VIA. Boedeker, D., and D. Sider, eds. (2001). The .New Simonides: Contexts of Praise and Desire. Oxford and New York. Boer, W. den (1967). 'Herodot und die Systeme der Chronologie'. Mnemosyne 4 / 2 1 : 30-60. Boiy, T. (2000). Laatachemenaeisch en hellenistisch Babylon: portret van een Mesopotamische stad in een cultured spanningsveld. Diss. Leuven. Bokovenko, N . A. (1996). 'Asian Influence on European Scythia'. Ancient Civilizations from Scythia to Siberia 3: 97 122. Bolton, J. D . P. (1962). Aristeas of Proconnesus. Oxford. Bongenaar, A. C. V. M . (1997). The Neo-Babylonian Ebabhar Temple at Sippar: Its Administration and its Prosopography. Uitgaven van het Nederlands Historisch-Archaeologisch Instituut te Istanbul L X X X . Leiden. Bonheim, H . (1982). The Narrative Modes: Techniques of the Short Stoiy. Cambridge. Borgeaud, P. (1988). The Cult ofPan in Ancient Greece, tr. K. Atlass and,]. Redfield. Chicago. Bornilz, H.-F. (1968). Herodot-Sludien. Beträge zum Verständnis der Einheit des Geschichtswerkes. Berlin. Borst, A. (1990). Computus, é(fit und zfihl in der Geschichte Europas. Berlin. Bouvier, D. (2000). 'Temps chronique et temps météorologique chez les premiers historiens grecs'. In Constructions du temps dans le monde grec ancien, ed. C. DarboPeschanski, 115 41. Paris. Bowersock, G. (1989). 'Herodotus, Alexander, and Rome'. The American Scholar, 58: 407-14, Bowra, C, M . (1972). Homer. London. Braund, D. C. (1998). 'Herodotus on the Problematics of Reciprocity'. In Reciprocity in Ancient Greece, ed. C. Gill, N . Postlethwaite, and R. Seaford, 159 80. Oxford. Braund, D. C , and G. R. Tsetskhladze. (1989). T h e Export of Slaves from Colchis'. CQ 39: 114-25. Brelich, A. (1958). Gli eroi greci. Un problema storico-religioso. Rome. Brenne, S. (2000). Oslrakismos und Prominenz in Athen: Attische Bürgel' des 5. Jlis. v. Chr. auf den Ostraka. Tyche Beiheft 3. Wien. . (2001). 'Die Ostraka (487-ra. 416 v. Chr.) als Testimonien'. In OslrakismosTestimonien, ed. P. Siewert. Bresciani, E. (1958). 'La satrapia d'Egitto'. SCO 7: 132-88. Briant, P. (1985). 'Dons des terres et des villes: L'Asie Mineure dans le contexte achéménide'. REA 87: 53-71. ·—. (1989). 'Histoire et idéologie: Les Grecs et la décadence perse'. In Mélanges P. Lévêque, vol. II, Anthropologie et Société, ed. M . - M . Mactoux and E. Geny, 33-47. Besançon. (2001). Reprint, tr. In Greeks and Barbarians, ed. T. Harrison, Edinburgh. -. ( 1992). 'La date des révoltes babyloniennes contre Xerxès'. Studia Iranica 21: 7-20. -. (1994). 'L'eau du Grand Roi'. In Drinking in Ancient Societies: History and Culture of Drinks in the Ancient Near East, ed. L. Milano, History of the Ancient Near East Studies 6, 45-65. Padua. . (1996). Histoire de l'empire perse de Cyrus à Alexandre. Paris. . (1998). 'Droaphernès et la statue de Sardes'. I n Studies in Persian History: Essays in Memory of David M. Lewis, ed. M . Brosius and A. Kuhrt, 205 26. Leiden. Brillante, C. (1990). 'Myth and History: Llistory and the Historical Interpretation of Myth'. In Approaches to Greek Myth, ed. L. Edmunds, 91 140. Baltimore.
595
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Brinkman, J. A. (1968). A History of Postkassite Babylonia (1158 722 B.C.). orientalia 43. Rome.
Analecta
— . (1984). Prelude to Empire: Babylonian Society and Politics, 747 626 B.C. Philadelphia.
Broadhead, H. D . (1960). The Persae of Aeschylus. Cambridge. Brosius, M . (1996). Women in Ancient Persia (559-331 B.C.). Oxford. Brown, G., and G. Yule. (1983). Discourse Analysis. Cambridge. Brown, T. S. (1962). 'The Greek Sense of Time in History as Suggested by their Accounts of Egypt'. Historia 2: 257 70. (1982). 'Herodotus' Portrait of Cambyses'. Historia 31: 387- 403. Bruns, I . (1896). Das literarische Porträt der Griechen im fünften und vierten Jahrhundert vor Christi Geburt. Berlin.
Brunt, P. A. (1993). Studies in Greek History and Thought. Oxford. Burkert, W. (1965). 'Demaratos, Astrabakos und Herakles'. MH 22: 166-77. (1980). 'Griechische Mythologie und Geistesgeschichte der Moderne'. In Les éludes classiques aux XIX'
et XX" siècles: leur place dams l'histoire des idées, Entretiens
Hardt 26, 159 99. Geneva. -. (1983). Homo Necans. Berkeley and Los Angeles. -. (1985). 'Das Ende des Kroisos: Vorstufen einer herodoteischen Geschichtserzählung'. In Catalepton. Festschrift für Bernhard Wyss, ed. C. Schäublin, 4-15. Basel.
. (1990). 'Herodot als Historiker fremder Religionen'. In Hérodote et les peuples non grecs, Entretiens Hardt 35, ed. G. Nenci, 1-39. Geneva. —. (1995). 'Lydia between East and West or How to Date the Trojan War: A Study in Herodotus'. In The Ages of Homer: A Tribute to Emily Townsend Vermeille,
ed. J. B. Burnett, A, Buxton, R. Cable, M . , Cairns, D.
Carter and S. P. Morris, 139 -48. Austin. P. (1998). Revenge in Attic and Later Tragedy. Berkeley. (1994). Imaginaiy Greece: Hie Contexts of Mythology. Cambridge. and F. French. (1950). The Gobi Desert. London. (1993). ALDOS: The Psychology and Ethics of Honour and Shame in Ancient
Greek Literature. Oxford.
(1996). 'Off with her AIDOS: Herodotus 1.8.3 4'. CQ 46: 78-83. Calame, C. (1988). 'Le récit hérodotien de la fondation de Cyrène: Mythe, récit épique et histoire'. In Métamorphoses du mythe en Grèce antique, ed. C. Calame, 105
25.
Geneva. - . (1990). 'Narrating the Foundation of a City: The Symbolic Birth of Gyrene'. In Approaches to Greek Myth, ed. L . Edmunds, 277-341. Baltimore. —.
(1995). The Craft of Poetic Speech in Ancient Greece, tr. J. Orion. Ithaca
and
London. (1996). Mythe et histoire dans l'Antiquité grecque. Lausanne.
(1998). 'Mémoire collective et temporalités en contact: Somare et Hérodote'. RHR 215: 341 67. Cantarella, R. (1952). ' I l frammento di Ossirinco su Gige'. Dioniso 15: 3 31. Carbonell, C.-O. (1985). 'L'espace et le temps dans l'oeuvre d'Hérodote'. Storia del. Storiografia 7: 138-49. Cardascia, G. (1951). Les archives des Murasu: Une famille d'hommes d'affaires babyloniens à l'époque perse (455-403 B.C.). Paris. Carlier, P. A. (1977). 'La vie politique à Sparte sous le règne de Cléomène 1": Essai d'interprétation'. Ktèma 2: 65-84. Cartledge, P. A. (1978). 'Literacy in the Spartan Oligarchy'. JUS 98: 25 37. —.
(1979). Sparta and Lakonia: A Regional History 1300-362 B.C. London.
—. (1982). 'Sparta and Samos: A Special Relationship?' CCI 32: 243-65. —. (1990). 'Herodotus and "the Other'": A Meditation on Empire'. EMC/CV 34, n.s. 9: 27-40. (1993). 'The Silent Women of Thucydides: 2.45.2 Re-viewed'. In Momodeiktes: Studies in Honor of Martin Ostwahl, ed. R. M . Rosen and J. S. Farrell, 125 32. Ann Arbor.
596
BIBLIOGRAPHY
-, (1995). '"We are all Greeks?": Ancient (Especially Herodotean) and Modern Contestations of Hellenism'. BICS 40: 75 82. -. (1997a). The Greeks: A Portrait of Self and Others. Rev. ed. Oxford. -. (1997b). 'Historiography and Greek Self-Definition'. In Routledge Companion to Historiography, ed. M . Bentley, 23-42. London. Cataudella, Q, (1957). 'Sulla cronologia del cosidetto "frammento di Gige'". Studi Calderini e Paribeni. 2: 103 16. Cavigneaux, A. (1981). Textes scolaires du temple de .Nabu sa harê. Texts from Babylon. Baghdad. Cawkwell, G. L . (1993). 'Sparta and her Allies in the Sixth Century'. C(M'i: 364 76. -. (1995). 'Early Greek Tyranny and the People'. CQ, 45: 73-86. (1997). Thucydicles and the Peloponnesian War. London. Ccccarelli, P. (1993). 'La fable des poissons de Cyrus (Hérodote 1.141): son origine et sa fonction dans l'économie des Histoires d'Hérodote'. Métis 8: 29-57. Chamoux, F. (1953). Cyrène sous les Batliades. Paris. Chantraine, P. (1968). Dictionnaire étymologique de la langue grecque, vol. 1. Paris. Chernenko, E. V. (1994). 'Investigations of the Scythian Tumuli in the Northern Pontic Steppe'. Ancient Civilizations from Scythia to Siberia 1: 45-53. Chiasson, C. C. (1982). 'Tragic Diction in Herodotus: Some Possibilities'. Phoenix 36: 156-61. . (1986). T h e Herodotean Solon'. GRBS 27: 249-62. Christ, M . R. (1994). 'Herodotean Kings and Historical Inquiry'. ClAnt 13: 167 202. Coates, G. W. (1992). (Joseph, Son of Jacob'. In The Anchor Bible Dictionary, ed. D. N . Freedman, 976-81. New York. Cobet, J. (1971). Herodots Exkurse und die Frage der Einheit seines Werkes, Historia Einzelschriften 17. Wiesbaden. . (1977) 'Wann wurde Herodots Darstellung der Perserkriege publiziert?' Hermes 105: 2-27. (1986). 'Herodotus and Thucydides on War'. In Past Perspectives: Studies in Greek and Roman Historical Writing, ed. I . S. Moxon, J. D. Smart, and A. J. Woodman, 1-18. Cambridge. (1988). 'Herodot und mündliche Überlieferung'. In Vergangenheit in mündlicher Überlieferung, ed. J. von Ungern-Sternberg and H . Reinau, Colloquium Rauricum 1, 226-33'. Stuttgart. (1997). 'Die Mauern sind die Stadt. Zur Stadtbefestigung des antiken Milct'. AA: 249 84. -. (1999). 'Herodot, Historien und die antike Geschichtsschreibung'. In Mediaiwisseiischaft 1, ed. J.-F. Leonhard et a l , Handbücher zur Sprach- und Kommunikationswissenschaft 15.1, 600-14. Berlin. . (2000). 'Die Ordnung der Zeiten'. I n Europa. Die Gegenwärtigkeit der antiken Uberlieferung, ed. J. Cobet, C. F. Gethmann, and D . Lau, Essener Studien zur Kulturgeschichte 2, 9-31. Aachen. Cocquerillat, D. (1968). Palmeraies et cultures de l'Eanna d'Uruk (559-520). Berlin. Cohen, D . (1991). Law, Sexuality, and Society, Cambridge. Coldstream. J. N . (1993). 'Mixed Marriages at the Frontiers of the Early Greek World'. OJA 12: 89-108. Cole, T. (1991). The Origins of Rhetoric in Ancient Greece. Baltimore. Connor, W. R. (1985). 'The Razing of the House in Greek Society'. TAPha 115: 79-102. -. (1987). 'Commentary on the Conference'. In Herodotus and the Invention of History, Arethusa 20, ed. D. Boedeker and J. Peradotto, 255-62. Buffalo. . (1993). 'The Histor in History'. I n Nomodeiktes: Greek Studies in Honor of Martin Oslwald, ed. R. M . Rosen a n d j . S. Farrell, 3-15. Ann Arbor. Conte, G.-B. (1986). The Rhetoric of Imitation. Princeton.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
597
Cook, J. M . (1988). The Persian Empire. London. Cooper, J. S. (1993). 'Sacred Marriage and Popular Cult in Early Mesopotamia'. In Official Cult and Popular Religion in the Ancient Mar East, ed. E. Matsushima, 81-96. Heidelberg. Corbey, R., and J. Lerssen, eds. (1991). Allenty, Identity, Image: Selves and Others in Society and Scholarship. Amsterdam. Corcella, A. (1984). Erodolo e t'analogia. Palermo. Corcella, A., and S. M . Medaglia. (1993). Erodoto, U, Stone. Libra hi: La Scizia e la Libia. Rome. Cornford, F. M . (1907). Tliucydides Mylhisloricus. Oxford. (1971). Reprint. Philadelphia. Craiiay, R. (1956;. hi littérature articulaire chez Hérodote. Paris. Craig, J. D. (1924). 'The Interpretation of Aeschylus' Persae', CR 38: 98 101. Crane, G. (1996). 77» Blinded Eye. Thucydides and the Invention of History. Lanham, M D . . (1998). Tliucydides and the Ancient Simplicity: The Limits of Political Realism. Berkeley. Cronon, W. (1992). 'A Place for Stories: Nature, History, and Narrative'. Journal of American History 78: 1347-76. Dalley, S. (1994). 'Babylon and the Hanging Gardens: Cuneiform and Classical Sources Reconciled'. Iraq 56: 45-58. Dandamaev, M . A. (1976). Persien unter den ersten Achämeniden (6. Jahrhundert v. Chr.). Beiträge zur Iranistik 8. Wiesbaden. . (1984). Stauet)' in Babylonia: From .Mabopolassar to Alexander the Great (626-331 B.C.). Rev. ed., tr. DeKalb, I L . Darbo-Peschanski, C. (1985). 'Les logoi des autres dans les Histoires d'Hérodote'. OS 22: 105-28. — -. (1987). I_£ discours du particulier: essai sur l'enquête hérodotêenne. Paris. (1995). (Juger sur paroles. Oralité et écriture dans hs Histoires d'Hérodote'. L'inactuel. Psychanalyse et culture: l'oral 4: 161-82. —. (1998). 'L'historien grec ou le passé jugé'. In Figures de l'intellectuel en Grèce ancienne, ed. N , Loraux and C. Miralies, 143-89. Paris. Dassow, E. von (1999). 'On Writing the History of Southern Mesopotamia'. Zeitschrift für Assynologie und verwandte Gebiete 89: 227 46. Davies, J. K. (1971). Athenian Propertied Families 600-300 B.C. Oxford. . (1984). 'The Reliability of Oral Tradition'. In The Tntjan War: Its Historicity and Context, ed. J. K. Davies and L. Foxhall, 87-110. Bristol. —. (1994a). 'The Moral Dimension of Pythian Apollo'. In 14%«/ is a God? Studies in the .Nature of Greek Divinity, ed. A. B. Lloyd, 43-64. London and Swansea. (1994b). T h e Tradition about the First Sacred War'. In Greek Historiography, cd. S. Hornblower, 193-212. Oxford. —. (1997). 'The "Origins of the Greek Polis": Where Should we be Looking?'. In Hie Development of the Polis in Archaic Greece, ed. L . G. Mitchell and P. J. Rhodes, 24 38. London and New York. Demand, D. (1987). 'Herodotus' Encomium of Athens: Science or Rhetoric?' AJPh 108: 746-58. Denniston, J. D. (1954). The Greek Particles. 2d ed. Oxford. Depew, l\'L, and D. Obbink, eds. (2000). Matrices of Genre: Authors, Canons, and Society. Center for Hellenic Studies Colloquia 4. Cambridge, M A . Derow, P. (1994). 'Historical Explanation: Polybius and his Predecessors'. In Greek Historiography, ed. S. Hornblower, 73 -90. Oxford. (1995). 'Herodotean Readings'. Classics Ireland 2: 29-51. Delii-i11ic. VI. (1967;. Lis maîtres de critic dans la Grete tuclitiïque. Paris. -. (1986). The Creation of Mythology. Chicago. Develin, R. (1985). 'Herodotus and the Alkmaeonids'. In 77« Craft of the Ancient Historian: Essays in Honor of Chester G. Starr, ed. J. W. Eadie and J. Ober, 125-39. Lanham.
598
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Dewald, C. (1981). 'Women and Culture in Herodotus' Histories'. In Reflections of Women in Antiquity, ed. H . P. Foley, 91 125. New York. (1985). 'Practical Knowledge and the Historian's Role in Herodotus and Thucydides'. In 77K Greek Historians: Papers Presented to A. E. Raubilschek, ed. M . H . Jameson, 47-63. Saratoga. — . (1987). 'Narrative Surface and Authorial Voice in Herodotus' Histories'. In Herodotus and the Invention of History, Arethusa 20, ed. D, Boedeker and J. Peradotto, 147 70. Buffalo. (1990). Review of F. Hartog, U miroir d'Hérodote. CPh 85: 217-24. -, (1993). 'Reading the World: The Interpretation of Objects in Herodotus' Histories'. In Momodetktes: Greek Studies in Honor of Martin Ostwald, ed. R. M . Rosen and J. S. Farrell, 55-70. Ann Arbor. (1997). 'Wanton Kings, Pickled Heroes, and Gnomic Founding Fathers: Strategies of Meaning at the End of Herodotus' Histories'. In Classical Closure: Reading the End in Greek and Latin Literature, ed. D. H . Roberts, F. M . Dunn, and D. Fowler, 62-82. Princeton. -. (1998). Introduction to Herodotus The Histories', tr. R. Waterfield, ix xli. Oxford. . (1999). 'The Figured Stage: Focalizing the Initial Narratives of Herodotus and Thucydides'. In Contextualizing Classics: Ideology, Performance, Dialogue, Festschr. Peradotto, ed. T. Falkner, N . Felson, and D. Konstan, 221-52. Lanham. (2002). 'Form and Content: The Question of Tyranny in Herodotus'. In Popular Tyranny: Sovereignty and lis Discontents in Classical Athens, ed. K. Morgan. Austin. Dewald, C , and J. Marincola. (1987). 'A Selective Introduction to Herodotean Studies'. In Herodotus and the Invention of History, Arethusa 20, ed. D. Boedeker and J. Peradotto, 9-40. Buffalo. Dickie, M . (1984). 'Hesychia and Hybris in Herodotus'. In Greek Poetry and Philosophy: Essays in Honour of Tonard Woodbury, ed. D . Gerber, 83-109. Chico, CA. Diels, H . , and W. Kranz. (1952). Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. 3 vols. 6th ed. Berlin. Dietrich, B. C. (1986). Tradition in Greek Religion. Berlin. Dihle, A. (1962a). 'Der fruchtbare Osten'. RhM n.f. 105: 97-110. (1984). Reprint. In A. Dihle, Antike und Orient: Gesammelle Aufsätze, Supplemente zu den Sitzungsberichte der Heidelberger Akademie der Wissenschaften, Philosophisch-historische Klasse 2, eel. V . Pöschl and H . Petersmann, 47-60. Heidelberg. .' (1962b). 'Herodot und die Sophistik'. Phüologus 106: 207-20. -. (1981). 'Die Verschiedenheit der Sitten als Argument ethischer Theorie'. In The Sophists and their Tgacy, Hermes Einzelschritten 44, ed. G. E. B. Kerferd, 5463. Wiesbaden. (1984). Reprint. In A. Dihle, Antike und Orient: Gesammelle Aufsätze, Supplemente zu den Sitzungsberichte der Heidelberger Akademie der Wissenschaften, Philosophisch-historische Klasse 2, ed. V. Pöschl and H . Petersmann, 191-200. Heidelberg. -. ( 1984). Antike und Orient: Gesammelte Aufsätze, Supplemente zu den Sitzungsberichte der Heidelberger Akademie der Wissenschaften, Philosophisch-historische Klasse 2, ed. V. Pöschl and H . Petersmann, Heidelberg. —. (1990). 'Arabien und Indien'. In Hérodote et les peuples non grecs, Entretiens Hardt 35, ed. G. Nenci, 41-67. Geneva. . (1994). Die Griechen und die Fremden. Munich. Dik, H . (1995). Word Order in Ancient Greek: A Pragmatic Account of Word Order Variations in Herodotus. Amsterdam. Düke, O. A. W. (1985). Greek and Roman Maps. London and Ithaca. Diller, H . (1934). Wanderarzt und Aitiologe: Studien zur hippokratischen Schrift Peri aerön hydatön topön, Phüologus Suppl. 26.3. Leipzig. -. (1962). 'Freiheit bei Thukydides als Schlagwort und als Wirklichkeit'. Gymnasium 69: 189-204. (1968). Reprint. In Thukydides, Wege der Forschung 98, ed. H . Herter, 6 3 9 6 0 . Darmstadt.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
599
Dillery, J. (1992). 'Darius and the Tomb of Nitocris'. CPh 87: 30 8. . (1995). Xenophon and the History of His Times. London. Donbaz, V.. and M . W. Stolper. (1997). Istanbul Murasû Texts. Uitgaven van het Nederlands Historisch-Archaeologisch Instituut te Istanbul L X X I X . Leiden. Dorandi, T. (1991). 'Den Autoren über die Schulter geschaut: Arbeitsweise und Autographie bei den antiken Schriftstellern'. %J>E 87: 11-33. Dorati, M . (2000). H, Storie dl Erodoto: etnografia e raeconto. Pisa and Rome. Dougherty, C. (1993). The Poetics of Colonization: From. City to Text in Archaic Greece. Oxford'. Dougherty, C , and L. Kurke. (1993), eds. Cultural Poetics in Archaic Greece. Cambridge, MA. Dovatur, Λ. I . , D. P. Kallistov, and I . A. Shishova. (1982). Namely nasheï strany υ Istorii Gerodota. Teksly, perevod, kommentarii. Moscow. Dover, K . J . (1974). Greek Popular Morality in the Time if Plato and Aristotle. Oxford. -. (1978). Greek Homosexuality. London. Drews, R. (1969). 'The Fall of Astyages and Herodotus' Chronology of the Early Kingdoms'. Historia 18: 1 I I . ·-. (1973). The Greek Accounts of Eastern History. Cambridge, M A . . (1997). Review of R. Rollinger, Herodots Babylonischer Ingos: Eine kritische Unter suchung der Glaubwürdigkeitsdiskussion. J.NES 56: 125-6. Drexler, H . (1972). Herodot-Studien. Hildesheim. Driel, G. van (1998). 'The "Eanna Archive'". Bibliotheca Orientalis 55: 58 79. Driolon, E., and J. Validier. (1962). L'Egypte. 4th cd, Paris. Dubois, L. (1996). Inscriptions grecques dialectales d'Olbia du Pont. Hautes études du monde gréco-romain 22. Geneva. Dumézil, G. (1930). Légendes sur les .Martes. Paris. -. (1978), Romans de Scythie et d'alentour. Paris. Dunlop, P. (1912). Perijë, voorheen en thons. Haarlem. Duplouy, A. (1999). 'Crésus dans l'idéologie aristocratique athénienne'. AC 68: 1- 22. Dux, G. (1989). 'Die geschichtliche Zeit Herodots'. In G. Dux, Die fe.it in der Geschichte. Ihre Entwieklungslogik vom Mythos zur Weltzeit., 273-85. Frankfurt am Alain. Dyson, Κ. Κ. (1971). A Various Universe: A Study of the Journals and Memoirs of the British Men and Women in the Indian Subcontinent, 1765 1856. Oxford. Edelmann, Η, (1970). "Ερημίη and έρημος bei Herodot'. Klio 52: 79 86. . (1975). 'Demokratie bei Herodot und Thukydides'. Klio 57: 313 27. Eder, W. (1998). 'Aristocrats and the Coming of Athenian Democracy'. In Dem ocracy 2500? Questions and Challenges, ΑΙΑ Colloquia and Conference Papers 2, ed. I . Morris and K. Raaflaub, 105-40. Dubuque. Edmunds, L. (1993). Thucydides in the Act of Writing'. In Tra.diz.ione e innovazione nella cultura greca. Festschrift Gcntili, vol. 2, ed. R. Pretagostini, 831-52. Rome. -. (1997). 'Mvth in Homer'. In A .New Companion to Homer, ed. I . Morris and B. Powell, 415·'·4L Leiden. Edzard, D. O. (1975). 'Chaldaia'. In Paulys Real-Entyclopädie der classischen Altertumswissenschaft, I : 1123-4. Stuttgart. Effenterre, H. van (1967). L'histoire en Grèce. Paris. Egcrmann, F. (1957). 'Arete und tragische Bewußtheit bei Sophokles und Herodot'. In Vom Menschen in der Antike, ed. F. Hörmann et al., 5-128. Munich. (1962). Reprint (extracts). In Herodot. Eine Auswahl aus der neueren Forschung. Wege der Forschung 26, ed. W. Marg. Munich. (1965). 2d ed. Munich. (1982)) 3d ed. Darmstadt. Ehrenberg, V. (1954). Sophocles and Pericles. Oxford. Ehrhardt, N . (1983). Müet und seine Kolonien. Frankfurt. Elayi, J. (1978). 'Le rôle de l'oracle de Delphes dans le conflit gréco-perse d'après Les Histoires d'Hérodote (1ère partie)'. IA 13: 93-118. (1979). 'Le rôle de l'oracle de Delphes dans le conflit gréco-perse d'après Les Histoires d'Hérodote (suite)'. IA 14: 67 151.
