4000 CONTRACT LAW: GENERAL THEORIES Richard Craswell Professor of Law, Stanford Law School © Copyright 1999 Richard Craswell
Abstract When contracts are incomplete, the law must rely on default rules to resolve any issues that have not been explicitly addressed by the parties. Some default rules (called ‘majoritarian’ or ‘market-mimicking’) are designed to be left in place by most parties, and thus are chosen to reflect an efficient allocation of rights and duties. Others (called ‘information-forcing’ or ‘penalty’ default rules) are designed not to be left in place, but rather to encourage the parties themselves to explicitly provide some other resolution; these rules thus aim to encourage an efficient contracting process. This chapter describes the issues raised by such rules, including their application to heterogeneous markets and to separating and pooling equilibria; it also briefly discusses some noneconomic theories of default rules. Finally, this chapter also discusses economic and non-economic theories about the general question of why contracts should be enforced at all. JEL classification: K12 Keywords: Contracts, Incomplete Contracts, Default Rules
1. Introduction This chapter describes research bearing on the general aspects of contract law. Most research in law and economics does not explicitly address these general aspects, but instead proceeds directly to analyze particular rules of contract law, such as the remedies for breach. That body of research is described below in Chapters 4100 through 4800. There is, however, some scholarship on the general nature of contract law’s ‘default rules’, or the rules that define the parties’ obligations in the absence of any explicit agreement to the contrary. The phrase, ‘complete contingent contract’ is sometimes used to describe an (imaginary) contract that would spell out in complete detail the exact legal rights and duties of each party under every possible state of affairs. While no real contract ever achieves this level of completeness, the concept is still useful to define one endpoint of a spectrum of completeness. If any contract ever succeeded in reaching this endpoint, the law’s default rules would then be irrelevant, as no issue would ever arise that could not be settled by the terms of the contract itself. Indeed, the same is true 1
2
Contract Law: General Theories
4000
of the interpretation of most other legal documents, such as wills (see Chapter 5830) or legislative enactments (see Chapter 9200). As long as legal documents fall short of this level of completeness, the law must have some set of presumptions or default rules, in order to resolve disputes that are not settled by the terms of the document itself. The law could, of course, simply refuse to enforce any contract (or any will, or any statute) that fell short of absolute completeness. But such a rule would itself be a ‘default rule’: it would be a legal rule defining the obligations (or lack of obligations) that result when a contract does not itself specify what rules should govern. As long as actual contracts fall short of full completeness, then, the existence of default rules is not so much a choice as a logical necessity. The only question is what the content of those default rules ought to be. In choosing the content of default rules for contractual relationships, it is often useful to distinguish default rules chosen to increase efficiency if they are allowed to remain in force (as discussed in Sections 2-4) from those chosen to increase efficiency if many parties contract around the default rule (discussed in Sections 5-9). In some cases, the steps required to contract around a default rule could themselves increase efficiency, by inducing one party to reveal private information (as discussed in Sections 6-8). In other cases, it may be too hard for the law to identify a single rule that would increase efficiency if allowed to remain in force, so the default rule may instead be selected purely for its simplicity or ease of administration (as discussed in Section 9). The choice between these approaches depends in part on the ability of courts or lawmakers to identify efficient default rules; this issue is addressed in Section 10. The possible effect of default rules on the parties’ own preferences is discussed in Section 11, while Section 12 discusses some non-economic theories of default rules. Finally, there is also a good deal of scholarship on the general question of when contracts ought to be enforceable, either through informal social sanctions or more by formal legal mechanisms. Section 16 introduces these issues, and discusses the choice of enforcement mechanisms. Sections 18-20 focus on the question of whether promises should be enforceable at all (whatever the mechanism), with Section 18 discussing noneconomic theories of enforcement and Sections 19-20 discussing the economic theories.
A. ‘Majoritarian’ or ‘Market-Mimicking’ Default Rules 2. Introduction to Majoritarian Default Rules One way to select a default rule is to identify the rule that would be most efficient if that rule were allowed to remain in place (for example, if the parties
4000
Contract Law: General Theories
3
did not specify some other rule in their contract). For example, if the expectation measure of damages were determined to be the most efficient remedy for breach of contract, this approach to selecting a default rule would argue for making expectation damages the default remedy. Much of the economically-oriented research on specific topics of contract law falls into this category. For example, many analyses of the remedies for breach aim to identify the remedy that would produce the most efficient result if that remedy were allowed to govern the parties’ relationship (for example, if the parties’ contract did not stipulate that some other remedy would govern). The same is true of many analyses of implied excuses such as impracticability and mistake, or of other terms such as implied warranties. This work is described at more length in Chapters 4500 (unforeseen contingencies), 4600 (remedies), and 4700 (warranties). This section addresses only those issues common to all default rules of this sort.
3. Majoritarian Rules and Hypothetical Consent Default rules selected on this basis - that is, on the grounds of their efficiency if allowed to remain in force - are sometimes described as the rules that the parties themselves would have chosen, if they had taken the time to agree explicitly on a rule to govern their relationship. In most cases, parties to a contract have an interest in maximizing the efficiency of their relationship, so the rule the parties themselves would have chosen will be the same as the rule that would be most efficient if allowed to remain in place. Thus, default rules chosen on this basis have also been labeled ‘market mimicking default rules’, or default rules based on the principle of ‘hypothetical consent’. To be sure, if there are third-party effects, or if the parties to the contract are imperfectly informed or are subject to any other market failures, the rule that would be chosen by the actual parties might no longer coincide with the rule that would in fact be most efficient. For general discussions of the relationship between efficient default rules and hypothetical consent, see Posner and Rosenfield (1977, p. 89), Ayres and Gertner (1989, pp. 89-93), Coleman, Heckathorn and Maser (1989), and Craswell (1992). Section 4 discusses some additional complexities that arise in heterogeneous markets, in which the same rule would not be chosen by every pair of contracting parties. This basis for selecting default rules has been supported by two economic arguments, both of which involve transaction costs. (Some noneconomic arguments will be discussed in Section 12 below.) The first economic argument applies when it would be prohibitively expensive for the parties to make their contract more complete by specifying the rule they want to govern a particular contingency. This is especially likely for extremely low-probability
4
Contract Law: General Theories
4000
contingencies, where the expected benefits of specifying a rule in advance are likely to be low. In such a case, any rule the law selects as a default rule will inevitably be left in place by the parties, so the only way to get the benefits of whatever rule is most efficient is to make that rule the default rule. The second economic argument applies if it would be costly, but not prohibitively expensive, for the parties to make their contract more complete by specifying their own rule. In such a case, selecting a default rule that matches whatever rule the parties prefer may save some parties from having to incur those transaction costs, thus producing all the benefits of the most efficient rule with lower total transaction costs. These arguments become more complicated, however, if a ‘marketmimicking’ default rule is being applied to a market that is imperfect in some respect. For example, if a remedy of expectation damages would in fact be most efficient, but if imperfect information has led the parties to believe that some other remedy would be more efficient, should the law adopt as its default remedy the one that is in fact most efficient, or should it adopt the less efficient remedy that the (imperfectly informed) parties would choose if left to their own devices? The transaction-cost argument discussed in the preceding paragraph could suggest that, if the cost of contracting around the default rule is sufficiently low that the parties are likely to do so, then the law might as well adopt the less efficient remedy as the default rule, because that is the remedy the parties will contract for anyway. Alternatively, if the costs of transacting around the default rule are so high that the parties are likely to leave the default rule in place, perhaps the law should adopt the remedy that in fact is most efficient, as that will give the parties the benefit of the more efficient rule. But this latter approach is complicated by the fact that the identity of the rule that is most efficient (if allowed to remain in force) may itself change if the parties are imperfectly informed, or if there are other market imperfections. Moreover, in some cases the presence of information asymmetries or other market imperfections may call for an entirely different approach to the selection of default rules, in which the default rules are intentionally chosen not to be left in force by many parties. This approach is discussed below in Sections 5-9.
4. Majoritarian Rules in Heterogeneous Markets Market-mimicking or ‘majoritarian’ default rules raise additional issues in markets characterized by heterogeneity, where different rules would be efficient for different contracting pairs. If a single default rule must be chosen to govern all contracts in such a market, the rule selected will determine which contracting pairs can do best by leaving the default rule in place and which pairs could potentially do better by incurring the transaction costs needed to
4000
Contract Law: General Theories
5
specify some other rule. It is sometimes assumed that the most efficient single default rule would be that which was most efficient for most of the contracting pairs (hence the label ‘majoritarian’ default rule, coined by Ayres and Gertner, 1989). But if transaction costs differ across heterogeneous parties, this conclusion actually depends on the exact levels of transaction costs that each member of each contracting pair would have to incur to contract around whatever default rule the law adopts (see Ayres and Gertner, 1989, pp. 112115). If different rules would be efficient for different contracting pairs, the law must also to decide the extent to which its default rules should be ‘tailored’, or customized to match the rule that would be most efficient for each individual contracting pair (see Ayres, 1993; Goetz and Scott, 1985; Baird and Weisberg, 1982). If the law adopts a single, untailored default rule, that will be most efficient for only some of the contracting pairs: all other pairs will have to incur either (1) the transaction costs of contracting around the default rule, or (2) the efficiency loss from leaving in place a default rule that is less than efficient for their contract. A set of default rules tailored to each individual contracting pair can in theory eliminate or reduce these costs, but such ‘tailoring’ will usually introduce other costs. For instance, individually tailored rules will usually be more complex, thus increasing the drafting costs that must be incurred by the legislature or other lawmaking body. Moreover, it is often impossible to spell out a complete set of individually tailored rules in advance, so the law will instead have to rely on vague standards to be applied by courts on a case-bycase basis (for example, an implied excuse in cases where performance is no longer commercially ‘reasonable’). Vague standards such as these usually entail higher litigation costs; they also introduce the possibility of case-by-case error in the application of the standard, and may make it hard for the parties to predict what rule will be applied to their relationship. In short, the question of how finely to tailor a default rule - and, indeed, whether to tailor it at all raises most of the same issues that are raised whenever the law faces a choice between specific rules and vague standards (see Chapter 9000).
B. ‘Information-Forcing’ or ‘Penalty’ Default Rules 5. Introduction to Information-Forcing Default Rules In many transactions, the two parties begin with differing amounts of information. In some cases, they may be differently informed about the relevant legal rules, or about the risks involved in the transaction. They may also be differently informed about the characteristics of the other party - for example, the seller may not know how much the buyer will lose if the seller’s product turns out to be defective. Differences such as these are often referred to as
6
Contract Law: General Theories
4000
‘information asymmetries’. While information asymmetries are often addressed directly through disclosure regulations and the like (see Chapter 5110), they can also have implications for the law’s choice of default rules. Section 6 below discusses cases where the two parties are differentially informed about the governing legal rule. Sections 7-8 then discuss cases where the two parties are differentially informed about some other aspect of the transaction.
6. Forcing Information about the Legal Rule In some cases, the choice of default rule may help correct one party’s information about the legal rule itself. For example, suppose that the default remedy for breach provides for only a small monetary payment. Suppose also that the seller (the potential breacher) knows this, but the buyer (the potential nonbreacher) does not. Suppose that the buyer instead thinks, incorrectly, that the law’s default rule provides for a very large payment in the event of breach. If left uncorrected, this information asymmetry could lead to either of two problems. First, if a larger remedy would be more efficient for this contracting pair, they may not alter their contract to provide for the larger and more efficient remedy, because the buyer will think that he or she already has the benefit of a larger remedy. Second, even if the smaller remedy provided by the default rule is in fact most efficient for this contracting pair, the buyer’s ignorance about the actual rule may keep him or her from optimally adapting his or her behavior to that rule. For example, the buyer may purchase insufficient insurance, or take insufficient precautions to reduce the losses that would be caused by breach. (The effect of legal remedies on the incentives governing decisions such as these is discussed at more length in Chapter 4600.) By contrast, suppose now that the default rule were changed to provide for a very large payment in the event of breach. If this remedy is left in place, that is, if the parties do not contract around it), then both parties will optimally adapt their behavior: the buyer will adapt because this rule matches what he or she thinks the rule is; while the seller will adapt because, by hypothesis, he or she is correctly informed about whatever the default rule is. And if this default remedy is not left in place (that is, if the parties contract around it by stipulating a smaller remedy), the act of stipulating some other remedy should serve to inform the buyer about what remedy will apply in the event of breach. Indeed, if the default rule is one that the parties will be certain to contract around - for example, if it is chosen to be highly unfavorable to whichever party is better informed about the law - that will virtually ensure that the other party will also become correctly informed about the resulting rule, by the very process of stipulating to some other rule in their contract. Hence, these default rules are sometimes described as ‘information forcing’ rules (Scott, 1990, p. 609), or as
4000
Contract Law: General Theories
7
‘penalty defaults’ slanted against the better-informed party to induce him or her to contract around the default rule (Ayres and Gertner, 1989, p. 97). A number of analyses of particular topics in contract law have recommended default rules chosen on this basis, or have suggested that actual legal rules could be understood as serving this function. See, for example, Ayres and Gertner (1989, pp. 98-99, 104-106), Goldberg (1984, pp. 295-296), Muris (1983, p. 390), Verkerke (1995, pp. 885-890), Isaacharoff (1996, pp. 1793-1795). One difficulty raised by default rules slanted against the better-informed party is that it may not be clear which party is better informed. This raises another ‘tailoring’ question of the sort discussed above in Section 4: should the party against whom the default rule is slanted be determined in advance for a broad category of cases, or individually on a case-by-case basis? Another difficult issue, even in cases where it is clear which party is least well-informed, concerns the comparison between the benefits and the costs of correcting the information asymmetry. The benefit of correcting the asymmetry will vary from case to case, depending on the information involved, so it is difficult to generalize. The costs of correcting the asymmetry clearly include the direct costs of contracting around the original default rule (which will depend in turn on the procedures that are required to contract around a default rule, as discussed in Section 14 below). The costs of correcting the asymmetry also depend on the risk that the parties will simply forget to contract around, thereby unintentionally leaving in force a default rule that was chosen not to be efficient for these contracting parties.
7. Forcing Information about the Other Contracting Party In many markets there is heterogeneity among the potential parties on a single side of a proposed transaction. For example, sellers may differ in the reliability of their products, or buyers may differ in the losses that they would suffer if the product they purchase fails to perform. At the outset of the transaction, this information is often known to one party but not to the other - for example, each buyer may already know how much loss he or she would suffer, but sellers may have no way of knowing how much any individual buyer has at stake. This is another example of information asymmetry. When this asymmetry is present, contract law’s default rules can again create incentives for one party to take actions that will reveal information to the other party. For example, if the default remedy for breach of contract provides for only a small monetary payment, buyers who would lose a larger amount in the event of breach may have an incentive to try to contract around that rule, by negotiating for a clause stipulating a larger payment in the event of breach. By contrast, if the default remedy is already set at a larger payment, buyers who
8
Contract Law: General Theories
4000
would lose less may be the ones with an incentive to contract around that rule, by negotiating for a smaller stipulated damage to get a more favorable price). In other words, the choice of default rule will determine which set of buyers buyers with little at stake, or buyers with lots at stake - have an incentive to try to contract around the default rule. As a result, sellers may be able to infer something about the amount that any given buyer has at stake by observing whether that buyer does or does not try to contract around the default rule. And if buyers also differ in the gains they would get from transacting around the default rule, or in the costs they would face in doing so, the resulting equilibrium may depend critically on which default rule the law adopts. (The welfare consequences of these differences are discussed below in Section 8.) These differences are often analyzed using signaling models from game theory (see generally Chapter 0550). If sellers have no information about how much any given buyer would lose in the event of breach, the result may be a pooling equilibrium in which all buyers are charged an identical price. But if this asymmetry can somehow be overcome, the result may be a separating equilibrium in which buyers who face large losses in the event of breach will have a right to collect those losses, but will pay a higher price (to compensate the seller for its greater potential liability), while buyers who face lower losses will pay a lower price. One way to achieve this separating equilibrium is to select a default rule that induces one of these classes of buyers to signal the amount they have at stake, by their actions in trying to contract around the default rule. For formal models of this effect see, for example, Ayres and Gertner (1989, 1992), Johnston (1990), Allen and Gale (1992), Hviid (1996).
8. Information-Forcing and Economic Welfare Unfortunately, it is often difficult to assess the welfare implications of default rules that produce separating equilibria. Part of the difficulty is that, while there will usually be efficiency gains from eliminating this information asymmetry, that will not always be the case. Gains could arise if information about each individual buyer’s potential losses may let some sellers make customized adjustments to the reliability of their products. Gains could also arise if this information let sellers calculate a price that better reflected the true risk of selling to that particular buyer, thus sending buyers the correct signals about whether to purchase that product (see Ayres and Gertner, 1989; Quillen, 1988). In some cases, though, information about the buyer’s potential losses may be of no relevance to sellers - as, for instance, when sellers operate mass businesses that cannot practicably adjust their actions or prices for individual buyers (Danzig, 1975; Eisenberg, 1992, pp. 591-596). In such markets, there will be no efficiency gains at all from curing the information asymmetry. In
4000
Contract Law: General Theories
9
still other markets, there may be positive gains from curing the asymmetry but those gains may not outweigh the costs of communicating the necessary information (Bebchuk and Shavell, 1991). Moreover, even when net efficiency gains are possible, the parties’ private incentives may lead them to act in a way that fails to achieve those gains. For example, if buyers face a price-discriminating monopolist who can charge higher prices to buyers who have more at stake in a particular transaction, buyers may be reluctant to do anything to reveal the amount they have at stake for fear of having to pay a higher price (Wolcher, 1989; Johnston, 1990; Ayres and Gertner, 1992). In other cases, some buyers may get private benefits (such as a more favorable price) by distinguishing themselves from other buyers, thus leading to socially excessive signaling (Rea, 1984; Aghion and Hermalin, 1990). At present, it is difficult to generalize about when the signaling or separating effects of a default rule will improve overall efficiency (see Hviid, 1996).
9. ‘Formalities’ as Default Rules Still another approach to selecting default rules aims entirely at ease of administration. That is, rather than trying to identify the default rule that would (1) be most efficient if left in place, or would (2) induce an efficient disclosure of information, this approach aims for default rules that are easily administered by courts, and easily learned and understood by contracting parties. In an influential early article, Fuller (1941) coined the term ‘formality’ to refer to rules designed to induce parties to specify their intentions in a way that could easily be recognized by courts. In this respect, Fuller’s rules were designed to force the parties to disclose information to the court, rather than (or in addition to) forcing one party to disclose information to the other contracting party. For example, if the parties to a contract fail to specify the quantity of goods they intend to convey, many jurisdictions refuse to enforce any obligation whatsoever, thus implicitly filling the gap with a quantity of ‘zero’ (see Ayres and Gertner, 1989, pp. 95-96). This default rule clearly is not designed to match what any contracting pair would have intended anyway. Instead, its purpose is to induce each pair to contract around the default rule by specifying the quantity they prefer, thus sparing the court from having to guess about the parties’ preferred quantity. Thus, unlike majoritarian or market-mimicking default rules, formalities are not necessarily intended to be left in place by the parties. Unlike other ‘penalty’ or ‘information-forcing’ rules, however (see Sections 5-8), formalities need not be slanted against any particular party. For example, the default rule for contracts that fail to specify any quantity of goods could just as easily be set at any specific number, not necessarily zero. True, a default rule of ‘zero’ has certain administrative advantages over any other number: there
10
Contract Law: General Theories
4000
is no way to breach an obligation to deliver a quantity of zero, and hence no need to ever measure damages. Still, the essential feature of a formality is merely that some number be fixed in advance and be easily learnable by the parties, so that they can determine whether they will have to specify some other number in their contract. The formality could even be set at the number that most parties would prefer (if that number were known), thus giving it one feature in common with a market mimicking or majoritarian default rule. The only key is that, since formalities are chosen for their simplicity and ease of administration, they will necessarily be ‘untailored’ in the sense defined earlier in Section 4. As a result, no matter what specific rule is adopted as the default formality, many (perhaps most) contracting pairs will find it in their interest to specify some other rule in their contract. Because formalities are designed to be easily administered, they will at least have the virtue of reducing litigation costs in all cases when the parties fail to specify some other rule in their contract, so the default rule remains in effect. This same ease of administration may also minimize another component of transaction costs: the cost to the parties of becoming informed about the legal rule, and of predicting how that rule might be applied. Also, if the formality is not chosen to be deliberately unfavorable to either party, it may reduce the costs imposed when parties forget to specify some other rule in their contract: in this way, formalities may reduce the cost of remaining uninformed about the law. (These two effects have offsetting influences on parties’ incentives to become informed about the law.)
C. Other Issues in Designing Default Rules 10. Default Rules and Institutional Capabilities The preceding sections have discussed three bases on which default rules might be selected: market-mimicking or majoritarian defaults (Sections 2-4), information-forcing or penalty defaults (Sections 5-8), and pure formalities (Section 9). The choice among these various approaches depends in part on the competence and capabilities of legal institutions. For example, the first two approaches - market mimicking or majoritarian defaults, and informationforcing or penalty defaults - place obvious demands on those institutions, either to identify the rule that would in fact be most efficient (if left in place) for most contracting pairs, or to identify the default rule that would induce the most efficient disclosure of information. These demands are only increased if either of these approaches is to be adopted on a relatively ‘tailored’ basis, requiring the legal decision makers to assess the effect on individual markets or even individual contracting pairs. Thus, it is obviously an oversimplification to
4000
Contract Law: General Theories
11
analyze how either of these approaches would work if it were to be administered by an omniscient legal decision maker. The real question is how well either of these approaches will work when administered by actual courts and legislatures. Two views of this question have developed in the contracts literature. The first begins by positing that certain rules - often, the rules that would have been efficient in a first-best world with perfect legal institutions - are simply beyond the capability of real legal institutions. This assumption is often made when the rule in question depends on information that, although observable by one or even both of the parties, cannot be demonstrated or verified publicly in court. For example, if the default remedy for breach were based on the net profits the breacher made, this would require a court to be able to measure the breacher’s revenues and costs, which might in some cases require more accounting expertise than real courts possess. Scholars often posit that such a rule would be unworkable in order to focus their analysis on alternative rules: rules that, while they might be less efficient in a first-best world, place fewer demands on the court or other legal decisionmaker (for example, Hermalin and Katz, 1993). For a general discussion and defense of this approach, see Schwartz (1992, pp. 279-280, 1993, pp. 403-406). By simply positing that certain rules are ‘unworkable’, though, these scholars implicitly assume an unfavorable balance between (1) the sum of all costs that would be imposed if courts tried to apply the unworkable rule, with the large number of errors that would entail; and (2) the sum of all costs associated with whatever rule is second-best. Other scholars have attempted a more finely-grained analysis by explicitly modeling the costs associated with judicial implementation of an unworkable rule. However, those costs depend in part on the nature and the probability of various errors courts might make in applying such a rule, and there is no consensus (and, regrettably, no empirical data) on how best to model such an error function. For two applications of this approach to contract issues, see Hadfield (1994), Hermalin and Katz (1991) and Allen and Gale (1992). The general discussion of legal errors and uncertain rules in other bodies of law (see Chapter 0790) is also relevant here.
11. Default Rules and Preference Formation In some situations, the law’s choice of default rules could alter contracting parties’ beliefs or preferences, thereby changing the value of the costs and benefits associated with different rules. For example, if the law adopts an implied warranty making sellers liable for all defects in their products (unless explicitly disclaimed), this could conceivably lead buyers to increase the value they place on such a warranty. At the same time, the adoption of the opposite default rule (no implied warranty) might lead buyers to the opposite view, if it
12
Contract Law: General Theories
4000
caused them to reduce the value they place on such a warranty. In that event, it would be possible for either default rule (an implied warranty, or the absence of an implied warranty) to be left in place by the parties, if the law’s adoption of each default rule changed the parties’ preferences sufficiently. It would also be possible for both default rules to be perfectly efficient, at least when judged by the preferences the parties would have once the law adopted either default rule. The possibility that default rules might influence parties’ preferences is only just beginning to be explored. Experimental tests of this possibility can be found in Schwab (1988) and Korobkin (1998); the latter also discusses many of the potential policy implications. (Other experimental work regarding the effect on preferences of legal rules generally is discussed in Chapter 0570). Brief discussions of the implications for default rules in particular can also be found in Charny (1991, pp. 1835-1840); and in Schwartz (1993, pp. 413-415), who refers to default rules with this effect as ‘transformative default rules’.
12. Non-Economic Theories of Default Rules While default rules have received less attention in scholarship outside of law and economics, there are several non-economic theories that deserve mention. For general discussions in the legal literature, see Charny (1991), Barnett (1992), and Burton (1993). The first, and least well-developed (at least as a general theory), depends on the identification of certain rules as morally superior, as a sort of ‘merit good’. That is, just as it is sometimes argued that all citizens ought to have certain goods (education, health care, and so on), it is sometimes said that all citizens ought to have certain contract rights, such as the right to complete compensation in the event of a breach; or that the law should especially promote certain kinds of relationships, such as those based on long-term cooperation. Arguments of this sort could be particularly compelling if the law’s choice of default rule influenced citizens’ own beliefs about the value of certain relationships, as discussed above in Section 11. A second non-economic theory rests on the idea of hypothetical consent. There is an entire family of non-economic theories that traces the binding force of contracts to individual autonomy, and to the fact that the contractual obligation was freely chosen by the contracting party (see Section 17 below). To be sure, these theories might seem to have little to say about the content of default rules, which (by definition) fill in the content of obligations that were not explicitly chosen by the parties (see Craswell 1989a). However, some have argued that, even in the absence of explicit consent, a party should still be bound to the rule that he or she would have consented to if he or she had explicitly negotiated an agreement on that point. Interestingly, this argument
4000
Contract Law: General Theories
13
converges with the market-mimicking or majoritarian approach discussed earlier in Sections 2-4. As a result, some economically-oriented scholars have sought to rest their recommendations on this philosophic position, as well as on more conventional economic grounds (for example, Schwartz, 1988, pp. 357-360). In the philosophical literature, however, it is disputed whether this invocation of hypothetical consent carries any of the moral force of ‘real’ consent, or whether it adds anything to standard efficiency arguments. For discussions in the legal literature of this issue, see Barnett (1992), Charny (1991), Coleman, Heckathorn and Maser (1989), Craswell (1992), and the exchanges between Coleman (1980a, 1980b) and Posner (1980, 1981). In the philosophical literature, useful discussions include Scanlon (1982), Gauthier (1986), and Brudney (1991). A third non-economic approach suggests that default rules should be designed to mimic the norms or customs that are already observed, either in the community at large or in the parties’ prior relationship. This approach is often employed in the ‘relational contract’ theory usually identified with Ian Macneil (1978, 1980, 1981); see also Brown and Feinman (1991), Feinman (1993), and Craswell (1993b). In addition, some scholars working from philosophical theories of individual autonomy and consent have seen the prevailing norms and customs as acceptable sources of default rules, at least in the absence of any explicit agreement to the contrary (Barnett, 1992; Burton, 1993). In particular cases, this approach could of course converge with any of the economic theories discussed here, depending on whether the norms or customs happened to be efficient (see the general discussion in Chapter 0800). Among the issues raised by this approach are questions about the manner in which the norms or customs are to be identified (see Bernstein, 1996, pp. 1787-1795; Craswell, 1998), and about the ability of courts or other legal decisionmakers to properly carry out this identification (see Section 10 above).
D. Contracting Around Default Rules 13. Displacing Default Rules by Agreement A default rule, by definition, leaves parties free to specify some other rule to govern their relationship if they so choose. There is, however, very little scholarly analysis of the steps the parties must take if they wish to specify some other rule. Most scholars implicitly assume that specifying some other rule would require a valid provision to that effect in a valid contract. This could suggest that the rules governing those steps can be left to the law of contract formation and contract interpretation, two bodies of law that are addressed at more length in Chapters 4300 and 4400.
14
Contract Law: General Theories
4000
Unfortunately, those bodies of law are themselves among the least analyzed portions of contract law. Moreover, the choices made by a legal system in selecting the rules of contract formation and interpretation can both be influenced by, and exert an influence upon, the choice of the original default rule. Sections 14 and 15 briefly discuss some of the interactions between these sets of rules.
14. Procedural Requirements for a Valid Agreement Any attempt to displace a default rule will normally have to satisfy (at a minimum) all the requirements of an enforceable contract. For example, depending on the legal regime, the agreement may (or may not) have to be in writing, and it may (or may not) have to be supported by consideration. These requirements, and the other rules governing contract formation, are discussed at more length in Chapter 4300. Should there be extra procedural requirements for parties who wish to contract around a default rule? If the default rule is presumptively valid, and especially if it is presumptively valid for moral or other non-economic reasons, it might be argued that parties who wish to choose a presumptively less valid rule should have to take extra steps, if only to ensure (and to demonstrate to a court) that this is what the parties really intend. For example, it might be argued that one party should not be able to displace a default rules by means of a single clause buried in a 30-page document that the other party will not normally bother to read. Arguments of this sort are often made in connection with standard form contracts and the legal doctrine of unconscionability (see Chapter 4100). Some of the links with standard default rule analysis are noted briefly in Craswell (1993a, pp. 12-14). Indeed, arguments of this sort may fit best in connection with informationforcing or penalty default rules. As discussed earlier (see Section 6), such rules may be deliberately designed to induce the better-informed party to contract around the default rule, in the hope that the process of contracting around the rule will itself give the other party more information about the rights that he or she now has. The efficacy of this approach, however, depends on whether the process of contracting around the rule really does inform the other party - and this, in turn, depends on the procedures that are required to contract around the rule. Again: if a default rule can be altered merely by inserting a clause in a 30page contract that nobody ever reads, the process of contracting around the default will not inform the other party at all. On the other hand, extra procedural requirements will usually increase the transaction costs required to contract around the default rule. For example, if altering a default rule requires the clause in question to be pointed out and
4000
Contract Law: General Theories
15
explained to the other party, the process of contracting around the default might indeed increase the other party’s information. However, this requirement may also be costly to satisfy, especially if a single contract alters a large number of default rules, and if the other party has no desire to sit through a lengthy set of explanations. In that event, the cost of altering the default rules via this procedure might turn out to be effectively prohibitive, so many parties would end up leaving the original default rules still in force. If so, this would require reevaluation of the original decision to select a default rule that was designed not to be left in force (that is, a default rule that was chosen to be inefficient precisely in order to induce the parties to contract around it). In this way, the rules governing the process of contracting around a default rule can themselves affect the principles on which the original default rule should be chosen.
15. Interpreting Contractual Terms that Alter a Default Rule Contracting parties often use language which appears to address an issue that would otherwise be governed by a default rule, but which is vague or ambiguous, and thus requires interpretation. For example, imagine a contract providing that the remedy to be paid in the event of a breach should be an amount that would ‘reasonably compensate’ the nonbreacher. Should the courts treat this vague language as leaving a gap in the contract, to be filled by the normal default remedy? Or should they instead apply some other set of principles? In conventional legal terminology, default rules are said to apply only when there is an actual gap in the contract, while questions of vague contractual language are usually described as questions of interpretation. There is, however, no consensus (and very little theory) on what should count as a ‘gap’ (see Ayres and Gertner, 1989, pp. 119-120). Fortunately, this distinction often will not matter, because the approaches used to interpret contracts (see Chapter 4400) have much in common with the approaches used to select default rules. In many cases, for example, vague or ambiguous language is interpreted so as to fit whatever the parties probably would have agreed to if they had discussed the matter, thus producing the same result as the majoritarian or marketmimicking default rules discussed in Sections 2-4 (see also Goetz and Scott, 1985). In other cases, vague or ambiguous language is interpreted against the party who drafted it, just as in the case of a penalty or information-forcing default rule designed to induce more careful and explicit communication (see Sections 5-9). Notice, though, that some decision must still be made to determine when the parties have taken enough steps to make their language sufficiently clear to avoid the rule construing ambiguities against the drafter, or when their language is sufficiently clear to avoid being interpreted in accordance with the
16
Contract Law: General Theories
4000
court’s idea of what most parties would have wanted. This is the question of precisely how far the parties must go to contract around an otherwise applicable default rule (or, in this case, around an otherwise applicable rule of interpretation). As discussed in Section 14, whatever requirements the law adopts here will have to be considered in deciding what default rule (or what interpretive presumption) to adopt in the first place.
E. The Enforceability of Contracts Generally 16. Introduction to Theories of Enforceability The analysis of default rules takes it as given that contracts are enforceable, and concerns itself with determining the content of the enforceable obligation. This Section addresses the opposite issue: given a contract of (let us assume) definite content, when should that contract be legally enforceable? One branch of this question asks whether contracts should be enforced by a legal system, or whether non-legal enforcement mechanisms might be superior (see, for example, Bernstein, 1992, 1996; Charny, 1991). Non-legal enforcement mechanisms could include arbitration panels or trade association boards that function much like a court, except for not being backed by official state sanctions. They could also involve much less formal mechanisms, such as the threat of withholding business from anyone who had broken a promise in the past. In both of these respects, they are similar to the non-legal mechanisms that might be used to enforce any other obligation (see Chapters 0780 and 0800), with which this literature has much in common. By contrast, most of the literature on whether contracts ought to be enforced typically abstracts from the choice of the enforcement mechanism, and focuses instead on the question of whether (and why) contracts ought to be enforced by any mechanism whatsoever. Non-economic theories are discussed briefly in Section 17 below, followed by a discussion of the law and economics literature in Sections 18-19.
17. Non-Economic Theories of Enforceability Moral philosophers have written extensively about the question of whether (or why) a promise should be morally binding. Some of their theories rest on utilitarian accounts that have much in common with the economic theories; these will be discussed in Sections 18-19. This section focuses instead on the non-utilitarian or non-instrumental accounts. In the legal literature, general
4000
Contract Law: General Theories
17
surveys of these accounts can be found in Atiyah (1981), Barnett (1986), Craswell (1989a, pp. 491-503), and Gordley (1991). One family of theories derives the obligation to keep one’s promise from considerations of individual freedom and moral autonomy. For example, Fried (1981) argues that if the law did not allow individuals to bind themselves with respect to their future conduct, it would thereby fail to respect the individuals’ status as autonomous moral agents. (For a variant account of when individual autonomy requires that promises be enforced, see Barnett, 1986.) These accounts do not imply that promises ought to be kept in every circumstance: this theory, like all of the others discussed in this section, allows for the possibility of a set of implied conditions or implied excuses. Instead, the goal of these theories is to explain why promises are prima facie binding, and this family of theories rests that binding force on the promise’s status as the voluntary commitment of a autonomous moral agent. Another, different set of theories rests the obligation to keep a promise on the substance of what has been promised. Perhaps the best-known theories in this set focus on harm to others: if one’s promise has led others to change their behavior in reliance on the promise, so that they would now be injured if the promisor failed to perform, that promise is binding because it is wrong to harm other agents. Making a promise and then failing to keep it might also be seen as a form of lying, for such a promisor has misled others about the future. Other theories in this set focus on reciprocity or restitution: if one has received a benefit and promised to pay for it, that promise is binding because it is only right to pay for the benefits one has received (Atiyah, 1981, pp. 34-36). Under some theories, the fairness of the terms of the promise is also relevant to whether the promise is binding (for example, Gordley, 1995). Under any of these substance-based theories, the promise’s status as the voluntary commitment of a free moral agent is less significant, for the agent is (in some sense) promising to do what he or she ought to be doing anyway. Indeed, under many of these theories, if there is no independent reason for the agent to perform the action - for example, if the agent has received no benefits, and if no one has yet relied on the promise - the obligation to keep the promise is seen as weaker or non-existent. These theories thus have difficulty explaining why the obligation should be stronger in the case of an individual who has made a promise than it is in the case of an individual who has acted identically but has explicitly disclaimed any promise (for example, ‘I think I’m going to do x, but I warn you that I’m not promising to do it, so you should rely only at your own risk’, or ‘you can confer those benefits on me if you want, but I warn you now that I have no intention of paying you anything for them’). Atiyah (1981, pp. 184-202) has argued that an explicit promise could serve as evidence, perhaps even conclusive evidence, that the underlying obligation really is a just one that ought to be enforced. If one asks why an individual’s
18
Contract Law: General Theories
4000
promise ought to be given such evidentiary weight, however, it is difficult to avoid falling back either on autonomy-based explanations of the sort discussed earlier in this section, or on utilitarian theories of the sort to be discussed in Sections 18 and 19.
18. Economic Theories of Free Exchange Economic theories of why promises should be enforced can be divided into two categories. One set of theories, to be discussed in this section, focuses on the utility created by the eventual performance of the promise. The other set, to be discussed in Section 19, focuses on the utility created by the ex ante incentives that the promise sets up. The first economic argument for enforcing promises rests on the utility that will be produced when the promise is eventually performed. Since voluntary transactions generally increase the welfare of all parties to the transaction, whenever a promise is voluntary it could be argued that welfare will usually be increased if the promise is carried out. Viewed in these terms, the economic argument for enforcing promises is very similar to the economic argument for free exchange and free markets generally (see Chapter 5000). This argument, however, could imply that a promise should not be binding if conditions have changed sufficiently that the promised transaction would not increase both parties’ welfare. For example, if a promisor’s costs have increased to the point where it is no longer efficient for him or her to perform the promise, this theory could suggest that the promisor ought to be released with no obligation to pay any damages at all, because this particular efficiency rationale for enforcing promises no longer applies. Under this theory, the only way to save the prima facie obligation to keep one’s promises (even after conditions have changed) is to argue for the virtues of a general rule over a case-by-case inquiry into the efficiency of any given transaction - in philosophical terms, by shifting from act-utilitarianism to rule-utilitarianism. That argument, in turn, must rest on empirical claims about the ability of courts to determine whether and when performance of the promise was still efficient. More generally, there is an important difference between permitting free exchange and permitting (or enforcing) binding promises. An exchange can take place instantaneously, but a promise necessarily involves a commitment to act in a certain way at some time in the future. Once this temporal element is recognized, it can be seen that enforcing promises does not simply transfer existing goods from one owner to another. Instead, the enforcement of promises creates a new good: it allows people to exchange ‘wheat to arrive on September 1' (for example), where without a binding promise they could only exchange actual bushels of wheat. Viewed in these terms, the economic case for enforcement rests on the proposition that this new good (that is, the good
4000
Contract Law: General Theories
19
represented by a future commitment) is a socially useful good which people frequently will want to exchange. To explain why such a commitment is useful and valuable, economists have focused more on the ex ante effects created by such a commitment, as discussed in Section 19 below.
19. Economic Theories of Advance Commitments Most economic justifications for enforcing promises have focused on the ex ante effects that would be created by a general rule of enforceability. In essence, these economic theories analyze promises as effectuating a present transfer not of goods and services, but of rights and duties. (For a similar view expressed in non-economic terms, see Barnett, 1986, pp. 291-300.) Such a transfer of rights and duties may itself produce efficiency gains, independently of whether it is efficient to actually carry out the promise. The efficiency gain that is analyzed most often stems from the effect on the promisee’s incentive to rely on the promised behavior (see Goetz and Scott, 1980). If the law denied promisees any compensation whenever a promisor could show that performance of the promise had become inefficient, this would shift more of the risk of a change in conditions to the promisee, and thus would reduce the promisee’s incentive to rely. To be sure, if the law instead guarantees that promisees will be compensated whenever the promisor fails to perform, this could create incentives for excessive reliance on the part of the promisee (see the discussion of reliance incentives in connection with remedies for breach in Chapter 4600). If the incentives for excessive reliance can be constrained by other legal doctrines, however, the net effect on the promisee’s reliance incentives could still be positive. The argument that enforceability is needed to induce one party to take the risky step of beginning his or her own performance (when the other party’s return performance is not due until later) is really a special case of this argument, since beginning performance is one of the many ways in which parties may rely on a contract. More generally, there are many other ex ante effects that could be produced by a rule requiring compensation even when conditions have changed to make performance unprofitable. If the promisor and promisee differ in their attitudes toward risk, a rule requiring compensation may achieve a better allocation of risk between the two parties (see, for example, Polinsky, 1983). A rule requiring compensation may also increase the promisor’s incentive to tell the truth about the conditions that will affect his or her performance, thus increasing the promisee’s information about those conditions (see Shavell, 1991; Craswell, 1989b; Katz, 1996, pp. 1289-1291). A compensation requirement may also give the promisor an incentive to affect those conditions directly, if the probability of performance rests on factors that are within the
20
Contract Law: General Theories
4000
promisor’s control. Generally speaking, all of the economic analysis of efficient remedies for breach (see Chapter 4600) is relevant here, since to make a promise enforceable is to set a non-zero remedy for the promise’s breach. The less-developed economic analysis of the conditions under which formation of a binding contract should be inferred (see Chapter 4300) is also relevant here.
Acknowledgments Richard Craswell is a professor of law at the Stanford Law School. Jack L. Goldsmith, Eric A. Posner, Cass R. Sunstein, and two anonymous referees provided helpful comments. Financial support was provided by the Lynde and Harry Bradley Foundation and the Sarah Scaife Foundation at the University of Chicago Law School.
Bibliography on Contract Law: General Theories (4000) Aghion, Philippe and Hermalin, Benjamin (1990), ‘Legal Restrictions on Private Contracts can Enhance Efficiency’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 381-409. Allen, Franklin and Gale, Douglas (1992), ‘Measurement Distortion and Missing Contingencies in Optimal Contracts’, 2 Economic Theory, 1-26. Ayres, Ian (1993), ‘Preliminary Thoughts on Optimal Tailoring of Contractual Rules’, 3 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal, 1-18. Ayres, Ian and Gertner, Robert (1989), ‘Filling Gaps in Incomplete Contracts: An Economic Theory of Default Rules’, 99 Yale Law Journal, 87-130. Ayres, Ian and Gertner, Robert (1992), ‘Strategic Contractual Inefficiency and the Optimal Choice of Legal Rules’, 101 Yale Law Journal, 729-73. Baird, Douglas G. and Weisberg, Robert (1982), ‘Rules, Standards and the Battle of the Forms: A Reassessment of “2-207”, 68 Virginia Law Review, 1217-62. Barnes, David W. and Stout, Lynn A. (1992), Economics of Contract Law, Minneapolis, West Publishing. Barnett, Randy E. (1992), ‘The Sound of Silence: Default Rules and Contractual Consent’, 78 Virginia Law Review, 821-911. Bebchuk, Lucien Ayre and Shavell, Steven (1991), ‘Information and the Scope of Liability for Breach of Contract: The Rule of Hadley v. Baxendale’, 7 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 284-312. Bernstein, Lisa (1992), ‘Opting Out of the Legal System: Extralegal Contractual Relations in the Diamond Industry’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 115-57. Bernstein, Lisa (1993), ‘Social Norms and Default Rule Analysis’, 3 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal, 59-90. Bernstein, Lisa (1996), ‘Merchant Law in a Merchant Court: Rethinking the Code’s Search for Immanent Business Norms’, 144 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1765-1821.
4000
Contract Law: General Theories
21
Birmingham, Robert L. (1968), ‘Legal and Moral Duty in Game Theory: Common Law Contract and Chinese Analogies’, 18 Buffalo Law Review, 99-117. Brown, Patricia A. and Feinman, Jay M. (1991), ‘Economic Loss, Commercial Practices, and Legal Process: Spring Motors Distributors, Inc. v. Ford Motor Company’, 22 Rutgers Law Journal, 30160. Charny, David (1990), ‘Nonlegal Sanctions in Commercial Relationships’, 104 Harvard Law Review, 375-467. Charny, David (1991), ‘Hypothetical Bargains: The Normative Structure of Contract Interpretation’, 89 Michigan Law Review, 1815-79. Coleman, Jules, Heckathorn, Douglas D. and Maser, Steven M. (1989), ‘A Bargaining Theory Approach to Default Provisions and Disclosure Rules in Contract Law’, 12 Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy, 639-709. Craswell, Richard (1989a), ‘Contract Law, Default Rules, and the Philosophy of Promising’, 88 Michigan Law Review, 489-529. Craswell, Richard (1989b), ‘Performance, Reliance, and One-Sided Information’, 18 Journal of Legal Studies, 365-401. Craswell, Richard (1992), ‘Efficiency and Rational Bargaining in Contractual Settings’, 15 Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy, 805-37. Craswell, Richard (1993a), ‘Property Rules and Liability Rules in Unconscionability and Related Doctrines’, 60 University of Chicago Law Review, 1-65. Craswell, Richard (1993b), ‘The Relational Move: Some Questions from Law and Economics’, 3 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal, 91-114. Craswell, Richard (1998), ‘Do Trade Customs Exist?’, in Krauss, Jody and Walt, Steven (eds), The Jurisprudential Foundations of Corporate and Commercial Law, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Craswell, Richard and Schwartz, Alan (eds) (1994), Foundations of Contract Law, New York, Oxford University Press. Danzig, Richard (1975), ‘Hadley v. Baxendale: A Study in the Industrialization of the Law’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 249-84. D’Ursel, Laurent (1985), ‘L’Analyse Économique du Droit des Contrats (Economic Analysis of Contract Law)’, 14 Revue Interdisciplinaire d’Etudes Juridiques, 45-88. Eisenberg, Melvin Aron (1992), ‘The Principle of Hadley v. Baxendale’, 80 California Law Review, 563-613. Farber, Daniel A. (1983), ‘Contract Law and Modern Economic Theory’, 78 Northwestern University Law Review, 303-339. Feinman, Jay M. (1983), ‘Critical Approaches to Contract Law’, 30 UCLA Law Review, 829-60. Feinman, Jay M. (1990), ‘The Significance of Contract Theory’, 58 University of Cincinnati Law Review, 1283-1318. Feinman, Jay M. (1993), ‘Relational Contract and Default Rules’, 3 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal, 43-58. Gillette, Clayton P. (1993), ‘Cooperation and Convention in Contractual Defaults’, 3 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal, 167-88. Gillette, Clayton P. (1990), ‘Commercial Relationships and the Selection of Default Rules for Remote Risks’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 535-81. Goetz, Charles J. and Scott, Robert E. (1980), ‘Enforcing Promises: An Examination of the Basis of Contract’, 89 Yale Law Journal, 1261-1322.
22
Contract Law: General Theories
4000
Goetz, Charles J. and Scott, Robert E. (1985), ‘The Limits of Expanded Choice: An Analysis of the Interactions Between Express and Implied Contract Terms’, 73 California Law Review, 261-322. Goldberg, Victor P. (ed) (1989), Readings in the Economics of Contract Law, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Goldberg, Victor P. (1984), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Lost-Volume Seller’, 57 Southern California Law Review, 283-97. Hadfield, Gillian K. (1994), ‘Judicial Competence and the Interpretation of Incomplete Contracts’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 159-84. Harris, Donald (1983), ‘Contract as Promise - A Review Article Based on Contract as Promise: A Theory of Contractual Obligation by Charles Fried’, 3 International Review of Law and Economics, 69-77. Harris, Donald and Veljanovski, Cento G. (1984), ‘The Use of Economics to Elucidate Legal Concepts: The Law of Contract’, in Daintith, Terence and Teuber, Gunther (eds), Law and the Social Sciences, Florence, European University Institute. Hermalin, Benjamin E. and Katz, Michael L. (1991), ‘Moral Hazard and Verifiability: The Effects of Renegotiation in Agency’, 59 Economica, 1735-1753. Hermalin, Benjamin E. and Katz, Michael L. (1993), ‘Judicial Modification of Contracts Between Sophisticated Parties: A More Complete View of Incomplete Contracts and Their Breach’, 9 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 230-255. Hillman, Robert A. (1988), ‘The Crisis in Modern Contract Theory’, 67 Texas Law Review, 103-136. Holderness, Clifford G. (1985), ‘A Legal Foundation for Exchange’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 321344. Horwitz, Morton J. (1974), ‘The Historical Foundations of Modern Contract Law’, 87 Harvard Law Review, 917-956. Hviid, Morten (1996), ‘Default Rules and Equilibrium Selection of Contract Terms’, 16 International Review of Law and Economics, 233-45. Johnston, Jason Scott (1990), ‘Strategic Bargaining and the Economic Theory of Contract Default Rules’, 100 Yale Law Journal, 615-64. Köhler, Helmut (1989), ‘Zur Ökonomischen Analyse der Regeln über die Geschäftsgrundlage (On the Economic Analysis of the Rules of the Implicit Basis of a Contract)’, in Ott, Claus and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (eds), Allokationseffizienz in der Rechtsordnung, Berlin, Springer, 148-162. Korobkin, Russell (1998), ‘The Status Quo Bias and Contract Default Rules’, 83 Cornell Law Review, 608-87. Kronman, Anthony T. (1980), ‘Contract Law and Distributive Justice’,89 Yale Law Journal, 472-511. Kronman, Anthony T. (1985), ‘Contract Law and the State of Nature’, 1 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 5-32. Kronman, Anthony T. and Posner, Richard A. (eds) (1979), The Economics of Contract Law, Boston, Little, Brown and Company. Lowry, S. Todd (1976), ‘Bargain and Contract Theory in Law and Economics’, 10 Journal of Economic Issues, 1-22. Macneil, Ian R. (1978), ‘Contracts: Adjustment of Long-Term Economic Relations Under Classical, Neoclassical, and Relational Contract Law’, 72 Northwestern University Law Review , 854-905.
4000
Contract Law: General Theories
23
Macneil, Ian R. (1980), The New Social Contract: An Inquiry Into Modern Contractual Relations, New Haven, Yale University Press. Macneil, Ian R. (1981), ‘Economic Analysis of Contractual Relations: Its Shortfalls and the Need for a “Rich” Classificatory Apparatus’, 75 Northwestern University Law Review, 1018-63. Marini, Giovanni (1990), Promessa ed Affidamento nel Diritto dei Contratti (Promise and Reliance in Contract Law), Napoli, Jovene. Perron, Edgar du (1990), ‘De Rechtseconomische Analyse van het Verbintenissenrecht (A Law-andEconomics Analysis of the Law of Obligations)’, 39 Ars Aequi, 770-776. Poughon, Jean-Michel (1990), ‘Une Constante Doctrinale: l’Approche Economique du Contract’, 12 Droits. Revue Française de Théorie Juridique, 47-59. Romani, Franco (1985), ‘Appunti sull’ Analisi Economica dei Contratti (Notes about the Economic Analysis of Contract Law)’, Quadrimestre, 15-29. Schwab, Stewart J. (1988), ‘A Coasean Experiment on Contract Presumptions’, 17 Journal of Legal Studies, 237-268. Schwartz, Alan (1992), ‘Relational Contracts in the Courts: An Analysis of Incomplete Agreements and Judicial Strategies’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 271-318. Schwartz, Alan (1993), ‘The Default Rule Paradigm and the Limits of Contract Law’, 3 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal, 389-419. Scott, Robert E. (1990), ‘A Relational Theory of Default Rules for Commercial Contracts’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 597-616. Simpson, A.W.B. (1979), ‘The Horwitz Thesis and the History of Contracts’,46 University of Chicago Law Review, 533-601. Symposium, ‘Default Rules and Contractual Consent’, 3 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal, 1-444. Verkerke, J. Hoult (1995), ‘An Empirical Perspective on Indefinite Term Employment Contracts: Resolving the Just Cause Debate’, 1995 Wisconsin Law Review, 837-917. Wang, William K.S. (1982), ‘Reflections on Contract Law and Distributive Justice: A Reply to Kronman’, 34 Hastings Law Journal, 513-527. Witt, Ulrich (1986), ‘Evolution and Stability of Cooperation without Enforceable Contracts’, 39 Kyklos, 245-266. Wonnell, Christopher T. (1986), ‘Contract Law and the Austrian School of Economics’, 54 Fordham Law Review, 507-543.
Other References Atiyah, P.S. (1979), The Rise and Fall of Freedom of Contract, Oxford, Clarendon Press. Atiyah, P.S. (1981), Promises, Morals, and Law, Oxford, Clarendon Press. Barnett, Randy E. (1986), ‘A Consent Theory of Contract’, 86 Columbia Law Review, 269-321. Brudney, Daniel (1991), ‘Hypothetical Consent and Moral Force’, 10 Law and Philosophy, 253-70. Buckley, F.H. (1988), ‘Paradox Lost’, 72 Minnesota Law Review, 775-827. Burton, Steven J. (1993), ‘Default Principles, Legitimacy, and the Authority of a Contract’, 3 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal, 115-66. Coleman, Jules L. (1980a), ‘Efficiency, Exchange, and Auction: Philosophic Aspects of the Economic Approach to Law’, 68 California Law Review, 221-49.
24
Contract Law: General Theories
4000
Coleman, Jules L. (1980b), ‘Efficiency, Utility, and Wealth Maximization’, 8 Hofstra Law Review, 509-51. Fried, Charles (1981), Contract as Promise: A Theory of Contractual Obligation, Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press. Fuller, Lon L. (1941), ‘Consideration and Form’, 41 Columbia Law Review, 799-824. Gauthier, David Peter (1986), Morals by Agreement, Oxford, Clarendon Press. Gordley, James (1991), The Philosophical Origins of Modern Contract Doctrine, Oxford, Clarendon Press. Gordley, James (1995), ‘Enforcing Promises’, 83 California Law Review, 547-614. Isaacharoff, Samuel (1996), ‘Contracting for Employment: The Limited Return of the Common Law’, 74 Texas Law Review, 1783-1812. Katz, Avery (1996), ‘When Should an Offer Stick? The Economics of Promissory Estoppel in Preliminary Negotiations’, 105 Yale Law Journal, 1249-1309. Muris, Timothy J. (1983), ‘Cost of Completion or Diminution in Market Value: The Relevance of Subjective Value’, 12 Journal of Legal Studies, 379-400. Perloff, Jeffrey M. (1981), ‘Breach of Contract and the Foreseeability Doctrine of Hadley v. Baxendale’, 10 Journal of Legal Studies, 39-63. Polinsky, A. Mitchell (1983), ‘Risk Sharing Through Breach of Contract Remedies’, 12 Journal of Legal Studies, 427-44. Posner, Richard A. (1980), ‘The Ethical and Political Basis of the Efficiency Norm in Common Law Adjudication’, 8 Hofstra Law Review, 487-507. Posner, Richard A. (1981), ‘A Reply to some Recent Criticisms of the Efficiency Theory of the Common Law’, 9 Hofstra Law Review, 775-94 Posner, Richard and Rosenfield, Andrew M. (1977), ‘Impossibility and Related Doctrines in Contract Law: An Economic Analysis’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 83-118. Quillen, Gwyn D. (1988), ‘Contract Damages and Cross-Subsidization’, 61 Southern California Law Review, 1125-41. Rea, Samuel A. Jr (1984), ‘Arm-Breaking, Consumer Credit and Personal Bankruptcy’, 22 Economic Inquiry, 188-208. Scanlon, Thomas (1982), ‘Contractualism and Utilitarianism’, in Sen, Amartya and Williams, Bernard (eds), Utilitarianism and Beyond, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Schwartz, Alan (1988), ‘Proposals for Products Liability Reform: A Theoretical Synthesis’, 97 Yale Law Journal, 353-419. Shavell, Steven (1991), ‘An Economic Analysis of Altruism and Deferred Gifts’, 20 Journal of Legal Studies, 401-21. Wolcher, Louis E. (1989), ‘Price Discrimination and Inefficient Risk Allocation Under the Rule of Hadley v. Baxendale’, 9 Research in Law and Economics, 9-31.
4100 CONTRACTUAL CHOICE Scott E. Masten Louis and Myrtle Research Professor of Business and Law, University of Michigan Business School © Copyright 1999 Scott E. Masten
Abstract This chapter discusses alternative theories of contract choice and design with special emphasis on (i) the interaction between contract design and contract enforcement and (ii) the explanatory power of alternative theories. After discussing the primary functions of contract, the entry reviews the assumptions and implications for contract design of the three dominant approaches to contracting in economics. An overview of the empirical literature on contracting and contractual choice identifies the main empirical regularities and their relation to the theory. A final section addresses implications for contract law and enforcement and directions for future research. JEL classification: D23, K12, D82 Keywords: Contracting, Contract Enforcement, Incentives, Transaction Costs
1. Introduction A contract, at its most basic level, is a legally enforceable agreement. Although economists - and occasionally lawyers - have used the term more expansively to describe essentially any transaction, the term contract as used in this chapter is reserved for formal, legal commitments to which each party gives express (though not necessarily written) approval and to which a particular body of law applies. ‘Breaching a contract’ differs from ‘canceling an order’, to use Stewart Macaulay’s (1963, p. 61) dichotomy. Ultimately, what distinguishes a contract from a mere transaction is the opportunity contracts afford transactors to invoke the formal dispute resolution machinery and coercive power of the state to enforce promises. Besides distinguishing true contracts from ‘implicit contracts’ or self-enforcing agreements, this definition of contract highlights the fundamental link between contract design, on the one hand, and contract enforcement, on the other: the choice of contract terms will depend in part on the legal rules and enforcement policies transactors expect courts to follow while, at the same time, the enforcement practices of efficiency-minded courts will depend on what courts perceive as the purpose and impediments to 25
26
Contractual Choice
4100
contracting. In short, the analysis of contract law and enforcement presupposes a theory of contracting behavior, and vice versa. Despite this interdependence, the literatures on contract design and contract enforcement have largely developed independently of one another. Economic theories of contracting, for the most part, give little explicit attention to enforcement issues, the presumption being that courts will see to it (subject only to verifiability constraints) that whatever terms contracting parties arrive at are fulfilled. Indeed, enforcing contracts as written is the court’s only function in mainstream contract theory (see, for example, Tirole, 1994). This judicial deference to contracts in economic theory contrasts with the far more intrusive role of courts in economic analyses of contract law, in which courts are called on to adjudicate disputes, fill gaps, and devise and implement default rules. Perspectives on contracting can be divided into three broad categories. The first consists of formal models associated with the principal-agent and asymmetric information literature, including theories of both complete and incomplete contracting; the second covers perspectives on contracting implicit in the law and economics literature on contract law and enforcement; while the third consists of what has come to be known as relational contracting theory, an approach often associated with transaction cost economics. Dimensions along which the theories differ include the functions of contracting, the impediments to contracting, and the role of courts and their implications for legal rules and contract enforcement. Last but not least, the theories differ in their ability to explain and predict actual contracting behavior.
2. Why Contract? As the definition in the introduction suggests, the essence of contract is commitment. Without some form of assurance that others will, when the time comes, uphold their end of a bargain, individuals will be justifiably reluctant to make investments, forego opportunities, or take other actions necessary to realize the full value of exchange. To be sure, reputation considerations - the prospect that trading partners will withhold future cooperation - often provide that assurance (Telser, 1980), especially in business transactions (Macaulay, 1963). But where the size or credibility of nonlegal sanctions is insufficient to constrain opportunism, contracting offers an additional recourse: by contracting, transactors expose themselves to legal sanctions for failing to honor their commitments. Beyond this basic commitment-enhancing function, contract theorists generally associate three broad motives with contracting: risk transfer, incentive alignment, and transaction cost economizing. In pure insurance or risk-transfer transactions, the objective is to shift risk to the less risk-averse
4100
Contractual Choice
27
transactor or ‘low-cost risk bearer’ (Cheung, 1969; Stiglitz, 1974). In incentive contracts, the aim is to align the parties’ (commonly, a principal and agent) individual incentives to take actions or reveal private information with their joint-surplus maximizing interests (for example, Hart and Holmstrom, 1987). Finally, transaction cost economists emphasize the use of contracts to reduce various costs of transacting, especially, ex post bargaining and ‘hold-up’ costs in transactions supported by relationship-specific investments (Williamson, 1975, 1979; Klein, Crawford, and Alchian, 1978) and ex ante sorting and search costs in contexts where additional information serves merely to redistribute rather than expand the available surplus (Kenny and Klein, 1983; Goldberg, 1985). While the essence of contracting is commitment, the design and interpretation of contractual agreements will depend on which of these three motives dominates.
3. Formal Economic Theories of Contractual Choice The search for contract terms that yield efficient outcomes is the subject of a prodigious theoretical literature in economics. The customary starting point for that inquiry is the complete contingent claims contract associated with the work of Arrow and Debreu (see, for example, Hart and Holmstrom, 1987). Although originally conceived as an analytical tool for modeling competitive equilibrium rather than as a theory of contracting per se (see Guesnerie, 1992), the efficiency properties associated with contingent trade in the Arrow-Debreu framework made complete contingent claims contracts - contracts specifying the physical characteristics, date, location, and price of a commodity for every future state of nature - appealing to contract theorists as an archetype against which to compare more realistic agreements: Arrow-Debreu complete contingent claims contracts represent what transactors would write in an ideal world free from ‘imperfections’. Mainstream contract theories developed specifically to analyze actual contracting practices fall into two categories depending on the nature and source of the ‘real world’ imperfections they emphasize. So-called complete contract theory analyzes the efficiency and contract design implications of the inability of courts to verify particular events or outcomes. Departures from the Arrow-Debreu ideal in complete contract theory thus derive from imperfections or limitations of adjudicators at the contract execution stage. Incomplete contract theory, in contrast, is concerned with the design and efficiency consequences of imperfections arising during contract formation, specifically, the limited capacity of transactors to anticipate, identify and describe optimal responses to future events.
28
Contractual Choice
4100
3.1 Complete Contracting The cornerstone of complete contract theory is the recognition that courts may not be able to verify some contingencies or outcomes and that contracting parties, therefore, may not be able to condition performance on every relevant contingency. The concern posed by nonverifiability is that, with the court no longer able to determine whether some aspect of promised performance has occurred, transactors stand to gain by strategically withholding information or by altering their behavior in ways that yield private benefits but reduce joint gains. In the standard terminology, the propensity to deviate from joint-surplus maximizing behavior in the presence of asymmetric information is called moral hazard when the distortion involves actions or information revelation ex post, and adverse selection where ex ante private information leads only those transactors with less desirable characteristics to transact (the so-called ‘lemons’ problem). The problem of contract design in the complete contracting framework consists of discovering a contingent payment schedule, or sharing rule, that is incentive compatible, that is, that satisfies the requirement that the contract leave the party with discretion over the unverifiable action at least as well off acting in the parties’ joint interests as taking any other feasible action. When only one party’s actions affect outcomes and that party is risk neutral, a contract that makes that party the residual claimant (and distributes expected gains to the other via a fixed payment) will be efficient. Nontrivial design tradeoffs arise when aligning one party’s incentives results either in inefficient risk sharing (if that party is also the more risk averse of the two) or in inefficient incentives for the other party (the case of double-sided moral hazard). In the latter settings, first-best outcomes will generally not be feasible. (Reviews of this literature can be found in Hart and Holmstrom, 1987, and Furubotn and Richter, 1998, among other sources.) Although contracts designed to elicit voluntary performance of unverifiable actions depart from the Arrow-Debreu ideal in leaving gains from trade potentially unrealized relative to the cooperative (nonstrategic) outcome, economists generally regard contracts optimally designed to deal with information asymmetries as complete in the sense that such agreements (i) still fully specify each party’s performance obligations for every possible contingency, and (ii) yield the best possible outcome given the information available to the courts at the time the agreement is carried out and thus ‘never need to be revised or complemented’ (Holmstrom and Tirole, 1989, p. 68). Despite the variety of settings in which risk sharing, moral hazard and adverse selection are potentially important (see below), complete contract theory’s performance as a positive theory has been disappointing. Aside from the broad prediction that efficient sharing rules will balance incentives for one party against inefficient risk bearing by that party or the incentives of trading
4100
Contractual Choice
29
partners, asymmetric information models yield few testable hypotheses. One reason for this is the ‘extreme sensitivity’ of optimal incentive schemes to slight changes in the relation between actual performance and verifiable information (Hart and Holmstrom, 1987, p. 105). Complete contract theory also fails to account for the observed simplicity of sharing rules in most real world contracts. Whereas the theory admits potentially detailed and complex payment rules specifying each party’s performance obligations for every possible contingency (in the case of discrete contingencies) and elaborate nonlinear pricing rules (in the continuous case), actual contracts incorporate few if any explicit contingencies and generally use simple, typically linear, pricing schemes (Holmstrom and Hart, 1987; Bhattacharyya and Lafontaine, 1995). Complete contract theory has also been faulted for its inability to distinguish between, and therefore account for the choice between, contracting and other institutional and organizational forms such as property rights and the firm. 3.2 Incomplete Contracting Contract theorists consider a contract incomplete, or to contain a ‘gap,’ if performance of the actual terms of the agreement would leave gains from trade unrealized given the information available to the parties and the courts at the time performance takes place (see, for example, Holmstrom and Tirole, 1989, p. 68; Tirole, 1994, p. 18). Under the assumption that transactors possess unlimited foresight and cognition, such an omission could never occur. Incomplete contract theory relaxes the extreme rationality assumption of complete contract theory and assumes that the limits on rationality that make courts less than fully omniscient apply to contracting parties as well: sophisticated but boundedly rational transactors will omit contingencies when the costs of anticipating, devising optimal responses to, and drafting provisions for improbable events outweigh the expected gains in efficiency from doing so. Departures from the Arrow-Debreu ideal may thus arise in incomplete contract theory from failures of the contracting parties to foresee and provide for contingencies in formulating their agreement, instead of or in addition to the inability of courts to verify performance. The prospect that contracts might leave gains unrealized raises an issue for the analysis of incomplete contracting that is not germane to complete contracting, namely, how, if at all, contracting parties respond to opportunities for mutually advantageous ex post adjustment. Two types of models can be distinguished: those that permit renegotiation ex post, and those that do not. (a) Models without Renegotiation Although linearity restrictions on sharing rules have often been imposed by complete contract theorists for tractability rather than theoretical or empirical reasons, exogenous restrictions on feasible contracts will, except under special conditions, lead to ex post inefficiencies.
30
Contractual Choice
4100
Accordingly, linear principal-agent contracts will in general be incomplete. (Not surprisingly, therefore, considerable effort has been applied to identifying the conditions under which linear contracts are sufficient for efficient outcomes; see, for example, Holmstrom and Milgrom, 1987; Bhattacharyya and Lafontaine, 1995.) Early principal-agent models mainly dealt with opportunities for mutually advantageous adjustment within linear contracts by ignoring them; contract terms were presumed to be definitive and immune to ex post bargaining, and any ‘residual loss’ from imperfect adjustment to changing events considered a component of ‘agency costs’ (Jensen and Meckling, 1976, p. 308; see also Matthewson and Winter, 1985; Allen and Lueck, 1992, 1993.) Because of their greater tractability and more realistic starting assumptions, linear agency models have been more successful than complete contract theories at generating predictions and explaining observed contracts. Settings in which moral hazard and adverse selection are likely to pose problems for contracting parties are numerous, and many relationships can be cast in principal-agent terms. Linear principal-agent models have been the primary framework for analyzing contract terms in franchising (Matthewson and Winter, 1985; Lal, 1990), agricultural share-cropping (Stiglitz, 1974; Eswaran and Kotwal, 1985), and product warranties (Priest, 1981; Cooper and Ross, 1985), among other settings. The linear agency model has also recently been extended to analyze multi-task settings in which agents perform either multiple activities or a single activity with multiple dimensions (Holmstrom and Milgrom, 1991). Formal tests of agency model predictions have proved difficult, however. The optimal sharing parameter that is the primary focus of these models depends on factors such as the relative risk aversion of the principal and agent and the relative effects of their actions on joint surplus. Because these factors are difficult or impossible to measure, acceptance of the model often turns on accepting the modeler’s risk preference and marginal productivity assumptions (Stigler and Becker, 1977; Allen and Lueck, 1995). More generally, heavy reliance by agency theorists on risk aversion to explain observed contracting practices has been criticized, especially in the context of commercial transactions, for diverting attention from other potentially more important considerations (see Williamson, 1985b, pp. 388-389; Goldberg, 1990). (b) Models with Renegotiation More recent models of incomplete contracting generally assume that transactors can negotiate to take advantage of any ex post gains on the grounds that (i) unrealized gains from trade create an incentive to renegotiate, and (ii) contract law generally allows modification of contract terms by mutual consent. Incorporating renegotiation into the analysis, however, requires a model of bargaining, a perennial difficulty for economic theory. The formal literature on incomplete contracting has generally circumvented that problem by assuming that the parties costlessly negotiate to
4100
Contractual Choice
31
the cooperative (Nash) outcome (Grossman and Hart, 1986; Hart and Moore, 1988; Lutz, 1995). The assumption of costless renegotiation assures ex post efficiency and thereby eliminates any role for contracts in establishing ex post incentives. Benefits may nevertheless accrue to contracting if either (i) transactors are risk averse or (ii) efficiency requires unverifiable ex ante investments. Even though the parties are free to modify their agreements by mutual consent, the ability of either party to enforce the contract’s original terms establishes the threat points in any subsequent negotiation. Hence, by contracting, transactors are able to influence the distribution of ex post surpluses and, thereby, the allocation of risk and expected return on investments. Incomplete contract theory has permitted formal analysis of alternative organizational and institutional arrangements, especially the existence and locus of property rights (for example, Grossman and Hart, 1986; Hart and Moore, 1990) for which the complete contract framework was unsuitable. In the eyes of some theorists, however, the gains in analytical scope come at the cost of generality. While sympathizing with the view that individuals are not capable of dealing with unlimited complexity, purists complain that, in the absence of an accepted model of bounded rationality, restrictions on feasible contract forms are unavoidably arbitrary and ad hoc (for example Tirole, 1994, pp. 15-17; Hart and Holmstrom, 1987, pp. 133, 148).
4. Contracting in Law and Economics In most respects, conceptions of contracting in law and economics conform to those in economic theory more generally. Like mainstream economics, the law and economics literature conceives of contracting as a device for communicating substantive performance objectives. As Goetz and Scott (1985, p. 265) describe it, contracting parties seek first ‘to negotiate a subjective understanding about the combination of underlying substantive rights that form the basis for mutually beneficial trade. What remains is an instrumental problem, that of formulating contractual terms that mirror the desired exchange.’ Like incomplete contract theory, law and economics also recognizes that limitations of language and foresight generally prevent transactors from drafting all-encompassing agreements, of which Arrow-Debreu contingent claims contracts are again the archetype (for example, Shavell, 1984; Schwartz, 1992a, 1992b; Ayres and Gertner, 1992, p. 730). As a consequence of these imperfections, contracts often contain gaps that leave performance under the contract potentially inefficient, thus creating opportunities for efficiencyenhancing adjustments. Where law and economics and economic treatments of incomplete contracting diverge is in the manner through which adjustments come about. In economic contract theories, courts mechanically enforce contract terms, and
32
Contractual Choice
4100
adjustments, if any, are accomplished through costless renegotiation. In law and economics, the courts, rather than the transactors, evaluate opportunities for adaptation and implement the necessary contractual modifications. In the typical scenario, one of the parties will find performance at the contractually specified price unprofitable and attempt to escape his contractual obligations, leading the other party to bring suit to enforce the contract. If the contract is incomplete and ex post bargaining is prohibitively costly, requiring performance as specified in the agreement will be inefficient on at least some occasions. By, instead, enforcing the contract in a way that corrects such defects, courts will enhance efficiency, first, by increasing the efficiency of performance ex post and, second, by reducing the need for transactors to formulate detailed agreements, and hence the cost of contracting, in the first place. In general, the law and economics literature on contract advises courts to complete incomplete contracts with terms the parties ‘would have bargained for’ themselves had the costs of anticipating and incorporating provisions for the event at hand been sufficiently low (see Chapters 4400 Implied Terms Interpretation; 4500 Unforeseen Contingencies - Risk Allocation; and 4600 Remedies). Since what the parties would have bargained for in the absence of imperfections encountered during contract formation is a complete contract, courts are essentially charged with discovering and implementing rules that yield the efficient outcome given the information available to (that is, verifiable by) the court (see Schwartz, 1992a, p. 281). Overall, law and economics offers a richer characterization of background legal rules and the role of courts in enforcing contracts from which economic theories of contracting could benefit. At the same time, legal scholarship on contracting can be faulted for not being more explicit about the purposes of contracting and the ramifications of contract law for contracting behavior. As Rubin (1996) observes, ‘When American legal scholars speak of “contracts” they typically do not mean contracts at all, but rather judicial decisions ... involving disputes about contracts. Contracts themselves, the transactions that create them, and the business decision to comply with them, renegotiate them, or breach them have rarely surfaced in the academic study of [contract]’ (as quoted in Williamson, 1996).
5. Relational Contracting Despite substantial differences in the roles they ascribe to courts, law and economics and economic contract theory operate under the ‘legal centralist’ assumption that courts perform their assigned functions in ‘an informed, sophisticated, and low-cost way’ (Williamson, 1983, p. 520). But whereas that function in economic theories of contracting entails enforcing explicit
4100
Contractual Choice
33
provisions, law and economics assigns courts the much more demanding responsibility of discovering contracting parties’ ‘real’ intentions and identifying opportunities for and implementing efficiency-enhancing adjustments. As Oliver Williamson (1985b, p. 201) has remarked, ‘Judgement based on detailed ex post knowledge of the particulars, including an examination of the magnitude of the profitability consequences that accrue, will often be the only way to ascertain whether an adjustment is warranted’ (compare Ayres and Gertner, 1989, pp. 116-117; Scott, 1990, pp. 600-601). The prescription that courts fill gaps in incomplete contracts with what the parties would have bargained for effectively presumes that courts possess such knowledge and the expertise to perform the substantive calculations the transactors would themselves have had to make to determine efficient performance. Law and economics’ confidence in the efficacy of court ordering and its emphasis on substantive performance contain a paradox, however: if courts are able to fill gaps accurately and costlessly, why would transactors ever incur the time and expense of drafting definite performance obligations in the first place? Instead, transactors could just indicate a vague intention to transact and let the courts fill in the details thereafter. In a world in which contract formation is costly and adjudication costless, a perfectly indefinite agreement, rather than comprehensive Arrow-Debreu bargains, becomes the ideal contract (see Charny, 1991, pp. 1840-1841). If transactors do specify definite performance obligations, it must be to reduce the cost or inaccuracy of court ordering. Explicit integration of adjudication costs into the analysis of contracting has two immediate implications for contract design. First, where transactors design contracts to avoid court ordering, the presumption that contract terms define the substantive outcomes the transactors wish to see take place is no longer justified. Transactors might reasonably prefer contract provisions that leave gains from trade unrealized, or that relegate sufficiently worthwhile adjustments to renegotiation or other forms of self help, over terms that specify the efficient course of action but increase the costs or likelihood of litigation. In such circumstances, express terms may have only an indirect, and possibly even a contradictory, relation to the parties’ substantive aims (for example, Masten and Snyder, 1993, pp. 60-63). Second, the existence of judicial imperfections opens the door to conduct designed to contrive cancellation, evade performance, or otherwise force a renegotiation of the existing terms. Unlike moral hazard, which is a passive response to price signals within an existing agreement, such behavior aims to exact a de jure modification of terms previously agreed to. Among the tactics available to a party seeking a redistribution of the gains from trade are suing for trivial deviations, ‘working to rule,’ and withholding relevant information in hopes of inducing breach (see Muris, 1981; Williamson, 1983, p. 526; Goldberg, 1985; Masten, 1988b). Contracts from this perspective do not so
34
Contractual Choice
4100
much define the terms of trade as determine the process through which the terms of trade are ultimately arrived at (Macaulay, 1985). As Victor Goldberg (1976, p. 428) has described it, the emphasis shifts from devising ‘a detailed specification of the terms of the agreement to a more general statement of the process of adjusting the terms of the agreement over time-the establishment, in effect, of a “constitution” governing the ongoing relationship’. Inasmuch as both regard contract terms as starting points for future negotiations, relational and incomplete contract theories bear a passing resemblance. The difference, however, is that renegotiation in the relational framework is costly and unilateral preservation of the contract’s original terms (including price) is neither certain nor free. An essential element of contract design, therefore, becomes structuring the relationship in a way that reduces the incentive to engage in wasteful efforts to evade performance or force a renegotiation (compare Williamson, 1983; Goldberg, 1985; Klein, 1992, 1995, 1996; Masten, 1988b). Contract terms will also be used to affect the extent of court ordering. Indefinite contracts that use terms such as ‘best efforts’, ‘gross inequity’, or ‘substantial performance’ to describe contractual obligations leave the parameters of acceptable performance ultimately to the courts. By contrast, contracts that specify precise performance obligations, define sanctions (such as liquidated damages or termination), and allocate discretion to invoke those sanctions unilaterally, shift the locus of decision making and adjustment, to the extent courts defer to written terms, from the courts to the transactors. Finally, a process orientation also highlights the interaction between judicial enforcement policies and contract design. To the extent that deviations between contract terms and transactors’ substantive intentions reflect efforts to economize on adjudication costs, judicial efforts to complete ‘incomplete’ agreements may frustrate rather than foster the parties’ intentions. The ability of contracting parties to achieve process objectives - to reduce court ordering through the use of more precise language, for example - depends on the extent to which courts are willing to defer to written terms.
6. Empirical Evidence on Contractual Choice Several reviews of the empirical literature on contracting have been published, the most recent of which are Shelanski and Klein, 1995; Crocker and Masten, 1996; Lyons, 1996, and Lafontaine and Slade, 1997, 1998. The following identifies some of the most prominent findings and regularities and their relation to the theories discussed above.
4100
Contractual Choice
35
6.1 Contracting and Contract Duration One of the most firmly established regularities in the empirical literature on contracting is the association between relationship-specific investments (or reliance) and the use and duration of contractual agreements. An early and well-known example is Joskow’s (1987) econometric analysis of the duration of nearly 300 coal contracts. Exploiting regional differences in the characteristics of coal and transportation alternatives and variations in contract quantity, Joskow’s study showed the duration of coal contracts to be significantly correlated with measures of physical- and site-specificity and dedicated assets. A more recent study of engineering subcontracting practices in the United Kingdom by Lyons’ (1994) suggests that specificity affects not only the duration of contracts but the decision to contract in the first place. The engineering firms and subcontractors in Lyons’ sample were significantly more likely to adopt formal contracts, over more flexible but less secure informal agreements, where investments in relationship-specific physical and human capital left the subcontractor vulnerable to ex post opportunism. Empirical research has also identified a correlation between long-term contracting and specificity in natural gas (Crocker and Masten, 1988); petroleum coke (Goldberg and Erickson, 1987); and ocean shipping contracts (Pirrong, 1993), among others. Contracting appears less attractive as a way of protecting reliance or relationship-specific investments, however, where the alternative to contracting is integrated ownership and production. Empirical research on integration decisions reveals a consistent preference for integration over contracting as the specificity of investments increases (for overviews, see Joskow, 1988; Shelanski and Klein, 1995; Crocker and Masten, 1996; and Chapter 0530 New Institutional Economics). Contracting thus appears to be only an imperfect response to the hazards posed by relationship-specific investments. Empirical research suggests, moreover, that the costs and limitations of contracting grow with the complexity and uncertainty of the transaction. In Lyons’ (1994) study of engineering transactions, for example, firms were less likely to use formal contracts for advanced technology projects than for relatively simple procurements. Meanwhile, Goldberg and Erickson (1987) and Crocker and Masten (1988) found that contract duration in petroleum coke and natural gas contracts decreased in periods of increased uncertainty, contrary to what would be expected if risk-sharing were the primary motive for contracting. Research on the determinants of make-or-buy decisions suggests that uncertainty and complexity diminish the attractiveness of contracting relative to integration as well (for example, Masten, 1984; Anderson and Schmittlein, 1984). Though clearly an important determinant, the protection of specific investments is not the sole motive for contracting. Unsupported assertions to the contrary notwithstanding, relationship-specific investments in franchising appear to be modest and unimportant as a motive for franchise contracting (see
36
Contractual Choice
4100
Lafontaine and Slade, 1997, 1998). Indeed, the viability of some contractual arrangements, such as franchising and equipment leasing, may depend on assets actually being redeployable at reasonably low cost (Klein, 1995; Masten and Snyder, 1993). Case studies have also shown benefits of contracting to accrue to the desire to control free-riding on the provision of information or services (for example, Rubin, 1978; Masten and Snyder, 1993) and to avoid unproductive search and sorting costs (Kenney and Klein 1983; Gallick, 1984). 6.2 Contract Design (a) Incentive Provisions The empirical literature offers broad support for the proposition that transactors choose contract terms to promote efficient adaptation and mitigate transaction costs. In contemporaneous studies of natural gas contracting, Masten and Crocker (1985) and Mulherin (1986) found that take-or-pay percentages in natural gas contracts varied with the alternative value of gas reserves, supporting an incentive interpretation over the alternative view that take-or-pay provisions serve distributional or risk-sharing purposes (for example, Hubbard and Weiner, 1986). Case studies describing the use of minimum purchase requirements for coal (Carney, 1978) petroleum coke (Goldberg and Erickson, 1987), and bauxite (Stuckey, 1983), among other products, corroborate this finding (see Masten, 1988a, pp. 91-92, for a discussion). In a related study, Crocker and Masten (1988) found that the prospect of inefficient adaptation associated with distortions in the size of take-or-pay provisions significantly reduced the willingness of parties to engage in long-term contracting. Incentive considerations also appear to be influential in determining sharing arrangements. Lafontaine (1992), for example, found that royalty rates across franchises tend to vary with the relative importance of franchisor and franchisee effort. Observed correlations between uncertainty and royalty rates (and the use of franchised versus company outlets) are inconsistent with the standard assumption of franchisee risk aversion, however. (Reviews of the empirical literature on franchise contracting can be found in Lafontaine and Slade, 1997, 1998). Risk sharing as a motive for contracting has fared poorly in other settings as well. Allen and Lueck (1992), for instance, conclude that the incidence of crop-share versus fixed-rent contracts between farmer-tenants and landowners are unrelated to the riskiness of crops. Similarly, Leffler and Rucker (1991) reject risk sharing as an explanation for why timber track owners and harvesters sacrifice the incentive advantages of lump-sum relative to royalty contracts in favor of the hypothesis that the use of royalty contracts on relatively remote and heterogeneous timber tracks reflects the desire to avoid wasteful pre-bid inspection under lump-sum contracts. Finally, Holmstrom and Milgrom (1991) interpret Anderson’s (1985) and Anderson and Schmittlein’s (1984)
4100
Contractual Choice
37
finding that importance of non-selling activities and difficulty measuring performance of sales agents explain manufacturer reliance on low-powered incentives as evidence that measurement costs in multitask settings are a critical determinant of the intensity of incentives in contractual relations (see also, Slade, 1996). (b) Relational Contracts Whereas most of the empirical contracting literature focuses on standard price and quantity provisions, research on relational contracting has sought to account for the widespread use of contracts that leave important terms like price and quantity indeterminate. Examples of such provisions include price renegotiation and ‘market out’ provisions in natural gas contracts (Crocker and Masten, 1991), ‘gross inequity’ provisions in long-term coal contracts (Joskow, 1985), termination-at-will and best-efforts clauses in franchise agreements (Hadfield, 1990), substantial performance requirements in construction contracts (Goetz and Scott, 1981), and other ‘open term’ agreements (for example, Gergen, 1992). Large-scale analyses of relational contract provisions have focused on methods of price adjustment. Crocker and Masten (1991), for instance, conclude from their study of price adjustment in natural gas contracts that circumstances favoring the use of long-term, fixed-quantity agreements favor the adoption of relatively indefinite price adjustment provisions over formulaic adjustment mechanisms that, although less costly to implement, are more likely to induce efforts to evade performance obligations in extreme situations. As Goldberg and Erickson (1987) note, greater reliance on renegotiation provisions in fixed versus variable quantity contracts is difficult to reconcile with incentive alignment motives. Crocker and Reynolds’ (1993) study of jet engine procurement contracts also found that price adjustment was likely to become less definite as performance horizons lengthened and technological uncertainty increased, while contractor litigiousness and the absence of alternative engine suppliers favored more definite price terms. The available evidence thus generally supports the notion that transactors’ choice of contract terms reflects a tradeoff between the specification costs and rigidities associated with specifying detailed performance obligations in uncertain or complex transactions, on the one hand, and the greater flexibility but higher expected cost of establishing the terms of trade ex post in less definite relational contracts.
7. Implications and Directions Economic research on contracting is important to both legal scholarship and practice. Contracting is a - perhaps the most - fundamental institution of legal as well as economic interaction (compare Williamson, 1996). At a practical level, the study of contracting stands to inform lawyers and lawmakers about
38
Contractual Choice
4100
the objectives of contracting parties and the sources of contractual failures. For lawyers, such knowledge can provide insights with which to help clients design more effective agreements. For legislatures and courts, understanding the functions and limitations of contracting is crucial to the formulation of appropriate legal rules and their application in individual cases. As noted previously, whether and how courts intervene in contractual relations will depend on the theory of contracting behavior to which they subscribe. Theories that place confidence in the ability of parties to effect private orderings either through ex ante specification of contingent performance or through low-cost, ex post negotiation will favor a policy of passive judicial enforcement, whereas theories that emphasize the behavioral and cognitive impediments to ex ante alignment and ex post negotiation without similar regard for the cognitive limitations of judges will tend to favor more active enforcement and intervention by the courts. As various commentators have noted, official contract law, as reflected in the United States in Section 2 of the Uniform Commercial Code and Restatement (2nd) of Contracts, has moved increasingly toward favoring more active judicial enforcement. Where once courts were discouraged from using extrinsic evidence in interpreting contractual obligations, modern contract law endorses an active enforcement policy, encouraging courts to interpret contractual agreements ‘in light of surrounding circumstances’. Despite this widely-noted shift, however, the evidence is that courts have been far from uniform in their approach to contract enforcement. In practice, courts as a group neither universally seek to discover the parties’ true intentions from the context of their agreement - as the Code and Restatement recommend - nor consistently defer to written terms (Goetz and Scott, 1985, p. 307; Schwartz, 1992a). Such variations, moreover, cannot be explained entirely by philosophical differences among courts; judicial enforcement policies appear to vary systematically across disputes, courts tending to enforce franchise and distributorship agreements more passively than contracts for intermediate goods between manufacturers and suppliers (see Hadfield, 1990, pp. 978-990; Schwartz, 1992a, pp. 271, 304-305; Farnsworth, 1990, p. 556). Further research on variations in judicial enforcement policies and the dimensions along which they vary is likely to shed additional light on the functions and limitations of contracting. Although there are indications that recent research on contractual choice has already begun to influence how courts think about contracting and resolve contract disputes (see, for instance, PSI Energy v. Exxon Coal, USA, 991 F.2d. 1265 (1993)), much more needs to be done before positive theories of contracting can provide a solid basis for normative prescriptions. Such basic questions as why transactors choose super-compensatory liquidated damages have yet to receive a fully satisfactory explanation. More subtle but important issues like the effects of contractual protections on the willingness of
4100
Contractual Choice
39
transactors to make relationship-specific investments are just beginning to receive scrutiny (for example, Saussier, 1998). Although theoretical tensions are likely to persist between those who value axiomatic rigor and those willing to invoke empirical regularities to develop testable predictions, on one issue at least, the two approaches appear to be converging, namely, that further progress on understanding contracting requires a better appreciation of the interactions of contract design and contract enforcement and the process functions of contracting (compare Tirole, 1994).
Acknowledgments Financial support from the Center for Research on Contracting and the Structure of Enterprises is gratefully acknowledged.
Bibliography on Contractual Choice (4100) Allen, Douglas W. and Lueck, Dean (1992), ‘Contract Choice in Modern Agriculture: Cropshare versus Cash Rent’, 35 Journal of Law and Economics, 397-426. Allen, Douglas W. and Lueck, Dean (1993), ‘Transaction Costs and the Design of Cropshare Contracts’, 24 Rand Journal of Economics, 78-100. Allen, Douglas W. and Lueck, Dean (1995), ‘Risk Preferences and the Economics of Contracts’, 85 American Economic Review, 447-451. Anderson, Erin (1985), ‘The Salesperson as Outside Agent or Employee: A Transaction Cost Perspective’, 4 Management Science, 234-254. Anderson, Erin and Schmittlein, David (1984), ‘Integration of the Sales Force: An Empirical Examination’, 15 Rand Journal of Economics, 385-395. Ayres, Ian and Gertner, Robert (1989), ‘Filling Gaps in Incomplete Contracts: An Economic Theory of Default Rules’, 94 Yale Law Journal, 96-114. Ayres, Ian and Gertner, Robert (1992), ‘Strategic Contractual Inefficiency and the Optimal Choice of Legal Rules’, 101 Yale Law Journal, 729-73. Baird, Douglas G. (1990), ‘Self Interest and Cooperation in Long-Term Contracts’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 535-596. Bernstein, Lisa (1996), ‘Merchant Law in a Merchant Court: Rethinking the Code’s Search for Immanent Business Norms’, 144 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1765-1821. Bhattacharyya, Sugato and Lafontaine, Francine (1995), ‘Double-Sided Moral Hazard and the Nature of Share Contracts’, 26 RAND Journal of Economics, 761-781. Carney, E.M. (1978), ‘Pricing Provisions in Coals Contracts’, in Rocky Mountain Mineral Law Institute, New York, Matthew Bender, 197-230. Charny, David (1990), ‘Nonlegal Sanctions in Commercial Relationships’, 104 Harvard Law Review, 373-467. Charny, David (1991), ‘Hypothetical Bargains: The Normative Structure of Contract Interpretation’, 89 Michigan Law Review, 1815-1879.
40
Contractual Choice
4100
Cheung, Steven N.S. (1969), ‘Transaction Costs, Risk Aversion, and the Choice of Contractual Arrangements’, 12 Journal of Law and Economics, 23-46. Cooper, Russ, and Ross, Thomas W. (1985), ‘Product Warranties and Double Moral Hazard’, 16 Rand Journal of Economics, 103-113. Crocker, Keith J. and Lyon, Thomas P. (1994), ‘What do “Facilitating Practices” Facilitate?: An Empirical Investigation of Most-Favored-Nation Clauses in Natural Gas Contracts’, 34 Journal of Law and Economics, 297-322. Crocker, Keith J. and Masten, Scott E. (1988), ‘Mitigating Contractual Hazards: Unilateral Options and Contract Length’, 19 Rand Journal of Economics, 327-343. Crocker, Keith J. and Masten, Scott E. (1991), ‘Pretia Ex Machina? Prices and Process in Long-Term Contracts’, 34 Journal of Law and Economics, 69-99. Crocker, Keith J. and Masten, Scott E. (1996), ‘Regulation and Administered Contracts Revisited: Lessons from Transaction-Cost Economics for Public Utility Regulation’,9 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 5-39. Crocker, Keith J. and Reynolds, Kenneth J. (1993), ‘The Efficiency of Incomplete Contracts: An Empirical Analysis of Air Force Engine Procurement’, 24 Rand Journal of Economics, 126-146. Eswaran, M. and Kotwal, A. (1985), ‘A Theory of Contractual Choice in Agriculture’, 75 American Economic Review, 352-67. Farnsworth, Alan (1990), Contracts (2nd edn), New York, Little, Brown, and Company. Furubotn, Eirik G. and Richter, Rudolf (1998), Institutions and Economic Theory: The Contribution of the New Institutional Economics. Ann Arbor, The University of Michigan Press. Gallanter, Marc (1981), ‘Justice in Many Rooms: Courts, Private Ordering, and Indigenous Law’, 19 Journal of Legal Pluralism, 1-47. Gallick, Edward C. (1984), Exclusive Dealing and Vertical Integration: The Efficiency of Contract in the Tuna Industry, Bureau of Economics Staff Report to the Federal Trade Commission, excerpted in Masten, Scott E. (ed), Case Studies in Contracting and Organization,Oxford, Oxford University Press. Gergen, Mark P. (1992), ‘The Use of Open Terms in Contract’, 92 Columbia Law Review, 997-1081. Goetz, Charles J. and Scott, Robert (1981), ‘Principles of Relational Contracts’, 67 Virginia Law Review, 1089-1151. Goetz, Charles J. and Scott, Robert (1983), ‘The Mitigation Principle: Toward a General Theory of Contractual Obligation’, 69 Virginia Law Review, 967-024 Goetz, Charles J. and Scott, Robert (1985), ‘The Limits of Expanded Choice: An Analysis of the Interactions between Express and Implied Contract Terms’, 73 California Law Review, 261-322. Goldberg, Victor P. (1976), ‘Regulation and Administered Contracts’, 7 Bell Journal of Economics, 426-448. Goldberg, Victor P. (1980), ‘Relational Exchange, Economics and Complex Contracts’, 23 American Behavioral Scientist, 337-352. Goldberg, Victor P. (1985), ‘Price Adjustment in Long-Term Contracts,’ 1985 Wisconsin Law Review, 527-543. Goldberg, Victor P. (1990). ‘Aversion to Risk Aversion in the New Institutional Economics’, 146 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 216-222. Goldberg, Victor P. and Erickson, John R (1987), ‘Quantity and Price Adjustment in Long-Term
4100
Contractual Choice
41
Contracts: A Case Study in Petroleum Coke’, 31 Journal of Law and Economics, 369-398. Reprinted in Masten, Scott E. (ed) (1996), Case Studies in Contracting and Organization, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Grossman, Sanford J. and Hart, Oliver D. (1986), ‘The Costs and Benefits of Ownership: A Theory of Vertical and Lateral Integration’, 94 Journal of Political Economy, 691-719. Guesnerie, Roger (1992), ‘The Arrow-Debreu Paradigm Faced with Modern Theories of Contracting: A Discussion of Selected Issues Involving Information and Time’, in Werin, L. and Wijkander, H. (eds), Contract Economics, Cambridge, MA, Basil Blackwell. 12-41 Hadfield, Gillian K. (1990), ‘Problematic Relations: Franchising and the Law of Incomplete Contracts’, 42 Stanford Law Review, 927-992. Hallagan, William (1978), ‘Self-Selection by Contractual Choice and the Theory of Sharecropping’, 9 Bell Journal of Economics, 344-354. Hart, Oliver D. and Holmstrom, Bengt (1987), ‘The Theory of Contracts’, in Bewley, T.R. (ed), Advances in Economic Theory, Fifth World Congress, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 369-398. Hart, Oliver D. and Moore, John (1988), ‘Incomplete Contracts and Renegotiation’, 56 Econometrica, 755-785. Hart, Oliver D. and Moore, John (1990), ‘Property Rights and the Nature of the Firm’, 98 Journal of Political Economy, 1119-1158. Holmstrom, Bengt and Milgrom, Paul (1987), ‘Aggregation and Linearity in the Provision of Intertemporal Incentives’, 55 Econometrica, 303-328. Holmstrom, Bengt and Milgrom, Paul (1991), ‘Multitask Principal-Agent Analyses: Incentive Contracts, Asset Ownership, and Job Design’, 7 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 24-52. Holmstrom, Bengt, and Tirole, Jean (1989), ‘The Theory of the Firm’, in Schmalensee, Richard and Willig, Robert D. (eds), Handbook of Industrial Economics, New York, Elsevier Science Publishing, 61-133. Hubbard, R. Glenn and Weiner, Robert J. (1986.), ‘Regulation and Long-Term Contracting in U.S. Natural Gas Markets’, 35 Journal of Industrial Economics, 31-79. Hubbard, R. Glenn and Weiner, Robert J. (1991), ‘Efficient Contracting and Market Power: Evidence from the U.S. Natural Gas Industry’, 3 Journal of Law and Economics, 25-68. Jensen, Michael C. and Meckling, William H. (1976), ‘Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behavior, Agency Costs and Ownership Structure’, 3 Journal of Financial Economics, 305-360. Johnston, Jason Scott (1990), ‘Strategic Bargaining and the Economic Theory of Contract Default Rules’, 100 Yale Law Journal, 615-664. Joskow, Paul L. (1985), ‘Vertical Integration and Long-Term Contracts: The Case of Coal-Burning Electric Generation Plants’, 1 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 33-79. Joskow, Paul L. (1987), ‘Contract Duration and Relationship-Specific Investments: Evidence from Coal Markets’, 77 American Economic Review, 168-185. Reprinted in Masten, Scott E. (ed) (1996), Case Studies in Contracting and Organization, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Joskow, Paul L. (1988), ‘Asset Specificity and the Structure of Vertical Relationships: Empirical Evidence’, 4 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 98-115. Joskow, Paul L. (1988b), ‘Price Adjustment in Long-Term Contracts: The Case of Coal,’ 31 Journal
42
Contractual Choice
4100
of Law and Economics, 47-83. Joskow, Paul L. (1990), ‘The Performance of Long-Term Contracts: Further Evidence from Coal Markets’, 21 Rand Journal of Economics, 251-274. Kaufman, Patrick J. and Lafontaine, Francine (1994), ‘Costs of Control: The Source of Economic Rents For McDonald’s Franchisees’, 37 Journal of Law and Economics, 417-543. Reprinted in Masten, Scott E. (ed) (1996), Case Studies in Contracting and Organization, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Kenney, Roy W. and Klein, Benjamin (1983), ‘The Economics of Block Booking’, 26 Journal of Law and Economics, 497-540. Klein, Benjamin (1980), ‘Transaction Cost Determinants of “Unfair” Contractual Arrangements’, 70 American Economic Review, 356-362. Klein, Benjamin (1992), ‘Contracts and Incentives: the Role of Contract Terms in Assuring Performance’, in Werin, Lars and Wijkander, Hans (eds), Contract Economics, Cambridge, MA, Basil Blackwell, 149-173. Klein, Benjamin (1995), ‘The Economics of Franchise Contracts’, 2 Journal of Corporate Finance , 9-37. Klein, Benjamin (1996), ‘Why Hold-Ups Occur: The Self-Enforcing Range of Contractual Relationships’, 34 Economics Inquiry, 444-463. Klein, Benjamin, and Leffler, Keith B. (1981), ‘The Role of Market Forces in Assuring Contractual Performance’, 89 Journal of Political Economy, 615-641. Klein, Benjamin, and Murphy, Kevin M. (1988), ‘Vertical Restraints as Contract Enforcement Mechanisms’, 31 Journal of Law and Economics, 265-297. Klein, Benjamin, and Saft, Lester F. (1985), ‘The Law and Economics of Franchise Tying Contracts’, 28 Journal of Law and Economics, 345-361. Klein, Benjamin, Crawford, R.A. and Alchian, Armen A. (1978), ‘Vertical Integration, Appropriable Rents, and the Competitive Contracting Proces’, 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 297-326. Knoeber, Charles R. (1982), ‘An Alternative Mechanism to Assure Contractual Reliability’,12 Journal of Legal Studies, 333-343. Laffont, Jean-Jacques, and Tirole, Jean (1988), ‘The Dynamics of Incentive Contracts’, 56 Econometrica, 1153-1175. Lafontaine, Francine (1992), ‘Agency Theory and Franchising: Some Empirical Results’, 23 Rand Journal of Economics, 263-283. Lafontaine, Francine (1993), ‘Contractual Arrangements as Signaling Devices: Evidence from Franchising’, 9 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 256-289. Lafontaine, Francine and Masten, Scott E. (1995), ‘Franchise Contracting, Organization, and Regulation’, special issue of the Journal of Corporate Finance. Lafontaine, Francine and Slade, Margaret E. (1997), ‘Retail Contracting: Theory and Practice’, 65 Journal of Industrial Economics, 1-25. Lafontaine, Francine and Slade, Margaret E. (1998), ‘Incentive Contracting and the Franchise Decision’, National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper 6544. Lal, R. (1990), ‘Improving Channel Performance through Franchising’,9 Marketing Science, 299-318. Leffler, Keith B. and Rucker, Randal R. (1991), ‘Transaction Costs and the Efficient Organization of Production: A Study of Timber-Harvesting Contracts’, 99 Journal of Political Economy, 1060-1087. Libecap, Gary D. and Wiggins, Steven N. (1984), ‘Contractual Responses to the Common Pool:
4100
Contractual Choice
43
Prorationing of Crude Oil Production’, 74 American Economic Review, 87-98. Lutz, Nancy A. (1995), ‘Ownership Rights and Incentives in Franchising’, 2 Journal of Corporate Finance, 103-131. Lyons, Bruce R. (1994), ‘Contract Specific Investment: An Empirical Test of Transaction Cost Theory’, 3 Journal of Economics and Management Strategy, 257-278. Lyons, Bruce R. (1996), ‘Empirical Relevance of Efficient Contract Theory: Inter-Firm Contracts’, 12 Oxford Review of Economic Policy, 27-52. Macaulay, Stewart (1963), ‘Non-Contractual Relations in Business: A Preliminary Study’, 28 American Sociological Review, 55-70. Macaulay, Stewart (1985), ‘An Empirical View of Contract’, 1985 Wisconsin Law Review, 465-482. Macneil, Ian R. (1974), ‘The Many Futures of Contracts’, 47 Southern California Law Review, 691-816. Masten, Scott E. (1984), ‘The Organization of Production: Evidence from the Aerospace Industry’, 27 Journal of Law and Economics, 403-417. Masten, Scott E. (1988a), ‘Minimum Bill Contracts: Theory and Policy’, 37 Journal of Industrial Economics, 85-97. Masten, Scott E. (1988b), ‘Equity, Opportunism, and the Design of Contractual Relations’, 144 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 180-195. Masten, Scott E. (1996), Case Studies in Contracting and Organization, New York, Oxford University Press. Masten, Scott E. and Crocker, Keith J. (1985), ‘Efficient Adaptation in Long-Term Contracts: Take-or-Pay Provisions for Natural Gas’, 75 American Economic Review, 1083-1093. Reprinted in Masten, Scott E. (ed) (1996), Case Studies in Contracting and Organization, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Masten, Scott E. and Snyder, Edward A. (1989), ‘The Design and Duration of Contracts: Strategic and Efficiency Considerations’, 52 Law and Contemporary Problems, 63-85. Masten, Scott E. and Snyder, Edward A. (1993), ‘United States v. United Shoe Machinery Corporation: On the Merits’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 33-70. Reprinted in Masten, Scott E. (ed) (1996), Case Studies in Contracting and Organization, Oxford, Oxford University Press; and 26 The Journal of Reprints for Antitrust Law and Economics, 1997. Matthewson, G. Frank, and Winter, Ralph A. (1985), ‘The Economics of Franchise Contracts’, 28 Journal of Law and Economics, 503-526. McAfee, R. Preston and Schwartz, Marius (1994), ‘Multilateral Vertical Contracting: Opportunism, Nondiscrimination, and Exclusivity’, 84 American Economic Review, 210-230. Milgrom, Paul and Roberts, John (1992), Economics, Organization and Management. Englewood Cliffs, NJ, Prentice Hall. Mulherin, J. Harold (1986), ‘Complexity in Long-Term Contracts: An Analysis of Natural Gas Contract Provisions’, 2 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 105-117. Muris, Timothy J. (1981), ‘Opportunistic Behavior and the Law of Contracts’, 65 Minnesota Law Review, 575-580. Palay, Thomas M. (1984), ‘Comparative Institutional Economics: The Governance of Rail Freight Contracting’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 265-87. Palay, Thomas M. (1985), ‘Avoiding Regulatory Constraints: Contracting Safeguards and the Role of Informal Agreements.’ 1 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 155-176.
44
Contractual Choice
4100
Pirrong, S. Craig (1993), ‘Contracting Practices in Bulk Shipping Markets: A Transaction Cost Explanation’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 937-976. Reprinted in Masten, Scott E. (ed) (1996), Case Studies in Contracting and Organization, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Priest, George (1981), ‘A Theory of the Consumer Product Warranty’, 90 Yale Law Journal, 1297-1352. Rasmusen, Eric, (1991), ‘Recent Developments in the Economics of Exclusionary Contracts’, in Khemani, R.S. and Stanbury, W.T. (eds), The Centenary of Competition Law in Canada, Halifax, Nova Scotia, The Institute for Research on Public Policy. Rogerson, William P. (1989), ‘Profit Regulation of Defense Contractors and Prizes for Innovation’, 97 Journal of Political Economy, 1284-1305. Rubin, Paul H. (1978), ‘The Theory of the Firm and the Structure of the Franchise Contract’, 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 223-233. Rubin, Edward L. (1996), ‘The Phenomenology of Contract: Complex Contracting in the Entertainment Industry’, 152 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 123-139. Salanié, Bernard (1997), The Economics of Contracts, Cambridge, MIT Press. Saussier, Stephane (1998a), ‘Duration and Transaction Costs: An Econometric Test’, 14 Recherches Economiques de Louvain. Saussier, Stephane (1998b), ‘Contractual Completeness and Transaction Costs: The Case of Électricité De France’, University of Paris I, ATOM, Working Paper. Saussier, Stephane (1998c), ‘Incomplete Contract Theory Meets Transaction Cost Economics : an Econometric Test’, University of Paris I, ATOM, Working Paper. Schwartz, Alan (1989), ‘A Theory of Loan Priorities’, 18 Journal of Legal Studies, 209-261. Schwartz, Alan (1992a), ‘Relational Contracts in the Courts: An Analysis of Incomplete Agreements and Judicial Strategies’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 271-318. Schwartz, Alan (1992b), ‘Legal Contract Theories and Incomplete Contracts’, in Werin, Lars and Wijkander, Hans (eds), Contract Economics, Cambridge, MA, Basil Blackwell, 79-108. Scott, Robert E. (1987), ‘Conflict and Cooperation in Long-Term Contracts’, 75 California Law Review, 2005-2053. Scott, Robert E. (1990), ‘A Relational Theory of Default Rules for Commercial Contracts’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 597-616. Shavell, Steven (1980), ‘Damage Measures for Breach of Contract’, 11 Bell Journal of Economics , 466-90. Shavell, Steven (1984), ‘The Design of Contracts and Remedies for Breach’, 98 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 121-148. Shelanski, Howard and Klein, Peter G. (1995), ‘Empirical Research in Transaction Cost Economics: A Review and Assessment’, 11 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 335-361. Shepard, Andrea (1993), ‘Contractual Form, Retail Price, and Asset Characteristics in Gasoline Retailing’, 24 Rand Journal of Economics, 58-77. Slade, Margaret (1996), ‘Multitask Agency and Contract Choice: An Empirical Explanation’, 37 International Economic Review, 465-486. Stigler, George J. and Becker, Gary S. (1977), ‘De Gustibus Non Est Disputandum’, 67 American
4100
Contractual Choice
45
Economic Review, 76-90. Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1974), ‘Incentives and Risk-Sharing in Sharecropping’, 41 Review of Economic Studies, 219-255. Stuckey, John A. (1983), Vertical Integration and Joint Ventures in the Aluminum Industry, Cambridge, Harvard University Press. Telser, Lester G. (1980), ‘A Theory of Self-Enforcing Agreements’, 53 Journal of Business, 27-44. Tirole, Jean (1994), ‘Incomplete Contracts: Where Do We Stand?’, Walras-Bowley lecture, delivered at the North American Summer Meetings of the Econometric Society, Quebec City. Werin, Lars and Wijkander, Hans (1992), Contract Economics, Cambridge, MA, Basil Blackwell Ltd. White, James J. (1982), ‘Contract Law in Modern Commercial Transactions, An Artifact of Twentieth Century Business Life?’, 22 Washburn Law Journal, 1-22. Williamson, Oliver E. (1971), ‘The Vertical Integration of Production: Market Failure Considerations’, 61 American Economic Review, 112-123. Williamson, Oliver E. (1975), Markets and Hierarchies: Analysis and Antitrust Implications, New York, The Free Press. Williamson, Oliver E. (1979), ‘Transaction-Cost Economics: The Governance of Contractual Relations’, 22 Journal of Law and Economics, 233-262. Williamson, Oliver E. (1983), ‘Credible Commitments: Using Hostages to Support Exchange’, 73 American Economic Review, 519-540. Williamson, Oliver E. (1985a), ‘Assessing Contract’,1 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 177-208. Williamson, Oliver E. (1985b), The Economic Institutions of Capitalism, New York, The Free Press. Williamson, Oliver E. (1996), ‘Revisiting Legal Realism: The Law, Economics, and Organization Perspective’, 5 Industrial and Corporate Change, 383-420. Reprinted in Medema, Stephen G. (ed.) (1998), Coasean Economics, Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers.
4200 LONG-TERM CONTRACTS AND RELATIONAL CONTRACTS Morten Hviid University of Warwick, Department of Economics © Copyright 1999 Morten Hviid
Abstract This chapter discusses the literature on long-term contracts and relational contracts. The central issues in the literature on long-term contracts are the effects of renegotiation and what these contracts can accomplish over and above a series of short-term contracts. The literature on relational contracts focuses on how self-enforceable terms can be supported without the use of enforceable contracts. Among the possible answers to this are repetition and norms. JEL classification: C72, D82, K12 Keywords: Long-Term Contracts, Renegotiation Proofness, Relational Contracts, Repeated Games, Norms
1. Introduction For contracts of a non-trivial duration, contract law faces the dilemma of, on the one hand, offering a means of commitment and, on the other, allowing for sufficient flexibility to adjust to changes in the environment. ‘This tension between the need to fix responsibilities at the outset and the need to readjust them over time permeates the long-term contractual relationship’ (Baird, 1990, p. 586). This tension is basic to both long-term and relational contracts. This entry discussed two classes of contracts, long-term contracts and relational contracts. Although closely related, neither is a subset of the other. Completely state-contingent long-term contracts are clearly not relational. Incomplete long-term contracts would in most cases be relational, although, as pointed out by Eisenberg (1995), they need not be. As regards relational contracts, ‘[t]wo features largely define what lawyers mean by a relational contract: incompleteness and longevity. Relational contracts govern continuing relations’ (Schwartz, 1992b, note 1, p. 271). However, as pointed out in Goetz and Scott (1981) a relational contract need not be a long-term contract, although in most cases it would be. 46
4200
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
47
The two literatures appear to address different issues and hence will be discussed separately below. The central issues in the literature on long-term contracts seems to be the effects or renegotiation as well as what can be accomplished by such contracts over and above what can be achieved by a series of short-term contracts. The literature on relational contracts assume that contract terms are not used and focus on how repeated interaction and social norms can ensure that obligations between parties can become self-enforceable.
A. Long-Term Contracts 2. Long-Term Contracts: General Summaries of the literature can be found in Bolton (1990), Hart (1987), Hart and Holmstrom (1987) and most recently in Salanié (1997, chs 6 and 7). For a recent survey focusing solely on labor contracts, see Malcolmson (1997). Following Salanié (1997, p. 150), a dynamic (long-term) contract is complete if ‘all variables that may have an impact on the conditions of the contractual relationship during its whole duration have been taken into account when negotiating and signing the contract’. This definition rules out any unforeseen contingencies which may arise during the duration of the contract. However, it does not rule out asymmetric information. If, for example, the principal can never observe the effort of an agent, the contract cannot stipulate a level of effort. According to the above definition, the contract is still complete if no information of future relevance will become available later on in the life of the contract. Some authors, such as Hart (1995) refer to this as a comprehensive contract, because ‘there will never be a need for the parties to revise or renegotiate the contract as the future unfolds’ (Hart, 1995, p. 22). For an early demonstration that long-term complete contracts can enable valuable commitment, see Grout (1984). In the case where complete contracts can be written, full commitment is always valuable, since a contract with full commitment can always mimic the outcome of any other contract with less commitment by committing to the same actions as lead to the outcome for the latter contract, see Salanié (1997, pp. 144-146). Commitment to a contract can either be broken by a unilateral deviation, namely breach, or multilateral deviation, namely renegotiation. In case of breach, one party has access to the legal system to either enforce the contract or to award damages. When using the legal system is costless, whether breach is actually possible depends on the breach remedies used by the court. If the remedy is specific performance, the contract can only be varied by mutual consent. If, as is more commonly the case, the remedy is expectation damages,
48
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
4200
one party can always decide to breach and pay the damages (see Chapter 4600 Contract Remedies: General). In the case of a multilateral deviation where both parties want to vary the contract term, it is in general not possible to hold the parties to the original contract by legal means. ‘[B]oth parties’ commitments are only as strong as their contracting partners’ desire to hold them to their original promises’ (Jolls, 1997, p. 203). Since commitment is valuable when complete contracts can be written, losses may occur if renegotiation at any point during the life of the contract cannot be prevented. Although Jolls (1997) does offer some suggestions for enforcing terms which both parties would later agree to vary, it would appear that renegotiation is difficult to rule out legally. This then leads to a focus on contracts which are renegotiation proof (see Dewatripont, 1989 and Bolton, 1990). One reason why there may be scope for renegotiation is that ex ante efficiency may require ex post inefficiency. For example, in order to separate out workers with different levels of unobservable productivity, the menu of contracts offered to the workers will generally not imply that all types get their first-best contract. However, once their type has been inferred from their choice of contract, it is (ex post) efficient to renegotiate these contracts. Doing so may make a renegotiated contract of a type A worker more attractive for a type B worker than the contract which ex ante was designed for type B and the original menu will no longer be fully separating. Thus removing the ex post inefficiencies may remove the incentives which ensured that the contract was ex ante efficient.
3. Renegotiation As pointed out among others by Bolton (1990, p. 304) ‘[i]t turns out that the role of and issues raised by renegotiation are somewhat different when the contracting problem is set in an environment of asymmetric information as opposed to an environment of symmetric but unverifiable information.’ The difference between the two cases relates to whether some ex post inefficiencies remain when renegotiation is possible. Asymmetric Information For the case of adverse selection, the value of commitment is very clear. Consider a dynamic contract between a principal and an agent, where initially the productivity of the agent is not known to the principal. In any separating equilibrium, the productivity of the agent will be known to the principal after the first period. For the ‘bad’ type of agent, separation involves a distortion leading to a lower utility in every period of the contract than would be the case if his true type was known. If the true type is really the bad type, the distortion
4200
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
49
can be removed after the first period when the agent’s type is known for sure. Hence if renegotiation is possible, it will take place - the contract is not robust against renegotiation. Moreover, since both parties want to renegotiate, it is difficult to see how the legal system can prevent this happening. Papers such as Dewatripont (1989) turn the focus on contracts which are renegotiation-proof, that is, contracts where there is never an incentive to renegotiation. With comprehensive contracting this is possible, because any incentive to renegotiate later could have been foreseen at the time of agreeing the original contract. As is shown in Dewatripont (1989), Hart and Tirole (1988), Laffont and Tirole (1987, 1990) the possibility of renegotiation slows down the speed of revelation. Essentially this is caused by a trade-off between speedy revelation and the damaging incentive to renegotiate. Moral Hazard For the case of moral hazard, the literature is less well developed. Fudenberg and Tirole (1990) consider a principal-agent model where there is a gap in time between the agent taking a hidden action and the outcome of this being known. If the principal can infer the agent’s action before the outcome is known, a renegotiation which perfectly insures the agent is optimal. However, if the agent realizes this, the incentive structure of the original contract is blunted. As in the case of adverse selection, information revelation has to be slowed down. In the moral hazard case this is achieved by the agent randomizing over its choice of action. The essential lesson from this model is that if renegotiation is possible after effort has been chosen, then the principal cannot make the agent choose the optimal effort for sure. Hence renegotiation again leads to an efficiency loss. Related papers in this area are Chiappori et al. (1994) and Ma (1991). Symmetric but Unverifiable Information Consider a contract on future trade between two parties. Because the information and hence the state of nature is unverifiable by a third party, a contract cannot be conditioned on this state. However, because information is symmetric, any negotiation of the sharing of the surplus in such a state will, given the symmetry of information, be efficient. Problems arise because the ex post sharing of the surplus need not be ex ante efficient. Contracts which are proof against renegotiation can still improve upon an allocation without any long-term contract by designing the environment of the renegotiation in the unverifiable state. Hart and Moore (1988) show how the ex ante contract can be constructed to affect the bargaining power of the two parties ex post. However, this literature is not as yet well developed, but other papers in this area are Aghion, Dewatripont and Rey, (1990) and Bolton (1990).
50
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
4200
4. Unforeseen Contingencies Because unforeseen contingencies may arise during the life of the contractual relationship, there is a need to fill in the consequent gap between obligations. Gap filling in general is discussed in Chapter 4000 (Contract Law). Renegotiation may be valuable as one would expect the contracting parties to be able to fill the gap at a lower cost than a third party, partly because the contracting parties can be assumed to have better information. As in the case of symmetric but unverifiable information, long-term contracts may allow the parties to at least partly design the environment under which the (re)negotiation takes place. In terms of modeling unforeseen contingencies, there is not as yet an agreed approach. What is clear is that at least for contract issues, simply treating unforeseen contingencies as events which occur with probability zero is not generally appropriate. If the contingency occurs with probability zero, the expected cost of not providing for it in a long-term contract is also zero, and hence the more flexible short-term contract would not appear to offer any advantage due to any unforeseen contingencies. For a survey of the state of the art as well as a discussion of incomplete contracts, see Dekel, Lipman and Rustichini (1998). The theory of residual control rights, developed in Grossman and Hart (1986) and Hart and Moore (1990), see also Hart (1995), offers one way in which we can approach the problem of modeling unforeseen contingencies. Residual control rights determine who has the right to decide on how a particular asset should be used whenever an unforeseen contingency occurs. Thus even if the actual event cannot be described, rules for who fills in the gap for a particular class of events can be described (see also Kreps, 1990). In general, in the case of unforeseen contingencies, the ability to renegotiate or put differently, contractual flexibility, may be efficiency enhancing rather than an added constraint.
5. Short-Term vs. Long-Term Contracts With asymmetric information, the possibility of renegotiation slows down info2mation revelation. This is equally true in the case where only a series of one-period (or spot) contracts can be signed, an effect known as the ratchet effect (see Freixas, Guesnerie and Tirole, 1985). What are then the fundamental differences between short-term and long-term contracts? The literature suggests that the performance of long-term contracts may differ from a series of short-term contracts for a number of reasons. The (transaction) costs of negotiating and policing one long-term contract may be lower than negotiating a series of short-term contracts. Long-term contracts
4200
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
51
may enable income smoothing if this is not available via credit markets. If regenotiation can be avoided, they also offer better commitment. Informational asymmetry may also favor long-term contracts. For a general discussion, see Hart and Holmstrom (1987). It is fairly obvious that differences in transaction costs may lead to differences in the performance of long-term and short-term contracts. Not only may the actual costs of writing the contracts be different, but if renegotiation is costly, the commitment aspect of long-term contracts may also be strengthened. This area does not appear to be well developed but see Dye (1985). In a principal-agent model of asymmetric information Malcomson and Spinnewyn (1988) show that, in the absence of renegotiation, long-term contracts can improve on short-term contracts only if they commit either the principal or agent to a payoff in some future circumstance which is lower than what could be obtained from a short-term contract negotiated if that circumstance occurs. Thus the long-term contract has to have some commitment value in order to be preferred to a series of short-term contracts. Similar results are obtained in Allen (1985). In the special case where the contracting parties have perfect information, Crawford (1988) shows that short-term contracting distorts investment decisions only when the efficient plan involves mainly sunk cost investment and the relationship plays a consumption smoothing role. In this case the main role for long-term contracts is to serve as a substitute for an efficient credit market. In a pure moral hazard principal-agent model, Chiappori et al. (1994) demonstrate that two conditions are necessary in order that there is no difference between what can be achieved by an optimal long-term contract and a series of spot contracts. Firstly, the long-term optimum must be renegotiation proof. This reduces the commitment value of a long-term contract. However, this is not sufficient. In addition, the spot contracts should provide efficient consumption smoothing. When the agent does not have access to credit markets, spot contracting does not allow for consumption smoothing and hence spot contracts cannot implement the long-term contract. However, if the agent has access to credit markets and the principal can monitor this, we do get spot implementation, a result also found in Fudenberg, Holmstrom and Milgrom (1990), Malcomson and Spinnewyn (1988) and Rey and Salanié (1990). The case where the agent has access to capital markets but where the access cannot be monitored is more complicated because the spot contract may involve more smoothing that the renegotiation-proof long-term contract. If consumption smoothing is a strong reason for preferring long-term contracts over short-term contracts, one might expect that in labor markets, the lower the wage, the more likely would be long-term employment contracts. This does not seem to be the case in reality. For this reason, Fudenberg, Holmstrom and Milgrom (1990) assume away any imperfect capital market
52
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
4200
influences and focus on problems caused by asymmetric information. They consider long-term contracts that cannot be renegotiated and set out the circumstances under which these have a value above a series of spot contracts or a contract which is renegotiation proof. Due to the asymmetric information, two types of adverse selection, which imply a value to the commitment of a long-term contract, can arise. The first case arises if the preferences of the principal and the agent over future contingent outcomes are not common knowledge. As was noted above, if more information about the agent becomes available over time, there may be scope for renegotiation. The second case arises when the outcome on some date $t$ conveys information on actions taken by the agent prior to that date. At date $t$, the principal, on the basis of this new information, may wish to punish or reward the agent for the past actions. However this is not possible if there is not a binding long-term contract. One of the main contributions of this paper is to make precise when there would be a benefit to ruling out renegotiation. The existing literature has demonstrated that even if renegotiation cannot be ruled out, long-term contracts may still dominate a series of short-term contracts. At the same time, the benefit of long-term contracts would be much enhanced if renegotiation could be at least limited.
6. Empirics Despite the huge problems of getting data, a substantial number of empirical studies have considered long-term contracts. A general survey and evaluation can found in Lyons (1996). An incomplete list of empirical case studies of long-term contracts include among others: Chisholm (1993) (the movie industry), Crocker and Lyon (1994), Crocker and Masten (1988, 1991) and Masten and Crocker (1985) (the design and duration of long-term contractual relationships for natural gas), Galassi (1992) (share contracts in early Renaissance Tuscany), Goldberg (1985a) (aluminium), Goldberg and Erickson (1987) (petroleum coke), Joskow (1985a, 1988, 1990) (contacts between electricity generators and coal suppliers), Lafontaine (1992) (franchising), Lyons (1994) (small subcontractors making specific inputs for customers in the engineering industry), Palay (1984) (rail freight).
4200
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
53
B. Relational Contracts 7. Relational Contracts: General The relational move appears to grow out of the empirical work by Macaulay (1963) with the origin of the term relational contract usually traced to MacNeil (1974). Given the impact of this work, it is surprising how few replications have been carried out to date. The best known of these is Beale and Dugdale (1975), but see also Kenworthy, Macaulay and Rogers (1996) and Esser (1996). The lack of replication is a concern because the modest sample sizes in these studies imply that the results are not generally statistically significant. For example, Macaulay’s sample was 68 businessmen and lawyers representing 43 companies and 6 law firms whereas Beale and Dugdale’s sample was 33 individuals in 19 firms of engineering manufacturers. Although in both cases the authors are careful to point out the potential weaknesses of their data, studies which rely on their results for motivation are less careful to point this out. The main empirical observation of relevance to the relational contract literature was that firms within the same industry tended to resort to neither contract terms nor contract law to settle disputes about obligations. Although persuasive, neither Macaulay (1963) nor Beale and Dugdale (1975, p. 47) offer any tests of statistical significance. Beale and Dugdale (1975, p. 47) do offer an insight into when the result did not hold, namely when firms in the sample were transacting with ‘outsiders’. ‘Firms frequently stated that they would take much greater care when contracting with relatively unknown parties, especially those outside the engineering trade’ (Beale and Dugdale, 1975, p. 47). From these studies it would appear that contracts have little relevance where the parties ‘knew’ each other. To aid a discussion of the contribution of relational contract scholarship, a clear definition of what is a relational contract would be helpful. However, although several have to date been offered, most of which are discussed in Eisenberg (1995), none appear to be universally accepted. Goetz and Scott (1981) argue that what makes a contract relational is that there are states of the world where obligations cannot ex ante be defined. ‘A contract is relational to the extent that the parties are incapable of reducing important terms of the arrangement to well-defined obligations. Such definitive obligations may be impractical because of the inability to identify uncertain future conditions or because of inability to characterize complex adaptations adequately even when the contingencies themselves can be identified in advance’ (Goetz and Scott, 1981, p. 1091). The central role for the relationship between the contracting parties for the duration of the contract would appear to be the manner in which a gap is filled.
54
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
4200
MacNeil, in a series of papers (MacNeil, 1974, 1978, 1981a, 1987a), highlights the importance of two principles of behaviour: solidarity and reciprocity. ‘Getting something back for something given neatly releases, or at least reduces, the tension in a creature desiring to be both selfish and social at the same time; and solidarity - a belief in being able to depend on another permits the projection of reciprocity through time’ (MacNeil, 1987a, pp. 274-275). The importance of these have been tested in Kaufmann and Stern (1988), who study how firms react to breach by a trading partner. They demonstrate how firms are initially very forgiving in order to maintain the relationship, but that once they judge that the partner has acted opportunistically, their attitude changes dramatically. For a discussion of this and other empirical work on relational contracts, see Lyons (1996, pp. 45-49). Relational contract theory can be seen as an attempt to generate a model able to explain when transacting parties do not resort to contracts and by what means they ensure that each party fulfils their obligations. The theory focuses on the relationship between the ‘contracting’ parties and posits that this leads to cooperation and to implicit obligations being self-enforcing. In the extreme, no formal contract is needed to ensure that all gains from a particular transaction are realized. The theory rests on repeated interaction within a particular well-defined group together with a set of norms governing the behaviour of the group members. Whereas the literature on long-term contracts focuses on the problems which arise because of incompleteness and the potential for renegotiation, the theory of relational contracts focuses on the relationship between the contracting parties which ensures that opportunistic behaviour does not arise. Unless we assume that individuals are naturally cooperative, the next step is to determine how cooperation might emerge anyway.
8. Endogenous Cooperation One way to understand the observations in Macaulay (1963), as well the attempts to define a relational contract, is as follows. If having the reputation of either keeping to a contract term, or modifying or bargaining to fill a gap in good faith, is sufficiently important (or valuable), the law is not needed to enforce this term. Reputation is valuable either when interacting with the same individual on several occasions or when interacting sequentially with several individuals. In a relational contract, the parties rely on each other to behave in a cooperative manner for the duration of the contract, rather than exploiting any opportunity which may come along. ‘Parties who enter contracts desire coordinated, and hence cooperative, actions on the part of their contracting opposites. Therefore, the principal measure of the success of our contract law is whether it in fact induces cooperation’ (Baird, 1990, p. 584).
4200
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
55
The remainder of this section considers briefly how and when cooperation can occur endogenously among, to follow MacNeil, creatures desiring to be both selfish and social at the same time. The discussion makes clear how norms can play an important role in this theory. The Folk Theorem and Repeated Games Repeated games consider the possibility of achieving cooperation through self-enforcing (possibly tacit) agreements. These are discussed more extensively in Chapter 0550 (Game Theory Applied to Law), see also Baird, Gertner and Picker (1995) and Hirshleifer (1994). Consider a game where the non-cooperative Nash equilibrium is Pareto dominated by another outcome. This is, for example, the case in the Prisoner’s Dilemma, or in a game where A must decide whether or not to lend B money and B must subsequently decide whether or not to pay A back. If the parties could write a binding contract, they could clearly implement a better outcome for both. If that is not the case, any (tacit) agreement to cooperate must be self-enforceable. Repeated interaction may enable cooperation, because of the potential for a current deviation to be punished in the future. For this to work, four conditions must be met. Any deviation must be observable and it must be punishable. This punishment must be credible so that it is clear that when required the punishment will be carried out, and the parties must be patient in the sense that the future matters to them. The folk theorem for repeated games, loosely speaking, states that if the players are sufficiently patient and the game is repeated for a sufficient number of periods, the players can cooperate to obtain a better outcome than the non-cooperative Nash equilibrium of the one-period game. Put differently, the short-term gain from deviation is more than offset by the present discounted value of the future punishment. The folk theorem generalizes to many different settings. Cases where there are uncertainty, informational asymmetries, differences in the identity of the players, overlapping generations of players and random matching between players can all give rise to folk theorem-type outcomes. Thus, for example, the repeated interaction does not have to be between the same two individuals over time. In order to cooperate, the parties have to ‘agree’ on two issues: which cooperative outcome should be support and which punishment should be used in case of a deviation. Although this agreement could be tacit, when we are talking about contractual relationships it is more natural to think of this as an explicit agreement. Not only are there typically many outcomes which could be supported, but each outcome may also be supportable by many different forms of punishment. Of the latter, the best known are Tit-for-Tat (each player in this period does what the other player did in the last period), the (Grim) Trigger Strategy (deviation is followed by non-cooperation in all future periods) and
56
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
4200
Stick and Carrot (severe punishment followed by forgiveness). Because there are many different potential punishments, norms may pay a crucial role in selecting which path is used. This is particularly important where the cooperation is between many different individuals over time. If A is willing to cooperate with or trust B because B cooperated with many other individuals in the past it is important that A understands if and when B is being punished. For more on this see Chapter 0780 (Non-legal Sanctions). Thus the theory would predict that cooperation is more likely between fairly homogeneous groups. There are cases where repetition does not admit cooperation. The most notable case is when the number of periods over which the game is played is finite and known, where the equilibrium of the one-period game is unique and where the exact characteristics of the players are known to all players. In the last period defection will occur because there is no future in which to punish this. But then cooperation in the penultimate period cannot be supported by a combination of a credible promise of cooperation in the last period combined with a threat of defection in the last period as a punishment. Much is made of this in Jolls (1997). However, if just one of the three conditions is violated, cooperation may emerge. If there is an uncertainty about whether this period is the last, then there is still a potential future and hence a future punishment to worry about if a player decides to deviate. If the stage game has multiple equilibria, cooperation may be possible because a credible threat consisting of the ‘worst’ equilibrium can be issued. If there is some small chance that one of the players is not a rational economic actor at all, but is an irrational type who will cooperate regardless, the rational type may prefer to maintain a reputation for being irrational. Some of the punishments which supports cooperative outcomes harm both the guilty and the innocent. In such cases, the innocent has an incentive to accept any request for forgiveness, which would destabilize the cooperative agreement as deviations from cooperation are not punished. Although there is no formal contract, this problem is one of renegotiation resembling that encountered in long-term contracts. A social norm entailing punishment for cheaters would clearly support cooperation. On the other hand, a social norm of forgiveness would not. Relational Contracts and Repeated Games Scott (1987b) represents an early, if incomplete, attempt to model long-term contracts as a repeated game. Unfortunately the paper does not fully utilize the then available theory on repeated games. Scott recognises that cooperation may arise without any contracts at all and points out that legal rules can affect both the formation of the contract (‘the initial risk allocation’) and later adjustments to the contract, but argue that the greater effect is on the initial risk allocation. This effect comes via implied terms and express invocations. Scott highlights
4200
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
57
the importance of norms, in particular the norm of ‘reciprocity’. The analysis is summarized as follows: Contracting parties use a mix of legal and extralegal mechanisms, as well as patterned and individualized responses, to ameliorate the information and enforcement deficits that threaten emergent patterns of cooperation. Nevertheless, contractual breakdowns are inevitable. Patterns of cooperation in contractual relationships are inherently unstable, especially where one party is threatened with substantial losses (or tempted with substantial gains). Where necessary adjustments are of lesser magnitude, however, social norms aimed at introducing long-term cooperation will often prompt adjustment, and legal rules provide appropriately remote, but harsh, deterrents and incentives. (Scott, 1987b, p. 2049)
Other attempts to model relational contracts using repeated games are found in Baird (1990), Baird, Gertner and Picker (1995), Campbell and Harris (1993), Hviid (1996, 1998) and, for an example of the use of experimental methods, Hackett (1994). One insight from the theory of repeated games is that successful cooperation does not necessarily involve observing either deviations or punishments. This does not reduce the importance of the punishment because it is what keeps opportunism in check. Contract law potentially affects the available punishments, their severity and the gains from deviation. Hadfield (1990) notes that in franchise contracts courts consistently fill gaps to the benefit of one side of the contract (the franchisor). This may severely hamper the ability of the franchisor to credibly promise to act in good faith. Contract terms also affect the ability to punish. The severity of the punishment can be increased by leaving the contract more incomplete than necessary (see Bernheim and Whinston, 1998; Hviid, 1998). Other examples are terms implying expensive third-party arbitration, rights to terminate the contract (for example, franchises), or demands of performance under the contract. All these terms can make non-cooperative behaviour potentially costly. Thus contract law and contract terms may matter even in relational contracts which are substantially relying on self-enforceable agreements and where the law is not seen to be used. Repetition may not in itself be sufficient to ensure cooperation. In some cases this depends on the available institutions. An interesting combination of repeated games and institutional design as a means to overcome incentives for short-term opportunistic behaviour is found in Greif, Milgrom and Weingast, (1994). They model the emergence of merchant guilds in the late medieval period as a response to the incentives of the ruler of a trade centre to opportunistically appropriate rents from some of the traders. In their model repetition as such is insufficient to ensure cooperative behaviour by a ruler because the ruler can abuse individual traders, whose threat of punishing the
58
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
4200
ruler by staying away from the centre is non-credible if most of the other relevant traders do not know about the abuse and hence continue to use the trading centre. Strong merchant guilds can credibly initiate a collective punishment (a boycott for a given period) by coordinating the actions of its members. One relevant lesson for relational contract theory is that institutions may still matter. Moreover, the institution of the guild had an effect even if a boycott was never observed in the same way that legal institutions may have an effect even if they are never seen to be active. Finally, what might on the face of it appear to be a mixture of relational and written contracts has been considered in Klein (1996), who argues that court enforcement and private enforcement need not be alternative contract enforcement mechanisms, but may be complements. The former may on its own generate too much rigidity, making it possible for one party to ‘hold-up’ the other when conditions change radically (one has to think of such radical changes as being insufficient to excuse performance, but radical enough that they were not covered by the original contract). The latter generates too much flexibility. The idea of Klein (1996) is that private enforcement creates a range of self-enforcement. So long as the change to the environment does not place the gains from a hold-up outside what can be negated by private punishment, the hold-up will not occur. Court-enforceable contract terms can be used to change this range, either by extending it, by shifting it, or by affecting the probability distribution over the value of a hold-up. It is in this way that court and private enforcement becomes complementary. It is worth noting that unless the definition of a relational contract is weakened, it does not seem that the framework in Klein (1996) provides an economic justification for relational contracts since the contract terms which have been agreed must be enforced, that is, there is nothing relational about that part of the contract. Moreover, if the courts fail to enforce the terms of a contract literally, then this may paradoxically create more scope for hold-ups.
9. Concluding Remarks The impact of the relational contract theory on the economic literature on incomplete long-term contracts as well as mainstream law appears to date to have been relatively modest. This may partly be because ‘it is impossible to locate, in the relational-contract literature, a definition that adequately distinguishes relational and non-relational contracts in a legally operational way - that is, in a way that carves out a set of special well-specified contracts for treatment under special well-specified rules’ (Eisenberg, 1995, p. 291; see also Craswell and Schwartz, 1994, p. 199). If this is not the case, there appears little point to making the distinction and given the lack of a common jargon
4200
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
59
between economics and law, it is not clear what would be achieved by relabelling contracts. The main contribution of the relational contract theory so far would appear to be to highlight the potential importance of the relationship between the contracting parties and the social groups to which these belong, including the importance of norms and non-legal sanctions. However, the success or failure of transacting does not solely depend on the relationship between the contracting parties, because contracts also play a significant role. A fruitful way to look at contracts would be as a combination of legally enforceable and self-enforceable obligations. This recognises that whereas some obligations need to be self-enforceable because third parties cannot verify the facts giving rise to a particular obligation, others need to be self-enforceable because of the (transactions) space costs of using the legal system. Moreover, in order to cope with unforeseen contingencies, the parties may either rely on each other to handle the new situation in good faith, or, by using the contract to allocate residual control rights, place the onus on a particular party. The paper by Klein (1996) is a promising step in that direction, offering the possibility of a more balanced view between incomplete contract theory and relational contract theory.
Acknowledgements I would like to thank David Campbell, Bruce Lyons and an anonymous referee for helpful comments on the first draft. They are naturally blameless for any remaining errors and shortcomings.
Bibliography on Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts (4200) Acheson, James M. (1985), ‘The Maine Lobster Market: Between Market and Hierarchy’, 1 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 385-398. Adams, Michael (1988), ‘Franchising - A Case of Long-Term Contracts: Comment’, 144 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 145-148. Adelstein, Richard P. (1991), ‘Deciding for Bigness: Constitutional Choice and the Growth of Firms’, 2(1) Constitutional Political Economy, 7-30. Aghion, Philippe, Dewatripont, Mathias and Rey, Patrick (1990), ‘On Renegotiation Design’, 34 European Economic Review, 322-329. Aivazian, Varouj A., Trebilcock, Michael J. and Penny, Michael (1984), ‘The Law of Contract Modifications: The Uncertain Quest for a Benchmark of Enforceability’, 22 Osgoode Hall Law Journal, 173-212. Reprinted in Goldberg, Victor P. (ed.) (1989), Readings in the Economics of Contract Law, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 207.
60
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
4200
Allen, Franklin (1985), ‘Repeated Principal-Agent Relationships with Lending and Borrowing’, 17 Economic Letters, 27-31. Arvan, Lanny and Leite, A.P.N. (1990), ‘Cost Overruns in Long-term Projects’, 8 International Journal of Industrial Organization, 443-467. Azariadis, Costas (1988), ‘Human Capital and Self-Enforcing Contracts’, 90 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 507-528. Baird, Douglas G. (1990), ‘Self-Interest and Cooperation in Long-Term Contracts’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 583-596. Baird, Douglas G., Gertner, Robert, H. and Picker, Randal C. (1995), Game Theory and the Law, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Barnett, Randy E. (1992), ‘Conflicting Visions: A Critique of Ian Macneil’s Relational Theory of Contracts’, 78 Virginia Law Review, 1175-1206. Beale, H. and Dougdale, Tony (1975), ‘Contracts Between Businessmen: Planning and the Use of Contractual Remedies’, 2 British Journal of Law and Society, 45-60. Bendor, Jonathan and Mookherjee, Dilip (1990), ‘Norms, Third-Party Sanctions, and Cooperation’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 33-63. Bernheim, B. Douglas and Whinston, Michael D. (1998), ‘Incomplete Contracts and Strategic Ambiguity ‘, 88 American Economic Review, 902-932 . Bernstein, Lisa (1992), ‘Opting out of the Legal System: Extralegal Contractual Relations in the Diamond Industry’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 115-157. Bernstein, Lisa (1996), ‘Merchant Law in a Merchant Court: Rethinking the Code’s Search for Immanent Business Norms’, 144 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1765-1821. Bester, Helmut (1989), ‘Incentive-Compatible Long-Term Contracts and Job Rationing’, 7 Journal of Labor Economics, 238-255. Bishop, William and Prentice, D.D. (1983), ‘Some Legal and Economic Aspects of Fiduciary Remuneration’, 46 Modern Law Review, 289 ff. Blair, Roger D. and Kaserman, David L. (1987), ‘A Note on Bilateral Monopoly and Formula Price Contracts’, 77 American Economic Review, 460-463. Blegvad, Britt-Mari (1990), ‘Commercial Relations, Contract, and Litigation in Denmark: A Discussion of Macaulay’s Theories’, 24 Law and Society Review, 397-411. Bolton, Patrick (1990), ‘Renegotiation and the Dynamics of Contract Design’, 34 European Economic Review, 303-310. Boudreaux, Donald J. and Ekelund, Robert B., Jr (1987), ‘Regulation as an Exogenous Response to Market Failure: A Neo-Schumpeterian Response’, 143 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 537-554. Bowers, James W. and Bigelow, John P. (1996), The Economics of Relationships and the Limits of the Law, Louisiana State University, Law and Economics Working Group. Brinig, Margaret F. (1994a), ‘Status, Contract and Covenant’, 79 Cornell Law Review, 1573-1602. Brinig, Margaret F. (1994b), ‘Comment on Jana Singer’s Alimony and Efficiency’, 83 Georgetown Law Journal, 2461-2479. Brinig, Margaret F. (1996), ‘The Family Franchise, Elderly Parents and their Adult Siblings’, Utah Law Review, 393 ff. Brinig, Margaret F. and Carbone, June R. (1988), ‘The Reliance Interest in Marriage and Divorce’, 62 Tulane Law
4200
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
61
Brinig, Margaret F. and Crafton, Steven M. (1994), ‘Marriage and Opportunism’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 869-894. Broadman, Harry G. and Toman, Michael A. (1986), ‘Non-Price Provisions in Long-Term Natural Gas Contracts’, 62 Land Economics, 111-118. Butler, Henry N. and Baysinger, Barry D. (1983), ‘Vertical Restraints of Trade as Contractual Integration: a Synthesis of Relational Contracting Theory, Transaction-Cost Economics and Organization Theory’, 32 Emory Law Journal, 1009-1109. Campbell, David (1990), ‘The Social Theory of Relational Contract: Macneil as the Modern Proudhon’, 18 International Journal of the Sociology of Law, 75-95. Campbell, David (1992), ‘The Undeath of Contract: A Study in the Degeneration of a Research Programme’, 22 The Hong Kong Law Journal, 20-47. Campbell, David (1996), ‘The Relational Constitution of the Discrete Contract’, in Campbell, David and Vincent-Jones, Peter (eds), Contract and Economic Organisation: Socio-legal Initiatives, Aldershot, Dartmouth, 40-66. Campbell, David (1997), ‘Socio-legal Analysis of the Law of Contract in the U.K.’, in Thomas, Philip A. (ed.), Socio-legal Studies, Aldershot, Dartmouth, 239-278. Campbell, David (1997), ‘The Relational Constitution of Contract and the Limits of “Economics”: Kenneth Arrow on the Social Background of Markets’, in Deakin, Simon and Michie, Jonathan (eds), Contracts, Co-operation and Competition: Studies in Economics, Management and Law, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Campbell, David (1997), ‘Law and Economics and its Relationship to Sociology’, in Tomasic, Roman (ed.), The Sociology of Law, 2nd edn, London, Sage. Campbell, David and Clay, Susan (1995), Long-Term Contracting: A Research Bibliography and Review of the Literature, Oxford, Centre for Socio-Legal Studies. Campbell, David and Harris, Donald R. (1993), ‘Flexibility in Long-term Contractual Relationships: The Role of Co-operation’, 20 Journal of Law and Society, 166-191. Campbell, David and Vincent-Jones, Peter (1997),Contract and Economic Organisation: Socio-legal Initiatives, Aldershot, Dartmouth. Canes, Michael E. and Norman, Donald A. (1984), ‘Long-term Contracts and Market Forces in the Natural Gas Market’, 10(1) Journal of Energy and Development, 73-96. Carbone, June R. and Brinig, Margaret F. (1991), ‘Rethinking Marriage: Feminist Ideology, Economic Change, and Divorce Reform’, 65 Tulane Law Review, 954-1010. Chiappori, Pierre Andre and Macho-Stadler, Ines (1990), ‘Contrats de Travail Répètes: la Memoire (Repeated Labour Contracts:The Memory)’, 17(1) Annales d’Économie et de Statistique, 47-70. Chiappori, P.A., Macho-Stadler, I., Rey, P. and Salani, B. (1994), ‘Repeated Moral Hazard: the Role of Memory, Commitment, and the Access to Credit Markets’, 38 European Economic Review, 1527-1553. Chisholm, Darlene C. (1993), ‘Asset Specificity and Long-Term Contracts: The Case of the Motion-Pictures Industry’, 19 Eastern Economic Journal, 143-155. Cooter, Robert (1996), The Rule of State Law and the Rule-of-Law State: Economic Analysis of the Legal Foundations of Development, Annual World Bank Conference on Development Economics. Cooter, Robert and Ulen, Thomas S. (1996), Law and Economics, 2nd edn, Reading, MA, Addison-Wesley.
62
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
4200
Craswell, Richard (1993), ‘The Relational Move: Some Questions from Law and Economics’, 3 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal, 91-114. Craswell, Richard and Schwartz, Alan (1994), Foundation of Contract Law, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Crawford, Vincent P. (1988), ‘Long-Term Relationships Governed by Short-Term Contracts’, 78 American Economic Review, 485-499. Crémer, Jacques (1984), ‘On the Economics of Repeat Buying’, 15 Rand Journal of Economics, 396-403. Crew, Michael A. (1988), ‘Equity, Opportunism and the Design of Contractual Relations: Comment’, 144 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 196-199. Crocker, Keith J. and Lyon, Thomas P. (1994), ‘What do Facilitating Practices Facilitate? An Empirical Investigation of Most Favored Nation Clauses in Natural Gas Contracts’, 37 Journal of Law and Economics, 297-322. Crocker, Keith J. and Masten, Scott E. (1988), ‘Mitigating Contractual Hazards: Unilateral Options and Contract Length’, 19 Rand Journal of Economics, 327-343. Crocker, Keith J. and Masten, Scott E. (1991), ‘Pretia ex Machina? Prices and Process in Long-Term Contracts’, 34 Journal of Law and Economics, 69-99. Crystal, Nathan M. (1988), ‘An Empirical View of Relational Contracts under Article Two of the Uniform Commercial Code’, Annual Survey of American Law, 293-306. Cukierman, Alex and Shiffer, Zalman F. (1976), ‘Contracting for Optimal Delivery Time in Long-Term Projects’, 7 Bell Journal of Economics, 132-149. Daintith, Terence C. (1987), ‘Oprettelse og Anvendelse af Langfristede Kontrakter (The Creation and Use of Longterm Contracts)’, in Blegvad, Britt-Mari and Collin, Finn (eds),Virksomheden Mellem ¢konomi og Jura. Deakin, Simon, Lane, C. and Wilkinson, F. (1994), ‘“Trust” or Law? Towards an Integrated Theory of Contractual Relations between Firms’, 21 Journal of Law and Society, 329-349. Dekel, Eddie, Lipman, B.L. and Rustichini, Aldo (1998), ‘Recent Developments in Modeling Unforeseen Contingencies’, 42 European Economic Review, 523-542. Dewatripont, Mathias (1989), ‘Renegotiation and Information Revelation over Time: The Case of Optimal Labor Contracts’, 103 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 589-619. Dnes, Antony W. (1992a), ‘Franchising’, in Eatwell, John, Milgate, Murray and Newman, Peter (eds), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Money and Finance, London , Macmillan. Dnes, Antony W. (1992b), ‘“Unfair ”’ Practices and Hostages in Franchise Contracts’, 148 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 484-504. Dnes, Antony W. (1993), ‘A Case-Study Analysis of Franchise Contracts’, 22 Journal of Legal Studies, 367-393. Dnes, Antony W. (1995), ‘The Law and Economics of Contract Modifications: the Case of Williams v. Roffey’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 225-240. Dnes, Antony W. (1996), ‘The Economic Analysis of Franchise Contracts’, 152 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 297-324. Dnes, Antony W. and Popovic, M. (1988), ‘Some Case-Study Results on Contracting Practices among Yugoslavian Self-managed firms’, 15 Journal of Industrial Affairs, 23-27. Doberstyn, Gary H. (1988), ‘A conceptual Approach to Negotiating Relational Contracts for the Small Business Client’, 36 Cleveland State Law Review, 541-558.