600
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Erbse, H . (1956). 'Der erste Satz im Werke Herodots'. Festschrift Bruno Snell, 20922. Munich. -. (1961). 'Tradition und Form im Werke Herodots'. Gymnasium 68: 239 57. (1979). 'Sieben Bemerkungen zu Herodot'. In Ausgewählte Schriften zur klassischen Philologie, 139-79. Berlin and New York. . (1981). 'Die Funktion der Novellen im Werke Herodots'. Gnomosyne. Menschliches Denken und Handeln in der frühgriechischen Literatur: Festschrift für Walter Marg zum 70. Geburlstag, ed. G. Kurz, D. Müller, and W. Nicolai, 251 69. Munich. -. (1991). 'Fiktion und Wahrheit im Werke Herodots'. .Nächrichten der Akademie der Wissenschaften in Göttingen, 131-50. Göttingen. -. (1992). Studien zum Verständnis Herodots. Berlin and New York. — •-. (1995). 'IrjTopîriç ànoSe^tç bei Herodot'. Glotta 73: 64 7. Erdmannsdörffer, 13. (1870). Die feitälter der Novelle in Hellas. Berlin. Etienne, R., and M . Piérart. (1975). 'Un décret du koinon des Hellènes à Platées en l'honneur de Glaucon, (ils d'Etéoclès, d'Athènes'. BCLI 99: 51-75. Euben, J. P. (1986). 'The Battle of Salamis and the Origins of Political Theory'. Political Theory 14: 359 90. Evans, J. A. S. (1961). 'The Dream of Xerxes and the "Nomoi" of the Persians'. CJ 57: 109-11. -. (1968). 'Father of History or Father of Lies: The Reputation of Herodotus'. CJ 64: 11-17. -. (1979a). 'Herodotus' Publication Date'. Athenaeum 57: 145-9. -. (1979b). 'Herodotus and Athens: the Evidence of the Encomium'. AC 48: 1 12 18. . (1981). 'Notes on the Debate of the Persian Grandees in Herodotus 3.80-82'. QIJCC 7: 69-84. -. (1982). Herodotus. Boston. . (1985). 'Candaules, Whom the Greeks Call Myrsilos'. GRBS 26: 229-33. -. (1987). 'i'he "Recent" Prominence of Themistocles'. AJPh 108: 382-4. -. (1988). 'The Story of Pythios'. LCM 13: 139. . (1990). 'Six New Studies on Herodotus'. AJPh 111: 92 104. (1991). Herodotus, Explorer of the Past: Three Essays. Princeton. Evans, R. (1997). In Defence of History. London. (2001). 2d ed. Fehling, D. (1969). Die Wiederholungsjiguren und ihr Gebrauch bei den Griechen vor Gorgias. Berlin. . (1971). Die Quelleiiangaben bei Herodot. Studien zur Erzählkunst Herodots. Berlin. . (1985). Die sieben Weisen und die friihgriechische Chronologie. Bern. -. (1989). Llerodotus and His 'Sources': Citation, Invention, and Narrative Art, tr. J. G. Howie. Leeds. Ferrill, A. (1978). 'Herodotus on Tyranny'. Histona 25: .385-98. Fîgueira, T. (1985). 'Herodotus on the Early Hostilities Between Aigina and Athens'. AJPh 106: 50 74. (1993). Reprint. In T. Figueira, Excursions in Epichonc History: Aiginetan Essays, 35-60. Lanham. Finkelberg, M . (1995). 'Sophocles Tr. 634-639 and Herodotus'. Mnemosyne 48: 146-52. Finley, J. H . (1942). Thucydides. Cambridge, M A . (1967). 'Euripides and Thucydides'. In Three Essays on Thucydides, 1 54. Cambridge, M A . Finley, M . 1. (1962). '4'he Black Sea and Danubian Regions and the Slave Trade in Antiquity'. Klio 40: 51-9. (1981). Reprint. In M . I . Finley, Economy and Society in Ancient Greece, ed. B. D . Shaw and R. P. Sailer, 167-75. London. — -. (1975). 'Myth, Memory, and History'. In M . I . Finley, The Use and Abuse of History, 1 - 33. New York. Fish, S. E. (1980). Is 'There A Text In This Class? The Authority of Interpretive Communities. Cambridge, M A .
BIBLIOGRAPHY
601
Fisher, N . R. E. (1992). Hybris: A Study in the Values of Guilt and Shame in Ancient Greece. Warminster. . (2000). 'Hybris, Revenge and Stasis in the Greek City-States'. In War and Violence in Ancient Greece, ed. H . van Wees, 83123. London and Swansea. Flory, S. (1978a). 'Arion's Leap: Brave Gestures in Herodotus'. AJPh 99: 411-21. . (1978b). 'Laughter. Tears, and Wisdom in Herodotus'. AJPh 99: 145 53. . (1980). 'Who'Read Herodotus' Histories?' AJPh 101: 12-28. . (1987). The Archaic Smile of Herodotus. Detroit. Flower, FI. I . (1991). 'Herodotus and the Delphic Traditions about Croesus'. In Georgica: Greek Studies in Honour of George Caivkwell. BICS Suppl. 58, ed. M . Flower and M . Toher, 57-77. London. Floyd, E. D. (1990). 'The Sources of Greek "Ioxcap "Judge, Witness". Glolia 68: 157-66. Pocke, F. (1927). Herodot als Historiker. Stuttgart. Fohl, H. (1913). Tragische Kunst bei Herodot. Diss. Rostock. Fol, A., and N . G. L . Hammond. (1988). 'Persia in Europe, apart from Greece'. In 77ze Cambridge Ancient History, vol. 4, ed. J. Boardman, N . G. L. Hammond, D. M . , Lewis,' and M . Ostwald, 234-53. 2d cd. Cambridge. Föllinger, S. (1996). Differenz und Gleichheit: Das Geschlechteroerhältnis in der Sicht griechischen Philosophen des 4. bis I . Jh. v. Chr. Hermes Einzelschriften 74. Stuttgart. Fontenrose, J. (1978). The Delphic Oracle. Berkeley. Femara, C. W. (1966). 'The Hoplite Achievement at Psyttaleia'. JHS 86: 51 4. -. (1971a). Herodotus: An Interpretative Essay. Oxford. (1971b). 'Evidence for the Date of Herodotus' Publication'. JHS 91: 25-34. •-. (1981). 'Herodotus' Knowledge of the Archidamian War'. Hermes 109: 149-56. -. (1983). The .Nature of Histoiy in Ancient Greece and Rome. Berkeley. . (1999). 'Human History and the Constraint of Fate in Herodotus'. In Conflict, Antithesis, and tfte Ancient Historian, ed. J. Allison, 25 45. Columbus. Forrest, W. G. (1957). 'Colonization and the Rise of Delphi'. Hisloria 6: 160-75. . (1968). A Histoiy of Sparta, 950-192 B.C. New York. • ···. (1979). 'Motivation in Herodotus: The Case of the Ionian Revolt'. International Histoiy Review 1: 311-22. . (1984). 'Herodotos and Athens'. Phoenix 38: 1-11. Forsdyke, S. (1999). 'From Aristocratic to Democratic Ideology and Back Again: The Thrasybulus Anecdote in Herodotus' Histories and Aristotle's Polities'. CPh 94: 361-72. . (2000). 'Exile, Ostracism, and the Athenian Democracy'. ClAnt 19: 232 63. -. (2001). 'Athenian Democratic Ideology and Herodotus' Histories'. AJPh 122: 333-62. Fowler, D. (1990). 'Deviant Focalisation in Virgil's Aenei.d'. PCPhS 36: 4 2 6 3 . Fowler, R. L. (1996). 'Herodotus and His Contemporaries'. JHS 116: 62 87. Francis, E. D., and M . Vickers. (1985). 'The Oenoe Painting in the Stoa Poikile, and Herodotus' Account of Marathon'. ABSA 80: 99 111. Francovitch, G. de (1965). 'Problems of Achaemenid Architecture'. East and West 16: 201 60. Frankel, H . (1960). Wege und Formen frühgriechischen Denkens. Munich. Frisch, H . (1942). The Constitution of the Athenians: A Philological-Historical Analysis of Pseudo-Xenophon's Treatise De re publica Atheniensium. Copenhagen. Frisch, P. (1968). Die Träume bei Herodot. Meisenheim am Glan, von Fritz, K. (1936). 'Herodotus and the Growth of Greek Historiography'. TAI'A 67: 315-40. . (1965). 'Die griechische eleulheria bei Herodot'. WS 78: 5-31. (1967). Die griechische Geschichtsschreibung: Von den Anfängen bis Thukydides. 2 vols. Berlin.
602
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Froidefond, C. (1971). Le mirage égyptien dans la littérature grecque d'Homère à Aristote. Aix-en-Provence. From the Lands of the Scythians: Ancient Treasures from, the Museums of the USSR, 3000 B.C. 100 B.C., The Metropolitan Museum of Art, The Los Angeles County Museum of Art. 1975. Frye, R. N . (1984). 'The History of Ancient Iran. Munich Frymer-Kensky, T. (1992). In the Wake of the Goddesses: Women, Culture and the Biblical Transformation of Pagan Myth. New York. Galiano, M . F. (1950-51). Tnformacion cientifica'. ECUs 1: 119. von Gall, Ff. (1974). 'Die Kopfbedeckung des persischen Ornats bei der Achämeniden'. Archäologische Mitteilungen aus Iran 7: 145-61. Gammie, J. G. (1986). 'Herodotus on Kings and Tyrants: Objective Historiography or Conventional Portraiture'. JNES 45: 171 95. Gardiner-Garden. J. R. (1987). 'Dareios' Scythian Expedition and its Aftermath'. Mo 69: 326-50." Gärtner, H. A. (1983). 'Les rêves de Xerxès et d'Artabane chez Hérodote'. Ktèma 8: 1118. Gauthier, P. (1966). 'Le parallèle Himère-Salamine au V et au I V siècle av. J . - C REA 68: 5-32. Gavrilov, A. K. (1997). 'Techniques of Reading in Classical Antiquity'. Ci) 47: 56-73. Gehrke, H.-J. (1987). 'Die Griechen und die Rache. Ein Versuch in historischer Psychologie'. Saeculum 38: 121 49. Genette, G. (1980). Narrative Discourse: An Essay in Method. Ithaca and London. Tr. of Discours du récit, Figures III. Paris, 1972. George, A. R. (1992). Babylonian Topographical Texts, Orienlalia Lovaniensia analecta 40. Leuven. -. (1993). 'Babylon Revisited: Archaeology and Philology in Harness'. Antiquity 67: 734-46. -. (1997). '"Bond of the Lands": Babylon, the Cosmic Capital'. In Die orientalische Stadl: Kontinuität, Wandel, Bruch, ed. G. Wilhelm, 125 45. Saarbrücken. Georges, P. B. (1994). Barbarian Asia and the Greek Experience. Baltimore. (2000). 'Persian Ionia under Darius: The Revolt Reconsidered'. Historia 49: 1-39. Georgini, G. (1993). La cilla e il tiranno. Milan. Gershevitch, I . , ed. (1985). The Cambridge History of Iran, Volume 2: the Median and Achaemenian Periods, 185-99. Cambridge. Giangiulio, M . (2001). 'Colonial Traditions and the Writing of History'. In The Historian's Craft, ed. N . Luraghi, 116-37. Oxford. Giddy, L., D. Jeffreys, and J. Malek. (1990). 'Memphis, 1989'. JEA 76: 1 15. Giddy, L., and D. Jeffreys. (1991). 'Memphis, 1990'. JEA 77: 1-6. -. (1992). 'Memphis, 1991'. JEA 78: 1-11. Gigante, M . (1952). 'Un nuovo frammento di Licofrone tragico'. PP 7: 5-17. Gillis, D. (1979). Collaboration with the Persians, Historia Einzelschriften 34. Wiesbaden. Gilula, D. (2002). 'Who was Actually Buried in the First of the Three Spartan Graves (Herod. 9.85.1)?'. In The World of Herodotus, Essays in Honour of W. G. Forrest ed. P. S. Derow and R. Parker, Oxford. Gimelli-Martin. C. (1990). 'Said, Herodotus, and the Discourse of Alterity'. Criticism 32: 51 1 29. ' Ginzburg, G. (1991). 'Checking the Evidence: The Judge and the Historian'. Critical Inquiry 18: 79-92. Giovannini, A. (1995). 'La guerre de Troie entre mythe et histoire'. Kt'ema 20: 139 76. Giraudeau, M . (1984a). Ts notions juridiques et sociales chez Hérodote: Eludes sur le vocabulaire. Paris. e
BIBLIOGRAPHY
603
-. (1984b). 'L'héritage épique chez Hérodote'. Bulletin rie l'Association G. Huit. 1984: 4-13. Glassncr, J.-J. (1993). Chroniques mésopotamiennes. Paris. Goldhill, S. D. (1988). 'Battle Narrative and Politics in Aeschylus' Persae, JHS 108: 189-93. Gomme, A. W. (1945). A Historical Commentary on 'Thucydicl.es, I . Oxford. -. (1954). 77K Greek Attitude toward Poetry and History. Berkeley and Los Angeles. (1956). A. Historical Commentary on Thucydides, I I . Oxford. Gomme, A. W., A. Andrewes, and K. J. Dover. (1970). A Historical Commentary on Thucydides, I V . Oxford. Goodnick-Westenholz, J. (1995). 'Heilige Hochzeit und kultische Prostitution im alten Mesopotamien: Sexuelle Vereinigung im sakralen Raum?' In Wort und Dienst, cd. H.-P. Stähli, 43-62. Bethel. Gorman, V. (2001). Miletus, the Ornament of Ionia: A History of the City to 400 BCE. Ann Arbor. Goudriaan, K. (1988). Ethnicity in Ptolemaic Egypt. Dutch Monographs on Ancient History and Archaeology V. Amsterdam. Gould,.). (1973). 'HIKETEIA'. JHS 93: 74 103. - —. (1980). 'Law, Custom and Myth: Aspects of the Social Position of Women in Classical Athens'. JHS 100: 38 -59. (1989). Herodotus. London. (1991). Give and Take in Herodotus. The Fifteenth J. L . Myres Memorial Lecture. Oxford. (1994). 'Herodotus and Religion'. In Greek Historiography, ed. S. Hornblowcr, 91-106. Oxford. (2001). Reprint. I n j . Gould, Myth, Ritual Memory, and Exchange: Essays in Greek Literature and Culture, 359 77. Oxford. (2001). Myth, Ritual Memory, and Exchange: Essays in Greek Literature and Culture. Oxford. Gouschin, V. (1999). 'Pisistratus' Leadership in A.P. 13.4 and the Establishment of the Tyrany of 561/60 B.C.' CO 49: 14-23. Grant, J. R. (1961). 'Leonidas' Final Stand'. G&R 15: 14-27. Grassl, A. (1904). Herodot als Ethnologe. Sulzbach. Gray, V . J . (1995). 'Herodotus and the Rhetoric of Otherness'. AJI'h 116: 185 211. (1996). 'Herodotus and Images of Tyranny: The Tyrants of Corinth'. A'jPh 117: 361 89. —. (1997). 'Reading the Rise of Peisistratus: Herodotus 1.56 68'. Hisios 1: http://www.dur.ac.uk/Classics/histos/1997/gray.html. Grayson, A. K. (1975). Assyrian and Babylonian Chronicles. Texts from Cuneiform Sources 5. Locust Valley, NY. Graziosi, B. (2002). Inventing Homer: The Early Reception of Epic. Cambridge. Greenhill, B. (1976). Archaeology of the Boat. London. Grene, D. (1961). 'Herodotus the Historian as Dramatist'. AJPh .58: 477 38. Gribble, D. (1998). 'Narrator Interventions in Thucydides'. JHS 118: 41 67. Griffiths, A. (1987). 'Democedes of Croton: A Greek Doctor at the Court of Darius'. In The Greek Sources. Proceedings of the Groningen 1984 Achaemenid History Workshop, Achaemenid History 2, ed. H . Sancisi-Weerdenburg and A. Kuhrt, 37 51. Leiden. -. (1989). 'Was Kleomenes Mad?' In Classical Sparta: Techniques behind her Success, ed. A. Powell, 51-78. London. -. (1999). 'Euenius the Negligent Nightwatchman (Herodotus 9, 92 6)'. In From Myth to Reason?, ed. R. Buxton, 169 82. Oxford. Gschnitzer, F. (1977). Die sieben Perser und das Königtum des Darews. Ein Beitrag zur Achaimenidengeschichte und zur hlerodotanalyse. Sitzungsberichte der Heidelberger Akademie der Wissenschaften, phil.-hist. K l . 1977, 3. Fleidelberg. Guthrie, W. K. C. (1962-69). A Hu lory of Greek Philosophy, vols. 1 3. Cambridge. :
604
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Gyles, M . F. (1959). Pharaonic Policies and Administration 663 to 323 AC. James Sprunt Studies in History and Political Science 41. Chapel Hill. Haeny, G. (1985). 'A Short Architectural History ol* Philae'. Bulletin de l'institut français d'archéologie orientale 85: 197-233. Haerinck, E. (1990). 'Anhang: Babylon unter der Herrschaft der Achämeniden'. In R. Koldewey Das wieder erstehende Babylon, ed. B. Hrouda, 37288. 5th ed. Munich. - - -. (1997). 'Babylon under Achaemenid Rule'. In Mesopotamia and Iran in the Persian Period: Conquest and Imperialism, 539-331 B.C. (Proceedings of a Seminar in Memory of Vladimir G. Luhnin), ed. J. Curtis, 26-34. London. Haidane, C, W., and C. W. Shelmerdine. (1990). 'Herodotus 2.96.1-2 Again'. CQ 40: 535-9. Hall, Ε. M . (1989a). Inventing the Barbarian: Greek Self-Definition through Tragedy. Oxford Classical Monographs. Oxford. (1989b). 'The Archer-Scene in Aristophanes' Thesmophoriazusae'. Philologus 133: 38 54. Flail, J. M . (1997). Ethnic Identity in Greek Antiquity. Cambridge. Halliday, W. R. (1910 11). Ά Note on the θήλεα νοΰσος of the Scythians'. ABSA 17: 95-102. Hammond, N . G. L . (1968). 'The Campaign and Batde of Marathon'. JHS 88: 13-57. (1988a). 'The Expedition of Datis and Artaphernes'. In The Cambridge Ancient History, vol. 4, ed. J. Boardman, N . G. L . Hammond, D. M . Lewis, and M . Ostwald, 491-517. 2d ed. Cambridge. . (1988b). T h e Expedition of Xerxes'. In The Cambridge Ancient History, vol. 4, ed. J. Boardman, N . G. L. Hammond, D . M . Lewis, and M . Ostwald, 518-90. 2d ed. Cambridge. Hammond, N . G. L., and L. J. Roseman. (1996). 'The Construction of Xerxes' Bridge Across the Hellespont'. JHS 116: 88-107. Hamon, P. (1993). Du Descriptif. Paris. Hampl, F. (1979). 'Herodot. Ein kritischer Forschungsbericht'. In Geschichte als hi tische Wissenschaft Bd. 3, ed. I . Weiler, 221-66. Darmstadt. Hansen, M . H . (1990). 'Solonian Democracy in Fourth-Century Athens'. In Aspects of Athenian Democracy, Classica et Mediaevalia Dissertationes X I , ed. J. R. Fears, 71-99. Copenhagen. Harder, R. (1943). 'Bemerkungen zur griechischen Schriftlichkeit'. Die Antike 19: 86-108. (1960). Reprint. In R. Harder, Kleine Schriften, 57-80. Munich. Harmatta, J. (1990). 'Herodotus, Historian of the Cimmerians and the Scythians'. In Hérodote et les peuples non grecs, Entretiens Hardt 35, ed. G. Nenci, 115 30. Geneva. (1992). 'Die Schrift bei den antiken Steppenvölkern'. ACD 28: 7 46. Harrison, Ε. Β. (1972). 'Preparations for Marathon, the Niobid Painter and Hero dotus'. The Art Bulletin 54: 390-412. Harrison, 1'. (1998). 'Herodotus' Conception of Foreign Languages'. Histos 2: http://vv-ww.dur.ac.uk/Classics/histos/ 1998/harrison.html. -. (2000a). The Emptiness of Asia: Aeschylus' Persians and the History of the Fifth Century. London. . (2000b). Divinity and. History: Hie Religion of Herodotus. Oxford. . (2000c). 'Sicily in the Athenian Imagination: Thucydides on the Persian Wars'. In Ancient Sicily from Aeneas to Cicero, ed. C.J. Smith and J. Serrati, 84-96; 199-201. Edinburgh. Harrison, T., ed. (2001). Greeks and Barbarians. Edinburgh. Hart, J. (1982). Herodotus and Greek History. London (1993). 2d ed. Hanley Swan, U K . Hartog, F. (1980). L· miroir d'Hérodote. Essai sur la représentation de l'antre. Paris (1991), 2d ed. Paris.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
605
- . (1988). The Mirror of Herodotus: The Representation of the Other in the Writing of History, tr. J. Lloyd. Berkeley. -. (1999). 'Myth into Logos: the Case of Croesus'. In From Myth to Reason?, ed. R. Buxton, 183-96. Oxford. Harvey, D. (1985). 'Women in Thueydides'. Arelhusa 18; 67-90. Harvey, F. D. (1966). 'The Political Sympathies of Herodotus'. Historia 15: 254 5. - . '(1980). 'Neokles, Father of Themistokles'. Histona 29: 110 11. Hatto, A. T. (1980). 'Kirghiz (Mid-nineteenth century)'. I n Traditions of Heroic and Epic Poetry I : The Traditions, ed. A. T. Hatto, 300-27. London. Havelock, Ε. Α. (1963). Preface to Plato. Cambridge, M A . -. (1972). 'War as a Way of Life'. I n Valeurs antiques et temps modernes, The Georges P. Vanier Memorial Lectures 1970 71, ed. Etienne Gareau, 17-78. Ottawa. Heath, M . (1989). Unity in Greek Poetics. Oxford. Heinimann, F. (1945). JVomos und Physis: Herkunft und Bedeutung einer Antithese im griechi schen Denken des 5. Jh. Basel. (1972). Reprint. Darmstadt. Heitsch, E. (1991). 'ανω κάτω bei Piaton'. RhM 134: 276 87. Helck, W., and E. Otto, eds. (1984). Hxikon der Ägyptologie V. Wiesbaden. Hellmann, F. (1934). Herodols Kroisos-Logos. Berlin. Helm, R., ed. (1984). Die Chronik des Hieronymus, 3d ed. Die griechischen christlichen Schriftsteller der ersten Jahrhunderte. Eusebius Werke 7. Berlin. Henderson, J. (2002). 'Demos, Demagogue, Tyrant in Attic Old Comedy'. In Popular Tyranny: Sovereignty and Its Discontents in Classical Athens, ed. K. Morgan. Austin. I l r n i , R. (1977;. Die Gespräche hei Herodol. I leilbronn. Herington, J. (1991a). 'The Closure of Herodotus' Histories'. ICS 16: 149 60. -. (1991b). 'The Poem of Herodotus'. Arion 1: 5-16. Herman, G. (1987). Ritualized Friendship and the Greek City. Cambridge. Hertel, D. (1991). 'Schliemanns These vom Fortleben Troias in den "Dark Ages" im Lichte neuer Forschungsergebnisse'. Studio Troica 1: 131 44. Heiter, H., ed. (1968). Thukydides, Wege der Forschung 98. Darmstadt. Heubeck, Α., and A. Hoestra. (1989). A Commentary on Homer's 'Odyssey' II: Booh ix-xvi. Oxford. Heuss, A. (1973). 'Motive von Herodots lydischem Logos'. Hermes 101: 385-419. (1995). Reprint. In A. Heuss, Gesammelte Schriften I , 68-102. Stuttgart. Hignett, C. (1963). Xerxes' Invasion of Greece. Oxford. Hodkinson, S. (2000). Property and Wealth in Classical Sparta. London. Hohti, P. (1974). 'Freedom of Speech in the Speech Sections in the Histories of Herodotus'. Arclos 8: 19 27. Holzberg, Ν. (1973). 'Zur Datierung der Gygestragödie'. ^4«/ 23: 273 86. Hommel, H . (1981). 'Herodots Einleitungssatz: ein Schlüssel zur Analyse des Gesamtswerks?' In Gnomosyne. Menschliches Denken und Handeln in derfiiihgriechischenLiteratur: Festschrift.für Waller Marg zum 70. Geburtstag, ed. G. Kurz, D. Müller, and W. Nicolai, 271-87. Munich. Hornblower, S. (1987). Thueydides. London. -. (1991). A Commentary on Thueydides, Vol. 1: Books I III. Oxford. —. (1992a). 'The Religious Dimension to the Peloponnesian War, or, What Thueydides Does not Tell Us'. IlSPh 94: 169-97. . (1992b). 'Thueydides' Use of Herodotus'. In Philolakön: Ijikonum Studies in Honour of Hector Catling, ed. J. M . Sanders, 141-54. (1996). Reprint. In S. Hornblower, . I Commentary on Thueydides, Vol. 2: Books IV-V.24, 122-37. Oxford. -. (1994a). 'Introduction'. In Greek Historiography, ed. S. Hornblower, 1-72. Oxford. (1994b). 'Narratology and Narrative Techniques in Thueydides'. In Greek Historiography, ed. S. Hornblower, 13166. Oxford. - — . ed. (1994c). Greek Historiography. Oxford. -. (1996a). A Commentary on Thueydides, Vol. 2: Booh IV-V.24. Oxford.