4200
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
63
Dye, Richard F. (1985), ‘Costly Contract Contingencies’, 26 International Economic Review, 233-250. Eger, Thomas (1992), ‘Eine Ökonomische Analyse der Zulieferbeziehungen in der Automobilindustrie (An economic Analysis of the Relations between Suppliers and Manufacturers in Automotive Industry)’, in Nagel, Bernhard, EG-Wettbewerbsrecht und Zulieferbeziehungen in der Automobilindustrie, Gutachten im Auftrag der EG-Kommission, Generaldirektion Wettbewerb (IV), Veröffentlichungen der Kommission, Luxemburg-Brussel, 1-35. Eger, Thomas (1995), Eine ökonomische Analyse von Langzeitverträgen (An Economic Analysis of Long-Term-Contracts), Marburg, Metropolis, 263 p. Eisenberg, Melvin Aron (1995), ‘Relational Contracts’, in Beatson, Jack and Friedmann, Daniel (eds), Good Faith and Fault in Contract Law, Oxford, Clarendon. Ekelund, Robert B., Jr and Higgins, Richard S. (1982), ‘Capital Fixity, Innovations, and Long-Term Contracting: An Intertemporal Economic Theory’, 72 American Economic Review, 32-46. Esser, John P. (1996), ‘Institutionalizing Industry: The Changing Form of Contract’, 21 Law and Social Inquiry, 593-629. Feinman, Jay M. (1993), ‘Relational Contract and Default Rules’, 3 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal, 43-58. Frech, H. Edward III and Comanor, William S. (1985), ‘The Competitive Effects of Vertical Agreements’, 75(3) American Economic Review, 539-546. Reprinted in 10(1) Journal of Reprints of Antitrust Law and Economics. Frech, H. Edward III and Comanor, William S. (1987), ‘The Competitive Effects of Vertical Agreements: Reply’, 77(5) American Economic Review, 1069-1072. Frech, H. Edward III and Decanio, Stephen J. (1993), ‘Vertical Contracts: A Natural Experiment in Gas Pipeline Regulation’, 149 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 370-392. Frech, H. Edward III and Springer, Robert F. (1986), ‘Deterring Fraud: The Role of Resale Price Maintenance’, 59(3) Journal of Business, 433-450. Freixas, X., Guesnerie, Roger and Tirole, Jean (1985), ‘Planning under Incomplete Information and the Ratchet Effect’, 52 Review of Economic Studies, 173-191. Fudenberg, Drew and Maskin, Eric (1986), ‘The Folk Theorem in Repeated Games with Discounting and Incomplete Information’, 54 Econometrica, 533-554. Fudenberg, Drew and Tirole, Jean (1990), ‘Moral Hazard and Renegotiation in Agency Contracts’, 58 Econometrica, 1279-1320. Fudenberg, Drew, Holmstrom, Bengt and Milgrom, P. (1990), ‘Short-Term Contracts and Long-Term Relationships’, 51 Journal of Economic Theory, 1-31. Furubotn, Eirik G. and Richter, Rudolf (eds) (1991), The New Institutional Economics: A Collection of Articles from the Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, College Station, TX, Texas A & M University Press. Galassi, Francesco L. (1992), ‘Tuscans and Their Farms: The Economics of Share Tenancy in Fifteenth Century Florence’, 9 Rivista di Storia Economica, 77-94. Gambetta, Diego (ed.) (1988), Trust: Making and Breaking Cooperative Relations, Oxford, Blackwell, 246 p. Gebhard, Joachim (1985), Finanzierungsleasing über Mobilien - Versuch einer Analyse eines expandierenden Finanzmarktes (Financial Leasing - An Analysis of an Expanding Capital Market), Wiesbaden, Gabler.
64
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
4200
Geddes, R. Richard (1994), ‘Privatization and Contracts in U.S. Electric Utilities’, in X (ed.), Private Power in the Pacific, Pacific Economic Cooperation Council, Minerals and Energy Forum, 11-24. Geddes, R. Richard and Crowley, Peter T. (1994), ‘Agency Costs and Governance in the United States Postal Service’, in Sidak, Gregory J. (ed.), Governing the Postal Service, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research. Gillette, Clayton P. (1985), ‘Commercial Rationality and the Duty to Adjust Long-Term Contracts’, 69 Minnesota Law Review, 521 ff. Gillette, Clayton P. (1990), ‘Commercial Relationships and the Selection of Default Rules for Remote Risks’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 535-581. Goetz, Charles J. and Scott, Robert E. (1981), ‘Principles of Relational Contracts’, 67 Virginia Law Review, 1089-1150. Goldberg, Victor P. (1976), ‘Toward an Expanded Economic Theory of Contract’, 10 Journal of Economic Issues, 45-61. Reprinted in Samuels, Warren J. (ed.) (1976), The Chicago School of Political Economy, East Lansing, Michigan: Division of Research, Graduate School of Business Administration, Michigan State University, 259-275. Goldberg, Victor P. (1976), ‘Regulation and Administered Contracts’, 7 Bell Journal of Economics, 426-448. Reprinted in Pierce, Richard (ed.) (1994), The Economics of Regulation: Cases and Materials, Cincinnati, Anderson Publishing. Goldberg, Victor P. (1977), ‘Competitive Bidding and the Production of Pre-contract Information’, 8 Bell Journal of Economics, 250-261. Goldberg, Victor P. (1979), ‘Law and Economics of Vertical Restrictions: A Relational Perspective’, 58 Texas Law Review, 91-129. Goldberg, Victor P. (1980a), ‘Bridges Over Contested Terrain: Exploring the Radical Account of the Employment Relationship’, 1 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 249-274. Goldberg, Victor P. (1980b), ‘Relational Exchange: Economics and Complex Contracts’, 23 American Behavioral Scientist, 337-352. Reprinted in Putterman (ed.) (1986), The Economic Nature of the Firm: A Reader, New York, Cambridge University Press. Goldberg, Victor P. (1981), ‘Pigou on Complex Contracts and Welfare Economics’, 3 Research in Law and Economics, 39-51. Goldberg, Victor P. (1984), ‘A Relational Exchange Perspective on the Employment Relationship’, in Stephen, Frank H. (ed.), Firms, Organization and Labour: Approaches to the Economics of Work Organization, London, Macmillan, 127-145. Goldberg, Victor P. (1985a), ‘Relational Exchange, Contract Law, and the Boomer Problem’, 141 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 570-575. Goldberg, Victor P. (1985b), ‘Price Adjustment in Long-Term Contracts’, Wisconsin Law Review, 527-543. Reprinted in Speidel, Summers and White (1987), Commercial Law: Teaching Materials, 4th edn. Goldberg, Victor P. and Erickson, John R. (1987), ‘Quantity and Price Adjustments in Long-Term Contracts: A Case Study of Petroleum Coke’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 369-398. Gordon, Robert W. (1985), ‘Macaulay, Macneil, and the Discovery of Solidarity and Power in Contract Law’, Wisconsin Law Review, 565-579. Gottlieb, Gidon (1983), ‘Relationism: Legal Theory for a Relational Society’, 50 University of Chicago Law Review, 567-612.
4200
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
65
Grandy, Christopher (1989), ‘Can Government be Trusted to Keep its Part of a Social Contract?: New Jersey and the Railroads, 1825-1888', 5 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 249-269. Greif, Avner (1989), ‘Reputation and Coalitions in Medieval Trade: Evidence on the Maghribi Traders’, 49 Journal of Economic History, 857-882. Greif, Avner (1992), ‘Institutions and International Trade: Lessons from the Commercial Revolution’, 82 American Economic Review, 128-133. Greif, Avner (1993), ‘Contract Enforceability and Economic Institutions in Early Trade: the Maghribi Traders’ Coalition’, 83 American Economic Review, 525-548. Greif, Avner (1994), ‘Cultural Beliefs and the Organization of Society: A Historical and Theoretical Reflection on Collectivist and Individualist Societies’, 102 Journal of Political Economy, 912-950. Greif, Avner (1994), ‘On the Political Foundations of the Late Medieval Commercial Revolution: Genoa during the Twelfth and Thirteenth Centuries’, 54 Journal of Economic History, 271-287. Greif, Avner (1995), ‘Political Organizations, Social Structure, and Institutional Success: Reflections from Genoa and Venice during the Commercial Revolution’, 151 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 734-740. Greif, Avner (1996), Contracting, Enforcement, and Efficiency: Economics Beyond the Law, Annual World Bank Conference on Development Economics. Greif, Avner, Milgrom, P. and Weingast, B. (1994), ‘Coordination, Commitment, and Enforcement: The Case of the Merchant Guild’, 102 Journal of Political Economy, 745-776. Grossekettler, Heinz (1978), ‘Der Fall “Deutsche SB-Kauf kontra adidas”. Volkswirtschaftliche Analyse einer Liefervereinigung (Economic Analysis of a Supply Relation)’, 9 Wettbewerb in Recht und Praxis, 619-634. Grossekettler, Heinz (1981), ‘Die Gesamtwirtschaftliche Problematik Vertraglicher Vertriebssysteme (The Economic Impact of Contractual Supply Systems)’, in Ahlert, D. (ed.), Vertragliche Vertriebssysteme zwischen Industrie und Handel, Grundzüge einer Betriebswirtschaftlichen, Rechtlichen und Volkswirtschaftlichen Beurteilung, Wiesbaden, Gabler, 225-314. Grossman, Sanford J. and Hart, Oliver D. (1986), ‘The Cost and Benefit of Ownership: A Theory of Vertical and Lateral Integration’, 94 Journal of Political Economy, 691-719. Grout, Paul (1984), ‘Investment and Wages in the Absence of Binding Contracts: a Nash Bargaining Approach’, 52 Econometrica, 449-460. Hackett, Steven C. (1994), ‘Is Relational Exchange Possible in the Absence of Reputations and Repeated Contract?’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 360-389. Hadfield, Gilliam K. (1990), ‘Problematic Relations: Franchising and the Law of Incomplete Contracts’, 42 Stanford Law Review, 927-992. Hadfield, Gilliam K. (1994), ‘Judicial Competence and the Interpretation of Incomplete Contracts’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 159-184. Hansmann, Henry B. and Kraakman, Reinier H. (1992), ‘Hands-Tying Contracts: Book Publishing, Venture Capital Financing, and Secured Debt’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 628-655. Harbison, John E. (1991), ‘Hard Times in the Softwoods: Contract Terms, Performance, and Relational Interests in National Forest Timber Sales’, 21 Environmental Law, 863-909.
66
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
4200
Harris, Milton and Holmström, Bengt (1987), ‘On the Duration of Agreements’, 28 International Economic Review, 389-406. Hart, Oliver D. (1987), ‘Incomplete Contracts’, in Eatwell, John, Milgate, Murray and Newman, Peter (eds), The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, London, Macmillan, 752-759. Hart, Oliver D. (1995), Firms Contracts and Financial Structure, Oxford, Clarendon. Hart, Oliver D. and Holmstrom, Bengt (1987), ‘The Theory of Contracts’, in Bewley, T. (ed.), Advances in Economic Theory. Fifth World Congress, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Hart, Oliver D. and Moore, John H. (1988), ‘Incomplete Contracts and Renegotiation’, 56 Econometrica, 755-785. Hart, Oliver D. and Moore, John H. (1990), ‘Property Rights and the Nature of the Firm’, 98 Journal of Political Economy, 1119-1158. Hart, Oliver D. and Tirole, Jean (1988), ‘Contract Renegotiation and Coasian Dynamics’, 55 Review of Economic Studies, 509-540. Hellwig, Martin F. (1988), ‘Equity, Opportunism, and the Design of Contractual Relations: Comment’, 144 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 200-207. Helper, Susan and Levine, David I. (1992), ‘Long-term Supplier Relations and Product Market Structure’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 561-581. Hermalin, Benjamin E. and Katz, Michael L. (1993), ‘Judicial Modification of Contracts between Sophisticated Parties: A More Complete View of Incomplete Contracts and Their Breach’, 9 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 230-255. Hillman, Robert A. (1987), ‘Court Adjustment of Long-Term Contracts: An Analysis under Modern Contract Law’, Duke Law Journal, 1-33. Hirshleifer, Jack (1994), ‘The Dark Side of the Force’, 32 Economic Inquiry, 1-10. Hubbard, R. Glenn and Weiner, Robert J. (1986), ‘Regulation and Long-term Contracting in U.S. Natural Gas Markets’, 35 Journal of Industrial Economics, 71-79. Hubbard, R. Glenn and Weiner, Robert J. (1991), ‘Efficient Contracting and Market Power: Evidence from the U.S. Natural Gas Industry’, 34 Journal of Law and Economics, 25-67. Hubbard, Steven W. (1982), ‘Relief from Burdensome Long-term Contracts: Commercial Impracticability, Frustration of Purpose, Mutual Mistake of Fact, and Equitable Adjustment’, 47 Missouri Law Review, 79-111. Huberman, Gur and Kahn, Charles M. (1988a), ‘Strategic Renegotiation’, 28 Economic Letters, 117-121. Huberman, Gur and Kahn, Charles W. (1988b), ‘Limited Contract Enforcement and Strategic Renegotiation’, 78 American Economic Review, 471-484. Hviid, Morten (1996), ‘Relational Contracts and Repeated Games’, in Campbell, David and Vincent-Jones, Peter (eds), Contract and Economic Organisation: Socio-legal Initiatives, Aldershot, Dartmouth. Hviid, Morten (1998), ‘Relational Contracts, Repeated Interactions and Contract Modification’, 5 European Journal of Law and Economics, 179-194. Johnson, Alex M., Jr (1988), ‘Correctly Interpreting Long-Term Leases Pursuant to Modern Contract Law: Toward a Theory of Relational Leases’, 74 Virginia Law Review, 751-808. Jolls, Christine (1997), ‘Contracts as Bilateral Commitments: A New Perspective on Contract Modification’, 26 Journal of Legal Studies, 203-237.
4200
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
67
Joskow, Paul L. (1985a), ‘Vertical Integration and Long-Term Contracts: The Case of Coal-Burning Electric Generating Plants’, 1 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 33-80. Joskow, Paul L. (1985b), ‘Long-term Vertical Relationships and the Study of Industrial Organization and Government Regulation’, 141 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 586-593. Joskow, Paul L. (1987), ‘Contract Duration and Relationship-Specific Investments: Empirical Evidence from Coal Markets’, 77 American Economic Review, 168-185. Joskow, Paul L. (1988), ‘Price Adjustment in Long-Term Contracts: The Case of Coal’, 31 Journal of Law and Economics, 47-83. Joskow, Paul L. (1990), ‘The Performance of Long-term Contracts: Further Evidence from Coal Markets’, 21 Rand Journal of Economics, 251-274. Kahan, Marcel and Tuckman, Bruce (1996), ‘Private versus Public Lending: Evidence from Covenants’, in Finnerty, John D. and Martin, S. Fridson (eds), The Yearbook of Fixed Income Investing 1995, New York, Irwin, 253-274. Kaufmann, Patrick J. and Stern, Louis W. (1988), ‘Relational Exchange Norms, Perceptions of Unfairness, and Retained Hostility in Commercial Litigation’, 32 Journal of Conflict Resolution, 534-552. Kenworthy, Lane, Macaulay, Stewart and Rogers, Joel (1996), ‘The More Things Change ...: Business Litigation and Governance in the American Automobile Industry’, 21 Law and Social Inquiry, 631-678. Klein, Benjamin (1996), ‘Why Hold Ups Occur: The Self Enforcing Range of Contractual Relationships’, 34 Economic Inquiry, 444-463. Klein, Benjamin, Crawford, Robert G. and Alchian, Armen A. (1978), ‘Vertical Integration, Appropriable Rents, and the Competitive Contracting Process’, 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 297-326. Koboldt, Christian (1991), ‘Kommentar on Schanze, Stellvertretung und ökonomische Agentur-Theorie’, in Ott, Claus and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (eds), Ökonomische Probleme des Zivilrechts, Berlin, Springer, 76-86. Kranton, Rachel E. (1996), ‘Reciprocal Exchange: A Self-Sustaining System’,86 American Economic Review, 830-851. Kranton, Rachel E. (1996), ‘The Formation of Cooperative Relationships’, 12 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 214-233. Kreps, David M. (1990), ‘Corporate Culture and Economic Theory’, in Alt, J. and Shepsle, K. (eds), Perspectives on Politive Political Economy, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Kronman, Anthony T. (1985), ‘Contract Law and The State of Nature’, 1 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 32-35. Laffont, Jean-Jacques and Tirole, Jean (1987), ‘Comparative Static of the Optimal Dynamic Incentive Contract’, 31 European Economic Review, 901-926. Laffont, Jean-Jacques and Tirole, Jean (1990), ‘Adverse Selection and Renegotiation in Procurement’, 75 Review of Economic Studies, 597-626. Lafontaine, F. (1992), ‘Agency Theory and Franchising: Some Empirical Results’, 23 Rand Journal of Economics, 263-283. Lambert, Richard A. (1983), ‘Long-Term Contracts and Moral Hazard’, 14 Bell Journal of Economics, 441-451.
68
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
4200
Lawrence, William H. (1989), ‘Lender Control Liability: An Analytical Model Illustrated with Applications to the Relational Theory of Secured Financing’, 62 Southern California Law Review, 1387-1447. Levmore, Saul and Kanda, Hideki (1994), ‘Explaining Creditor Priorities’, 80 Virginia Law Review, 2103-2154. Lewis, Tab, Lindsey, R. and Ware, R. (1986), ‘Long-Term Bilateral Monopoly: The Case of an Exhaustible Resource’, 17 Rand Journal of Economics, 89-104. Lewis, Tracy R. (1986), ‘Reputation and Contractual Performance in Long-Term Projects’, 17 Rand Journal of Economics, 141-157. Lindenberg, Siegwart and De Vos, Henk (1985), ‘The Limits of Solidarity: Relational Contracting in Perspective and Some Criticism of Traditional Sociology’, 141 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 558-569. Linzer, Peter (1988), ‘Uncontracts: Context, Contorts and the Relational Approach’, Annual Survey of American Law, 139-198. Lyons, B.R. (1994), ‘Contracts and Specific Investment: An Empirical Test of Transaction Cost Theory’, 3 Journal of Economics and Management Strategy, 257-278. Lyons, Bruce R. (1995), ‘Specific Investment, Economies of Scale, and the Make or Buy Decision: A Test of Transaction Cost Theory’, 26 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 431-443. Lyons, Bruce R. (1996), ‘Empirical Relevance of Efficient Contract Theory: Inter-Firm Contracts’, 12 Oxford Review of Economic Policy, 27-52. Lyons, Bruce R. and Mehta, Judith (1997), ‘Contracts Opportunism and Trust: Self-Interest and Social Orientation’, 21 Cambridge Journal of Economics, 239-257. Ma, C. (1991), ‘Adverse Selection in Dynamic Moral Hazard’, 106 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 255-275. Macario, Francesco (1996), Adempimento e Rinegoziazione nei Contratti a Lungo Termine (Performance and Renegotiation in Long-term Contracts), Napoli, Jovene. Macaulay, Stewart (1963), ‘Non-Contractual Relations in Business: A Preliminary Study’, 25 American Sociological Review, 55-70. Reprinted in Goldberg, Victor P. (ed.) (1989), Readings in the Economics of Contract Law, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 4-15. Macaulay, Stewart (1977), ‘Elegant Models, Empirical Pictures and the Complexities of Contract’, 11 Law and Society Review, 507-528. Macaulay, Stewart (1985), ‘An Empirical View of Contract’, 5 Wisconsin Law Review, 465-482. Macho-Stadler, I. and Pérez-Castrillo, J. David (1988), ‘Sobre los Compromisos Multiperíodo en los Modelos de Riesgo Moral Repetido (Multiple Period Commitments in Repeated Moral Hazard Models)’, 5 Revista Española de Economía, 143-158. MacLeod, W. Bentley and Malcomson, James M. (1988), ‘Reputation and Hierarchy in Dynamic Models of Employment’, 96 Journal of Political Economy, 832-854. MacNeil, Ian R. (1974), ‘The Many Futures of Contracts’, 47 Southern California Law Review, 691-816. MacNeil, Ian R. (1975), ‘A Primer of Contract Planning’, 48 Southern California Law Review, 627-704. MacNeil, Ian R. (1978), ‘Contracts: Adjustment of Long-Term Economic Relations Under Classical, Neoclassical, and Relational Contract Law’, 72 Northwestern University Law Review, 854-905.
4200
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
69
MacNeil, Ian R. (1980a), ‘Power, Contract and the Economic Model’, 14 Journal of Economic Issues, 909-923. MacNeil, Ian R. (1980b), The New Social Contract: An Inquiry Into Modern Contractual Relations, New Haven, Yale University Press, 164 p. MacNeil, Ian R. (1981a), ‘Economic Analysis of Contractual Relations’, in Burrows, Paul and Veljanovski, Cento G. (eds), The Economic Approach to Law, London, Butterworths, 61-92. MacNeil, Ian R. (1981b), ‘Economic Analysis of Contractual Relations: Its Shortfalls and the Need for a Rich Classificatory Apparatus’, 75 Northwestern University Law Review, 1018-1063. MacNeil, Ian R. (1983), ‘Values in Contract: Internal and External’, 78 Northwestern University Law Review, 340-418. MacNeil, Ian R. (1985), ‘Relational Contract: What We Do and Do Not Know’, Wisconsin Law Review, 483-525. MacNeil, Ian R. (1985), ‘Reflections on Relational Contract’, 141 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 541-546. MacNeil, Ian R. (1986), ‘Exchange Revisited: Individual Utility and Social Solidarity’, 96 Ethics, 567-593. MacNeil, Ian R. (1987a), ‘Relational Contract Theory as Sociology: A Reply’, 143 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 272-290. MacNeil, Ian R. (1987b), ‘Barriers to the Idea of Relational Contracts (The Complex Long-Term Contract. Structures and International Arbitration)’, in Nicklisch, Fritz (ed.), Der Komplexe Langzeitvertrag. Strukturen und Internationale Schiedsgerichtsbarkeit, Heidelberg, Müller Juristischer Verlag, 31-46. Malcomson, James M. (1997), ‘Contracts, Hold-Up, and Labor Markets’, 35 Journal of Economic Literature, 1916-1957. Malcomson, James M. and Spinnewyn, F. (1988), ‘The Multiperiod Principal Agent Problem’, 55 Review of Economic Studies, 391-407. Masten, Scott E. and Crocker, Keith J. (1985), ‘Efficient Adaptation in Long-Term Contracts: Take-or-Pay Provisions for Natural Gas’, 75 American Economic Review, 1083-1093. McKendrick, Ewan (1995), ‘The Regulation of Long-Term Contracts in English Law’, in Beatson, Jack and Friedmann, Daniel (eds), Good Faith and Fault in Contract Law, Oxford, Clarendon. Milgrom, Paul R., North, Douglass C. and Weingast, Barry R. (1990), ‘The Role of Institutions in the Revival of Trade: The Law Merchant, Private Judges, and the Champagne Fairs’, 2 Economics and Politics, 1-23. Milhaupt, Curtis, J. (1996), ‘A Relational Theory of Japanese Corporate Governance: Contract, Culture, and the Rule of Law’, 37 Harvard International Law Review, 3-64. Mulherin, J. Harold (1986), ‘Complexity in Long-Term Contracts: An Analysis of Natural Gas Contractual Provisions’, 2 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 105-117. Muller Graff, Christian Peter (1988), ‘Franchising: A Case of Long-term Contracts’, 144 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 122-144. Mullock, Philip (1983), ‘The New Paradigm of Contract: A Hermeneutical Approach’, 17 Valparaiso University Law Review, 677-704.
70
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
4200
Nagel, Bernhard (1988), ‘Der Lieferant on line - unternehmensrechtliche Probleme der Just-in-Time-Produktion am Beispiel der Automobilindustrie (Delivery online. Legal Problems of Just-in-Time Production in the Automobile Sector)’, DB, 2291-2294. Nagel, Bernhard (1991), ‘Schuldrechtliche Probleme bei Just-in-Time-Lieferbeziehungen - dargestellt am Beispiel der Automobilindustrie (Problems with Law of Contract in Just-in-Time Delivery Relations)’, DB, 319-326. Nagel, Bernhard (1992), ‘Zulieferbeziehungen der Automobilindustrie und Wettbewerbsrecht der EG (Delivery Relations in the Automobile Industry and the Competition Law of the EG)’, Wirtschaft und Wettbewerb, 818-829. Nagel, Bernhard (1992), EG-Wettbewerbsrecht und Zulieferbeziehungen der Automobilindustrie, Gutachten im Auftrag der EG-Kommission (EU-Competition Law and the Delivery Relations in the Automobile Industry), Veröffentlichungen der Kommission, Luxemburg und Brüssel, 1992. Narasimhan, Subha (1986), ‘Of Expectations, Incomplete Contracting, and the Bargain Principle’, 74 California Law Review, 1123-1202. Narasimhan, Subha (1989), ‘Relationship or Boundary? Handling Successive Contracts’,77 California Law Review, 1077-1122. Nicklisch, Fritz (1987), Der Komplexe Langzeitvertrag. Strukturen und Internationale Schiedsgerichtsbarkeit (The Complex Long-Term Contract. Structures and International Arbitration), Heidelberg, Müller Juristischer Verlag, 597 p. Palay, Thomas M. (1984), ‘Comparative Institutional Economics: The Governance of Rail Freight Contracting’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 265-287. Palzer, Keith A. (1988), ‘Relational Contract Theory and Sovereign Debt’, 8 Northwestern Journal of International Law and Business, 727-758. Pauly, Mark V. (1986), ‘Relational Contracting, Transaction Cost Economics and the Governance of HMOs’, 59 Temp. Law Quarterly, 927 ff. Pauly, Mark V. (1990), ‘The Rational Nonpurchase of Long-Term Insurance’, 98 Journal of Political Economy, 153-168. Pittman, Russell (1992), ‘Specific Investments, Contracts, and Opportunism: The Evolution of Railroad Sidetrack Agreements’, 34 Journal of Law and Economics, 565-589. Polinsky, A. Mitchell (1987), ‘Fixed Price versus Spot Price Contracts: A Study in Risk Allocation’, 3(1) Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 27-46. Posner, Eric A. (1997), ‘Altruism, Trust, and Status in the Law of Gifts and Gratuitous Promises’, 17 Wisconsin Law Review. Ramseyer, J. Mark (1991a), ‘Indentured Prostitution in Imperial Japan: Credible Commitments in the Commercial Sex Industry’, 7 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 89-116. Ramseyer, J. Mark (1991b), ‘Legal Rules in Repeated Deals: Banking in the Shadow of Defection in Japan’, 20 Journal of Legal Studies, 91-117. Ramseyer, J. Mark (1994), ‘Explicit Reasons for Implicit Contracts: The Legal Logic To the Japanese Main Bank System’, in Masahiko, Aoki and Patrick, Hugh T. (eds), The Japanese Main Bank System: Its Relevance For Developing and Transforming Economies, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 231 ff. Rey, Patrick and Salanié, B. (1990), ‘Long-Term, Short-Term and Renegotiation: On the Value of Commitment in Contracting’, 58 Econometrica, 597-619.
4200
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
71
Rice, Danton B. and Schlueter, Michael A. (1985), ‘Deregulation and Natural Gas Purchase Contracts: Examination through Neoclassical and Relational Contract Theories’, 25 Washburn Law Journal, 43-65. Salanié, Bernard (1997), The Economics of Contracts, London, MIT Press. Schanze, Erich (1989), Langzeitverträge im Spannungsfeld von Vertrags-, Gesellschafts-, Wettbewerbs- und Arbeitsrecht, Symbiotische Bezugs- und Absatzsysteme, Vorlage für die Tagung für Rechtsvergleichung Würzburg 1989 (Long-Term Contracts between Contract, Corporation, Competition, and Labor Law), Fachgruppe für Grundlagenforschung, Arbeitssitzung, 14 Sept 1989. Schanze, Erich (1991), ‘Symbiotic Contracts: Exploring Long-Term Agency Structures between Contract and Corporation’, in Joerges, Christian (ed.), Regulating the Franchise Relationship: Comparative and European Aspects, Baden-Baden, Nomos. Schwab, Stewart J. (1993), ‘Life-Cycle Justice: Accommodating Just Cause and Employment At Will’, 92 Michigan Law Review, 8-62. Schwartz, Alan (1992a), ‘Legal Contract Theory and Incomplete Information’, in Werin, Lars and Wijkander, Hans (eds), Contract Economics, Oxford, Blackwell. Schwartz, Alan (1992b), ‘Relational Contracts in the Courts: An Analysis of Incomplete Agreements and Judicial Strategies’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 271-318. Scott, Robert E. (1987a), ‘Risk Distribution and Adjustment in Long-Term Contracts (The Complex Long-Term Contract. Structures and International Arbitration)’, in Nicklisch, Fritz (ed.), Der Komplexe Langzeitvertrag. Strukturen und Internationale Schiedsgerichtsbarkeit, Heidelberg, Müller Juristischer Verlag, 51-100. Scott, Robert E. (1987b), ‘Conflict and Cooperation in Long-Term Contracts’, 75 California Law Review, 2005-2054. Scott, Robert E. (1990), ‘A Relational Theory of Default Rules for Commercial Contracts’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 597-616. Speidel, Richard E. (1981), ‘Court-Imposed Price Adjustements Under Long-Term Supply Contracts’, 76 Northwestern University Law Review, 369-422. Strasser, Kurt A. (1981), ‘Contract’s ‘Many Features’ after Death: Unanswered Questions of Scope and Purpose’, 32 South Carolina Law Review, 501-546. Talley, Eric (1994), ‘Contract Renegotiation, Mechanism Design, and the Liquidated Damages Rule’, 46 Stanford Law Review, 1195-1243. Trebilcock, Michael J. (1993), The Limits of Freedom of Contract, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Triantis, George G. (1992), ‘Contractual Allocation of Unknown Risks: A Critique of the Doctrine of Commercial Impracticability’, 42 University of Toronto Law Journal, 450-483. Triantis, George G. (1993), ‘The Effects of Insolvency and Bankruptcy on Contract Performance and Adjustment’, 43 University of Toronto Law Journal, 679-710. Van Pelt, Mark H. (1985), ‘Introduction’, 5 Wisconsin Law Review, 461-463. Verkerke, J. Hoult (1995), ‘An Empirical Perspective on Indefinite Term Employment Contracts: Resolving the Just Cause Debate’, 15 Wisconsin Law Review, 837-918. Vincent-Jones, Peter (1994), ‘The Limits of Contractual Order in Public Scetor Transacting’, 14 Legal Studies, 364 ff. Whincop, Michael J. (1997), ‘A Relational and Doctrinal Critique of Shareholders’ Special Contracts’, 19 Sydney Law Review.
72
Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts
4200
Whitford, William C. (1985), ‘Ian Macneil’s Contribution to Contracts Scholarship’, Wisconsin Law Review, 545-560. Wiley, John Shepard Jr, Rasmusen, Eric and Ramseyer, Mark J. (1990), ‘The Leasing Monopolist’, 37 UCLA Law Review, 693 ff. Williamson, Oliver E. (1983), ‘Credible Commitments: Using Hostages to Support Exchange’, 73 American Economic Review, 519-540. Williamson, Oliver E. (1984), ‘Credible Commitments: Further Remarks’, 74 American Economic Review, 488-490. Williamson, Oliver E. (1985), The Economic Institutions of Capitalism: Firms, Markets, Relational Contracting, New York, Free Press, 450 p. Williamson, Oliver E. (1989), Antitrust Economics: Mergers, Contracting and Strategic Behavior, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 363 p. Zolt, Eric M. and Berkowitz, Jeffrey I. (1978), ‘An Economic Perspective on the Law of Excessive Profit Recovery’, 45 University of Chicago Law Review, 882-905. Zundel, Michael N. (1982), ‘Equitable Reformation of Long-Term Contracts - The “New Spirit” of ALCOA’, Utah Law Review, 985-1008. Zupan, Mark A. (1990), ‘Why Nice Guys Finish Last: A Comment on Robert Axelrod’s the Evolution of Cooperation’, 65(3) Public Choice, 291-293.
4300 CONTRACT FORMATION © Copyright 1999 Boudewijn Bouckaert and Gerrit De Geest
Bibliography Collected by the Editors Adams, Michael (1984), ‘Ökonomische Analyse des Gesetzes zur Regelung des Rechts der Allgemeinen Geschäftsbedingungen’, in Neumann, M. (ed.), Ansprache, Eigentums- und Verfügungsrechte, Berlin, Duncker and Humblot, 655-680. Adams, Michael (1986), ‘Zur Behandlung von Irrtümern und Offenbarungspflichten im Vertragsrecht (On Mistake and Information Revelation Duties in Contract Law)’, 186 Archiv für die Civilistische Praxis, 453-489. Barnes, David W. and Stout, Lynn A. (1992), Economics of Contract Law, Minneapolis, West Publishing. Barnett, Randy E. and Becker, Mary E. (1987), ‘Beyond Reliance: Promissory Estoppel, Contract Formalities, and Misrepresentation’, 15 Hofstra Law Review, 443 ff. Baudenbacher, Carl (1983), ‘Echtliche Grundprobleme der Allgemeinen Geschäftsbedingungen (Standard Term Clauses: Basic Problems of Economic, Liability and Procedural Law)’, in Zurich, Schulthess (ed.), Wirtschafts- schuld- und verfahrens. Bessone, Mario (1984), ‘Gli “standards” dei Contratti di Impresa e l’Analisi Economica del Diritto (The ‘Standards’ in Contracts and Economic Analysis)’, Giurisprudenza di merito, 982-987. Birmingham, Robert L. (1988), ‘The Duty to Disclose and the Prisoner’s Dilemma:’, William & Mary Law Review, 249-283. Bishop, William (1980), ‘Negligent Misrepresentation through the Economists’ Eyes’, 96 Law Quarterly Review, 360-379. Bishop, William (1981), ‘Negligent Misrepresentation: An Economic Reformulation’, in Burrows, Paul and Veljanovski, Cento G. (eds), The Economic Approach to Law, London, Butterworths, 167-186. Bouckaert, Boudewijn and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (1995), ‘Mistake of Law and the Economics of Legal Information’, in Bouckaert, Boudewijn and De Geest, Gerrit (eds), Essays in Law and Economics II: Contract Law, Regulation, and Reflections on Law and Economics, Antwerpen, Maklu, 217-245. Braunstein, Michael (1989), ‘Remedy, Reason, and the Statute of Frauds: A Critical Economic Analysis’, Utah Law Review, 383-431. Campbell, David (1997), ‘The Relational Constitution of Contract and the Limits of Economics: Kenneth Arrow on the Social Background of Markets’, in Deakin, Simon and Michie, Jonathan (eds), Contracts, Co-operation and Competition: Studies in Economics, Management and Law, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 529-596. Caruso, Daniela (1991), ‘Note in tema di danni precontrattuali (Nota a Cass., 11 maggio 1990, n. 4051, Bellucci c. Min. difesa) (Notes about Precontractual Damages)’, 1 Il Foro Italiano, 188-200. Caruso, Daniela (1991), ‘Relazioni Precontrattuali e Teoria dei Giochi (Precontractual Relations and Game Theory)’, Quadrimestre, 810-832.
73
74
Contract Formation
4300
Caruso, Daniela (1993), La Culpa in Contrahendo - L’Esperienza Statunitense e Quella Italiana (Culpa in Contrahendo - The American and Italian Experience), Milano, Giuffrè. Castermans, A.G. (1989), ‘Schadevergoeding bij Dwaling (Damages for Misrepresentation)’, Rechtsgeleerd Magazijn Themis, 136-146. Castermans, A.G. and Notermans, R. (1985), ‘Naar een Economische Analyse van de Mededelingsplicht bij Dwaling (Towards an Economic Analysis of the Duty to Inform in Misrepresentation Law)’, BW-krant Jaarboek 1985, BW-NBW: twee sporen, één weg, Leiden, Rijksuniversiteit Leiden, 141-155. Chisholm, Darlene C. (1996), ‘Continuous Degrees of Residual Claimancy: Some Contractual Evidence’, 3 Applied Economics Letters, 739-741. Coleman, Jules, Heckathorn, Douglas D. and Maser, Steven M. (1989), ‘A Bargaining Theory Approach to Default Provisions and Disclosure Rules in Contract Law’, 12 Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy, 639-709. Craswell, Richard (1988), ‘Precontractual Investigation as an Optimal Precaution Problem’, 17 Journal of Legal Studies, 401-436. Craswell, Richard (1996), ‘Offer, Acceptance and Efficient Reliance’, 48 Stanford Law Review, 481-553. Curnes, Ellen J. (1987), ‘Protecting the Virginia Homebuyer: A Duty to Disclose Defects’, 73 Virginia Law Review, 459-481. Daintith, Terence C. (1987), ‘Oprettelse og Anvendelse af Langfristede Kontrakter (The Creation and Use of Longterm Contracts)’, in Blegvad, Britt-Mari and Collin, Finn (eds), Virksomheden Mellem ¢konomi og Jura (The Firm between Law and Economics), Samfundslitteratur. Dalzell, John (1942), ‘Duress by Economic Pressure’, 20 North Carolina Law Review, 237-277. Reprinted in Kronman, Anthony T. and Posner, Richard A. (eds) (1979), The Economics of Contract Law, Boston, Little Brown, 67-72. Reprinted in Goldberg, Victor P. (ed.) (1989), Readings in the Economics of Contract Law, 188-193. De Geest, Gerrit (1995), ‘Contracting by Way of Non-Simultaneous Assent: An Economic Analysis of Irrevocable Offers, Clauses for the Benefit of a Third Party, Assignments and Testaments’, in Bouckaert, Boudewijn and De Geest, Gerrit (eds), Essays in Law and Economics II: Contract Law, Regulation, and Reflections on Law and Economics, Antwerpen, Maklu, 9-27. Diamond, Peter A. and Maskin, Eric (1979), ‘An Equilibrium Analysis of Search and Breach of Contract, I: Steady States’, 10 Bell Journal of Economics, 282-316. Diamond, Peter A. and Maskin, Eric (1981), ‘An Equilibrium Analysis of Search and Breach of Contract II: A Nonsteady State Example’, 25 Journal of Economic Theory, 165-195. Dnes, Anthony W. (1995), ‘The Law and Economics of Contract Modifications: The Case of Williams v. Roffey’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 225-240. Duggan, A.J. (1982), ‘An Economic Analysis of Standard Form Contracts’, in Cranston, Ross and Schick, Anne (eds), Law and Economics, Canberra, Australian National University, 145-162. Duggan, A.J. (1995), ‘Silence as Misleading Conduct: An Economic Analysis’, in Richardson, Megan and Williams, Philip (eds), The Law and the Market: Essays in Honour of Maureen Brunt, Melbourne, The Federation Press, 195-223.
4300
Contract Formation
75
Eisenberg, Melvin Aron (1979), ‘Donative Promises’, 47 University of Chicago Law Review, 1-33. Eisenberg, Melvin Aron (1982), ‘The Bargain Principle and its Limits’, 95 Harvard Law Review, 741-801. Epstein, Richard A. (1975), ‘Unconscionability: A Critical Reappraisal’, 18 Journal of Law and Economics, 293-315. Feeny, David, Berkes, Fikret, McCay, Bonnie J. and Acheson, James M. (1990), ‘The Tragedy of the Commons: Twenty-Two Years Later’, 18(1) Human Ecology, 1-19. Fishman, Michael J. and Hagerty, Kathleen M. (1990), ‘The Optimal Amount of Discretion to Allow in Disclosure’, 104 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 427-444. Fuller, Lon L. (1941), ‘Consideration and Form’, 41 Columbia Law Review, 799 ff. Reprinted in Kronman, Anthony T. and Posner, Richard A. (eds) (1979), The Economics of Contract Law, Boston, Little Brown, 40-45. Gallo, Paolo (1992), ‘Errore sul Valore, Giustizia Contrattuale e Trasferimenti Ingiustificati di Ricchezza alla Luce dell’Analisi Economica del Diritto (Mistake on Value, Contractual Justice and Unjust Enrichment)’, Quadrimestre, 656-703. Goldberg, Victor P. (1977), ‘Competitive Bidding and the Production of Pre-contract Information’, 8 Bell Journal of Economics, 250-261. Hatzis, Aristides N. (1997), The Absence of Theory: Common vs. Civil Contract Law, paper presented at the XIVth Annual Conference of the European Association of Law & Economics, held at Barcelona, September 4-6, 1997. Hatzis, Aristides N. (1998), An Economic Theory of Greek Contract Law, Ph.D. Thesis, University of Chicago Law School. Holm, Hakan J. (1995), ‘Computational Cost of Verifying Enforceable Contracts’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 127-140. Johnston, Jason Scott (1990), ‘Strategic Bargaining and the Economic Theory of Contract Default Rules’, 100 Yale Law Journal, 615-664. Katz, Avery (1990a), ‘The Strategic Structure of Offer and Acceptance: Game Theory and the Law of Contract Formation’, 89 Michigan Law Review, 215-295. Katz, Avery (1990b), ‘Your Terms or Mine: The Duty to Read the Fine Print in Contracts,’, 21 Rand Journal of Economics, 518-537. Katz, Avery (1993), ‘Transaction Costs and the Legal Mechanics of Exchange: When Should Silence in the Face of an Offer be Construed as Acceptance?’, 9 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 77-97. Katz, Avery (1996), ‘The Economics of Promissory Estoppel in Preliminary Negotiations’, 105 Yale Law Journal, 1249-1309. Koboldt, Christian (1991), ‘Kommentar on Schanze, Stellvertretung und ökonomische Agentur-Theorie’, in Ott, Claus and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (eds), Ökonomische Probleme des Zivilrechts, Berlin, Springer, 76-86. Koch, Harald (1981), ‘Die Ökonomie der Gestaltungsrechte. Möglichkeiten und Grenzen der ökonomische Analyse des Rechts am Beispiel von Kündiging und Anfechtung (The Economics of Dispositive Right. Possibilities and Limits of the Economic Analysis of Law)’, in Bernstein, H., Drobnig, U. and Kötz, H. (eds), Festschrift für Konrad Zweigert zum 70. Geburtstag, Tübingen, Mohr, 851-877. Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1976), ‘Unconscionability in Standard Forms’, 64 California Law Review, 1151 ff.
76
Contract Formation
4300
Kostritsky, Juliet P. (1989), ‘Illegal Contracts and Efficient Deterrence: A Study in Modern Contract Theory’, 74 Iowa Law Review, 115-163. Krauss, Michael I. (1986), ‘L’affaire Lapierre: vers une Théorie Economique de l’Obligation Quasi-Contractuelle (The Lapierre Case: Toward an Economic Theory of the Quasi-Contractual Obligation)’, 31 McGill Law Journal, 683-721. Kronman, Anthony T. (1978), ‘Mistake, Disclosure, Information, and the Law of Contracts’, 7 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-34. Kull, Andrew (1992), ‘Reconsidering Gratuitous Promises’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 39-65. Lehmann, Michael (1980), ‘Die Untersuchungs- und Rügepflicht des Käufers in BGB und HGB. Rechtsvergleichender Überblick - ökonomische Analyse (The Duty to Examine and Notify a Defect in the German Civil and Commercial Code. A Comparative Survey - Economic Analysis)’, Wertpapiermitteilungen, 1162-1169. Lehmann, Michael (1981), Vertragsanbahnung durch Werbung (Contract Formation by Advertising), München, Beck. MacNeil, Ian R. (1984), ‘Bureaucracy and Contracts of Adhesion’, 22 Osgoode Hall Law Journal, 5-28. Mather, Henry (1982), ‘Contract Modification under Duress’, 33 North Carolina Law Review, 615-658. Miceli, Thomas J. (1995), ‘Contract Modification when Litigating for Damages is Costly’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 87-99. Orlic, V. Miodrag (1993), Zakljucivanje Ugovora (Conclusion of Contracts), Institut za uporedno pravo, Beograd. Ott, Claus (1991), ‘Vorvertragliche Aufklärungspflichten im Recht des Güter- und Leistungsaustausches (Precontractual Obligation to Provide Information in the Law)’, in Ott, Claus and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (eds), Ökonomische Probleme des Zivilrechts, Berlin, Springer, 142-162. Ott, Claus (1995), ‘Comment: Contracting by Way of Non-Simultaneous Assent in the German Civil Code’, in Bouckaert, Boudewijn and De Geest, Gerrit (eds), Essays in Law and Economics II: Contract Law, Regulation, and Reflections on Law and Economics, Antwerpen, Maklu, 29 ff. Pacces, Alessio and Pardolesi, Roberto (1997), ‘Clausole Vessatorie in Crisi d’Identità. Appunti di Analisi Economica del Diritto (The Identity Crisis of Unfair Terms. Remarks of Economic Analysis of Law)’, in Furgiuele (ed.), Diritto privato, Padova. Parisi, Francesco (1987), Il Contratto Concluso Mediante Computer (The Formation of Contracts Via Computer), Cedam. Png, Ivan Paak-Liang and Lee, T.K. (1990), ‘The Role of Instalment Payments in Contracts for Services’, 21 Rand Journal of Economics, 83-99. Posner, Eric A. (1995), ‘Contract Law in the Welfare State: A Defense of the Unconscionability Doctrine, Usury Laws, and Related Limitations on the Freedom to Contract’, 24 Journal of Legal Studies, 283-319. Posner, Eric A. (1996), ‘Norms, Formalitiies, and the Statute of Frauds: A comment on “Discovering Contract”’, 145 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1971-1986. Posner, Richard A. (1977), ‘Gratuitous Promises in Economic and Law’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 411-426. Rasmusen, Eric and Ayres, Ian (1993), ‘Mutual and Unilateral Mistake in Contract Law’, 22 Journal of Legal Studies, 309-343.
4300
Contract Formation
77
Robinson, Thorton (1983), ‘Enforcing Extorted Contract Modifications’, 68 Iowa Law Review, 699-707. Roth, Gabriel (1977), ‘Der Schutzzweck richterlicher Kontrolle von AGB’ (The Protection Goal of the Judicial Control of Standard Term Clauses)’, 4(2) Österreichische Zeitschrift für Wirtschaftsrecht, 32-37. Rottenberg, Simon (1985), ‘Mistaken Judicial Activism: Proposed Constraints on Creditor Remedies’, 4 Cato Journal, 335-350. Reprinted in Dorn, James A. and Manne, Henry G. (eds), Economic Liberties and the Judiciary, Fairfax, George Mason University Press, 1987, 335-349. Schanze, Erich (1991), ‘Stellvertretung und ökonomische Agentur-Theorie - Probleme und Wechselbezüge (The Law of Agency and Agency Theory - Problems and Relations)’, in Ott, Claus and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (eds), Ökonomische Probleme des Zivilrechts, Berlin, Springer, 60-75. Scheppele, Kim Lane (1988), Legal Secrets, Equality and Efficiency in the Common Law, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 363 p. Schwartz, Alan (1977), ‘A Re-examination of Nonsubstantive Unconscionability’, 63 Virginia Law Review, 1053-1083. Shavell, Steven (1991), ‘An Economic Analysis of Altriusm and Deferred Gifts’, 20 Journal of Legal Studies, 401-421. Smith, Janet Kiholm and Smith, Richard L. (1990), ‘Contract Law, Mutual Mistake, and Incentives to Produce and Disclose Information’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 467-488. Spier, Kathryn E. (1992), ‘Incomplete Contracts and Signalling’, 23 (3) Rand Journal of Economics, 432-443. Stout, Lynn A. and Barnes, David D. (1992), Economics of Contract Law, Minneapolis, West Publishing. Trebilcock, Michael J. (1976), ‘The Doctrine of Inequality of Bargaining Power: Post-Benthamite Economics in the House of Lords’, 26 University of Toronto Law Journal, 359-385. Reprinted in Kronman, Anthony T. and Posner, Richard A. (eds) (1979), The Economics of Contract Law, Boston, Little Brown, 78-92. Trebilcock, Michael J. (1980), ‘An Economic Approach to the Doctrine of Unconscionability’, in Reiter, Barry J. and Swan, John (eds), Studies in Contract Law, Toronto, Butterworths. Trebilcock, Michael J. (1988), ‘The Role of Insurance Considerations in the Choice of Efficient Civil Liability Rules’, 4 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 243-265. Trebilcock, Michael J. and Dewees, Donald N. (1981), ‘Judicial Control of Standard Form Contracts’, in Burrows, Paul and Veljanovski, Cento G. (eds), The Economic Approach to Law, London, Butterworths, 93-119. Villa, Gianroberto (1988), ‘Errore Riconosciuto, Annullamento del Contratto ed Incentivi alla Ricerca di Informazioni (Known Mistake, Contract Avoidance and Incentives Towards Acquisition of Information)’, Quadrimestre, 286-300. Wils, Wouter P.J. (1993), ‘Who Should Bear the Costs of Failed Negotiations? A Functional Inquiry into Precontractual Liability’, 4 Journal des Economistes et des Etudes Humaines, 93-134.
4400 IMPLIED TERMS AND INTERPRETATION IN CONTRACT LAW George M. Cohen Edward F. Howrey Research Professor of Law, University of Virginia School of Law © Copyright 1999 George M. Cohen
Abstract This chapter examines the economic arguments for textualism and contextualism, the two primary methodologies used by courts to determine the intentions of contracting parties with respect to their performance obligations. Textualism, which is rooted in the idea of complete contracting, calls for a more restrictive approach to implied terms and interpretation than contextualism, which is rooted in the idea of incomplete contracts. The primary conclusions are that, as in other areas of contract law, the choice between the two interpretive methodologies depends on the transaction costs of drafting, the relative likelihood of court error, and the risks of opportunistic behavior. Neither methodology dominates so much that it should be uniformly employed, which is consistent with how courts actually behave. JEL classification: K12 Keywords: Contracts, Completeness, Interpretation, Implied Terms, Opportunism, Contextualism, Textualism
1. Introduction Questions of how courts interpret, and should interpret, contract terms and when courts imply, and should imply, terms to which the contracting parties have not explicitly agreed, loom large in contract disputes and in the legal literature on contract law. Law and economics scholars, however, have written far more extensively on other topics in contract law than on these questions. For example, Judge Posner’s treatise has no section specifically discussing interpretation or implied terms, and discusses contractual good faith in only two paragraphs (Richard Posner, 1998, pp. 103, 126). Other leading textbooks also have no discussion of interpretation or implied terms. One possible explanation for this discrepancy is that there is little need for research specifically on interpretation and implied terms because much of the economic analysis of other areas of contract law carries over straightforwardly to these
78
4400
Implied Terms and Interpretation in Contract Law
79
questions. An alternative explanation is that economic analysis has less to say about interpretation methods than it does about other questions in contract law. This article, which will summarize and expand on the literature that does exist, aims to demonstrate that economic analysis has a good deal to say about interpretation questions, but the issues are complex and there are many fruitful avenues for further research. The argument that there is no real need for a separate economic analysis of interpretation and implied terms stems from the fact that the delineation of the topic is based on legal rather than economic considerations. In contract law, interpretation usually refers to problems arising from express contract terms that are reasonably susceptible of more than one meaning. Implied terms are those that are added to, or place limits on, expressly stated terms. The two are closely related, yet not identical. For example, if a contract contains a ‘best efforts’ clause, determining what that clause requires is a question of interpretation; if the contract contains no such clause, courts may have to decide whether to imply a best efforts obligation, and if they do, they have to determine the content of that obligation. On the other hand, some questions of interpretation do not involve questions of implication, for example, a dispute over the meaning of the word ‘chicken’. In some sense, all contract disputes involve questions of interpretation and implied terms. For example, force majeure clauses - usually discussed in the context of the (implied) impossibility defense - present questions of interpretation, and most contract formation, excuse, and damage rules are ‘implied terms’. But contract law has generally used the labels ‘interpretation’ and ‘implied terms’ more narrowly, to refer to questions of contract performance, rather than questions of formation, excuse, defense, or remedy. That is, the legal issue addressed by these doctrines is whether one or more parties have performed as the contract requires, or have breached. Thus, I will assume for purposes of this discussion that the parties have made an enforceable contract, there are no changed circumstances or ‘mistakes’ sufficient to give rise to an excuse claim, the applicable remedies in the event of breach are accepted, and there are no third-party effects. How do courts decide - and how should they decide - what the performance obligations are and whether the parties have met them?
2. Complete or Incomplete Contracts Economic analyses of contract law have tended to start with the idealized concept of a ‘complete’ contract, though this term has perhaps engendered more confusion than clarity. Traditionally, a complete contract has referred to one that provides a complete description of a set of possible contingencies and
80
Implied Terms and Interpretation in Contract Law
4400
explicit contract terms dictating a performance response for each of these contingencies (Al-Najjar, 1995; Hart and Moore, 1988). Contingencies include changes in ‘exogenous’ economic variables, such as a production cost increase. But they also include ‘endogenous’ behavioral responses, such as falsely claiming a cost increase or seeking refuge from a now-disadvantageous bargain behind a contract term intended to serve a different purpose. Economic analyses generally conclude that if a contract is complete, there is no beneficial role for a court other than to enforce the contract according to its terms; that is, incompleteness is a necessary, though not sufficient, condition for an active court role in interpretation and implied terms. But because no real-world contracts are fully complete in this sense, the concept of completeness does not get us very far. The concept can be rescued in one of three ways. One way is to view completeness as a useful benchmark, similar to perfect competition. Just as some markets are close enough to being perfectly competitive that the perfect competition model is a useful predictor, so some contracts may be complete enough that no reasonable interpretation or implied term questions arise. The law refers to these contracts as ‘integrated’. But tying completeness to integration simply reduces to a tautology the statement that a complete contract obviates the need for interpretation or implied terms. The question is how do courts know when a contract is complete in this sense. One way courts can know a contract is complete is if the parties tell them. Thus, a second way to rescue completeness is to recognize that contracting parties can make a contract complete by using general ‘catchall’ clauses that state what happens in all unspecified states of the world (Hermalin and Katz, 1993, p. 236; Hadfield, 1994, p. 160, n.5). For example, a catchall clause might state: ‘The price term will be x, and will apply regardless of any change in circumstances or conduct by either party’. Alternatively, the parties could state their general desire not to have courts interpret or imply terms. But although contracting parties often use general clauses such as merger clauses, which direct a court to apply a particular interpretive methodology (that is, do not look beyond the writing), they do not seem to use catchall clauses that are broad enough to make contracts complete. Of course, clauses that are not stated as catchalls could be - and sometimes are - interpreted that way, but, to lawyers at least, if not economists, that act of interpretation then requires justification (Hadfield, 1994, p. 160). Even clauses that are stated as catchalls might require interpretation (Charny, 1991). Moreover, contracting parties often use contracting clauses that are the exact opposites of completeness catchalls: general clauses such as ‘good faith’ or ‘best efforts’ clauses signal contracting incompleteness, as opposed to completeness (Hadfield, 1994, p. 163). A third way to rescue completeness, more common in formal economic modeling, is to tie the concept of completeness to the efficient use of available
4400
Implied Terms and Interpretation in Contract Law
81
information. A complete contract is one that makes full use of the private information available to the contracting parties (Hermalin and Katz, 1993, p. 235). The point of this definition is to make clear that parties can write efficient contracts that do not expressly specify the response to every contingency, yet obviate the need for court intervention (Hermalin and Katz, 1993, p. 242). But the fact that parties may in a simplified model be able to write ‘economically complete’ contracts does not answer the question of whether in a given legal dispute they have in fact written one. And the ability of private parties to write economically complete contracts in the real world is unclear. We do not seem to see, for example, contracts of the type described by Hermalin and Katz, in which the contract leaves the quantity and price unspecified, then after some period one party names the price and the other names the quantity. Perhaps the costs of writing these contracts (including the costs of strategic circumvention) are too high. Perhaps the current enforcement regime interferes with, or discourages, the parties, writing of such contracts, though this seems unlikely. It seems fair to say, however, that many if not most contracts are incomplete, or at least the question of their completeness is itself a legitimate question for judicial interpretation. The incompleteness may be intended by both parties, which creates so-called ‘relational contracts’ (Goetz and Scott, 1981), or ‘fiduciary contracts’ (Easterbrook and Fischel, 1983, p. 438). It may result from unintended ‘formulation error’ which occurs when, as a result of defective contractual instructions, the occurrence of some contingency produces surprising consequences (Goetz and Scott, 1985, p. 267, n. 11). It may result from strategic withholding of information by one party. Or incompleteness may result from court error. Whether a contract that the parties think is complete, but is misinterpreted by a court, should in fact be viewed as an ‘incomplete’ contract depends on how completeness is defined. If completeness is defined with reference to the obviation of interpretive questions, the definition must assume that completeness means that a contract’s terms are ‘unambiguous’, that is, the contract terms represent a confluence of the parties’ intentions and the court’s ability to interpret those intentions correctly (unless the contract is somehow self-enforcing). Incomplete contracts may be efficient contracts, even if the incompleteness is unintended. The costs of contractual completeness would often exceed the benefits, just as the costs of reducing crime or pollution or accidents to zero would exceed the benefits. Incomplete contracts will tend to be efficient when contracts are relatively complex, that is, when there are a large number of low-probability contingencies that could affect the value of contractual performance, and the efficient responses to those contingencies vary greatly and so cannot easily be specified in advance (Hadfield, 1994, p. 165, n.15). In these cases the transaction costs of negotiating, drafting, monitoring, and enforcing a complete contract are high.
82
Implied Terms and Interpretation in Contract Law
4400
More generally, in the language of institutional economics, a complete contract is only one form of ‘governance mechanism’ for guiding the behavior of contracting parties (Al-Najjar, 1995). Alternative governance mechanisms include the courts and extralegal enforcement, such as social sanctions and reputation. In this approach, incomplete contracts will tend to be efficient whenever governance mechanisms superior to a detailed contract exist, that is, whenever the opportunity costs of completeness are high. In fact, contrary to the usual economic approach, the actual historical development of contracts is probably best described as starting as incomplete as possible, then becoming more complete and formal as governance mechanisms other than the written contract proved to be inadequate. The question of contract interpretation and implied terms is really a question of when the courts are a superior governance mechanism. Courts may be able through interpretation and implied terms to provide necessary flexibility - efficient adjustments to contingencies - that an incomplete contract otherwise lacks. Courts may also be superior to nonlegal institutions such as reputation because reputation effects may be weak due to such things as cognitive dissonance, optimism about the ability of a party with a poor reputation to change, the difficulty of knowing when a contracting partner has behaved badly, and the last period problem. In general, the role for courts in interpreting contracts and implying terms increases as contracts become more efficiently incomplete.
3. Incomplete Contracts and Contractual Intent Now suppose the contract is incomplete, as are most contracts that are the subject of litigation. What should a court do? The economists’ (and courts’) usual assumption is that courts should follow the intentions of the parties, but to admit incompleteness is to admit that the intention of the parties is uncertain, or at least disputed (some would say nonexistent). The next best solution is to adopt the term - or interpretive methodology - the parties would have chosen had they bargained over the matter, that is, presumed or hypothetical intent. But how is presumed intent determined? There are two general possibilities on which economic analyses have focused (Hadfield, 1992, 1994, p. 161). First, courts might presume that complete contracting is both feasible and desirable. This presumption has both a positive and a negative component. On the positive side, the express terms of the contract are presumed to be the best approximations of the parties’ intentions and deemed to create a complete contract. This strategy is usually referred to as textualism. On the negative side, if parties fail to write a complete contract, the incompleteness is presumed to be inefficient, whether unintended
4400
Implied Terms and Interpretation in Contract Law
83
or strategic, and the court’s approach should be to deter this behavior and encourage complete contracting. This strategy is a variant of what has come to be known as penalty defaults (Ayres and Gertner, 1989), which is itself a variant of an old idea in the Austrian School of economics that individuals should bear the consequences of their actions so that they become more rational over time (for example, Wonnell, 1986, p. 520). The second general approach involves a presumption that contractual incompleteness is unavoidable and/or desirable, due to limitations of money, time, comprehension and foresight (Hadfield, 1992, p. 259). The courts then fill in the gaps by presuming the parties intended to contract with reference to some standard external to the written contract. Courts might presume parties contracted with reference to their current (course of performance) or prior (course of dealing) conduct, or to the conduct and understandings of similarly situated parties (trade usage or custom or business mores). Strategies that focus on these presumptions, which are featured predominantly in the Uniform Commercial Code, are usually referred to as contextualist. Alternatively, courts might presume the parties contracted with the expectation that courts would fill in any gaps with a joint maximizing term that would have been written by rational parties under conditions of low transaction costs (Goetz and Scott, 1981). In practice, the joint maximization strategy will often dissolve into contextualism, as courts lack the data necessary to do pure joint maximization. It is important to remember that all of these strategies involve presumptions. It is all too easy for courts or proponents of a particular strategy to criticize the alternatives as failing to hew closely enough to the parties’ intentions, when in fact the parties’ intentions in incomplete contracts are at least uncertain, and the question is which strategy is more likely to be successful at approximating these intentions. For example, suppose a buyer rejects goods delivered late after the market price drops below the contract price. A court might be called upon to decide whether to imply a good faith limitation on the buyer’s ability to reject. A textualist might argue no on the ground that such an implication would be contrary to the parties’ intentions as expressed in the time of delivery term. But the parties’ intentions - whether actual or hypothetical - may well be that a good faith obligation should be implied rather than that the time of delivery term should be interpreted as absolute. A proposition that textualism, contextualism, penalty defaults, or joint maximization best represents the parties’ intentions needs to be defended. Economic analysis can help to identify the conditions under which the various interpretive strategies are more likely to approximate the parties’ intentions, and whether courts are better off pursuing a pure interpretive strategy or a mixed one.
84
Implied Terms and Interpretation in Contract Law
4400
4. Default versus Mandatory Rules and Contractual Intent The recognition of incomplete contracting and the uncertainty of contractual intent renders problematic another distinction that has played an important role in economic discussions of contracts, namely default rules versus mandatory rules. The term ‘default rule’ refers to several different characteristics: (1) if the parties specify some contract term, the court will enforce that term; (2) if the parties fail to specify some contract term, the court will fill in the gap and supply one; and (3) if the parties fail to specify some contract term but do not want the court to fill in the gap, the court will honor that intent (that is, the gap-filling rule itself is a default). UCC § 2-305 on open price terms is a good example of a rule that satisfies all three characteristics. Default rules are usually contrasted with mandatory rules, which term can also refer to three characteristics. Mandatory rules can refer to situations in which the court knowingly: (1) imposes a term that contradicts a term the parties specified; (2) refuses to fill in a gap that the parties left when the parties wanted the court to fill the gap; and (3) fills in a gap that the parties did not want the court to fill in. When economists refer to mandatory terms, they usually mean the first sense, that is the court rejecting a term the parties specified. An example would be a liquidated damage clause deemed to be a penalty, or a term deemed to be unconscionable. The usual critique of mandatory terms is that because they disregard the intentions of the parties, the parties who prefer these terms will be made worse off. For example, if a court imposes a stronger performance obligation on an obligor than the parties intended, then future obligors will extract a higher price, which is more than the obligee wanted to pay (else he would have paid for it originally) (for example, Easterbrook and Fischel, 1993, p. 431). This critique makes sense if contracts are assumed to be complete. But once we allow for the possibility of efficiently incomplete contracts and unclear intent, it becomes much more difficult to distinguish mandatory rules from default rules. Take, for example, the implied duty of good faith, or the duty of loyalty in fiduciary contracts. Are these defaults or mandatory rules? That depends on how well one thinks the duty of good faith tracks contractual intent. If one believes that parties may write incomplete contracts for which they expect courts to fill in the gaps, the duty of good faith or the duty of loyalty might easily be viewed as a default. If the parties want a particular obligation that conflicts with what courts ordinarily view as good faith or loyalty, and they specify that obligation, courts will generally enforce it. This is the view espoused by Easterbrook and Fischel (1993). On the other hand, if one believes that courts use the duty of good faith or the duty of loyalty to fill in gaps that the parties did not want to be filled, or to reject obligations the parties thought they had fully specified, then the duty of good faith looks more like a mandatory term. UCC § 1-102(3) evidences this ambivalence about the good faith obligation.
4400
Implied Terms and Interpretation in Contract Law
85
The mirror image issue is presented by the doctrine of certainty, which says that courts may sometimes decline to fill gaps the parties have left in contracts. The doctrine could be viewed as a default if one is willing to presume that when the parties have left ‘too many’ gaps for the courts to fill, they do not have contractual intent, and if they do have such intent they will override the default by filling in the terms themselves. Alternatively, the doctrine could be viewed as a mandatory rule if one assumes that the courts use it to refuse to fill in gaps when the parties wanted them to. The point is that the labels ‘default’ and ‘mandatory’ are conclusions that can mask the assumptions being made about contractual completeness and intent, and so do not by themselves resolve the questions of implied terms and interpretation.
5. Unintended or Strategic Incompleteness: Encouraging Better Contracting If the contracting parties wanted to write a complete contract but failed in some way, the failure can be viewed as analogous to an accident in tort law. The accident may occur because one or both parties failed to take cost-effective ‘contract-based precautions’ (Cohen, 1992, p. 949). Alternatively, one of the parties might make a contract incomplete to serve his strategic bargaining interests by withholding information. In either case, courts can use the doctrines of interpretation and implied terms to encourage the parties to ‘facilitate improvements in contractual formulation’ (Goetz and Scott, 1985, p. 264). One way to encourage better contracting is to encourage more complete contracts, that is, the greater use of express written terms. If a court is willing to ‘insure’ parties through flexible interpretations and implied terms it creates a classic moral hazard problem: the parties have less incentive to write good contracts themselves, for example contracts with more precise language. Doctrines such as the parol evidence rule encourage parties to write more complete contracts by giving more weight to the written document and limiting the extrinsic evidence courts can consider. Strict application of these doctrines may thereby increase the accuracy of contract enforcement (reduce contractual accidents) by reducing the interpretive risks of relying on extrinsic evidence (Eric Posner, 1998, p. 546). As in tort law, the goal of encouraging better contracting makes economic sense if the precautions are cost-effective. That will be the case if one or both of the contracting parties face low ex ante transaction costs of drafting and monitoring express contract terms that successfully specify performance obligations in response to different regret contingencies, as well as if the expected losses from interpretive accidents are high (Eric Posner, 1998, pp. 543-547). Moreover, courts must be able to identify accurately situations in
86
Implied Terms and Interpretation in Contract Law
4400
which precautions are cost-effective. Usually, the best courts can do is to use proxies to make reasonable comparative judgments. In particular, in investigating precautions, courts can compare the capabilities of contracting parties and they can compare the contract in dispute to other litigated contracts (Eric Posner, 1998, pp. 553-561). In comparing contracting parties, courts might conclude that one contracting party is the ‘least cost avoider’, or in this case the ‘cheaper contract drafter’, namely the party in a better position to clarify a term or to identify what should happen in the event of some contingency. This approach explains such interpretive rules such as contra proferentum, which encourage the party in the better position to draft a more complete contract to do so. Similarly, if one of the parties is a repeat contractor or is assisted by legal counsel and the other is not (as in many consumer contracts), imposing liability on the repeat and represented contractor in cases of contractual ambiguity or incompleteness will encourage that party to improve the terms of its contracts. In addition, if one of the parties has an informational advantage, imposing liability on that party could encourage similarly situated parties in the future to reveal the information. But there may not always be a ‘cheaper contract drafter’, or if there is, the necessary precautions might not be cost-effective. Such might be the case, for example, with a party who commits a ‘scrivener’s error’ in a written contract, especially if the error is one that the other party could reasonably have noticed. The alternative of comparing similar contracts rather than contracting parties can also yield some useful guidelines. For example, one piece of relevant evidence about ex ante transaction costs would be how common a particular term is in similar contracts. The more common a term, the more likely the costs of contracting over that term are low. Courts can then presume that most parties who wanted such a term would have contracted expressly for it and those who have not can be deemed negligent or strategic. Alternatively, one might argue that transaction costs are low for relatively ‘simple’ contracts or for ‘crucial’ terms. But even if courts are able through comparative analysis to identify simple contracts or common or crucial terms, there is a further difficulty: ease of contracting may not be a sufficient justification for imposing liability. The reason is that encouraging better contracting does not necessarily mean encouraging greater contractual completeness; it may mean encouraging greater contractual incompleteness through reliance on implied terms. Under a majoritarian default approach to implied terms, courts would minimize transaction costs by choosing the mix of express and implied terms that most contracting parties would want. The majority of contracting parties might want courts to use implied terms, especially in well-developed markets, because they believe that will save on the costs of contracting, even if the transaction costs of contracting are relatively low. Alternatively, the majority of contracting parties might believe that relying solely on express terms - even those that
4400
Implied Terms and Interpretation in Contract Law
87
simply try to mimic implied terms - might be less reliable than relying on well-established implied terms either in conjunction with or instead of express terms; that is, they might fear court misinterpretation more than court misimplication. The only contracting parties who should be encouraged to contract more explicitly under this approach are those who have ‘idiosyncratic’ preferences. Thus, the fact that parties fail to contract expressly (or unambiguously) for a given term - even a common or crucial one - may simply be an expression of intent to be bound by the majoritarian understanding of that obligation. An example of the majoritarian default approach is the rule that contracting parties ‘in the trade’ are bound by trade usages, even if they did not know about them. This rule encourages the parties in a trade to develop such usages (which are majoritarian understandings) and to familiarize themselves rapidly with these usages, hence reducing the need for heavily lawyered documents (Warren, 1981). Thus, implied terms serve as a public good, a standard set of contract terms that parties either accept or reject. The same majoritarian approach could also apply to the interpretation of express terms. The ‘plain meaning rule’ could be viewed as a way of encouraging contracting parties to learn the common (one might even say implied) meaning of words, thus reducing the need for and costs of elaborate definition and explanation. Of course, the majoritarian approach to encouraging better contracting itself presents problems. For example, identifying the majoritarian default seems to call for an empirical inquiry, which courts are often ill-equipped to make, though to the extent that there is a recognized trade usage, or a course of dealing or course of performance, this problem is mitigated. Verkerke (1995) attempts to remedy this problem in the context of employment contracts by surveying employers about the discharge terms contained in their employment documents. He found that 52 percent of employers reported that their employment documents specified an ‘at will’ provision (the prevailing default), 15 percent reported that their documents contain a ‘just cause’ provision, and 33 percent reported that they do not have documents that address the issue explicitly (Verkerke, 1995, p. 867). He also found that larger firms and firms from more ‘liberal’ jurisdictions are more likely to contract explicitly for the at will rule. From these data, Verkerke concludes that the at will default is the majoritarian default. A more cautious conclusion would be that a broadly defined just cause provision is not a majoritarian default, but given the limitations many states have put on the at will doctrine and the possibility of unwritten (or written, but narrow) qualifications on the right to discharge, whether the majoritarian default is the strong form of the at will doctrine expressed in many employer documents or a more limited form is less clear. An additional problem with the majoritarian default approach is the need to determine when the parties have contracted around the default. Goetz and Scott (1985) argue that it is often difficult for courts to tell whether parties are
88
Implied Terms and Interpretation in Contract Law
4400
using express terms to trump (opt out of) implied terms or merely to supplement them. That is, it may be difficult for courts to tell in a particular case whether the parties intended to incorporate implied terms by writing an incomplete contract, or whether they intended the express terms they used to create a complete contract; thus, the contractual ‘accident’ results from the parties’ unintended failure to resolve the tension between the express terms and implied terms. The more courts favor and encourage implied terms and common usages, the more costly it becomes for the parties who want to contract out of those terms to do so. As discussed above, ostensible default rules begin to look more like mandatory rules. The courts’ choice of interpretive strategy, therefore, may affect not only the parties’ incentives to contract more expressly, but also their ability to contract around the implied default rule. Goetz and Scott argue that the more likely it is that contracting parties will be unhappy with the court’s implied terms and interpretations - the more heterogeneous contracting parties are likely to be - the more inefficient an expansive approach to implied terms and interpretation will be. In contrast, where contracting parties are more likely to engage in homogeneous and repetitive transactions - that is, where the transactional variance is low - the more likely a contextual approach will be efficient because it will foster the development of more standardized terms by trade groups, lawyers, and the parties themselves. One could also justify the contextual approach in such cases on the ground that in ‘conventional’ contracts, court error is likely to be low (Eric Posner, 1998, pp. 553, 556). Implementing this notion is often more difficult than stating it, however. For example, Goetz and Scott suggest that in well-developed markets courts should generally allow context evidence to supplement express terms, but should generally not allow context evidence to override the plain meaning of express terms (Goetz and Scott, 1985, pp. 313-315). Eric Posner has recently criticized this argument on the ground that there is no theoretical justification for having a flexible approach with respect to incompleteness (implied terms) but a strict approach with respect to ambiguity (interpretation of express terms) (Eric Posner, 1998, pp. 559-560). On the one hand, it should not matter whether the parties use, for example, a best efforts clause or leave one out and let the court imply it; if the courts consider extrinsic evidence in one case, they should do so in the other. On the other hand, the ‘plain meaning’ of a best efforts clause requires a kind of context evidence, namely the general understanding of the clause. Thus, there may be no inconsistency in having a flexible approach to incompleteness and a plain meaning approach to ambiguity: both favor allowing a certain type of contextual evidence, namely general contextual evidence. The problem arises when the contextual evidence being considered is not general but specific to the contracting parties, such as course of dealing, course of performance, or prior negotiations. Here a flexible
4400
Implied Terms and Interpretation in Contract Law
89
approach to incompleteness would allow the specific context evidence to trump the general, but the plain meaning rule would have the general context evidence trumping the specific. At this level of generality, Posner’s argument seems correct. Although one could imagine cases in which a court might want to use a flexible approach to incompleteness and a strict approach to ambiguity, it is difficult to make any general statements about such cases; in fact, one could just as easily imagine cases in which a strict approach to implied terms and a flexible approach to ambiguity would be appropriate. Goetz and Scott’s argument about the plain meaning rule perhaps should be read as limited to express terms that are commonly understood as general trumping terms that override implied terms, such as merger clauses, disclaimers, or clauses granting one party broad discretion. If the parties go to the trouble of using such a general trumping term, then arguably that should be a sufficient signal of their idiosyncracy. But even this interpretation is unsatisfactory because, as with the at will term discussed above, it may not be clear whether the parties simply intended to use the trumping clause to reject an overly broad implied term or whether they also meant it to convey the full measure of the parties’ obligations to the exclusion of all extrinsic evidence. The discussion in this section so far has assumed that ex ante transaction costs are low. The higher the ex ante transaction costs of drafting and monitoring become, the less likely it will be efficient for a court to adopt restrictive rules of interpretation and implied terms that encourage parties to contract more explicitly, because it will not be cost-effective for the parties to do so. Reliance on the types of contextual evidence discussed above now becomes relatively more cost-effective as the accuracy of the written contract declines. If courts take too restrictive a view of interpretation and implied terms, the development of cost-saving interpretive devices might be discouraged in favor of more complete, but costlier, writings (Burton, 1980, p. 373). Alternatively, too few contracts might be formed ex ante, as the promisor’s costs rise to cover an anticipated remedy that the promisee does not value at this cost. And too much performance might occur ex post, as the promisor performs even when the cost of doing so exceeds the value of performance (Easterbrook and Fischel, 1993, p. 445). Once again, stating the general principle may be easier than applying it. Classic examples of high-transaction costs contracts are principal-agent contracts usually referred to as ‘fiduciary’. These contracts typically involve complex tasks for which the principal cannot easily measure the agent’s effort or outcome, thus making express contracting difficult (Cooter and Freedman, 1991a, p. 1051; Easterbrook and Fischel, 1993, p. 426). Other examples include contracts between unsophisticated parties or long-term contracts. Even in high-transaction cost contracts, however, a more restrictive approach to interpretation and implied terms might be appropriate if the contracting parties’
90
Implied Terms and Interpretation in Contract Law
4400
preferences with respect to certain obligations are likely to be idiosyncratic, or equivalently if the relevant context evidence is less reliable (Eric Posner, 1998, pp. 557-558). By the same token, the same concerns raised by high-transaction cost contracts might exist even in ordinary sales contracts. For example, if a contract allows for a 10 percent variation in the quantity for the (unstated) purpose of avoiding liability over loss during transportation, a question might arise whether the seller could take advantage of this provision to deliberately increase or decrease the quantity as the market price drops or rises. Although one could say that the buyer could contract to prevent such behavior by, say, limiting the application of the quantity variation provision to losses suffered in transit (Gillette, 1981, p. 655), it may be quite difficult to draft such a clause. What should happen, for example, if both a market price change and damage to the goods occur? What about damage to the goods before and after transit? Is it always desirable to have the parties provide explicitly for all these contingencies? The point is that a given contract may be viewed as low-transaction cost for some purposes and high-transaction cost for others.
6. Deterring Opportunistic Behavior Getting the mix of express and implied contracting terms right - that is, encouraging the optimally complete written contract - is only one consideration (and perhaps not the most important) that courts do or should face when deciding questions of interpretation or implied terms. A second approach to the question of how courts should interpret contracts and when they should imply terms focuses not on encouraging efficient contracting, but on deterring opportunistic contractual behavior (though obviously the two overlap). Opportunism can be broadly defined as deliberate contractual conduct by one party contrary to the other party’s reasonable expectations based on the parties’ agreement, contractual norms, or conventional morality (Cohen, 1992, p. 957). Alternatively, opportunism is an attempted redistribution of an already allocated contractual pie, that is a mere wealth transfer (Muris, 1981; compare Burton, 1980, p. 378). For example, a contract may require B to paint A’s portrait ‘to A’s satisfaction’ (Richard Posner, 1998, pp. 103-104). This provision allows A to reject the portrait even if others like it if it does not suit A’s taste. But if A rejects the portrait for reasons other than unhappiness with the painting’s quality - say because A remarries a spouse who does not want A’s portrait in the house - A acts opportunistically. The problem of opportunistic behavior is perhaps the key justification for court intervention in contracts. In general, ‘the threat of opportunism increases transaction costs because potential opportunists and victims expend resources perpetrating and protecting against opportunism’, which ‘do not help produce
4400
Implied Terms and Interpretation in Contract Law
91
a commodity or service that the contracting parties mutually value’ (Muris, 1981, p. 524). More specifically, opportunistic behavior makes complete contracting extremely difficult. Even if contracting parties could anticipate all of the possible changes in economic variables, they would have a much harder time anticipating and protecting against opportunistic behavior by the other party. At the extreme, the more one contracting party is willing to contemplate the possible opportunistic behavior of his contracting partner, the less likely he will be to want to contract with that partner at all. Some degree of trust is necessary for contracting to occur. More important, many seemingly airtight contract terms can seem awfully leaky once a clever lawyer and a highly motivated client get through analyzing them. Just as cartel members can often find ways to cheat on cartels involving the most standardized products, so disappointed contractors can often find a way to act opportunistically in the most standardized contracts. Because contracting parties cannot solve all problems of opportunism on their own, courts can reduce transaction costs by imposing liability on the ‘most likely opportunist’. But there are difficulties with using courts to deter opportunism. In particular, opportunism is often ‘subtle’, that is, difficult to detect or easily masked as legitimate conduct (Muris, 1981, p. 525). Contract performance disputes arise when one party becomes unhappy with the contract. This unhappiness may stem from the occurrence of a risk that party had contractually agreed to bear. However, the disappointed party might be able to exploit some contract term to claim that the other party had breached or to allow the contested behavior, even though the term was intended to handle another situation. Alternatively, the disappointed party might be able to exaggerate or misrepresent the extent of a contingency that might excuse his performance, and so escape his contractual obligations. The problem that subtle opportunism poses for courts is often surmountable. In the fiduciary context, courts adopt, via the duty of loyalty, a strong presumption of wrongful misappropriation by an agent when that agent has a conflict of interest, engages in self-dealing, or withholds information from the principal (Cooter and Freedman, 1991a, p. 1054). More broadly, opportunism may be more possible whenever one party has a significant information advantage over the other. In other contexts, courts can find ‘objectively verifiable circumstances that act as surrogates for the existence of opportunism’ (Muris, 1981, p. 530). On the one hand, when the contract assigns a particular risk to one of the parties, and that risk materializes, the court should be skeptical of attempts by that party to escape his obligations via a different contract term. The classic example is a change in market price. If a buyer in a requirements contract suddenly experiences a large drop in ‘requirements’ after the market price has fallen below the contract price, or a large increase in requirements after the market price has risen above the contract price, the court
92
Implied Terms and Interpretation in Contract Law
4400
should suspect opportunism or, in legal terms, a violation of the implied obligation of good faith. On the other hand, whereas a change in market price suggests opportunism, a change in economic circumstances either not contemplated by the contract or whose risk the contract places on the party seeking strict enforcement, suggests a lack of opportunism. To return to the requirements contract example, if the buyer’s requirements decrease or increase because of a change in costs or technology subsequent to the contract, the buyer’s behavior is likely not opportunistic (is in good faith) because the very purpose of the requirements contract is to assign some risk of variation in the buyer’s needs to the seller. Another example of objectively verifiable circumstances on which courts can focus is ex post transaction costs. If the market for substitute performance is thick, opportunism is less likely (Goetz and Scott, 1983). Opportunism can occur only when it is costly to switch to a new contracting partner, that is, when at least one party has made sunk, specific investments. Although this test may be useful in establishing general presumptions, it is of limited help in deciding specific cases. Litigated cases tend to be precisely those in which ex post transaction costs are likely to be high; otherwise, the cases would be settled. Although opportunism is often discussed as an ex post problem, opportunism can occur ex ante as well. For example, under a strict parol evidence rule, a party might intentionally make oral statements that the other party understands and relies on as part of the contract, then leave the provision out of (or put a contradictory provision in) the writing. One common situation is where a party tells the other to ignore the terms on the back of the first party’s forms, then later tries to enforce those terms. On the other hand, under a more flexible parol evidence rule, a party might intentionally ‘pad’ the negotiation record with statements that party knows will be rejected by the other party both orally and in writing, in the hopes that the first party can later convince the court that these statements were in fact part of the contract (a common practice in legislative history) (Eric Posner, 1998, pp. 564-565). This latter form of opportunism helps explain why courts tend to be much more skeptical of evidence that the parties can easily manipulate - especially prior negotiations - than evidence over which the parties have less control especially common usages. It may also explain the motivation behind the use of merger clauses as well as one reason why they should not be interpreted too broadly. It is difficult for a party to predict in advance which negotiation tidbit the other side might seize on later (Eric Posner, 1998, p. 572), so it is necessary to write a broad clause that excludes them all. The same is not true for less manipulable evidence, but it might be difficult to specify all such evidence in writing in advance, especially in a single ‘anti-merger’ clause. It is important to recognize once again that the opportunism approach is dependent on determining contractual intent, which is often uncertain. Stating that courts do and should deter opportunism does not by itself explain how
4400
Implied Terms and Interpretation in Contract Law
93
courts do and should resolve the question of how to determine contractual intent; it simply opens the question up. Professor Muris, who first articulated the opportunism approach to good faith, recognized that to apply the approach courts need to consider ‘risk allocation’, which is a question of ‘interpretation’ that is ‘analytically prior to [the question] of opportunism’ (Muris, 1981, pp. 561-562, n.110). Nevertheless the opportunism approach may have something to say about how courts should go about determining intent. First, courts should hesitate to interpret a contract in such a way as to permit conduct that would ordinarily be understood as opportunistic. Second, courts should hesitate to attribute to contracting parties an intention not to have courts police against opportunistic behavior (compare Muris, 1981, p. 573, n.138). Because contextualism and textualism are both useful for deterring different types of opportunism, we should therefore expect - and we find - that courts are never completely committed to one or the other.
7. The Problem of Joint Fault or Multiple Contingencies In many contractual disputes, there are often precautionary steps that both parties could have taken to have avoided or mitigated the contractual loss. We have already considered one such precaution - drafting a better contract. Quite separate from the costs of drafting better terms are the costs of reducing the likelihood of, or harm from, some risk ex ante, and of mitigating losses ex post. Parties seeking to have the court imply or interpret a term in their favor may be attempting to avoid a risk that the contract assigned to them or to extricate themselves from a vulnerable position of their own making, which they could have avoided at low cost. In these cases, courts may have to make judgments about the relative fault of both parties to decide whose behavior it is more important to deter in a particular case. In particular, if one party is the least cost avoider of some contingency while the other party regrets the contract for other reasons and is opportunistically seeking to avoid its obligations, courts face a ‘negligence-opportunism tradeoff’ (Cohen, 1992, pp. 983-990). To take a classic example, suppose a builder promises to use a particular brand of pipe in building a house but inadvertently substitutes a different, but functionally equivalent brand, a fact not discovered by the owner until the house is nearly completed. The owner refuses to make the final payment on the house. The court must choose between placing liability on the negligent builder or the potentially opportunistic owner. There is an economic case to be made that opportunism - if sufficiently proved - is more costly behavior and deterrence of that behavior should take priority (Cohen, 1992). On the other hand, the more likely it is that the builder ‘built first and asked questions later’ (Goldberg,
94
Implied Terms and Interpretation in Contract Law
4400
1985, p. 71), the more willing courts should be to find for the owner by implying a condition. To take another example of the negligence-opportunism tradeoff, suppose that a buyer rejects goods delivered late after a market price drop and the seller sues. There are two contingencies here: the price drop and the late delivery. The contract assigns the risk of the price drop to the buyer and the late delivery to the seller. Textualism will not resolve this dispute: either the price term or the time of delivery term cannot be read absolutely. It is not sufficient to say that only the seller has breached, because what constitutes a breach and the consequences of that breach are precisely what is at issue. Nor can it be said that only the seller could take precautions here because neither party could do anything about the price drop and the buyer did not cause the delay in delivery. If the buyer’s rejection is viewed as opportunistic behavior, then refraining from such behavior could be viewed as a ‘precaution’. Depending on the circumstances, there is an economic argument to be made for implying a good faith ‘limitation’ on the buyer’s ability to escape its obligations.
8. Court Error One of the main criticisms of courts’ taking too contextualist an approach to interpreting and implying contractual terms is the problem of court error and incompetence. At one extreme, if courts make no errors in importing contextualist evidence, then such evidence should always be allowed, at least if the cost of producing such evidence is not too high. At the other extreme, if courts make too many mistakes in interpreting or implying terms, then textualism becomes superior if the transaction costs of contracting are lower than the expected savings resulting from fewer court errors (Eric Posner, 1998, pp. 542-544). If courts make the methodological error of choosing contextualism in situations of high court error, then the parties will respond by attempting to contract around the court’s rules through detailed language or broad merger clauses, by avoiding courts (for example, arbitration) or contracts (for example, vertical integration), or by engaging in inefficient contractual behavior to adjust to the court’s erroneous legal standard. But the problem of court error does not necessarily favor textualism. In the first place, as Hadfield (1994) has argued, the feared inefficient responses to court error may not occur. Developing a formal model of good faith clauses in intentionally incomplete contracts in the presence of probabilistic court error, Hadfield concludes that the possibility of court error does not always caution against court intervention. If courts are of such low competence that the parties cannot reduce their marginal liability by improving their contractual efforts in a cost-justified way (that is, liability is essentially strict), then the parties will not change their behavior under the contract and will adjust to the anticipated
4400
Implied Terms and Interpretation in Contract Law
95
court error by adjusting the price of the contract rather than by declining to contract. On the other hand, if courts are of higher, but still limited, competence, then enforcement of good faith clauses may lead to greater joint profits for the parties than nonenforcement. This will occur if the court error does not have too severe an adverse effect on the parties’ incentives, and if the private mechanisms for inducing optimal effort without court enforcement are relatively weak. In addition, Hadfield argues that courts of low competence should not follow bright line rules or precedent, but instead should use standards. By bright line rules she means rules requiring a certain level of conduct that is independent of changing economic conditions; for example, a bright line rule might say to a supplier in an output contract that to act in good faith it cannot reduce its output to zero unless continued production puts the firm on the verge of bankruptcy. By standards she means required actions that vary depending on the economic circumstances, such as a rule that says an agent subject to a best efforts clause must adopt reasonable sales methods. Bright line rules thus correspond to textualism, whereas standards correspond to contextualism. Bright line rules may compound rather than ameliorate court error by a court of limited competence, because a bright line rule setting forth a required action will so often be ‘wrong’. Thus, parties will respond to a bright line rule either by ignoring it or by conforming their behavior to the inefficient safe harbor established by the rule. Standards, by contrast, are more likely to encompass the ‘efficient’ response because courts using standards will set the minimum required action low and set the safe harbor high. Thus, contracting parties are likely to realize that their marginal liability can be reduced through increases in cooperative effort (because courts are likely to notice and take those efforts into account), and so the parties will be encouraged to take steps in the direction of optimal behavior. The point is that the presence of court error does not preclude the desirability of court flexibility. A similar argument might apply even outside the relational contract context. The argument for textualism here is that if transaction costs are low, court error will be minimized because the parties will be encouraged to put more terms in the writing. Textualist courts will interpret this writing more accurately than contextualist courts, which will sometimes erroneously rely on contextual evidence in addition to the writing (Eric Posner, 1998, pp. 545-546). The argument assumes that transaction costs include, as has been suggested above, not merely the cost of drafting, but the cost of drafting in such a way that courts make fewer interpretive mistakes. But low drafting costs may not be sufficient to ensure that court error is reduced under textualism. If, for example, drafting costs decrease (as they probably have due to technological progress) so that it is relatively easy for parties to add more terms to their writings, court error could in fact increase if more detailed contracts are more likely to have conflicting terms or courts are more likely to misinterpret a term to cover a
96
Implied Terms and Interpretation in Contract Law
4400
particular contingency the parties did not intend to cover. Another aspect of court error that some argue supports textualism is error in interpretive methodology, namely the choice between textualism and contextualism itself. The contracting parties may prefer textualism and express that preference through, for example, merger clauses. But if courts make errors in determining the parties’ intentions generally, they will also err in determining the parties’ methodological preference. Courts may therefore choose contextualism too often (Eric Posner, 1998, pp. 547-548, 570-571). But once again, this conclusion depends on the assumption that if courts use textualism (this time to decide the parties’ methodological preference) they will err less often because the costs to the parties of accurately expressing their methodological intentions are low. One would think, however, that the costs to the parties of drafting a particularized methodological term are quite high. Methodological preference is only a second-order concern for the parties. It is difficult for the parties to predict how court error will likely impact the wide variety of possible disputes they might have, and methodological preference terms have no contractual use to the parties outside of litigation. As a result, it is not obvious a priori that choosing a textualist approach minimizes court error. Suppose, for example, that the parties generally prefer a textualist approach and expect interpretation x of some term. There are actually three ways the court could err. The court could take a contextual approach but reach interpretation x. Or the court could take a textual approach and reach interpretation y. Or the court could take a contextual approach and reach interpretation y. Although the parties prefer the textualist approach, it might be more important to them that the court gets the term right, however the court does it. If courts are more likely to choose the desired interpretation x using a contextual approach and interpretation y using a textual approach - either because the parties underestimate the courts’ competence with respect to that term or because their expressed preference for textualism inaccurately conveys the parties’ correct estimate of the courts’ competence in this instance - then error costs could be reduced if the court ‘mistakenly’ used a contextual approach. To give a simple numerical example, suppose the court can choose either a textualist or contextualist methodology. If it chooses textualism, the likelihood of interpreting the term the way the parties want is 0.4; if it chooses contextualism, the likelihood of interpreting the term the way the parties want is 0.6. Suppose further that ex ante the parties would value the court’s using textualism and choosing x at 100; would value the court’s using contextualism and choosing x at 80; would value the court’s using textualism and choosing y at 50; and would value the court’s using contextualism and choosing y at 10. Thus, the parties prefer textualism to contextualism, but prefer the right outcome more. The expected value if the court uses a textualist approach is (0.4 @ 100) + (0.6 @ 50) = 40 + 30 = 70. The expected value if the court uses a
4400
Implied Terms and Interpretation in Contract Law
97
contextualist approach is (0.6 @ 80) + (0.4 @ 10) = 48 + 40 = 88 > 70. The point is that the possibility of court error does not always argue in favor of textualism. Both textualist and contextualist methodologies lead to court error. The real question is which methodology has the lowest error rate and at what cost. It is hard to answer this question in the abstract. This may help to explain why courts do not - and never will - use pure interpretive methodologies, but tend to switch back and forth depending on the circumstances.
9. Summary and Future Research To a large degree, the economic approach to interpretation and applied terms parallels the approach in other areas of contract law. Court intervention is most justifiable when transaction costs are high and the likelihood of court error is low. Transaction costs include not only the ex ante costs of drafting in such a way as to reduce court error, but the ex post costs associated with sunk specific investments that make possible opportunistic behavior, as well as the costs of alternative governance institutions such as extralegal sanctions. Most of the economic arguments that suggest a restrictive court approach to interpretation and implied terms have counterarguments. Therefore the institutional and contractual context matters greatly in deciding what approach efficiency-minded courts should take. The literature to date has mapped out the broad contours. Future work will have to do the hard digging. That means paying more attention to why people write the contracts they do and the circumstances that motivate nonperformance.
Bibliography on Implied Terms and Interpretation in Contract Law (4400) Al-Najjar, Nabil I. (1995), ‘Incomplete Contracts and the Governance of Contractual Relationships’, 85 American Economic Review Papers and Proceedings, 432-436. Barnes, David W. and Stout, Lynn A. (1992), The Economics of Contract Law, St Paul, MN, West Publishing Co. Burton, Steven J. (1980), ‘Breach of Contract and the Common Law Duty to Perform in Good Faith’, 94 Harvard Law Review, 369-403. Burton, Steven J. (1981), ‘Good Faith Performance of a Contract within Article 2 of the Uniform Commercial Code’, 67 Iowa Law Review, 1-30. Cohen, George M. (1992), ‘The Negligence-Opportunism Tradeoff in Contract Law’, 20 Hofstra Law Review, 941-1016. Cooter, Robert D. and Freedman, Bradley J. (1991a), ‘The Fiduciary Relationship: Its Economic Character and Legal Consequences’, 66 New York University Law Review, 1045-1075. Reprinted in Pardolesi, Roberto and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds) (1990), Law and Economics, Some Further Insights: 7th European Law and Economics Association Conference, Rome, Sept. 3-5, 17-50.
98
Implied Terms and Interpretation in Contract Law
4400
Cooter, Robert D. and Freedman, Bradley J. (1991b), ‘An Economic Model of the Fiduciary’s Duty of Loyalty’, 10 Tel Aviv Studies in Law, 297 ff. Easterbrook, Frank H. and Fischel, Daniel R. (1993), ‘Contract and Fiduciary Duty’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 425-446. Gergen, Mark P. (1995), ‘A Defense of Judicial Reconstruction of Contracts’, 71 Indiana Law Journal, 45-99. Gillette, Clayton P. (1981), ‘Limitations on the Obligation of Good Faith’, 1981 Duke Law Journal , 619-665. Goetz, Charles J. and Scott, Robert E. (1983), ‘The Mitigation Principle: Toward a General Theory of Contractual Obligation’, 69 Virginia Law Review, 967-1024. Goetz, Charles J. and Scott, Robert E. (1985), ‘The Limits of Expanded Choice: An Analysis of the Interactions between Express and Implied Contract Terms’, 73 California Law Review, 261-322. Goldberg, Victor P. (1985), ‘Relational Exchange, Contract Law, and the Boomer Problem’, 141 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 570-575. Reprinted in Goldberg, Victor P. (ed.) (1989), Readings in the Economics of Contract Law, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 67-71, 126-127. Graham, Daniel A. and Peirce, Ellen R. (1989), ‘Contract Modification: An Economic Analysis of the Hold-Up Game’, 52(1) Law and Contemporary Problems, 9-32. Hadfield, Gillian K. (1992), ‘Incomplete Contracts and Statutes’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 257-259 . Hadfield, Gillian K. (1994), ‘Judicial Competence and the Interpretation of Incomplete Contracts’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 159-184. Hart, Oliver D. and Moore, John (1988), ‘Incomplete Contracts and Renegotiation’, 56 Econometrica, 755-785. Hansmann, Henry and Kraakman, Reinier (1992), ‘Hands Tying Contracts: Book Publishing, Venture Capital Financing, and Secured Debt’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 628-655. Hermalin, Benjamin and Katz, Michael L. (1993), ‘Judicial Modification of Contracts Between Sophisticated Parties: A More Complete View of Incomplete Contracts and Their Breach’, 9 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 230-255. Kahan, Marcel (1994), ‘The Qualified Case Against Mandatory Terms in Bonds’, 89 Northwestern University Law Review, 565 ff. Kahn, Charles and Huberman, Gur (1989), ‘Default, Foreclosure, and Strategic Renegotiation’,52 Law and Contemporary Problems, 49-61. Muris, Timothy J. (1981), ‘Opportunistic Behavior and the Law of Contracts’, 65 Minnesota Law Review, 521-590. Narasimhan, Subha (1986), ‘Of Expectations, Incomplete Contracting, and the Bargain Principle’, 74 California Law Review, 1123-1202. Posner, Eric (1995), ‘Contract Law in the Welfare State: A Defense of the Unconscionability Doctrine, Usury Laws, and Related Limitations on Freedom to Contract’, 24 Journal of Legal Studies, 283-319. Posner, Eric (1998), ‘The Parol Evidence Rule, the Plain Meaning Rule, and the Principles of Contractual Interpretation’, 146 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 533-577. Snyderman, Mark (1988), ‘What’s So Good About Good Faith? The Good Faith Performance Obligation in Commercial Lending’, 55 University of Chicago Law Review, 1335-1370.
4400
Implied Terms and Interpretation in Contract Law
99
Verkerke, J. Hoult (1995), ‘An Empirical Perspective on Indefinite Term Contracts: Resolving the Just Cause Debate’, 1995 Wisconsin Law Review, 837-918. Warren, Elizabeth (1981), ‘Trade Usage and Parties in the Trade: An Economic Rationale for an Inflexible Rule’, 42 University of Pittsburgh Law Review, 515-582. Williamson, Oliver E. (1985), ‘Assessing Contract’, 1 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 177-208.
Other References Ayres, Ian and Gertner, Robert (1989), ‘Filling Gaps in Incomplete Contracts: An Economic Theory of Default Rules’, 99 Yale Law Journal, 87-130. Charny, David (1991), ‘Hypothetical Bargains: The Normative Structure of Contract Interpretation’, 89 Michigan Law Review, 1815-1879. Goetz, Charles J. and Scott, Robert E. (1981), ‘Principles of Relational Contracts’, 67 Virginia Law Review, 1089-1150. Posner, Richard A. (1998), Economic Analysis of Law, Boston, MA, Little, Brown and Co. Wonnell, Christopher T. (1986), ‘Contract Law and the Austrian School of Economics’, 54 Fordham Law Review, 507-543.
4500 UNFORESEEN CONTINGENCIES. RISK ALLOCATION IN CONTRACTS George G. Triantis University of Virginia School of Law © Copyright 1999 George G. Triantis
Abstract Contracts allocate risks by providing for future contingencies with variable degrees of specificity: they partition future states of the world more or less finely and set obligations for each state in the form of prices, quantity, remedies for breach, and so on. The partitioning may be conditioned on quantitative or qualitative factors. Refined qualitative partitioning based on verifiable outcomes can exploit comparative advantages in precaution-taking and in hedging or diversification. The expected benefit from refined partitioning of remote contingencies may not be worth the contracting costs. In these cases, the court may promote efficient risk-bearing activity by setting the parties’ obligations in these states of the world ex post, as long as the court’s determination in each state is predictable. JEL classification: K12, D81 Keywords: Incomplete Contracts, Uncertainty, Risk Allocation, Unforeseeability, Commercial Impracticability, Contract Remedies
1. Introduction When the occurrence of an unforeseeable event would cause a promisor to bear an unexpectedly large loss in performing her contractual obligation, the parties might renegotiate and modify the promisor’s contract. In most cases, the law will enforce their agreement as modified. However, even in default of such adjustment, a set of common law doctrines may offer relief to the promisor. The unexpected loss triggering the relief might be an increase in the cost of performance (out-of-pocket or opportunity cost) or a decrease in the value of the reciprocal obligation of the promisee. The common law doctrines of impossibility and commercial impracticability release the promisor from her obligation on the grounds of an unforeseeable supervening event that increases the cost of either literal performance or damages liability to a level beyond the anticipated range of values at the time of contracting. The doctrine of frustration excuses when the supervening event impairs the ‘purpose’ of the
100
4500
Unforeseen Contingencies. Risk Allocation in Contracts
101
agreement: in other words, the value that would be realized from the reciprocal performance of the other party. Mutual mistake about the subject matter of the contract excuses performance when new information comes to light that moves the value of the exchange to either party outside the range mutually anticipated by the parties at the time of contracting. Finally, under the rule in Hadley v. Baxendale, a promisor who breaches is released from liability for losses of the promisee that were unforeseeable. Thus, the release of contract obligations under these various common law doctrines hinges not only on whether the parties provided for the risk in their contract, but also on the unforeseeability of the contingency responsible for the threatened unexpected loss. Law and economics scholarship has examined at great length the efficiency of contractual allocations of risk in incomplete contracts. A subset of this literature has struggled with the relevance of unforeseeability in this analysis. This essay provides a review of the significance of the risk of unforeseeable contingencies in commercial contracting and the common law of contracts. The chapter begins with an outline of the means and ends of risk allocation in contracts and the determinants of a contract’s specificity in partitioning future states of the world (in economic terms, the contract’s completeness). The contractual allocation of risks has significant efficiency consequences because it sets investment incentives for each party (resource allocation) and exploits differences in their respective risk-bearing capabilities (risk-sharing). Contracts allocate risks in larger or smaller bundles that may be defined qualitatively or quantitatively. The price, quantity or remedy term of a contract may shift to the buyer the risk of cost increases within specified ranges. Or, these terms may be conditioned on outcomes produced by specified causes. Either the quantitative ranges or the qualitative causes may be broadly or narrowly defined (Triantis, 1992). Comparative advantages in precautions or risk-bearing may be exploited more fully when contracts partition future states of the world more finely. However, the higher contracting and verification costs of refined risk allocation may offset the expected benefits. In particular, the more remote the risk, the heavier the discount on the benefit from specific allocation and the less likely is a net benefit from specific treatment of risks. Most law and economics scholars treat the risk of unforeseeable contingencies as the limiting instance of remote risks: by definition, the cost of specifying ex ante the contractual obligations in the unforeseeable state of the world exceeds the expected benefit. Indeed, modern doctrinal statements of the excuses of frustration, impossibility and impracticability reflect this approach by referring to ‘the occurrence of an event [or contingency] the non-occurrence of which was a basic assumption on which the contract was made’, which seems to encompass those risks to which the parties attached a probability of near zero (Restatement (Second) of Contracts §§261, 265; Uniform Commercial Code §615). In these cases, the courts may promote efficient risk-bearing activity by setting the parties’
102
Unforeseen Contingencies. Risk Allocation in Contracts
4500
obligations ex post, particularly if their determination is conditioned on verifiable outcomes and predictable.
2. Contract Partitions and Incompleteness Parties enter into executory contracts instead of present exchanges for two principal reasons: (1) to protect and thereby encourage relationship specific (or reliance) investments which increase the value of their exchange and (2) to transfer risks and thereby to exploit comparative advantages in risk-bearing. Accordingly, a distinction may be drawn between two types of contracts that define opposite ends of a spectrum: (1) exchanges of goods and services for which close substitutes are readily available in thick markets (‘market’ contracts) and (2) exchanges for which there are no such substitutes because of specific investments made by either or both parties before the exchange is complete (‘off-market’ contracts). By definition, the investment of a party to a market contract is not specific to the relationship; the availability of market substitutes protects the investing party from opportunism (Klein, Crawford and Alchian 1978; Williamson 1979). The gain from executory market contracts derives from the allocation of market risks, not the actual delivery of goods or services or the protection of reliance investments. The parties contract to exploit comparative advantages in risk-bearing that are due to differences in their respective degrees of risk aversion and in their ability to hedge or shift risks in their other contracts and activities. In contrast, off-market executory contracts both protect specific investments and allocate risks associated with uncertainty in the environment and the imperfect information of the parties. The allocation of risks in these contracts has a significant impact on various important investment decisions: the parties’ investment in information prior to contracting, the promisor’s decision to perform or breach, the promisee’s specific (reliance) investments, and either party’s precautions against the probability and impact of adverse risks that threaten the value of the exchange. Because of its impact on resource allocation, the task of allocating risks in off-market contracts is more complex than in market contracts. Enforcement of off-market contracts is also more difficult because of the obstacle of verification: the cost of proving breach and damages to a third-party enforcer, typically a court. Thus, each party has a greater temptation to avoid performing obligations that threaten to inflict large losses. Consequently, the parties may wish to dampen incentives to chisel by sharing risks more evenly under the contract and thereby reducing the variance in the returns of each party (Goldberg, 1985). Without attempting to describe fully the various tensions that exist among the objectives of risk allocation, this essay reviews contract terms, such as price and remedies, that partition the
4500
Unforeseen Contingencies. Risk Allocation in Contracts
103
future according to qualitative or quantitative factors. This review sets the stage for a discussion of how foreseeability is relevant in the common law of contracts. Consider the following sales contract. Seller agrees to manufacture and deliver a specific good to Buyer one year later. Buyer maximizes the value of the good to him at delivery (V) by making a reliance investment of R. The cost to Seller of making and delivering the good is C. To keep the discussion simple, assume that Seller has no other use for the good, no third party would bid for the good and the exchange has no external effect on third parties. Therefore, the social gain (or loss) from the completed exchange is the difference: V - R - C. The parties contract under uncertainty and with imperfect information about the state of the world that will materialize at the time of delivery. V and C are stochastic and their respective distributions are neither perfectly positively nor perfectly negatively correlated. The latter assumption allows the parties to have conflicting interests with respect to the decision to terminate their contract. At the time of contracting, Seller and Buyer observe the same joint distribution of V and C, although the actual values at the time of contracting is private information. The terms of the contract divide the gain (or loss) from the exchange (V - R - C) between Buyer and Seller and the parties may decide to condition the division on the state of the world existing at delivery. A complete contingent contract would specify the parties’ obligations in each possible state of the world and the division of the gain (or loss) from the contract in each state. An efficient complete contingent contract sets optimal investment incentives and sharing of risks over each state of the world. Each state can be defined in both quantitative and qualitative terms: by the realized values of V and C and the factors that produced V and C. The motivating premise for contracts law and economics scholarship is that contracting and verification costs make complete contingent contracts infeasible. Shavell states that incompleteness is efficient to the extent that the bargaining costs are high to provide for that contingency, the contingency has a low probability of occurring, the cost of verifying its occurrence is high and the cost of settling disputes is low in the event that the contract does not provide for the contingency (Shavell, 1984). In practice, contracts are incomplete because they group states of the world into more broadly framed partitions (Schwartz, 1992). In the sales contract described above, for example, the terms governing price, quantity and remedy for breach would typically establish the rights and obligations of the parties according to more or less broadly framed quantitative states of the world. At one extreme, for example, if the contract has fixed price and quantity, and is specifically enforced, the contract does not distinguish between different outcomes: each party’s obligation is the same regardless of the realized state.
104
Unforeseen Contingencies. Risk Allocation in Contracts
4500
3. Quantitative Partitions: Price and Remedy 3.1 Price To isolate the comparison among fixed and flexible price terms, assume for the moment that contracts are specifically enforced. On the one hand, a fixed price provides a certain revenue to the seller and a certain contractual obligation to the buyer. On the other hand, a flexible price can provide a hedge against fluctuations in the seller’s cost of performance or the buyer’s valuation of performance. As a general matter, the contract price may offset risks created by other contracts and activities of either party. This point is demonstrated by Polinsky in his comparison of fixed and spot prices in market contracts (Polinsky, 1987). To the extent that fluctuations in spot prices reflect changes in cost conditions in the industry that are experienced by the seller, a spot price contract reduces the risk of the seller (and shifts cost risk onto buyer). Conversely, to the extent that spot price fluctuations are driven by demand-side conditions that reflect changes in the value of the good to buyers, a spot price transfers the risk of such value fluctuations to the seller. Thus, Polinsky says: a spot price contract will ... tend to insure the seller against production cost ncertainty...although the upward slope of the industry supply curve and the less than perfect correlation between the seller’s costs and shifts in the industry supply curve reduces the value of a spot price contract as insurance against production cost uncertainty... A fixed price contract would insure the seller against... demand side uncertainties [that cause shifts in the industry demand curve]...A spot price contract will tend to insure the buyer against valuation uncertainty, while a fixed price contract will insure the buyer against supply side uncertainties. (Polinsky, 1987, p. 29)
Spot price contracts condition only on the revealed spot market price at the time scheduled for delivery. Other distinctions among states of the world existing at that time - such as idiosyncratic increases in seller’s costs - are ignored either because there are no benefits to such further partitioning or because the contracting and verification costs of doing so outweigh the benefits. In the absence of a spot market for a close substitute or in cases where the spot price provides a poor fit because of idiosyncracies of the seller or buyer, other flexible price terms may be more closely tailored to the conditions of the seller or buyer to achieve the desired allocation of risk. For example, the price may be adjusted by reference to the realized values or determinants of C and V (for example cost plus or royalty contracts) or to accessible indices correlated with the cost or value of performance (Joskow, 1988). Alternatively, the contract may provide that a price must be reset upon the occurrence of certain
4500
Unforeseen Contingencies. Risk Allocation in Contracts
105
contingencies (Joskow, 1988). Each alternative has its own shortcomings. Realized values of C and V are often private information and not observable or verifiable. In longer term contracts, indices can fall out of line with C or V as easily as spot market prices. Yet, the renegotiation of off-market contracts raise the prospect of opportunistic appropriation of quasi-rents (Williamson, 1979). 3.2 Remedies The effect of the standard breach of contract remedies on investment incentives is well known. Under assumptions of perfect enforcement (including no insolvency risk) and no renegotiation, expectation damages set socially efficient performance incentives for the promisor, while reliance and restitution measures lead to moral hazard and excessive breach by the promisor. Specific performance produces insufficient breach. Expectation and reliance damages encourage too much reliance expenditure by the promisee (Shavell, 1980). Although the mitigation rule requires the promisee to take all reasonable loss avoiding measures after the breach occurs, information about the reasonableness of the promisee’s actions is difficult to verify. In contrast, restitutionary damages or no recovery (under a doctrine of excuse, for instance) are superior in inducing efficient amounts of reliance and mitigation by the promisee (Bruce, 1982; Goldberg, 1988). Thus, when the promisor’s liability cannot be conditioned on efficient investment levels on the part of each party because of contracting and verification costs, there is a tension between the goals of setting the correct incentives for the promisor and for the promisee. The next paragraph describes a further complication that arises when one or both of the contracting parties are averse to bearing risks. Breach of contract remedies allocate the risk of fluctuations in C and V. For example, suppose the contract has a fixed price that is payed in advance and consider the risk borne by the seller. If the contract is specifically enforced, then the seller bears the risk of fluctuations in C. If the sanction for breach is the payment of damages, the measure of damages (D) serves to divide the risks between the parties. For any given level of V, the seller bears the risk of cost fluctuations in the range C < D; the buyer risks losing V − D if C > D. Unless damages are punitive, neither party bears the risk of C > V; this is the range of efficient breach. Fluctuations in V matter to the seller if damages are a function of V (for example, under the expectation measure): the seller bears the risk of V when the cost of performance is greater than the fixed price. The correlation between C and V therefore is also significant to the seller. For example, if C and V are negatively correlated, a rise in C and fall in V may induce the buyer to repudiate the contract and thereby release the seller from her obligation. Thus, the standard breach of contract remedies divide the joint distribution of C and V and thereby establish incentives for breach, reliance, and investment in precautions against adverse changes in C or V. They can also exploit
106
Unforeseen Contingencies. Risk Allocation in Contracts
4500
differences in the risk preferences of the parties. For example, a seller insures the buyer against the risk of cost increases under remedies of specific performance and expectation damages, which is an efficient risk-sharing arrangement if the seller is risk-neutral and the buyer is risk averse and does not hold a hedge against that risk (Polinsky, 1983; Shavell, 1984). If the remedy is conditioned on C and V (or their proxies), significant tradeoffs exist between the goals of efficient investment incentives and optimal risk-sharing. If the seller is risk averse, the measures of damages that optimize the sharing of cost risk create a moral hazard of underperformance by the seller. Of course, in other cases, only one of the performance or risk-sharing goals are relevant: for example, if the seller is risk-neutral (expectation damages are efficient) or if the seller is risk averse but has no control over the cost of performance (some measure less than expectation is efficient, depending on the buyer’s risk aversion). White suggests that discharge under an excuse doctrine should be analyzed under a unified approach as a breach sanctioned by damages equal to zero. She demonstrates that zero damages produce optimal risk-sharing only in very exceptional circumstances and always encourage excessive breach (White, 1988). However, the advantage of discharge comes from the effect on the buyer’s investment incentives, particularly reliance and precaution expenditures, which she removes from her analysis (Bruce, 1982; Goldberg, 1988). The role of these incentives becomes more salient when the allocation of risk by cause is discussed in Section 4. Even if a contract addresses risks only in quantitative terms, it might condition the remedy (as opposed to the calculation of damages) on the realized value of C. Instead of one measure of damages (for example expectation), the contract might provide for two measures depending on whether the cost of production falls within one region or another of the distribution. For example, if breach occurs when C < min (C',V) then the promisor pays expectation damages; if breach occurs when C > C' > V, then the promisor’s obligation is discharged. Even though optimal risk-sharing is the only objective (because C' > V), it is not clear that this partitioning of future states creates a superior risksharing arrangement, even if the seller is risk averse and the buyer is riskneutral. Even a risk-neutral buyer will offer to pay a lower price for the good when he faces the prospect of undercompensation in the event of breach. Therefore, in the region of the distribution of C when the seller is not excused, expectation damages will be larger than under a regime of single damages measure. This increases the variance of returns for the seller in that region, while decreasing it within the region of discharge. One would require more information about the seller’s utility function to know whether she would prefer this risk profile (Sykes, 1990). The theoretical discussion of the incentive and risk-sharing effects of remedies usually assumes perfect enforcement. If this assumption is relaxed, the benefits of the various remedies are compromised. The parties may set payment
4500
Unforeseen Contingencies. Risk Allocation in Contracts
107
terms to achieve the allocation of risks that would be achieved by price and remedies in perfect enforcement. A payment or performance schedule allows either party to walk away from the contract at any point in time with a roughly adequate allocation of gains and losses. For example, Goldberg suggests that ‘there are a large number of reasons why a particular contract might not be completed and one way to protect one’s interests is to assure that at each point in time, the performance rendered and compensation received are not too far out of whack’ (Goldberg, 1988, pp. 113-114). Kull makes a similar point in discussing cases decided under the doctrine of frustration. Under the contract in Fibrosa S.A. v. Fairbairn Lawson Combe Barbour, the buyer promised to pay one-third of the price of textile machinery with its order and the balance against shipping documents. Kull suggests that the parties intended to allocate the risk of loss caused by the frustrating event (the German invasion of Poland) by allowing the seller to keep one-third of the price in the event of the buyer’s breach. This is a reasonable interpretation of the intention of parties who opt for a self-enforcing contract by letting losses lie where they fall. Indeed, a contract might assign the entire risk of the contract to the buyer by requiring full payment in advance or to the seller by providing for payment only upon delivery (Kull, 1991). White demonstrates that advance payments are efficient where negative damages (from buyer to breaching seller) are optimal because of the seller’s risk aversion, but the parties believe that a court would be more likely to allow the breaching seller to retain a deposit than to order negative damages (White, 1988).
4. Qualitative Partitioning of Remedies In the foregoing discussion, the obligations of the parties and the sharing of the returns from the exchange are conditioned on the realized values of V and C, or their respective quantitative proxies. In deciding how finely to partition the joint distribution of these variables, the parties weigh the benefit of more tailored risk allocation against the correspondingly higher costs of contracting and verification. The other dimension over which the parties may contract is qualitative: the cause of fluctuations in the cost and value of performance. Qualitative partitioning may be preferred because of the enhanced efficiency of risk allocation by cause or the lower contracting and verification costs. Force majeure clauses release the promisor upon the occurrence of specified events that impair the value of her contract. Common law doctrines of excuse are triggered when an unforeseeable event occurs that causes performance to be impossible or commercially impracticable, or that frustrates the value of the reciprocal performance. The discussion in this part focuses on the contractual specification of risk by cause and the next part addresses the judicial treatment of unspecified remote risks through the doctrines of excuse.
108
Unforeseen Contingencies. Risk Allocation in Contracts
4500
4.1 Precautions Suppose that contingency x and contingency y can each cause the same increase in the cost of performance and have the same probability of occurring at the time of the contract. What reasons might justify allocating the risk of x to the seller (for example specific enforcement or expectation damages) and the risk of y to the buyer (for example excuse or remedy of restitution)? The cause of the increase in cost does not affect the optimal performance/breach decision or the efficient level of reliance. It is, however, relevant to efficient precautions and risk-sharing. Posner and Rosenfield set the framework for the analysis of efficient risk allocation in their influential article on the common law doctrines of excuse. The superior risk bearer is the party who is in the best position to accomplish the following measures: to minimize the probability of the adverse contingency, to minimize the extent of the loss to the promisee resulting from nonperformance either before it occurs (precaution) or after (mitigation), or to insure (by self or with third parties) against the residual risk of the loss that cannot be feasibly avoided (Posner and Rosenfield, 1977). The relative ability of each party to bear or insure against the residual risk is significantly more difficult to determine than the comparative advantage in taking precautions against the risk, and so we set aside the former for the moment. Comparative advantages in the taking of precautions are related almost by definition to the cause of the threatened loss from an increase in cost or decrease in the value of the contract. The question is not only whether it is feasible to partition by cause, but how specifically to do so. A cost increase may be due to a natural disaster (general cause), which may be a tornado, earthquake, flood or drought (specific cause). To the extent that the risk is endogenous, there may be benefits to specific allocation because it sharpens the assignment of responsibility for precautions. Irrigation systems are effective precautions against droughts, but not tornadoes. Of course, obligations may be conditioned not on the contingency but directly on the precautionary actions of the parties. For example, damages liability of the breaching promisor may be conditioned on the reasonableness of the actions of the parties under the circumstances (Shavell, 1980). This approach is signficantly less common in contracts than torts (Cooter, 1985; Cohen, 1994). Contracting parties might condition damages liability on the failure of the seller to take reasonable precautions against cost increases and the reasonable precautions of the buyer (including efficient level of reliance). However, as noted earlier, contracts are rarely written in these terms because reasonable behavior is typically based on unverifiable information - particularly because the ex ante probability of breach is difficult to prove ex post at trial. The cost of verifying information concerning actions before breach or repudiation explains why contracts condition on contingencies rather than the actions of the parties. The mitigation requirement in contract law does limit the
4500
Unforeseen Contingencies. Risk Allocation in Contracts
109
recovery of the promisee to the loss that could not be avoided by reasonable measures taken only after the promisee learns of the promisor’s repudiation or breach. Although verification problems undermine the effectiveness of the mitigation rule in this regard, at least the assessment of the ex ante probability of breach is not a factor. There is some evidence that judges may choose between expectation and reliance measures of damages based on their assessment of the reasonableness of the conduct of the promisor and promisee in any given case (Cohen, 1994). However, complete discharge of obligations under the doctrines of excuse is conditioned on the occurrence of events, rather than the actions of the parties (as long as the event in question was not due to the fault of the promisor). 4.2 Residual Risk Posner and Rosenfield suggest that the ability to bear residual risk (after all cost effective precautions are taken) is a function of cost of appraising the risk, the transaction cost of obtaining third party insurance and the degree of risk aversion. As noted above, a party might also self-insure by hedging its risk under the contract against other contracts and activities. Corporate parties often have elaborate webs of commercial and financing contracts that spread and transfer the risks of their activities. Indeed, the rules of debtor-creditor relations provide important risk allocations that should be integrated into the discussion of risk-sharing in commercial contracts. If the cost of performance rises to a level such that the seller cannot perform, she breaches and becomes liable for damages. However, if the seller becomes insolvent as a result, the buyer will recover only a fraction of these damages. Even in the case where expectation damages are awarded, the buyer bears the risk of a cost increase that threatens its seller’s solvency and shares this risk with other unsecured creditors of the seller (Triantis, 1992; Treblicock, 1994). Thus, the ability to take precautions against a given risk is likely to be of greater significance than the ability to bear residual risk in the identification of the superior risk bearer in a contract. In addition, one party may be in a better position to hedge specifically the risk of a dramatic increase in the cost of performance that hinges on a specific cause. If, for example, the cause is an exogenous increase in fuel cost and the buyer of the good owns oil fields or shares in oil companies, the buyer may be the superior risk bearer even if risk averse (Triantis, 1992). The contingency itself may inflict a loss on the seller beyond the liability for contract breach. For example, suppose the seller is a farmer who contracts to deliver crops grown on his land for a fixed price. A natural disaster - flooding destroys those crops. At the same time, the market price for the crops has increased substantially since the time of contracting as a result of the disaster. If the seller is not excused, she bears two losses: the loss of crops and the liability resulting from the increase in the market price of the crops. If the seller is risk averse, it may be efficient to pass on the second loss to another party,
110
Unforeseen Contingencies. Risk Allocation in Contracts
4500
such as the buyer. The parties may signal that they intend this result when they provide for the sale of crops grown on a particular tract of land (Posner and Rosenfield, 1977; Sykes, 1998). Another instance of this approach is the rule that the destruction of identified goods prior to delivery, without fault of either party, discharges contractual obligations (U.C.C. 2-613; Taylor v. Caldwell, where lease of a music hall was rendered impossible because destroyed by fire). In theory, the point may be generalized to any case in which the promisor makes a substantial specific investment toward performance that is lost when she is compelled by circumstances to breach. If the promisee has incurred less significant reliance costs, excuse might provide a more even sharing of the losses caused by the occurrence of the contingency. The reason that excuse is not generally available in these cases may be that a promisor’s wasted investment is less verifiable than the physicial destruction of an asset (for example lost crops or identified goods). In some cases, the superior risk bearer is easy to identify. For example, the risk of a cost increase from a given cause should shift to the buyer if the seller cannot affect its probability or the loss suffered by the buyer as a result of nonperformance, if the buyer has at least as good information about the probability and magnitude of loss as the seller and if the buyer is risk-neutral or can hedge the risk of loss against its risk exposure from other activities. As several commentators have noted, however, the various factors determining risk-bearing advantage may well point to different parties and the task of determining the superior risk bearer overall may be very complicated (White, 1988; Treblicock, 1988). This reflects similar tensions discussed above with respect to the choice of remedies for breach, but complicated here because of the focus on specific causes and effects.
5. Judicial (ex post) Partitioning The discussion describes loosely the complex task of risk allocation in commercial contracts. An important part of it is deciding how to partition future states of the world. As Sykes demonstrated in the case of a regime of excuse conditioned on C > C' (see above), the benefits from fine partitions of quantitative outcomes in contracts are questionable and therefore the unforeseeability of the tails of the relevant distributions is not likely to be a concern. On the other hand, when a contract partitions according to the qualitative cause of contingencies, the remoteness of the contingency matters. The benefit of dealing with the specific cause must be discounted by its low probability. In addition, by definition, the parties have less experience with low probability events and therefore information is more costly. As a result, the
4500
Unforeseen Contingencies. Risk Allocation in Contracts
111
benefit of addressing a remote risk may not be worth its cost (Gillette, 1985, 1990). At the same time, however, some causes tend to be more verifiable than the realized quantitative measures of cost or value of performance. All other things equal, it is less feasible for the parties to incur the cost of allocating remote risks specifically. They therefore would bundle them in more broadly framed risks, in much the same manner as travellers budget unexpected incidentals without identifying them specifically (Gillette, 1985; Triantis, 1992). As uncertainty resolves during the term of the contract and remote risks become more likely or materialize, the benefit from more specific allocation becomes correspondingly greater in order to reduce or avoid the risk in the most cost-effective manner. Recontracting in light of the new information is likely to be impeded by transaction costs and strategic behavior. The common law, industry custom or contract provisions (for example gross inequities provision requiring renegotiation in good faith) may address these obstacles by imposing duties on both parties to cooperate in adjusting the terms of their bargain. There is some debate about the extent to which the law should require cooperative adjustment to preserve the value of the exchange (Gillette, 1990; Scott, 1990). Moreover, if a dispute should arise at a later date, a court will be presented with the difficult task of distinguishing between efficient modifications and those obtained by strategic behavior (Aivazian, Treblicock and Penny, 1984). However, the issue of consensual adjustment of contracts is covered elsewhere in the encyclopedia. Posner and Rosenfield suggest that the courts can complete the contract with respect to those remote risks the parties could not foresee at the time of contracting, according to the principles of efficient risk allocation (Posner and Rosenfield, 1977). The benefit of specific allocation may be reproduced if a court later allocates ex post the once-remote risk, but only if the ruling is predictable. The judicial allocation of losses cannot yield the intended efficiency benefits of efficient precaution and insurance unless it can be predicted ex ante (Kull, 1991; Triantis, 1992). As discussed above, the superior risk bearer analysis must play with sets of criteria that often cut in opposite directions and call for information that is often unverifiable. (Treblicock, 1988; Schwartz, 1992). As a result, parties may well contract ex ante to avoid the additional risk of judicial intervention or may overinvest in precautions. (Triantis, 1992; Trebilcock, 1994). In an important recent article, Schwartz argues that common law excuse rules conditioned on unobservable or unverifiable information will be unusable by courts and rejected by future contracting parties (Schwartz, 1992). The concern with conditioning judicial allocation of risk on verifiable factors, in particular, seems to be a persuasive explanation for the greater inclination of the courts to excuse performance in cases where it has become impossible (for example by the destruction of the subject matter or because of government regulation) rather than impracticable. (Schwartz, 1992). As a normative matter, the courts should intervene to
112
Unforeseen Contingencies. Risk Allocation in Contracts
4500
allocate remote risks when the incompleteness of the contract is due only to contracting costs, and not to obstacles of verification.
Bibliography on Unforeseen Contingencies. Risk Allocation in Contracts (4500) Adams, Michael (1986), ‘Der Irrtum über Künftige Sachverhalte. Anwendungsbeispiel und Einführung indie ökonomische Analyse des Rechts (Error about Future Facts)’, RECHT, Zeitschrift für Juristische Ausbildung und Praxis, 14-23. Adams, Michael (1986), ‘Zur Behandlung von Irrtümern und Offenbarungspflichten im Vertragsrecht (On Mistake and Information Revelation Duties in Contract Law)’, 186 Archiv für die Civilistische Praxis, 453-489. Aivazian, Varouj A., Trebilcock, Michael J. and Penny, Michael (1984), ‘The Law of Contract Modifications: The Uncertain Quest for a Benchmark of Enforceability’, 22 Osgoode Hall Law Journal, 173-212. Reprinted in Goldberg, Victor P. (ed.), Readings in the Economics of Contract Law, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1989, 207. Ashley, Stephen S. (1975), ‘The Economic Implications of the Doctrine of Impossibility’, 26 Hastings Law Journal, 1251-1276. Barnes, David W. and Stout, Lynn A. (1992), Economics of Contract Law, Minneapolis, West Publishing. Bellantuono, Giuseppe (1995), ‘Polizza Fideiussoria, Reticenza e Obblighi d Informazione (Performance Bond, Non-Disclosure and Duties of Information)’, V Il Foro Italiano, 1905-1909. Birmingham, Robert L. (1969), ‘A Second Look at Suez Canal Cases: Excuse for Nonperformance of Contractual Obligations in the Light of Economic Theory’, 20 Hastings Law Journal, 1393-1416. Brinig, Margaret F. and Alexeev, Michael V. (1995), ‘Fraud in Courtship: Annulment and Divorce’, 2 European Journal of Law and Economics, 45-63. Bruce, Christopher J. (1982), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Impossibility Doctrine’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 311-323. Centner, Terence J. and Wetzstein, Michael E. (1987), ‘Reducing Moral Hazard Associated with Implied Warranties of Animal Health’, 68 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 143-150. Centner, Terence J. and Wetzstein, Michael E. (1988), ‘Reducing Moral Hazard Associated with Implied Warranties of Animal Health: Reply’, 70 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 413-414. Chami, Ralph (1996), ‘King Lear’s Dilemma: Precommitment versus the Last Word’, 52 Economics Letters, 171-176. Chami, Ralph and Fischer, Jeffrey (1996), ‘Altruism, Matching and Nonmarket Insurance’, 34 Economic Inquiry, 630-647. Chisholm, Darlene C. (1993), ‘Asset Specificity and Long-Term Contracts: The Case of the Motion-Pictures Industry’, 19 Eastern Economic Journal, 143-155. Chisholm, Darlene C. (1996), ‘Continuous Degrees of Residual Claimancy: Some Contractual Evidence’, 3 Applied Economics Letters, 739-741.
4500
Unforeseen Contingencies. Risk Allocation in Contracts
113
Chisholm, Darlene C. (1997), ‘Profit-Sharing versus Fixed-Payment Contracts: Evidence From the Motion Pictures Industry’, 13 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 169-201. Cohen, George M. (1994), ‘The Fault Lines in Contract Damages’, 80 Virginia Law Review, 1225 ff. Cooter, Robert (1985), ‘Unity in Tort, Contract, and Property: The Model of Precaution’, 73 California Law Review, 1 ff. Craswell, Richard (1988), ‘Precontractual Investigation as an Optimal Precaution Problem’, 17 Journal of Legal Studies, 401 ff. Eidenmüller, Horst (1995), ‘Neuverhandlungspflichten bei Wegfall der Geschäftsgrundlage (Renegotiation Duties Following a Fundamental Change of Circumstances)’, 16 Zeitschrift für Wirtschaftsrecht, 1063-1071. Farnsworth, Allan E. (1968), ‘Disputes over Omission in Contracts’, 68 Columbia Law Review, 860 ff. Frech, H. Edward III and Decanio, Stephen J. (1993), ‘Vertical Contracts: A Natural Experiment in Gas Pipeline Regulation’, 149 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 370-392. Gemtos, Petros A. (1976), ‘Antimetopises tou Plethorismou os Oikonomikon kai Nomikon Provlema. Sygchronos Symvole eis ten Diereunesin ton Themeliakon Scheseon ton Pragmatologikon kai ton Kanonistikon Epistemon (The Treatment of Inflation as an Economic and Legal Problem. Contemporary Contribution to the Examination of the Fundamental Relations between the Positive and Normative Sciences)’, 30 Harmenopoulos, 830-846. Gillette, Clayton P. (1985), ‘Commercial Rationality and the Duty to Adjust Long-Term Contracts’, 69 Minnesota Law Review, 521 ff. Gillette, Clayton P. (1990), ‘Commercial Relationships and the Selection of Default Rules for Remote Risks’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 535 ff. Goldberg, Victor P. (1985), ‘Price Adjustment in Long-Term Contracts’, Wisconsin Law Review, 527-543. Reprinted in Speidel, Summers and White (1987), Commercial Law: Teaching Materials, fourth edition. Goldberg, Victor P. (1988), ‘Impossibility and Related Excuses’, 144 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 100-116. Hansmann, Henry B. and Kraakman, Reinier H. (1992), ‘Hands-Tying Contracts: Book Publishing, Venture Capital Financing, and Secured Debt’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 628-655. Hasen, Richard L. (1990), ‘Comment, Efficiency Under Informational Asymmetry: The Effect of Framing on Legal Rules’, 38 UCLA Law Review, 391 ff. Hatzis, Aristides N. (1998), An Economic Theory of Greek Contract Law, Ph.D. Thesis, University of Chicago Law School. Herrmann, Harald (1988), ‘Vertragsanpassung - Ein Problem des Freiheitsschutzes nach Vertragsschluß (Contract Adaptation - A Problem of Liberties’ Protection after Contract Conclusion)’, JURA, 505-511. Hurst, Thomas R. (1976), ‘Freedom of Contract in an Unstable Economy: Judicial Reallocation of Contractual Risks under UOC’ Section 2-615', 54 North Carolina Law Review, 545-583. Johnsen, D. Bruce, and (1995), ‘The Quasi-Rent Structure of Corporate Enterprise: A Transaction Cost Theory’, 44 Emory Law Journal, 1277 ff.
114
Unforeseen Contingencies. Risk Allocation in Contracts
4500
Joskow, Paul L. (1977), ‘Commercial Impossibility, the Uranium Market and the Westinghouse Case’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 119-176. Joskow, Paul L. (1988), ‘Price Adjustments in Long-Term Contracts: The Case of Coal’, 31 Journal of Law and Economics, 47 ff. Klein, Benjamin, Crawford, Robert G. and Alchian, Armen A. (1978), ‘Vertical Integration, Appropriable Rents, and the Competitive Contracting Process’, 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 297 ff. Koller, Ingo (1979), Die Risikozurechnung bei Vertragsstörungen in Austauschverträgen (The Risk Allocation of Contract Disturbances in Bilateral Contracts), München, C.H. Beck, 474 p. Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1983), ‘Reliance, Reputation, and Breach of Contract’, 26 Journal of Law and Economics, 691 ff. Kronman, Anthony T. (1979), ‘Mistake, Disclosure, Information, and the Law of Contracts’, 7 Journal of Legal Studies, 1 ff. Kull, Andrew (1991), ‘Mistake, Frustration, and the Windfall Principle of Contract Remedies’, 43 Hastings Law Journal, 1 ff. Mackaay, Ejan and Fabien, Claude (1983), ‘Le Droit Civil aux Prises avec l’Inflation (Civil Law on Prices with Inflation)’, Revue de Droit de McGill, 284-334. Mackaay, Ejan and Fabien, Claude (1984), ‘Civil Law and the Fight against Inflation - A Legal and Economic Analysis of the Quebec Case’, 44 Louisiana Law Review, 719-754. Miceli, Thomas J. (1995), ‘Renegotiation of Listing Contracts, Seller Opportunism, and Efficiency: an Economic Analysis’, 23 Real Estate Economics, 369-383. Miceli, Thomas J. (1995), ‘Contract Modification when Litigating for Damages is Costly’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 87-99. Mousseron, Jean-Marc (1987), ‘La Gestion des Risques par le Contrat (Risk Management by Contract)’, Revue trimestrielle de Droit Civil, 481 ff. Pardolesi, Roberto (1996), ‘Regole di Default e Razionalità Limitata: per un (Diverso) Approccio di Analisi Economica al Diritto dei Contratti (Default Rules and Bounded Rationality: for a (Different) Economic Approach to Contract Law)’, Rivista Critica del Diritto Privato, 451-466. Perloff, Jeffrey M. (1981), ‘The Effects of Breaches of Forward Contracts Due to Unanticipated Price Changes’, 10 Journal of Legal Studies, 221-235. Phillips, Jenny (1978), ‘Comments on Posner’s and Rosenfield’s Paper’, in Skogh, Göran (ed.), Law and Economics. Report from a Symposium in Lund, Lund, Juridiska Föreningen, 95-96. Polinsky, A. Mitchell (1983), ‘Risk Sharing through Breach of Contract Remedies’, 12 Journal of Legal Studies, 427-444. Polinsky, Mitchell A. (1987), ‘Fixed Price versus Spot Price Contracts: A Study in Risk Allocation’, 3 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 27-46. Posner, Richard A. and Rosenfield, Andrew M. (1977), ‘Impossibility and Related Doctrines in Contract Law: An Economic Analysis’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 83-118. Reprinted in Skogh, Göran (ed.) (1978), Law and Economics. Report from a Symposium in Lund, Sweden, 24-26 August 1977, Lund, Juridiska Föreningen, 57-94. Reprinted in Goldberg, Victor P. (ed.) (1989), Readings in the Economics of Contract Law, 200-212. Rasmusen, Eric and Ayres, Ian (1993), ‘Mutual and Unilateral Mistake in Contract Law’, 22 Journal of Legal Studies, 309-343.
4500
Unforeseen Contingencies. Risk Allocation in Contracts
115
Ribhegge, Hermann (1994), ‘Ökonomische Theorie des Effizienten Vertragsbruchs und die Normativen Grundlagen der Ökonomischen Theorie des Rechts (The Economic Theory of Efficient Breach of Contracts and the Normative Foundations of the Economic Analysis of Law)’, 11 Homo Oeconomicus, 113-141. Schwartz, Alan (1976), ‘Sales Law and Inflations’, 50 Southern California Law Review, 1 ff. Reprinted in Kronman, Anthony T. and Posner, Richard A. (eds) (1979), The Economics of Contract Law, Boston, Little Brown, 138-142. Schwartz, Alan (1992), ‘Relational Contracts in the Courts: An Analysis of Incomplete Agreements and Judicial Strategies’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 271 ff. Schwartze, Andreas (1988), ‘Die Beseitigung des Wegfalls der Geschäftsgrundlage: Zur wirtschaftlichen Effizienz und zur juristischen Konsistenz eines ökonomischen Modells’ (The Abolition of the Frustration of Contract: On Economic Efficiency and Legal Consistency of an Economic Model)’, Recht und Risiko, 155-170. Scott, Robert E. (1990), ‘A Relational Theory of Default Rules for Commercial Contracts’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 597 ff. Seita, Alex Y. (1984), ‘Uncertainty and Contract Law’, 46 University of Pittsburgh Law Review, 75-148. Shavell Steven (1980), ‘Damages Measures for Breach of Contract’, 11 Bell Journal of Economics, 466 ff. Shavell Steven (1984), ‘The Design of Contracts and Remedies for Breach’, 20 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 121 ff. Smith, Janet Kiholm (1987), ‘Trade Credit and Informational Asymmetry’, 42 Journal of Finance, 863-872. Smith, Janet Kiholm and Cox, Steven R. (1985), ‘The Pricing of Legal Services: A Contractual Solution to the Problem of Bilateral Opportunism’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 167-183. Smith, Janet Kiholm and Smith, Richard L. (1985), ‘A Theory of Ex Post Versus ex ante Price Determination’, 23 Economic Inquiry, 57-67. Smith, Janet Kiholm and Smith, Richard L. (1990), ‘Contract Law, Mutual Mistake, and Incentives to Produce and Disclose Information’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 467-488. Speidel, Richard E. (1980), ‘Excusable Nonperformance in Sales Contracts: Some Thoughts About Risk Management’, 32 South Carolina Law Review, 241 ff. Speidel, Richard E. (1981), ‘Court-Imposed Price Adjustements Under Long-Term Supply Contracts’, 76 Northwestern University Law Review, 369-422. Spier, Kathryn E. (1992), ‘Incomplete Contracts and Signalling’, 23 (3) Rand Journal of Economics, 432-443. Spindler, Gerald (1988), ‘Geschäftsgrundlage und Steuerrechtsänderungen (Changes of tax law and their impact on long term contracts - an economic analysis)’, in Finsinger and Simon (eds), Recht und Risiko. Juristische und ökonomische Analysen, München, Florentz, 288-325. Stout, Lynn A. and Barnes, David D. (1992), Economics of Contract Law, Minneapolis, West Publishing. Sykes, Alan O. (1990), ‘The Doctrine of Commercial Impracticability in a Second-best World’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 43-94. Sykes, Alan O. (1998), ‘Impossibility Doctrine in Contract Law’, in Newman, Peter (ed.), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law, London, Macmillan.
116
Unforeseen Contingencies. Risk Allocation in Contracts
4500
Trebilcock, Michael J. (1988), ‘The Role of Insurance Considerations in the Choice of Efficient Civil Liability Rules’, 4 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 243 ff. Trebilcock, Michael J. (1994), The Limits of Freedom of Contract, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Triantis, Alexander J. and Triantis, George G. (1998), ‘Timing Problems in Contract Breach Decisions’, 41 Journal of Law and Economics, 163 ff. Triantis, George G. (1992), ‘Contractual Allocation of Unknown Risks: A Critique of the Doctrine of Commercial Impracticability’, 42 University of Toronto Law Journal, 450-483. Trimarchi, Pietro (1989), ‘Der Wegfall der Geschäftsgrundlage aus allokativer Sicht - Kommentar (The Frustration of Contract from an Allocative Perspective - Commentary)’, in Ott, Claus and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (eds), Allekationseffizienz in der Rechtsordnung, Berlin, Springer, 163-167. Trimarchi, Pietro (1991), ‘Commercial Impracticability in Contract Law: An Economic Analysis’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 63-82. Vandegrift, Donald (1997), ‘Decision Costs, Contract Excuse and the Westinghouse Commercial Impracticability Case’, 4 European Journal of Law and Economics, 41-54. Veljanovski, Cento G. (1988), ‘Impossibility and Related Excuses: Comment’, 144 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 117-121. Walt, Steven (1990), ‘Expectations, Loss Distribution and Commercial Impracticability’, 24 Indiana Law Review, 65 ff. Warren, Elizabeth (1981), ‘Trade Usage and Parties in the Trade: An Economic Rationale for an Inflexible Rule’, 42 University of Pittsburgh Law Review, 515 ff. White, Michelle J. (1988), ‘Contract Breach and Contract Discharge due to Impossibility: A Unified Theory’, 17 Journal of Legal Studies, 353-376. Williamson, Oliver E. (1979), ‘Transaction Cost Economics: The Governance of Contractual Relations’, 22 Journal of Law and Economics, 233 ff. Wladis, John D. (1988), ‘Impracticability as Risk Allocation: The Effect of Changed Circumstances Upon Contract Obligations for the Sale of Goods’, 22 Georgia Law Review, 503 ff.
Cases Fibrosa S.A. v. Fairbairn Lawson Combe Barbour, Ltd., 143 App. Cas. 32 (1942) Hadley v. Baxendale, Ex. 341, 156 Eng. Rep. 145 (1854) Taylor v. Caldwell, 122 Eng. Rep. 309 (K.B. 1863)
4600 CONTRACT REMEDIES: GENERAL Paul G. Mahoney Professor of Law and Albert C. BeVier Research Professor, University of Virginia School of Law © Copyright 1999 Paul G. Mahoney
Abstract This chapter surveys and analyzes the substantial literature on optimal remedies for contract breach in a variety of settings. It begins with a standard analysis of the behavioral effects of expectation and reliance damages, then discusses the application of these damage measures in a world where courts are not perfectly informed about the parties’ valuations of the contract. When valuation problems are extreme, courts may turn to alternative remedies such as specific performance, or parties may attempt to solve the problem themselves through liquidated damages clauses. The chapter considers whether these solutions to the valuation problem alleviate or exacerbate opportunistic behavior by the parties. It also highlights the recent contributions that game theory and options theory have made to the understanding of remedial choices. JEL classification: K12 Keywords: Contract Damages, Remedies
1. Introduction The principal remedy for breach of contract in Anglo-American law is an award of money damages. The preferred measure of damages is the expectation measure, under which the promisee receives a sum sufficient, in theory, to make him indifferent between the award and the performance. Other damage measures, and other remedies such as specific performance and rescission, are available in special circumstances. This chapter discusses the basic design of the remedial system.
A. The General Problem 2. Sanctions and Incentives A contract is an exchange of promises or an exchange of a promise for a present performance, and the parties enter into it because each values the thing 117
118
Contract Remedies: General
4600
received more than the thing foregone. These values are based on expectations about the future because some or all of the contractual performance will occur in the future. When the future diverges from what a party expected, he may conclude that the performance he will receive under the contract is no longer more valuable than the performance he must provide. He has, in the terminology of Goetz and Scott (1980), experienced a ‘regret contingency’ and now would prefer not to perform and not to receive the promised performance from the other party. Absent a system of contract remedies, a party who regrets entering into a contract will not perform unless he fears that the breach will result in sanctions by the other party (who might have required security for the performance) or by third parties (who might revise their opinion of the breacher and reduce their economic and/or social interactions with him accordingly). The economic function of contract remedies, then, is to alter the incentives facing the party who regrets entering into the contract, which will directly affect the probability of performance and indirectly affect the number and type of contracts people make, the level of detail with which they identify their mutual obligations, the allocation of risks between the parties, the amount they invest in anticipation of performance once a contract is made, the precautions they take against the possibility of breach, and the precautions they take against the possibility of a regret contingency. An administratively simple system of remedies would aim to reduce the probability of breach to near zero. That could be achieved by the routine (and speedy) grant of injunctions against breach backed by large fines for disobeying the injunction or by imposing a punitively large monetary sanction for breach. This would give promisees a high degree of confidence that the promised performance will occur and induce a high level of investment in anticipation of performance. In the standard parlance, this would be a ‘property’ rule because it would entitle the promisee to the performance except to the extent the promisor is able to negotiate a modification on terms acceptable to the promisee.
3. Efficient Contracts and Efficient Nonperformance Were it possible to enter into complete state-dependent contracts (that is, contracts that identified every possible contingency (state) and specified the required actions of the parties for each), parties would be willing to be bound to contracts even were the sanction for breach punitive. Such contracts would require performance in some states but excuse it in others, in such a way that each party would be willing ex ante to be absolutely bound to perform the required actions in all states. Shavell (1980) defines a ‘Pareto efficient complete contingent contract’ as a complete state-dependent contract to which no mutually beneficial modifications could be made, viewed at the time of
4600
Contract Remedies: General
119
contracting. We will call such contracts ‘efficient’. In doing so, we will assume unless otherwise stated that the parties are risk neutral, each party’s objective is to maximize his wealth, post-contractual renegotiation is prohibitively costly, performance is all or nothing (that is, partial performance is not possible), and the contracts do not create uncompensated gains or losses for third parties. Under what conditions would an efficient contract excuse performance? Shavell demonstrates that the contract would require performance in all circumstances except those in which nonperformance would result in greater joint wealth. An example will illustrate the point. Imagine that Seller agrees to manufacture and sell to Buyer a machine that Buyer will use in its own manufacturing process. The value of the machine to Buyer is $300; however, Buyer has an opportunity to make certain alterations to his manufacturing plant, at a cost of $50, which will increase the value of the machine to $375. Such investments by a promisee in anticipation of performance are called ‘reliance expenditures’ or ‘reliance investments’ in the literature, and we will use the terms interchangeably. Assume for the moment that the future can be represented as a set of two possible states; Seller’s production cost is $200 in one state and $400 in the other. An efficient contract would require Seller to make the machine in the low-cost state but not in the high-cost state. In the high-cost state, the joint wealth of the parties is greater if Seller does not perform than if it does. This can be seen by comparing the cost of performance to Seller ($400) with the benefit to Buyer ($300 or $375, depending on whether Buyer makes the reliance investment). The contract price is irrelevant as it is transferred from Buyer to Seller and does not affect their joint wealth. Both parties can be made to prefer this contract to one that requires performance in both states. They can allocate between themselves the extra wealth created by the efficient contract, and there will be some allocations under which each party’s expected gain exceeds the expected gain from the contract that always requires performance. By choosing such an allocation, each party will be better off at the time of contracting and willing to be bound to perform or not perform as required. In the literature, a breach that occurs in circumstances in which an efficient contract would excuse performance is called an ‘efficient breach’.