606
BIBLIOGRAPHY
(1996b). 'Thucydides'. Oxford Classical Dictionnaiy, 3d ed., 1520-1. Oxford. -. (2000). 'Personal Names and the Study of the Ancient Greek Historians'. In Greek Personal Marnes: Their Value as Evidence, ed. S. Hornblower and E. Matthews, 129-43. Oxford. (2001). 'Epic and Epiphanies: Herodotus and the New Simonides'. In The Mew Simonides: Contexts of Praise and Desire, ed. D. Boedeker and D. Sider, 135-47. Oxford and New York. [Forthcoming]. 'Panionios of Chios and Hermotimos of Pedasa (Hdt. 8. 104-106)'. In The World of Herodotus Essays in Honour of W. G. Forrest, ed. P. S. Derow and R. Parker. Oxford. Hornung, E. (1983). Conceptions of God in Ancient Egypt: The One and the Many, tr. John Baines. London. How, W. W., a n d j . Wells. (1912). A Commentary on Herodotus. 2 vols. Oxford. (1928). 2d ed. Howald, E. (1923). 'Ionische Geschichtsschreibung'. Hermes 58: 113-46. (1945). Vom Geist antiker Geschichtsschreibung. Munich. Huber, L. (1965a). Religiöse und politische Beweggründe des Handelns in der Geschichtsschreibung des Herodot. Diss. Tübingen. —. (1965b). 'Herodots Homerverständnis'. In Synusia. Festgabe für W. Schadewäldl, 29 52. Pfullingen. Humphreys, S. (1987). 'Law, Custom, and Culture in Herodotus'. In Herodotus and the Invention of History, Arethusa 20, ed. D. Boedeker and J. Peradotto, 211-20. Buffalo. Hunger, H . (1968). Babylonische und assyrische Kolophone. Alter Orient und Altes Testament 2. Neukirchen-Vluyn. Hunt, P. (1998). Slaves, Warfare and Ideology in the Greek Historians, Cambridge. Hunter, V. (1977). 'The Composition of Thucydides' History. A New Answer to the Problem'. Hislona 26: 269-94. (1982). Past and Process in Herodotus and Thucydides. Princeton. Hunzinger, C. (1995). 'La notion de 8fiua chez Hérodote'. Klèma 20: 47-70. Hussey, E. (1972). The Presocralics. London. —. (1985). 'Thucydidean History and Democritean Theory'. In Crux: Essays in Greek History Presented to G. E. M. de Ste Croix, ed. P. Cartledge and F. D. Harvey, 118-38. London. Huxley, G. L. (1962). Early Sparta. Cambridge, M A . -. (1978). 'Simonides and His World'. PRIA 78G: 231-47. -. (1989). Herodotus and the Epic. Athens. Immerwahr, H . R. (1954). 'Historical Action in Herodotus'. TAPha 85: 16-45. . (1956/57). 'Aspects of Historical Causation in Herodotus'. TAPha 87: 241-80. -. (1956/57). 'The Samian Stories in Herodotus'. CJ 52: 312-22. . (1960). ''Ergon: History as a Monument in Herodotus and Thucydides'. A'fPh 81: 261-90. -. (1966). Form and Thought in Herodotus. APA Philological Monographs 23. Cleveland. Isager, S. (1999). 'The Pride of Halicarnassos. Editio Princeps of an Inscription from Salmakis'. fPE 123: 1 23. Ivantchik, A. I . (1993a). Les Cimmériens au Proche-Orient. Orbis Biblicus et Orientalis 127. Fribourg and Göttingen. -. (1993b). 'La datation du poème l'Arimaspée d'Aristéas de Proconnèse'. AC 62: 35-67. — -. (1997). 'Das Problem der ethnischen Zugehörigkeit der Kimmerier und die kimmerische archäologische Kultur'. Praehistorische feitschrft 72: 12-53. —. (1999). 'The Scythian 'Rule over Asia': The Classical Tradition and the Historical Reality'. In Ancient Greeks West and East, ed. G. R. Tsetskhladze, 497-520. Leiden.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
607
Jackson, P., and D. Morgan. (1990). The Mission of Friar William of Rubruck: His Journey to the Court of the Great Khan Möngke, 1253-1255. London. Jacob, C. (1991). Géographie el ethnographie en Grèce ancienne. Paris. Jacoby, F. (1912). 'Hekataios'. In Pauly-Wissoma V I I I 1, 104 53. -. (1913). 'Herodotos'. In Paulys Real-Enyclopädie der classischen Allerlumswvssenschafl, ed. W. Kroll, Supplement-Band I I , 205 520. Stuttgart. (1956). Reprint. In F. Jacoby, Griechische Historiker, 7 164. Stuttgart, . (1923- ). Die Fragmente der griechischen Historiker. Berlin-Leiden. (1949). Allhis: Hie Local Chronicles of Ancient Athens. Oxford. -, (1956). Griechische Historiker. Stuttgart. Jeffery, L. H . (1988). 'Greece before the Persian Invasion'. In The Cambridge Ancient History, vol. 4, ed. J. Boardman, N . G. L . Hammond, D. -VI. Lewis, and M . Ostwald, 347-67. 2d ed. Cambridge. Jettmar, K. (1964). Die Frühen Sleppenvijlker. Der eurasiatische Tierstil, Entstehung und sozialer Hinlergrund. Baden-Baden. - -, (1967). Art of the Steppes: The Eurasian Animal Style, tr. K. Jettmar. London. Joannes, F. (1990). 'Pouvoirs locaux et organisation du territoire en Babylonie achéménide'. Transeuphratène 3: 173 89. . (1995). 'L'extinction des archives cunéiformes dans la seconde partie de l'époque perse'. Revue d'Assyriologie 89: 13947. (1997). 'La situation de la Babylonie dans l'empire perse'. In Dans les pas des Dix-Mille: peuples et pays du Proche-Orient vus par un Grec, Pallas. Revue d'études antiques 43, ed. P. Briant, 279 86. Toulouse. Joannès, F., and A. Lemaire. (1996). 'Contrats babyloniens d'époque achéménide du Bît-Abî Râm avec une épigraphe arameénne'. Revue d'Assyriologie 90: 41-60. Johnson, W. A. (1994). O r a l Performance and the Composition of Herodotus' Histories'. GRES 35: 229-54. Jones, W. H . S. (1923). Hippocrates, vol. I I . Loeb Classical Library. Cambridge and London. de Jong, I. J. F. (1987). .Narrators and Localizers: The Presentation of the Story in the 'Iliad: Amsterdam. -. (1997). 'Gar introducing Embedded Narratives'. In New Approaches to Greek Particles, ed. A. Rijksbaron, 175 85. Amsterdam. -. (1999). 'Aspects narratologiques des Histoires d'Hérodote'. Lahes 19: 217-75. -, (200!). 'The Anachronical Structure of Herodotus' Histories'. In Texts, Ideas, and the Classics: Scholarship and Theory in Classical Literature, ed. S. Harrison, 93-116. Oxford. Jordan, B. (1986). 'Religion in Thucydides'. TAPha 116: 119-47. Jouanna, J. (1981). 'Les causes de la défaite des barbares chez Eschyle, Hérodote et Hippocrate'. Klèma 6: 3 15. (1996a). Llippocrale: Airs, Eaux, Lieux. Paris. -. (1996b). 'Hippocrate et les Problemala d'Aristote: essai de comparaison entre Airs, eux, lieux, ch. 10, Aphorismes 111, 11 14 et Problemala I , 8-12 et 19-20'. In Hippokratische Medizin und antike Philosophie, Medizin der Antike 1, ed. R. Wittern and P. Pellegrin, 273-93. Hildesheim. (1999). Hippocrates, tr. M . B. Deßevoise. Baltimore. Jursa, M . (1995). Die Landwirtschaft in Sippar in neubabylonischer Jjiit, Archiv für Orientforschung. Beiheft 25. Vienna. Kakridis, j ( T. (1951). Ή ΓΥΝΑΙΚΑ ΤΟΥ ΚΑΝΔΑΥΛΗ'. Hellenica 12: 1-14. Karttunen, Κ. (1988). 'Expedition to the End of the World: An Ethnographic τόπος in Herodotus'. Studio Orientalin 64: 177-81. -. (1989). India in Early Greek Literature. Studia Orientalia 65. Helsinki. (1997). India and the Hellenistic World. Studia Orientalia 83. Helsinki. Kassel) R. (1974). 'Herodot und der Gyges-Drama'. %ΡΕ 14: 226.
608
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Kazazis, J. N . (1987). Herodotos' Stories and History: A Proppian Analysis of his Narrative Technique. University Microfilms International. Ann Arbor. Keaveney, A. (1996). 'Persian Behaviour and Misbehaviour: Some Herodotean Examples'. Athenaeum 74: 23-48. Kennedy, G. (196.3). The Art of Persuasion in Greece. Princeton. Kent, R. G. (1953), Old Persian: Grammar, Texts, Lexicon. 2d ed. New Haven. Kerferd, G. B. (1981a). 77K Sophistic Movement. Cambridge. Kerferd, G. B., ed. (1981b). The Sophists and Their legacy. Wiesbaden. Kessler, K . - H . (1991). Urkunden aus Privathäusern: Die Wohnhäuser westlich des EannaTernpelbereichs. Tal 1: Die Archive der Söhne des Bel-usallim, des .Nabü-usallim und des Bel-supe-muhur. Ausgrabungen in Uruk-Warka, Endbericht 8. Mainz. Kienitz, F. K. (1953). Die politische Geschichte Ägyptens vom 7. bis zum. 4. Jahrhundert vor der Zeitwende. Berlin. Kilmer, M . (1993). Greek Erotica. London. Kirchberg, J. (1965). Die Funktion der Orakel im Werke Herodots. Hypomnemata I I . Göttingen. Kirk, G.'' S., J. E. Raven, and M . Schofield. (1983), The Presocratic Philmophers: A Critical Hislmy with a Selection of Texts. 2d ed. Cambridge. Klamp, G. (1930). 'Zu Herodot I , 207 und I I , 39 (40)'. Philologische Wochenschrift 29: 890-3. Klasens, A. (1945 48). 'Egypte onder Perzen en Grieken-Romeinen (Cambyse en Egypte)', Jaarbericht van het Vooraziatisch-Egyptisch Genootschap Ex Oriente Lux 10: 339 49. Kleingünther, A. (1933). Prötos Heuretes. Untersuchungen zur Geschichte einer Fragestellung. Philologus Suppl. 26.1. Leipzig. Kleinknecht, H . (1940). 'Herodot und Athen, 7.139/8.140-44'. Hermes 75: 241-62. Köhnken, A. (1988). 'Der dritte Traum des Xerxes bei Herodot'. Hermes 1 16: 26-40. Koldewey, R. (1990). Den wieder erstehende Babylon, ed. B. Hrouda. 5th ed. Munich. Konstan, D. (1983). 'The Stories in Herodotus' Histories: Book F. Helios 10: 122. -. (1987). 'Persians, Greeks, and Empire'. In Herodotus and the. Invention of History, Arcthusa 20, ed. D. Boedeker and J. Pcradotto, 59-73. Buffalo. Korfmann, M . (1993). 'Ausgrabungen 1992'. Studia Troica 3: 1-37. Koselleck, R. (1979). Vergangene Zukunft. Z Semantik geschichtlicher Zeilen. Frankfurt am Main. Kracauer, S. (1973). Geschichte—Vor den letzten Dingen. Frankfurt am Main, Kraeling, E. G. (1969). The Brooklyn Museum Aramaic Papyri. New York. Krischer, T. (1965). 'Herodots Prooimion'. Liemes 93: 159-67. -. (1971). Formale Konventionen der homerischen Epik, Zetemata 56, Munich. Kühne, H . et al. (1993). State Archives of Assyria Bulletin 7: 75 150. Kühner, R., and B. Gerth. (1898-1904). Ausführliche Grammatik der griechischen Sprache. 2. Teil: Satzlehre. Hannover. Kuhrt, A. (1982). 'Assyrian and Babylonian Traditions in Classical Authors: A Critical Synthesis'. In Mesopotamien und seine Nachbarn. Politische und kulturelle Wechselbeziehungen im alten Vorderasien vom. 4. bis 1. Jahrtausend v. Chr., ed. FI.-J. Nissen and J. Renger, Berliner Beiträge zum Vorderen Orient 1, 539-54. Berlin. • -. (1983). 'The Cyrus Cylinder and Achaemenid Imperial Policy'. Journal for the Study of the Old Testament 25: 83-97. (1987). 'Usurpation, Conquest and Ceremonial: From Babylon to Persia'. In Rituab of Royalty: Power and Ceremonial in Traditional Societies, ed. D. Cannadine and S. R. Price, Past and Present, 20-55. Cambridge. . (1988). 'Babylonia from Cyrus to Xerxes'. I n 77K Cambridge Ancient History, vol. 4, ed. J. Boardman, N . G. L . Hammond, D. M . Lewis, and M . Ostwald, 112-38. 2d ed. Cambridge. . (1989). 'Non-Royal Women in the Late Babylonian Period: A Survey'. In ur
BIBLIOGRAPHY
609
Women's Earliest Records from Ancient Egypt and Western Asia, ed. B. Lesko, Brown Judaic Studies 166, 215-39. Atlanta. . (1990a). 'Achaemenid Babylonia: Sources and Problems'. In Centre and Periphery: Proceedings of the Groningen 1986 Achaemenid History Workshop, Achaemenid History 4, ed. H . Sancisi-Weerdenburg and A. Kuhrt, 177-94. Leiden. -. (1990b). 'Alexander and Babylon'. In Hie Roots of the European Tradition: Proceedings of the Groningen 1987 Achaemenid History Workshop, Achaemenid History 5, cd, H. Sancisi-Weerdenburg and J. W. Drijvers, 121 30. Leiden. -. (1990c). 'Nabonidus and the Babylonian Priesthood'. In Pagan Priests, cd, M . Beard and J. North, 119 55. London. - -, (1995a). '77K Ancient .Near East c. 3000-330 B.C. London. . (1995b). 'The Assyrian Heartland in the Achaemenid Period'. I n Dans les pas dci Dix-Mille: peuph t et pays du Proche-Orient vus par un Grec, Pallas. Revue d'études antiques 43, ed. P. Briant, 239 54. Toulouse. • . (1995c). 'Ancient Mesopotamia in Classical Greek and Hellenistic Thought'. In Civilizations of the Ancient .Near East, ed. J. M . Sasson et al., 55 66. New York. (1997). 'Some Thoughts on P. Briant, Histoire de l'empire perse'. In Recherches récentes sur l'empire achéménide, Topoi Suppl. I , 287-97. Lyon. Kuhrt, A., and S. Sherwin-White. (1987). 'Xerxes' Destruction of Babylonian Temples'. In 77K Greek Sources: Proceedings of die Groningen 1984 Achaeminid History Workshop, Achaemenid History 2, ed. H . Sancisi-Weerdenburg and A. Kuhrt, 69 78. Leiden. Kurke, L. (1995). 'Herodotus and the Language of Metals'. Helios 22: 30 64. —. (1999). Coins, Bodies, Games, and Gold: Hie Politics of Meaning in Archaic Greece. Princeton. Kurz, G., D. Müller, and W. Nicolai, eds. (1981). Gnomosyne. Menschliches Denken und Handeln in der frühgiiechischen Literatur. Festschrift für Walter Marg zum 70. Geburtstag. Munich. Lachcnaud, G. (1978). Mythologies, religion el philosophie de l'histoire dans Hérodote. Lille and Paris. Lambert, W. G. (1963). 'The Reign of Nebuchadnezzar I : A Turning Point in the History of Ancient Mesopotamian Religion'. In The Seeds of Wisdom: Essays in Honor of T. G. Meek, ed. W. S. MacCullough, 3 13. Toronto. Lanfranchi, G. B. (2000). 'The Ideological and Political Impact of the Assyrian Imperial Expansion on the Greek World in the 6th and 7th Centuries B.C.' In The Heirs of Assyria, Melammu Symposia 1, ed. S. Aro and R. M . Whiting, 7 34. Helsinki. Lang, M . L . (1967/68). 'Scapegoat Pausanias'. CJ 63: 79-85. . (1968). 'Herodotus and the Ionian Revolt'. Hhtoria 17: 24-36. — . (1984). Herodotean .Narrative and Discourse. Cambridge, MA. •-. (1987). 'Commentary on Nagy and Boedeker'. In Herodotus and the Invention of History, Arethusa 20, ed. D. Boedeker and J. Peraclotto, 203 7. Buffalo. (1990). Ostraka. The Athenian Agora 25. Princeton. Langdon, S. (1912). Die neubabylonischen Köuigsinschripien. Vorderasiatische Bibliothek 4. Leipzig. Lanza, D. (1977). Il tiranno e il suo pubblico. Turin. Larsen, M . T. (1976), The Old Assyrian City-State and its Colonies. Mesopotamia 4. Copenhagen. Lasserre, F. (1976). 'L'historiographie grecque à l'époque archaïque'. Qß 4: 113 42. Lateiner, D. (1977). 'No Laughing Matter: A Literary Tactic in Herodotus'. TAI'ha 107: 173-82. . (1984). 'Herodotean Historiographical Patterning: The Constitutional Debate'. OS 20: 257-84. . (1985). 'Limit, Propriety, and Transgression in the Histories of Herodotus'. In The Greek Historians: Papers Presented ter A. E. Raubitschek, ed. M . H.Jameson, 87-100. Saratoga.