4. Barriers to Efficient Contracting; Remedies as a Substitute for Efficient Contracts To reiterate, faced with an efficient contract, courts would have the simple task of requiring strict adherence to its terms. Unfortunately, the writing of efficient contracts is no easy task. It is costly to bargain over remote contingencies and the parties may lack the foresight to deal with all possible states. Moreover, the
120
Contract Remedies: General
4600
parties may not have equal access to the information necessary to tell which state occurs. In the above example, Seller may know whether the cost of manufacturing the machine is $200 or $400, but Buyer may have no way to verify Seller’s assertion. Given these barriers to efficient contracting, the law faces a more complex problem than that of compelling adherence to efficient contracts. Instead, it must take incomplete contracts and augment them by damage measures that induce behavior that mimics reasonably closely the behavior that an efficient contract would require. A particular damage measure can be termed ‘efficient’ with respect to a particular decision if it creates an incentive for the relevant party to make the same decision it would under an efficient contract. Because standard damage measures allow a promisor to breach and pay compensatory (rather than punitive) damages, they are called ‘liability’ rules in contrast to property rules as defined above.
5. Other Approaches An alternative framework for the design of damage measures is offered by Barton (1972). He poses the problem as one of designing damage measures that would induce the parties to make the same decisions regarding performance or breach, and reliance prior to performance or breach, that they would make were the parties divisions of a single, integrated firm and had the sole objective of maximizing the value of the firm. Shavell and Barton each show that the objective of an efficient regime of contract damages is to cause the parties to maximize their joint wealth, although one might prefer Shavell’s conceptual approach on the grounds that Barton’s assumes away the problem by positing a wealth-maximizing firm. A more recent perspective on contract damages is to consider money damages as an option under which, for example, Seller may purchase Buyer’s entitlement to Seller’s performance. The option expires on the date fixed for performance and its strike price is the damage award (which may from the parties’ perspective be a random variable). The value of the option is reflected in the contract price (see Mahoney, 1995; Ayres and Talley, 1995). This literature derives from the more general use of option theory to analyze decision making under uncertainty (see Dixit and Pindyck, 1994). We will make occasional reference to the options perspective below.
4600
Contract Remedies: General
121
B. The Standard Damage Measures 6. A Taxonomy of Damage Measures The preferred measure of contract damages is the amount of money that will make the promisee indifferent between performance and damages. It should be noted at the outset that this formulation of the measure of damages is not fully accurate; there are a number of limiting doctrines, discussed in Chapter 4620, that often reduce money damages below the promisee’s subjective valuation of the performance. There is also some evidence that courts award greater damages for breaches that appear opportunistic (see Cohen, 1994). As courts express it, however, the preferred measure of damages is the amount necessary to put the aggrieved party in the same position as if performance had occurred, which is known as the expectation measure. Fuller and Perdue (1935) provide the standard taxonomy of contract damage measures. They identify three different ‘interests’ of the promisee that are affected by a breach - expectation, reliance, and restitution - and state that the most common damage measures provide compensation for one of the three. The expectation interest is measured by the net benefit the promisee would receive should performance occur, as described above. The restitution interest consists of any benefit the promisee has provided the breaching party. For example, if a seller agrees to make monthly deliveries of a commodity in return for fixed payments due 60 days after each delivery and the buyer repudiates the contract after receiving and retaining two deliveries but making no payments, restitutionary damages would restore to the seller the value of the delivered goods. The reliance interest is measured by the promisee’s wealth in the pre-contractual position. Reliance damages provide compensation both for any benefit conferred on the breaching party and for any other reliance investments made by the promisee in anticipation of performance to the extent such investments cannot be recovered. In most instances, the restitution measure will provide the lowest recovery and the expectation measure the highest. One complication is how to treat other contractual opportunities that Buyer passed up in order to enter into the contract with Seller. Analytically, these seem similar to reliance investments and are often treated as such. In a competitive market, where Buyer could have entered into another contract at an identical price had he not contracted with Seller, the reliance measure and the expectation measure will converge approximately. ‘Approximately’, because the value of the alternative contract is a function of the probability that it will be performed (see Cooter and Eisenberg, 1985) and of the damage remedy if it is not performed, and thus the problem is somewhat circular. When analyzing the difference between expectation damages and reliance damages below, we will assume that they
122
Contract Remedies: General
4600
differ and that Buyer’s expectation interest exceeds his reliance interest. We will also assume that the reliance interest equals or exceeds the restitution interest, although we will relax that assumption in Section 12 below.
7. Incentives Within an Existing Contract: The Decision to Perform or Breach The expectation measure leads to efficient decisions to perform or breach an existing contract, given a fixed level of reliance (see Barton, 1972; Shavell, 1980; Kornhauser, 1986). This can be illustrated using the example set out above. Assume that the contract price for the machine is $250 and that Buyer makes an irrevocable decision to invest $50 in reliance, an investment that has no value absent the contract. When production costs are $200, Seller will manufacture the machine and Buyer will pay $250 for it. Buyer then obtains a machine worth $375 to him for a total expenditure (contract price plus reliance expenditure) of $300. The transaction increases Buyer’s wealth by $75. When production costs are $400, Seller will breach. The expectation measure seeks to make Buyer as well off as if Seller had performed. Seller’s breach relieves Buyer from his obligation to pay the contract price. Accordingly, if Seller pays Buyer damages of $125, Buyer will be in the same position as if Seller had performed, having paid out a non-recoverable $50 in reliance and received $125, for a net increase in wealth of $75. So long as Buyer is awarded $125 in the event of breach, Seller will breach only when the cost of performance exceeds $375, the value of the performance to Buyer. Compare this result to that obtained under the reliance measure. Under the reliance measure, Seller must compensate Buyer for his $50 reliance investment. Assume for a moment that there is a third possible state under which Seller’s cost of production is $350. Performance would be efficient because its value to Buyer exceeds its cost to Seller. Seller will perform given expectation damages, because the damage award of $125 exceeds the net loss from performance ($350 cost minus the $250 contract price). Given reliance damages, however, Seller will breach and pay $50 rather than perform at a loss of $100. More generally, it is obvious that given expectation damages, only when the production cost reaches $376 will Seller become better off by breaching and paying damages then by performing and losing the difference between his production cost and the contract price. The expectation measure, unlike the reliance measure, causes Seller to internalize fully the effect on Buyer’s wealth of Seller’s decision to perform or breach.
4600
Contract Remedies: General
123
8. Incentives within an Existing Contract: The Decision to Rely While the expectation measure produces efficient decisions to breach given reliance, it does not produce efficient levels of reliance. In general, expectation damages result in excessive reliance expenditures, because they cause Buyer to act as if performance were always forthcoming. In the example, Buyer will always spend $50 to increase the value of performance from $300 to $375, because either (1) the performance will be forthcoming or (2) Buyer will be compensated for the lost $375 in value. In the high-cost state, however, the parties’ joint wealth would be greater if Buyer refrained from investing. Seller would be liable for damages of $300 less the $250 contract price, or $50. By contrast, if Buyer relies, he receives $125 in damages as shown above and increases his wealth by $75 net of the reliance expenditure. Unlike the no-reliance case, where Buyer gains $50 and Seller loses $50, here Buyer gains $75 and Seller loses $125. The difference reflects the fact that the $50 expenditure is wasteful in the high-cost state. Expectation damages, then, do not cause Buyer to internalize fully the effect on Seller’s wealth of Buyer’s decision to make a reliance investment. The reliance measure is subject to the same objection. Under the reliance measure, Buyer will recover $50 if it invests that amount in reliance. Once again, Buyer’s investment decision will be made as if the investment is not risky, even though it is (because performance is inefficient in some states). Indeed, reliance damages create a perverse incentive for Buyer in some circumstances. Assume for a moment that Seller’s production cost is $310. Under the reliance measure, Seller will pay damages of $50 rather than perform and suffer a loss of $60 ($310 minus the $250 contract price). Breach deprives Buyer of a $75 gain (showing again that any measure of damages less than the expectation measure induces inefficient breach decisions). Buyer may be able to avoid breach, however, by making an additional (and we will assume wasteful) reliance expenditure of $11. Now reliance damages amount to $61, and Seller performs. Thus the excessive breach problem can be cured in part, but at the cost of excessive reliance. In general, as Shavell (1980) demonstrates, the reliance measure will result in greater (inefficient) reliance expenditures than the expectation measure. There is no measure of damages that results both in efficient decisions to perform or breach and efficient decisions to make or not make reliance expenditures. However, expectation damages do better than reliance damages at inducing efficient breach decisions, and do no worse than reliance damages at inducing efficient reliance decisions. Accordingly, given the various assumptions outlined above, the expectation measure is preferable on efficiency grounds. The analysis to this point has assumed risk neutrality. A risk-averse Buyer would have additional cause to prefer the expectation measure, because it eliminates variability from Buyer’s outcome. At the same time, the expectation measure introduces greater variability into Seller’s outcome than does the
124
Contract Remedies: General
4600
reliance measure. It is accordingly possible that where both parties are risk averse, they may find that a sum of damages greater than the reliance measure but less than the expectation measure offers the highest joint utility level. The precise formulation of the damage amount would depend on the parties’ comparative levels of risk aversion (see Polinsky, 1983). It seems plausible that courts have not tried to alter damage measures to accommodate risk aversion (except to the extent specific performance can do so, as discussed in Section 10 below) because of the administrative and error costs that would result. The analysis has also assumed that renegotiation at the time of breach is prohibitively costly. Were negotiation costless, the damage rule would be irrelevant, as the parties would in all cases bargain to Pareto efficient breach/performance and reliance decisions, as per the Coase Theorem (Coase, 1960). In the more plausible situation where renegotiation is costly but not always prohibitively so, the choice of remedy is necessarily more difficult. Some critics have therefore argued that much of the literature on damage remedies is beside the point, as the choice of remedies should be informed principally by an analysis of transaction costs (see Friedmann, 1989; MacNeil, 1982). Friedmann analyzes potential transaction costs in a variety of contractual settings and argues that over compensatory remedies (remedies that provide compensation to the promisee in excess of the expectation interest) will generally be efficient.
9. Incentives at the Stage of Contract Formation Friedmann and MacNeil are surely correct to argue that a better understanding of the costs of postcontractual renegotiation is necessary for making efficient remedial choices. It is also, however, worth paying attention to the effect of remedies on precontractual negotiations. The price Seller will require to enter into a contract is increasing in the damage measure. Returning to our example, when Buyer makes a $50 reliance expenditure and Seller breaches, again assuming no opportunity costs, Buyer’s wealth decreases by $50. Buyer can be no worse off from entering into the contract so long as the remedy for breach is at least $50. Will Buyer be willing to pay more for the more generous expectation measure, and will Buyer and Seller prefer the resulting contract to one that provides for reliance damages only? As Friedman (1989) notes, the difference in remedies affects the contract price, the quantity contracted, and the quantity actually consumed, with effects that vary with market structure and utility functions. In general, however, the range of contract prices for which the contract increases both parties’ wealth will be greater under a reliance measure than an expectation measure. That is, the reliance measure will create a greater bargaining range, which might increase the number of contracts entered into.
4600
Contract Remedies: General
125
The choice of remedies where precontractual as well as postcontractual incentives are analyzed remains an underdeveloped area. Friedman (1989) provides a formal analysis of expectation and reliance for two contexts in which those measures diverge. The first is the case of a breaching buyer who has contracted to purchase from a monopolist selling at a single price. The second is the case of a breaching buyer in a competitive market where the seller does not know its production cost in advance but the buyer does. Friedman demonstrates that neither damage remedy dominates the other under those conditions. Friedman’s analysis is limited, however, by his assumption that reliance is fixed and exogenous. The situations he analyzes, moreover, have the desired formal characteristics (expectation and reliance measures diverge) but are probably not very common. A possible alternative would be to start by assuming that the expectation and reliance measures diverge without specifying market structure in detail. A model could then be developed in which the choice between expectation and reliance damages affects the structure of the contract, the decision to breach, and the decision to rely. The equilibrium and comparative statics of such a model might shed light on the type of market conditions under which expectation or reliance damages would be more nearly optimal. It would also be valuable to consider carefully whether there are plausible conditions under which the cost of negotiating around an inefficient damages measure at the time of contracting is greater or less than the cost of renegotiating at the time of performance.
C. Alternative Damage Measures 10. Specific Performance Disappointed promisees are not in all cases limited to an award of damages; under appropriate circumstances, they may seek the equitable remedy of specific performance. A decree of specific performance requires the breaching party to perform according to the contract. The principal criterion for awarding specific performance is a demonstration that money damages are insufficient to compensate the promisee for the lost performance. Traditionally, this was most often found when the breaching party was a seller who had agreed to sell a ‘unique’ good. Real estate has long been presumed in many jurisdictions to be unique, while other goods such as artworks and heirlooms are often found to be unique. Specific performance is analogous to a punitive sanction that seeks to deter breach absolutely. In order for it to have that effect, we must assume that renegotiation is costly. It would then seem clear that expectation damages are preferable to specific performance, because the latter would sometimes result
126
Contract Remedies: General
4600
in performance even though nonperformance would result in greater joint wealth. On the other hand, it should be clear that the assumption that courts can adequately calculate a sum of money sufficient to make the promisee indifferent between damages and breach is not always accurate, particularly where cover is not possible. In such circumstances we must rely on a lost surplus measure of damages, and the calculation of Buyer’s consumer surplus is necessarily subjective. This is not a fatal objection if we believe that courts will guess correctly on average, but if they systematically underestimate Buyer’s surplus, the monetary remedy will result in too much breach, just as specific performance results in too much performance. Kronman (1978) started the law and economics debate on specific performance by employing a framework similar to that of the prior paragraph. He notes that specific performance is a property rule in the sense defined in Section 2 above; it effectively assigns the promisee an absolute entitlement to the goods from the moment the contract is made. This does not make sense in most instances because renegotiation (meaning a transfer of the property right back to the promisor) is costly and the result will be an inefficiently high level of performance. The danger of undercompensation, which would result in an inefficiently low level of performance, is normally lower because there is often a substitute price available. When, however, there is no substitute price available (the case of ‘unique’ goods), the danger of under compensation likely outweighs the cost of renegotiation. Accordingly, the legal rules, in a rough manner, promote efficiency. Schwartz (1979) argues that undercompensation is not merely an isolated problem limited principally to goods for which there is no obvious substitute, but is built into the structure of money damages. The reluctance of courts to award damages that are uncertain, difficult to measure, or unforeseeable (see Chapter 4620), or to provide compensation for emotional harm resulting from a breach, makes money damages systematically under compensatory. Schwartz argues that the resulting inefficiencies are likely greater than those resulting from renegotiation costs, and accordingly that specific performance, rather than money damages, should be the default remedy. Bishop (1985) adopts a similar analytic approach but argues that both Kronman and Schwartz have overgeneralized their arguments. He breaks down contract breaches into a number of categories depending on the identity of the breaching party (buyer or seller), the type of contract, and the alternative transactions available to buyer and seller. He also identifies another cost of awarding specific performance. Because the value of a specific performance award (including the amount the promisor will pay to be released from performance) will in some cases exceed the value of performance to the promisee, the promisee will be tempted to behave opportunistically in hopes of causing a breach and satisfying the conditions for specific performance. Bishop
4600
Contract Remedies: General
127
argues that in some categories the problem of excessive breach resulting from undercompensation will dominate, and in others the problem of excessive performance resulting from renegotiation costs and opportunism will dominate. The relative magnitudes of the inefficiencies generated by costly renegotiation and undercompensation are ultimately empirical questions and to date the literature does not provide data from which we could confidently identify the preferred remedy. Accordingly, Mahoney (1995) takes a different approach to the problem, using the option methodology outlined above. The methodology is first employed to confirm the argument made by Craswell (1988) that were renegotiation costless and money damages perfectly compensatory, risk-averse contracting parties would always prefer money damages to specific performance. The intuition is that entering into a contract with a money damages remedy is analogous to holding a hedged position in a commodity, whereas the identical contract with a specific performance remedy is analogous to holding an unhedged position. The variance of possible outcomes is greater for both parties with the unhedged contract and they will accordingly prefer money damages. In the face of costly renegotiation and undercompensation, we can still make some sense of the case law using the option heuristic. Many contracts involving ‘unique’ goods are prompted by the desire of the buyer to speculate on the future value of the land, artwork, and so on, and speculation involves holding an unhedged position. Thus buyer and seller would likely prefer specific performance. Other cases in which specific performance has been consistently awarded (long-term contracts to supply a fuel input to a public utility or other regulated entity) can be explained by noting that the buyer is likely more risk averse with respect to price fluctuations than is the seller, and specific performance better accommodates that distinction.
11. Liquidated Damages We began the analysis of damages by arguing that court-awarded damages function as a substitute for complete state-dependent contracts. The court’s application of an efficient damages rule creates appropriate incentives to perform or not perform, rely or not rely, and so on, and thereby saves the parties the trouble of drafting their contract to provide for all contingencies. Some parties, however, choose to create a tailor-made incentive structure by specifying the amount of damages payable in the event of breach. Courts have adopted a skeptical attitude toward these so-called liquidated damages clauses. In general, courts will enforce a liquidated damages clause only if (a) at the time of contracting, the damage that the promisee will suffer in the event of breach (that is, the promisee’s expectation) is uncertain, and (b) the amount of liquidated damages is both a reasonable estimate of (the mean of) those
128
Contract Remedies: General
4600
damages and not disproportionate to the actual (ex post) damages. A larger amount is called a ‘penalty’ and is unenforceable. This attitude is puzzling to most law and economics scholars. Absent some reason to believe that one or both parties misunderstood the terms of the agreement, we would normally assume that they went to the trouble to specify liquidated damages because the resulting contract is Pareto superior to a contract that calls for the ordinary court-awarded damages. The courts’ approach might increase the net wealth of the parties, but only if the existence of a penalty is strong evidence that the contract does not represent the parties’ actual intent, perhaps because one defrauded the other. The focus of scholarship in the area, therefore, has been to ask under what circumstances rational, well-informed parties would agree to a penalty clause. Goetz and Scott (1977) note, in terms similar to those of the later specific performance debate, that damages measures do not adequately compensate for the subjective value the promisee attaches to performance, particularly when close substitutes for the performance are unavailable or the timing of the performance is critical. In those circumstances, normal damage measures will lead to excessive breach. The promisee could purchase third-party insurance that would pay off in the event of breach in an amount sufficient to make him whole. In some circumstances, however, the probability of breach is determined not just by exogenous variables beyond the parties’ control, but also the level of care taken by the promisor. For example, a delivery service can affect the probability of timely delivery by the level of care it takes with the package. In such circumstances, the promisor can insure more cheaply than a third-party because the promisor can alter its level of care in response to the insurance clause. In other circumstances, the promisor may be better informed about the probability of breach than a third-party insurer. The delivery service, for example, may be better informed than the promisee or any third-party insurer about the breakdown rate of its trucks. In such cases, the promisor can use its willingness to agree to a penalty clause as a means of credibly signaling a low probability of breach. It is accordingly not true that the mere existence of a penalty clause is a strong indicator of fraud or mistake; there are plausible conditions under which a penalty clause would make both parties better off. Schwartz (1990) supplements this analysis by considering the effects of a penalty clause on pre-contractual incentives. He notes that the price that the promisor will charge is increasing in the damage measure. To the extent promisees insist on inefficiently large penalties, therefore, they will either pay too much or enter into too few contracts. The promisee accordingly has an incentive to demand a penalty clause only when it would increase the joint wealth of the parties.
4600
Contract Remedies: General
129
Other commentators have argued that penalty clauses can create externalities. Aghion and Bolton (1987), for example, demonstrate that a supply contract containing a penalty clause for buyer’s breach can restrict entry by competing sellers. We might at first conclude that buyer would have no incentive to agree to a contract that limited competition from other sellers. A well-designed penalty, however, will merely redistribute wealth from the new entrant to the contractual buyer and seller. To see why, assume a contract between Buyer and Seller with a contract price of $200, and Seller’s cost of performance is $150. At a later time, Entrant appears, who can provide the good for $100. Seller’s expectation damages will be $50, so absent a penalty Buyer can profitably breach if Entrant offers a price of $149 or less. Assuming that Entrant does not face competition, Entrant will demand a price of $149. Now imagine that Buyer must pay a penalty of $80 upon breach. Now it is not profitable for Buyer to breach unless Entrant offers a price of $119 or less. Entrant can still profitably sell at that price, and will do so. Thus the penalty transfers wealth from Entrant to Seller (which Seller can agree ex ante to share with Buyer). Aghion and Bolton’s analysis works only if Entrant has market power. The externality arguments for the most part are not sufficiently general to provide a compelling explanation for the judicial hostility toward penalty clauses. Moreover, while they can provide support for part of the judicial approach (disallowing liquidated damages that are not a fair ex ante estimate of actual damages), they cannot explain the failure to enforce liquidated damages that are excessive ex post.
12. Rescission/Restitution Courts divide contract breaches into ‘partial’ and ‘total’ breach. A partial breach gives the promisee the right to seek a remedy but not to refuse his own performance. The classic example is when a builder constructs a house that contains a minor deviation from the agreed architectural plan. The builder must compensate the owner for the difference in value (in theory, the difference in subjective value to buyer, but it will usually be difficult to convince a court that this differs substantially from the difference in market value). The owner may not, however, refuse to accept delivery of the house and to pay the agreed price. A total breach, by contrast, permits the promisee to refuse to render his own performance. In effect, a total breach permits the promisee to rescind the contract. As courts express it, a promisee can respond to a total breach by seeking expectation damages or by rescinding and seeking recovery of any value he has provided to the breaching promisor. The latter alternative is equivalent to the restitution measure of damages (although in some circumstances the promisee
130
Contract Remedies: General
4600
may seek return of the performance in specie rather than its monetary equivalent). Restitution is also a remedy in quasi-contractual situations, such as when parties partly performed a contract that is voidable for mutual mistake, but the following discussion will be limited to restitution damages as a remedy for breach. In the typical case, expectation damages will exceed restitutionary damages and the promisee will seek the former. There are two instances, however, in which we would expect the promisee to seek the latter. The first is when the promisee is risk averse and prefers the certainty of the return of money or property that he has given the promisor to the uncertainties of a jury’s assessment of his expectation and the additional litigation costs that would be incurred in the attempt. The second is when the contract was a losing deal for the promisee, so that his expectation is negative. Where the promisee has provided something of value to the promisor that cannot be easily returned, but can be valued in a judicial proceeding, the promisee may be better off receiving that value in cash than receiving the promised performance. This might be thought a remote possibility, but it occurs in a number of reported cases. The textbook example is one in which a builder agrees to build a house for an owner and the builder’s costs turn out to be greater than expected, making the contract a losing one for the builder. The owner, however, later decides it does not want the house and repudiates the contract when the house is partly completed. The builder’s expectation is negative because of the unexpectedly high costs of construction, so the builder seeks restitution. Restitution in this instance is measured by the value the builder has conferred on the owner, or the market value of the nearly-completed house. By hypothesis, this exceeds the contract price. When promisees have attempted to recover reliance damages for a losing contract, courts have concluded that the expectation measure puts an upper bound on the recovery (see L. Albert & Son v. Armstrong Rubber Co.). By contrast, some courts have permitted a promisee to recover restitution damages in excess of expectation (see Boomer v. Muir). This seeming inconsistency has been largely ignored in the law and economics literature. The most useful discussions appear in a symposium issue of the Southern California Law Review in 1994. In it, Kull (1994) provides an analysis of restitution that is similar in many respects to Bishop’s analysis of specific performance. Money damages are not always an adequate substitute for performance and the damage calculation is in any event uncertain. Thus where the promisee has provided something of value to the promisor that can easily be returned, the promisee may prefer to rescind the transaction, putting both parties back in the pre-contractual position. For example, the promisee may have paid in advance for a good or service that the promisor fails to provide. Taking litigation costs into account, the promisee may prefer to rescind the transaction and retrieve the
4600
Contract Remedies: General
131
advance payment. One example of a situation in which it seems likely that rescission and restitution will minimize the costs associated with breach is where a seller delivers goods that do not conform to the contractual specifications. The perfect tender rule, recognized under the common law and the Uniform Commercial Code, permits a buyer to reject nonconforming goods even if the variation is minor. As noted by Priest (1978), the administrative costs involved in calculating the difference in value between the goods as delivered and as promised will likely exceed the cost of returning the goods to Seller and money to Buyer. The costs associated with salvaging the nonconforming goods might also be minimized by the perfect tender rule, as in many instances it will be cheaper for Seller to find another purchaser for the goods than it will be for Buyer to adapt the goods to Buyer’s own use. On the other hand, where the contract is a losing one for the promisee and the promisee has conferred a benefit on the promisor that cannot easily be returned, the remedy of rescission and restitution is potentially over compensatory. Kull argues that the threat of opportunistic behavior (that is, socially wasteful efforts to exploit an inefficient remedy to obtain an unbargained-for benefit) will be substantial for such contracts. The promisee can turn a loss into a gain by inducing breach by the promisor (or convincing a court that mutual uncooperativeness constituted or resulted from such a breach). By contrast, the perfect tender rule permits a buyer to behave opportunistically by unreasonably claiming that goods are defective when their market value has declined, but because the goods can be returned to Seller, the parties are spared the additional cost of a court proceeding to determine their value.
D. Calculation of Expectation and Reliance Damages 13. A Categorization of Approaches to Calculating Damages There is consensus that the expectation measure is in most circumstances superior to reliance or restitution damages. A separate but no less important question is how expectation and reliance are to be defined and measured in typical contractual settings. Parties’ valuations are often unknown to one another and to the court, and promisees have an incentive to overstate their valuations, making the calculation of expectation damages difficult in some settings. Cooter and Eisenberg (1985) present a very helpful categorization and analysis of alternative calculation methods. They identify five broad categories and note that the calculation of money damages in reported cases usually falls into one of these categories. They are:
132
Contract Remedies: General
4600
(i) Substitute Price. Often there is a spot market for the contractual performance at the time and place that performance was due, most obviously if the performance consists of the delivery of a marketable commodity. In such an event, Buyer can respond to Seller’s breach by cover, or the purchase of the commodity on the spot market. (Seller can respond to a breach by Buyer by selling on the spot market.) The difference between the contract price and the price at which cover occurred or could have occurred is then a measure of the cost of making Buyer (or Seller) indifferent between the contract and the substitute performance. We should note, however, that the substitute price measure can be overcompensatory when a promisee chooses not to cover but instead to sue for the difference between the contract price and the spot price. That choice itself suggests that the promisee may value the commodity at less than its market price. (ii) Lost Surplus. When cover is unavailable, Buyer’s expectation can be thought of as the lost consumer surplus from the contract. In our ongoing example, if Buyer cannot cover, he loses the difference between his valuation of the machine ($300 or $375, depending on reliance) and the $250 contract price. The analysis of Seller’s lost producer surplus from Buyer’s breach is analogous. The lost surplus measure is feasible only when a court can obtain credible evidence of the promisee’s valuation. (iii) Opportunity Cost. If a market exists for the performance, Buyer could have entered into a contract to buy the machine from any one of a number of competing sellers. The value to Buyer of the best alternative contract available at the time of the contract with Seller is an important component of his reliance. This value cannot be measured objectively because Buyer did not enter into this hypothetical contract and we do not know whether the hypothetical contractual party would have performed. Assuming that the probability of performance of the alternative contract is high, however, then the difference between the spot price at the time and place of breach and the price of the foregone contract is a good measure of reliance (augmented by any out-of-pocket expenditures in reliance on the contract with Seller). In a competitive market, the next-best price and the contract price should be the same, and the opportunity cost measure will equal the substitute price measure (a conclusion consistent with Fuller and Perdue’s conclusion that expectation and reliance damages are equal in a competitive market). (iv) Out-of-Pocket Cost. This is the amount of reliance investment, less any salvage value of that investment. Out-of-pocket cost is the most common measure of reliance damages; a more complete measure of reliance damages is out-of-pocket cost plus opportunity cost. (v) Diminished Value. So far we have ignored partial performance. In the real world, however, performance is often rendered but is defective or incomplete. In such cases an appropriate measure of Buyer’s lost expectation is the
4600
Contract Remedies: General
133
difference between Buyer’s valuation of the promised performance and his valuation of the actual performance. As these alternative methods of calculation should make clear, the measure of damages is usually straightforward and uncontroversial where cover is possible. The accepted measure of damages in such cases is the difference between the cover price and the contract price, which is easy to apply and provides appropriate incentives regarding the decision to perform or breach. The difficult questions arise when there is no perfect substitute for the performance (or there is room for debate about whether the substitute is adequate) or where the manner or timing of the breach causes harm that cannot be remedied by cover. We will provide two examples of cases that arise frequently and that have been the much discussed in the literature, in which there is debate over the appropriate means of measuring the non-breaching party’s expectation.
14. Example 1: Anticipatory Repudiation Common law judges and scholars initially found anticipatory repudiation - a definitive statement by a promisor, made prior to the time for performance, that he intended to breach - extraordinarily vexing. Some concluded that any such statement must be without legal effect; the performance was due on a particular date and breach could therefore only occur on that date (Williston, 1901). Courts eventually came to the view that the promisee could treat the repudiation as a breach (Hochster v. De La Tour), but found it more difficult to decide how damages should be measured. The most famous early case, Missouri Furnace v. Cochrane, held that the appropriate measure was the difference between the contract price and the spot price at the time specified for performance. The Uniform Commercial Code, by contrast, encourages prompt cover, presumably in the futures market. As noted by Jackson (1978), the legal literature on anticipatory repudiation from the early part of this century is voluminous. Jackson argued that in applying the Uniform Commercial Code’s provisions on cover to anticipatory repudiation, courts should fix damages at the difference between the contract price and the futures price at the time of repudiation. He noted that the Missouri Furnace method is systematically overcompensatory. Imagine, for example, that Seller breaches a contract to supply a commodity in the future and that the spot and futures prices at the time of repudiation are higher than the contract price. Over a large number of contract breaches, however, the spot price at the time of performance will sometimes be higher, and sometimes lower, than the contract price (in present value terms). Whenever it is lower, Buyer will not bring a damages action because he has been made better off by the breach. He is under no obligation to share this gain with Seller. When the spot price is higher than the contract price, Buyer will
134
Contract Remedies: General
4600
recover the difference between the two. Averaged over a large number of contracts, buyers in the aggregate receive more than would be required to make them as well off as they were under the contract. Awarding the difference between the contract price and the futures price, by contrast, puts each buyer in the position he occupied prior to the repudiation and at a lower average cost to sellers. We might simplify Jackson’s argument by noting that the Missouri Furnace rule replaces a forward contract by an option with a strike price equal to the forward price. Because the value (prior to expiration) of an option with a strike price of X is always greater than the value of a forward contract with a contract price of X, the Missouri Furnace damage measure is overcompensatory.
15. Example 2: The Lost-Volume Seller Sellers in a competitive market have often argued that the Substitute Price measure of damages, which awards them the difference between the contract price and the spot price, is undercompensatory. In many instances, there is little or no difference between the contract price and the spot price, and accordingly the damage award is trivial. Sellers contend, however, that they are not ‘made whole’ by selling in the spot market; the seller had the capacity to sell to both the substitute buyer and the original buyer at the market price, and the breach reduced their sales volume by one unit. Thus in place of two sales and two profits, they have received only one sale and one profit. Courts have often awarded the so-called ‘lost-volume seller’ an amount of damages equal to its ordinary profit on one sale. In the well-known case of Neri v. Retail Marine Corp., Retail Marine, a dealer in boats, agreed to sell a boat to Neri at a fixed price. Retail Marine ordered the boat from the manufacturer but Neri repudiated the contract. Retail Marine sold the boat to another customer for the same price and successfully sued Neri for the profit it would have made on the sale to him. The court concluded that Retail Marine, as a dealer, had an ‘inexhaustible’ supply of boats, and Neri’s breach deprived it of a profitable sale. There is a substantial law and economics literature on the lost-volume seller. An early contribution appeared in an anonymous student-written comment (Anonymous, 1973). The comment noted that in a perfectly competitive market, each seller would choose output by equating marginal cost with demand and the demand curve would be presumed horizontal. At the chosen output, the firm’s marginal cost would be rising and therefore any additional sale would be at a cost in excess of the price. Because the seller could not, in fact, satisfy additional buyers at the market price, the breach and resale would create no ‘lost volume’ in a perfectly competitive market. A seller with market power (that is, one facing a downward-sloping demand curve) might be able to make additional sales at a profit. However, by hypothesis, such a seller
4600
Contract Remedies: General
135
could eliminate the ‘lost volume’ by reducing its price and making an additional sale. Thus the standard contract price minus cover price measure would fully compensate such a seller. Goetz and Scott (1979) provide an additional argument against awarding lost profits to the retailer who has market power. They note that the breach removes the breaching buyer as a competing seller. The buyer presumably breaches because it no longer wants the good at the contract price. In lieu of breaching, however, the buyer could complete the purchase and then resell the good. This resale, if made in the same market in which the retailer operates, shifts the demand curve facing the retailer to the left by one unit. Once again, if we compare the retailer’s position after the breach to its position assuming no breach but resale by buyer, there is no lost volume. Goldberg (1984) disputes Goetz and Scott’s analysis. He first argues that the observation that a non-breaching buyer could sell in competition with the retailer is unrealistic. In fact, he argues, the buyer, lacking expertise, would have to engage the services of a retailer. The retailer’s usual markup is a reasonable estimate of the fee the retailer would charge for his services. Accordingly, the award of lost profit to the retailer approximates the result that would obtain if the buyer purchased and resold. Goldberg also argues that it is inaccurate to say that the retailer ‘saves’ the marginal cost of a sale when the original buyer breaches and then incurs that marginal cost when the substitute buyer appears. He contends that the retailer’s cost of servicing an additional buyer consists principally of the cost of ‘fishing’ for a buyer, or convincing the marginal buyer to purchase (represented, perhaps, by costs of advertising, wages paid to salespeople, and so on). That cost is irretrievably lost once a contract is concluded with the original buyer and must be incurred again in order to induce another buyer to purchase. More recently, Scott (1990) argues that Goldberg’s equation of marginal cost with the cost of ‘fishing’ is inaccurate; for some goods, the cost of delivery and preparation for delivery are significant, and those costs are not incurred twice when a buyer defaults. Cooter and Eisenberg (1985) provide an analysis similar to Goldberg’s, but focus on the seller with market power. They argue that many sellers hold price at a constant level reflecting expected demand and marginal cost over some period, rather than constantly adjusting price to reflect realized demand. Such sellers can lose volume in a particular period. Goldberg also notes that consumer demand is decreasing in the damage measure. Accordingly, were the legal rule to shift suddenly from a substitute price damages measure to one awarding lost profits, the demand curve facing the retailer would shift downward, offsetting the benefit of the higher damage awards. Whether consumers and producers would prefer the resulting contract to one that provides only substitute price damages again depends on comparative levels of risk aversion.
136
Contract Remedies: General
4600
It appears that the literature on the lost-volume seller is at an impasse. The identification of the best damages rule turns on complex and contestable claims about market structure. A better avenue of inquiry would be to pay attention to actual contractual practice. Many sellers of custom goods require non-refundable deposits, which in effect contracts for a lost-profits measure. Other sellers (such as many computer retailers) permit a buyer to return an item for a full refund for some period after delivery, which in effect contracts for an even more lenient approach than the substitute price measure. It seems likely that greater ground will be gained by empirical analysis of the characteristics of markets in which varying cancellation/return policies are used than by further refinements of the theoretical arguments.
E. Conclusions 16. The Puzzle of Overcompensatory Remedies and Some Suggestions for Further Research Most of the prior analysis could be summed up as follows: when courts and contracting parties are well-informed about each party’s valuation of the contract, money damages measured by the promisee’s valuation (or expectation) provide reasonably good incentives for efficient pre- and post-contractual behavior. Problems arise, however, when there are significant informational asymmetries between the parties and/or between each party and the court. Such asymmetries raise two pervasive issues in contract law. The first is subjective value. The existence of potentially over compensatory remedies such as specific performance, liquidated damages and restitution can be attributed to judicial recognition that money damages measured by the promisee’s expectation will sometimes undercompensate, because courts use objective indicators of value that may diverge from the promisee’s subjective valuation. Only a few brief attempts have been made, however, to explore subjective value as a unifying theme in contract remedies (see De Alessi and Staaf, 1989; Muris, 1983). The second issue is opportunism. The possibility that a remedy, although designed to be perfectly compensatory, will in fact undercompensate (overcompensate) may encourage the breaching party (non-breaching party) to use the defect in the remedy to gain bargaining leverage over the other party. The risk of opportunism is the likely reason why courts have not responded to the problem of subjective valuation by instituting overcompensatory remedies across the board. A worthwhile avenue for additional work would be a careful comparison of the ways in which courts have or have not managed to reduce the risk of opportunism across a range of remedial choices. A promising approach to this
4600
Contract Remedies: General
137
question appears in the liability rule versus property rule literature. When neither party knows the other’s true valuation of the contract, each has an incentive to over- or understate his valuation in an attempt to capture as much as possible of the gains from contract modification or cancellation. The result is to make agreement more costly. The costs imposed by asymmetric information, which we will call ‘bargaining costs’, are a subset of the cost of reaching a deal. The key question is whether the choice of remedy affects bargaining costs. A specific application to liquidated damages is offered by Talley (1994). He uses the mechanism design branch of game theory to analyze the effects of different enforcement rules on bargaining costs, concluding that enforcement of liquidated damages that exceed actual damages ex post creates significant bargaining costs. By refusing to enforce penalty clauses, courts may make it more likely that the parties will bargain to an efficient outcome. The argument is unique in offering a plausible economic justification of the ex post component of the liquidated damages rule. Ayres and Talley (1995), employ game theory to argue that bargaining costs are generally lower under liability rules than under property rules. The intuition is as follows. Going back to our contract between Seller and Buyer, imagine that Seller wishes to breach, and believes Buyer’s valuation of the contract to be uniformly distributed on the interval [$300, $400]. Consider a rule that provides for damages of $500 in response to Seller’s breach. Buyer’s offer to rescind the contract for a payment of $400 would provide Seller with no new information - Seller already knows that Buyer’s valuation is no greater than $400. Now consider a rule providing for damages of $350. Buyer might now conceivably offer to cancel the contract in return for a payment from Seller (if Buyer’s valuation is less than $350), or it might offer Seller a payment to forego breach (if Buyer’s valuation is more than $350). Thus the type of offer that Buyer makes conveys information about its valuation and ameliorates the bargaining costs resulting from asymmetric information. Johnston (1995) offers an analogous argument to show that bargaining costs can be lower under a ‘standard’, in which an entitlement is dependent on a discretionary judicial determination, than under a ‘rule’, in which the entitlement is more precisely defined. Kaplow and Shavell (1995) criticize Ayres and Talley’s analysis on the grounds that it is not a marginal analysis. They argue that in most contexts in which bargaining is impossible or prohibitively costly, liability rules will dominate property rules for the reasons outlined in our discussion of expectation damages above. Thus for liability rules to dominate property rules where bargaining is possible does not prove that they generate lower bargaining costs; the latter point would be proved conclusively only if liability rules dominate property rules to an even greater extent where bargaining is possible than where it is impossible.
138
Contract Remedies: General
4600
It is perhaps unfortunate that the game-theoretic analysis of bargaining costs has been used principally to analyze the relative efficiency of liability and property rules. The more general question is the design of remedies that will create optimal incentives for the parties to reveal their actual valuations or other private information about the state of the world. A liability rule (that is, a rule under which the damage award may be greater or less than the promisee’s valuation) might create superior incentives compared to a property rule (that is, one under which the damage award is at or beyond the endpoint of the promisee’s valuation), but we should be able to make similar comparisons between different liability rules. The discussion to date has covered liability and property rules generally, whether located within the law of property, torts and contract. There is accordingly room for a more focused look at bargaining costs in contractual settings, with an additional emphasis on ex ante mechanisms other than judicially-crafted damage rules that might help to reduce ex post bargaining costs.
Acknowledgements Paul G. Mahoney thanks Eric Talley and two anonymous referees for helpful comments.
Bibliography on Contract Remedies: General (4600) Anonymous (1973), Comment: Microeconomics and the Lost-Volume Seller, 24 Case Western Reserve Law Review, 712 ff. Reprinted in Kronman, Anthony T. and Posner, Richard A. (eds) (1979), The Economics of Contract Law, Boston, Little Brown, 1979, 213-220. Aghion, Philippe and Bolton, Patrick Bolton (1987), ‘Contracts as Barriers to Entry’, 77 American Economic Review, 388-401. Ayres, Ian and Talley, Eric L. (1995), ‘Solomonic Bargaining: Dividing a Legal Entitlement To Faciliate Coasean Trade’, 104 Yale Law Journal, 1027-1117. Barton, John H. (1972), ‘The Economic Basis of Damages for Breach of Contract, 1 Journal of Legal Studies, 277-304. Bishop, William (1985), ‘The Choice of Remedy for Breach of Contract’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 299-320. Reprinted in Goldberg, Victor P. (ed.), Readings in the Economics of Contract Law, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1989, 122-125. Coase, Ronald H. (1960), ‘The Problem of Social Cost’, 3 The Journal of Law and Economics 1-44. Cohen, George M. (1994), ‘The Fault Lines in Contract Damages’, 80 Virginia Law Review, 1225-1349. Cooter, Robert D. and Eisenberg, Melvin Aron (1985), ‘Damages for Breach of Contract’, 73 California Law Review, 1432-1481.
4600
Contract Remedies: General
139
Craswell, Richard (1988), ‘Contract Remedies, Renegotiation, and the Theory of Efficient Breach’, 61 Southern California Law Review, 629-670. De Alessi, Louis and Staaf, Robert J. (1989), ‘Subjective Value in Contract Law’, 145 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 561-577. Dixit, Avinash K. and Pindyck, Robert J. (1994), Investment Under Uncertainty, Princeton, New Jersey, Princeton University Press. Friedman, David D. (1989), ‘An Economic Analysis of Alternative Damage Rules for Breach of Contract’, 32 Journal of Law and Economics, 281-310. Friedmann, Daniel (1989), ‘The Efficient Breach Fallacy’, 18 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-24. Fuller, Lon L. and Perdue, William (1935), ‘The Reliance Interest in Contract Damages’, 46 Yale Law Journal, 52-98. Reprinted in Goldberg, Victor P. (ed.) (1989), Readings in the Economics of Contract Law, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 77-79. Goetz, Charles J. and Scott, Robert E. (1977), ‘Liquidated Damages, Penalties and the Just Compensation Principle: Some Notes on an Enforcement Model and a Theory of Efficient Breach’, 77 Columbia Law Review, 554-594. Reprinted in Kronman, Anthony T. and Posner, Richard A. (eds) (1979), The Economics of Contract Law, Boston, Little Brown, 194-207. Goetz, Charles J. and Scott, Robert E. (1979), ‘Measuring Sellers’ Damages: The Lost-Profits Puzzle’, 31 Stanford Law Review, 323-373. Goetz, Charles J. and Scott, Robert E. (1980), ‘Enforcing Promises: An Examination of the Basis of Contract’, 89 Yale Law Journal, 1261-1300. Goldberg, Victor P. (1984), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Lost-Volume Retail Seller’, 57 Southern California Law Review, 283-298. Reprinted in Goldberg, Victor P. (ed.) (1989), Readings in the Economics of Contract Law, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 106-113. Jackson, Thomas H. (1978), ‘“Anticipatory Repudiation” and the Temporal Element in Contract Law: An Economic Inquiry into Contract Damages in Cases of Prospective Nonperformance’, 31 Stanford Law Review, 69-119. Johnston, Jason S. (1995), ‘Bargaining Under Rules versus Standards’, 11 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization 256-281. Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (1995), ‘Do Liability Rules Facilitate Bargaining? A Reply to Ayres and Talley’, 105 Yale Law Journal 221-233. Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1986), ‘An Introduction to the Economic Analysis of Contract Remedies’, 57 Colorado Law Review, 683-725. Kronman, Anthony T. (1978), ‘Specific Performance’, 45 University of Chicago Law Review, 351-382. Reprinted in Kronman, Anthony T. and Posner, Richard A. (eds), The Economics of Contract Law, Boston, Little Brown, 181-194. Kull, Andrew (1994), ‘Restitution as a Remedy for Breach of Contract’, 67 Southern California Law Review, 1465-1518. Macneil, Ian R. (1982), ‘Efficient Breach of Contract: Circles in the Sky, 68 Virginia Law Review 947-969. Mahoney, Paul G. (1995), ‘Contract Remedies and Options Pricing’, 24 Journal of Legal Studies; 139-63. Muris, Timothy J. (1983), ‘Cost of Completion or Diminution in Market Value: The Relevance of Subjective Value’, 12 Journal of Legal Studies, 379-400. Reprinted in Goldberg, Victor P. (ed.) (1989), Readings in the Economics of Contract Law, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press,
140
Contract Remedies: General
4600
128-132. Polinsky, A. Mitchell (1983), ‘Risk Sharing through Breach of Contract Remedies’, 12 Journal of Legal Studies, 427-444. Priest, George L. (1978), ‘Breach and Remedy for the Tender of Nonconforming Goods Under the Uniform Commercial Code: An Economic Approach’, 91 Harvard Law Review, 960-1001. Reprinted in Kronman, Anthony T. and Posner, Richard A. (eds) (1979), The Economics of Contract Law, Boston, Little Brown, 167-175. Schwartz, Alan (1979), ‘The Case for Specific Performance’, 89 Yale Law Journal, 271-306. Schwartz, Alan (1990), ‘The Myth that Promisees Prefer Supracompensatory Remedies: An Analysis of Contracting for Damage Measures’, 100 Yale Law Journal, 369-407. Scott, Robert E. (1990). ‘The Case for Market Damages: Revisiting the Lost Profits Puzzle’, 57 The University of Chicago Law Review, 1155-1202. Shavell, Steven (1980), ‘Damage Measures for Breach of Contract’, 11 Bell Journal of Economics, 466-490. Talley, Eric, L. (1994), ‘Contract Renegotiation, Mechanism Design, and the Liquidated Damages Rule’, 46 Stanford Law Review, 1195-1243. Williston, Samuel (1901), ‘Repudiation of Contracts’, 14 Harvard Law Review, 317-331 (Part I), 421-441 (Part II).
Cases Hochster v. De La Tour, 118 Eng. Rep. 922 (Q.B. 1853). Missouri Furnace v. Cochrane, 8 F. 463 (C.C.W.D. Pa. 1881). Neri v. Retail Marine Corp., 30 N.Y.2d 393 (1972). L. Albert & Son v. Armstrong Rubber Co., 178 F.2d 182 (2d Cir. 1949). Boomer v. Muir, 24 P.2d 570 (Cal. App. 1933).
4610 PENALTY CLAUSES AND LIQUIDATED DAMAGES Gerrit De Geest Professor at the University of Ghent Researcher at the Economic Institute/CIAV, Utrecht University
Filip Wuyts, M.Sc. © Copyright 1999 Gerrit De Geest and Filip Wuyts
Abstract This chapter surveys the economic literature on stipulated damages. In the literature there seems to be a consensus that liquidated and underliquidated damages should be respected. Liquidated damages can be a rational option, especially if parties have more information about the possible losses than judges. Underliquidated damages may can serve as a technique to let parties share the risk of increased production costs. Penalty clauses, on the other hand, have been the subject of a fierce controversy for a long time. Most authors seem to defend the prohibition of penalty clauses. Yet it can be argued that they should be allowed under some conditions. JEL classification: K12 Keywords: Stipulated Damages, Underliquidated Damages, Remedies, Breach of Contract
1. Introduction Sometimes parties to a contract ex ante agree upon how much compensation will have to be paid should one of them breach the contract. These stipulated damages are called ‘liquidated damages’ when they are ex ante reasonable estimations of the true losses. They are called
142
Penalty Clauses and Liquidated Damages
4610
contracting parties in this way. In 1979 Posner (1979, p. 290) described the penalty doctrine as ‘a major unexplained puzzle in the economic theory of law’. The penalty doctrine seemed to form an important exception to Posner’s general thesis that common law is efficient. Before starting to review the literature it might be helpful to pay attention to the precise definition of the borderlines between penalty clauses and liquidated damages. Rea (1984a) has argued that much of the confusion around the penalty doctrine occurs because of the failure to distinguish ex ante and ex post valuation of losses. It is not because stipulated damages ex post turn out to be overcompensatory that they will be considered penalty clauses by American courts. American courts only check whether the clauses are reasonable ex ante. When clauses are ex ante reasonable estimations of the true losses, or to put it differently, when clauses reflect the expected losses, they will be enforced. In addition, liquidated damages are meant to compensate fully for losses, including subjective and other hard to prove losses. It is possible that courts mistakenly consider liquidated damages to be penalty clauses because they underestimate subjective costs. Yet, from an analytical point of view these clauses should be seen as liquidated damages. An early article of Goetz and Scott (1977) can serve as an illustration of this confusion. Goetz and Scott argued that a penalty clause is often just a way for a contracting party to insure itself against idiosyncratic harm or otherwise uncompensated damages. They give the example of a group of alumni who attach an enormous subjective value to attending a baseball game of their college team. Therefore, they stipulate in the contract with the bus driver that the latter wil have to pay a high amount of damages in case he arrives late. This amount is high but just reflects their true subjective losses. Moreover, the promisor will very often be a better insurer than a traditional third party insurer. This argument, however, is in fact just a plea for respecting liquidated damage clauses and not necessarily an argument for supracompensatory penalty clauses.
2. Liquidated Damages, Penalty Clauses and Underliquidated Damages as Compared to Other Remedies Many arguments for or against penalty clauses hold for other, less contested remedies as well. Therefore, it is important to situate these sanctions within the complete set of contract remedies, including the reliance measure, the expectation measure and specific performance.
4610
Penalty Clauses and Liquidated Damages
143
At first sight, liquidated damages seem to be equivalent to the expectation measure. Liquidated damages are meant to fully compensate the promisee and ‘fully’ includes the expected profits (only in cases were the expected profits are compensated, the promisee is really indifferent with regard to performance or breach). The major difference seems to lie in the fact that liquidated damages are calculated ex ante (at the time of contracting) while the expectation damages are calculated or made operational ex post (after breaching). One major disadvantage of expectation damages that is that they discourage efficient entering into contracts (see Chapter 4600), which holds for liquidated damages as well. To put it differently, if sellers demand liquidated damages in case of breach, fewer buyers than optimal will sign the contract. With respect to breaching decisions, however, there is a difference. The expectation measure leads to efficient breaching (Birmingham, 1970; Shavell, 1980). Liquidated damages, however, are determined ex ante, so at the time the promisor decides whether to breach or to perform, he may already know that the stipulated damages are over- or undercompensatory. If they are overcompensatory, the promisor might overperform; if they are undercompensatory, the promisor might overbreach. This difference may be smaller than it seems. Judges do not compensate perfectly under the expectation measure either. If the promisor expects the judge to overcompensate he will overperform. If the promisor expects the judge to undercompensate he will overbreach. To summarize, liquidated damages may create incentives to overperforming as well as to overbreaching. Whether incentives are worse than under the expectation measure depends on how well judges valuate the losses. If judges systematically and seriously undercompensate, then liquidated damages may be the superior remedy when it comes to incentives to breaching. Penalty clauses and specific performance have in common that both are supracompensatory sanctions. One consequence is that both lead to overperformance, or to put it differently, that both discourage efficient breaches. Penalty clauses, however, award an amount of money to the promisee, while specific performance makes the promisor perform in natura. At first sight this leads to an important difference: only penalty clauses create an incentive for the promisee to induce breach. But much depends on how specific performance works in practice. Under American law, nonperforming promisors have to pay a fine on the basis of ‘contempt of court’. This fine is paid to the court so it does not alter the incentives of the promisee But in France, Belgium and the Netherlands, specific performance is obtained by ‘astreintes’, high amounts of money (usually for each day of
144
Penalty Clauses and Liquidated Damages
4610
non-performance), determined by a judge but to be paid to the promisee. Astreintes create incentives to induce the other party’s breach as well. An important difference between penalty clauses and specific performance lies in the temporal dimension (De Geest, 1994); for a more general discussion of the temporal dimensions of liability rules and property rules see Levmore, 1997). Specific performance needs some time before it becomes operational. It works only for the future and not for the past. If by the time the promisee goes to court performance in natura is no longer possible (or no longer desirable), then courts will award just damages. Suppose someone had promised to deliver a wedding cake at the promisee’s wedding, but did not show up. Specific performance makes no sense afterwards, so awarding damages is all the courts can do. On the other hand, penalty clauses can be awarded for breaches in the past. This means that a specific performance regime might in the real world be compensatory and that parties wanting extracompensatory sanctions may have no choice but to include penalty clauses in their contracts. Finally, underliquidated damages can be the equivalent of anything inbetween a perfectly applied expectation measure and no damages at all. They may be the equivalent of reliance damages but also of an undercompensatory expectation measure. Just as in the case of the reliance measure they lead to overbreaching. The problem of undercontracting will be smaller than under the expectation measure or even nonexistent, if they are set just to compensate reliance damages.
A. Liquidated Damages 3. Liquidated Damages Avoid Ex Post Valuation Difficulties With liquidated damages losses are estimated ex ante, at the time of contracting. Such clauses avoid that judges have to compute the damages ex post. It is well known that judges may have serious difficulties in finding out the true losses. This holds especially for subjective harm. It is impossible for a judge to know the promisee’s preferences precisely. Nor can he rely on what the promisee tells him, because the latter has no incentive to reveal his preferences in an honest way. This kind of preference revelation problem does not arise when the loss is determined ex ante. At that time the parties are still free to enter the contract or not. The higher the amount stipulated, the higher the price: the debtor will require compensation for his additional prevention costs and for the additional risk he has to insure. An ex ante
4610
Penalty Clauses and Liquidated Damages
145
estimation is also useful for other forms of damage which are difficult to prove. The costs of forgone chances are one example. Lacking clear evidence, courts will underestimate such losses. In this respect, liquidated damages reduce the risk of legal error. The probability that a judge will err in estimating the damage is largely eliminated. Of course the danger that a judge will erroneously consider the clause to be a forbidden penalty clause still exists. The risk that a judge wrongly applies the liquidated damage clause even though the debtor did not breach the contract, also remains. A somewhat related advantage of liquidated damage clauses is that they allow us to avoid adverse selection problems. These problems arise when the seller does not know how high the losses of the buyer will be in case of breach. Because of this lack of information, the seller will assume ex ante that the potential promisee represents an average risk. The doctrine of foreseeability (Hadley v. Baxendale) serves to mitigate the adverse selection problems. It forces people whose damage may be higher than usual to communicate this to the seller. A liquidated damage clause can perform this function as well. However one crucial condition is that the liquidated damage clause is tailor-made. If liquidated damages do not take into account the individual characteristics of the buyer, but consist of standard term clauses, they no longer have this function.
4. Liquidated Damages Create Incentives for Optimal Reliance and Optimal Precaution Cooter (1985) proved that damage clauses create a ‘double responsibility at the margin’. First, the promisor receives an incentive to make an optimal amount of precaution costs. Second, the promisee gets a perfect incentive not to make too many reliance costs, because he will receive a fixed compensation in case of a breach of contract, regardless of the amount of reliance costs he has effectively incurred. This is not the case with normal expectation or reliance damages awarded by a judge, because judges generally do not examine whether the reliance costs made by the promisee were excessive or not. To be sure, the same result could be reached with damages that are judicially determined by compensating only for the efficient reliance costs. In practice, however, insuperable difficulties of proof often arise, which hamper the application of this remedy.
146
Penalty Clauses and Liquidated Damages
4610
5. Liquidated Damages Substantially Increase Ex Ante Transaction Costs To estimate the losses ex ante is nearly always more expensive than ex post. Ex ante, damages have be to estimated under all circumstances, even if ex post no loss is incurred. All states of the world have to be taken into account, while an ex post determination requires only information about the one situation that has really occurred. Finally, ex post there is usually more information on what really happened than ex ante. To put if differently, the ex ante information costs are higher because what will happen is still remote.
6. Ex Post Undercompensatory Liquidated Damages Lead to Ineffecient Breaches, Ex Post Overcompensatory Liquidated Damages to Inefficient Performance Liquidated damage clauses aim at correctly compensating the promisee’s loss. However they are set ex ante, when full information may not be available yet. If ex post the compensation turns out to be clearly lower than the real damage, incentive problems arise, as briefly explained in Section 2. If ex post the compensation turns out to exceed the actual loss clearly, the promisee will have an incentive to head for an inefficient breach of contract. The promisor will not breach the contract, even if it is efficient to do so. In case of a breach of contract, the promisee is overinsured; the contract thus contains a gambling clause. In return for this the creditor has had to pay a premium. Other aspects may outweigh this disadvantage. A liquidated damage clause contains information on the possible magnitude of the loss. This information is useful for the promisor who has to decide whether a breach of contract is efficient or not. Because this information is produced in advance, the promisor may make more efficient decisions. The promisor will also be able to decide more quickly whether the good has to be sold to a third party. For the same reason, a liquidated damage clause can also lead to a more optimal level of prevention costs. If the loss or the possible loss is lower than what the debtor would normally expect, it is also desirable that he makes fewer prevention costs than usual. The opposite holds when the damage is higher than usual.
4610
Penalty Clauses and Liquidated Damages
147
B. Penalty Clauses 7. The Rationality Argument and the Signing Without Reading Problem One earlier argument against the penalty doctrine was directly derived from the rationality assumption in economics: we may assume that people are rational, so if they sign a penalty clause they must have good reasons to do so. The contract must be efficient, otherwise they would not have signed it. This argument is implicitly used in the very first economic paper on the subject (Barton, 1972, p. 286). Barton argued that all liquidated damage clauses should be enforced without distinction, at least when the provision was knowledgeably and fairly bargained-for. The rationality argument is more explicit in Kronman and Posner (1979). Criticizing Clarkson, Miller and Muris (1978) they argue that if penalty clauses would really create an incentive for the promisee to induce the promisor to breach, this danger would be reflected in the parties’ negotiations over the contract price or other terms of the contract. If the penalty clause survives the negotiation process, this is presumably because the benefits to the promisee exceed the costs to the promisor. According to Kronman and Posner (1979) there may be room for intervention if one thinks that the parties cannot assess these costs correctly, but then the basis for intervention is paternalism. As a limitation on the freedom to contract, the penalty doctrine is more paternalistic than the contractual incapacity of minors or the invalidity of contracts of self-enslavement. A somewhat similar idea can be found in Farber (1983) who argued that in addition to contract law (the principle of freedom of contract) seems to embody a kind of safety belt against individual catastrophic losses (including losses resulting from penalty clauses). Ulen (1984, p. 356) used the rationality assumption to defend penalty clauses very explicitly ‘there is every reason to believe that they will stipulate the most efficient remedy, considering all the factors’. This argument, however, is not very convincing. Even though economic science is based on the assumption of rational behavior, the existence of information problems is generally accepted. ‘Rational’ does not mean perfectly informed. It cannot be denied that allowing penalty clauses implies an important danger: signing without reading (Mackaay, 1982; De Geest, 1994). Contracting parties do not always read or understand what they are signing. The party drafting the contract may speculate on this and include certain clauses which would never have been accepted if they had been read. It must be clear that this problem is not merely theoretical: penalty clauses may ruin one’s business and make others rich.
148
Penalty Clauses and Liquidated Damages
4610
The signing without reading problem is elaborated by Mackaay (1982). Contract terms are in general more costly to verify than most physical features of commodities. Since most consumers will not inspect the terms, the market may adapt ‘harsh-term-low-price’ policies. In order to counter this perversity, some form of government intervention may be desirable. Of course it would be undesirable to solve the signing-without-reading problem by declaring all signed contracts void. A better strategy is therefore to prove that under certain circumstances some clauses will never be signed by rational, well-informed parties. The fact that some people in the real world do sign such clauses can then be considered as evidence that there was a serious procedural deficiency in the formation of the contract (for a good example of this strategy see Rea, 1984a).
8. The Costs of Legal Error are Higher for Penalty Clauses than for Liquidated Damages Accepting a penalty clause is always a bit risky, even for those promisors who perform exactly as promised. There is always a chance that a judge will erroneously enforce a penalty clause, due to either a mistake or difficulties of proof. A promisor who behaves optimally but cannot prove, for example, that there was force majeure, could wrongly be sentenced to pay an enormous amount. The risk of legal error is very hard to insure. A comparison can be drawn with criminal law. If the judicial system worked perfectly and if everybody behaved rationally, punishments could be infinitely harsh. After all, a rational person would never commit a crime and therefore nobody would be erroneously convicted. But just because the judicial system works imperfectly, sanctions should not be infinitely harsh. The same holds for sanctions for breach of contract.
9. Penalty Clauses Discourage Efficient Breaching In the second edition of his textbook, Posner (1977, p. 93) suggested that the law may refuse to enforce penalty clauses because they give an incentive to complete the contract, even when breaching would be efficient. This argument is correct, but should be put in context, as argued in Section 2. All extracompensatory sanctions have this disadvantage. This applies to specific performance, to liquidated damages that ex post turn out to be overcompensatory, and to the expectation measure if judges systematically overcompensate the promisees.
4610
Penalty Clauses and Liquidated Damages
149
10. Penalty Clauses give Promisees an Incentive to Induce Breach of Contract This was first elaborated by Clarkson, Miller and Muris (1978). Suppose I sign a contract with a builder. If the builder fails to perform in time, my true losses are $1,000, but a penalty clause will award me $1,001,000. So I hope the promisor will breach the contract and I will even do whatever I can to make the promisor miss the deadline. However in many cases I will not have any opportunity to mislead or hinder the debtor. Even if I have the opportunity I must be able to do it covertly, because if the debtor can prove that I am responsible for the breach, I will get no compensation. Covenants not to compete, and clauses where the sole relation between the parties is that of borrower and lender are a few examples given by Clarkson, Miller and Muris (1978) where inducement of breach is no danger. But where covertly induced breaching is possible, penalty clauses should be forbidden. For a similar argument, see X (1978). In a student note (X, 1978) the thesis that preagreed damage clauses should be reasonable in the light of actual harm is defended too. This test enables full compensation of the non-breaching party to occur since the preagreed damage clause will be enforced as long as the breaching party is unable to show that actual damages are less than the sum of objective and subjective damages. In addition, the ex post test is consistent with the discouragement of wagering and breach-inducing activities. Theoretically, the argument is correct. Yet it applies to all other supracompensatory sanctions as well. As argued in Section 2, there is a similar problem when specific performance is made operational through the use of ‘astreintes’. The major question is in how many cases the promisee has an opportunity to covertly induce breach. It is not so easy to make a debtor fail when he is aware of the dramatic consequences of his breach. However a technique (not considered by Clarkson, Miller and Muris, 1978) that has more chances to succeed is to let a promisor sign a contract that he did not read.
11. Do Penalty Clauses Lead to More Trials? Landes and Posner (1979) mentioned that historically the penalty doctrine was created at a time when judges were paid from litigation fees. As argued by Rea (1984a) this argument does not explain why the penalty doctrine persisted in an era of subsidized courts. Rubin (1981) built on the theory of self-enforcing contracts introduced by Telser (1980) and argued that penalty clauses are not self-enforcing; they can be enforced only by court intervention. Every breach of contract by the
150
Penalty Clauses and Liquidated Damages
4610
debtor will therefore lead to a trial. The costs of these trials are not fully borne by the parties themselves. Courts are largely subsidized. Because some costs are externalized, parties will stipulate penalty clauses more often than is optimal. Rea (1984a) remarked, however, that this argument could be used in many more cases. There are numerous areas in which courts seem to encourage the use of judicial resources, even though they are supplied at little cost. Furthermore, the additional uncertainty associated with the unenforceability of penalty clauses might increase litigation too. The reasoning of Rubin (1981) is implicitly contradicted by the modern economic literature on settlement versus trial (see Chapters 7000 and 7400). In principle rational parties do not go to court. They prefer a settlement rather than an expensive trial. Why would a rational debtor refuse to pay the damages stipulated in the contract spontaneously if these clauses are valid in that legal system? It would cost him a lot more if the promisee went to court. A trial between two rational parties is only possible if they have different perceptions of their chances to win. This will happen more often if it is hard to predict the decision of the judge. With a legal rule allowing all penalty clauses, the probability of different perceptions will be reduced to nearly zero. The judge will certainly declare the penalty clause valid. Discussions, on the other hand, may arise if penalty clauses are forbidden while liquidated damage clauses are allowed, or when such clauses are forbidden if they exceed the highest damage possible. In those cases the judge has to draw a line and where that line lies is not always clear. Whether this is a valid argument against regulations prohibiting (certain) penalty clauses, is doubtful, however. The problem of the excessive subsidization of courts can be solved more easily by increasing the trial costs.
12. Penalty Clauses as a Barrier to Entry? In the literature it has been argued that penalty clauses entail another serious potential danger: their use as a barrier to entry. Diamond and Maskin (1979) are the first to clearly demonstrate the external effects of damages. In their model, individuals search for partners and negotiate contracts to produce output. The individuals may decide to breach their contract and form a new partnership. Since the surplus of this new partnership depends on the damages that a breaching party has to pay to its old partner, they also affect its new partner. By stipulating liquidated damages parties to a contract can therefore exert some monopoly power over potential partners. By illustrating how liquidated damage clauses can reduce competition Aghion and Bolton (1987) again stress the external effects of such clauses.
4610
Penalty Clauses and Liquidated Damages
151
In their model an incumbent seller and a buyer can sign a contract specifying a price and liquidated damages in case the buyer breaches the contract. In line with Diamond and Maskin (1979) it is shown that this contract gives the parties some joint monopoly power over a potential competitor. The buyer will not breach the contract and trade with a new entrant unless the latter compensates him for the liquidated damages that he owes to the incumbent seller. The liquidated damages thus act as an entry fee which enables the contracting parties to appropriate part of the surplus of a more efficient producer who enters the market. Because of this entry fee a welfare-enhancing entry is blocked and the contract introduces a social cost. Chung (1992) analyzes the effects of the penalty doctrine in a framework similar to that of Aghion and Bolton (1987). But in his model the buyer also has to make a reliance decision and the third party is a new buyer with a higher valuation for the good. He shows again that by stipulating in the initial contract a high level of liquidated damages, the parties to a contract could raise the price that a third party has to pay to induce a breach of contract. However, when the reliance investment of the buyer is fixed, the penalty doctrine, by putting an upper limit on the enforceable stipulated damages, eliminates this inefficiency and allows the implementation of the first-best outcome. This no longer holds when the reliance investment of the buyer is variable. Then the promisee will overrely on it, even with the penalty doctrine in place. In the literature, the Aghion and Bolton model is often used as an argument against penalty clauses. However, this barrier-to-entry-argument applies to the expectation measure and to liquidated damages as well. Consider a contract for the duration of 10 years that binds all consumers in a market to a monopolistic seller. The production costs of the current monopolist are 50 and the price is 100. The sanction for breach is the expectation measure (the standard remedy under both Anglo-American and continental law), which means that a breaching buyer has to pay 50. A new entrant with a production cost of 50 offers the same product at a price of 51. None of the buyers will breach. If the product is sold at production costs, that is 50, consumers are indifferent. But if we assume that changing partners always involves positive transaction costs (a very plausible assumption), the new entrant will still not attract any of the existing consumers. So the expectation measure, which is the normal sanction for breach in Anglo-American law, as well as in continental law, can serve as a barrier to entry as well. Aghion and Bolton (1987) merely view their paper as an illustration of the much broader problem of the endogenous creation of switching costs. Other examples include advance deposits in rental contracts, frequent flyer programs, trading stamps, deferred rebates by shipping firms, fixed fees in
152
Penalty Clauses and Liquidated Damages
4610
franchise contracts and so on. Even if the penalty doctrine is needed to counter the use of damage clauses as a barrier to entry, it will not necessarily capture other contract clauses which may have the same effect. Given the variety and complexity of potential contract clauses, antitrust authorities face an almost impossible task here.
13. Can Penalty Clauses Have a Signalling Function? The idea that penalty clauses can be useful as a signal for a promisor’s reliability was first articulated by Posner (1977, p. 93). According to Posner, this signalling function is important especially for new entrants in the market who have not yet built up a reputation. An effective way for a promisor to convince other parties that he will perform as promised is to offer a penalty clause against himself. The fact that the promisor is willing to offer such a heavy sanction on his non-performance signals that he is convinced that he is willing and able to perform. Thus a penalty clause has a communicative function: it is a signal of reliability sent by the debtor. Although this idea has been seriously criticized in the literature, Posner retains this argument in the third and the fourth editions of his handbook (Posner, 1986, 1992). Apparently, this argument was countered in a convincing way by Muris (1981) and Rea (1984a). According to those authors a liquidated damage clause can perform this function equally well. A liquidated damage clause fully compensates the promisee, making him indifferent as to whether the promisor will breach or perform. So if a new entrant promises to fully compensate the losses in case of non-performance, potential parties are satisfied too. But compared to penalty clauses, liquidated damages entail fewer incentive problems. This may be reflected in a lower price of the product or service. A similar argument was developed by Schwartz (1990). De Geest (1994), however, has argued that under some conditions, the signalling theory becomes defendable. It is cheaper to draft a penalty clause than a liquidated damage clause. In the case of a liquidated damage clause one has to form an idea of all possible damage cases that might occur and to compute an average of them. For a penalty clause it suffices to estimate the highest possible damage. A penalty clause may therefore be desirable when a precise liquidated damage clause is too costly and the courts systematically award a compensation which is too small or which is exact on average but uncertain. A debtor may, for instance, want to use a standard form contract with a penalty clause to his own detriment. It may be too costly to draft a liquidated damages clause for every person individually. Therefore a standard form contract is used with a penalty clause compensating for the highest loss
4610
Penalty Clauses and Liquidated Damages
153
possible. For most creditors the compensation exceeds the real damage and even the ex ante estimation of it. Therefore, one clearly has to do with a penalty clause. If the loss of the average creditor is taken as a starting point, an adverse selection problem would therefore arise in such cases. The creditors with the highest real damage would not contract. On the other hand no high premium has to be demanded in return for the penalty clause when the only risk consists of non-performance by the debtor. For a bona fide debtor this risk is almost equal to zero, leaving aside the legal error costs. However, this signalling argument can never justify a penalty clause that applies to force majeure cases (De Geest, 1994). Such a penalty clause that applies in case of force majeure is an instance of overinsurance, a gambling clause. The suggestion of Posner (1973) that courts are taking a stand against gambling contracts makes sense in that respect.
14. Penalty Clauses as Punitive Sanctions when the Apprehension Rate is Lower than 1 In the economic literature on tort law it is generally accepted that punitive damages may be economically desirable when the injurer has a significant chance of escaping liability for the harm he caused (Polinsky and Shavell, 1998). While apprehension rates are generally higher in contract than in tort cases, there may be contract cases where it is difficult to discover or prove the debtor’s breach. It has been argued that punitive damages should be awarded in those cases (Perlstein, 1992; Polinsky and Shavell, 1998, pp. 936-939). See also Farber (1980) and Schwartz (1990) for a discussion of the economic function of punitive damages in breach of contract disputes. Penalty clauses may remedy this problem as well. Their extracompensatory nature compensates apprehension rates lower than 1. Which of both remedies is the best - punitive damages or penalty clauses - is still a relatively unexplored issue. Punitive damages have one comparative advantage: the apprehension rate can be calculated more realistically, because it is determined ex post, when more information about what happened is available. But this ex ante lack-of-information argument is a more general one that can be used against liquidated damages as well (ex ante it is more difficult to predict the magnitude of the harm than ex post). It may therefore be insufficient in itself to justify the penalty doctrine.
154
Penalty Clauses and Liquidated Damages
4610
15. Penalty Clauses as a Technique to Obtain Backward-Looking Specific Performance In Section 2 we have already discussed an important difference between penalty clauses and the specific performance remedy. Specific performance only works for the future and not for the past. If performance in natura is no longer desirable, courts will award just damages. On the other hand, penalty clauses can be awarded for breaches in the past. This means that the traditional specific performance remedy may sometimes not be enough of a disadvantage to make the promisor perform specifically. Penalty clauses may therefore be the only technique to really guarantee specific performance.
16. Penalty Clauses as a Technique to Create Risk Sharing Polinsky (1983) demonstrated that stipulated damages, which differ from expectation damages, can be necessary to obtain an optimal risk allocation. Under some conditions, penalty clauses can be a technique to let parties share the risk of a higher third party bid. Consider a contract to sell a Van Gogh painting. The price is 100 but the buyer’s true valuation is 150. There is a chance that before the date of delivery a third party will arrive offering 200. Suppose that the parties want to share that risk equally. This result can be obtained by stipulating in the contract that the seller should pay damages amounting to 75 in case of a breach. Should there be a third party offer, then the seller will indeed breach and make an additional profit of 25 (a price increase of 100 minus 75 damages). The buyer will be 25 better off as well. Yet the damages of 75 are overcompensatory (at least if the buyer had no sufficient knowledge of the market to have found the third party himself). A penalty clause exceeding 100 (in the latter example) allocates the risk entirely to the buyer. At first sight, penalty clauses are not necessary here, however, since the specific performance remedy obtains the same result. Yet, rational parties may prefer penalty clauses in those cases for the reasons discussed in the former section (specific performance cannot always restore breaches in the past). Of course, penalty clauses can be a good second-best solution when specific performance could clear the job as well but is not available in the legal system.
4610
Penalty Clauses and Liquidated Damages
155
17. Do Penalty Clauses Increase the Number of Bankruptcies? Penalty Clauses to Sanction Debtors Financing their Commercial Activities via Delayed Payments According to Farber (1983) penalty clauses lead to more bankruptcies. A debtor will have to pay a much higher amount in case he breaches and will therefore more easily get into financial distress. If the bankrupted party is involved in a web of long-term business relations with others, these too will be disrupted. If the other contracting parties fail to include penalty clauses in their own contracts, they will be disadvantaged when it comes to receiving a share of the assets in bankruptcy. If the use of penalty clauses were widespread, a wave of business failures triggered in a recession by penalty clauses could have a severe effect on investor confidence. But Farber (1983) does not take into account another cause of insolvency, as argued by De Geest (1994). Entrepreneurs who are working with other people’s capital sometimes take on excessive commercial risks. This danger is particularly serious when they finance their activities with fixed interest loans. Then the downward risk of the entrepreneurs is externalized while the upward risk is internalized. This is why shareholdership is a more common way of raising money. Yet there is a subtle way to coerce non-assenting people to lend money at a fixed interest rate: let them work for you or deliver goods and simply delay paying them. The creditor can then go to court, but it may take a long time before he is able to enforce his rights. This problem is most pressing in case of corporations that are about to go bankrupt. A penalty clause will not really prevent the entrepreneurs from taking on commercial risks. They can always turn to any owner of capital they may find. The latter will only lend out his money if he believes that he will benefit from it. In case of intrinsically loss-making projects this is almost impossible. A penalty clause in relation to an obligation to pay a sum of money just makes it more costly to force creditors to lend capital against their will. Penalty clauses will direct capital seeking entrepreneurs from non-specialized borrowers (painters, sellers, builders, ...) to specialized borrowers (bank, shareholders, ...). The result is economically desirable and may lead to a lower number of bankruptcies, or at least to lower drains in case of bankruptcy. By the same token, a penalty clause may be efficient in the case of loans. A penalty clause that corresponds to the highest possible risk premium possible will create proper incentives for a debtor to borrow additional money from parties that explicitly give their consent.
156
Penalty Clauses and Liquidated Damages
4610
C. Underliquidated Damages 18. Unliquidated Damages as a Technique to Create Risk Sharing Probably, the most important function of underliquidated damages is to make risk sharing possible for production cost uncertainties. In case of underliquidated damages against a producer, the risk of increased production costs is shared between the debtor and the creditor. The debtor only bears this risk to the extent of his own profit and a fraction of the consumer surplus of the creditor. The creditor bears the risk to the extent of the remaining part of his consumer surplus. Underliquidated damages against a consumer are possible as well. They imply that a consumer who cancels a reservation or an order, does not have to compensate the total profit of the producer or the seller. The risk of decreased utility is shared between the creditor and the debtor. The creditor bears this risk to the extent of his own consumer surplus and only a fraction of the profit of the debtor. The debtor bears the risk to the extent of the remaining part of his profit. Underliquidated damages thus allow agreement on, for instance, the reliance measure, the default rule prescribing the expectation measure.
19. Other Advantages and Disadvantages of Underliquidated Damages Underliquidated damages create a number of inefficient incentives. The creditor gets an incentive to avoid by all means an efficient breach of contract, because his compensation given a breach of contract is lower than his consumer surplus with specific performance. The debtor gets an incentive to head for an inefficient breach of contract in case of increased performance costs of the seller or decreased utility for the buyer. Underliquidated damages for the risk of a higher third party offer boil down to a gambling clause. With respect to the allocation of that risk, this is always undesirable unless the creditor is risk seeking. But underliquidated damages resemble the reliance measure. Also, with the latter, the compensation is lower than the real (expectation) damage. Compared with expectation damages, reliance damages have one big advantage: they lead to an optimal level of contracting. Because rational parties may have good reasons to stipulate underliquidated damages, it is not desirable to readjust this clause. That would be a type of regulation which does not necessarily improve the situation.
4610
Penalty Clauses and Liquidated Damages
157
As shown by Stole (1992) underliquidated damages may also play a role as screening device. Standardized underliquidated damages can give highvalue buyers an incentive to reveal their true valuations. We could compare this with the foreseeabilility doctrine in ordinary contract law: if parties do no use stipulated damages, courts will undercompensate the promisor if his losses were unforeseeable to the promisee (Hadley v. Baxendale in the common law). The economic function of that rule is to make promisees reveal in advance that they are more vulnerable.
D. Conclusions 20. Liquidated and Underliquidated Damages should be Allowed In the literature there seems to be a consensus that liquidated and underliquidated damages should be respected. This means that judges should not test liquidated damages against the real ex post damage. If judges always corrected liquidated damages that turn out to differ from the real losses, this would mean that the ex post valuation of the judge is the only thing that ultimately counts (except for those cases where judges are uncertain as to what are the true losses and put the burden of proof with the party that argues that the true losses differ from what is stipulated ex ante). Liquidated damages can be a rational option, especially if parties have more information about the possible losses than judges. Underliquidated damages may among other things be useful to let parties share the risk of increased production costs.
21. Under what Conditions should Penalty Clauses be Allowed? Penalty clauses, on the other hand, have been the subject of a fierce controversy for a long time. Most of authors seems to defend the penalty doctrine - the common law doctrine that forbids penalty clauses. It cannot be denied that penalty clauses have many disadvantages. Yet they may have a number of functions as well. Though penalty clauses should be forbidden in most cases, we nevertheless believe that they should be allowed under a few well-defined conditions. (a) A penalty clause against the drafter of a standard term contract should be allowed when it reflects the highest possible losses. Consumers may indeed have varying losses in case of breach. Drafting a tailor-made liquidated damages clause for each consumer individually may simply be too
158
Penalty Clauses and Liquidated Damages
4610
costly. The signing-without-reading problem is extremely unlikely to occur if the penalty clause is conceived against the drafter of the contract. (b) A penalty clause for the obligation to pay an amount of money in time should be allowed. Here it is quite rational to set the interest rate so that it reflects the highest possible commercial risk. An interest rate of 200 percent a year may discourage bad-faith promisors to finance risky, commercial projects by retarding payment to non-consenting promisees. Of course there is still a signing-without-reading danger here. But this may be limited if the interest rate is not set at a nearly infinite level but at one that just reflects a very high commercial risk. Yet in case of force majeure, these penalty clauses should not be enforceable even if conditions (a) and (b) are fulfilled. It is impossible for a penalty clause to have a signalling function here. This would be an instance of overinsurance, a gambling clause.
Acknowledgements The authors would like to thank Roger Van den Bergh for having organized the anonymous refereeing procedure.
Bibliography on Penalty Clauses and Liquidated Damages (4610) Alghion, Philippe and Bolton, Patrick (1987), ‘Contracts as Barriers to Entry’, 77 American Economic Review, 388-401. Anderson, James E. and Gollop, Frank M. (1986), ‘The Effect of Warranty Provisions on Used Car Prices’, in Ippolito, Pauline M. and Scheffman, David T. (eds), Empirical Approaches to Consumer Protection Economy, Washington, Federal Trade Commission, 67-102. Barton, John H. (1972), ‘The Economic Basis of Damages for Breach of Contract’, 1 Journal of Legal Studies, 277-304. Centner, Terence J. (1985), ‘Are FmHA Loans Entitlements Protected by the Due Process Clause?’, 34 Drake Law Review, 389-427. Centner, Terence J. and White, F.C. (1987), ‘FmHA’s Efforts Against Delinquent Borrowers: Property Interests and Transaction Costs.’, 12 Western Journal of Agricultural Economics, 35-41. Chung, Tai-Yeong (1992), ‘On the Social Optimality of Liquidated Damage Clauses: An Economic Analysis’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 280-305. Clarkson, Kenneth W., Miller, Roger Leroy and Muris, Timothy J. (1978), ‘Liquidated Damages v. Penalties: Sense or Nonsense?’, 54 Wisconsin Law Review, 351-390. Reprinted in Goldberg, Victor P. (ed.) (1989), Readings in the Economics of Contract Law, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 152-160.
4610
Penalty Clauses and Liquidated Damages
159
Coopersmith, Jeffrey B. (1990), ‘Comment: Refocusing Liquidated Damages Law for Real Estate Contracts: Returning to the Historical Roots of the Penalty Doctrine’, 39 Emory Law Journal, 267 ff. Cooter, Robert D. (1985), ‘Unity in Torts, Contracts and Property: The Model of Precaution’, 73 California Law Review, 1-51. De Alessi, Louis and Staaf, Robert J. (1989), ‘Subjective Value in Contract Law’, 145 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 561-577. De Geest, Gerrit (1994), Economische Analyse van het Contracten- en Quasi-Contractenrecht: een Onderzoek naar de Wetenschappelijke Waarde van de Rechtseconomie, Antwerpen, Maklu, 568 p. Diamond, Peter A. and Maskin, Eric (1979), ‘An Equilibrium Analysis of Search and Breach of Contract, I: Steady States’, 10 Bell Journal of Economics, 282-316. Farber, Daniel A. (1980), ‘Reassessing the Economic Efficiency of Compensatory Damages for Breach of Contract’, 66 Virginia Law Review, 1443-1484. Farber, Daniel A. (1983), ‘Contract Law and Modern Economic Theory’, 78 Northwestern University Law Review, 303-339. Goetz, Charles J. and Scott, Robert E. (1977), ‘Liquidated Damages, Penalties and the Just Compensation Principle: Some Notes on an Enforcement Model and a Theory of Efficient Breach’, 77 Columbia Law Review, 554-594. Reprinted in Kronman, Anthony T. and Posner, Richard A. (eds) (1979), The Economics of Contract Law, Boston, Little Brown, 194-207. Gross, Leonard E. (1986), ‘Contractual Limitations on Attorney Malpractice Liability: An Economic Approach’, 75 Kentucky Law Journal, 793 ff. Harris, Frederick H. (1987), ‘Security and Penalty in Debt Contracts: Comment’, 143 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 168-174. Hess, James D. and Knoeber, Charles R. (1987), ‘Security and Penalty in Debt Contracts’, 143 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 149-167. Jarrell, Gregg A. and Peltzman, Sam (1985), ‘The Impact of Product Recalls on the Wealth of Sellers’, 93 Journal of Political Economy, 512-536. Reprinted in Ippolito, Pauline M. and Scheffman, David T. (1986) (eds), Empirical Approaches to Consumer Protection Economics, Washington, DC, Federal Trade Commission, 377-409. Kahan, Marcel and Bruce Tuckman (1996), ‘Private versus Public Lending: Evidence from Covenants’, in Finnerty, John D. and Martin, S. Fridson (eds), The Yearbook of Fixed Income Investing 1995, 253-274. Kaplan, Philipp R. (1977), ‘A Critique of the Penalty Limitation on Liquidated Damages’, 50 Southern California Law Review, 1055-1090. Koller, Ingo (1981), ‘Die Verteilung des Scheckfälschungsrisikos zwischen Kunde und Bank (The Division of the False Cheque Risk Between Client and Bank)’, Neue Juristische Wochenschrift, 2433 ff. Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1983), ‘Reliance, Reputation, and Breach of Contract’, 27 Journal of Law and Economics, 691-706. Kötz, Hein (1983), ‘Haftungsausschluss der Chemischreiniger (Exemption Clauses in Cleaning Contracts, Legal Validity and Economic Efficiency)’, in Walz, W. Rainer and Rascher-Friesenhausen, Hein (eds), Sozialwissenschaften im Zivilrecht: Fälle und Lösungen in Ausbild und Prüfung, Neuwied und Darmstadt, Luchterhand, 76-88.
160
Penalty Clauses and Liquidated Damages
4610
Kötz, Hein (1983), ‘Haftungsausschlussklauseln, Eine juristisch-ökonomische Analyse (Exemption Clauses, a Legal-Economic Analysis)’, 25 Jahre Karlsruher Forum. Beiheft zu Versicherungsrecht, 145-152. Kötz, Hein (1989), ‘Zur Effizienz von Haftungsausschlussklauseln (On the Efficiency of Exemption Clauses)’, in Ott, Claus and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (eds), Allokationseffizienz in der Rechtsordnung, Berlin, Springer, 189-200. Kronman, Anthony T. and Posner, Richard A. (1979), The Economics of Contract Law, Boston, Little Brown, 274 p. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1979), ‘Adjudication as a Private Good’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 235-284. Langenfeld, James (1986), ‘The Effect of Warranty Provisions on Used Car Prices: Comments’, in Ippolito, Pauline M. and Scheffman, David T. (eds), Empirical Approaches to Consumer Protection Economy, Washington, Federal Trade Commission, 105-107. Mackaay, Ejan (1982), Economics of Information and Law, Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers. Masten, Scott E. and Snyder, Edward A. (1989), ‘The Design and Duration of Contracts: Strategic and Efficiency Considerations’, 52(1) Law and Contemporary Problems, 63-85. Mattei, Ugo (1995), ‘The Comparative Law and Economics of Penalty Clauses’, 43 American Journal of Comparative Law, 427-445. Milner, Alan (1979), ‘Liquidated Damages: An Empirical Study in the Travel Industry’, 42 Modern Law Review, 508-532. Muris, Timothy J. (1981), ‘Opportunistic Behaviour and the Law of Contracts’, 65 Minnesota Law Review, 521-590. Nagel, Bernhard (1991), ‘Kommentar (Comment On Wehrt, Die Qualitätshaftung des Verkäuf)’, in Ott, Claus and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (eds), Ökonomische Probleme des Zivilrechts, Berlin, Springer, 260-264. Perlstein, Barry (1992), ‘Crossing the Contract-Tort Boundary: An Economic Argument for the Imposition of Extracompensatory Damages for Opportunitistic Breach of Contract’, 58 Brooklyn Law Review, 877-911. Polinsky, A. Mitchell (1983), ‘Risk Sharing through Breach of Contract Remedies’, 12 Journal of Legal Studies, 427-444. Posner, Richard A. (1973), Economic Analysis of Law, Boston, Little Brown, 415 p. Posner, Richard A. (ed.) (1977), Tort Law: Cases and Economic Analysis, Boston, Little Brown. Posner, Richard A. (1979), ‘Some Uses and Abuses of Economics in Law’, 46 University of Chicago Law Review, 281-306. Posner, Richard A. (1986), Economic Analysis of Law, 3rd edn, Boston, Little Brown. Posner, Richard A. (1992), Economic Analysis of Law, 4th edn, Boston, Little Brown. Rea, Samuel A., Jr (1984a), ‘Efficiency Implications of Penalties and Liquidated Damages’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 147-167. Rea, Samuel A., Jr (1984b), ‘Arm-breaking, Consumer Credit, and Personal Bankruptcy’, Economic Inquiry, 188-208. Rea, Samuel A., Jr (1988), ‘Liquidated Damages and Penalties: An Economic Perspective’, in Knapp, Charles L. (ed.), Commercial Damages, New York, Matthew Bender, 99-108.
4610
Penalty Clauses and Liquidated Damages
161
Rubin, Paul H. (1981), ‘Unenforceable Contracts: Penalty Clauses and Specific Performance’, 10 Journal of Legal Studies, 237-247. Sappington, David E.M. (1983), ‘Limited Liability Contracts between Principal and Agent’, 29 Journal of Economic Theory, 1-21. Schumann, Jochen (1987), ‘Security and Penalty in Debt Contracts: Comment’, 143 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 175-179. Schwartz, Alan (1990), ‘The Myth that Promisees Prefer Supracompensatory Remedies: An Analysis of Contracting for Damage Measures’, 100 Yale Law Journal, 369-407. Seidl, Christian (1989), ‘Kommentar (Comment on Kötz, Zur Effizienz von Haftungsausschl)’, in Ott, Claus and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (eds), Allekationseffizienz in der Rechtsordnung, Berlin, Springer, 201-207. Spier, Kathryn E. and Whinston, Michael D. (1995), ‘On the Efficiency of Privately Stipulated Damages for Breach of Contract: Entry Barriers, Reliance and Renegotiation’, 26 Rand Journal of Economics, 180-202. Stake, Jeffrey E. (1991), ‘Status and Incentive Aspects of Judicial Decisions’, 79 Georgetown Law Journal, 1447-1497. Stole, Lars A. (1992), ‘The Economics of Liquidated Damage Clauses in Contractual Environments with Private Information’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 582-606. Thorpe, Jeremy (1994), ‘Economists Divided: Different Perceptions of Contract’s Penalty Doctrine’, 6(2) Bond Law Review, 189 ff. Ulen, Thomas S. (1984), ‘The Efficiency of Specific Performance: Toward a Unified Theory of Contract Remedies’, 83 Michigan Law Review, 341-403. Warren, Elizabeth (1983), ‘Formal and Operative Rules Under Common Law and Code’, 32 UCLA Law Review, 898 ff. X (1978), ‘Note: Liquidated Damages and Penalties Under the Uniform Commercial Code and Common Law: An Economic Analysis of Contract Damages’, 72 Northwestern University Law Review, 1055-1094.
Other References Birmingham, Robert L. (1970), ‘Breach of Contract, Damage Measures, and Economic Efficiency’, 24 Rutgers Law Review, 273-292. Levmore, Saul (1997),
4620 CONTRACT REMEDIES: FORESEEABILITY, PRECAUTION, CAUSATION AND MITIGATION Eric A. Posner Assistant Professor of Law, University of Pennsylvania Law School © Copyright 1999 Eric A. Posner
Abstract This section discusses undercompensatory damages rules in contract law. These are rules that reduce the award to the promisee to an amount below that to which he would be entitled under the expectations rule. The reason for reducing compensation is to encourage the promisee to behave in a value-maximizing manner. The Hadley rule, which denies recovery for losses that the promisor could not ordinarily foresee, is thought to provide promisees with incentives to reveal how much they value performance, in order to give the promisor optimal with incentives to take care. The mitigation rule, which denies recovery for losses that the promisee could have avoided by mitigating damages after the breach, is thought to provide promisees with the proper incentives to reduce losses caused by the promisor’s breach. Several theoretical and empirical ambiguities, however, weaken these arguments. Two other undercompensatory damages rules - the reasonable certainty doctrine and the emotional distress doctrine - are also discussed. The section also deals with precautionary behavior by both the promisor and the promisee. The expectations rule encourages the promisor to take optimal precautions, but it also discourages the promisee from taking precautions. To encourage the promisee also to take optimal precautions, damages must be invariant with respect to the amount of reliance and, ideally, should be set at the efficient level of reliance. Causation is not an important concept in contract law and scholarship. JEL classification: K12 Keywords: Contract Remedies: Foreseeability, Precaution, Causation, and Mitigation
1. Introduction The expectation measure of contract damages, which requires the breaching promisor to pay the promisee an amount of money sufficient to put the promisee in the position it would have been in if the promisor had performed,
162
4620
Contract Remedies
163
is the standard measure of damages in Anglo-American law, but it is subject to several exceptions. First, the award is reduced when a portion of the promisee’s loss is attributable to circumstances that the promisor could not ordinarily foresee. This result is due to the rule of consequential damages, also known as the Hadley rule, after Hadley v. Baxendale (1854). Second, the award is reduced when a portion of the promisee’s loss is attributable to the promisee’s failure to take actions that would have minimized its losses subsequent to the promisor’s breach. This result is due to the mitigation rule. Two less important doctrines hold that the award is reduced when the promisee cannot show that the loss was reasonably certain, and when the loss consists of emotional distress. Because these four rules on average produce an award lower than that produced by the expectation rule if applied unconditionally, they can be thought of as composing a larger category of undercompensatory contract damages rules. The value of the Hadley, mitigation, reasonable certainty and emotional distress rules, like that of all other rules of contract law, depends on their effects on the various forms of contract-related behavior. This behavior includes the selection of contracting partners, the choice of contracting rather than using other forms of commitment, the care in drafting the contract, the disclosure by each party of private information, investment in anticipation of performance, the taking of precautions to minimize the expected loss from breach, the allocation of risk, performance rather than breach, and the readiness to renegotiate contractual obligations in light of changed circumstances. We concentrate on the promisee’s incentives to disclose information, to take precautions and to mitigate damages. The Hadley rule and the mitigation rule have their greatest impact on these forms of behavior, and they will be discussed in the first and second sections of this chapter. The third section discusses the effect of damages rules on the parties’ incentives to take precautions. The fourth section discusses causation, which, however, is not an important concept in contract law. The fifth section briefly discusses the reasonable certainty and emotional distress rules; however, these rules either have not received much attention in the literature or are discussed in other chapters of this encyclopedia.
2. The Hadley Rule The Hadley rule states that promisors are not liable for losses that are not ‘foreseeable’. This term has attracted a great deal of criticism. Some commentators charge that courts simply call a loss ‘unforeseeable’ whenever they believe, for an unarticulated reason of policy, that the loss should not fall on the promisor (see Fuller and Perdue, 1936). Whether or not this skepticism is justified, the term does not provide much guidance, because sophisticated parties can foresee and often do foresee the range of losses considered
164
Contract Remedies
4620
unforeseeable by courts. For example, if a carrier fails to deliver goods or delivers them late, and this breach causes large losses for the shipper, perhaps because the goods were to perform a crucial role in the production process, the carrier will usually be liable for a limited amount, such as the purchase price, rather than the amount necessary to satisfy the shipper’s expectation. In the traditional doctrine, the shipper receives full expectation damages only if the losses are predictable or if the shipper informs the carrier of the size of the anticipated loss prior to agreement. But surely the uninformed carrier can ‘foresee’ that some shippers place a greater value on performance than other shippers. When courts say that a loss is unforeseeable, the best interpretation of this conclusion is that the loss is considerably greater than the average of the losses that result from the kind of breach in question. The Hadley rule is a default rule: parties are free to bargain around it and frequently do. Carriers, for example, often limit their liability and separately sell insurance against losses from misdelivery of expensive goods. The question asked by the Hadley literature is why the default rule limits liability to foreseeable damages, rather than imposing full liability on the promisor. It is thus typical to compare the Hadley (or ‘limited liability’ rule) to a full expectation rule (or ‘unlimited liability’). Default rules have well-recognized functions: by providing background terms they spare the parties the costs of negotiating ‘complete’ contracts and they provide a focus to their negotiations. Assuming for the moment that the only purpose of default rules is to minimize transaction costs, the optimal default rule is the one that on average minimizes the necessity of bargaining, or, what is the same thing, that maximizes the ex ante value of the contract. The relative advantages of the Hadley rule and expectation damages depend on which of the forms of behavior mentioned above has the greatest impact on the ex ante value of the contract. Inefficient breach, for example, is not fully deterred by the Hadley rule. To see why, consider a promisor (for concreteness, the ‘seller’) who would gain more from breaching than keeping its promise to the promisee (the ‘buyer’). Suppose that when deciding whether to breach, the seller accurately anticipates the buyer’s loss from breach. If the seller expects to be required to pay only average damages, it will breach even when the loss to the buyer from breach exceeds the seller’s gains from breach. In contrast, the expectations measure deters inefficient breach. The reason for the different outcomes is that the Hadley rule does not permit compensation for the loss of the buyer’s private, idiosyncratic value if not disclosed to the seller; but this loss is real, and if the seller is permitted to ignore it, then it will breach even when the buyer’s loss exceeds the seller’s gain. The effects of the rules on precaution - to take another example - are more complex. By forcing the buyer to incur part of the loss caused by the breach, any undercompensatory damages rule, including the Hadley rule, gives the buyer an incentive to take precautions
4620
Contract Remedies
165
against the loss. There is, however, no necessary relation between the Hadley rule and the optimal level of buyer precaution. (More on this later.) Unifying the analysis of the different effects of the Hadley and expectation rules is difficult. It is possible that for some broad class of transactions the ex ante value of contracts depends mostly on deterring inefficient breach, whereas for another class of transactions the ex ante value of contracts depends mostly on deterring insufficient precaution-taking by the promisee. If so, the Hadley rule should be enforced more vigorously in the second class than in the first. This approach has not, however, been taken in the literature, and it is not clear whether it would be fruitful. The literature has focused instead on the problem of asymmetric information. Suppose that the carrier deals with two kinds of customers: highvalue shippers, who suffer a large loss in case of misdelivery, and low-value shippers, who suffer a small loss in case of misdelivery. The carrier does not know whether a particular customer is high-value or low-value, but does know the proportion of each type in the population. Shippers know their own type. All parties are neutral with respect to risk. Because the loss avoided by investing in precautionary measures increases from the low type to the high type, the optimal contract with the high-value shipper would require the carrier to take costly precautions, whereas the optimal contract with the low-value shipper would require the carrier to take few precautions. Suppose that the expectation rule prevails. With full information the carrier would simply charge a higher fee for the high-precaution shipments than for the low-precaution shipments, and take the optimal level of precaution in each case. Without full information, the carrier would take an intermediate level of precaution and charge an intermediate price, producing two sorts of inefficiency. First, the carrier would take a suboptimal level of care when making high-value shipments. Second, too few contracts with low types will occur, because the intermediate price charged for unnecessary care will drive some of the low types from the market; and too many contracts with high types will occur, because their price is subsidized by the low types who remain in the market. The Hadley literature originated with an influential argument that the Hadley rule cures these two inefficiencies. The argument asserts that under the expectation rule the high-value shipper has no incentive to reveal information. Whether or not the high-value shipper reveals its type, the expectation rule awards it damages sufficient to cover its loss. Because the shipper therefore expects full compensation whether the carrier breaches or not, it is indifferent as to whether the carrier breaches or not; and so it does not care whether the carrier minimizes the chance of breach by taking the optimal (high) level of precaution. The carrier can take the optimal level of precaution only if it knows the shipper’s valuation; but because the shipper does not care about whether the carrier takes precautions, the shipper does not disclose its high valuation.
166
Contract Remedies
4620
Under the Hadley rule, in contrast, the high-value shipper is undercompensated if it does not disclose its type, because the average level of damages is intermediate between high and low. To ensure adequate compensation in case of breach, the high-value shipper discloses its type. Now ‘foreseeing’ the large loss should it breach, the carrier will be liable under the Hadley rule for high damages if it breaches. To limit its expected liability the carrier invests in precautions until their marginal cost equals the marginal gain from avoided loss. Thus does the carrier invest in optimal precaution. Meanwhile, the carrier can distinguish the low-value shippers as those who do not state that they belong to the high type. The carrier can therefore charge the low-value shippers a lower fee, also taking the fewer precautions that are optimal for low-value shippers. Thus are the optimal number of low-value contracts entered. The Hadley rule cures both forms of inefficiency (see Barton, 1972; more recent treatments include Perloff, 1981; Bishop, 1983; Quillen, 1988; Cooter and Ulen, 1988; Ayres and Gertner, 1989; Bebchuk and Shavell, 1991; Eisenberg, 1992; and Posner, 1992). A problem with some of the earlier discussions in the literature results from their focus on the behavior of the high-value shippers to the exclusion of the behavior of the low-value shippers. The argument tacitly assumes that although high-value shippers can and do contract out of the Hadley rule, low-value shippers would not contract out of the expectation rule. If the low-value shippers cannot contract around the expectation rule, then, of course, inefficiencies result. If the low-value shippers can contract around the rule, however, they will. The reason is that the low-value shippers prefer a package offering a low price, few precautions and low damages, to the package offering intermediate price, intermediate precautions and intermediate damages. Therefore, the low-value shippers will identify themselves as low-value shippers and offer to agree to limited liquidated damages in case of breach. Because their liability in case of breach of contract with low-value shippers is thus limited, the carriers take fewer precautions. The carriers also charge the low-value shippers a reduced fee, which attracts back into the market all lowvalue shippers who value shipment more than its marginal cost to the carrier. This cures the problem of too few contracts with low-value shippers. Since the carriers know that only high-value shippers would decline to identify themselves as low-value shippers, the carriers know to charge a high fee to any shipper that fails to identify itself as a low-value shipper. Because the carriers remain subject to full expectation damages with respect to the high-value shippers, and because they can accurately predict the extent of their liability (now that the high-value shippers are no longer pooled with the low-value shippers), they will increase their level of precaution to the optimal level with respect to the high types. This cures the problem of inefficient precaution (see Perloff, 1981; Ayres and Gertner, 1989; Bebchuk and Shavell, 1991).
4620
Contract Remedies
167
Barring further analysis or empirical work, the arguments are in equipoise. To see more clearly why, observe that to compare default rules, one sums (1) the expected costs of contracting around the rules (also sometimes called the ‘communication costs’), and (2) the losses resulting from the failure to contract around when doing so is not individually cost-justified. Consider one element of the expected costs of contracting around each rule: the proportion of high and low types in the population. If low types form a majority, then more contracts require disclosure of information under the expectation rule, where low types bargain around, than under the Hadley rule, where high types bargain around. If it is costly to bargain around contracts by disclosing information, then, everything else being equal, the Hadley rule generates fewer costs. The problem with the argument, however, is that there is no reason for believing that low types outnumber high types. More likely, the valuations are approximately normally distributed, and if a model requires bifurcation of the distribution then it should assume that half the types are high and half are low, an assumption which, unfortunately, renders the analysis indeterminate. These considerations appear to account for the skepticism toward the Hadley rule in Perloff (1981). Ayres and Gertner (1989) and Bebchuk and Shavell (1991) argue informally that the Hadley rule is superior when communication is socially optimal, but it is clear from their models, as the authors appear to recognize, that this conclusion depends on the assumption that high types form a minority. Consider now the costs of bargaining around a default rule - the costs of communicating one’s type and of negotiating and drafting the contracts. Suppose that the low types and the high types are equal in number. The Hadley rule is favored if the cost to low types is systematically higher than the cost to high types. There is no reason, however, to assume that the different types would typically incur different bargaining costs. As an aside, note that if the bargaining costs are trivial, never preventing parties from bargaining around, then the entire default analysis becomes irrelevant, since the parties can always choose the optimal terms. Finally, when the cost of communication exceeds the gains produced when the carrier takes the optimal level of precaution rather than the intermediate level of precaution, it is socially suboptimal for communication to occur, but under certain conditions the Hadley rule, but not the expectation rule, will cause the high types to communicate (see Bebchuk and Shavell, 1991). To see why, imagine that the equilibrium obtains in which only the high types communicate. If a high type were to deviate, then it would save the costs of communication, but it would incur an expected loss as a result of the carrier’s move from high to low precautions. The high type would stop communicating its type only if the former exceeded the latter. But from the perspective of social welfare, the relevant comparison is between the savings in communication costs, on the one hand, and the loss resulting from the move from the high level
168
Contract Remedies
4620
of precaution to the intermediate level of precaution. The reason is that if no high types communicated, then the carrier would offer the intermediate package of precaution, price and damages, not the low package. It is thus possible that communication costs for high types are high enough that no communication is socially optimal, but also low enough that no high type would decline to communicate, given that all other high types are communicating. To be sure, the low types are injured by a move from a communication to a no-communication equilibrium, since they communicate in neither case and prefer the package of price, precaution and damages in the first case. But under the right conditions their injury is smaller than the gain to the high types. In sum, although a cursory reading of the literature may suggest otherwise, the information revelation arguments do not clearly favor the Hadley rule or the expectation rule. The Hadley rule dominates the expectation rule only under special conditions, and there is no reason to believe that these conditions generally prevail or that, when they do prevail, courts can reliably identify them for the purpose of applying the rules. The indeterminacy is not surprising, given that the Hadley articles so far discussed rely on signaling models, and the difficulty of ranking equilibria produced in signaling models is well-known. Another branch of the Hadley literature also assumes asymmetric information but assumes further that the party without the private information has market power. Suppose the carrier has market power and the shippers do not. The existence of market power changes the high-value shippers’ calculations under the Hadley rule. If they reveal their type, they will expect the carrier to respond by charging them a supracompetitive price. If they do not reveal their type, however, they will not gain the benefit of full compensation in case of breach. In weighing these costs, shippers will sometimes choose not to reveal information, resulting in the precaution and number-of-transactions inefficiencies discussed above (Wolcher, 1989; Johnston, 1991). In contrast, under the expectation rule, the low-value shippers lose nothing from revealing their type. Indeed, they gain. Because the carrier can price-discriminate against the high types only if it can identify them, and it can identify them only if the low-value shippers disclose their type, the carrier will offer the low types a lower price in order to encourage such disclosure. The parties thus distinguished, the carrier will offer each type a different package of price, compensation and care. On these grounds Johnston (1990) prefers the expectation rule to the Hadley rule. The argument does not, however, show that the expectation rule dominates the Hadley rule under general conditions. To see why, observe that the carrier can force the parties to reveal their types only by offering alternative contracts, one of which (the ‘high’ contract) the high types prefer to the other (the ‘low’ contract), but the other of which the low types prefer to no contract at all. At the same time, the carrier will maximize profits by exploiting its monopoly
4620
Contract Remedies
169
power, and this means charging prices that are as close to the types’ valuations as possible. To encourage the low types to accept the low contract, the carrier must give them a price below their valuation; but if this price is too low, the high types will choose the low contract over the high contract, frustrating the carrier’s attempt to maximize profits. To make the low contract sufficiently unattractive to the high types, the carrier will set the damages level at a low level. Obviously, the carrier would not set the damages level above the low type’s valuation; but it can also be shown mathematically (see Ayres and Gertner, 1992, pp. 768-769) that the damages level in the low contract will be lower than the low type’s valuation. (The intuition for this result is that a high damages level for the low contract would drive the price for the low contract down, leading to a greater difference in prices for the high and low contracts, which would attract the high types to the low contract, but this would prevent the carrier from price discriminating against them.) But if the damages level in the low contract is less than the low type’s valuation, then the carrier will take an inefficiently low level of precautions. This efficiency loss occurs under both the expectations and the Hadley rule. The relative size of the efficiency loss depends on a variety of factors, such as the parties’ relative valuations, the proportions of types in the population, and so on, so that one cannot describe abstract conditions under which each rule produces better outcomes. The analysis of Hadley thus plummets into theoretical indeterminacy, but a few routes may lead out of this impasse. First, greater attention to historical and current commercial practices may reveal that some common assumptions are implausible and can safely be ignored in analysis. Legal and commercial constraints, for example, may inhibit the exercise of market power by carriers and other promisors. The empirical efforts of Danzig (1975), Landa (1987), Epstein (1989) and Johnston (1990) provide a foundation for such work. Second, greater attention to institutional issues may put helpful constraints on the analysis. If courts have general knowledge about valuations in an industry, if they can reliably distinguish between cases in which transaction costs are high and cases in which they are low, and if they can detect market power, then they should apply a rule that makes the extent of liability turn on all these factors; but if they cannot, then perhaps a bright-line rule should be used, such as unlimited liability, on the grounds that it would put the least demands on their abilities.
3. The Mitigation Rule The mitigation doctrine requires the promisee to take steps to reduce the loss from breach after it learns of the breach or acquires reason to know of it. If the promisee fails to take such steps, it will not recover full expectation damages. Instead, it will receive damages sufficient to compensate it for the loss that it
170
Contract Remedies
4620
would have incurred if it had taken the proper steps to mitigate. In this way, the mitigation doctrine, like the Hadley rule, is an undercompensatory damages remedy. Also like the Hadley rule, the mitigation doctrine is a default rule. The buyer (that is, the promisee) often has a chance to minimize the loss resulting from breach. For example, upon learning that the seller will not make a timely delivery of components that the buyer plans to use in producing goods, the buyer can consider buying replacements on the market and using them instead, or it can suffer a delay in production. If it does not purchase replacements, then it will lose profits from the delay in production. If it does purchase replacements and their price exceeds the contract price of the promised goods, then it will incur a loss equal to the difference in price. Mitigation refers to the buyer’s choice of the response that minimizes the loss resulting from breach. The most thorough analysis of the mitigation doctrine is that of Goetz and Scott (1983). See also Wittman (1981), and the comments in Bebchuk and Shavell (1991). Suppose that renegotiation is prohibitively expensive and that no mitigation rule exists, and that after the seller breaches, the buyer has the opportunity to reduce its expected loss from $100 to $50 by taking some action, like purchasing a substitute on the spot market. (For simplicity, the cost of mitigation is built into the loss; this could also be understood as the buyer incurring a $10 expense to reduce the expected loss from breach to $40.) We also assume throughout that the buyer can more cheaply reduce the expected loss than the seller can; otherwise, there is no problem, since the seller has every incentive to reduce its own liability. Under the rule of expectation damages, the buyer expects to be fully compensated for its loss regardless of whether it mitigates. If it mitigates properly, then it will incur only a $50 loss, but it will receive only the $50 damages necessary to compensate it. If it fails to mitigate and so loses profits, then it will incur a $100 loss, but it will receive the $100 in damages necessary to compensate it. Thus, the buyer has no incentive to engage in mitigation in the absence of the mitigation rule. But clearly mitigation is efficient: it reduces net losses by $50. The reason the buyer does not mitigate is that the seller enjoys the gains while the buyer incurs the costs. To give the buyer the incentive to mitigate, it must be penalized when it fails to do so. The mitigation rule produces this penalty by imposing on the buyer the loss that the seller would otherwise incur from the buyer’s failure to mitigate. If the buyer fails to mitigate, it would incur a loss of $100 but receive damages of only $50; if it mitigates, the $50 damages would fully compensate it for the $50 loss. Therefore, the buyer would mitigate. Notice that the buyer has an incentive to mitigate as long as it does not recover actual damages and that the amount it does receive is unrelated to actual loss. While the mitigation doctrine performs this function, so would any damages rule that provides an amount that is invariant with respect to the
4620
Contract Remedies
171
actual loss - for example, a rule of zero damages. The argument is less straightforward if renegotiation costs are low. In the absence of the mitigation rule, the seller could, at the time of breach or in anticipation of breach, offer to pay the buyer to mitigate. Since the seller bears the full costs of the failure to mitigate, it will pay the buyer to the extent that the gains from mitigation exceed its costs; and as long as this is the case, the buyer would be willing to accept the payment and to engage in mitigation. In the example, the seller would offer to pay the buyer up to $50 to mitigate, since mitigation would reduce the seller’s liability by $50. The efficient outcome is obtained. The only difference between this result and the result under the mitigation rule is that the cost of mitigation is fully borne by the buyer under the mitigation rule, whereas in the absence of the rule the cost of mitigation is fully or partly borne by the seller, depending on its bargaining power. This argument, at first glance, suggests that the value of the mitigation rule depends on its effect on incentives to engage in ex post renegotiation. One might argue that the no-mitigation rule creates worse incentives to renegotiate. Under the no-mitigation rule the buyer has strong incentives to hold out for a large payment from the seller and the seller has strong incentives to pay as little as possible, so that the gains from mitigation would be dissipated as the parties haggle. This problem, however, is offset by an advantage of the no-mitigation rule, namely, that it forces the seller to disclose an anticipated breach at the earliest possible moment. In contrast, under the mitigation rule the buyer must guess the likelihood and time of breach, and take steps to mitigate in light of its incomplete information. For discussions of the complex problems of the timing of breach, and of repudiation and cure, see Jackson (1978), Goetz and Scott (1983) and Craswell (1990). Even supposing low renegotiation costs, the mitigation and the nomitigation rules have different effects on behavior. Consider, for example, the parties’ incentives to take precautions against loss. The seller has higher expected costs under the no-mitigation rule than under the mitigation rule, because under the former it must pay the buyer to mitigate in case of breach. These costs will encourage the seller to take precautions against the loss from breach; but at the same time the expected gain to the buyer in mitigation payments in case of breach will deter the buyer from taking precautions. Under the mitigation rule, the buyer no longer has this disincentive to take precautions, but now the seller, because it no longer expects to have to pay the buyer to mitigate, has less reason to take precautions. Another example of the different effects the rules have on the parties’ behavior concerns the allocation of risk. Under the no-mitigation rule, the seller charges the buyer a premium to make up for the expected cost of paying the buyer to mitigate. The premium can be thought of as the cost of a lottery ticket that gives the buyer the chance, equal to the probability of breach, to gain the value of the premium. There is
172
Contract Remedies
4620
no reason to think that a buyer would be willing to purchase this lottery ticket. Risk-averse buyers do not want to take on risk, and risk-preferring buyers can gamble more profitably by visiting a casino (compare Craswell, 1990). The nomitigation rule creates an added cost to contracting, and this cost will deter people from entering otherwise value-maximizing contracts. If a mitigation rule seems superior to a no-mitigation rule, some authors doubt that courts apply the mitigation rule in a proper way. For example, some courts award the buyer the difference between the contract price and the market price of the substitutes without taking into account the possibility that the buyer should mitigate also by purchasing fewer substitutes or substitutes of lower quality. But when prices of goods rise, users of them generally should reduce consumption (see Fenn, 1981). Another example is the practice of refusing to compensate buyers who engage in high-risk mitigation strategies that result in no actual loss reduction, or allowing full compensation of buyers who decline to engage in mitigation strategies that require high capital outlays. As MacIntosh and Frydenlund (1987) point out, the net present value of a mitigation strategy, not its riskiness or costliness, determines its suitability. These criticisms, however, do not undermine the mitigation rule so much as raise the issue of whether it should be enforced as a series of strict liability rules, as reflected in the doctrines criticized, or as a negligence-like standard as the authors implicitly argue. A standard taxes judicial competence, but whether this cost outweighs the systematic distortions caused by rules is not known. To return to more general issues, one might ask why the mitigation analysis and the Hadley analysis follow such different paths. The disclosure of information, which is the focus of the Hadley analysis, and the mitigation of losses, which is the focus of the mitigation analysis, are but aspects of promisee behavior that minimizes the expected loss from breach. Indeed, the Hadley rule encourages the promisee to mitigate post-breach whenever the ‘unforeseeability’ of the magnitude of its prospective loss threatens it with an undercompensatory remedy. And the mitigation rule encourages the promisee to disclose information prior to contracting whenever the disclosure of information would enable the promisor to take precautionary steps that are more cost-effective than post-breach mitigation by the promisee. Both the Hadley rule and the mitigation rule threaten the promisee with undercompensatory damages in order to encourage it to engage in lossminimizing behavior: in this way, they address the same problem in a similar manner. The convenient but artificial distinction in the doctrine has created an unjustified divergence in scholarly analysis.
4620
Contract Remedies
173
4. The Precaution Decision A ‘precaution’ can be defined as any act by a person that reduces the expected loss from breach of contract. A person can take precautions by using care in selecting a contracting partner, by disclosing information to that partner, by drafting the contract in clear and simple language, by purchasing insurance against loss from breach, by modifying its capital investments to minimize the loss from breach, by mitigating, by renegotiating, and so on - in short, by taking any of the value-maximizing steps that were discussed in prior sections. One should take care in reading the literature, because commentators use the word ‘precaution’ in different ways. Goetz and Scott (1980) limit their discussion of precaution to the promisor’s use of clear contracting language that encompasses an adequate quantity of contingencies. Cooter (1985) limits his discussion of precaution to efforts made by the promisor and the promisee to minimize the expected loss from breach of contract between the signing of the contract, on the one hand, and performance or breach, on the other. Because we have already discussed disclosure of information and mitigation, and because discussion of the other aspects of precaution can be found in Chapter 4600, we follow Cooter. The only sustained discussion of precautionary behavior as an aspect of contract law (it appears routinely, however, in commentary on the law of products liability and, of course, on the law of torts generally) is that of Cooter (1985) (see also Cooter and Ulen, 1988). In Cooter’s model, a promisor agrees to deliver goods at a certain time. The promisor and the promisee choose whether to take precautions, and the jointly maximizing behavior of each party is to take precautions. For example, if the promisor agrees to rent warehouse space to the promisee at a future date, the promisee can take a precaution against breach by reserving storage space at another site or by letting its inventory run down. The precaution is costly to the promisee, but we suppose that it reduces the expected loss from breach by more than it costs the promisee. It is therefore efficient for the promisee to take the precaution, in the sense that the gains from the precaution exceed the cost. Indeed, a complete contract would require the promisee to take the precautions. When transaction costs prevent the parties from describing the promisee’s duty to take a particular precaution, however, the promisee would not take the precaution in the absence of a legal rule compelling it to do so. The reason is that it incurs the costs of the precaution but the promisor enjoys the gains. A legal rule that forced the promisee to take the precaution might therefore seem desirable. Similarly, the promisor can incur costs to lower the expected loss from breach. For example, the promisor can take a precaution against breach by hiring a guard to protect the premises, so that the warehouse will not be destroyed by fire. If the cost of hiring the guard is less than the expected loss, the promisor would maximize the value of the contract by hiring the guard. A
174
Contract Remedies
4620
legal rule should force the promisor to take such a precaution. What kind of rules would serve these purposes? For the promisor, expectation damages would ensure the optimal level of precaution. Since expectation damages force the promisor to bear the promisee’s loss, the promisor would take precautions to the point where their marginal cost equals the marginal expected reduction in the promisee’s loss. The problem with expectation damages, however, is that they would discourage the promisee from taking precautions. The reason is that if the promisee is fully compensated whether or not it takes precautions, it has no incentive to take them. Another rule is necessary for encouraging the promisee to take precautions. One possibility is a rule that awards zero damages. To see why, imagine that the breach would result in an expected loss of $100 if the promisee fails to take a precaution, and in an expected loss of $50 if the promisee takes a precaution that costs it $10. Under the zero damages rule, the promisee expects to bear the full loss, and so would take the $10 precaution in order to reduce the loss from $100 to $50. The problem with zero damages, however, is that it gives the promisor no incentive to take precautions. Thus, there is a tension between creating incentives for the promisor to behave properly and creating incentives for the promisee to behave properly. One possible resolution is a rule, analogous to the mitigation rule, that would require the promisee to take precautions whenever they produce gains greater than their costs. Such a rule might hold that the promisee must take ‘reasonable’ precautions against breach, meaning that the promisee suffers a reduction in damages equal to the amount of loss it could have avoided by taking precautions minus the cost of those precautions. Under this rule the promisee will take cost-justified precautions in order to avoid the reduction in damages. Then the promisor would bear any residual losses caused by its (the promisor’s) failure to take cost-justified precautions, and to avoid these costs the promisor would take precautions as well. Another possibility is a rule that limits the promisee’s damages to an amount that is invariant with respect to its level of reliance. We already saw that a rule that gave the promisee zero damages would cause it to use the precaution, because by doing so it incurs a $10 cost in order to reduce its losses by $50. Similarly, a rule that gave the promisee $50 of damages would cause it to use the precaution, because the $10 cost of the precaution is less than the reduction in the uncompensated loss from $50 (that is, $100 loss minus $50 damages) to $0 (that is, $50 loss minus $50 damages). Even a rule that gave the promisee $200 in damages would cause it to use the precaution. The promisee expects to gain more from taking the precaution (-$50 - $10 + $200 = $140) than by failing to take the precaution (-$100 + $200 = $100). The crucial distinction between this rule and expectation damages is that under the former the promisee benefits from taking precautions, whereas under the latter the
4620
Contract Remedies
175
promisor benefits when the promisee takes precautions. The promisee can be forced to internalize the cost of failing to take precautions only by a rule that makes its damages award invariant with respect to the amount which it invests in precautions. To be sure, the $200 rule, like the $0 rule, would create improper incentives for the promisor. It would cause the promisor to take too many precautions and to perform when it should breach. The optimal damages rule with respect to both promisor and promisee incentives would require an amount equal to what would be necessary to put the promisee in the position it would have been in if the promisor had performed and the promisee had taken efficient precautions. The reader might recall from Chapter 4600 that a similar conclusion was reached with respect to the question of promisee ‘reliance’. The connection between precaution and reliance is indeed very close. Scholars often talk of the promisee engaging in too much reliance or engaging in too little reliance on promises, by which they mean that the promisee invests more or less than the jointly value-maximizing amount between the signing of the contract and the completion of performance. The notions of promisee reliance and promisee precaution capture similar phenomena but from opposite directions: a promisee who takes too few precautions relies too much; a promisee who takes too many precautions relies too little. Commentary on reliance has focused on the behavior of the promisee in relation to the promisor’s incentive to breach, whereas analysis of precaution has dealt with the precautionary behavior of both the promisor and the promisee. But the conclusions of the two analyses are the same: the remedy of expectation damages is suboptimal because it allows the promisee to externalize costs on the promisor. The optimal damages rule would give the promisee the value of the expectation it would have had if it had engaged in the optimal level of reliance or - what is the same thing - the optimal level of precaution. This rule, however, does not exist. No rule straightforwardly encourages promisees to take efficient precautions. To be sure, promisees may fear that the Hadley rule and the mitigation rule will result in undercompensatory damages, and thus take precautions in order to limit their expected losses (compare Cooter, 1985). But neither the Hadley rule nor the mitigation rule directs courts to take account of a promisee’s precautions other than those of disclosing information pre-contract and mitigating damages post-breach. Cooter (1985) notes that parties can contractually limit damages to encourage the promisee to rely, but parties are free (usually) to contract around any damages rule. The question is why there is no default rule that, on an analogy to the Hadley rule and the mitigation rule, encourages precautionary behavior when transaction costs prevent the parties from stipulating damages in advance. There is not an obvious answer, but one possible direction of research would inquire into whether courts are more competent at making some kinds of evaluations, such as the reasonableness of mitigation, than others, such as the propriety of
176
Contract Remedies
4620
precautionary behavior.
5. Causation Causation is not an important concept in Anglo-American contract law. This is partly because the concept of causation is captured by other contract doctrines. If the promisee fails to mitigate, one might say that the promisor did not cause the entire loss, and therefore should not be fully liable; but this result is produced through application of the mitigation doctrine, and a separate ‘causation doctrine’ is not necessary, as it is in tort law. In only a handful of contract cases do courts discuss causation as a distinct issue. These cases involve a promisee who has separate contracts with two different breaching promisors, both of which breaches are sufficient to cause some or all of the loss. These cases have not attracted the attention of scholars, probably because of their rarity. The tort doctrine of proximate causation has an analogy in the Hadley doctrine and the doctrine of ‘reasonable certainty’. All of these doctrines release the wrongdoer from some or all liability when the victim’s loss is not entirely attributable to the promisor’s wrongdoing.
6. Related Doctrines Two other doctrines are related to the themes that have been discussed. The first limits expectation damages to an amount sufficient to compensate the promisee for a loss that is ‘reasonably certain’. The second denies promisees compensation for emotional distress arising from a breach of contract. Both doctrines, like the Hadley rule and the mitigation rule, are undercompensatory. The reasonable certainty doctrine requires the promisee to prove its loss with a greater degree of certainty than that required by the preponderance of evidence test that governs the other elements of civil actions. Some commentators argue that, in practice, the courts use the doctrine in a highly flexible way to prevent recovery of damages whenever they seem to overcompensate the promisee. Possibly, courts use the doctrine to punish promisees who engage in too much reliance, take too few precautions, or misbehave in other ways. This would support the analysis of Cooter (1985), described above. Another possibility is that the reasonable certainty doctrine actually does have analytic bite, and serves the purpose of preventing parties from externalizing the cost of resolving disputes on the courts. Unlike the injurers and victims under tort law, which has no analogous doctrine, the parties to a contract can anticipate a legal dispute and take steps in advance of performance to facilitate adjudication. For example, if they anticipate that a loss, such as the
4620
Contract Remedies
177
loss of good will or the loss of personal enjoyment of the goods or services, will be hard for a court to measure, they can arrange for a liquidated damages provision to specify that loss in advance. To deter parties from externalizing the cost of determining loss onto the courts, and to encourage them instead to supply a liquidated damages provision, a doctrine denying compensation for uncertain loss might be justified. See Chapter 4600 for discussion of the closely related issue of subjective loss. The ‘emotional distress’ doctrine raises issues similar to those raised by the reasonable certainty doctrine, but it raises one additional issue. The tort literature suggests that the case for compensation for emotional distress is uneasy. On the one hand, it is not clear that people would purchase insurance against nonpecuniary loss, because the marginal utility of money in the accident state of the world, once pecuniary losses are compensated, is not necessarily higher than the marginal utility of money in the non-accident state of the world. On the other hand, if the promisor is not forced to pay damages for emotional distress, it will have an incentive to take too few precautions against breach. For discussion of these issues, see Chapter 5140.
Acknowledgments The author thanks Richard Craswell, Steven Shavell, and two referees for helpful comments.
Bibliography on Contract Remedies: Foreseeability, Precaution, Causation and Mitigation (4620) Ayres, Ian and Gertner, Robert (1989), ‘Filling Gaps in Incomplete Contracts: An Economic Theory of Default Rules’, 99 Yale Law Journal, 87-130. Ayres, Ian and Gertner, Robert (1992), ‘Strategic Contractual Inefficiency and the Optimal Choice of Legal Rules’, 101 Yale Law Journal, 729-773. Bebchuk, Lucian Ayre and Shavell, Steven (1991), ‘Information and the Scope of Liability for Breach of Contract: The rule of Hadley vs. Baxendale’, 7 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 284-312. Bishop, William (1983), ‘The Contract-Tort Boundary and the Economics of Insurance’, 12 Journal of Legal Studies, 241-266. Cooter, Robert D. (1985), ‘Unity in Tort, Contract, and Property: The Model of Precaution’, 73 California Law Review, 1-51. Danzig, Richard (1975), ‘Hadley v. Baxendale: A Study in the Industrialization of the Law’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 249-284. Eisenberg, Melvin Aron (1992), ‘The Principle of Hadley v. Baxendale,’ 80 California Law Review, 563-613.
178
Contract Remedies
4620
Epstein, Richard A. (1989), ‘Beyond Foreseeability: Consequential Damages in the Law of Contract’, 18 Journal of Legal Studies, 105-138. Fenn, Paul (1981), ‘Mitigation and the ‘Correct’ Measure of Damage’, 1 International Review of Law and Economics, 223-226. Goetz, Charles J. and Scott, Robert E. (1983), ‘The Mitigation Principle: Toward a General Theory of Contractual Obligation’, 69 Virginia Law Review, 967-1024. Johnston, Jason S. (1990), ‘Strategic Bargaining and the Economic Theory of Contract Default Rules’, 100 Yale Law Journal, 615-664. Landa, Janet T. (1987), ‘Hadley v. Baxendale and the Expansion of the Middleman Economy’, 16 Journal of Legal Studies, 455-470. MacIntosh, Jeffrey G. and Frydenlund, David C. (1987), ‘An Investment Approach to a Theory of Contract Mitigation’, 37 University of Toronto Law Journal, 113-182. Perloff, Jeffrey M. (1981), ‘Breach of Contract and the Foreseeability Doctrine of Hadley v. Baxendale,’ 10 Journal of Legal Studies, 39-63. Quillen, Gwyn D. (1988), ‘Contract Damages and Cross-Subsidization’, 61 Southern California Law Review, 1125-1141. Wittman, Donald (1981), ‘Optimal Pricing of Sequential Inputs: Last Clear Chance, Mitigation of Damages, and Related Doctrines in the Law’, 10 Journal of Legal Studies, 65-91. Wolcher, Louis E. (1989), ‘Price Discrimination and Inefficient Risk Allocation Under the Rule of Hadley v. Baxendale’, 12 Research in Law and Economics, 9-31.
Other References Barton, John H. (1972), ‘The Economic Basis of Damages for Breach of Contract’, 1 Journal of Legal Studies, 277-304. Cooter, Robert and Ulen, Thomas (1988), Law and Economics, Glenview, Scott, Foresman, 644 p. Craswell, Richard (1990), ‘Insecurity, Repudiation, and Cure’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 399-434. Fuller, Lon L. and Perdue, William (1936), ‘The Reliance Interest in Contract Damages’, 46 Yale Law Journal, 52-98. Goetz, Charles J. and Scott, Robert E. (1980), ‘Enforcing Promises: An Examination of the Basis of Contract’, 89 Yale Law Journal, 1261-1300. Jackson, Thomas H. (1978), ‘‘Anticipatory Repudiation’ and the Temporal Element of Contract Law: An Economic Inquiry into Contract Damages in Cases of Prospective Nonperformance’, 31 Stanford Law Review, 69-119. Posner, Richard A. (1992), Economic Analysis of Law (4th edn), Boston, Little Brown, 722p.
Cases Hadley v. Baxendale (1854), 9 Ex. 341, 156 Eng. Rep. 145.
4700 WARRANTIES Klaus Wehrt Hochschule Harz © Copyright 1999 Klaus Wehrt
Abstract The objective of this chapter is to give the reader an overview of the approaches found in the warranty literature. The main question examined is whether the parties of a sales contract voluntarily specify an efficient warranty provision. The chapter starts with the investigation of unilateral cases in which only the seller influences the probability of a product breakdown. Then it switches to bilateral problems in a ‘one-shot’ relationship. Finally, it studies bilateral problems under repeated purchases. The outcome is that there is no need for legal intervention in this field. JEL classification: K12, L15, D18 Keywords: Warranty, Product Quality
1. Introduction A good can be defined by its properties. Some of the properties can be observed before the purchase. According to Nelson (1970) we call these attributes search properties. Other characteristics cannot be observed. We call such characteristics experience properties when their true quality is only revealed some time after the purchase (for example, functionability, duration). Otherwise they have to be classified according to Darby and Karny (1973) as credence properties (for example, therapeutic influence). Warranties control the quality of the experience characteristics of a good. However, if we take a look at what happens in reality, we discover that warranties are actually only offered for a subgroup of the set of experience characteristics (see Priest, 1981). Commonly, the guarantee expires after a certain time period after the purchase, and therefore only those experience properties are covered which reveal themselves within the warranty period. Apparently, the warranty is not a panacea against bad products. What is a warranty? A warranty is a promise of the seller to take contractually specified measures in case the performance of the purchased item is bad. Such measures (for a comparison of the different measures; see Wehrt, 1995) are typically money-back warranties (see Mann and Wissink, 1988, 1990), price reductions (see Grossman, 1981; Cooper and Ross, 1985), and 179
180
Warranties
4700
subsequent-improvement (see Wehrt, 1995) or replacement warranties (see Mann and Wissink, 1990, Gal-Or, 1989). The warranty condition has to be met before the buyer gets warranty compensation. Normally the warranty condition states that the purchased unit has to become defective, that is the bought item breaks down, parts of it do not work normally or the item is in a bad condition. The defect may result from two different situations. The first is when a deficiency in the technical development of the product caused a constructional flaw. In this case the defect is inherent in every item of the product and the average quality of the good is bad. The second concerns shortcomings in the production process, which may cause a manufacturing flaw. In this case only a fraction of the items sold will become defective. If one looks at the warranty as an instrument to signal high product quality, it is obvious that the supplier of a product with a constructional flaw is not going to offer a warranty. Only in cases where the supplier was unaware of the constructional flaw before putting the product on the market, the supplier will erronously offer a warranty. These considerations may explain why the warranty literature focuses on manufacturing flaws. The present article is divided into two parts. The first section addresses unilateral problems of moral hazard and adverse selection in a ‘one-shot’ relationship and, if need be, how they can be solved by warranties. In the second part bilateral problems are discussed. First we will discuss the problems in a ‘one-shot’ game. Afterwards we will introduce long-term relationships. The analyses will explain why warranties are often partial, and restricted in magnitude and duration.
A. Warranties in a Unilateral Context 2. Warranties as a Device of Insurance The simpliest type of problem is the following: risk-averse consumers demand goods from risk-neutral sellers. A certain fraction of the sold items will become defective after a period of use. When signing the purchase contract, neither the consumers nor the sellers know which units will be critical, but the parties process symmetric information about the average probability of failure. This failure probability ( cannot be influenced, either by the sellers’ investment in the manufacturing process or by the consumers’ care-taking. The seller offers the product at a price p. He faces constant unit costs of production: c > 0. In case of a defect he has to compensate the consumer by means of a warranty payment: w (0 < w < p). His profits V can be expressed as:
4700
Warranties
181
V = p − c − (@w The consumer values a faultless item with q (> p) monetary units. A defective item causes him a loss of F/l. The utility function U is defined over the monetary income. It expresses the risk aversion of the consumer and therefore increases with decreasing rates: U' > 0, U'' < 0. The expected utility is:
EU = (1 − ()@U(q − p) + (@U(q − p − F / l + w) Assuming a constant profit on the side of the suppliers, the product price becomes dependent on the magnitude of the promised warranty: p = p(w). A Pareto-optimal allocation requires marginal utility to be identical in situations both with and without a product defect. We therefore have: w* = l. This resource allocation will be achieved automatically in the long run in a competitive market, see Figure 1 for illustration. Every point of the diagram represents a price-warranty combination. Price-warranty combinations along the vertical axis insure the seller against product risks because no warranty compensation has to be paid at all, whereas the buyer will be fully insured if a combination from the vertical line w = l is taken. Free market entry drives the product price down to unit cost level: c + (@w. The straight line V = 0 represents this zero-profit level. The slope of this zero-profit line depends on the failure probability of the product. It is steep if the probability of failure is high, and relatively flat if the probability is low. The tangency point between the indifference curve EU1 and the zero-profit line represents the competitive equilibrium. This equilibrium is stable. A firm considering a smaller warranty level has to be aware that the consumers will look for lower prices in case of lower warranty levels. Reducing the warranty level from l to l' lowers the firm’s cost and therefore the product price by (@(l − l'). For such an offer a risk-neutral consumer would bid for a price which is (@(l − l') monetary units smaller. He would therefore be indifferent with respect to the choice of either offer. Risk-averse consumers would not only fear the pure monetary effect, but also the risk exposure which is caused by the now only partial warranty. Therefore they would refuse the new offer. Our first result is: warranties protect risk-averse consumers against manufacturing flaws. The consumers prefer a ‘full’ warranty, unrestricted in magnitude and duration.
182
Warranties
4700
Figure 1 Insurance against product defects
3. Warranties as a Signal of Quality Signalling literature can be traced back to Spence (1973) who wrote an article on ‘Job Market Signalling’. Grossman (1981, p. 479) argued that ‘when firms have tools available which they can use to convey information they will do so’. With warranties we have such a tool of information transfer. Assume there are two types of manufacturers. Type L produces at low unit costs cL but has a large rate of defective units (L, whereas type H has higher unit costs cH but a smaller quota of defective items (H. Let us assume that the customers know about the average market failure rate, but keep them uninformed about the firm-specific quota. Let us suppose furthermore that there are enough potential suppliers of each type to satisfy the demand within the whole market. When offering the product without a warranty, firms of type L would get the whole market demand at price p = cL, because the customers are not able to distinguish between these two types of firms. It is not useful for customers to buy at price p = cH. By charging this price, low quality firms may pretend to sell items of high quality. Firms of type H may start to advertise, in order to inform the consumers about the high quality of their products. Similarly to statements about price, as long as the right to make untrue statements is not sanctioned, advertising signals can be imitated by low quality suppliers (however, in a long-term relationship advertising may signal quality. For more information on this topic
4700
Warranties
183
(see Nelson, 1974; Schmalensee, 1978; Kihlstrom and Riordan, 1984; Milgrom and Roberts, 1986). It is because of the legal system that warranty commitments become credible signals. Putting aside those cases in which a firm is dissolved before the defects of its sold products are revealed, the legal order enforces warranty claims. Therefore, a firm which promises a warranty has to be aware of the resulting warranty costs in the future. Since low-quality suppliers face higher defect rates, they have to expect higher warranty costs. It is therefore cheaper for firms of type H than for firms of type L to use the warranty signal. Hence, they will do so and offer a full warranty, which is preferred most by the buyers anyway. Nevertheless, when they observe the supplementary warranty of competing high-quality suppliers, firms of type L will also offer a warranty. The competitive outcome as to which type of producer finally succeeds in serving the market then depends on the answer to the question : will the higher warranty costs of low quality firms be lower than the original differences in unit costs of production? Referring to the model of the previous paragraph, we know that risk-averse consumers prefer being fully insured against the monetary loss of a product defect: w = l. They favour a full warranty when contracting with either type H or L firms. Their expected utility therefore equals: EUi = U(q − pi) If and only if pH < pL, which means that cH + (H @ l < cL + (L @ l , firms of type H will be able to serve the market. Look at Figure 2 for an illustration. The diagram includes the zero-profit lines of two representative firms of type L and H. The point of intersection determines a specific partial warranty provision. Given this warranty provision, both firms face the same costs. Expanding the warranty further, the sharper warranty-cost increase for firms of type L creates a competitive disadvantage: the additional warranty costs in comparison to high-quality suppliers exceed the original unit cost difference. Therefore according to this example - firms of type H offer their products at the cheapest price. The tangency point A between the zero-profit line VH and the indifference curve EUH represents market equilibrium. Notice that the diagram contains two overlaying systems of indifference curves. The system EUH informs us about the expected utility of representative customers if they contract with firms of type H, the system EUL informs us about contracts with type L. The intersecting curves EU ' and EU represent the L
H
same level of expected utility. Since they intersect at a full-warranty price, consumers do not care about the firm-specific defect rate. Under full warranty the same price leads to the same expected utility, irrespective of which type of firm will sell. To distort the equilibrium, low-quality firms therefore have to
184
Warranties
4700
make an offer in the south-eastern area of the EU L' curve. Since such offers would cause losses, firms of type L refrain from doing so. Therefore the tangency point A characterizes a stable competitive equilibrium. Figure 2 Signalling high quality
The outcome is Pareto-optimal. Since the consumers prefer to be insured, the tangency points A and B are the only candidates for a Pareto optimum condition under the restriction of zero profits. A dominates B because the expected utility of the representative consumer is higher with lower prices. The assumptions of the original model can be altered in several respects: 1. The individual losses differ. Risk-averse consumers prefer a warranty coverage which compensates for their individual losses. Firms will then come up with offers varying in warranty coverage. Low-quality firms serve customers with small individual losses, whereas high-quality firms serve the more sensitive customers. The outcome is Pareto-optimal. It does not deviate from an outcome that would occur, if firms had truthfully disclosed their failure rate and offered an insurance against defective items (see Spence, 1977, p. 570). 2. A monopolist serves the market. The monopolist will increase warranty coverage as long as the marginal buyers’ willingness to pay increases with this coverage (Grossman, 1981, p. 475). Problems arise in cases where the individual losses differ: the social planner will look at inframarginal buyers to control warranty coverage, whereas the monopolist observes the marginal buyers’ willingness to pay (Spence, 1975). 3. The market structure is oligopolistic. Gal-Or (1989) showed that the informational content of warranties is limited, as multiple equilibria may exist.
4700
Warranties
185
4. Warranties as an Incentive to Invest in Quality It was Priest (1981, pp. 1307-1319) who emphasized the ‘Investment Theory of Warranty’. According to his interpretation a warranty is a device which controls the efforts taken by the manufacturer and the consumer to maintain a functioning product. The only relevant variable in a unilateral case - as discussed here - is the effort of the manufacturer to keep the failure rate optimal. Similar to the situations in the previous paragraphs, the customers are interested in being fully insured against the loss caused by a potential product breakdown: w = l. The seller, who, by assumption, is also the manufacturer, thus internalizes the buyer’s potential losses. The manufacturer therefore has to choose a level of quality investment x* which minimizes unit costs of production plus expected losses:
c(x) + ((x)@l Assuming c'(0) = 0, c' > 0, c'' > 0, (' < 0, ('' > 0, there is an optimal positive level of quality investment. This level will be chosen by the manufacturer. His investment will thereby be guided by the following consideration: the effect of a quality investment is to reduce the defect rate. Evaluated in monetary terms, this effect has to be weighed against avoided losses. For any additional quality investment to be taken, the loss-reducing effect has to be larger than the costs of this investment. 5. Underestimated Failure Rates Spence (1977, p. 563) already showed that no warranties will be offered in a competitive market where risk-neutral customers systematically underestimate the failure rate (. In case of risk-averse consumers only a partial warranty will be offered. Let r(() be the failure rate which is perceived by the buyers: r(() < (. Expected utility can then be expressed as: EU = [1 − r(() @ Uq − p(w)] + r(() @ U[q − p(w) − l + w] Maximization with respect to w then leads to the outcome: U ′ ( q − V − c + (1 − Π ) ⋅ w − l ) U ′ (q − V − c − Π ⋅ w )
=
[1 − r ( Π )] r ( Π ) >1 [1 − Π ] Π
Hence the representative consumer prefers a partial warranty: w* < l . Figure 3 illustrates the special case in which the underestimation of the failure rates leads to the outcome that consumers are no longer interested in warranties. The slope of the zero-profit line VL = 0 indicates the true quota of defective items of supplier L. However, consumers expect a failure rate that
186
Warranties
4700
corresponds to the slope of zero-profit line VL' = 0 . They believe that the quota is one third of the true quota. Clearly, their system of indifference curves has to be constructed according to the wrongly assumed quota. The first-best choice of these consumers would be a price-warranty combination as is shown by point P with a full warranty. However, these customers have to realize that the desired contract is not offered in the market. Offering this contract would create losses for firm L, because the true rate of defective items is higher than the customers expected. The minimum price firm L would claim for a full warranty contract is determined by point Q. The representative consumer values this offer with expected utility EU ' and concludes that there is a more valuable L
contract (utility EU L' ' ) without a warranty indicated by point T. Figure 3 Underestimated Failure Rates
Given this situation, we now assume that high-quality firms of type H are also in the market and sell the same product with a smaller rate of defective items. The corresponding system of indifference curves is characterized by the EUH-lines. Compared with firms of type L the offer of the H type is of higher social value, because the full-warranty price of these firms determined by point R is less than the full-warranty price of firm L determined by point Q. Consequently, it is to be expected that firms of type H serve the market. However, just as the customers underestimate the rate of defective items of
4700
Warranties
187
firms L, the rate of defective items of firms H is underestimated by a factor of '
3 (see line VH = 0). The current offer of firms L, selling the product without a warranty as indicated by point T, leads to utility EU L'' . The full-warranty contract indicated by S creates the same utility. Moreover, S is also a point on the indifference curve EU H'' . Therefore we have: EU L'' = EU H'' . The curve EU H'' intersects the ordinate at a price level which is less than cH. Consequently, as cH is the minimum price firms H have to charge for their goods without a warranty, the consumers expect that the utility of the offer characterized by point U is less than EU L'' . So, offer T is preferred to U. The awkward consequence of this example is that the consumers choose the wrong firms and the wrong warranty contracts. Therefore, we have to ask the question, whether the amount market failure can be corrected. Basically there are three ways of legal interference. The most restrictive kind of intervention is to introduce a mandatory legal warranty over the typical lifetime of a product. However, this type of interference should only be applied in situations where the rate of failure is exclusively determined by the firm. If it is also influenced by inherent attributes of failure inclination on the side of the buyer (Wilson, 1977; Rothschild and Stiglitz, 1976), by the intensity of use (Emons, 1989a) or by buyers’ care (Priest, 1981; Kambhu, 1982; Cooper and Ross, 1985) then partial warranties would be better. The second type of legal intervention is a disclosure rule which obliges the sellers to reveal the true failure rate before the purchase is made (Grossman, 1981). I expect that a third alternative will solve the problem with lower social costs: if firms are allowed comparative advertising, then the firm discriminated against will undertake the job to inform the buyers about the true quota of failure.
B. Warranties in a Bilateral Context 6. Warranties in a One-Shot Relationship Observations in reality contradict the picture of long-lasting, fully compensating warranties (see Priest, 1981, p. 1319, for a detailed empirical investigation of warranty contracts). Warranties are always limited in duration. Mostly, the warranty periods cover only part of the lifetime of a product. Often the warranty periods are restricted to one year. Warranties which last for three or more years can rarely be found, although the lifetime of consumer durables often exceeds ten years.
188
Warranties
4700
With respect to the scope of warranties - German standard form contracts predominantly specify subsequent improvement or subsequent delivery - one often detects clauses which exclude the warranty with regard to certain uses or which make the validity of the warranty dependent on the buyer’s intermediate input. Exclusions in warranties are typical for retailing and commercial uses. Often these exclusions are directed against aggressive use or the non-compliance with regular maintenance. Commonly, the operation of certain fragile parts falls under the warranty but the warranty coverage expires if attempts are made to open the product. On the other hand, parts housed deep within the product, inaccessible to the consumer’s influence, are often protected by an extended warranty. This short overview makes it clear that the organization of warranty contracts is essentially determined by the consumer’s potential influence on parts of the product. However, the consumer’s influence on the failure rate has not yet been investigated. Therefore, we have to extend the analysis to bilateral warranty problems, situations in which both parties, the manufacturer as well as the user, control the product’s failure rate. According to the investment theory of Priest (1981) every bilateral warranty problem is a mixture of different unilateral problems and hence can be reduced to its elementary ingredients. This view presupposes that it is a certain type of defect which points to the responsibility of, respectively, the seller or buyer. If this approach was correct, then the optimal warranty contract would have to stipulate a full warranty for those product risks which are under the control of the manufacturer and a full warranty exclusion for those risks which are under the control of the consumer. However, in addition to the elementary unilateral problems and their combinations, there is a real bilateral problem which cannot be decomposed. The optimal control of many of the product risks calls for a certain combination of seller’s and buyer’s care. Take for instance the case of a car engine. Its safe functioning requires the necessary mechanical and electronical adjustments on the part of the manufacturer as well as responsible behavior on the part of the driver. The breakdown probability increases if any of the parties fail to perform their duties. The problem of bilateral investments is addressed in articles by Kambhu (1982), Cooper and Ross (1985), Mann and Wissink (1988), Emons (1988). All these models assume that warranty promises are enforceable. Clearly, if warranties could not be enforced, sellers would cheat on the warranty and the outcome would be minimum product quality. Therefore, I also assume an enforceable warranty. Let the damage function d be dependent on the manufacturer’s quality investments x and the consumer’s costs of care-taking y:
4700
Warranties
189
d(x, y) = ((x, y) @ l Let furthermore: (x < 0, (xx > 0, (y < 0, and (yy > 0. The representative consumer is risk-neutral. Let us assume that his willingness to pay for an intact item is q and that his utility is measured in money terms and equals his willingness to pay. Then the expected utility is: EU = q − ( @ (l − w) − y − p The seller’s profit is:
V = p − x − (@w Maximization of the joint surplus with regard to x and y leads to the following first order conditions: − (x(x, y) @ l = 1
and − (y(x, y) @ l = 1 Now we have to answer the question whether the parties will control their quality and maintenance as described with the first order conditions. Thereby we assume two steps of decisionmaking. During the first step the parties compete, when unobserved by the other party, and choose a certain level of investment. Afterwards they cooperate, when fixing a warranty compensation which maximizes the joint surplus. For the first step the following first-order conditions are relevant: − (x(x, y) @ w = 1
and − (y(x, y) @ (l − w) = 1 A comparison with the Pareto conditions reveals a degree of tension. Pareto optimal quality investments of the manufacturer require a warranty level of w = l, whereas Pareto optimal care-taking of the consumers presupposes a level of w = 0. Therefore, a joint surplus-maximizing allocation is impossible (compare Cooper and Ross, 1985, p. 107), and a ‘second best’ solution will be the outcome. Let the functions x+(y, w) and y+(x, w) describe which level of investments a party will choose given the warranty promise w and the investment of the other party x or y, respectively. Let the pair [xE(w), yE(w)] denote the point of intersection of both functions. It represents the Nash equilibrium of the noncooperative part of the game. When jointly arriving at a conclusion about the level of the warranty, both parties anticipate their reciprocal pattern of unobserved behavior (Cooper and Ross, 1985, p. 109). They consequently maximize their joint surplus under the restriction of the Nash equilibrium, described above: max EU + V = q − Π ⋅ l − x − y w
subject to x = x° ( w)
and
y = y° ( w)
The first-order condition requires:
190
Warranties
4700
xE'(w) @ [ − (x(x, y) @ l − 1] + yE'(w) @ [ − (y(x, y) . l − 1] = 0 According to the first-order conditions of unobserved party behavior we have: − (x(x, y) = 1/w and − (y(x, y) = 1/(l − w), respectively. Therefore the first-order condition is: l l x° ' ( w) − 1 + y° '( w) − 1 = 0 w l−w
On condition that xE' > 0 and yE' < 0 the outcome will always be a partial warranty which, on the one hand, is greater than zero, but, on the other hand, is less than l. If the degree of warranty coverage w/l converges to one, the first term of the above equation vanishes. The derivative is therefore negative. If the degree of coverage converges to zero, the second term disappears. Hence the derivative is positive. However, as is indicated by the equations of party behavior, the conditions of xE' > 0 and yE' < 0 are not always fulfilled. Its validity depends on the magnitude and the sign of (xy (complementary or substitutionary investments). The outcome of the bilateral model is: 1. Parties who feel unobserved when carrying out their product investments normally agree to a partial warranty. 2. This voluntary agreement solves the bilateral problem in a suboptimal manner. Kambhu (1982) raises the question whether or not it is possible to design legal rules which solve the problem of suboptimal incentives. He starts from the assumption that any warranty rule has to be ‘balanced’, which means that the seller, in making the warranty payment , loses the same amount of money as the buyer gets. According to Kambhu (1982) no legal warranty rule exists which offers both parties the Pareto-optimal incentives. This result becomes quite clear if one considers the restrictions under which the legislator has to develop the warranty rule. He has to accept that the legal consequence of the rule cannot depend on unobservable constituent facts. Deviating from the above analyses, Emons (1988) examines the case of a voluntary warranty in which the quality investments of the manufacturer and the consumer’s precautional measures do not continuously vary. He distinguishes two levels of f respectively, quality investments and care-taking. His conclusions are: if risk-averse consumers in a competitive market benefit from a full warranty more than from an incentive-compatible warranty, only a second-best solution is feasible, because the consumers will exert a low level of care. However, if the benefit of full insurance is lower and if the incentive-compatible warranty is extensive enough not to destroy the seller’s
4700
Warranties
191
quality-assuring incentive, then the levels of quality and care will be optimal. The last result of Emons (1988) is crucially predetermined by the assumption of discontinuous variables. With continuous variables a full warranty coverage is necessary to assure the optimal quality investment of the seller. However, this coverage will eliminate the consumer’s incentive to handle the good carefully. Mann and Wissink (1988) discussed the case of a voluntary money-back warranty. The buyer is allowed to return the product within a period specified beforehand. The authors conclude that under extreme conditions the double-sided moral-hazard problem is solved by the first-best levels of care-taking. However, the assumptions of the model used are not realistic. On the one hand, the authors implicitly presuppose a very short period of exchange. This is assumed because buyers do not derive any benefit from the use of the product. On the other hand, the model presupposes that within this period the buyers detect all possible shortcomings of the product. So it seems that the authors really investigate the case of a search good.
7. Warranties in a Long-Term Relationship: The Model The outcome of the above analysis is that in a one-shot relationship with enforceable warranties the first-best levels of parties’ investments in quality and care-taking, respectively, cannot be achieved in general. This section now aims to examine the question whether the market outcome will improve if buyers purchase from sellers who have a good reputation. Deviating from the analysis of the last paragraph I assume unenforceable warranties. This assumption, which complicates the incentive problem, is used to show how reputation really works. Consumer durables are the type of goods for which warranties are most important. Consumers remember the experiences they had with typical brands. These experiences are shared with other customers by word-of-mouth communication. Therefore, companies which have sold brands that customers disliked, may lose part of their reputation and therefore future sales. The mere possibility of future losses may give the seller the incentive to make adequate quality investments. The following model (see Wehrt, 1995b) assumes a perfect competitive market. A multitude of sellers offer the same product with different warranty commitments in the market. However, the brands differ with respect to the unobservable quality investments and therefore varying failure probabilities. Consumers also influence the failure probabilities by their care investments. Satisfied consumers award their sellers with a certain reputation. This reputation is earned, if during the previous period the seller at least delivered the quality he had signalled with the price beforehand and if he kept the given
192
Warranties
4700
warranty promise. A firm’s reputation in period t is therefore a function of the quality-warranty package of the previous period: Rt = (xt-1, wt-1). The earned reputation allows the firm to ask a price in the next period which corresponds to its reputation: pt(Rt) = pt(xt-1, wt-1). Firms which have never earned a reputation or which have abused it are avoided by the consumers. A reputational equilibrium can be defined by four conditions (compare Shapiro (1983)): 1. Every buyer chooses the quality-warranty package and the level of care-taking which maximizes his consumer surplus. 2. Buyers’ expectations come true: a seller whom the buyers expect to meet a certain level of quality investments and to keep his warranty promise, performs in this way: (xt, wt) = Rt = (xt-1, wt-1). 3. In every partial market defined by a certain level of promised quality and warranty, supply equals demand. 4. Market entrance and market exit are not profitable. The consumers are assumed to behave in a risk-neutral way. They can be distinguished by their willingness to pay q and the certain loss l that a breakdown of the purchased item causes. Thus the expected utility is: EUql = q − ( @ (l − w) − y − p where q 0 [0, 4), l 0 [0, q] According to the first equilibrium condition, a consumer of type ql maximizes his expected utility with respect to the variables y, x, w. Therefore, we have three marginal conditions: − (y(xql ,yql ) . (l − wql ) = 1
− (x(xql ,yql ) . (l − wql ) = px
((xql ,yql ) = pw The optimal values of the three variables yql, xql, wql do not vary with respect to a consumer’s willingness to pay q, but as the appearance of the individual loss l in the first two conditions shows, they depend on l. Consumers with identical individual losses are members of the same class. They prefer a certain level of quality, warranty and own care-taking. Therefore, a firm with a certain reputation serves the consumers of a certain class. The reputational equilibrium also requires that sellers have no incentive to abuse their reputation once it has been built up. A seller who exploits his reputation earns profits only during the next period. After that period the customers will avoid him. Therefore that seller’s profit is
4700
Warranties
193
V1 = p(x, w) − x0, where x0 determines the cost of the minimum quality. If the firm keeps its reputation Rt permanently, it will earn profits during all the subsequent periods. Using the interest rate r, the discounted future profits can be stated as:
V2 = {p(x, w) − x − (@w} @ (1 + r) / r Defending the reputation requires profits V2 to be at least as high as profits V1. Therefore we have:
p(x, w) > x + (@w + r {x + (@w − x0} In the above, the term in the third position of the inequality stands for the quality premium the seller earns from complying with his reputation. On the other hand, according to equilibrium condition 4, the profitability of market entrance has to be prevented. A seller who enters the market will earn the following stream of profits:
V3 = x0 − x − (@w + {p(x, w) − x − (@w} / r These profits are not allowed to exceed zero. Thus the above inequality has to hold with ‘<’. Hence, equality results. The price function calculates the equilibrium prices that sellers with different quality-warranty reputations will realize. Under the restriction of this price function, customers are not interested in buying with a guarantee: w = 0. Inspection of the price function shows that if buyers consider purchasing from another partial market in which the offered guarantee is one monetary unit instead of no warranty, they have to be aware that the price will increase not only by factor (1 + r) @ (, but that it will further increase, as sellers in this new partial market have to take into consideration that their customers are more careless because of the offered warranty. On the other hand, having chosen the optimal levels of quality and care-taking under the premise of no warranty, a consumer’s net benefit is lower than the price increase, because the expected utility will only grow by a factor of ( when switching to the other partial market. Consolidated with the price increase, the net effect is therefore negative. Therefore, risk-neutral consumers will decide against the warranty. With respect to this outcome, the first-order conditions of consumer behavior will be simplified to: − (y(xql, yql) @ l = 1
− (x(xql, yql) @ l = 1 + r The important result therefore is: risk-neutral parties will approximately choose the first-best levels of quality investments and care-taking, if the discount rate
194
Warranties
4700
of future profits is small enough. So, even in a situation where warranties are not enforceable, there is a realistic chance that parties will choose the optimal quality and care investments.
8. Warranties in a Long-Term Relationship: Discussion What are the main variables that influence the magnitude of the discount rate r? The interest rate r connects the periods of usefulness. It therefore represents a measure of the speed with which the information about the experience characteristics of the purchased goods spreads to the buyers. According to the model, agreements will only be contracted at the beginning of a period. Hence acquired experience can be applied no earlier than at the beginning of the next period. In this case the discount rate r - and therefore the quality premium - is indeed determined by the length of the period of usefulness. When putting the model into reality, two additional effects have to be taken into account. On the one hand, consumers do not buy on command at the beginning of a new period, but at different points in time during a current period. Therefore acquired experience begins to spread to the buyers immediately after a product defect is detected. In this case it is not only the length of the period of usefulness that influences the discount rate r, but rather the length of time that passes before the defect is discovered. So those kinds of flaws which immediately reveal themselves after the purchase (for example, compatibility) lead to a small discount rate, whereas other types of flaws which appear after a long period of use (for example, durability) result into higher discount rates. Smaller deviations from the optimal quality investments can therefore be expected with regard to easily detected product failures, larger deviations with respect to hidden defects. On the other hand, information needs time to spread to the consumers. A seller who has misrepresented his reputation will not lose his customers overnight, but in relation to the speed with which the information about the quality of his product diffuses. This aspect increases the interest rate r. The model presupposes risk-neutral consumers. If the consumers are assumed to behave in a risk-averse way, then voluntary warranty contracts will be observable. Buyers of this type are ready to accept a mark-up that exceeds the expected monetary value of the warranty. Below a critical threshold of the discount rate r, they therefore prefer a warranty. However, the seller’s quality premium which is necessary to let him comply with the given warranty promise, increases in proportion to how late the experience characteristics of the product will reveal themselves. Therefore, even risk-averse consumers are not interested in buying insurance against those defects which can only be detected in a late stage. These offers are too expensive. This aspect explains
4700
Warranties
195
why warranties are fully compensating but limited in duration, rather than partially compensating and unrestricted in duration (other explanations of this aspect are offered by Emons, 1989a; Cooper and Ross, 1988). If the legal order enforces warranties, then the quality premium is no longer necessary to make the seller comply with the warranty promise. The sole function of the quality premium then is to assure the seller’s quality investments. However, the enforced guarantee is also an instrument of quality assurance. For instance, in the case of a full warranty the seller has no opportunity to externalize failure costs to his buyers. Therefore buyers profit twice from an increase in the warranty coverage. Firstly, it offers more compensation in case of a defect. Secondly, it reduces the quality premium and possibly - if the monetary effect of the diminished quality premium exceeds the additional costs of the expanded warranty - makes the product cheaper. This effect explains the outcome of the altered model. In case of enforced guarantees and a positive discount rate r even risk-neutral consumers prefer positive warranty coverage (see Wehrt, 1995b, p. 172).
9. Conclusions The purpose of this chapter was to give a brief overview of the approaches and the literature written in the field of product warranties. Starting with unilateral problems we discovered a contradiction between the types of warranty contracts we observe in reality (partial warranties) and the optimal design of such contracts which was derived from the analysis (full warranties). Hence, it could be that market failures explain the deviation between ‘what is’ and ‘what should be’. An explanation was offered by considering the possibility that customers systematically underestimate the firms’ rates of defective items. In such a case the wrongly assessed failure rate makes consumers erroneously decide against a full warranty. Expanding the analysis to bilateral problems, we found out that the problem’s optimal solution changes. The original gap between model and reality disappears. Certainly specified partial warranties form the optimal type of contract. However, we have to conclude that the optimality of this contract is due to the restrictions of unobservability. Its optimality is not due to a world in which either party is fully informed about how the other party handled the product. But even a legislator has to accept that he cannot get access to the best of all worlds. We finally looked at repeated purchases. As the seller often sells the same product, consumers have a broader basis for drawing inferences about the seller’s quality investments. Therefore, the veil of ignorance slightly lifts and an additional step into the direction of the best of all worlds can be made.
196
Warranties
4700
Bibliography on Warranties (4700) Barnes, David W. and Stout, Lynn A. (1992), Economics of Contract Law, Minneapolis, West Publishing. Basedow, J. (1988), Die Reform des deutschen Kaufrechts, Köln, Bundes anzeiger. Bellantuono, Giuseppe (1995), ‘Polizza Fideiussoria, Reticenza e Obblighi di Informazione (Performance Bond, Non-Disclosure and Duties of Information)’, Il Foro Italiano, 1905-1909. Bigelow, John P., Cooper, R. and Ross, Thomas W. (1993), ‘Warranties without Commitment to Market Participation’, 34 International Economic Review, 85-100. Blischke, W. and Murphy, D. (1995), The Product Warranty Handbook, Dekkers. Bogle, Charles and Hoen, Iris (1995), ‘Comment: Warranty Remedies and Transaction Costs’, in Bouckaert, Boudewijn and De Geest, Gerrit (eds), Essays in Law and Economics II: Contract Law, Regulation, and Reflections on Law and Economics, Antwerpen, Maklu, 71-76. Bryant, W. Keith and Gerner, Jennifer L. (1978), ‘The Price of a Warranty: The Case for Refrigerators’, 2 Journal of Consumer Affairs, 30-47. Centner, Terence J. (1989), ‘Imposition of Liability and Allocation of Damages for Defective Seed’, 5 Agribusiness: An International Journal, 597-606. Centner, Terence J. (1992), ‘The New “Tractor Lemon Laws”: An Attempt to Squeeze Manufacturers Draws Sour Benefits’, 14(2) Journal of Products Liability, 121-137. Centner, Terence J. (1993), ‘Separating Lemons: Automobiles and Tractors under the “Motor Vehicle Warranty Rights Act” and the “Farm Tractor Warranty Act”’, 30(1) Georgia State Bar Journal, 36-43. Centner, Terence J. (1995), ‘Lemon Laws: Sour Options for Consumers of Farm Tractors’, 18(3) Hamline Law Review, 347-362. Centner, Terence J. and Wetzstein, Michael E. (1987), ‘Reducing Moral Hazard Associated With Implied Warranties of Animal Health’, 68 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 143-150. Centner, Terence J. and Wetzstein, Michael E. (1988), ‘Reducing Moral Hazard Associated With Implied Warranties of Animal Health: Reply’, 70 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 413-414. Centner, Terence J. and Wetzstein, Michael E. (1995), ‘Obligations and Penalties under Lemon Laws: Automobiles Versus Tractors’, 20(1) Journal of Agricultural and Resource Economics, 135-145. Chapman, Kenneth and Meurer, Michael J. (1989), ‘Efficient Remedies for Breach of Warranty’, 52(1) Law and Contemporary Problems, 107-131. Cooper, Russell and Ross, Thomas W. (1985), ‘Product Warranties and Double Moral Hazard’, 16 Rand Journal of Economics, 103-113. Cooper, Russell and Ross, Thomas W. (1988), ‘An Intertemporal Model of Warranties’, 21 Canadian Journal of Economics, 72-286. Courville, Léon and Hausman, Warren H. (1979), ‘Warranty Scope and Reliability under Imperfect Information and Alternative Market Structures’, 52 Journal of Business, 361-378. Crocker, Keith J. (1986), ‘A Reexamination of the “Lemons” Market when Warranties are not Prepurchase Quality Signals’, 2 Information Economics and Policy, 147-162.
4700
Warranties
197
Eisenach, Jeffrey A., Higgins, Richard S. and Shughart, William F., II (1984), ‘Warranties, Tie-ins, and Efficient Insurance Contracts: A Theory and Three Case Studies’, 6 Research in Law and Economics, 167-185. Emons, Winand (1987), On the Economic Theory of Warranties, Bonn, 84 p. Emons, Winand (1988), ‘Warranties, Moral Hazard, and the Lemons Problem’, 46 Journal of Economic Theory, 16-33. Emons, Winand (1989a), ‘On the Limitation of Warranty Duration’, 37 Journal of Industrial Economics, 287-301. Emons, Winand (1989b), ‘The Theory of Warranty Contracts’,3 Journal of Economic Surveys, 43-57. Gal-Or, E. (1989), ‘Warranties as a Signal of Quality’, 22 Canadian Journal of Economics, 50-61. Gerner, Jennifer L. and Bryant, W. Keith (1981), ‘Appliance Warranties as a Market Signal?’, 15 Journal of Consumer Affairs, 75-86. Gill, Harley Leroy and Roberts, David C. (1989), ‘New Car Warranty Repair: Theory and Evidence’, 55 Southern Economic Journal, 662-678. Grossman, Sanford J. (1981), ‘The Informational Role of Warranties and Private Disclosure about Product Quality’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 461-483. Haas, L. (1992), ‘Vorschläge zur Überarbeitung des Schuldrechts: Die Mängelhaftung bei Kauf- und Werkverträgen (Proposals for a Reform of the German Contract Law: Seller’s Liability for Flaws in the Execution of Sales and Service Contracts)’, 38 Neue Juristische Wochenschrift, 2389-2395. Heal, Geoffrey M. (1977), ‘Guarantees and Risk Sharing’, 44 Review of Economic Studies, 549-560. Holdych, Tom (1996), ‘The Basis of the Bargain Requirement: A Market and Economic Based Analysis of Express Warranties’, 45 DePaul Law Review, 781-857. Holdych, Tom and Ferrell (1990), ‘Individual Negotiation of Warranty Disclaimers: An Economic Analysis of a Presumably Market Enhancing Rule’, 13 U.P.S. Law Review, 601-643. Huber, U. (1981a), ‘Leistungsstörungen (Breach of Contract)’, 1 Gutachten und Vor schläge zur Überarbeitung des Schuldrechts, 647-909. Huber, U. (1981b), ‘Kaufvertrag (The Sales Contract)’, 1 Gutachten und Vor Schläge zur Überarbeitung des Schuldrechts, 911-949. Kambhu, John (1982), ‘Optimal Product Quality under Asymmetric Information and Moral Hazard’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 483-492. Kubo, Yuji (1986), ‘Quality Uncertainty and Guarantee’,30 European Economic Review, 1063-1079. Laband, David N. (1991), ‘An Objective Measure of Search versus Experience Goods’, 26 Economic Inquiry, 497-509. Leland, Hayne E. (1979), ‘Quacks, Lemons, and Licensing: A Theory of Minimum Quality Standards’, 87 Journal of Political Economy, 1328-1346. Leland, Hayne E. (1981), ‘Comments on Grossman’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 485-489. Lowenthal, Franklin (1983), ‘Product Warranty Period: A Markovian Approach to Estimation and Analysis of Repair and Replacement Costs: A Comment’, 58 Accounting Review, 837-838.
198
Warranties
4700
Lutz, Nancy A. (1989), ‘Warranties as Signals Under Consumer Moral Hazard’, 20 Rand Journal of Economics, 239-254. Mann, Duncan P. and Wissink, Jennifer P. (1988), ‘Money-Back Contracts with Double Moral Hazard’, 19 Rand Journal of Economics, 285-292. Mann, Duncan P. and Wissink, Jennifer P. (1990), ‘Money-Back Warranties vs. Replacement Warranties: A Simple Comparison’, 80 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 432-436. Matthews, Steven and Moore, John (1987), ‘Monopoly Provision of Quality and Warranties: An Exploration in the Theory of Multidimensional Screening’, 55 Econometrica, 441-467. Nelson, Philip (1970), ‘Information and Consumer Behaviour’, 78 Journal of Political Economy, 311-329. Pacces, Alessio and Pardolesi, Roberto (1997), ‘Clausole Vessatorie in Crisi d’Identitã. Appunti di Analisi Economica del Diritto (The Identity Crisis of Unfair Terms. Remarks of Economic Analysis of Law)’, in Furgiuele (ed.), Diritto Privato, Padova. Palfrey, Thomas R. (1986), ‘An Experimental Study of Warranty Coverage and Dispute Resolution in Competitive Markets’, in Ippolito, Pauline M. and Scheffman, David T. (eds), Empirical Approaches to Consumer Protection Economics, Washington, DC, Federal Trade Commission, 307-372. Palfrey, Thomas R. and Romer, Thomas (1983), ‘Warranties, Performance, and the Resolution of Buyer-Seller Disputes’, 14 Bell Journal of Economics, 97-117. Priest, George L. (1981), ‘A Theory of the Consumer Product Warranty’, 90 Yale Law Journal, 1297-1352. Reprinted in Goldberg, Victor P. (ed.) (1989), Readings in the Economics of Contract Law, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 174-184. Priest, George L. (1992), ‘Can Absolute Manufacturer Liability be Defended’, 9 Yale Journal on Regulation, 237-263. Schwartz, Alan and Wilde, Louis L. (1983a), ‘Warranty Markets and Public Policy’, 1(1) Information Economics and Policy, 55-67. Schwartz, Alan and Wilde, Louis L. (1983b), ‘Imperfect Information in Markets for Contract Terms: The Examples of Warranties and Security Interests’, 69 Virginia Law Review, 1387-1485. Shapiro, C. (1982), ‘Consumer Information, Product Quality, and Seller Reputation’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 20-35. Shapiro, C. (1983), ‘Premiums for High Quality Products as Returns to Reputations’, 98 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 659-679. Shavell, Steven (1991), Acquisition and Disclosure of Information Prior to Economic Exchange, Harvard Law School Discussion Paper, No. 91. Shogren, Jason F. (1988), ‘Reducing Moral Hazard Associated with Implied Warranties of Animal Health: Comment’, 70 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 410-412. Spence, M. (1977), ‘Consumer Misperceptions, Product Failure and Producer Liability’, 44 Review of Economic Studies, 561-572. Ungern-Sternberg, T.v. (1984), ‘Marktschutz und Legaler Schutz auf Märkten mit Qualitätsunsicherheit (Consumer Protection by Legal Rules and Competition on Markets with Unknown Qualities)’, in X (ed.), Ansprüche, Eigentums- und Verfügungsrechte, Berlin, Duncker & Humblot, 725-738.
4700
Warranties
199
Wehrt, Klaus (1991), ‘Die Qualitätshaftung des Verkäufers aus ökonomischer Sicht (The Quality Liability of Sellers from an Economic Point of View)’, in Ott, Claus and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (eds), Ökonomische Probleme des Zivilrechts, Berlin, Springer, 235-259. Wehrt, Klaus (1995a), ‘Strategic Behaviour, Defective Products and Subsequent Performance’, in Bouckaert, Boudewijn and De Geest, Gerrit (eds), Essays in Law and Economics II: Contract Law, Regulation, and Reflections on Law and Economics, Antwerpen, Maklu, 35-69. Wehrt, Klaus (1995b), Ökonomische Analyse der Gewährleistungs für Sachmängel, Hamburg, habilitation theses. Welling, L.A. (1989), ‘Satisfaction Guaranteed or Money (Partially) Refunded: Efficient Refunds under Asymmetric Information’, 22 Canadian Journal of Economics, 62-78. Welling, L.A. (1991), ‘ A Theory of Voluntary Recalls and Product Liability’, 57 Southern Economic Journal, 1092-1111. Whitford, William C. (1982), ‘Comment (on a Theory of the Consumer Product Warranty)’, 91 Yale Law Journal, 1371-1385.
Other References Darby, M. and Karny, E. (1973), ‘Free Competition and the Optimal Amount of Fraud’, 16 Journal of Law and Economics, 67-88. Kihlstrom and Riordan (1984), ‘Advertising as a Signal’, 92 Journal of Political Economy, 427-450. Milgrom, P. and Roberts, J. (1986), ‘Price and Advertising Signals of Product Quality’, 94 Journal of Political Economy, 796-821. Nelson (1974), ‘Advertising as Information’, 82 Journal of Political Economy, 729-754. Rothschild, M. and Stiglitz, J.E. (1976), ‘Equilibrium in Competitive Insurance Markets: An Essay in the Economics of Imperfect Information’, 90 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 629-649. Schmalensee (1978), ‘A Model of Advertising and Product Quality’, 86 Journal of Political Economy, 485-503. Spence, M. (1973), ‘Job Market Signalling’, 87 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 355-374. Spence, M. (1975), ‘Monopoly, Quality and Regulation’, 6 Bell Journal of Economics, 417-429. Wilson, C. (1977), ‘A Model of Insurance Markets with Incomplete Information’, 16 Journal of Economic Theory, 167-207.
4800 RIGHTS AND OBLIGATIONS OF THIRD PARTIES Aristides N. Hatzis University of Chicago Law School © Copyright 1999 Aristides N. Hatzis
Abstract Three different issues, related to third-party involvement in a contractual relationship, are examined. The first two (assignment of contractual rights/delegation of contractual duties and third-party beneficiary contracts) are examined in a unified way. After pointing to the striking similarity between beneficiary and assignment contracts, we discuss the non-simultaneous assent argument, the danger of creating open classes of beneficiaries without the intention of the contracting parties, and other problems. In a second part, we deal with the controversial issue of efficient breach due to inducement by a third party. After reviewing the literature, we briefly consider the use of liquidated damages as an instrument that is better-suited than a tort for the protection of the subjective valuation and the risk aversion of the promisee. JEL classification: K12 Keywords: Privity, Third Party Beneficiary, Assignment, Delegation, Open and Closed Classes, Inducement to Breach, Efficient Breach, Full Compensation Principle
1. Preface The ‘two-parties bargaining’ dimension of contract is so prominent that some tend to perceive it as a sine qua non condition of a contract, as part and parcel of its very definition and as a unique characteristic which differentiates it from other areas of the law, such as tort. The bargaining model is prevalent in common law countries and quite influential in many civil law countries. Thus, it is no coincidence that the entanglement of third parties in contracts concluded by two other persons is theoretically considered an ‘anomaly’ - an exception to the rule, a problem that is difficult for a theory to accommodate without adulterating itself. We will deal with three different problems concerning third parties involvement in a contract. The first two, ‘third-party beneficiaries’ and ‘assignment-of-rights/delegation-of-duties’, are well -known to contract scholars. Even though they are seemingly two separate themes and are often treated dissimilarly, they revolve around the same issue: the assumption by a 200
4800
Rights and Obligations of Third Parties
201
third person who is not a participant to the contract of the rights (third-party beneficiary, assignment) or duties (delegation) of one of the contracting parties. We contend that the key to the question of the third party’s role in a contract is, first of all, approaching the problem in a unified way. In the second part of this chapter, we will discuss another problem (in the literal sense), namely the inducement to breach by a third party. This is not a topic that distinctly falls within contract law, since the inducement is tortified in many jurisdictions. However, it leans heavily on contract law and especially on a sacrosanct subject for law and economics scholars: efficient breach.
A. The Transfer of Rights and Duties to a Third Party 2. Introduction In a contractual relation, the basic question concerning third parties is whether or not it is desirable for the law to facilitate and enforce the substitution of either party by a third person, not a party to the original contract. Several theories have provided us with answers to the above question, although these answers are often contradictory with each other. The will theory, championing the enforcement of the will of the parties, acquiesces to any transfer provided that the latter is the goal of both parties (however see Fried, 1981, pp. 44-45, but also Collins, 1993, pp. 287-288). The bargain theory, by contrast, especially in its strictest form that includes a hard-bitten ‘privity’ doctrine (Collins, 1993, pp. 283-300) could create insurmountable obstacles by refusing to acknowledge any rights to a third person who is a beneficiary of a contract for which he has not offered consideration, that is quid pro quo (see generally Atiyah, 1995, pp. 355-394). Economic theory is usually closer to the will theory (Kronman and Posner, 1979, p. 5) and this is also true for the problem of third parties. Thus, the question of the desirability of third parties involvement has puzzled legal theory and practice, in both civil and common law countries, for a reason that does not seem obvious today: even though the law's enforcement of this transfer was an indispensable condition for the unbridled functioning of a modern market economy (Fuller and Eisenberg, 1990, pp. 795-796, 819-824), legal scholars and judges proved extremely reluctant to follow society and economy. According to Calamari and Perillo (1987, p. 724), ‘[t]he history of the law of assignments is an interesting illustration of the struggle between commercial needs and the tenacity of legal conceptualism’ (see also Simpson, 1975, pp. 475-485; Farnsworth, 1990, pp.744-748; Fuller and Eisenberg, 1990, Appendix E; Karsten, 1991; Eisenberg, 1992, pp. 1360-1374; Nicholas, 1992, pp.182-187).
202
Rights and Obligations of Third Parties
4800
After the developments in the financial sector of the economy, the transfer of money, and entitlements in general, assumed an unprecedented variety of different forms (Dupré, 1981); as a result, the needs for overcoming the privity requirement became pressing. But even then, courts in some jurisdictions were reluctant to recognize the rights of third parties in many respects (Speidel, 1987). A classic example is English courts which, even today, do not recognize the rights of third party beneficiaries (see Atiyah, 1995, pp. 360-362, 364-365, 367-369; Collins, 1993, pp. 284-285). By contrast, the United States was the first common law country to recognize these rights as early as 1859 (Lawrence v. Fox, 20 N.Y. 268 (1859), see also Hoeflich and Perelmuter, 1988).
3. The Economic Approach The economic rationale underlying the enforcement of a clause for the benefit of a third party by the beneficiary resembles the one used by economists to justify the existence of contract law, but also freedom of contracts in general. The economic role of contract law is to facilitate transactions, to help parties realize their goals (thus creating value through exchange) and to encourage rational planning by the parties (Eisenberg, 1992, p.1374). An economic theory of contract law should construct legal rules which will accommodate rather than interfere with existing business practices (Hay, Shleifer and Vishny, 1996). The role of contract law is, therefore, initially to enforce people's promises, since these promises are by default value-enhancing (and utility-enhancing), that is to maximize the wellbeing of the members of society. Consequently, if the will of the parties is to confer benefits to a party outside the contract, this must be satisfied by being enforced by law. As Stephen (1988, p. 157) put it, ‘contract law can be seen as ensuring that the optimal number of contracts is entered into’ (see also Kronman and Posner, 1979, pp. 1-2; Cooter and Ulen, 1988, pp. 226-227). Any approach to the problem, other than the legal enforcement of third party rights, would lead to insuperable problems of opportunism, and consequently to inefficiency (Goetz and Scott, 1980). There is no apparent reason for the courts to create legal rules that hinder the will of the parties, as long as there is no market failure. In fact, there is a specific business practice, the ‘objectification’ of the promise, that is increasingly becoming a kind of intangible property (Waters, 1985, p. 1189; Farnsworth, 1990, p. 745), which must be transferable ‘[O]wnership without the privilege of transferability is only a limited form of ownership’ (Goetz, 1984, p. 38). The only issue which needs special consideration is finding a way to detect the true will of the parties. Especially in a contract for the benefit of a third party, it is essential to discover if the parties did or did not want the beneficiary to obtain a direct right. But this is a general problem in contract formation.
4800
Rights and Obligations of Third Parties
203
Another problem is the transferability to a third party of the rights and duties created in a contract, without the explicit or the implicit consent of the promisor. Before we proceed to a more detailed discussion of the aforementioned problems in the light of an economic perspective, we should take a closer look at the relationship between the two ‘different’ procedures for the transfer of contractual rights.
4. The Paradox of the Transfer of Rights In most textbooks, the issues of third party beneficiaries and ‘assignment and delegation’ are independently discussed. However, we cannot help but notice the striking similarity between the two (Calamari and Perillo, 1987, p. 723; Roszkowski, 1989, pp. 289-307; Tsai, 1985). The clauses of the contract which establish a third party as a beneficiary often have similar economic effects with the clauses of an assignment contract that transfers the rights arising from a contract to a third person, with no synchronous delegation of the duties (if they exist). The only difference is that in the first case we have an ex ante transfer of rights and in the second case an ex post transfer with a second contract (often regulated by different rules). It is apparent that the existence of two different ways of transferring contractual rights are due to the desire of the parties to economize on transaction costs (see, for example, the example used by McGaha, 1985, pp. 797) to illustrate the basic format of a third-party-beneficiary contract]. A contract which confers rights to a third party is economizing on transaction costs by reducing the number of deeds necessary for the transfer of these rights from the promisee to the third party. At the same time, it creates a greater sense of security for the third party whose claim against the promisor may not be attacked as non-assignable. Thus, with a third-party beneficiary clause, there is no need for an additional assignment contract. The third party may obtain the rights of the assignee without the extra transaction costs. Evidently, this is only possible when all information is available before the contract for the benefit of the third party is concluded, and the promisor expressly agrees to the substitution. The ex ante agreement of the promisor is an indication that the transaction is efficient and that the relations among the three parties are well-functioning. It is obvious that the unenforceability of third-party clauses in a given legal order seems rather anomalous (Atiyah, 1995, p. 359) when it is accompanied by the enforcement of assignment contracts. This anomaly results in making more costly, with no apparent reason or benefit, the transfer of contractual rights to a third party (since an assignment contract will be the only alternative). The differentiated treatment of the two issues seems pointless if we view the third-party beneficiary contract as a type of cost-reducing assignment
204
Rights and Obligations of Third Parties
4800
contract (in some jurisdictions, for example Louisiana, assumptions of obligations were often considered as third-party-beneficiary contracts, see Tsai, 1985, p. 819). The only essential difference between the two is that in the ex-ante transfer for the benefit of a third party, the promisee has the privilege of in-advance information in relation to his duties towards third parties. He knows that he should ‘transfer’ the rights of the contract to a third person (it does not make a difference if this transfer is necessary for the payment of a debt or for a gift) and he prefers to make a contract for the benefit of this third party directly. He thus frees himself from the extra costs of a separate performance or of a new contract for the assignment of rights. He also minimizes the danger of opportunistic behavior on the part of the promisor. At the same time, he maintains control of the tripartite relationship and reserves the right to revoke the transfer before the establishment of rights. The promisor is also better off when a third party clause is available and preferred by the promisee. This is so because the promisor can control the assignment of rights (that is his duties) to a third person, unknown to him. The fact that he has concluded the contract with the promisor demonstrates that he doesn't have any problem with the transfer (or that he has been compensated enough to accommodate it). The third party is also better off, since he economizes on transaction costs (there is no need for an assignment contract) and always has the option of accepting or refusing performance by the promisor. Additionally, in a number of jurisdictions, he can free himself from opportunistic objections by the promisor to an assignment contract (such as the objection of the non-assignability of the contract).
5. De Geest’s Non-Simultaneity Argument The issues that arise from the substitution of either one of the parties by a third person have not yet attracted the interest of economists. The only significant attempt to treat these problems from an economic perspective is Gerrit De Geest’s (1995) ambitious effort (also see De Geest, 1994, ch. 5). De Geest treats the transfer of rights to a third party as a problem of contract formation by ‘non-simultaneous assent’. According to De Geest, in some cases it is efficient to permit non-simultaneous assent since a requirement of simultaneity in all cases could lead to additional transaction costs and problems of opportunism. Non-simultaneity implies that the assent of the first party is ‘frozen’ or ‘fixed’ for a specific time period. Thus, in the case of a third-party beneficiary clause in a contract, another contract is implicitly concluded after the acceptance of the benefit by the third party. The promisor of the original contract assents to
4800
Rights and Obligations of Third Parties
205
the transfer of rights to the third party (a kind of ‘offer’ for the implicit contract) and the third party’s acceptance to become a beneficiary (even after many years, as in life insurance contracts) is the necessary requirement for the formation of the new contract (De Geest, 1995, p. 11). Additionally, in any other type of contract, the promisor declares that he is willing to perform in the hands of a third party in case of a later assignment (given that a default contract rule allows for the assignment of contractual rights). De Geest’s theory is similar to the ‘theory of offer’ that developed in France in the middle of the nineteenth century and was soon abandoned because of doctrinal and practical difficulties (Nicholas, 1992, p. 188; Fried, 1981, p. 45). His main target is opportunism created by the temporal element which is an essential part of the definition of contract (Kronman and Posner, 1979, p. 3; De Geest, 1995, pp.18-19). The construct of De Geest is an interesting and quite useful attempt to objectify contract law (and consent) by remaining inside its boundaries. Even though De Geest’s idea of a ‘frozen’ assent is engaging (see however Fuller and Eisenberg, 1990, p. 745), I do not see any reason for labeling the acceptance of a ‘frozen’ (by law) assent as a contract - not only because there was no bargaining and meeting of the minds, but also because this legal fiction could create many other problems, when it is treated as just another contract. For example, what is the role of the promisee in this relation (for example, De Geest, 1995, pp. 19-20) and especially, what is the import of the relation between promisor and promisee? Whose intent should prevail? How should we acknowledge the contract defenses of the promisor against the third party based on the promisor-promisee relation? Or shouldn’t we? The problematic nature of the non-simultaneous assent, however, is underscored by the impasse that it could create when the two original contracting parties wish to modify their contract, especially given the differences in the nature of third party involvement (donee or creditor beneficiary) in the contract (Summers, 1982, p.885-886). The problem with De Geest’s construct is its effort to stretch the notion of contract beyond its connotation in business life. This stretching is more than apparent in the treatment of assignment. According to De Geest, the promisor, when signing the original contract, ‘declared that he was willing to perform in the hands of a third party, in case of a (later) assignment’ (De Geest, 1995, p. 11). It is quite difficult to imagine such an intention in most contracts, with the exception of certain special transactions and cases where there is use of commercial paper. Even when there is an acceptance of the probability of assignment, even then, this acceptance is far from being an ‘offer’ for the creation of a new contract. The problem is more apparent in delegation cases, where (in De Geest’s opinion, 1995, p. 21) ‘there should be no regulation which forbids the clause according to which the debtor can assign contractual obligations without the (ex post) assent of the creditor’.
206
Rights and Obligations of Third Parties
4800
De Geest’s approach calls to mind the phenomenon of the expansion of contractual liability during the nineteenth century, when an endeavor of common law judges and theorists to characterize a number of varying and different obligations as deriving from fictitious (Ott, 1995, p. 30) implicit contracts, failed (Gilmore, 1974). This reasoning is followed by De Geest, especially when he declares: ‘From an economic point of view, an accepted testament is a contract’ (De Geest, 1995, pp. 11, 20). Having discussed the economic role of third party beneficiaries, assignment and delegation contracts, we note that there are several issues that require further clarification, like the conditions under which the transfer of rights is enforceable by the courts, and the nature and extent of the rights and duties of the three parties involved. Space constraints limit going into all these problems analytically, but we will touch upon those that are important for the well-functioning of the mechanism of substitutability in a relation of obligation.
6. Assignment and Delegation A fundamental question relating to the assignment of contractual rights is the extent of the promisee’s power to assign his rights. Should there be limits to this power of the assignee? Should the law associate the validity of the assignment with the promisor’s assent? There is general consensus that the promisor’s state of mind should not affect the validity of the assignment. However, all jurisdictions have established conditions on the power of the promisee to transfer his rights. These conditions range from typical requirements (like a simple notice from the promisee to the promisor) to more substantive guarantees of the non-material change in the promisor’s duties. For example, in American contract law the assignment should not materially increase the burden of performance or the risk imposed by the contract, should not impair the promisor’s likelihood to obtain the return performance in the case of bilateral contracts and should not reduce the value of this performance to the promisor (UCC §2-210(2), Restatement (Second) of Contracts §317(2)). There is no doubt that these conditions have been established in order to safeguard freedom of contract (and freedom not to contract) of the parties, as well as economic efficiency. Nevertheless, they require further elaboration, from an economic point of view: i. The problem of the promisor’s assent. Theoretically, the promisor’s assent to the transfer of contractual rights should best guarantee the efficiency of the transfer, since an ‘assent requirement’ would be closer to the principle of freedom of contracts (see generally Epstein, 1975, pp. 431-432). But in practice
4800
Rights and Obligations of Third Parties
207
this is not desirable, since this transfer is crucial to economic life and not just an exception to the rule. The transfer of rights is so common and the need for the transferability of rights so pressing in many situations of business life, that a contrary rule (even when it is not part of jus cogens) could create many problems to the parties due to opportunism. It is more efficient for the law to allow these transfers to take place and to let the parties decide if they want to restrict them (Ott, 1995, pp. 32-33). A different rule could substantially increase transaction costs before or after the contract. ii. The problem of the material change of the promisor’s duty. From the standpoint of legal and economic certainty, a more objective standard and the courts’ scanty use of the concept of material change would enhance efficiency since, after all, there is always the possibility of a contrary agreement between the parties. As cases of material change we should consider those that can be objectively characterized as causing substantial deterioration of the promisor’s situation - a deterioration that alters the character or substantial terms of the agreement and goes against business ethics and trade usage. It goes without saying that the claims and defenses of the promisor against the assignor must also be made available against the assignee. The same problem arises in cases of delegation of contractual duties, especially those which involve contracts for personal services. Here, the concept of material change is crucial (see generally DiMatteo, 1994) and the discussion can be associated with the problem of economic rent. A classic example is employment contracts, especially the contracts of members of the entertainment industry, professional athletes, artists and other professionals (lawyers, physicians, and so on), whose expertise is the most important reason they are chosen by the other contracting party. However, a main problem in delegation cases is the liability of the delegating party. Should the delegator remain liable after the delegation? In most legal systems, the answer is positive. Otherwise, it would be very easy for a person to avoid a contractual obligation by simply delegating it (Roszkowski, 1989, p. 293; Ott, 1995, p. 33). The performance of a duty (especially when this duty is not the payment of money) usually involves personal services. In the typical contract relationship, where one party pays another a sum of money in exchange for the other’s performance, the buyer is usually the one who chooses among many sellers and prefers one over the others, for a number of advantages that are not usually delegated, especially in conditions of monopolistic competition (De Geest, 1995, p. 20). Subsequently, a rule according to which the delegator remains liable is more efficient, since the need for its modification by the parties will seldom arise. This ‘objective’, ‘per se’ approach has been criticized as applying nineteenth-century rationale to modern economic relations. According to DiMatteo (1994, p. 410), delegation should be allowed when the subjective
208
Rights and Obligations of Third Parties
4800
expectations can be satisfied even without the use of personal services, that is when the delegatee’s performance meets the expectations of the promisee or the performance of the delegatee is equivalent to the performance that would have been rendered by the promisor/delegator. Aside from these qualifications, the assignment of rights and the delegation of duties should be readily available to the parties if they so choose (the same holds for the clauses prohibiting assignment or delegation). Assignment should be less restricted given its economic role, and delegation more restrained because of the great danger of opportunism. Finally, there is one more question that needs to be considered. Should all rights and duties be transferable? This is a matter of public policy, since there is no apparent economic reason for the prohibition of the transfer of any particular right or the delegation of any particular duty. In many jurisdictions, there are various prohibitions which reflect public policies, such as the proscription of the assignment of rights against the state, the assignment of future wages, the assignment of political rights or rights that are too personal and the delegation of debts which are not subject to execution. In most of these cases, economics are (at least at first blush) irrelevant and other considerations should be weighed as more important (Allcock, 1983; Radin, 1987).
7. Third-Party Beneficiaries We have already stressed the importance of this device to economic life (Ott, 1995, p. 32) and called attention to its cost-saving function, which renders it an ancillary tool that serves the needs of the parties. If we approach the problem in this perspective, there will not be any difficulties in answering the question of the third party’s ability to enforce a contract that confers a benefit upon him. The rights of beneficiaries have been recognized in nearly all jurisdictions, with variations in the default rules and the extent of the beneficiaries’ powers. However, a host of other problems emerge after accepting the rights of the beneficiary. The most significant is the possible confusion between positive externalities and third-party rights created by a contract. A contract concluded by two parties does not create legal and economic results solely for the two parties involved. It creates, almost necessarily, effects for third parties either intentionally or accidentally. These external effects can be either positive or negative. The problem is which externalities should be regulated by law. More generally, a broader problem in economic (as well as political) theory is the definition and delineation of an externality (see Trebilcock, 1993, pp. 58-77; Parisi, 1994, pp. 216-218) and more generally (Papandreou, 1994). The law has provided its own solutions to the problems created by externalities. Negative externalities are treated mainly by property,
4800
Rights and Obligations of Third Parties
209
environmental and tort law. But what about the third-party beneficiary problem? (Collins, 1993, pp. 289-292). Is this an example of a positive externality? Holderness (1985) provided the most satisfactory answer to the problem, emphasizing that the mere definition and assignment of property rights is not sufficient. A necessary foundation for exchange is that the law assigns all rights in any resource to a closed class of clearly identifiable persons, each of whom is able to contract at any moment. A class is closed when persons can enter the class - and thus obtain the right - only by first purchasing the right from a current class member (Holderness, 1985, p. 322). The rights, therefore, must lend themselves to voluntary transfer and this is not possible when the rights are assigned to open classes (a class is open when entry to it is unrestricted). If they are, then no voluntary transactions can take place and resources are blocked from moving to higher-valued uses. Thus, a legal policy which treats a positive externality stemming from a contract as an enforceable right by a third party creates open classes, since there are at least some individuals who can enter the class and obtain usage rights, without the intention of the owner of those rights. The denial of rights to third parties, even when they rely upon the formation of a contract or benefit from its completion, in both common and civil law, should be viewed under this prism as an endeavor to maintain the closedness of the class of contracting parties (Holderness, 1985, pp. 328, 330). Otherwise, the class of rights-holders would be open and large, impairing alienability and making exchange very costly. In any case, the problems associated with the rights of a third party from a contract are not externality problems, if we define externality as an unintended consequence or, better yet, as a consequence that was not specifically intended by the contracting parties and is obviously not the result of another contract. We cannot characterize a benefit to a third party as a positive externality when this benefit was the objective of the contracting parties, even when the third party was not informed or asked about it. Assigning enforcement rights only to named beneficiaries closes the class by identifying all the class members (Holderness, 1985, p. 332). Therefore, a contract’s unintentional beneficial effect for a third party should not be the source of enforceable rights for third parties who benefit from it. The law must not recognize vested interests in this case. This is so for two reasons: (i) When the parties have no intention (that is intention by the promisee and assent by the promisor) of conferring a benefit upon a third party by means of their contract, an opposite legal rule could be an infringement of the freedom of contracts, and according to the established mainstream view in economic analysis of law, paternalistic intervention in a contract must be justified by a market failure (Cooter and Ulen, 1988, pp. 232-242).
210
Rights and Obligations of Third Parties
4800
(ii) A rule which would endow third parties with rights deriving from a contract when there is no corresponding intention of the parties, could be so inefficient as to dramatically augment transaction costs, without any benefit to society. Obviously, such an imprudent rule could destroy economic life altogether, since entry into transactions would become very costly (see Holderness, 1985, 1989; Metzger and Phillips, 1989, pp. 968-969, and more generally Posner, 1992, pp. 126-128, and the economic literature on the related issue of consequential damages). As a result, in all jurisdictions the marginal case for the creation of rights for a third party in a contract is when the beneficiary was not expressly mentioned by the parties, but it was their clear intention, manifested in the contract, to confer a legally enforceable right upon him (Summers, 1982, pp. 898-899). However, the courts or the legislators have sometimes attempted to extend these rights to cases where there is no intent to benefit third parties, but only positive externalities from government contracts (for the intended beneficiaries of public programs in which funding contracts are employed, see Adelson, 1985; Waters, 1985). But as we saw, this direction can create severe economic problems (Metzger and Phillips, 1989, p. 974). We should approach the other problems created by the third-party beneficiary contractual rights by treating them in similar fashion with assignment of contract problems. This is reasonable since we should treat the beneficiary as an assignee. For example, the principle that a person cannot avoid a contractual duty by transferring it to a third party is valid here, as in the assignment. Consequently, the promisor can employ any defenses that he has against the promisee. Another issue we should consider is the exact point in time when the rights of the beneficiary are vested. There are basically four alternatives (apparently, a contract clause that explicitly or implicitly deals with the matter, should prevail): (a) immediately after the formation of the contract which establishes someone as a beneficiary, (b) after a simple notice to the beneficiary, (c) after acceptance by the beneficiary, (d) after reliance by the beneficiary. We believe that the acceptance of rights by the beneficiary should be the point at which these rights are vested. Acceptance signifies that there is consensus among the three parties concerning the transfer of rights, that is all parties regard it as efficient. At the same time, the danger of impairing alienability by creating rights in unidentified persons is reduced (Holderness, 1985, p. 331) and even De Geest’s non-simultaneous assent is satisfied.
4800
Rights and Obligations of Third Parties
211
B. Tortious Interference in a Contractual Relationship 8. Efficient Breach and Tort Law Another problem which involves third parties and has preoccupied law and economics scholarship for many years, is ‘efficient breach’ induced by a third party. We will not get into the problem of efficient breach as such in this entry. The literature on efficient breach is perhaps the most important contribution (in terms of impact) of economic analysis to contract law (but first see Holmes, 1881, p. 301, 1897, p. 463; see also Birmingham,1970; Posner, 1992, pp.118-120, 128-129; Cooter and Ulen, 1988, pp. 289-292; Craswell, 1988; and for critiques, Macneil, 1982; Friedmann, 1989; Harrison, 1995, pp. 126-130). We will examine efficient breach as the result of a third party’s interference in a contractual relationship, an interference which takes the form of a better offer by the third party to the promisor (after all, a better deal is the essence of a competitive order). This interference has been characterized as tortious by American law and the law in many other countries. This ‘criminalization’ of the better offer by a third party has been widely disputed by lawyers and economists as creating inefficiency. The essential legal question appears to be the following: given the practical problem of calculating expectation damages, the corresponding high administrative costs and the parallel appearance of opportunism, in most situations, should we accept efficient breach or should we adhere to a theory which sanctifies promise, assent (De Geest, 1994, pp. 318-322) and/or good faith (and which, supposedly, will substantially reduce transaction and administrative costs)? The ethical dilemma which surfaces is that the two regimes can lead to quite different distributive outcomes. In an injunction regime, the new surplus will be shared by the three parties, but in a damages/efficient-breach regime the surplus will be divided between the third party and the promisor.
9. Review of the Literature The first papers that questioned the soundness of the tort of interference appeared in the early 1980s, greatly influenced by the dissemination of law and economics and efficient breach theory in particular. A tort which criminalizes the better offer, necessary for the efficient breach, would be inefficient, as far as it disrupts the process which leads to efficient breaches, discourages the optimum number of breaches and distorts incentives. As a result, in a number of arguments articulated in a series of papers, written mostly by economically-minded lawyers, the authors tried to point out the problems created by the tort of interference and to limit it (if not abolish it entirely) to a
212
Rights and Obligations of Third Parties
4800
few cases where there is another economic or public policy reason for tortious treatment of the breach. Dobbs (1980) is the first in this line of authors to acknowledge the need for the availability of efficient breach (pp. 360-363), that is impaired by tortification, but he bases his opposition on rather doctrinal and philosophical arguments (challenging the ‘property conception’ of contract rights and the relevancy of mental states). Two years later, two important papers fortified the case for limiting the tort, based entirely on economic arguments. In the first paper, Rizzo (1982), without much acknowledging the aspect of wealth maximization through the reallocation of resources to higher-valued uses (not totally unexpected from a leading ‘Austrian’), limits tort-based recovery to those cases where contracting costs are high and the relevant economic losses are concentrated on a few persons, that is essentially when the litigation costs are fewer than the expected value of recovery, making the latter socially beneficial (Rizzo, 1982, pp. 283-285). The second paper, written by Harvey Perlman, defined (and refined) the economic approach and became the point of reference for friends and foes since then. Perlman (1982, pp. 83-85), recognizing the delicate balance of a tort which essentially overrides the terms of a private relationship, tracks two different sources of inefficiency created by an unrestricted tort of interference: (a) prevention of efficient breaches and (b) augmentation of transaction, negotiation and salvage costs. He then categorizes interference cases into (a) those in which the act of interference is independently unlawful (fraud, antitrust violation, and so on) or malicious and, (b) those in which the behavior of the third party is otherwise lawful. An unlawful means test could restrict tort liability to cases of the first category. In the second category of cases, contract remedies promote efficiency which can be inhibited by a subjugation to a tort regime. However, this is essentially an abolition of a tort of interference as a self-sufficient independent base for liability (but see also Chutorian, 1986). For Perlman, if there is a problem with the current remedies and full-compensation is untenable, the tortification of breach is not the solution. Dowling (1986) notes the promisor’s counterintuitive opportunistic incentive (created by the tort) to breach inefficiently (ibid., pp. 507-508) and the throwing off balance of the delicate contract damage system produced by the ‘spectre’ of double recovery (ibid., p. 509, see also Wexler, 1994, p. 281). He expands Perlman’s limitation beyond the unlawful means test, making the conceptual distinction between interference with contract and tortious interference with business relations. For Dowling, the latter deserves stronger protection than the former. The protection of the promisee in a contractual relationship is superfluous, given his pre-existing contractual right to collect damages (ibid., pp. 514-519) (for the importance of the distinction, see also Feltham, 1988, and Gergen, 1996, pp. 1180-1181).
4800
Rights and Obligations of Third Parties
213
The problem of ‘double recovery’ is treated primarily by Landes and Posner (1987), who look upon the issue as mainly a problem of joint liability where the injured party can sue the promisor for breach of contract or, alternatively, the third party for tortious interference. The third party is the lower-cost avoider of the harm most of the times (but see Dowling, 1986, p. 508) and should be liable in cases of undercompensation of plaintiff (insolvency, litigation costs, and so on). Indeed, even though the liability of the promisor is a strict liability and that of the third party is based on negligence (which should be proved in court), a rational promisee may choose to sue the third party and get an award of punitive damages as a bonus (see the (in)famous Pennzoil Co. v. Texaco Inc. case and also Austin, 1996). BeVier (1990) reconsiders inducement, agreeing with much of the abovementioned criticism and the need for reconciliation with efficient breach. However, she defends a limited tortious liability for the protection of the creditor and his incentives to collect information and invest (reliance), especially in cases where specific performance and damages are unavailable (ibid., 1990, p. 905) or inapplicable (p. 910), that is when contract remedies under-protect contract rights. Relational contracts constitute the typical example. In such complex relations, the assumption of a perfect replication of performance is often unrealistic; additionally, the tort of interference can differentiate freeriders from those who truly value performance more than the promisee (ibid., p. 890, for similar views, see also Partlett, 1992, p. 775). Myers (1993) correctly observes that the law of tortious interference has been carried along in the tide of liability expansion in recent years in the USA, with considerably less attention given to concerns of efficiency than antitrust law (compare Lao, 1997). This conflict with now-accepted antitrust reasoning is due to the considerable doctrinal confusion of tortious interference law which leads to unfortunate results: tort law gives excessive protection to tenuous contractual relationships at the expense of competition and efficiency. Further, the availability of punitive damages may deter efficient breaches of contract, thereby heightening the doctrinal conflict. Thus, tort protection for existing contracts (from unlawful acts and especially antitrust law violations) is economically defensible, but only with the burden of proof to the plaintiff, without the availability of punitive damages and with limitation to actual damages. In antithesis to Dowling, he believes the there is no economic reason for the protection of prospective business relations. De Geest (1994), after reviewing previous work and criticizing the requirement of prior information (notice) for the liability of the third party as leading to inefficient results, classifies the cases of inducement into four different categories with various criteria (the availability of damages or specific performance, the economic situation of the debtor, and so on) and examines the alternatives that do not support an extensive use of tortious liability.
214
Rights and Obligations of Third Parties
4800
Finally, in the most unequivocal full-scale attack to the tort of interference, Wexler (1994), charges it as frustrating the underlying policies of the law of contracts and antitrust, deterring efficient breaches of contract and procompetitive conduct, and even intruding into basic individual rights (for a similar argument, that the imposition of tort liability for the mere communication of truthful information is a violation of fundamental First Amendment principles, see Tucker, 1997). Thus, it places an unnecessary burden on the legal system and commerce (for similar views, see also Grothe, 1989). Until recently, Richard Epstein had posited the most (if not the only) authoritative defense of the tort (after the attack by economists). Although many theoretical (‘corrective justice-based’) arguments against the tort of interference were grounded in an earlier much-discussed Epstein (1975) paper, Epstein (1987) himself dealt directly with the problem, supporting the soundness of tortious liability and ‘following’ the path of a former student of his (see Fine, 1983, who ‘read’ Epstein, 1975, quite differently than others and more compatibly with Epstein’s later views), finding analogies in property law. However, he bases his defense on novel ground. According to Epstein (who essentially equalizes contractual rights with property rights), ‘[t]he tort of inducement of breach of contract is best understood as an unsuspected manifestation of the problem of ostensible ownership’, and inducement is a form of taking of this property right to promisor’s performance (Epstein, 1987, p. 2 and Friedmann, 1989, pp. 20-23, who agrees; see also Epstein, 1997, pp. 51-53). Nonetheless, the third party must be liable only when he knows the preexisting contractual relationship. After a notice informing the third party of the existence of a prior contract (Epstein, 1987, pp. 24-26), the inducer should be liable in tort in order to ‘regularize business transactions among trading parties’ (Epstein, 1987, p. 41, however, see Epstein, 1985, p. 42 and Macaulay et al., 1995, vol. 2, pp. 186-187 for side-effects). Other defenders of the tort (based on philosophical/dogmatic grounds but discussing extensively economic arguments) include Gergen (1996) who uses it to bolster the argument for allowing a contract claim for breach of the duty of good faith. Recently, the doctrine of tortious interference was strongly advocated by three scholars who disputed the economic analysis based on the efficient breach theory. For Woodward (1996), the tort stands for a community’s interest in the maintenance of contracts and the relationships they embody. The supporters of efficient breach are essentially based on a quantity of unknown empirical information with the major problem of efficient breach theory being the unrealistic nature of its requirement of ‘full compensation’ principle, due to transaction costs and proof problems (Woodword, 1996, pp. 1155-1163). Lao (1997) discusses the growing use of tortious interference law in what were traditionally antitrust cases (see Myers above) and the ensuing criticism that
4800
Rights and Obligations of Third Parties
215
such use is inefficient and irreconcilable with federal antitrust policy. She supports this use employing similar arguments with Woodward. A mainstream economist, McChesney (1998), begins by questioning the usefulness of the efficient-breach model in the typical interference case. The concept of efficient breach may make sense in a two-person world when costs of performance rise ex post and the parties have not specifically allocated risk of that event ex ante, but does not in the three-party setting in which contractual interference actually occurs. In a two-party Coasean situation (and as long as there can be recontracting once costs change) the result is the same, regardless of the initial allocation of property rights (ignoring wealth effects). However, initial allocation is important when subsequent transaction costs effectively prevent recontracting. Moreover, in a three-party tortious interference case, the situation is quite different. The breach deprives the promisee not only of the ‘use value’ of the performance, but also of its ‘exchange value’. The issue thus comes down to the question of who owns or should own the increased exchange value. McChesney points to the promisee, since expectation damages are difficult to calculate and this difficulty dramatically increases litigation costs, not to mention the additional negotiation costs (see contra Posner, 1992, p. 119). Thus, efficient breach entails two sets of transaction costs (negotiation and litigation costs) and tortious interference involves only one (negotiation costs). A liability rule would be similar to reverting to the efficient breach model and thus the default option for asset protection should be a property rule, that is a mandatory rule of promisee ownership of promisor’s performance. And that is exactly what the tort of interference does. McChesney’s endeavor has many problems, the most important among them being the rigidity of the tort (that is of a property rule) itself. However, his paper offers the best case against efficient breach and for the tort of inducement, based principally on the increase of litigation costs and the difficulty in measuring expectation damages. The problem boils down to statistical evidence, which McChesney offers at a preliminary stage.
10. Efficient Breach with a Simultaneous Protection of Idiosyncratic Values Efficient breach is a peculiar transfer. Here the promisor ‘transfers’ his promise from the promisee to the third party, without the acceptance of the former, because the third party has offered a better deal. This transfer seems unorthodox. The promise, after the formation of contract, has been transformed into a kind of property and no longer belongs to the promisor. However, if we embrace Holme’s intuition that this property can have an exact monetary equivalent, that is a user value (even a purely subjective value), then we can
216
Rights and Obligations of Third Parties
4800
condone such a transfer. We can then say that the new property is an entitlement to the monetary equivalent of the promisee’s expectations (user value) or his subjective valuation of the promisor’s promise. There is no reason for the enactment of a rigid mandatory rule for the protection of the promisee, since the manipulation of the remedies by the judges could prove more useful. Judges can discern the cases where administrative costs are high and order specific performance instead of damages (Kronman, 1978). When the administrative costs are low, they can order expectation damages. Thus, the dangers of unfairness and perhaps inefficiency which an ‘efficient breach’ regime could induce, can be mitigated in every particular case by the judge’s discretionary power to award damages or specific performance (and by letting the Coase theorem do the work, automatically taking into account the promisee’s expectations-subjective value). Promisees can always ask for penal clauses or high liquidated damages, reflecting their subjective valuation of the contract or their risk aversion. Those who are risk averse or value performance higher than its market price can insure themselves or can ask for either a penal or a ‘liquidated damages’ clause to be included in the contract (for the pattern of incentives that can be created in a legal system with ‘free efficient breach’ and enforcement of penal clauses, inferences can be drawn from Ayres and Gertner, 1989 and 1992; but see contra Schwartz, 1996, p. 37). This way, the promisee who has concluded an ordinary contract in a competitive market would be protected less than the one who struck a deal that he considers unique for personal reasons (see also BeVier, 1990, p. 898). In a seminal paper, Goetz and Scott (1977) emphasized the proof problems inherent in fully recovering idiosyncratic values. These problems prevent the non-breaching party from recovering his subjective expectations, if recovery is limited to legally determined ‘objective’ remedies. Accordingly, efficiency will be enhanced, under many circumstances, by the enforcement of liquidated damage clauses that represent the most efficient means by which parties can insure against the otherwise non-compensable consequences of breach (Goetz and Scott, 1977, pp. 557-558). These clauses prohibit breaches that are not efficient, since their presence usually signifies a difference between market price and subjective value (a spacious consumer surplus). Even in cases where the penalty clause was redundant, purely gambling, or opportunistic, the Coase theorem is at work and should lead to the same result that specific performance would lead to (Hatzis, 1997, p. 15, 1998, ch. 5). To ‘criminalize’ this anomalous transfer by punishing the third party through tort law is very often a mistake. The fear of punishment and tort liability can stop many efficient transactions, not because the promisee is actually hurt but because of opportunism and strategic behavior. This does not
4800
Rights and Obligations of Third Parties
217
signify that in some extreme cases certain actions should not be characterized as torts, since their basic purpose is to willfully damage the promisee (as in the case of the ‘paulian claim’, that is defraud of creditors). But this tort liability is actually based on behavior that should be in any case punished as unfair (or extremely inefficient). The essence of the free market is competition and this includes offering someone a better deal. The criminalization of competition can bring about only distorted effects, since the incentives to search would be diminished and the outcome cannot be Pareto optimal. Contract is a mechanism devised for better allocating resources. If this allocation can be improved with the non-performance of a contract and without injury to anyone, that is if there is a way (with no damage to contract stability) to a Pareto improvement, then the purposes of contract law have been served.
11. Conclusion Rigid legal doctrines and philosophies have created many problems to the third parties involved in contractual relations. The privity requirement can be economically explained as the law’s attempt to assign the rights of any resource to a closed class of clearly identifiable individuals. However, the non-enforcement of third-party beneficiary clauses has rather been the result of dogmatic adherence to a principle without the parallel reconsideration of its economic rationale, thus augmenting opportunism. The simultaneous enforcement of assignment contracts has created an anomaly in the relation between the third parties, augmenting transaction costs. The same can be said for the tortification of efficient breach. Based more on the theory of ‘sanctity of contract’ rather than on an economic rationale, it frustrates the most important process in a free market, namely competition. The issues discussed here have once again demonstrated the need for a coherent and scientific theory of contract law, grounded in economic science and business practice.
Acknowledgements I wish to thank Gerrit De Geest, Fred McChesney, Aspasia Tsaoussis-Hatzis and an anonymous referee for their help.
218
Rights and Obligations of Third Parties
4800
Bibliography on Rights and Obligations of Third Parties (4800) BeVier, Lillian R. (1990), ‘Reconsidering Inducement’, 76 Virginia Law Review, 877-936. Birmingham, Robert L. (1970), ‘Breach of Contract, Damage Measures, and Economic Efficiency’, 24 Rutgers Law Review, 273-292. Chutorian, Sandra (1986), ‘Note. Tort Remedies for Breach of Contract: The Expansion of Tortious Breach of the Implied Covenant of Good Faith and Fair Dealing into the Commercial Realm’, 86 Columbia Law Review, 377-406. Craswell, Richard (1988), ‘Contract Remedies, Renegotiation, and the Theory of Efficient Breach’, 61 Southern California Law Review, 629-670. De Geest, Gerrit (1995), ‘Contracting by Way of Non-Simultaneous Assent: An Economic Analysis of Irrevocable Offers, Clauses for the Benefit of a Third Party, Assignments and Testaments’, in Bouckaert, Boudewijn and De Geest, Gerrit (eds), Essays in Law and Economics, vol. 2, Antwerpen, Maklu, 9-27. DiMatteo, Larry A. (1994), ‘Depersonalization of Personal Service Contracts: The Search for a Modern Approach to Assignability’, 27 Akron Law Review, 407-443. Dobbs, Dan B. (1980), ‘Tortious Interference with Contractual Relationships’, 34 Arkansas Law Review, 335-376. Dowling, Donald C., Jr (1986), ‘A Contract Theory for a Complex Tort: Limiting Interference with Contract Beyond the Unlawful Means Test’, 40 University of Miami Law Review, 487-519. Dupré, James Thornton (1981), ‘Note. “Privity” - The Latest Victim of Jurisprudential Economics’, 6 Oklahoma City University Law Review, 67-74. Epstein, Richard A. (1985), ‘The Pirates of Pennzoil’, 9(6) Regulation, 18-24, 42. Epstein, Richard A. (1987), ‘Inducement of Breach of Contract as a Problem of Ostensible Ownership’, 16 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-41. Fine, Benjamin L. (1983), ‘Comment. An Analysis of the Formation of Property Rights Underlying Tortious Interference with Contracts and Other Economic Relations’, 50 University of Chicago Law Review, 1116-1145. Friedmann, Daniel (1989), ‘The Efficient Breach Fallacy’, 18 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-24. Gergen, Mark P. (1996), ‘Tortious Interference: How it is Engulfing Commercial Law, why this is not Entirely Bad, and a Prudential Response’, 38 Arizona Law Review, 1175-1232. Goetz, Charles J. and Scott, Robert E. (1977), ‘Liquidated Damages, Penalties, and the Just Compensation Principle: Some Notes on an Enforcement Model and a Theory of Efficient Breach’, 77 Columbia Law Review, 554-594. Grothe, Gina M. (1989), ‘Note. Interference with Contract in the Competitive Marketplace’, 15 William Mitchell Law Review, 453-474. Holderness, Clifford G. (1985), ‘A Legal Foundation for Exchange’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 321-344. Holderness, Clifford G. (1989), ‘The Assignment of Rights, Entry Effects, and the Allocation of Resources’, 18 Journal of Legal Studies, 181-189. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1980), ‘Joint and Multiple Tortfeasors: An Economic Analysis’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 517-555. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1987), The Economic Structure of Tort Law, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.
4800
Rights and Obligations of Third Parties
219
Lao, Marina (1997), ‘Tortious Interference and the Federal Antitrust Law of Vertical Restraints’, 83 Iowa Law Review, 35-77. Macneil, Ian R. (1982), ‘Efficient Breach of Contract: Circles in the Sky’, 68 Virginia Law Review, 947-969. McChesney, Fred S. (1998), ‘Tortious Interference with Contract Versus “Efficient” Breach: Theory and Empirical Evidence’, (unpublished manuscript). Myers, Gary (1993), ‘The Differing Treatment of Efficiency and Competition in Antitrust and Tortious Interference Law’, 77 Minnesota Law Review, 1097-1152. Ott, Claus (1995), ‘Comment: Contracting by Way of Non-Simultaneous Assent in the German Civil Code’, in Bouckaert, Boudewijn and De Geest, Gerrit (eds), Essays in Law and Economics, vol. 2, Antwerpen, Maklu, 29-34. Perlman, Harvey S. (1982), ‘Interference with Contract and Other Economic Expectancies: A Clash of Tort and Contract Doctrine’, 49 University of Chicago Law Review, 61-129. Rizzo, Mario J. (1982), ‘A Theory of Economic Loss in the Law of Torts’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 281-310. Sales, James B. (1991), ‘The Tort of Interference with Contract: An Argument for Requiring a “Valid Existing Contract” to Restrain the Use of Tort Law in Circumventing Contract Law Remedies’, 22 Texas Tech Law Review, 123-156. Speidel, Richard E. (1987), ‘Warranty Theory, Economic Loss, and the Privity Requirement: Once More into the Void’, 67 Boston University Law Review, 9-58. Wexler, Gary D. (1994), ‘Note. Intentional Interference with Contract: Market Efficiency and Individual Liberty Considerations’, 27 Connecticut Law Review, 279-328. Woodward, William J., Jr (1996), ‘Contractarians, Community, and the Tort of Interference with Contract’, 80 Minnesota Law Review, 1103-1182.
Other References Adelson, Robert S. (1985), ‘Note. Third Party Beneficiary and Implied Right of Action Analysis: The Fiction of One Governmental Intent’, 94 Yale Law Journal, 875-894. Allcock, Bob (1983), ‘Restrictions on the Assignment of Contractual Rights’, 42 Cambridge Law Journal, 328-346. Atiyah, P.S. (1995), An Introduction to the Law of Contract, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 5th edn. Austin, Mike (1996), ‘Man Wins $8 Million Verdict on Tortious Interference Claim’, Chicago Daily Law Bulletin, Oct. 23, 1996, 3 ff. Ayres, Ian and Gertner, Robert (1989), ‘Filling Gaps in Incomplete Contracts: An Economic Theory of Default Rules’, 99 Yale Law Journal, 87-130. Ayres, Ian and Gertner, Robert (1992), ‘Strategic Contractual Inefficiency and the Optimal Choice of Legal Rules’, 101 Yale Law Journal, 729-773. Beatson, Jack (1992), ‘Reforming the Law of Contracts for the Benefits of Third Parties: A Second Bite at the Cherry’, 45 Current Legal Problems, 1-28. Calamari, John D.and Perillo, Joseph M. (1987), The Law of Contracts, St. Paul, MN, West Publishing Co., 3rd edn. Collins, Hugh (1993), The Law of Contract, London, Butterworths, 2nd edn. Cooter, Robert D. and Ulen, Thomas (1988), Law and Economics, New York, HarperCollins Publishers.
220
Rights and Obligations of Third Parties
4800
Corbin, Arthur (1930), ‘Contracts for the Benefit of Third Persons’, 46 Law Quarterly Review, 12. Danforth, John (1981), ‘Note. Tortious Interference with Contract: A Reassertion of Society’s Interest in Commercial Stability and Contractual Integrity’, 81 Columbia Law Review, 1491-1524. De Geest, Gerrit (1994), Economische Analyse van het Contracten-en Quasi-Contractenrecht. Een Onderzoek naar de Wetenschappelijke Waarde van de Rechtseconomie, Antwerpen, Maklu. Eisenberg, Melvin Aron (1992), ‘Third-party Beneficiaries’, 92 Columbia Law Review, 1358-1430. Epstein, Richard A. (1975), ‘Intentional Harms’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 391-442. Epstein, Richard A. (1997), ‘Contracts Small and Contracts Large: Contract Law through the Lens of Laissez-Faire’, John M. Olin Program in Law and Economics, Working Paper No. 49 (2nd series), University of Chicago Law School. Farnsworth, E. Allan (1990), Contracts, Boston, Little, Brown & Co., 2nd edn. Feltham, Timothy S. (1988), ‘Note. Tortious Interference with Contractual Relations: The Texaco Inc. v. Pennzoil Co. Litigation’, 33 New York Law School Law Review, 111-144. Fried, Charles (1981), Contract as Promise: A Theory of Contractual Obligation, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Fuller, Lon L. and Eisenberg, Melvin Aron (1990), Basic Contract Law, St. Paul, MN, West Publishing Co., 5th edn. Gilmore, Grant (1974), The Death of Contract, Columbus, OH, Ohio State University Press. Goetz, Charles J. (1984), Cases and Materials on Law and Economics, St. Paul, MN, West Publishing Co. Goetz, Charles J. and Scott, Robert E. (1980), ‘Enforcing Promises: An Examination of the Basis of Contract’, 89 Yale Law Journal, 1261-1322. Harrison, Jeffrey L. (1995), Law and Economics in a Nutshell, St. Paul, MN, West Publishing Co. Hatzis, Aristides N. (1997), ‘The Absence of Theory: Common vs. Civil Contract Law’, paper presented at the XIVth Annual Conference of the European Association of Law and Economics, held at Barcelona, September 4-6, 1997. Hatzis, Aristides N. (1998), An Economic Theory of Greek Contract Law, Ph.D. Thesis, Chicago, University of Chicago Law School. Hay, Jonathan R., Shleifer, Andrew and Vishny, Robert W. (1996), ‘Toward a Theory of Legal Reform’, 40 European Economic Review, 559-567. Hoeflich, M.H. and Perelmuter, E. (1988), ‘The Anatomy of a Leading Case: Lawrence v. Fox in the Courts, the Casebooks, and the Commentaries’, 21 University of Michigan Journal of Law Reform, 721-744. Holmes, Oliver Wendell, Jr (1881), The Common Law, New York, Dover Publications (repr. 1991). Holmes, Oliver Wendell, Jr (1897), ‘The Path of the Law’, 10 Harvard Law Review, 457-478. Karsten, Peter (1991), ‘The Discovery of Law by English and American Jurists of the Seventeenth, Eighteenth, and Nineteenth Centuries: Third-Party Beneficiary Contracts as a Test Case’, 9 Law and History Review, 327-381. Kessler, Friedrich, Gilmore, Grant and Kronman, Anthony T. (1986), Contracts: Cases and Materials, Boston, Little, Brown & Co., 3rd edn.
4800
Rights and Obligations of Third Parties
221
Kortman, Bas and Faber, Dennis (1994), ‘Contract and Third Parties’, in Hartkamp, A.S., Hesselink, M.W., Hondius, E.H., du Perron, C.E. and Vranken, J.B.M. (eds), Towards a European Civil Code, Nijmegen-Dordrecht, Ars Aequi Libri & Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 237-265. Kronman, Anthony T. (1978), ‘Specific Performance’, 45 University of Chicago Law Review, 351-382. Kronman, Anthony T. and Posner, Richard A. (1979), The Economics of Contract Law, Boston, Little, Brown & Co. Macaulay, Stewart, Kidwell, John, Whitford, William and Galanter, Marc (1995), Contracts: Law in Action, Charlottesville, VA, Michie Co., 2 vols. McGaha, Fred (1985), ‘Note. Third-Party Beneficiary Contracts’, 45 Louisiana Law Review, 797-810. Metzger, Michael B. and Phillips, Michael J. (1989), ‘Promissory Estoppel and Third Parties’, 42 Southwestern Law Journal, 931-974. Murray, John Edward , Jr (1991), Contracts: Cases and Materials, Charlottesville, VA, Michie Co., 4th edn. Nicholas, Barry (1992), The French Law of Contract, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 2nd edn. Palmer, Vernon V. (1989), ‘The History of Privity: The Formative Period (1500-1680)’, 33 American Journal of Legal History, 3-52. Papandreou, Andreas A. (1994), Externality and Institutions, Oxford, Clarendon Press. Parisi, Francesco (1994), ‘Autonomy and Private Ordering in Contract Law’, 1 European Journal of Law and Economics, 213-227. Partlett, David F. (1992), ‘From Victorian Opera to Rock and Rap: Inducement to Breach of Contract in the Music Industry’, 66 Tulane Law Review, 771-835. Posner, Richard A. (1992), Economic Analysis of Law, Boston, Little, Brown & Co., 4th edn. Radin, Margaret J. (1987), ‘Market-Inalienability’, 100 Harvard Law Review, 1849-1937. Roszkowski, Mark E. (1989), Business Law: Principles, Cases, and Policy, Glenview, IL, Scott, Foresman & Co., 2nd edn. Schwartz, Alan (1996), ‘The Law and Economics Approach to Contract Theory’, Working Paper, Yale Law School. Simpson, A.W.B. (1975), A History of the Common Law of Contract, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Stephen, Frank H. (1988), The Economics of the Law, Ames, IA, Iowa State University Press. Summers, David M. (1982), ‘Note: Third Party Beneficiaries and the Restatement (Second) of Contracts’, 67 Cornell Law Review, 880-899. Swan, John (1991), ‘Privity of Contract and Third Party Beneficiaries: The Selective Use of Precedent’, 4 Journal of Contract Law, 129-134. Trebilcock, Michael J. (1993), The Limits of Freedom of Contract, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Tsai, John (1985), ‘Note. Assumption of Obligations: Third Party No More’, 45 Louisiana Law Review, 819-829. Tucker, Robert L. (1997), ‘“And the Truth Shall Make You Free”: Truth as a First Amendment Defense in Tortious Interference with Contract Case’, 24 Hastings Constitutional Law Quarterly, 709-739.
222
Rights and Obligations of Third Parties
4800
Waddams, S.M. (1981), ‘Third party beneficiaries in the Supreme Court of Canada’, 59 Canadian Bar Review, 549-556. Waters, Anthony Jon (1985), ‘The Property in the Promise: A Study of the Third Party Beneficiary Rule’, 98 Harvard Law Review, 1109-1210. Wheeler, S. and Shaw, J. (1994), Contract Law: Cases, Materials and Commentary, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Whincup, Michael H. (1992), Contract Law and Practice: The English System and Continental Comparisons, Deventer, Kluwer Law & Taxation Publishers, 2nd edn.
5000 GENERAL THEORIES OF REGULATION Johan den Hertog Economic Institute/ CLAV, Utrecht University © Copyright 1999 Johan den Hertog
Abstract This chapter makes a distinction between three types of theories of regulation: public interest theories, the Chicago theory of regulation and the public choice theories. The Chicago theory is mainly directed at the explanation of economic regulation; public interest theories and public choice theories envisage in addition to that an account of social regulation. The core of the diverse theories is discussed as well as the criticisms that have been leveled at them. It can be derived from the theories in what sectors regulation can be expected and what form the regulation will take. The extent to which these theories are also able to account for deregulation, and the expectations for the future, are discussed. JEL classification: D72, D78, H10, K20 Keywords: Regulation, Deregulation, Public Interest Theories, Private Interest Theories, Interest Groups, Market Failures
1. Introduction In legal and economic literature, there is no fixed definition of the term ‘regulation’. Some researchers devote considerable attention to the various definitions and attempt through systematization to make the term amenable to further analysis (Mitnick, 1980). Other researchers, however, entirely abstain from a further definition of regulation (Joskow and Noll, 1981). In order to delineate the subject and because of the limited space, a further definition of regulation is nevertheless necessary. In this article, regulation will be taken to mean the employment of legal instruments for the implementation of social-economic policy objectives. A characteristic of legal instruments is that individuals or organizations can be compelled by government to comply with prescribed behavior under penalty of sanctions. Corporations can be forced, for example, to observe certain prices, to supply certain goods, to stay out of certain markets, to apply particular techniques in the production process or to pay the legal minimum wage. Sanctions can include fines, the publicizing of violations, imprisonment, an order to make specific arrangements, an injunction against withholding certain actions, or closing down the business.
223
224
General Theories of Regulation
5000
A distinction is often made between economic and social regulation, for example Viscusi, Vernon and Harrington (1996). Economic regulation consists of two types of regulations: structural regulation and conduct regulation (Kay and Vickers, 1990). ‘Structural regulation’ is used for regulating market structure. Examples are restrictions on entry and exit and rules against individuals supplying professional services in the absence of recognized qualifications. ‘Conduct regulation’ is used for regulating behavior in the market. Examples are price control, rules against advertising and minimum quality standards. Economic regulation is mainly exercised on natural monopolies and market structures with limited or excessive competition. Social regulation comprises regulation in the area of the environment, labor conditions (occupational health and safety), consumer protection and labor (equal opportunities and so on) Instruments applied here include regulation dealing with the discharge of environmentally harmful substances, safety regulations in factories and workplaces, the obligation to include information on the packaging of goods or on labels, the prohibition of the supply of certain goods or services unless in the possession of a permit and banning discrimination on race, skin color, religion, sex, or nationality in the recruitment of personnel. In the theories of economic regulation, a distinction can be made between positive and normative theories. The positive variant is directed to the economic explanation of regulation and deriving the consequences of regulation. The normative variant investigates which type of regulation is the most efficient. The latter variant is called normative because there is usually an implicit assumption that efficient regulation would also be desirable; for the distinction between positive and normative theories, see the discussion between Blaug (1993) and Hennipman (1992). In the rest of this chapter, theories will be discussed which are directed to the economic explanation of regulation. These theories can be divided into public interest (Sections 2-8) and private interest (Sections 9-14) theories of regulation, see for example Ogus (1994). The normative theories will not be discussed further in this overview, except in a number of literature references below. The inefficiencies of natural monopolies can be eliminated by government bodies, regulated private bodies, or by means of franchising; for a comparison see Viscusi, Vernon and Harrington (1996). Public and private bodies are compared by Boardman and Vining (1989), Borcherding, Pommerehne and Schneider (1982), Daves and Christensen (1980) and Davies (1971, 1977). External effects such as pollution and accidents can be opposed by taxes, regulation, or systems of liability (see Shavel, 1984a, 1984b; Weitzman, 1974; White and Wittman, 1983 and Wittman, 1977). Various instruments for solving information problems, such as information regulation, prior approval, target standards, specification standards and performance standards are compared in Ogus (1994). Normative theories of regulation make a cost-benefit analysis of various regulatory
5000
General Theories of Regulation
225
instruments. The following costs can be distinguished in this: 1. 2. 3. 4.
the costs of formulating and implementing regulation; the costs of maintaining regulation; the costs of compliance with the rules for industry; the dead weight costs resulting from distortive changes in connection with 1-3.
The benefits consist of improvements in the static and dynamic efficiency in the application of scarce resources. The static efficiency comprises productive and allocative efficiency. In productive efficiency, production takes place at minimum cost, whereas allocative efficiency means that the correct range of goods is produced. Dynamic efficiency refers to future improvements in the application of scarce resources. Through such means as organizational or technological innovations, fewer resources are necessary in the production of certain goods. New products and product varieties can also be developed that better serve the preferences. Finally, dynamic efficiency refers to the speed at which markets clear and economies stabilize.
2. Public Interest Theories of Regulation The first group of regulation theories account for regulation from the point of view of aiming for public interest. This public interest can be further described as the best possible allocation of scarce resources for individual and collective goods. In western economies, the allocation of scarce resources is to a significant extent coordinated by the market mechanism. In theory, it can even be demonstrated that, under certain circumstances, the allocation of resources by means of the market mechanism is optimal (Arrow, 1985). Because these conditions are frequently not adhered to in practice, the allocation of resources is not optimal and a demand for methods for improving the allocation arises (Bator, 1958). One of the methods of achieving efficiency in the allocation of resources is government regulation (Arrow, 1970; Shubik, 1970). According to public interest theory, government regulation is the instrument for overcoming the disadvantages of imperfect competition, unbalanced market operation, missing markets and undesirable market results. In the first place, regulation can improve the allocation by facilitating, maintaining, or imitating market operation. The exchange of goods and production factors in markets assumes the definition, allocation and assertion of individual property rights and freedom to contract (Pejovich, 1979). The guarantee of property rights and any necessary enforcement of contract compliance can be more efficiently organized collectively than individually.
226
General Theories of Regulation
5000
Furthermore, the costs of market transactions are reduced by property and contract law. The freedom to contract can, however, also be used to achieve cooperation between parties opposed to market operation. Agreements between producers give rise to prices deviating from the marginal costs and an inefficient quantity of goods is put on the market. Antimonopoly legislation is aimed at maintaining the market operation through monitoring the creation of positions of economic power and by prohibiting competition limiting agreements or punishing the misuse thereof. Imperfect competition can also result from the special characteristics of the production process in relation to the magnitude of the demand in the market. At a given magnitude of demand average total costs would be minimized if the production were to be concentrated in one company. In that case a natural monopoly exists. If several companies produce the same total quantity of goods, the unit costs of production rise. An example of how such a situation arises is when the production process requires a great deal of capital. In that case, the fixed costs can continue to decline as production increases. Especially in the case of modest marginal costs that hardly rise, if at all, average total costs may persistently fall (Baumol, 1977). In such cases it is desirable, from the point of view of productive efficiency, to concentrate the production in a single company. A monopolist striving for maximization of profits will, however, set a price that deviates from the marginal costs. The stimulation of productive efficiency in the production process then acts to the detriment of the aim for allocative efficiency. Natural monopolies are then either put under control of the state, as happens in many European countries, or highly regulated, as for example in the United States. In the latter case, regulation consists of barring entry to the market and the enforcement of price rules that promote efficient allocation (Braeutigam, 1989). In this way, the market results of perfect competition are simulated. Examples of companies assumed at some time to have possessed the characteristics of a natural monopoly are railways, electricity distribution, gas and oil pipelines, telecommunication networks and drinking water distribution.
3. Unbalanced Market Operation In the second place, regulation is capable of contributing to the stabilization of market operation and the earlier achievement of market equilibrium. Imbalances within an economy occur at the level of separate markets and on a macro level. In separate markets, what is known as destructive or excessive competition can arise, often as a result of long-term over-capacity. The development of a new equilibrium can take a long time if the individual participants are in a prisoner’s dilemma. For all market parties jointly,
5000
General Theories of Regulation
227
efficiency is achieved if the existing over-capacity can be rationalized. For an individual producer, however, the ‘sunk costs’ can mean that it is rational to wait until other suppliers have sorted out the capacity. Because this consideration applies to all producers, the over-capacity can persist for a considerable time. Over-capacity situations can also arise when the production capacity is adjusted to the demand during peak moments or peak periods. Examples are peak loads in the rush-hour (busses, underground railways and trains), during the harvest in agriculture (trucks) and during the tourist high season (touring cars, aircraft). Excessive or ruinous competition can finally also arise in a natural oligopoly. In that case efficiency is achieved if only a few companies supply the market. The small number of companies allows them to react to each other’s market strategies, so that among other things, price wars can be waged. A consequence of excessive competition is not only that the price level sinks below the average total costs, but also that the price level fluctuates more widely. This causes insecurity and inefficient decision making on the part of both producers and consumers. Finally, excessive competition can be at the expense of safety and reliability when consumers are not in a position to assess the quality of goods (Kahn, 1988, pp. 172-178). In the past it was assumed that the situation of excessive competition applied to sectors such as air travel and passenger or goods transport by road or water. For these sectors, business licensing restrictions were devised and the capacity was pruned, sometimes in combination with minimum price regulation. However, modern regulatory theory considers the collection of excessive competition-rationales of government intervention to be ‘an empty box’ (see Breyer, 1982, pp. 29-32). Except at the level of the individual sectors, imbalances can also occur on a macro economic level. Market economies are characterized by a trade cycle, the regular alternation of periods of increasing and declining economic activity. In the course of the trade-cycle, a self-sustaining process comes about in the goods market that is not compensated by adjustments in the labor market. This arises partly because of lack of information, long-term labor contracts and efficiency wages. Trade-cycle policies can be desirable to prevent temporary disturbances to the equilibrium having permanent effects. For example, capital goods of limited usefulness in other market segments can be lost forever in a recession. Furthermore, structural unemployment can arise when unemployed workers lose their skill and motivation. Finally, stabilization of the trade cycle can be desirable to prevent the decline of production and employment such that different social groups are unequally affected by the economic rise and fall. Traditionally, trade-cycle policies are put into effect together with instruments of budgetary and monetary policy; for an overview of the significance of these instruments and the underlying theories, see Snowdon, Vane and Wynarczyk (1994). Because these instruments are not directed to specific sectors and only take effect after some time, wage and price regulation have been developed in
228
General Theories of Regulation
5000
some market economies. To combat a wage-price spiral, governments have for example developed the means to freeze wages and prices for a period of between a half to one year, possibly in designated sectors (Ogus, 1994, pp. 300ff. and Breyer, 1982, pp. 60ff.).
4. Information Problems Public interest theory explains regulation from viewpoints not restricted to imperfect competition and unbalanced market operation. For a number of reasons, markets may not exist for some goods for which the utility or the ‘willingness to pay’ exceeds the production costs. Markets might not exist as a result of information problems and transaction costs in the case of external effects and public goods. In these cases, regulation can improve the allocative efficiency of the economy. In the first place, missing markets can be accounted for by hidden information or an asymmetric distribution of information with respect to prices, quantities or quality of goods (Hirshleifer and Riley, 1979). In this connection, it is useful to make a distinction between ‘search goods’, for which the quality of a product can be determined prior to purchase, ‘experience goods’, for which quality only becomes apparent after consumption of the good and ‘credence goods’, for which the quality cannot even be established after consumption (Nelson, 1970; Darby and Karni, 1973). Examples of each are the purchase of flowers, second-hand cars and medical advice, respectively. When it is not possible to establish the quality of goods or services in advance, purchasers will be prepared to pay an average price corresponding with the expected quality. Sellers of goods of high quality will not be prepared to offer the goods at that asking price, and will withdraw from the market. The consequence is that the quality of goods traded on the market will decline, as will the price buyers are prepared to pay (Akerlof, 1970). In this process of adverse selection, highquality goods are driven out of the market by low-quality goods. In addition, the asymmetric distribution of information can also give rise to moral hazard in the enforcement of contracts, which means that parties misuse their information advantage. Examples are painters who use poor quality paint and lawyers who give unfounded advice. The problems of adverse selection and moral hazard may explain the existence of, for example, certificates, licenses and other trading regulations for professional groups such as building contractors, hairdressers and plasterers. By means of these rules, minimum requirements can be set on the commercial knowledge, professional skill and creditworthiness, so that the transaction costs decline and the information problems are reduced (Leland, 1979). Because of the nature of credence goods, it is difficult to set minimum quality standards precisely in those cases where the risks of moral hazard are high. In such circumstances, legally sanctioned
5000
General Theories of Regulation
229
self regulation can combat the problems of adverse selection and moral hazard (Van den Bergh and Faure, 1991; Den Hertog, 1993). Not only do those involved have a vested interest in the maintenance of the minimum quality, they are also better able to formulate and maintain quality rules (Gehrig and Jost, 1995). Problems of adverse selection and moral hazard arise particularly in insurance markets (Rothschild and Stiglitz, 1976). Insured parties have superior information available with respect to the incidence of risks but they lack information regarding the quality and independence of intermediaries. In many countries, social legislation is introduced as a reaction to these problems, and rules are established for intermediaries. Shrinking markets can also arise as a result of search costs incurred by consumers when relevant information is not available to them. Because in their purchases consumers compare the utility of goods with the effective prices, search costs give rise to shrinking markets. Search costs can be kept to a minimum through rules related to price and quantity marking, and in the case of credence goods, also for example a ban on advertising (Barzel, 1982, 1985). Finally, under certain circumstances transaction costs can be kept to a minimum by rules relating to misleading information (Beales, Craswell and Salop, 1981; Schwartz and Wilde, 1979).
5. External Effects and Public Goods In addition to information failures, prohibitively high transaction costs can also result in missing markets. Transaction costs can impede, for example, the coming into existence of a market for efficient use of the environment. In a market economy, resources are efficiently used when the production of goods is increased until the marginal costs equal the marginal benefits of production. In a market with perfect competition, an individual producer aiming for maximization of profit will increase his production until his marginal costs equal his market price. However, an inefficient allocation of resources can arise in the presence of external effects (Meade, 1973). External effects are influences of economic action having consequences for the conditions of production or the level of utility of third parties and which come into being outside the market. An often cited example concerns the discharge of waste material by a factory such that downstream drinking water companies must incur costs of water purification. Because the private costs for the discharging manufacturer differ from the social costs, production will be increased further than would be desirable from the point of view of efficient allocation. According to the Coase theorem, an efficient allocation of resources can nonetheless result from a process of negotiation in the case of clearly described property rights and in the absence of transaction costs (Coase, 1960). The
230
General Theories of Regulation
5000
transaction costs of negotiation can, however, be prohibitively high if several parties are involved in the negotiating process and an element of strategic behavior exists (Veljanovski, 1982a). In such cases, the government can attempt to internalize the external effects by means of regulation (Gruenspecht and Lave, 1989). Examples are safety regulations for items such as automobiles and food, noise levels for aircraft, the obligation to use catalytic converters in automobiles and limits for the emission of hazardous substances in permits. Missing markets may result in the third place with goods having specific characteristics, the so-called public goods (Samuelson, 1954). These types of goods have two special characteristics. For the supplier of these types of goods it is first of all either impossible or too expensive to exclude people from consumption who fail to pay for the good; the technical term for this is non-excludability. In the second place, consumption of these types of goods by one person is not at the expense of another person; the technical term for this is non-rivalness (Musgrave, 1969). Classical examples of these types of goods are lighthouses, public order, defense, street lighting and sea defenses, and television and radio signals. Public goods are either not produced at all or not in the optimum quantity by a market because of free-rider problems and problems with establishing the ‘willingness to pay’ for these goods (Bohm, 1987). If a supplier has already produced the goods, consumers can be tempted to take a free ride on the willingness to pay of others: after all, they can no longer be excluded from consumption of the good. To establish the optimum quantity of the collective good, the marginal utility of single increments of this good must be known from all the consumers involved. Because of its non-rival character, the aggregate willingness to pay for marginal units is compared against the marginal costs. When consumers are asked to reveal this willingness to pay for extra units, they will exaggerate or minimize this for strategic reasons. Exaggeration will occur when the willingness to pay for extra units is not linked with actual payment for extra units of the good. Minimization will occur when the financing of the public good is linked to the willingness to pay that was indicated. Because consumers cannot be excluded, there will be a tendency to hitch a ride on others’ willingness to pay, and for strategic reasons they will indicate a modest willingness to pay for themselves. For these reasons, a market economy will not be able to produce these goods in optimum quantities, if at all. Government regulation is necessary for establishing the optimum quantity of the goods concerned, and for enforcing the payment of these goods. Many goods, such as education, health care, parks and roads have a public good dimension. In such cases also, government regulation can theoretically contribute to an efficient use of resources in an economy.
5000
General Theories of Regulation
231
6. Undesirable Market Results According to public interest theory, regulation can be explained not only by imperfect competition, unbalanced market operation and missing markets, but finally also by the need to prevent or correct undesirable market results. In a competitive market economy, participants in the economic process are rewarded according to their marginal productive contribution. This result of the market process can be undesirable for economic and other reasons. In the first place it is possible that an efficient redistribution will increase the general level of economic welfare situations effects such as the prisoner’s dilemma impede voluntary transfers (Hochman and Rogers, 1969, 1970). An efficient redistribution could also occur where marginal utility of income diminishes and satisfaction capacity does not differ widely among people. However, in economics it is customary to assume the unfeasibility of cardinal measurement of utility and interpersonal utility comparison, so that this last form of efficient redistribution cannot theoretically be justified from an economic point of view (Robbins, 1932). The correction of undesirable market results can furthermore also be considered desirable for other than economic reasons, such as considerations of justice, paternalistic motives or ethical principles. In that case, tradeoffs can arise between, for example, economic efficiency and equality: incentive effects of redistribution can result in a decline in the level of individual utility (Okun, 1975). Public interest theory is usually applied to explain regulation as an aim for economic efficiency (Joskow and Noll, 1981, p. 36). In other cases, public interest theory is more broadly interpreted and regulation is accounted for as aiming to correct inefficient or inequitable market practices (Posner, 1974). According to this last view, regulation can be accounted for as aiming for a socially efficient use of scarce resources. Examples of laws and rules intended to prevent or ameliorate undesirable market results are a legal minimum wage, maximum rents, cross-subsidies in postal delivery, telephone calls and passenger transport, rules enhancing the accessibility of health care, rules guaranteeing an income in the event of sickness, unemployment, disablement, old-age and so on.
7. Criticism of Public Interest Theory The theory that regulation can be explained as an answer to market failures has been criticized from several points of view. (a) In the first place, criticism has been directed at the theory of market failure underlying the explanation of government regulation (Cowen, 1988). In practice it appears that the market mechanism itself is often able to compensate for any inefficiencies. In that way problems of adverse selection are
232
General Theories of Regulation
5000
solved by companies themselves by, for example, the issue of guarantees, the use of brand names and extensive advertising campaigns as a signal of quality (Nelson, 1974). The market sector also appears able to avail itself of goods traditionally characterized as typical public goods, such as lighthouses (Coase, 1974). The conclusion that monopoly power or external effects give rise to an inefficient allocation of resources can only be understood by assuming a model in which transaction costs are absent. The allocation of resources appears efficient if transaction costs are included in the analysis (Dahlman, 1979) and (Toumanoff, 1984). The assumption of market failure in the case that only one or a few companies are responsible for the production of goods is similarly criticized (Demsetz, 1976). Any significant returns could be a result of superior efficiency of these companies and furthermore, account must be taken of the possibility of competition for the market (Baumol, Panzar and Willig, 1982) as opposed to competition in the market. A more general criticism of the theory of market failure is its limited explanatory power. An economist generally needs only 10 minutes to rationalize government intervention by constructing a form of market failure (Peltzman, 1989). (b) In the second place, the original theory assumes that government regulation is effective and can be implemented without great cost (Posner, 1974). So precisely the transaction costs and information costs, which underlie market failure, are assumed to be absent in the case of government regulation. This assumption has been criticized in both empirical and theoretical research. Theoretical research, the theory of the second best, has demonstrated that the partial aim for efficient allocation does not make the economy as a whole more efficient if unavoidable inefficiencies persist elsewhere in the economy (Ng, 1990). An unavoidable inefficiency such as imperfect competition in the commodity market distorts allocation in the whole economy. Not only is the good concerned produced in insufficient quantity, but also too many resources are devoted to other goods in the economy. These distortions also mean that the allocation in the factor market is suboptimal. Consider the case that the government wishes to aim for allocative efficiency in an economy in which allocation is suboptimal. In that case, it is of little use to aim for allocative efficiency through, for example, price regulation of electricity production. A ‘second best’ solution would be to supply electricity to the competition limited sector on prices higher than marginal costs. In reality however, a great many of these unavoidable inefficiencies exist. These inefficiencies are a consequence of such things as external effects, taxation, imperfect competition and flawed information. That renders the achievement of a second-best optimum unfeasible in practice (Utton, 1986). Other theoretical research points to the flawed information available to regulators, both in the drawing up of the rules and in their enforcement (Sappington and Stiglitz, 1987). A consequence is, for example, that regulated businesses select inefficient combinations of production
5000
General Theories of Regulation
233
factors, so that they are unable to produce to minimal costs (Baumol and Klevorick, 1970). Furthermore, x-inefficiencies arise so that production to minimal costs no longer takes place (Leibenstein, 1966). Another consequence is that inefficient safety standards are applied by regulators, see for example Viscusi (1985). Empirical research into the effectiveness and efficiency of government regulation also gives rise to criticism of the public interest theory. For a general overview of the effects of economic regulation, see Joskow and Rose (1989). The research into economic regulation was started with the famous article by Stigler and Friedland (1962) about the effects of price regulation on electricity producers. An earlier synthesis of this type of research showed firstly that the influence of regulation on natural monopolies was slight if not non-existent (Jordan, 1972). In the second place, it appeared that regulating potentially competing sectors such as air traffic and freight resulted in an increase in prices and a restricted number of competitors. Empirical research further demonstrates that regulation prescribed an inefficient price structure in which mainly consumer groups received cross subsidies (Posner, 1971). Research into the effects of economic deregulation demonstrated furthermore that mainly consumers, but to some extent also producers, derived a benefit on balance from less government regulation (Winston, 1993). Social regulation appeared to keep costs and benefits more or less in balance (Hahn and Hird, 1991) although there is also empirical evidence suggesting that much social regulation is poorly targeted or is over-stringent (Sunstein, 1990; Hahn, 1996). A qualifying remark can be made pertaining to social regulation, that it is hardly if at all possible to quantify many of the benefits. For example, how can a value be put on the preservation of a variety of life forms and how can the preferences of future generations be determined? Finally, there are arguments for assuming that even competition legislation is misused as an instrument of monopolization (Baumol and Ordover, 1985). The points of criticism given under (a) and (b) make clear that at the root of the public interest theory lies what is known as the Nirvana approach (Demsetz, 1968). Regulation can be explained by assuming that a theoretically efficient institution is able to replace or correct imperfect real institutions. It is no longer the case that transaction costs and administrative costs under regulatory systems tend to be ignored; see the work of what has variously been referred to as the ‘New Haven’ or ‘Progressive School’ of Law and Economics (for example, Rose-Ackerman, 1988, 1992). (c) Public interest theory usually assumes that regulation can be accounted for as aiming for economic efficiency. Interpreted in this way, the theory is unable to explain why on occasions other objectives such as procedural fairness or redistribution are aimed for at the expense of economic efficiency (Joskow and Noll, 1981, p. 36). On the other hand, when it is assumed that regulation can be accounted for as aiming for social efficiency, another problem is
234
General Theories of Regulation
5000
encountered. Where there is conflict between efficiency and equity, it is impossible for at least two reasons to establish the social efficiency of regulation (Sen, 1979a, 1979b). In contrast to the case of economic considerations, where the criteria of Pareto and Kaldor-Hicks are generally applied, in the case of considerations of justice there are no generally applicable standards of justice available. No agreement exists regarding the definition of justice in concrete situations (Dworkin, 1981). Secondly, the establishment of social efficiency of regulation requires that economic efficiency and justice be weighed against each other. The theoretically justified and practically usable scale of values that this calls for is not available (Ng, 1985). The absence of generally applicable standards of justice and the lack of insight into the relationship between justice and efficiency renders empirical testing of the public interest theory as an explanatory theory of regulation impossible. A key problem of the public interest theory is that the evaluating, normative theory of economic welfare is using a positive explanatory theory of regulation (Joskow and Noll, 1981). (d) A final point of criticism is that public interest theory is incomplete. In the first place, the theory does not indicate how a given view on the public interest translates into legislative actions that maximize economic welfare (Posner, 1974). The political decision-making process consists of various participants who will aim for their own objectives under different constraints. In contrast to the market economy, it is unclear in the political decision-making process how the interaction of the participants will lead to maximum economic welfare. Secondly, a theory of regulation should be able to predict which branches of industry or sectors should be regulated, and to whom the advantages and disadvantages are to accrue. The theory should also be able to predict what form regulation is to take, such as subsidies, restricted entry, or price regulations (Stigler, 1971). Of course, much normative public interest analysis has been undertaken on the forms of regulation, and not only of economic regulation. There is the well-known literature on standards versus prices for pollution and other externalities. On consumer safety, see Asch (1988). Other valuable studies include Stewart (1981), Dewees (1983) and Trebilcock and Hartle (1982). Public interest theory does not appear able to come up with relevant predictions that are amenable to testing by empirical economic science. Furthermore, facts are observed in social reality which are not well accounted for by public interest theory. Why should companies support and even aim for regulation intended to cream off excess profits?
8. A More Sophisticated Version of Public Interest Theory Criticism of the public interest theory has led to a more serious public interest theory (see Noll, 1983, 1989a). According to the naïve public interest theory,
5000
General Theories of Regulation
235
regulation can be accounted for by market failure under conformance to the conditions of the Coase theorem. This implies the assumption of absence of transaction costs and freely available, conveniently processed information in the political process. By letting go of these assumptions, a more sophisticated version of the public interest theory comes about. Is it possible to see regulation as an answer to market failure when account is taken of transaction costs and information costs? In the presence of transaction costs, regulation can form a more efficient solution to market failure than private negotiations between the parties involved. Costs of organization can also be avoided when for example in the case of environmental pollution, politicians bundle the preferences of those negatively affected. In the case of flawed information, political entrepreneurs can detect the causes of market failure and report them to those involved. In this way, knowledge about, for example, accidents can be picked up through safety regulations in factories. Regulation may be more efficient in this case because the government can obtain information less expensively. On the one hand, the government can enforce the provision of information about accidents, for example, on the other hand information is often a byproduct of other government activities. This sophisticated version of the public interest theory does not therefore require regulation to be perfect. It does, however, assume that market failure exists, that regulation is the most effective means of combating it and that regulation does not continue to exist once the costs exceed the benefits. This theory also assumes that politicians support open decision-making processes and spread information widely about the effects of market results and regulation. According to this theory, then, regulation can be accounted for as the efficient solution to market failure. The problems stated under Section 7(b) and (c) are not, however, solved with this version.
9. Private Interest Theories of Regulation After the public interest theory had fallen into disrepute through empirical and theoretical research, the capture theory was developed mainly by political scientists; for a discussion see Posner (1974). This theory assumes that in the course of time, regulation will come to serve the interests of the branch of industry involved. For example, it is assumed that legislators subject the branch to additional regulation by an agency if misuse of the economic position of power is detected. In the course of time, other political priorities arrive on the agenda and the monitoring of the regulatory agency by legislators is relaxed. The agency will tend to avoid conflicts with the regulated company because it is dependent on this company for its information. Furthermore, there are career opportunities for the regulators in the regulated companies. This leads in time to the regulatory agency coming to represent the interests of the branch
236
General Theories of Regulation
5000
involved. For an overview of the various strategies available to be applied by agencies and regulated companies, see Owen and Braeutigam (1978). The capture theory is unsatisfactory in a number of respects. In the first place there is insufficient distinction from the public interest theory, because the capture theory also assumes that the public interest underlies the start of regulation. In the second place, it is not clear why a branch can succeed in subjecting an agency to its interests but cannot prevent its coming into existence. In the third place, regulation often appears to serve the interests of groups of consumers rather than the interests of the branch. Regulated companies are often obliged to extend their services beyond the voluntarily chosen level of service. Examples are transport services, the supply of gas, water and electricity and telecommunication services to consumers living in widely scattered geographical locations. In the fourth place, much regulation, such as environmental regulation, regulation of product safety and labor conditions are opposed by companies because of the negative effect on profitability. Finally, the capture theory is more of a hypothesis than a theory. It does not explain why a branch is able to ‘take over’ a regulatory agency and why, for example, consumer groups fail to prevent this takeover.
10. The Chicago Theory of Regulation In 1971 a start was made on the development of a theory of regulation called by some the economic theory of regulation (Posner, 1974) and by others the Chicago theory of government (Noll, 1989a). ‘The Theory of Economic Regulation’ by George Stigler (1971) appeared in that year. His central proposition was that ‘as a rule, regulation is acquired by the industry and is designed and operated primarily for its benefit’. The benefits of regulation for a branch of industry are obvious. The government can grant subsidies or ban the entry of competitors to the branch directly so that the level of prices rise. In the second place, the government can maintain minimum prices more easily than a cartel. In the third place, the government can suppress the use of substitutes and support complements. An example of support to complements is the subsidizing of airports for the benefit of airlines. A demand will therefore arise on the one hand for government regulation. The political decision-making process on the other hand makes it possible for branches of industry to exploit politics for its own ends. For this proposition, Stigler makes use of the insights of Downs (1957) and Olson (1965). In the political decision-making process, interest groups will exercise political influence, as opposed to individuals. Individuals will not participate because forming an opinion about political questions is expensive in terms of time, energy and money, while the benefits in terms of political influence will be negligible. A representative democracy
5000
General Theories of Regulation
237
would more readily honor the strongly felt preferences of majorities and minorities than the less passionately expressed preferences. This is related to the costs of organization of such minority and majority groups. Some groups can organize themselves less expensively than others. Small groups have the advantage because the transaction costs are lower and the ‘free-rider’ problem is smaller than is the case with large groups. Furthermore, in small groups the preferences will be more homogeneous than in large groups. Small groups also have the advantage in that for the same total yield, the yield per member of the group is greater. The fact that apparently large branches can still be well organized is explained by Stigler through concentration and asymmetry (Stigler, 1974). The large companies in a concentrated branch will see themselves as a small group. In the case of asymmetry in the branch, for example as a result of product diversity or widely varying production techniques, separate companies will wish to prevent unfavorable regulation and will participate in the organization. The result of variation in the costs of organization is that producers organize more readily than consumers. Not only are the costs more modest for producers, but also the burden of regulation in the form of such things as higher prices per consumer is too slight to justify organization. Politicians aim for re-election. Organized branches can contribute to re-election in two ways: by supplying votes and other resources. Examples of these resources are campaign contributions, chairing fundraising committees and the offer of employment to party members. The larger branches have an advantage in this over smaller branches, unless the smaller branches have something in their favor such as a strong geographical concentration. Politicians will honor the demand for regulation by branches because it is not worth the while of the majority of opponents to gather the information and organize. The conclusion is that regulation is not directed at the correction of market failures, but at setting up income transfers in favor of the industries in exchange for political support.
11. Extensions to the Chicago Theory of Regulation In the same issue of the Bell Journal of Economics in which Stigler put forward his theory of economic regulation, Posner (1971) implicitly supplied the first criticism. He observed that in many cases regulation strongly advantaged certain consumer groups. For instance, uniform prices were prescribed for such things as rail transport, the supply of gas, water and electricity, telecommunications traffic and mail distribution. The costs of the services supplied differ considerably between consumer groups, however, depending on their geographical spread, among other factors. Other examples are the supply of drinking water to households, schools and fire services, either free of charge or at a price lower than the marginal costs; free rail travel for government
238
General Theories of Regulation
5000
workers and military personnel; the supply of electricity to hospitals at less than marginal costs and so on. This phenomenon of internal or cross-subsidization does not fit in with Stigler’s theory of regulation. Even if other consumer groups are obliged to pay higher than marginal costs for their goods and services to compensate, cross-subsidization works against the aim of maximum profit. An explanation of cross-subsidization is provided in an extension to the theory of regulation by Peltzman (1976). He assumes that politicians will choose their policy of regulation such that political support is maximized. It is not likely that regulation will benefit industry exclusively. Some consumer groups will also be able to organize themselves effectively. Moreover, organization and information costs are an obstacle to the immediate and total withdrawal of political support in the event of a small decrease in cartel profit. Lower prices are favorable to consumers, higher prices generate more political support from industry. According to Peltzman, the core problem for regulators is efficient regulation: what price level should be settled on such that the gain in votes resulting from the income transfer just balances the loss of votes resulting from the rise in prices. This extended theory explains not only the phenomenon of cross-subsidization, but also predicts which branches will be regulated. These are the relatively competitive branches and the monopolistic branches. In the first case, the branches have a keen interest in regulation and, in the second case, consumers have a great interest in regulation. It can be expected of intermediate branches that any regulated price level will not deviate widely from the actually existing price level. In that case it is not worthwhile for consumers or producers to organize to acquire favorable regulation. The practice of regulation appears to confirm this prediction. Regulated branches are either monopolistic, such as rail transport and telecommunications, or highly competitive, such as freight, agriculture, independent professions and cab companies. As well as the types of branches, the theory of regulation also predicts the form the benefits as allocated will take. In principle, transfers can come about directly through subsidies or indirectly through price or quantity regulation or restriction to market entry. Stigler originally assumed that branches would choose indirect support. The granting of subsidies would result in entry, so that the subsidy per producer would be dissipated. In an extension to the theory of regulation, Migué (1977) has shown that the form of the transfers is partly dependent on the elasticity of supply of the production factors in the branch concerned. In the political market, the public are both consumers and suppliers of production factors. Suppliers of production factors will give preference to subsidies when the supply is inelastic. The taxation necessitated by the subsidy is distributed over many taxpayers, while the subsidy accrues to a limited group of suppliers of production factors. This extension to the theory of regulation explains why subsidies are granted in sectors such as education, health care,
5000
General Theories of Regulation
239
domestic housing and city transport, and why quota systems and price regulation can be found in sectors such as agriculture, airlines, road transport and railways. Similar reasoning explains why polluting companies give preference to prescribed limitation of production (quotas) above taxation (Buchanan and Tullock, 1975). Another extension to the theory of regulation is from McChesney (1987, 1991). He sees politicians not as neutral agents between competing private interests directed to obtaining transfers of income. In his view, politicians also try to gain advantages by putting private parties under pressure. He gives examples in which Congress, under the threat of price reductions or cost increases, forces concessions from private parties. To make such rent extractions possible, politicians encourage private parties to organize. Organization not only enhances the probability of gaining transfers of income, it also increases the risk of having one’s own surplus threatened and expropriated. Finally, Keeler (1984) has supplemented Peltzman’s model with public interest considerations. In his model, politicians gain not only political support through transfers of income between interest groups. Through an increase in economic efficiency, for example with economies of scale and external effects, resources are acquired which can be distributed among producers and consumers. Rational politicians will not omit to make use of this possibility.
12. The Competition Between Pressure Groups: Becker A further contribution to the Chicago theory of regulation was made by Becker (1983, 1985a, 1985b). He concentrated on the consequences of the competition between interest groups, which he calls pressure groups. As the political pressure increases, political influence also increases and the financial yield from the pressure exerted rises. Some groups are more efficient in the exertion of political pressure than others. This can be a consequence of the economies of scale in the production of pressure, more effective combating of free-riding, better access to the media and other matters. In this way, transfers of income occur from less efficient to more efficient groups, in the form of subsidies, but also through such things as price regulation. A limit exists for these transfers, however. The transfers are associated with loss of economic welfare, which are known as the deadweight costs. As a result of this loss of welfare the loss of the least efficient pressure group is larger than the gain of the more efficient pressure group. As the welfare losses become greater, the pressure of the more efficient group will decline because the yield of the pressure is lower. At the same time, the pressure of the less efficient group increases with the scale of the loss of welfare because the potential yield of pressure increases. This countervailing pressure limits the possibility of transfers to the more efficient
240
General Theories of Regulation
5000
pressure group. It can be deduced from this analysis that politically successful groups are small in proportion to the group bearing the burden of the transfers. The larger the burdened group, the smaller the levy per member of the group and the smaller the deadweight costs. This diminishes the countervailing pressure. The smaller the receiving group, the larger the potential yield per member of the group, which serves to increase the pressure exerted. The analysis explains, for instance, why in countries where the agriculture sector is small it is subsidized, while large agriculture sectors elsewhere are heavily taxed. In Stigler’s and Peltzman’s view, competing branches have information and organization advantages through which advantageous regulation can be predicted. In practice, such regulation of competitive sectors is rarely seen. The explanation is found in Becker’s theory. Loss of welfare is greater where the elasticity of supply is greater. In competitive sectors, these elasticities are large. The transfers of income and the welfare losses associated with regulation are so large that the countervailing pressure invoked eliminates the investment in political influence. It can be further deduced from the analysis that regulation is more likely in branches exhibiting market failures, a result in agreement with the public interest theory of regulation. In monopolistic branches, for example, consumers can obtain transfers larger than the losses of the producers. In competing branches, on the other hand, the gain of the winners is smaller than the loss of the losers. All other things being equal, more pressure will be exerted in monopolistic branches by the potential winners and less pressure by the potential losers than in competing branches. Market failure is therefore not a sufficient condition for regulation, such as in the public interest theory of regulation; regulation is also dependent on the relative efficiency of pressure groups in exerting political pressure. In contrast to Olson (1982), the competition between pressure groups will not have any negative effects on the growth of the national product and productivity, at least provided pressure groups of equal size and efficiency are involved in producing the pressure. The competition between pressure groups will also lead to the most efficient form of regulation. Even if under certain circumstances the results of competition among pressure groups is efficient, Becker claims that the production of pressure is not. All pressure groups would be better off if they decreased their expenditure on pressure by equal amounts. Various laws and rules directed to limiting the influence of pressure groups can be explained as instruments for opposing wasteful expenditure on political pressure. The Chicago theory of regulation seems primarily suited to the explanation of so-called economic regulation. Social regulation, the regulation in the area of safety, environment and health, seems at first sight to be less amenable to explanation by this theory. There are diseconomies in the area of organization, the advantages are divided among many involved parties and the costs of
5000
General Theories of Regulation
241
regulation are allocated to concentrated groups. Nonetheless, private interest explanations are also put forward for social regulation (see for example Bartel and Thomas, 1985, 1987; Pashigian, 1984a, 1984b). In this the application of rules and standards is in the interests of those companies already complying with the standard. Furthermore, large companies have an advantage when it is necessary to comply with administrative obligations or costly measures. Small companies are driven out of the market, so that the competition is limited. Legal requirements are above all often differentiated into existing producers and new producers. By setting higher standards on new producers, entry to the market is impeded and competition is limited.
13. Criticism of the Chicago Theory of Regulation A weak point of the Chicago theory of regulation is the risk of tautology (Noll, 1989a). Redistribution is seen as the cause of regulation. In practice, however, regulation is always associated with redistribution. Investigating who derives benefit from regulation and who carries the costs, has not established the cause of regulation. Another weak point is that it cannot be predicted which groups will be the most effective politically and who will collect the income transfers. Research has shown that it was workers who enjoyed the main advantage of regulation rather than producers. This result can possibly be rationalized but cannot be predicted with the Chicago theory. Furthermore, the Chicago theory is incomplete. The Chicago theory of regulation assumes that interest groups determine the outcomes of elections, that legislators honor uncurtailed the wishes of the interest groups and that legislators are able to control regulators. In this theory of regulation there is therefore little or no attention to the following three subjects: a. the motivation and behavior of the various political actors, such as voters, congressmen, legislators, government workers and agencies; b. the interactions between the various actors in the regulation process; c. the mechanism through which legislators and regulators conform to the wishes of the organized partial interests. In fact it is assumed that the operation of the political process of legislation and regulation has hardly any independent influence on the pattern and form of regulation, if at all. This assumption has been criticized from several quarters and several attempts have been made in the literature to fill in the three gaps. The theory of regulation partly overlaps with the public choice theory; overviews from the literature are given by Romer and Rosenthal (1987), Noll (1989a), Levine and Forrence (1990) and, specifically for the area of public choice, Mueller (1989), Frey (1978, 1983) and Frey and Ramser (1986).
242
General Theories of Regulation
5000
For the interests of bureacrats in regulatory systems see Dunleavy (1991). The idea that only organized interest groups have their wishes honored uncurtailed by legislators has been criticized by the likes of Wilson (1974, 1980). The origin of regulatory legislation can, according to Wilson, be explained by analyzing the concentration and spread of costs and benefits. Majoritarian politics in Congress is to be expected with distributed costs and benefits; antimonopoly legislation is one example. Interest group politics arise with concentrated costs and benefits; labor legislation and railway regulation are examples of this. Client politics is the result of concentrated advantages and distributed costs; examples of this are the protection of professional groups by means of licensing and the subsidizing of companies and branches. A final form of policy is what is known as entrepreneurial politics, in which the costs are concentrated and the benefits distributed; examples are protection of the environment, of consumers against unsafe products and of workers against industrial accidents and occupational illnesses. This last form of regulation is difficult or impossible to explain with the Chicago theory. According to Wilson, interest groups are therefore not the only origin of regulation. Wilson goes on to criticize the assumption of Chicago that legislators are able to control regulators unimpaired. In his view, the behavior of the agencies can be better accounted for through an analysis of the motivations of those involved internally. He distinguishes careerists, professionals and politicians and uses this to account for various types of regulation policy. Price regulation, for example, will be simple in structure if set up by careerists and more complex if it is developed by professionals. Contrary to Wilson, Derthick and Quirk (1985) assume that the regulation policy of agencies is actually heavily influenced by surrounding forces. They show that agencies honored diffuse interests at the expense of the concentrated interests of the regulated branch. They account for this deregulation with the intellectual climate in combination with the pressure exerted by the president, Congress and the legal powers on the agencies. In agreement with the Chicago theory of regulation, Weingast (1981) also sees no independent role for agencies. Changes in the regulatory behavior of agencies are a consequence of changes in the preferences of Congress or its commissions. Contrary to Chicago, Weingast shows how a structure-induced equilibrium of policy choice arises as a reaction to the instability of majority rule voting. In an equilibrium of congressional committees, the agencies and the interest groups have divergent but comparable goals. Weingast’s model describes why the wishes of interest groups are honored and how diffuse single-issue groups such as environmental groups and consumer organizations are able to acquire political power at the expense of traditional interest groups such as industry, employees and agriculture.
5000
General Theories of Regulation
243
The assumption that legislators honor the wishes of interest groups uncurtailed comes in for particular criticism from the point of view of the principal-agent theory. The acquisition of information about the behavior of legislators and regulators is expensive. Because of this, legislators and regulators get the room to escape the attention of voters and interest groups and to act in their own interests or ideological preferences (Kalt and Zupan, 1984, 1990). In this connection, Levine and Forrence (1990) distinguish two types of motivation and two types of political dominance. Depending on what a political actor is aiming for, private and public interests can be distinguished. Private interests are preferences of political actors with respect to their self-interest. Public interests are preferences related to the interests of others. The private and public interests indicate what a political actor will maximize when there is room to aim for their own preferences. General-interest policy is a policy that should be ratified in the absence of information, organization, transaction and monitoring costs. Special-interest policies should not be ratified by the general polity in the absence of monitoring costs and so on. Because of the existence of monitoring cost, a ‘slack’ or policy drift arises, in other words agents’ room to maneuver to pursue their own objectives. On the one hand this policy can allow discretion to be used to favor special interest groups, on the other hand, it can be used to promote the interests of others. Here again there are two possibilities. In the absence of monitoring costs and so on, this policy slack would either not be ratified by the general polity or it would be. The capture debate is concerned with the question who dominates the political process and is therefore concerned less with private or public interests than with general and special interests. According to Levine and Forrence, general interests will prevail to the extent that the slack is reduced. The amount of slack decreases drastically when issues come up on the public agenda. Favorable conditions for this are: political competition, special interest organizations, public policy intelligentsia and the news media. A general-interest policy does not otherwise imply that the policy is also efficient. When, for example, the rented sector is a substantial part of the housing market, a policy of rent control will achieve ready approval without any guarantee of efficiency.
14. Rent Seeking A completely different criticism of the Chicago theory of regulation comes from the Virginia School of Public Choice (Rowley, Tullock, Tollison, McCormick et al.). For an overview of the work of the Virginia School, see Tullock (1993), Buchanan, Tollison and Tullock (1980) and Rowley, Tollison and Tullock (1988). In their theories, the term coined by Ann Krueger (1974), rent seeking, is a central feature. Rent seeking means the political activity of individuals and
244
General Theories of Regulation
5000
groups to devote scarce resources to the pursuit of monopoly rights granted by governments. The Virginia School criticizes the Chicago theoreticians for their disregard of the inefficiencies of regulation. With their emphasis on the inefficiencies of rent seeking, the Virginia School practices mainly normative economic theory; behavior and institutions are judged according to the degree of efficiency in the allocation of scarce resources. In what has become a classic contribution, Tullock (1967) has shown that the inefficiency of monopoly consists not only of what is known as the Harberger triangle, but that through the competition between potential monopolists for monopoly rights the inefficiencies can increase with the Tullock rectangle. Furthermore, the potentially disadvantaged consumers will apply scarce resources to prevent the creation of a monopoly if possible. After the creation of a monopoly, scarce resources will be wasted because the monopolist will protect his monopoly rights against possible threats, from potential competitors and disadvantaged consumers. Finally, monopoly rights can cause x-inefficiencies: the monopolist does not produce a given level of production at minimal costs (Leibenstein, 1966; see, however, Stigler, 1976). In Stigler’s and Peltzman’s view a non-contestable monopolist will not aim for regulation because with regulation no higher income can be achieved. However, according to the Virginians, the incentives for regulation remain, though now from the side of bureaucracy and politics. The interests of bureaucrats and politicians can be served through giving certain groups of consumers the privilege of cross-subsidies in a disguised form (Crew and Roley, 1988). Furthermore, in the view of Chicago, redistributive instruments such as taxation, subsidies or regulation are equivalent either to respect of efficiency or to the precise nature of political equilibrium. The Virginians point, however, to the visibility of taxes and subsidies and the waste of scarce resources through the reactions provoked by such instruments. Regulation gives more room to politicians and bureaucrats to put their own objectives into effect. Between regulation and taxation there are also large differences concerning the degree of inefficiency. Traditionally, account is taken only of the Harberger triangle, which is actually smaller with taxation under certain circumstances than with regulation. It is to be expected, however, that the Tullock rectangle inefficiencies will be larger with taxation than with regulation. The rent-seeking theorems have been criticized for the overestimation of the assumed losses of welfare. It is not likely that monopolists are forced to use the entire Tullock rectangle in order to acquire their monopoly and, furthermore, rent-seeking outgoings have positive effects on welfare (Varian, 1989). A fundamental criticism is given by Samuels and Mercuro (1984), who judge that the limiting assumptions lead to misleading conclusions and that the normative analyses are too selective and limited to serve as a basis for policy.
5000
General Theories of Regulation
245
15. Regulation and Deregulation Once the Chicago theory of regulation had been developed, social developments seemed to refute it. While this theory explained regulation as aiming for transfers of income, at the end of the 1970s and the beginning of the 1980s, many complexes of rules were dispensed with in a process of deregulation. This deregulation was mainly concerned with economic regulation of sectors such as transport (airlines and freight), telecommunications, energy and the financial sector. The social regulation increased in scale, even though the nature of this regulation changed (more cost-benefit analyses, more risk analyses, more performance standards, fewer specification standards) (Winston and Crandall, 1994). For a description of this process of deregulation and re-regulation see for example Bailey (1986), Hahn (1990) and Kahn (1990) for the USA, and Vickers (1991) for the UK. From the theories of regulation discussed here, various explanations can be derived for this process of deregulation (see Den Hertog, 1996; Peltzman, 1989; Keeler, 1984). From public interest theory two explanations of deregulation can be derived. In the first place, it is possible that the cause of market failure is removed by technological or demand factors. Through a strongly increasing demand for, for example, transport facilities, a natural monopoly can change into a competitive market. Furthermore, technological developments such as communication via satellite instead of by cable can undermine natural monopolies. A second explanation for deregulation is that there are more efficient alternatives to regulation for solving the problem of market failure. New instruments may have been developed such as franchising or yardstick competition (Kay and Vickers, 1990). It is also possible that better insight exists into the envisaged and non-envisaged effects of regulations; see the literature cited under point (b) in Section 7 as well as Baldwin (1990), Stewart (1985), Wilson (1984) and Wolf (1979). Finally, it is possible that theoretical developments, such as, for example, contestable markets, inspire more confidence in the operation of the market mechanism (Bailey and Baumol, 1984). At least four causes of deregulation can be derived from the Chicago theory of regulation. In the first place, shifts can come about in the relative political power of pressure groups, for example, as a result of the more efficient combating of free-riding, the more efficient use of media or as a result of special entrepreneurship (Ralph Nader). In the second place, deregulation can arise when politically effective groups believe that they can better promote their economic interests in an unregulated market, for example by self regulation. In the third place, deregulation can be the result of declining profits, so that the political yield of regulation declines. The fixing of prices or the introduction of entry restrictions in sectors consisting of multiple companies, such as airlines or freight, will result in competition taking place in other dimensions of the
246
General Theories of Regulation
5000
product. Competition in the area of service, such as the frequency of transport, will result in a decline in profits. In Becker’s view, that leads to a decreased pressure from the branch involved and an increased pressure from consumers for price reduction. In Peltzman, politics will seek more fruitful regulation yields. Finally, deregulation can be accounted for by increasing deadweight costs. These costs increase in the course of time because substitutes for regulated products are developed and because costly methods of evading and avoiding particular regulations are discovered. The deregulation of sectors such as transport, telecommunications and banking, can then be seen as an echo of the regulation movement of the 1930s. Increasing deadweight costs are in the second place a result of the increasing marginal tax rates in the 1960s and 1970s. According to Becker, this stimulated the pressure on tax payers who were able to collect more political support than the groups who had the benefit of social security programs. According to the public choice theories of regulation, deregulation can first of all be accounted for by a changed balance of power of pressure groups. In the second place, structure-induced equilibrium can be disturbed by the actions of political entrepreneurs, such as the chairpersons of regulatory commissions. In the third place, politicians can seek political support for deregulation by providing voters with information about the inefficiencies of regulation. Alternatively, politicians could try to use the complexities of regulatory issues by claiming that economic deregulation would greatly advance economic and social welfare. A general comparison of deregulation practice and the various theories gives a mixed picture (see Peltzman, 1989; Noll, 1989b). If the public interest theory were generally applicable, deregulation would have taken place sooner. On the other hand, events such as the deregulation of freight are once again difficult to account for with the Chicago theory: in this sector profit was being made and the employees also had much to lose from deregulation. Various circumstances including political entrepreneurship were considered to be applicable and have also played a role in practice. In other cases, Congress has played no role and the legislation was changed after deregulation was already a fact. Also the expectations with respect to the future development of regulation and deregulation are mixed. On the one hand there are researchers such as Kahn (1990) and Hahn (1990) who are convinced of the relative efficiency of the market mechanism and of regulation mechanisms that support and sustain the market. They see a greater role for government in the area of competition politics and in setting constraints to the functioning of markets, such as in the area of safety. On the other hand, there are voices, such as that of Cudahy (1993), who assumes that the process of deregulation will be followed in the downward phase of the business cycle by a phase of renewed regulation. The disadvantages of deregulation, such as predatory pricing, fluctuating prices and
5000
General Theories of Regulation
247
discriminatory prices, insufficient service, increased lack of safety, job insecurity and redundancy for large groups of employees will ring in a new age of regulation.
16. Summary This article makes a distinction between three types of theories of regulation: public interest theories, the Chicago theory of regulation and the public choice theories. The Chicago theory is mainly directed at the explanation of economic regulation; public interest theories and public choice theories envisage in addition to that an account of social regulation. The core of the diverse theories is discussed as well as the criticisms that have been leveled at them. It can be derived from the theories in what sectors regulation can be expected and what form the regulation will take. The extent to which these theories are also able to account for deregulation, and the expectations for the future, are discussed.
Acknowledgment The author is grateful for the valuable comments made by Anthony Ogus and two anonymous referees, none of whom may be held responsible for the views expressed in this paper.
Bibliography of General Theories of Regulation (5000) Abrams, Burton A. and Lewis, Kenneth A. (1987), ‘A Median Voter Model of Economic Regulation’, 52 Public Choice, 125-142. Ackley, Gardner (1972), ‘Observations on Phase II Price and Wage Controls’, 1 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 173-190. Aghion, Philippe and Hermalin, Benjamin E. (1990), ‘Legal Restrictions on Private Contracts Can Enhance Efficiency’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 381-409. Akerlof, George A. (1970), ‘The Markets for ‘Lemons’: Qualitative Uncertainty and the Market Mechanism’, 84 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 488-500. Amacher, Ryan C. et al. (1987), ‘The Behavior of Regulatory Activity over the Business Cycle: An Empirical Test’, in Mackay, Robert J., Miller, James C., III and Ya (eds), Public Choice and Regulation: A View from Inside the Federal Trade Commission, Stanford, Hoover Institute Press, Stanford University, 145-153. Ames, Edward (1976), ‘The Firm and Price Control’, 29(1) Journal of Economics and Business, 10-15. Ames, Edward (1977), ‘The Consumer and Wage Price Controls’, 30 Journal of Economics and Business, 15-22. Anton, James J. and Gertler, Paul J. (1988), ‘External Markets and Regulation’, 37 Journal of Public
248
General Theories of Regulation
5000
Economics, 243-260. Aragon, George (1980), ‘Mandatory Price Controls: Managing a Response’, 15(3) Business Economics, 25-31. Arnould, Richard J. (1972), ‘Pricing Professional Services: A Case Study of the Legal Services Industry’, 38 Southern Economic Journal, 495-507. Arrow, Kenneth J. (1970), ‘The Organization of Economic Activity: Issues Pertinent to the Choice of Market Versus Nonmarket Allocation’, in Haveman, Robert H. and Margolis, Julius (eds), Public Expenditure and Policy Analysis, Chicago, Rand MacNally College Publishing Company, 67-81. Arrow, Kenneth J. (1985), ‘The Potentials and Limits of the Market in Resource Allocation’, in Feiwel, G.R. (ed.), Issues in Contempory Microeconomics and Welfare, London, The Macmillan Press, 107-124. Asch, Peter (1988), Consumer Safety Regulation, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Averch, H. and Johnson, L.L. (1962), ‘Behaviour of the Firm under Regulatory Constraints’, 52 American Economic Review, 1052-1069. Baeck, L., Ongena, H. and Cools, J.P. (1987), ‘Begripsbepaling en Situering van het Dereguleringsverschijnsel in de Geschiedenis van het Economisch Denken (Definition and Sketch of the Deregulation Phenomenon in the History of Economic Thought)’, in X (ed.), 18de Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Brussel 8 en 9 mei 1987, Sociaal-economische Deregulering, Brussel, V.E.H.U.B., 29-47. Bailey, Elizabeth E. (1986), ‘Deregulation: Causes and Consequences’, 234 Science, 1211-1216. Bailey, Elizabeth E. (ed.) (1987), Public Regulation: New Perspectives on Institution, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 404 p. Bailey, Elizabeth E. and Baumol, William J. (1984), ‘Deregulation and the Theory of Contestable Markets’, 1 Yale Journal of Regulation, 111-137. Baldwin, G.R. and Veljanovski, Cento G. (1982), Regulation and Cost-Benefit Analysis - The U.S. Experience, Oxford, Centre for Socio-Legal Studies. Baldwin, Robert E. (1990), ‘Why Rules Don’t Work’, 53 Modern Law Review, 321-337. Barcella, Mary L. (1984), ‘In Defense of Price Controls for ‘Old’ Natural Gas’, 19(4) Business Economics, 24-33. Baron, David P. (1988), ‘Regulation and Legislative Choice’, 19 Rand Journal of Economics, 467-477. Bartel, Ann P. and Thomas, Lacy Glenn (1985), ‘Direct and Indirect Effects of Regulation: A New Look at OSHA’s Impact’, 28 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-25. Bartel, Ann P. and Thomas, Lacy Glenn (1987), ‘Predation through Regulation: The Wage and Profit Effects of the Occupational Safety and Health Administration and the Environmental Protection Agency’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 239-264. Barzel, Yoram (1982), ‘Measurement Cost and the Organisation of Markets’, 25 Journal of Law and Economics, 27-48. Barzel, Yoram (1985), ‘Transaction Costs: Are They Just Costs?’, 141 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 4-16. Bator, Francis M. (1958), ‘The Anatomy of Market Failure’, 72 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 351-379. Baum, Herbert (1976), ‘Das Stabilisierungspotential Staatlich Administrierter Preise (On the Stabilization Effects of Public Regulated Prices)’, 190 Jahrbuch für National Ökonomie und Statistik, 349-376.
5000
General Theories of Regulation
249
Baum, Herbert (1978), ‘Verteilungswirkungen der Staatlichen Preispolitik (Effects of Public Regulated Prices on Distribution of Income)’, 193 Jahrbuch für National Ökonomie und Statistik, 220-243. Baumol, William J. (1977), ‘On the Proper Cost Tests for Natural Monopoly in a Multiproduct Industry’, Dec. American Economic Review. Baumol, William J. (1986), ‘Minimum and Maximum Pricing Principles for Residual Regulation’, in Baumol, William J. (ed.), Microtheory: Applications and Origins, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 151-164. Baumol, William J. and Klevorick, Alvin K. (1970), ‘Input Choices and Rate-of-Return Regulation: an Overview of the Discussion’, 1 Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, 162-190. Baumol, William J. and Ordover, Janusz A. (1985), ‘Use of Antitrust to Subvert Competition’, 28 Journal of Law and Economics, 247-265. Baumol, William J., Panzar, John C. and Willig, Robert D. (1982), Contestable Markets and the Theory of Industry Structure, San Diego, Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. Beales, J. Howard III (1980), ‘The Economics of Regulating the Professions’, in Blair, Roger D. and Rubin, Stephen (eds), Regulating the Professions: A Public-Policy Symposium, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Beales, J. Howard III, Craswell, Richard and Salop, Steven (1981), ‘The Efficient Regulation of Consumer Information’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 491-544. Beck, R., Hoskins, C. and Connolly, J.M. (1992), ‘Rent Extraction through Political Extortion: An Empirical Examination’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 217-224. Becker, Gary S. (1983), ‘A Theory of Competition among Pressure Groups for Political Influence’, XCVIII Quarterly Journal of Economics, 371-400. Becker, Gary S. (1985a), ‘Public Policies, Pressure Groups, and Dead Weight Costs’, 28 Journal of Public Economics, 329-347. Becker, Gary S. (1985b), ‘Pressure Groups and Political Behavior’, in Coe, Richard D. and Wilber, Charles K. (eds), Capitalism and Democracy: Schumpeter Revisited, Indiana, University of Notre Dame Press, 120-146. Becker, Gilbert (1986), ‘The Public Interest Hypothesis Revisited: A New Test of Peltzman’s Theory of Regulation’, 49 Public Choice, 223-234. Bell, Joe A. (1988), ‘The Disinterest in Deregulation: Comment’, 78 American Economic Review, 282-283. Benston, George J. (1989), ‘Party Realignments and the Growth of Federal Economic Regulation, 1861-1986: Comments’, 2 Journal of Financial Services Research, 227-229. Blackmon, B. Glenn, Jr and Zeckhauser, Richard (1991), ‘Mispriced Equity: Regulated Rates for Auto Insurance in Massachusetts’, 81 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 65-69. Blaug, Mark (1993), ‘Pieter Hennipman on Paretian Welfare Economics: a Comment’, 1 De Economist, 127-129. Boardman, Anthony E. and Vining, Aidan R. (1989), ‘Ownership and Performance in Competitive Environments: A Comparison of the Performance of Private, Mixed, and State-owned Enterprises’, 32 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-33. Boehm, E.A. (1972), ‘Prices and Incomes Policies in the United States’, 18 Australian Economic Review, 37-46. Bohm, Peter (1987), Social Efficiency, London, Macmillan.
250
General Theories of Regulation
5000
Bollard, Alan (1987), ‘More Market: The Deregulation of Industry’, in Bollard, Alan and Buckle, Robert (eds), Economic Liberalisation in New Zealand, Wellington, Allen and Unwin, 25-45. Bollard, Alan and Buckle, Robert (eds) (1987), Economic Liberalisation in New Zealand, Wellington, Allen and Unwin, 364 p. Borcherding, Thomas, Pommerehne, Werner W. and Schneider, Friedrich (1982), ‘Comparing the Efficiency of Private and Public Production: An International Survey’, 89 Zeitschrift für Nationalökonomie, 127-156. Boudreaux, Donald J. and Ekelund, Robert B., Jr (1987), ‘Regulation as an Exogenous Response to Market Failure: A Neo-Schumpeterian Response’, 143 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 537-554. Bourgoignie, Th. (1973), ‘Overheid en Bedrijfsleven: La reglementation des prix en Belgique (Price Regulation in Belgium)’, 27 Economisch en Sociaal Tijdschrift, 387-400. Bowles, Roger A. and Phillips, Jennifer (1977), ‘Solicitors’ Renumeration: A Critique of Recent Developments in Conveyancing’, 40 Modern Law Review, 639-650. Boyer, Kenneth D. (1987), ‘The Costs of Price Regulation: Lessons from Railroad Deregulation’, 18 Rand Journal of Economics, 408-416. Boyer, Marcel (1995), La Réglementation Incitative (Inciting Regulations), Montréal, Centre Interuniversitaire de Recherche en Analyse des Organisations. Bracke, F. (1987), ‘Deregulering en algemeen belang: 1. Bronnen en doelstellingen (Deregulation and General Interest: Sources and Purposes)’, in X (ed.), 18de Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Brussel 8 en 9 mei 1987, Sociaal-Economische Deregulering, Brussel, V.E.H.U.B., 101-122. Bradley, Ian and Price, Catherine (1988), ‘The Economic Regulation of Private Industries by Price Constraints’, 37 Journal of Industrial Economics, 99-106. Braeutigam, Ronald R. (1989), ‘Optimal Policies for Natural Monopolies’, in Schmalensee, Richard and Willig, Robert D. (eds), Handbook of Industrial Organization II, Amsterdam, North Holland. Braeutigam, Ronald R. and Panzar, John C. (1989), ‘Diversification Incentives Under “Price-Based” and “Cost-Based” Regulation’, 20 Rand Journal of Economics, 373-391. Breyer, Stephen G. (1979), ‘Analysing Regulatory Failure: Mismatches, Less Restrictive Alternatives, and Reform’, 92 Harvard Law Review, 549-609. Reprinted in Ogus, Anthony I. and Veljanovski, Cento G. (eds) (1984), Readings in the Economics of Law and Regulation, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 234-239. Breyer, Stephen G. (1982), Regulation and its Reform, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 472 p. Breyer, Stephen G. (1984), ‘Reforming Regulation’, 59 Tulane Law Review, 4-23. Breyer, Stephen G. (1985), ‘Economists and Economic Regulation’, 47 University of Pittsburgh Law Review, 205-218. Brock, William A. and Evans, David S. (1985), ‘The Economics of Regulatory Tiering’, 16 Rand Journal of Economics, 398-409. Brown, Donald J. and Heal, Geoffrey M. (1985), ‘The Optimality of Regulated Pricing: A General Equilibrium Analysis’, in Alisprantis, C.D., Burkinshaw, O. and Rothman D.J. (eds), Advances in Equilibrium Theory, New York, Springer, 43-54. Browning, Edgar K. and Culbertson, William Patton, Jr (1974), ‘A Theory of Black Markets under Price Control: Competition and Monopoly’, 12 Economic Inquiry, 175-189. Brunner, Karl and Meltzer, Allan H. (1976), ‘The Economics of Price and Wage Controls: An
5000
General Theories of Regulation
251
Introduction’, 2 Journal of Monetary Economics, 1-6. Buchanan, James M. and Tullock, Gordon (1975), ‘Polluters’ Profits and Political Response: Direct Controls Versus Taxes’, 65 American Economic Review, 139-147. Buchanan, James M., Tollison, Robert D. and Tullock, Gordon (1980), Toward a Theory of the Rent-Seeking Society, College Station, Texas A&M; University Press. Button, Kenneth J. and Swann, Dennis (eds) (1989), The Age of Regulatory Reform, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 339 p. Caillaud, B., Guesnerie, Roger, Rey, P. and Tirole, Jean (1988), ‘Government Intervention in Production and Incentives Theory: A Review of Recent Contributions’, 19 Rand Journal of Economics, 1-26. Campos, Jose Edgardo L. (1989), ‘Legislative Institutions, Lobbying, and the Endogenous Choice of Regulatory Instrument: A Political Economy Approach to Instrument Choice’, 5 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 333-353. Candler, Wilfred and Kennedy, George (1975), ‘Food Cost Stabilization Using Food Coupons’, 23 Canadian Journal of Agricultural Economics, 33-45. Carlton, Dennis W. and Perloff, Jeffrey M. (1990), Modern Industrial Organisation, Illinois, Glenview. Carlton, Dennis W. and Perloff, Jeffrey M. (1994), Modern Industrial Organisation, 2nd edn, New York, Harper collins. Carney, William J. (1982), The Changing Role of the Corporate Attorney, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Castles, Francis G. (1988), Australian Public Policy and Economic Vulnerability: A Comparative and Historical Perspective, Winchester, Allen and Unwin, 184 p. Chapman, Bruce and Quinn, J.J. (1982), ‘Efficiency, Liberty and Equality: Three Ethical Justifications for Regulatory Reform’, 20 Osgoode Hall Law Journal, 512-535. Cherkes, Martin, Friedman, Joseph and Spivak, Avia (1986), ‘The Disinterest in Deregulation: Comment’, 76 American Economic Review, 559-563. Cherot, Jean-Yves (1987), ‘Elements pour une Théorie de la Réglementation (Elements for a Theory of Regulation)’, 2 Revue de la Recherche Juridique. Chesney, James D. (1982), ‘The Politics of Regulation: An Assessment of Winners and Losers’, 19 Inquiry, 235-245. Cheung, Steven N.S. (1974), ‘A Theory of Price Control’, 17 Journal of Law and Economics, 53-71. Coase, Ronald H. (1960), ‘The Problem of Social Cost’, 3 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-44. Reprinted in Ackermann, Bruce A. (1975), Economic Foundations of Property Law, Boston, Little Brown, 17-22. Reprinted in Medema, Steven G. (1995), The Legacy of Ronald Coase in Economic Analysis, Vol. 2, Aldershot, Edward Elgar Publishing, 1995, 5-48. Reprinted in Coase, Ronald H. (1988), The Firm, the Market and the Law, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Coase, Ronald H. (1974), ‘The Lighthouse in Economics’, 23 Journal of Law and Economics, 357-376. Cochrane, James L. and Griepentrog, Gary L. (1978), ‘Sulphur and the U.S. Government: Price Fighting in the 1960s’, 16 Economic Inquiry, 360-384. Colander, David (1984), ‘Galbraith and the Theory of Price Control’, 7 Journal of Post Keynesian Economics, 30-42. Cooter, Robert D. and Rubin, Edward L. (1988), ‘Orders and Incentives as Regulatory Methods: The Expedited Funds Availability Act of 1987’, 35 UCLA Law Review, 1115-1186.