610
BIBLIOGRAPHY
(1986). 'The Empirical Element in the Methods of Early Greek Medical Writers and Herodotus: A Shared Epistemological Respoit.se'. Antichi 20: 1 -20. (1987). 'Nonverbal Communication in the Histories of Herodotus'. I n Herodotus and the Invention, of History, Arethusa 29. ed. D . Bocdekcr and J. Peradotto, 8 3 · 119. Buffalo. , (1989). The Historical Method of Herodotus. Toronto. Latte, K . (1950). 'Ein antikes Gygesdrama'. Eranos 48: 136--44. (1958). 'Die Anlange der griechischen Geschichtsschreibung'. In Histoire el historiens dans Vantiquité. Entretiens Hardt 4, ed. K . Latte, 1 2 0 . Geneva. Latttmore, R. (1939). 'The Wise Adviser in Herodotus'. CPh 34: 24-35. (1958). 'The Composition of the History of Herodotus'. CPh 53: 9- -21. Laurot, B. (1981). 'Idéaux grecs et barbarie chez Hérodote'. Ktèrna 6: 39 48. (1995). 'Remarques sur la tragédie' de Grés us'. Ktèma 20: 95 103. Lavelle, B. M . (1.993). The Sorrow and the Pity: A Prolegomenon, to a PI is tory of Athens ander the Peins tratids, c. 500 510 B.C. Htstoria Einzelschritten 80. Stuttgart. Lazenhy, J. F. (1993). The Defence of Greece... 490-479 B.C. Warminster. Legrand, P.-E. (1942). Hérodote, Histoires. Vol V. Paris. (1966). Hérodote. Introduction. Paris. Leick, G. (1994). Sex and Eroticism in Mesopotarnian literature, London. Lcndon, J. E. (2000). 'Homeric Vengeance and the Outbreak o f Greek Wars'. In War and Violence in Ancient. Greece, ed. H . van Wees, 1 30. London and Swansea. Le il fa nt, D. (1996). G testas et Hérodote, ou les réécritures de l'histoire dans la Perse achéménide'. REG 109: 348 80. Lesky, A. (.1953). 'Das hellenistische Gygesdrama'. Hermes 81: I-10. (1959). 'Aethiopika'. Henries 87: 27 38. (1977). 'Tragödien bei Herodot?' In Greece and the Eastern. Mediterranean, in. Ancient History and Prehistory: Studies presented to Fritz Sduichmneyr, ed. K. Kinzel, 224-30. Berlin and New York. Levi, M . A. (1989). Nornadi allajrontiera: Ipopoli delle steppe e I'anlico immdo greco-romarm. Rome Levy, E. (1981). 'Les origines du mirage scythe'. Ktèma 6: 57 68. (1999). 'La Sparte d'Hérodote'. "Ktèma 24: 123-34. Lewis, B. (1980). The Saigon liegend. Cambridge, M A . Lewis, D . M . (1.977). Sparta and Persia. Cincinnati Classical Studies, n.s. 1. Leiden. (1985). ''Persians in Herodotus'. In The Greek Historians: Papers Presented, to A. E. Rauirilsclu'k, ed. M , H.Jameson, 89-105. Palo Alto. (1997). Reprint. In D . M . .Lewis, Selected Papers in Greek and .Near Eastern .History, ed. P.J. Rhodes, 345 6.1. Cambridge. . (1987). 'The King's Table'. In The Greek Sources: Proceedings of the Groningen 1984 Achaemenxd History Workshop, Achacmenid History 2, ed. H . Saneisi-Weerdenburg and A. Kühr I, 79 87. Leiden. (1997). Reprint. In D. M . Lewis, Selected Papers in Greek and Near Eastern. History, cd. P.J. Rhodes, 332-41. Cambridge. (1997). Selected Papers in Greek and Mar Eastern History, ed. P. J. Rhodes. Cambridge. Lewis, S. (1996). jVews and Society in the Greek Polis. London. (1998). 'Who is Pythios the Lydiatv. Hislos 2: http:// www .dur. ac. uk / CI ass ics / his tos /1998/1ewi s. h tin I. von Leyden, W. M . (1.94-9/50). 'Spatium Historic urn: The Historical Past as Viewed by Hccataeus, Herodotus, and Thucydides'. Durham, university Journal n.s. 11: 89 104, (1962). Reprint. In Herodot. Eine Auswahl aus der neueren. Forschung. Wege der Forschung 26, ed. W . Marg. Munich. (1965). 2d ed. Munich. (1982). 3d ed. Darmstadt. Lieber, E. (1996). 'The Hippocratic "Airs, Waters, Places" on Cross-Dressing Eunuchs: "Natural" yet also "Divine"'. I n Hippokratische Medizin und antike Philosophie, ed. R. Wittern and P. Pellegrin, 451 76. Hildes heim. 1
1
611
BIBLIOGRAPHY
van Lieshout, R. G. A. (S970). 'À Dream on a KAIROS of History: An Analysis of Herodotus' Hist. V I I . 12 19, 47'. Mnemosyne p: 225 49. Lloyd, A. B. (197.!)). Herodotus, Book II: Introduction, Etudes préliminaires aux religions orientales dans l'Empire romain 4-3. Leiden. (1976). Herodotus, Book II: Commentary 1-98. Etudes préliminaires aux religions orientales dans l'Empire romain 43. Leiden. (S979). 'Herodotus 2.96.1-2'. C'Q, 29: 45 8. (1982). 'The Inscription of Udjahorresnet: A Collaborator's Test anient . JFA 68: 166-80. (1988a). Herodotus, Book II: Commentary 99-182. Etudes préliminaires aux religions orientales clans l'Empire romain 43. Leiden. . (1988b). 'Herodotus on Cambyses: Some Thoughts on Recent Work'. In Method and Theory: Proceedings of the London 1985 Acliaemenid His ton Workshop, Achaemenid History 3, eel. A. Kuhrt and H. Sancisi-Weerdenburg, 55 66. Leiden. (1988c). 'Herodotus' Account of Pharao nie History'. Historia 31: 25 53. (1990). 'Herodotus on Egyptians and Libyans'. In Hérodote et les peuples non grecs, Entretiens Hardt 35, ed. G. Nenci, 215-53. Geneva. (1995). 'Herodotus on Egyptian Buildings: A Test Case'. In Greek Ilisloiy and Historians, cd. A. Powell. 273 300. London and New York. Lloyd, G. E. R. (1966). Polarity and Analogy: Tivo Types of Argumentation in Early Greek Thought. Cambridge. (1987). Reprint. Bristol. (1979). Magic, Reason and Experience: Studies in the Origin and Development of Greek Science. Cam I) ridge. Lloyd, Ai. (1984). 'Croesus' Priority: Herodotus 1.5.3'. LCM 9: 11. (1987). 'Cieobis and Biton (Herodotus 1,3)}'. Heimes 115: 22-8, Lloyd-Jon es, H . (1952). 'The Gyges- Fragment : A New Possibi !i ty '. PCPhS 2: 36- •• 4 3. (1983). The 'justice of /feus, 2d ed. Berkeley. . (1999). T h e Pride of Halicarnassos'. %PÊ 124: 1 14. Lobel, E. (1950). 'A Greek Historical Drama'. PBA 35: 207 16. Long. T. (1987). Repetition and. Variation in the Short Stories of Herodotus. Beiträge zur Klassischen Philologie 179. Frankfurt am Main. Loraux, N . (1986a). 'Thucydide a écrit la guerre du Péloponnèse'. Métis 1: 139 61. (1986b). The Invention of Athens, tr. A. Sheridan, Cambridge, M A . (1995). 'Feminine Nature in History'. In The Experiences oj'Tiresias: The Feminine and the Greek Man, 227-48. Princeton. I .oraux, N., and C. Mira lies, eds. (1998). Figures de. l'intellectuel en Grèce ancienne. Paris. Lord, A. B. (1970). 'Tradition and the Oral Poet'. In IM poena epica e la sua formazione, Arcade m ia nationale dei Lincei. Problem! attuali di scienza e di cultura, cjuaelerno 139. Rome. Lucas, A. (1962). Ancient Egyptian. Materials and Industries. 4th ed. Revised by J. Harris. London. Luce, T . J . (1997). The Greek Historians. London. , ed. (1982). Ancient Writers: Greece and Rome, I . New York. Luraglii, N . (2001a). 'Local Knowledge in Herodotus' Histories'. In The Historian's Craft, ed. N . Luraghi. 138-60, Oxford. , ed. (2001b), The Historian's Craft in the Age of Herodotus. Oxford. Maas, P. (1950). Review of Lobel 1950. Gnomon 22: 142 3. Macan, R. \V. (1895). Herodotus, Books ivvi. London. MacDowell, D. M . (1983). T h e Nature of Aristophanes' Akharnians'. G&R 30: 143 62. MaeGinnis, J. (1986). 'Herodotus' Description of Babylon'. BICS 33: 67-86. . (1995). Letter Orders from Sippar and. the Administration, of the. Ebabarra in the LateBabylonian Period. Poznan. MacLeod, C. (.1983). Thucyelides and Tragedy'. In C. MacLeod, Collected Essays. 140 58. Oxford. 1
612
BIBLIOGRAPHY
MacNeal, R. A. (1988). 'The Brides of Babylon: Herodotus 1.196'. Histoid 37: 54-71. Makres, A. (forthcoming). 'Herodotus IX.85: ipéeç or ipéveç?' Malkin, I . (1987). Religion and Colonization in Ancient Greece. Leiden. (1994). Myth and History in the Spartan Mediterranean. Cambridge. Marchenko, K., and Y. Vinogradov. (1989). 'The Scythian Period in the Northern Black Sea Region (750 250 B.C.)'. Antiquity. 63: 803-13. Maig, W. (1965). 'Selbstsichcrheit bei Herodot'. (1962). Reprint. In Herodol. Eine Auswahl aus der neueren Forschung. Wege der Forschung 26, ed. W. Marg, 290 -301. Munich. (1965). 2d ed. Munich. (1982). 3d ed. Darmstadt. Marg, W., ed. (1962). Herodot. Eine Auswahl aus der neueren Forschung. Wege der Forschung 26. Munich. (1965). 2d ed. Munich. (1982). 3d ed. Darmstadt. Margreth, D. (199,3). Shythische Schamanen? Die Nachrichten über Enarees-Anarieis bei Herodol und Hippokrates. Schillhausen. Marinatos, N . (1981). Thucydides and Religion. Beiträge zur klassischen Philologie 129. Königstein. Marincola, J. (1987). 'Herodotean Narrative and the Narrator's Presence'. In Herodotus and the Invention of History, Arethusa 20, ed. D. Boedeker and J. Peradotto, 121 37. Buffalo. —. (1994). 'Plutarch's Refutation of Herodotus'. AncW 25: 191-203. (1996). Herodotus: The Histories. Revision, with Introductory Matter and Notes. Harmondsworth. -. (1997a). Authority and Tradition in Ancient Historiography. Cambridge. . (1997b). 'Odysseus and the Historians'. Hislos 1: http://www.dur.ac.uk/Classics/histos/ 1997/marincola.html. ~ . (1999). 'Genre, Convention, and Innovation in Greco-Roman Historiography'. In The Limits of Historiography: Genre and Narrative in. Ancient Historical Texts, ed. C. S. Kraus, 281 324. Leiden. iVIarr, J. L. (1998). Plutarch: Themistocles. Warminster. Martin, V. (1965). 'La politique des Achéménides: L'exploration prélude de la conquête'. MIL 22: 28 38. Masaracchia, A. (1977). Erodoto: La Battaglia di Salamina, Libra VIII délie Storie. Verona. Masson, O. (1950). 'A propos d'un rituel hittite pour la lustration d'une armée'. RHR 137: 5-25. Matthews, J. F. (1989). The Roman Empire of Ammianus. London. May, C. E. (1995). The Short Story: Hie Reality of Artifice. New York. McGlew, J. F. (1993). Tyranny and Political Culture in Ancient Greece. Ithaca. Meier, C. (1973). 'Die Enstehung der Historie'. In Geschichte-Ereignis und Erzählung, ed. R. Koselleck and W.-D. Stempel, 251-305. Munich. - --. (1978). 'Prozeß und Ereignis in der griechischen Historiographie des 5. Jahrhunderts v. Chr. und vorher'. In Historische Prozesse, Beiträge zur Historik 2, "ed. K.-G. Faber and C. Meier, 69-97. Munich. -. (1980). 'Die Enttstehung der Historie'. In C. Meier, Die Entstehung des Politischen bei den Griechen, 360-434. Frankfurt am Main. - -. (1986). 'Die Entdeckung der Ereignisgeschichte bei Herodot'. Storia delta storiografia 10: 5 25. -. (1987). 'Historical Answers to Historical Questions: The Origins of History in Ancient Greece'. In Herodotus and the Invention of History, Arethusa 20, ed. D. Boedeker and J. Peradotto, 41-57. Buffalo. Meiggs, R., and D. M . Lewis. (1969). A Selection of Greek Historical Inscriptions to the End of the Fifth Century B.C. Oxford. (1988). Rev. ed. Oxford. Melyukova, A. I . (1990). 'The Scythians and Sarmatians'. In The Cambridge History of Early Inner Asia, ed. D. Sinor, 97-117. Cambridge. Meuli, K . (1935). 'Scythica' Hermes 70: 121-78. (1975). Reprint. In K . Meuli, Gesammelle Schriften, vol. 2. Basel and Stuttgart. Meyer, E. (1892). 'Herodots Chronologie der griechischen Sagengeschichte. M i t
BIBLIOGRAPHY
613
Excursen zur Geschichte der griechischen Chronograpie und Historiographie'. In Forschungen zur alten Geschichte I , 151-209. Halle. —. (1899). Forschungen zur alten Geschichte I I . Halle. (1901). Geschichte des alterthums I I I . Stuttgart. (1937). 2d ed. Stuttgart and Berlin. (1944). 4th ed., vol. I V 14. Berlin. Mikalson, J. D. (1983). Athenian Popular Religion. Chapel Hill. - - . (1991). Honor Thy Gods: Popuhr Religion in Greek Tragedy. Chapel Hill. Mutender, E. (2001). 'Spartan Literacy Revisited'. ClAnt 20: 121 64. Miller, M . (1965). 'Herodotus as Chronographer'. Klio 46: 109-28. Miller, M . C. (1995). 'Persians: The Oriental Other'. Source: Notes in the History of Art 15-16: 38-44. -. (1997). Athens and Persia in the Fifth Century. London. Mink, L. (1987). Historical Understanding, ed. B. Fay, E. Golob, and R. Vann. Ithaca. Minns, E. H . (1913). Scythians and Greeks: A Survey of Ancient History and Archaeology on the North Coast of the Euxine from the Danube to the Caucasus. Cambridge. Missiou, A. (1998). 'Reciprocal Generosity in the Foreign Affairs of Fifth-Century Athens and Sparta'. In Reciprocity in Ancient Greece, ed. C. Gill, N , Postlethwaite, • i.
|< \ . . •!..·. • I:. I
I i |.,.. I
Mitchel, F. (1956). 'Herodotos' Use of Genealogical Chronology'. Phoenix 10: 48 69. Mitchell, B. M . (1975). 'Herodotus and Samos'. JHS 95: 75-91. Mitchell, L. G. (1997). Greeks Bearing Gifts: Hie Public Use of Private Relationships in the Greek World, 435-323 BC. Cambridge. . (2000). 'Herodotus and Panhellenism'. Histos 3:#http://www.dur.ac.uk/Classics/ histos. Moles, J. (1993). 'Truth and Untruth in Herodotus and Thucydides'. In Lies and Fiction in the Ancient World, ed. C. Gill and T. P. Wiseman, 88-121. Austin. (1996). 'Herodotus Warns the Athenians'. In Papers of the Leeds International Latin Seminar 9: 259-84. Leeds. -. (1999). 'Anathema kai Ktema: the Inscriptional Inheritance of Ancient Historiography'. Histos 3: http://www.dur.ac.uk/Glassics/histos/ 1999/moles.html. ·—. (2000). 'What's in a Name? Herodotus on Themistocles'. Histos 3:#http://www. dur.ac.uk/Classics/histos. Momigliano, A. D. (1958). 'The Place of Herodotus in the History of Historiography'. History 43: 1-13. (1966). Reprint. In Studies in Historiography, 127 42. London. •-. (1960). 'Some Observations on Causes of War in Ancient Historiography', In A. D. Momigliano, Secondo contributo alia storia degli studi classici, 13-27. Rome. (1966a). Studies in Historiography. London. -. (1966b). 'Time in Ancient Historiography'. History and Theory Suppl. 6: 1-23. (1969). Reprint. In A. Momigliano, Quarto contributo alia storia degli studi classici, 13-41. Rome. (1978). 'The Historians of the Classical World and Their Audiences: Some Suggestions'. AS/VP ser. 3, 8: 59 75. . (1979). 'Persian Empire and Greek Freedom'. In The Idea of Freedom: Essays in Honour of Sir Isaiah Berlin, cd. A, Ryan, 139-51. Oxford. (1984). Reprint. In A. Momigliano, Sellimo contributo alia storia degli studi classici e del mondo antico, 61 75. Rome. Moniot, H . (1970). 'Lcs sources clc J'histoirc africaine'. In His to ire generale de I'Afrique noire 1, ed. H . Deschamps, 134-5. Paris. Monoson, S. S. (1994). 'Citizen as Ernstes: Erotic Imagery and the Idea of Reciprocity in the Periclean Funeral Oration'. Political Theory 22: 253-76. Mora, F. (1986). Religione e religioni nelle storie di Erodoto. Le edizioni universitarie Jaca 18. Milan. Morgan, D. (1986). '77K Mongols, Oxford. Morgan, K., ed. (2002). Popular Tyranny: Sovereignty and Its Discontents in Classical Athens. Austin.
614
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Morris, I . (1997). 'Periodization and the Heroes: Inventing a Dark Age'. In Inventing Ancient Culture: Hisloricism, Periodization, and the Ancient World, ed. M . Golden and P. Toohey, 96-131. London. Morris, I . , and K. Raaflaub, ed. (1998). Democracy 2500? Questions and Challenges. A I A Colloquia and Conference Papers 2. Dubuque. Morrison, J. S. (1941). 'The Place of Protagoras in Athenian Public Life'. CO 35: 1 — 16. -. (1950). 'Pericles Monarches' (with a response by A. W. Gomme). J HS 70: 76 7. Mosshammer, A. A. (1979). The Chronicle of Eusebius and Greek Chronographie Tradition. Cranbury, NJ. Mossman, J. M . (1995). Wild Justice: A Study of Euripides' Hecuba. Oxford. Moxon, I . S., J. D. Smart, and A . J . Woodman, eds. (1986). Past Perspectives: Studies in Greek and Roman Historical Writing. Cambridge. Müller, D. (1980). Satzbau, Satzgliederung und Satzverbindung in der Prosa Herodots. Meisenheim am Glan. . (1981). 'Herodot Vater des Empirismus? Mensch und Erkenntnis im Denken Herodots'. In Gnomosyne. Menschliches Denken und Handeln in der frühgriechischen Literatur. Festschrift für Walter Marg zum 70. Geburlstag, ed. G. Kurz, G., D . Müller, and W. Nicolai, 299 318. Munich. Müller, F. (1926). 'De "historiae" vocabulo atque notione'. Mnemosyne 54: 234-57. Müller, K, E. (1972). Geschichte der antiken Ethnographie und ethnologischen Theoriebildung vom den Anfangen bis auf die byzantinischen Historiographen I . Wiesbaden. Munson, R. V. (1983). Transitions in Herodotus. Diss. University of Pennsylvania. —. (1986). 'The Celebratory Purpose of Herodotus: The Story of Arion in Histories 1.23-24'. Ramus 15: 93-104. -. (1988). 'Artemisia in Herodotus'. ClAnl 7: 91-106. (1991). 'The Madness of Cambyses (Herodotus 3.16-38)'. Arelhusa 24: 43-65. . (1993). 'Herodotus' Use of Prospective Sentences and the Story of Rhampsinitus and the Thief in the Histories'. AJPh 114: 27-44. (2001). Telling Wonders: Ethnographic and Political Discourse in the Work of Herodotus. Ann Arbor. Mure, Sir William of Caldwell. (1853). Critical History of the Language and Literature of Ancient Greece, vol. 4. London. Murray, G. (1907). The Rue of the Greek Epic. Oxford. Murray, O. (1972). 'Herodotus and Hellenistic Culture'. CO 22: 200-3. -. (1987). 'Herodotus and Oral History'. In The Greek Sources: Proceedings of the Groningen 1984 Achaemenid History Workshop, Achaemenid History 2, ed. H . SancisiWeerclenburg and A. Kuhrt, 93115. Leiden. (2001). Reprinted in The Historian's Craft, ed. N . Luraghi, 16 44, Oxford. (1988). 'The Ionian Revolt'. In The Cambridge Ancient History, vol. 4, eel. J. Boardman, N . G. L. Hammond, D. M . Lewis, and M . Ostwald, 461-90. 2d ed. Cambridge. - -. (1993). Early Greece. 2d ed. London. Murray, O., ed. (1990). Sympotica: A Symposium on the Symposion. Oxford. Myres, J. L. (1914). 'Herodotus the Tragedian'. In A Miscellany presented to J. A4. MacKay, 88 96. Liverpool. -. (1953). Herodotus, Father of History. Oxford. Nagy, G. (1987). 'Herodotus the Logios'. In Herodotus and the Invention of History, Arethusa 20, ed. D. Boedeker and J. Peradotto, 17584. Buffalo. ——. (1990). Pindar's Homer: Tie lyric Possession of an Epic Past. Baltimore and London. Naiden, F. S. (1999). 'The Prospective Imperfect in Herodotus'. HSPh 99: 135-49. Nenci, G. (1990). 'L'occidente 'barbarico". In Herodote et les peuples nori grecs, Entretiens Hardt 35, ed. G. Nenci, 301 21. Geneva.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
615
Nesselrath, H.-G. (1996). 'Herodot und der griechische Mythos'. Poetica 28: 275-96. •-. (1999). 'Hcrodot und Babylon'. In Babylon: Focus mesopolamischer Geschichte, Wiege früher Gelehrsamkeit, Mythos der Moderne, ed. J. Renger, 189-206. Saarbrücken. Nestle, W. (1908). Herodots Verhältnis zur Philosophie und Sophislik. Schöntal. . (1942). Vom Mythos zum Logos. 2d ed. Stuttgart. (1966). Reprint. Aalen. Nickau, K . (1990). 'Mythos und Logos bei Hcrodot'. In Memoria rerum veterum. Neue Beiträge zur antiken Histonographie und allen Geschichte. Festschrift für Carl Joachim (lassen, ed. W. Ax, 83-100. Stuttgart. Nicolai, W. (1986). Versuch über Herodots Geschichtsphilosophie. Heidelberg. Nippel, W. (1990). Griechen, Barbaren und 'Wilde'. Alte Geschichte und Sozialanlhropologie. Frankfurt am Main. -. (1996). 'La costruzione dell' "altro"'. In I Greet: Storia, natura, arte, societä I , ed. Salvatore Settis, 165-96. Turin. Nyberg, H . S. (1954). 'Das Reich der Achämeniden'. In Der Aufstieg Europas, Historia Muncü 3, ed. G. Devoto et af, 56-115. Munich. Ober, J. (1993). T h e Athenian Revolution of 508/7 B.C.E.: Violence, Authority, and the Origins of Democracy'. In Cultural Poetics in Archaic Greece, ed. C. Dougherty and L. Kurke, 215-32. Cambridge, M A . -. (1998). 'Revolution Matters: Democracy as Demotic Action (A Response to Kurt Raaflaub)'. In Democracy 2500? Questions and Challenges. A I A Colloquia and Conference Papers 2, ed. I . Morris and K. Raaflaub, 67 85. Dubuque. (2001). 'Thucydides Theoretikos/Thucydides Histor: Realist Theory and the Challenge of History'. In War and Democracy: A Comparative Study of the Korean War and the Peloponnesian War, ed. D. R. McCann and B. S. Strauss, 273 306. Armonk, NY and London. Ogden, D. (1997). 77K Crooked Kings of Ancient Greece. London. O'Neil, J. L. (1995). 77«; Origins and Development of Ancient Greek Democracy. Maryland. Osborne, R. G. (1994). 'Archaeology, the Salaminioi and the Politics of Sacred Space in Archaic Attica'. In Placing the Gods, ed. S. Alcock and R. Osborne, 143 -60. Oxford. . (1996). Greece in the Making, 1200 479 B.C. London. Ostwakl, M . (1991). 'Herodotus and Athens'. ICS 16: 137 48. -· -. (1992). 'Athens as a Cultural Centre'. In 77K Cambridge Ancient History, vol. 5, ed. D. M . Lewis, J. Boardman, J. K. Davies, and M . Östwald, 306- 69. 2d cd. Cambridge. Oswald, R. (1995). 'Gedcnkliche und thematische Linien in Herodots Werk'. GB 21: 17 59 Otto, E, (1954). Die biographischen Inschriften der ägyptischen Spätzeil. Probleme der Ägyptologie 2. Leiden. Packman, Z. (1991). 'The Incredible and the Incredulous: The Vocabulary of Disbelief in Herodotus, Thucydides, and Xenophon'. Hermes 119: 401 14. Page, D. L. (1950). 'On the'New Greek Historical Drama'. C£) 44: 125. (1951). 'A New Chapter in the History of Greek Tragedy'. Inaugural lecture. Cambridge. . (1962). 'An Early Tragedy on the Fall of Croesus'. PCPhS 8: 47 9. Parke, H. W., and D. E. W. Wormell. (1956). The Delphic Oracle, 2 vols. Oxford. Parker, R. (1985). 'Greek States and Greek Oracles'. In CRUX: Essays in Greek History Presented to G. E. XL de Sie Croix, ed. P. Cartledge and D. Harvey, 298-326. Exeter. . (1996). Athenian Religion: A History. Oxford. Parker, R. C. T. (1998). 'Pleasing Thighs: Reciprocity in Greek Religion'. In Reciprocity in Ancient Greece, ed. C. Gill, N . Postlethwaite, and R. Seaford, 105-26. Oxford. Parsons, P. J. (1992). '3965.Simonides, Elegies,' The Oxyrhynchus Papyri 59: 4-50. Patzek, B. (1992a). Homer und Xlykene. Mündliche Dichtung und Geschichtsschreibung. Munich. . (1992b). 'Der Mythos vom Schicksalstag Troias'. In Archäologie und historische
616
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Erinnerung. .Nach 100 Jahren Heinrich Schliemann, ed. J. Cobct and B. Patzek, 157-69. Essen. Patzer, A. (1986). Der Sophist Hippias ab Philo Sophiehistoriker. Freiburg and Munich. Payen, P. (1991). 'Franchir, transgresser, résister: autour de Tomyris et Cyrus chez Hérodote'. Métis 6: 253-81. -. (1997). Les îles nomades. Conquérir et résister dans /'Enquête d'Hérodote. Paris. Pearce, T. E. V. (1981). '"Epic Regression" in Herodotus'. Eranos 79: 87-90. Pedersén, O. (1998). Archives and Libraries in the Ancient Near East, 1500 300 B.C. Bethesda, M D . Pelliccia, H . (1992). 'Sappho 16, Gorgias' Helen, and the Preface to Herodotus' Histories'. YCIS 29: 63-84. Pelling, C. B. R. (1991). Thucydides' Archidamus and Herodotus' Artabanus'. In Georgica: Greek Studies in Honour of George Cawkwell, B1CS Suppl. 38, ed. M . A. Flower and M . Toiler, 120 42. London. (1996). 'The Urine and the Vine: Astyages' Dream at Herodotus 1.107 8'. C<1 hi: 68-77. -. (1997a). 'Aeschylus' Perm and History'. In Greek Tragedy and the Historian, ed. C. B. R. Pelling, 1-19. Oxford. (1997b). 'East is East and West is West Or are they? National Stereotypes in Herodotus'. Elistos 1: http://\ww.dur.ac.uk/Classics/histos/1997/pelling.html. . (2000). Literary Texts and the Greek Historian. London. Pembroke, S. (1965). 'Last of the Matriarchs: A Study in the Inscriptions of Lycia'. JESI-IO 8: 217-47. (1967). 'Women in Charge: The Function of Alternatives in Early Greek Tradition and the Ancient Idea of Matriarchy'. JWC 30: 1 35. (1977). 'The Early Human Family. Some Views 1770-1870'. In Classical Influences in Western Thought AD 1650-1870, ed. R. Bolgar, 275 91. Cambridge. -. (1996). s.v. 'Prostitution, sacred'. In Hie Oxford Classical Dictionary, ed. S. Hornblower and A. Spawforth, 12637. 3d ed. Oxford. Perdrizet, P. (1912). 'La légende du châtiment de 1'Hellespont par Xerxès'. PTA 14: 357-69. Pernot, L. (1995). 'Le plus panégyrique des historiens'. Ktéma 20: 125-36. Pinto, M . (1955). 'Echi erodotei neu' Elettra di Sofocle'. Diomso 18: 162-74. Podlecki, A. J. (1977). 'Herodotus in Athens?' I n Greece and the Eastern Mediterranean: Studies Presented to Fritz Schachermeyer, ed. K . Kinzel, 246-65. Berlin and New York. Pohlenz, M . (1937). Herodot, der erste Geschichtsschreiber des Abendlandes. Leipzig. (1961). Reprint. Stuttgart. (1938). Hippokrates und die Begründung der wissenschaftlichen Medizin. Berlin. Pongratz-Leisten, B. (1994). Ina sulmi irub: Die kulttopographische und ideologische Programmatik der aLilii Prozession in Babylonien und Assyrien im 1. Jahrtausend v. Chr., Baghdader Forschungen 16. Mainz. Porada, E. (1985). 'Classic Achaemenian Architecture and Sculpture'. In Cambridge History of Iran, 2, ed. I . Gershevitch, 793-827. Cambridge. Porten, B. (1968). Archiaes from Elephantine. Berkeley. Posener, G. (1936). La premiere domination perse en Egypte: recueil d'inscriptions hiéroglyphiques, Bibliouhèque d'étude 11. Cairo. Powell, J, E. (1938). A Lexicon to Herodotus. Cambridge. (1939). The History of Herodotus. Cambridge. (1967). Reprint. Amsterdam. Prakken, D. W. (1948). Studies in Greek Genealogical Chronology. Lancaster, PA. Press, G. A. (1982). The Development of the Idea of History in Antiquity. Kingston and Montreal. Price, J. (2001). Thucydides and Internal Conflict: Stasis as a Model for the Peloponnesian War. Cambridge.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
617
Prince, Ε. F. (1981). 'Toward a Taxonomy of Given/New Information'. In Radical Pragmatics, ed. P. Cole, 223 56. New York. Pritchett, W. K. (1993). The Liar School of Herodotus. Amsterdam. Propp. V. (1968). Morphology of the Folk Tale. 2d ed., tr. L. Scott. Austin. Raaflaub, K . A. (1985). Die Entdeckung der Freiheit. Munich: Beck. (2002). 2d ed., tr. Chicago. (1987). 'Herodotus' Political Thought and the Meaning of History'. In Herodotus and the Invention of History, Arethusa 20, ed. D. Boedeker and J. Peradotto, 221 48. Buffalo. . (1988a). 'Athenische Geschichte und mündliche Überlieferung'. In Vergangenheil in mündlicher Überlieferung, Colloquium Rauricum 2, ed. J. von Ungern-Sternberg and H . Reinau, 197-225. Stuttgart. ·. (1988b). 'Homer and the Beginning of Political Thought in Greece'. Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 4: 1-25. -. (1988c). 'Politisches Denken im Zeitalter Athens'. In Pipers Handbuch der politischen Ideen I : Frühe Hochkulturen und europäische Antike, ed. I . Fetscher and H . Münkler, 273-368. Munich. (1989). 'Contemporary Perceptions of Democracy in Fifth-Century Athens'. C&M 40: 33 70. —. (1994). 'Democracy, Power, and Imperialism in Fifth-Century Athens'. In Athenian Political Hioughl and the Reconstruction of American Democracy, ed. J. P. Euben, J. R. Wallach, and J. Ober, 103-46. Ithaca. . (1997). 'Homeric Society'. I n A New Companion to Hornel, ed. I . Morris and B. Powell, 624-48. Leiden.' —. (1998a). 'Power in the Hands of the People: Foundations of Athenian Democracy'. I n Democracy 2.500? Questions and Challenges, ΑΙΑ Colloquia and Conference Papers 2, ed. I . Morris and K. Raaflaub, 31-66. Dubuque. (1998b). 'The Thetes and Democracy (A Response to Josiah Ober)'. In Democracy 2500? Questions and Challenges, ΑΙΑ Colloquia and Conference Papers 2, ed. I . Morris and K. Raaflaub, 87-103. Dubuque. (2000). 'Poets, Lawgivers, and the Beginnings of Political Reflection in Archaic Greece'. In Hie Cambridge History of Greek and Roman Political Thought, ed. C. Rowe and M . Scholield, 23-59. Cambridge. —. (2001). 'Father of All—Destroyer of All: War in Late Fifth-Century Athenian Discourse and Ideology*. In War and Democracy: A Comparative Study of the Korean War and the Peloponnesian War, ed. D. R. McCann and B. S. Strauss, 307 56. Armonk, NY and London. . (2002a). 'Herodot und Thukydides. Persischer Imperialismus im Lichte der athenischen Sizilienpolitik'. In Widerstand, Anpassung, Integration. Festschrift für Jürgen Deiningei um 65. Geburtstag, cd. L . M . Günther and N . Ehrhardt. Stuttgart. — . (2002b). 'Stick and Glue: The Function of Tyranny in Fifth-Century Athenian Democracy'. In Popular Tyranny: Sovereignty and Its Discontents in Classical Athens, ed. K. Morgan. Austin. Rankin, H . D. (1969). '"Eating People is Right": Petroniusl41 and a τόπος'. Hermes 97: 381-4. Raubitschek, A. E. (1939). "Έργα μεγάλα τε κα'ι θωμαστά'. REA 41: 217-22. — . (1955). 'Gyges in Herodotus'. CW 48: 48 51. Rechenauer, ( i . (1991). Thukydides und die hippokratische Medizin: Naturwissenschaftliche Methodik als Modell für Geschichtsdeutung. Spudasmata 47. Hildesheini. Reden, S. von (1995). Exchange in Ancient Greece. London. Reclfield, J. M . (1985). 'Herodotus the Tourist'. CPh 80: 97-118. Reese, W. (1914). Die griechischen Nachrichten über Indien Ins zum Feldzuge Alexanders des Grossen. Leipzig.