252
General Theories of Regulation
5000
Cosentino, Fabrizio (1995), ‘Il Dilemma dell’Economia Informale: Proibizione o Deregolamentazione? (The Dilemma of Informal Economy: Prohibition or Dergulation?)’, Politica del Diritto, 635-653. Cottle, Rex L. and Wallace, Myles S. (1983), ‘Economic Effects of Non Binding Price Constraints’, 31 Journal of Industrial Economics, 469-474. Coursey, Don L. and Smith, Vernon L. (1983), ‘Price Controls in a Posted Offer Market’, 73 American Economic Review, 218-221. Cousineau, Jean Michel and Lacroix, Robert (1978), ‘L’Impact de la Politique Canadienne de Controle des Prix et des Revenus sur les Ententes Salariales (The Effect of Canadian Price and Income Control Policy on the Wages)’, 4 Canadian Public Policy, 88-100. Cowen, Tyler (ed.) (1988), The Theory of Market Failure, Fairfax, George Mason University Press. Cox, Charles C. (1980), ‘The Enforcement of Public Price Controls’, 88 Journal of Political Economy, 887-916. Crandall, Robert W. (1983), ‘Deregulation: The U.S. Experience’, 139 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 419-434. Crandall, Robert W. (1986), ‘Economic Rents as a Barrier to Deregulation’, 6 Cato Journal, 173-194. Crew, Michael A. and Rowley, Charles K. (1986), ‘Deregulation as an Instrument in Industrial Policy’, 142 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 52-70. Crew, Michael A. and Rowley, Charles K. (1987), ‘The Myth of Disinterest in Deregulation’, in Rowley, Charles K., Tollison, Robert D. and Tullock, Gordon (eds), The Political Economy of Rent-Seeking, Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 163-178. Crew, Michael A. and Rowley, Charles K. (1988), ‘Toward a Public Choice Theory of Monopoly Regulation’, 57 Public Choice, 49-67. Csikos Nagy, Bela (1980), ‘The New Path of Hungarian Price Policy’, 118 Nationalokonomisk Tidsskrift, 201-211. Cudahy, Richard D. (1993), ‘The Coming Demise of Deregulation’, 10 Yale Journal on Regulation, 1-15. Cukierman, Alex and Leiderman, Leonardo (1984), ‘Price Controls and the Variability of Relative Prices’, 16 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 271-284. Curwen, P.J. (1979), ‘The Price Commission Report on Books. A Short Critique’, 27 Journal of Industrial Economics, 295-299. Daems, H. and De Grauwe, Paul (1981), ‘Determinanten van de overheidsreglementering (Determinants of Government Regulation)’, in X (ed.), Overheidsinterventies, Effectiviteit en Efficiëntie. Vijftiende Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Leuven, Departement Toegepaste Economische Wetenschappen, 25-41. Dahlman, Carl J. (1979), ‘The Problem of Externality’, 22 Journal of Law and Economics, 141-162. Darby, Michael R. (1976a), ‘Price and Wage Controls: The First Two Years’, 2 Journal of Monetary Economics, 235-263. Darby, Michael R. (1976b), ‘Price and Wage Controls: Further Evidence’, 2 Journal of Monetary Economics, 269-271. Darby, Michael R. and Karni, Edi (1973), ‘Free Competition and the Optimal Amount of Fraud’, 16 Journal of Law and Economics, 67-88. Daughety, Andrew F. and Forsythe, Robert (1987), ‘The Effects of Industry-Wide Price Regulation on
5000
General Theories of Regulation
253
Industrial Organization’, 3 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 397-434. Daves, D.W. and Christensen, L.R. (1980), ‘The Relative Efficiency of Public and Private Firms in a Competitive Environment: The Case of Canadian Railroads’, 88 Journal of Political Economy, 958-976. Davies, David G. (1971), ‘The Efficiency of Public versus Private Firms: The Case of Australia’s Two Airlines’, 14 Journal of Law and Economics, 149-165. Davies, David G. (1977), ‘Property Rights and Economic Efficiency - the Australian Airlines Revisited’, 20 Journal of Law and Economics, 223-226. De Bondt, Raymond (1978), ‘Industrial Economic Aspects of Belgian Price Regulation’, 23 Tijdschrift voor Economie en Management, 249-264. De Bondt, Raymond and Van Herck, G. (1981), ‘Prijsbeleid en Economische Efficiëntie (Price Policy and Economic Efficiency)’, in X (ed.), 18de Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Brussel 8 en 9 mei 1987, Sociaal-economische Deregulering, Brussel, V.E.H.U.B., 253-278. Deacon, Robert T. (1978), ‘An Economic Analysis of Gasoline Price Controls’, 18 Natural Resources Journal, 801-814. Deacon, Robert T. and Sonstelie, Jon (1989a), ‘The Welfare Costs of Rationing by Waiting’, 27 Economic Inquiry, 179-196. Deacon, Robert T. and Sonstelie, Jon (1989b), ‘Price Controls and Rent Seeking Behavior in Developing Countries’, 17 World Development, 1945-1954. Deaton, Thomas, Tollison, Robert D. and Crafton, Steven M. (1976), ‘A Note on the Theory of Black Markets under Price Controls’, 14 Economic Inquiry, 300-3304. Degraba, Patrick J. (1987), ‘The Effects of Price Restrictions on Competition Between National and Local Firms’, 18 Rand Journal of Economics, 333-347. Demsetz, Harold (1968), ‘Information and Efficiency: Another Viewpoint’, 12 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-22. Demsetz, Harold (1976), ‘Economics as a Guide to Antitrust Regulation’, 19 Journal of Law and Economics, 371-384. Demski, Joel S. and Sappington, David E.M. (1987), ‘Hierarchical Regulatory Control’, 18 Rand Journal of Economics, 369-383. Den Hertog, Johan A. (1993), ‘An Economic Analysis of Self-Regulation of Physicians in the Netherlands’, in Faure, Michael, Finsinger, Jorg, Siegers, Jacques and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds), Regulation of Professions, Antwerpen, Maklu, 195-225. Den Hertog, Johan A. (1996), ‘The Policy of Deregulation in The Netherlands’, 40 European Economic Review, 979-987. Derthick, Martha and Quirk, Paul J. (1985), ‘Why the Regulators Chose to Deregulate’, in Noll, Roger G. (ed.), Regulatory Policy and the Social Sciences, Berkeley, University of California Press, 200-231. Dewees, Donald N. (ed.) (1983), The Regulation of Quality: Products, Services, Workplaces and the Environment, London, Butterworths. Diver, Colin S. (1980), ‘A Theory of Regulatory Enforcement’, 28 Public Policy, 257-299. Dnes, Antony W. (1981), ‘The Case of Monopoly and Pollution’, 30 Journal of Industrial Economics, 213-216. Dnes, Antony W. (1996), ‘An Economic Analysis of the BSE Scare’, 43 Scottish Journal of Political Economy, 343-348. Dnes, Antony W. (1997), ‘The Future of the British Post Office’, 4 European Journal of Law and
254
General Theories of Regulation
5000
Economics, 93-102. Doherty, Neil A. and Garven, James R. (1986), ‘Price Regulation in Property Liability Insurance: A Contingent Claims Approach’, 41 Journal of Finance, 1031-1050. Downs, Anthony (1957), An Economic Theory of Democracy, New York, Harper and Row. Duggan, A.J. (1991), ‘Some Reflections on Consumer Protection and the Law Reform Process’, 17 Monash University Law Review, 145-162. Duharcourt, Pierre (1988), ‘‘Théories’ et ‘Concept’ de la Régulation (Regulation as a Theory and as a Concept)’, 22(5) Economies et Sociétés, 135-161. Dunleavy, Patrick S. (1991), Bureaucracy and Public Choice: Economic Explanations in Political Science, Brighton, Harvester Press. Dworkin, Ronald M. (1981), ‘What is Equality?’, 10 Philosophy And Public Affairs, 185-345. Eads, George C. (1971), ‘A.E. Kahn: The Economics of Regulation’, 2 Bell Journal of Economics, 678-682. Edwards, Clark (1974), ‘Exchangeable Coupon Gas Rationing’, 26(3) Agricultural Economics Research, 55-68. Ehemann, Christian (1974), ‘General Disequilibrium, Fiscal Policy, and a Wage Price Freeze’, 12 Economic Inquiry, 35-52. Ekelund, Robert B., Jr and Tollison, Robert D. (1981), Mercantilism as a Rent Seeking Society: Economic Regulation in Historical Perspective, College Station, Texas A&M; University Press, 169 p. Erickson, Edward W. et al. (1978), ‘The Political Economy of Crude Oil Price Controls’, 18 Natural Resources Journal, 787-780. Escarmelle, Jean Francois and Hujoel, Luc (1986), ‘Privatization and Deregulation. Its Implementation in Belgium’, 57 Annals of Public and Cooperative Economy, 253-273. Evely, Richard W. (1976), ‘The Effects of the Price Code’, 77 National Institute Economic Review, 50-59. Fenili, Robert N. and Lane, William C. (1985), ‘Thou Shalt Not Cut Prices! Sales-Below-Cost Laws for Gas Stations’, 9(5) Regulation, 31-35. Fiedler, Edgar R. (1972), ‘The Price Wage Stabilization Program’, 1 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 199-1206. Flowers, Marilyn R. and Stroup, Richard L. (1979), ‘Coupon Rationing and Rent Seeking Bureaucrats’, 34 Public Choice, 473-479. Frey, Bruno S. (1978), Modern Political Economy, Oxford, Martin Robertson. Frey, Bruno S. (1983), Democratic Economic Policy: A Theoretical Introduction, Oxford, Basil Blackwell. Frey, Bruno S. and Ramser, Hans Jürgen (1986), ‘Where are the Limits of Regulation?’, 142 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 571-580. Gehrig, Th. and Jost, P.J. (1995), ‘Quacks, Lemons and Self-Regulation: a Welfare Analysis’, 7 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 309-325. Gey, Steven G. (1980), ‘The Political Economy of the Dormant Commerce Clause’, 17 New York University Review of Law and Social Change, 9-901. Ghali, Moheb A. (1977), ‘The Effect of Controls on Wages, Prices, and Strike Activity’, 30 Journal of Economics and Business, 23-30. Gifford, Adam, Jr (1987), ‘Rent Seeking and Nonprice Competition’, 27(2) Quarterly Review of Economics and Business, 63-70. Gilligan, Thomas W., Marshall, William J. and Weingast, Barry R. (1989), ‘Regulation and the Theory
5000
General Theories of Regulation
255
of Legislative Choice: The Interstate Commerce Act of 1887,’ 32 Journal of Law and Economics, 35-61. Gitlow, Abraham L. (1976), ‘Are Peacetime Wage Price Controls Effective?’, 23 Rivista Internazionale di Scienze Economiche e Commerciali, 722-739. Golbert, J.P. and Lowenstein, Paul (1982), ‘The Court and the Marketplace: Who Should Regulate Whom?’, 34 Baylor Law Review, 39-65. Goldberg, Victor P. (1976), ‘Regulation and Administered Contracts’, 7 Bell Journal of Economics, 426-448. Reprinted in Pierce, Richard (ed.) (1994), The Economics of Regulation: Cases and Materials, Cincinnati, Anderson Publishing. Goldberg, Victor P. (1988), ‘Clarifying the Record: A Comment’, 144 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 885-888. Goodman, John C. and Porter, Philip K. (1988), ‘Theory of Competitive Regulatory Equilibrium’, 59 Public Choice, 51-166. Gordon, Daniel V. (1988), ‘The Effect of Price Deregulation on the Competitive Behaviour of Retail Drug Firms’, 20 Applied Economics, 641-652. Gordon, Robert J. (1972), ‘Wage Price Controls and the Shifting Phillips Curve’, 2 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 385-421. Gordon, Robert J. (1973), ‘The Response of Wages and Prices to the First Two Years of Controls’, 3 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 765-778. Granziol, Markus J. (1985), ‘Direct Price Controls as a Source of Instability in the Interest Rate/Inflation Rate Relationship’, 9 Journal of Banking and Finance, 275-288. Greco, Anthony J. (1987), ‘State Fluid Milk Regulation: Antitrust and Price Controls’, 32 Antitrust Bulletin, 165-188. Gribbin, J.D. (1978), ‘The United Kingdom 1977 Price Commission Act and Competition Policy’, 23 Antitrust Bulletin, 405-439. Gruenspecht, Howard K. and Lave, L.B. (1989), ‘The Economics of Health, Safety and Environmental Regulation’, in Schmalensee, Richard and Willig, Robert D. (eds), Handbook of Industrial Organization II, Amsterdam, North Holland, 1508-1550. Guesnerie, Roger (1988), ‘Regulation as an Adverse Selection Problem: An Introduction to the Literature’, 32 European Economic Review, 473-481. Haddock, David D. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1987), ‘Regulation on Demand: A Private Interest Model, with an Application to Insider Trading Regulation’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 311-352. Hahn, Robert W. (1990), ‘Regulation: Past, Present and Future’, 13 Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy, 167-228. Hahn, Robert W. (ed.) (1996), Risks, Costs and Lives Saved, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Hahn, Robert W. and Hird, John A. (1991), ‘The Costs and Benefits of Regulation: Review and Synthesis’, 8 Yale Journal on Regulation, 233-278. Haley, John O. (1986), ‘Administrative Guidance versus Formal Regulation: Resolving the Paradox of Industrial Policy’, in Saxonhouse, Gary R. and Yamamura, Kozo (eds), Law and Trade Issues of the Japanese Economy: Amer, Seattle, University of Washington Press, 107-128. Hamilton, Mary T. (1974), ‘Price Controls in 1973: Strategies and Problems’, 64 American Economic Review, 100-104. Hannequart, Achille and Greffe, Xavier (1985), Economie des Interventions Sociales (Economics of Social Interventions), Paris, Economica, 264 p.
256
General Theories of Regulation
5000
Harmathy, Attila (1979), ‘A Gazdasági Szabályozók és a Szerzödések kapcsolata (The Connection between Economic Regulation and Contracts)’, 12 Jogtudományi Közlöny, 906-913. Harris, Richard A. and Milkis, Sidney M. (1989), The Politics of Regulatory Change: A Tale of Two Agencies, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 331 p. Hartle, Douglas and Trebilcock, Michael J. (1982), ‘Regulatory Reform and the Political Process’, 20 Osgoode Hall Law Journal, 643-677. Hekathorn, Douglas D. and Maser, Steven M. (1987), ‘Bargaining and the Sources of Transaction Costs: The Case of Government Regulation’, 3 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 69-98. Helpman, Elhanan (1988), ‘Macroeconomic Effects of Price Controls: The Role of Market Structure’, 98 Economic Journal, 340-354. Hempel, George H. (1973), ‘Wage and Price Controls for State and Local Governments: Their Effectiveness and the Potential Effects of Phase III’, 21 Public Policy, 425-436. Hennipman, P. (1992), ‘The Reasoning of a Great Methodologist: Mark Blaug on the Nature of Paretian Welfare Economics’, 4 De Economist, 413-445. High, Jack (1990), ‘Can Rents Run Uphill? A Note on the Theory of Regulation’, 65 Public Choice, 229-237. Hill, Raymond D. (1979), ‘Profit Regulation in Property - Liability Insurance’, 10 Bell Journal of Economics, 172-191. Hillman, Arye L. and Schnytzer, Adi (1986), ‘Illegal Economic Activities and Purges in a Soviet-Type Economy: A Rent-Seeking Perspective’, 6 International Review of Law and Economics, 87-99. Hirshleifer, Jack and Riley, John G. (1979), ‘The Analytics of Uncertainty and Information’, 17 Journal of Economic Literature, 1375-1421. Hochman, Harold M. and Rodgers, James D. (1969), ‘Pareto Optimal Redistribution’, 59(4) American Economic Review, 542-557. Hochman, Harold M. and Rodgers, James D. (1970), ‘Pareto Optimal Redistribution: Reply’, 60(5) American Economic Review, 997-1002. Héglund, Bengt (1984), Spelet om Resurserna i den Svenska Blandekonomin (The Swedish Mixed Economy), Lund, Dialogos. Holcombe, Randall G. and Holcombe, Lora P. (1986), ‘The Market for Regulation’, 142 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 684-696. Horwich, George (1990), ‘Disasters and Market Response’, 9 Cato Journal, 531-555. Houston, Douglas A. (1987), ‘The Mixed Interest in Regulation and Deregulation’, 63 Land Economics, 403-405. Houthakker, Hendrik S. (1972), ‘Are Controls the Answer?’, 54 Review of Economics and Statistics, 231-233. Huerta De Soto, Jesús (1992), Socialismo, Cálculo Económico y Función Empresarial (Socialism, Economic Calculation and Enterpreneurship), Madrid, Uni¢n Editorial, 442p. Huerta De Soto, Jesús (1995), ‘Enterpreneurship and the Economic Analysis of Socialism’, in Gerrit Meijer (ed.), New Perspectives on Austrian Economics, Routledge, London, 228-253. Huyse, Luc (1987), ‘Deregulering en Algemeen Belang: 2. Deregulering als Maatschappelijke Reconstructie (Deregulation and General Interest: Deregulation as Social Reconstruction)’, in X (ed.), 18de Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Brussel 8 en 9 mei 1987, Sociaal-economische Deregulering, Brussel, V.E.H.U.B., 123-140.
5000
General Theories of Regulation
257
Ippolito, Richard A. (1979), ‘The Effects of Price Regulation in the Automobile Insurance Industry’, 22 Journal of Law and Economics, 55-89. Isaac, R. Mark and Plott, Charles R. (1981), ‘Price Controls and the Behavior of Auction Markets: An Experimental Examination’, 71 American Economic Review, 448-459. Jarrell, Gregg A. (1984), ‘Change at the Exchange: The Causes and Effects of Deregulation’, 27 Journal of Law and Economics, 273-312. Jenny, F. (1981), ‘From Price Controls to Competition Policy in France: The Uneasy Alliance of Economical and Political Considerations’, 52 Annals of Public and Cooperative Economy, 477-490. Johnson, Ronald N. (1985), ‘Retail Price Controls in the Diary Industry: A Political Coalition Argument’, 28 Journal of Law and Economics, 55-75. Jones, Clifton T. and Bremmer, Dale S. (1990), ‘Regional Impacts of Petroleum Price Regulation: The Case of Texas, 1973-1983’, 11 Energy Journal, 135-154. Jordan, William A. (1972), ‘Producer Protection, Prior Market Structure and the Effects of Government Regulation’, 15 Journal of Law and Economics, 151-176. Joskow, Paul L. and Noll, Roger C. (1981), ‘Regulation in Theory and Practice: An Overview’, in Fromm, Gary (ed.), Studies in Public Regulation, Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press, 1-66. Joskow, Paul L. and Rose, Nancy L. (1989), ‘The Effects of Economic Regulation’, in Schmalensee, Richard and Willig, Robert D. (eds), Handbook of Industrial Organization II, Amsterdam, North Holland, 1450-1506. Kahn, Alfred E. (1987), ‘Comment: Deregulatory Schizophrenia’, 75 California Law Review, 1059-1068. Kahn, Alfred E. (1988), The Economics of Regulation: Principles and Institutions, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 559 p. Kahn, Alfred E. (1990), ‘Deregulation: Looking Backward and Looking Forward’, 7 Yale Journal on Regulation, 325-354. Kalt, Joseph P. and Leone, Robert A. (1986), ‘Regional Effects of Energy Price Decontrol: The Roles of Interregional Trade, Stockholding, and Microeconomic Incidence’, 17 Rand Journal of Economics, 201-213. Kalt, Joseph P. and Zupan, Mark A. (1984), ‘Capture and Ideology in the Economic Theory of Politics’, 74(3) American Economic Review, 279-300. Reprinted in Rowley, C.K. (ed.) (1993), Public Choice Theory, Cheltenham, Edward Elgar Publishing Limited. Kalt, Joseph P. and Zupan, Mark A. (1990), ‘The Apparent Ideological Behavior of Legislators: Testing for Principal-Agent Slack in Political Institutions’, 33 Journal of Law and Economics, 103-131. Karp, Gordon and Yohe, Gary W. (1979), ‘The Optimal Linear Alternative to Price and Quantity Controls in the Multifirm Case’, 3 Journal of Comparative Economics, 56-65. Katzmann, Robert A. (1990), ‘Comments on Levine and Forrence, ‘Regulatory Capture, Public Interest, and the Public Agenda: Toward a Synthesis’, 6(S) Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 199-202. Kay, John A. and Vickers, John S. (1990), ‘Regulatory Reform: An Appraisal’, in Majone, Giandomenico (ed.), Deregulation or Re-regulation, London, Pinter Publishers, 223-251. Keeler, Theodore E. (1984), ‘Theories of Regulation and the Deregulation Movement’, 44 Public Choice, 103-145.
258
General Theories of Regulation
5000
Keller, Robert R. (1980), ‘Inflation, Monetarism, and Price Controls’, 19 Nebraska Journal of Economics and Business, 30-40. Keller, Robert R. and Gray, S. Lee (1975), ‘A Neo Classical Argument for Wage Price Controls’, 6(2) Intermountain Economic Review, 46-54. Kemp, Kathleen A. (1989), ‘Party Realignments and the Growth of Federal Economic Regulation, 1861-1986', 2 Journal of Financial Services Research, 213-225. Keyserling, Leon H. (1984), ‘The New Deal and Its Current Significance in the National Economic and Social Policy’, 59 Washington Law Review, 795 ff. Kirchner, Christian (1986), ‘Deregulation as an Instrument in Industrial Policy: Comment’, 142 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 75-78. Kirzner, Israel M. (1985), ‘The Perils of Regulation: A Market-Process Approach’, in Kirzner, Israel M. (ed.), Discovery and Capitalist Process, Chicago, IL, University of Chicago Press, 119-149. Kitch, Edmund W. (1977), ‘Can We Buy Our Way Out of Harmful Regulation?’, in Martin, Donald L. and Schwartz, Warren F. (eds), Deregulating American Industry: Legal and Economic Problems, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Kitch, Edmund W. (1981), ‘Review of Chapter 11 of Volume XI of the International Ecyclopedia of Comparative Law: Legal Consequences of State Regulation’, 9 International Journal of Law Libraries, 230 ff. Kling, Robert W. (1988), ‘Building an Institutionalist Theory of Regulation’, 22 Journal of Economic Issues, 197-209. Krauss, Michael I. (1994a), ‘La Réglementation Contre le Marché dans le Développement de Normes (Regulation against the Market in Norms Formation)’, 5 Journal des Économistes et des Études Humaines, 573-599. Krauss, Michael I. (1994b), ‘Regulation vs. Markets in the Development of Standards’, 3 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal, 781-808. Krueger, Anne O. (1974), ‘The Political Economy of the Rent-seeking Society’, 64 American Economic Review, 291-303. Lanzillotti, Robert F. and Roberts, Blaine (1974), ‘The Legacy of Phase II Price Controls’, 64 American Economic Review, 82-87. Larsen, Anders and Olsen, Ole Jess (1995), Konkurrence i Energisektoren og Statslig Regulering (Competition in the Energy-Sector and State Regulation), AKF rapport 1995. Latin, Howard (1985), ‘Ideal versus Real Regulatory Efficiency: Implementation of Uniform Standards and ‘Fine-Tuning’ Regulatory Reforms’, 37 Stanford Law Review, 1267-1332. Le Pen, Claude (1988), ‘Reglementation des Prix et Formes de la Concurrence dans l’Industrie Pharmaceutique (Price Regulation and Competition Patterns in the Ethical Drug Industry)’, 39 Revue Économique, 1159-1191. Lee, Dwight R. (1976), ‘The Firm’s Response to an Input Quota Constraint: Some Price Control Implications’, 16(4) Quarterly Review of Economics and Business, 35-45. Lee, Dwight R. (1978), ‘Price Controls, Binding Constraints, and Intertemporal Economic Decision Making’, 86 Journal of Political Economy, 293-2301. Lee, Dwight R. (1979), ‘Price Controls on Non Renewable Resources: An Intertemporal Analysis’, 46 Southern Economic Journal, 179-188. Leibenstein, Harvey (1966), ‘Allocative Efficiency vs. X-Efficiency’, 56 American Economic Review, 392-415. Leland, Hayne E. (1979), ‘Quacks, Lemons, and Licensing: A Theory of Minimum Quality Standards’,
5000
General Theories of Regulation
259
87 Journal of Political Economy, 1325-1346. Levi, Maurice and Dexter, Albert (1983), ‘Regulated Prices and their Consequences’, 9 Canadian Public Policy, 24-31. Levine, Michael E. and Forrence, Jennifer L. (1990), ‘Regulatory Capture, Public Interest, and the Public Agenda: Toward a Synthesis’, 6(S) Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 167-198. Levy, Santiago (1988), ‘Efectos Macroecónomicos del Control de Precios: un Análisis de Equilibrio General a Corto Plazo (The Macroeconomic Effects of Price Controls: A Short run General Equilibrium Analysis. With English summary)’, 3 Estudios Economicos, 27-56. Libecap, Gary D. (1986), ‘Deregulation as an Instrument in Industrial Policy: Comment’, 142 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 71-74. Lipsey, Richard G. (1977), ‘Wage Price Controls: How to do a Lot of Harm by Trying to do a Little Good’, 3 Canadian Public Policy, 1-13. Lott, John R., Jr and Fremling, Gertrud M. (1989), ‘Time Dependent Information Costs, Price Controls, and Successive Government Intervention’, 5 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 293-306. Lott, John R., Jr and Roberts, Russell D. (1989), ‘Why Comply: One-sided Enforcement of Price Controls and Victimless Crime Laws’, 18 Journal of Legal Studies, 403-414. Lueck, Dean (1991), ‘Ownership and the Regulation of Wildlife’, 29 Economic Inquiry, 249-260. Lueck, Dean (1995), ‘The Economic Organisation of Wildlife Institutions’, in Anderson, Terry L. and Hill, Peter J. (eds), Wildlife in the Market Place, Rowman and Littlefield Press. Lueck, Dean and Schenewerk, Philip (1996), ‘An Economic Analysis of Unitized and Non-Unitized Reservoirs’, XXXProceedings of the 1996 Society of Petroleum Engineers Annual Technical Conference, 67-76. Lueck, Dean and Yoder, Jonathan (1996), ‘Federalism and Wildlife Conservation in the West’, in Anderson, Terry L. and Hill, Peter J. (eds), Environmental Federalism in the West, Rowman and Littlefield Press. Lueck, Dean, Olsen, Reed and Ransom, Michael (1991), ‘Why Do States Regulate Admission to the Bar? Theories and Empirical Evidence’, 14(2) George Mason Law Review, 253-286. Lueck, Dean, Olsen, Reed and Ransom, Michael (1995), ‘Market and Regulatory Forces in the Pricing of Legal Services’, 7(1) Journal of Regulatory Economics, 63-83. MacKaay, Ejan (1987), ‘Le Paradoxe des Droits Acquis (The Paradox of Acquired Rights)’, in X (ed.), De ‘l’Ancienne’ à la ‘Nouvelle’ Économie. Essais à l’Occasion de la Dixième Université d’état‚ de la Nouvelle Économie, Aix-en-Provence, Librairie de l’Université, 205-219. MacKay, Robert J., Miller, James C., III and Yandle, Bruce (1987), ‘Public Choice and Regulation: An Overview’, in Mackay, Robert J., Miller, James C., III and Ya (eds), Public Choice and Regulation: A View from Inside the Federal Trade Commission, Stanford, Hoover Institute Press, Stanford University, 3-12. Maloney, Michael T., McCormick Robert E. and Tollison, Robert D. (1984), ‘Economic Regulation, Competitive Governments, and Specialised Resources’, 27 Journal of Law and Economics, 329-338. Martens, B. (1977), ‘Effectiveness and Efficiency of Price Controls in Belgium’, 22 Tijdschrift voor
260
General Theories of Regulation
5000
Economie en Management, 405-418. Martin, Donald L. and Schwartz, Warren F. (eds) (1977),Deregulating American Industry: Legal and Economic Problems, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books, 120 p. McChesney, Fred S. (1987), ‘Rent Extraction and Rent Creation in the Economic Theory of Regulation’, 16 Journal of Legal Studies, 101-118. McChesney, Fred S. (1991), ‘Rent Extraction and Interest-Group Organization in a Coasean Model of Regulation’, 20 Journal of Legal Studies, 73-90. McCormick, Robert E. and Tollison, Robert D. (1981), Politicians, Legislation, and the Economy, Boston, Nijhoff, 134 p. McCormick, Robert E., Shughart, William F., II and Tolli Son, Robert D. (1984), ‘The Disinterest in Deregulation’, 74 American Economic Review, 1075-1079. McCormick, Robert E., Shughart, William F., II and Tollison, Robert D. (1986), ‘The Disinterest in Deregulation: Reply’, 76 American Economic Review, 564-565. McCormick, Robert E., Shughart, William F., II and Tollison, Robert D. (1988), ‘Reply’, 78 American Economic Review, 284ff. McCubbins, Mathew D., Noll, Roger G. and Weingast, Barry R. (1990), ‘Slack, Public Interest, and Structure-Induced Policy’, 6(S) Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 203-212. McGraw, Thomas K. (1981), ‘Discussion [The Response of the Giant Corporations to Wage and Price Controls in World War II] 1[Planning for Peace: The Surplus Property Act of 1944]’, 41(1) Journal of Economic History, 136-137. McKie, James W. (1970), ‘Regulation and the Free Market: The Problem of Boundaries’, 1 Bell Journal of Economics, 6-26. McNally, David (1988), Political Economy and the Rise of Capitalism: A Reinterpretation, Berkeley, University of California Press, 329 p. Meade, James, A. (1973), The Theory of Economic Externalities, Leiden, Sijthoff. Meier-Schatz, Christian (1989), Wirtschaftsrecht und Unternehmenspublizität (Economic Legislation and Enterprise Publicity), Zurich, Schulthess. Mendershausen, H. (1949), ‘Prices, Money and the Distribution of Goods in Postwar Germany’, 39 American Economic Review, 646 ff. Mentre, Paul (1987), ‘Regulation and Deregulation: An Economic Viewpoint’, in Van De Kar, Hans M. and Wolfe, Barbara L. (eds), The Relevance of Public Finance for Policy-Making, Detroit, Wayne State University Press, 293-305. Meyer, Dirk (1989), ‘Rent Seeking durch Rationalisierungsschutz oder die Wohlfahrtsverluste einer Kostensenkungssteuer (Rent Seeking through Regulations Protecting Human Capital from Devaluation Due to Technological Innovation)’, 35 Konjunkturpolitik, 188-1200. Meyers, Jan and Steenbergen, Jacques (1987), ‘Deregulering, Europese Eenmaking en Bescherming van het Nationaal Belang (Deregulation, European Unification and Protection of National Interest)’, in X (ed.), 18de Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Brussel 8 en 9 mei 1987, Sociaal-economische Deregulering, Brussel, V.E.H.U.B., 51-75. Michielssen, F. and Van Hecke, M. (1973), ‘Prijsbeleid (Price Policy)’, in X (ed.), 18de Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Brussel 8 en 9 mei 1987, Sociaal-economische Deregulering, Brussel, V.E.H.U.B., 189-223. Migué‚ Jean-Luc (1977), ‘Controls versus Subsidies in the Economic Theory of Regulation’, 20 Journal of Law and Economics, 213-221.
5000
General Theories of Regulation
261
Mills, D. Quinn (1975), ‘Some Lessons of Price Controls in 1971-1973', 6 Bell Journal of Economics, 3-49. Miranda, Mario J. and Helmberger, Peter G. (1988), ‘The Effects of Commodity Price Stabilization Programs’, 78 American Economic Review, 46-58. Mirer, Thad W. (1975), ‘The Distributive Impact on Purchasing Power of Inflation during Price Controls’, 15 Quarterly Review of Economics and Business, 93-96. Mitchell, Daniel J.B. and Azevedo, Ross E. (1975), ‘Price Controls and Shortages: A Note’, 48 Journal of Business, 571-574. Mitnick, Barry M. (1980), The Political Economy of Regulation, New York, Columbia University Press. Moore, Thomas Gale (1985), ‘An Agenda for Regulatory Reform’, in Boaz, David and Crane, Adward H. (eds), Beyond the Status Quo: Policy Proposals for America, Washington, Cato Institute, 145-163. Morgan, Thomas D. (1976), Economic Regulation of Business: Cases and Materials, St Paul, West Publishing. Morgan, Thomas D. (1982), ‘The Deregulation Bandwagon: Too Far, Too Fast?’, 2 Journal of Law and Commerce, 1 ff. Morgan, Thomas D., Harrison, J. and Verkuil, Paul R. (1985), Economic Regulation of Business: Cases and Materials, St Paul, West Publishing. Mueller, Dennis C. (1988), ‘Anarchy, the Market, and the State’, 54 Southern Economic Journal, 821-830. Mueller, Dennis C. (1989), Public Choice II, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Mukherji, Badal, Pattanaik, Prasanta K. and Sundrum, R.M. (1980), ‘Rationing, Price Control and Black Marketing’, 15 Indian Economic Review, 99-118. Murphy, Michael M. (1980), ‘Price Controls and the Behavior of the Firm’, 21 International Economic Review, 285-291. Musgrave, Richard A. (1969), ‘Provision for Social Goods’, in Margolis, Julius and Guitton H. (eds), Public Economics, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 124-145. Needham, Douglas (1983), The Economics and Politics of Regulation: A Behavioral Approach, Boston, Little Brown, 482 p. Nelson, Philip (1970), ‘Information and Consumer Behavior’, 78 Journal of Political Economy, 311-329. Nelson, Philip (1974), ‘Advertising as Information’, 82 Journal of Political Economy, 729-754. Ng, Yew Kwang (1985), ‘Some Fundamental Issues in Social Welfare’, in Feiwel, G.R. (ed.), Issues in Contempory Microeconomics and Welfare, London, The Macmillan Press, 435-469. Ng, Yew Kwang (1990), Welfare Economics, London, Macmillan. Niskanen, William A. (1989), ‘Economic Deregulation in the United States: Lessons for America, Lessons for China’, 8 Cato Journal, 657-668. Noll, Roger G. (1983), ‘The Political Foundations of Regulatory Policy’, 139 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 377-404. Noll, Roger G. (1987), ‘The Political Foundations of Regulatory Policy’, in McCubbins, Mathew D. and Sullivan, Terry (eds), Congress: Structure and Policy, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 462-492. Noll, Roger G. (1988), ‘Regulation After Reagan’, 12(3) Regulation, 13-20. Noll, Roger G. (1989a), ‘Economic Perspectives on the Politics of Regulation’, in Schmalensee,
262
General Theories of Regulation
5000
Richard and Willig, Robert D. (eds), Handbook of Industrial Organization II, Amsterdam, North Holland, 1253-1287. Noll, Roger G. (1989b), ‘Comments and Discussions’, 1989 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity: Microeconomics, 48-58. Noll, Roger G. (ed.) (1985), Regulatory Policy and the Social Sciences, Berkeley, University of California Press, 400 p. Noll, Roger G. and Owen, Bruce M. (1983), The Political Economy of Deregulation, Washington, American Enterprise Institute. Noll, Roger G. and Owen, Bruce M. (1983b), ‘What Makes Reform Happen?’, 7 Regulation. Ogus, Anthony I. (1994), Regulation: Legal Form and Economic Theory, Oxford, Clarendon. Oi, Walter Y. (1976), ‘On Measuring the Impact of Wage Price Controls: A Critical Appraisal’, 2 Journal of Monetary Economics, 7-64. Okun, Arthur (1975), Equality and Efficiency: the Big Tradeoff, Washington, Brookings Institution. Olson, C. Vincent and Trapani II, John M. (1981), ‘Who has Benefited from Regulation of the Airline Industry? ‘, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 75-93. Olson, Mancur (1965), The Logic of Collective Action. Public Goods and the Theory of Groups, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Olson, Mancur (1982), The Rise and Decline of Nations, New Haven, Yale University Press. Ordover, Janusz A. and Weiss, Andrew (1981), ‘Information and the Law: Evaluating Legal Restrictions on Competitive Contracts’,71 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 399-404. Ostry, Sylvia (1978), ‘Industrial Relations after Wage and Price Control: Panel Discussion’, 4 Canadian Public Policy, 425-430. Outreville, Jean François (1990), ‘Price Regulation and Segmented Insurance Markets’, in Louberg‚ Henri (ed.), Risk, Information and Insurance. Essays in the Memory of Karl H. Borch, Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 221-229. Owen, Bruce M. (1984), Cynicism and Credulity in Explaining Regulation, Political Economy of Regulation: Private Interests in the Regulatory Process, FTC Law and Economics Conf. Owen, Bruce M. (1985), ‘Interest Group Behavior and the Political Economy of Regulation’, in Meyer, Jack A. (ed.), Incentives vs. Controls in Health Policy: Broadening the Debate, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research. Owen, Bruce M. and Braeutigam, Ronald R. (1978), The Regulation Game: Strategic Use of the Administrative Process, Cambridge, MA, Ballinger, 271 p. Palay, Thomas M. (1985), ‘Avoiding Regulatory Constraints: Contracting Safeguards and the Role of Informal Agreements’, 1 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 155-175. Papanikolaou, Panagiotis A. (1991), Peri ton Orion tes Prostateutikes Paremvaseos tou Dikaste ste Symbase: Pros mia Genike Theoria Peri Katachreseos tes Symvatikes Eleutherias (On the Boundaries of the Paternalistic Intervention of the Judge on a Contract: Towards a General Theory on the Abuse of Freedom of Contracts), Athens-Komotini, Ant. N. Sakkoulas Publications. Pashigian, B. Peter (1984a), ‘Environmental Regulation: Whose Self-Interests Are Being Protected’, 23 Economic Inquiry.
5000
General Theories of Regulation
263
Pashigian, B. Peter (1984b), ‘The Effect of Environmental Regulation on Optimal Plant Size and Factor Shares’, 27 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-28. Pasour, E.C., Jr (1984), ‘Information: A Neglected Aspect of the Theory of Price Regulation’, 3 Cato Journal, 855-867. Pastor, Santos (1988), ‘Estado, Mercado, Eficiencia y Equidad (The Market, the State, Efficiency and Equity)’, in Corcuera, J. and Garcia Herrera, M.A. (eds), Derecho y Economía en el Estado Social, Tecnos & Gobierno Vasco. Paukert, Felix (1988), ‘Price Policies as a Form of Incomes Policy in Developing Countries: 1. Objectives and Instruments’, 127 International Labour Review, 135-151. Paul, Chris and Schoening, Niles (1991), ‘Regulation and Rent-Seeking: Prices, Profits, and Third-Party Transfers’, 68 Public Choice, 185-194. Peacock, Alan T. (ed.) (1984), The Regulation Game: How British and West German Companies Bargain with Government, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 170 p. Pejovich, Svetozar (1979), Fundamentals of Economics: a Property Rights Approach, Dallas, Fisher Institute. Peltzman, Sam (1976), ‘Towards a More General Theory of Regulation’, 19 Journal of Law and Economics, 211-240. Peltzman, Sam (1982), ‘Peltzman on Regulation and Politics: Reply’, Public Choice. Peltzman, Sam (1989), ‘The Economic Theory of Regulation After a Decade of Deregulation’, Brookings Papers on Economic Activity: Microeconomics, 1-41. Peltzman, Sam (1991), ‘Comments on A. Klevorick “Directions and Trends in Industrial Organization”’, Brookings Papers on Economic Activity: Microeconomics. Peltzman, Sam (1993), ‘George Stigler’s Contribution to the Economics of Regulation’, 101 Journal of Political Economy. Pencavel, John H. (1976), ‘A Comment on the Papers at the Conference on Wage Price Controls’, 2 Journal of Monetary Economics, 303-304. Perloff, Jeffrey M. and van ’t Veld, Klaas T. (1994), Instructor’s Manual and Test Bank, New York, Harpercollins. Phelps, C.E. (1982), ‘Kalt’s the Economics and Politics of Oil Price Regulation: Federal Policy in the Post-Embargo Era’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 289-295. Png, Ivan Paak-Liang and Mookherjee, D. (1992), ‘Monitoring vis-a-vis Investigation in Enforcement of Law’, 82 American Economic Review, 556-565. Png, Ivan Paak-Liang and Mookherjee, D. (1994), ‘Marginal Deterrence in Enforcement of Law’, 102 Journal of Political Economy, 1039-1066. Png, Ivan Paak-Liang and Mookherjee, D. (1995), ‘Corruptible Law Enforcers: How Should They be Compensated?’, 105 Economic Journal, 145-159. Pollefliet, E. (1987), ‘Prijsvorming en Mededingingsbeleid: 1. Economische Aspecten (Price Formation and Competition Policy: Economic Aspects)’, in X (ed.), 18de Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Brussel 8 en 9 mei 1987, Sociaal-economische Deregulering, Brussel, V.E.H.U.B., 145-170. Poole, Keith T. and Rosenthal, Howard (1993), ‘The Enduring Nineteenth Century Battle for Economic Regulation: The Interstate Commerce Act Revisited’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 837-860. Poole, William (1973), ‘Wage Price Controls: Where Do We Go from Here?’, 1 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 285-299. Posner, Richard A. (1971), ‘Taxation by Regulation’, 2 Bell Journal of Economics, 22-50. Posner, Richard A. (1974), ‘Theories of Economic Regulation’, 5 Bell Journal of Economics and
264
General Theories of Regulation
5000
Management Science, 335-358. Possen, Uri M. (1978), ‘Wage and Price Controls in a Dynamic Macro Model’, 46 Econometrica, 105-125. Prasad, Ravi (1995), ‘A Guide to Regulation Impact Statements’, Office of Regulation Review. Pustay, Michael W. and Zardkoohi, Asghar (1988), ‘An Economic Analysis of Liquor Price Affirmation Laws: Do They Burden Interstate Commerce?’, 48 Louisiana Law Review, 649-676. Quaden, Guy (1981), ‘Price Control Policy in Belgium’, 52 Annals of Public and Cooperative Economy, 465-476. Ramos Tercero, Raul (1988), ‘Monopolistic Competition, Credibility and the Output Costs of Disinflation Programs: An Analysis of Price Controls: Comments’, 29 Journal of Development Economics, 399-401. Rasmusen, Eric and Zupan, Mark A. (1991), ‘Extending the Economic Theory of Regulation to the Form of Policy’, 72(3) Public Choice, 167-191. Reagan, Michael D. (1986), The Politics of Policy, Boston, Little Brown, 241 p. Ricketts, Martin and Peacock, Alan T. (1986), ‘Bargaining and the Regulatory System’, 6 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-16. Robbins, Lionel (1932), An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science, London, Macmillan. Robertson, Leon S. (1977), ‘A Critical Analysis of Peltzman’s ‘The Effects of Automobile Safety Regulation’’, 11 Journal of Economic Issues, 587-600. Rockoff, Hugh (1981), 'The Response of the Giant Corporations to Wage and Price Controls in World War II', 41 Journal of Economic History, 123-128. Rockoff, Hugh (1984), Drastic Measures: A History of Wage and Price Controls in the United States, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 289 p. Rogerson, William P. (1982), ‘The Social Costs of Monopoly and Regulation: a Game-Theoretic Analysis’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 391-401. Romer, Thomas and Rosenthal, Howard (1987), ‘Modern Political Economy and the Study of Regulation’, in Bailey, Elizabeth E. (ed.), Public Regulation: New Perspectives on Institutions and Policies, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 73-116. Rosa, J.J. (1984), ‘Deréglementation et Théorie du Droit (Deregulation and Legal Theory)’, 33 Politique Economique. Rose, Jonathan (1983), ‘Professional Regulation: The Current Controversy’, 6 (Spec.) Law and Human Behavior, 103-116. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1988), ‘Progressive Law and Economics - and the New Administrative Law’, 98 Yale Law Journal, 341-368. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1990a), ‘Defending the State: A Skeptical Look At “Regulatory Reform” in the Eighties’, 61 University of Colorado Law Review, 517-535. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1990b), ‘Deregulation and Reregulation: Rhetoric and Reality’, 6 Journal of Law and Politics, 287-309. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1992), Rethinking the Progressive Agenda: The Reform of the American Regulatory State, New York, NY, Free Press. Ross, Thomas W. (1984), ‘Uncovering Regulators’ Social Welfare Weights’, 15 Rand Journal of Economics, 152-155. Rothschild, Michael and Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1976), ‘Equilibrium in Competitive Insurance Markets’, 90 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 639-650.
5000
General Theories of Regulation
265
Rousslang, Donald J. (1988), ‘Import Injury in U.S. Trade Law: An Economic View’, 8 International Review of Law and Economics, 117-122. Rowley, Charles K. (1984), ‘Towards a Political Economy of British Labor Law’, 51 University of Chicago Law Review, 1135-1160. Rowley, Charles K. (1985), ‘The Relationship between Economics, Politics and the Law in the Formation of Public Policy’, in Matthews, R.C.O. (ed.), Economy and Democracy, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 127-150. Rowley, Charles K., Tollison, Robert D. and Tullock, Gordon (1988), The Political Economy of Rent-Seeking, Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers. Sagoff, Mark (1985), ‘Must Regulatory Reform Fail?’, 4 Journal of Policy Analysis and Management, 433-436. Salant, Walter S. (1986), ‘Effects of Price Control on Output and the Price Level’, in Colander, David C. (ed.), Incentive Based Incomes Policies: Advances in TIP and MAP, Cambridge, MA, Harper and Row, 58-70. Samuels, Warren G. and Mercuro, Nicholas (1984), ‘A Critique of Rent-Seeking Theory’, in Collander, David C. (ed.), Neoclassical Political Economy, reprinted in Samuels, Warren J. (ed.) Essays on the Economic Role of Government, volume 2, Boston, Ballinger Publishing Co., 55-70. Samuels, Warren J. (1978), ‘Normative Premises in Regulatory Theory’, 1 Journal of Post Keynesian Economics, 100-114. Reprinted in Samuels, Warren J. and Schmid, A. Allen (eds) (1981), Law and Economics: An Institutional Perspective, Boston, Nijhoff, 128-142. Samuels, Warren J., Schmid, A. Allan and Shaffer, James D. (1981), ‘Regulation and Regulatory Reform: Some Fundamental Conceptions’, in Samuels, Warren J. and Schmid, A. Allan (eds), Law and Economics: An Institutional Perspective, Boston, Nijhoff, 248-266. Samuelson, Paul A. (1954), ‘The Pure Theory of Public Expenditure’, 36 Review of Economic Statistics, 387-389. Sappington, David E.M. and Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1987), ‘Information and Regulation’, in Bailey, Elizabeth E. (ed.), Public Regulation: New Perspectives on Institutions and Policies, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 3-43. Schlagenhauf, Don E. and Shupp, Franklin R. (1977), ‘Inflation and Price Controls in a Flexprice Fixprice Model’, 6 Annals of Economic and Social Measurement, 501-519. Schmalensee, Richard (1981), ‘Comments on Beales, Craswell, and Salop’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 541-544. Schmalensee, Richard (1989), ‘Good Regulatory Regimes’, 20 Rand Journal of Economics, 417-436. Schultz, George P. and Dam, Kenneth W. (1977), ‘Reflections on Wage and Price Controls’, 30 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 139-151. Schwartz, Alan and Wilde, Louis L. (1979), ‘Intervening in Markets on the Basis of Imperfect Information: A Legal and Economic Analysis?’, 127 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 630-682. Schwartz, Louis B. (1987), ‘Some Additional Safeguards for the Newly Liberated Marketplace: Deregulatory Schizophrenia’, 75 California Law Review, 1049-1057. Schwarzer, Stephan (1992), Die Genehmigung von Betriebsanlagen (The Approval of Plants), Vienna. Schwarzer, Stephan (1996), ‘Die Beschleunigung von Genehmigungsverfahren als Wirtschafts- und
266
General Theories of Regulation
5000
umweltpolitisches Anliegen - zugleich ein Vorwort (The Acceleration of Approval-Processes as a Policy-Issue - a Preface)’, in Schwarzer, Stephan (ed.), Die Beschleunigung von Genehmigungsverfahren für Betriebsanlagen - Möglichkeiten nach geltendem Recht und Reformansätze, forthcoming. Schwert, G. William (1981), ‘Using Financial Data to Measure Effects of Regulation’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 121-158. Reprinted in Posner, Richard A. and Scott, Kenneth E. (eds) (1980), Economics of Corporation Law and Securities Regulation, Boston, Little Brown. Sen, Amartya K. (1979a), ‘Personal Utilities and Public Judgements: or What’s Wrong with Welfare Economics’, 89 Economic Journal, 537-558. Sen, Amartya K. (1979b), ‘Utilitarianism and Welfarism’, 76 Journal of Philosophy, 463-489. Sevic, Zeljko (1994), ‘Socijalisti i Svojina: Prilog Pravnoj i Ekonomskoj Teoriji (Prava) Svojine (Socialists and Property: Contribution to the Legal and Economic Theory of Property Rights)’, in X (ed.), Evropska Levica Danas (European Left Today), Belgrade, SPS. Sevic, Zeljko (1994b), Pravni Status Centralne Banke u Savremenoj Trzisnoj Privredi (Status of the Central Bank in a Contemporary Market Economy), Belgrade, Faculty of Law, University of Belgrade. Sevic, Zeljko (1996), Centralna Banka: Polozaj - Organizacija - Funkcije (Central Bank: Position - Organization - Functions), Belgrade, Cigoja-stampa. Sevic, Zeljko (1996b), Law and Economics I: Ekonomska Analiza Prava Svojine u Tranziciji (Law and Economics I: Economic Analysis of the Property Rights in Transition), Pravni Zivot. Shavell, Steven (1984a), ‘Liability for Harm Versus Regulation of Safety’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 357-374. Shavell, Steven (1984b), ‘A Model of the Optimal Use of Liability and Safety Regulation’, 15 Rand Journal of Economics, 271-280. Shogren, Jason F. (ed.) (1989),The Political Economy of Government Regulation, Dordrecht, Kluwer, 210 p. Shubik, Martin (1970), ‘On Different Methods for Allocating Resources’, 13 Kyklos, 332-338. Shughart, William F., II and Tollison, Robert D. (1985), ‘The Cyclical Character of Regulatory Activity’, 45 Public Choice, 303-311. Sieber, Hugo (1981), ‘Wirtschaftsfreiheit und Wirtschaftspolitik (Festschrift für Hans Huber zum 80. Geburtstag) (Economic Freedom and Economic Policy)’, in X (ed.), Recht als Prozess und Gefüge, Bern, Haupt, 447-465. Sigler, Jay A. and Murphy, Joseph E. (1988), Interactive Corporate Compliance: An Alternative to Regulatory Compulsion, Westport, Greenwood, 211 p. Silbertson, Aubrey (1972), ‘Should Prices be Controlled?’, 19 Australian Economic Review, 41-43. Skogh, Göran (1982), Marknadens Villkor (The Terms of the Market), Stockholm, Timbro. Slayton, Philip and Trebilcock, Michael J. (eds) (1978), The Professions and Public Policy, Toronto, University of Toronto Faculty of Law, 346 p. Smith, Rodney T., Bradley, Michael D. and Jarrell, Gregg A. (1986), ‘Studying Firm-Specific Effects of Regulation with Stock Market Data: An Application to Oil Price Regulation’, 17 Rand Journal of Economics, 467-489.
5000
General Theories of Regulation
267
Smith, Vernon L. and Williams, Arlington W. (1981), ‘On Nonbinding Price Controls in a Competitive Market’, 71 American Economic Review, 467-474. Snowdon, Brian, Vane, Howard and Wynarczyk, Peter (1994), A Modern Guide to Macroeconomics, Cambridge, Edward Elgar. Spiller, Pablo T. (1990), ‘Politicians, Interest Groups, and Regulators: A Multi-Principals Agency Theory of Regulation, or ‘Let Them Be Bribed’’, 33 Journal of Law and Economics, 65-101. Stewart, Richard B. (1981), ‘Regulation, Innovation and Administrative Law: A Conceptual Framework’, 69 California Law Review, 1256-1377. Stewart, Richard B. (1985), ‘Economics, Environment, and the Limits of Legal Control’, 9 Harvard Environmental Law Review, 1-22. Stewart, Richard B. (1990), ‘Madison’s Nightmare’, 57 University of Chicago Law Review, 335-356. Stigler, George J. (1971), ‘The Theory of Economic Regulation’, 2 Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, 3-21. Stigler, George J. (1974), ‘Free Riders and Collective Action: an Appendix to Theories of Economic Regulation’, 5 Bell Journal of Economics, 359-365. Stigler, George J. (1975a), ‘The Goals of Economic Policy’, 18 Journal of Law and Economics, 283-292. Stigler, George J. (1975b), The Citizen and the State. Essays on Regulation, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 209 p. Stigler, George J. (1976), ‘The Xistence of X-Efficiency’, 66 American Economic Review, 213-216. Stigler, George J. and Friedland, Claire (1962), ‘What Can Regulators Regulate? the Case of Electricity’, 5 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-16. Stollery, Kenneth R. (1981), ‘Price Controls on Nonrenewable Resources when Capacity is Constrained’, 48 Southern Economic Journal, 490-498. Stout, Lynn A. and Barnes, David D. (1992), Cases and Materials on Law and Economics, St Paul, West Publishing. Sunstein, Cass R. (1990a), After the Rights Revolution: Reconceiving the Regulatory State, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 284 p. Sunstein, Cass R. (1990b), ‘Paradoxes of the Regulatory State’,57 University of Chicago Law Review, 407-441. Swaan, Wim (1989), ‘Price Regulation in Hungary: Indirect but Comprehensive Bureaucratic Control’, 31(4) Comparative Economic Studies, 10-52. Swann, Dennis (1988), The Retreat of the State: Deregulation and Privatization in the U.K. and U.S., Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 344 p. Symposium (1976), ‘Deregulation’, 57 Indiana Law Journal, 682-755. Symposium (1979), ‘Regulation and Innovation’, 43(1) Law and Contemporary Problems. Symposium (1981), ‘Managing the Transition to Deregulation’, 44(1) Law and Contemporary Problems. Théret, Bruno (1990), ‘La place de l’État dans les Théories Économiques Françaises de la Regulation: Éléments Critiques et Repositionnement à la Lumière de l’Histoire (The Place of the State in French Economic Theories of Regulation; Critical Arguments and New Posture Brought to Light by History)’, 43(2) Économie Appliquée, 43-81. Thiemeyer, Theo (1983), ‘Deregulation in the Perspective of the German Gemeinwirtschaftslehre’, 139 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 405-418.
268
General Theories of Regulation
5000
Tool, Marc R. (1990), ‘Some Reflections on Social Value Theory and Regulation’, 24 Journal of Economic Issues, 535-544. Toumanoff, Peter G. (1984), ‘A Positive Analysis of the Theory of Market Failure’, 37 Kyklos, 529-541. Trebilcock, Michael J. and Hartle, D.G. (1982), ‘The Choice of Governing Instrument’, 2 International Review of Law and Economics, 29-46. Trebilcock, Michael J. and Prichard, J. Robert S. (1979), ‘Economic Analysis of Commercial Law’, in Ziegel, Jacob B. (ed.), Proceedings of the Seventh Annual Workshop on Commercial and Consumer Law, Toronto, Canada Law Book. Trebilcock, Michael J., Weaverman, L. and Prichard, J. Robert S. (1978), ‘Markets for Regulation: Implications for Performance Standards and Institutional Design’, in X (ed.), Government Regulation - Issues and Alternatives, Toronto, Ontario Economic Council. Trebing, Harry M. (1987), ‘Regulation of Industry: An Institutionalist Approach’, 21 Journal of Economic Issues, 1707-1737. Tullock, Gordon (1967), ‘The Welfare Costs of Tariffs, Monopolies and Theft’, 5 Western Economic Journal, 224-232. Tullock, Gordon (1987), ‘Concluding Thoughts on the Politics of Regulation’, in Mackay, Robert J., Miller, James C., III and Ya (eds), Public Choice and Regulation: A View from Inside the Federal Trade Commission, Stanford, Hoover Institute Press, Stanford University, 333-343. Tullock, Gordon (1993), Rent Seeking, Aldershot, Edward Elgar. Turnbull, Shann (1997), ‘Stakeholder Cooporation’, 29(3) Journal of Co-operative Studies, 18-52. Uitermark, P.J. (1972), ‘Maximumprijzen: een Vergeten Hoofdstuk? (Maximum Prices: A Forgotten Chapter?)’, 36 Maandschrift Economie, 465-484. Ulen, Thomas S. (1997), ‘Book Review: Regulation: Legal Form and Economic Theory’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 293-295. Utton, M.A. (1986), The Economics of Regulating Industry, Oxford, Blackwell, 243 p. Van den Bergh, Roger and Faure, Michael G. (1991), ‘Self Regulation of the Professions in Belgium’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 165-182. Van Gerven, Walter (1986), ‘Herijken van Economische Wetgeving (over Reguleren en Dereguleren) (Re-Stamping of Economic Regulation - on Regulating and Deregulating)’, 49 Rechtskundig Weekblad, 286-308. Van Hulle, K. (1987), ‘Informatie en Markttransparantie (Information and Market Transparency)’, in X (ed.), 18de Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Brussel 8 en 9 mei 1987, Sociaal-economische Deregulering, Brussel, V.E.H.U.B., 79-97. Van Wijnbergen, Sweder (1988), ‘Monopolistic Competition, Credibility and the Output Costs of Disinflation Programs: An Analysis of Price Controls’, 29 Journal of Development Economics, 375-398. Varian, H.R. (1989), ‘Measuring the Deadweight Costs of DUP and Rent Seeking Activities’, Journal of Economics and Politics, 81-95. Vartikar, V.S. (1990), ‘Inflationary Price Controls’, 37 Rivista Internazionale di Scienze Economiche e Commerciali, 1-6. Vazquez Vega, Pablo (1995), ‘Reforma de las Estructuras y Eficiencia Económica: la Nueva Regulación (Reforming Structures and Economic Efficiency: The New Regulation)’, 60 Boletín del Círculo de Empresarios.
5000
General Theories of Regulation
269
Vazquez, Pablo (1990), ‘Grupos de Interés en la Comunidad Económica Europea. Apuntes sobre un Regulación Actual (The Regulation of Interest Groups in the European Community)’, 102 Informacíon Comercial Española, 688-689. Veljanovski, Cento G. (1982a), ‘The Coase Theorems and the Economic Theory of Markets and law’, 35 Kyklos, 53-74. Veljanovski, Cento G. (1982b), ‘Regulatory Enforcement - An Economic Case Study of the British Factory Inspectorate’, 4 Law and Policy Quarterly. Veljanovski, Cento G. (1984), ‘The Economics of Regulatory Enforcement’, in Hankins, Keith and Thomas, John M. (eds), Enforcing Regulation, Boston, Kluwer-Nijhoff, 169-188. Veljanovski, Cento G. (1987), Selling the State: Privatisation in Britain, London, Weidenfeld and Nicholson, 239 p. Vesenka, Mary H. (1989), ‘Economic Interests and Ideological Conviction: A Note on PACs and Agricultural Acts’, 12 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 259-263. Vickers, John S. (1991), ‘Government Regulatory Policy’, 7 Oxford Review of Economic Policy, 13-30. Viscusi, W. Kip (1985), ‘Market Incentives for Safety’, 63 Harvard Business Review, 133-138. Viscusi, W. Kip, Vernon, John M. and Harrington, Joseph E., Jr (1996), Economics of Regulation and Antitrust, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Vukadin Emilija (1988), ‘Instrument Kompenzacije u Jugoslovenskom Privrednom Sistemu: Karakter Uslova i Mogucnost Primene (Compensation as an Instrument in Yugoslav Economic System: Character of Conditions and its Feasibility)’, 4 Anali Pravnog Fakulteta u Beogradu, 386-398. Warren-Boulton, Frederick R. (1988), ‘Maricopa and Maximum Price Agreements: Time for a New Legal Standard? Editorial’, 7 Journal of Health Economics, 185-190. Waters, Melissa and Moore, William J. (1990), ‘The Theory of Economic Regulation and Public Choice and the Determinants of Public Sector Bargaining Legislation’, 66 Public Choice, 161-175. Weber, Arnold R. (1972), ‘A Wage Price Freeze as an Instrument of Incomes Policy: Or the Blizzard of ‘71', 62 American Economic Review, 251-257. Weidenbaum, Murray L. (1972), ‘New Initiatives in National Wage and Price Policy’, 54 Review of Economics and Statistics, 213-217. Weigel, Wolfgang (1990), ‘Grenzen der Wettbewerbspolitik (The Limits of Competition Policy)’, 37(6) Wirtschaftspolitische Blätter, 560-566. Weiler, Paul (1978), ‘Industrial Relations after Wage and Price Control: Panel Discussion’, 4 Canadian Public Policy, 433-442. Weingast, Barry (1981), ‘Regulation, Reregulation, and Deregulation: The Political Foundations of Agency Clientele Relationships’, 44 Law and Contemporary Problems, 147-177. Weisbrod, Burton A., Handler, Joel F. and Komesar, Neil K. (eds) (1978), Public Interest Law: An Economic and Institutional, Berkeley, University of California Press, 580 p. Weiss, Leonard W. and Klass, Michael W. (eds) (1986), Regulatory Reform: What Actually Happened, Boston, Little Brown. Weitzman, Martin L. (1974), ‘Prices versus Quantities’, 41 Review of Economic Studies, 477-491. White, Michelle J. and Wittman, Donald A. (1983), ‘A Comparison of Taxes, Regulation, and Liability
270
General Theories of Regulation
5000
Rules under Imperfect Information’, 12 Journal of Legal Studies, 413-425. Whitworth, Alan (1980), ‘Monopoly and the Case for Price Control in Poor Countries’, 17 Journal of Development Studies, 80-95. Whitworth, Alan (1982), ‘Price Control Techniques in Poor Countries: The Tanzanian Case’, 10 World Development, 475-488. Wilson, Graham, K. (1984), ‘Social Regulation and Explanations of Regulatory Failure’, 32 Political Studies, 203-225. Wilson, James Q. (1974), ‘The Politics of Regulation’, in McKie, James W. (ed.), Social Responsibility and the Business Predicament, Washington, The Brookings Institution, 135-168. Wilson, James Q. (1980), ‘The Politics of Regulation’, in Wilson, James Q. (ed.), The politics of regulation, New York, Basic Books, 357-394. Wilton, David A. (1984), ‘An Evaluation of Wage and Price Controls in Canada’, 10 Canadian Public Policy, 167-176. Winston, Clifford (1993), ‘Economic Deregulation: Days of Reckoning for Microeconomists’, 31(3) Journal of Economic Literature, 1263-1289. Winston, Clifford and Crandall, Robert W. (1994), ‘Explaining Regulatory Policy’, Brookings Papers on Economic Activity: Microeconomics, 1-49. Wittman, Donald A. (1977), ‘Prior Regulation versus Post Liability: The Choice Between Input and Output Monitoring’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 193-211. Wolf, Charles, Jr. (1979), ‘A Theory of Nonmarket Failure: Framework for Implementation Analysis’, 22 Journal of Law and Economics, 107-139. Wolf, Charles, Jr (1993), Markets or Governments, Choosing between Imperfect Alternatives, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Wood, Stephen G., Fletcher, Don C. and Holley, Richard F. (1987), ‘Regulation, Deregulation and Re-Regulation: An American Perspective’, Brigham Young University Law Review, 381-465. X (ed.) (1987), 18de Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Brussel 8 en 9 mei 1987, Sociaal-economische Deregulering, Brussel, V.E.H.U.B., 892 p. Yandle, Bruce (1987), ‘Regulatory Reform in the Realm of the Rent Seekers’, in Mackay, Robert J., Miller, James C., III and Ya (eds), Public Choice and Regulation: A View from Inside the Federal Trade Commission, Stanford, Hoover Institute Press, Stanford University, 121-142. Yandle, Bruce and Young, Elizabeth (1986), ‘Regulating the Function, Not the Industry’, 51 Public Choice, 59-70. Yohe, Gary W. (1977), ‘Comparisons of Price and Quantity Controls: A Survey’, 1 Journal of Comparative Economics, 213-233. Zerbe, Richard O., Jr and Urban, Nicole (1988), ‘Including the Public Interest in Theories of Regulation’, 11 Research in Law and Economics, 1-23. Zorn, Thomas S. (1984), ‘The Allocative Effect of Non-binding Price Controls’, 22 Economic Inquiry, 136-141. Zupan, Mark A. (1991), ‘Local Benefit-Seeking in the Legislature: An Investigation of Congessional Staffing Decisions’, 3(2) Economics and Politics, 163-175. Zycher, Benjamin (1990), ‘Automobile Insurance Regulation, Direct Democracy, and the Interests of Consumers’, 13(2) Regulation, 67-77.
5110 INFORMATION REGULATION (INCLUDING REGULATION OF ADVERTISING) Paul H. Rubin Department of Economics, Emory University © Copyright 1999 Paul H. Rubin
Abstract There are three major policy implications from the analysis of advertising regulation: advertising of truthful information should not be restricted by regulatory authorities; deception is most likely and most harmful in the case of ‘credence’ goods, and regulation is most useful (if it is useful at all) in the case of these goods; and laws or rules mandating disclosure (as opposed to laws banning explicit deception) are generally not needed, and often counterproductive. These points are applied in particular to regulation of price advertising, of health claims, and of advertising by attorneys. An important point of the analysis is that advertising can help markets move to new equilibria, and excess regulation can retard such movements, with consequent losses in consumer welfare. The role of the FTC is stressed throughout since this agency uses economic analysis in its regulation of advertising. JEL classification: D83, K29, M37 Keywords: Information, Advertising, Lawyers, Search Goods, Experience Goods, Credence Goods
1. Introduction More than many areas of law and economics, the literature on regulation of information and deception has been a policy-oriented literature. This may be because much of the literature has been generated by economists and attorneys associated with the FTC who initiated their research as part of a policy-oriented analysis. It is also true that most of this literature is from a statutory and regulatory, rather than from a common law, setting; an exception is Jordan and Rubin (1979). In any event, in discussing this literature it will be useful to organize it in terms of policy related considerations. Coase (1977) has argued that advertising (‘commercial speech’) deserves as much protection as any other form of speech. Singdahlsen (1991) makes a similar argument with respect to private competitor suits, although his reasoning would apply more generally. Of course, there are criminal and civil
271
272
Information Regulation
5110
penalties for explicit fraud, so the regulation that occurs is for information violations that do not rise to this level. Fraud, including deception, is discussed in Lott (1996). Moreover, it is useful in many cases for government to devise an appropriate metric, or scoring system, for measuring some attribute. The US Truth in Lending statute requires the use of the Annual Percentage Rate as the interest rate; the FTC ‘R-value’ rule requires the use of R values for measuring the effectiveness of insulation (see Beales, Craswell and Salop, 1981b). There is a tenable position that these should be the only functions of government regulation of information, and one with which I have much sympathy. However, it is not a position that policy makers have adopted. In what follows, I assume that there will be some regulation of advertising beyond this minimal level, and ask what efficient regulation would look like. A general point is that if one believes that there is some market failure caused by a lack of information, then the preferred solution is to provide the missing information, rather than regulate the market directly. Schwartz and Wilde (1979) provide a theoretical basis for this result. Viscusi, Magat and Huber (1986) provide some evidence of consumers’ ability to use information effectively in the context of safety regulation. The literature has derived three major policy conclusions. First, advertising of truthful information should not be restricted by regulatory authorities. Second, deception is most likely and most harmful in the case of ‘credence’ goods, and regulation is most useful (if it is useful at all) in the case of these goods. Finally, laws or rules mandating disclosure (as opposed to laws banning explicit deception) are generally not needed, and often counterproductive. In the next three sections, I discuss these issues: advertising and prices; regulation and types of goods; and mandated disclosure. The following two sections examine regulation of particular types of advertising that have been particularly well studied in the literature: health-related advertising and advertising of legal services. I then discuss remedies for deception. The economic literature on advertising is voluminous, and I mention only those parts which are relevant to issues of information regulation and deception. For some more general surveys see Comanor and Wilson (1979), McAuliffe (1987) and Ekelund and Saurman (1988). There have been several papers examining the implications of the economics of information for the regulation of deceptive advertising: Schwartz and Wilde (1979), Jordan and Rubin (1979), Beales, Craswell and Salop (1981b), Craswell (1985, 1991), Muris (1991), Rubin (1991). I rely heavily on these papers, and particularly on Rubin (1991) in what follows. A thorough summary of Supreme Court cases on the issue from an economic perspective is available in McChesney (1996). First, I introduce some institutional background for the US. While the particular institutions discussed apply in the US, similar functions may be performed by other institutions in other countries. There are at least five
5110
Information Regulation
273
sources of regulation of advertising: The Federal Trade Commission (FTC); other federal agencies, such as the Food and Drug Administration (FDA); state attorneys general; industry self regulation, under the auspices of the National Advertising Review Board (NARB) or the National Advertising Division (NAD) of the Council of Better Business Bureaus (American Bar Association, 1989); and private civil litigation under the Lanham Act and other statutes of common law doctrines, including self-regulation by professional societies including local or state bar associations. Of all of these regulatory bodies, the FTC is now the only organization with responsibility for advertising regulation which explicitly considers economics in its decision making. Economists and attorneys associated with the FTC have contributed a significant share of the literature on advertising regulation. Of those cited here, these include at least: Altrogge, Beales, Bond, Calfee, Calvani, Craswell, Ippolito, Jacobs, Keith (Masson), Langenfeld, Lynch, Kwoka, Mathios, McChesney, Muris, Murphy, Nash, Pappalardo, Pitofsky, Plummer, Porter, Rubin, Salop, Schneider, Shughart, and Steiner (see also Calvani, 1989). McChesney (1996) shows that the Supreme Court at one time used economic reasoning in its commercial speech jurisprudence, but has more recently moved away from this form of analysis. One issue in regulating advertising is the question of the burden of proof: do regulators need to prove that an ad is deceptive, or must advertisers prove that it is true? In 1970, the FTC shifted the burden of proof. Before that time, the agency was required to prove deception. After 1970, an advertiser was required to have adequate ‘substantiation’ for an ad, meaning essentially that the advertiser had the burden of proof. Sauer and Leffler (1990) have shown that this change caused advertising to become more informative. On the other hand, Higgins and McChesney (1986) have shown that the main effect was to provide increased profits to large advertising agencies. Singdahlsen (1991) shows that this issue also arises under private litigation under the Lanham Act. This issue could benefit from further research.
2. Regulation of Price Advertising ‘Deceptive pricing’ is the advertising of reference prices which are not actually common transaction prices. Ads like ‘Regularly $100, now $75’ or ‘$100 elsewhere, here $75’, where $100 is the reference price and $75 is the transactions price, are sometimes considered deceptive unless there have been ‘enough’ sales at the $100 reference price, where enough can be defined in various ways. If a product usually sells for $75 and the firm advertises it as being normally $100, on sale for $75, this ad will have no immediate benefits. That is, consumers are not given any new options, since $75 is the normal price. This is why such ads are sometimes challenged as being deceptive.
274
Information Regulation
5110
Nonetheless, the process started by this ad will likely lead ultimately to lower prices for consumers. Price-conscious consumers will be drawn to this firm since it is stressing price in its ads, and all consumers will be given some information about the distribution of prices in the marketplace. Other firms will be forced to respond to the ad, and some will respond by actually lowering prices below their current level, in part because of the price competition started by the information conveyed in the ad. Ultimately, even the firm initially advertising a price of $75 may be forced to sell for $70 as price advertising spreads throughout the industry. On the other hand, if the ad is initially stopped as being ‘deceptive’ information about low prices is less likely to spread. One general point which will recur in the analysis is that in analyzing advertising it is important to distinguish markets which are in equilibrium from those which are not. Schwartz and Wilde (1979) indicate that high price equilibria are unstable, so that advertising of better prices or terms can destroy a ‘monopoly’ equilibrium in an industry. For a market to be in disequilibrium implies some informational failure, and advertising, by providing information, can move markets towards equilibrium (Ekelund and Saurman, 1988). For example, a market may be in a disequilibrium with prices above the equilibrium level. Advertising may be an effective method of moving from the high-priced disequilibrium to the low-priced equilibrium. During the transition some ads may appear deceptive, but stopping these ads may have the effect of retarding the movement towards the new equilibrium. The general point is that there should be no restrictions on true advertising of prices. Though the FTC does not generally bring cases involving deceptive pricing, the states often do. There are two types of allegations in such cases. One is that goods are not truly available at the advertised transaction price. A second claim is that prices are deceptive because consumers view price as a signal of quality and a fictitious reference price will mislead consumers into overestimating the quality of the good. I consider each type. Both are inconsistent with the Schwartz and Wilde (1979) analysis. There is also substantial empirical analysis of the benefits of advertising in reducing prices: see Benham (1972), Steiner (1973), Marvel (1976), Cady (1976), Farris and Albion (1980), Kwoka (1984) and Haas-Wilson (1986). Indeed, this research has been cited by the US Supreme Court in providing some protection to ‘commercial speech’ (that is, advertising). Before proceeding, it is worth mentioning that in general the states do not do as good a job as the FTC in regulating advertising and deception (Beales and Muris, 1993; Muris, 1991). State regulators often bring cases for political reasons, and anyway do not have access to the large staff of the FTC. Moreover, Beales and Muris (1993) point out that having multiple regulators is likely to lead to more restrictionof advrtising than is appropriate.
5110
Information Regulation
275
2.1 Lack of Availability This is best discussed through an example. There have been recent attempts in the US to regulate advertising of prices of airline tickets on the grounds that not ‘enough’ tickets have been available at advertised low fares. Cases such as this will likely have the ultimate effect of raising prices paid by consumers by reducing incentives of sellers to advertise, and thus offer, low prices. The ads are true but allegedly incomplete. However, discouraging these ads is likely to lead to higher prices. New reservation systems are quite sophisticated and enable airlines to track reservations on each flight on a real time basis. If a flight is not selling as well as expected, it is possible for the airline to offer more discounts on that flight. Thus, advertised low prices may be available only on an irregular basis. However, if consumers call and ask for such fares, travel agents will be able to determine which flights have low fares available. If advertising of these fares is outlawed, then airlines will have reduced incentives to offer such low rates. 2.2 Price as Information The second argument regarding deceptive pricing is that consumers may be misled about quality if they perceive price as a signal of quality. Firms have been ordered to reduce advertising of sales and specials for this reason. There are two problems with cases based on this argument. First, there is no persuasive evidence that consumers are deceived by these ads. Second, there are large social costs from preventing this type of advertising, even if there is deception. There is a substantial marketing literature examining the effects of price ads on consumer expectations of quality. This is not an appropriate place to summarize this literature, particularly as there are two recent summaries available. Both indicate that the results of the empirical literature examining this issue are at best inconclusive. Zethami (1988, p. 2) says that: ‘research on these concepts [price, quality, and value] has provided few conclusive findings’. Similarly, Monroe and Krishnan (1985, p. 229) indicate that ‘We have not been able to identify conceptually or empirically when buyers will infer product quality on the basis of price’, and ‘Considering previous studies individually, it is troubling to find such inconsistency in the results across studies’. Liefeld and Heslop (1985) and Blair and Landon (1981) find similar results. Thus, the evidence for the existence of consumer deception associated with price advertising is highly uncertain. Even if some consumers are deceived by some comparative price advertising, the costs of limiting or forbidding such advertising are likely to be substantial. For example, consider the issue of the volume of sales which must occur at some price before it can be advertised as the ‘regular’ or ‘normal’ price, a common feature of attempts to regulate deceptive pricing. A firm might engage in predictable seasonal promotions, such as sales of tires or white sales
276
Information Regulation
5110
of household furnishings. If consumers are aware that such sales occur, they will refrain from buying except during the sale period. Thus, there will be relatively few units sold at ‘regular’ prices, even though these prices may be commonly available. In such circumstances, any attempt to limit advertising would have one of two effects. The firm might be forced to offer less frequent specials so that more items would be sold at the normal price, a course of action which would clearly harm consumers. Alternatively, it might cease advertising the regular price, but if, for example, this price is comparable to other prices in the market, then consumers would be denied valuable information. Similarly, if a firm errs in choosing a price, it might sell few items at that price, but restrictions on advertising of reference prices might make it difficult to inform customers of the change (see also Muris, 1991). Moreover, even if consumers are deceived, there is no evidence that they are harmed. In one experimental study (Urbany, Bearden and Weilbaker, 1988) which did find consumers deceived by price ads, it was nonetheless found that there was no measurable injury even to those consumers who were deceived. The authors found that there is some effect of even of unrealistic exaggerated prices and that ‘consumers can be skeptical of advertised sale offers but can still be influenced by them’. Nonetheless, even given this strong finding of deception, it was still determined that there is ‘no significant difference between the ending bank balances’ of subjects in groups with and without advertised reference prices. Bond and Murphy (1992) found that, averaged over all products, department stores using reference pricing had prices below the average of all competitors. Interestingly, the authors attribute their results regarding deception in part to the fact that their subjects may have believed that it is illegal to exaggerate reference prices, and that the law is strictly enforced. This indicates that incomplete enforcement of deceptive pricing laws may actually be harmful. If consumers are normally skeptical of such ads, then they cause little if any injury. However, partial enforcement may lead consumers to overestimate the level of enforcement and relax their normal skepticism. This will be particularly likely if there is wide publicity given to the few enforcement efforts which do occur. This is itself likely, given the political orientation of many state enforcement officials. Schmalensee (1978) presents a model where there may be losses to consumers from deceptive advertising, and where losses are greater as consumers believe ads. Here we argue the converse: losses may be greater as consumers believe that there is enforcement of rules against deception. Viscusi (1985) has found that consumers who believe that the government is enforcing safety standards at a greater level than is true may be ‘lulled’ into accepting greater risk, and it is plausible that similar results apply to advertising. The basic problem with policies against deceptive pricing is that in general it is discount firms and firms stressing price which engage in these promotions.
5110
Information Regulation
277
As a result, any effort to limit such advertising is likely to lead to higher prices in the market. As Robert Pitofsky (1977, p. 688), an advocate of rigorous enforcement of consumer protection regulations, has argued, ‘as long as consumers are accurately informed of the offering price, they can make sensible decisions, and the transactions may still be at prices lower than could be obtained at most other outlets in the marketing area’. Pitofsky views reduced enforcement of deceptive pricing claims as a gain for consumers. This is especially true since the possible gains from such enforcement are doubtful and speculative, while the costs are obvious and substantial.
3. Regulation and Types of Goods A public authority charged with advertising regulation has a substantial amount of discretion. The nature of language is such that almost any claim could be interpreted as being deceptive or misleading under some readings, so that there are a large number of cases which could be brought (Craswell, 1985). Moreover, most cases brought by the government are settled through consent decrees (an agreement by the firm not to engage in the behavior in the future), so that there is little litigation over the issue of deception and the correctness of the agency’s position is not tested in court. This may be because of the high reputation cost to a firm from being named as engaging in ‘deception’ (Peltzman, 1981). Mathios and Plummer (1989) generally find that firms which contest FTC orders end up with greater capital losses than firms which consent without a contest. In this circumstance, it is important for regulatory officials to have a strong theoretical basis for bringing some cases and not others. Economics provides this theoretical basis. Economists argue that the basis for regulation should be the effect of claims on consumer welfare, and economics provides a framework for determining which types of ads are most likely to reduce consumer welfare. Economic analysis indicates that there are three types of characteristics of goods with respect to advertising. These are called ‘search’, ‘experience’ and ‘credence’ characteristics. For the discussion of search and experience goods, see Nelson (1970, 1974). For credence goods, see Darby and Karni (1973). For applications to regulation of advertising, see Jordan and Rubin (1979), Saunders (1991) and Heald (1988). Search characteristics can be determined before the associated goods are purchased; an example is the color of a suit. Goods must be purchased and used before experience characteristics can be evaluated; an example is the cleansing power of a soap. For credence characteristics, the consumer may never know if the characteristic exists, even after purchase; an example is unnecessary repair to a TV (or unnecessary surgery), for the TV (or the body) will work afterwards even if the repair was unneeded.
278
Information Regulation
5110
Given this classification, some principles of regulation of advertising are instantly apparent. First, for search characteristics, there is no need for regulation. Consumers can immediately determine if the good possesses the advertised characteristic, and cannot be deceived. Moreover, since this is so and firms understand that it is so, there is no incentive for deceptive advertising with respect to these characteristics. Transaction price is a search characteristic (that is, consumers will know the transaction price before purchase), which is why attempts to regulate advertising of transactions prices, discussed above, are unneeded and counterproductive. Second, for inexpensive goods, there is little cost to deception with respect to experience characteristics. The consumer will be deceived at most one time with respect to such goods, and therefore in general losses will be small. In Schmalensee (1978) there are losses to consumers from deceptively advertised experience goods, with losses increasing as consumers believe ads. Regulators should concentrate on relatively expensive experience goods and particularly on credence goods. This analysis has additional implications. In particular, it points to the importance of reputation as a protection against deception and to the importance of advertising in generating a reputation (see Rubin, 1990, Chapter 8). Economists had long been puzzled by apparently noninformative advertising. Nelson (1974) showed that in certain circumstances the very existence of advertising would itself provide information. Advertising would only be worthwhile if it led to repeat sales for experience goods, but firms could expect repeat sales only if the product were of sufficiently high quality. Therefore, the willingness of a firm to spend money on advertising would itself provide information to the market that the firm expected repeat sales because it believed that its products were of high quality. Problems of assuring or guaranteeing quality arise in many markets. The problem was first analyzed by George Akerlof in a famous article dealing with ‘Lemons’ (Akerlof, 1970). A lemons market is defined as a market which fails in that only low quality items are sold, even though consumers would be willing to pay high prices for high quality items. Three conditions are necessary to generate a lemons market. First, consumers must be unable to determine quality before purchase. Second, it is necessary that higher quality goods cost more to produce than lower quality. Finally, there cannot be a credible way for a firm to guarantee quality. If these three conditions are met, then the market mechanism may break down. This will happen because no firm will be able to convincingly promise high quality items. As a result consumers cannot be sure of obtaining the higher quality and so will not pay the higher price for quality items. Thus, even though consumers would be willing to pay a higher price in order to obtain quality, there will not be an effective way in which this desire can be satisfied. It is in this sense that the market may malfunction.
5110
Information Regulation
279
The lemons problem identified by Akerlof (1970) exists only if firms cannot convincingly communicate to consumers the level of quality in their products. If firms can produce high quality products and convince consumers that they are doing so, then the market failure disappears. There is a substantial literature devoted to the economics of information which demonstrates ways in which markets can and do solve the problem (see Ippolito, 1986). The implications of this literature for advertising regulation have not been fully explored. Klein and Leffler (1981) explicitly related Nelson’s discussion of advertising to Akerlof’s lemons problem. They showed that the mechanism identified by Nelson and related mechanisms could be used to solve the lemons problem. Investments in nonsalvageable firm-specific capital (capital which would become worthless if the firm were to shut down) would serve to guarantee quality since the firm would lose the value of these investments if consumers dissatisfied with low quality products forced it to shut down by withdrawing patronage. In addition to advertising (including endorsements by celebrities) such capital includes investments in establishing trademarks and brand names, and also in physical assets, such as signs and decor. Shapiro (1982, 1983) showed that firms could invest in establishing a reputation for being quality producers and that what might appear to be excess profits would actually be a return on this investment. Generalizations of these results were provided by Allen (1984) and by Kihlstrom and Riordan (1984). Milgrom and Roberts (1986) showed that the results were robust to allowing price variation, and that in this situation price itself could sometimes serve as an additional signal of quality. Lynch et al. (1986) provided an experimental test of these models. They found that it is possible to generate lemons markets in laboratory settings, that truthful advertising will eliminate problems associated with such markets and that reputations will sometimes serve to eliminate these problems. Arguments regarding incentives to produce quality are routinely accepted in the economics literature. For example Landes and Posner (1987, p. 270) indicate that ‘creating such a reputation [for high quality] requires expenditure on product quality, service, advertising and so on’. This article also discusses the importance of creation of property rights in trademarks and brand names. It is only if such property rights are created that firms have proper incentives to maintain quality. Once it has been decided to confine regulation to particular types of ads and product characteristics, however, the problem is not solved. Any deceptive ad will deceive some and inform others. Therefore, a balancing test of some sort is required in order to determine if a case is worth bringing. Recently, an economic analysis of deception has provided exactly this sort of balancing test: ‘An advertisement is legally deceptive if and only if it leaves some consumers holding a false belief about a product, and the ad could be cost-effectively
280
Information Regulation
5110
changed to reduce the resulting injury’ (Craswell, 1985, p. 657; see also Craswell, 1991). This criteria for deception essentially says that an ad is deceptive only if the costs of changing it are less than the benefits. Included in the cost of changing the ad is any information lost by those consumers who were not deceived by the initial ad and who would find a proposed substitute less informative. This cost-benefit criterion is a useful guideline for exercise of prosecutorial discretion, and a guideline based on an explicitly economic analysis. There have also been analyses of competitors suits leading to private enforcement of remedies for deception under the Lanham Act. Jordan and Rubin (1979) are skeptical of the potential benefits of such suits. On the other hand, Saunders (1991) argues that in the context of claims regarding popularity of a product and claims regarding certain categories of credence goods competitors could do a good job of policing. There have been many additional Lanham Act suits since the empirical analysis in Jordan and Rubin (1979) and this is an interesting area for further research.
4. Deception by Omission and Mandated Disclosures So far, I have dealt with deception in the form of false statements. However, a further class of acts which are sometimes viewed as deceptive are statements which are true but incomplete in some way which is viewed as material. For these cases, regulatory agencies impose various remedies. Sometimes sellers are held to commit ‘deception by omission’. In other cases, there is some mandated disclosure associated with an ad. These mandated disclosures may be required ‘across-the-board’ for all advertising of a product, or may be ‘triggered’ by some claim (See Beales, Craswell and Salop, 1981a). An example of mandated disclosure is the set of warnings on cigarette packs and in cigarette advertising. These disclosures are across-the-board since any ad for a cigarette requires a health warning. Triggered disclosures are disclosures required only if some other claim is made. For example, under the US Truth in Lending statute, whenever a statement about down payments is made, there must also be statements about the interest rate (Annual Percentage Rate) and the number and size of monthly payments. Another example is provided by the FTC ‘Funeral Rule’ which required that funeral providers give consumers various types of information. In a study of this rule, McChesney (1990) found large costs and no measurable benefits. While such disclosure remedies are common, economic analysis casts doubt on their general utility. There is support in the literature for the hypothesis that, as long as explicit deception is forbidden, sellers have incentives to reveal negative attributes of their products, because otherwise consumers will
5110
Information Regulation
281
rationally assume that an advertisement will omit a critical piece of information (say, the weight of a notebook computer) only if the value of that attribute for that product is low. Thus, producers of products with quality levels above the minimum will have incentives to advertise this fact, and in the limit the market will provide complete information. The models which prove this result are quite general, and the result seems robust. This result has been shown in Grossman (1981), Milgrom (1981), Jovanovic (1982) and Milgrom and Roberts (1986). Jovanovic (1982) shows that in many circumstances there will actually be too much information disclosed. Matthews and Postlewaite (1985) show that under some circumstances mandated disclosure laws will induce firms not to test their products for quality. An example is the advertising of tar and nicotine content of cigarettes (Calfee, 1986). In the 1950s (and perhaps earlier) consumers began to fear the health effects of smoking, and began to believe that tar and nicotine were undesirable. (The process described here generally requires at least some consumer information regarding the negative characteristic. However, regulation is unlikely to occur in an environment where there is a total lack of such knowledge.) As a result, cigarette companies began to advertise the levels of tar and nicotine, with the advertising being stimulated by those brands with the lowest levels. The process was greatly slowed down in 1959 when the FTC virtually stopped such advertising. Nonetheless, there was a substantial incentive for advertisers to publicize the negative aspects of their products, as long as some brands had less negative characteristics than others. From a theoretical perspective, the process of advertising negative characteristics is the obverse of the lemons problem, discussed above. In a lemons market, information is not verifiable, and as a result only low quality products are sold because sellers cannot convince buyers to pay for high quality products. The process discussed in this section requires some form of verification, but the theory indicates that if there is some method of checking on claims, then sellers will offer complete information about both high and low quality products. Indeed, the analysis is just the mirror image of the lemons analysis. That analysis shows that if the lemons problem can be solved, sellers of high quality products will have incentives to reveal that their products are indeed of high quality. But this means in the limit that any seller of a product which is of any quality above the minimum will indicate quality. Consumers may then assume that any product which does not disclose quality is of minimum quality, and the informational problem is solved. In making policy with respect to disclosure, it is important to distinguish between equilibrium and disequilibrium situations. At equilibrium, there will be a substantial amount of disclosure in markets. However, many interesting policy issues occur in periods of disequilibrium. The disequilibrium may be with respect to advertising, but it may be in terms of actual product
282
Information Regulation
5110
characteristics as well. Advertising affects sales at current prices of existing products. It also influences characteristics and prices of products which firms will offer in the future. Advertising changes future product characteristics because a firm will only produce products or establish prices that it expects to be able to advertise. (See Calfee and Pappalardo, 1989, for a discussion in the context of health claims.) An example is the introduction of Nutrasweet (aspartame) into diet soft drinks. Initially, diet products used a combination of saccharin and aspartame, and advertised ‘Now Contains Nutrasweet’. Some states believed that this claim implied the products had no saccharin, and would have stopped the advertising. The FTC, however, did not do so. Rather quickly, other drinks began to use Nutrasweet exclusively, and advertise that fact. Now, virtually all drinks use only Nutrasweet. Thus, the ability to advertise Nutrasweet during the transition was essential to reaching the new equilibrium. A disequilibrium is likely in a market which has changed in some way. Possible changes are in product characteristics, in information about products, or in consumers’ tastes. Because there has been some change, existing products will not perfectly satisfy consumers’ desires. Nonetheless, producers of those products which are closest to satisfying new desires will have an incentive to advertise this fact. In such circumstances, some advertisers may initially offer partial information to consumers. At some point other advertisers will compete by offering more complete information, and others may compete by further changing the product to reflect changed tastes. The ultimate equilibrium will occur with relatively full information and with the optimal set of products being offered. However, if the process is stopped because regulatory authorities think that the partial information is deceptive, then the full information equilibrium will never be reached, and the best set of products may not be sold. Moreover, information useful during the disequilibrium period may be different from information needed once the new equilibrium is reached. Disclosure requirements based on information needed in the disequilibrium may simply impose costs with no benefits once the equilibrium is reached. A good example is the history of advertising of the fiber content of breakfast cereals (Ippolito and Mathios, 1990). This advertising was contrary to the FDA’s policies regarding advertising of health claims in foods. Nonetheless, once the advertising began, cereals with higher fiber content increased sales, and new cereals with increased fiber were marketed. Moreover, during the same period, levels of sodium and fat in cereals also decreased. Advertising did a more effective job of spreading this information to consumers than had governmental attempts at communication. Another example of a change in product characteristics caused by advertising is cigarette advertising, mentioned above (Calfee, 1986). When advertising began, tar content of filter cigarettes was virtually no lower than for regular cigarettes. Nonetheless, over a short period (1957-59) as a result of
5110
Information Regulation
283
heavy advertising of tar and nicotine content, levels (weighted by sales) fell by 40 percent. The first cigarettes to advertise had perhaps only marginally lower tar levels than other brands, and when regulators looked at this advertising they ultimately stopped it as being deceptive. The long-run effect of the advertising before it was stopped was to actually change product characteristics. As sellers competed by advertising tar and nicotine levels, some producers found it worthwhile to reduce levels in order to be able to advertise lower amounts. Other firms responded, and the ultimate result was reduced levels of tar and nicotine. The benefits to consumers of this dynamic effect of the advertising greatly outweighed any potential harmful effects from any alleged initial deception.
5. Regulation of Health Claims In order to evaluate regulation of health advertising (and particularly advertising of prescription drugs) it is necessary to first look at the effect of the advertising. Leffler (1981) examined prescription drug advertising and found that it informed physicians about the effects of superior new products but also created some barriers to new entry by later competitors. Nonetheless, he found a beneficial effect of advertising and promotion. Hurwitz and Caves (1988) find similar results, and conclude that a law making entry by generics easier should lower the barriers to entry created by advertising of established brands. Rubin (1994) found that there was no evidence of deception in pharmaceutical advertising. The FTC generally allows any advertising which is truthful, with only a few exceptions, such as mandated disclosure, discussed above. The FDA, on the other hand, greatly restricts even truthful advertising, including advertising of true claims for prescription medicines. Presumably it is for the same reason that the agency is excessively cautious in approving new drugs (Peltzman, 1973). If a direct to consumer print ad for a prescription drug mentions both the name and the use of the drug, it must also provide an extensive discussion of contraindications and side effects. These disclosures are commonly pages of small print. As a result, prescription drug ads often indicate either the name of the drug (usually for price comparison purposes) or that one should ‘see your physician’ for some unnamed treatment for particular symptoms, although some ads do contain the complete set of warnings in small print. TV ads for prescription drugs were until recently effectively forbidden by the disclosure requirements. There are both health and economic benefits to be expected from prescription drug advertising, and the FDA does not pay sufficient attention to the benefits from promotion (Masson and Rubin, 1985, 1986). In addition to providing health benefits, increased advertising would lead to lower prices for prescription drugs. Advertising could inform consumers of substitution possibilities and thus put pressure on prices. As of now, many
284
Information Regulation
5110
retailers advertise prices of drugs by name, but they cannot indicate the use of the drug. Some consumers may recognize that the advertised drug is the one that they are taking, but others will not and will not be able to benefit from the low prices. For some studies of the effect of advertising on prices, see Benham (1972), Steiner (1973), Marvel (1976), Farris and Albion (1980), Kwoka (1984) and Haas-Wilson (1986). (See also the references in Section 7 regarding advertising by attorneys.) The FDA has advertising jurisdiction over some aspects of nonprescription or over-the-counter (OTC) drugs and also over some aspects of food advertising, particularly with respect to health claims. The FDA is sometimes unwilling to allow true claims about even OTC drugs. It is continuing its policy of discouraging truthful advertising of the large effects of aspirin in reducing heart attacks, in spite of overwhelming scientific evidence about the truth of this claim and evidence that physicians do not communicate this benefit to patients (Keith, 1995). The FDA also generally requires prior approval of the substance of many advertising claims. Beales (1994) discusses the costs and benefits of this prior approval in the context of unapproved uses for prescription drugs that are marketed for other uses, and finds that the costs are greater than the benefits. In recent years, the FTC, which shares jurisdiction in a complex way with the FDA (discussed in Calfee and Pappalardo, 1989, and in Beales, 1994) has suggested more leniency in allowing true advertising claims than has the FDA. Part of this disagreement is because economists at the FTC focus on benefits as well as costs of advertising and therefore are more likely to advocate allowing true claims. An issue which arises in discussing ‘true’ claims is the standard of truth. Many claims about product characteristics are uncertain and their validity is probabilistic. Many health claims are of this sort: it is not certain whether or not some claim is true. The proper standard of proof in this case is a costbenefit test. That is, health claims would be allowed if the expected value (in terms of health outcomes) is positive. If there is some chance that a drug might save lives and if it has relatively insignificant side-effects, then a claim might be allowed even if there is a relatively small probability of its being true. The FDA often seems to require a higher standard, under which a claim would not be allowed unless there were perhaps a 95 percent chance that it is true. This would deny consumers much valuable information (Calfee and Pappalardo, 1989). Urban and Mancke (1972) discuss federal regulation of aging claims regarding US whiskey. They show that the regulation (which required that whiskey be aged in new, rather than reused barrels in order to claim to be ‘aged’) had the effect of benefiting manufacturers of barrels, producers of traditional US ‘heavy’ whiskey, and importers, and harming producers of US light whiskey and consumers.
5110
Information Regulation
285
Schneider, Klein and Murphy (1981) show that the 1971 ban on cigarette advertising on television in the US did not reduce and may have increased cigarette consumption, but that information regarding the risk associated with smoking did lead to long term reductions. Mitchell and Mulherin (1988) find that the ban led to an increase in stock prices of cigarette manufacturers, presumably because the ban made entry more difficult.
6. Advertising by Lawyers There have also been explicit studies of advertising by attorneys. The FTC found that whenever there was a significant difference in price of a particular legal service as a function of advertising restrictiveness, prices were higher in cities where there was greater restriction of advertising (Jacobs et al., 1984; see also Cox, Deserpa and Canby, 1982), and Calvani, Langenfeld and Shuford, 1988). Hudec and Trebilcock (1982) discuss the case of Canada and also suggest much less regulation than has been traditional. The organized bar has historically favored advertising restrictions. Advertising by attorneys provides benefits to consumers and to some attorneys, but overall attorneys lose money from such advertising. Posner, for example, indicates that advertising is more important for new entrants and that prohibition of advertising is a part of the traditional attorney cartel (Posner, 1993). That such bans on advertising are consistent with the self interest of attorneys is obvious from the FTC study, which shows that reduction on restrictions on advertising lead to lower prices for attorney services. The evidence indicates that ‘legal clinics’ offer higher quality service than traditional lawyers (McChesney and Muris, 1979; Muris and McChesney, 1979). The general issue is also discussed in McChesney (1985) and the Supreme Court cases are summarized in McChesney (1996).
7. Remedies Some remedies for deception which have been used or proposed are, in increasing order of severity, cease and desist orders, corrective advertising, consumer redress and fines. In order to evaluate these remedies, it is useful to set forth a theory as to the goal of the remedy. The ultimate goal is of course maximization of consumer welfare and this can be achieved if it does not pay for firms to engage in acts which are likely to lower welfare. Policies should therefore be aimed at making sure that harmful acts do not pay. What is relevant is that a remedy provide the correct amount of deterrence. For the types of activities discussed in this paper, it is possible to have either
286
Information Regulation
5110
underdeterrence or overdeterrence. Underdeterrence is the situation in which whatever penalties exist are too low, so that too much deception occurs. Overdeterrence occurs when penalties are too high. While it may appear that it is impossible to have ‘too little’ deception, it is nonetheless possible to overdeter deceptive advertising. This is because, as indicated at many points in this paper, the line between deception and useful information is not always clear and one result of overdeterring deception through excessive penalties would be the suppression of provision of information that many consumers will find useful. On the general issue of optimal deterrence, see Becker (1968), Posner (1993, Chapter 7) and Polinsky and Shavell (1979). For an application based on the FTC see Nash (1991). For a discussion of overdeterrence of ‘white collar crime’ see Rubin and Zwirb (1987). Advertising is discussed in ibid., pp. 904-905. The traditional FTC remedy for deception was a cease and desist order which required the firm to stop the offending ad. In general, such orders include language forbidding the practice in question in the future, and are enforced by fines. This remedy appears relatively mild and therefore unlikely to overdeter, although there is evidence dealing with the stock market effects of these orders which indicates that they may be much more costly than is apparent (Peltzman, 1981; Mathios and Plummer, 1989). This may be in part because such orders contain ‘fencing in’ provisions that may apply to additional advertising for other products or claims, although the capital market effects are still larger than seems reasonable. The Magnuson-Moss FTC Improvements Act of 1975 has given the Commission broader powers, including the power to enforce rules with monetary penalties and also the power to seek redress for fraud under some circumstances (for a discussion of FTC remedies, see Muris, 1991). The Commission has relied heavily on the theory of optimal deterrence in computing fines, and the economists are deeply involved in these computations. For most deception cases, the Commission still relies on cease and desist orders. In most cases, this is the appropriate remedy. As indicated above, a determination that an ad is deceptive is difficult, and many ads may be innocently written and later interpreted as being deceptive. Even when using their best efforts, firms will sometimes err and produce an ad which is later held to be deceptive. Since this is so, any penalties more severe than an order to stop could easily cause firms to reduce the amount of potentially actionable material in their ads; this would be done by simply reducing the information content of the ads, and relying instead on puff or image advertising. Another remedy is ‘corrective advertising’, requiring the advertiser to pay for advertising to counter the deceptive advertising. This remedy may be inappropriate since most evidence indicates that the effects of advertising are short lived (Ehrlich and Fisher, 1982; McAuliffe, 1987, p. 69; Thomas, 1989) and therefore the effects would likely have dissipated before the corrective ad would appear. The only purpose of a corrective ad would therefore be additional
5110
Information Regulation
287
deterrence, but if desired this can be achieved more efficiently through direct methods. Heald (1988) discusses remedies in private civil suits where the courts have ordered losing defendants to pay large damages based on the cost to the defendants of the deceptive advertising, in theory to be used by winning plaintiffs to finance corrective advertising. He finds these payments excessive, leading to overdeterrence. Singdahlsen (1991) is also concerned with overdeterrence. The FTC has powers to name advertising agencies as well as advertisers in complaints for deception. If agencies have skills in assuring that ads are not illegally deceptive, then finding them liable would seem to increase the ability of the Commission to deter deception. However, advertisers have contractual agreements with agencies. Therefore, if advertisers want agencies to help them comply with the law they can contract for these services, as shown in the Coase theorem. It would even be possible for an advertiser to contract with an agency for indemnification by the agency in the event of liability. More generally, it would not be efficient for agencies to determine the truth or degree of substantiation for each ad they produce. Imposing liability would increase the costs of advertising since agencies would be forced to make an independent investigation of each ad. For those acts which are to be punished by a fine, it is important to use the correct fine. First, it is appropriate to restrict the use of fines to true fraud (deception where the firm is consciously attempting to deceive) since this reduces the chances of overdeterring provision of true information. Second, the correct fine is one which is just equal to the (expected) harm caused by the deception. Such a fine will provide firms with the correct incentives. Since some who engage in deception will not be caught, the actual fine must be greater than the observed harm for those who are detected. If, for example, one offender of three is detected, then the fine must be equal to three times the harm caused by those who are punished. In this case, the probabilistic value of the fine to someone considering violation will just be equal to the harm his act will cause, and the result will be that firms will not undertake acts which impose net harms on consumers. As indicated above, this is the exact goal of deterrence. (For a discussion of computation of probabilities, see Feinstein, 1990, and Nash, 1991.) Altrogge and Shughart (1984) found that FTC fines in advertising cases transfer money from small to large firms, consistent with the literature on rent seeking.
288
Information Regulation
5110
Bibliography on Information Regulation (Including Regulation of Advertising) (5110) Akerlof, George A. (1970), ‘The Market for Lemons: Qualitative Uncertainty and the Market Mechanism’, 84 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 488-500. Allen, Franklin (1984), ‘Reputation and Product Quality’, 15 Rand Journal of Economics, 311-327. Altrogge, Phyllis and Shughart, William F., II (1984), ‘The Regressive Nature of Civil Penalties’, 4 International Review of Law and Economics, 55-66. American Bar Association (1989), ‘Report of the American Bar Association Section of Antitrust Law Special Committee to Study the Role of the Federal Trade Commission’, 58 Antitrust Law Journal, 43-178. Arruñada, Benito (1990), ‘La Regulación de la Información Empresarial (Regulation of Corporate Information)’, 51 Boletín del Círculo de Empresarios, 11-42. Assmann, Heinz-Dieter (1983), ‘Entwicklungstendenzen der Prospekthaftung (Tendencies of Liability for Misleading Information)’, WM, 138-144. Assmann, Heinz-Dieter (1985), Prospekthaftung (Liability for Misleading Information Included in Prospectuses), Köln, Heymann, 456 p. Ayanian, Robert (1975), ‘Advertising and Rate of Return’, 18 Journal of Law and Economics, 479-506. Beales, J. Howard, III (1986), ‘Comments (The Effects of the Advertising Substantiation Program on Advertising Agencies) (An Economic Analysis of the FTC’s Ad Substantiation Program)’, in Ippolito, Pauline M. and Scheffman, David T. (eds), Empirical Approaches to Consumer Protection Economics, Washington, DC, Federal Trade Commission, 213-216. Beales, J. Howard III (1994), ‘Economic Analysis and the Regulation of Pharmaceutical Advertising’, 24 Seton Hall Law Review, 1386-1386. Beales, J. Howard III and Muris, Timothy J. (1993), State and Federal Regulation of National Advertising, Washington, American Enterprise Institute. Beales, J. Howard, III, Craswell, Richard and Salop, Steven C. (1981a), ‘Information Remedies for Consumer Protection’, 71 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 410-413. Beales, J. Howard, III, Craswell, Richard and Salop, Steven C. (1981b), ‘The Efficient Regulation of Consumer Information’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 491-539. Becker, Gary S. (1968), ‘Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach’, 76 Journal of Political Economy, 169-217. Benham, Lee (1972), ‘The Effect of Advertising on the Price of Eyeglasses’, 15 Journal of Law and Economics, 337-352. Benham, Lee and Benham, Alexandra (1975), ‘Regulating Through the Professions: A Perspective on Information Control’, 18 Journal of Law and Economics, 421-447. Benham, Lee and Benham, Alexandra (1978), ‘Prospects for Increasing Competition in the Professions’, in Slayton, Philip and Trebilcock, Michael J. (eds), The Professions and Public Policy, Toronto, University of Toronto Faculty of Law. Blair, Edward A. and Landon, Laird E., Jr (1981), ‘The Effects of Reference Prices in Retail Advertisements’, 45 Journal of Marketing, 61-69. Bond, Ronald and Murphy, Dennis (1992), An Analysis of Department Store Reference Pricing in Metropolitan Washington, Washington, DC, , Federal Trade Commission.
5110
Information Regulation
289
Cady, J. (1976), Restricted Advertising and Competition: The Case of Retail Drugs, Washington, American Enterprise Institute. Cafaggi, Fabrizio (1995), ‘Pubblicitá Commerciale (Commercial Advertising)’, 9 Digesto Commerciale, 433-500. Cafaggi, Fabrizio, Cuffaro, Vincenzo and Di Via Luciano (1993), ‘Attuazione della Direttiva n. 450/84/Cee in Materia di Pubblicitá Ingannevole (d.leg. 25 gennaio 1992 n. 74) (Implementation of EC Directive no. 450/84 on Misleading Advertising)’, Le Nuove Leggi Civili Commentate, 671-761. Calfee, John E. (1986), ‘The Ghost of Cigarette Advertising Past’, 10 Regulation, 35-45. Calfee, John E. and Pappalardo, Janis K. (1989), How Should Health Claims for Food Be Regulated: An Economic Perspective, Washington, DC, Bureau of Economics, Federal Trade Commission. Calvani, Terry (1989), ‘Advertising Regulation: The States v. FTC’, 58 Antitrust Law Journal, 253-266. Calvani, Terry, Langenfeld, James and Shuford, Gordon (1988), ‘Attorney Advertising and Competition at the Bar’, 41 Vanderbilt Law Review, 761-788. Coase, Ronald H. (1977), ‘Advertising and Free Speech’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-34. Comanor, William S. and Wilson, Thomas A. (1979), ‘The Effect of Advertising on Competition: A Survey’, 17 Journal of Economic Literature, 453-476. Cooter, Robert D. (1985), ‘Defective Warnings, Remote Causes, and Bankruptcy: Comment on Schwartz’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 737-750. Costley, Carolyn L. and Brucks, Merrie (1987), ‘The Roles of Product Knowledge and Age on Children’s Responses to Deceptive Advertising’, in Bloom, Paul N. (ed), Advances in Marketing and Public Policy, Greenwich, CT, JAI Press, 41-63. Cox, Steven R., Deserpa, Allan C. and Canby, William C., Jr (1982), ‘Consumer Information and the Pricing of Legal Services’, 30 Journal of Industrial Economics, 305-305. Craswell, Richard (1985), ‘Interpreting Deceptive Advertising’, 65 Boston University Law Review, 657-732. Craswell, Richard (1991), ‘Regulating Deceptive Advertising: The Role of Cost-Benefit Analysis’, 64 Southern California Law Review, 549-604. Curran, Christopher (1994), ‘The Burden of Proof and the Liability Rule for Suppliers of Services in the EEC’, 70 Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance, 85-98. Darby, Michael R. and Karni, Edi (1973), ‘Free Competition and the Optimal Amount of Fraud’, 16 Journal of Law and Economics, 111-126. De Turck, Mark A. and Goldhaber, Gerald M. (1989), ‘Effectiveness of Product Warning Labels: Effects of Consumers’ Information Processing Objectives’, 23 Journal of Consumer Affairs, 111-126. Demsetz, Harold (1976), ‘More on Collusion and Advertising: A Reply’, 19 Journal of Law and Economics, 205-209. Duggan, A.J. (1978), ‘The Great Soap Opera’, 11 Melbourne University Law Review, 467-502. Ehrlich, Isaac and Fisher, Lawrence (1982), ‘The Derived Demand for Advertising: A Theoretical and Empirical Approach’, 71 American Economic Review, 366-388. Ekelund, Robert B., Jr and Saurman, David S. (1988), Advertising and the Market Process, San Francisco, Pacific Research Institute. Elzinga, Kenneth G. (1980), Regulating the Professions: A Public-Policy Symposium, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books.
290
Information Regulation
5110
Farris, Paul and Albion, Mark (1980), ‘The Impact of Advertising on the Price of Consumer Products’, 44 Journal of Marketing, 17-35. Feinstein, Jonathan S. (1990), ‘Detection Controlled Estimation’, 33 Journal of Law and Economics, 233-276. Ferguson, James M. (1983), ‘Daily Newspaper Advertising Rates, Local Media Cross-Ownership, Newspaper Chains, and Media Competition’, 26 Journal of Law and Economics, 635-654. Finsinger, Jörg (1989), ‘Kommentar’ Die Zivilrechtliche Haftung für Werbeangaben bei der Vertragsanbahnung als Problem der Allokationseffizienz (Comment on Lehmann)’, in Ott, Claus and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (eds), Allekationseffizienz in der Rechtsordnung, Berlin, Springer-Verlag, 185-187. Frech, H. Edward III and Rochlin, Clifford B. (1979), ‘Advertising as a Privately Supplied Public Good’, 27(2) Economic Inquiry, 414-418. Frech, H. Edward III and Rochlin, Clifford B. (1982), ‘A New Economic View of Advertising’, 1 Journal of Advertising, 213-222. Goldberg, Victor P. (1986), ‘Fishing and Selling’, 15 Journal of Legal Studies, 173-180. Grady, Mark F. (1981), ‘Regulating Information: Advertising Overview’, in Clarkson, K.W. and Muris, T.J. (eds), The Federal Trade Commission Since 1970: Economic Analysis and Bureaucratic Behavior, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Grossman, Sanford J. (1981), ‘The Informational Role of Warranties and Private Disclosure about Product Quality’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 461-483. Haas-Wilson, Deborah (1986), ‘The Effect of Commercial Practice Restrictions: The Case of Optometry’, 29 Journal of Law and Economics, 165-186. Hazard, Geoffrey C., Jr, Pearce, Russell G. and Stempel, Jeffrey W. (1983), ‘Why Lawyers Should be Allowed to Advertise: A Market Analysis of Legal Services’, 58 New York University Law Review, 1084-1113. Heald, Paul J. (1988), ‘Money Damages and Corrective Advertising: An Economic Analysis’, 55 University of Chicago Law Review, 629-658. Higgins, Richard S. and McChesney, Fred S. (1986), ‘Truth and Consequences: The Federal Trade Commission’s Ad Substantiation Program’, 6 International Review of Law and Economics, 151-168. Higgins, Richard S. and McChesney, Fred S. (1986), ‘An Economic Analysis of the FTC’s Ad Substantiation Program’, in Ippolito, Pauline M. and Scheffman, David T. (eds), Empirical Approaches to Consumer Protection Economics, Washington, DC, Federal Trade Commission, 197-211. Hilke, John C. (1986), ‘Early Mandatory Disclosure Regulations’, 6 International Review of Law and Economics, 229-239. Holdych, Tom (1994), ‘Standards for Establishing Deceptive Conduct Under State Deceptive Trade Practices Statutes that Impose Punitive Remedies’, 73 Oregon Law Review, 235-344. Hudec, Albert J. and Trebilcock, Michael J. (1982), ‘Lawyer Advertising and the Supply of Information in the Market for Legal Services’, 20 University of Western Ontario Law Review, 53-99. Hurwitz, Mark A. and Caves, Richard E. (1988), ‘Persuasion or Information? Promotion and the Shares of Brand Name and Generic Pharmaceuticals’, 31 Journal of Law and Economics, 299-320. Ippolito, Pauline M. (1986), ‘Consumer Protection Economics: A Selective Survey’, in Ippolito,
5110
Information Regulation
291
Pauline M. and Scheffman, David T. (eds), Empirical Approaches to Consumer Protection Economics, Washington, DC, Federal Trade Commission, 1-33. Ippolito, Pauline M. and Mathios, Alan D. (1990), ‘Information, Advertising and Health Choices: A Study of the Cereal Market’, 21 Rand Journal of Economics, 459-480. Ippolito, Pauline M. and Scheffman, David T. (1986), Consumer Protection Economics, Washington, DC, Federal Trade Commission. Jacobs, William W. et al. (1984), Improving Consumer Access To Legal Services: The Case For Removing Restrictions On Truthful Advertising, Washington, DC, Report of the Staff of the Federal Trade Commission. Jordan, Ellen R. and Rubin, Paul H. (1979), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Law of False Advertising’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 116-155. Reprinted in Rubin, Paul H. (1983), Business Firms and the Common Law, Praeger. Jovanovic, Boyan (1982), ‘Truthful Disclosure of Information’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 36-44. Kassarjian, Harold H. and Kassarjian, Waltraud M. (1988), ‘The Impact of Regulation on Advertising: A Content Analysis’, 11 Journal of Consumer Policy, 269-285. Keith, Alison (1995), ‘Regulating Information About Aspirin and the Prevention of Heart Attack’, 85 American Economic Review, 96-99. Kelley, Craig A., Gaidis, William C. and Reingen, Peter H. (1989), ‘The Use of Vivid Stimuli to Enhance Comprehension of the Content of Product Warning Messages’, 23 Journal of Consumer Affairs, 243-266. Kihlstrom, Richard E and Riordan, Michael H. (1984), ‘Advertising as a Signal’, 92 Journal of Political Economy, 427-450. Kitch, Edmund W. (1995), ‘The Theory and Practice of Securities Disclosure’, 61 Brooklyn Law Review, 761 ff. Kitch, Edmund W. and Perlman, Harvey (1991), Legal Regulation of the Competitive Proces: Cases, Materials and Notes on Unfair Business Pratices, Trademarks, Copyrights and Patents, Mineola, NY, Foundation Press. Klein, Benjamin and Leffler, Keith B. (1981), ‘The Role of Market Forces in Assuring Contractual Performance’, 89 Journal of Political Economy, 615-641. Kohl, Helmut, Kübler, Friedrich, Walz, W. Rainer and Wüstrich, Wolfgang (1974), ‘Abschreibungsgesellschaften, Kapitalmarkteffizienz und Publizitätszwang - Plädoyer für ein Vermögensanlagegesetz (Tax Shelter Companies, Efficiency of Capital Markets and Information Regulation? A Plea for a Law Regulating the Public Offer of Investment Opportunities)’, 138 Zeitschrift für das Gesamte Handels- und Wirtschaftsrecht, 1-49. Kotowitz, Y. and Mathewson, G. Frank (1979), ‘Advertising, Consumer Information, and Product Quality’, 10 Bell Journal of Economics, 566-588. Kwoka, John (1984), ‘Advertising and the Price and Quality of Optometric Services’, 74 American Economic Review, 211-216. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1987), ‘Trademark Law: An Economic Perspective’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 265-309. Reprinted in 21 Intellectual Property Law Review, 1989, 229-273. Leffler, Keith B. (1981), ‘Persuasion of Information? The Economics of Prescription Drug Advertising’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 45-74. Lehmann, Michael (1981), Vertragsanbahnung durch Werbung (Contract Preparing through Promotion), München, C.H. Beck. Lehmann, Michael (1989), ‘Die Zivilrechtliche Haftung für Werbeangaben bei der Vertragsanbahnung
292
Information Regulation
5110
als Problem der Allokationseffizienz (Civil Liability for Advertising as a Problem of Allocative Efficiency)’, in Ott, Claus and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (eds), Allokationseffizienz in der Rechtsordnung, Berlin, Springer-Verlag, 169-184. Liefeld, John and Heslop, Louise A. (1985), ‘Reference Prices and Deception in Newspaper Advertising’, 11 Journal of Consumer Research, 868-876. Lott, John R., Jr (1996), ‘The Optimal Level of Fines to Prevent Fraud when Reputations Exist and Penalty Clauses are Unenforceable’, 17 Managerial and Decision Economics, 363-368. Lynch, Michael, Miller, Ross M., Plott, Charles R. and Porter, Russell (1986), ‘Product Quality, Consumer Information and “Lemons” in Experimental Markets’, in Ippolito, Pauline M. and Scheffman, David T. (eds), Empirical Approaches to Consumer Protection Economics, Washington, DC, Federal Trade Commission, 251-306. Lyndon, Mary L. (1989), ‘Information Economics and Chemical Toxicity: Designing Laws to Produce and Use Data’, 87 Michigan Law Review, 1795-1861. MacKaay, Ejan (1979), Proceedings of the Seventh Annual Workshop on Commercial and Consumer Law, Canada Law Book. MacKaay, Ejan (1992), ‘An Economic View of Information Law’, in Korthals Altes, Willem F., Dommering, Egbert J., Hugenholtz, P. Bernt and Kabel, Jan J.C. (eds), Information Law Towards the 21st Century, Deventer, Kluwer, 43-65. Marvel, Howard P. (1976), ‘The Economics of Information and Retail Gasoline Price Behavior’, 84 Journal of Political Economy, 1033-1060. Masson, Alison and Rubin, Paul H. (1985), ‘Matching Prescription Drugs and Consumers’, 313 New England of Medecine, 513-515. Masson, Alison and Rubin, Paul H. (1986), ‘Plugs for Drugs’, 10(1) Regulation, 37-43. Mathios, Alan D. and Plummer, Mark (1989), ‘The Regulation of Advertising by the Federal Trade Commission: Capital Market Effects’, 12 Research in Law and Economics, 77-93. Matthews, Steven and Postlewaite, Andrew (1985), ‘Quality Testing and Disclosure’, 16 Rand Journal of Economics, 328-340. McAuliffe, Robert E. (1987), Advertising, Competition and Public Policy: Theories and New Evidence, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. McChesney, Fred S. (1985), ‘Commercial Speech in the Professions: The Supreme Court’s Unanswered Questions and Questionable Answers’, 134 University of Pennsylvania Law Review. McChesney, Fred S. (1990), ‘Consumer Ignorance and Consumer Protection Law: Empirical Evidence from the FTC Funeral Rule’, 7 Journal of Law and Politics, 81-139. McChesney, Fred S. (1996), ‘De-Bates and Re-Bates: The Supreme Court’s Latest Commercial Speech Cases’, Supreme Court Economic Review. McChesney, Fred S. and Muris, Timothy J. (1979), ‘The Effects of Advertising on the Quality of Legal Services’, 65 American Bar Association, 1503-1503. Mensch, Elizabeth and Freeman, Alan (1990), ‘Efficiency and Image: Advertising as an Antitrust Issue’, 40 Duke Law Journal, 321 ff. Milgrom, Paul R. (1981), ‘Good News and Bad News: Representation Theorems and Application’, 12 Bell Journal of Economics, 380-391. Milgrom, Paul R. and Roberts, John (1986a), ‘Relying on the Information of Interested Parties’, 17 Rand Journal of Economics, 18-32. Milgrom, Paul R. and Roberts, John (1986b), ‘Price and Advertising Signals of Product Quality’, 94
5110
Information Regulation
293
Journal of Political Economy, 796-821. Mitchell, Mark L. and Mulherin, J. Harold (1988), ‘Finessing the Political System: The Cigarette Advertising Ban’, 54 Southern Economic Journal, 855-862. Monroe, Kent B. and Krishnan, R. (1985), Perceived Quality, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Muris, Timothy J. (1991), ‘Economics and Consumer Protection’, 60 Antitrust Law Journal, 103-121. Muris, Timothy J. and McChesney, Fred S. (1979), ‘Advertising and the Price and Quality of Legal Services: The Case for Legal Clinics’, 1 American Bar Foundation Research Journal, 179-207. Nagle, Thomas T. (1981), ‘Do Advertising-Profitability Studies Really Show That Advertising Creates a Barrier to Entry?’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 333-349. Nash, John F. (1991), ‘To Make the Punishment Fit the Crime: The Theory and Statistical Estimation of a Multi-Period Optimal Deterrence Model’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 101-110. Nelson, Philip (1970), ‘Information and Consumer Behavior’, 78 Journal of Political Economy, 311-329. Nelson, Philip (1974), ‘Advertising as Information’, 82 Journal of Political Economy, 729-754. O’Reilly, James T. (1987), ‘The Risks of Assumptions: Impacts of Regulatory Label Warning upon Industrial Products Liability’, 37 Catholic University Law Review, 85-117. Peltzman, Sam (1973), ‘An Evaluation of Consumer Protection Legislation: The 1962 Drug Amendments’, 81 Journal of Political Economy, 1049-1091. Peltzman, Sam (1981), ‘The Effects of FTC Advertising Regulation’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 403-448. Peltzman, Sam (1987), ‘The Health Effects of Mandatory Prescriptions’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 207-238. Pitofsky, Robert (1977), ‘Beyond Nader: Consumer Protection and the Regulation of Advertising’, 90 Harvard Law Review, 661-701. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1979), ‘The Optimal Tradeoff between the Probability and Magnitude of Fines’, 69 American Economic Review, 880-891. Posner, Richard (1986), Economic Analysis of Law, 3rd edn, Boston, Little Brown. Posner, Richard A. (1993), ‘The Material Basis of Jurisprudence’, 69 Indiana Law Review, 1 ff. Rizzo, John A. and Zeckhauser, Richard J. (1990), ‘Advertising and Entry: The Case of Physician Services’, 98 Journal of Political Economy, 476-500. Roth, Günter H. (1994), ‘Kommentar zu Bernd Oppermann: Marktransparenz und Marktaufschließung durch Werbung im Recht des unlauteren Wettbewerbs (Transparency of the Market, Market Entry by Advertising and the Law of Unfair Competition - A Comment on Bernd Oppermann’s Paper)’, in Ott, Claus and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (eds),Ökonomischer Analyse der Rechtliche Organisation von Innovationen, Tübingen, J.C.B. Mohr Publisher. Rubin, Paul H. (1990), Managing Business Transactions, New York, Free Press. Rubin, Paul H. (1991), ‘Economics and the Regulation of Deception’, 11 Cato Journal, 667-690. Rubin, Paul H. (1993), From Bad To Worse: Recent Fda Initiatives and Consumer Health, Media Institute, Bad Prescription for the First Amendment: Fda Censorship af Drug Advertising and
294
Information Regulation
5110
Promotion. Rubin, Paul H. (1994), ‘Are Pharmaceutical Ads Deceptive?’, Food and Drug Law Journal, 7-21. Rubin, Paul H. and Zwirb Robert (1987), ‘The Economics of Civil RICO’, 20 U.C. Davis Law Review, 883-917. Sauer, Raymond D. and Leffler, Keith B. (1990), ‘Did the Federal Trade Commission’s Advertising Substantiation Program Promote More Credible Advertising?’, 80 American Economic Review, 191-203. Saunders, Robert S. (1991), ‘Replacing Skepticism: An Economic Justification for Competitors’ Actions for False Advertising Under Section 43(a) of the Lanham Act’, 77 Virginia Law Review, 563-601. Schmalensee, Richard (1978), ‘A Model of Advertising and Product Quality’, 86 Journal of Political Economy, 485-505. Schneider, Lynne, Klein, Benjamin and Murphy, Kevin M. (1981), ‘Governmental Regulation of Cigarette Health Information’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 575-612. Schwartz, Alan and Wilde, Louis L. (1979), ‘Intervening in Markets on the Basis of Imperfect Information: A Legal and Economic Analysis?’, 127 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 630-682. Shapiro, Carl (1980), ‘Advertising and Welfare: Comment’, 11 Bell Journal of Economics, 749-752. Shapiro, Carl (1982), ‘Consumer Information, Product Quality, and Seller Reputation’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 20-35. Shapiro, Carl (1983), ‘Premiums for High Quality and Seller Reputation’, 98 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 659-679. Singdahlsen, Jeffrey P. (1991), ‘Note: Risk of Chill: A Cost of the Standards Governing the Regulation of False Advertising Under Section 43(a) of the Lanham Act’, 77 Virginia Law Review, 339-395. Spiller, Pablo T. (1986), ‘Comments (The Effects of the Advertising Substantiation Program on Advertising Agencies)’, in Ippolito, Pauline M. and Scheffman, David T. (eds), Empirical Approaches to Consumer Protection Economics, Washington, DC, Federal Trade Commission, 217-220. Spulber, Daniel F. (1989), Regulation and Markets, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Steiner, Robert (1973), ‘Does Advertising Lower Consumer Prices ?’,37 Journal of Marketing, 19-26. Stout, Lynn A. (1988), ‘The Unimportance of Being Efficient: An Economic Analysis of Stock Market Pricing and Securities Regulation’, 87 Michigan Law Review, 613-709. Stout, Lynn A. (1990), ‘Are Takeover Premiums Really Premiums? Market Price, Fair Value, and Corporate Law’, 99 Yale Law Journal, 1235-1296. Stout, Lynn A. (1995a), ‘Agreeing To Disagree Over Excessive Trading’, 81 Virginia Law Review, 751 ff. Stout, Lynn A. (1995b), ‘Betting the Bank: How Derivatives Trading Under Conditions of Uncertainty Can Increase Risks and Erode Returns in Financial Markets’, 21 Journal of Corporate Law, 53 ff. Stout, Lynn A. (1995c), ‘Are Stock Markets Costly Casinos? Disagreement, Market Failure, and Securities Regulation’, 81 Virginia Law Review, 611 ff. Stout, Lynn A. (1996a), ‘Insurance Or Gambling? Derivatives Trading in A World of Risk and
5110
Information Regulation
295
Uncertainty’, 39 Brookings Review. Stout, Lynn A. (1996b), ‘Type I Error, Type II Error, and the Private Securities Litigation Reform Act’, 38 Arizona Law Review, 711 ff. Stout, Lynn A. (1996c), ‘Insurance or Gambling? Derivatives Trading in a World of Risk and Uncertainty’, 39 Brookings Review. Stout, Lynn A. (1997), ‘A Technology, Transactions Costs, and Investor Welfare: Is a Motley Fool Born Every Minute?’, 75 Washington University Law Quarterly. Temin, Peter (1983), ‘Costs and Benefits in Switching Drugs from Rx to OTC’, 2 Journal of Health Economics, 187-205. Thomas, Lacy Glenn (1989), ‘Advertising in Consumer Goods Industries: Durability, Economies of Scale, and Heterogeneity’, 32 Journal of Law and Economics, 163-193. Torres Lopez, Juan (1992), ‘Regular la Información, Problemas Económicos, Perspectivas Jurídicas (Economic and Legal Issues in the Regulation of Information)’, 14 Revista de Economía. U.S. Congress (1990), ‘Nutrition Labeling and Education Act of 1990, Approved Nov. 8', Public Law, 101-535. Urban, Raymond and Mancke, Richard (1972), ‘Federal Regulation of Whiskey Labelling: From the Repeal of Prohibition to the Present’, 15 Journal of Law and Economics, 411-426. Urbany, Joel E., Bearden, William O. and Weilbaker, Dan C. (1988), ‘The Effect of Plausible and Exaggerated Reference Prices on Consumer Perceptions and Price Search’, 15 Journal of Consumer Research, 95-110. Viscusi, W. Kip (1985), ‘Consumer Behavior and the Safety Effects of Product Safety Regulation’, 28 Journal of Law and Economics, 527-553. Viscusi, W. Kip, Magat, Wesley A. and Huber, Joel (1986), ‘Informational Regulation of Consumer Health Risks: An Empirical Evaluation of Hazard Warnings’, 17 Rand Journal of Economics, 351-365. Wilkie, W.L. (1980), ‘The Impact of Professional Advertising on Consumers’, in Blair, Roger D. and Rubin, Stephen (eds), Regulating the Professions: A Public-Policy Symposium, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Williams, Stephen F. (1973), ‘Optimizing Water Use: The Return Flow Issue’, 44 University of Colorado Law Review, 301 ff. Reprinted in Stout, Lynn A. (1995), ‘Betting the Bank: How Derivatives Trading Under Conditions of Uncertainty can Increase Risks and Erode Returns in Financial Markets, 21 Journal of Corporate Law 53. Willner, Kenneth M. (1988), ‘Failures to Warn and the Sophisticated User Defense’, 74 Virginia Law Review, 579-607. Wils, Wouter and Wils, Geert (1990), ‘Free Movement of Goods and Quality Regulations for Foodstuffs’, 1 European Food Law Review, 92-117. Winsen, Joseph K. (1980), ‘Regulation of Financial Reporting’, August Australian Business Law Review, 232-255. Zethami, Valerie A. (1988), ‘Consumer Perceptions of Price, Quality and Value: A Means-End Model and Synthesis of Evidence’, 52 Journal of Marketing, 2-22.
5120 LICENSING, MARKET ENTRY REGULATION Shirley Svorny Professor at California State University © Copyright 1999 Shirley Svorny
Abstract Licensing describes the set of regulations that limit service provision to individuals or entities who meet state-established criteria. Despite claims that licensure increases service quality, the effect of licensure on consumption quality is ambiguous. That fact that service providers actively promote licensing has led to the suspicion that licensing benefits these groups at the expense of providers of competing services or consumers. Also at issue is whether information asymmetries or agency costs are strong enough to warrant government intervention. Many believe that, in the absence of government intervention, markets would generate sufficient information through reputation and other mechanisms to meet the needs of consumers. JEL classification: D18, H11, I18, J44, K12, L15 Keywords: Licensure, Labor Supply Restrictions, Regulation, Information Asymmetries, Product Quality, Consumer Protection
1. Introduction Licensure fits into the broad category of public policy aimed at reducing stubborn agency costs in the marketplace. Where one individual or a group of individuals provides services to another, a divergence of interests is impossible to avoid. There is a fair amount of leeway for the provider (the ‘agent’) to fail to perfectly represent or serve the purchaser. Although several market mechanisms exist to improve the position of the procurer (also called the ‘principal’) - to reduce the likelihood that he will encounter an opportunistic agent, or one that purposely and systematically misrepresents her product none is perfect. Market entry regulation or licensure is most often favored for its perceived ability to offer a layer of protection for consumers. Licensing involves laws and regulations which limit service provision to individuals or entities authorized to practice by the state. There are three points at which constraints have been imposed. The first is at the point of initial entry. Providers are denied entry if they do not meet established criteria or if legal limits on supply have been met. Second, it is not uncommon to regulate the production process itself. Practitioners who fail to stay within the prescribed set 296
5120
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
297
of permissible activities may have their license suspended or revoked. Finally, outcomes assessment can lead to the discipline of errant providers. Despite claims that licensure increases service quality, there is a theoretical ambiguity as to the effect of licensure on consumption quality. If, under a system of licensure, the restrictions on service provision shift a sizable portion of consumers to do-it-yourself remedies or to the black market, average quality can decline. Policy debates about licensure center on justifying entry restrictions and on whether or not the state can assure performance once individuals are granted entry. The identification of qualified personnel is not a sufficient justification for licensure, as this can be accomplished through certification. Certification, or ‘voluntary’ licensure identifies entities that meet entry standards or standards of performance, but does not restrict the practice of others. Under a system of certification, consumers have access to information about service providers, but they are not constrained from purchasing services from non-certified providers; competition is not limited. That fact that service providers, trade associations and medical societies actively promote and support licensing has led to the suspicion that licensing benefits these groups at the expense of other providers or consumers (for example, see Rottenberg 1980). Critics of market entry restrictions note that service providers’ earnings rise as competition declines and that consumers are left with fewer options and higher prices. Also at issue is whether information asymmetries or agency costs are strong enough to warrant government intervention. Many believe that in the absence of government intervention, markets would generate sufficient information through reputation and other mechanisms to meet the needs of consumers. Finally, there is the question of whether there is not some other, preferred form of public policy to insure product quality. Potential alternatives include increased civil and criminal penalties and other institutional arrangements which increase the consequences of malfeasance. In addition to its proported value in reducing agency costs, two other justifications for licensure have withstood the test of time. One age-old justification for licensure is that it provides protection from external effects associated with the purchase of low quality goods and services. This is an externalities argument. The argument is, essentially, that licensure protects society from the side-effects of poor consumption decisions of its individual members. Another traditional defense of licensure is that some people need to be guided by the state in making choices. To justify licensure, the benefits must outweigh the losses associated with reduced competition. Not one empirical study has attempted to calculate the net gain. Rather, the focus has been on testing observable implications of licensing restrictions - the effect on earnings, supply, mobility and quality.
298
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
5120
Finally, not all licensing arrangements are alike; institutional arrangements that govern licensing boards are of consequence. For example, there is support for the idea that things such as a board’s level of autonomy or its source of funding will affect its actions and decisions.
2. Basic Characteristics of Licensing Arrangements Market entry restrictions can be very simple, an agency may set quantitative limits, precluding further entry once the designated limit has been reached. Quantitative controls are the least common, however. Instead, entry is most often limited by imposing costly barriers to entry. Potential entrants may be required to make specific capital investments, to pass an examination or complete course work in approved programs and to conform with certain personal criteria (age, character, citizenship, criminal record). Where examinations are the basis for licensing, they may be designed and administered by the board, or the board may require passage of an exam administered by another organization. Filing fees and variations in application procedures affect entry to the profession as well. For example, the score required to pass an entry examination and other rules, such as the number of times an individual may re-take a required examination, may be modified to increase or decrease the difficulty of entry. Only individuals who have received a license from the state may legally offer services. In health care, ‘scope-of-practice’ restrictions, which define the extent of the profession, make it illegal for non-licensed individuals to provide similar services. Reciprocity and/or endorsement in licensing refers to situations where one jurisdiction accepts the license of another as a valid basis for licensure. Without such provisions, professionals must take licensing exams and meet other conditions of entry when they seek to practice in a new jurisdiction. Once licensed, boards attempt to control service quality. License modification, suspension and revocation are the major tools of discipline available to boards. The state may revoke a license to practice for a variety of reasons including misconduct and incompetence. Standards of proof to which disciplinary hearings are held influence the ability of the board to affectively penalize practitioners, as does the amount of funding allocated to disciplinary functions. Continuing education requirements, which require licensed individuals to take classes or engage in training to maintain their skills, are mandated in some cases. Although governing bodies have the ultimate power over licensure and discipline, the actual operations are often delegated to a public agency. Some boards are fairly autonomous, others are less so. ‘Self-regulation’ generally refers to a situation where the board is fairly autonomous and comprised of
5120
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
299
representatives of the profession to be regulated. Because self-regulation includes the potential for professional groups to restrict supply unduly to raise prices, it has been strongly criticized. Proponents of self-regulation argue its merits in circumstances where the skills to be assessed are unique to members of the profession and when consumers would be put at great risk by an incompetent or malfeasant service provider (see Tuohy and Wolfson, 1976).
3. A Brief History of Western Licensure Rubin (1980) describes the historical patterns in western law that led to modern licensing laws in the United States and other western countries (also see Council of State Governments, 1952; Derbyshire, 1969). According to Rubin, vocational societies were first formed in Europe in the eleventh and twelfth centuries. By the thirteenth century, education became an important separating criteria of the professions. Crafts and trade associations turned to apprenticeship programs to set their members apart. By the fifteenth century, desire for economic security and prestige had resulted in detailed lists of qualifications for entry and practice in almost every vocation. The private guilds of the Middle Ages - often thought of as the predecessors of modern state restrictions on occupational entry - actually served several purposes. Guilds served social, religious, insurance and trade functions. In exchange for monopoly positions, the private guilds provided a source of tax revenue for monarchs. Hickson and Thompson (1991) suggest that the establishment of guilds served to resolve defense externalities associated with overcapitalization and to connect military-aged youths to their communities in medieval times. The decline of the feudal structure of the middle ages increased mobility, and led individuals to compete with private guilds. By 1410, Rubin explains that, in England, rules governing entry and practice had fallen to court challenges, reflecting the attitude of the English courts that individual rights to earn a livelihood should be protected. English guilds responded by seeking statutory protection. Over time, representatives of guilds were successful in England and other Western European countries in establishing state-controlled monopolies in many vocations, with social, economic and religious entry standards. Once again, competition was prohibited and control over practice and discipline was left to representatives of the guilds. This system of public monopolies was overturned in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, as economic forces of the Industrial Revolution transformed Western Europe. According to Rubin, as power shifted from monarchs to democratic assemblies, direct licensing evolved. During the
300
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
5120
nineteenth and twentieth centuries, many new professions emerged, leading to a resurgence in vocational regulation in Western Europe. Efforts to license physicians are said to have begun in earnest in the United States with the formation of the American Medical Association in 1846. Up until that time, entry was virtually unrestricted (Hogan, 1983). Lack of support for national licensing left occupational regulation to the states (Rubin, 1980). The first state to pass licensing laws in the United States was Texas in 1873. A West Virginia law, passed in 1881, was challenged in the US Supreme Court in 1889, and the power of the state to license was upheld (Derbyshire, 1969). The American Nurses’ Association and the National League for Nursing launched a campaign to introduce public certification for nurses in the United States in 1900 (White, 1983). By 1923 all states had enacted certification laws for professional nurses. The first mandatory licensing laws were passed in New York and California in the late 1930s. A 1952 study by the Council of State Governments lists the dates of initial state licensing legislation for occupations in the United States (see also Moore, 1961). Included are professionals in many groups, from accountants and architects to veterinarians and watchmakers. In 1994 the state of California Department of Consumer Affairs licensed more than three dozen classifications of professional and vocational personnel, the largest groups being accountants, automotive repair professionals, barbers and cosmetologists (by far the largest category), contractors, dental assistants, behavioral science professionals, physicians, nurses, professional engineers and land surveyors, and security and investigative service providers.
4. The Economics of Market Entry Regulations The Simplest Case - Formal Quantity Controls The simplest case of market entry restrictions is to set formal quantity controls which limit entry to a fixed number of service suppliers. Where more individuals apply for than are granted licenses, market entry restrictions reduce the stock of providers, pushing prices higher than in an unregulated market. Where entry is restricted in this manner, individuals who secure licenses (through random drawings, for example) will earn economic rents; they earn more than similarly skilled individuals in alternative professions. Examples of quantity controls include restrictions on entry in local taxi markets in the United States and restrictions on the number of pharmacists in Belgium (determined by the population and distance between pharmacies). If sale of licenses is allowed (as is the case with taxi licenses (medallions) in many large US cities and pharmacies in Belgium), the present value of expected future profits will be capitalized in the sale price. The seller captures
5120
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
301
all future profits, leaving new entrants with a normal return on their investment. (Frankena and Paulter, 1984, describe taxicab regulation in the United States; see also Gallick and Sisk, 1987. Van den Bergh and Faure, 1991, discuss the licensing of pharmacists in Belgium.) Whether or not there is a deadweight loss associated with licensure depends on the benefits to consumers. In the extreme case, if there are no benefits to consumers, entry restrictions necessarily result in a deadweight loss to society. As with all restricted markets, resources with a higher value in the restricted market than elsewhere are prohibited from entering. Besides the potential for a deadweight loss from licensure, there may be a loss associated with rent-seeking behavior. If entry is restricted to arbitrarily chosen service providers, there will be a social loss associated with rent-seeking behavior. As potential entrants compete for licenses, real resources are consumed or lost in the rent-seeking process. A third loss may result, depending on conditions in the market, from the non-transferability of professional licenses. Despite not being the lowest cost provider, those who have made sunk, nontransferable investments to obtain a license will remain in the market as long as there is a positive rent on their investment (Lott, 1987, 1989; Gahvari, 1989; Zardkoohi and Pustay, 1989). Raising the Cost of Entry The most common form of entry barriers do not arbitrarily assign licenses, but raise the costs of entry by requiring investments of one sort or another. Often, educational and training requirements are specified in detail. Entrants may be required to attend and complete an accredited program that has specific time and content characteristics. The explicit costs of this investment include payments for tuition and books, but the primary cost is usually implicit - the opportunity cost of the applicant’s time. Entry fees, passing marks on state-administered examinations and other requirements (such as citizenship) also make entry more costly. As costs rise, service providers are discouraged from entering the market. Supply declines through retirements, or as demand grows faster than supply, and the price of services rises. Not until earnings rise to offset the increase in costs of entry will new professionals be attracted to the market. In this situation, although earnings are higher after regulation, new entrants are not earning profits. They earn only a normal return on their (higher) costs of entry. The new market equilibrium will be one with a lower stock of practitioners and higher prices than would have been observed in an unregulated market. Adjusted for entry costs, earnings will be no more or no less than those for similarly skilled individuals in alternative occupations. A common practice is to ‘grandfather’ (exempt) existing service providers when entry requirements are made more stringent. This means that only new entrants must meet the stricter requirements; existing providers are not held to
302
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
5120
new rules. As higher costs discourage new entrants and earnings and profitability rise, existing practitioners benefit. These gains create incentives for professional associations to lobby for increasingly strict entry requirements over time. It is also possible that ‘grandfather’ clauses are included to reduce the opposition of less-trained personnel to restrictions that will limit practice to a more elite set of professionals (see White, 1979). Licensure necessarily results in a redistribution of wealth from consumers to providers as limits on entry cause product prices to rise. Also, there can be significant redistributional effects across consumer groups. For example, if there are economies of scale in producing higher quality services, consumers who desire higher quality services will benefit from licensing laws that require advanced training. In contrast, consumers who prefer lower quality care (due to taste and/or income constraints) are worse off, as the supply of lower skilled providers is reduced or eliminated altogether.
5. The Debate over Occupational Licensing As may be obvious by now, the debate over occupational licensing is multifaceted. There is disagreement over whether information asymmetries are sufficiently great to justify government intervention, and whether the state can improve upon free consumer choice. Two theories of the role of licensure - that licensure eliminates a ‘lemons’ problem for consumers and that it decreases the marginal cost of producing quality - fail to justify licensure over certification. Two traditional arguments for licensure over certification - that it reduces the spread of disease and protects those too ignorant to protect themselves - remain. A third justification for licensure is that it creates incentives which mitigate agency costs. The following sections discuss these ideas in detail. Information Asymmetries Proponents of licensure argue that consumers have insufficient information to make an appropriate selection from the set of available suppliers. Information asymmetries are thought by some to be unusually strong in health care markets, justifying barriers to entry in medicine (Arrow, 1963; Trebilcock, 1976). One way for consumers to acquire information about product quality is by direct observation. Also, providers develop reputations over time as their service is tested and re-tested by consumers. Arguments for licensure rest on the premise that, in some markets, direct observation is impractical and reputation fails to offer sufficient protection. If consumers lack information, and if the state (or its agent) can identify and enforce appropriate standards to which practitioners should be held, it follows that state regulation has the potential to improve conditions by limiting entry to professionals who meet those standards.
5120
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
303
Writing about medical markets, Pauly and Satterthwaite (1981) suggest that reputation fails when there are so many providers, as would be the case in large cities, that the efficiency of consumer search declines. According to Pauly and Satterthwaite, as the number of physicians within a community increases, consumer information about each physician decreases and it is more difficult to search for a new physician. Friedman (1962), Rottenberg (1980) and Havighurst (1982) resist the pressure to view consumers as incapable of making reasoned choices in medical markets. Friedman notes that licensure has never been a major source of assurance about physician quality to consumers. Consumers do not choose a physician blindly from the list of licensed physicians but, instead, make choices about physicians on the basis of advice and direction from others, including referring physicians, friends and family. This information, along with specialty board certification (offered by the profession, not the state), offers protection to consumers against physician malfeasance. One empirical measure, the disparity in incomes among licensed physicians in the United States, supports the premise that consumers are capable of making judgements about physician quality unaided by state licensing regulations. Being licensed did not make International Medical Graduates the equal of US trained physicians in the US medical market (see Svorny, 1979). Quality Assurance? With respect to medical markets, critics point out how unfathomable it is that medical licensure provides consumers with useful information upon which to make informed decisions (see, for example, Goodman, 1980; Rayack, 1982; Young, 1987; Benham, 1991). Licensure does not restrict physicians to practice in a particular area of medicine. (In the United States, it is not against the law for an ophthalmologist to perform heart surgery.) Furthermore, it is hard to argue that passing a standardized exam after graduation from medical school (perhaps after several sittings) offers much information about physician competence or success. Institutional accreditation can only insure that the quality of education meets a set standard, not that the program produces qualified practitioners. Consumers can only gain from licensure if it is possible to assess ability and if greater ability is reflected in higher service quality. Perhaps most important, a licensing exam cannot screen out individuals who might cheat or defraud patients. Clearly, the case that a public agency can identify practitioners from whom customers may expect to receive the appropriate level of service quality is not convincing. Even Arrow, whose 1963 paper is probably the most-quoted as favoring government intervention to assist consumers, said ‘insofar as this is possible’ (p. 966).
304
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
5120
Surveys of practitioner quality find large percentages of individuals in the market who do not meet standards set by researchers. These results are used to argue that licensure does not assure service quality (Hogan, 1983). A further complaint is that disciplinary procedures fail to deal with incompetence in professional practice. In the United States, critics of medical licensure point out that the majority of disciplinary actions have nothing to do with competence but, instead, focus on inappropriate prescription of drugs or self-abuse of alcohol or drugs (US Department of Health and Human Services, 1986). A study of disciplinary cases handled by the Antwerp Bar in the 1980s found sanctions most often imposed for personal characteristics (drunk driving, nonpayment of debts) or for improper behavior towards the professional association (such as failure to provide immediate or truthful information). Low rates of discipline by state boards are cited as evidence that improving quality for consumers comes second to protecting the interests of the licensed professionals. In contrast, Svorny (1987) shows that disciplinary procedures by state medical boards are as common as criminal penalties in the broader population. Licensure as a Cartel Many observers complain that licensure fosters cartel-like restrictions which raise prices, benefiting professionals at the expense of consumers (Friedman, 1962; Kessel, 1958; Rottenberg, 1962). The interests of professionals in licensure are seen as primarily self-serving, an attempt to establish monopoly power in an otherwise competitive industry. Scope-of-practice restrictions, which limit paraprofessionals and others from providing services within the bounds of the licensed profession, contribute to the view that licensing rules are anticompetitive. In medical markets, for example, prohibiting nurse practitioners from prescribing drugs or offering treatment without physician supervision is thought to unduly restrict the potential for optimal division of labor and efficiency in resource use. Some argue that licensure has been used to sustain hierarchical systems involving multiple occupations (see Glib, 1966; White and Marmor, 1982). In this context, licensure may be both a vehicle for imposing control over subordinate occupations (as when physicians attempt to limit the powers of other allied health personnel through support of strict scope of practice regulation) and for subordinate occupations to challenge the control of dominant occupations (as when nurse practitioners press for the right to provide services traditionally allowed only of physicians). Where education and training standards are specified, critics lament the lack of opportunity for innovation and the bias toward existing methods of education and training. Why, they ask, should everyone be trained in the same method and with a similar philosophy? In medicine, the lack of competition is
5120
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
305
seen as hindering the development of alternative treatments that might improve or prolong lives. In his 1958 paper, Reuben Kessel painted a damning picture of state medical societies in the United States, suggesting that their actions to limit the supply of physicians were simply efforts to enforce cartel-like restrictions that would raise prices and benefit physicians. Kessel argued that the cornerstone of American Medical Association (AMA) monopoly power was its control over the accreditation of medical schools for the purpose of licensing. In each state, medical society members had been successful in reserving the right to the AMA to determine what was an appropriate medical school for purposes of medical licensure. Based on this power, Kessel argued that the AMA could control both the number of schools and the rate of production of physicians - limiting the supply of physicians. Schools that did not heed the demands of state societies to limit enrollment could be sanctioned by excluding them from the list of acceptable schools for licensure. As further evidence of cartel behavior, Kessel pointed to AMA efforts to enforce price-fixing schemes (price discrimination) and medical society-enforced prohibitions on advertising. Resolving a ‘Lemons’ Problem One justification offered in support of licensure is that it solves a ‘lemons’ problem in markets where information about service quality is costly to obtain. Leland (1979, 1980) points out that when consumers cannot identify high quality physicians, all physicians must charge the same fee (equal to the average quality). As a result, the most talented individuals choose other professions (where their superior ability can be revealed). Only the low quality providers (the ‘lemons’) are left. Under these conditions, Leland shows that setting minimum quality standards will raise the average price and quality of the product. The intuition is that barriers not only exclude the least skilled, but they increase earnings, attracting more able individuals to the market. Leland emphasizes that his work should be seen as a counter-example to the monopoly/cartel effects of limiting entry. His work shows that it is not true that minimum quality standards can never improve welfare. He does not conclude that licensure is desirable. In fact, he supports certification over licensure as a less intrusive way of achieving the same improvement in service quality. Benefits to a Third Party In the search for benefits from licensure, White (1987) notes that there may be benefits to firms that hire licensed providers, such as hospitals. He argues that, even if the firms are low-cost monitors of the skills of the service providers and, therefore, do not gain from licensure directly, they may benefit indirectly. First, if consumers’ perceptions of service quality increase with licensure, large providers of services (such as health maintenance organizations) benefit from
306
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
5120
the short-run profits that accompany an increase in demand for their services. Also, licensure may benefit employers of service providers if it limits their liability. In the case of nurses, White concludes that it does not, as employers of nurses (hospitals and physicians) have been the most active in lobbying against nurse licensing. A Principle-Agent Framework It is clear that attempts to justify licensure must rest on quality assurance. There are two issues associated with quality assurance, finding individuals who are qualified, and motivating them to perform in the interests of the individuals they serve. The second problem is a principal-agent problem. One individual (the principal) hires another (the agent) to do some work, but the disparity in their self-interests causes problems for the principal in getting the agent to do as he or she would like. Shapiro (1986) describes how licensure might be seen as a means to resolve the incentive problem associated with the agency relationship in medical markets. In Shapiro’s model, entry restrictions magnify physicians’ incentives to acquire reputation by reducing the marginal cost of producing quality. The premise is that physicians who have made investments in medical education can produce high quality services with less effort. Because it is easier for them to do a good job, they do so more often. The value of licensure in Shapiro’s model is predicated on their being some market value to professional reputation (due to imperfectly observable outcomes), but insufficient production of reputation in an unregulated market. Shapiro justifies standardized training requirements (often seen as evidence of AMA control) on the basis that it is otherwise costly to reveal training levels to consumers. Licensure vs. Certification Like that of Heyne, Shapiro’s model provides a theoretical justification for licensure in response to complaints that licensure is motivated by self-interest on the part of practitioners who want to limit competition. But, both authors explicitly state that a system of certification would produce the same results, and neither argues for licensure over certification. Economists have long favored certification over licensure (see Friedman, 1962). Economists favor certification because consumers can use certification as a guide, but may purchase care from non-certified practitioners if they so choose. As Leland notes, under certification ‘buyers have a wider range of choice ... they can buy low-quality goods or services if they wish’ (p. 283). Support for licensure over certification comes from two traditional arguments. First, there may be significant externalities associated with the consumption of physician services. If the bad care that one person receives
5120
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
307
makes someone else worse off - as is the case if infectious disease is not treated properly - then it might be desirable to constrain the sale of physician services (through licensure) to those individuals who have been trained to keep infectious disease from spreading. Of course, if the higher cost of licensed professionals shifts large numbers of consumers into do-it-yourself remedies, infectious disease may spread even more under a system of licensure than without it. Or, if the high price of licensed electricians causes consumers to attempt electrical repairs themselves, the result may be an increase in externalities - home fires that threaten adjacent properties. A second common justification for licensure is paternalistic. Society may, as a whole, decide that some people are not smart enough to make their own choices and that the government should decide for them. However, a counter argument is that if this not-smart-enough group of individuals is also poor, the higher prices under licensure may lead them to even poorer choices in the black market than they would have made in an unregulated market. Theoretical Support for Licensure over Certification Is it possible to justify licensure over certification on grounds other than externalities and the need to make choices for others? Svorny (1987, 1992) suggests that licensure is useful in reducing agency costs in the market for physician services, an objective that certification is unable to accomplish. Licensure’s barriers to entry result in (1) abnormal profits and (2) investments in medical training that are lost when malfeasance leads to license suspension or revocation. Profits and the return on investments are accessible to the physician as long as he or she acts in ways deemed appropriate by the state medical board. Svorny argues that the profits created by simple restrictions in supply may serve as a premium stream to discourage agent malfeasance. Similar to an ‘efficiency wage’ arrangement which pays workers a wage above their value elsewhere, licensure produces an earnings stream that is lost upon license suspension or revocation. The higher earnings and potential for loss create incentives for agents to act in the interest of the principle, to self-monitor. Such arrangements are thought to prevail when monitoring costs are high (see Lazear, 1981). Along the same lines, Van den Bergh and Faure (1991) suggest that a ‘confidence premium’ in price fixing arrangements may be justified on the basis that trust of a professional economizes on information costs. By requiring internships and apprenticeships, licensing can steepen professional earnings profiles, creating strong penalties for malfeasance. Wages are depressed initially, but then rise above market values later in professional careers to compensate for the initial investment. This means that, as they enter the profession of their choice, new entrants to a licensed profession earn less that they would earn elsewhere. For example, those who wish to be certified
308
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
5120
public accountants in California must work for two years in jobs that pay very low wages and require long hours to qualify for licensure. Once licensed, wages rise above what could be earned elsewhere. Fear of losing this return through the revocation of one’s license discourages malfeasance. In medicine, a malfeasant physician loses not only the return to his or her required investment in training, but also the profits generated by restricting entry. Discipline results in a substantial loss. Blair and Kaserman (1980) and Gellhorn (1956) emphasize the incentive effects of disciplinary sanctions, but do not emphasize the potentially valuable role of licensure in increasing those losses by making medical practice more profitable. Under a system of certification, non-certified individuals would compete with certified practitioners, making it impossible to maintain abnormal profits to discourage physician malfeasance. Svorny proposes that the value of licensure rests on the inability of alternative methods of government intervention to provide a severe enough penalty for opportunistic behavior. Because agents can avoid civil and criminal fines (through asset flight or bankruptcy), the maximum penalty that can be assessed through alternative methods may not be sufficient (see also Eaton and White, 1983). Similarly, if it is not feasible to fully bond agents because of concerns about moral hazard by principles (Shapiro and Stiglitz, 1984), licensure may be preferable to bonding arrangements. Taking the view that profits in the market for physician services are welfare-enhancing, one can argue that restrictions on advertising (often mentioned as evidence of cartel activity) are desirable as they protect the abnormal profitability generated by restrictions on entry. Following the same logic, state requirements that physicians be US citizens (now illegal) may have served the purpose of maintaining profitability in the market for physician services. The physician price fixing schemes that Kessel found so offensive may actually have been socially useful. In contrast to profits created by limiting the quantity of services provided, price discrimination raises physician income in an efficient way. Price discrimination transfers wealth from consumers (consumer surplus) to physicians without affecting resource allocation. At the extreme, perfect price discrimination (where each consumer is charged the most he or she is willing to pay), allows large wealth transfers with no social cost or deadweight loss. Quantities sold are as they would be in a competitive market. Barriers to Taxicab Entry Barriers to entry can similarly benefit consumers of taxicab services. In many cities, restrictions on entry to taxi markets result in substantial profits. Only taxicabs drivers that own medallions issued by the government are allowed to offer taxi services, making the medallions very valuable. Gallick and Sisk
5120
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
309
(1987) describe how the profits associated with ownership of a medallion benefit consumers. They argue that regulating taxi rates makes consumers better off by reducing redundant search, allowing riders to cheaply estimate the price of any particular trip without searching among alternative drivers. One problem is that average pricing encourages drivers to seek out trips to locations where the probability of finding a return fare is relatively high. To mitigate this negative effect of average pricing rules, incentives must exist to encourage drivers to accept trips randomly, to reject no one. Gallick and Sisk suggest that the potential loss of a valuable asset, the taxi medallion, discourages drivers from violating the law that requires drivers to accept all trips, assuring all riders of access to average priced service. The ‘Value’ of Licensure Falls when Incentives of Other Actors Change Changes in institutional arrangements can increase or decrease the societal value of licensure arrangements. For example, in the United States, where the courts have shifted liability for physician malfeasance to hospitals and health maintenance organizations, incentives have surely changed. Coupled with growing concern over reputation in increasingly competitive markets, hospitals and HMOs have moved toward serious internal peer review. Also, record keeping has progressed to the point that profiling physician practice and maintaining disciplinary databases is possible, making it possible to identify physicians who practice outside of professional norms. This includes physicians who inappropriately dispense narcotics, a large share of disciplined physicians in the United States. Under these circumstances, the argument for licensure to assure quality in medical markets is weakened significantly (see Haug, 1980; Stevens, 1986; Ginsberg and Moy, 1992, Svorny, 1992,).
6. Evidence Much of the discussion of the value of licensure includes arguments that are not empirically testable. For example, the fact that licensure has existed in many parts of the world and for many years is used to suggest that it must have some value to society (Leffler, 1978).
Empirical Problems Where researchers do attempt to empirically test for the consequences of licensure, or the factors that lead to licensure, they run into problems. Researchers often use licensing examination pass rates to proxy the strictness of licensing regulations in a particular jurisdiction. The problem with this is that pass rates are not exogenous, they are determined by both the supply of
310
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
5120
potential entrants and the degree of strictness of the regulatory authority. Similarly, attempts to assess the wage impacts of licensing regulations may be hindered by a relationship between wages and the ability of a professional group to lobby for entry regulation. If the passage of licensing laws is endogenous to market conditions, then attributing high wages to licensing laws may be inappropriate. Another empirical problem that seems to pervade much of the literature is that of potentially spurious correlation. A researcher who finds an inverse relationship between licensing exam pass rates and service provider earnings often concludes that there is causality between these two variables. It is not uncommon to draw the conclusion that licensing boards manipulate pass rates to benefit service providers at the expense of consumers. However, where consumers are relatively wealthy, there may be a relatively high demand for quality that results in both strictness of licensing criteria and high service provider earnings. This literature is not alone in having to deal with problems of spurious correlation by any means. As always, researchers must be careful in assigning causality to observed empirical relationships. A caveat is appropriate as well for the empirical studies that examine the effect of licensure on quality. Because quality is very hard to measure, researchers must use proxies whose connection to service quality can only be presumed. The studies of Carroll and Gaston (discussed below) have used innovative measures to proxy for quality. But, clearly, the usefulness of these studies in assessing the outcomes of licensure depend critically on the ability to find good proxies for quality. The Demand for Licensure Examining the market for physician services, Leffler (1978) finds licensing laws to be most restrictive (he uses examination pass rates and other proxies) in states where consumer demand for quality would be expected to be relatively great, suggesting that consumer interests influence the political decision-making process. Proxies for the demand for service quality have been empirically studied to see if they are associated with licensing in two other studies. A study of Certified Public Accountants by Donabedian (1991) finds stricter licensing requirements in states having high concentrations of large businesses, his proxy for a demand for quality. In a study of nurse licensing, White (1987) finds adoption of mandatory licensing for nurses to be positively related to a relatively high demand for the services of registered nurses (the nursing category that involves the most training). Whether it is easier to get licensing laws through in these states because consumers have fewer objections, or whether the laws actually improve consumer welfare, cannot be determined from these results.
5120
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
311
Professional Influence Although individual service providers have much to gain from licensing restrictions, their ability to control the regulatory arena depends on several factors. As Stigler (1971) and Peltzman (1976) note, the odds of passage of market entry regulations are greatest where gains are concentrated among a small group of service providers, where the costs of professional organization are relatively low, and where costs are spread across a large segment of the population (this reduces organized consumer opposition). Looking at self-regulating professions in Illinois, Moore (1961) concludes that the set of licensed professions reflects the relative advantage of certain occupations in lobbying the legislature. In his view, self-interest has played a large part in the establishment of licensing restrictions. White (1987) notes that state nursing associations have uniformly led local efforts to pass licensing laws. But a nursing lobby variable in his regressions on the introduction of mandatory licensing of registered nurses (RNs) is not significant. Nor do Svorny and Toma (forthcoming) find evidence that numerically strong state medical societies influence either board structure or the number of physicians in a state. In contrast, Begun, Crowe and Feldman (1981) find evidence of professional influence over the degree of state regulation of optometry. Work by Graddy (1991) suggests that a range of organized interest groups influence occupational regulation, and that the public interest also plays a role. Noether (1986) interprets evidence of increased competition in medical markets in the United States since 1965 as suggestive of declining professional influence over physician licensure. Paul (1984) examines the effect of state medical society lobbies on the onset of licensure. He finds a positive relationship between AMA membership and the early onset of licensing. However, AMA membership per capita is highly correlated with the physician/population ratio in a state, which is not included in the regression. Paul’s results may simply confirm what the demand for licensure studies have found; where consumers already purchase large quantities of physician services relative to other health care services, licensure restrictions on practice face less opposition from consumers. Evidence Relating to Cartel Restrictions Attempts have been made to use measured profitability to provide evidence of cartel-like supply restrictions on the part of the medical profession. Early studies found a medical career to be profitable (Friedman and Kuznets, 1945; Sloan, 1970; Fein and Weber, 1971). Lindsay (1973) argued that there were a variety of issues in measuring returns that these papers failed to address. Differences in work hours and non-pecuniary benefits make direct comparisons of professional income less than perfect in assessing physician profitability. Also, Lindsay suggests that the appropriate rate to use to discount future
312
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
5120
earnings should include a risk premium, as investments in medical education leave the individual undiversified. Lindsay’s recalculation of the returns to training estimated in previous studies produced no evidence of above normal returns to medical training. Psacharopoulos (1975) reviews the literature and concludes that the evidence does not fully support the existence of monopoly incomes. Of course, normal returns for new entrants can be consistent with above-normal returns for those members of the profession ‘grandfathered’ as entry barriers are increased. Two studies challenge the premise in Kessell (1958) and elsewhere that the supply of physicians is constrained through the ability of the AMA to limit enrollment in medical schools. Leffler and Lindsay (1981) find that a traditional market model, focusing on supply and demand, is sufficient to explain the relationship between the market for care and the market for medical education. Hall and Lindsay (1980) examine enrollment in medical schools in the United States. They find medical school output positively related to donor and applicant demand. These results are inconsistent with the hypothesis that medical school enrollments are controlled by organized medicine. Earnings Empirical evidence supports the premise that earnings rise with restrictive licensing policies, that supply declines, that mobility is restricted, that inputs are combined inefficiently, and that consumers lose access to low quality services. Studies by Benham and Benham (1975) (the optometric profession), Benham, Maurizi and Reder (1968) (physicians and dentists), Pfeffer (1974) (insurance agents and brokers, real estate brokers and salesmen, plumbers), Shepard (1978) (dental care), White (1978) (clinical lab personnel), Perloff (1980) (the construction industry), Pazderka and Muzondo (1983) (Canadian licensure), Haas-Wilson (1986) (optometry) and Van den Bergh and Faure (1991) (Belgian attorneys, architects, physicians, and pharmacists) have shown measures of licensing strictness to be positively associated with costs, prices or earnings. Efficient Division of Labor Two studies have looked at the effect of licensure on the efficient division of labor. Examining the eyewear industry, Maruizi, Moore and Shepard (1981) find a low representation of opticians where restrictive regulations favor optometrists. Devany et al. (1982) examined dental firms in the United States. They find evidence that state legal restrictions on the use of paradentals have resulted in dentist-paradental labor input ratios higher than would be observed in unregulated markets.
5120
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
313
Labor Market Mobility Licensing may be used to limit mobility of service providers across political jurisdictions. For example, the costs of preparing for unique state exams has the potential to deter movement across state borders. But limited mobility does not necessarily accompany licensure. In medical markets in the United States, the trend has been to move away from state-specific toward standardized exams, which then allows almost perfect mobility across states. Holen (1965), Pashigian (1979), Pratt (1980), and Kleiner, Gay and Greene (1982) examine the effect of entry restrictions on professional mobility. Pratt examines sixteen occupations in the United States and finds that the more states that license a profession, the less mobile are its workers. Kleiner, Gay and Greene look at fourteen occupations and find that where rules are the most strict, mobility is limited and earnings enhanced by licensure. Both Holen and Pashigian find mobility restricted for dentists and lawyers. That earnings are higher and professionals less mobile should come as no surprise. Restrictions on entry, by definition, reduce mobility, raise professional incomes, and shift the sale of low quality services to the black market, reducing their availability. The real question is whether consumers gains are sufficient to offset the negative effects of licensure. Svorny (1987) suggests a test for the relative influence of consumer and professional interests over licensure. If licensure benefits consumers (by lowering search and monitoring costs), licensure should cause the demand for services to increase, increasing consumption despite higher costs of entry. If there are no benefits to consumers, there will be no increase in demand, and the equilibrium quantity of services will be lower where barriers are the most strict. Finding this, she is led to conclude that physician interests dominate the regulatory process. This, however, assumes homogeneity among consumers. Licensure may have redistributional effects, so that benefits accrue to some groups of consumers and practitioners (for example, those in the high quality sector of the market), but make other members of both groups worse off. Service Quality Despite claims that licensure enhances service quality, it is possible that high prices shift some consumers to do-it-yourself remedies. Aggregate quality may rise or fall, depending on the extent and consequences of such shifts (Carroll and Gaston, 1983). Attempts to measure the effects of licensure on product quality are limited by the difficulty in measuring quality. Carroll and Gaston (1981a) identify variables likely to proxy poor quality in seven licensed occupations. For example, in the market for electricians the number of accidental deaths by electric shock is used as a proxy for quality. Electrical shock deaths could result when ill-skilled professionals provide services or when consumers turn to do-it-yourself repairs. Carroll and Gaston
314
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
5120
find a negative association between proxies for strict licensing regulations and the number of licensed professionals, from which they conclude that licensing restricts entry. Also, where there are fewer licensed professionals, their proxies for quality suggest lower quality services are being consumed. They conclude that licensure reduces quality. Turning to real estate markets, Carroll and Gaston (1979) find lower quality (proxied by the proportion of vacant houses on the market for more than six months) where licensing restrictions were the most strict. Maruizi (1980) looked at contractor licensing in California. Over the period from 1954 to 1975, he found average quality (measured by the number of complaints) declined. He attributes this decline to the rapid growth in exam-preparation schools, which allowed relatively poorly trained individuals to pass the exam. Other results suggest that entry barriers are quality enhancing. Carroll and Gaston (1981b) found measures of attorney quality to be higher in those states with the most restrictive licensing policies. Johnson and Loucks (1986) find licensing in real estate improves quality; a reduction in licensees results in a decrease in complaints per transaction. Using length of eye exams, office equipment and examination complexity as proxies for service quality, Begun (1981) found quality to be positively related to optometry standards. McChesney and Muris (1979) provide evidence that eliminating barriers (in this case on advertising) does not reduce the quality of legal services provided to consumers and appears to increase it. The empirical work on quality suggests the effect of licensure on service quality varies across occupations. The need to proxy quality, with what are clearly imperfect measures of how consumers view a product, makes it hard to draw strong conclusions about the effects of licensure on quality.
7. Licensure vs. Discipline Where markets fail to protect consumers, it is possible to view licensure and discipline as substitutes in the production of service quality. Dollars spent on licensing could be shifted to efforts to identify and discipline incompetent and malfeasant practitioners, with a potential loss or gain, depending on the relative incentives generated. Guntermann and Smith (1988) address this issue, but with very weak data. They find that dollars spent on compliance and enforcement efforts reduce complaints against licensed real estate agents. Finding no evidence that prelicensing education requirements reduce complaints, they conclude that state governments are best off allocating more of their dollars to enforcement efforts and less to efforts to assure prelicensing educational attainment. (See also Phelan’s 1974 examination of TV repair in three cities.)
5120
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
315
8. The Choice Despite years of debate, there is no clear agreement on whether state licensing improves consumer welfare. Where consumers can easily buy low quality services on a black market, there will be little impact on consumer welfare. But where black market provision of services is costly (as, perhaps, with surgical procedures, where the consumer must travel to another country), consumers seeking to purchase low quality services are worse off. Because they restrict the supply of professional services available to consumers, market entry restrictions can be welfare enhancing only if the gains to consumers offset the welfare loss associated with the reduction in supply. Because service providers tend to be more organized than consumers and individual service providers have much to gain from restricting licensure, economic theory tells us that a democratic political process will overshoot the optimal/socially desirable level of entry restrictions. (Ramseyer, 1986), however, discusses the lack of success lawyers have had in Japan in furthering their own interests.) Only where consumers are well-organized or jointly represented by larger entities, as is increasingly the case in health care markets in the United States, will service providers have problems in securing protective regulation that goes beyond socially optimal levels of control (Stigler, 1971). What this means is that our choice is not between socially optimal regulation and an unregulated market, but between sub-optimal regulation and an unregulated market. Horowitz (1980) suggests that the persistence of self-regulation suggests a deal between society and the profession. Consumers can be sure of a minimal level of competence in exchange for allowing self-serving licensing restrictions to persist. Finally, an attraction of licensure to politicians is that its costs are hidden to consumers. Stigler (1971) makes the point that politicians prefer regulation whose primary cost is indirect and hard to identify over regulation involving public funds and tax expenditures. Licensing arrangements are attractive becuase their costs are off-budget, they are generally funded through the assessment of periodic fees on service providers. With a licensing scheme, all consumers - those who find value in regulation, and those who do not, pay a hidden cost of regulation in the form of higher priced services.
9. Institutional Issues Given the incentive for the regulated profession to lobby for rules which benefit the profession at the expense of consumers, a corollary question is whether it is politically possible to achieve an institutional structure which will reduce or
316
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
5120
eliminate the major imperfections associated with state regulation. Institutional arrangements have the potential to influence the regulatory outcome by affecting the costs special interest groups face in lobbying the agency (see Svorny and Toma, forthcoming). For example, in the United States, variations in institutional arrangements across states include differences in board autonomy in the nomination and selection of members, the ratio of professional to public or lay members on the board, standards for disciplinary procedures, and whether the board is self-funded, through fees, or receives an allocation of funds from the state legislature. The challenge is, first, to identify institutional arrangements that lower the costs of special interest lobbying and, second, to reach a political equilibrium where such arrangements are precluded. This is not a simple task, as interest groups will fight to protect arrangements that increase their influence over public policy.
10. Who Should be Licensed? Given the lack of clear evidence that licensure benefits consumers, some areas of practice are clear targets for eliminating state regulation over entry. Where services are characterized by repeat purchases and where outcomes are clearly observable, as is the case with the services of barbers or hair stylists, it seems hard to justify state controls. Similarly, the benefits of licensing dental and physician assistants may outweigh the costs. The employing professional or the employing facility has the ability (through observation, reputation and knowledge of professional training) to ascertain the quality of an assistant. Where there is also a strong legal incentive to assess quality, licensing professional assistants appears redundant. In the case of physicians, a system of certification would work as well in most circumstances. The only suggested theoretical value of licensure over certification is in creating a profit stream that discourages malfeasance. In the United States, because physicians practicing in hospitals and working for health maintenance organizations are subject to peer review (with teeth added by the increased liability assigned to such institutions by the courts), perhaps it is only physicians working in sole practice, or in small communities with no institutional liability and no professional peer oversight, for whom continued licensure is desirable. The ironic part is that states with disproportionate rural or medically underserved communities have been the first to innovate away from physicians, extending the legal scope of practice for physician assistants (Jones and Cawley, 1994). Shortages of medical doctors in rural areas have led governments to be more flexible, allowing greater latitude for paraprofessionals
5120
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
317
to offer services. If existing law shifts from licensure in areas where, theoretically, it can be of value relative to certification, it is hard to argue the benefits of licensure’s restrictions on entry for the population as a whole. Institutional licensure has been proposed to reduce the burden of licensing on state agencies. Hershey (1969) proposed replacing licensing with a system that invests health services institutions and agencies with the responsibility of regulating the provision of services. He argues that the rigidity of the current system deters hospitals from grouping skills and capabilities in ways that best serve patients. Replacing the current system with one of institutional licensure would allow a greater degree of flexibility in assigning personnel, reducing the cost of providing services. Each market is different and broad prescriptions about licensure just do not apply. For example, the licensing of taxicabs may be of value where taxicabs primarily service travelers. The lack of repeat customers, and the externalities associated with treating travelers well (that is, more tourism), may call for large penalties for malfeasance, exactly what a medallion system can supply. Although it is not clear that a national or international brand name would not be established to provide quality assurance at airports and other tourist locations if local taxi monopolies were to be eliminated, the externalities with respect to tourism may justify local control. Taxicabs operating within a community, serving the needs of those who do not drive, are subject to repeat purchases, so that licensure is an unnecessary expense. On the other hand, if taxis serve a very elderly population, one that may have greater than average difficulty in protecting itself from unscrupulous providers, then penalties offered by the medallion system for malfeasance take on value (and perversely, given the population, raise prices). The potential for large losses if malfeasance is caught creates incentives for licensed individuals to behave in ways that benefit their clientele, even if that clientele is not a good monitor of quality. Future Research One area that has received little attention is the allocation of public funds between licensing and discipline. Clearly substitutes for one another, it would be interesting to see if most jurisdictions allocate their spending efficiently, equating the marginal product of both activities at the margin. Also useful would be research assessing the net value of licensure to society. Ad hoc presumptions that licensure benefits consumers are clearly challenged by researchers that have studied regulated occupations. Trading an imperfect regulatory solution for an imperfect market solution may not be worth the cost.
318
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
5120
Bibliography on Licensing, Market Entry Regulation (5120) Arrow, Kenneth J. (1963), ‘Uncertainty and the Welfare Economics of Medical Care’, 53 American Economic Review, 941-973. Arruñada, Benito (1992), ‘Profesionales del Monopolio (Professionals of Monopoly)’, 14 Revista de Economía, 95-101. Arruñada, Benito (1995a), Análisis Económico del Notariado (Economic Analisis of the Notary), Madrid, Consejo General del Notariado. Arruñada, Benito (1995b), ‘Colegios Profesionales y Diseño Institucional (Professional Corporation and Institutional Design)’, 63 Economistas, 86-90. Reproduced in J. Velarde et al. (eds) (1995), Regulación y Competencia en la Economía Española, Madrid, Cívitas, 65-75. Arruñada, Benito (1996a), ‘Liberalización de Servicios y Colegios Profesionales (Liberalization of Professional Services and Associations)’, in several authors, Reforma de estructura, Barcelona, Sociedad de Estudios Económicos, 49-71. Arruñada, Benito (1996b), ‘The Economics of Notaries’, 3 European Journal of Law and Economics, 5-37. Baron, C.H. (1983), ‘Licensure of Health Care Professionals: The Consumer’s Case for Abolition’, 9 American Journal of Law and Medicine, 335-356. Barron, John F. (1961), ‘Restrictive Hiring Practices in Institutions of Higher Learning in California’, 4 Journal of Law and Economics, 186-193. Beales, J. Howard, III (1980), ‘The Economics of Regulating the Professions’, in Blair, Roger D. and Rubin, Stephen (eds), Regulating the Professions: A Public-Policy Symposium, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Begun J.W. and Feldman, R. (1990), ‘Policy and Research on Health Manpower Regulation: Never Too Late to Deregulate?’, 11 Advances in Health Economics and Health Services Research, 79-110. Begun, J.W. (1981), Professionalism and the Public Interest: Price and Quality in Optometry, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Begun, J.W. and Lippincott, R.C. (1982), ‘A Case Study in the Politics of Free-Market Health Care’, 7 Journal of Health Politics, Policy and Law, 667-685. Begun, J.W., Crowe, E.W. and Feldman, R. (1981), ‘Occupational Regulation in the States: A Casual Model’, 6 Journal of Health Politics, Policy and Law, 229-254. Benham, L. (1980), ‘The Demand for Occupational Licensing’, in Rottenberg, Simon (ed.), Occupational Licensure and Regulation, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute, 13-25. Benham, Lee (1991), ‘Licensure and Competition in Medical Markets’, in Frech III, H.E. (ed.), Regulating Doctors’ Fees: Competition, Benefits, and Controls Under Medicare, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 75-90. Benham, L. and Benham, A. (1975), ‘Regulation Through the Professions: A Perspective on Information Control’, 18 Journal of Law and Economics, 421-47. Benham, L. and Benham, A. (1978), ‘Prospects for Increasing Competition in the Professions’,The Professions and Public Policy, University of Toronto Press, 41-45. Benham, Lee, Maurizi, Alex R. and Reder, Melvin W. (1968), ‘Migration, Location and Remuneration of Medical Personnel: Physicians and Dentists’, 50 Review of Economics and Statistics, 332-347. Berlant, J.L. (1975), Profession and Monopoly, Berkeley, University of California Press.
5120
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
319
Blair, Roger D. and Kaserman, D.L. (1980), ‘Preservation of Quality and Sanctions within the Profession’, in Blair, R.D. and Rubin, Stephen (eds), Regulating the Professions: A Public Policy Symposium, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books, 185-198. Bond, R.S., Kwoka, J.E., Jr, Phelan, J.J. and Whirren, I.T. (1983), ‘Self-Regulation in Optometry: The Impact on Price and Quality’, 7 Law and Human Behavior, 219-234. Boulier, B.L. (1980), ‘An Empirical Examination of the Influence of Licensure and Licensure Reform on the Geographical Distribution of Dentists’, in Rottenberg, Simon (ed.),Occupational Licensure and Regulation, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 78-97. Brinig, Margaret F., Holcombe, Randall G. and Schwartzstein, Linda A. (1993), ‘Public Choice and Lobbying Regulation’, 74 Public Choice, 377-384. Carpenter, E.S. (1987), The Health Occupations Under Review: An Update on State Sunrise Activities, 1985-1987, Lexington, KY, Council of State Governments. Carroll, Sidney L. and Gaston, Robert J. (1979), ‘State Occupational Licensing Provisions and Quality of Service: The Real Estate Business’, 1 Research in Law and Economics, 1-13. Carroll, Sidney L. and Gaston, Robert J. (1981a), ‘Occupational Licensing and the Quality of Service Received: Some Evidence’, 47 Southern Economic Journal, 959-976. Carroll, Sidney L. and Gaston, Robert J. (1981b), ‘A Note on the Quality of Legal Services’, 3 Research in Law and Economics, 251-260. Carroll, Sidney L. and Gaston, Robert J. (1983), ‘Occupational Licensing and the Quality of Service: An Overview’, 7 Law and Human Behavior, 139-146. Cohen, Harris S. (1980), ‘On Professional Power and Conflict of Interest: State Licensing Boards on Trial’, 5 Journal of Health Politics, Policy and Law, 291-308. Cohen, H.S. and Milke, L.H. (1974), ‘Toward a More Responsive System of Professional Licensure’, 4 International Journal of Health Services, 265-272. Conrad D.A. (1981), ‘State Dental Practice Acts: Implications for Competition’, 5 Journal of Health Politics, Policy and Law, 610-629. Conrad D.A. and Sheldon, G.G. (1982), ‘The Effects of Legal Constraints on Dental Care Prices’, 19 Inquiry, 51-67. Corgel, John B. (1987), ‘Occupational Boundary Setting and the Unauthorized Practice of Law by Real Estate Brokers’, 10 Research in Law and Economics, 161-175. Corgel, J.B. and Jaffe, A.J. (1984), Should Real Estate Appraisers Be Licensed?, Society of Real Estate Appraisers. Council of State Governments (1952), Occupational Licensing Legislation in the States: a Study of State Legislation Licensing the Practice of Professions and Other Occupations, Council of State Governments. Curran, Christopher (1993), ‘The American Experience with Self-regulation in the Medical and Legal Professions’, in Faure, Michael, Finsinger, Jörg, Siegers, Jacques and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds), Regulation of Professions, Antwerpen, Maklu, 47-87. Davis, Anthony and Thiessen, Victor (1988), ‘Public Policy and Social Control in the Atlantic Fisheries’, 14 Canadian Public Policy, 66-77. Devany, Arthur S., Gramm, Wendy L., Saving, Thomas R. and Smithson, Charles W. (1982), ‘The Impact of Input Regulation: The Case of the U.S. Dental Industry’, 25 Journal of Law and Economics, 367-381. Derbyshire, R.C. (1969), Medical Licensure and Discipline in the United States, Maryland, Johns Hopkins University Press.
320
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
5120
Dolan, A.K. (1980a), ‘Occupational Licensure and Obstruction of Change in the Health Care Delivery System: Some Recent Developments’, in Blair, Roger D. and Rubin, Stephen (eds), Regulating the Professions: A Public-Policy Symposium, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Dolan, Andrew K. (1980b), ‘The Potential of Institutional Licensing and Brand-Name Advertising in the Medical Care System’, 9 Journal of Contemporary Business, 35-43. Donabedian, Bairj (1991), ‘The Economic Rationales of CPA Licensing’, 10 Journal of Accounting and Public Policy, 85-103. Dranove, D. and White, W.D. (1987), ‘Agency and the Organization of Health Care Delivery’, 24 Inquiry, 405-415. Duggan, A.J. (1984), ‘Occupational Licensing and Related Forms of Control’, in Galligan, D. (ed.), Essays in Legal Theory, Melbourne, Melbourne University Press, 51-73. Eaton, B. Curtis and White, William D. (1983), ‘The Economy of High Wages: An Agency Problem’, 50 Economica, 175-181. Edwards, Linda N. and Edwards, Franklin R. (1974), ‘Measuring the Effectiveness of Regulation: The Case of Bank Entry Regulation’, 17 Journal of Law and Economics, 445-460. Evans, R.G. (1976), ‘Does Canada Have Too Many Doctors? - Why Nobody Loves an Immigrant Physician’, 11 Canadian Public Policy, 147-159. Evans, R.G. (1978), ‘Universal Access: the Trojan Horse’, in Slayton, Philip and Trebilcock, Michael J. (eds), The Professions and Public Policy, Toronto, University of Toronto Faculty of Law. Evans, R.G. (1980), ‘Professionals and the Production Function: Can Competition Policy Improve Efficiency in the Licensed Professions?’, in Occupational Licensure and Regulation, American Enterprise Institute, 225-264. Faith, Roger L. and Tollison, Robert D. (1983), ‘The Supply of Occupational Regulation’, 21 Economic Inquiry, 232-240. Faure, Michael, Finsinger, Jorg, Siegers, Jacques and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds) (1993), Regulation of Professions, Antwerpen, Maklu. Fein, Rashi (1967), The Doctor Shortage: An Economic Diagnosis, Washington, DC, The Brookings Institution, 199 ff. Fein, R. and Weber, G. I. (1971), Financing Medical Education, An Analysis of Alternative Policies and Mechanisms, Carnegie Commission on Higher Education and the Commonwealth Fund, New York. Feldman, R. and Begun, J.W. (1978), ‘The Effects of Advertising: Lessons from Optometry’, 13 Journal of Human Resources, 247-262. Feldman, R. and Begun, J.W. (1985), ‘The Welfare Costs of Quality Changes Due to Professional Regulation’, 34 Journal of Industrial Economics, 17-32. Feldstein, P.J. (1977), Health Associations and the Demand for Legislation, Cambridge, MA, Ballinger Publishing. Feldstein, P.J. (1988), The Politics of Health Legislation: An Economic Perspective, Ann Arbor, MI, Health Administration Press. Fenn, Paul T., Rickman, Neil and McGuire, Alistair (1992), ‘Professional Liability and the Licensed Profession’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 479-496. Frankena, Mark W. and Paulter, Paul A. (1984), ‘An Economic Analysis of Taxicab Regulation’, Bureau of Economics Staff Report, U.S. Federal Trade Commission. Fraundorf, K.C. (1984), ‘Organized Dentistry and the Pursuit of Entry Control’, 8 Journal of Health
5120
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
321
Politics, Policy and Law, 759-781. Frech, H. Edward III (1975), ‘Occupational Licensure and Health Care Productivity: The Issues and the Literature’, in Rafferty, John A. (ed.), Health, Manpower and Productivity, Lexington, MA, D.C. Heath and Company, 119-142. Frech, H. Edward III (1982), ‘A Hard Pill to Swallow, Review of Taking Your Medicine: Drug Regulation in the United States by Peter Temin’, 13 Reason, 51-52. Frech, H. Edward III (1988), ‘Review of the Health Economy by Victor Fuchs’, 95 Journal of Political Economy, 1337-1340. Freund, D.A. and Shulman, J.D. (1984), ‘Regulation of the Professions: Results from Dentistry’, in Sheffler, R.M. and Rossiter, L.F. (eds), Advances in Health Economics and Health Services Research (Vol. 5), Greenwich, CT, JAI Press, 161-180. Friedman, Milton (1962), Capitalism and Freedom, ch. 9, Chicago, IL, University of Chicago Press. Friedman, Milton and Kuznets, S. (1945), Income from Independent Professional Practice, New York, National Bureau of Economic Research. Gahvari, Firouz (1989), ‘Licensing and Nontransferable Rents: Comment’, 79 American Economic Review, 906-909. Gallick, Edward C. and Sisk, David E. (1987), ‘A Reconsideration of Taxi Regulation’, 3 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 117-128. Garcia Gallego, Aurora and Georgantzis, Nikolaos (1996), ‘Competition Intensity vs. Service Quality: On the Distribution of Para-Pharmaceutical Products in Spain’, in Martin, Stephen (ed.), Interaction of Member State and EU Competition Policy, Amsterdam, forthcoming. Gaumer, G.L. (1984), ‘Regulating Health Professionals: A Review of Empirical Literature’, 62 Milbank Memorial Fund Quarterly/Health and Society, 380-416. Gellhorn, Walter (1956), Individual Freedom and Governmental Restraints, Baton Rouge, Louisiana State University Press. Gellhorn, Walter (1976), ‘The Abuse of Occupational Licensing’, 44 University of Chicago Law Review, 6-27. Gerstle, J. and Jacobs, G. (1976), Professions for the People, Cambridge, MA, Schenkman. Ginsberg, P.B. and Hammons, G.T. (1988), ‘Competition and the Quality of Care: The Importance of Information’, 25 Inquiry, 108-115. Ginsberg, Paul B. and Moy, Ernest (1992), ‘Physician Licensure and the Quality of Care’, Regulation, 32-39. Glib, Corinne L. (1966), Hidden Hierarchies: The Professions and Government, New York, Harper and Row. Goodman, John C. (1980), The Regulation of Medical Care: Is the Price Too High?, San Francisco, The Cato Institute. Graddy, Elizabeth (1991), ‘Interest Groups or the Public Interest---Why Do We Regulate Health Occupations?’, 16(1) Journal of Health Politics, Policy and Law, 25ff. Graddy, Elizabeth and Nichol, Michael B. (1989), ‘Public Members on Occupational Licensing Boards: Effects on Legislative Regulatory Reforms’, 55 Southern Economic Journal, 610-625. Graddy, Elizabeth and Nichol, Michael B. (1990), ‘Structural Reforms and Licensing Board Performance’, 18 American Politics Quarterly, 376-400. Grembowski, D., Conrad, D.D., Weaver, M. and Milgrom, P. (1988), ‘The Structure and Function of Dental-Care Markets: A Review and Agenda for Research’, 26 Medical Care, 132-147.
322
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
5120
Gross, Stanley J. (1978), ‘The Myth of Professional Licensing’, 33 American Psychologist, 10091016. Gross, S.J. (1984), Of Foxes and Hen Houses: Licensing and the Health Professions, Westport, CT, Quorum Books. Guntermann, Karl L. and Smith, Richard L. (1988), ‘Licensing Requirements, Enforcement Effort and Complaints Against Real Estate Agents’, 11 The Journal of Real Estate Research, 11-20. Haas-Wilson, Deborah (1986), ‘The Effect of Commercial Practice Restrictions: The Case of Optometry’, 29 Journal of Law and Economics, 165-186. Hailey, G., Latsey, C., Klurfeld, S.P., Hilder, E.R., Summers, E.L., Kinscheck, R. and Latanich, T.S. (1980), State Restrictions on Vision Care Providers: The Effects on Consumers, Staff Report, Bureau of Consumer Protection, U.S. Federal Trade Commission. Hall, Thomas D. and Lindsay, Cotton M. (1980), ‘Medical Schools: Producers of What? Sellers to Whom?’, 23 Journal of Law and Economics, 55-80. Haug, Marie (1980), ‘The Sociological Approach to Self-Regulation’, in Blair, Roger D. and Rubin, Stephen (eds), Regulating the Professions, Lexington Books, Lexington, Massachusetts, 61-80. Havighurst, Clark (1982), Deregulating the Health Care Industry: Planning for Competition, Cambridge, MA, Ballinger Publishing. Hazelkorn, H.M. and Christoffel, T. (1984), ‘Denturism’s Challenge to the Licensing System’, 5 Journal of Public Health Policy, 104-117. Hershey, Nathan (1969), ‘An Alternative to Mandatory Licensure of Health Professionals’, Hospital Progress, 71-74. Hickson, Charles R. and Thompson, Earl A. (1991), ‘A New Theory of Guilds and European Economic Development’, 28 Explorations in Economic History, 127-168. Hogan, Daniel B. (1983), ‘The Effectiveness of Licensing: History, Evidence, and Recommendations’, 7 Law and Human Behavior, 117-138. Holen, Arlene S. (1965), ‘Effects of Professional Licensing Arrangements on Interstate Labor Mobility and Resource Allocation’, 73 Journal of Political Economy, 492-498. Horowitz, Ira (1980), ‘The Economic Foundations of Self-Regulation in the Professions’, in Blair, R.D. and Rubin, S. (eds), Regulating the Professions: A Public Policy Symposium, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books, 3-28. Jaffe, Austin J. and Corgel, John B. (1984), ‘Should Real Estate Appraisers be Licensed?’, 50 Real Estate Appraiser and Analyst, 21-26. Johnson, Linda L. and Loucks, Christine (1986), ‘The Effect of State Licensing Regulations on the Real Estate Brokerage Industry’, 14 AREUEA Journal, 567-582. Johnson, S.B. and Corgel, J.B. (1983), ‘Market Intervention by the Courts: The Economics of Occupational Boundary Settings’, 6 Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy, 197-218. Jones, P. Eugene and Cawley, James F. (1994), ‘Physician Assistants and Health System Reform’, 271 Journal of the American Medical Association, 1266-1272. Julin, J.R. (1980), ‘The Legal Profession: Education and Entry’, in Blair, Roger D. and Rubin, Stephen (eds), Regulating the Professions: A Public-Policy Symposium, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Kessel, Reuben A. (1958), ‘Price Discrimination in Medicine’, 1 Journal of Law and Economics, 2053.
5120
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
323
Kessel, Reuben A. (1970), ‘The A.M.A. and the Supply of Physicians’, 35 Law and Contemporary Problems, 267-283. Kirp, David L. and Soffer, Eileen M. (1985), ‘Taking Californians to the Cleaners’, 9 Regulation, 24-26. Kitch, Edmund W., Isaacson, Marc and Kasper, Daniel (1972), ‘The Regulation of Taxicabs in Chicago’, 14 Journal of Law and Economics, 285-350. Reprinted in Brookings Institute Reprint No. 255, 1972. Kleiner, M.M., Gay, R.S. and Greene, K. (1982), ‘Barriers to Labor Migration: The Case of Occupational Licensing’, 21 Industrial Relations, 383-391. Kwoka, J.E., Jr (1984), ‘Advertising and the Price and Quality of Optometric Services’, 74 American Economic Review, 211-216. Larson, M.S. (1977), The Rise of Professionalism, Berkeley, University of California Press. Leffler, Keith B. (1978), ‘Physician Licensure: Competition and Monopoly in American Medicine’, 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 165-186. Leffler, Keith B. (1980), ‘Commentary on Leland’s Minimum-Quality Standards and Licensing in Markets with Asymmetric Information’, in Rottenberg, Simon (ed.), Occupational Licensure and Regulation, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute, 1238-1246. Leffler, Keith B. and Lindsay, Cotton M. (1981), ‘Markets for Medical Care and Medical Education: An Integrated Long-Run Structural Approach’, 16 The Journal of Human Resources, 20-40. Leland, Hayne E. (1979), ‘Quacks, Lemons, and Licensing: A Theory of Minimum Quality Standards’, 87 Journal of Political Economy, 1325-1346. Leland, Hayne E. (1980), ‘Minimum-Quality Standards and Licensing in Markets with Asymmetric Information’, in Rottenberg, Simon (ed.), Occupational Licensure and Regulation, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 264-284. Leunis, J. and De Vos, G. (1986), ‘De Wet betreffende de Handelsvestigingen: De Eerste 10 Jaar (The Licensing Law: The First 10 Years)’, 31 Tijdschrift voor Economie en Management, 309-333. Levin, Harvey J. (1962), ‘Federal Control of Entry in the Broadcast Industry’, 5 Journal of Law and Economics, 49-67. Lewisch, Peter (1989), Erwerbsfreiheit und Bedarfsprüfung (The Freedom to Earn one’s Living as Subjected to Regulations Concerning Needs), Vienna, Marktwirtschaftliche Schriften des Carl Menger Institutes, 47 p. Lewisch, Peter (1991), ‘The Political Economy of Barriers to Entry: The Example of the Amendment for Taxicab Regulation in Austria’, in Weigel, Wolfgang (ed.)), Economic Analysis of Law - A Collection of Applications, Vienna, Österreichischer Wirtschaftsverlag, 222-234. Lindsay, Cotton M. (1973), ‘Real Returns to Medical Education’, 8 Journal of Human Resources, 331-348. Lott, John R., Jr (1987), ‘Licensing and Nontransferable Rents’, 77 American Economic Review, 453-455. Lott, John R., Jr (1989), ‘Licensing and Nontransferable Rents: Reply’, 79 American Economic Review, 910-912.
324
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
5120
Lueck, Dean, Olsen, Reed and Ransom, Michael (1991), ‘Why Do States Regulate Admission to the Bar? Theories and Empirical Evidence’, 14 George Mason Law Review, 253-286. Lueck, Dean, Olsen, Reed and Ransom, Michael (1995), ‘Market and Regulatory Forces in the Pricing of Legal Services’, 7 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 63-83. Massaguer, Josep María (1994), ‘La Regulación de Servisios Profesionales (un Análisis de Racionalidad Económica y Legitimidad Antitrust) (The Regulation of the Profession’s Economic Rationality and Antitrust Legitimacy)’, 3 Iuris, 85-120. Mathewson, G. Frank and Winter, Ralph A. (1989), ‘The Economic Effects of Automobile Dealer Regulation’, 15-16 Annales d’Economie et de Statistique, 409-426. Maurizi, Alex R. (1974), ‘Occupational Licensing and the Public Interest’, 82 Journal of Political Economy, 399-413. Maurizi, A. (1980), ‘The Impact of Regulation on Quality: The Case of California Contractors’, in Occupational Licensure and Regulation, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute, 399413. Maurizi, Alex R., Moore, Ruth L. and Shepard, Lawrence (1981), ‘Competing for Professional Control: Professional Mix in the Eyeglasses Industry’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 351-364. McChesney, Fred S. and Muris, Timothy J. (1979), ‘The Effect of Advertising on the Quality of Legal Services’, 65 American Bar Association Journal, 1503-1506. McCleery, R.S., Keelty, L.T., Lam, M., Phillips, R.E. and Quirim, T.M. (1971), One Life-One Physician: An Inquiry into the Medical Profession’s Performance in Self-Regulation, Public Affairs Press. McGee, Robert W. (1982), ‘Into the Accountants Hands’, Management Accounting, 83ff. Mennemeyer, S.T. (1978), ‘Really Great Returns to Medical Education?’, 13 Journal of Human Resources, 75-90. Moore, Thomas G. (1961), ‘The Purpose of Licensing’, 4 Journal of Law and Economics, 93-117. Muzondo, Timothy R. and Pazderka, Bohumir (1983), ‘Income-Enhancing Effects of Professional Licensing’, 28 Antitrust Bulletin, 397-415. Noether, Monica (1986), ‘The Effect of Government Policy Changes on the Supply of Physicians: Expansion of a Competitive Fringe’, 29 Journal of Law and Economics, 231-262. Pashigian, B. Peter (1977), ‘The Market for Lawyers: The Determinants of the Demand for and Supply of Lawyers’, 20 Journal of Law and Economics, 53-85. Pashigian, B. Peter (1979), ‘Occupational Licensing and the Interstate Mobility of Professionals’, 22 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-25. Pashigian, B.P. (1980), ‘Has Occupational Licensing Reduced Geographical Mobility and Raised Earnings?’, American Enterprise Institute, 299-333. Pastor, Santos (1990), ‘El Análisis Económico del Acceso a la Justicia (The Economics of Access to Justice)’, 687 Información Comercial Española, 23-42. Paul, Chris (1984), ‘Physician Licensure Legislation and the Quality of Medical Care’, 12 Atlantic Economic Journal, 18-30. Pauly, Mark V. and Satterthwaite, Mark A. (1981), ‘The Pricing of Primary Care Physicians’ Services: A Test of the Role of Consumer Information’, 12 The Bell Journal of Economics, 488-506.
5120
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
325
Pazderka, B. and Muzondo, T. (1983), ‘The Consumer Costs of Professional Licensing Restrictions in Canada and Some Policy Alternatives’, 23 Journal of Law and Economics, 55-75. Perloff, Jeffrey M. (1980), ‘The Impact of Licensing Laws on Wage Changes in the Construction Industry’, 23 Journal of Law and Economics, 409-428. Pfeffer, J. (1974), ‘Some Evidence on Occupational Licensing and Occupational Incomes’, 53 Social Forces, 102-111. Phelan, J.J. (1974), Regulation of the Television Repair Industry in Louisiana and California: A Case Study, US Government Printing Office. Prasad, Ravi (1991), ‘Pay TV: Why Regulate’, Office of Regulation Review. Pratt, Leila J. (1980), ‘Occupational Licensing and Interstate Mobility’, 15 Business Economics, 7880. Psacharopoulos, G. (1975), Earnings and Education in OECD Countries, Paris, OECD. Ramseyer, J. Mark (1986), ‘Lawyers, Foreign Lawyers, and Lawyer-Substitutes: The Market for Regulation in Japan’, 27 Harvard International Law Journal, 499-986. Rayack, Elton (1967), Professional Power and American Medicine: The Economics of the American Medical Association, NewYork, World Publishing Company. Rayack, Elton (1976), An Economic Analysis of Occupational Licensure, US Department of Labor. Rayack, Elton (1982), ‘The Physician Services Industry’, in Adams, Walter (ed.), The Structure of American Industry, New York, Macmillan Publishing Co., Inc., 188-226. Rayack, Elton (1983), ‘Medical Licensure: Social Costs and Social Benefits’, 7 Law and Human Behavior, 147-56. Rose, Jonathan (1979), ‘Occupational Licensing - A Framework for Analysis’, Arizona State Law Journal, 189. Rose, Jonathan (1983), ‘Professional Regulation: The Current Controversy’, 6 Law and Human Behavior (Special Issue), 103-116. Rosenstein, D.I., Joseph, L.P., Mackenzie, L.J. and Wyden, R. (1980), ‘Professional Encroachment: A Comparison of the Emergence of Denturists in Canada and Oregon’, 70 American Journal of Public Health, 614-618. Rottenberg, Simon (1962), ‘The Economics of Occupational Licensing’, in Alchian, Armen A. and Kessel, R., Aspects of Labor Economics (Competition, Monopoly and the Pursuit of Money), Princeton, Princeton University Press. Rottenberg, S. (ed.) (1980), Occupational Licensure and Regulation, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 354p. Rovin, S. and Nash, J. (1982), ‘Traditional and Emerging Forms of Dental Practice: Cost, Accessibility, and Quality Factors’, 72 American Journal of Public Health, 656-662. Rubin, Stephen (1980), ‘The Legal Web of Professional Regulati on’, in Blair, Roger D. and Rubin, Stephen (eds), Regulating the Professions: A Public-Policy Symposium, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books, 29-60. Schifrin, L.G. and Rich, W.J. (1984), The Contact Lens Industry: Structure, Competition, and Public Policy, Washington, DC, U.S. Congress, Office of Technology Assessment. Schreiber, Chanoch (1975), ‘The Economic Reasons for Price and Entry Regulation of Taxicabs’, 9 Journal of Transport Economics and Policy, 268-279. Schutz, Howard G. (1983), ‘Effects of Increased Citizen Membership on Occupational Licensing Boards in California’, 11 Policy Studies Journal, 504-516. Shaked, Avner and Sutton, John (1981a), ‘The Self-Regulating Profession’, 47 Review of Economic
326
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
5120
Studies, 217-234. Shaked, Avner and Sutton, John (1981b), ‘Heterogeneous Consumers and Product Differentiation in a Market for Professional Services’, 15 European Economic Review, 159-177. Shapiro, C. (1983), ‘Premiums for High Quality Products as Returns to Reputations’, 98 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 659-679. Shapiro, Carl (1986), ‘Investment, Moral Hazard, and Occupational Licensing’, 53 Review of Economic Studies, 843-862. Shapiro, Carl and Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1984), ‘Equilibrium Unemployment as a Worker Discipline Device’, 74 American Economic Review, 433-444. Shedd, P.J. (1981), ‘Real Estate Agents and the Unauthorized Practice of Law’, 10 Real Estate Law Journal, 135-142. Shepard, Lawrence (1978), ‘Licensing Restrictions and the Cost of Dental Care’, 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 187-201. Shimberg, B. (1982), Occupational Licensing: A Public Perspective, Princeton, Princeton Educational Testing Service. Shimberg, B., Esser, B. and Kruger, D.H. (1973), Occupational Licensing, Public Affairs Press. Shryock, R.H. (1967), Medical Licensing in American, 1650-1965, Maryland, Johns Hopkins University Press. Slayton, Philip (1978), ‘Professional Education and the Consumer Interest: a Framework for Inquiry’, in Slayton, Philip and Trebilcock, Michael J. (eds), The Professions and Public Policy, Toronto, University of Toronto Faculty of Law. Sloan, Frank A. (1970), ‘Lifetime Earnings and Physicians’ Choice of Specialty’, 24 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 47-56. Sloan, Frank and Lindsay, Cotton M.(1976), ‘Real Returns to Medical Education: Comment and Reply’, 11 Journal of Human Resources, 118-30. Smith, Janet Kiholm (1982), ‘An Analysis of State Regulations Governing Liquor Store Licensees’, 25 Journal of Law and Economics, 301-320. Smith, Janet Kiholm (1982), ‘Production of Licensing Legislation: An Economic Analysis of Interstate Differences’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 117-137. Stacey, Meg (1997), ‘The Case for and Against Medical Self-Regulation’, 84 Federal Bulletin: The Journal of Medical Licensure and Discipline, 17-25. Stevens, Rosemary A. (1986), ‘The Future of the Medical Profession’, in Ginzberg, Eli (ed.), From Physician Shortage to Patient Shortage: The Uncertain Future of Medical Practice, Second Conference on Health Policy, Cornell University Medical College. Boulder, CO, Westview Press. Stigler, George J. (1971), ‘The Theory of Economic Regulation’, 2 Bell Journal of Economics, 3-21. Svorny, Shirley (1979), Foreign-Trained Physicians and Health Care in the United States, Ph.D. Dissertation, University of California, Los Angeles. Svorny, Shirley (1987), ‘Physician Licensure: A New Approach to Examining the Role of Professional Interests’, 25 Economic Inquiry, 497-509. Svorny, Shirley (1991), ‘Consumer Gains from Physician Immigration to the U.S.: 1966-1971’, 23 Applied Economics, 331-337. Svorny, Shirley (1992), ‘Should We Reconsider Licensing Physicians?’, 10 Contemporary Policy Issues, 31-38.
5120
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
327
Svorny, Shirley (1993), ‘Advances in Economic Theories of Medical Licensure, Federation Bulletin’, 80 Journal of Medical Licensure and Discipline, 27-32. Svorny, Shirley and Toma, Eugenia Froedge (1996), ‘Entry Barriers and Medical Board Funding Autonomy’, Public Choice, forthcoming. Swan, Peter L. (1982), Human Tissue Transplants, Law and Economics, Canberra, Australian National University. Taman, L. (1978), ‘The Emerging Legal Paraprofessionals’, in Slayton, Philip and Trebilcock, Michael J. (eds), The Professions and Public Policy, Toronto, University of Toronto Faculty of Law. Tuohy, Carolyn J. and Alan D. Wolfson (1976), ‘Self-regulation: who qualifies?’, in Slayton, Philip and Trebilcock, Michael J. (eds), The Professions and Public Policy, Toronto, University of Toronto Press, 111-124. Trebilcock, Michael J. (1976), ‘The Professions and Public Policy: The Nature of the Agenda’, in Slayton, Philip and Trebilcock, Michael J. (eds), The Professions and Public Policy, Toronto, University of Toronto Press, 3-14. Ulrich, Alvin, Furtan, William H. and Schmitz, Andrew (1987), ‘The Cost of a Licensing System Regulation: An Example from Canadian Prairie Agriculture’, 95 Journal of Political Economy, 160-178. US Department of Health and Human Services (1986), Medical Licensure and Discipline: An Overview, Boston. Van den Bergh, Roger (1986), ‘Belgian Public Policy Towards the Retailing Trade’, in Graf Von Der Schulenburg, J.-Matthias and Skogh, Göran (eds), Law and Economics and The Economics of Legal Regulation, Dordrecht, Kluwer, 185-205. Van den Bergh, Roger (1986), ‘De Economische Reguleringstheorie en de Belgische Vestigingswetgeving voor Kleine en Middelgrote Handels- en Ambachtsondernemingen (The Economic Theory of Regulation and the Belgian Licensing Law for Small and Middle Size Companies)’, in Van den Bergh, Roger (ed.), Verslagboek Eerste Werkvergadering Recht en Economie, Antwerpen, Handelshogeschool, 38-49. Van den Bergh, Roger and Faure, Michael G. (1991), ‘Self Regulation of the Professions in Belgium’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 165-182. Weingast, Barry R. (1980), ‘Physicians, DNA Research Scientists, and the Market for Lemons’, in Blair, Roger D. and Rubin, Stephen (eds), Regulating the Professions: A Public-Policy Symposium, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Wertz, Dorothy (ed.) (1988), Turf Battles and the Theory of Professional Dominance, Research in the Sociology of Health Care (Vol. 7), Greenwich, CT, JAI Press, 203-225. White, William D. (1978), ‘The Impact of Occupational Licensure of Clinical Laboratory Personnel’, 13 Journal of Human Resources, 91-102. White, William D. (1979a), ‘Dynamic Elements of Regulation: The Case of Occupational Licensure’, 1 Research in Law and Economics, 15-33. White, William D. (1979b), Public Health and Private Gain: The Economics of Licensing Clinical Laboratory Personnel, Chicago, Maaroufa Press. White, William D. (1983), ‘Labor Market Organization and Professional Regulation: A Historical Analysis of Nursing Licensure’, 7 Law and Human Behavior, 167-170. White, William D. (1987), ‘The Introduction of Professional Regulation and Labor Market Conditions Occupational Licensure of Registered Nurses’, 20 Policy Sciences, 27-51. White, William D. and Marmor, Theodore R. (1982), ‘Old Demands, New Occupations: The Public
328
Licensing, Market Entry Regulation
5120
Regulation of Paraprofessionals’,1 Journal of Public Policy Analysis and Management, 243-256. Wolfson, A.D., Trebilcock, M.J. and Tuohy, C.J. (1980), ‘Regulating the Professions: A Theoretical Framework’, in Rottenberg, S. (ed.), Occupational Licensure and Regulation, Washington, DC, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 354 p. Wright, D.T. (1978), ‘The Objectives of Professional Education’, in Slayton, Philip and Trebilcock, Michael J. (eds), The Professions and Public Policy, Toronto, University of Toronto Faculty of Law. X. (1974), ‘Note: Restrictive Licensing of Dental Paraprofessionals’, 83 Yale Law Journal, 806-826. Young, S. David (1987), The Rule of Experts: Occupational Licensing in America, Washington, DC, Cato Institute. Zardkoohi, Asghar and Pustay, Michael W. (1989), ‘Does Transferability Affect the Social Costs of Licensing?’, 62 Public Choice, 187-190.
Other References Begun, J. et al. (1981), ‘Occupational Regulation in the States: A Causal Model’, 6 Journal of Health Politics, Policy and Law, 229-54. Eaton, B. Curtis and White, William D. (1983), ‘The Economy of High Wages: An Agency Problem,’ 50 Economica, 175-181. Faure, Michael, Jorg Finsinger, Jacques Siegers, and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds) (1993). Regulation of Professions, Antwerpen, Maklu. Glib, Corinne L. (1966), Hidden Hierarchies: The Professions and Government, New York, Harper and Row. Lazear, Edward P. (1981), ‘Agency, Earnings Profiles, Productivity, and Hours Restrictions’, 71 American Economic Review, 606-620. Peltzman, Sam (1976), ‘Toward a More General Theory of Regulation’, Journal of Law and Economics, 211-240. Stacey, Meg (1997), ‘The Case for and Against Medical Self-regulation’, 84 Federation Bulletin: The Journal of Medical Licensure and Discipline, 17-25.
5130 PRODUCT SAFETY REGULATION Alessandra Arcuri, LL M © Copyright 1999 Alessandra Arcuri
Abstract Market failures paired with private law failures call for safety regulation. The main dilemma for policymakers is to find ‘the optimal level’ of product safety regulation. Hence, in this chapter science and cost-benefit analysis are presented as important technocratic tools for risk assessment and risk management. As product safety regulation covers a wide range of industrial activities, a variety of empirical studies have been reviewed. The lively controversies on the effectiveness of some regulations, often arisen among specialists, show how difficult the appraisal of cost and benefit of regulation is, especially in the presence of ‘risk-compensation’ behavior. JEL classification: K32 Keywords: Product Safety Regulation, Tort Law, Information Regulation, Cost-Benefit Analysis, Automobile Safety Regulation
1. Introduction The need for product safety regulation should no longer be a source of controversy. Welfare economics provides a theoretical justification for such regulation. If it were realistic to assume individuals to behave ‘rationally’, possessing perfect information coupled with the absence of externalities, there would be no need for regulation. It has been generally recognized that the aforementioned assumptions should be, at least partially, disregarded when analyzing the real world. When these assumptions are fulfilled the interaction of market forces will generate allocative efficiency. The reason for governmental intervention is given by the ‘market failures’ that arise when the aforementioned assumptions are relaxed. Even the most liberal and market-oriented economist would agree on this point. At the present moment, the conjugation of private and public regulation seems to be the only available answer to the question whether it is better to have a system based on tort or on product safety regulation. While investigating which is the better type of regulation, information regulation seems the most attractive option, because it preserves the consumer’s choice. It improves competition among firms and does not induce technological rigidity which, for instance, may be caused by specification standards. 329
330
Product Safety Regulation
5130
However, the shortcomings of this type of regulation, such as the problem consumers have in absorbing the disclosed information, or the harmful consequences suffered by bystanders, call for command-and-control regulation as a necessary complement of information regulation. Once the need for product safety regulation, both in the form of information and command-and-control regulation, has been recognized and justified as a valid formula to correct market failures, the next step is to identify which are the most effective tools to find the optimal amount and formulation of regulation. If we accept that science is the best tool available for public risk assessment, then an indirect way to articulate efficiently regulation is to finance and protect scientific research. Up till now, much emphasis has been placed on the importance of using cost-benefit analysis in regulatory process. However, the flaws of cost-benefit analysis have induced some authors to entirely reject its use. What is suggested in this paper is that the proper question to pose is not whether it is opportune to use cost-benefit analysis, but how and when the application of cost-benefit analysis is suitable. The analysis of the downfalls of cost-benefit analysis already gives useful insights to answer these crucial questions. The task of policymakers should not be a pure elaboration of safety regulations. Rather, it should be the elaboration of effective safety regulations. A brief survey of case studies highlights the question that safety regulations have not always resulted in being effective. However, there is frequently a lack of consensus on results. Therefore, it might be desirable to take into account how the author’s beliefs might have affected the results of the empirical study. Moreover, from this review it appears that what Thomas Huxley said in 1860 is still valid: ‘[s]cience … warns me to be careful how I adopt a view which jumps with my preconceptions, and to require stronger evidence for such belief than for one to which I was previously hostile. My business is to teach my aspirations to conform themselves to fact, not to try and make facts harmonize with my aspirations’. Hence, the result of an empirical study might be considered more reliable when it is supported by other empirical studies, which, even if utilizing different methods, lead to similar results. Even if prima facie the analysis of the rationales for having product safety regulation may appear fragmentary, a more accurate look at it will disclose the deep interdependencies between the several issues treated in this paper. On the one hand, the benefits that different analytical approaches provide should not be underestimated. On the other hand, a global view of the points in question is valuable for a systematic and consistent formulation of product safety regulation and call for a crucial co-ordination with other regulatory policies.
5130
Product Safety Regulation
331
2. The Spectrum of Legal Regimes from Tort Law to Safety Regulation From an economic perspective, tort law and public safety regulation are two branches of law with the same goal: the minimization of accident costs (Calabresi, 1970). The issue of the relative desirability of having a system based on tort or on regulation has been frequently discussed. A review of the main literature on this topic shows that, in some circumstances, tort law will bring about an optimal allocation of resources whereas, in other cases, the contrary will be true. Shavell (1984) points out four theoretical determinants of the relative desirability of liability and safety regulation and argues for a joint use of liability and regulation as the best solution to the problem of the control of risk, ‘with the balance between them reflecting the importance of the determinants’. Rose-Ackerman (1991), who identifies three forms of complementarities, has addressed the issue of complementarity between tort and regulation. An overall conclusion is that, in order to control activities creating risks of harm, it is not conceivable to employ only liability or safety regulation (see also Shavell, 1987; Burrrows, 1992; Rose-Ackerman, 1992). As Skogh (1989) points out ‘[t]he reason is that cost-liability, regulation, private insurance and public insurance have specific benefits and shortcomings that make a mixture favorable’. However, in order to choose the best policy option to control the risk of harm, it seems crucial to take into account all the theoretical analyses, which are useful to distinguish the case when it is better to have a system based mainly on safety regulation, even if integrated by liability rules as opposed to a system based mainly on liability rules. Therefore, when tort liability turns out to be an inefficient tool to correct market failures there is a call for regulation. However, among the different types of regulation there are some that still preserve the consumer’s freedom of choice, that is information regulation. The demand for information regulation originates from the presence of information asymmetry, which is an exceptional source of market failures. The literature on this point is copious, but the topic is covered in another chapter (5110, Information Regulation), and therefore this survey is concise. The seminal article by Akerlof (1970) illustrates the consequences of information asymmetry relative to the quality of the product. Also cited is the article by Nelson (1970), who distinguishes ‘search’ and ‘experience’ goods and that of Darby and Karny (1973) who describe those types of goods which are said to bear ‘credence’ qualities. If the lack of information about the quality has the evident consequence of an inefficient market outcome, the same is true for the uncertainty related to the safety of the item. Imperfect information about safety can be defined as the consumer ignorance about risks, or in other words, as a high degree of
332
Product Safety Regulation
5130
uncertainty about the probabilities that a certain outcome will occur. It should be clear that facing a risk means facing an uncertain outcome that has certain probabilities; whereas uncertainty refers to unknown probabilities. If the consumer underestimates risk (that is, the risk of stroke), the quantity demanded will be more than optimal, whereas if the consumer overestimates the risk (that is, the risk of dying in an airline crash) the quantity demanded will be suboptimal (Asch, 1988). However, it is noteworthy that in some circumstances a mandatory disclosure of information may turn out to have the opposite of the desired effect. This can happen, for instance, when the object of regulation is technically complex, as a succinct description of the product is almost impossible. In addition, it is predictable that an overload of information will not be read or digested by consumers (Bardach and Kagan, 1982). For empirical evidence of this theoretical statement see the study by Forrest (1992). Notably, the theoretical perspective adopted, significantly affects the assessment of the information regulation’s effectiveness. On the one hand, information regulation might be considered as an adequate political measure when a ‘rationalist’ approach is adopted, as the main assumption is that well-informed people make optimal decisions (Bernoulli, 1738/1954). On the other hand, ‘behavioralists’ believe that individuals do not act ‘optimally’, in the rationalist sense, especially when faced with risky choices. Actually, heuristics used to make complex decisions often lead to systematic errors. Such an approach is based on a wide range of literature and on empirical studies carried out by cognitive psychologists that show how people, when faced with risky decisions, make inconsistent choices (that is Allaix, 1953; Lichtenstein and Slovich, 1971, 1973; Tversky and Kahneman, 1974, 1981; Grether and Plott, 1979; Akerlof and Dickens, 1982 Karni and Safra, 1987). Consequently, an important task for policymakers is to communicate information in an effective manner. Thus, the knowledge of how consumers respond to a certain communication effort is crucial. Notably, Magat and Viscusi (1992) provide ‘specific guidelines for when different types of information provision instruments are effective and when they are not, as well as which kind of instruments will have the greatest impact’. Even if a complete analysis of information regulation is beyond the scope of this chapter, it is worthwhile to spend some words on its distributional consequences. Pildes and Sunstein (1995) have argued that ‘[i]nformation remedies tend to favor the relatively well off’. This consideration leads to the normative conclusion that if politicians want to take into account the regulation’s distributional effects as well, they should supplement informational remedies by other means such as education.
5130
Product Safety Regulation
333
3. Safety Regulation From the previous analysis it results that, even if information regulation is the least interventionist measure and has the advantage to preserve the consumer’s choice, it has some limits. Therefore, product standards are necessary in order to correct market failures arising from information deficits and externalities. Ogus (1994) subdivides standards into three categories: (1) target standards, which impose criminal liability for accidents caused by the product; (2) performance standards which require the product to satisfy certain conditions without specifying which production process should be employed; (3) specification standards which impose (or prohibit) specific production methods. When standards are not sufficient to correct market failures, prior approval might be used. To choose one of these techniques, it is important to assess their efficacy. Thus, the relevant question is: ‘how much regulation is efficient?’ Some advocates of consumer protection could probably argue that it is worthwhile to regulate until the point product risks are reduced to zero. The Delaney ‘anticancer’ amendment to the Food, Drug and Cosmetic Act of 1938 is a striking example of ‘zero-risk’ legislation. For a comment see Asch (1990). Each regulation, however, has its opportunity costs. The point where the curve of marginal benefits intersects the one of marginal costs indicates what the optimal amount of product safety regulation is. A first hint from an economic analysis is that regulation should not be adopted if its benefits do not exceed its costs (Asch, 1988). This finding should not induce the regulator to adopt a measure whenever its benefits exceed its costs. In other words, the condition of higher benefits than costs is necessary, but not sufficient. A regulation to be adopted should also be the cheapest. If it does exist, the alternative regulation that can achieve the same results at lower cost, or better results at the same cost, should be adopted. Thus, we have found two criteria to refer to: (1) benefits should offset the costs and (2) between alternative regulations (effectiveness to be equal) the cheapest one should be chosen, or in case of diverse forms of regulations, having the same costs, the one that has the best outcome should be adopted. To make use of cost-benefit analysis and to compare the effectiveness of different regulations, it is necessary to be able to assess costs and benefits. In the case of product safety regulation, the figures relative to costs and benefits are mainly based upon the probability that a product will harm the consumers or bystanders. The assessment of risk is, therefore, preliminary in a regulatory process. Nichols and Zeckhauser (1986) give the following definition of risk assessment and risk management. ‘Measuring risks and deciding what to do about them are distinct activities. “Risk assessment”
334
Product Safety Regulation
5130
refers to the primarily scientific enterprise of estimating risks. “Risk management” refers to formulations of policies to control those risks; relying on political, ethical, and economic judgements, it is informed but not determined by science.’ In order to assess the probabilities that a substance will turn out to be harmful for consumers or bystanders, science is used. It can be easily said that questions posed in the domain of risk assessment of hazardous products are hardly answerable with certainty. As scientific knowledge always grows, it can be inferred that risk assessment is never complete. For a case of integration of scientific expertise into regulatory decision making see Hankin (1996). In spite of its limits, science is still the only tool that should be used in risk assessment. Science is the only method for ranking risk. In addition, it should be remembered that science is knowledge so systematized that prediction and verification are still possible, which implies that the public can monitor the work of regulators. This makes science even more valuable in a democratic society. Given the information provided by scientific research, the competent authority should judge whether the risk is acceptable or not. Therefore, here we move from the determination of risk to the decisions concerning risk. In doing so, it is highly recommended to take into account not only the risk but also the product efficacy, which measures the probability and the intensity of beneficial effects. Even if the general strength of cost-benefit analysis has been recognized, cost-benefit analysis as a technique of risk management has its pitfalls as well. As the issue is definitely broad, the flaws of cost-benefit analysis will be only rapidly and partially reviewed (Trebilcock and Fraiberg, 1997). For a critique against benefit-cost analysis see Lave (1996). In the absence of firm data or scientific consensus, it might be that public agencies make use of ‘conservative’ assumptions (upper bound estimates). The point to be stressed is that ‘differences in the degree of conservatism distort priorities and may well result in lower overall safety’ (Nichols and Zeckhauser, 1986; Hendee, 1996). Furthermore, in some cases, it is difficult in itself to attribute monetary values to the cost and benefit of regulation. For example it is very difficult to put a financial value on life (see Viscusi, 1996). Another non-trivial difficulty stems from the necessity of discounting the value of future benefits and costs. This is very complicated calculus fraught with several uncertainties. Furthermore, a common criticism of cost-benefit analysis is that it is not capable of coping with questions of distributive justice. The analysis might become even more tangled when the ‘countervailing risks’ created by the safety regulations themselves are taken into account, as it might turn out very difficult to assess their performance. On this point see Graham and Weiner (1995).
5130
Product Safety Regulation
335
Moreover, it is noteworthy to remember that people, in fact, have different attitudes toward the nature of risk. A possible policy implication might be that in calculating the value of life, the nature of risk should be taken into account as well. Slovic (1990) argues that public ‘conceptualization of risk is much richer than that of the experts and reflects legitimate concerns that are typically omitted from expert risk assessment. ... Each side, expert and public, has something valid to contribute.’ A quite different solution has been reached by Breyer (1993), who highlights the public’s misperception of risk and advocates the creation of a group of expert to build a coherent risk-regulation system. A suggestion can be that, for catastrophic events, the risk-conversion factor should be exponential, limited by the rule about effectively discounting zero probabilities. A very balanced approach is the one of Noll and Krier (1990), who point out the relevance of cognitive psychology for risk regulation. In the light of the downfalls of the cost-benefit analysis, some general criteria to refer to should be found. Trebilcock and Fraiberg (1997) suggest the following rules: (1) maximize expected values, (2) avoid catastrophes, (3) dismiss extremely remote possibilities and (4) adopt equitable regulations. In addition, an easier alternative method to cost-benefit analysis is the so-called cost-effectiveness analysis, which compares the costs of diverse regulations. Arrow et al. (1996) discuss the importance of cost-benefit analysis for regulatory decisionmaking. They suggest eight principles for an appropriate use of cost-benefit analysis, among which are the following: all major regulatory decisions should be based on cost-benefit analysis. The regulatory agencies should not be bound by strict benefit-cost tests. Economic variables such as the social discount rate, the value of reducing risks of premature death and accidents and the value associated with other improvements in health should be used in cost-benefit analysis. Distributional consequences should be taken into account as well. For a multi-disciplinary approach to cost-benefit analysis see Hahn (1996).
4. Review of Relevant Empirical Studies on Automobile Safety Regulation In the previous section, the issue of cost-benefit analysis as a valuable technocratic tool for policymakers has been analyzed. In this and in the next two sections, a survey of the empirical literature devoted to an appraisal of safety regulation in different areas is presented. A relevant number of studies has focused attention on automobile safety regulation, as in the USA during the 1970s several regulations related to automobile safety were issued. The lively controversy on this topic deserves some attention.
336
Product Safety Regulation
5130
Peltzman (1975) shows that auto safety regulation has had no effect on the highway death rate. One explanation given to this finding is that ‘drivers have offset’ the benefit of the regulation (that is, the reduced risk of death from accident) ‘by taking greater accident risk’. In addition, a lower level of driving care may increase the number of pedestrians harmed. The Peltzman contribution has given rise to an animated debate among specialists. As the amount of empirical literature on the topic is enormous, only some of it will be reviewed. To be noted is the critical analysis carried out by Robertson (1977). The latter reached different results applying a revised model. However, Peltzman (1977) rejected the criticism arguing about the inconsistency of the revisions with a model of rational driver choice. For a critique of the Peltzman model, see Joksch (1976). Some years later, the alternative analytical approach adopted by Graham and Garber (1984) has seriously challenged Peltzman’s results. The central point emphasized by these authors is that Peltzman’s results are very sensitive to his specifications. They have shown how the recalculation of Peltzman’s regression estimates, changing the functional form (variables were expressed in the classical form and not in the logarithmic form), leads to different conclusions (that is, ‘estimates suggest that regulation averted roughly 5000 fatalities between 1966 and 1972, rather than causing about 10000 deaths as Peltzman’s estimates suggest’). At a more general level, the article gains relevance, as it tends to illustrate how general shortcomings in using statistical results in policy analysis can be avoided. Accordingly, it is contended ‘that a political process can be greatly enhanced by taking into account how beliefs of the analyst might have affected the analysis’. In defense of the auto safety regulation is the article of Claybrook and Bollier (1985), but they do not present convincing evidence to support their thesis. More convincing evidence is presented by Crandall and Graham (1984), Graham (1984) and by Crandall et al. (1986) who have found overall positive lifesaving effects of automobile safety regulation, as ‘the intrinsic engineering effects of safety devices appear to swamp the behavioral responses’. Analogous conclusions have been drawn by Lindgren and Stuart (1980) who have found no offsetting behavioral response to Swedish vehicle safety and speed law. More general is the piece by Asch (1986). Even if aware of the risk of paternalism, he outlines that ‘the benefits of regulation, though uncertain, are potentially enormous’. For further discussion, see also Arnould and Grabowsky (1983), Mashaw and Harfst (1987, 1990). All the studies reviewed tell us something about the effects of auto safety regulation. Therefore, they might be used to draw normative conclusions. Also few studies devoted to investigate the issue of consumer demand for vehicle safety might turn out to be useful for drawing valuable normative conclusions for policymakers. An example is the writing of McCarthy
5130
Product Safety Regulation
337
(1990), who uses extensive data set to focus the attention on the individual’s demand for safety. He argues for the desirability of a policy, which mandates car dealers to make public crash test results. This normative conclusion stems from the positive conclusion of his analysis, which illustrates that individuals do exhibit a demand for safety. Also see Winston and Mannering (1984) who have carried out a cost-benefit analysis of safety regulation estimating the benefits on the consumer demand for automobile safety.
5. Evaluating Risk-Compensation Behavior Particularly intriguing are the studies carried out by Viscusi (1984a, 1992, 1996) who has tried to determine the net risk effects of a certain regulation by comparing the risks reduced with the risks generated by such regulation. Viscusi (1984a, 1992) illustrates how consumers have responded to some of the CPSC (Consumer Product Safety Commission) regulations. The principal case he analyses is the effect of the regulation which imposes protective bottle caps on poisonings. He finds that there is no evidence of favorable impact on aspirin poisonings. Viscusi interprets this data as evidence of the so-called ‘lulling effect’. The enactment of a safety regulation may have three effects. It might give incentives to people to lower their level of care (similar to moral hazard problems in the insurance context). Additionally, if people misperceive the new risk, overestimating the new level of safety, the outcome of the regulation may turn out to be such that the overall level of safety is reduced. Hence, it may happen that a safety regulation reduces the risk so much that people completely ignore the risk. Finally, there can be spillover effects on the safety of unregulated products, in the case of indivisible actions. In the case of ‘child resistant’ caps for aspirins, if medicines are kept altogether, it is predictable that after the regulation all the drugs will no longer be locked in a cupboard. As a result, the risk of poisonings by other medicines will be increased by this behavior. Again, this outcome might offset the benefit of the regulation. The case of child resistant caps fits perfectly the theoretical model, which implicates that regulation may be counterproductive. In this perspective the knowledge of how consumers react to regulation assumes a fundamental role. The more is known about their behavior, the more is possible to issue an effective regulation. Therefore, these adverse effects should be taken into account in the phase of risk management. Nevertheless, Kelman (1988) casts some doubts on the reliability of Viscusi’s analysis. He objects to Viscusi not taking into account the sharp drop in the absolute number of deaths from open bottles and he is also
338
Product Safety Regulation
5130
highly critical of Viscusi’s methodology, particularly of the econometric model. Therefore, Kelman seriously challenges the conclusions drawn by Viscusi that the regulation was counterproductive. The hypothesis that the effectiveness of safety regulation can be offset by behavioral response of the consumer is also investigated by Adams (1983). He has analyzed the case of motorcycle helmet legislation and has found that helmet laws are not effective in decreasing motorcycle fatalities because of the ‘risk-compensation’ behavior by motorcycle riders. Similarly, Graham and Lee (1986) have observed an offsetting behavior by riders, but they conclude that helmet laws are effective public health policies. Moreover, they strongly advise to take more seriously the hypothesis of long-run behavioral feedback to safety regulation.
6. Some More Empirical Studies on Product Safety Regulation The regulation of pharmaceutical products deserves special attention because, as it has been said by Kaufer (1989), ‘the supply of drugs is an exceptional blend of actual and suspected sources of market failures’. Among the multitude sources of market failures present in this market, one can mention at least the dramatic problem of asymmetric information and the fact that pharmaceuticals ‘may generate enormous externality’ (Ogus, 1994). Ogus argues that ‘this is a consequence both of the large numbers of individuals who may consume them, and of the size of harm which may ensue’ (that is, the case of Thalidomide). Moreover, it is very likely that there will be also ‘private law failures’, as it is highly probable that a drug seller would not face the threat of suit for harm done given the insolvency risk, the difficulty for the average consumer in recognizing the etiological relation between harm and its cause (in our case, the medicine), the presence of causal uncertainty, especially for poli-pharmaceutical treatments, and given that a long length of time often elapses before the harm manifests itself. Therefore, the presence of market failures and ‘private law failures’ is the public interest justification for the co-existence of several type of regulations, which go from information regulation (in Europe see Directive 92/27/EEC) to a system of prior approval (in Europe see Directive 93/39/EEC and Regulation 2309/93/EEC) and prescription-only regulation (in Europe see Directive 92/26/EEC). As in the pharmaceutical industry firms’ innovative capacity is a crucial factor, the sharp decline in new product introduction, which was predominant in the US, has induced several authors to investigate whether this was due to the regulation’s rigidity. Peltzman (1973a, 1973b) has studied the effects of the 1962 Amendments to the 1938 Food, Drug and
5130
Product Safety Regulation
339
Cosmetic Act, which added a ‘proof of efficacy’ requirement to the proof of safety requirement of 1938. He has concluded that the 1962 Amendments have reduced the flow of new drugs marketed and increased the gestation period for any new drug reaching the market. As a consequence, he has estimated that the amendments, intended to benefit consumers, have had the opposite effect. The consumer’s losses stemmed from the forgone benefits (the consumer’s surplus) due to the reduced flow of new drugs and from higher prices for existing drugs. However, Pettinga (1975) has pointed out that the principal cause of the decline of new drug introduction was to be identified in the advances in pharmacological science. Similarly, the analysis of Grabowski, Vernon and Thomas (1978), reformulating a model previously developed by Baily (1972), suggests that other non-regulatory factors have an important aggregative effect on innovation. Thus, the decline in US productivity was not only caused by the tighter regulation introduced with the 1962 Amendments, but also by other factors such as the rise in costs, as a result of advances in the technology of safety testing, a general depletion of research opportunities and the Thalidomide incident which has made firms and physician more cautious (see also Ashford and Heaton, 1983; Backhaus, 1983; Wardell and Sheck, 1984; Wiggins, 1984). Notably, in Europe ‘most of the drugs are available only on prescription and the OTC (over-the-counter) sector is no more than 10-20 per cent of the whole’ (Burstall, 1985). The underlying rationale of a mandatory prescription of some medicine is, of course, to protect consumers, which are supposed to know nothing about the therapeutic efficacy and the side-effects of drugs. Almost twenty years ago Temin (1980), discussing the prescription only regulation in the American system stated: ‘[i]t is tempting to imagine the mandatory use of prescriptions as the consequence of medical pressure on the regulatory process, and the result of the doctors ability to “capture” the FDA. But there is no indication that the process worked this way.’ The same conclusion is well grounded for the European system. An interesting point emphasized by Temin is that if judges tend to consider consumers unable to understand information at all, consumers will not take into account the costs of their behavior offsetting the benefits of prescription-only regulation (case reported Incollingo v. Ewing et al., 1971; see also Temin, 1979). Critical to prescription-only regulation is Peltzman (1987), who argues that individual behavior may completely offset the safety effects of regulation. At last, the fact can be stressed that it is quite impossible to reach precise conclusions about the need and effectiveness of different types of regulation within the pharmaceutical sector, as the calculation of costs and benefits of such regulations involves large imponderables. Even if very difficult for the aforementioned reasons, it would be stimulating to
340
Product Safety Regulation
5130
investigate whether this mixed system (information regulation, prior approval and prescription-only regulation) does not lead to over-regulation. Aggregate impact analyses, which provide a broader perspective than case studies, have been reviewed by Dewees, Duff and Trebilcock (1996, p. 227). They mention a report completed by the Consumer Federation of America (CFA) (unpublished), from which resulted that the creation of CPSC has had overall positive effects. From this report there followed a study by Viscusi (1985) who, applying regression analysis, concluded that any beneficial effect of CPSC regulation was too small to estimate reliably. Even if the study of Viscusi is much more technically refined from the one of the CFA, it did not escape criticism. Contrary to what Viscusi contended, Zick et al. (1986) found that the state’s accidental home death rate dropped by 0.017 each year as a result of the CPSC’s existence. A rather different possible way of looking at the issue of product safety regulation is to analyze its effects on income redistribution. An overall comment might be that, in most cases, it is very likely that standards benefit large firms at the expense of smaller firms. As an example, Linneman (1980) has not only showed that consumer safety has not been significantly improved by the 1973 flammability standards, but he has also estimated that the 1973 flammability standards ‘induced large and anticipatable income redistribution from small to large producers’. Inherent to the issue of product safety regulation is also the analysis of the legal regimes governing the professions. Many studies have found that licences can be used as instruments to create barriers to entry and might generate rents for the practitioners themselves. For a review of the literature concerning this topic see Chapter 9400, Self-Regulation). Very intriguing contributions have been given by Beales (1980), Maurizi (1974), Moore (1961), Van den Bergh and Faure (1991).
7. An Overview of the EC Legal Context In the USA, the Consumer Product Safety Act of 1972 has established the Consumer Product Safety Commission (CPSC), which is charged ‘to protect the public against unreasonable risks associated with consumer products’ and therefore ‘has the power to establish mandatory product safety requirements’. The main difference between the American and the European system is that, in Europe, products safety is regulated mainly by directives and regulations (notably in the Member States by national laws implementing directives or directly by EC regulations). In Europe, in order to control mass production risks, three important directives have been issued: EC Directive 85/374 on Product Liability, EC
5130
Product Safety Regulation
341
Directive 92/59 on General Product Safety and EC Directive 93/68 on the Certification of Products. Even a brief economic analysis of the EC Product Liability Directive is beyond the scope of this paper. A significant contribution to this issue has been provided by Fisinger and Simon (1989). Nevertheless, when investigating whether the legal context reflects the economic goal of optimal safety, it is worthwhile to focus on the desirability of studying the convergence, divergence and the interaction of the three directives. Cafaggi (1997) argues that the system based on certification of products should not necessarily be considered as an alternative technocratic tool to administrative controls on product safety. Actually, such a system, given its important signaling function, renders the administrative controls on product safety into a more valuable tool. It is noteworthy to recall that when the Product Liability Directive was issued, safety regulation was to be considered as a special and residual discipline. The emphasis then shifted to safety regulation and with Directive 92/59, safety regulation became a general discipline parallel to tort law system. Such development of EC law might have been the outcome of a general consciousness that tort law was far from being a satisfactory answer to problems originating from mass production. Although a development of the legislation was needed, the co-existence of the two directives have given rise to some concerns such as the question of duplication of controls and, consequently, of costs, and of the useless waste of scarce resources. Furthermore, one of the shortcomings of Directive 92/59 is that social benefits of products are not even mentioned. Therefore, it is quite difficult to introduce cost-benefit analysis in the European process of risk management. However, the Product Safety Directive contains some valuable rules such as, for instance, the general possibility of withdrawing defective products from the market. This rule seems valuable mainly because it renders the system more flexible and might balance the fact that, in the Directive, there is no mention of the definition of product defect in accordance with the state of science and technology. The words spent on EC legal context do not give a complete idea of the European juridical scenario, not only because these general directives have not been entirely analyzed, but also because, parallel to such a general system, there are several specific directives regulating the safety of particular categories of products (that is, food, pharmaceuticals, toys, and so on). It might be attractive in the future to investigate whether the combination of such specific regulatory regimes with the general Directives would pass a cost-benefit test.
342
Product Safety Regulation
5130
Bibliography on Product Safety Regulation (5130) Arnould, Richard J. and Grabowski, Henry G. (1983), ‘Automobile Safety Regulation: A Review of the Evidence’, 5 Research in Law and Economics, 735-749. Asch, Peter (1986), ‘Automobile Safety: Is Government Regulation Really Our Savior?’, 3 Yale Journal on Regulation, 383-389. Asch, Peter (1990), ‘Food Safety Regulation: Is the Delaney Clause the Problem or Symptom?’ 23 Policy Science, 97-110. Ashford, Nicholas A. and Heaton, George R., Jr (1983) ‘Regulation and Technological Innovation in the Chemical Industry’, 46(3) Law and Contemporary Problems, 109-157. Backhaus, Jürgen G. (1983), ‘Competition, Innovation and Regulation in the Pharmaceutical Industry’ 4(2) Managerial and Decision Economics, 107-121. Beales, J. Howard, III (1980), ‘The Economics of Regulating the Professions’ in Blair, R. D. and Rubin, S. (eds) Regulating the Professions: A Public-Policy Symposium, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Burrows, Paul (1992), ‘Consumer Safety Under Products Liability and Duty to Disclose’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 457-478. Claybrook, Joan and Bollier, David (1985), ‘The Hidden Benefits of Regulation: Disclosing the Auto Safety Payoff’, 3 Yale Journal on Regulation, 87-131. Crandall, Robert W. and Graham, John D. (1984), ‘Automobile Safety Regulation and Offsetting Behavior: Some new Empirical Estimates’, 74 American Economic Review. Paper and Proceedings, 328-331. Crandall, Robert W. et al. (1986), Regulating the Automobile, Washington, DC, Brookings Institution. Dewees, Donald N., Duff, David and Trebilcock, Michael J. (1996), Exploring the Domain of Accident Law: Taking the Facts Seriously, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Grabowski, Henry G., Vernon, John M. and Thomas, Lacy Glenn, (1978), ‘Estimating the Effects of Regulation on Innovation. An International Comparative Analysis of the Pharmaceutical Industry’, 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 133-163. Graham, John D. (1984), ‘Technology, Behavior, and Safety: An Empirical Study of Automobile Occupant-Protection Regulation’, 17 Policy Science, 141-151. Graham, John D. and Garber, Steven (1984), ‘Evaluating the Effects of Automobile Safety Regulation’, 3 Journal of Policy Analysis and Management, 206-224. Graham, John D. and Lee, Younghee (1986), ‘Behavioral Response to Safety Regulation: The Case of Motorcycle Helmet Wearing Legislation’, 19 Policy Science, 253-273. Linneman, Peter (1980), ‘The Effects of Consumer Safety Standards: The 1973 Mattress Flammability Standard’, 23 Journal of Law and Economics, 461-479. Mashaw, Jerry L. and Harfst, David L. (1987), ‘Regulation and Legal Culture: The Case of Motor Vehicle Safety’, 4 Yale Journal on Regulation, 257-316. Mashaw, Jerry L. and Harfst, David L. (1990), The Struggle for Auto Safety, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. McCarthy, Patrick S. (1990), ‘Consumer Demand for Vehicle Safety: An Empirical Study’, 28 Economic Inquiry, 530-543. Nichols, Albert L. and Zeckhauser, Richard J. (1986), ‘The Perils of Prudence: How Conservative Risk Assessment Distort Regulation’, 6 Regulation, 13-24.
5130
Product Safety Regulation
343
Noll, Roger G. and Krier, James E. (1990), ‘Some Implications of Cognitive Psychology for Risk Regulation’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 747-779. Peltzman, Sam (1973a), ‘An Evaluation of Consumer Protection Legislation: The 1962 Drug Amendments’, 81 Journal of Political Economy, 1049-1091. Peltzman, Sam (1975), ‘The Effects of Automobile Safety Regulation’, 83 Journal of Political Economy, 677-795. Peltzman, Sam (1977), ‘A Reply to Leon S. Robertson: “A Critical Analysis of Peltzman’s The Effects of Automobile Safety Regulation”’, 11 Journal of Economic Issues, 672-678. Robertson, Leon S. (1977), ‘A Critical Analysis of Peltzman’s ‘The Effects of Automobile Safety Regulation’’, 11 Journal of Economic Issues, 587-600. Temin, Peter (1979), ‘The Origin of Compulsory Drug Prescriptions’, 22 Journal of Law and Economics, 91-105. Viscusi, W. Kip (1984a), ‘The Lulling Effect: The Impact of Child Resistant Packaging on Aspirin and Analgesic Ingestions’, 74 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 324-327. Viscusi, W. Kip (1984b), Regulating Consumer Product Safety, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research. Wardell, William M. and Sheck, Lorraine E. (1984), ‘Is Pharmaceutical Innovation Declining? Interpreting Measures of Pharmaceutical Innovation and Regulatory Impact in the USA, 1950-1980’, in Lindgren, B. (ed.), Pharmaceutical Economics: Paper Presented at the 6th Arne Ryde Symposium, Helsenborg, Sweden, 1982, Malmö, Liber, 177-189. Wiggins, Steven N. (1984) ‘The Effects of U.S. Pharmaceutical Regulation on New Introductions’, in Lindgren, B. (ed.), Pharmaceutical Economics: Paper Presented at the 6th Arne Ryde Symposium, Helsenborg, Sweden, 1982, Malmö, Liber, 191-205. Winston, Clifford and Mannering, Fred (1984), ‘Consumer Demand for Automobile Safety’, 74 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 316-319.
Other References Adams, J.G.U. (1983) ‘Public Safety Legislation and the Risk Compensation Hypothesis: The Example of Motorcycle Helmet Legislation’, 1 Environmental Planning Government and Policy, 193-203. Allaix, Maurice (1953) ‘Le Comportement de l’Homme Rationel devant le Risque: Critique des Postulates et Axiomes de l’Ecole Americaine’, 21 Econometrica, 503-504. Akerlof, George A. (1970), ‘The Market for “Lemons”: Quality Uncertainties and the Market Mechanism’, 89 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 488-500. Akerlof, George A. and Dickens, William T. (1982), ‘The Economic Consequences of Cognitive Dissonance’, 72 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 307-319. Arrow, Keith J. et al. (1996), ‘Is There a Role for Benefit-Cost Analysis in Environmental, Health and Safety Regulation?’, 272 Science, 221-222. Asch, Peter (1988), Consumer Safety Regulation. Putting a Price on Life and Limb, Oxford.
344
Product Safety Regulation
5130
Baily, Martin N. (1972), ‘Research and Development Costs and Returns: The U.S. Pharmaceutical Industry’, 80 Journal of Political Economy, 70-85. Bardach, Eugene and Kagan, Robert A. (1982), Going by the Book: The Problem of Regulatory Unreasonableness, New York, Bergin & Garvey. Bernoulli, Daniel (1738/1954) ‘Specimen Theorie Novae de Mesura Sortis’, 5 Commentari Academiae Scientiarum Imperialis Petropolitanae, 175-192. English translation: 22 Econometrica (1954), 23-36. Breyer, Stephen (1993), Breaking the Vicious Circle: Toward Effective Risk Regulation, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Burstall, Michael L. (1985), The Community Pharmaceutical Industry, London, Commission of the European Community Document - Economists Advisory Group. Cafaggi, Fabrizio (1997), ‘La Responsabilità dell’Impresa per Prodotti Difettosi’ (Firm’s Liability for Defective Products) in Lipari (ed.), Diritto Privato Europeo (European Private Law), PA. Calabresi, Guido (1970), The Costs of Accidents. A Legal and Economic Analysis. New Haven, Yale University Press. Darby, Michael R. and Karny, Edi (1973), ‘Free Competition and the Optimal Amount of Fraud’, 16 Journal of Law and Economics, 67-88. Fisinger, Jörg and Simon, Jürgen (1989) ‘An Economic Assessment of the EC Product Liability Directive and the Product Liability Law of the Federal Republic of Germany’, in Faure, Michael G. and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds), Essays in Law and Economics, 185-211. Forrest, Anne S. (1992), Consumer Response to Risk Information, Master thesis published by UMI. Graham, John D. and Weiner, J.D. (eds) (1995), Risk versus Risk. Tradeoffs in Protecting Health and the Environment, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Grether, David M. and Plott, Charles R. (1979), ‘Economic Theory and the Choice of Preference Reversal Phenomenon’, 69 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 623-638. Hahn, Robert W. (ed.) (1996), Risks, Costs and Lives Saved: Getting Better Results from Regulation, New York and Oxford, Oxford University Press. Hankin, Rober (1996), Integrating Scientific Expertise into Regulatory Decision-Making. The Case of Food and Pharmaceuticals, EUI Working Papers, RCS N. 96/7, Florence. Hendee, William R. (1996), ‘Modeling Risk at Low Level of Exposure’, in Hahn, R.W. (ed.), Risks, Costs and Lives Saved: Getting Better Results from Regulation, New York and Oxford, Oxford University Press. Joksch, H.C. (1976), ‘A Critique of Sam Peltzman’s Study’, 8 Accident Analysis and Prevention, 129-137. Karni, Edi and Safra, Zvi (1987), ‘”Preference Reversal” and the Observability of Preferences by Experimental Methods’, 55 Econometrica, 675-685. Kaufer, Erich (1989), The Regulation of Drug Development: In Search of a Common European Approach, EUI Working Papers, RCS N. 89/411, Florence. Kelman, Mark (1988), ‘On Democracy-Bashing’, 74 Vanderbilt Law Review 199. Lave, Lester B. (1996), ‘Benefit-Cost Analysis: Do the Benefits Exceed the Costs?’, in Hahn, R.W. (ed.), Risks, Costs and Lives Saved: Getting Better Results from Regulation, New York and Oxford, Oxford University Press.
5130
Product Safety Regulation
345
Lichtenstein, Sarah and Slovic, Paul (1971), ‘Reversals of Preferences between Bids and Choices in Gambling Decisions’, 89 Journal of Experimental Psychology, 46-55. Lichtenstein, Sarah and Slovic, Paul (1973), ‘Response-Induced Reversals of Preference in Gambling: An Extended Replication in Las Vegas’, 101 Journal of Experimental Psychology, 16-20. Lindgreen, Björn and Stuart, Charles (1980), ‘The Effect of Traffic Safety Regulation in Sweden’, 82 Journal of Political Economy, 412-427. Magat, Wesley A. and Viscusi, W. Kip (1992), Informational Approaches to Regulation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology . Maurizi, Alex R. (1974), ‘Occupational Licencing and the Public Interest’, 82 Journal of Political Economy, 399-413. Moore, Thomas G. (1961), ‘The Purpose of License’, 5 Journal of Law and Economics, 93-117. Nelson, Philipp (1970), ‘Information and Consumer Behavior’, 78 Journal of Political Economy, 311-329. Ogus, Anthony I. (1994), Regulation: Legal Form and Economic Theory, New York, Oxford University Press. Peltzman, Sam (1973b), ‘The Benefits and Costs of 1962 Amendments to the 1938 Food, Drug and Cosmetic Act’, in Landau (ed.), Regulating New Drugs, University of Chicago Center for Policy Study. Peltzman, Sam (1987), ‘The Health Effects of Mandatory Prescriptions’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 207-238. Pettinga (1975), in Cooper, J.D. (ed.), Regulating, Economics and Pharmaceutical Innovation, 281. Pildes, Richard H. and Sunstein, Cass R. (1995), ‘Reinventing the Regulatory State’, 62 The University of Chicago Law Review, 1-129. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1991), ‘Tort Law as a Regulatory System: Regulation and the Law of Torts’, 81 American Economic Review. Paper and Proceedings, 54-58. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1992), Rethinking the Progressive Agenda: the Reform of the American Regulatory State, New York, 118. Shavell, Steven (1984), ‘Liability for Harm versus Regulation of Safety’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 357-374. Shavell, Steven (1987), Economic Analysis of Accident Law, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Slovic, Paul (1990), ‘Perception of Risk’, 236 Science, 280-285. Skogh, Göran, (1989) ‘The Combination of Private and Public Regulation of Safety’, in Essays in Law and Economics I, Antwerpen, Maklu, 87-101. Temin, Peter (1980), ‘Regulation and the Choice of Prescription Drugs’, 70(2) American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 301-305. Trebilcock, Michael J. and Fraiberg, Jeremy D. (1997), A Primer on Risk Regulation: Technocratic Tools for Regulatory Reform, Paper presented at the International Conference ‘Institutions, Markets and Economic Performance: Deregulation and its Consequences’ held in Utrecht in December 1997. Tversky, Amos and Kahneman, Daniel (1974), ‘Judgement Under Uncertainty: Heuristic and Biases’ 184 Science, 453-458. Tversky, Amos and Kahneman, Daniel (1981), ‘The Framing of Decisions and the Psychology of Choice’, 211 Science, 453-458.
346
Product Safety Regulation
5130
Van den Bergh, Roger and Faure, Michael G. (1991), ‘Self-Regulation of the Professions in Belgium’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 165-182. Viscusi, W. Kip (1985), ‘Consumer Behavior and the Safety Effects of Products Regulation’ 28 Journal of law and Economics, 527-533. Viscusi, W. Kip (1992), Fatal Trade-off: Public and Private Responsibilities for Risk, New York: Oxford University Press. Viscusi, W. Kip (1996), ‘Economic Foundations of the Current Regulatory Reform Efforts’, 10 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 119-134. Zick, Cathleen D. et al. (1986), ‘Does the U.S. Consumer Product Safety Commission Make a Difference? An Assessment of its First Decade’, 6 Journal of Consumer Policy, 25 ff.
5140 PRODUCTS LIABILITY Mark Geistfeld New York University School of Law © Copyright 1999 Mark Geistfeld
Abstract Designing the products liability system to promote efficiency is justifable because the injurer (seller) and victim (consumer) typically are in a contractual relationship. Contracting will not lead to efficient outcomes when consumers undervalue the benefits of seller liability, as would occur, for example, when consumers underestimate product risk. Although tort liability often would reduce product risk in these situations, forcing sellers to pay for product-caused injuries is likely to increase the average cost of injury compensation. This tension between safety and insurance considerations makes it difficult to reach firm conclusions regarding the efficiency properties of the main products liability doctrines. Nevertheless, in many instances the legal rules do not depend upon the relevant economic considerations, suggesting that the current system could be made more efficient. JEL classification: D18, K13, L15 Keywords: Products Liability, Product Risk, Product Safety, Insurance
1. Introduction Products liability - the body of law governing the allocation of losses caused by product use - has rapidly gained prominence over the past 50 years. The importance of products liability stems from the substantial social cost of product-caused injuries. According to government data, product accidents in the United States cost roughly $50 billion per year (Keeton et al., 1989, p. 2). These data are crude, however (Viscusi, 1984, pp. 48-55). Relying on survey evidence, Hensler et al. (1991) estimate that accidents in the United States, excluding those resulting in latent injuries, institutionalization, or death, impose direct and work-loss annual costs of $175.9 billion or 4 percent of Gross National Product. Approximately 30 percent of these accidents involved product use, and another 18 percent were associated with motor-vehicle use. The social cost of nonfatal product accidents is substantial, then, and including fatalities and latent injuries (like those caused by exposure to toxic substances) considerably increases the total. The magnitude of these losses and the volume of product transactions indicate that products liability rules have a significant 347
348
Products Liability
5140
impact on producers, consumers, and the general economy. Consequently, products liability has become one of the most important, and politically controversial, forms of civil liability. Legal scholars who analyzed the emerging field of products liability rarely addressed efficiency concerns (McKean, 1970a; Priest, 1985). Similarly, court opinions in products liability cases have paid little or no explicit attention to efficiency (Henderson, 1991). But as the economic analysis of products liability has developed over the past few decades, so too have legal decision -makers become more concerned about the economic consequences of these liability rules. Today efficiency considerations often strongly influence the formulation of products liability laws, as reflected by the Restatement (Third) of Torts: Products Liability (American Law Institute, 1997). This emphasis on efficiency is defensible. Sellers include their liability costs in the product price. Consumers (potential victims) accordingly pay for and receive the benefits of tort liability, so their preference for efficient liability rules - those that maximize the net benefit of seller liability - should govern. By analyzing products liability with an economic perspective, it becomes apparent that this body of law could be merely a specific application of contract law, since if unregulated market transactions were efficient, courts would only have to enforce contractual allocations of product risk in order to ensure efficient outcomes. Many product-caused injuries are governed by tort law, however, making it necessary to identify the market failures that may justify tort regulation. Sections 2 through 10 accordingly develop the economic framework for evaluating different liability rules. Sections 11 through 13 describe the impact that the products liability system has had on product safety, innovation, and the market for liability insurance. The remaining sections discuss the efficiency properties of the main doctrines in products liability.
2. The Basic Model for Analysing the Efficiency Properties of Contracting and Tort Liability Much of the economic analysis of products liability can be described in terms of a simple model. Shavell (1987) and Spulber (1989) provide more rigorous analyses of many of these issues. As the focus of the inquiry is on product-caused injuries, the model does not consider any product characteristics unrelated to the risk of injury (such as aesthetics, functionality, and durability). Hence the ‘product’ to be analyzed is homogeneous in all respects except for the risk of injury posed by the product and the extent of contractual liability the seller incurs under the product warranty. The following assumptions are also unrealistic, but most will be relaxed in the ensuing discussion. All firms have identical production
5140
Products Liability
349
technologies and sell the product, exclusive of safety and liability costs, in a perfectly competitive market at the unit cost of p. By making safety investments of s per unit of product, a firm affects the probability or risk r(s) that the product will cause injury. Increased safety investments reduce the risk of injury at a decreasing rate [r'(s) < 0; r''(s) > 0]. All injuries caused by the product have a monetary equivalent of L that is suffered by risk-neutral buyers who are identical and unable to influence the risk of injury. In light of these assumptions, the total cost or ‘full price’ P of the product is given by (1) P = p + s + r(s)L. If perfectly informed consumers bear the injury cost L in the event of accident, they pay a purchase price of p + s for the product but recognize that this cost is increased by the expected accident cost r(s)L. Consequently, consumers make their purchase decisions on the basis of the full price P rather than the price they pay to purchase the product, so consumer demand QD = QD(P). Sellers then compete by offering the amount of safety and warranty coverage that minimize P. Under these conditions, it does not matter whether a perfectly informed consumer or the seller is liable for the injury (for example, Hamada, 1976). If the consumer is liable, the seller must choose the amount of safety investments to minimize P, which from equation (1) implies that the seller chooses the amount s* defined by 1 = − r'(s*)L. (2) In other words, the seller invests in safety until the last dollar spent reduces expected injury costs by one dollar. Such a product is optimally safe. If the seller is fully liable for the consumer's injuries, it sells the product and warranty at a price of p + s + r(s)L = P. Once again, the seller must minimize the full price, so it chooses the optimal amount of safety investment s*. Whether the consumer or producer is liable for the product-caused injury therefore does not affect product safety or the full price.
3. The Significance of Imperfectly Competitive Markets An early, influential justification for tort regulation was based on the notion that manufacturers can take advantage of their market power by supplying unsafe products (Priest, 1985). However, the results obtained from the basic model are unaffected if the market is not perfectly competitive (for example, Epple and Raviv, 1978). A seller’s market power can be represented by the amount it can increase the product’s full price above the competitive level. By
350
Products Liability
5140
increasing the product price by this amount, the seller increases its profits per sale by that same amount. Alternatively, by reducing safety investments below the optimal level s*, the seller can also increase the product’s full price as each $1 of reduced safety investment necessarily increases expected accident costs r(s)L by more than $1. This strategy does not affect the seller’s profits per sale, however, because the product must sell for a reduced price equal to the unit cost of p + s (any price above cost is equivalent to an increase in the product price). Hence a monopolist can make higher profits by selling perfectly informed consumers an optimally safe product at a supracompetitive price. Similar reasoning shows that if it would be efficient for the seller to bear full liability under the warranty, then a monopolist would maximize profits by offering a full warranty while selling the product at a supracompetitive price (for example, Heal, 1977). It is possible, though, for market structure to affect product safety. The basic model assumes a constant marginal cost of safety investment (the term s) per unit of product. Consequently, a manufacturer’s decision regarding safety investments does not depend upon its output level (as reflected by equation (2) above), implying that product safety will be unaffected by the reduced quantity of output that occurs in imperfectly competitive markets. Many product risks are likely to depend upon the quantity of products sold or consumed by an individual, however. As Marino (1988a, 1988b) points out, toxic chemicals may present a health hazard due to their cumulative effect on consumers. Conversely, consumers may develop a tolerance from cumulative exposure, thereby reducing the risk. The higher prices, and reduced consumption, of products sold in imperfectly competitive markets would affect these kinds of product risk. In addition, when the cost of safety investments depends upon a manufacturer’s output level, the amount of safety investments made by a monopolist depends on the cross-effects of safety investments and output on the monopolist’s costs (Spulber, 1989, pp. 407-410). Whether sellers in imperfectly competitive markets supply products that are insufficiently safe therefore is a difficult empirical question. But if such market failures exist, they probably are better addressed by the antitrust laws.
4. The Role of Consumer Information About Product Risk The analysis so far has assumed that consumers are perfectly informed of risk, an assumption typically made by early economic analyses of products liability (for example, McKean, 1970a; Oi, 1973). But as Goldberg (1974) argued, product safety becomes a regulatory problem only if consumers are inadequately informed. Subsequent economic analyses focused on the effects of imperfect information. When imperfectly informed consumers are liable for their injuries, they
5140
Products Liability
351
must estimate their expected injury costs, denoted E[r(s)L], and hence the full price, denoted E[P]. Consequently, equation (1) above is changed to E[P] = p + s + E[r(s)L]. (1') In this setting, a seller must minimize E[P] if consumers are to buy its product, so sellers choose the amount of safety investment s that minimizes E[P]: 1 = − E[r'(s)L]. (2') Thus, when consumers are imperfectly informed of product risk, the seller invests in safety until the last dollar spent on safety reduces the consumer’s estimate of expected injury costs by one dollar (Spence, 1977). If consumers underestimate the decrease in expected injury costs, they will undervalue risk reduction and demand less than the optimal amount of safety; that is, if − E[r'(s)L] < − r'(s)L, then s < s*. A similar result occurs when consumers cannot observe manufacturer safety investments, because consumers who cannot tell the difference between a low-risk and high-risk product treat the differential in safety as if − E[r"(s)L] = 0 when in fact − r'(s)L > 0. Manufacturers have no incentive to incur the higher cost of producing the low-risk product, so they supply only high-risk products, an outcome analogous to the ‘lemons problem’ analyzed by Akerlof (1970). Imperfect information need not result in overly unsafe products. If consumers overestimate the way in which increased safety investments reduce risk, they will attribute too great a value to safety investments and demand more than the optimal amount of safety. Although this outcome is inefficient, it seems unwise to construct a regulatory regime, with its attendant administrative costs, in order to reduce product safety. Hence there is a pressing need to regulate market transactions only if consumers undervalue safety investments.
5. Market Mechanisms that Promote Product Safety Landes and Posner (1987, pp. 280-281) argue that it is too costly for consumers to obtain perfect information about product risks, and imperfectly informed consumers tend to underestimate the small risks ordinarily posed by products, causing them to undervalue safety investments. In assessing this argument, we must recognize that the cost consumers incur to get risk-related information, and their need for it, depends upon a variety of market mechanisms. For example, manufacturers have an incentive to provide optimally safe products if there is a large enough proportion of well-informed ‘shoppers’ in the market (Schwartz and Wilde, 1983a). The information held by some consumers therefore may benefit others who undervalue product safety. Similarly, consumers who communicate among themselves by ‘word of mouth’
352
Products Liability
5140
advertising may increase the amount of high-quality goods in the market (Rogerson, 1983). Consumers also can purchase product-related information from intermediaries, and such information may come from sellers. Brand names, for example, are a method sellers use to implicitly guarantee superior quality (Klein and Leffler, 1981), because product quality must be sufficiently high if the seller is to attract repeat purchases (for example, Shapiro 1982, 1983). For the same reason, sellers can convey indirect information about product quality through advertising and prices (Milgrom and Roberts, 1986). The way in which price signals quality is highly dependent on the market context, however, as in some settings low prices signal high quality, whereas in other settings high prices signal high quality (Tirole, 1990, pp. 110-12). In addition, prices signal product quality only if consumers have at least some brand-specific information about quality, although this information need not be perfect (Wolinsky, 1983). As long as consumer experience with a product brand provides enough information so that consumers are more likely to believe the brand is of high quality when in fact it is, high-quality firms will attract more customers (Rogerson, 1983). The need to protect their reputation or brand name may force sellers to provide more safety than is suggested by the analysis in the prior section. Nevertheless, it is unlikely that unregulated market transactions will yield optimally safe products when consumers are imperfectly informed of product risk. A seller’s reputation can remain intact even though its product is not optimally safe, because consumers often have little or no ability to learn from product use about the product’s safety characteristics. Many risks are latent and do not become manifest for years (like carcinogens). In addition, many safety characteristics are not observable during normal product use (such as whether a motor vehicle is optimally designed to minimize the risk of injury for different types of accidents). Given the very low probabilities of most product-caused injuries and the fact that optimally safe products typically pose some risk of injury, very little information will be conveyed by a consumer’s experience of ‘no accident’ or ‘accident’. For example, suppose an unsafe product doubles the risk of injury from 1 in 10,000 to 2 in 10,000. Based upon their experience, it could take consumers a long time (involving numerous iterations of Bayesian updating) to discover the increased risk. Another problem is that the price-quality relationship depicted by signalling models is based on equilibrium conditions for products that vary in one dimension of quality. Even within the confines of such a simplified market, it is doubtful that consumers ordinarily will have enough information about the market context to draw the correct inferences about product safety. And once one allows for the (realistic) possibility of disequilibria in markets for products that are heterogeneous in more than one dimension, it becomes even less likely that consumers will be able to obtain good information about product safety from
5140
Products Liability
353
prices. Indeed, one empirical study found that price might serve as a quality signal for only one type of product - frequent but unimportant purchases (Caves and Greene, 1996). Given the limited amount of information provided by market mechanisms, it is puzzling why sellers do not voluntarily disclose risk-related information, particularly since such disclosures would be credible due to the legal prohibition against fraud. Because only high-quality sellers would benefit from voluntary disclosure, consumers could infer from the fact of nondisclosure that a seller is not offering an optimally safe product. All sellers therefore would have to disclose, forcing them to provide optimally safe products. It is possible that high-quality sellers do not voluntarily disclose risk-related information because consumers tend to overreact to negative information about products (see the sources cited in A. Schwartz, 1988, p. 381). Consequently, any seller that discloses risk-related information could cause consumers to believe that its product is unsafe, so high-quality sellers are better off by not disclosing. Burrows (1992) provides other reasons why sellers might not voluntarily disclose information about product risk, and Geistfeld (1997) explains why a system of voluntary disclosure would function much like a tort regime of negligence.
6. Do Consumers Undervalue Product Safety? As the previous discussion suggests, individuals often process risk-related information in a manner that does not correspond to the standard economic model of decisionmaking. A substantial literature on cognitive psychology seeks to understand how individuals assess risks (for example, Kahneman, Slovic and Tversky, 1982). Based on these studies, A. Schwartz (1988, 1992) concludes that consumers tend to overestimate product risks, whereas Latin (1994) concludes that consumers usually underestimate risk and thus undervalue product safety. Both agree these studies find that individuals tend to overestimate risks that are brought to their attention (which may explain why sellers do not voluntarily disclose risk-related information). Latin, however, persuasively argues that most product risks are not salient because product-caused injuries are a rare occurrence for most individuals, leading consumers to infer (erroneously) from the more common or representative experience of safe product use that risk is not present or worth worrying about. Consequently, as Landes and Posner claimed, imperfectly informed consumers tend to underestimate product risks. Although consumer understanding of product risk is relevant to the regulatory problem, it should also be recognized that consumers can undervalue product safety even if they are perfectly informed of product risks. Suppose consumers are risk averse and find it worthwhile to purchase a fully compensatory health insurance policy. Suppose also that the product-caused
354
Products Liability
5140
injury would be fully covered by this policy. Insurance companies ordinarily do not adjust premiums to reflect the riskiness of products purchased by their policyholders (Hanson and Logue, 1990). As the consumer’s health insurance premium is unaffected by her consumption choices, neither it nor the expected cost of injury (which is fully insured) are relevant to the consumer’s purchase decision. The full price to the consumer consequently is given by P = p + s, and sellers minimize this full price by setting s = 0. Simply put, fully insured consumers have no need for risk reduction, so it does not pay for sellers to invest in product safety. Of course, this example is extreme (because insurance policies rarely provide full coverage), but the conclusion is general: fully informed consumers will undervalue product safety when they can externalize some of their injury costs onto an insurance company.
7. Product Warranties and the Use of Seller Liability to Promote Safety As discussed in Section 2, when the seller is fully liable for product-caused injuries, the price at which the product sells on the market equals the full price, forcing the seller to provide the cost-effective amount of product safety. In these circumstances, imperfectly informed consumers only need to find the product that sells for the lowest price in order to get the optimally safe product. Seller liability therefore remedies the consumer’s informational problem in a straightforward way, creating the possibility that imperfectly informed consumers might be able to rely on warranties to obtain optimally safe products. For example, assume as in Grossman (1981) that the manufacturer is the least-cost insurer and that consumers are unable to observe manufacturer safety investments. In this setting, insurance costs are minimized if the manufacturer provides a warranty that fully compensates the consumer for any product-caused injuries. A manufacturer that provides full warranty coverage must also provide an optimally safe product in order to minimize the market price (which equals the full price) of its product. A manufacturer that does not provide the optimally safe product therefore would signal this fact to consumers due to the product’s higher market price, so to avoid this outcome such a manufacturer cannot offer a full warranty. Imperfectly informed consumers would infer this type of behavior, though, and assume that products without full warranty coverage must not be optimally safe. Manufacturers accordingly have no choice but to offer imperfectly informed consumers optimally safe products with full warranty coverage. Thus, when sellers are the least-cost insurers, imperfectly informed consumers can use product warranties to attain efficient outcomes: by choosing warranties that impose full liability on sellers, consumers can ensure that
5140
Products Liability
355
products will be optimally safe and insurance costs will be minimized. Full warranties (or seller liability in tort) might not result in such equilibria, though, if sellers purchase insurance to cover their liability under the warranty. A study directed by the US Department of Commerce found that liability insurance in the 1970s was rarely priced in a manner that reflected the degree of risk posed by the manufacturer-policyholder’s products (Inter-Agency Task Force on Products Liability, 1977). Although such insurance reduces the manufacturer’s incentive to invest in product safety (as the increased accident costs do not increase premiums), developments in the liability-insurance market have significantly restored this incentive. Based on estimates of firms’ total liability costs, Priest (1991) found that self-insurance costs accounted for 4.9 percent of the total in 1970 and increased to 51.7 percent in 1979. The amount of uninsured risk exposure faced by firms probably increased in the 1980s. Moreover, products liability insurance policies now commonly rely on pricing elements that are responsive to the level of risk posed by the policyholder’s products (G. Schwartz, 1990, pp. 320-321). Hence there are good reasons for expecting that the prospect of liability gives sellers an incentive to invest in safer products.
8. Are Product Sellers the Least-Cost Insurer? Despite the safety benefits of seller liability, warranties that make sellers fully liable for product-caused injuries are unlikely to be efficient because sellers rarely are the least-cost insurer for all product risks. Although manufacturers are likely to have a comparative advantage in insuring against some risks, like those involving repair of complicated machinery, consumers typically will have a comparative advantage in insuring against other risks (Priest, 1981). In particular, risk-averse consumers ordinarily will have a comparative advantage in insuring against many of the risks associated with physical injury, because the cost consumers incur in making their own insurance arrangements ‘first-party insurance’ - often is lower than the cost sellers incur in making insurance arrangements to cover product-caused injuries suffered by consumers - ‘third-party insurance’. In part, first-party insurance is cheaper because it is more capable of minimizing the costs of moral hazard and adverse selection (Epstein, 1985; Priest, 1987). The primary reasons for the cost differential between the two insurance mechanisms stem from the event that triggers coverage and the scope of coverage. Coverage under many first-party insurance policies, such as health insurance, is triggered by the fact of loss (like medical expenses), making the cause of injury irrelevant in most cases. The fact of injury or loss usually is easy to prove (submitting bills), so policyholders typically do not have to hire a lawyer to receive insurance proceeds. By contrast, the third-party insurance
356
Products Liability
5140
supplied by product sellers is triggered only if the product caused the injury. Often, many products are causally implicated in an accident, and a potentially contentious factual inquiry may be needed to resolve the liability question (Geistfeld, 1992). Some items of damages, particularly those pertaining to pain-and-suffering damages and future economic loss, are also costly to determine. The resultant litigation expenses increase the cost of third-party insurance, which probably explains why the administrative costs of third-party insurance per dollar of coverage exceed the administrative costs of first-party insurance (Geistfeld, 1992, pp. 639-642). With respect to the scope of coverage, third-party insurance provides compensation for pain-and-suffering injuries whereas first-party insurance typically does not. It might be inefficient for consumers to insure against pain-and-suffering injuries (for reasons given in Section 20 below). If so, it would be more efficient for consumers to suffer these injuries without compensation (a form of first-party insurance), providing another cost advantage for first-party insurance. In other respects, the scope of coverage provided by third-party insurance is not extensive enough, as it does not cover losses unrelated to product use. To cover these contingencies (like medical expenses due to illness), individuals need to purchase other insurance. But since first-party insurance coverage is usually triggered by the fact of loss rather than its cause, individuals who have such insurance might receive double compensation when injured by products: the first-party insurer is obligated to pay whenever the policyholder suffered an insured-against loss; and the seller is obligated to pay (due to the collateral-source rule) even though the consumer received other insurance proceeds. Double recovery can be avoided if the first-party insurer exercises a contractual or statutory right to indemnification out of the tort recovery received by the policyholder, but the separate legal proceeding often is complicated and expensive due to the need to determine which part of the tort award or settlement is covered by the policy. For this and other reasons, many insurers do not exercise this right. Insurance provided by product sellers therefore may be an inefficient form of double insurance or otherwise increase the administrative cost of first-party insurance policies, providing another reason why consumers may reduce their insurance costs if they disclaim seller liability under the warranty. Sellers therefore will typically not be the least-cost insurer for all product risks. Hence, imperfectly informed consumers ordinarily will not be able to rely on full warranty coverage to ensure that products are optimally safe and insurance costs are minimized. It is still an open question, though, whether tort regulation would be efficiency-enhancing.
5140
Products Liability
357
9. The Regulatory Problem To account for differences in the cost faced by consumers and manufacturers in insuring against product losses, LI will denote the consumer’s cost of compensating the injury and LW the seller’s cost of compensating the injury under the product warranty. Whether the seller is liable for the injury may affect product safety, so the seller’s safety investment will be denoted by sI when the consumer insures against the injury and by sW when the seller is liable under the warranty. Finally, we will assume that any insurance costs faced by the consumer equal the actuarially fair amount r(sI )LI . (The other extreme - the case in which premiums do not depend on risk - was discussed in Section 6.) There are two possible full prices to consider: PI = p + sI + r(sI )LI .
(3)
(4) PW = p + sW + r(sW)LW. Consumers will disclaim seller liability when doing so would reduce the full price (that is, when PI < PW), and otherwise will purchase full warranty coverage (when PI > PW). To illustrate how the difference in insurance costs affects the analysis, suppose consumers are unable to observe manufacturer safety investments. For reasons given in Section 4, manufacturers will set sI = 0. Consumers, however, will infer such behavior on the manufacturer’s part, recognizing that the full price is given by PI = p + r(0)LI . By contrast, when the manufacturer is fully liable under the warranty, it provides an optimally safe product. Hence PW = p + sW* + r(sW*)LW. Even though product safety increases when the manufacturer is fully liable under the warranty (sW* > sI = 0), if the consumer has a comparative advantage in compensating the injury (LI < LW), it is possible that PI < PW. Consumers therefore may be better off with the less-safe products and reduced insurance costs than with the safer products and more expensive insurance provided by full product warranties. Thus, there often is a tradeoff between safety and insurance considerations when consumers are imperfectly informed: although increasing the amount of seller liability can lead to safer products, it is also likely to increase the average cost of compensating an injury. This inefficiency does not necessarily create a need for tort regulation, however (Geistfeld, 1995a). As long as imperfectly informed consumers can accurately compare PI and PW, as in the example just given, they will choose warranties that strike the appropriate balance between the costs and benefits of seller liability. At best, a tort rule could achieve a similar balance, but more likely it will not. Inefficiencies in product markets therefore need not create an efficiency-enhancing role for tort liability.
358
Products Liability
5140
Imperfectly informed consumers will not choose appropriate warranties, though, when they underestimate product risk and thus underestimate the product’s full price. (If E[r(s)] < r(s), then E[PI ] < PI .) In this case, consumers sometimes choose warranties that disclaim manufacturer liability when it would be inefficient do so (that is, when E[PI ] < PW < PI ). A tort rule that imposes full liability on sellers would be efficiency enhancing in this situation. It is also possible, however, that consumers disclaim manufacturer liability when it would be efficient to do so (because E[PI ] < PI < PW). Consequently, tort regulation is not necessarily efficiency enhancing when consumers underestimate product risk. The type of market failure that might justify tort regulation accordingly depends upon conditions that cause consumers to disclaim seller liability when it would be inefficient to do so. This conclusion is not affected by extending the analysis to include the possibility that consumers can affect the risk of injury by exercising care while using the product. As long as sellers cannot observe the amount of consumer care, full warranty coverage is likely to reduce the consumer’s incentive to take costly efforts to avoid (the fully insured) injury. Yet, the reduction in warranty coverage reduces the manufacturer’s incentive to make costly safety investments, so the warranty must balance conflicting safety and insurance considerations (Cooper and Ross, 1985a; Emons, 1988). Holding manufacturers liable in tort for product-caused injuries does not solve the informational problem, however, so this form of tort regulation cannot improve upon a warranty that efficiently allocates liability given the informational constraint. An additional consideration arises if consumers have different risk profiles due to differences in product use, abilities to reduce risk for a given level of care, or damages. Although ‘low-risk’ and ‘high-risk’ consumers may demand products of different qualities, manufacturer liability can force sellers to provide only one level of quality. According to Oi (1973), that outcome is inefficient because low-risk (that is, low-damage) consumers are forced to subsidize high-risk consumers. Absolving sellers of liability would eliminate this inefficiency, because sellers could then provide products of different quality at different prices in a manner that sorts low-risk and high-risk consumers into the appropriate product markets. However, Ordover (1979) shows that in order for such separating equilibria to occur, low-risk consumers must differentiate themselves from high-risk consumers by purchasing incomplete warranty coverage. There may be cases in which the benefits of successful differentiation are less than the benefits of mandated seller liability. Hence tort regulation is not necessarily inefficient even though some consumers would be better off without such regulation.
5140
Products Liability
359
10. The Choice Between Negligence and Strict Liability We have been analyzing seller liability in terms of a rule that holds sellers strictly liable for injuries caused by product use. Most product accidents are governed by a rule of negligence, however, which makes sellers liable for injuries caused by products that are not reasonably safe. According to the economic interpretation of negligence, a product is not reasonably safe if it contains less than the optimal amount of safety s* defined by equation (2) above. Because each dollar of safety investment below s* increases expected accident (and thus liability) costs by more than one dollar, sellers minimize total costs by making total safety investments equal to s*. Thus, a negligence standard that is properly defined and perfectly enforced gives sellers an incentive to supply optimally safe products, the same incentive created by strict liability. Negligence differs from strict liability in that consumers under a negligence rule bear liability for injuries caused by optimally safe products, giving them the opportunity to enter into insurance arrangements that minimize the cost of injury compensation. In theory, then, a negligence regime can yield optimally safe products while enabling consumers to minimize insurance costs. Nevertheless, negligence will not lead to efficient outcomes, when consumers are imperfectly informed of product risk (Shavell, 1980; Polinsky, 1980). Because sellers are not liable for injuries caused by their (optimally safe) products, the product sells for p + s*. Consumers in a negligence regime therefore need to estimate expected injury costs r(s*)LI in order to determine the product’s full price P. Consumers who underestimate product risk will underestimate the full price, increasing their demand above the amount they would choose if they were perfectly informed. Thus, even though products are optimally safe, consumers will purchase too many products (and there will be too many firms in the industry). This overconsumption increases the total number of injuries above the efficient amount whenever optimally safe products pose a positive risk of injury. Another problem with a negligence rule is that it often will be difficult (and expensive) for the plaintiff to show that the product should have been made differently. Consider, for example, the complicated issues that must be resolved in order to determine whether a product is optimally designed. The cost of litigating these issues may undermine the safety incentives of negligence liability. Prior to filing suit, injured consumers who are not well-informed about manufacturer safety investments often will be unable to determine whether the product is reasonably safe. These consumers (or their contingent-fee attorneys) may be unwilling to incur the cost of proceeding with the lawsuit, enabling some manufacturers with suboptimally safe products to escape liability. Under these conditions, a proportion of manufacturers choose to be negligent (Simon, 1981).
360
Products Liability
5140
Another reason for expecting that the negligence standard will not be perfectly enforced stems from the possibility that judges and juries will make mistakes. The complicated issues in products liability cases (many of which are discussed below) make court error possible. Hylton (1990) shows that a negligence standard with court error and costly litigation can lead to over- or underdeterrence. Overdeterrence can occur because sellers of optimally safe products may be held liable due to court error. By increasing product safety, the seller decreases the risk of injury, thereby reducing the likelihood that it will be subjected to a lawsuit and an erroneous imposition of liability. But even though court errors can increase product safety, the increased legal uncertainty has deleterious effects (also discussed later). Moreover, overdeterrence may involve the withdrawal of socially beneficial products from the marketplace. Strict liability, by contrast, is less costly for plaintiffs and easier for courts to administer, which increases the likelihood that it will be perfectly enforced. In addition, strict liability can lead to the efficient level of risk even though consumers are imperfectly informed. Hence strict liability has a better potential for reducing product risk. Negligence, on the other hand, allows for a greater range of insurance arrangements and accordingly has more potential to reduce the average cost of compensating an injury. The choice between negligence and strict liability therefore reflects the same safety-insurance tradeoff described earlier: increased seller liability (that is, strict liability) is likely to increase safety and per-injury insurance costs, whereas decreased seller liability (negligence) is likely to reduce safety and the average cost of compensating an injury.
11. Empirical Studies of the Effect of Seller Liability on Product Safety Whether seller liability reduces product risk is a difficult empirical question, because the available accident data are not sufficiently refined and the injury rate is affected by a number of other factors such as changes in technology and the composition of products and users. Indeed, data limitations undermine the conclusions one can draw from attempts to measure the impact that seller liability has had on product safety. For example, Priest (1988a) compares the amount of products liability litigation to death rates and the rate of product-related injuries requiring emergency room treatment, concluding that the expansion in litigation had no discernible effect on accident rates. Although Priest acknowledges that the study is exploratory, Huber and Litan (1991, p. 6) assert that it raises ‘serious doubts that the benefits of expanded seller liability have been large’. But as Dewees, Duff and Trebilock (1996, p. 203) point out, Priest’s study does not necessarily show anything about the relationship between seller liability and accident rates. The accidents in the study could be caused by a number of factors unrelated to manufacturer safety investments.
5140
Products Liability
361
Moreover, increased seller liability should reduce the number of ‘defective’ (suboptimally safe) products, but the injury data are not segregated into accidents involving defective and nondefective products, making it difficult to draw useful conclusions from the study. For example, the prior level of tort liability could have significantly increased the number of nondefective products on the market. Greater consumption of these nondefective products (due to increased wealth, for example) could increase the overall injury rate, even though the expansion in seller liability reduced product risk by reducing the amount of defective products on the market. Higgins (1978) relies on accidental fatalities in the home as a proxy for product-caused injuries. The econometric analysis finds that producer liability reduces the frequency of these accidents in states with low levels of educational attainment and increases it in states with high levels. If low educational attainment corresponds to imperfectly informed consumers, this study partially supports the claim that producer liability increases safety when consumers are not well informed of risk. However, in addition to the previously mentioned problems of relying on such aggregated accident data, this study is problematic because it measures the impact of producer liability in a state by reference to the year when its highest court expanded producer liability by eliminating the contractual requirement of privity. It is doubtful that this expansion in seller liability was significant enough to produce observable results, particularly since the numerous exceptions to the privity doctrine meant that sellers were already exposed to considerable liability for injuries suffered by victims with whom there was no direct contractual relationship. Graham (1991) attempts to determine the relationship between products liability and passenger-car death rates. The regression does not detect any beneficial impact of liability on aggregate death rates, with the extent of liability measured by an index based on the annual number of crashworthiness cases reported in the LEXIS database. Measuring liability rules by published judicial opinions is particularly problematic, however, because most lawsuits are settled prior to trial. A very effective liability rule, for example, could cause all cases to settle, giving sellers a strong incentive to reduce risk. Yet Graham’s model would not impute this risk reduction to the liability rule. Moreover, MacKay (1991) argues that federal regulations of automobile design have forced all manufacturers toward a common standard, which undermines the attempt to derive a simple causal link between products liability and traffic accidents. Other studies have circumvented these data problems (and created others) by asking producers how their behavior has been influenced by liability. Eads and Reuter (1983) conducted interviews with nine large manufacturers, concluding that products liability significantly influences product-design decisions. Based on interviews with 101 senior-level corporate executives from the largest publicly held companies in the United States, Egon Zehnder
362
Products Liability
5140
International (1987) found that over half of these companies had added safety features as a result of liability concerns. About 20 percent of the companies chose not to introduce new products on account of products liability. Two other studies conducted by the Conference Board surveyed risk managers and CEOs of major corporations, finding that products liability concerns led to significant safety improvements while also causing a significant number of firms to discontinue product lines or not introduce new products (Weber, 1987; McGuire, 1988). The Egon Zehnder survey is probably the most reliable due to its excellent response rate; the Conference Board surveys had poor return rates and may have been influenced by a variety of biases (G. Schwartz, 1994a, pp. 408-410). A different approach to evaluating the effects of seller liability examines the impact of prominent products liability lawsuits on stock prices. Viscusi and Hersch (1990) find that news stories reporting on products liability suits significantly decrease a firm’s stock value. Similarly, Jarrell and Peltzman (1985) (criticized by Hoffer, Pruitt and Reilly, 1988) and Rubin, Murphy and Jarell (1988) find that safety-related administrative actions (product recalls) substantially reduce stock prices. In all of these studies, adverse publicity concerning product safety costs the firm more due to the reduced stock value than does the associated liability or recall costs. These findings suggest that firms suffer a loss of reputation when there is an adverse event (litigation or administrative action) pertaining to the safety of its product. As described earlier, a firm’s reputation for safety is important when consumers are not well-informed of product risk. These studies therefore indirectly confirm that individuals are not perfectly informed of product risks. Moreover, the loss in stock value gives firms an additional incentive to avoid products liability litigation, providing another reason for believing that seller liability increases safety.
12. The Impact of Tort Liability on Innovation The political debate regarding products liability reform in the US has often involved the claim that tort liability reduces innovation and consequently undermines the competitiveness of domestic products in a global economy. Although tort liability probably has reduced some types of innovation, the welfare effects of that reduction are unclear. Moreover, tort liability has also induced beneficial innovation, making it even more difficult to assess the net impact of tort liability on innovation. Tort liability can increase a producer’s cost, relative to a rule of no liability, by forcing the firm to increase its safety investments. Tort liability also requires that firms make disclosures in product warnings so that imperfectly informed consumers can better estimate accident costs (see Section 18 below). Insofar as tort liability increases safety investments and consumer estimates of accident
5140
Products Liability
363
costs, there is an increase the product’s full price. Consequently, tort liability is likely to encourage safety innovations much in the same way that other cost-driven price increases, such as those stemming from labor scarcity, induce innovation. An increase in cost enhances the profitability for the firm of any innovation which reduces that cost. The resultant increase in firm demand for such technical change should produce more innovation, a theory of technical change called ‘induced innovation’. This theory has substantial analytical and empirical support for innovations unrelated to product safety (Thirtle and Ruttan, 1987). There is no apparent reason why the theory is not also applicable to safety innovations. For example, an optimal research and development (R&D) program without a fixed budget will expend resources until the marginal cost of additional research equals the marginal benefit. The benefit depends on the potential cost savings from the research, savings that are increased as firms face increased tort liability. Expansions in tort liability therefore should increase R&D expenditures for safety technologies. This conclusion is consistent with the analytical results obtained by Daughety and Reinganum (1995), and the empirical study by Egon Zehnder International (1987) which found that over half of the surveyed companies had increased their R&D expenditures as a result of liability concerns. Insofar as the increased R&D expenditures have yielded more safety innovations, tort liability has promoted safety innovation. A liability rule that increases the product’s price can also have a negative effect on innovations unrelated to product safety. Assuming that the increased price reduces consumer demand, both theory (Binswanger, 1974) and historical evidence (Schmookler, 1966) indicate that the reduced profitability of the product line discourages innovation. But insofar as the change in demand reflects consumer response to a product price that more accurately reflects accident costs, the reduced innovation may be welfare enhancing. Viscusi and Moore (1991a, 1991b, 1993) study the effect of liability costs on innovation, finding that firms with new products have higher liability insurance costs. Econometric analysis shows that increased seller liability increases safety incentives, but at some point further increases in liability reduce innovation by making new products unprofitable (ibid., 1991b, 1993). One study (1993) shows that 10 industry groups were at or near this threshold in the mid-1980s, indicating that the incentive effects of seller liability vary across industries. This variable effect is confirmed by case studies of different industries regarding the impact of tort liability on innovation (Ashford and Stone, 1991; Craig, 1991; Graham, 1991; Johnson, 1991; Lasagna, 1991; Martin, 1991; Swazey, 1991). Products liability can also affect innovation due to its influence on the structure of business organization. If a firm suspects that a product may pose risks that are long term and likely to result in widespread injury, it has an incentive to avoid paying damages by divesting production tasks that involve
364
Products Liability
5140
such products. To insulate itself from legal liability, the parent company must divest early in the R&D stage. This dynamic is consistent with an empirical study of the US economy which found that increased seller liability appears to have increased the number of small corporations in hazardous sectors between 1967 and 1980 (Ringleb and Wiggins, 1990; see also Merolla, 1998). The cost of innovation for products involving such risks will be increased by the need to divest an operation that can more cost-effectively (absent liability concerns) be administered within a single organization. The increased cost in turn provides some disincentive for innovation.
13. The Relationship Between Tort Liability and the Market for Liability Insurance A report published by the US Attorney General’s Tort Policy Working Group concluded that increased tort liability was a major cause of the so-called ‘liability insurance crisis’ that occurred in the mid-1980s (US Department of Justice, 1986). The liability-insurance market was in turmoil during this period: premium revenues tripled and the supply of coverage severely contracted (Viscusi, 1991a). It is not evident why a contraction in the liability-insurance market would be caused by legally mandated expansions in seller liability, however, as expansions in tort liability should increase the demand for liability insurance. This conundrum has attracted much attention, leading to a number of different explanations for the liability-insurance crisis (surveyed in American Law Institute, 1991a, pp. 66-97). For our purposes, the most interesting finding to emerge from this literature pertains to the way in which legal uncertainty affects the cost of liability insurance. A standard liability-insurance policy covers a product seller’s legal liability for personal injury or property damage that ‘occurs’ to third parties during the policy year. Often a number of years pass before legal liability is incurred by the policyholder (who is then indemnified by the insurer). During the period between the issuance of the policy, manifestation of injury, and conclusion of the lawsuit, any changes in tort law may affect the costs the insurer will incur under the policy. Thus, in order to forecast its expected costs for a group of policies, a liability insurer needs to predict how tort standards, damage rules, and insurance law (like the interpretation of an ‘occurrence’) will change over time. In periods of legal stability, the insurer can be fairly confident about its predicted liability exposure. However, as Abraham (1987) and Trebilcock (1987) emphasize, there were various sources of legal uncertainty that liability insurers faced in the 1980s, making it difficult to predict the likelihood or magnitude of covered losses. In theory, this increased uncertainty increased the variance of the insurer’s expected loss and thus the cost of bearing that risk
5140
Products Liability
365
(Venezian, 1975). Empirical studies also show that legal uncertainty increases the cost of liability insurance. Kunreuther, Hogarth and Meszaros (1993) surveyed actuaries, underwriters and insurers, finding that they will add an additional cost above the expected value of loss when there is uncertainty (or ‘ambiguity’) regarding the probability or magnitude of the insured-against loss. Similarly, in an econometric study involving a large number of insurance policies issued during 1980-84, Viscusi (1993a) concludes that risk ambiguity tended to exert a positive influence on actual premium rates, controlling for the regulated rate. Winter (1991) provides a theoretical explanation for why this uncertainty can also affect the industry supply of liability insurance. It seems likely, then, that any increased legal uncertainty created by the tort system contributed to the liability-insurance crisis in the 1980s. In response to this and an earlier insurance crisis in the 1970s, a number of states enacted legislation limiting a seller’s tort liability. Most of these measures also reduced legal uncertainty (for example, by placing caps on the most unpredictable elements of damages). Viscusi (1990a) finds that both the profitability and availability of liability insurance were enhanced during 1980-84 by prior legislative reforms that limited firms’ liability. Viscusi et al. (1993) find that the reforms adopted by the states between 1985 and 1988 reduced liability costs and the premiums for liability insurance. This study also concludes that its findings are consistent with the possibility that the fact of comprehensive reform is more consequential than its components. One way to explain such an outcome is that the enactment of legislative reform reduces legal uncertainty by indicating that the legal climate is not hospitable to expanded tort liability for product sellers. In such a climate, liability insurers may be more confident that they will not be exposed to unanticipated expansions in legal liability, thereby reducing the cost of legal uncertainty that is built into premiums for liability insurance. But even if the reductions in seller liability mandated by these legislative reforms reduced liability costs and premiums, it does not follow that the reforms were efficient. Croley and Hanson (1991) argue that the rise in liability-insurance costs reflected a more efficient level of deterrence due to the internalization of costs that had been externalized prior to the expansion of seller tort liability. Indeed, due to the higher cost of third-party insurance, increased seller liability should have a pronounced effect on insurance costs. Moreover, because increased tort liability will decrease demand when consumers underestimate risks (see Sections 10 and 11 above), Manning’s (1996) empirical finding that tort liability reduced consumer demand for childhood vaccines does not necessarily establish, as he claims, that consumers place no value on this form of tort insurance. Instead, the relevant question for policy purposes is whether the increased insurance costs of tort liability, and any decline in consumer demand, are justified by a reduction in product risk.
366
Products Liability
5140
14. Introduction to the Economic Analysis of Products Liability Doctrines Depending on the issue involved, the current products liability regime in the US relies upon contracting, negligence, or strict liability to allocate liability for product-caused injuries. The prior analysis of the costs and benefits of these methods therefore can be used to analyze the efficiency properties of various products liability doctrines. Consequently, the ensuing discussion will delineate the role of contracting, negligence, and strict liability while raising a number of previously undiscussed considerations relevant to the economic analysis of products liability law. Epstein (1980) provides a more comprehensive overview of products liability law and discusses the economic implications of various doctrines. The American Law Institute (1991b) provides more extensive economic analysis of the main products liability doctrines. Although this focus on US law is limiting, the doctrines to be disscused have influenced the development of products liability laws in other countries, particulary the European Community and Japan.