618
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Regenbogen, O. (1930a). 'Die Geschichte von Solon und Krösus'. Das humanistische Gymnasium 41: 1-20. (1961). Reprint. In O. Regenbogen, Kleine Schriften, 101-24. Munich. (1962). Reprint. In Herodot. Eine Auswahl aus der neueren Forschung. Wege der Forschung 26, ed. W. Marg. Munich. (1965). 2d ed. Munich. (1982). 3d ed. Darmstadt. Regenbogen, O. (1930b). 'Herodot und sein Werk. Ein Versuch'. Die Antike 6: 202 48. (1961). Reprint. In O. Regenbogen, Kleine Schriften, 57 100. Munich. (1962). Reprint. In Herodot. Eine Auswahl aus der neueren Forschung. Wege der Forschung 26, ed. W. Marg. Munich. (1965). 2d ed. Munich. (1982). 3d ed. Darmstadt. Reid, I . (1977). 77K Short Story. The Critical Idiom 37. London. Reinhardt, K. (1940). 'Herodots Persergeschichten. Östliches und Westliches im Übergang von Sage zu Geschichte'. In Geistige Überlieferung. Ein Jahrbuch, 138—84. Berlin. (1960). Reprint. In K . Reinhardt, Vermächtnis der Antike. Gesammelte Essays zur Philosophie und Geschichtsschreibung, 133-74. Göttüngen. (1962). Reprint. In Herodot. Eine Auswahl aus der neueren Forschung. Wege der Forschung 26, ed. W. Marg. Munich. (1965). 2d ed. Munich. (1982). 3d ed. Darmstadt. —. (1965). 'Herodots Persergeschichten'. (1962). Reprint. In Herodot. Eine Auswahl aus der neueren Forschung. Wege der Forschung 26, ed. W. Marg. Munich. (1965). 2d ed. Munich. (1982). 3d ed. Darmstadt. Reinhold, M . (1985). 'Human Nature as Cause in Ancient Historiography'. In The Graft of the Ancient Historian: Essays tu Honor of Chester G. Starr, ed. J. W. Eadie and J. Ober, 21-40. Lanham. Rhodes, P. J. (1981). A Commentary on the Aristotelian Athenäum Polileia. Oxford. Richardson, S. (1990). '77K Homeric .Narrator. Nashville. Rieks, R. (1975). 'Eine tragische Erzählung bei Herodot (Hist. I , 34 35)'. Poetica 7: 23-44. Rieman, K.-A. (1967). Das herodoteische Geschichtswerk in der Antike. Diss. Munich. Rijksbaron, A. (1988). 'The Discourse Function of the Imperfect'. In In the Footsteps of Raphael Kühner, ed. A. Rijksbaron, H . A. Mulder, and G. C. Wakker, 237-54. Amsterdam. Risch, E. (1985). 'Homerisch èwénco, Lakonisch êcp£vé7tovn und die alte Erzählprosa', ZPE 60: 1-9. Robertson, N . (1986). 'A Point of Precedence at Plataia: The Dispute between Athens and Sparta over Leading the Procession'. Hesperia 55: 88-102. Robinson, E. W. (1997). 77K First Democracies: Early Popular Government outside Athens. Stuttgart. Rochberg-Halton. F. (1984). 'New Evidence for the History of Astrology'. JJŒS 43: 114-40. -, (1991). 'Between Observation and Theory in Babylonian Astronomical Texts'. JNES 50: 107 20. Roisman, J. (1985). 'Maiandrios of Samos'. Historia 34, 257-77. Rolle, R. (1979). Totenkult der Skythen, Vol. 1. Das Steppengebiet, 1-2. Vorgeschichtliche Forschungen 18. Berlin. . (1980'. Die Welt der Skythen. Lucerne and Prankfurt. -. (1989). 77K World cf the Scythians, tr. R. Rolle. London. Rolle, R., M . Müller-Wille, and K. Schietzel, eds. (1991). Gold der Steppe: Archäologie der Ukraine. Neumünster. Röllig, W. (1969). 'Nitokris von Babylon'. In Beiträge zur alten Geschichte und deren Nachleben: Festschrift F. Altheim, ed. R. Stiehl and H . E. Stier, 127-35. Berlin. Rollinger, R. (1993). Herodots babylonischer Logos. Eine kritische Untersuchung der Glaubwürdighitsdiskussion. Innsbrucker Beiträge zur Kulturwissenschaft, Sonderheft 84. Innsbruck. -, (1998). 'Überlegungen zu Herodot, Xerxes und dessen angeblicher Zerstörung Babylons'. AOF 25: 339-73.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
619
. (1999). 'Xerxes und Babylon'. Notes Assyriobgiques Brefs et Utilitaires, note 8. de Romilly, J. (1962). 'Le Pseudo-Xénophon et Thucydide. Étude sur quelques divergences de vues'. RPh 3d ser. 36: 225—41. (1963). Thucydides and Athenian Imperialism, tr. P. Thody. Oxford. ——. (1971a). L· temps dans la tragédie grecque. Paris. (1971b). 'La vengeance comme explication historique dans l'œuvre d'Hérodote'. REG 84: 314-37. (1977). The Rise and Fall of Greek States According to Greek Authors. Ann Arbor. -. (1984). Réflexions parallèles chez Euripide et Thucydide. Mededelingen der Koninklijke Nederlandse Akademie van Wetenschappen, Afd. Letterkunde, n.s. 3. Amsterdam. -. (1992). The Great Sophists in Periclean Athens, tr. J. Lloyd. Oxford. Romm. J. S. (1992). The Edges of the Earth in Ancient Thought. Princeton. -. (1998). Heroéiius. New Haven and London. Rood, T. C. B. (1998). Thucydides: Narrative and Explanation. Oxford. —. (1999). 'Thucydides' Persian Wars'. In The Limits of Historiography: Genre and Narrative in Ancient Hutorical Texts, ed. C. S. Kraus, 141-69. Leiden. Rose, C. (1879). Liai Eferodot sein Werk seihst herausgegeben? Progr. Gießen. Rosén, H . B. (1993). "loropinç àïiôSeçtç. Ein Problem der herodoüschen.Textkritik'. Glotta 71: 146 53, -, ed. (1997). Herodoti Historiae I I . Stuttgart and Leipzig. Rosenbloom, D. (1995). 'Myth, History, and Hegemony in Aeschylus'. In History. Tragedy, Theory: Dialogues on Athenian Drama, ed. B. Goff, 91 130. Austin. -. [ Forthcoming]. Playing the Tyrant: Athenian Drama and the Logic of Athenian. Imperialism. Rosenmeyer, T. f 1982). 'History or Poetry? The Example of Herodotus'. Clio 11: 239-59. (1996). 'Ironies in Serious Drama'. I n Tragedy and the Tragic: Greek Theatre and Beyond, ed. M . Silk, 497-519. Oxford. Rosier, W. (1991). 'Die 'Selbsthistorisierung' des Autors. Zur Stellung Herodots zwischen Mündlichkeit und Schriftlichkeit'. Philologus 135: 215-20. Rossellini, M . , and S. Said. (1978). 'Usages des femmes et autres nomoi chez les "sauvages" d'Hérodote: essai de lecture structurale'. ASNP 8: 949-1005. Rostovtzeff, M . I . (1922). Iranians and Greeks in South Russia. Oxford. Roth, M . T. (1987). 'Age at Marriage and the Household: A Study of Neo-Assyrian and Neo-Babylonian Forms'. Comparative Studies in Society and History 29: 715 47. -. (1989). Babylonian Marriage Agreements, 7th to 3rd centuries B.C. Alter Orient und Altes Testament 222. Neukirchen-Vluyn. Rudenko, S. I . (1970). Frozen Tombs of Siberia. London. Rudhardt, J. (1992). 'De l'attitude des Grecs à l'égard des religions étrangères'. RHR 209: 219-38. Ruschenbuseh, E. (1992). 'Zur Genese der Uberlieferung über die archaische Zeit Griechenlands und das 5. und 4. Jh. v. Chr'. Historia 41: 385-94. —. (1995). 'Eine schriftliche Quelle im Werk Herodots (FGrHist 3, Pherekydes von Athen)'. In Historische Interpretationen. Festschrift G. Walser, ed. VI. WeinmannWalser, Historia Einzelschriften 100, 131 49. Stuttgart. (1999). 'Neue Beobachtungen zu Pherekydes von Athen'. In Text and. Tradition: Studies in Greek History and Historiography in Honor of M. Chambers, ed. R. Mellor and L. Tritle, 229-38. Claremont, CA. (2000). 'Weitere Untersuchungen zu Pherekydes von Athen'. Klio 82: 335-43. Russo, J. (1997). 'Prose Genres for the Performance of Traditional Wisdom in Ancient Greece: Proverb, Vlaxim, Apothegm'. In Poet, Public, and Performance in Ancient Greece, ed. L. Edmunds and R. W. Wallace, 49-64. Baltimore. Rutherford, I . (1996). 'The New Simonides: Towards a Commentary'. Arelhusa 29: 267-92.
620
BIBLIOGRAPHY
(2001). 'The New Simonides: Towards a Commentary'. In The New Simonides: Contexts of Praise and Desire, ed. D. Boedeker and D. Sider, 33-54. Oxford. Sachs, A . J . (1948). 'A Classification of the Babylonian Astronomical Tablets of the Seleucid Period'. JCS 2: 271-90. —. (1952). 'Babylonian Horoscopes'. JCS 6: 49-75. Sachs, A. J., and H . Hunger. (1988). Astronomical Diaries and Related Texts from Babylonia, vol. I: Diaries from 652 B.C. to 262 B.C. Denkschriften Österreichische Akademie der Wissenschaften, Philosophisch-Historische Klasse 195. Vienna. Said, E. (1994). Representations of the Intellectual. The 1993 Reith Lectures. London. Said, S. (1978). La faute tragique. Paris. -(1981). 'Darius et Xerxès dans les Perses d'Eschyle'. Ktèma 6: 17-38. . (1988). 'Tragédie et renversement: L'exemple des Perses'. Métis 31: 321-41. Sakellariou, M. B., ed. (1996). Colloque international: Démocratie athénienne et culture. Athens. Sancisi-Weerdenburg, H . (1980). Yauna en Persai. Grieken en Per zen in een ander pespectief. Diss. Leiden. - - . (1983). 'Exit Atossa: Images of Women in Greek Historiography on Persia'. In Images of Women in Antiquity, ed. A. Cameron and A. Kuhrt, 20-33. London. . (1988a). "Persikon de karta ho stralos down': A Typically Persian Gift (Hdt. I X 109)'. Hislona 37: 372-4. —. (1988b). 'Was there ever a Median Empire?' In Method and Theory: Proceedings of the London 1985 Achaemenid History Workshop, Achaemenid History 3, ed. A. Kuhrt and H . Sancisi-Weerdenburg, 197-212. Leiden. (1989). 'The Personality of Xerxes, King of Kings'. In Archaeologica Iranien et Orientalia. Miscellanea in honorem, Louis Vanden Berghe, ed. L. de Meyer and E. Haerinck, 549 61. Ghent. (2002). Reprint. This volume, 579-90. —. (1994). 'The Orality of Herodotus' Medikos logos'. In Continuity and Change: Proceedings of the last Achaemenid History Workshop, April 6-8, 1990, Ann Arbor, Michigan, Achaemenid History 8, ed. H . Sancisi-Weerdenburg, A. Kuhrt, and M . Cool Root, 39-55. Leiden. Sanctis. G. de (1926). 'La composizione della storia di Erodoto'. RFIC, N.S. 4, 54: 289-309. Sansone, D. (1985). 'The Date of Herodotus' Publication'. ICS 10: 1-9. Sauge, André. (1992). De l'épopée à l'histoire. Fondement de la notion d'historié. Frankfurt. Sauneron, S. (1957). Ts prêtres de l'ancienne Egypte. Bourges. Saxonhouse, A. W. (1996). 'Herodotus, Democracy, and Equality'. I n Athenian Democracy: Modem Mythmakers and Ancient Theorists, 31-57. Notre Dame. Scanlon, T. F. (1994). 'Echoes of Herodotus in Thucydides: Self-Sufficiency, Admiration, and Law'. Historia 43: 143-76. Schadewaldt, W. (1934). D i e Anfänge der Geschichtsschreibung bei den Griechen'. Die Antike 10: 144-68. (1960). Reprint. In W. Schadewaldt, Hellas und Hespenen, 559-80. Zürich-Stuttgart. Scharfer, H . (1932). Staatsform und Politik: Untersuchungen zur griechischen Geschichte des 6. und 5. Jh. Leipzig. Sehiffrin, D. (1987). Discourse Markers. Cambridge. Schütz, V. (1994). Les Scythes et les nomades des steppes: Ville siècle avant J.-C.—F' siècle après J.-C. Paris. Schmid, H . (1981). 'Ergebnisse einer Grabung am Kernmassiv der Zikkurat in Babylon'. Baghdader Mitteilungen 12: 87-131. - - . (1990). 'Anhang. Rekonstruktionsversuche und Forschungsstand der Zikkurat von Babylon'. In R. Koldewey Das wieder erstehende Babylon, ed. B. Hrouda, 303-42. 5th ed. Munich. -. (1995). Der Tempelturm Etemenanki in Babylon. Mainz.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
621
Schmie!, W., and Ο. Staehlin. (1934), Geschichte der griechischen Literatur. Handbuch der Altertumswissenschaft 7, 1,2. Munich. (1959). Reprint. Schöll, A. (1855). 'Herodots Vorlesungen'. Philologus 10: 410-31. Schott, R. (1968). 'Das Geschichtsbewußtsein schriftloser Völker'. Archiv für Begriffsgeschichte 12: 166-205. Schwab!, H . (1969). 'Herodot als Historiker und Erzähler'. Gymnasium 76: 25372. . (1999). 'Ein Monument Darius 1. aus Babylon'. Zeitschrift für Assyriologie und verwandle Gebiete 89: 101-14. Schwartz, J. (1948). 'Les conquérants perses et la littérature égyptienne'. Bulletin de l'Institut français du Caire 48: 6 5 8 0 . Seaford, R. (2002). 'Tragic Tyranny'. In Popular Tyranny: Sovereignty and Its Discontents in Classical Athens, ed. K. Morgan, Austin. Sealey, R. (1957). 'Thucydides, Herodotus, and the Causes of War'. Cff 7: 1 12. Sebeok, T., and E. Brady. (1979). 'The Two Sons of Croesus. A Myth about Communication in Herodotus'. QJJCC 30: 7-22. Seidl, U . (1976). Tan Relief Dareios' I . in Babylon'. Archäologische Mitteilungen aus Iran 9: 125-30. — (1999). 'Ein Monument Darius I . aus Babylon'. Zeitschrift für Assyriologie und verwandte Gebiete 89: 101-14. de Sélincourt, Α. (1996). Herodotus: The Histories'. Rev. J. Marincola. London. Shafer, Β. E., ed. (1991). Religion in Ancient Egypt: Gods, Myths, and Personal Practice. London. Shapiro, S. O. (1996). 'Herodotus and Solon'. ClAnt 15: 348 64. - -. [Forthcoming], A Word to the Wise: The Role of Advice in Herodotus' Histories. Shaw, B. (1982/83). 'Eaters of Flesh, Drinkers of Milk: The Ancient Mediterranean Ideology of the Pastoral Nomad'. AncSoc 13/14: 5-31. Shaw, V. (1983). The Short Story: A Critical Introduction. New York. Shimron, B. (1973). 'πρώτος των ημείς ϊδμεν'. Eranos 71: 45-51. -. (1989). Politics and Belief in Herodotus. Historia Einzelschriften 58. Stuttgart. Shipley, G. (1987). A History of Samos, 800-188 BC. Oxford. Shramko, B. A. (1987). Bel'skoe Gorodishche skfskoi epoklu (Gorod Gehn). Kiev. Shrimpton, G. (1997). History and Memory in Ancient Greece. Montreal and London. Sicking, C. M . J., and P. Stork. (1997). 'The Grammar of the So-Called Historical Present in Ancient Greek'. In Grammar as Interpretation: Greek Literature in its Linguistic Contexts, ed. E.J. Bakker, 131 68. Leiden. Sinor, D., ed. (1990). The Cambridge History of Early Inner Asia. Cambridge. Slings, S. R. (1992). 'Written and Spoken Language: An Exercise in the Pragmatics of the Greek Sentence'. CPh 87: 95-109. . (1994). 'Een tandje lager: Aanzetten voor een orale grammatica van Homerus'. Pampas 27: 411-27. (1997a). 'Figures of Speech and their Lookalikes: Two Further Exercises in the Pragmatics of the Greek Sentence'. In Grammar as Interpretation: Greek Literature in its Linguistic Contexts, ed. Κ J. Bakker, 169-214. Leiden. — -. (1997b). 'Adversative Relators between PUSH and POP'. In New Approaches to Greek Particles, ed. A. Rijksbaron, 101-29. Amsterdam. (1999). 'Information Unit and Metrical Unit'. In One Hundred Tears of'Bacchylides: Proceedings of a Colloquium Held at the Vrije Universität Amsterdam, ed. I . L. Pfeijffer and S. R. Slings, 61 75. Amsterdam. -. (2000). Symposium: Speech and ideology. Two Llerrneneulical Issues in Early Greek Lyric, with Special Reference to Mimnermus. Mededelingen K N A W afd. Letterkunde, 63.1. Amsterdam. Small, J. P. (1997). Wax Tablets of the Mind: Cognitive Studies of Memory and Literacy in Classical Antiquity. London and New York.
622
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Smart, J. D. (1977). 'Review Article: The Athenian Empire'. Phoenix 31: 245-57. Snell, B. (1924). Die Ausdrücke für den Begriff des Wissens in der vorplatonischen Philosophie. Philologische Untersuchungen 29. Berlin. . (1944). 'Die Nachrichten über die Lehre des Thaies und die Anfänge der griechischen Philosophie- und Literaturgeschichte'. Philologus 96: 170-82. (1966). Rev. ed. In B. Snell, Gesammelte Schriften, 119-28. Göttingen. (1973). 'Gyges und Kroisos als Tragödien-Figuren'. 2PE 12: 197-205. Snodgrass, A. M . (1971). Tlie Dark Age if Greece: An Archaeological Survey of the Eleventh, to the Eighth Centuries BC. Edinburgh. Snowden, F. (1970). Bloch in Antiquity. Ethiopians in the Greco-Roman Experience. Cambridge, M A . Solmsen, F. (1959). Review of H. Dörrie, Leid und Erfahrung. Gnomon .3: 471 5. (1974). 'Two Crucial Decisions in Herodotus'.' MAWBL 37: 1-33. Sourvinou-lnwood, C. (1988). ' " M v t h " and History: On Herodotus III.48 and 50 53'. OAth 17: 167-82. (1991). 'Reading' Greek Culture: Texts and Images, Rituals and Myth: Oxford. Souza, P. de (1998). 'Towards Thalassocracy? Archaic Greek Naval Developments'. In Archaic Greece, ed. N . Fisher and H . van Wees, 271-94. London. Spek, R. J. van der (1983). 'Cyrus de Pers in Assyrisch perspectief. Tijdschrift voor Geschiedenis 96: 1-27. Spencer, A . J . (1993). Early Egypt: The Rise of Civilisation in. the Nik Valley. London. Spiegel, G. (1992). 'History and Post-Modernism I V . Past and Present 135: 194-208. Städter, P. (1992). 'Herodotus and the Athenian Arche'. ASNP ser. 3, 22: 781-809. —. (1997). 'Herodotus and the North Carolina Oral Narrative Tradition'. Histos 1: 1 23. Stahl, H . P. (1968). 'Herodots Gyges-Tragödie'. Hermes 96: 385-400. (1975). 'Learning through Suffering? Croesus' Conversations in the Histoiy of Herodotus'. YCIS 24: 1-36. Stahl, M . (1983). 'Tyrarmis und das Problem der Macht. Die Geschichten Herodots über Kypselos und Periander von Korinth'. Hermes 111: 202-20. . (1987). Aristokraten und Tyrannen im archaischen Athen. Stuttgart. Stambler, S. (1982). 'Herodotus'. In Ancient Writers. Greece and Rome, ed. T . J . Luce, 209-32. New York. Starr, C. G. (1965). 'On the Credibility of Early Spartan Histoiy'. Huloria 14: 257-72. . (1978). 'Thucydides on Sea Power'. Mnemosyne 31: 343 50. de Ste Croix, G. E. M . (1973). Review of Fornara, Herodotus: An Interpretative Eissay. Eng. Hut. Rev. 88: 157-8. . (1977). 'Herodotus'. G&R 24: 130-48. - -. (1992). 'Aristotle on History and Poetry'. In Essays on Aristotle's Poetics, ed. A. O. Rorty, 23-32. Princeton. Stein, H . (1883). Herodotos, 1. Band. Berlin. Sterling, N . P. (1998). Laconic Persuasion: Rhetorical Arrangement of Events in Xenophon's Hellenika. Diss. Brown University. Stern, J. (1991). 'Scapegoat Narratives in Herodotus'. Hermes 119: 304-11. Stolper, M . W. (1977). 'Three Iranian Loan-Words in Late Babylonian Texts'. In Mountains and hndands: Essays in the Archaeology of Greater Mesopotamia, ed. T. C. Young and L, D. Levine, Bibliotheca Mesopotamia 7, 250-3. Malibu, CA. —. (1985). Entrepreneurs and Empire: The MurasU Archive, the Murasü Firm and Persian Rule in Babylonia. Leiden. . Ü987). 'Bclsunu the Satrap'. In Language. Lilcialure. ami llhlmy: Philological ami Historical Studies Presented to Erica Reiner, American Oriental Series 67 ed. F. RochbergHalton, 389-402. New Haven. . (1988). 'Some Ghost Facts from Achaemenid Babylonian Texts'. JHS 108: 196 8.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
623
—. (1989). 'The Governor of Babylon and "Across-the- River" in 486 B . C . JJYES 48: 283-305. —. (1990). 'The Kasr Archive'. In Centre and Periphery: Proceedings of the Groningen 1986 Achaemenid History Workshop, Achaemenid History 4, ed. H . Sancisi-Weerdcnburg and A. Kuhrt, 195-205. Leiden. —. (1994). 'Mesopotamia, 482 330'. In The Cambridge Ancient History, vol. 6, ed. D. M . Lewis, J. Boardman, S. Hornblower, and M . Ostwald, 234-60. 2d ed. Cambridge. —. (1995). 'The Babylonian Enterprise of Belsunu'. In Dans les pas des Dix-Mille: peuples et pays du Proche-Orient mis par un Grec, Pallas. Revue cl' etudes antiques, 43, ed. P. Briant, 217-38. Toulouse. Stone, E. (1997). 'Ziggurat'. Tfie Oxford Encyclopedia of Archaeology in the Ancient Near East, 390-1. Oxford. Strasburger, H . (1954a). 'Der Einzelne und die Gemeinschaft im Denken der Griechen'. HZ 177: 227-48. (1982). Reprint. In H . Strasburger, Studien, zur allen Geschichte, 1, ed. W. Schmitthenner and R. Zoepffel, 423-48. Hildesheim. -. (1954b). 'Die Entdeckung der politischen Geschichte durch Thukydides'. Saeculum 5: 395-428. (1968). Reprint. I n Thukydides, ed. H . Herter, 412-76. Darmstadt. (1982). Reprint. H . Strasburger, Studien zur alten Geschichte, 2, ed. W. Schmitthenner and R. Zoepffel, 527-91. Hildesheim. — . (1955). 'Herodot und das perikleische Athen'. Hisloria 4: 1-25. (1962). Reprint. In Herodot. Eine Auswahl aus der neueren Forschung. Wege der Forschung 26, cd. W. Marg. Munich. (1965). 2d ed. Munich. (1982). 3d ed. Darmstadt. (1982). Reprint. In H . Strasburger, Studien zur alten Geschichte, 2. ed. W. Schmitthenner and R. Zoepffel, 592-626. Hildesheim. . (1956). 'Herodots Zeitrechung'. Hislona 5: 129-61. (1962). Reprint (with corrections). In Herodot. Eine Auswahl aus der neueren Forschung. Wege der Forschung 26, ed. W. Marg. Munich. (1965). 2d ed. Munich. (1982). 3d ed. Darmstadt. (1982). Reprint. In H. Strasburger, Studien zur allen Geschichte, 2, ed. W. Schmitthenner and R. Zoepffel, 627-75. Hildesheim. -. (1958). 'Thukydides und die politische Selbstdarstellung der Athener'. Hermes 86: 17-40, (1968). Reprint. In Thukydides, Wege der Forschung 98, ed. H . Herter, 498-530. Darmstadt. (1982). Reprint. In H . Strasburger, Studien zur alten Geschichte, vol. 2, ed. W. Schmitthenner and R. Zoepffel, 676 708. Hildesheim. -. (1965). 'Herodot und das perikleische Athen'. (1962). Reprint. In Herodot. Eine Auswahl aus der neueren Forschung. Wege der Forschung 26, ed. W. Marg. Munich. (1965). 2d ed. Munich. (1982). 3d ed. Darmstadt. -. (1972). Flomer und die Geschichtsschreibung. Sitzungsberichte der Heidelberger Akademie der Wissenschaften. Philosophisch-historische Klasse. Heidelberg. (1982a). 'Herodot als Geschichtsforscher'. In Studien zur allen Geschichte, vol. 2, ed. W. Schmitthenner and R. Zoepffel, 837-919. Hildesheim. -. (1982b). Studien zur alten Geschichte, ed. W. Schmitthenner and R. Zoepffel, 2 vols. Hildesheim. Strassler, R. B., ed. (1996). 77K Landmark Tliucydides: A Comprehensive, Guide to the Peloponnesian War. New York. Strauss, B. (1997). 'The Problem of Periodization: The Case of the Peloponnesian War'. In Inventing Ancient Culture, ed. P. Toohey and M . Golden, 165-75. London. Stroheker, K. F. (1953/54). 'Zu den Anfangen der monarchischen Theorie in der Sophistik'. Historia 2: 381-412. Sulimirski, T., and T. Taylor. (1991). 'The Scythians'. In 77K Cambridge Ancient History, vol. 3.2, ed. I . E. S. Edwards et al. 547 90, 2d ed., Cambridge. Svenbro, J. (1993). Phrasikleia: An Anthropology of Reading in Ancient Greece, tr. J. Lloyd. Ithaca and London. Syme, R. (1962). 'Thucydides'. PDA 1962: 39-56.