15. The Focus of the Legal Inquiry and Its Implications for the Choice of Liability Rules Sellers are liable for their negligent conduct resulting in product-caused injuries. In the vast majority of states and the European Community, sellers are also liable for injuries caused by product ‘defects’. Although this rule is commonly called ‘strict products liability’, it is not the same as strict liability because liability depends upon the existence of a defect. In most states, defect is defined by reference to the product itself. As discussed in the ensuing sections, the choice between negligence and strict liability follows from the definition of defect and is not based on the efficiency properties of these tort rules. Other states and the European Community define defect by reference to consumer expectations. Although it is easier to give this approach an economic interpretation, it too does not rely upon efficiency considerations in making the choice between negligence and strict liability. More precisely, the consumer expectations test can operate like a rule of strict liability, since an optimally safe product is defective if it does not conform to consumer expectations. This outcome occurs when consumers underestimate risk, as products will always be more dangerous than consumers expect them to be. Conversely, when consumers are well-informed of product risk, the product always conforms to consumer expectations and consequently absolves the seller from tort liability. The consumer expectations test therefore limits tort liability to the cases in which it has the greatest potential to be
5140
Products Liability
367
efficiency-enhancing (when consumers underestimate risk), but it does not rely upon an economic rationale for its choice of strict liability over negligence.
16. Manufacturing Defects Manufacturing defects are physical deviations from a product’s intended design, thereby implicating the quality control of manufacturing and inspection processes. These processes usually cannot be made perfect, so some products containing manufacturing defects will reach the marketplace. Whenever such a defect causes physical injury, the seller is liable even if it employed the most efficient quality-control measures. Defining defect by reference to the product accordingly results in a rule of strict liability for these cases. Jurisdictions that rely on the consumer expectations test also employ strict liability for these cases by assuming that consumers do not expect a product to contain a manufacturing defect. Most agree that strict liability is the better rule for these cases. G. Schwartz (1979, pp. 459-462), for example, argues that most manufacturing defects are attributable to negligence, but it often will be difficult for plaintiffs to prove that the seller or one of its agents did not use appropriate quality-control measures. Thus, even though negligence in principle would eliminate tort liability whenever increased deterrence is not desirable - that is, when efficient quality-control measures already are being used - the benefit in these few cases is less than the costs that would be created for all cases if the plaintiff had to prove that the defect was caused by inadequate quality control. Strict liability may also be more efficient because it gives sellers a better incentive to foster advances in technology that reduce the incidence of manufacturing defects (Landes and Posner, 1985).
17. Design Defects A product that conforms to the manufacturer’s design specifications is defective if the design is defective. Unlike manufacturing defects, which can be determined by reference to deviations from product design, there is no readily available definition of design defect. Consequently, courts had to develop such a definition. Many jurisdictions define defect by reference to consumer expectations. This test, however, suffers from an inherent ambiguity. The inquiry could address consumer expectations of product risk. As previously noted, because consumers who underestimate risks will always find a product to be more dangerous than they expect, sellers are subjected to liability even if the product
368
Products Liability
5140
design satisfies the cost-benefit test. This logic explains the controversial result in Denny v. Ford Motor Company, and is consistent with the rule that consumer expectations justify holding sellers strictly liable for manufacturing defects. Alternatively, the inquiry could address consumer expectations of product safety. Consumers who underestimate risk ordinarily expect less safety than is contained in a product. For example, consumers who are unaware of risk expect there to be no safety investments, implying that any amount of product safety surpasses consumer expectations, even if the product is less safe than would be efficient. That consumer expectations tend to establish a safety standard below that of the cost-benefit test was recognized in the influential case Barker v. Lull Engineering Company. Whether consumer expectations should be defined by reference to risk or safety is an issue that can only be resolved by determining why consumer expectations matter, an issue that courts have not adequately addressed. The choice between risk and safety does not matter, though, for jurisdictions that define defectiveness by reference to reasonable consumer expectations. A reasonable consumer expects that sellers would reduce product risk in the most cost-effective manner. Hence a product design does not conform to consumer expectations only if the seller failed to take measures that efficiently reduce product risks. The consumer expectations test therefore can be turned into a negligence test for design defects. Note, though, that the logic needed to justify a negligence rule for design defects is inconsistent with the rationale for making sellers strictly liable for manufacturing defects, since reasonable consumers also expect that sellers ordinarily are unable to eliminate all manufacturing defects. The other approach for defining a design defect is based on the risk-utility test. The traditional formulation of this test is not limited to the factors relevant to the issue of whether the product design efficiently minimizes product risk (A. Schwartz, 1988; Viscusi, 1990b). However, the Restatement (Third) of Torts: Products Liability states that ‘the test is whether a reasonable alternative design would, at reasonable cost, have reduced the foreseeable risks of harm posed by the product, and if so, whether the omission of the alternative design ... rendered the product not reasonably safe’ (American Law Institute, 1997, p. 19). The risk-utility test therefore has evolved into a cost-benefit test. Because this test absolves sellers from liability (there is no defect) when the design efficiently minimizes risk, these cases, in effect, are governed by a negligence rule. The biggest problem with a negligence standard for design defects relates to the court’s ability to evaluate the technical engineering issues involved in product design (Henderson, 1973; A. Schwartz, 1988). An erroneous finding of design defect is particularly problematic, because tort liability potentially attaches to the entire product line. Consequently, any legal uncertainty in this area will have significant repercussions, suggesting that design-defect litigation
5140
Products Liability
369
has significantly influenced developments in the market for liability insurance (Viscusi, 1991b). Courts could avoid these difficult issues by defining defectiveness on the basis of relative safety, but that type of approach is unlikely to yield efficient outcomes (Boyd and Ingberman, 1997a). First consider a rule which holds that a product is not defectively designed if it conforms to industry custom. Because conformance to custom immunizes firms from tort liability, custom reflects market equilibria absent tort regulation. As such equilibria are often characterized by inefficiently low safety levels, adherence to custom is not ordinarily sufficient to establish that the product is properly designed (see Section 9 above). Now consider an alternative rule that defines a product as being defectively designed whenever a safer product is available on the market (‘state of the art’). A seller whose product is defective under this definition is fully liable for all injuries, so it usually minimizes costs by choosing the efficient amount of safety. The seller, however, could avoid liability altogether by increasing its safety investments above the efficient amount if doing so would make its product safer than others on the market. This liability rule therefore might give sellers an incentive to provide an inefficiently high amount of safety. Hence efficient safety levels ordinarily will not be obtained if courts determine defectiveness solely on the basis of relative safety considerations pertaining to custom or state of the art. The difficulty of determining whether a product is defectively designed has led the courts to limit the scope of tort liability for design defects. Usually courts are unwilling to consider whether a product is defective no matter how it is designed, recognizing that they cannot competently evaluate the total costs and benefits of a product except in the most extreme cases (Henderson and Twerski, 1991). For example, courts will not consider whether a subcompact car is defectively designed merely because larger (more expensive) cars are safer. Instead, design-defect litigation tends to involve modifications to existing product lines (like redesigning the gasoline tank in a subcompact car to reduce risk). Limiting the scope of tort liability in this manner allows the market to determine the viability of product lines (subcompact cars versus larger, safer cars), which enhances the likelihood that product lines can be varied to better satisfy consumers with different preferences. Under strict liability, by contrast, manufacturers make design choices by reference to the average consumer, thereby reducing the variety of product lines offered in the market and the likelihood that heterogeneous consumers can find products that closely match their preferences (Oi, 1973).
370
Products Liability
5140
18. Warning Defects A product can be defective because it does not adequately warn or instruct the consumer about product risks. As was true for design defects, the courts had to develop a definition for this type of defect, with most choosing to define warning defects in terms of a cost-benefit or risk-utility test. In principle, to satisfy this test the warning must provide the minimal amount of information necessary for the representative consumer to estimate the product’s full price, which can occur only if the warning increases the consumer’s information by describing unavoidable material risks and cost-effective methods of use that reduce risk (Geistfeld, 1997). Courts have recognized that warnings which satisfy these criteria are not defective and accordingly absolve the seller of liability, even if the warning did not disclose a risk that injured the plaintiff. The liability standard for warning defects therefore operates like a rule of negligence. By contrast, the consumer expectations test functions like a rule of strict liability for nondisclosed risks that are not sufficiently appreciated by the ordinary consumer. One implication of this approach is that the seller is liable even if the risk was not scientifically knowable at the time of sale. In order to make this and other cost-related considerations relevant to the liability determination, the test must adopt the expectations of a consumer who reasonably expects sellers to disclose risks whenever it would be cost-effective to do so. At present, the most problematic aspect of this form of tort liability relates to the cost of disclosure. A warning is defective if it does not disclose, sufficiently describe, or properly emphasize the risk which caused injury. Even if the benefit of a proposed warning alteration is slight, courts often find the warning to be defective on the ground that the cost of the requested disclosure is minimal or nonexistent (Henderson and Twerski, 1990). This is a mistake. Empirical studies have found that the amount and format of hazard information contained in a product warning affects consumers’ ability to recall the information, so that added disclosures can reduce the effectiveness of other disclosures in the warning (for example, Magat and Viscusi, 1992). Additional disclosures also increase the time consumers must spend to read warnings. Because these costs of disclosure are not sufficiently recognized by the courts, sellers have an incentive to disclose more than the optimal amount of risk information, thereby reducing the effectiveness of the warning for most consumers. For example, upon reading disclosures that offer little or no benefit, most consumers may rationally decide that the cost of reading the entire warning is not worth the effort. Some courts have recognized that the risk-utility test for warnings should account for information-processing costs. This position is taken by the Restatement (Third) of Torts: Products Liability (American Law Institute,
5140
Products Liability
371
1997, p. 32). Indeed, ignoring the way in which information costs affect consumer behavior is inconsistent with the various rules regarding an adequate warning (Geistfeld, 1997, p. 328). As virtually all jurisdictions have adopted these rules, there is ample precedent for courts to rely upon information costs when evaluating warnings. If they do, jury instructions can be formulated that would significantly improve the likelihood that jurors will properly evaluate warnings (ibid, pp. 329-37), although some argue that jurors and judges cannot competently evaluate information-processing costs (Latin, 1994, p. 1284). Another reason for believing that the warning doctrine is not currently producing efficient outcomes pertains to the method of disclosure. The most effective form of risk communication probably involves symbols and common formats (A. Schwartz, 1992; Viscusi, 1993b). The public-good nature of effective risk communication may require a regulatory rather than judicial solution. For this reason, strict liability is unlikely to result in efficient warnings, contrary to the argument of Croley and Hanson (1993). Cooter (1985) shows that strict liability may lead to inefficiently strong warnings because the manufacturer only considers how disclosure affects profits rather than social welfare. This result is hard to understand, however. For risks that are unavoidable or inherent in the product, disclosure will not reduce risk (or liability costs) unless it induces the buyer not to purchase the product. In some situations, disclosure would induce only high-risk buyers to opt out of the market, so the seller could reduce average liability costs by disclosing. But if disclosure does not reduce average liability costs, the seller has no incentive to disclose even when disclosure would be efficient. By contrast, when disclosure pertains to care that the consumer must exercise in order to reduce risk, the strictly liable seller has an incentive to disclose the efficient amount of information - that which minimizes average liability (injury) costs. Strict liability also gives sellers an incentive to discover the efficient amount of information (Shavell, 1992). But since sellers are liable for risks that were not scientifically knowable at the time of sale, strict liability could result in inefficient outcomes. Firms that otherwise are financially viable may be forced into bankruptcy by unanticipated liability costs that could not have been discovered by a cost-effective R&D program (A. Schwartz, 1985). Negligence avoids this problem, but different formulations of the negligence rule are possible and not all of them induce sellers to acquire the efficient amount of information (Shavell, 1992). And because plaintiffs often will have a hard time proving that a seller was negligent for not having discovered information, sellers apparently do not have a sufficient incentive to research product risk (Wagner, 1997).
372
Products Liability
5140
19. Defenses Based on Consumer Conduct In most states and the European Community, recovery is reduced for plaintiffs whose misuse of the product combined with the defect in causing the injury. Whether ‘comparative fault’ is less efficient than barring the plaintiff from recovery depends upon a variety of factors (Shavell, 1987, pp. 83-104), but it seems unlikely that comparative fault reduces the consumer’s incentive to use the product properly under ordinary circumstances. Survey evidence shows that for product-associated injuries that are serious but do not result in latent injuries, long-term institutionalization, or death, only 7 percent of victims in the US take action to initiate a liability claim if the injury did not occur at work, and 16 percent take action if the injury occurred at work (Hensler et al., 1991, p. 127). For the vast majority of cases, then, individuals do not expect to recover any damages from the seller, so comparative fault plays little, if any, role in the individual’s decision regarding product use. Denying recovery to those individuals who misused the product for other reasons, or due to inadvertence, would reduce the seller’s incentive to invest in product safety. This seems to be a large price to pay in exchange for the occasional benefit of denying recovery to those plaintiffs who intentionally misused the product because they expected to receive some compensation from the seller, particularly since the compensation that such individuals receive depends upon proof of defect and is likely to be substantially reduced by comparative fault principles. A more worrisome question is whether a product that is nondefective in normal use can become defective when misused. Many jurisdictions require sellers to design products to account for foreseeable misuse. Landes and Posner (1987, pp. 299-301) argue that this doctrine could be efficient if properly limited. Difficult issues also surround the defense of assumption of risk, which in some jurisdictions bars a plaintiff from recovering. The defense could be efficient if it limits seller liability to those cases in which consumers are not well-informed of risk. But merely because a consumer is aware of a risk does not imply that she is well-informed, particularly since perfect information involves an understanding of how different safety configurations affect risk (and price). Moreover, availability of the defense gives sellers an incentive to make design defects visible or to disclose the risk in the warning. Latin (1994) argues that warnings ordinarily are less effective at reducing risk than are design changes.
20. Nonmonetary Damages Plaintiffs can recover monetary damages for nonmonetary injuries such as pain and suffering. These damages may be inefficient. Nonmonetary injuries alter the individual’s utility function (the victim receives less utility for any given
5140
Products Liability
373
level of wealth following the accident), which can affect the marginal utility of wealth in different ways. These different effects are important, because an individual maximizes welfare by purchasing insurance (a transfer of money from the noninjured state to the contingent, injured state) until the marginal utility of wealth in the ‘injury’ and ‘no injury’ states of the world are equalized. For nonmonetary injuries that increase the marginal utility of wealth, individuals prefer a positive amount of insurance compensation. The insurance proceeds reduce the marginal utility of wealth in the injured state so that it equals the marginal utility of wealth in the noninjured state. But for injuries that decrease the marginal utility of wealth (like when the victim is comatose), negative insurance is efficient, as the individual would be better off by transferring money from the injured state (unconscious) to the noninjured state (healthy and conscious), where more utility can be derived from each dollar (Cook and Graham, 1977). Because consumers (potential victims) do not prefer to pay for insurance against these kind of injuries, fully compensatory tort awards for nonmonetary injuries may be inefficient. Survey evidence is consistent with this view (Calfee and Winston, 1993). Many point to pain-and-suffering damages as a primary source of inefficiency in the current system (for example, Danzon, 1984; Calfee and Rubin, 1992; A. Schwartz, 1988). One proposed remedy is to eliminate tort damages for nonmonetary injuries (thereby eliminating the insurance inefficiency) while requiring that firms pay a fine to the state equal to the amount needed for efficient deterrence (Shavell, 1987; Polinsky and Che, 1991). Eliminating pain-and-suffering damages within the current system is unlikely to be efficient, however. The absence of widespread first-party insurance for these injuries does not necessarily indicate a lack of consumer demand, but could stem from supply-side problems related to the cost of moral hazard and adverse selection (Croley and Hanson, 1995). Moreover, the analysis which shows that pain-and-suffering damages are inefficient unrealistically assumes that there is no deterrence value to the tort award; that consumers are optimally insured against all other tortiously caused injuries; and that sellers are forced to internalize the cost of all tortiously caused nonmonetary injuries. Revising the analysis to account for more realistic assumptions shows that pain-and-suffering tort damages in the current system could be efficient if courts were to instruct juries on how to calculate the appropriate award, which is based on consumer willingness to pay to eliminate the risk (Geistfeld, 1995b).
21. Punitive Damages Punitive damages have become a focal point in the debate over products liability reform in the United States, even though they are awarded infrequently
374
Products Liability
5140
(Daniels and Martin, 1990; Rustad, 1992). Punitive damages can be efficient when victims with valid legal claims do not sue, enabling sellers to escape liability in some cases (Cooter, 1989a). For example, if only 50 percent of all victims sue, compensatory damages must be doubled if the seller is to internalize the full cost of injury. Punitive damages can also be used to deter sellers from sending misleading signals of product quality (Daughety and Reinganum, 1997). The optimal adjustment to the compensatory damages award can be positive or negative, however, because it depends upon a variety of other factors such as the possibility of court error (Polinsky and Shavell, 1989), the impact of litigation costs on social welfare (Polinsky and Rubinfeld, 1988), insolvency (Knoll, 1997), and risk aversion (Craswell, 1996). It is doubtful that punitive damage awards are set on the basis of these economic considerations, as juries typically are given little or no instruction on how to compute the appropriate award. It is also doubtful that punitive damages are awarded when it would be efficient to do so (American Law Institute, 1991b, pp. 243-248). The legal standards governing the availability of punitive damage awards have been substantially, if not wholly, influenced by intentional torts (for which punitive damages were available under the early common law). These standards create problems in the products liability context, where the critical issue is not whether the manufacturer’s actions were deliberate (they usually are), but whether the manufacturer knew it was selling a defective product. By focusing on deliberate conduct rather than on the seller’s awareness of defect, the inquiry can easily lead to unwarranted punitive damages. If hindsight shows that the manufacturer erred in concluding that the cost of a safety improvement outweighed the benefit of risk reduction, then even if the manufacturer thought the product was optimally safe, the legal standard for punitive damages may be satisfied. In choosing not to decrease risk out of cost concerns, the manufacturer engaged in ‘wanton’ or ‘wilful’ conduct that ‘consciously disregards the rights or safety of others’. Any type of cost-benefit balancing involving the risk of injury therefore might be subjected to punitive damages, so manufacturers in design-defect cases often are unwilling to admit that they made safety decisions on the basis of cost considerations (G. Schwartz, 1991a). This is a perverse result given that the legal test for design defects relies on cost-benefit balancing, and indicates that the punitive damages standard undermines the accuracy of legal determinations of design defect.
22. The Enforceability of Contractual Waivers of Seller Liability Contract terms that disclaim a seller’s liability for product defects ordinarily are not enforceable unless the disclaimer pertains to cases in which a product damages itself, causing economic loss such as lost profits, but does not cause
5140
Products Liability
375
personal injury or damage to any other property. Contracting probably is a more efficient way to allocate these damages (‘economic losses’), because buyers have better control over and information regarding the magnitude of loss (Jones, 1990). Moreover, allowing sellers to disclaim liability for economic loss is unlikely to have significant deterrence effects, as the seller remains liable for any physical injury or property damage caused by the product defect. In some jurisdictions, sellers can also disclaim liability for physical loss if the buyer is a commercial party. These buyers tend to be sophisticated and knowledgeable about the consequences of risk allocation, so contracting in these situations is more likely to be efficient. A number of scholars argue that it would be efficient if courts were to enforce a greater variety of contractual limitations of seller liability (for example, Epstein, 1989; Rubin, 1993). But unless the contracting process is structured to give consumers risk-related information, these proposals raise the same safety-insurance tradeoff presented by any proposal to limit a seller’s tort liability. One way contracting can increase risk-related information is if the enforceability of a disclaimer is conditioned on the requirement that the seller provides a separate price quotation of its liability costs under a rule of strict liability. Such a price tells consumers something about the product’s safety and enables them to compare safety across brands (Geistfeld, 1988; A. Schwartz, 1988). Nevertheless, imperfectly informed consumers are still likely to disclaim seller liability when it would be inefficient to do so (Geistfeld, 1994). Giving consumers the opportunity to sell their ‘unmatured tort claims’ to third parties also has interesting possibilities (Cooter, 1989b; Choharis, 1995), although this reform may also lead to inefficient reductions in seller liability (A. Schwartz, 1989a). But even though these proposals do not resolve the regulatory problem, measures like them that enhance information and facilitate contracting are a promising approach to efficient reform (A. Schwartz, 1995).
23. Directions for Future Research It is commonplace to say that more empirical research is needed, but developments over the past decade provide a good opportunity for studying the relationship between tort liability and injury rates. Prior empirical studies of this issue suffer from the common problem of being unable to adequately define when seller liability expanded by an amount significant enough to be captured by statistical analysis. The evolutionary nature of common-law change makes such a definition elusive. The change in liability standards has been more abrupt since the mid-1980s, however, as the insurance crisis has spawned numerous reforms that limit seller liability. Because these widespread reforms occurred over a short period of time and were the result of legislative
376
Products Liability
5140
enactment, the timing of the change in liability can be readily defined, which should make it easier to uncover any statistical relationship between seller liability and injury rates. Regarding issues amenable to theoretical analysis, it would be useful to discover whether prices signal product safety under market conditions that are more realistic than those previously studied. A pressing issue concerns the relationship between liability and innovation, which relative to its importance is the most understudied aspect of products liability. There are also a number of products liability doctrines that have not been subjected to rigorous economic analysis. For example, an issue of present concern relates to the conditions under which suppliers of raw materials should be liable for injuries caused by the final product. Those who grapple with the issue have done so largely without the benefit of economic analysis, making it difficult to understand how lawmakers could place much reliance on efficiency considerations in deciding how to resolve the issue. Absent more widespread economic analysis of the range of doctrines that comprise products liability, it seems likely that efficiency considerations will continue to exert an uneven influence on the development of this area of the law.
Bibliography on Products Liability (5140) Abraham, Kenneth S. (1987), ‘Making Sense of the Liability Insurance Crisis’, 48 Ohio State Law Journal, 399-411. Abraham, Kenneth S. (1988), ‘The Causes of the Insurance Crisis’, in Olson, Walter (ed.), New Directions in Liability Law, New York, The Academy of Political Science, 54-66. Abraham, Kenneth S. (1990), ‘Products Liability Law and Insurance Profitability’,19 Journal of Legal Studies, 837-844. Adams, Michael (1987), ‘Ökonomische Analyse der Produkthaftung (Economic Analysis of Product Liability)’, 87 Der Betriebs-Berater. Adams, Michael (1987), ‘Produkthaftung - Wohltat oder Plage - Eine ökomische Analyse (Product Liability - Benefit or Plague - An Economic Analysis)’, 3124 Der Betriebs-Berater. Adams, Michael (1989), ‘Ökonomische Begründung des AGB-Gesetzes - Verträge bei asymetrischer Information (The Economic Basis of the German Unfair Contract Terms Law)’, Der Betriebs-Berater, 781-788. Adams, Michael (1995), ‘The Conflict of Jurisdictors - An Economic Analysis of Pretrial Discovery, Fact Gathering and Cost Allocation Rules in the United States and Germany’, 3(1) European Review of Private Law, 53-94. Akerlof, George A. (1970), ‘The Markets for ‘Lemons’: Qualitative Uncertainty and the Market Mechanism’, 84 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 488-500. Partially reprinted in Goldberg, Victor P. (ed.), Readings in the Economics of Contract Law, New York, Cambridge University Press. Allen, Franklin (1984), ‘Reputation and Product Quality’, 15 Rand Journal of Economics, 311-327.
5140
Products Liability
377
American Law Institute (1991a), Reporters’ Study, ‘Enterprise Liability for Personal Injury: Volume I, The Institutional Framework,’ Philadelphia, The American Law Institute. American Law Institute (1991b), Reporters’ Study, ‘Enterprise Liability for Personal Injury: Volume II, Approaches to Legal and Institutional Change’, Philadelphia, The American Law Institute. American Law Institute (1997), Restatement of the Law (Third) of Torts: Products Liability, Philadelphia, The American Law Institute. Arlen, Jennifer H. (1992), ‘Book Review: W. Kip Viscusi, Reforming Products Liability’, 30 Journal of Economic Literature, 2170 ff. Arlen, Jennifer H. (1993), ‘Compensation Systems and Efficient Deterrence’, 52 Maryland Law Review, 1093 ff. Armstrong, Dwight L. (1976), ‘Products Liability, Comparative Negligence and the Allocation of Damages among Multiple Defendants’, 50 Southern California Law Review, 73-108. Arrow, Kenneth J. (1971), Essays in the Theory of Risk Bearing, Chicago, Markham. Arrow, Kenneth J. (1982), ‘Risk Perception in Psychology and Economics’, 20 Economic Inquiry, 1-9. Ashford, Nicholas A. and Stone, Robert F. (1991), The Liability Maze: The Impact of Liability Law on Safety and Innovation, Washington, DC, The Brookings Institution. Attanasio, John B. (1988), ‘The Principle of Aggregate Autonomy and the Calabresian Approach to Products Liability’, 74 Virginia Law Review, 677-750. Ausness, Richard C. (1997), ‘An Insurance-Based Compensation System for Product-Related Injuries’, 58 University of Pittsburg Law Review, 669-717. Bagwell, Kyle and Riordan, Michael H. (1991), ‘High and Declining Prices Signal Product Quality’, 81 American Economic Review, 224-239. Barker, Drucilla K. (1991), ‘An Empirical Analysis of the Effects of Product Liability Laws on Underwriting Risk’, 51 Journal of Risk and Insurance, 63 ff. Beales, J. Howard, III, Craswell, Richard and Salop, Steven C. (1981), ‘The Efficient Regulation of Consumer Information’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 491-539. Beales, J. Howard, III, Craswell, Richard and Salop, Steven C. (1981), ‘Information Remedies for Consumer Protection’, 71 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 410-413. Becker, Gary S. and Ehrlich, Isaac (1972), ‘Market Insurance, Self-insurance, and Self-protection’, 80 Journal of Political Economy, 623-648. Bell, John W. (1977), ‘Averting a Crisis in Product Liability : An Evolutionary Process of Socioeconomic Justice’, 65 Illinois Bar Journal, 640-648. Bell, Peter A. (1990), ‘Analyzing Tort Law: The Flawed Promise of Neocontract’, 74 Minnesota Law Review, 1177-1249. Ben-Shahar, Omri (1997), ‘Should Products Liability be Based on Hindsight?’, Working Paper No. 14-97, The Foerder Institute for Economic Research, Tel Aviv University.. Benson, Bruce L. (1996), ‘Uncertainty, the Race for Property Rights, and Rent Dissipation due to Judicial Changes in Product Liability Tort Law’, Cultural Dynamics. Blight, Catherine (1989), ‘’What if that Snail had been in a Bottle of Milk?’ or Product Liability in the UK - the Special Case of Agricultural Products’, in Faure, Michael and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds), Essays in Law and Economics: Corporations, Accident Prevention and Compensation for Losses, Antwerpen, Maklu, 215-232.
378
Products Liability
5140
Bonney, Paul R. (1985), ‘Manufacturers’ Strict Liability for Handgun Injuries: An Economic Analysis’, 73 Georgetown Law Journal, 1437-1463. Boyd, James and Ingberman, Daniel E. (1994), ‘Extending Liability: Should the Sins of the Producer Be Visited Upon Others?’, Business, Law, and Economics Center Working Paper BLE. Boyd, James and Ingberman, Daniel E. (1994), ‘Noncompensatory Damages and Potential Insolvency’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 895-910. Boyd, James and Ingberman, Daniel E. (1997a), ‘Should ‘Relative Safety’ be a Test of Product Liability?’, 26 Journal of Legal Studies, 433-473. Boyd, James and Ingberman, Daniel E. (1997b), ‘The Search for Deep Pockets: Is ‘Extended Liability’ Expensive Liability?’, 13 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 232-258. Brown, John Prather (1974), ‘Product Liability: The Case of an Asset with Random Life’, 64 American Economic Review, 149-161. Brüggemeier, Gert (1989), ‘Die Gefährdungshaftung der Produzenten nach der EG-Richtlinie - ein Fortschritt der Rechtsentwicklung? (Strict Liability of Producers According to the EC-Regulation A Directive of Legal Evolution)’, in Ott, Claus and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (eds),Allokationseffizienz in der Rechtsordnung, Berlin, Springer-Verlag, 228-247. Bryant, W. Keith and Gerner, Jennifer L. (1978), ‘The Price of a Warranty: The Case for Refrigerators’, 12 Journal of Consumer Affairs, 30-47. Buchanan, James M. (1970), ‘In Defense of Caveat Emptor’, 38 University of Chicago Law Review, 64-73. Burrows, Paul (1992), ‘Consumer Safety under Products Liability and Duty to Disclose’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 457-478. Burrows, Paul (1994), ‘Products Liability and the Control of Product Risk in the European Community’, 10 Oxford Review of Economic Policy, 68-83. Butters, Gerard R. (1986), ‘The Impact of Product Recalls on the Wealth of Sellers: Comments’, in Ippolito, Pauline M. and Scheffman, David T. (eds), Empirical Approaches to Consumer Protection Economics, Washington, DC, Federal Trade Commission, 411-413. Calabresi, Guido (1984), ‘First Party, Third Party, and Product Liability Systems: Can Economic Analysis of Law Tell Us Anything About Them?’, 69 Iowa Law Review, 833-851. Calabresi, Guido and Bass, Kenneth C. II (1970), ‘Right Approach, Wrong Implications: A Critique of McKean on Products Liability’, 38 University of Chicago Law Review, 74-91. Calabresi, Guido and Hirschoff, Jon T. (1972), ‘Toward a Test for Strict Liability in Tort’, 81 Yale Law Journal, 1054-1085. Reprinted in Rabin, Robert L. (ed.) (1983), Perspectives on Tort Law, Boston, Little Brown, 192-212. Calfee, John E. and Rubin, Paul H. (1992), ‘Some Implications of Damage Payments for Nonpecuniary Losses’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 371-411. Calfee, John E. and Winston, Clifford (1988), ‘Economic Aspects of Liability Rules and Liability Insurance’, in Litan, Robert E. and Winston, Clifford (eds), Liability: Perspectives and Policy, Washington, DC, The Brookings Institution, 16-41. Calfee, John E. and Winston, Clifford (1993), ‘The Consumer Welfare Effects of Liability for Pain and Suffering: An Exploratory Analysis’, 1 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity: Microeconomics, 133-196.
5140
Products Liability
379
Camerer, Colin F. and Kunreuther, Howard (1993), ‘Making Decisions About Liability and Insurance: Editors’ Comments’, 7 Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5-15. Cass, Ronald A. and Gillette, Clayton P. (1991), ‘The Government Contractor Defense: Contractual Allocation of Public Risk’, 77 Virginia Law Review, 257-336. Caves, R.E. and Greene, D.P. (1996), ‘Brands’ Quality Levels, Prices, and Advertising Outlays: Empirical Evidence on Signals and Information Costs’, 14 International Journal of Industrial Organization, 29-52. Centner, Terence J. (1992), ‘The New ‘Tractor Lemon Laws’: An Attempt to Squeeze Manufacturers Draws Sour Benefits’, 14 Journal of Products Liability, 121-137. Centner, Terence J. (1993), ‘Separating Lemons: Automobiles and Tractors under the “Motor Vehicle Warranty Rights Act” and the “Farm Tractor Warranty Act”’, 30 Georgia State Bar Journal, 36-43. Centner, Terence J. (1995), ‘Lemon Laws: Sour Options for Consumers of Farm Tractors’, 18 Hamline Law Review, 347-362. Centner, Terence J. and Wetzstein, Michael E. (1995), ‘Obligations and Penalties under Lemon Laws: Automobiles Versus Tractors’, 20 Journal of Agricultural and Resource Economics, 135-145. Chan, Yuk-Shee and Leland, Hayne E. (1982), ‘Prices and Qualities in Markets with Costly Information’, 49 Review of Economic Studies, 499-516. Chapman, Kenneth and Meurer, Michael J. (1989), ‘Efficient Remedies for Breach of Warranty’, 52(1) Law and Contemporary Problems, 107-131. Choharis, Peter Charles (1995), ‘A Comprehensive Market Strategy for Tort Reform’, 12 Yale Journal on Regulation, 435-525. Coleman, Jules L. (1992), Risks and Wrongs, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Cook, Philip J. and Graham, Daniel A. (1977), ‘The Demand for Insurance and Protection: The Case of Irreplaceable Commodities’, 91 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 143-156. Cooper, Russell and Ross, Thomas W. (1984), ‘Prices, Product Qualities and Asymmetric Information: the Competitive Case’, 51 Review of Economic Studies, 197-208. Cooper, Russell and Ross, Thomas W. (1985a), ‘Product Warranties and Double Moral Hazard’, 16 Rand Journal of Economics, 103-113. Cooper, Russell and Ross, Thomas W. (1985b), ‘Monopoly Provision of Product Quality with Uninformed Buyers’, 3 International Journal of Industrial Organization, 433-449. Cooter, Robert D. (1985), ‘Defective Warnings, Remote Causes, and Bankruptcy: Comment on Schwartz’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 737-750. Cooter, Robert D. (1989a), ‘Punitive Damages for Deterrence: When and How Much?’, 40 Alabama Law Review, 1143 ff. Cooter, Robert D. (1989b), ‘Towards a Market in Unmatured Tort Claims’, 75 University of Virginia Law Review, 383-411. Cooter, Robert D. (1991), ‘Economic Theories of Legal Liability (Italian translation:’Le Teorie Economiche della Risponsibilità Efficenza Produttiva: Alcuni Contributi su Noti Argomenti’ 379-409)’, 5 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 11-30. Reprinted in Medema, Steven G. (ed.), The Legacy of Ronald Coase in Economic Analysis, Cheltenham, Edward Elgar Publishing, forthcoming. Italian translation: ‘Le Teorie Economiche Della Risponsabilit Legale’, published in Gianandrea Goisis. Cooter, Robert D. and Sugarman, Stephen D. (1988), ‘A Regulated Market in Unmatured Tort Claims: Tort Reform by Contract’, in Olson, Walter (ed.), New Directions in Liability Law, New York, The Academy of Political Science, 174-185.
380
Products Liability
5140
Cooter, Robert D. and Ulen, Thomas S. (1988), Law and Economics, Glenview, IL, Scott, Foresman and Company. Cosentino, Fabrizio (1989), ‘Responsabilità da Prodotto Difettoso: Appunti di Analisi Economica del Diritto (nota a U.S. Supreme Court California, 31 marzo 1988, Brown c. Abbott Laboratories) (Liability for Defective Products: An Economic Analysis of Law)’, 4 Foro Italiano, 137-143. Courville, Léon and Hausman, Warren H. (1979), ‘Warranty Scope and Reliability under Imperfect Information and Alternative Market Structures’, 52 Journal of Business, 361-378. Cousy, Herman (1976), ‘Produktenaansprakelijkheid. Proeve van een Juridisch-Economische Analyse (Product Liability. Attempt of a Legal-Economic Analysis)’, Tijdschrift voor Privaatrecht, 995-1035. Craig, Andrew (1991), ‘Product Liability and Safety in General Aviation’, in Huber, Peter W. and Litan, Robert E. (eds), The Liability Maze: The Impact of Liability Law on Safety and Innovation, Washington, DC, The Brookings Institution, 456-477. Craswell, Richard (1991), ‘Passing on the Costs of Legal Rules: Efficiency and Distribution in Buyer-Seller Relationships’, 43 Stanford Law Review, 361-398. Craswell, Richard (1996), ‘Damage Multipliers in Market Relationships’, 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 463-492. Croley, Steven P. and Hanson, Jon D. (1991), ‘What Liability Crisis? An Alternative Explanation for Recent Events in Products Liability’, 8 Yale Journal on Regulation, 1-111. Croley, Steven P. and Hanson, Jon D. (1993), ‘Rescuing the Revolution: The Revived Case for Enterprise Liability’, 91 Michigan Law Review, 683-797. Croley, Steven P. and Hanson, Jon D. (1995), ‘The Nonpecuniary Costs of Accidents: Pain and-Suffering Damages in Tort Law’, 108 Harvard Law Review, 1785-1917. Curran, Christopher (1992), ‘The Spread of Comparative Negligence in the United States’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 317-332. Daniels, Stephen and Martin, Joanne (1990), ‘Myth and Reality in Punitive Damages’, 75 Minnesota Law Review, 1-64. Danzon, Patricia M. (1984), ‘Tort Reform and the Role of Governement in Private Insurance Markets’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 517-549. Danzon, Patricia M. (1985), ‘Comments on Landes and Posner: A Positive Economic Analysis of Products Liability’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 569-583. Danzon, Patricia M. (1988), ‘The Political Economy of Workers’ Compensation: Lessons for Product Liability’, 78 American Economic Review: Papers and Proceedings, 305-310. Daughety, Andrew F. and Reinganum, Jennifer F. (1995), ‘Product Safety: Liability, R&D, and Signaling’, 85 American Economic Review, 1187-1206. Daughety, Andrew F. and Reinganum, Jennifer F. (1997), ‘Everybody Out of the Pool: Products Liability, Punitive Damages, and Competition’, 13 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 410-432. De Alessi, Louis (1994), ‘Reputation and the Efficiency of Legal Rules’, 14 Cato Journal, 11-21. De Alessi, Louis and Staaf, Robert J. (1987), ‘Liability, Control and the Organization of Economic Activity’, 7 International Review of Law and Economics, 5-20. Dewees, Donald N., Duff, David and Trebilcock, Michael J. (1996), Exploring the Domain of
5140
Products Liability
381
Accident Law: Taking the Facts Seriously, New York, Oxford University Press. Dorfman, Robert (1970), ‘The Economics of Product Liability: A Reaction to McKean’, 38 University of Chicago Law Review, 92-102. Dungworth, Terence (1988), Product Liability and the Business Sector: Litigation Trends in Federal Courts, Santa Monica, CA, Institute for Civil Justice, Rand Corporation. Eads, George C. and Reuter, Peter (1983), Designing Safer Products: Corporate Reponses to Product Liability Law and Regulation, Santa Monica, CA, Institute for Civil Justice, Rand Corporation. Egon Zehnder International (1987), ‘The Litigious Society: Is It Hampering Creativity, Innovation, and Our Ability to Compete?’, 2(3) Corporate Issues Monitor, 1 ff. Eisman, Deborah E. (1983), ‘Product Liability: Who Should Bear the Burden?’, 27 American Economist, 54-57. Emons, Winand (1988), ‘Warranties, Moral Hazard, and the Lemons Problem’, 46 Journal of Economic Theory, 16-33. Emons, Winand (1990), ‘Some Recent Developments in the Economic Analysis of Liability Law: An Introduction’, 146 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 237-248. Epple, Dennis and Raviv, Artur (1978), ‘Product Safety: Liability Rules, Market Structure, and Imperfect Information’, 68 American Economic Review, 80-95. Epstein, Richard A. (1980), Modern Product Liability Law, Westport, Quorum Books, 211p. Epstein, Richard A. (1984), ‘The Legal and Insurance Dynamics of Mass Tort Litigation’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 475-506. Epstein, Richard A. (1985), ‘Products Liability as an Insurance Market’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 645-669. Epstein, Richard A. (1986), ‘The Temporal Dimension in Tort Law’, 53 University of Chicago Law Review, 1175-1218. Epstein, Richard A. (1987), ‘The Risks of Risk/Utility’, 48 Ohio State Law Journal, 469-477. Epstein, Richard A. (1988), ‘The Political Economy of Product Liability Reform’, 78 American Economic Review: Papers and Proceedings, 311-315. Epstein, Richard A. (1989), ‘The Unintended Revolution in Product Liability Law’, 10 Cardozo Law Review, 2193-2222. Faure, Michael G. (1986), ‘Commentaar bij de paper van Dr. Jan C. Bongaerts: Coase en Produktenaansprakelijkheid (Comment on the paper of Dr. Jan C. Bongaerts: Coase Products Liability)’, in Van den Bergh, Roger (ed.), Verslagboek Eerste Werkvergadering Recht en Economie, Antwerpen, Handelshogeschool, 31-37. Faure, Michael G. and Van Buggenhout, Willy (1987), ‘Produktenaan sprakelijkheid. De Europese Richtlijn: Harmonisatie en Consumentenbescherming? (The European Directive Concerning Product Liability, Harmonization and Consumer Protection?)’,51 Rechtskundig Weekblad, 33-88. Finsinger, Jörg (1991), ‘The Choice of Risky Technologies and Liability’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 11-22. Finsinger, Jörg, Hoehn, T. and Pototschnig, A. (1991), ‘The Enforcement of Product Liability Rules: A Two-Country Analysis of Court Cases’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 133-148. Finsinger, Jörg and Simon, Jürgen (1988), Eine ökonomische Bewertung der EG-Produkthaftung (An
382
Products Liability
5140
Economic Appreciation of the EC Product Liability Rules), Lüneburg, Arbeitsbericht Hochschule Lüneburg, Fachbereich Wirtschafts- und Sozialwissenschaften, 44 ff. Finsinger, Jörg and Simon, Jürgen (1989), ‘An Economic Assessment of the EC Product Liability Directive and the Product Liability Law of the Federal Republic of Germany’, in Faure, Michael and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds), Essays in Law and Economics: Corporations, Accident Prevention and Compensation for Losses, Antwerpen, Maklu, 185-214. Fischoff, Baruch and Merz, Jon F. (1994), ‘The Inconvenient Public: Behavioral Research Approaches to Reducing Product Liability Risks’, in Hunziker, Janet R. and Jones, Trevor O. (eds), Product Liability and Innovation: Managing Risk in an Uncertain Environment. Gal-Or, Esther (1989), ‘Warranties as a Signal of Quality’, 22 Canadian Journal of Economics, 50-61. Galitsky, S. (1979), ‘Manufacturers’ Liability: An Examination of the Policy and Social Cost of a New Regime’, 3 University of New South Wales Law Journal, 145-174. Geistfeld, Mark (1988), ‘Note: Imperfect Information, the Pricing Mechanism, and Products Liability’, 88 Columbia Law Review, 1057-1068. Geistfeld, Mark (1992), ‘Implementing Enterprise Liability: A Comment on Henderson and Twerski’, 67 New York University Law Review, 1157 ff. Geistfeld, Mark (1994), ‘The Political Economy of Neocontractual Proposals for Products Liability Reform’, 72 Texas Law Review, 803-847. Geistfeld, Mark (1995a), ‘Manufacturer Moral Hazard and the Tort Contract Issue in Products Liability’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 241-257. Geistfeld, Mark (1995b), ‘Placing a Price on Pain and Suffering: A Method for Helping Juries Determine Tort Damages for Nonmonetary Injuries’, 83 California Law Review, 773-852. Geistfeld, Mark (1997), ‘Inadequate Product Warnings and Causation’, 30 University of Michigan Journal of Law Reform, 309-351. Gerner, Jennifer L. and Bryant, W. Keith (1981), ‘Appliance Warranties as a Market Signal?’, 15 Journal of Consumer Affairs, 75-86. Gilmore, Grant (1970), ‘Products Liability: A Commentary’, 38 University of Chicago Law Review, 103-116. Goldberg, Victor P. (1974), ‘The Economics of Product Safety and Imperfect Information’, 5 Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, 683-688. Goldberg, Victor P. (1988), ‘Accountable Accountants: Is Third-Party Liability Necessary?’, 17 Journal of Legal Studies, 295-312. Graham, Daniel A. and Price, Ellen R. (1984), ‘Contingent Damages for Products Liability’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 441-468. Graham, John D. (1991), ‘Product Liability and Motor Vehicle Safety’, in Huber, Peter W. and Litan, Robert E. (eds), The Liability Maze: The Impact of Liability Law on Safety and Innovation, Washington, DC, The Brookings Institution, 120-190. Grether, David M., Schwartz, Alan and Wilde, Louis L. (1986), ‘The Irrelevance of Information Overload: An Analysis of Search and Disclosure’, 59 Southern California Law Review, 277-303. Grether, David M., Schwartz, Alan and Wilde, Louis L. (1988), ‘Uncertainty and Shopping Behavior: An Experimental Analysis’, 55 Review of Economic Studies, 323-342. Grether, David M., Schwartz, Alan and Wilde, Louis L. (1992), ‘Price, Quality and Timing of Moves
5140
Products Liability
383
in Markets with Incomplete Information: An Experimental Analysis’, 102 Economic Journal, 754-771. Grossman, Sanford J. (1981), ‘The Informational Role of Warranties and Private Disclosure about Product Quality’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 461-483. Gupta, Pola and Ratchford, Brian T. (1992), ‘Estimating the Efficiency of Consumer Choices of New Automobiles’, 13 Journal of Economic Psychology, 375-397. Hamada, Koichi (1976), ‘Liability Rules and Income Distribution in Products Liability’, 66 American Economic Review, 228-234. Hamada, Koichi (1995), ‘Product Liability Rules: A Consideration of Law and Economics in Japan’, 46 Japanese Economic Review, 2-22. Hamada, Koichi, Ishida, Hidetoh and Murakami, Masahiro (1986), ‘The Evolution and Economic Consequences of Product Liability Rules in Japan’, in Saxonhouse, Gary R. and Yamamura, Kozo (eds), Law and Trade Issues of the Japanese Economy: Amer, Seattle, University of Washington Press, 83-106. Hammitt, James K., Carroll, Stephen J. and Relles, Daniel A. (1985), ‘Tort Standards and Jury Decisions’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 751-762. Hanson, Jon D. and Logue, Kyle D. (1990), ‘The First-Party Insurance Externality: An Economic Justification for Enterprise Liability’, 76 Cornell Law Review, 129-196. Harrington, Scott E. (1988), ‘Prices and Profits in the Liability Insurance Market’, in Litan, Robert E. and Winston, Clifford (eds), Liability: Perspectives and Policy, Washington, DC, The Brookings Institution, 42-100. Harrington, Scott E. (1991), ‘Liability Insurance: Volatility in Prices and in the Availability of Coverage’, in Schuck, Peter H. (ed.), Tort Law and the Public Interest: Competition, Innovation, and Consumer Welfare, New York, W.W. Norton & Co., 47-79. Hay, Bruce L. (1992), ‘Conflicts of Law and State Competition in the Product Liability System’, 80 Georgetown Law Journal, 617-652. Heal, Geoffrey M. (1977), ‘Guarantees and Risk Sharing’, 44 Review of Economic Studies, 549-560. Heinkel, R. (1981), ‘Uncertain Product Quality: the Market for Lemons with an Imperfect Testing Technology’, 12 Bell Journal of Economics, 625-636. Henderson, James A. (1973), ‘Judicial Review of Manufacturer’s Conscious Design Choices: The Limits of Adjudication’, 73 Columbia Law Review, 1531 ff. Henderson, James A. (1980), ‘Extending the Boundaries of Strict Products Liability: Implications of the Theory of Second Best’, 128 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1036-1093. Henderson, James A. (1983), ‘Product Liability and the Passage of Time: The Imprisonment of Corporate Rationality’, 58 New York University Law Review, 765-795. Henderson, James A. (1991), ‘Judicial Reliance on Public Policy: An Empirical Analysis’, 59 George Washington Law Review, 1570 ff. Henderson, James A. and Twerski, Aaron D. (1990), ‘Doctrinal Collapse in Products Liability: The Empty Shell of Failure to Warn’, 65 New York University Law Review, 265-327. Henderson, James A. and Twerski, Aaron D. (1991), ‘Closing the American Products Liability Frontier: The Rejection of Liability Without Fault’, 66 New York University Law Review, 1263-1331. Hensler, Deborah R., Marquis, M. Susan, Abrahamse, Allan F., Berry, Sandra H., Ebener, Patricia A., Lewis, Elizabeth G., Lind, E. Allan, Maccoun, Robert J., Manning, Willard G., Rogowski,
384
Products Liability
5140
Jeannette A. and Vaiana, Mary E. (1991), Compensation for Accidental Injuries in the United States, Santa Monica, CA, Institute for Civil Justice, Rand Corporation. Higgins, Richard S. (1978), ‘Producers’ Liability and Product Related Accidents’, 7 Journal of Legal Studies, 299-321. Higgins, Richard S. (1981), ‘Products Liability Insurance, Moral Hazard, and Contributory Negligence’, 10 Journal of Legal Studies, 111-130. Hoffer, George E., Pruitt, Stephen W. and Reilly, Robert J. (1988), ‘The Impact of Product Recalls on the Wealth of Sellers: A Reexamination’, 96 Journal of Political Economy, 663-670. Holmström, Bengt (1979), ‘Moral Hazard and Observability’, 10 Bell Journal of Economics, 74-91. Horvitz, Sigmund A. and Stern, Louis H. (1987), ‘Liability Rules and the Selection of a Socially Optimal Production Technology’, 7 International Review of Law and Economics, 121-126. Huber, Peter W. (1986), ‘Safety and the Second Best: The Hazards of Public Risk Management in the Courts’, 85 Columbia Law Review, 277-337. Huber, Peter W. (1988), Liability: The Legal Revolution and Its Consequences, New York, Basic Books, 260 p. Huber, Peter W. (1992), ‘Liability and Insurance Problems in the Commercialization of New Products: A Perspective from the United States and England’, in Rosenbergh, Nathan, Landau, Ralph and Mowery, David C. (eds), Technology and the Wealth of Nations, Stanford, Stanford University Press, 207-221. Huber, Peter W. and Litan, Robert E. (1991), ‘Overview’, in Huber, Peter W. and Litan, Robert E. (eds), The Liability Maze: The Impact of Liability Law on Safety and Innovation, Washington, DC, The Brookings Institution, 1-27. Hylton, Keith (1990), ‘Costly Litigation and Legal Error Under Negligence’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 433 ff. Inter-Agency Task Force on Products Liability (1977), Report, Washington, DC, United States Department of Commerce. Jarrell, Gregg A. and Peltzman, Sam (1985), ‘The Impact of Product Recalls on the Wealth of Sellers’, 93 Journal of Political Economy, 512-536. Reprinted in Ippolito, Pauline M. and Scheffman, David T. (eds), Empirical Approaches to Consumer Protection Economics, Washington, DC, Federal Trade Commission, 377-409. Johnson, Rollin B. (1991), ‘The Impact of Liability on Innovation in the Chemical Industry’, in Huber, Peter W. and Litan, Robert E. (eds), The Liability Maze: The Impact of Liability Law on Safety and Innovation, Washington, DC, The Brookings Institution, 428-455. Jones, P. and Hudson, J. (1996), ‘Signalling Product Quality: When is Price Relevant?’, 30 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 257-66. Jones, William K. (1990), ‘Product Defects Causing Commercial Loss: The Ascendency of Contract Over Tort’, 44 University of Miami Law Review, 731-806. Kahneman, Daniel and Tversky, Amos (1979), ‘Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision Under Risk’, 47 Econometrica, 160-173. Kahneman, Daniel, Slovic, Paul and Tversky, Amos (1982), Judgment and Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Kambhu, John (1982), ‘Optimal Product Quality under Asymmetric Information and Moral Hazard’,
5140
Products Liability
385
Bell Journal of Economics, 483-492. Kaprelian, Mark A. (1985), ‘Privity Revisited: Tort Recovery by a Commercial Buyer for a Defective Product’s Self-Inflicted Damage’, 84 Michigan Law Review, 517-540. Keenan, Donald C. and Rubin, Paul H. (1988), ‘Shadow Interest Groups and Safety Regulation’, 8 International Review of Law and Economics, 21-36. Keeton, W. Page, Owen, David, Montgomery, John E. and Green, Michael D. (1989), Products Liability and Safety: Cases and Materials (2nd edn), Mineola, NY, Foundation Press. Kinkaid, Peter M. and Stuntz, William J. (1983), ‘Note: Enforcing Waivers in Products Liability’, 69 Virginia Law Review, 1111-1152. Kirchner, Christian (1989), ‘Kommentar (Comment On Brüggemeier)’, in Ott, Claus and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (eds), Allekationseffizienz in der Rechtsordnung, Berlin, Springer-Verlag, 248-253. Kitch, Edmund W. (1988), ‘American Law and Preventive Vaccination Programs’, in Plotkin, Stanley A. and Mortimer, Edward A. (eds), Vaccines, Philadelphia, W.B. Saunders Company, 612 ff. Kitch, Edmund W. and Mortimer, Edward A., Jr (1994), ‘American Law, Preventive Vaccine Programs, and the National Vaccine Injury Compensation Program’, in Plotkin, Stanley A. and Mortimer, Edward A. (eds), Vaccines, Philadelphia, W.B. Saunders Company, 93 ff. Klein, Benjamin and Leffler, Keith B. (1981), ‘The Role of Market Forces in Assuring Contractual Performance’, 89 Journal of Political Economy, 615-641. Knoll, Michael S. (1997), ‘Products Liability and Legal Leverage: The Perverse Effect of Stiff Penalties’, 45 UCLA Law Review, 99-141. Kolstad, Charles D., Ulen, Thomas S. and Johnson, Gary V. (1990), ‘Ex Post Liability for Harm vs. Ex Ante Safety Regulation: Substitutes or Complements?’, 80 American Economic Review, 888-901. Komesar, Neil K. (1990), ‘Injuries and Institutions: Tort Reform, Tort Theory, and Beyond’, 65 New York University Law Review, 23-77. Kunreuther, Howard, Hogarth, Robin M. and Meszaros, Jacqueline (1993), ‘Insurer Ambiguity and Market Failure’, 7 Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 71-88. Lacey, N.J. (1988), ‘Recent Evidence on the Liability Crisis’, 55 Journal of Risk and Insurance, 499-508. Lamken, Jeffrey A. (1989), ‘Note: Efficient Accident Prevention as a Continuing Obligation: The Duty to Recall Defective Products’, 42 Stanford Law Review, 103 ff. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1984), ‘Tort Law as a Regulatory Regime for Catastrophic Personal Injuries’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 417-434. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1985), ‘A Positive Economic Analysis of Products Liability’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 535-567. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1986), ‘New Light on Punitive Damages’, 10(1) Regulation, 33-36. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1987), The Economic Structure of Tort Law, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 330 p. Larsen, Kim D. (1984), ‘Note: Strict Products Liability and the Risk-Utility Test for Design Defect: An Economic Analysis’, 84 Columbia Law Review, 2045-2067. Lasagna, Louis (1991), ‘The Chilling Effect of Product Liability on New Drug Development’, in Huber, Peter W. and Litan, Robert E. (eds), The Liability Maze: The Impact of Liability Law on
386
Products Liability
5140
Safety and Innovation, Washington, DC, The Brookings Institution, 334-359. Latin, Howard (1994), ‘’Good’ Warnings, Bad Products, and Cognitive Limitations’, 41 UCLA Law Review, 1193-1295. Lawrence, William H. and Minon, John H. (1984), ‘The Effect of Abrogating the Holder-in-Due-Course Doctrine on the Commercialization of Innovative Consumer Products’, 64 Boston University Law Review, 325-374. Letsou, Peter V. (1986), ‘A Time-Dependent Model of Products Liability’, 53 University of Chicago Law Review, 209-231. Litan, Robert E. (1991a), ‘The Safety and Innovation Effects of U.S. Liability Law: The Evidence’, 81 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 59-64. Litan, Robert E. (1991b), ‘The Liability Explosion and American Trade Performance: Myths and Realities’, in Schuck, Peter H. (ed.), Tort Law and the Public Interest: Competition, Innovation, and Consumer Welfare, New York, W.W. Norton & Co., 127-150. Litan, Robert E. and Winston, Clifford (1988), ‘Policy Options’, in Litan, Robert E. and Winston, Clifford (eds), Liability: Perspectives and Policy, Washington, DC, The Brookings Institution, 223-241. Lutz, Nancy A. (1989), ‘Warranties as Signals Under Consumer Moral Hazard’, 20 Rand Journal of Economics, 239-254. Lyndon, Mary L. (1995), ‘Tort Law and Technology’, 12 Yale Journal on Regulation, 137-176. MacKay, Murray (1991), ‘Liability, Safety, and Innovation in the Automotive Industry’, in Huber, Peter W. and Litan, Robert E. (eds), The Liability Maze: The Impact of Liability Law on Safety and Innovation, Washington, DC, The Brookings Institution, 1 ff. Magat, Wesley A. and Viscusi, W. Kip (1992), Informational Approaches to Regulation, Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press. Magat, Wesley A., Viscusi, W. Kip and Huber, Joel (1988), ‘Consumer Processing of Hazard Warning Information’, 1 Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 201-232. Manne, Henry G. (1970), ‘Edited Transcript of AALS-AEA Conference on Products Liability’, 38 University of Chicago Law Review, 117-141. Manning, Richard L. (1994), ‘Changing Rules in Tort Law and the Market for Childhood Vaccines’, 37 Journal of Law and Economics, 247-275. Manning, Richard L. (1996), ‘Is the Insurance Aspect of Producer Liability Valued by Consumers? Liability Changes and Childhood Vaccine Consumption’, 13 Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 37-51. Mantell, Edmund H. (1984), ‘Allocative and Distributive Efficiency of Products Liability Law in a Monopolistic Market’, 7 Journal of Products Liability, 143-152. Marino, Anthony M. (1988a), ‘Products Liability and Scale Effects in a Long-Run Competitive Equilibrium’, 8 International Review of Law and Economics, 97-107. Marino, Anthony M. (1988b), ‘Monopoly, Liability and Regulation’, 54 Southern Economic Journal, 913-927. Marino, Anthony M. (1991), ‘Market Share Liability and Economic Efficiency’, 57 Southern Economic Journal, 667-675. Martin, Robert (1991), ‘General Aviation Manufacturing: An Industry Under Siege’, in Huber, Peter W. and Litan, Robert E. (eds), The Liability Maze: The Impact of Liability Law on Safety and
5140
Products Liability
387
Innovation, Washington, DC, The Brookings Institution, 478-499. Matthews, Steven and Moore, John (1987), ‘Monopoly Provision of Quality and Warranties: An Exploration in the Theory of Multidimensional Screening’, 55 Econometrica, 441-467. Matthews, Steven and Postlewaite, Andrew (1985), ‘Quality Testing and Disclosure’, 16 Rand Journal of Economics, 328-340. Maxwell, John W. (1998), ‘Minimum Quality Standards as a Barrier to Innovation’, 58 Economics Letters, 355-60. McFadden, Daniel L. and Train, Kenneth E. (1996), ‘Consumers’ Evaluation of New Products: Learning from Self and Others’, 104 Journal of Political Economy, 683-703. McGuire, E. Patrick (1988), The Impact of Product Liability, New York, Conference Board. McKean, Roland N. (1970a), ‘Products Liability: Trends and Implications’, 38 University of Chicago Law Review, 3-63. McKean, Roland N. (1970b), ‘Products Liability: Implications of Some Changing Property Rights’, 84 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 611-626. Merolla, A. Todd (1998), ‘The Effect of Latent Hazards on Firm Exit in Manufacturing Industries’, 18 International Review of Law and Economics, 13-24. Milgrom, Paul R. and Roberts, John (1986), ‘Price and Advertising Signals of Product Quality’, 94 Journal of Political Economy, 796-821. Moore, Michael J. and Viscusi, W. Kip (1990), Compensation Mechanisms for Job Risks: Wages, Workers’ Compensation, and Product Liability, Princeton, Princeton University Press. Moorhouse, John C. (1992), ‘Joint Torts and Interfirm Contracting’, 20 Atlantic Economic Journal, 10-20. Nakao, Takeo (1982), ‘Product Quality and Market Structure’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 133-142. Neely, Richard (1988), The Product Liability Mess: How Business Can Be Rescued from the Politics of the State Courts, New York, Free Press/Macmillan, 181 p. Nelson, Phillip (1970), ‘Information and Consumer Behavior’, 78 Journal of Political Economy, 311-329. Nelson, Phillip (1974), ‘Advertising as Information’, 82 Journal of Political Economy, 729-754. O’Connell, Jeffrey (1988), ‘Neo-No-Fault: A Fair Exchange Proposal for Tort Reform’, in Olson, Walter (ed.), New Directions in Liability Law, New York, The Academy of Political Science, 186-195. O’Reilly, James T. (1987), ‘The Risks of Assumptions: Impacts of Regulatory Label Warning upon Industrial Products Liability’, 37 Catholic University Law Review, 85-117. Oi, Walter Y. (1973), ‘The Economics of Product Safety’, 4 Bell Journal of Economics, 3-28. Oi, Walter Y. (1974), ‘The Economics of Product Safety: a Rejoinder’, 5 Bell Journal of Economics, 3-28. Olson, Walter (1988), ‘Overdeterrence and the Problem of Comparative Risk’, in Olson, Walter (ed.), New Directions in Liability Law, New York, The Academy of Political Science, 42-53. Ordover, Janusz A. (1979), ‘Products Liability in Markets with Heterogeneous Consumers’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 505-525. Ordover, Janusz A. and Weiss, Andrew (1981), ‘Information and the Law: Evaluating Legal
388
Products Liability
5140
Restrictions on Competitive Contracts’,71 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 399-404. Owen, David G. (1985), ‘The Intellectual Development of Modern Products Liability Law: A Comment on Priest’s View of the Cathedral’s Foundations’,14 Journal of Legal Studies, 529-533. Page, Joseph A. (1990), ‘Deforming Tort Reform, (book review of Peter Huber, ‘Liability: The Legal Revolution and Its Consequences)’, 78 Georgetown Law Journal, 649-697. Palfrey, Thomas R. and Romer, Thomas (1983), ‘Warranties, Performance, and the Resolution of Buyer-Seller Disputes’, 14 Bell Journal of Economics, 97-117. Png, Ivan Paak-Liang and Reitman, David (1995), ‘Why Are Some Products Branded and Others Not?’, 38 Journal of Law and Economics, 207-224. Polinsky, A. Mitchell (1980), ‘Strict Liability Versus Negligence in a Market Setting’, 70 American Economic Review, 363-367. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Che, Yeon-Koo, (1991), ‘Decoupling Liability: Optimal Incentives for Care and Litigation’, 22 Rand Journal of Economics, 562-570. Polinsky, Mitchell A. and Rogerson, William P. (1983), ‘Products Liability, Consumer Misperceptions, and Market Power’, 14 Bell Journal of Economics, 581-589. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1988), ‘The Welfare Implications of Costly Litigation for the Level of Liability’, 17 Journal of Legal Studies, 151-164. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1989), ‘Legal Error, Litigation, and the Incentive to Obey the Law’, 5 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 99-108. Prasad, Ravi (1992), ‘Amendments to the New Australian Products Liability Laws’, Office of Regulation Review. Priest, George L. (1981), ‘A Theory of the Consumer Product Warranty’, 90 Yale Law Journal, 1297-1352. Partially reprinted in Goldberg, Victor P. (ed.) (1989), Readings in the Economics of Contract Law, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 174-184. Priest, George L. (1982), ‘The Best Evidence of the Effect of Products Liability Law on the Accident Rate: Reply’, 91 Yale Law Journal, 1386-1401. Priest, George L. (1985), ‘The Invention of Enterprise Liability: A Critical History of the Intellectual Foundations of Modern Tort Law’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 461-527. Priest, George L. (1987), ‘The Current Insurance Crisis and Modern Tort Law’, 96 Yale Law Journal, 1521-1590. Priest, George L. (1988a), ‘Products Liability Law and the Accident Rate in Liability: Perspectives and Policy’, in Litan, Robert E. and Winston, Clifford (eds), Liability: Perspectives and Policy, Washington, DC, The Brookings Institution, 184-222. Priest, George L. (1988b), ‘The Disappearance of the Consumer from Modern Products Liability Law’, in Maynes, E. Scott and ACCI Research Committee (eds), The Frontier of Research in the Consumer Interest: Proceedings of the International Conference on Research in the Consumer Interest, Columbia, American Council on Consumer Interests, 771-791. Priest, George L. (1988c), ‘Understanding the Liability Crisis’, in Olson, Walter (ed.), New Directions in Liability Law, New York, The Academy of Political Science, 196-211. Priest, George L. (1989), ‘Strict Products Liability: The Original Intent’, 10 Cardozo Law Review, 2301-2327. Priest, George L. (1991), ‘The Modern Expansion of Tort Liability: Its Sources, Its Effects, and Its Reform’, 5(3) Journal of Economic Perspectives, 31-50. Priest, George L. (1992), ‘Can Absolute Manufacturer Liability be Defended?’, 9(1) Yale Journal on
5140
Products Liability
389
Regulation, 237-263. Priest, George L. (1993), ‘Economic Problems of Accidents and Compensation’, 15 University of Hawaii Law Review, 544-552. Ramseyer, J. Mark (1996), ‘Products Liability Through Private Ordering: Notes on a Japanese Experiment’, 144 University of Pennsylvania Law Review. Rea, Samuel A., Jr (1982), ‘Nonpecuniary Loss and Breach of Contract’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 35-53. Rea, Samuel A., Jr (1984), ‘Contingent Damages, Negligence and Absolute Liability: A Comment on Graham and Peirce’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 469-474. Rea, Samuel A., Jr (1985), ‘Comments on Epstein’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 671-674. Rice, David A. (1985), ‘Product Quality Laws and the Economics of Federalism’, 65 Boston University Law Review, 1-64. Ringleb, Al H. and Wiggins, Steven N. (1990), ‘Liability and Large-Scale, Long-Term Hazards’, 98 Journal of Political Economy, 574-595. Riordan, Michael H. (1986), ‘Monopolistic Competition with Experience Goods’, 101 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 265-279. Risa, Alf Erling (1994), ‘Preference Revelation in Strict Liability Product Safety Markets’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 41-52. Rogerson, Carol and Trebilcock, Michael J. (1986), ‘Products Liability and the Allergic Consumer: A Study in the Problems of Framing an Efficient Liability Regime’, 36 University of Toronto Law Journal, 52-103. Rogerson, William P. (1983), ‘Reputation and Product Quality’, 14(2) Bell Journal of Economics, 508-516. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1990), ‘Market-Share Allocations in Tort Law: Strengths and Weaknesses’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 739-746. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1991), ‘Tort Law in the Regulatory State’, in Schuck, Peter H. (ed.), Tort Law and the Public Interest: Competition, Innovation, and Consumer Welfare, New York, W.W. Norton & Co., 80-104. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1991), ‘Regulation and the Law of Torts’, 81 American Economic Review: Papers and Proceedings, 54-58. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1994), ‘Product Safety Regulation and the Law of Torts’, in Hunziker, Janet R. and Jones, Trevor O. (eds), Product Liability and Innovation: Managing Risk in an Uncertain Environment, Washington, DC, National Academy Press, 151 ff. Rothschild, Michael and Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1976), ‘Equilibrium in Competitive Insurance Markets: An Essay on the Economics of Imperfect Information’, 90 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 629-649. Rubin, Paul H. (1993), Tort Reform by Contract, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research. Rubin, Paul H. and Bailey, Martin J. (1994), ‘The Role of Lawyers in Changing the Law’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 807-831. Rubin, Paul H., Murphy, Dennis and Jarrell, Gregg A. (1988), ‘Risky Products, Risky Stocks’, 1 Regulation, 35-39. Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1984), ‘On Determining the Optimal Magnitude and Length of Liability in Torts’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 551-563. Rustad, Michael (1992), ‘In Defense of Punitive Damages in Products Liability’, 78 Iowa Law Review, 1-88.
390
Products Liability
5140
Sage, William M. (1988), ‘Drug Product Liability and Health Care Delivery Systems’, 40 Stanford Law Review, 989-1026. Satterthwaite, Mark A. (1979), ‘Consumer Information, Equilibrium Industry Price, and the Number of Sellers’, 10 Bell Journal of Economics, 483-502. Saving, Thomas R. (1995), ‘Comment: Legal Implications of Imperfect Information in Consumer Markets’, 151 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 52-57. Schlee, Edward E. (1996), ‘The Value of Information about Product Quality’, 27 RAND Journal of Economics, 803-815. Schwartz, Alan (1985), ‘Products Liability, Corporate Structure, and Bankruptcy: Toxic Substances and the Remote Risk Relationship’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 689-736. Schwartz, Alan (1988), ‘Proposals for Products Liability Reform: A Theoretical Synthesis’, 97 Yale Law Journal, 353-419. Schwartz, Alan (1989a), ‘Commentary on ‘Towards a Market in Unmatured Tort Claims’: A Long Way Yet to Go’, 75 Virginia Law Review, 423-430. Schwartz, Alan (1989b), ‘Views of Addiction and Duty to Warn’, 75 Virginia Law Review, 509-560. Schwartz, Alan (1990), ‘The Myth That Promisees Prefer Supracompensatory Remedies: An Analysis of Contracting for Damage Measures’, 100 Yale Law Journal, 369-407. Schwartz, Alan (1992), ‘The Case Against Strict Liability’, 60 Fordham Law Review, 819-842. Schwartz, Alan (1995), ‘Legal Implications of Imperfect Information in Consumer Markets’, 151 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 31-48. Schwartz, Alan and Wilde, Louis L. (1979a), ‘Intervening in Markets on the Basis of Imperfect Information: A Legal and Economic Analysis?’, 127 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 630-682. Schwartz, Alan and Wilde, Louis L. (1979b), ‘Equilibrium Comparison Shopping’, 46 Review of Economic Studies, 543-553. Schwartz, Alan and Wilde, Louis L. (1982), ‘Competitive Equilibria in Markets for Heterogeneous Goods under Imperfect Information: a Theoretical Analysis with Policy Implications’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 181-193. Schwartz, Alan and Wilde, Louis L. (1983a), ‘Imperfect Information in Markets for Contract Terms: The Examples of Warranties and Security Interests’, 69 Virginia Law Review, 1387-1485. Schwartz, Alan and Wilde, Louis L. (1983b), ‘Warranty Markets and Public Policy’, 1 Information Economics and Policy, 55-67. Schwartz, Alan and Wilde, Louis L. (1985), ‘Product Quality and Imperfect Information’, 52 Review of Economic Studies, 251-262. Schwartz, Gary T. (1979), ‘Foreword: Understanding Products Liability’, 67 California Law Review, 435-496. Schwartz, Gary T. (1983), ‘New Products, Old Products, Evolving Law, Retroactive Law’, 58 New York University Law Review, 796-852. Schwartz, Gary T. (1985), ‘Directions in Contemporary Products Liability Scholarship’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 763-778. Schwartz, Gary T. (1986), ‘Economic Loss in American Tort Law: The Examples of J’Aire and of Products Liability’, 23 San Diego Law Review, 37-78. Schwartz, Gary T. (1990), ‘The Ethics and the Economics of Tort Liability Insurance’, 75 Cornell Law Review, 313-365.
5140
Products Liability
391
Schwartz, Gary T. (1991a), ‘The Myth of the Ford Pinto Case’, 43 Rutgers Law Review, 1013-1068. Schwartz, Gary T. (1991b), ‘Products Liability and Medical Malpractice in Comparative Context’, in Huber, Peter and Litan, Robert (eds), Liability Maze: The Impact of Liability Law on Innovation and Safety, 28-80. Schwartz, Gary T. (1993), ‘The A.L.I. Reporters’ Study’, 15 University of Hawaii Law Review, 529-543. Schwartz, Gary T. (1994a), ‘Reality in the Economic Analysis of Tort Law: Does Tort Law Really Deter?’, 42 University of California Los Angeles Law Review, 377-444. Schwartz, Gary T. (1994b), ‘A National Health Program: What its Effect Would be on American Tort Law and Malpractice Law’, 79 Cornell Law Review, 1339-1381. Schwartz, Victor (1983), ‘The Post-Sale Duty to Warn: Two Unfortunate Forks in the Road to a Reasonable Doctrine’, 58 New York University Law Review, 892-905. Schwartz, Victor E. (1992), ‘Innovation and Our Product Liability System: Let us End the Conflict on Incentives’, 27(4) Business Economics, 15-18. Shapiro, Carl (1982), ‘Consumer Information, Product Quality, and Seller Reputation’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 20-35. Shapiro, Carl (1983), ‘Consumer Information, Product Quality, and Seller Reputation’, 98 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 659-679. Shavell, Steven (1979), ‘Risk Sharing and Incentives in the Principal and Agent Relationship’, 10 Bell Journal of Economics, 55-73. Shavell, Steven (1980), ‘Strict Liability versus Negligence’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-25. Shavell, Steven (1982), ‘On Liability and Insurance’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 120-132. Shavell, Steven (1984), ‘A Model of the Optimal Use of Liability and Safety Regulation’, 15 Rand Journal of Economics, 271-280. Shavell, Steven (1984), ‘Liability for Harm versus Regulation of Safety’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 357-374. Shavell, Steven (1987), Economic Analysis of Accident Law, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 312 p. Shavell, Steven (1992), ‘Liability and the Incentives to Obtain Information about Risk’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 259-270. Shieh, Shiou (1993), ‘Incentives for Cost-Reducing Investment in a Signaling Model of Product Quality’, 24 Rand Journal of Economics, 466-477. Siliciano, John A. (1987), ‘Corporate Behavior and the Social Efficiency of Tort Law’, 85 Michigan Law Review, 1820-1864. Simon, Marilyn J. (1981), ‘Imperfect Information, Costly Litigation, and Product Quality’, 12 Bell Journal of Economics, 171-184. Simon, Marilyn J., Wolf, Robert G. and Perloff, Jeffrey M. (1985), ‘Product Safety, Liability Rules and Retailer Bankruptcy’, 51 Southern Economic Journal, 1130-1141. Smallwood, Dennis E. and Conlisk, John, ‘Product Quality in Markets Where Consumers are Imperfectly Informed’, 93 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 1-23. Smithson, Charles W. and Thomas, Christopher R. (1988), ‘Measuring the Cost to Consumers of Product Defects: The Value of ‘Lemon Insurance’‘, 31 Journal of Law and Economics, 485-502. Sowle, Kathryn Dix (1991), ‘Toward a Synthesis of Product Liability Principles: Schwartz’s Model and the Cost-Minimization Alternative’, 46 University of Miami Law Review, 1-110.
392
Products Liability
5140
Speir, John P. (1990), ‘Efficiency Implications of the Sindell-Rexall Rule’, 10 Cato Journal, 603-607. Spence, A. Michael (1975), ‘Monopoly, Quality and Regulation’, 6 Bell Journal of Economics, 417-429. Spence, A. Michael (1977), ‘Nonprice Competition’, 67 American Economic Review, 255-259. Spence, A. Michael (1978), ‘Consumer Misperception, Product Failure and Product Liability’, 44 Review of Economic Studies, 561-572. Spulber, Daniel F. (1989), Regulation and Markets, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Swazey, Judith P. (1991), ‘Prescription Drug Safety and Product Liability’, in Huber, Peter W. and Litan, Robert E. (eds), The Liability Maze: The Impact of Liability Law on Safety and Innovation, Washington, DC, The Brookings Institution, 291-333. Sykes, Alan O. (1989), ‘Reformulating Tort Reform (Book Review of Peter Huber, “Liability: The Legal Revolution and Its Consequences”)’, 56 University of Chicago Law Review, 1153 ff. Symposium (1970), ‘Products Liability: Economic Analysis and the Law’, 38 University of Chicago Law Review, 1-141. Thoman, Lynda (1994), ‘Strict Liability and Negligence Rules when the Product is Information’, 44 Economic Letters, 205-213. Tietz, Gerald F. (1993), ‘Strict Products Liability, Design Defects and Corporate Decisionmaking: Greater Deterrence Through Stricter Process’, 38 Villanova Law Review, 1361-1460. Tirole, Jean (1990), The Theory of Industrial Organization, Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press. Trebilcock, Michael J. (1987), ‘The Social-Insurance-Deterrence Dilemma of Modern North American Tort Law: A Canadian Perspective on the Liability Insurance Crisis’, 24 San Diego Law Review, 929-1002. Trebilcock, Michael J. (1990), ‘Comment (on Viscusi, ‘The Performance of Liability Insurance in States with Different Products-Liability Statutes’)’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 845-849. Twerski, Aaron D. (1983), ‘The Role of the Judge in Tort Law: From Risk-Utility to Consumer Expectations: Enhancing the Role of Judicial Screening in Product Liability Litigation’, 11 Hofstra Law Review, 861 ff. US Department of Justice Tort Policy Working Group (1986), Report on the Causes, Extent, and Policy Implications of the Current Crisis in Insurance Affordability and Availability, Washington, DC, Government Printing Office. Venezian E.C. (1975), ‘Insurer Capital Needs Under Parameter Uncertainty’, 42 Journal of Risk and Insurance, 19 ff. Viscusi, W. Kip (1984), Regulating Consumer Product Safety, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research. Viscusi, W. Kip (1985), ‘Consumer Behavior and the Safety Effects of Product Safety Regulation’, 28 Journal of Law and Economics, 527-553. Viscusi, W. Kip (1986), ‘The Determinants of the Disposition of Product Liability Claims and Compensation for Bodily Injury’, 15 Journal of Legal Studies, 321-346. Viscusi, W. Kip (1988a), ‘Product Liability and Regulation: Establishing the Appropriate Institutional Division of Labor’, 78 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 300-304.
5140
Products Liability
393
Viscusi, W. Kip (1988b), ‘Product Liability Litigation with Risk Aversion’, 17 Journal of Legal Studies, 101-121. Viscusi, W. Kip (1988c), ‘Pain and Suffering in Product Liability Cases: Systematic Compensation or Capricious Awards?’, 8 International Review of Law and Economics, 203-220. Viscusi, W. Kip (1989a), ‘Toward a Diminished Role for Tort Liability: Social Insurance, Government Regulation, and Contemporary Risks to Health and Safety’, 6 Yale Journal on Regulation, 65-107. Viscusi, W. Kip (1989b), ‘The Interaction between Product Liability and Workers’ Compensation as Ex Post Remedies for Workplace Injuries’, 5 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 185-210. Viscusi, W. Kip (1989c), ‘Prospective Reference Theory: Toward an Explanation of the Paradoxes’, 2 Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 235-264. Viscusi, W. Kip (1990a), ‘The Performance of Liability Insurance in States with Different Products-Liability Statutes’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 809-836. Viscusi, W. Kip (1990b), ‘Wading Through the Muddle of Risk-Utility Analysis’, 39 American University Law Review, 573-614. Viscusi, W. Kip (1991a), ‘The Dimensions of the Product Liability Crisis’, 20 Journal of Legal Studies, 147-177. Viscusi, W. Kip (1991b), Reforming Products Liability, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Viscusi, W. Kip (1991c), ‘Product and Occupational Liability’, 5(3) Journal of Economic Perspectives, 71-91. Viscusi, W. Kip (1993a), ‘The Risky Business of Insurance Pricing’, 7 Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 117-139. Viscusi, W. Kip (1993b), Product-Risk Labelling: A Federal Responsibility, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research. Viscusi, W. Kip and Hersch, Joni (1990), ‘The Market Response to Product Safety Litigation’, 2 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 215-230. Viscusi, W. Kip and Magat, Wesley A. (1987), Learning About Risk: Consumer and Worker Responses to Hazard Information, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Viscusi, W. Kip and Moore, Michael J. (1991a), ‘Rationalizing the Relationship between Product Liability and Innovation’, in Schuck, Peter H. (ed.), Tort Law and the Public Interest: Competition, Innovation, and Consumer Welfare, New York, W.W. Norton & Co., 105-126. Viscusi, W. Kip and Moore, Michael J. (1991b), ‘An Industrial Profile of the Links between Product Liability and Innovation’, in Huber, Peter W. and Litan, Robert E. (eds), The Liability Maze: The Impact of Liability Law on Safety and Innovation, Washington, DC, The Brookings Institution, 81-119. Viscusi, W. Kip and Moore, Michael J. (1993), ‘Product Liability, Research and Development, and Innovation’, 101 Journal of Political Economy, 161 ff. Viscusi, W. Kip, Magat, Wesley A. and Huber, Joel (1987), ‘An Investigation of the Rationality of Consumer Valuations of Multiple Health Risks’, 18 Rand Journal of Economics, 465-479. Viscusi, W. Kip, Zeckhauser, Richard J., Born, Patricia and Blackmon, Glenn (1993), ‘The Effect of 1980s Tort Reform Legislation on General Liability and Medical Malpractice Insurance’, 6
394
Products Liability
5140
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 165-186. Wade, John W. (1983), ‘On the Effect in Product Liability of Knowledge Unavailable Prior to Marketing’, 58 New York University Law Review, 734-764. Wagner, Wendy E. (1997), ‘Choosing Ignorance in the Manufacture of Toxic Products’, 82 Cornell Law Review, 773-855. Ward, John O. (1988), ‘Origins of the Tort Reform Movement’, 6(3) Contemporary Policy Issues, 97-107. Weber, Nathan (1987), Product Liability: The Corporate Response, New York, Conference Board. Weicher, John C. (1981), ‘Product Quality and Value in the New Home Market: Implications for Consumer Protection Regulation’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 365-397. Weinrib, Ernest J. (1985), ‘The Insurance Justification and Private Law’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 681-687. Welling, Linda (1991), ‘A Theory of Voluntary Recalls and Product Liability’, 57 Southern Economic Journal, 1092-1111. Wheeler, Malcolm E. (1984), ‘The Use of Criminal Statutes to Regulate Product Safety’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 593-618. Wilde, Louis L. (1992), ‘Comparison Shopping as a Simultaneous Move Game’, 102 Economic Journal, 562-569. Williams, Stephen F. (1993), ‘Second Best: The Soft Underbelly of Deterrence Theory in Tort’, 106 Harvard International Law Journal, 932 ff. Williamson, Oliver E. (1995), ‘Legal Implications of Imperfect Information in Consumer Markets: Comment’, 151 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 49-51. Winter, Ralph A. (1988), ‘The Liability Crisis and the Dynamics of Competitive Insurance Markets’, 5 Yale Journal on Regulation, 455-499. Winter, Ralph A. (1991), ‘The Liability Insurance Market’, 5(3) Journal of Economic Perspectives, 115-136. Wolinsky, Asher (1983), ‘Prices as Signals of Product Quality’, 50 Review of Economic Studies, 647-658. X (1987), ‘Note: Designer Genes That Don’t Fit: A Tort Regime for Commercial Releases of Genetic Engineering Products’, 100 Harvard Law Review, 1086-1105. X (P.M.K. and W.J.S.) (1983), ‘Note: Enforcing Waivers in Products Liability’, 69 Virginia Law Review, 1111-1152.
Other References Binswanger, Hans P. (1974), ‘A Microeconomic Approach to Induced Innovation’, 84 Economic Journal, 940-58. Schmookler, Jacob (1966), Invention and Economic Growth, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Thirtle, Colin G. and Ruttan, Vernon W. (1987), The Role of Demand and Supply in the Generation and Diffusion of Technical Change, Chur, Harwood Academic Publishers, 173 p.
5140
Products Liability
Cases Barker v. Lull Engineering Company, 573 P.2d 443 (Cal. 1978) Denny v. Ford Motor Company, 87 N.Y.2d 248 (N.Y. 1995)
395
5200 PRICE REGULATION: A (NON-TECHNICAL) OVERVIEW Janet S. Netz Department of Economics, Purdue University © Copyright 1999 Janet S. Netz
Abstract This chapter surveys the literature on various forms of price regulation. After explaining why natural monopolies should be regulated, I describe rate of return regulation, the traditional approach to regulating prices. I then discuss the resulting problems, primarily the incentive of the firm to overinvest in capital. I discuss peak load pricing and Ramsey-Boiteux pricing as regulatory mechanisms for multi-product firms. I then describe more recent attempts to design regulatory mechanisms that are not subject to the types of disincentives associated with cost-based price regulation. These forms of regulation include price-cap and profit-sharing regulatory mechanisms. I also discuss the regulation of networks, where a regulated firm competes with rivals and supplies them with an essential input, generally access to a network. I conclude by describing how regulation has been practiced. JEL classification: L51, K23 Keywords: Price Regulation, Price-Cap Regulation, Incentive Regulation
A. Overview 1. Introduction Economists have long recognized that the market outcome for natural monopolies leaves much to be desired. In particular, price is higher and output is lower than the social optimum. Recognition of this problem, among other issues, has led to a long history of attempts to regulate natural monopolists and to a vast literature discussing the problems of attempts at regulation. (Regulation has been enacted for a variety of other reasons, as well. For example, regulation may be motivated by distribution concerns, as the market outcome for natural monopolies redistributes surplus away from consumers to producers. In other cases regulation may occur at the behest of the firms themselves, who may be seeking protection from too much competition (see Chapter 5000 General Theories of Regulation for a discussion of the political
396
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
397
and economic forces that have led to regulation). The goal of this survey is to lay out the economic (efficiency) problems caused by natural monopolies, the various forms of regulation that have been attempted, and their economic effects. The chapter is organized as follows. In Section 2, I present the basic issue: that is, why regulate at all? I focus on the natural monopoly problem, though much price regulation occurs outside industries that are natural monopolies. I briefly discuss examples of price regulation that move the outcome towards the social optimum. This section can be skipped by those familiar with the theory of natural monopolies. Perhaps the most widely used early form of price regulation was really rate-of-return regulation, which I describe in Section 3. Though under this model the regulator specifies an allowed rate-of-return, in practice rate-of-return regulation is implemented when the regulator specifies the allowed prices that a regulated firm may charge that the regulator estimates will give the firm the allowed rate-of-return. As summarized in Section 4, Averch and Johnson (1962) show that such an approach to regulation encouraged the utility to overinvest in capital and to expand into other markets in order to increase its rate base and hence increasing the aggregate amount of profits it could earn subject to the regulatory constraint. In Section 5, I describe extensions to the Averch-Johnson model, as well as summarize empirical estimation of these negative effects. In Section 6, I discuss the multi-product regulated firm. While many of the issues discussed in Part B in the context of a single-product firm apply, the fact that firms produce many products complicates regulation. The largest complication arises because of the existence of common costs; that is, costs that are used to produce more than one product. The issue is discussed in Section 7. In Sections 8 and 9. I discuss two of the most common approaches to regulating a multi-product firm, peak-load pricing and Ramsey-Boiteux pricing. I conclude Part by discussing how the resulting price structure can cause the regulatory regime to be unstable (unsustainable.) Regulation theory has more recently focused on designing regulatory mechanisms that do not provide the utility with the adverse incentives described above. In Part D, I consider alternative forms of price regulation that fall under the rubric ‘incentive regulation’, focusing on price-cap regulation in Sections 12 and 13 and on other forms of incentive regulation such as profitsharing in Section 14. In Section 15 I highlight some of the attempts to compare incentive regulation to other forms of regulation, both in terms of their welfare effects and on the feasibility of implementation. Section 16 discusses the few empirical attempts to measure the impact of incentive regulation. In Part E, I discuss one of the most recent developments in regulation: regulation of access pricing in situations where an incumbent firm provides access to an essential facility, generally a physical network, to rivals. I conclude in Part F by discussing price regulation in practice, including the several recent waves of deregulation.
398
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
I make no claims that this is an exhaustive survey; indeed, in the interests of brevity, many subject areas will be almost completely omitted. Also, because other chapters in this encyclopedia cover the topics, I will omit discussion of: the theory of regulation, or why different forms of price regulation might be implemented (see Chapter 5000, General Theories of Regulation), as well as regulation in particular sectors (see Chapters 5660, Regulation of the Securities Market; 5700, Insurance Regulation; 5850, Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets; 5900, Transportation; 5930, Telecommunications; and 5940, Public Utilities). I attempt to balance discussion of the theoretical work that has been done in the area with empirical analysis of the effect of various types of price regulation mechanisms.
2. The Problem: Natural Monopolies As mentioned above, the market does not achieve production and allocative efficiency if technology is such that the industry structure is one of natural monopoly. In essence, a natural monopoly arises if technology and demand are such that it is cheaper for one firm to serve the market than for several firms to serve the market. (See Panzar, 1989, for a complete, technical discussion of the technology that lead to a natural monopoly. The conditions, especially for a multi-product firm, are considerably more complicated than the simple graph I present. (See Chapter 5400, Regulation of Natural Monopolies for a more complete discussion.) To illustrate the problem, consider Figure 1, which illustrates a natural monopoly arising from economies of scale over the relevant range of production for a firm that sells a single-product. Figure 1 Market Outcome versus Regulated Outcomes
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
399
The average total cost curve (ATC) is shown to be everywhere declining (and hence the marginal cost curve, MC, is beneath the average total cost curve). Thus, the industry is a natural monopoly; any market structure involving several firms would involve the unnecessary duplication of fixed costs. Assume that the firm (and regulator) can charge only a single price; that is, price discrimination is not allowed. If the firm is not regulated, it will maximize profits by setting marginal revenue equal to marginal cost, leading to price PM and output QM. Productive efficiency requires producing at the minimum point of the average total cost curve; clearly the market outcome does not satisfy this condition. Allocative efficiency requires that production occurs where the marginal cost curve crosses the demand curve; again, the market outcome does not satisfy this condition. Relative to the social optimum, social welfare has been reduced by areas A, B, C and D (termed the deadweight loss). Price regulation can theoretically lead to the social optimum if regulators specify that price be set equal to PE, where the E subscript denotes ‘efficient’. (However, price regulation is not the only solution. See, for example, Demsetz, 1968, and Williamson, 1976, who discuss how competition for the market, rather than within the market, can lead towards the social optimum.) Then allocative efficiency is met. The outcome has moved towards productive efficiency; pure productive efficiency cannot be achieved simply because demand is not of sufficient magnitude for production to occur at the minimum average total cost curve. However, a firm that charges PE and produces at QE will not generate sufficient revenue to cover costs of production; in particular, the firm will be short by the amount of its fixed cost. Thus, the regulator must alter the regulatory mechanism in order that the firm remains in the market. To ensure that the market is served, the regulator might offer the firm a subsidy equal to its fixed costs. (The general equilibrium effects of the scheme used to raise the subsidy may distort other markets, so that efficiency in the regulated market may obtain at the expense of inefficiency in other markets.) (If a natural monopoly arises via subadditive costs as defined in Panzar, 1989, but without economies of scale over the entire range of production, then marginal cost pricing would not require a subsidy.) If provision of a subsidy is not politically feasible, the regulator may alternatively specify that the firm charge PF, the price where the average total cost curve crosses the demand curve (the F subscript indicates ‘feasible’). At this price the firm charges the lowest price possible, subject to the constraint that it cover all costs. This regulatory mechanism increases social welfare by areas A, B and C, relative to the market outcome. Society is still losing area D, but this may be acceptable relative to the political cost of providing the firm with a subsidy equal to the firm’s fixed costs. A variety of other pricing schemes are available that may be feasible and may succeed in achieving the social optimum. In general, these pricing
400
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
schemes relax the assumption made above that the firm can charge only a single price. Consider, for example, an alternative scheme that may be available if price discrimination is allowed. The regulator could require the firm to sell at price PF to those consumers who are willing and who can afford that price, and charge PE to those customers who are willing and who can afford PE but not PF. Revenues earned from customers paying PF will cover the variable costs of serving them and all of the fixed costs; revenues earned from customers paying PE would cover the variable costs of serving them. Of course, a practical problem immediately arises. How could the firm classify consumers into the two pricing categories? No consumer would willingly admit that she was willing to pay the higher price. Furthermore, the product must be one that cannot be resold. If it could, then even if the firm could distinguish between types of consumers, the consumers facing the lower price would buy and resell to the consumers facing the higher price. Price discrimination can be adopted only in situations where the firm can identify customers by type and can prevent resale of the product. Alternatively, consider that a firm may charge different prices for different amounts of the good purchased. A common such scheme, called a two-part tariff, is one where each customer pays a monthly fixed price for access equal to the total fixed costs divided by the total number of customers and then the customer pays an additional fee equal to the marginal cost for each unit consumed. The fixed fee covers the fixed cost of operation and the per unit fee covers variable costs. Since total revenues cover total costs, the firm would not require a subsidy. This pricing scheme is efficient only if consumer surplus, which is the value the consumer places on consuming the product less the cost the consumer must pay, for the consumer with the smallest demand is greater or equal to the fixed price. Otherwise some consumers will exit the market, in which case the scheme does not achieve the social optimum. Other types of non-linear pricing exist, as well, which may or may not achieve, or have the objective of achieving, efficiency. For example, block pricing, where consumers pay one price for the first block of the product that they use (say, the first 500 kilowatt hours of electricity used), then a different price for the second and subsequent blocks. Standard or declining block pricing refers to declining prices for subsequent blocks, inverted block pricing refers to increasing prices for subsequent blocks. (Block pricing of either kind is a common feature of gas, electricity and water price structures.) If used alone, a declining block pricing scheme optimally charges a price on the first block sufficiently high to cover the fixed costs of operation and charges a price equal to marginal cost on subsequent demand. (This is simply a variation of the scheme described above where some consumers pay PF and some pay PE.) Alternatively, block pricing can be used in conjunction with a fixed fee of the type discussed above. In a declining block pricing scheme, efficiency may be
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
401
enhanced over the two-part tariff described above if the two-part tariff has a sufficiently high fixed fee so as to induce some consumers to exit the market. In a declining block pricing scheme with a fixed fee (that is, a multi part tariff), the higher price on initial units can be used to reduce the fixed fee, which increases efficiency by inducing more customers to remain in the market. Inverted block pricing is incompatible with efficiency, and is generally adopted to redistribute income (as in many developing countries; Maddock and Castano, 1991, study the effects of the inverted block structure adopted in Medellin, Colombia for electricity rates on redistribution, the stated objective of the policy, and find that the policy is effective at redistributing income, though of course at a cost to efficiency) or to encourage conservation (as in several municipalities in California for water during the droughts of the 1980s; some succeeded in reducing demand so successfully that they were forced to raise rates in order to generate sufficient revenue to cover costs!). See Train (1991) for a full description of block pricing. In sum, price regulation of some form can increase social welfare relative to the market outcome. It is theoretically possible to achieve the social optimum, where the marginal cost and demand curves cross, though in practice it may only be possible to move towards the social optimum, not to achieve it.
B. Rate-of-return Regulation and its Problems, or the Unintended Consequences of Regulation 3. Introduction to Rate-of-return Regulation Price regulation, as practiced in the US, has often involved rate-of-return regulation. Under such regulation, the regulatory agency sets prices in such a way that the utility earns the allowed (‘fair’) rate-of-return on its investment. While this form of regulation is seemingly simple, and seems as if it would achieve feasible average cost prices, in practice average cost prices are not achieved because the regulatory mechanism gives the firms an incentive not to minimize cost. (In the simple analysis presented above, a competitive rate-ofreturn to the utility was built into the average total cost curve, as total costs must include an adequate return on investments. Thus, average cost pricing at PF is an example of rate-of-return regulation, where the allowed rate-of-return is equal to the competitive rate-of-return.) Before turning to the effects of regulation, I briefly describe the institutions that were adopted in the US to implement regulation (see Kaserman and Mayo, 1995, for a detailed description of the regulatory process). While historically most other countries chose public ownership as the common method for controlling natural monopolies, the US generally chose to separate the
402
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
ownership of the firm from the government agencies that regulated them. (Utilities that serve the majority of demand are investor owned. Typically utilities are granted a franchise (monopoly) over a geographic area, and are subject to regulation.) Because of the movement towards privatization worldwide, the structure of the regulatory bodies may be of more general interest as other countries establish regulatory agencies to oversee newly privatized firms. In the US, local (retail) electricity and natural gas distribution, local phone service, and private water systems (this last is the most commonly municipally owned utility in the US), are regulated by an independent state public utility commission or PUC. (Long-distance phone rates (until very recently) and wholesale electricity and natural gas transactions are regulated in a similar manner, but by a federal agency, since under the US Constitution interstate transactions fall under the purview of the federal government.) State PUCs consist of from one to seven commissioners, who may be appointed (most commonly) by the governor with legislative approval or elected, depending on the state, and a professional staff. Prices are set to allow utilities to earn a fair rate-of-return on their capital investment. (The level and structure of prices may also be set to accomplish other goals, such as subsidizing some consumer groups over others.) Rulings by the US Supreme Court mandate that state PUCs provide regulated firms with a fair rate-of-return, whatever the PUCs other goals in setting prices may be. In Smyth v. Ames (169 US 466, 1898), the Court stated that ‘The company is entitled to ask for a fair return upon the value of that which it employs for the public convenience’. At the same time, the Court ruled that consumers deserved protection, as well: ‘while the public is entitled to demand ... that no more be extracted from it ... than the services are reasonably worth’. The Supreme Court ruled further in Federal Power Commission v. Hope Natural Gas Co. (320 US 591, 1944) that regulated firms are entitled to a ‘just and reasonable’ rate-of-return, so that the firm is able ‘to operate successfully, to maintain its financial integrity, to attract capital, and to compensate its investors for the risks assumed’. In order to set the price structure to generate the fair rate-of-return, the PUC first determines the utility’s revenue requirement, which consists of the sum of operating expenses, current depreciation, taxes, and the allowed rate-of-return times the rate base. The rate base is the value of assets, often measured as the original cost of equipment less accumulated depreciation. (This measure has the advantage of being easy to calculate, though a variety of other methods are used, often involving the replacement cost of capital.) The rate-of-return must be chosen high enough to raise capital, but low enough to prevent the use of market power. The PUC then forecasts demand and, based on the revenue requirement and the quantity forecast, the agency stipulates the prices that the regulated firm is
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
403
allowed to charge. Often the utility proposes a rate structure and, based on information from a ‘test year’, typically the latest year for which the necessary data are available, demonstrate that the price structure would yield the revenue requirement. Ex post, depending on the rate-of-return actually earned by the utility, the firm or consumer groups or the regulatory agency may request or undertake a rate hearing to alter prices if the earned rate-of-return deviates substantially (in either direction) from the allowed rate-of-return. In addition, the staffs of the commissions often periodically monitor the firms’ performance, in which case they may request that the commission hold a new rate hearing. The method used to gather information and to decide new rates is rather like a court hearing. A variety of groups may give testimony, including the commission staff, the firm, consumer groups and rival firms. In some states consumers are formally represented at regulatory hearings by the Office of Public Utility Counsel. A rate hearing consists of the presentation of evidence to the commission. There are formal rules of procedure à la a judicial proceedings. The commission announces a hearing, then publishes the rules of discovery (that is, the rules by which parties are granted access to the factual data of other parties) and a timetable for the hearing. Typically, first the utility is required to file written testimony supporting its rate change. Then, typically 30 to 90 days later, other parties (rivals, consumers, and so on) are allowed to present testimony supporting or opposing the utility’s proposed rate change. Rate hearings often have two phases, the first determining the revenue requirement and the second designing the rates that will allow the utility to earn the revenue requirement. One area of contention regards costs incurred by the utility. Operating expenses are typically non-controversial. However, as shown in the next section, regulated firms have an incentive to invest in capital beyond the efficient level. Thus, public utility commissions determine whether costs, typically capital costs, are prudent. Typically, a firm that is expanding capacity will construct the new plant, and only once the construction is completed will the rate base change. If the new capital was automatically added to the rate base, then firms may have the incentive to invest in plants that are bigger than necessary in order to inflate the rate base and increase profits. Regulators have the authority to determine the prudence of expenditures on addition to capital. Prudence is determined by whether the capital is necessary to provide the service and whether it is cost effective relative to alternatives. The fact that capital investment may be disallowed encourages the firm to invest wisely. (Most states have to authority to require advance approval of capital budgets; yet even with advance approval, there is no guarantee that the investment will be allowed into the rate base.) The most commonly used example of disallowances involves the building of nuclear power plants. Public Utility Commissions have in fact allowed several utilities to go bankrupt as a result of
404
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
disallowances.
4. The Averch-Johnson Model Averch and Johnson (1962) model the regulated firm as seeking to maximize profits subject to a constraint on the earned rate-of-return, and show that if the regulated rate-of-return is higher than the cost of capital (it must be equal to or higher than the cost of capital if the firm is going to produce at all), then the regulated firm (1) will not minimize costs and (2) may expand into other markets, even if it operates at a loss in these markets, and hence may drive competitive firms out of the market (or discourage them from entering). The firm will not minimize cost because, so long as the regulated return on capital is higher than the cost of capital, the firm makes a profit for each additional unit of capital. (Indeed, Baron, 1989, points out that the regulated firm would like the price to be set as low as possible, to increase the quantity sold. That gives the firm the opportunity to employ as much capital as possible, and every additional unit of capital employed gives the firm a profit.) This gives the firm an incentive to invest more in capital than is efficient given the actual cost of capital relative to other input prices. Consider, for example, an unregulated firm. This firm will, for each quantity produced, combine labor and capital (assuming these are the only inputs) in such a way that the last dollar spent on labor gives the same output value as the last dollar spent on capital. That is, each input is used until the cost of the last unit employed is equal to the revenues that can be earned with that input’s output. A regulated firm, on the other hand, not only earns revenues by selling the output produced by capital, but also on the capital itself. Hence, each unit of capital provides higher revenue to a regulated firm than to an unregulated firm, encouraging the regulated firm to employ a larger amount of capital than will an unregulated firm. The regulated firm then uses too much capital relative to labor, producing at higher than minimum cost. The degree to which a firm overcapitalizes depends on its ability to substitute between inputs. The more substitution the technology allows, the more inefficient a firm will be. Now consider a multi-product firm that may operate in several markets, assuming that the regulatory body allocates at least some of the capital used for production in the other markets to the firm’s rate base (as was commonly done in practice, given the problem of allocating common costs; see Section 7). Based on the same logic described above, the firm has an incentive to increase its use of capital, and now may do so in other markets. Suppose that in its initial market the regulated firm has invested in the optimal (from its point of view) amount of capital. The firm now considers investing in additional markets. As an extreme, suppose that this firm is not competitive in another
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
405
market: that is, its costs are above rival firms. Then it will lose money on each unit that it sells in the market. However, suppose for each unit of capital that it uses to produce the profit- losing product, it earns revenue because it loosens the rate-of-return constraint. Then the firm will operate in the new market until the extra revenues earned per additional unit of capital are offset by the cost of capital, other inputs, and the loss from sales of the product. That is, a firm will operate in a second, non competitive market, so long as (s1! r2) x2, where s1 is the allowed rate-of-return in the original market, r2 is the cost of capital in the other market, and x2 is the amount of capital used in the other market that is allowed into the rate base, is less than the losses from operating in the market. (Averch and Johnson, 1962, argue that the descriptive evidence suggests that AT&T behaved along the lines predicted by their model in terms of both overinvesting in capital and moving into other markets.) Thus, not only will the firm’s input use be distorted in the regulated market, but inefficiencies can spill into competitive markets as competitive firms are driven out of business or are prevented from entering markets in which they have lower costs. (Braeutigam and Panzer, 1989, examine this issue more rigorously, arriving at the same conclusion.) In sum, rate-of-return regulation as practiced provides firms with the incentive to overinvest in capital, both in the regulated market itself, and by inefficient diversification into other markets.
5. Extensions, Reinterpretations and Tests of the Averch-Johnson Model The Averch-Johnson model led to a variety of work applying the basic idea to other settings. One intellectually unappealing aspect of the Averch-Johnson model is the fact that the regulator does not recognize the firm’s strategic response and hence modify the regulatory mechanism to mitigate the capital disincentives. Baron (1989) recasts the Averch-Johnson model in terms of a mechanism adopted to deal with the regulatory body’s incomplete information on the firm’s costs or on demand. If the regulator could observe the production function and factor prices, the regulator could set price equal to the efficient marginal cost (that is, the marginal cost that arises from the optimal use of capital relative to labor), thus eliminating the production inefficiency. However, suppose that the regulator does not observe the production function and/or factor prices. Then in essence, the regulator adjusts price as a function of the cost incurred by the firm. In Baron’s view, the Averch-Johnson outcome is plausible in a setting where the regulator and the firm have different information about costs and demand or the regulator cannot observe all actions of the firm. In such a setting, the Averch-Johnson approach could arise endogenously. Along similar lines, Woroch (1984) analyzes investment by firms using a non cooperative model of the firm regulator relationship, and
406
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
allows the regulatory mechanism to arise endogenously as well. He allows firms to invest strategically. Woroch finds that achieving ‘credibility’ of regulation, which requires that the regulator issue a welfare maximizing response to the capital investment, may lead to an outcome that is indistinguishable from the Averch-Johnson model. In other words, the AverchJohnson model may be recast in different, perhaps more plausible, frameworks, but the disincentives caused by regulation may still arise. Bailey and Coleman (1971), Baumol and Klevorick (1970), Bawa and Sibley (1980), Davis (1973), Klevorick (1973) and Logan, Masson and Reynolds (1989) extend the Averch-Johnson model to incorporate regulatory lag. These authors recognize that, in practice, rate hearings occur with a lag after a change in cost or demand. Under regulatory lag, a firm can appropriate increased profits from cost reduction for the time period between the innovation and the rate hearing (and likewise, the firm absorbs any losses). This reintroduces to the firm the incentive to reduce costs, though the incentive is not as large as it would be if the firm appropriates gains from cost reductions forever. Encinosa and Sappington (1995) and Lyon (1991, 1992) examine a firm’s incentive to over- or under-invest in capital under a situation where regulators review a firm’s capital investments and can (and do) disallow some capital expenditures. The Averch-Johnson model was based on a more certain environment where the firm knows that it will earn the allowed rate-of-return on its entire capital investment. More recently, regulatory agencies have become tougher in allowing capital expenditures into the rate base. It has been typically accepted that regulatory hindsight, especially if regulators punish bad ex post outcomes rather than bad ex ante decisions, will lead to underinvestment in capital. Lyon (1991), on the contrary, finds that hindsight review can be used to reduce the firm’s tendency to build large, risky projects, moving the firm closer to the cost-minimizing input choice. In addition, Encinosa and Sappington (1995) find that rewards as well as penalties are optimal. Lyon (1992) examines prudency reviews in the context of contracts for variable inputs, and finds that prudency reviews will cause a firm to increase its capital stock and to rely more heavily on spot market purchases for variable inputs; while the firm earns lower profits, the welfare effects on consumers are ambiguous. The Averch-Johnson model has also been included a dynamic setting including adjustment costs of investment. For example, El-Hodiri and Takayama (1981) show that the long-run level of capital stock increases when a rate-of-return constraint is imposed. Moretto (1989) adjusts the AverchJohnson model in two dimensions: to incorporate an adjustment cost approach to investment and to allow for uncertainty over the revenue function. The Averch-Johnson effect may not obtain; it holds only when the rate of growth of the marginal adjustment cost is concave. In contrast to El-Hodiri and Takayama (1981) and Appelbaum and Harris (1982) but along the lines of
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
407
Moretto (1989), Dechert (1984) adopts a dynamic adjustment-cost model and finds that underinvestment may obtain, in contrast to the Averch-Johnson overinvestment result. The factor driving is result is whether a firm is operating in the increasing return or decreasing return portion of average cost. (This holds for the static Averch-Johnson model as well.) Dechert (1984) argues that natural monopolies arise under economies of scale, in which case profits are not concave, at least not over the entire input range; in contrast, other Averch-Johnson models assume concavity of the profit function. (Note, however, that natural monopolies can obtain outside the increasing returns portion of the average total cost curve; see Panzar, 1989, for an explanation.) The importance of whether costs are increasing or decreasing may explain the mixed empirical evidence regarding the Averch-Johnson model. A fair bit of empirical work has been done trying to test the Averch-Johnson model, mostly focusing on electricity production. The results of these tests have been mixed. Nemoto, Nakanishi and Madano (1993) find that seven of nine Japanese electric utilities do significantly overinvest, while Tawada and Katayama (1990) find much weaker support for the Averch-Johnson effect in the same industry. Indeed, they find that production was efficient in some time periods, despite the form of regulation. In the US, Courville (1974), Hayashi and Trapani (1976)and Spann (1974) all find support for the Averch-Johnson effect in electric utilities. Hayashi and Trapani (1976) also find that tightening regulation increases the distortion. Boyes (1976), on the other hand, does not find support for the Averch-Johnson effect, also using data on electric utilities in the US. Hsu and Chen (1990) find empirical evidence of the presence of an Averch-Johnson effect for the Taiwan Power Company. Oum and Zhang (1995) find empirical support for the hypothesis that the introduction of competition in the US telephone industry induces incumbents subject to rate-ofreturn regulation to use capital closer to the optimal level, reducing the AverchJohnson effect. Thus, theoretical models support the Averch-Johnson findings of a tendency towards overinvestment in capital by firms subject to a rate-of-return constraint, though introducing some modifications of the framework in order to make it more realistic, such as regulatory lag and cost disallowances, mitigates the overinvestment effect to some extent. There is somewhat more empirical support for the Averch-Johnson effect than against it. As I will discuss in Part D, the form of regulation has changed a great deal, much of it in response to the debate over the Averch-Johnson overcapitalization effect in the face of rateof-return regulation.
408
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
C. The Multi-product Regulated Firm 6. Introduction to Multi-product Issues The discussion thus far has focused on a single-product firm (except during the discussion that a regulated firm has an incentive to enter other markets in order to increase its rate base). In reality, of course, most regulated firms produce a variety of products. Even in the case of a single commodity, say electricity, it is more proper to think of the firm providing electricity during certain time periods. In other words, the market for electricity during the day is separate from the market for electricity during the evening and night-time. Before discussing various price mechanisms for regulating the multi-product firm, an important concept must be addressed: how to allocate common costs, that is, costs common to production of several products, to individual products? (If the goal of regulation is to maximize social welfare, that is, to achieve allocative and productive efficiency, separating costs across services is meaningless. It is generally done by regulators, however, when they have an interest in the distribution of surplus across groups; that is, regulators often desire to determine whether a given customer group is covering the costs of servicing them.) After describing the problem, I discuss two of the more commonly used regulatory mechanisms, peak-load pricing and Ramsey-Boiteux pricing.
7. The Common Cost Problem Consider an example, following Braeutigam (1989), where a firm produces two products with constant marginal costs of m1 and m2 and has total fixed costs F, giving a simple total cost function of TC = F + m1 y1 + m2 y2 . Analogously to the discussion of a single-product firm, the social optimum requires that each product be priced at its marginal cost; however, the firm will then not earn sufficient revenues to cover costs. Recall that a simple solution in the singleproduct case was to require that the firm price at average cost. The problem here is that the calculation of the average cost for each product necessitates a division of the fixed costs across the two products. While infinitely many ways exist to divide the fixed costs, some will lead to higher levels of social welfare than others. Thus the more interesting problem is how to allocate fixed costs in the optimal manner. In practice, a variety of weighting schemes have been used, including weighting by gross revenues, by physical output levels, or by directly attributable costs. (Directly attributable costs typically include all variable costs, and may also include some portion of fixed costs, if some fixed costs are associated with the production of only one of the products.) Alternatively,
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
409
sometimes the Allais rule is used, where marginal cost proportional mark-ups are used, with the mark-up being determined in such a way as to raise sufficient revenue that the firm breaks even. Attributing costs in this manner is typically referred to as fully distributed cost. In practice, once the common cost is assigned to the different outputs, prices are set so that revenues from each output cover costs. There are several problems with this approach to dividing costs for a multiproduct firm, including the fact that such division is inherently arbitrary and, from an economic point of view, not very sensible. As summarized by Laffont and Tirole (1996), the drawbacks include the fact that, since it is cost-based, firms do not have a strong incentive to minimize costs; that the price structure is inappropriate as prices are too low for inelastic demand services and too high for elastic demand services (see the discussion of Ramsey-Boiteux pricing in Section 9); that it does not use non-linear pricing; and that some forms encourage inefficient entry. Economists have developed several pricing approaches to maximize social welfare given the constraint that the multi-product firm must break even. These pricing schemes do not require allocation of common costs. (Ex post one could calculate the proportion of the common cost that is paid for by each output; however, ex ante the only necessary information needed is the total amount of fixed cost.) I discuss two of the most common methods: peak-load pricing and Ramsey-Boiteux pricing.
8. Peak-load Pricing Peak-load pricing is a particular regulatory mechanism that is appropriate when the firm provides a non-storable good during different time periods and is constrained to choose a single capacity level. (See Crew, Fernando and Kleindorfer, 1995, for a survey on peak-load pricing theory.) Formulating prices for different time periods relates to the common cost problem: optimal prices depend on how much of the capacity cost, a common cost, is allocated to each time period. Consider the following simple model. A production period (a day or year) is divided into T equal increments. During each period t, xt units of a variable input are used. Let K denote the total amount of capital used. K is the common cost, the cost of the production facility that operates in all periods. Let yt = f(xt,K) represent the production function, and let Pt = Pt(yt) denote the inverse demand curve (the notation and example are based on Braeutigam, 1989). Steiner (1957) assumed that the production function was Leontief; in other words, yt = min(xt, K), where, for notational simplicity, I have assumed one unit of capital and one unit of the variable input produce one unit of output. (The qualitative results hold for an fixed proportion of capital to the variable
410
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
input.) Let the cost of the variable input be given by b, and let ß be the rental cost of capital. Assuming that the firm is constrained by the regulatory authority to meet demand in all periods, it will choose capacity to equal the maximum amount demanded. Then the total cost function can be written as T
TC = b ∑ yt + β max yt t =1
In other words, total cost is equal to the cost of the variable input times the total amount of the variable input used in all time periods plus the rental cost of capital times the maximum output produced in any period. The social optimum requires that price be set equal to marginal cost in each period. Based on the total cost function, this means that the price in every nonpeak period is optimally set equal to the cost of the variable input, Pnon-peak = b. (Marginal cost in a non-peak period is given by dTC/dyt = b, the derivative of the first term in the cost function, since the second term does not contain output in any period except the peak period.) Price in the peak period is set equal to the cost of the variable input and the cost of capacity, Ppeak = b + ß. In other words, consumers during the peak period are responsible for both their variable costs and total capacity costs. Given that the technology exhibits constant returns to scale, peak-load pricing leads not only to the social optimum, but also allows the firm to earn sufficient revenues to cover total costs, obviating the need for a subsidy. However, Panzar (1976) shows that this result is not robust to changes in technology. Suppose that the production function is given in a general form as yt = f(xt, K), so that the firm can substitute to some extent between the variable and the capital inputs. The production function is assumed to be subject to diminishing returns (that is, increases in either input increase output, but at a declining rate). Let the total variable cost function be written as V(yt, b, K). This function gives the minimum total variable costs required to produce output yt, given input prices b and capacity K. First, pricing in each period is given by Pt = MV/Myt. This condition indicates that price in each period is equal to the marginal variable cost. In this case, prices in off peak periods will not be equal since marginal cost varies with output. For example, suppose that output in period 2 is larger than output in period 1. Given the assumptions on the production function that an increase in inputs increases output at a declining rate, the marginal variable cost will be higher in period 2 than in period 1, and therefore so will the price in period 2. Second, optimal pricing requires that S tt=1 MV/MK =!ß. This condition shows that the firm will choose capital such that the total variable costs saved equals the cost of employing the last unit of capital. The model using Leontief production did not have a second condition, because the firm had no choice in capital. The firm was required to produce enough to satisfy demand in each
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
411
period (a regulatory constraint), and technology was such that satisfying the regulatory constraint dictated the amount of capital used. In the production function used here, the firm can substitute between the variable input and the capital input, choosing the cheapest ratio of the two, depending on their relative prices. Thus, while peak-load optimal prices can be derived from a more flexible production function, it no longer remains true that only the peak consumers pay for capacity costs. However, it remains true that peak-load pricing raises sufficient revenues to cover costs. The existence of uncertainty over demand or supply can complicate the application of peak-load pricing. Koschat, Srinagesh and Uhler (1995) derive peak-load prices when demand in different periods is stochastic and test the implications of the theory using data on local telephone service. They find that ignoring uncertainty in demand can lead to inefficient prices and inefficient industry-wide capacity choices. Perhaps most interestingly, they find that spot pricing of phone calls, so that prices are high during actual congestion rather than during times of expected congestion, can be considerably more efficient. Kleindorfer and Fernando (1993) also consider peak-load pricing under uncertainty in demand, but add to the analysis by considering uncertainty in supply as well, focusing particularly on electricity (where uncertainty in supply is a common problem). In this setting, the regulatory agency must account for a variety of costs that arise when supply and demand do not clear.
9. Ramsey-Boiteux Pricing The peak-load pricing mechanism described above, by assuming constant returns to scale, led to prices that were not only socially optimal, but under which revenues covered costs. Thus, peak-load prices are efficient and feasible. However, without constant returns to scale, marginal cost pricing will not raise sufficient revenue that the firm will cover total costs. As an alternative, Ramsey-Boiteux prices can be used to satisfy the constraints that the firm charge a single price for each product and that the firm raises enough revenue to cover total costs. (Ramsey, 1927, introduced this pricing scheme as an optimal form of taxation that raised the required revenues at the lowest deadweight loss cost. Boiteux, 1956, applied the idea to the determination of regulated prices.) Assuming the demands for the different products are independent, RamseyBoiteux prices are the solution to the following constrained maximization problem, max p CS ( y) + p ⋅ y − C( y, w ) s.t. p ⋅ y − C( y, w ) ≥ 0,
412
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
where CS(y) is consumer surplus as a function of the entire output vector y; p is the price vector; and C(y, w) is total cost as a function of outputs and the vector of input prices w. The social planner (regulator) maximizes social welfare, defined as the sum of consumer surplus and firm profits, subject to the constraint that profits be non negative. Solving the maximization problem leads to the following relationship:
p i & Cy pi
i
eii '
p j & Cy pj
j
ejj,
œ i, j,
where Cyi is the marginal cost of product i, pi is the price of product i, and eii is the elasticity of demand for product i. This relationship, one of several formulations of the Ramsey-Boiteux pricing rule, shows that optimal prices are such that the price-cost margin multiplied by the product’s elasticity of demand be equal across all products produced by the firm. Thus, the price of the more inelastic good is higher than the price of the elastic good. How is it that prices set according to this pricing rule maximize social welfare, subject to the constraint that firms earn zero economic profits? (Dierker, 1991, formally proves that Ramsey-Boiteux prices are second best prices.) First, note that maximizing social welfare is equivalent to minimizing the deadweight loss. Then the optimality of Ramsey-Boiteux pricing can best be explained graphically. Figure 2 illustrates two related markets. In the upper panel, the firm is constrained to set the same price in each market. Price P is chosen such that the areas A and B equal the fixed costs faced by the firm, so that the firm just breaks even. In the lower panel, the firm is allowed to choose separate prices for each market, and the areas C and D also add up to fixed costs. The shaded areas in both panels are the deadweight loss arising from the fact that price deviates from marginal cost. The two shaded areas in the lower panel are in sum smaller than the two shaded areas in the upper panel, reflecting the fact that the prices chosen in the lower panel minimize the deadweight loss. Intuitively, this comes about because demand in the left panels is inelastic; thus, price can be increased in this market with a relatively small deadweight loss, since as price rises, demand does not decline too much. On the other hand, increasing price in the right panels where demand is elastic induces a large decline in quantity, and hence a large deadweight loss.
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
413
Figure 2 Deadweight Loss with a Single Price (top panel) Deadweight Loss with Ramsey-Boiteux Prices (lower panel)
The description of Ramsey-Boiteux pricing presented above assumes that demand for the two products be independent. This may be an overly strong assumption, but the approach can be extended to the case where demands for the products are interdependent; see, for example, Dreze (1964), Rohlfs (1974) and Zajac (1974b). In this case, one must take into account the cross partial derivatives; that is, the impact of the price of one good on the quantity demanded of the other good(s). Dreze (1964) derives the Ramsey-Boiteux pricing rule when demand is not interdependent, and arrives at a pricing rule similar in form to that above. More precisely,
p i & Cy pi
i
(ei & eji) '
p j & Cy pj
j
(ej & eij),
œ i, j,
414
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
where eij is the elasticity of good i with respect to the price of good j. In essence the net elasticity, ei ! eji, gives the effect of i’s price on its own demand less the effect on demand for the other product. (Note that this form of the RamseyBoiteux pricing rule reduces to the original form if the cross elasticities are zero. An alternative formulation of the Ramsey-Boiteux rule when demand is interdependent involves ‘superelasticities’, which account for substitution and complementarity among goods. See, for example, Laffont and Tirole, 1993.) Ramsey-Boiteux prices have also been derived in more complicated settings. For example, Horowitz, Seeto and Woo (1996) assume that costs are unknown to both the regulator and the firm. Passmore (1984) assumes demand is uncertain and that the firm chooses capacity simultaneously with prices. Berry (1992) incorporates risk in marginal cost. Braeutigam (1979b) incorporates competition in some products produced by the firm. Brock and Dechert (1983) and Braeutigam (1983) extend Ramsey-Boiteux pricing to a dynamic setting. The previous work has assumed that the regulator sets prices. But a Ramsey-Boiteux price structure may endogenously arise when firms choose prices, depending on the regulatory regime. Logan, Masson and Reynolds (1989) develop a regulatory mechanism under which the firm is allowed to choose prices subject to a rate-of-return constraint. Regulators review performance, and there is a higher probability that regulators will request a new rate hearing as the firm’s return deviates from the constrained rate. If regulators do not review negative returns too quickly relative to positive returns, the model predicts that the firm’s prices will converge to RamseyBoiteux prices and that productive efficiency will obtain. The model indicates that relatively simple regulatory mechanisms that do not require much information lead to Ramsey-Boiteux efficient prices. (As discussed in Section 12, price-cap regulation, in some circumstances, also leads firms to choose prices that converge to Ramsey-Boiteux prices.) A number of empirical studies have been undertaken to compare regulated prices to Ramsey-Boiteux prices; that is, to determine whether regulated prices are set at the optimal (from a constrained efficiency maximization point of view) level. Matsukawa, Madono and Nakashima (1993) examine pricing by Japanese electric utilities. They find that the prices do not satisfy the RamseyBoiteux pricing rule, and that moving towards Ramsey-Boiteux prices may require a large increase in residential electricity rates and a slight decrease in industrial electricity rates. Liu (1993) examines local telephone pricing in Taiwan and also finds that prices do not satisfy the Ramsey-Boiteux pricing rule. In the US, DeLorme, Kamerschen and Thompson (1992) find that electricity generated via nuclear power is not priced according to the RamseyBoiteux rule either, but rather that prices respond to political influences. To my knowledge, no empirical study has found regulated prices that conform to the Ramsey-Boiteux ideal. Perhaps the most obvious explanation
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
415
is that regulators have a goal that is different from minimization of the deadweight loss subject to a break even constraint. For example, Sheehan (1991b) argues vehemently that Ramsey-Boiteux pricing is inappropriate for telecommunications regulation, in part because it does not protect ‘captive’ consumers from the use of market power. Friedlaender (1992) considers regulation of a firm that serves two markets, one of which is competitive so that prices are at marginal cost, and one of which is ‘captive’ so that consumers in this market have no alternative supplier. Then the captive sector bears the entire revenue burden. She applies her model to freight transportation by railroad, and shows that the application of Ramsey-Boiteux pricing would cause the price to captive coal shippers to rise to ‘socially unacceptable levels’ since they would be forced to bear the entire revenue requirement. Ashraf and Sabih (1992) extend the Ramsey-Boiteux model to incorporate ‘life-line’ rates (that is, the idea that all households should be able to afford a minimum amount of telephone service) and still find empirically that the pricing structure of electricity in Pakistan deviates from the amended Ramsey-Boiteux prices. Thus, while Ramsey-Boiteux prices have a number of desirable characteristics from a strict efficiency point of view, in practice efficiency and other concerns lead regulators to deviate from them, often to a substantial degree.
10. Non-linear Pricing and Sustainability Non-linear pricing (including two-part tariffs, block pricing, peak-load pricing, and Ramsey pricing) lead to issues of sustainability. That is, given non-linear pricing, can the regulated monopoly continue in existence? Two issues in particular arise: the likelihood of cream-skimming and of bypass. Cream-skimming refers to entry of firms into the high-profit markets served by the regulated monopolist. Without entry, the profits earned in one market are used to ‘subsidize’ prices in another market, either for efficiency reasons as in peak-load and Ramsey-Boiteux pricing or for fairness reasons as in business phone rates subsidizing residential rates. An entrant observes profits to be made in the high-price market, and may be induced to enter that market only. (This is named cream skimming because the entry skims the cream (high profits) and leaves the milk (low profits).) For example, in the US, MCI was interested only in entering the long distance market, from which AT&T was obtaining revenues to keep prices for local calls substantially below cost. (Note that such entry may not be efficient. Price in the high-profit market is above theincumbent’s marginal cost, allowing firms with higher marginal cost, but a marginal cost less than the regulated price, to enter the high-profit market.) In addition, high rates in some markets or during some time periods may
416
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
induce consumers, typically large commercial consumers, to bypass the regulated monopoly and obtain the product elsewhere. (Cream skimming is often characterized as bypass, since, for example, MCI was able to bypass the long- distance network owned by AT&T.) Again, the regulated firm sees a reduction in revenues in the high price market that were used to subsidize rates in other markets. The existence of cream-skimming and bypass combine to make the regulated monopoly less financially viable, since they are deprived of a large source of revenue yet often continue to be obligated by regulators to provide service to at least some segments of the market at low prices. Regulators in such a situation must consider several questions. For example, how much bypass should be allowed? (Recall that regulators often control entry in these situations.) Which firms should be allowed to enter? How should prices be restructured in the face of entry and bypass? The theoretical literature discussing these issues is somewhat limited. Einhorn (1987) considers a case where the potential entrants have access to a bypass technology to which the regulated monopolist does not have access. He shows that the optimal pricing structure involves the monopolist charging a usage price below marginal cost to the largest users, that is, those users most likely to bypass the monopolist. (These consumers still generate net revenue to the firm since they also pay a fixed fee.) Curien, Jullien and Rey (1998) find, similarly to the earlier work, that smaller users are charged a price above marginal cost while larger users are charged a price less than marginal cost. When bypass is regulated, too little bypass occurs, while competitive bypass (that is, free entry) leads to too much bypass. In any case, distributional effects occur, with large users gaining at the expense of either small users or taxpayers, depending on how the loss of revenue is financed (by raising prices to small users or subsidizing the monopoly with tax dollars). Laffont and Tirole (1990a) consider optimal pricing strategies given the possibility of bypass under conditions of asymmetric information. They assume two sources of asymmetric information: that the firm cannot distinguish between high and low demand customers and that the firm has superior knowledge about its technology relative to the regulator. (Einhorn, 1990b, considers asymmetric information only in the latter dimension.) The first assumption prevents a charge to high-demand customers below marginal cost, as arises in Einhorn (1987) and Curien, Jullien and Rey (1998), because the customers cannot be typed, and hence third degree price discrimination is not an option. Laffont and Tirole (1990a) find that bypass should be prevented when the regulated monopolist is efficient, and support the finding of Einhorn (1987) and Curien, Jullien and Rey (1998) that charging high demand consumers a price below marginal cost is optimal since keeping these customers contributes towards covering fixed costs through the fixed fee of a two-part tariff. They also find that low-demand consumers may benefit from
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
417
the possibility of bypass, if bypass constrains the monopolist (that is, the monopolist reduces prices in order to deter entry). Some empirical work has been done that is related to cream-skimming and bypass. One common theme has been regarding natural gas prices in regional markets. For example, De Vany and Walls (1996) and Walls (1994) find that local bypass and access to pipeline transportation lead to natural gas prices that move with field prices, as one would expect due to arbitrage. Parsons and Ward (1995) find that larger long-distance phone companies are more likely to bypass the local phone companies switched services than are smaller long-distance companies. Finally, Donald and Sappington (1995) find that as bypass activity increases, regulators are less likely to adopt incentive regulation (which is discussed in the next section), since bypass activity reduces the gains a regulated monopolist can attain by investing in cost reduction. This concludes the discussion of regulation as traditionally practiced in the US I now turn to the more recent advances in price regulation, where the UK has led the way as it moved from a system of largely nationalized firms to regulated, privatized companies.
D. Incentive Regulation 11. Introduction to Incentive Regulation In large part, the problems arising in the Averch-Johnson model are due to the fact that the regulated firms do not have an incentive to operate at minimum cost. (As discussed in Section A5, a variety of circumstances exist to mitigate the Averch-Johnson effect, such as regulatory lag and prudence reviews. However, while the deviation from cost-minimization may be reduced, in most if not all formulations of rate-of-return regulation it is not eliminated.) Prices are set such that revenues cover operating costs plus the allowed rate-of-return on investment. Thus, any cost savings will be passed on to consumers via a lower regulated price. Similarly, the firm need not worry about rising costs, because those costs will be covered with a higher regulated price. Part of the motivation behind incentive regulation is to provide the firm with the motivation to behave in a manner more consistent with the social optimum (Crew and Kleindorfer, 1996, present an overview of incentive regulation in the UK and the US). One of the earliest forms of incentive regulation, price-cap regulation, was designed to eliminate the cost disincentives other forms of price regulation had caused; an additional benefit arose because price-cap regulation reduces regulatory administrative costs (at least in theory). Thus, any cost savings are, at least in part, retained by the firm, reinstating the incentive of the firm to minimize cost. (On the other hand, because firms have more price flexibility,
418
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
they also have a greater opportunity to exercise market power.) In addition, in a pure price-cap regime, the regulated market is effectively decoupled from other markets, eliminating the inefficient incentives firms subject to rate-ofreturn regulation face in regards to entering markets in which they are not competitive. Finally, price-cap regulation may have added benefits in industries where technology is changing rapidly. Maintaining rate-of-return regulation in such situations is administratively difficult, as the regulator must convene more frequent rate hearings and has less past information on costs on which to base pricing decisions. Price-cap regulation requires less information regarding technological change to implement. (This may explain why telecommunications regulation adopted price-cap regulation more quickly than other industries. Einhorn, 1991a; Mitchell and Vogelsang, 1997; and Sappington and Weisman, 1996a provide comprehensive treatment of incentive regulation in the telecommunications industry.) Price-cap regulation was adopted in the United Kingdom in 1984 to regulate the recently privatized telecommunications industry; the United Kingdom now applies this form of regulation to gas, electricity water, as well as telecommunications. (Beesley and Littlechild, 1989, and Armstrong, Cowan and Vickers, 1994 describe incentive regulation in the United Kingdom.) It has also been adopted for use in the US, primarily in telecommunications, at the state and federal level. By 1993, thirty states had adopted a form of price-cap regulation for some industries, though generally the mechanism included an aspect of profit-sharing, as discussed in Section 14. The FCC plan divided AT&T’s products among three baskets, each subject to a price-cap, in order to reduce or eliminate cross subsidization between the baskets. Several other countries have also adopted this form of regulation, including Australia, France, Hong Kong, the Netherlands, Mexico, Germany, Sweden and Denmark. To give an idea of how price-cap regulation works in general, consider the following scenario. The regulatory agency chooses two values in setting the price-cap. The initial price-cap is chosen, P0; then the regulator chooses an adjustment term, x, so that subsequent price-caps are equal to P0! x. The adjustment term may occur at any point in time specified by the regulator; often it is an annual adjustment. During the time the price-cap is in effect, the regulated firm may either choose a price below or equal to the price-cap. (Note that the firm is granted a high degree of pricing flexibility; in particular, the firm typically acquires substantial flexibility over the structure of prices. Thus, price-cap regulated firms are relatively free to abandon cross subsidies that may have been imposed under rate-of-return regulation. In the US, subsidies to, for example, rural areas, continue in a different form: telecommunications firms are taxed, the proceedings used for direct subsidization, rather than accomplishing subsidization via the price structure.) The firm can request a rate hearing, which it might do, for example, if its costs were higher than the
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
419
price-cap. At some specified point in the future, either price-cap regulation continues with a hearing to establish a new price-cap, or the regulatory mechanism reverts to a rate-of-return approach.
12. Price-cap Regulation Cabral and Riordan (1989) set out a fairly simple model of price-cap regulation. (Vogelsang and Finsinger, 1979, derive a regulatory mechanism that is similar to price-cap regulation.) One of the key assumptions is that marginal cost is a function of an investment in cost reduction, denoted as e (for effort). A lag occurs between the investment in cost reduction and its realization, and the effect of e on cost reduction may be certain or uncertain, so long as higher effort increases the likelihood that marginal cost will fall. Let C denote the firm’s original marginal cost; the price-cap is P0! x and is set below C; and let M(C) denote the unconstrained monopoly price for a marginal cost of C. Then the price actually charged by the regulated firm, which is a function of the price-cap and of marginal cost and is denoted as B(P0! x,C), is equal to max {C, min{P0 ! x, M(C)}. If costs are above the price-cap, the firm asks the regulator for a rate hearing and essentially chooses to revert to rate-of-return regulation. If costs are below the price-cap, but not so low that the price-cap is not binding, then the firm prices at the cap. Finally, if costs are low enough that the monopoly price is less than the price-cap, M(C) < P0! x, then the firm prices at the monopoly price. The firm’s maximization problem with respect to investments in cost reduction can be written as
[(
)
] [(
)]
max e π ( P0 − x, e) = B P0 − x, C( e) − C( e) ⋅ D B P0 − x , C( e) − e,
where D[B] is the demand curve as a function of the price charged by the regulated firm. Cabral and Riordan (1989) derive several illustrative results. First, in the certainty case (that is, when the firm knows by how much marginal cost will be reduced for a given investment e), they show that if the price-cap is too tight, then the firm has no incentive to invest in cost reduction because the return to innovation is too small relative to the cost. Essentially the firm opts for rate-ofreturn regulation. Second, they show that if the price-cap is binding, then an increase in x, that is a tighter price-cap, marginally increases the investment in cost reduction. The increased incentive is caused by the fact that the tighter the price-cap, the more units the firm is selling; the aggregate increase in profits for a decline in marginal cost is higher than it would be for the same decline in marginal cost at a higher price-cap, since at the higher price-cap, a smaller quantity would be sold. In the case of uncertainty (that is, when the firm does not know the cost that will result from a given level of effort e), the results are
420
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
not as tight. They are able to show that for low values of x, the optimal choice of effort increases as does x (that is, a tighter price-cap leads to more cost reduction). In summary, Cabral and Riordan (1989) show that a firm regulated under a price-cap mechanism will have an incentive to invest in cost reduction, depending on the level of the price-cap. However, if the price-cap is too low, the firm may have no incentive to invest in cost reduction. Clemenz (1991) extends the work of Cabral and Riordan (1989) by deriving the effect of price-cap regulation on consumers and by deriving the socially optimal price-cap. (Clemenz, 1991, notes that the impact on consumers is important since, unlike economists, regulators may place a higher weight on consumer welfare than producer welfare.) Cabral and Riordan’s (1989) basic results are confirmed: in a finite horizon model, price-cap regulation gives the firm larger incentives to reduce cost than does rate-ofreturn regulation and achieves higher social welfare. These conclusions are even stronger in an infinite horizon setting. Clemenz (1991) also shows that price-cap regulation is capable not only of raising welfare in general but also in increasing consumer surplus. Sibley (1989) and Lewis and Sappington (1989) derive the optimal regulatory policy in a given environment characterized by asymmetric information; the optimal regulatory mechanism is similar to price-cap regulation. Sibley (1989) assumes the firm has full information about technology and demand while regulators have no information; he also assumes that regulators can observe lagged expenditures by the firm, prices, and outputs. Sibley’s (1989) scheme is derived such that it leads to efficient pricing and input usage; the optimal scheme is remarkably similar to a price-cap regime. Lewis and Sappington (1989) present a model in which the regulated firm has private information about its capabilities and cost-reducing activities. The endogenously-determined optimal regulatory policy includes a form of pricecap regulation as a component (firms are offered a choice between price-cap regulation and a regulatory regime that shares gains with consumers). They suggest that while price-cap regulation may be superior in some environments, it may not be in others, and hence should be considered as part of the optimal regulatory regime. A number of papers have considered the effect of price-cap regulation on the structure of prices. In the multi-product setting, price-cap regulation is generally implemented by imposing a price index on a basket of goods, giving the firm the freedom to adjust the price structure. A possible additional benefit arising from price-cap regulation is that the firm will choose prices across products in a way that will lead prices to have a Ramsey-Boiteux structure, which allows the firm to cover costs in the most efficient manner (that is, at the smallest deadweight loss). Bradley and Price (1988) and Vogelsang (1989) have demonstrated this result. Others, however, have shown that the result is not general. For example, Neu (1993) finds that prices approach a Ramsey-
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
421
Boiteux structure only in certain situations, such as under static conditions. By example he shows that under a number of parameter conditions relating to differential growth in demand, differential price elasticities, and different shares across services, prices will diverge from the Ramsey-Boiteux structure. Fraser (1995) finds that cost increases for a firm’s products can cause prices to diverge from the Ramsey-Boiteux structure if the cost increases or demand elasticities are not uniform. However, if additional cost changes do not occur and the previous period outputs are used as weights in the price-cap, then prices will converge to the Ramsey-Boiteux structure. He concludes that only when cost changes are recurring will price diverge from the Ramsey-Boiteux structure on a continuing basis. Bradley (1993) points out that, since the definition of commodity bundles is largely endogenous (for example, should day time rates end at 4pm, 5pm, or 6pm?) and under the influence if not sole discretion of the regulated firms, the definitions may be manipulated in such a way that Laspeyres quantity based price-caps may very well not lead to an efficient Ramsey-Boiteux price structure. (The role of indices is discussed in the next section.) Thus, price-cap regulation can give firms a larger incentive to invest in cost reduction than does rate-of-return regulation and the price structure may approach the second best Ramsey-Boiteux prices, and there is some evidence that price-cap regulation is, or can be, part of the optimal regulatory mechanism.
13. Problems and Extensions of Price-cap Regulation While the discussion above casts a positive light on price-cap regulation and its effects on innovation and efficiency, subsequent theoretical work and experience from the implementation of price-cap regulation suggest that it is not the panacea that it once seemed. Problems arise in terms of the proper calculation of the price index, the optimal pricing structure, the impact on quality, and the end game and renegotiation problems. Typically the price-cap is implemented as requiring that a price index of the different products be below the price-cap; at issue are the weights used to form the price index. Law (1993) shows that Laspeyres index price-cap regulation under revenue weights causes the firm to price in order to manipulate the weights in such a way that reduces consumer and increases producer welfare in the first period and may reduce consumer welfare in the second period. Foreman (1995) extends the analysis to indicate when and why such weight manipulation incurs. Suppose the price-cap is set in the following way
422
ji
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
pt i
i
pt&1
i
i
×
5200
pt&1 xt&1
i ji (pt&1 xt&1) i
# 1 % CPI & x,
where pti is the price of good i in period t, xti is the quantity sold of good i in period t, CPI is the consumer price index, and x is the productivity change. The second term in brackets is the weight; it is defined as last period’s revenues from good i as a fraction of last period’s total revenues. In essence, by considering the effect of price charged today on the index set tomorrow, the firm may be able to earn higher profits tomorrow. For example, by setting a low price for a service today, the weight on the service tomorrow will be reduced when demand is inelastic (as is typical for telecommunication services). The more inelastic demand, the more sensitive are relative revenue shares to small price changes. Even small price changes manipulate the weights sufficiently that profits increase but social welfare declines. He shows that replacing the revenue weights with quantity weights reduces the effect of weight manipulation, especially as demand becomes less elastic. (Further discussion of index issues is contained in Cowan, 1997; Diewert, 1993; and Vickers and Yarrow, 1988a.) Sappington and Sibley (1992) consider another type of index manipulation; they analyze the effect of price-cap regulation as the FCC planned to implement for AT&T on the firm’s incentive to engage in strategic, non-linear pricing. In their model, the firm sells a single-product and can use two-part tariffs. The price-cap index is represented as
pt %
Et Qt&1
# p0,
where E is the fixed part of the two-part tariff, p is the per unit charge, and Q is the quantity sold. In other words, average revenue in period t, based on prices charged in t and on quantities sold in t!1, must be below the price-cap. They show that incentives are created for the firm to offer a two-part tariff rather than a uniform price, and that such pricing can reduce consumers’ and total surplus. They identify two welfare-improving modifications. First, the index could be specified as a function of the quantities sold in the initial period (replace Qt!1 with Q0). This eliminates the incentive of the firm to reduce the usage charge today (increasing Qt!1) so that the fixed fee can be increased in the future. The second alternative, which increases welfare even more (and never
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
423
reduces consumer surplus) is to require the firm to allow consumers the option to purchase under the original tariff terms before price-cap regulation was implemented. Armstrong and Vickers (1991) consider another aspect of the role of price structure in a price-cap regulatory scheme. They are interested in whether a multi-product monopolist should be allowed to price discriminate across customer classes, and find that the answer depends on whether a price-cap index is calculated using weights in proportion to demands at uniform prices or whether there is a cap applied to average revenue. Armstrong, Cowan and Vickers (1995) consider how a firm facing a price-cap based on average revenue sets the price structure. (Unlike Sappington and Sibley, 1992, the price-cap is based on prices and quantities this period, so the incentive to set prices this period with an eye to how it would affect the cap next period is eliminated.) They also consider a case where the firm must offer consumers the option of buying at the uniform price. The firm prefers the average revenue constraint to the option constraint, and, of course, likes uniform pricing the least. Consumers overall prefer the option constraint, while ranking the average revenue constraint the least. However, welfare under the various schemes is ambiguous. The effect of price-cap regulation on quality seems to be a potentially large problem since a decline in quality is in essence a disguised increase in price. (Fraser, 1994, reports that since July 1992, the Australian regulatory body AUSTEL has included quality of service in its evaluation of whether prices have risen in its regulation of Telecom Australia.) Fraser (1994) considers the effect of price-cap regulation on reliability of supply in electric supply; in other words, he incorporates possible changes in the degree of quality when a firm is regulated under a price-cap. He considers two regulatory regimes: in one, the regulator does not incorporate changes in reliability; and in the other, changes in reliability are incorporated into the price-cap. In the latter case, a weighted average of the change in price and the change in reliability must be less than the cap. When reliability is not included in the index, the firm may protect profits by lowering reliability if cost increases must be absorbed (the price-cap is binding). However, when the price-cap is not binding, the firm may increase reliability, given the positive relationship between reliability and price. Including reliability in the price index eliminates the problem of lower reliability when the price-cap is binding, but introduces a new problem of over pricing when the price-cap is not binding. Thus, whichever way the price-cap is formulated, price-cap regulation affects the quality of the service. Implementation of price-cap regulation has revealed two related, large problems: what is to prevent the regulator from renegotiating the regulatory compact, and how is the end game problem resolved. Part of the reason pricecap regulation works to achieve reductions in cost is by allowing the firm to keep (at least some of) the gains from cost reduction. For this incentive to
424
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
work, the regulator must credibly commit not to intervene during the period in which the price-cap is to be in effect. However, such a commitment may not be credible, especially if profits from cost savings rise ‘too much’. If profits rise greatly, the regulatory agency may face pressure from consumer groups to revise the level of the price-cap. In the UK, the electricity distribution regulator decided in June 1995 to revise price-caps, only two months after they had been set, in part because of the gains in productivity (see Studness, 1995) and ‘previously unsuspected financial strength’. Thus, the commitment not to intervene for five years did not even last three months. If regulated firms believe that price-caps will be revised to appropriate the gain from cost savings, or even if there is a chance that revision may occur, then their incentive to invest in cost savings is reduced. Isaac (1991) considers the problems that may arise when a firm will be regulated under a price-cap for some known, finite period of time, after which rate-of-return regulation will be implemented. He identifies several potential end game problems. First, the firm may manipulate the system by shifting costs into the future. Second, the regulator faces two commitment problems: a commitment not to change the price-cap or intervene in price setting during the price-cap period, and also not use the rate review when moving to rate-ofreturn regulation to appropriate profits earned by the firm during the price-cap regime. (He discusses these problems in light of the experience of regulation of the Tucson Electric Power Company during the 1980s.) While several authors have identified these issues as potential problems, not much theoretical work has tackled the issue, with the exception of Armstrong, Rees and Vickers (1995). They derive a model of price-cap regulation with an endogenously determined length of time until the next review. (Most models assume that the price-cap lasts for an exogenously given amount of time and do not consider the effects of a future change in regime on behavior under the current regime.) They identify the following trade off: the longer the amount of time between reviews, the more likely it is the price will be low at the next review, as firms have a higher pay off to investing in cost reduction because they retain profits for a longer period, but the longer is the amount of time during which the price is high. The higher the initial cost when price-cap regulation is implemented, the more likely the former effect is to dominate the latter. They also demonstrate that demand elasticity and the effectiveness of investments in cost reduction are key determinants of the optimal interval between hearings. Weisman (1993) theoretically analyzes the effect of renegotiation on firm behavior. Given a non zero probability that the regulator will rewrite the regulatory contract and assuming that the probability increases in the regulated firm’s profits, the firm has an incentive to engage in pure waste. In that way the firm may be able to reduce the likelihood of the regulator imposing more stringent regulation. (Sappington, 1980, shows a similar result with respect to
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
425
Vogelsang and Finsinger’s 1979 regulatory mechanism.) Thus, while price-cap regulation does have the benefit of increasing the incentive to firms to invest in cost reduction, it induces a variety of new problems. I now turn to other forms of incentive regulation that may offer improvements to straight price-cap regulation.
14. Alternative Forms of Incentive Regulation While price-cap regulation is the most commonly discussed and used form of incentive regulation, a few alternatives have been considered as well. The most common alternative is some form of profit-sharing, under which the firm retains some fraction of its profits and rebates the remaining fraction to consumers. Indeed, given the practical problems that arose under price-cap regulation in the UK, profit-sharing regulation was often put forward as a superior regulatory regime that should be adopted. Mayer and Vickers (1996) point out that many of the existing problems would remain under profit-sharing and other, more serious, problems would arise in addition. An alternative often used in the US is a combination price-cap/rate-ofreturn/profit-sharing approach to regulation. For example, most US states that have adopted price-cap regulation have included a provision whereby the firm is also subject to a rate-of-return constraint, the form of which Braeutigam and Panzar (1993) term ‘sliding scale’. (In 1992, 22 of 48 states with regional Bell operating companies used a form of sliding scale/price-cap regulation, while 19 states continued with traditional rate-of-return regulation.) Under these provisions, the firm is allowed pricing flexibility below the price-cap, provided that the rate-of-return is not above its cap. (In some states adjustments may be made if the firm’s rate-of-return falls below a floor, as well.) As the rate-ofreturn rises above the cap, the firm is entitled to a smaller and smaller portion of the increase in profits, typically refunding the rest to consumers. One immediate implication pointed out by Braeutigam and Panzar (1993) is that such an approach eliminates one benefit to price-cap regulation: savings in administrative costs. Under such a hybrid approach, the regulator will still need to calculate rates of return, with all its attendant problems. Lyon (1996b), using numerical techniques, shows that adding a profitsharing mechanism to price-caps always increases expected welfare relative to pure price-caps. Welfare may be increased by large amounts of profit-sharing and by allowing firms a greater share of gains than of losses. Profit-sharing is particularly beneficial if the firm’s initial costs are high and cost innovations are difficult to achieve. However, Weisman (1994) shows that the firm prefers profit-sharing to pure price-cap regulation. In essence, this form of regulation gives the regulatory agency an incentive not to take adverse actions against the
426
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
firm, since such actions also harm the regulatory agency via the profit-sharing arrangement. Weisman (1993) considers a ‘modified price-cap’ regulatory regime, which he views as more accurately describing the type of price-cap regulation that has been implemented in the US. Under this regime, the regulator sets a price-cap in the regulated (‘core’) market and allows the firm to retain only part of the profits generated. However, the firm also operates in unregulated (‘non core’) markets as well. To undertake profit-sharing, costs must be allocated across the core and non core markets. Given the difficulty in allocating costs (see the discussion in Section C7), distortions are generated. This type of pricecap/profit-sharing regulation can reduce welfare compared to rate-of-return regulation applied to one market (which also requires that costs be allocated across regulated and unregulated markets). (Braeutigam and Panzar, 1989, early recognized that price-cap regulation can in principle cause a firm to produce efficiently in non core markets and enter these markets only if efficient. However, they analyze a regulatory regime of pure price-cap regulation without profit-sharing, so the problem of allocation of common costs is totally eliminated.)