624
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Taussig, M . (1993). Mimesis and Alterily: A Particular History of trie Senses. London. Taylor, T. (1994). 'Thracians, Scythians and Dacians 800 B.C. A.D. 300'. In Oxford Illustrated Prehistory of Europe, ed. B. Cunliffe, 372-410. Oxford. — . (1996). The Prehistory of Sex. London. Thomas, R. (1989). Oral Tradition and Written Record in Classical Athens. Cambridge. -. (1992). Literacy and Oralily in Ancient Greece. Cambridge. (1993). 'Performance and Written Publication in Herodotus and the Sophistic Generation'. In Vermittlung und Tradierung von Wissen in der griechischen Kultur, ScriptOralia 61, ed. W. Kulimann and J. Althoff, 225-44. Tübingen. (1996). 'Review Article I : Herodotus'. JHS 116: 175-8. (1997). 'Ethnography, Proof and Argument in Herodotus' Histories'. PCPhS 43: 128 48. . (2000). Herodotus in Context: Ethnography, Science and the Art of Persuasion. Cambridge. (2001). 'Herodotus' Histories and the Floating Gap'. In The Historian's Craft, ed. N . Luraghi, 198 210, Oxford. Thompson, N . (1996). Herodotus and the Origins of the Political Community: Arion's Tap. New Haven. Thomsen, R. (1972). The Origin of Ostracism: A Synthesis. Copenhagen. Thomson, J. A. K. (1935). Tie Art of the Logos. London. Tourraix, A. (1976). 'La femme et le pouvoir chez Hérodote. Essai d'histoire des mentalités antiques'. DHA 2: 369 86. Tozzi, P. (1978). La Rivolta ioniea. Pisa. T renkner, S. (1958). The Greek Novella in the Classical Period. Cambridge. Trüdinger, K. (1918). Studien zur Geschichte der griechisch-römischen Ethnographie. Diss. Basel. Tsetskhladze, G. R. (1998). The Greek Colonisation of the Black Sea Area: Historical Interpretation if Archaeology, Historia Einzelschriften 121. Stuttgart. Tuplin, C. (1993). Trie Failings of Empire. Historia Einzelschriften 76. Stuttgart. Turner, E. G. (1952). Athenian Books in the Fifth and Fourth Centuries B.C. London. Unger, E. (1928). 'Babylon'. RIA 1: 330-69. - (1931). Babylon die heilige Stadt nach der Beschreibung der Babylonier. Berlin. (1970). Reprint. Ungern-Sternberg, J. von. (1986). 'Das Grab des Theseus und andere Gräber'. In Antike in der Moderne, ed. W. Schuller, 321-9. Konstanz. Usener, S. (1994). Isokrates, Piaton und ihr Publikum. Tübingen. Vainshtein, S. (1980). Nomads of South Siberia: The Pastoral Economies of Tuva, tr. M . Colenso. Cambridge. Vallat, F. (1989). 'Le palais d'Artaxerxès I I à Babylone'. Northern Akkad Project Reports 2: 3 6. ~ Vandiver, E. (1991). Heroes in Herodotus: The Interaction of Myth and History. Frankfurt am Main. Vannicelli, P. (1993). Erodoto e h storia dell'alto e medio archaismo (Sparta-Tessaglia-Cirene). Incunabula Graeca 45. Rome. (2001). 'Herodotus' Egypt and the Origins of Universal History'. In The Historian's Craft, ed. N . Luraghi, 211 40, Oxford. Vansina, J. (1985). Oral Tradition as History. London. van der Veen, J. E. (1996). The Significant and the Insignificant: Fine Studies in Herodotus' View of History. Amsterdam. Veenhof, K. (1995). 'Kanesh: An Assyrian Colony in Anatolia'. In Civilizations of the Ancient Near East, ed. J. Sasson et al., 859-72. New York. Verdin, H . (1971). De historisch-kritische méthode van Herodotus. Brussels. -. (1975). 'Hérodote historien? Quelques interpretations récentes'. AC 44: 668-85. —. (1977). 'Les remarques critiques d'Hérodote et Thucydide sur la poésie entant que source historique'. Historiographid anliqua: commenlationes Lovanienses in honorem
r
BIBLIOGRAPHY
625
W. Fermons septuagenarii editae, Symbolae Facultatif Litterarum et Philosophiae Lovaniensis. Ser. A, 6, 53-76. Leuven. — . (1982). 'Hérodote et la politique expansionniste des Achéménides: Notes sur Hdt.VII.8'. In Studio. Paulo Master Oblata II, Orientalin Lovaniensia analecta 12 13, 327-36. Leuven. Ventant, J.-P. (1982). 'From Oedipus to Periander: Lameness, Tyranny, Incest in Legend and History'. Arethusa 15: 19 38. Versnel, H . (1987). 'What D i d Ancient Man See When He Saw a God? Some Reflections on Greco-Roman Epiphanies'. In Effigies Dei: Essays on the History of Religions, ed. I ) . van der Pias, 4 2 5 5 . Leiden. -. (1990). 'What's Sauce for the Goose Is Sauce for the Gander'. In Approaches to Greek Myth, ed. L. Edmunds, 23-90. Baltimore. Veyne, P. (1971). Comment on écrit l'histoire; essai d'epistemologie. Paris, FLditions du Seuil. —. (1984). Writing History: Essay in Epistemology. tr. M . Moore-Rinvolucri. Middlelown, CT. -. (1988). Did The Cheeks Believe in Then Myths? An Essay on the Ilon.\/itulive Imagination, tr. P. Wissing. Baltimore. Vidal-Naquet, P. (1960). 'Temps des dieux et temps des homines. Essai sur quelques aspects de l'expérience temporelle chez les Grecs'. RHR 157: 55-80. Vinogradov, J. G. (1994). 'Greek Epigraphy of the North Black Sea Coast, the Caucasus and Central Asia (1985-1990)'. Ancient Civilizations from Scythia to Siberia 1: 63-74. . (1997). Politische Studien. Mainz. Vinogradov, J. G., and S. D . Kryzickij. (1995). Olbia: Eine altgriechische Stadt im nordwestlichen Schwarzmeerraum. Leiden. Visser, M . (1982). 'Worship your Enemy: Aspects of the Cult of Heroes in Ancient Greece'. HTIiR 75: 403-28. ' Vos, M . F. (1963). Scythian Archers in. Archaic Vase-Painting. Groningen. Wace, Α., and F. Stubbing*. (1962). A Companion to Homer. London. Wackernagel, J. (1892). 'Über ein Gesetz der indogermanischen Wortstellung', IF 1, 333 436. (1953). Reprint. I n j . Wackernagel, Kleine Schriften 1, 1 104. Göttingen. Walbank, F. (1938). 'ΦΙΛΙΠΠΟΣ f ΡΑΓΩΙΔΟΥΜΕΝΟΣ: A Polybian Experiment'. JHS 58: 55 68. (1985;. Reprint. In F. Walbank, Selected Papers: Studies in Greek and Roman History and Historiography, 210-23. Cambridge. . (1955). 'Tragic History: A Reconsideration'. BIGS 2: 4 14. —. (1960). 'History and Tragedy'. Historia 9: 216-34. (1985). Reprint. I n F. Walbank, Selected Papers: Studies in Greek and Roman History and Historiography, 224-41. Cambridge. Walker, C. (1997). 'Achaemenid Chronology and the Babylonian Sources'. In Mesopotamia and Iran in the Persian Period: Conquest and Imperialism, 539-331 B.C., ed. J. Curtis, 17-25. London. Wallace, R. W. (1998). 'The Sophists in Athens'. In Democracy, Empire, and the Arts in Fifth-Century Athens, Center for Hellenic Studies Colloquiaz, ed. D. Boedeker and'K. Raaflaub, 203-22. Cambridge, M A . Wallinga, H. T. (1991). 'Polycrates and Egypt: the Testimonia of the Samaina'. In Asia Minor and Egypt: Old Cultures in a Mew Empire: Proceedings of the Groningen 1988 Achaemenid History Workshop, Achaemenid History 6, ed. H . Sancisi-Wecrdenburg and A. Kuhrt, 179 97. Leiden. Walter, U. (1993). 'Herodot und die Ursachen des ionischen Aufstandes'. Historia 42: 257-78. Waterfield, R. (1998). Herodotus, The Histories, with an Introduction and Motes by Carolyn Dewald. Oxford. Waters, K. H . (1966). 'The Purposes of Dramatisation in Herodotus'. Historia 15: 157 71.
626 -. 15. -. -.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
(1971). Herodotus on Tyrants and Despots: A Study of Objectivity. Historia Einzelschriften Wiesbaden. (1972). Herodotus and Polities'. G&R n.s. 19: 1:16 50. ( 1974 . The Structure o f Ihmdotos' Narrative". Anlichthon 8: 1 III (1985). Herodotus the Historian: His Problems, Methods and Originality. London and Sydney. Weber, H . (1976). Herodots Verständnis von Historie: Untersuchungen zur Methodologie und Argumentationsweise Herodots. Frankfurt. Wecowski, M . (2000). L'auxêsis dÄthenes: Hérodote, Thucydide et un aspect de l'idéologie athénienne du V siècle av. J.-C. Diss. EHESS, Paris. Wees, H . van (2000). 'Megara's Mafiosi: Timocracy and Violence in Theognis'. In Alternatives to Athens: Varieties of Political Organization and Community in Ancient Greece, ed. R. Brock and S. Hodkinson, 52-67. Oxford. Weidner, E. F. (1939). 'Jojachin, König von Juda, in babylonischen Keilschrifttexten'. In Méhnges syriens offerts à M. René Dussaud, vol. 2, 923-35. Paris. Wells, J. (1923). Studies in Herodotus. Oxford. West, M . L. (1966). Hesiod, Theogony. Oxford. - -. (1990). Studies in Aeschylus. Stuttgart. -. (1992). Iambi et Elegi Graeci ante Alexandrum Cantati, vol. 2. 2d ed. Oxford. -. (1993). 'Simonides Redfvivus'. 98: 1-14. West, S. R. (1985). 'Herodotus' Epigraphical Interests'. CQ, 35: 278-305. (1987). 'And it Came to Pass that Pharaoh Dreamed: Notes on Herodotus 2.139, 141'. CQ. 37: 262-71. , (1988). 'The Scythian Ultimatum (Herodotus iv 131,132)'. JMS 108: 207-11. -, (1991). 'Herodotus' Portrait of Hecataeus'. JHS 111: 144-60. -. :1999a . Introducing the Sc\ilu,ins: Herodotus on Koumiss (4.2)'. Mil 56: 76 86. . (1999b-. 'Hippocrates' Scythian Sketches'. Eirent 35: I I 32. •. (1999cj. '.Sophocles' Antigoru and Herodotus Book 111'. In Sophocles lievisited: Essays Presented to Sir Hugh Lloyd Jones, 109 36. Oxford. . (2000). 'Herodotus in the North? Reflections on a Colossal Cauldron (4.81)'. SCI 19: 15-34. —. [Forthcoming]. 'Herodotus on Aristeas'. Colloquia Pontica 8. West, W. C. (1970). 'Saviors of Greece'. GRBS 11: 271-82. White, H . (1978). 'The Historical Text as Literary Artifact'. In The Writing of History, ed. R. H . Canary and H . Kozicki, 41 62. Madison. White, H . (1978). Tropics of Discourse: Essays in Cultural Criticism. Baltimore. (1987). The Content of the Form: Narrative Discourse and Historical Representation. Baltimore. White, M . E. (1969). 'Herodotus' Starting Point'. Phoenix 23: 39-48. Wiedemann, T. E. J. (1983). 'Elachislon. . . en tois arsesi kleos: Thucydides, Women, and the Limits of Rational Analysis'. G&R 30: 163-70. Wiesehöfer, J. (1987). 'Kyros und die unterworfenen Völker. Ein Beitrag zur Entstehung von Geschichtsbewußtsein'. QS 26: 107-26. (1999). 'Kontinuität oder Zäsur? Babylonien unter den Achämeniden'. In Babylon: Focus mesopotamischer Geschichte, Wiege früher Gelehrsamkeit, Mythos in der Moderne, ed. J. Renger, 167-88. Saarbrücken. Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, U . von (1905). 'Die griechische Literatur und Sprache'. In U . von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff et af, Die griechische und lateinische Literatur und Sprache, 1-236. Berlin: Teubner. Willemsen, F. (1991). 'Ostraka einer Meisterschale'. MDAEN) 106: 137-45. Willemsen, F., and S. Brenne. (1991). 'Verzeichnis der Kerameikos-Ostraka'. MDAI(A) 106: 147-56. Winkler, J. J. (1990). 77z« Constraints of Desire: The Anthropology of Sex and Gender in Ancient Greece. NY and London.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
627
Wiseman, T. P. (1979). Clio's Cosmetics. Leicester. Wohl, V. (1999). 'The Eros of Alcibiades*. Clint 18: 349 85. Wolff, E. (1964). 'Das Weib des Masistes'. Hermes 92: .51 81. (1962). Reprint. In Herodot. Eine Auswahl aus der neueren Forschung. Wege der Forschung 26, ed. W. Marg. Munich. (1965). 2d ed. Munich. (1982). 3d ed. Darmstadt. Wood, FL (1972). The Histories of Herodotus: An Analysis of the Formal Structure. The Hague. Wunsch, C. (2000). Das Egibi-Archiv I. Die Felder und Gärten. 2 vols. Cuneiform Monographs 20 A & B. Groningen. Young. D. C. (1984). The Olympic Myth of Greek Amateur Athletics. Chicago. Young) T. C. (1980). '480/479 B.C. À Persian Perspective'. IA 15: 213 39. . (1988). 'The Consolidation of the Empire and its Limits of Growth under Darius and Xerxes'. In The Cambridge Ancient History, vol. 4, cd. J. Boardman, N . G. L. Hammond, D. M . Lewis, and M . Ostwald, 53-111. 2d ed. Cambridge. Zellner, H. M . (1997). 'Antigone and the Wife of Intaphrenes'. CW 90: 315-18. Zgusta, L. (1955). Die Personennamen griechischer Städte der nördlichen Schwarzmeerküste. Prague. Zhmud, L. (1997). Wissenschaft, Philosophie und Religion im frühen Pylhagoreismas. Berlin. Zografou, G. (1995). 'L'argumentation d'Hérodote concernant les emprunts laits par les Grecs à la religion égyptienne'. Kemos 8: 187 203.
GENERAL INDEX
Abydos 564, 587 Achaemenid empire: see Persia Adda-guppi 486 Adyrmachidae 461 Aegina 340, 497, 503, 517, 527-8, 547 Aeschylus 173, 194, 510, 571 2 Aethiopia 403-5 aetiological mydis 560 Agariste 504 Agathyrsi 461 agriculture 462, 472
aidas 208 aide 4, 7, 13. 17 19, 85 6 Ajax 188 Alcaeus 510, 513 Alcm(a)eonids 40-2, 211, 504, 534-6, 543, 547, 573-4 Alcuadac 559 Alexander 1 382 3 Alexandropol 452 alterity: see 'Other' Aly, W. 247 Alyattes 502, 511 Amasis 332. 423-4, 426, 434, 503. 517 Amazons 453 Amel-Marduk 486 Amestris 580, 585 Ammon 358 Amompharetus 562, 565 Anacharsis 279, 376, 444, 455 analogy 156, 280 anaphora 60, 66 Anaxandridas 515 Anaximander 156 68, 419 andreia 368; see also bravery Androphagi 367, 462, 465 Annequin, J. 234 Anthylla 328 Antidorus of Lesbos 562 ants, gold-digging 465, 470, 472, 474 Apadana 580 Aphrodite 442, 449 50 apodexis 4, 8-12, 20-26, 28-32, 269 Apollo 187-8, 191, 195, 450; see also Delphi
Apries 332, 423-4, 426, 525 Arabia, Arabians 461, 464-5, 468-9, 474 Arcadia, Arcadians 326, 338, 381 Arcesilaus of Cyrene 507-8, 516-17 Archias of Pitana 374, 376 7, 500, 527 Archilochus 510 archives, royal Babylonian 483; royal Persian 576; temple 483-4 Ardericca 479 Ares 197, 450 arete 203-4 Argippaei 462-5, 473 Argonauts 497 Argos 338, 341-2, 345, 502, 505. 546-7 Arimaspians 445, 465, 472-3 Arion 512 Aristagoras 157, 385, 508, 529 34. 557-8 Arisleas 361, 444 5, 466, 472 3 Aristcides 519, 574 Aristodemus 562 Aristodicus of Cyme 381 Aristogeiton 326, 535 Aristophanes 510, 514 Aristotle 443, 469, 474, 514 15
arkhe 328 n. 14, 341; see also imperialism Armenia 477 Arrian 474 Artabanus 175, 182, 559. 569-70, 584, 587 Artaphernes 539, 557-8 Artaxerxes 1 341, 490, 495 Artaxerxcs I I 493, 495 Artayctes 347 8, 553, 559, 567 Artaynte 580, 585-7 Artemis 188, 189, 197 Artemisia 240-1, 267, 568 70, 584 Artemisium 190 2, 359 60, 561, 565 Artoxerxes: see Artaxerxes I Arzhan 451 Ascalon 331 Ashdod 323 Asia 415, 553 7, 561
630
GENERAL
Assyria 327. 330 2, 335-6, 475, 485-96, 511 Astyages 128 9 Asychis 422-3 Atarantes 468 atasthalia 188. 193-94 Athena 188, 189 Athens, Athenian(s) 381, 385, 500, 502-3. 513, 517-19, 533-45: empire 166, 169-70, 174, 178; ideology 152 3, 561, 572; imperialism 549, 553, 567; power of 337-8, 340; role of, in Persian wars 42 3, 341 2, 347 8, 382-3, 568, 574-5 Atlanles 464, 470 Atossa 579-80, 586 atrekeos 360-2 Atthidographers 514 Augila 466 austerity: see luxury authority 279, 351-2, 356 autochthony 326 Autonoos 188, 189 autopsy 13 15, 278, 355-6, 419, 424, 442-4 Babylonia, Babylonian(s) 197, 325, 330 1, 333, 475-96, 511; astronomical texts 484; chronicles 482, 485; customs 494-5; government 495; palaces 483, 491-2, 496; population 494 5; revolt 579; royal titles 489-90. 579, 581; texts 484, 488-9 Bacchiads 518, 544 Bacis 358 Badian. E. 380, 382. 392 Bakhtin 276 Bakker, E. J. 55 barbarians 105, 364 7; see also 'Other' Barca 345 Bardiya 488 barrows: see burial mounds battle narratives 564-5 Battles: of Champions 502, 515; of Hysiae 508; of Sybota 558; of the Fetters 515 Battus, Battiads 383, 506-7 Bauman, R. 277-8 beauty 563, 566 bees '471 Behistun 488, 493 Bel 475. 478, 489, 491
INDEX
Bel'sk 454 Berezan 454 bias 522; see also Herodotus, bias in Bias of Priene 513, 556 Blok, A. 453 Boeotia 511, 548 Boer, W. den 388, 392 Bornitz, H.-F. 251 Borst, A. 412 Borysthenes, Borysdienites 443, 465 Bosporus 511 boundaries 172 3, 330, 465, 554, 556 bravery 323, 368, 561-2, 564, 566 bribery 569 Brillante, C. 114 Budini 465 burial mounds 451-4 Burkert, W. 391, 410 Byzantium 443 Calame, C. 113 calendar 387, 401; see also chronology Callatians 366, 461 Calliades, archonship of 334, 501 Callicrates 562 Callippidae 440, 446 Cambyses 130-1, 193, 333 5, 437. 466 7, 487 8, 503, 524 Candaules 55-8, 192, 368 cannibalism 461-4 Carbonell, C.-O. 252 3 Caria, Carians 325, 499 Cassiteridcs 471 catalogue of ships 103 cavalry 565, 577 Chalcis 509. 511 Chaldaeans 475, 478-80, 489 Chantraine, P. 362 characterisation 423-4, 579-90 Cheops 424, 429, 511 Chephren 424 Chertomlyk 452 .3 Chiton 515 Chios 502, 531 chronology 329-34, 387-8, 390-2, 407, 421 2, 439, 497, 499 504; see
also spalium historicum, synchronism 'chunking', in sentence structure 54-5,'.59-64, 67. 70; literary use of 62 3, 77 Cimmerians 323, 331, 440 Cimon 211 cinnamon 465, 469
GENERAL
Cleisthenes of Athens 337-8, 504, 518, 538 41 Cleisthenes of Sicyon 503 4, 517, 538, 542 Cleomenes 193, 348, 357, 385, 500, 515, 532-3, 538 9, 545 8 climate 443, 445, 464 Coates, G. 427 Cobet, J. 110, 251-2 Cole, T. 9 colonization 378, 383 Connor, W. R. 14, 179 80 Constitutional Debate 528, 534, 542 5; see also government, forms of contact 555 6, 558 Corcyra 502 3 Corinth 339, 385, 502-3, 512, 516, 542, 544-5 counsel, lack of: see 'wise adviser' craftsmen 385 Crete 499, 506-7 Croesus 35 6, 132-7, 162, 167-74, 188, 193, 196, 218 20, 287, 330, 335-6, 344, 346-7, 351-2, 357, 369, 395, 406, 409, 502-3, 511, 554 crucifixion 348 Ctesias 460, 465, 469, 472, 571 cults 560 cultures, 'soft' and 'hard' 480. 482, 532 3 custom: see nomos Cybebe 346 Cyclopes 461, 464 Cylon 504, 513 Cyprus 3 3 2 3 , 344, 477, 481 Cypselids 542 Cypselus 127, 501, 516, 544 Cyrene 334, 383-4, 505 8, 516- 17, 519 Cyrus 129, 162, 188, 274, 332 3, 3.36, 339, 477-8, 487. 554; birth of 110 11 Cythera 568 Daiva inscription 581, 588-9 Darbo-Peschanski, C. 280-1, 287 Darius 187, 323, 333, 335, 341, 344-5, 366, 437, 439, 441, 448, 456, 477, 488, 503, 556 8. 579, 589 Darius Codomannus 469 Darius I I Ochus 495 Dark Age 411
INDEX
631
date palm 477, 480, 493 Davies. }. K. 384 De Jong, I . J. F. 253 eleixis 29 32, 269 Delos 510 Delphi, Delphic oracle 187, 189-90, 199-200. 279. 282, 357, 369. 378-9, 381, 384, 499, 502, 506, 511-12, 527-8, 536, 546-7, 571, 574 Demaralus 111, 126, 161, 182, 192. 348, 357, 545 6, 566, 568, 575, 584 Demeter 188, 189, 195 Democedes 345, 556 7 democracy 325, 327, 374 5, 385, 514, 529-30, 534-45, 549, 577; see also freedom Demonax of Mantineia 516 descriptions 254, 262-3 deserts 465 destiny: see fate Deutsche Orient Gesellschaft 491 deviant localization 284 Dewald, C. 173, 234-6, 271 2, 277, 362 dialogic 18, 276 Dieneccs 562—3 digressions: see Hbtories. digressions in Dik, H . 56 Dionysius of Phocaea 531 Dionysus 197 discourse analysis 53-77 discourse topic 56-8, 68-70, 72, 74 6; see also topic divine envy/jealousy 215, 532-3, 559-61; see also gods, religion Dodecarchs 421,423 4 Dodona 196, 374 Dorians 326 7, 497, 503 Dougherty, C. 114 Dracon 513 dreams 103, 110, 175, 194-6, 559 dual determination 561; see also gods, religion dynastic sequence 400 2, 406; see also chronology; genealogy F.gibi family 484, 494 Egypt, Egyptians 14 16, 19, 20, 155. 157, 159-60, 196 8, 267. 274, 278-9, 282, 325 9, 331-2, 354-5, 365, 387, 396, 401-3, 407, 410, 415 35, 437, 442, 444 5, 448. 497, 499-501; building works 422-3; daily life 433-4; economy 429-30;
632
GENERAL
history 334, 420-7; kingship 420 7; physical traits 420; religion 430-2; society 420, 427 8 elenkhos 352 eleutheria: see freedom, democracy Eleutheria (festival) 190 embassies 481 empires, rise and fall of 328-36; see also imperialism, fortune Enarees 442, 449 Eneti 472 Ephialtes 561 Ephorus 474, 508 epic poetry, influence of 27-8, 97-109, 322, 352; see also Homer epic rhythm 103 Epidaurus 497 epideixis, epideictic 9-10, 21-2, 107 Erbse, H . 105 Eretria 509-10 erga {megala) 4, 24-8, 31, 99, 282 3, 503; see also thomata Eridanus 471 es erne 322 eskhatiai 457 Esther 585 Etemenanki 491 Ethiopia, Ethiopians 197, 281, 461, 464, 466-7, 462 3, 554, 556 ethnicity, see Greek identitv ethnography 13-15, 17, 332. 378, 415-19, 434-5, 457 74 Euboea 344 Eupalinus' tunnel 503 Euphemus 383—4 Euphrates 475, 477, 480, 485, 491 Euripides 150, 154, 161 Europa 497 Europe 415, 470 2, 553, 561 Eusebius 391, 393, 411 Evans, J. A. S. 163 Exampaeus 442 excursuses: see Histories, digressions in expeditions 465-6 expert's persona 268, 286, 288: see also Herodotus as a critic faction fighting 537-9, 541 fame: see kleos family traditions: see oral tradition fate ' 192-3, 431, 558, 587-8 Fehling, D. 353-4, 374, 378-9 First Sacred War 384 flashbacks (analepses) 263-6
INDEX
'floating gap': see chronology, spatium hislorieum Floyd. E. 16 Focke, F. 248 focus 54, 57-8, 61, 64 food: see luxury Fomara, C. 152, 179 80, 551 Forsdyke, S. 537 fortune, changeability of 172, 177, 328, 357, 523. 578; see also fate Fowler, R. 153 Fraenkel, H . 247 8 freedom 386, 342, 420, 529, 534, 565-6; see also democracy funerals 461 Gandarae 470 Garamantes 462 Ge 450 Gelon 341, 548 Gelonus 440, 446, 454 gender 364, 367-9; see also masculinity, women genealogy 155, 324. 390-1, 401, 410, 497, 502 generation, length of 501 geography 4, 14, 159, 181, 360 1, 415, 441-2, 457, 560 Getae 439 Gillus of Taras 345-6 Gimmirri 440 gnome 15, 23-4, 278 Gobryas 487 8 gods: see Herodotus, gods in Golden Age 460, 462-4, 467 Gorgias 7, 160 Gorgo 533 Gould, J. 180, 376, 380 1, 384 government, forms of 463, 518-20; see also Constitutional Debate Gray, V. 240 Greek colonies, in the Black Sea 441, 444, 453, 471-2 Greek identity, challenged 324-8 Greeks, superiority of 335, 565 6; weakness of 328, 337 43; see also 'Other' Griffiths, A. 547 Gyges 510 Halicarnassos inscription Flalys 330 Hammurabi 491 Harem inscription 581
97
GENERAL
Harmodius 326, 535 Harrison, T. 354, 384 Hartog, F. 280, 365 Hecataeus 100, 157. 159, 267, 401, 415, 419, 445. 467-8, 473-4, 497. 504 hegemonia 328 n. 14, 342; see also imperialism Helen of Troy 354 6, 497 Hellenocentrism 581 2, 584-5, 589-90 Hellespont 585 hemp-inhaling 450 Heraeles 197, 274, 278, 282, 450, 497 Heraclitus 100, 158 herms 325 Herodias 585 Herodotus: and Athens 33-52: as a critic 322-3, 3.37, 348-9, 351-71, 374, 381-3, 385-6, 419. 425-6, 457, 459-60, 504 5, 513 (see abo expert's persona); as 'actor' 278; as a researcher 13 15, 28—29, 158-59, 278-79; authorial voice of 11, 183, 267-89; becoming a historian 4, 177, 181; bias in" 378 80, 382, 573-5; causation in 522 3, 528-30, 556-9 (see abo war, causes of); comparison with Odysseus 99; cultural background of 152, 67; explanation in 217-24, 497', 502, 504; generalisation in 384-5; generation of 152, 399; gods in 325, 354, 369-70, 379, 384. 431-2, 497, 500, 560-1, 570-1; human tragedy in 502; intellectual oudook of 153 86; knowledge of Halicamassos 267; 'literary personality' of 523; reliability 352 3, 358 63. 564, 571 7: religion 183, 187 198, 325-6, 348-9, 381-3, 385, 431-2, 460-1; 'reticence' 380-3, 431-2; selectivity 383-4; showmanship 562; 'silent cities' in 509; synchronisms 502, 563, 575 [see also synchronism); use of numbers 441, 564, 575-6; use of oral tradition 376, 425, 504 9, 521 49, 562 3; use of sources 373 86, 424-5, 478-82, 504-9, 583-5; use of written sources 374-5, 510 (see abo inscriptions); see also Histories heroes 188 9, 497 heroic age 388-89, 407
INDEX
633
Hesiod 197, 388 9, 400-1, 431, 500, 510 Hestia 450 1 Himera 502 Hipparchus 196, 274, 500, 501, 535 Hippias 165, 535 Hippocrates, Hippocratic corpus 9, 13-14, 150-1, 153 4, 161 4. 433, 445, 447, 449-50, 464, .512; 'Hippocratic filter' 386 Histiaeus 529- 31 histôr 14, 16, 273, 267-89 historical explanation: see Herodotus, explanation in historié 3 4, 7-10. 12-19. 24. 28 9, 32, 278, 322. 419, 478 Histories: aim of 28 32, 91-3, 179 81, 417; analytic approach to 5; and Aeschylus' Persians 137-47; as narration 229-30; as narrative 253-4, 269; audience of ,321-2; cross-references in 11 12, 275 'digressions' in 255 7, .321, 415, 118, 459, 500, 535, 560; graphein in 88-90; Homeric nature of 6—8, 120, 253-4, 263 (see also epic, Homer); juridical nature of 14-18; origin as lectures 8-9, 82, 85, 150, 152, 163; predisciplinary nature of 5; publication of 4, 8-12, 163; scope of 321; structure of 1112, 82-8, 253 4, 500, .551, 553, 555, 560, 567; 'tragic' nature of 117-47; unity of 4 5, 246-55, 551 ; see also Herodotus Homer 97-109, 150, 165, 180, 197. 198, 355, 388-90, 400-1, 405, 411, 415, 419, 431, 461, 466, 473, 500, 510; see also epic honouring one's family 204-8 Hornblower, S, 186, 384 Howald, E. 247 Hunter, V . 158 Hunzinger. C. 360 hybris 174-6, 193-4, 221-2, 341, 577, 587-8 Hyperboreans 466, 473 Hypernolii 467 Immerwahr, H . 5, 250-1, 276 imperialism 328-36, 343-8. 422-3. 506, 530, 553-5, 577; see also Athens Indians 333, 366, 461, 464, 470
634
GENERAL
inscriptions, deictic orientation of 30: used as evidence 332, 511-12 instability: see fortune, fate internal division in Greek cities 345-6 interpreters 420, 428 intertextuality 373 Io 497 Ionia, Ionians 267, 282, 325, 327. 338-9, 341, 358, 511. 554 Ionian revolt 101-2, 187, 192, 346 7, 398. 509, 528-31, 557 Iraq 479, 485 irony 123-4 irrigation 429 30, 477, 480 Isagoras 501, 538-40 isegoria 537; see also democracy Ishtar gate 492 isonomia 530, 533; see also democracy Issedones 197, 461-2, 464, 472 Issyk 451 Ister 471 -2 lus primae noctis 461 -2 Iyrcae 462 Jacoby, F. 83 5. 159. 246 7, 377 8, 391-2, 534 James, H . 373-4 Johnson, W. 31 Jong, I . de 105 justice 199 200 Karttunen, K. 465 kleos 8, 10, 27-28, 31, 99, 108, 180, 322 Knossos 499 Kolaios 499, 507, 512, 517 kratos 351 Krischer, T. 6 8 Kuban 452 Kuhrt, Amélie 486 K u f Oba 45.3 kurgans: see burial mounds Labynetos 477, 486 Labyrinth 423 Lade 502, 511, 531 Laestrygonians 461 Lake Moeris 333 landscape: see geography, topography Lang, M . 105, 107, 376 language 326 Lateiner, D. 106, 163, 280, 287, 587 laughter, significance of 587
INDEX
Laurion 568 Lavelle, I f 541 leadership: see arkhe, imperialism, hegemonia Lelantine war 339 n. 40, 384, 508 9 Leleges 337 Leonidas 191 Leotychides 348 Lewis, D . 378 lexis eiromene 247-8 Libya, Libyans 325 6, 403 4, 415, 143, 459, 461, 463-4, 468, 506 literacy 455 Lloyd, A. B. 354, 392-93, 474 Lloyd, G. E. R. 9 logioi 17-8, 269, 376 logistics 335, 564-5, 570 logos, logoi 17-19, 28, 255, 267-89, 459; see also novella, short stories, variant versions Lotophagi 462 luxury, corrupting power of 172, 201-2, 336, 342, 553 -4, 563, 567 Lycia 475 Lycidas 566 Lycopes 527 Lycurgus 338, 500, 515, 519 Lydia, Lydians 324-5, 335- 6, 378 Märchen-motiü 441 Macan, R. W. 455 6 Magi 362 makhimoi 420, 428 Malkin, Irad 383 Mandrocles 511 Mantels 194-96 Marathon 187, 192, 381, 518, 547 8, 573, 576 Mardonius 167, 171, 187, 188, 19), 196, 495, 559, 567, 569-70, 579 Marduk 475, 489, 491 3, 579, 581 Marincola, J, 278, 355 marriage 461 marriage-market 481, 494 marvels: see thbmala masculinity 335-6, 342-3, 367 8, 566; see also bravery, gender, women Masistes 580, 584 Massagetae 197, 450, 460, 462-3. 472, 554 mathematical texts 484 Medea 497 Medes 325, 330-1, 335-6, 486 medical writers: see Hippocratic corpus
GENERAL
medism 566 9, 573 4 Megara 333 Megasthenes 474 Meier, Chr. 105, 185 Melanchlaeni 445, 465 Meroe 467 messages, secret 530, 546, 563 Messenia 338 Messenian Wars 338, 508, 516 metanarrative statements 274-6 Metapontum 361
metis
530-1
Meuli, Karl 449 Meyer, E. 391, 410 migration stories 324 Miletus 339, 502, 509 10 military tactics 564-5, 576 -7 Millender, E. 527 Miltiades the Elder 545 Miltiades the Younger 211, 379-80, 545 mimetic narrative 106 M i n 321, 421 2, 429 Minos 337, 339 Mitchel, F. 391 Moeris 422, 429 Momigliano, A. 385, 583 monarchy 553 moral values 202 17, 328, 426-7, 434-5, 532-3 Mosshammer, A. 390, 396 Munson, R. 276 Murashu family 484 Murray, G. 409 Murray, O. 108, 378, 384, 474, 523 mutilated corpse, theme of 102, 567 Mycerinus 423-4 Myres.J. L. 250, 392. 513 myth, use of 18, 28, 109-16, 118. 159, 345, 405, 407-8, 459, 497, 499 mythical time 110; see also chronology; spatium historicum Mytileneans 510 Nabonidus 486-8, 495 Nabopolassar 486 Nabu sa hare temple 484 Nagy, G. 10-11, 13-14, 115, 376 Naqs-I Rustam reliefs 590 narrative unit 276 narratology 375 narrator ' 267-89 Nasamones 461-2, 466, 468
INDEX
635
natural disasters 561 Naucratis 424, 430 Naxos 340, 344-5, 502, 530, 5.57 Nearchus 474 Nebuchadnezzar 488 Nebuchadnezzar I I 483, 486, 491, 495 Necho I I 332, 423-4, 429 Necos: see Necho I I Neo-Babylonian empire 475, 479, 481-96 Neriglissar 486 Neuri 465 New Year Festival (Babylon) 489 90, 492 Nicandra 374 Niger 468 Nile 358, 365, 468 Nineveh 331, 475 475 Nippur 484 Nitoeris 424, 429, 477 9, 481, 486, 196, 511, 556 nomads 440, 443-53, 460 74
nomos 418, 459, 464, 479, 555, 566; see also physis non-verbal communication 587 novella 257-8, 427, 434; see also logos, short stories Ober, J. 539 42 Ocean(us) 4.57, 471-3 Oedipus 511
oikoumenê 45 7 Olbia 443, 454 Old Oligarch 150 Old Testament 388 Olen 510 Olympia 190 Olympic games 565-6 omens 188, 194-6, 570-1 Onomacritus 559 Opis 487 opsis: see autopsy oracles 121-2, 188, 191, 194-6, 358, 571, 574; see also Delphi oral poetry 451 oral tradition 100, 277, 399; East Greek traditions 523; family traditions 525, 532, 534 6, 540, 545, 573-4; Panhellenic traditions 522, 542, 545, 547; polis traditions, popular and official 522, 525 8, 531-2, 534-48; see also Herodotus, use of oral tradition; orality
636
GENERAL
orality 5, 53, 107, 114; see also spoken language Orestes, Bones of 515 origins ' 324-8, 449, 451 Oroetes 557 Orphics 434 Ossetes 451 ostraka, ostracism 547 8 'Other', 'othering' 238-41, 363 71, 415, 417, 435, 481
INDEX
Phocis 566 Phoenicia, Phoenicians 269—70, 324-6 Phrygia, Phrygians 326 Phrynichus 510 phthonos 193-94 Plrylakos 188, 189
physis 160 1, 163, 185; see also nomas
pilots 420, 428 Pindar 367, 383, 385, 418, 446, 507, 510 Padaei 461-2 Pisistratus 189, 400 Pan 379, 381-2, 500 Pittacus 513 Panaetius of Tenos 562 Plataea 548 paratactic style 5, 251, 253-4; see also Plataea, battle of 191. 370. 561 3. lexis eiromene 565-7 parenthetical remarks 285 Platea 507 Paros 340, 347, 379-80 Plato 151 Parysatis 495 pleonexia 341, 347 Plutarch 275, 282, 327, 512, 515, Pausanias, author 508, 516 Pausanias, regent of Sparta 342, 571 369-70, 553-4, 567 poetic language 100-3 Payen, P. 363 Pohlenz, M . " 248-50 Pazyryk 450-1 poihlia 246 Pedasus 551 polarity 155, 363-71 Peisistratus, Peisistratids 37-8, 211, political thought 150, 164-83, 183 501, 504, 513-15, 525, 543, 559 Polybius 443 Pelasgians 196, 325 6, 328, 431, 504 Polvcrates 110, 124 6, 157, 170, 193, Peloponnesian war 4, 149, 153, 166. 196, 211 3, 282, 339-40, 407-8, 169-71, 176, 343, 384, 404 424, 426, 434, 499, 503, 517, Pembroke, S. 237-8 524-8, 557 Periander 112, 127, 206, 368, 503, polvvocalism 276 516, 525, 544 Poseidon 188, 190-1, 193, 450 Pericles 166, 170, 553, 567 poverty 336, 342, 566; see also luxury Persepolis 576, 580, 589 90 power 151-2, 160; see also kratos Perseus 326-7, 497 praise 282 Persia, Persian(s) 325, .327, 3 3 2 6 , Prakken, D. W. 391 344-8, 362, 365-6, 502, 508. presentation through negation 375 512-13, 518 20; army, size of Prexaspes 131 334: customs and attitudes 566. priests 424, 427, 497, 499 569 70, 575; defeat of 563, probability 279, 281; see also 565-6; empire 500, 554-7; Herodotus as a critic engineering 563—4; government progressive style 84 577; kings 569-70; religious policy Promeneia 374 577, 579-90; royal buildings 580, 582; proof 9, 11, 20-1; see also Herodotus inscriptions 482, 484, 493, 588-90 as a critic Persian wars 518-20, 551-78 prophasis 346 Peter the Great 452 prophecies 559 Pheidon of Argos 517, 519 prose 10-1 1, 97, 180-1 Pheros 422 4, 426 proskhema 346 Philaids 545 proskynesis 577; see also Persia, customs Philippides 381 prostitution, sacred 479, 481, 494, philosophy, Ionian 156 9 496 Phocaea, Phocaeans 339, 471 Protagoras 161 L
GENERAL
Protesilaus 115-16, 189, 193. 409, 553 Proteus 422, 424
INDEX
637
savages 460-74; see also 'Other' school 502 scorched-earth tactics 335, 448 protos heuretes 155 Scylax 465, 470 Psammenitus 426 Scyles 192, 446, 455 Psammetichus 332, 423-4, 428 Scyllias 359 60, 504-5 Psammis 332, 42.3-4 Scythia, Scythians 15, 17, 182, 323, Psyttaleia 572-3 331, 336, 361, 403-5, 437-56, Pygmies 467 461-5, 4 7 2 3 , 511, 554 5; Scythian INiliatforas ! 57 archers 446 7 Pythios .584 Semiramis 477, 496 Serpent Column 511-12 Qiiellenforschung 373, 377 sesame 477, 480, 493 Sesostris, conquests of 331 2, 337, Raaflaub, K. 165, 538 422 4, 429, 439 n. 5. 511 rape 497, 553 Sestos 347 8, 511 razor's edge metaphor 101-2 Sethos 421, 423 4, 427 reciprocity 209-12, 439, 509, 522 shamans 450 records, 323-4; see thomata Shammuramat 496 register 273, 284 sheep, fat-tailed 469 relativism: see nomas, physis short stories 584-6; analogy in reliability: see Herodotus, reliability of 305 15, content of 294; definition religion: see Herodotus, religion in of 291-9; incremental triple in resources 557, 563, 568 297; meaning of 306-15; narrative retaliation: see revenge, reciprocity art of 292-4; narrative modes of revenge 121, 209 12, 214-17, 323, 299; organization and placement of .346-8, 555 3 0 2 4 ; patterns in 294-6, 299-302; Rhampsinitus 424, 427 terms for 291; thematic relevance rhetoric 7, 9, 160, 286 of 304-6; transmission and truth of Rhodopis 510 315-17; see also novella, logos Rhoikos' temple 503 Shrimpton, G. S. 378, 380 ring composition 71-3, 104-5, Sicinnus 568 260-1, 377 siege warfare 565 Risch, E. 107 Sigeion 510 Romm, j . 356, 360 Sigynnae 472 Rossellini, M . 239-40, 460, 462-4 Simonides 370, 510 Royal Scyths 440 Sindians 439 'rule': see arkhe, imperialism, hegemoniaSiphnos 527-8 Russo, J. 21 Sippar 483-4, 487 Siris 568 Sabacos 423 slaves, slavery 336, 347, 446-7. 494, Sacae 440 573 Sahara 465, 468 Small, J, 362-3 Said, S. 239 40, 460, 462-4 Smerdis 488 Salamis, battle of 188, 191. 502, snakes 469 561-2, 564-6, 568-9, 571-3, Socles 516, 544-5 576-7, 579, 584 Solon 168-69, 351-2. 357, 369, 501, Samos, Samians 267, 333, 376, 499, 510, 513-14 502-3, 507, 516-18, 524-8, 531, Sophanes of Decelea 562 5.56 sophists, sophistic 7. 1.53-4, 156, Sandanis 553, 556 160 2, 280 Sappho 510 Sophocles 369 Sardinia 341, 466, 557 Sostratos 499 Sardis 346, 510 Sourvinou-Inwood, C. 112-14
638
GENERAL
INDEX
Sparta, Spartan(s) 385, 428. 433. Thermopylae, battle of 510 11, 497, 500. 502-4, 508, 511. 515-16. 561 2, 565, 576, 584 526-8, 531-3. 543-8; customs 325, Thersander 351, 374, 376-7 368; kings 326-7, 501, 519, Thomas, R. 9 11, 13 15. 20, 163-4, 545-6; power of 338, 340; role of, 354, 384, 478-9, 535-6 in Persian wars 341 2, 347, thomata 282, 323-4, 359-60, 365, 566-7, 575 418, 428, 430, 432, 434, 479, 551, Spartan-Athenian hostility 566 8 561, 578; see also erga spatium historicum, spatium mythkum 110, Thonis 422 270, 287, 389-92, 395, 405-14; Thrace, Thradans 333, 335, 439, see also chronology 461, 463, 471 speeches 101, 104, 106, 375, 384 Thrasybulus 544 spoken language 53-77; see also Thucvdides 4, 31 32, 79-82. 117, 'chunking', theme, 'tail' 149-54, 169, 175, 179, 181-86. Stahl, M . 112 226-7, 281, 268, 288, 322-3, Stambler, S. 106 338-40, 343, 349, 370, 375-7, Stoa Poikile 573 379-80, 384, 386, 390, 397, 408, storms 561, 570 513, 535. 543. 547 8, 551, 558, story-patterns 232 3; see also short 575 stories Tigris 477, 485 Strabo 460, 479 Timarete 374 Strasburger, H . 106, 392-3, 395, time 27, 29, 252-3, 387-412; see also 408 chronology Syloson 345, 503, 556 Tolstaya Mogila 452-3 synchronism 392, 398-400, 409; see topic 54, 56, 58, 60-1, 67, 74; also Herodotus, synchronisms in see also discourse topic Syracuse 341 topography 573 Tourraix, A. 2 3 2 4 , 238 la legomena 356, 499, 502, 505 trade, traders 324, .336, 366. 441, Table of the Sun 467 446, 499 'tail', in sentence structure 54, 56—9, tragic themes/motifs 119-24 64-9 tribute (pharos) 330-4, 337 Talthybius 114-16 Troglodytes 462, 467 Tartessos 339, 507 Troy, Trojan War 108. 114-15, 323, Tauri 439, 440 n. 10 337, 339, 345, 389, 395, 403, taxation 484, 493-4 408-11, 499-500, 553 Tegea 338, 497, 512, 515 tumuli: see burial mounds Teisamenus, Bones of 516 Tymnes 374, 454 Tenos 51 1 tyrants, tyranny 173-7, 274, 337-8. textuality 54-5 385, 585-6, 513-15, 518-19, 524-6, thalassocracy 333, 337-40, 499 529, 535-45 Thales 156, 325 tyrant-slayers 326 Thar desert 465 Tyrtaeus 508, 510 Thasos 340 Thebes, Egyptian 475 unity, importance of, among Greeks Thebes, Thebans 347, 511, 569 335, 340-3, 463, 566-9. 571-2 theme, in sentence structure 54, 56, 65 Uruk 483 Themistocles 43-8, 188, 193-94, 282, 519, 547, 561, 563, 567-9, variant versions 270, 275 571, 574-5 Vernant, j . - P . 112-14 Themistocles Decree 573 Versnel, H . 116 theogony, Greek 500 Veyne, P. 356 Theopompus 474 voice 267 89; see also polyvocalism Thera 383, 506-8 Von Fritz, K. 392
GENERAL
war, causes of 343 8, 555 9; see also Herodotus, causation in warfare 202 3, 324 5, 447 8 'wamer' motif: see 'wise adviser' Waters, ft. 252 Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, U . von 165 William of Rubruck 448 'wise adviser' 119, 122-3. 171. 299 302, 351 2, 546, 5.53, 569 70, 584 Wolf, E. 230-2 women 183, 207-8, 225 42, .564, 585-6
639
INDEX
Xanthippus
553, 567
xenia 209 11 Xenophanes 157 Xerxes 105, 161, 173, 174-75. 182, 187-89, 193-94, 196, 335, 341, 344, 347 8, 368-9, 403, 408, 475. 478. 488-90, 559, 569-70, 579-90 yurt
446
Zeus 188, 190 1, 197, 450, 475 ziggurat 480, 491 2, 496
INDEX
Aeschylus Agamemnon 1295 1296-8 1318-19
120, 133 123 123 121
Choephori 273 4 555-9 556 7 888 930
120, 133 131 131 121 121 121
Eurnenides 453-4 700-3
136 123 449
Per.sae 230-45 399 401
131, 137 45 572 572
128.
OF
PASSAGES
1451 b.34-5 1452a1820
126 126
Politics 1313a
519
Problems 25.6
4 43
Arrian, Anabasis 2.25.4 7.20
469 474
Diodorus Siculus 10.25.1
1 1.24.1
11.29.1
187 575 190
Dionysius of Halicarn. On Tliucjdid.es 23 ' 97
Prometheus Vmctus 707-35 445 790807 445
Empedocles D K B108
157
Septem 743-52
133
Ephorus F 115
508
Supplices F 198 Radt
120. 133 449
Gorgias Helen 10-11
160
Hecataeus FGrH 1 F 1 FGrH 1 F 184-90
157, 399 4-15
Hermogenes Peri ideon 330-1 336 408
10.9 100101 98, 103. 109
Aristophanes Birds 941-43 1660
446 514
Aristotle Alhenaion Polileia 1.4 514 514 9 514 12 514 18.1-2 515 16-17 Gen. An. 755b6 Poetics 145 la-b 145 lb 1-41
109 98 117
Herodotus Histories Book One Proem:
3-32 passim. 93 4. 99-100, 202-3. 269-70, 282, 321. 395. 551, 583
642 1.1-5
1.1-3 1.1.1 1.2.3 1.3.2 1.4.1 1.4.4 1.5-91 1.5-33 1.5 1.5.3 1.5.4
1.6
1.6.2 1.7 1.7.2 1.8-12 1.8.1 1.10.2 1.11.5 1.12 1.14.4 15.1 1.17.1 3 1.19-22 1.19-20 1.20 1.23-24 1.24 1.26.3 1.27 1.27.1 1.28.3 1.29-33 1.29 1.30.1 1.30.3 1.32 1.34 1.35 45 1.44.2 1.45.1 1.45.3 1.46-92 1.46 56 1.46.1 1.49 1.51 1.51.4
INDEX
O F PASSAGES
18, 28, 114, 269 -70, 287, 395. 398, 408, 553, 556 497, 499 7, 17, 324, 376 18 18 345 553 168-69. 172-74 35-6 86, 92, 322, 328, 345, 347, 357 18. 159, 177, 270, 281, 395, 411, 499 352 86 330 501 55-56 230-2, 293, 368 55-59 63 21 510 72 36 195 210 378 292 3, 298, 306-8 512 347 298, 300, 304, 335, 513, 556 330 36 201, 293, 300 513 22, 409 357 177, 369 174 134-5, 160, 195, 196, 205 66-67 76 76 136-7 188 554 513 •279, 282. 511 370
1.52 1.56-68 1.56-64 1.56.1-2 1.58 1.59-68 1.59- 64 1.59 1.60 1.60.3-5 1.64.1 1.65-68 1.65.1 2 1.66 1.67 1.68.3 1.71 1.74 1.76.2 1.77.1 1.79-80 1.79 1.82 1.84 1.85-91 1.91.4 6 1.92.1 1.93 1.94.1 1.95 1.95.1 1.95.2 1.96-100 1.101 1.103.1 1.103-106 1.105 1.105.4 1.106.12 1.107 130 1.108 1.110-13 1.110.3 1.113.2 1.114 1.118-119 1.122.3 1.123 124 1.124 1.124.1 1.124.3 1.126.6 1.130 1.130.3
64 567 37 16. 170 328, 3.37 502-3 211, 518 515 385 189 525 170, 338 195, 508 512 407 65-66, 161 171, 404, 553, 556 401 344 335 336 162 515 336 188, 219-20 195 554 282, 511 324-5 88, 486 274. 276. 441 331 173 330 325 437 449 442 331 110 554 208. 228 21 21 553 111 111 111 89 188 62 188 437, 555 344
INDEX
1.131-132 1.131 1.134.1 1.136 1.136.1 1.140 1.140.1 1.143 1.143.1 1.143.2 1.146-147 1.153 160 1.153 1.153.1 -2 1.155 1.155.4 1.157 160 1.163 1.167.1 2 1.169 1.169.2 1.170 1.170.3 1.171 1.171.2 3 1.171.4 1.175 1.177-178.1 1.178 200 1.181-183 1.183 1.184-185 1.184 1.185 186 1.185 1.185.1 1.186.1 1.187 1.191.6 1.194 1.196 1.199 1.201-216 1.201-214 1.202 1.202.2 1.203 1.205-216 1.207 1.209.4 1.214.5 1.216
197 157. 197 577 21 570 102, 362 499 397 333 337-9 327 381 572 324 162 336 121, 193 339 195 86 554 341, 466 325 408, 499 337 325 551 554 475, 477 8 197, 478 88, 479, 488-9, 579 228 25, 331 556 478-9 26, 554 26 478 333 479 228, 479 479 472 55 1 472 450 474 227 23, 25, 172, 177, 411 188 274 197, 461
643
O F PASSAGES
Book Two 2.1 2.2 2.3 4 2.3 2.3.1 2.3.2 2.4.1 2.4.2 2.5 2.11-12 2.12.1 2.14.2 2.15-17 2.15.1 2.16.1 2.18.1 2 2.18.1 2.18.3 2.19 25 2.19 2.20 25 2.20 2.22.2 2.23 2.24.1 2.29.1 2.29.1-2 2.29.7 2.30.5 2.32.4 2.33-34 2.33 2.34.1 2.35-36 2.35 2.35.1-2 2.35.1 2.35.2 2.37.5 2.42.2 2.43 44 2.43.1 2.44 2.45 2.46 2.46.4 2.48 2.49 2.50 2.50.1 2.52 2.53 2.53.1
87, 555 407 158-59, 407 278, 402. 407, 431 376 198 273, 387, 401, 407 197, 402 159 157, 159, 401 358 429 160 20, 396, 401-2 20, 282 358 9 20 419-20 160, 282 278 354 282 359 109, 352, 457, 473 24, 282 15, 419 355 197 365 64 155 471 16, 282 155. 162, 181 227, 282, 448 365 418 433 427 22 197 274, 396 16, 278. 401. 407 109, 282, 407 431 22 432 195, 197, 401 196 354 196 157, 197, 401, 500 354
644 2.55.3 2.58 2.60-63 2.65.2 2.68.2 2.70 2.77 2.77.1 2.77.3 2.77.5 2.78 2.91 2.93 2.98.1 2.99-141 2.99.1-2 2.99.1 2.101.1 2.101.2 2.104 2.110.1 2.116 2.119.3 2.100 2.100.3 2.102 110 2.102 6 2.103.2-105 2.104.2 2.107.1 2.110.2-3 2.111 2.113.3 2.114 2.116-117 2.117 2.119.3 2.120 2.120.5 2.122 2.123 2.124 136 2.125 2.127.2 2.131 2.133.1 2.133.3 2.134 2.135 2.136 2.139 2.141
INDEX
374 155. 197 432 198 282 88 162, 401 376 433 420 432 432 109 328 421-3, 425 355 15, 278, 419 25 26 88 26 108 16 406 429 331 511 332 420 422 332 426 422 193 355 275 355 156 58, 193, 215, 408, 426 356 427, 432 19, 88 90, 157, 376, 388, 419, 432 422 511 429 279, 283 421 431 282 510 26, 511 122, 426 426, 511
O F PASSAGES
2.141.1 2.141.3 4 2.142 2.143 2.144.2 2.145 146 2.145 2.147 3.64 2.147 51 2.147.1 2.148 2.148.2 2.152.3 2.154 2.154.4 2.156 2.158 2.161.2 2.161.3 2.161.4 2.162.2 2.164.1 2.167 2.169 2.172.5 2.177 2.178-179 2.182 2.182.2
421 421, 396. 410, 267, 401. 421 197 407. 423 122 419 503 25 421 401, 419, 510 429 426 192 525 421 420 385 426 420 397, 430 91 332
430 398, 402, 406. 501 279, 327, 396. 497, 510
500 5
406 499
513
Book Three 3.1 3.1.1 3.3 3.6 3.9 3.9.2 3.12 3.13.4 3.14 3.16.2 3.16.3 3.17 25 3.21 3.21.2-3 3.25-26 3.25 3.27-30 3.34.4 3.37.1 3.38
87 61 274 430 90-1 505 161 3,34 301, 426 193 197 466-7 405, 464 556 554 193. 335, 466 193 333 193 366, 385, 459. 461, 510
INDEX
3.39-60 3.39-43 3.40 3.44 53 3.44-45 3.45 3.46-56 3.46 3.47 3.47.1 3.48-53 3.49.1 3.55 3.55.2 3.56 3.57-59 3.58 3.60 3.61-66 3.65.5 3.72 3.80-82
3.80 3.82.5 3.84 87 3.88 3.89-95 3.89 3.90-97 3.94 3.95 3.98-106 3.99 3.100 3.101 3.102 3.103 3.106 3.107-113 3.108 3.109 3.113 3.115 3.116 3.117 3.119 3.120-149 3.120-125 3.120 3.120.1 3.122
113, 124 6, 211, 409, 524 8 296, 426 7 89 206 524 157, 212, 282 526-7 526 212 508 112, 127, 516 502 374, 399, 500, 502 527 503 527 408 275, 282, 503 130 1 193 160, 161 161, 173. 185. 279, 325, 327, 374, 528, 534, 544-5 21 1 569 518-19 511 333 4 366 555 470 333 470 461 470 470 465 88 162 468 9 160 469 469 470-2 445, 472 333 120, 301 2 556 124-6, 203-4. 211, 296 212-3 503 110, 170, 407
645
O F PASSAGES
3.122.2-3 3.124-125 3.125 3.130.3 3.131-138 3.133 3.134,1 3.134.2-4 3.138.3-4 3.139 3.142 3.148 3.151.2 3.166
339- -40, 499 195, 196 213 22 344- -5 311 22 555 345 -6 503 165, 184, 190 212 123 465
Book Four 4.1-144 4.1.1 4.1.2 4.4 4.5-13 4.5 4.5.3 4.8 4.8,2 4.13 4,13.1 4.15.1-2 4.16-21 4.16.1 4.17-27 4.17.1 4.17.2 4.18.1 4.19 4.20.1 2 4.22.3 4.24 4.25-36 4.26 4.27 4.28-30 4.28-29 4.30.1 4.35 4.36-45 4.36 4.44 4.45 4.46 4.46.1 4.46.2 ,3 4,47-58 4.48
437 439 437, 437 441 403, 449 457 20 465, 361, 361 439 361. 441 443, 440, 440, 440 440, 440 441 472197, 465, 83 443 83 510 457 155, 470 471 182, 376 335, 439, 471
56 440
404
472 444 5
444 446 449 449 445
3 461, 464 472
157, 282, 457
403 448, 454 441
646 4.56-57 4.59 4.59.1 4.60-2 4.67 4.70-72 4.71.1-2 4.73-75 4.76.6 4.77 4.78.1 4.78.3 4.79.1 4.79.2 4.81 4.81.1 4.82 4.83-144 4.84 4.87 4.88 4.91 4.95.1 4.99 117 4.99-101 4.106 4.108 4.110-117 4.118 4.131-132 4.136 4.137 139 4.145-159 4.145-149 4.145.1 4.150-156 4.152 4.152.3 4.155 157 4.160-162 4.161 4.163 164 4.173-174 4.174 4.178 4.180 4.180.4 4.181-196 4.183 4.184 4.189 4.189.3 4.191 4.192.3
INDEX
440 450, 461 1 li) 150 449 452- -3 440 450 374 279, 444 446 443 192 195, 443 442 17, 28, 440 282 554 -5 206 379. 511 511 511 60-61, 157 441 439 367 440, 446, 454 227, 453 437 455 87 87 383 497 506 506 -8 512, 517 499 195 228 195 122, 517 284- -5, 403 464 40.3 459 325 468 281- -2 464 159 325 403, 464 16, 282
O F PASSAGES
4.195 4.195.2 4.197 4.197.2 4.202-205
89 505 282, 404 555 214 5, 228
Book Five 5.1 5.3-10 5.3 5.3.1 5.5 5.7 5.9.3 5.10 5.12 14 5.12-13 5.12.1 5.13 5.14.1 5.17-18 5.18-20 5.18 5.25 26 5.28-38 5.28-30 5.28 5.30-36 5.30 31 5,31.1-3 5.33.2 5.35.3 5.36 5.36.2-3 5.37 5.38-97 5.39-54 5.39 5.42.1 5.45 5.49 5,49.8 5.50 5.51.2 5.55-96 5.55 78 5.55-56 5.57.1 5.58 5.59 61 5.62 5.63-65 5.63 5.63.2
403 471-2 463 335 474 197 395, 396, 403. 412 471 556 67 71, 403 71 403 71 285 297 106 73-76 346 170 339, 502 557 530 344 192 530 510 339 185. 530 567 531-3 515 547 91 2 157. 347, 532 338, 508 533 533 249, 263-6 38 40. 170 196 326 80 511 274 535-6 385 193, 369
INDEX
5.66 73 5.66-67 5.66.1 5.67-68 5.67 5.69-73 5.69.1 5.69.2 5.71 5.73 5.74 78 5.74-75 5.76 5.77 5.78
5.98 5.99 5.99.1 5.101-102.1 .5.102 5.102.3 5.105 5.106 107 5.113 5.114 5.114.2 5.125
539 42 211 536 504, 517. 518 400 21 1 338 542 504 382 541 193 38 38 9, 511 161, 337. 385, 518 5.37 503, 517 497 193 39 543 193, 543 173, 186, 192, 516. 544 40 127, 210 518 192 501 368. 525 204 202, 346 7, 385, 533-4, 557 530 384 509 187 346 510 187, 557, 572 531, 557 510 195 497 510
Book Six 6.2.1 6.11.2 6.11.3 6.14 6.14.2-3 6.15 -16 6.19.3
557 102 192 89, 511 531 531 187
5.82-89 5.82-84 5.90.1 5.91 5.91.1 5.91.2 5.92 5.92a2 5.92ß 5.92ß 7 5.92.5.1 5.92.Ç.1 5.9211.2-3 5.95 5.97
647
O F PASSAGES
6.21.2 6.22.1 6.25 6.27 6.32 6.33-41 6.43 6.43.3 6.43.4 6.44.1 6.52-53 6.53 55 6.53 6.56-60 6.61.1 6.62 6.63 69 6.64.1 6.66-70 6.67.3 6.69.4 6.72 6.74-75 6.75.3 6.76.1 6.79 80 6.79.1 6.80 6.82.1 2 6.84.3 6.85 93 6.85-86 6.86 6.91 6.95 6.96 6.98 6.98.2 6.101.3 6.103-104 6.105-106 6.105 6.108 6.109-110 6.109.3 6.109.5 6.115 6.121-131 6.121 6.123 6.126-1.30 6.126-127 6.127.3 6.131.1
510 531 187 195, 502 187 211, 545 374, 530 279 62, 161, 135 344 504 326-7 89, 274, 497 515, 519 546 311 111 126 546 107 497 200 547 193 195 193 61 195 357 357 547 199 193 193 510 187 166. 410 341 187 21 1 381-2 109 548 518 567 192 573 40-2, 211, 504, 573 547 535 211, 517 502 65 538
648 6.132 136 6.132 133 6.135.3 6.136 6.137
INDEX
O F PASSAGES
195, 379-80 347 192 510 504
Book Seven Bks 7 8 7.1 2 7.3 7.5 18 7.5-9 7.6.4 7.8-11 7.8 7.8a. 1 7.8.P 7.9B 7.9.2 7.10 7.10.1 7.10Ô.2 7.10s 7.1093 7.12-18 7.13 7.14.1 7.16 7.16a.l 7.16ß 7.1.8 7.20 7.20.2-21.1 7.2 1 7.27-29 7.28.1 7.30 7.33 37 7.34 35 7.35 7.37 7.38-39 7.39.3 7.43.2 7.45 7.47.2 7.49 7.49.1 7.57-58 7.58.2 7.59.1 7.60 7.61-99 7.64.2
137 45 579 580 174--76, 344 220 1 192 569 587 554 187 171 344 156 23 161 160 102 103, 195 570 531 221- 2 570 157 584, 587-8 403, 408 323, 334, 336, 437, 499 26 206, 299 101 511 563 194 576 196 206, 299 576 561 587 335 335 570 196 560 565 513 103, 555, 560 440
428 562 368 161, 163. 182, 300, 398, 405. 566 518 7.102 7.102.1 342 7.104 518 7.111 397 7.113.1 137. 1 121 7.114 580, 585 563 7.120 7.125 560 7.128 130 560 110 7.129 7.132.2 191 7.133-436 565 7.133-134 114-15 184, 185 7.135 7.136 352 577 7.136.1 7.137 93, 114-15, 398, 404 7.138-139 42 7.139-144 191, 195 382, 574 5 7.139 23, 167 7.139.1 568 -9 7.139.3 4 7.139.5 188-89 187 7.140.3 7.143-144 44-5 7.144 547. 568, 574 171 7.145 7.147 446 564 7.147.2-3 7.148-149 191, 341 546 7.148 19, 110, 274, 356, 367, 7.152.3 370. 376, 419, 505 7.153 548 341 2 7.158 162 7.159 101 7.163-164 211 7.166 98, 398, 575 7.166.1 502 7.168.3 571 7.169-171 191, 499 7.178 103, 190, 191, 574 7.184-187 334 7.187 105 7.187.2 566 190, 191 7.189 7,190 296 7.191 560 7.89.3 7.96.2 7.99.1 7.102-104
INDEX
7.192 7.193 7.197 7.204 7.209 7.209.1 7.209.4 7.210.2 7.213-214 7.214 7.220.3 4 7.224.1 7.225 226 7.225 7.226.2 7.228 7.235-237 7.235 7.238 7.239
190 560 560 410. 500 300. 398 566 575 566 561 89 191 562 561 2 108 26 123, 510 11 300, 568 515, 546 216-7 303, 305, 546. 563
Book Eight Bks 7-8 ' 8.2 3 8.3 8.4 5 8.8 8.11.3 8.13 8.15 8.19 8.22 8.26 8.26.3 8.30 8,32.2 33 8.35-39 8.35.2 8.36 37 8.46.4 8.49 8.51 8.51.1 8.53.1 8.53.2 8.54 55 8.55 8.56-57 8.58-63 8.59 8.60y
137-45 42-3, 202 167, 171. 185, 342. 574 569 110, 279, 359- 60, 504-5 562 192. 561 575 568 511, 568 566 348 566 187 187, 191, 571 21 379 562 567-8 395, 398 334, 501 193 187 561 187 45-6 46 563 561
649
O F PASSAGES
8.62 63 8.62 8.62.1 8.64 8.65 8.68 8.70.2 8.74-75 8.74 8.77.1 2 8.78-79 8.79 8.82 8.82.1 8.84 8.85.2 3 8.86 8.89 8.91 8.94 8.99-100 8.101.2 8,103- 107 8.103 8.104 8.108 110 8.109 112 8.109 8.109.3 8.111 112 8.114 8.114.2 8.118 8.121-122 8.124 8.128 8.129 8.131 8.133 135 8.135.1 8.136 8.136.2-3 8.140-144 8.143-144 8.143.2 8.144
568 46 575 195 195, 561 568, 570 567-8 568 567 8 358 46-7, 216-7 519, 574 511 562 564 562 566 565 24 564, 574 570 25 206, 215, 297, 303, 308-10 570 551 47 204, 224 224 188, 194, 369, 407, 561 47 191, 196 123 295 191 282 274 193, 561 410, 500 571 274 571 575 301, 571 43. 566 188 167, 347
Book .Nine 9.2 9.3 9.5 9 9.13.2
569 395, 569-70 566 7 187
650 9.14 9.16 9.16.5 9.19 9.21 9.26 9.33-35 9.36 38 9.40 9.41-43 9.41.4 9.42.1 9.46-47 9.53 9.61.3-62.1 9.62.3 9.63.2 9.65 9.65.2 9.67 9.68 9.70.2 9.71.2 9.71.3 9.72 9.72.2 9.73 9.74 9.76 9.78-79 9.78 9.81.1 9.82 9.83 9.84 9.85 9.87-88 9.100 9.100.2 9.102.2 9.104 122 9.104 9.108-114 9.109 9.113-115 9.114-122 9.116-20 9.120-122 9.120 9.121 9.122
INDEX
O F PASSAGES
333 123, 178, 274, 302. 374, 398 351 570 565 408, 497 191 195, 196 25 196 570 351 565 565 570-1 566 565 561 189 25 565 565 562 24 563 27 n. 56 93 562 567 300, 314 567 190, 191 377, 554, 567 161 275 562 347 561 575 567 48-9 557 230 2, 368, 577, 580 192, 587 310-13 216-17 115, 189, 193, 297, 313-14, 409, 553 87 347 8 303, 314 15 49, 162, 188, 3.36, 520, 55.3
Hesiod
Catalogue of Women F 150.15 F 151
444 444
Theogony 27 38 209
360 389 194
Works and Days 106-201 389 Hippias D K B17
160
Hippocrates
Airs, Waters, Pfaces 12 16 17-22 17 19.2-4 21.3 22 24
1 62 162 445 453 443 447 449 162
De Arte 1
9
On Ancient Medicine 20 13 Homer Iliad 1.1 1.4-5 1.245-6 1.423 2.1-40 2.485 2.488 2.494 760 2.69.5-709 6.356-8 3.3 If. 7.91 7.125 10.173 12.447 13.5 r. 18.501 22.304-5
6-7, 100 102 107 467 n. 13 103 389 28 103 115 99, 388 467 n. 14 99, 389 101 101 388-9 444 16 27
Odyssey 1.1
100
INDEX
1.22 ff. 4.85 4.350 4.710 9.105 15 11.14-19 12.389-90 17.462-5 23.67
466443 101 99 405 440 106 106 194
Longinus, On the ! 13.3 98 Megasthenes F 21 469 F 23 474 474 F 27b
O F PASSAGES
Republic 359c6-360b2
133
Lao s 694d
579
Plutarch Aiist. 19 21
190
De Herodoti Malisnitate 275 856C 512 870c 327 13-15 327 23 Moralia 785b
117
Pericles 36
160
Themistocles 14.2 24 32
571 571 571
SEG 36.694 40.611
443 443
Ovid Epistuke ex Ponto 1.3.53 443
Simonides 11W 11.13-28W
370 103-
Pausanias 2.24.7 3.2.6-7 7.1.78 8.39.3-5
Sophocles Ajax Integral 1028-37
122 125
Antigone Integral
122
Electra Integral
127
Oedipus Rex Integral Trachiniae
122, 117,
Theognis 22-31
31
Thucydides 1.1 1.1-20
4, 81, 149, 396 384
Ncarchus F 8
474
New Testament Matthew 585 14,1-12 Old Testament Isaiah
5.26-8
Pindar Pythian 5
447
508 508 516 508
507
Plato Hipp. M i n . 363c-d 84 Protagoras 321b
160
Phaedo 96a
13
Phaedrus 278d
84
652 1.1-8 1.219 1.3.1 1.8.4-11.2 1.13.2-5 1.13.6-14.1 1.15 1.21-22 1.38 1.49 1.69.5 1.70 -71 1.76 1.88 1.97.2 1.130.1 1.132.2 2.2 2.5.6 2.8 2.47-53 2.48.3 2.63 2.67 2.71-74 2.79 3.45
INDEX OF PASSAGES .338 9 390, 408 338 339 339 339 384 31-2, 79, 81. 1.50, 179, 268, .322, .375, 397 113 558 577 151 151 543 375 567 370 396 377 167 151 386 166 398 190 441 151
3.68.5 3.81-84 4.104-8 4.122.6 5.26.5 5.84-114 5.89 6.54-9
548 151 149 377 149 151 152 535
Xanthus, FgrHist 90, 44 11--47
133
Xenophanes D K A33.5 D K Bl 1 -16 D K B22
157 157 399-400
Xenophon
Hellenka 5.1.4
324
Persian Royal Inse riptions 488, 493, DB 581, 589 589 n. 5 DNb 579 XPf 30-2 XPh 589 n. 5 XP1 581, 589