15. Comparison of Incentive-based Regulation to Other Forms of Price Regulation Cabral and Riordan (1989) and Clemenz (1991) derive models of price-cap regulation and then proceed to compare the outcomes to several alternative regulatory regimes. Cabral and Riordan (1989) compare cost-based (rate-ofreturn) regulation with regulatory lag and price-cap regulation. Because there is regulatory lag in their formulation of cost-based regulation, the firm has some incentive to reduce cost. Any increase in profits between the time of cost reduction and the time of the new rate hearing are kept by the firm. However, the longer regulatory lag and the price flexibility increase the incentive to reduce costs relative to the incentive under rate-of-return regulation with regulatory lag. Cabral and Riordan (1989) also compare the level of price under the two alternatives. Under cost-based regulation, at each rate hearing the price is set to cover costs. If the price-cap is initially set below the price that would obtain under cost-based regulation (as it must if the firm is to have an incentive to reduce costs), then for a period prices will be lower under price-cap regulation than under cost-based regulation. However, in future periods the price under price-cap regulation may be higher. Continuing in the same vein, Pint (1992) considers two differences in pricecap regulation and rate-of-return regulation. She points out that, under pricecap regulation as implemented in the UK, hearings occur at fixed intervals and
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
427
use all information available since the previous hearing, while under rate-ofreturn regulation as implemented in the US, hearings occur only when requested (typically by the firm) and utilize information from a single test year (usually the most recent year for which complete data is available). Assuming that regulation of either form is binding, the firm chooses the level of capital stock, the level of managerial effort (which reduces costs), and, under rate-ofreturn regulation, when to request a new rate hearing. Both forms of regulation lead to an over investment in capital and underinvestment in effort, especially during periods when cost data are gathered for hearings. Pint (1992) shows that rate-of-return regulation can be improved by using fixed intervals between hearings (continuingto use test year data) if the intervals are not too short, and the welfare gains are primarily realized by the firm. If data on costs since the last hearing are used in conjunction with fixed intervals, welfare increases dramatically, with gains going to consumers (indeed, profits fall). Thus, two aspects of price-cap regulation are seen to increase welfare. (Weisman, 1993, and Baron, 1991, also discuss the degree to which price-cap regulation in practice differs from rate-of-return regulation. Weisman, 1993, points out that in practice (in telecommunications in the US) price-cap regulation involves an element of cost-based regulation. As a result, greater distortions may arise under the hybrid form of regulation than result from pure cost-based regulation.) Several papers use simulation techniques to compare various regulatory regimes and the degree to which welfare may be increased. Schmalensee (1989a) considers a variety of regulatory regimes, including price-cap regulation, imposed on a risk-neutral, single-product monopolist. He considers what he terms linear regimes, which can be written as P = ? + ?(C ! a), where P is the regulated price, ? is the base price, ? the cost sharing fraction, C is observed cost, and a is the expected unit cost under the pre reform regulatory regime. That is, any change in cost is passed on linearly to price; the higher is ?, the more responsive price is to changes in cost. He finds that price-cap regulation is inferior to cost-based regulation over a wide range of plausible parameter values. While, as many have shown, price-cap regulation provides a higher incentive to invest in cost reduction, if uncertainty is sufficiently high, the price-cap must be set at such a high level to keep the firm profitable that welfare declines. Gasmi, Ivaldi and Laffont (1994) also use simulation techniques to compare welfare under a variety of regulatory regimes, including a price-cap mechanism and price-cap regulation in conjunction with profitsharing. They characterize their main findings as: (1) pure price-cap regulation leaves substantial rents to the firm; (2) introducing downward price flexibility improves the efficiency of price-cap regulation relative to Schmalensee’s (1989a) best linear regulatory regime; and (3) profit-sharing often yields welfare near the optimal regulated level by partially correcting the distribution distortion of a pure price-cap scheme.
428
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
Several works have theoretically examined the performance of price-cap regulation with other types of regulation, and have found it useful to deviate from pure price-cap regulation. For example, performance may be enhanced by offering alternative regulatory mechanisms or alternative pricing schemes, respectively. Lewis and Sappington (1989) suggest that firms should be offered a choice between a variation on price-cap regulation and a profit-sharing form of regulation, with gains going to consumers. Sibley (1989) finds that the regulator uses slagged profits to design its own two-part tariff, and the firm will offer its two-part tariff as well as the regulator’s two-part tariff as an option to consumers. Finally, Schmalensee (1989a) finds that several regulatory mechanisms that are simpler than price-caps can achieve the same gains, particularly if the regulator weights consumer surplus highly. To recapitulate, theoretical work suggests that some form of incentive regulation can be used to improve the outcome relative to traditional cost-based methods of regulation. However, analysis also shows that, as implemented, incentive regulation often does not replace cost-based methods, and thus new problems arise. Whether incentive-based regulation is superiod to cost-based regulation in practice remains to be seen.
16. Empirical Analysis of the Effect of Incentive Regulation The increasing use of incentive-based regulation has provided economists with a wide range of natural experiments for empirically analyzing the effect of incentive-based regulation on prices, costs and welfare. (Sappington and Weisman, 1996b, concentrating on the telecommunications industry, identify some of the problems that can arise in attempting to do such empirical work, and suggest ways to avoid these problems.) Kridel, Sappington and Weisman (1996) review empirical work on incentive regulation in telecommunications, while Xavier (1995) provides a descriptive narrative of the impact of price-cap regulation in telecommunications, especially in Australia, the UK, and the US. In general, the results have been very encouraging. Productivity, investment in infrastructure, and new service offerings have increased. Prices have generally remained stable or declined slightly, and quality has not declined. However, there is no evidence that incentive-based regulation has led to reduced administrative costs. Face (1988) examines the use of price-cap regulation for Michigan Bell, estimating that costs savings in 1982 amounted to about $40 million relative to that which would have occurred under rate-of-return regulation. Majumdar (1997) focuses on the impact of incentive regulation on productivity for the case of US local exchange carriers. He finds that pure price-cap regulation leads to
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
429
an increase in technical efficiency, but only with a lag; price-cap regulation in conjunction with profit-sharing leads to a smaller but immediate impact on technical efficiency; and finally that a pure profit-sharing scheme actually harms technical efficiency. Mathios and Rogers (1989) find that prices in states that regulated AT&T using a price-cap are 7 to 10 percent lower than in states that use rate-of-return regulation. They use variation in state regulatory mechanisms with a simple price-cap/not price-cap dummy variable. The results are sugges tive, but more detailed analysis taking into account the detailed differences in the different state regulatory mechanisms would be desirable. Despite the variety of problems identified by the theory regarding the implementation of incentive regulation, the empirical studies to date suggest that implementation has led to substantial gains.
E. Regulation of Networks 17. Introduction to the Issues As competition has been introduced into at least some areas of industries that have long been regulated, a new industry structure is arising. The new structure consists of a situation where a regulated firm controls an essential facility, generally a physical network, to which competitors must have access in order to compete with the regulated firm in at least some markets. For example, in the US much of the competition in local telephone service, at least initially, is expected to come from firms that lease access from the regulated local phone company on which the competitor can send calls. The question is how to appropriately price access to the essential facility. The first-best solution, marginal cost pricing, is generally not feasible because the regulated firm will not recover sufficient revenues to cover the fixed cost of providing the network. (Typically, provision of the network remains a regulated monopoly due to economics of scale.) Thus, the relevant question for economists and the regulator is how to efficiently structure prices subject to the constraint that the regulated firm cover its costs. Why is regulation necessary in this situation? The economic justification continues to be to reduce the deadweight loss that arises under monopoly. However, the issue is more complicated because the owner of the network competes with others in sectors that are potentially competitive. (When AT&T was broken up, the initial industry structure prohibited the regional operating companies (local service) from competing in these potentially competitive markets (long distance). With the Telecommunications Act of 1996 and deregulation of electricity in the US, the exclusion of network owners from the competitive sectors is declining.) A natural incentive arises for network owners to price access to the network in such a way to give itself an advantage in the
430
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
competitive sectors. Another important issue regards the overall regulatory structure and how the competitive market/sector fits in. For example, if prices are high in some potentially competitive sectors in order to subsidize regulated sectors, as was done in the US with regard to long-distance and local service, respectively, then the effect of access/entry on the ability of the firm to maintain such price subsidies must be considered. Thus, the same sustainability issues discussed in Section 10 arise again. I now describe the work that has attempted to characterize the optimal access price.
18. Access Pricing Baumol and Sidak (1994a) describe the traditional (in the US until the early 1980s) approach for pricing access. Suppose that a regulated firm earns T from a particular service towards its overall revenue shortfall, defined as the difference between total incremental revenue less total incremental cost. Asuming that the price for the final product is fixed, the traditional approach assigns an access fee equal to the average incremental cost of providing access to the competitive firm plus a charge that would leave the regulated firm with its market share weighted share of T. That is, if upon granting access a firm is expected to keep two thirds of the market, then the total price for access will be such that the regulated firm earns in total two-thirds of T. However, in this situation the firm is not ade quately compensated for its common fixed costs. In addition, inefficient entry may occur. The entrant essentially does not have to cover as large a portion of fixed costs as does the regulated firm, and hence can still profitably enter even if its average incremental cost is higher than the regulated firms. To remedy the entry inefficiency induced by the traditional approach, Baumol, Sidak and Willig have proposed perhaps the most commonly known and used access pricing rule, the efficient component pricing rule (ECPR) or the Baumol-Willig rule. (The rule is generally attributed to Willig, 1979, and Baumol, 1983, and is extensively discussed by Baumol and Sidak, 1994a and 1994c. It has been used in the US by the Interstate Commerce Commission in the rail industry since the early 1980s, by the California Public Utilities Commission in local telephone service since 1989, and in New Zealand in the telecommunications industry since the early 1990s.) Essentially, the rule proposes that access to essential facilities should be priced at the direct cost of providing access plus the opportunity cost to the regulated firm of granting access to a competitor. The opportunity cost to the incumbent is the profit that would have been earned had the incumbent supplied the final product rather than the entering firms. One of the benefits of such a rule is that it leads to efficient entry. In other words, no firm will enter the competitive market unless its marginal cost is less than or equal to the marginal cost of the incumbent regulated firm. Kahn and Taylor (1994) point out an additional potential
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
431
benefit. By including the regulated firm’s opportunity cost in the access charge, subsidies mandated by regulators can be maintained. (I call this a potential benefit since many of these cross-subsidies are not efficient. However, this is not always the case, as in Ramsey-Boiteux pricing.) For example, in the days of a common local and long-distance regulated firm, high prices in longdistance service were used to subsidize rates for local service. As discussed in Section 10, entry into the high-profit markets can make the regulatory regime unstable; access pricing under the ECPR can allow entry but sustain the regulatory regime by maintaining the contribution towards the fixed costs provided by that service. A number of critiques of the ECPR have arisen. In particular, several have questioned the generality of the rule, noting that its efficiency result is contingent on a number of rather strict assumptions. Baumol and Sidak (1994a) and Kahn and Taylor (1994) note that the ECPR gives the efficient solution to pricing access subject to the assumption that the price of the final product is subject to effective regulation or effective competition. Economides and White (1995) develop a rigorous model analyzing the efficiency of the ECPR in the case where the firm that controls the essential facility has market power in the potentially competitive market. They assume that the price for the final product is not regulated, and that the incumbent therefore is able to charge the full monopoly price. Their argument reduces to the point that entry of an inefficient firm, that is a firm with marginal costs above that of the regulated incumbent, can be socially beneficial if entry sufficiently reduces the deadweight loss that arises when the regulated monopolist prices above marginal cost for the final product, while the ECPR in this circumstance acts to protect the monopolist from any competitive challenge. Economides and White (1995) show that under Bertrand or Cournot competition in the final product market, the gain from increased competition can offset some degree of inefficiency on the part of the entrant. The criticisms of the ECPR highlight an important aspect of the debate: whether the ECPR is efficient depends crucially on the overall regulatory environment, technology, and demand. Is the price for the final product effectively regulated? Laffont and Tirole (1996) emphasize this point: ‘A discussion of an access rule without reference to the rest of the regulatory environment has limited interest. The quality of an access pricing rule depends on the determination of prices for the final products.’ Are products perfect substitutes? Is technology subject to constant returns to scale? It seems clear that the ECPR does not have the wide applicability first claimed. Indeed, many show that while the ECPR arises as a special case of the optimal access rule in certain circumstances, more often than not the optimal access rule may be higher or lower than the EPCR. Armstrong, Doyle and Vickers (1996) take the ECPR as their framework and analyze how the opportunity cost should be properly measured under
432
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
different assumptions regarding demand and supply. They begin with the clear-cut case where the final product is homogeneous; inputs, including access, are used in fixed proportions; no bypass is possible, that is, access is a necessary input into production of the final product and cannot be obtained from any source except the incumbent; and the entrant is a price taker. They then relax some of these assumptions, allowing for product differentiation, variable proportions, and the possibility of bypass. They show that under these new assumptions, the optimal access charge is less than the access charge suggested by the ECPR, because under these assumptions the opportunity cost of access is reduced as the incumbent loses fewer final product sales given entry. However, they also point out that the optimal access charge can be interpreted as an extension of the ECPR, taking into account the ‘displacement ratio’, which is the change in the incumbent’s final product sales over the change in sales of access to competitors as the access price changes slightly. (They also show that, when incorporating the firm’s budget constraint, a positive RamseyBoiteux price must be added to the access charge, so that the optimal price subject to the budget constraint is higher than the ECPR access price.) They also show that, when the opportunity cost is analyzed properly, the informational demands of the ECPR are not as low as others have argued; in particular, proper calculation of the opportunity cost requires information regarding demand and supply elasticities. Armstrong, Doyle and Vickers (1998) consider access pricing in the situation where the price of the final product is not regulated, given that that is the direction in which many industries are headed. They find that, with linear demand and linear competitive supply, and no binding break-even constraint, the optimal price for access is set at marginal cost. More generally the relationship between the optimal access price and marginal cost is ambiguous. In essence the same trade-off identified in Economides and White (1995) is present: setting a high access price raises the price of the final product, resulting in the standard allocative inefficiency associated with monopoly pricing, but it reduces the margin available to competitors, reducing inefficient supply and increasing productive efficiency. Laffont and Tirole (1994) derive the optimal access price in a wide variety of situations and under pretty general conditions: degrees of effort exerted by the incumbent in operating the network, private information on the part of the incumbent regarding technology, various informational regimes, the presence and absence of government transfers, various degrees of market power on the part of the entrant, various regulatory regimes, and under the possibility of bypass. They also compare the optimal access price to that suggested by the ECPR. They identify the following assumptions as necessary to ensure the efficiency of the ECPR: (1) the regulated firm’s price for the final product is based on marginal-cost pricing; (2) the products produced by the regulated firm and the entrant are perfect substitutes; (3) production of the final product is
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
433
characterized by constant returns to scale; (4) the entrant has no market power; and (5) the regulated firm’s marginal cost can be accurately observed. If any of these fail to hold, then the access price must be adjusted from the ECPR level to achieve efficiency. Larson and Lehman (1997) demonstrate that ECPR pricing can be derived as a special case of Ramsey-Boiteux pricing with interdependent demands, but also show that ECPR is not always efficient. In particular, in order for a Ramsey-Boiteux pricing structure to arise, the following assumptions must hold: (1) entrants must have a fixed proportions technology; (2) the essential facility must be strict, that is have a zero elasticity of substitutions for other inputs; (3) perfect competition must exist in the non essential inputs; (4) the regulated firm and entrants must face the same elasticity of demand for the final product; (5) the entrants set price at the level charged by the regulated firm; (6) Bertrand competition ensues in the downstream market, which in combination with assumption (5) results in equal market shares for the regulated firm and entrants; and (7) there is symmetry of weighted income effects. They then discuss the many reasons why these assumptions are likely to be violated. Finally, Laffont and Tirole (1996) consider a completely different approach to regulating interconnection. They suggest that access be regulated under a global price-cap. Under this approach, the price-cap would apply the weighted sum of price changes for final products and price changes for intermediate products sold to rivals, including access. They argue that one benefit is that it requires no more informational requirements than existing regulatory policies. The firm will adopt the optimal Ramsey-Boiteux price structure given its information about demand and cost; the regulator does not require information on marginal costs nor demand elasticities. (Ramsey-Boiteux prices obtain so long as all goods, including access, are included in the definition of the price cap and the weights are exogenously set at the level of output to be realized.) They also consider a global price-cap that also imposes the ECPR as a price ceiling on the access price, though the informational requirements of the ECPR are severe under more realistic assumptions, as shown by Armstrong, Doyle and Vickers (1998). The benefits identified by Laffont and Tirole (1996) from adding an ECPR price ceiling is to provide a better setting of the weights in the price-cap and to limit predatory behavior (the incumbent may increase the access price and reduce the final output price, squeezing out entrants) by tying the access and output prices. The theoretical work suggests that a general approach to pricing access at the direct marginal cost of access plus the opportunity cost is appropriate. However, it appears that calculating the opportunity cost is not as easy as originally proposed. In addition, the work illustrates the importance of taking into account the entire regulatory regime, including the regime covering the competitive sector. (I found no empirical work regarding access prices.)
434
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
F. Conclusion 19. Regulation in Practice As regulation theory has advanced, especially in the last decade or two, regulation in practice has changed tremendously. The US saw immense deregulation occur beginning in the 1970s, mostly in industries that were never believed to be natural monopolies but had been regulated for other reasons. (For example, regulation of trucking in the US largely developed in order to protect regulation of railroads, which were thought to be natural monopolies.) In particular, deregulation occurred in railroad and trucking, air passenger transportation, natural gas, electricity, telecommunications, and cable television. (About the only move in the US in the opposite direction was the 1992 Cable Consumer Protection and Competition Act, which re regulated cable television in response to the increase in cable prices after deregulation in the Cable Communications Policy Act of 1984. It is not clear how regulation affected the quality adjusted price; Hazlett, 1993, for example, believes the quality-adjusted price declined under deregulation, while Otsuka, 1997, suggests that the quality- adjusted price was kept low under regulation. However, cable was rederegulated with the passage of the Telecommunications Act of 1996.) Other countries have seen an impressive move away from handling natural monopolies by nationalizing them to regulation of privatized firms. These countries, especially the United Kingdom, have led the way towards the use of incentive regulation. Not only has the US moved towards deregulation, but the form of regulation has been changing rapidly over the 1980s and 1990s. There is a general movement away from cost-based regulation towards incentive-based regulation, in an effort to achieve a better outcome. The United Kingdom led the way with adoption of price-cap regulation in 1984, after privatizing its telecommunications industry. Privatization of other industries spread the use of price-cap regulation to electricity, gas and water. Price-cap regulation in practice in the United Kingdom has included a bit of a mix of cost-based regulation. For example, gas, water and electricity utilities can pass on increases in costs of inputs outside their control. Nonetheless, this method of regulation has proved to be revolutionary, leading to changes in the approach to regulation in many countries.
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
435
Acknowledgments I gratefully acknowledge the comments of Ken Boyer and of an anonymous referee. Their comments significantly improved the content and organization of the paper and extended the bibliography. Chris Haan, Vivian Lei and Aaron White provided valuable assistance in compiling the bibliography.
Bibliography on Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview (5200) Abbott, Thomas A., III (1995), ‘Price Regulation in the Pharmaceutical Industry: Prescription or Placebo?’, 14 Journal of Health Economics, 551-565. Acton, Jan Paul and Mitchell, Bridger M. (1980), ‘Evaluating Time-of-Day Electricity Rates for Residential Customers’, in Mitchell, Bridger M. and Kleindorfer, Paul R. (eds), International Symposium on Public Policy for Regulated Monopolies and Public Enterprises: European and United States Perspectives, Lexington, Lexington Books. Acton, Jan Paul and Vogelsang, Ingo (1989), ‘Price-Cap Regulation: Introduction’, 20 Rand Journal of Economics, 369-372. Aigner, Dennis J. (1984), ‘The Welfare Econometrics of Peak-Load Pricing for Electricity: Editor’s Introduction’, 26 Journal of Econometrics, 1-15. Aigner, Dennis J. (1985), ‘The Residential Electricity Time-of-Use Pricing Experiments: What Have We Learned?’, in Hausman, Jerry A. and Wise, D.A. (eds), Social Experimentation, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Aigner, Dennis J. and Lillard, Lee A. (1984), ‘Measuring Peak-Load Pricing Response from Experimental Data: An Exploratory Analysis’, 2 Journal of Business and Economic Statistics, 21-39. Allen, Bruce W. (1986), ‘Ramsey Pricing in the Transportation Industries’, 13 International Journal of Transport Economics, 293-330. Amit, Eilon (1981), ‘On Quality and Price Regulation under Competition and under Monopoly’, 47 Southern Economic Journal, 1056-1062. Anderson, Richard K. and Enomoto, Carl E. (1986), ‘Product Quality and Price Regulation: A General Equilibrium Analysis’, 53 Economica, 87-95. Andrade, Thompson Almeida (1995), ‘A Oferta Privada de Servicos Publicos e a Determinacao de Precos com Objetivos Sociais’, 25 Pesquisa e Planejamento Economico, 223-240. Annable, James E. (1973), ‘The ICC, the IBT, and the Cartelization of the American Trucking Industry’, 13 Quarterly Review of Economics and Business, 33-47. Appelbaum, Elic and Harris, Richard G. (1982), Capital Accumulation and Investment in the Regulated Firm, Working Paper, University of Western Ontaria and Queens University. Armstrong, Mark and Vickers, John S. (1991), ‘Welfare Effects of Price Discrimination by a Regulated Monopolist’, 22 Rand Journal of Economics, 571-580. Armstrong, Mark and Vickers, John S. (1996), ‘Regulatory Reform in Telecommunications in Central and Eastern Europe’, 4 Economics of Transition, 295-318. Armstrong, Mark, Cowan, Simon and Vickers, John S. (1994), Regulatory Reform: Economic Analysis and British Experience, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Armstrong, Mark, Cowan, Simon and Vickers, John S. (1995), ‘Nonlinear Pricing and Price-Cap
436
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
Regulation’, 58 Journal of Public Economics, 33-55. Armstrong, Mark, Doyle, Chris and Vickers, John S. (1996), ‘The Access Problem: A Synthesis’, 44 Journal of Industrial Economics, 131-150. Armstrong, Mark, Doyle, Chris and Vickers, John S. (1998), ‘The Access Pricing Problem with Deregulation: A Note’, 46 Journal of Industrial Economics, 115-121. Armstrong, Mark, Rees, Ray and Vickers, John S. (1995), ‘Optimal Regulatory Lag under Price-Cap Regulation’, 0(S) Revista Española de Economía, 93-116. Ashraf, Javed and Sabih, Farhan (1992), ‘Welfare Implications of Ramsey-Boiteux Pricing of Electricity in Pakistan’, 17 Journal of Energy and Development, 279-290. Atkinson, Anthony B. and Waverman, L. (1973), ‘Resource Allocation and the Regulated Firm: Comment’, 4 Bell Journal of Economics. Atkinson, Scott E. and Halvorsen, Robert (1980), ‘A Test of Relative and Absolute Price Efficiency in Regulated Industries’, 62 Review of Economics and Statistics, 81-88. Averch H. and Johnson, L.L. (1962), ‘Behavior of the Firm Under Regulatory Constraint’, 52 American Economic Review, 1053-1069. Bailey, Elizabeth E. (1972), ‘Peak-load Pricing Under Regulatory Constraint’, 80 Journal of Political Economy, 662-679. Bailey, Elizabeth E. (1973), Economic Theory of Regulatory Constraint, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Bailey, Elizabeth E. (1976), ‘Innovation and Regulation: A Reply’, 5 Journal of Public Economics, 393-394. Bailey, Elizabeth E. (1981), ‘Contestability and the Design of Regulatory and Antitrust Policy’, 71 American Economic Review, 178-183. Bailey, Elizabeth E. (1986), ‘Deregulation: Causes and Consequences’, 234 Science, 1211-1216. Bailey, Elizabeth E. and Coleman, R.D. (1971), ‘The Effect of Lagged Regulation in the Averch-Johnson Model’, 2 Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, 278-292. Bailey, Elizabeth E. and Malone, J. (1970), ‘Resource Allocation and the Regulated Firm’, 1 Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, 129-142. Bailey, Elizabeth E. and White, Lawrence J. (1974), ‘Reversals in Peak and Off-Peak Prices’, 5 Bell Journal of Economics, 75-92. Bailey, Elizabeth E., Graham, David R. and Kaplan, David P. (1985), Deregulating the Airlines, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Barcella, Mary L. (1984), ‘In Defense of Price Controls for ‘Old’ Natural Gas’, 19 Business Economics, 24-33. Barnes, David W. and Stout, Lynn A. (1992), Economic Foundations of Regulation and Antitrust Law, St Paul, West Publishing. Baron, David P. (1981), ‘Price Regulation, Product Quality, and Asymmetric Information’, 71 American Economic Review, 212-220. Baron, David P. (1985a), ‘Regulation of Prices and Pollution under Incomplete Information’, 28 Journal of Public Economics, 211-231. Baron, David P. (1985b), ‘Regulatory Strategies under Asymmetric Information’, in Boyer, M. and Kihlstrom, R. (eds), Bayesian Models in Economic Theory, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 155-180. Baron, David P. (1985c), ‘Noncooperative Regulation of a Nonlocalized Externality’,16 Rand Journal of Economics, 553-568.
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
437
Baron, David P. (1988), ‘Regulation and Legislative Choice’, 19 Rand Journal of Economics, 467-477. Baron, David P. (1989), ‘Design of Regulatory Mechanisms and Institutions’, in Schmalensee, Richard and Willig, Robert D. (eds), Handbook of Industrial Organzation, volume 2, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 1347-1447. Baron, David P. (1991), ‘Information, Incentives, and Commitment in Regulatory Mechanisms: Regulatory Innovation in Telecommunications’, in Einhorn, Michael A. (ed.), Price-caps and Incentive Regulation in Telecommunications, Topics in Regulatory Economics and Policy Series, Norwell, MA and Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic, 47-75. Baron, David P. and Besanko, David A. (1984a), ‘Regulation, Asymmetric Information, and Auditing’, 15 Rand Journal of Economics, 447-470. Baron, David P. and Besanko, David A. (1984b), ‘Regulation and Information in a Continuing Relationship’, 1 Information Economics and Policy, 267-302. Baron, David P. and Besanko, David (1987), ‘Commitment and Fairness in a Dynamic Regulatory Relationship’, 54 Review of Economic Studies, 413-436. Baron, David P. and Debondt, Raymond R. (1981), ‘On the Design of Regulatory Price Adjustment Mechanisms’, 24 Journal of Economic Theory, 70-94. Baron, David P. and Myerson, Roger B. (1982), ‘Regulating a Monopolist with Unknown Costs’, 50 Econometrica, 911-930. Baron, David P. and Taggart, Robert A., Jr (1977), ‘A Model of Regulation under Uncertainty and a Test of Regulatory Bias’, 8 Bell Journal of Economics, 151-167. Baron, David P. and Taggart, Robert A., Jr (1980), ‘Regulatory Pricing Policies and Economic Incentives’, in Crew, Michael A. (ed.), Issues in Public Utility Pricing Regulation, Lexington, Lexington Books, 27-49. Baum, Herbert (1976), ‘Das Stabilisierungspotential Staatlich Administrierter Preise (On the Stabilization Effects of Public Regulated Prices)’, 190 Jahrbuch für Nationalökonomie und Statistik, 349-376. Baum, Herbert (1978), ‘Verteilungswirkungen der staatlichen Preispolitik (Effects of Public Regulated Prices on Distribution of Income)’, 193 Jahrbuch für Nationalökonomie und Statistik, 220-243. Baumol, William J. (1977), ‘On the Proper Costs Tests for Natural Monopoly in a Multiproduct Industry’, 67 American Economic Review, 43-57. Baumol, William J. (1983), ‘Some Subtle Issues in Railroad Regulation’, 10 International Journal of Transport Economics, 341-355. Baumol, William J. (1986), ‘Minimum and Maximum Pricing Principles for Residual Regulation’, in Baumol, William J. (ed.), Microtheory: Applications and Origins, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 151-164. Baumol, William J. and Klevorick, Alvin K. (1970), ‘Input Choices and Rate-of-Return Regulation: an Overview of the Discussion’, 1 Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, 162-190. Baumol, William J. and Sidak, J. Gregory (1994a), ‘The Pricing of Inputs Sold to Competitors’, 11 Yale Journal on Regulation, 171-202. Baumol, William J. and Sidak, J. Gregory (1994b), ‘The Pricing of Inputs Sold to Competitors: Rejoinder and Epilogue’, 12 Yale Journal on Regulation, 177-186. Baumol, William J. and Sidak, J. Gregory (1994c), Toward Competition in Local Telephony, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Baumol, William J. and Sidak, J. Gregory (1996), Transmission Pricing and Stranded Costs in the Electric Power Industry, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute.
438
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
Baumol, William J. and Willig, Robert D. (1981), ‘Fixed Cost, Sunk Cost, Entry Barriers and Sustainability of Monopoly’, 95 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 405-431. Baumol, William J., Bailey, Elizabeth E. and Willig, Robert D. (1977), ‘Weak Invisible Hand Theorems on the Sustainability of Prices in a Multiproduct Monopoly’, 67 American Economic Review, 350-365. Bawa, V. and Sibley, David (1980), ‘Dynamic Behavior of a Firm Subject to Stochastic Regulatory Review’, 21 International Economic Review, 627-642. Becker, Klaus G. (1991), ‘Ramsey Pricing without Cross-Subsidization: A Note’, 25 Journal of Economic Issues, 1149-1151. Beesley, Michael E. and Littlechild, Stephen C. (1989), ‘The Regulation of Privatized Monopolies in the United Kingdom’, 20 Rand Journal of Economics, 454-472. Beil, Richard O., Kaserman, David L. and Ford, Jon M. (1995), ‘Entry and Product Quality under Price Regulation’, 10 Review of Industrial Organization, 361-372. Berg, Sanford V. and Jeong, Jinook (1991), ‘An Evaluation of Incentive Regulation for Electric Utilities’, 3(1) Journal of Regulatory Economics, 45-55. Berg, Sanford V. and Jeong, Jinook (1994), ‘An Evaluation of Incentive Regulation: Corrections’, 6 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 321-328. Berg, Sanford V. and Tschirhart, John (1988), Natural Monopoly Regulation: Principles and Practice, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 564 p. Bergström, Ted and MacKie-Mason, Jeffrey K. (1991), ‘Some Simple Analytics of Peak-Load Pricing’, 22 Rand Journal of Economics, 241-249. Berkowitz, Michael K. (1977), ‘Power Grid Economics in a Peak-Load Pricing Framework’, 10 Canadian Journal of Economics, 621-636. Berkowitz, Michael K. and Jen, Frank C. (1977), ‘A Note on Production Inefficiency in the Peak-Load Pricing Model’, 44 Southern Economic Journal, 374-379. Berry, S. Keith (1990), ‘Expected Rate Minimization and Excess Capacity in Regulated Utilities’, 30 Quarterly Review of Economics and Business, 85-95. Berry, S. Keith (1992), ‘Ramsey Pricing in the Presence of Risk’, 13 Managerial and Decision Economics, 111-117. Besanko, David and Sappington, David E.M. (1987), Designing Regulatory Policy with Limited Information, Fundamentals of Pure and Applied Economics, New York, Harwood. Besanko, David, Donnenfeld, Shabtai and White, Lawrence J. (1988), ‘The Multiproduct Firm, Quality Choice, and Regulation’, 36 Journal of Industrial Economics, 411-429. Binder, John J. (1985), ‘Measuring the Effects of Regulation with Stock Price Data’, 16 Rand Journal of Economics, 167-183. Blackmon, Glenn (1994), Incentive Regulation and the Regulation of Incentives, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers. Blair, Roger D., Kaserman, David L. and McClave, James T. (1986), ‘Motor Carrier Deregulation: The Florida Experiment’, 68 Review of Economics and Statistics, 159-164. Bohm, Peter (1967), ‘On the Theory of Second Best’, 34 Review of Economic Studies, 301-314. Boiteux, Marcel (1956), ‘Sur la Gestion des Monopoles Publics Astreint a l’Equilibre Budgetaire (On the Regulation of Public Monopolies within the Budgetairy Equilibrium)’, 24 Econometrica, 22-40. Boiteux, Marcel (1960), ‘Peak-Load Pricing’, 33 Journal of Business, 157-179.
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
439
Boiteux, Marcel (1971), ‘On the Management of Public Monopolies Subject to Budgetary Constraints’, 3 Journal of Economic Theory, 219-240. Borenstein, Severin and Zimmerman, Martin B. (1988), ‘Market Incentives for Safe Commercial Airline Operation’, 78 American Economic Review, 913-935. Bos, Dieter and Nett, Lorenz (1990), ‘Privatization, Price Regulation, and Market Entry: An Asymmetric Multistage Duopoly Model’, 51 Zeitschrift für Nationalökonomie, 221-257. Bourgoignie, Thierry (1973), ‘Overheid en Bedrijfsleven/3 La Reglementation des Prix en Belgique (Price Regulation in Belgium)’, 27 Economisch en Sociaal Tijdschrift, 387-400. Boyer, Kenneth D. (1977), ‘Minimum Rate Regulation, Modal Split Sensitivities, and the Railroad Problem’, 85 Journal of Political Economy, 493-512. Boyer, Kenneth D. (1981), ‘Equalizing Discrimination and Cartel Pricing in Transport Rate Regulation’, 89 Journal of Political Economy, 270-286. Boyer, Kenneth D. (1986), ‘What do we Understand about the Economics of Regulation: The Effects of U.S. Transport Deregulation’, in De Jong, H.W. and Shepherd, William G. (eds), Mainstreams in Industrial Organization. Book 2. Policies: Antitrust, Deregulation and Industrial, Studies in Industrial Organization series, vol. 6, Hingham, MA, Dordrecht and Lancaster, Kluwer Academic, 317-345. Boyer, Kenneth D. (1987), ‘The Costs of Price Regulation: Lessons from Railroad Deregulation’, 18 Rand Journal of Economics, 408-416. Boyer, Kenneth D. (1989), ‘The Safety Effects of Mode Shifting Following Deregulation’, in Moses, Leon N. and Savage, Ian (eds), Transportation Safety in an Age of Deregulation, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 258-276. Boyes, William J. (1976), ‘An Empirical Examination of the Averch-Johnson Effect’, 14 Economic Inquiry, 25-35. Bradley, Ian (1993), ‘Price-Cap Regulation and Market Definition’, 5 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 337-347. Bradley, Ian and Price, Catherine Waddams (1988), ‘The Economic Regulation of Private Industries by Price Constraints’, 37 Journal of Industrial Economics, 99-106. Bradley, Ian and Price, Catherine Waddams (1991), ‘Average Revenue Regulation and Regional Price Structure’, 21 Regional Science and Urban Economics, 89-108. Braeutigam, Ronald R. (1979a), ‘The Effect of Uncertainty in Regulatory Delay on the Rate of Innovation’, 43 Law and Contemporary Problems, 98-111. Braeutigam, Ronald R. (1979b), ‘Optimal Pricing with Intermodal Competition’, 69 American Economic Review, 38-49. Braeutigam, Ronald R. (1980), ‘An Analysis of Fully Distributed Cost Pricing in Regulated Industries’, 11 Bell Journal of Economics, 182-196. Braeutigam, Ronald R. (1983), ‘A Dynamic Analysis of Second Best Pricing’, in Finsinger, Jörg (ed.), Public Sector Economics, London, Macmillan, 103-116. Braeutigam, Ronald R. (1984), ‘Socially Optimal Pricing with Rivalry and Economies of Scale’, 15 Rand Journal of Economics, 124-131. Braeutigam, Ronald R. (1989), ‘Optimal Policies for Natural Monopolies’, in Schmalensee, Richard and Willig, Robert D. (eds), Handbook of Industrial Organization vol. 2, Amsterdam, North Holland. Braeutigam, Ronald R. and Noll, Roger G. (1984), ‘The Regulation of Surface Freight Transportation: The Welfare Effects Revisited’, 56 Review of Economics and Statistics, 80-87. Braeutigam, Ronald R. and Panzar, John C. (1989), ‘Diversification Incentives Under ‘Price-Based’
440
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
and ‘Cost-Based’ Regulation’, 20 Rand Journal of Economics, 373-391. Braeutigam, Ronald R. and Panzar, John C. (1993), ‘Effects of the Change from Rate-of-Return to Price-Cap Regulation’, 83 American Economic Review, 191-198. Brennan, Michael J. and Schwartz, Eduardo S. (1982), ‘Consistent Regulatory Policy under Uncertainty’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 506-524. Brennan, Timothy J. (1991a), ‘Regulating by Capping Prices’, 1 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 133-148. Brennan, Timothy J. (1991b), ‘Cross-Subsidization and Cost Misallocation by Regulated Monopolists’, 2 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 37-51. Brennan, Timothy J. and Palmer, Karen L. (1994), ‘Comparing the Costs and Benefits of Diversification by Regulated Firms’, 6 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 115-136. Breyer, Stephen G. (1982), Regulation and its Reform, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Broadman, Harry G. and Kalt, Joseph P. (1989), ‘How Natural is Monopoly? The Case of Bypass in Natural Gas Distribution Markets’, 6 Yale Journal on Regulation, 181-208. Broadman, Harry G. and Montgomery, David W. (1983), Natural Gas Markets after Deregulation, Washington, Resources for the Future. Brock, William A. and Dechert, W. Davis (1983), ‘Dynamic Ramsey Pricing’, 26 International Economic Review, 569-591. Brock, William A. and Evans, David S. (1983), ‘Cream-Skimming’, in Evans, David S. (ed.),Breaking up Bell: Essays on Industrial Organization and Regulation, Amsterdam, North-Holland. Brock, William A. and Scheinkman, Jose A. (1983), ‘Free Entry and the Sustainability of Natural Monopoly: Bertrand Revisited by Cournot’, in Evans, David S. (ed.), Breaking up Bell: Essays on Industrial Organization and Regulation, Amsterdam, North-Holland. Brown, Allan and Cave, Martin (1992), ‘The Economics of Television Regulation: A Survey with Application to Australia’, 68 Economic Record, 377-394. Brown, Donald J. and Heal, Geoffrey M. (1985), ‘The Optimality of Regulated Pricing: A General Equilibrium Analysis’, in Alisprantis, C.D., Burkinshaw, O. and Rothman (eds), Advances in Equilibrium Theory: Proceedings of the Conference on General Equilibrium Theory, New York, Springer, 43-54. Brown, Donald J. and Heal, Geoffrey M. (1987), ‘Ramsey Pricing in Telecommunications Markets with Free Entry’, in Crew, Michael A. (ed.), Regulating Utilities in an Era of Deregulation, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 77-83. Brown, Lorenzo (1988), ‘Modelling Diversified Utilities and Cross Subsidization’, 10 Resources and Energy, 213-224. Brown, Lorenzo, Einhorn, Michael A. and Vogelsang, Ingo (1991), ‘Toward Improved and Practical Incentive Regulation’, 3 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 323-338. Brown, Stephen J. and Sibley, David S. (1986), The Theory of Public Utility Pricing, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Burness, H. Stuart and Patrick, Robert H. (1991), ‘Peak-Load Pricing with Continuous and Interdependent Demand’, 3 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 69-88. Burness, H. Stuart, Montgomery, David W. and Quirk, James P. (1980), ‘Capital Contracting and the Regulated Firms’, 70 American Economic Review, 342-354. Cabral, Luis M.B. and Riordan, Michael H. (1989), ‘Incentives for Cost Reduction under Price-Cap Regulation’, 1 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 93-102. Caillaud, Bernard, Guesnerie, Roger, Rey, Patrick and Tirole, Jean (1988), ‘Government Intervention
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
441
in Production and Incentives Theory: A Review of Recent Contributions’, 19 Rand Journal of Economics, 1-26. Cairns, Robert D. and Liston-Heyes, Catherine (1996), ‘Competition and Regulation in the Taxi Industry’, 59 Journal of Public Economics, 1-15. Call, Gregory D. and Keeler, Theodore E. (1985), ‘Airline Deregulation, Fares, and Market Behavior: Some Empirical Evidence’, in Daughety, Andrew F. (ed.), Analytical Studies in Transport Economics, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Card, David (1986), ‘The Impact of Deregulation on the Employment and Wages of Airline Mechanics’, 39 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 527-538. Carlton, Dennis W. (1977), ‘Peak-Load Pricing with Stochastic Demand’, 67 American Economic Review, 1006-1010. Carroll, Thomas M. and Ciscel, David H. (1982), ‘The Effects of Regulation on Executive Compensation’, 64 Review of Economics and Statistics, 505-509. Carron, Andrew S. and Macavoy, Paul W. (1981), The Decline of Service in the Regulated Industries, Washington, American Enterprise Institute. Caves, Douglas W. and Swanson, Joseph A. (1981), ‘Productivity Growth, Scale Economies and Capacity Utilization in U.S. Railroads’, 71 American Economic Review, 994-1002. Caves, Douglas W., Christensen, Laurits R. and Swanson, Joseph A. (1981), ‘Economic Performance in Regulated and Unregulated Environments: A Comparison of U.S. and Canadian Railroads’, 66 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 559-581. Caves, Douglas W., Christensen, Laurits R. and Herriges, Joseph A. (1984), ‘Modeling Alternative Residential Peak-Load Electricity Rate Structures’, 24 Journal of Econometrics, 249-268. Cebula, Richard J. (1982), ‘A Simple Peak-Load Pricing Model’, 29 Rivista Internazionale di Scienze Economiche e Commerciali, 821-824. Chang, Ha Joon (1997), ‘The Economics and Politics of Regulation’, 21 Cambridge Journal of Economics, 703-728. Chang, Yang Ming and Warren, John T. (1997), ‘Allocative Efficiency and Diversification under Price-Cap Regulation’, 9 Information Economics and Policy, 3-17. Chao, Hung-Po (1983), ‘Peak-load Pricing and Capacity Planning with Demand and Supply Uncertainty’, 14 Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, 179-180. Chappell, Henry W. Jr and Wilder, Ronald P. (1986), ‘Multiproduct Monopoly, Regulation, and Firm Costs: Comment’, 52 Southern Economic Journal, 1168-1174. Christainsen, Gregory B. and Haveman, Robert H. (1981), ‘Public Regulations and the Slowdown in Productivity Growth’, 71 American Economic Review, 320-325. Christensen, Laurits R. and Greene, William H. (1976), ‘Economies of Scale in U.S. Electric Power Generation’, 84 Journal of Political Economy, 655-676. Christensen, Laurits R., Cummings, Diane and Schoech, P. (1983), ‘Econometric Estimation of Scale Economies in Telecommunications’, in Courville, Leon, De Fontenay, Alain and Dobell, Rodney (eds), Economic Analysis of Telecommunications: Theory and Applications, Amsterdam, North-Holland. Clark, David D. (1998), ‘A Taxonomy of Internet Telephony Applications’, in MacKie-Mason, Jeffrey K. and Waterman, David (eds), Telephony, the Internet, and the Media, Papers from the 25th Annual Telecommunications Policy Research Conference, Mahwah, NJ, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Clark, John Maurice (1923), Studies in the Economics of Overhead Costs, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Clarke, Roger G. (1980), ‘The Effect of Fuel Adjustment Clauses on the Systematic Risk and Market
442
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
Values of Electric Utilities’, 35 Journal of Finance, 347-358. Clemenz, Gerhard (1991), ‘Optimal Price-Cap Regulation’, 39 Journal of Industrial Economics, 391-408. Coase, Ronald H. (1946), ‘The Marginal Cost Controversy’, 13 Economica, 169-189. Comnes, Alan G., Kahn, Edward P. and Belden, Tim N. (1996), ‘The Performance of the U.S. Market for Independent Electric Generation’, 17 Electricity Journal, 23-29. Corts, Kenneth S. (1995), ‘Regulation of a Multi-product Monopolist: Effects on Pricing and Bundling’, 43 Journal of Industrial Economics, 377-397. Costello, Kenneth W. and Hemphill, Ross C. (1990), ‘Competitive Pricing in the Electric Industry’, 12 Resources and Energy, 49-63. Cottle, Rex L. and Wallace, Myles S. (1983), ‘Economic Effects of Non-Binding Price Constraints’, 31 Journal of Industrial Economics, 469-474. Coursey, Don L. and Smith, Vernon L. (1983), ‘Price Controls in a Posted Offer Market’, 73 American Economic Review, 218-221. Courville, Léson (1974), ‘Regulation and Efficiency in the Electric Utility Industry’, 5 Bell Journal of Economics, 38-52. Cowan, Simon (1997), 'Price-Cap Regulation and Inefficiency in Relative Pricing’, 12 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 53-70. Cox, James C. and Isaac, R. Mark (1987), ‘Mechanisms for Incentive Regulation: Theory and Experiment’, 18 Rand Journal of Economics, 348-359. Cox, James C. and Isaac, R. Mark (1992), ‘Incentive Regulation and Innovation’, in Isaac, R. Mark (ed.), Research in Experimental Economics, Volume 5, Greenwich, Conn. and London, JAI Press, 171-187. Cramer, Curtis A. (1994), ‘Local Competition for Telephone Services’, 9(3) Journal of Industrial Organization, 273-291. Craven, John (1985), ‘Peak-Load Pricing and Short-Run Marginal Cost’, 95 Economic Journal, 778-780. Crew, Michael A. (ed.) (1992), Economic Innovations in Public Utility Regulation, Topics in Regulatory Economics and Policy Series, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers. Crew, Michael A. (ed.) (1994), Incentive Regulation for Public Utilities, Topics in Regulatory Economics and Policy Series, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers. Crew, Michael A. and Kleindorfer, Paul R. (1975), ‘Optimal Plant Mix in Peak-Load Pricing’, 22 Scottish Journal of Political Economy, 277-291. Crew Michael, A. and Kleindorfer, Paul, R. (1976), ‘Peak-load Pricing with a Diverse Technology’, 7 Bell Journal of Economics, 207-231. Crew Michael, A. and Kleindorfer, Paul R. (1981), ‘Regulation and Diverse Technology in the Peakload Problem’, 48 Southern Economic Journal, 335-343. Crew, Michael A. and Kleindorfer, Paul R. (1983), ‘Peak-Load Pricing of Public Utilities: Some Comments’, 5 Energy Economics, 137 ff. Crew, Michael A. and Kleindorfer, Paul R. (1986), The Economics of Public Utility Regulation, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 304 p. Crew, Michael A. and Kleindorfer, Paul R. (1987), ‘Productivity Incentives and Rate-of-Return Regulation’, in Crew, Michael A. (ed.), Regulating Utilities in an Era of Deregulation, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 7-23. Crew, Michael A. and Kleindorfer, Paul R. (1992), ‘Incentive Regulation, Capital Recovery and Technological Change in Public Utilities’, in Crew, Michael A. (ed.), Economic Innovations in Public Utility Regulation, Topics in Regulatory Economics and Policy Series, vol. 10, Norwell,
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
443
MA, and Dordrecht Kluwer Academic, 57-79. Crew, Michael A. and Kleindorfer, Paul R. (1996), ‘Incentive Regulation in the United Kingdom and the United States: Some Lessons’, 9 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 211-225. Crew, Michael A., Fernando, Chitru S. and Kleindorfer, Paul R. (1995), ‘The Theory of Peak-Load Pricing: A Survey’, 8 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 215-248. Cross, John G. (1970), ‘Incentive Pricing and Utility Regulation’, 84 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 236-253. Cross, John G. (1972), ‘Incentive Pricing and Utility Regulation: Reply’, 86 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 145-147. Cross, Phillip S. (1995), ‘Performance-Based Ratemaking’, 133 Public Utilities Fortnightly, 44-46. Csikos Nagy, Bela (1980), ‘The New Path of Hungarian Price Policy’, 118 Nationalokonomisk Tidsskrift, 201-211. Culbertson, William Patton, Jr (1977), ‘A Redistributive Effect of Natural Gas Price Regulation’, 16 Nebraska Journal of Economics and Business, 91-95. Curien, Nicolas, Jullien, Bruno and Rey, Patrick (1998), ‘Pricing Regulation under Bypass Competition’, 29 Rand Journal of Economics, 259-279. Currier, Kevin M. (1989), ‘An Algorithm for Ramsey Pricing by Multiproduct Public Firms under Incomplete Information’, 13 Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control, 283-300. Danielsen, Albert L. (1979), ‘Oil Price Regulation in the United States’, 13 Journal of World Trade Law, 383-394. Danielsen, Albert L., Kamerschen, David R. and Keenan, Donald C. (1990), ‘Third Best Pricing Rules for Regulated Utilities’, 56 Southern Economic Journal, 628-638. Dansby, Robert E. (1978), ‘Capacity Constrained Peak-Load Pricing’, 92 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 387-398. Das, S. (1980), ‘On the Effective Rate-of-return Regulation Under Uncertainty’, 70 American Economic Review, 456-460. Daughety, Andrew F. (1984), ‘Regulation and Industrial Organization’, 92 Journal of Political Economy, 932-953. Davis, E. (1973), ‘A Dynamic Model of the Regulated Firm with a Price Adjustment Mechanism’, 4 Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, 270-282. De Alessi, Louis (1977), ‘Ownership and Peak-Load Pricing in the Electric Power Industry’, 17 Quarterly Review of Economics and Business, 7-26. De Salvia, Donald N. (1969), ‘An Application of Peak-Load Pricing’, 42 Journal of Business, 458-476. De Vany, Arthur and Walls, W. David (1996), ‘The Law of One Price in a Network: Arbitrage and Price Dynamics in Natural Gas City Gate Markets’, 36 Journal of Regional Science, 555-570. Deacon, Robert T. (1978), ‘An Economic Analysis of Gasoline Price Controls’, 18 Natural Resources Journal, 801-814. Deacon, Robert T. and Sonstelie, Jon (1989), ‘Price Controls and Rent Seeking Behavior in Developing Countries’, 17 World Development, 1945-1954. Dechert, W. Davis (1984), ‘Has the Averch-Johnson Effect been Theoretically Justified?’, 8 Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control, 1-17. DeLorme, Charles D., Jr., Kamerschen, David R. and Thompson, Herbert G., Jr (1992), ‘Pricing in the Nuclear Power Industry: Public or Private Interest?’, 73 Public Choice, 385-396.
444
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
Demsetz, Harold (1968), ‘Why Regulate Utilities’, 11 Journal of Law and Economics, 55-65. Demski, Joel S. and Sappington, David E.M. (1987), ‘Hierarchical Regulatory Control’, 18 Rand Journal of Economics, 369-383. Diamond, Peter and Mirrlees, James (1971), ‘Optimal Taxation and Public Regulation’, 61 American Economic Review, 261-678. Dierker, Egbert (1991), ‘The Optimality of Boiteux-Ramsey Pricing’, 59 Econometrica, 99-121. Diewert, Erwin W. (1993), ‘Index Number Issues in Incentive Regulation’, University of British Columbia Department of Economics Discussion Paper, No. 93-06. Doherty, Neil A. and Garven, James R. (1986), ‘Price Regulation in Property Liability Insurance: A Contingent Claims Approach’, 41 Journal of Finance, 1031-1050. Donald, Stephen G. and Sappington, David E.M. (1995), ‘Explaining the Choice among Regulatory Plans in the U.S. Telecommunications Industry’, 4 Journal of Economics, 237-265. Donnenfeld, Shabtai (1984), ‘Domestic Price Regulation and the Exporting Monopolist’, 36 Oxford Economic Papers, 285-287. Douglas, George W. (1972), ‘Price Regulation and Optimal Service Standards: The Taxicab Industry’, 6 Journal of Transport Economics and Policy, 116-127. Douglas, George W. and Miller, J.C. (1974), Economic Regulation of Domestic Air Transport: Theory and Policy, Washington, Brookings Institution. Doyle, Chris (1995), ‘Some Efficiency Aspects of Price Regulation’, 6 European Transactions on Telecommunications Special Focus on the Economics of Telecommunications. Dreze, J. (1964), ‘Some Postwar Contributions of French Economists to Theory and Public Policy, with Special Emphasis on Problems of Resource Allocation’, 545 American Economic Review, 1-64. Economides, Nicholas and White, Larry (1995), ‘Access and Interconnection Pricing: How Efficiency is the ECPR’, 40 Antitrust Bulletin, 557-579. Economides, Nicholas and White, Larry (1998), ‘The Inefficiency of the ECPR yet Again: A Reply to Larson’, 43 Antitrust Bulletin. Ehrenberg, Ronald G. (1979), The Regulatory Process and Labor Earnings, New York, Academic Press. Einhorn, Michael A. (1987), ‘Optimality and Sustainability: Regulation and Intermodal Competition in Telecommunications’, 18 Rand Journal of Economics, 550-563. Einhorn, Michael A. (1990a), ‘Electricity Wheeling and Incentive Regulation’, 2 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 173-189. Einhorn, Michael A. (1990b), ‘Incentive Mechanisms for Cost Revelation with Intermodal Competition’, 4 Information Economics and Policy, 281-290. Einhorn, Michael A. (1991c), ‘Optional Calling Plans and Bypass Efficiency’, in Einhorn, Michael A. (ed.), Price-caps and Incentive Regulation in Telecommunications, Topics in Regulatory Economics and Policy Series, Norwell, Mass. and Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic, 207-220. Einhorn, Michael A. (ed.) (1991a), Price-caps and Incentive Regulation in Telecommunications, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 244 p. Einhorn, Michael A. (1991b), ‘Price-Caps and Incentive Regulation in Telecommunications:
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
445
Introduction’, in Einhorn, Michael A. (ed.), Price-caps and Incentive Regulation in Telecommunications, Topics in Regulatory Economics and Policy Series, Norwell, MA and Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic, 1-14. El-Hodiri, M. and Takayama, A. (1973), ‘Behavior of the Firm under Regulatory Constraint: Clarifications’, 63 American Economic Review, 235-237. El-Hodiri, M. and Takayama, A. (1981), ‘Dynamic Behavior of the Firm with Adjustments Costs under Regulatory Constraint’, 3 Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control, 29-41. Ellig, Jerome (1991), ‘Endogenous Change and the Economic Theory of Regulation’, 3 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 265-274. Ellig, Jerome (1995), ‘Why Do Regulators Regulate? The Case of the Southern California Gas Market’, 7 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 293-308. Encinosa, William E., III and Sappington, David E.M. (1995), ‘Toward a Benchmark for Optimal Prudency Policy’, 7 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 111-130. Erickson, Edward W. and Spann, Robert M. (1971), ‘Supply Response in a Regulated Industry: The Case of Natural Gas’, 2 Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, 94-121. Erickson, Edward W. et al. (1978), ‘The Political Economy of Crude Oil Price Controls’, 18 Natural Resources Journal, 787-780. Escarraz, Donald Ray (1970), ‘The Peak-Load Problem: Davidson’s Solution Reconsidered’, 10 Quarterly Review of Economics and Business, 85-90. Evans, David S. and Heckman, James J. (1984), ‘A Test for Subadditivity of the Cost Function with an Application to the Bell System’, 74 American Economic Review, 615-623. Evans, Lewis and Garver, Steven (1989), ‘The Rational Regulator’s Pricing Response to Enhanced Opportunities to ‘Bypass’ the Public Telephone Network’, 1 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 271-291. Face, Howard K. (1988), ‘The First Case Study in Telecommunications Social Contracts’, 121 Public Utilities Fortnightly, 27-31. Faulhaber, Gerald R. (1975), ‘Cross-Subsidization: Pricing in Public Enterprises’, 65 American Economic Review, 966-977. Faulhaber, Gerald R. and Levinson, Stephen (1981), ‘Subsidy Free Prices and Anonymous Equity’, 71 American Economic Review, 1083-1091. Feldman, Stephen L. (1975), ‘On the Peak-Load Pricing of Urban Water Supply’, 11 Water Resources Research, 355-356. Finsinger, Jörg (1980), ‘Peak-Load Pricing and Rationing Policies’, 40 Zeitschrift für Nationalökonomie, 169-182. Finsinger, Jörg (ed.) (1983), Economic Analysis of Regulated Markets, New York, St. Martin’s Press. Finsinger, Jörg and Vogelsang, Ingo (1981), ‘Alternative Institutional Frameworks for Price Incentive Mechanisms’, 34 Kyklos, 388-404. Fiorina, Morris P. and Noll, Roger G. (1978), ‘Voters, Bureaucrats and Legislators: A Rational Choice Perspective on the Growth of Bureaucracy’, 9 Journal of Public Economics, 239-254. Foreman, R. Dean (1995), ‘Pricing Incentives under Price-Cap Regulation’, 7 Information Economics and Policy, 331-351. Frankena, Mark W. and Owen, Bruce M. (1993), ‘Flawed Reasoning’, 131 Public Utilities Fortnightly, 25-27.
446
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
Fraser, Rob (1994), ‘Price, Quality and Regulation: An Analysis of Price-Capping and the Reliability of Electricity Supply’, 16 Energy Economics, 175-183. Fraser, Rob (1995), ‘The Relationship Between the Costs and Prices of a Multi-Product Monopoly: The Role of Price-Cap Regulation’, 8 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 23-31. Frech, H. Edward III (1981), ‘The Long-Lost Free Market in Health Care: Government and Professional Regulation in Medicine’, in Olson, Mancur (ed.), A New Appraoch to the Economics of Health Care, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 44-66. Frech, H. Edward III (1984), ‘The Social Benefits of Price Competition in Medicine’, 28 Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 40-48. Frech, H. Edward III (1991a), ‘Overview of Policy Issues’, in Frech, H.E., III (ed.), Regulating Doctor’s Fees: Competition, Benefits and Controls under Medicare, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 1-34. Frech, H. Edward III (1991b), Regulating Doctor’s Fees: Competition, Benefits and Controls under Medicare, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research. Frech, H. Edward III (1993), ‘What Can Reform Achieve in Health Care Cost-Containment: Commentary’, in Helms, Robert B. (ed.), American Health Policy: Critical Issues for Reform, Washington, American Enterprise Institute, 298-302. Frech, H. Edward III and Samprone, Joseph C., Jr (1980), ‘The Welfare Loss of Excess Nonprice Competition: The Case of Property-Liability Insurance Regulation’, 13 Journal of Law and Economics, 429-440. Friedlaender, Ann F. (1969), The Dilemma of Freight Transport Regulation, Washington, Brookings Institution. Friedlaender, Ann F. (1992), ‘Coal Rates and Revenue Adequacy in a Quasi-regulated Rail Industry’, 23 Rand Journal of Economics, 376-394. Friedlaender, Ann F. (1993), ‘Rail Costs and Capital Adjustments in a Quasi-regulated Environment’, 27 Journal of Transport Economics and Policy, 131-152. Friedlaender, Ann F. and Spady, Richard H. (1981), Freight Transport Regulation, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Friedman, Lee S. (1991), ‘Energy Utility Pricing and Customer Response’, in Gilbert, Richard J. (ed.), Regulatory Choices: A Perspective on Developments in Energy Policy, Berkeley, LA, and Oxford, University of California Press, 10-62. Gabel, David and Weiman, David F. (eds) (1997), Opening Networks to Competition: The Regulation and Pricing of Access, Topics in Regulatory Economics and Policy Series, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers. Galbi, Douglas (1998), ‘The Implications of Bypass for Traditional International Interconnection’, in MacKie-Mason, Jeffrey K. and Waterman, David (eds), Telephony, the Internet, and the Media, Papers from the 25th Annual Telecommunications Policy Research Conference, Mahwah, NJ, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Gallant, A. Ronald and Koenker, Roger W. (1984), ‘Costs and Benefits of Peak-Load Pricing of Electricity: A Continuous-Time Econometric Approach’, 26 Journal of Econometrics, 83-113. Gasmi, Farid, Ivaldi, Marc and Laffont, Jean-Jacques (1994), ‘Rent Extraction and Incentives for Efficiency in Recent Regulatory Proposals’, 6 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 151-176. Gasmi, Farid, Laffont, Jean-Jacques and Sharkey, William W. (1998), ‘A Technico-Economic
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
447
Methodology for the Analysis of Local Telephone Markets’, in MacKie-Mason, Jeffrey K. and Waterman, David (eds), Telephony, the Internet, and the Media, Papers from the 25th Annual Telecommunications Policy Research Conference, Mahwah, NJ, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Gaudry, Marc (1977), ‘Quelques Problèmes de Tarification du Transport des Voyageurs à Montréal (Some Tarification Problems Regarding Public Transit in Montreal)’, 3 Canadian Public Policy, 307-314. Geddes, R. Richard and Griffes, Peter H. (1990), ‘The Electric Utility Industry: New Challenges and Old Questions’, 12 Resources and Energy, 1-15. Gerstner, Eitan (1986), ‘Peak-Load Pricing in Competitive Markets’, 24 Economic Inquiry, 349-361. Gilbert, Richard J. (1991), ‘Issues in Public Utility Regulation’, in Gilbert, Richard J. (ed.), Regulatory Choices: A Perspective on Developments in Energy Policy, Berkeley, LA, and Oxford, University of California Press, 63-86. Gilbert, Richard J. and Kahn, Edward P. (eds) (1996), International Comparisons of Electricity Regulation, Cambridge, New York and Melbourne, Cambridge University Press. Gilbert, Richard J. and Newbery, David M.G. (1994), ‘The Dynamic Efficiency of Regulatory Constitutions’, 25 Rand Journal of Economics, 538-554. Goldberg, Victor P. (1976), ‘Regulation and Administered Contracts’, 7 Bell Journal of Economics, 250-261. Goldman, M. Barry, Leland, Hayne E. and Sibley, David S. (1984), ‘Optimal Nonuniform Prices’, 51 Review of Economic Studies, 305-319. Gollop, Frank M. and Karison, Stephen H. (1978), ‘The Impact of the Fuel Adjustment Mechanism on Economic Efficiency’, 60 Review of Economics and Statistics, 574-584. Gordon, Daniel V. (1988), ‘The Effect of Price Deregulation on the Competitive Behavior of Retail Drug Firms’, 20 Applied Economics, 641-652. Gravelle, Hugh S.E. (1976), ‘The Peak-Load Problem with Feasible Storage’, 86 Economic Journal, 256-277. Greco, Anthony J. (1687), ‘State Fluid Milk Regulation: Antitrust and Price Controls’, 32 Antitrust Bulletin, 165-188. Green, Richard C. and Newbery, David M.G. (1992), ‘Competition in the British Electricity Spot Market’, 100 Journal of Political Economy, 929-953. Green, Richard C. and Price, Catherine Waddams (1995), ‘Liberalisation and Divestiture in the UK Energy Sector’, 16 Fiscal Studies, 75-89. Greene, Robert L. (1973), ‘Peak-Load Pricing: An Application’, 13 Quarterly Review of Economics and Business, 105-114. Greene, William H. and Smiley, Robert H. (1984), ‘The Effectiveness of Utility Regulation in a Period of Changing Economic Conditions’, in Marchand, Maurice, Pestieau, Pierre and Tulkens, Henry (eds), The Performance of Public Enterprises: Concepts and Measurement, Amsterdam, Elsevier Science Publishers B.V.. Greenstein, Shane, McMaster, Susan and Spiller, Pablo T. (1995), ‘The Effect of Incentive Regulation on Infrastructure Modernization: Local Exchange Companies’ Deployment of Digital Technology’, 4 Journal of Economics, 187-236. Greenwald, Bruce C. (1984), ‘Rate Base Selection and the Structure of Regulation’, 15 Rand Journal of Economics, 85-95. Gribbin, J. Denys (1978), ‘The United Kingdom 1977 Price Commission Act and Competition Policy’, 23 Antitrust Bulletin, 405-439.
448
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
Grieve, Willie and Levin, Stanford L. (1998), ‘Telecom Competition in Canada and the U.S.: The Tortoise and the Hare’, in MacKie-Mason, Jeffrey K. and Waterman, David (eds), Telephony, the Internet, and the Media, Papers from the 25th Annual Telecommunications Policy Research Conference, Mahwah, NJ, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Grupe, Hector J.C. (1990), ‘Regulacion Economica y Teoria del Monopolio Natural Economic Regulation and Theory of Natural Monopoly. With English Summary.’, 36 Economica, 71-96. Hagerman, James (1991), ‘Regulation by Price Adjustments’, 21 Rand Journal of Economics, 72-82. Hagerman, Robert L. and Ratchford, Brian T. (1978), ‘Some Determinants of Allowed Rates of Return on Equity to Electric Utilities’, 9 Bell Journal of Economics, 46-55. Hagg, P. Goran T. (1997), ‘Theories on the Economics of Regulation: A Survey of the Literature from a European Perspective’, 4 European Journal of Law and Economics, 337-370. Hancock, Ruth and Price, Catherine Waddams (1995), ‘Competition in the British Domestic Gas Market: Efficiency and Equity’, 16 Fiscal Studies, 81-105. Harkenrider, Gregory D. (1993), ‘Ramsey Pricing Revisited: A Note on Michael Sheehan’s “Why Ramsey Pricing is Wrong”‘, 27 Journal of Economic Issues, 1241-1247. Harrington, Scott E. (1984), ‘The Impact of Rate Regulation on Prices and Underwriting Results in the Property-Liability Insurance Industry: A Survey’, 51 Journal of Risk and Insurance, 577-623. Hartman, Raymond S., Jensen, Kenneth A. and Seiden, Kenneth P. (1994), ‘Strategic Rate-Making in the Context of Dynamic Ramsey Pricing’, 26 Applied Economics, 363-374. Hayashi, Paul M. and Trapani, John M. (1976), ‘Rate-of-Return Regulation and the Regulated Firm’s Choice of Capital-Labor Ratio: Further Empirical Evidence on the Averch-Johnson Model’, 42 Southern Economic Journal, 384-398. Hazlett, Thomas W. (1993), ‘Cable TV Reregulation: The Episodes You Didn’t See on C-SPAN’, 16 Regulation, 45-52. Hendricks, Wallace, Feuille, Peter and Szerszen, Carol (1980), ‘Regulation, Deregulation, and Collective Bargaining in Airlines’, 34 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 67-81. Hendricks, Wallace, Koenker, Roger W. and Poirier, Dale (1979), ‘Stochastic Parameter Models for Panel Data: An Application to the Connecticut Peak-Load Pricing Experiment’, 2 International Economic Review, 707-724. Hendricks, Walter (1975), ‘The Effect of Regulation on Collective Bargaining in Electric Utilities’, 6 Bell Journal of Economics, 451-465. Hendricks, Walter (1977), ‘Regulation and Labor Earnings’, 8 Bell Journal of Economics, 483-496. Herriges, Joseph A. and King, Kathleen Kuester (1994), ‘Residential Demand for Electricity under Inverted Block Rates: Evidence from a Controlled Experiment’, 12 Journal of Business and Economic Statistics, 419-430. Heyes, Anthony G. (1996), ‘Towards an Efficiency-Interpretation of Regulatory Implementation Lags’, 10 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 81-98. Heyes, Anthony G. and Liston-Heyes, Catherine (1998), ‘Price-Cap Regulation and Technical Change’, 68 Journal of Public Economics, 137-151. Hillman, Jordan Jay and Braeutigam, Ronald R. (1989), Price Level Regulation for Diversified Public
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
449
Utilities, Boston, Kluwer. Hirsch, Barry T. (1988), ‘Trucking Regulation, Unionization, and Labor Earnings: 1973-1985', 23 Journal of Human Resources, 296-319. Hirschberg, Joseph G. (1991), ‘Elasticities of Rate Schedule Parameters’, 3 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 165-173. Holthausen, Duncan M. (1979), ‘A Model of Incentive Regulation’, 12 Journal of Public Economics, 61-73. Horowitz, Ira, Seeto, Dewey and Woo, Chi Keung (1996), ‘Ramsey Pricing of Electricity under Unknown Bypass Costs’, 17 Energy Journal, 59-77. Horwitz, Robert B. (1998), ‘Telecommunications Policy in the New South Africa: Participatory Policies and Sectoral Reform’, in MacKie-Mason, Jeffrey K. and Waterman, David (eds), Telephony, the Internet, and the Media, Papers from the 25th Annual Telecommunications Policy Research Conference, Mahwah, NJ, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Hotelling, Harold (1938), ‘The General Welfare in Relation to Problems of Taxation and Railway and Utility Rates’, 6 Econometrica, 242-269. Houston, Douglas A. (1982), ‘Revenue Effects from Changes in a Declining Block Pricing Structure’, 58 Land Economics, 351-363. Houthakker, H.S. (1958), ‘Electricity Tariffs in Theory and Practice’, 61 Economic Journal, 1-25. Hsu, George J.Y. and Chen, Tser Yieth (1990), ‘An Empirical Test of an Electric Utility under an Allowable Rate-of-return’, 11 Energy Journal, 75-90. Huntington, Hillard G. (1978), ‘Federal Price Regulation and the Supply of Natural Gas in a Segmented Field Market’, 54 Land Economics, 337-347. Hurley, William (1995), ‘Is it Necessary to Regulate Prices in Freight Transport Markets’, 29 Journal of Transport Economics and Policy, 169-178. Ippolito, Richard A. (1979), ‘The Effects of Price Regulation in the Automobile Insurance Industry’, 22 Journal of Law and Economics, 55-89. Ippolito, Richard A. and Masson, Robert T. (1978), ‘The Social Cost of Government Regulation of Milk’, 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 33-65. Isaac, R. Mark (1982), ‘Fuel Cost Adjustment Mechanisms and the Regulated Utility Facing Uncertain Fuel Prices’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 158-169. Isaac, R. Mark (1991), ‘Price-Cap Regulation: A Case Study of Some Pitfalls of Implementation’, 3 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 193-210. Isaac, R. Mark and Plott, Charles R. (1981), ‘Price Controls and the Behavior of Auction Markets: An Experimental Examination’, 71 American Economic Review, 448-459. Jackson, Raymond (1973), ‘Peak-Load Pricing Model of an Electric Utility Using Pumped Storage’, 9 Water Resources Research, 556-562. Jaffe, Adam B. and Kanter, David M. (1990), ‘Market Power of Local Cable Television Franchises: Evidence from the Effects of Deregulation’, 21 Rand Journal of Economics, 226-234. Jaffee, Bruce L. (1972), ‘Incentive Pricing and Utility Regulation: Comment’, 86 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 143-144. Johnson, Ronald N. (1985), ‘Retail Price Controls in the Diary Industry: A Political Coalition Argument’, 28 Journal of Law and Economics, 55-75. Jones, Clifton T. and Bremmer, Dale S. (1990), ‘Regional Impacts of Petroleum Price Regulation: The Case of Texas, 1973-1983', 11 Energy Journal, 135-154. Jordan, W. John (1983), ‘Heterogeneous Users and the Peak-Load Pricing Model’, 98 Quarterly
450
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
Journal of Economics, 127-138. Jordan, W. John (1985), ‘Capacity Costs, Heterogeneous Users and Peak-Load Pricing’, 100 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 1335-1337. Jorgenson, Dale W. and Slesnick, Daniel T. (1985), ‘Efficiency versus Equity in Natural Gas Price Regulation’, 30 Journal of Econometrics, 301-316. Jorgenson, Dale W. and Slesnick, Daniel T. (1987), ‘General Equilibrium Analysis of Natural Gas Price Regulation’, in Bailey, Elizabeth E. (ed.), Public Regulation: New Perspectives on Institutions and Policies. MIT Press Series on the Regulation of Economic Activity, no. 14, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 153-190. Joskow, Paul L. (1972), ‘The Determination of the Allowed Rate-of-Return in a Formal Regulatory Hearing’, 3 Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, 632-644. Joskow, Paul L. (1973), ‘Cartels, Competition and Regulation in the Property-Liability Insurance Industry’, 4 Bell Journal of Economics, 375-427. Joskow, Paul L. (1974), ‘Inflation and Environmental Concern: Structural Change in the Process of Public Utility Price Regulation’, 17 Journal of Law and Economics, 291-327. Joskow, Paul L. (1979), ‘Public Utility Regulatory Policy Act of 1978: Electric Utility Rate Reform’, 19 Natural Resources Journal, 787-809. Joskow, Paul L. (1989), ‘Regulatory Failure, Regulatory Reform, and Structural Change in the Electric Power Industry’, Brookings Papers on Economic Activity: Microeconomics, 125-208. Joskow, Paul L. (1991), ‘The Evolution of an Independent Power Sector and Competitive Procurement of New Generating Capacity’, 13 Research in Law and Economics, 63-100. Joskow, Paul L. (1996), ‘Introducing Competition into Regulated Network Industries: From Hierarchies to Markets in Electricity’, 5 Industrial and Corporate Change, 1-42. Joskow, Paul L. and Noll, Roger C. (1981), ‘Regulation in Theory and Practice: An Overview’, in Fromm, Gary, (ed.), Studies in Public Regulation, Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press, 1-65. Joskow, Paul L. and Rose, Nancy L. (1989), ‘The Effects of Economic Regulation’, in Schmalensee, Richard and Willig, Robert D. (eds), Handbook of Industrial Organization, vol. 2, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 1449-1506. Joskow, Paul L. and Schmalensee, Richard (1983), Markets for Power: An Analysis of Electric Utility Deregulation, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Joskow, Paul L. and Schmalensee, Richard (1986), ‘Incentive Regulation for Electric Utilities’, 4(1) Yale Journal on Regulation, 1-49. Kafoglis, M. (1969), ‘Output of the Restrained Firm’, 59 American Economic Review, 553-559. Kahn, Alfred E. (1970), The Economics of Regulation: Principles and Institutions, Vol. 1 , New York, John Wiley and Sons. Kahn, Alfred E. (1971), The Economics of Regulation: Principles and Institutions, Vol. 2 , New York, John Wiley and Sons. Kahn, Alfred E. (1983), ‘Deregulation and Vested Interests: The Case of Airlines’, in Noll, R. and Owen, B. (eds), The Political Economy of Deregulation, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute. Kahn, Alfred E. and Taylor, W. (1994), ‘The Pricing of Inputs Sold to Competitors: A Comment’, 11 Yale Journal on Regulation, 225-240.
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
451
Kahn, Edward (1994), ‘Cost and Competition’, 24 Independent Energy, 66-69. Kale, Jayant R. and Noe, Thomas H. (1995), ‘Dilution Cost, Underinvestment, and Utility Regulation under Asymmetric Information’, 7 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 177-197. Kalt, Joseph P. (1981), The Economics and Politics of Oil Price Regulation: Federal Policy in the Post-Embargo Era, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Kalt, Joseph P. (1983), ‘The Costs and Benefits of Federal Regulation of Coal Strip Mining’, 23 Natural Resources Journal, 893-915. Kalt, Joseph P. and Leone, Robert A. (1986), ‘Regional Effects of Energy Price Decontrol: The Roles of Interregional Trade, Stockholding, and Microeconomic Incidence’, 17 Rand Journal of Economics, 201-213. Kalt, Joseph P. and Zupan, Mark A. (1984), ‘Capture and Ideology in the Economic Theory of Politics’, 74 American Economic Review, 279-300. Reprinted in Rowley, C.K. (ed.) (1993), Public Choice Theory, Cheltenham, Edward Elgar Publishing Limited. Kamien, Morton L. and Vincent, Daniel R. (1991), ‘Price Regulation and Quality of Service’, Northwestern University Center for Mathematical Studies in Economics and Management Science Discussion Paper, No. 920: 28. Kanazawa, Mark (1993), ‘Pricing Subsidies and Economic Efficiency: The U.S. Bureau of Reclamation’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 205-234. Kanemoto, Yoshitsugu and Kiyono, Kazuharu (1995), ‘Regulation of Commuter Railways and Spatial Development’, 25 Regional Science and Urban Economics, 377-394. Karp, Gordon and Yohe, Gary W. (1979), ‘The Optimal Linear Alternative to Price and Quantity Controls in the Multifirm Case’, 3 Journal of Comparative Economics, 56-65. Kaserman, David L. and Mayo, John W. (1994), ‘Cross-Subsidies in Telecommunications: Roadblocks on the Road to More Intelligent Telephone Pricing’, 11 Yale Journal on Regulation, 119-147. Kaserman, David L. and Mayo, John W. (1995), Government and Business: The Economics of Antitrust and Regulation, Orlando, FL, The Dryden Press. Kaserman, David L., Mayo, John W. and Pacey, Patricia L. (1993), ‘The Political Economy of Deregulation: The Case of Intrastate Long Distance’, 5 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 49-63. Kay, John A. (1979), ‘Uncertainty, Congestion and Peak-Load Pricing’, 46 Review of Economic Studies, 601-611. Keeler, Theodore E. (1972), ‘Airline Regulation and Market Performance’, 3 Bell Journal of Economics, 399-424. Keeler, Theodore E. and Small, K. (1977), ‘Optimal Peak-Load Pricing, Investment, and Service Levels on Urban Expressways’, 85 Journal of Political Economy, 1-25. Kennedy, Thomas E. (1975), ‘Incentive Pricing and Utility Regulation: A Comment’, 89 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 311-313. King, Stephen P. (1997), ‘Access Pricing under Rate-of-Return Regulation’, 30 Australian Economic Review, 243-255. Kiss, Ferenc (1991a), ‘Constant and Variable Productivity Adjustments for Price-Cap Regulation’, in Einhorn, Michael A. (ed.), Price-caps and Incentive Regulation in Telecommunications, Topics in Regulatory Economics and Policy Series, Norwell, MA and Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic, 95-126. Kiss, Ferenc (1991b), ‘A Sequential Mechanism for Direct Price Regulation’, in Einhorn, Michael A. (ed.), Price-caps and Incentive Regulation in Telecommunications, Topics in Regulatory Economics and Policy Series, Norwell, MA and Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic, 153 ff.
452
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
Kitch, Edmund W. (1967), ‘The Permian Basin Area Rate Case and the Regulatory Determination of Price’, 116 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 191 ff. Kitch, Edmund W. (1968), ‘Regulation of the Field Market for Natural Gas by the Federal Power Commission’, 11 Journal of Law and Economics, 243-280. Kitch, Edmund W. and Bowler, Clara Ann (1978), ‘The Facts of Munn v. Illinois’, Supreme Court Review, 313 ff. Kitch, Edmund W., Isaacson, Marc and Kaspar, Daniel (1971), ‘The Regulation of Taxicabs in Chicago’, 14 Journal of Law and Economics, 285-350. Klein, Christopher C. (1993), ‘A Comparison of Cost-Based Pricing Rules for Natural Gas Distribution Utilities’, 15 Energy Economics, 176-182. Kleindorfer, Paul R. and Fernando, Chitru S. (1993), ‘Peak-Load Pricing and Reliability under Uncertainty’, 5 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 5-23. Klevorick, Alvin K. (1966), ‘The Graduated Fair Return: A Regulatory Proposal’, 56 American Economic Review, 577-584. Klevorick, Alvin K. (1973), ‘The Behavior of a Firm Subject to Stochastic Regulatory Review’, 4 Bell Journal of Economics, 57-88. Knieps, Gunter and Vogelsang, Ingo (1982), ‘The Sustainability Concept under Alternative Behavioral Assumptions’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 234-241. Koenker, Roger W. (1979), ‘Optimal Peak-Load Pricing with Time-Additive Consumer Preferences’, 9 Journal of Econometrics, 175-192. Kohler, Daniel F. (1983), ‘The Bias in Price Elasticity Estimates under Homothetic Separability: Implications for Analysis of Peak-Load Electricity Pricing’, 1 Journal of Business and Economic Statistics, 202-210. Koschat, Martin A., Srinagesh, Padmanabhan and Uhler, Linda J. (1995), ‘Efficient Price and Capacity Choices under Uncertain Demand: An Empirical Analysis’, 7 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 5-26. Kovacic, William E. (1991), ‘Commitment in Regulation: Defense Contracting and Extensions to Price-Caps’, 3 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 219-240. Kridel, Donald J., Sappington, David E.M. and Weisman, Dennis L. (1996), ‘The Effects of Incentive Regulation in the Telecommunications Industry: A Survey’, 9 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 269-306. Kunreuther, Howard, Kleindorfer, Paul H. and Pauly, Mark V. (1983), ‘Insurance Regulation and Consumer Behavior in the United States: The Property and Liability Industry’, 139 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 452-472. Kwoka, John E., Jr (1991a), ‘Productivity and Price-Caps in Telecommunications’, in Einhorn, Michael A. (ed.), Price-caps and Incentive Regulation in Telecommunications, Topics in Regulatory Economics and Policy Series, Norwell, MA and Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic, 77-93. Kwoka, John E., Jr (1991b), ‘Price-Cap Reform of Telecommunications Regulation: A Penny Saved’, 14 Regulation, 15-18. Labus Miroljub (1990), ‘Devalvacija i Administrativna Kontrola Cena (Devaluation and Administrative Control of Prices)’, 1 Ekonomska Misao, 1-24. Laffont, Jean-Jacques (1994), ‘The New Economics of Regulation Ten Years After’,62 Econometrica, 507-537. Laffont, Jean-Jacques and Tirole, Jean (1986), ‘Using Cost Observation to Regulate Firms’, 94 Journal of Political Economy, 614-641.
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
453
Laffont, Jean-Jacques and Tirole, Jean (1990a), ‘Optimal Bypass and Cream-Skimming’,80 American Economic Review, 1042-1061. Laffont, Jean-Jacques and Tirole, Jean (1990b), ‘The Regulation of Multiproduct Firms: Part I: Theory’, 43 Journal of Public Economics, 1-36. Laffont, Jean-Jacques and Tirole, Jean (1990c), ‘The Regulation of Multiproduct Firms: Part II: Applications to Competitive Environments’, 43 Journal of Public Economics, 1-36. Laffont, Jean-Jacques and Tirole, Jean (1993), A Theory of Incentives in Procurement and Regulation, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Laffont, Jean-Jacques and Tirole, Jean (1994), ‘Access Pricing and Competition’, 38 European Economic Review, 1673-1710. Laffont, Jean-Jacques and Tirole, Jean (1996), ‘Creating Competition through Interconnection: Theory and Practice’, 10 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 227-256. Laffont, Jean-Jacques, Rey, Patrick and Tirole, Jean (1998a), ‘Network Competition: I. Overview and Non-Discriminatory Pricing’, 29 Rand Journal of Economics, 1-37. Laffont, Jean-Jacques, Rey, Patrick and Tirole, Jean (1998b), ‘Network Competition: II. Price Discrimination’, 29 Rand Journal of Economics, 38-56. Lam, Pun Lee (1996), ‘Transition to Competition in Hong Kong’s Local Telephone Industry’, 20 Telecommunications Policy, 517-529. Larson, Alexander C. (1998), ‘The Efficiency of the Efficient-Component-Pricing Rule: A Comment’, Antitrust Bulletin, forthcoming. Larson, Alexander C. and Lehman, Dale E. (1997), ‘Essentiality, Efficiency, and the Efficient Component-Pricing Rule’, 12 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 71-80. Law, Peter J. (1993), ‘Welfare Effects of Strategic Price Setting in Anticipation of Price Regulation’, 45 Bulletin of Economic Research, 147-159. Le Pen, Claude (1988), ‘Reglementation des Prix et Formes de la Concurrence dans l’Industrie Pharmaceutique (Price Regulation and Competition Patterns in the Ethical Drug Industry)’, 39 Revue Economique, 1159-1191. Lee, Sang Kyu and Kim, Jae Cheol (1996), ‘An Incentive Scheme of a Non-Linear Price Schedule for Regulating a Monopolist with Unknown Cost’, 50 Economics Letters, 271-278. Leland, Hayne E. and Meyer, Robert G. (1976), ‘Monopoly Pricing Structure with Imperfect Discrimination’, 7 Bell Journal of Economics, 449-462. Levi, Maurice and Dexter, Albert (1983), ‘Regulated Prices and their Consequences’, 9 Canadian Public Policy, 24-31. Levin, Richard C. (1978), ‘Allocation in Surface Freight Transportation: Does Rate Regulation Matter?’, 9 Bell Journal of Economics, 18-45. Levin, Richard C. (1981), ‘Railroad Rates, Profitability, and Welfare under Deregulation’, 12 Bell Journal of Economics, 1-26. Levine, Michael E. (1965), ‘Is Regulation Necessary? California Air Transportation and National Regulatory Policy’, 74 Yale Law Journal, 1416-1447. Lewellen, Wilbur G. and Mauer, David C. (1993), ‘Public Utility Valuation and Risk under Incentive Regulation’, 5 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 263-287. Lewis, Tracy R. and Sappington, David E.M. (1989), ‘Regulatory Options and Price-Cap Regulation’, 20 Rand Journal of Economics, 405-416. Lewis, Tracy R. and Sappington, David E.M. (1992), ‘Incentives for Conservation and Quality-Improvement by Public Utilities’, 82 American Economic Review, 1321-1340. Linhart, Peter B., Radner, Roy and Sinden, Franker W. (1991), ‘A Sequential Mechanism for Direct Price Regulation’, in Einhorn, Michael A. (ed.), Price-caps and Incentive Regulation in
454
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
Telecommunications, Topics in Regulatory Economics and Policy Series, Norwell, MA and Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic, 127-153. Lioukias, Spyros K. (1983), ‘Peak-Load Pricing under Periodic and Stochastic Supply’, 20 European Economic Review, 13-21. Lipsey, Richard G. and Lancaster, Kelvin (1956), ‘The General Theory of Second Best’, 24 Review of Economic Studies, 11-32. Liston-Heyes, Catherine (1993), ‘Price-Cap Versus Rate-of-Return Regulation’, 5 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 25-48. Littlechild, Stephen C. (1970), ‘Peak-Load Pricing of Telephone Calls’, 1 Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, 191-200. Liu, Chorng Jian (1993), ‘An Econometric Analysis of Local Telephone Pricing Policy: The Optimal Two-Part Tariff’, 21 Academia Economic Papers, 183-225. Loeb, Martin and Magat, Wesley A. (1979), ‘A Decentralized Method for Utility Regulation’, 22 Journal of Law and Economics, 399-404. Logan, John W., Masson, Robert T. and Reynolds, Robert J. (1989), ‘Efficient Regulation with Little Information: Reality in the Limit?’, 30 International Economic Review, 851-861. Loube, Robert (1995), ‘Price-Cap Regulation: Problems and Solutions’,71 Land Economics, 286-298. Lyon, Thomas P. (1990), ‘Spot and Forward Markets for Natural Gas: The Effects of State Regulation’, 2 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 299-316. Lyon, Thomas P. (1991), ‘Regulation with 20-20 Hindsight: Heads I Win, Tails You Lose?’, 22 Rand Journal of Economics, 581-595. Lyon, Thomas P. (1992), ‘Regulation with 20-20 Hindsight: Least-Cost Rules and Variable Costs’, 40 Journal of Industrial Economics, 277-289. Lyon, Thomas P. (1995), ‘Regulatory Hindsight Review and Innovation by Electric Utilities’, 7 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 233-254. Lyon, Thomas P. (1996a), ‘Evaluating the Performance of Non-Bayesian Regulatory Mechanisms’, 9 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 41-60. Lyon, Thomas P. (1996b), ‘A Model of Sliding Scale Regulation’, 9 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 227-247. Lyon, Thomas P. and Huang, Haizou (1995), ‘Asymmetric Regulation and Incentives for Innovation’, 4 Industrial and Corporate Change, 769-776. Lyon, Thomas P. and Toman, Michael A. (1991), ‘Designing Price-Caps for Gas Distribution Systems’, 3 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 175-192. Ma, Ching To Albert and Burgess, James F., Jr (1993), ‘Quality Competition, Welfare, and Regulation’, 58 Journal of Economics, 153-173. Mabley, R. and Strack, Walter (1982), ‘Deregulation: A Green Light for Trucking Efficiency’, 36 Regulation, 42-56. Macavoy, Paul W. (1973), ‘The Regulation-Induced Shortage of Natural Gas’, 4 Bell Journal of Economics, 454-498. Macavoy, Paul W. and Snow, John W. (eds) (1977), Regulation of Entry and Pricing in Truck Transportation, Washington, American Enterprise Institute. Macavoy, Paul W., Spulber, Daniel F. and Stangle, Bruce E. (1989), ‘Is Competitive Entry Free? Bypass and Partial Deregulation in Natural Gas Markets’, 6 Yale Journal on Regulation, 209-247. MacKie-Mason, Jeffrey K. and Waterman, David (eds) (1998), Telephony, the Internet, and the
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
455
Media, Papers from the 25th Annual Telecommunications Policy Research Conference, Mahwah, NJ, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Maddock, Rodney (1990), ‘Welfare Analysis with Rising Block Pricing’, 11 Resources and Energy, 159-168. Maddock, Rodney and Castano, Elkin (1991), ‘The Welfare Impact of Rising Block Pricing: Electricity in Colombia’, 12 Energy Journal, 65-77. Maddock, Rodney, Castano, Elkin and Vela, Frank (1992), ‘Estimating Electricity Demand: The Cost of Linearising the Budget Constraint’, 74 Review of Economics and Statistics, 350-354. Majumdar, Sumit K. (1997), ‘Incentive Regulation and Productive Efficiency in the U.S. Telecommunications Industry’, 70 Journal of Business, 547-576. Malko, J. Robert, Lindsay, Malcolm A. and Everett, Carol T. (1977), ‘Towards Implementation of Peak-Load Pricing of Electricity: A Challenge for Applied Economics’, 3 Journal of Energy and Development, 82-102. Manning, Willard G., Jr, Mitchell, Bridger M. and Acton, Jan Paul (1979), ‘Design of the Los Angeles Peak-Load Pricing Experiment for Electricity’, 11 Journal of Econometrics, 131-194. Mansell, Robin E. (1986), ‘The Telecommunications Bypass Threat: Real or Imagined’, 20 Journal of Economic Issues, 145-164. Marino, Anthony M. (1978a), ‘Peak-Load Pricing in a Neoclassical Model with Bounds on Variable Input Utilization’, 9 Bell Journal of Economics, 249-259. Marino, Anthony M. (1978b), ‘Peak-Load Pricing under Regulatory Constraint: Two Remarks’, 44 Southern Economic Journal, 606-615. Mathios, Alan D. and Rogers, Robert P. (1989), ‘The Impact of Alternative Forms of State Regulation of AT&T on Direct-Dial, Long-Distance Telephone Rates’, 20 Rand Journal of Economics, 437-453. Mathios, Alan D. and Rogers, Robert P. (1990), ‘The Impact and Politics of Entry Regulation on Intrastate Telephone Rates’, 2 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 53-68. Matsukawa, Isamu, Madono, Seishi and Nakashima, Takako (1993), ‘An Empirical Analysis of Ramsey Pricing in Japanese Electric Utilities’, 7 Journal of the Japanese and International Economy, 256-276. Mayer, Colin and Vickers, John S. (1996), ‘Profit-Sharing Regulation: An Economic Appraisal’, 17 Fiscal Studies, 1-18. Mayo, John W. (1984), ‘Multiproduct Monopoly, Regulation and Firm Costs’, 51 Southern Economic Journal, 208-218. McCormick, Robert E., Shughart, William F., II and Tollison, Robert F. (1984), ‘The Disinterest in Deregulation’, 74 American Economic Review, 1075-1079. Melnick, Glenn A., Wheeler, John R.C. and Feldstein, Paul J. (1981), ‘Effects of Rate Regulation on Selected Components of Hospital Expenses’, 18 Inquiry, 240-246. Meyer, John R. and Oster, Clinton V., Jr. (1984), Deregulation and the New Airline Entrepreneurs, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Meyer, Robert A. and Leland, Hayne E. (1980), ‘The Effectiveness of Price Regulation’, 62 Review of Economics and Statistics, 555-566. Mirman, Leonard J. and Sibley, David (1980), ‘Optimal Nonlinear Prices for Multiproduct Monopolies’, 11 Bell Journal of Economics, 659-670. Mirman, Leonard J. and Tauman, Yair (1982), ‘Demand Compatible, Equitable, Cost Sharing Prices’, 7 Mathematics of Operations Research, 40-56. Mirman, Leonard J., Samet, Dov and Tauman, Yair (1983), ‘Axiomatic Approach to the Allocation
456
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
of a Fixed Cost Through Prices’, 14 Bell Journal of Economics, 139-151. Mitchell, Bridger M. (1978), ‘Optimal Pricing of Local Telephone Service’, 68 American Economic Review, 517-537. Mitchell, Bridger M. and Vogelsang, Ingo (1991),Telecommunications Pricing: Theory and Practice, Cambridge, MA, Cambridge University Press. Mitchell, Bridger M. and Vogelsang, Ingo (1995), ‘Expanded Competitiveness and Regulatory Safeguards in Local Telecommunications’, 16 Managerial and Decision Economics, 451-467. Mitchell, Bridger M. and Vogelsang, Ingo (1997), Telecommunications Competition: The Last Ten Miles, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Mitchell, Bridger M., Manning, Willard G., Jr and Acton, Jan Paul (1978), Peak-Load Pricing: European Lessons for U.S. Energy Policy, Cambridge, MA, Ballinger. Mixon, Franklin G., Jr and Hsing, Yu (1997), ‘The Determinants of Market Share for the ‘Dominant Firm” in Telecommunications’, 9 Information Economics and Policy, 309-318. Mohring, Herbert (1970), ‘The Peak-Load Problem with Increasing Returns and Pricing Constraints’, 60 American Economic Review, 693-705. Molka-Danielsen, Judith A. and Weiss, Martin B.H. (1998), ‘Firm Interaction and the Expected Price for Access’, in MacKie-Mason, Jeffrey K. and Waterman, David (eds), Telephony, the Internet, and the Media, Papers from the 25th Annual Telecommunications Policy Research Conference, Mahwah, NJ, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Monson, Calvin S. and Larson, Alexander C. (1991), ‘Pricing and Investment Incentives under Price Ceiling Regulation’, in Einhorn, Michael A. (ed.), Price-caps and Incentive Regulation in Telecommunications, Topics in Regulatory Economics and Policy Series, Norwell, MA and Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic, 221-237. Moore, Thomas G. (1975), ‘Deregulating Surface Freight Transportation’, in Phillips, A.(ed.), Promoting Competition in Regulated Markets, Washington, DC, The Brookings Institution. Moore, Thomas G. (1976), Trucking Regulation: Lessons from Europe, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 148 p. Moore, Thomas G. (1978), ‘The Beneficiaries of Trucking Regulation’, 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 327-343. Moore, Thomas G. (1986), ‘Rail and Trucking Deregulation’, in Weiss, Leonard W. and Klass, Michael W. (ed.), Regulatory Reform: What Actually Happened, Boston, Little Brown, 14-39. Moretto, Michele (1989), ‘L’Impresa l’Accumulazione e il Controllo Esterno del Tasso di Rendimento: un Riesame dell’Effetto Averch-Johnson (Capital Accumulation in the Regulated Firm: Re-examination of the Averch-Johnson Effect. With English Summary)’,36 Rivista Internazionale di Scienze Economiche e Commerciali, 75-95. Morgan, Charles S. (1923), Regulation and the Management of Public Utilities, Boston, Houghton Mifflin. Morrison, Steven A. and Winston, Clifford (1986), The Economic Effects of Airline Deregulation, Washington, Brookings Institution. Murphy, F.H. and Soyster, A.L. (1982a), ‘Optimal Output of the Averch-Johnson Model’, 10 Atlantic Economic Journal, 77-81. Murphy, F.H. and Soyster, A.L. (1982b), ‘The Averch-Johnson Model with Leontief Production
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
457
Functions: Extensions and Applications’, 4 Energy Economics, 169-179. Murphy, Michael M. (1980), ‘Price Controls and the Behavior of the Firm’, 21 International Economic Review, 285-291. Navarro, Peter (1982), ‘Public Utility Regulation: Performance, Determinants and Energy Policy Impacts’, 3 Energy Journal, 119-149. Nelson, Jon P., Roberts, Mark J. and Tromp, Emsley P. (1987), ‘An Analysis of Ramsey Pricing in Electric Utilities’, in Crew, Michael A. (ed.), Regulating Utilities in an Era of Deregulation, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 85-109. Nelson, Randy A. and Wohar, Mark E. (1983), ‘Regulation, Scale Economies, and Productivity in Steam-Electric Generation’, 24 International Economic Review, 57-78. Nemoto, Jiro, Nakanishi, Yasuo and Madono, Seishi (1993), ‘Scale Economies and Over-Capitalization in Japanese Electric Utilities’, 34 International Economic Review, 431-460. Neu, Werner (1993), ‘Allocative Inefficiency Properties of Price-Cap Regulation’, 5 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 159-182. Neufeld, John L. (1987), ‘Price Discrimination and the Adoption of the Electricity Demand Charge’, 47 Journal of Economic History, 693-709. Newbery, David M.G. (1995), ‘Power Markets and Market Power’, 16 Energy Journal, 39-66. Nguyen, D. and MacGregor-Reid, G.J. (1977), ‘Interdependent Demands, Regulatory Constraint and Peak-Load Pricing’, 25 Journal of Industrial Economics, 275-293. Nieswiadomy, Michael and Molina, David J. (1989), ‘Comparing Residential Water Demand Estimates under Decreasing and Increasing Block Rates Using Household Data’, 65 Land Economics, 280-289. Noll, Roger C. (1989), ‘Economic Perspectives on the Politics of Regulation’, in Schmalensee, Richard and Willig, Robert D. (eds), Handbook of Industrial Organzation, vol. 2, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 1253-1287. Noll, Roger G. and Owen, Bruce M. (1983), The Political Economy of Deregulation: Interest Groups in the Regulatory Process, Washington, American Enterprise Institute. Norton, Seth W. (1985), ‘Regulation and Systematic Risk: The Case of Electric Utilities’, 28 Journal of Law and Economics, 671-686. Nowell, C. and Shogren, Jason F. (1991), ‘The Timing of a Rate Request by a Regulated Firm’, 57 Southern Journal of Economics, 1054-1060. Olson, C. Vincent and Trapani, John M. (1981), ‘Who Has Benefited from Regulation of the Airline Industry?’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 75-94. Ordover, Janusz A. and Panzar, John C. (1980), ‘On the Nonexistence of Pareto Superior Outlay Schedules’, 11 Bell Journal of Economics, 351-354. Oster, Sharon M. (1982), ‘The Strategic Use of Regulatory Investment by Industry Subgroups’, 20 Economic Inquiry, 604-618. Otsuka, Yasuji (1997), ‘A Welfare Analysis of Local Franchise and Other Types of Regulation: Evidence from the Cable TV Industry’, 11 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 157-180. Oum, Tae Hoon and Tretheway, Michael W. (1988), ‘Ramsey Pricing in the Presence of Externality Costs’, 22 Journal of Transport Economics and Policy, 307-317. Oum, Tae Hoon and Zhang, Yimin (1995), ‘Competition and Allocative Efficiency: The Case of the U.S. Telephone Industry’, 77(1) Review of Economics and Statistics, 82-96. Owen, Bruce M. and Braeutigam, Ronald R. (1978), The Regulation Game: Strategic Use of the Administrative Process, Cambridge, MA, Ballinger.
458
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
Pal, Debashis (1993), ‘Regulating a Monopoly with Unknown Demand: An Alternative Approach’, 5 Information Economics and Policy, 253-267. Palmer, Karen L. (1991a), ‘Using an Upper Bound on Stand-Alone Cost in Tests of Cross Subsidy’, 35 Economics Letters, 457-460. Palmer, Karen L. (1991b), ‘Diversification by Regulated Monopolies and Incentives for Cost-Reducing R&D’, 81 American Economic Review, 266-270. Palmer, Karen L. (1992), ‘A Test for Cross-Subsidies in Local Telephone Rates: Do Business Customers Subsidize Residential Customers’, 23 Rand Journal of Economics, 415-431. Panzar, John C. (1976), ‘A Neoclassical Approach to Peak-Load Pricing’, 7 Bell Journal of Economics, 521-530. Panzar, John C. (1980), ‘Sustainability, Efficiency and Vertical Integration’, in Kleindorfer, Paul and Mitchell, Bridger M. (eds), Regulated Industries and Public Enterprise, Lexington, Heath. Panzar, John C. (1989), ‘Technological Determinants of Firm and Industry Structure’, in Schmalensee, Richard and Willig, Robert D. (eds), Handbook of Industrial Organization II, Amsterdam, North Holland, 3-59. Panzar, John C. and Willig, Robert D. (1977), ‘Free Entry and the Sustainability of Natural Monopoly’, 8 Bell Journal of Economics, 1-22. Parsons, Steve G. (1994), ‘Seven Years after Kahn and Shew: Lingering Myths on Costs and Pricing Telephone Service’, 11 Yale Journal on Regulation, 141-170. Parsons, Steve G. and Ward, Michael R. (1995), ‘Factor Substitution in Long-Distance Telecommunications’, 62 Southern Economic Journal, 405-410. Pasour, Ernest C., Jr (1984), ‘Information: A Neglected Aspect of the Theory of Price Regulation’, 3 Cato Journal, 855-867. Passmore, Stuart Wayne (1984), ‘Ramsey Optimal Price and Capacity with Uncertainty’, Federal Reserve Bank of New York Research Papers, No. 8419. Pastor, Santos (1982a), ‘El Mercado de Transporte Marítimo en los Primeros Ochenta (The Maritime Transport in the Eighties: Problems and Policies)’, 2 Anuario de Derecho Marítimo. Pastor, Santos (1982b), ‘La Construcción Naval Española veinte Años Despuís (The Shipbuilding Industry Twenty Years After: Dynamics and Regulation)’, in Raga, Jos T. (ed.), Homenaje al Profesor Lucas Beltrón, Madrid, IEF. Pastor, Santos (1984), ‘Política Marítima Española: Valoración e Implicaciones de Futuro (The Regulation of the Shipping Industry)’, in X (ed.), El Libro Transporte Marítimo y Política Económica, Madrid, IETC-Ministerio de Transportes. Paukert, Felix (1988a), ‘Price Policies as a Form of Incomes Policy in Developing Countries: 1. Objectives and Instruments’, 127 International Labour Review, 135-151. Paukert, Felix (1988b), ‘Price Policies as a Form of Incomes Policy in Developing Countries: 2. Instruments and Effects’, 127 International Labour Review, 293-316. Peles, Yoram C. (1981), ‘A Proposal for Peak-Load Pricing of Public Utilities’, 3 Energy Economics, 187-190. Peles, Yoram C. and Stein, J. L. (1976), ‘The Effect of Rate-of-return Regulation is Highly Sensitive to the Nature of Uncertainty’, 66 American Economic Review, 278-289. Peles, Yoram C. and Whittred, Greg (1996), ‘Incentive Effects of Rate-of-Return Regulation: The Case of Hong Kong Electric Utilities’, 10 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 99-112. Peltzman, Sam (1976), ‘Toward a More General Theory of Regulation’, 19 Journal of Law and
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
459
Economics, 2111-2140. Petersen, H. Craig (1975), ‘An Empirical Test of Regulatory Effects’, 6 Bell Journal of Economics, 111-126. Phelps, Charles E. (1982), ‘Kalt’s The Economics and Politics of Oil Price Regulation: Federal Policy in the Post-Embargo Era’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 289-295. Phillips, Owen R. and Mason, Charles F. (1996), ‘Market Regulation and Multimarket Rivalry’, 27 Rand Journal of Economics, 596-617. Pindyck, Robert S. (1974), ‘The Regulatory Implications of Three Alternative Econometric Supply Models of Natural Gas’, 5 Bell Journal of Economics, 633-645. Pint, Ellen M. (1991), ‘Nationalization vs. Regulation of Monopolies: The Effects of Ownership on Efficiency’, 44 Journal of Public Economics, 131-164. Pint, Ellen M. (1992), ‘Price-Cap versus Rate-of-Return Regulation in a Stochastic-Cost Model’, 23 Rand Journal of Economics, 564-578. Platts, A.R. (1981), ‘Traditional Peak-Load Pricing Theory: A Synthesis’, 8 Journal of Economic Studies, 47-51. Polemarchakis, Heraklis (1979), ‘Incomplete Markets, Price Regulation, and Welfare’, 69 American Economic Review, 662-339. Posner, Richard A. (1969), ‘Natural Monopoly and Its Regulation’, 21 Stanford Law Review, 548-643. Posner, Richard A. (1974), ‘Theories of Economic Regulation’, 5 Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, 335-358. Pospischil, Rudolf (1995), ‘A Bypass for the Local Loop: Deutsche Telekom’s Strategy for Fiber to the Home’, 19 Telecommunications Policy, 579-585. Price, Catherine Waddams (1989), ‘Gas Privatization: Effects on Pricing Policy’, in Bishop, Matthew, Kay, John and Mayer, Colin (eds), Privatization and Economic Performance, Oxford and New York, Oxford University Press, 137-161. Price, Catherine Waddams (1992), ‘Regulation of the U.K. Gas Industry: The First Five Years’, 63 Annals of Public and Cooperative Economics, 189-206. Price, Catherine Waddams (1994), ‘Gas Regulation and Competition: Substitutes or Complements?’, in Helm, Dieter, Kay, John and Thompson, David (eds), The Market for Energy, Oxford and New York, Oxford University Press, 263-278. Price, Catherine Waddams (1995), ‘Structure, Regulation, and Interconnection: A Comparative Study of the UK Energy Market’, 5 Pacific and Asian Journal of Energy, 249-260. Price, Catherine Waddams (1997a), ‘Regulating for Fairness’, 4 New Economy, 117-122. Price, Catherine Waddams (1997b), ‘Competition and Regulation in the UK Gas Industry’, 13 Oxford Review of Economic Policy, 47-63. Price, Catherine Waddams and Weyman-Jones, Thomas G. (1996), ‘Malmquist Indices of Productivity Change in the UK Gas Industry before and after Privatization’, 28 Applied Economics, 29-39. Quaden, Guy (1981), ‘Price Control Policy in Belgium’, 52 Annals of Public and Cooperative Economy, 465-476. Ramsey, Frank P. (1927), ‘A Contribution to the Theory of Taxation’, 37 Economic Journal, 47-61. Rapp, Richard Tilden and Lloyd, Adam (1994),‘“Civilized” Pharmaceutical Price Regulation: Can the U.S. Have It Too?’, 17(2) Regulation, 72-82. Rees, Ray (1984), Public Enterprise Economics, London, Weidenfeld and Nicholson. Renshaw, Edward F. (1980), ‘Expected Welfare Gains from Peak-Load Electricity Charges’, 2 Energy
460
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
Economics, 37-45. Richter, Wolfram F. and Weimann, Joachim (1985), ‘Ramsey Pricing the Telephone Services of the Deutsche Bundespost’, 141 Zeitschrift für die Gesamte Staatswissenschaft, 516-524. Riordan, Michael H. (1984), ‘On Delegating Price Authority to a Regulated Firm’, 15 Rand Journal of Economics, 108-115. Riordan, Michael H. and Sappington, David E.M. (1987), ‘Awarding Monopoly Franchises’, 77 American Economic Review, 305-332. Robichek, Alexander (1978), ‘Regulation and Modern Finance Theory’, 33 Journal of Finance, 693-705. Roeloffs, Matthew (1998), ‘Local Measured Service Revisited: A Southern Wisconsin Test Case’, 26 Atlantic Economic Journal. Rohlfs, Jeffrey (1974), ‘A Theory of Interdependent Demand for a Communications Service’, 5 Bell Journal of Economics, 16-37. Romer, Thomas and Rosenthal, Howard (1987), ‘Modern Political Economy and the Study of Regulation’, in Bailey, Elizabeth E. (ed.), Public Regulation: New Perspectives on Institutions and Policies. MIT Press Series on the Regulation of Economic Activity, no. 14, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Ros, Agustin J. and Harvill, Terry S. (1995), ‘Incentive Ratemaking in Illinois: The Transition to Competitive Market’, 133 Public Utilities Fortnightly, 22-25. Rose, Nancy L. (1985), ‘The Incidence of Regulatory Rents in the Motor Carrier Industry’, 16 Rand Journal of Economics, 299-318. Rose, Nancy L. (1987), ‘Labor Rent Sharing and Regulation: Evidence from the Trucking Industry’, 95 Journal of Political Economy, 1146-1178. Rubinovitz, Robert N. (1993), ‘Market Power and Price Increases for Basic Cable Service since Deregulation’, 224 Rand Journal of Economics, 1-18. Russo, Michael V. and Teece, David J. (1991), ‘Natural Gas Distribution in California’, in Gilbert, Richard J. (ed.), Regulatory Choices: A Perspective on Developments in Energy Policy, Berkeley, LA and Oxford, University of California Press, 120-186. Salant, David J. and Woroch, Glenn A. (1992), ‘Trigger Price Regulation’, 23 Rand Journal of Economics, 29-51. Samet, Dov and Tauman, Yair (1982), ‘A Characterization of Price Mechanisms and the Determination of Marginal Cost Prices under a Set of Axioms’, 50 Econometrica, 895-910. Samprone, Joseph C., Jr (1979), ‘Rate Regulation and Nonprice Competition in the Property and Liability Insurance Industry’, 46 Journal of Risk and Insurance, 683-696. Sappington, David E.M. (1980), ‘Strategic Firm Behavior under a Dynamic Regulatory Adjustment Process’, 11 Bell Journal of Economics, 360-372. Sappington, David E.M. (1983), ‘Optimal Regulation of a Multiproduct Monopoly with Unknown Technological Capabilities’, 14 Bell Journal of Economics, 453-463. Sappington, David E.M. (1994), ‘Designing Incentive Regulation’, 9 Review of Industrial Organization, 245-272. Sappington, David E.M. and Sibley, David S. (1988), ‘Regulating Without Cost Information: The Incremental Surplus Subsidy Scheme’, 29 International Economic Review, 297-306. Sappington, David E.M. and Sibley, David S. (1992), ‘Strategic Nonlinear Pricing under Price-Cap Regulation’, 23 Rand Journal of Economics, 1-19. Sappington, David E.M. and Sibley, David S. (1993), ‘Regulatory Incentive Policies and Abuse’, 5
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
461
Journal of Regulatory Economics, 131-141. Sappington, David E.M. and Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1987), ‘Information and Regulation’, in Bailey, Elizabeth E. (ed.), Public Regulation: New Perspectives on Institutions and Policies. MIT Press Series on the Regulation of Economic Activity, no. 14, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Sappington, David E.M. and Weisman, Dennis L. (1996a), Designing Incentive Regulation for the Telecommunications Industry, Cambridge, MA, Aei Press. Sappington, David E.M. and Weisman, Dennis L. (1996b), ‘Potential Pitfalls in Empirical Investigations of the Effects of Incentive Regulation Plans in the Telecommunications Industry’, 8 Information Economics and Policy, 125-140. Sappington, David E.M. and Weisman, Dennis L. (1996c), ‘Revenue Sharing in Incentive Regulation Plans’, 8 Information Economics and Policy, 229-248. Saving, Thomas R. and De Vany, Arthur S. (1981), ‘Uncertain Markets, Reliability and Peak-Load Pricing’, 47 Southern Economic Journal, 908-923. Scarpa, Carlo (1994), ‘Regulation as a Bargaining Process: Negotiation over Price and Cost-Reducing Investments’, 46 Oxford Economic Papers, 357-365. Schmalensee, Richard (1977), ‘Comparative Static Properties of Regulated Airline Oligopolies’, 8 Bell Journal of Economics, 565-576. Schmalensee, Richard (1979), The Control of Natural Monopolies, Lexington, DC, Heath. Schmalensee, Richard (1981), ‘Monopolistic Two-Part Pricing Arrangement’, 12 Bell Journal of Economics, 445-466. Schmalensee, Richard (1989a), ‘Good Regulatory Regimes’, 20 Rand Journal of Economics, 417-436. Schmalensee, Richard (1989b), ‘The Potential of Incentive Regulation’, in Helm, Dieter, Kay, John and Thompson, David (eds), The Market for Energy, Oxford and New York, Oxford University Press. Schwert, G. William (1981), ‘Using Financial Data to Measure Effects of Regulation’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 121-158. Reprinted in Posner, Richard A. and Scott, Kenneth E. (eds) (1980), Economics of Corporation Law and Securities Regulation, Boston, Little Brown. Sen, Amitava and Sengupta, Jati K. (1969), ‘Optimal Capacity Models under Periodic Demand: A Survey of Peak-Load Pricing Theory and Appraisal’, 125 Zeitschrift für die Gesamte Staatswissenschaft, 371-395. Sharkey, William W. (1981), ‘Existence of Sustainable Prices for Natural Monopoly Outputs’, 12 Bell Journal of Economics, 144-154. Sharkey, William W. (1982a), The Theory of Natural Monopoly, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Sharkey, William W. (1982b), ‘Suggestions for a Game Theoretic Approach to Public Utility Pricing and Cost Allocation’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 57-68. Sheehan, Michael F. (1991a), ‘Ramsey Pricing without Cross-Subsidization? Response’, 25 Journal of Economic Issues, 1152-1155. Sheehan, Michael F. (1991b), ‘Why Ramsey Pricing is Wrong: The Case of Telecommunications Regulation’, 25 Journal of Economic Issues, 21-32. Sheehan, Michael F. (1993), ‘Why Ramsey Pricing is Wrong: The Case of Telecommunications Regulation: A Response’, 27 Journal of Economic Issues, 1247-1254. Sherman, R. (1995), ‘Price-Cap Regulation and the Financing of Firms’, 0 Revue d’Economie Industrielle, 7-18.
462
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
Sherman, R. and Visscher, Michael (1978), ‘Second Best Pricing with Stochastic Demand’, 68 American Economic Review, 41-53. Sheshinski, Eytan (1971), ‘Welfare Aspects of a Regulatory Constraint: Note’, 61 American Economic Review, 175-178. Shih, Jun Ji (1989), ‘Edgeworth’s Contribution to the Theory of “Ramsey Pricing’’, 21 History of Political Economy, 345-349. Shleifer, Andrei (1985), ‘A Theory of Yardstick Competition’, 16 Rand Journal of Economics, 319-327. Sibley, David (1989), ‘Asymmetric Information, Incentives and Price-Cap Regulation’, 20 Rand Journal of Economics, 392-404. Sibley, David S., Heyman, Daniel P. and Taylor, William E. (1991), ‘Optional Tariffs for Access under the FCC’s Price-Cap Proposal’, in Einhorn, Michael A. (ed.),Price-caps and Incentive Regulation in Telecommunications, Topics in Regulatory Economics and Policy Series, Norwell, MA and Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic, 191-206. Sloan, Frank A. (1981), ‘Regulation and the Rising Cost of Hospital Care’, 63 Review of Economics and Statistics, 479-487. Sloan, Frank A. and Steinwald, Bruce (1980), ‘Effects of Regulation on Hospital Costs and Input Use’, 23 Journal of Law and Economics, 81-109. Sloss, James (1970), ‘Regulation of Motor Freight Transportation: A Quantitative Evaluation of Policy’, 1 Bell Journal of Economics, 327-366. Smallwood, Douglas E. (1975), ‘Competition, Regulation, and Product Quality in the Automobile Insurance Industry’, in Phillips, A.(ed.), Promoting Competition in Regulated Markets, Washington, DC, The Brookings Institution. Smiley, Robert H. and Greene, William H. (1983), ‘Determinants of the Effectiveness of Electric Utility Regulation’, 5 Resources and Energy, 65-81. Smith, Rodney T., Bradley, Michael and Jarrell, Gregg A. (1986), ‘Studying Firm-Specific Effects of Regulation with Stock Market Data: An Application to Oil Price Regulation’, 17 Rand Journal of Economics, 467-489. Snowberger, Vinson (1988), ‘Firm Behavior in the Rate Design Phase of the Regulatory Process’, 27 Economics Letters, 381-385. Sorenson, John, Tschirhart, John and Winston, Andrew (1976), ‘A Game Theoretic Approach to Peak-Load Pricing’, 7 Bell Journal of Economics, 497-520. Sorenson, John, Tschirhart, John and Winston, Andrew (1978), ‘A Theory of Pricing under Decreasing Costs’, 68 American Economic Review, 614-624. Spady, Richard H. and Friedlaender, Ann F. (1978), ‘Hedonic Cost Functions for the Regulated Trucking Industry’, 9 Bell Journal of Economics, 159-179. Spann, Robert M. (1974), ‘Rate-of-Return Regulation and Efficiency in Production: An Empirical Test of the Averch-Johnson Thesis’, 5 Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, 38-52. Spence, A. Michael (1975), ‘Monopoly, Quality and Regulation’, 6 Bell Journal of Economics, 417-429. Spence, A. Michael (1981a), ‘Multi-Product Quantity Dependent Prices and Profitability Constraints’, 47 Review of Economic Studies, 821-841. Spence, A. Michael (1981b), ‘Nonlinear Prices and Welfare’, 8 Journal of Public Economics, 1-18. Spiegel, Yossef and Spulber, Daniel F. (1994), ‘The Capital Structure of Regulated Firms’, 25 Rand Journal of Economics, 424-440.
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
463
Spiller, Pablo T. and Vogelsang, Ingo (1993), ‘Regulation Without Commitment: Price Regulation of U.K. Utilities’, Boston University Industry Studies Program Discussion Paper, No. 41,28. Starkey, Margarete Z. and Van Pelt, John W., Jr (1995), ‘Productivity Measurement and Price-Cap Regulation’, 19 Telecommunications Policy, 151-160. Steiner, P.O. (1957), ‘Peak-load and Efficient Pricing’, 71 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 585-610. Stigler, George J. (1975), The Citizen and the State. Essays on Regulation, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 209 p. Stigler, George J. and Friedland, Claire (1962), ‘What Can Regulators Regulate? The Case of Electricity’, 5 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-16. Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1977), ‘Monopoly, Nonlinear Pricing and Imperfect Information’, 44 Review of Economic Studies, 407-430. Stollery, Kenneth R. (1981), ‘Price Controls on Nonrenewable Resources when Capacity is Constrained’, 48 Southern Economic Journal, 490-498. Stout, Lynn A. and Barnes, David D. (1992), Economic Foundations of Regulation and Antitrust Law, St Paul, West Publishing. Strimling, David V. and Mirakhor, Abbas (1974), ‘A Note on the Averch-Johnson Effect Controversy’, 41 Southern Economic Journal, 149-151. Studness, Charles M. (1995), ‘Price-Cap Regulation: Will It Survive in U.K.?’, 133 Public Utilities Fortnightly, 36-37. Sullivan, Edward J. and Pry, Kevin B. (1991), ‘Eighteenth Century London Theater and the Capture Theory of Regulation’, 15 Journal of Cultural Economics, 41-52. Swaan, Wim (1989), ‘Price Regulation in Hungary: Indirect but Comprehensive Bureaucratic Control’, 31 Comparative Economic Studies, 10-52. Sweeney, George (1982), ‘Welfare Implications of Fully Distributed Cost Pricing Applied to Partially Regulated Firms’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 525-533. Takayama, A. (1969), ‘Behavior of the Firm under Regulatory Constraint’, 59 American Economic Review, 255-260. Tam, Mo Yin S. (1988), ‘A Mechanism to Induce Ramsey Pricing for Natural Monopoly Firms’, 6 International Journal of Industrial Organization, 247-261. Taussig, Frank W. (1913), ‘Railway Rates and Joint Costs’, 27 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 692-694. Tawada, Makoto and Katayama, Sei Ichi (1990), ‘On the Technical Efficiency under Regulation: A Case for the Japanese Electric Power Industry’, 41 Economic Studies Quarterly, 34-47. Taylor, Lester D. and Weisman, Dennis L. (1996), ‘A Note on Price-cap Regulation and Competition’, 11 Review of Industrial Organization, 459-471. Thomadakis, Stavros B. (1982), ‘Price Regulation under Uncertainty in an Asymmetric Decision Environment’, 97 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 689-698. Train, Kenneth E. (1991), Optimal Regulation: The Economic Theory of Natural Monopoly, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Turvey, Ralph (1968), Optimal Pricing and Investment in Electricity Supply, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Turvey, Ralph (1969), ‘Marginal Cost’, 79 Economic Journal, 282-299. Tye, William B. (1994), ‘The Pricing of Inputs Sold to Competitors: A Response’, 11 Yale Journal on Regulation, 203-224. Tzoannos, J. (1977), ‘An Empirical Study of Peak-Load Pricing and Investment Policies for the
464
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
Domestic Market of Gas in Great Britain’, 9 Applied Economics, 133-153. Upadhya, Kamal P. and Mixon, Franklin G., Jr (1995), ‘Regulatory Capture and the Price of Electricity: Evidence from Time Series Estimates’,22 International Journal of Social Economics, 16-23. Vickers, John S. and Yarrow, George (1988a), Privatization: An Economic Analysis, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Vickers, John S. and Yarrow, George (1988b), ‘Regulation of Privatised Firms in Britain’, 32 European Economic Review, 465-472. Vickrey, William (1985), ‘The Fallacy of Using Long-Run Cost for Peak-Load Pricing’, 100 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 1331-1334. Visscher, Michael (1973), ‘Welfare Maximizing Price and Output with Stochastic Demand: Comment’, 63 American Economic Review, 224-229. Voge, Jean Paul (1986), ‘A Survey of French Regulatory Policy’, in Snow, Marcellus S. (ed.), Marketplace for Telecommunications: Regulation and Deregulation in Industrialized Democracies, University of Pennsylvania, Annenberg School of Communications Series, New York and London, Longman, 106-130. Vogelsang, Ingo (1988), ‘Price-Cap Regulation of Telecommunications Services: A Long-Run Approach’, in Crew, Michael A. (ed.), Deregulation and Diversification of Utilities, Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 21-42. Vogelsang, Ingo (1988), ‘A Little Paradox in the Design of Regulatory Mechanisms’, 29 International Economic Review, 467-476. Vogelsang, Ingo (1989), ‘Two-Part Tariffs as Regulatory Constraints’, 39 Journal of Public Economics, 45-66. Vogelsang, Ingo and Finsinger, Jörg (1979), ‘A Regulatory Adjustment Process for Optimal Pricing by Multiproduct Monopoly Firms’, 10 Bell Journal of Economics, 157-171. Vogelsang, Ingo and Mitchell, Bridger M. (1997), Telecommunications Competition: The Last Ten Miles, Boston, MA, The MIT Press. Von der Fehr, Nils-Henrik Morch and Harbord, David (1993), ‘Spot Market Competition in the UK Electricity Industry’, 103 Economic Journal, 531-546. Walls, W. David (1994), ‘Price Convergence across Natural Gas Fields and City Markets’, 15 Energy Journal, 37-48. Waverman, L. (1975), ‘Peak-load Pricing Under Regulatory Constraint: A Proof of Efficiency’, 83 Journal of Political Economy, 645-654. Wedig, Gerard J. (1993), ‘Ramsey Pricing and Supply-Side Incentives in Physician Markets’, 12 Journal of Health Economics, 365-384. Weidenbaum, Murray L. (1978), The Cost of Government Regulation of Business, Washington, DC, US Congress, Joint Economic Committee, Subcommittee on Economic Growth and Stabilization. Weil, Roman L., Jr (1968), ‘Allocating Joint Costs’, 58 American Economic Review, 1342-1345. Weisman, Dennis L. (1993), ‘Superior Regulatory Regimes in Theory and Practice’, 5 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 355-366. Weisman, Dennis L. (1994), ‘Why Less May be More under Price-Cap Regulation’, 6 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 339-361. Weiss, Lawrence and Klass, Michael W. (1981), Case Studies in Regulation: Revolution and Reform, Boston, Little Brown. Weiss, Lawrence and Klass, Michael W. (1986), Regulatory Reform: What Actually Happened,
5200
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
465
Boston, Little Brown. Weiss, Nitzan and Lee, Phil (1986), ‘Sustainability of the Multiproduct Monopoly and Ramsey-Optimal Pricing’, 142 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 473-492. Weitzman, Martin L. (1978), ‘Optimal Rewards for Economic Regulation’, 68 American Economic Review, 683-691. Wellisz, Stanislav, H. (1963), ‘Regulation of Natural Gas Pipeline Companies: An Economic Analysis’, 71 Journal of Political Economy, 30-43. Wenders, John T. (1976), ‘Peak-Load Pricing in the Electric Utility Industry’, 7 Bell Journal of Economics, 232-241. White, Lawrence J. (1976), ‘Price Regulation and Quality Rivalry in a Profit-Maximizing Model: The Case of Bank Branching’, 8 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 97-106. White, Lawrence J. (1979), ‘Economics of Scale and the Question of “Natural Monopoly” in the Airline Industry’, 44 Journal of Air Law and Commerce, 545-573. Whitworth, Alan (1980), ‘Monopoly and the Case for Price Control in Poor Countries’, 17 Journal of Development Studies, 80-95. Wiggins, Steven N. (1983), ‘The Impact of Regulation on Pharmaceutical Research Expenditures: A Dynamic Approach’, 22 Economic Inquiry, 115-128. Williamson, Oliver E. (1966), ‘Peak-load Pricing and Optimal Capacity under Indivisibility Constraints’, 56 American Economic Review, 810-827. Williamson, Oliver E. (1974), ‘Peak-Load Pricing: Some Further Remarks’, 5 Bell Journal of Economics, 223-228. Williamson, Oliver E. (1976), ‘Franchise Bidding for Natural Monopolies - in General and with Resect to CATV’, 7 Bell Journal of Economics, 73-104. Willig, Robert D. (1978), ‘Pareto Superior Nonlinear Outlay Schedules’,9 Bell Journal of Economics, 56-59. Willig, Robert D. (1979), ‘The Theory of Network Access Pricing’, in Trebing, H.M. (ed.), Issues in Public Utility Regulation, East Lansing, Michigan, Michigan State Public Utilities Papers, 109-152. Willig, Robert D. and Bailey, Elizabeth E. (1979), ‘The Economic Gradient Method’, 69 American Economic Review, 96-101. Wilson, James Q. (1980), The Politics of Regulation, New York, Basic Books. Winston, Clifford (1981a), ‘The Welfare Effects of ICC Rate Regulation Revisited’, 12 Bell Journal of Economics, 232-244. Winston, Clifford (1981b), ‘Explaining Regulatory Policy’, 0 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity: Microeconomics, 1-31. Winston, Clifford (1981), ‘Economic Deregulation: Days of Reckoning for Microeconomists’, 31 Journal of Economic Literature, 1263-1289. Woo, Chi Keung (1988), ‘Optimal Electricity Rates and Consumption Externality’, 10 Resources and Energy, 277-292. Woo, Chi Keung et al. (1994), ‘Emission Costs, Consumer Bypass and Efficient Pricing of Electricity’, 15 Energy Journal, 43-54. Woroch, Glenn A. (1984), ‘Credible Regulation and the Possibility of Workable Monopoly’, Rochester Department of Economics Discussion Paper, No. 84-3. Xavier, Patrick (1995), ‘Price-Cap Regulation for Telecommunication: How Has it Performed in Practice?’, 19 Telecommunications Policy, 599-617. Ye, Meng-Hua and Yezer, Anthony M.J. (1994), ‘Collective Choice of Price-Caps and Freight
466
Price Regulation: A (Non-Technical) Overview
5200
Absorption’, 24 Regional Science and Urban Economics, 185-205. Zajac, Edward E. (1970), ‘A Geometric Treatment of Averch-Johnson’s Behavior of the Firm Model’, 60 American Economic Review, 117-125. Zajac, Edward E. (1972), ‘Note on “Gold-Plating” or “Rate Base Padding”’, 1 Bell Journal of Economics. Zajac, Edward E. (1974a), ‘A Geometric Treatment of Averch-Johnson’s Behavior of the Firm Model’, 60 American Economic Review, 117-125. Zajac, Edward E. (1974b), ‘Note on an Extension of the Ramsey Inverse Elasticity of Demand Pricing or Taxation Formula’, 3 Journal of Public Economics, 181-184. Zajac, Edward E. (1978), Fairness or Efficiency: An Introduction to Public Utility Pricing, Cambridge, MA, Ballinger. Ziemes, Georg (1985), ‘The Averch-Johnson Effect in a Simple Oligopoly Model’, 141 Zeitschrift für die Gesamte Staatswissenschaft, 444-451. Zupan, Mark A. (1974), ‘On Cream-Skimming, Coase, and the Sustainability of Natural Monopolies’, 22 Applied Economics, 487-492.
5300 ANTITRUST LAW Patrick Van Cayseele Professor of Economics Katholic University of Leuven and F.U.N.D.P. Namur
Roger Van den Bergh Professor of Law and Economics Erasmus University Rotterdam and Utrecht University © Copyright 1999 Patrick Van Cayseele and Roger Van den Bergh
Abstract The first part of this chapter surveys the interaction of the economics of competition and antitrust in a somewhat historical perspective. The evolution of economic theories on competition can be divided into four stages: (1) the origins of competition: the dynamic concept of competition in classical economic literature and the static concept of competition in price theory, followed by the development of models of imperfect competition and monopolistic competition; (2) the structure-conduct-performance paradigm (Harvard School of Industrial Organisation); (3) the ‘antitrust revolution’ of the Chicago School and the related theory of contestable markets, and (4) the new industrial economics, making use of game theory and transaction cost analysis. The second part of this chapter investigates how far economic theory and concepts of industrial economics have had an influence on antitrust law. In the USA economic views on competition theory have had a much clearer impact on antitrust law: legal rules tend to change when the underlying economic theory changes. In Europe, competition law seems to be influenced more by political objectives than by economic theory; economic considerations are often either absent or outdated. The discussion of some leading antitrust cases illustrates the differences between the American and the European approach. JEL classification: K21 Keywords: Cartels, Competition, Structure, Conduct, Performance, Chicago School, Bounds Approach
1. Introduction The economics of competition and antitrust law have a long-lasting tradition of fruitful interaction. Since the very beginning of antitrust legislation, 467
468
Antitrust Law
5300
microeconomics has influenced the context as well as the implementation of the law. And as one of the great economists of this century, Lord Keynes, pointed out, practitioners always adhere to the theories of a defunct economist, leading contemporary economists to write papers on the inadequate or outdated application of economics on antitrust legislation. Nowadays, not only the economics of competition, but also the economics of information and the theory of economic federalism have exercised their influence. The field of economics of competition is currently called industrial organisation or industrial economics. This has, however, a much broader scope by also focusing on the economics of regulation, innovation and advertising, among others. For a leading textbook, see Tirole (1988), for an introduction, see Scherer and Ross (1990) or Carlton and Perloff (1994). The economics of information was recently recognised in the economics profession by awarding the Nobel prize to Vickrey and Mirrlees. The economics of information only could advance due to major breakthroughs in the field of noncooperative game theory under incomplete information. Nash, Selten and especially Harsanyi pioneered contributions in this area, for which they got the 1994 Nobel prize in economics. Game theory also made its way to the law (see Baird, Gertner and Picker (1994) and Phlips (1988, 1995) for pioneering contributions regarding antitrust economics. Applications of information economics to the law can be found in Levine and Lippman (1995). For a combined effort of information economics with the economic theory of (fiscal) federalism within the context of antitrust, see Smets and Van Cayseele (1995). The present contribution will try to survey the abovementioned interaction in a somewhat historical perspective. This contribution therefore is organised along the following table of contents: the next section sketches the antecedents and the very beginning. Then the old paradigm in industrial economics, together with its application to antitrust in a carefree era, is discussed. More troublesome was the application of these old industrial organisation theories to a number of antitrust cases in the 1970s and 1980s. The criticisms advanced by the Chicago School will receive special attention. The response by the new industrial economics (NIE) as well as the new empirical industrial organisation (NEIO) is put under scrutiny in the following sections. Then follows a description of the current situation in terms of academic research with respect to concentrations. Last but not least, in the final section we investigate what can be retrieved from all this research in legal practice. This structure to some extent follows Van Cayseele (1996), who engages in a similar survey from a pure industrial economics point of view, rather than focusing on antitrust.
5300
Antitrust Law
469
2. The Origins of Competition The roots of the concept of ‘competition’ are as old as economic science if the latter starts with the famous book The Wealth of Nations (see Smith, 1776, 1937). Even before that time the merits of and problems with competition often submerged in economic writings. In an overview, McNulty (1967) referred to the seventeenth-century mercantilist Johann Joachim Becher, writings by Turgot and Hume and to Sir James Stuart, who provided the most complete pre-Smithian analysis of competition. Smith, by anticipating the welfare theorems with his ‘invisible hand’ theory, generalised competition to a force driving economies to the very best outcomes that are feasible. The most frequently quoted passage in the book is: He [specifically each individual] generally, indeed neither intends to promote the public interest, nor knows how much he is promoting it… [He] intends only his own gain, and he is in this, as in many other cases, led by an invisible hand to promote an end which was no part of his intention.
Subsequently economists have proved those theorems and showed their shortcomings (see the Nobel prize winners Arrow and Debreu). Parallel with those mathematical models of a general equilibrium nature - which sacrifice much of the institutional details of competition in real markets - economists have engaged in the mathematical modelling of market forces in much more institutional detail, including asymmetries in information, transaction costs and the concentration and use of power. As already argued in the introduction, these models were only recently recognised. What does classical economics then have as an implication for competition policy? According to classical economics, healthy competition signifies both reciprocal rivalry and the absence of government restrictions, such as the exclusive privileges which characterised the mercantilist period. The common law in relation to restraints of trade reflected the classical view of competition. Modes of conduct with limited individual freedom were condemned as restrictive to competition. Hence a widespread belief in the ‘laissez faire’ principle was held. Government intervention in general certainly would not improve upon the results of the competitive process although Smith himself was a believer of keeping entry into the market open. Competition was hailed as a process but limited government intervention sometimes would be necessary to allow for the process to work. Neoclassical economists continued to believe in the healthy effects of competition but somewhat shifted the interest from competition as a process to competition as a situation, as one later would say, a market structure. The necessary conditions to achieve a perfectly competitive outcome are: (i) the
470
Antitrust Law
5300
rivals must act independently or noncooperatively in today’s terminology; (ii) the number of rivals, potential as well as present, must be sufficient; (iii) the economic decision makers must possess knowledge of the market opportunities; (iv) there must be freedom to act on this knowledge; and (v) sufficient time must elapse for resources to flow in the directions desired by their owners with no restrictions on the magnitude of these flows. Although Stigler (1968) attributes these necessary conditions to Smith, the characterisation and implications of perfect competition and alternating market structure emerged most pronouncedly in this period. In particular, Edgeworth (1925) and Cournot ([1838], 1971) introduced pioneering contributions which until today remain at the heart of daily antitrust practice. A perfectly competitive market now was defined as a set of properties such as supply and demand exercised by a very large number of actors, free entry and exit, homogeneous products being traded on the market and zero search or transaction costs. The outcome of such a market is an efficient one in that no other outcome can achieve the same level of welfare for society. Yet it relies on many conditions which are unachievable, such as very large numbers of suppliers (in the presence of scale economies), no search costs (difficult to maintain in the few cases one has very many suppliers) and so on. The model of perfect competition therefore has to be seen as a yardstick against which other market structures are to be judged. In all instances in which this set of properties are not met, a case of market failure is seen to exist. For a long time, the mere existence of such market failures were seen to be sufficient reasons for government policies, such as antitrust laws or the creation of public utilities. Nowadays, this viewpoint has changed. A market failure is a necessary condition for government intervention, but not a sufficient one. The cost of government failures, for instance due to government officials and regulators being captured by private and social interest groups (as documented so well in the public choice literature and avocated by Stigler, 1971), has to fall short of the costs due to market failures. In general, antitrust policy, due to its distance vis-à-vis redistributive issues, and due to its permanent and ‘generic’ character is not an area of government intervention where one expects a lot of capture a priori (see De Bondt and Van Cayseele, 1985). Cournot and Edgeworth introduced models of imperfect competition. Cournot ([1838], 1971) explicitly took into account the possibility of only a few suppliers in the market. As shown by Novshek (1985), his model can replicate both the perfectly competitive outcome as well as the other extreme, that is, monopoly. While Cournot’s model still abstracts from the price formation process by assuming the existence of a Walrasian auctioneer, it substantially adds to realism due to the introduction of conjectures on behalf of the rivals. Recent research, for example by Kreps and Scheinkman (1983) sustains the Cournot model without the Walrasian assumption. But Davidson and
5300
Antitrust Law
471
Deneckere (1986) and Van Cayseele and Furth (1996a) demonstrate that the conclusion is very fragile. Edgeworth readily abandoned the abstractions of a price equilibrating process and allowed rivals to undercut each others’ price and engage in price warfare. While his conclusions as to cyclical behaviour of prices with periods of collusive pricing alternating with price wars could only be interpreted by means of game-theoretical models half a century later, another model of oligopoly had been conceived. Many textbooks in microeconomics deal with these models as the leading paradigm (see among others Pindyck and Rubinfeld, 1993, and Schotter, 1994). Meanwhile monopoly, as a market structure that occurs in reality and can be analysed, was also studied. Indeed, the quantitative contributions of economists such as Cournot and Edgeworth allowed for an estimation of the costs associated with monopoly. A clear definition of consumer and producer surplus by Marshall (1920) or Lerner (1934), as well as the recognition of deadweight losses associated with monopoly pricing, was an essential step into giving empirical content to the problem of monopoly. The estimates of the direct loss in welfare of course vary across nations and over time, but are in the range of 0.1 percent to as much as 9 percent. For the US, these estimates can be found in Harberger (1954) or Worcester (1973). Cowling and Mueller (1983) estimated the direct welfare effects in France. The indirect losses are due to rent-seeking phenomena, and can be in the order of magnitude of the direct effects. They, of course, have to be added and illustrate the need to work with models that capture the dynamic aspects of competition. These quite substantial amounts of losses certainly justify the operation of antitrust control, at least from an economic point of view. In addition to this concern with allocative efficiency, other reasons have been put forward to embrace antitrust enforcement. Each of these, however, is disputed. We therefore only mention them briefly. First, many believe that monopolies and cartels are less innovative than firms operating in competitive market structures. This is sort of the ‘opposite Schumpeterian assumption’. While this literature is vast, in particular the empirical studies trying to detect a link between concentration and innovation are highly inconclusive (for a survey see Van Cayseele, 1998). The abovementioned rent-seeking effects are particularly pronounced in the theoretical literature regarding the dynamics of innovation. This is quite natural as one realises that market structure will not only influence innovative activity, but that also the opposite is true. This begs the question whether incumbent monopolies will exploit innovative activities, for example by winning subsequent patents, to continue their position, or whether some kind of ‘leapfrogging’ will take place, where today’s market leaders are tomorrow’s followers, a paradigm nowadays acclaimed by Microsoft officials. A second belief which still is disputed is the following: monopolies and cartels, by being sheltered from competition, become lazy. This gives rise to
472
Antitrust Law
5300
organisational slack or X-efficiency (see Leibenstein, 1966, the critique by Stigler, 1976, and the reply by Leibenstein, 1978). Finally, many object to the transfer of wealth from consumers to firms with market power, or the shareholders beyond these firms. While the economic foundations for redistribution are seriously disputed, Lande (1982) believes that the principle reason behind the enactment of antitrust laws was to prevent these wealth transfers, implying political economy motivations for antitrust. Further relaxations of the perfectly competitive model occurred with the abandoning of the homogeneous goods assumption by, for example, Hotelling (1928), Chamberlin (1933) and Robinson (1964). By allowing for differences with respect to the products sold, each producer gets some monopoly power over those consumers who are addicted to his brand. Nonetheless, there may be many producers in the market, so that the focus here is not necessarily game-theoretic, that is, the recognition of mutual interdependency need not to be central, although contemporary contributions in the field of product differentiation all recognise this interdependency. In doing so, the economic models of product differentiation have provided the foundations to determine the relevant market, a concept used currently in antitrust legislation (see Van Cayseele, 1994). As reviewed by Friedman (1984), each and every of these departures from the competitive model proved to be path-breaking for the development of the field of oligopoly theory. A few decades and antitrust filibusters later, the socalled new industrial organisation would pick up from here. On the other hand, each of these departures also showed the tremendous richness in terms of modelling possibilities that exist for analysing competition in an industry, and hence the difficulties that will arise in constructing models of general relevance. As such it is difficult to formulate a legal approach that is theoretically correct, predictable and easy and inexpensive to administer for a majority of antitrust issues that can come up, although this has been tried, as the next section shows.
3. The Structure, Conduct, Performance Paradigm (S-C-P Paradigm) Each and every one of the original models of competition discussed in the previous section has a few items in common. First, the number of suppliers as those who have access to a certain technology is specified. Next, the consumers who have different tastes can make their choice over different brands. In general, the technology and tastes constitute market structure. Still this allows for many different outcomes unless a particular structure entails a certain type of conduct. This is what the S-C-P paradigm tried to achieve: a general theory that mapped common elements in the market structure of any industry into a performance indicator of that sector.
5300
Antitrust Law
473
The S-C-P paradigm was developed by Edward S. Mason (1949a) at Harvard University in the late 1930s and early 1940s. The original empirical applications of the new theory were by Mason’s colleagues and students, the most famous of whom was Joe S. Bain (1968). The paradigm implies that market results (the success of an industry in producing benefits for consumers, employment, stable prices, technological advancement and so on) in an industry are dependent on the conduct of sellers and buyers (as regards decision variables like advertising, R&D, and so on). Conduct, as mentioned, is determined by the structure of the relevant market. The structure of an industry depends on basic conditions, such as technology and preference structure. Government policy (antitrust policy, regulation, taxes, and so on) may affect the basic conditions, and hence the structure, conduct and performance of an industry. If true, research along this paradigm would allow any outsider to know profits and consumer surplus in any industry simply by plugging in the variables representing the market structure, at least if a significant and positive relationship was detected in the study. Hundreds of studies have attempted to link market structure to market performance. Concerning static performance (profits and consumer surplus), three major measures of market performance are used: (1) the rate of return, which is based upon profits earned per dollar of investment; (2) the price-cost margin, which should be based upon the difference between price and marginal cost, and is related to the Lerner index of monopoly power and (3) Tobin’s q, which is the ratio of the market value of a firm to its value based upon the replacement cost of its assets (for more details see Carlton and Perloff, 1994). The initial studies are by Bain (1951, 1956). In the latter publication Bain argues that profits are higher in industries with high concentration and high barriers to entry. Many studies followed, to name just a few: Schwartzman (1959), Levinson (1960), Fuchs (1961), Minhas (1963), Weiss (1963), Comanor and Wilson (1967), Collins and Preston (1969), Kamerschen (1969), and many others. Other performance criteria, such as the cyclical behaviour of price-cost margins or pricing behaviour as such have been carried out (see, respectively, Domowitz, Hubbard and Petersen, 1986, and Weiss, 1989). To examine how performance varies with structure, measures of market structure are needed. Industry concentration is typically measured as a function of the market shares of some or all of the firms in a market. The four-firm concentration ratio (CR4) is the sum of the market shares of the four largest firms. The eight-firm concentration ratio (CR8) focuses attention on the top eight firms in measuring concentration. Alternatively, market structure may be measured by using a function of all the individual firm’s market shares. The Herfindahl-Hirschman Index (HHI) is the sum of the squares of the market shares of every firm in the relevant market. Later, when the empirical Harvard tradition underlying the S-C-P paradigm was no longer tenable, the pioneering game-theoretic Cournot model was able to strike a link between the Lerner
474
Antitrust Law
5300
index and the HHI, which suddenly made it quite popular (see Scherer and Ross, 1990). The fact was already known to Stigler (1968). The concentration indices (CR4 or CR8 and the HHI) can be related to one another (see Weiss, 1969). Many studies indeed found a positive and significant relationship between market structure and performance, yet others casted doubt as to whether the relationship would hold for different sets of industries or in other eras. Nonetheless the paradigm condemns high degrees of concentration, especially if they are not the result of scale economies but of barriers to entry. Regarding market shares, some studies have made clear that substantial market shares are not evidence prima facie for the presence of market power. On the contrary, it seems to be the case that the resulting larger market shares are the result of superior efficiency, as predicted by a Cournot model with cost asymmetries. In the United States, the Harvard analysis became the cornerstone of competition policy in the 1960s and remained so until the neoclassical and neoinstitutional approaches began to win the upper hand in the mid 1970s. In the 1968 Merger Guidelines of the American Department of Justice it was stated that an analysis of market structure was fully adequate for showing that the effect of a merger, as spelled out in Section 7 of the Clayton Act, ‘may be substantially to lessen competition, or to tend to create a monopoly’. The Department announced that its merger policy would focus on market structure ‘because the conduct of the individual firms in a market tends to be controlled by the structure of that market’ (see also Section 7 below). An enforcement policy emphasizing a limited number of structural factors would not only produce adequate economic predictions for the showing of anticompetitive effects, but would also facilitate both enforcement decision making and business planning, and as such contribute to legal certainty. Such rudimentary decision making, however, also holds some dangers, for example in allowing firms to accomplish the target indirectly, by circumventing the limited number of structural factors. In some cases this will lead to the same outcome, at a higher cost, or at a counterproductive outcome, as claimed by Bittlingmayer (1985). Here the trade-off will need to strike a balance between the additional costs resulting from closing down all the loopholes vis-à-vis the advantage of a simple and transparant attack to antitrust. In many cases, the second order effects probably will not be important enough to tip the balance in favour of an extensive enlargement of the set of structural factors to be monitored, but we know industries can differ in many respects.
4. The Chicago School The antecedents of the new theories of competition have to be found in the original contributions discussed in Section 2 and, most importantly, to the
5300
Antitrust Law
475
presence and interaction of Director and Stigler at the University of Chicago in the 1950s. In 1942, Stigler had already written that ‘it is doubtful whether the monopoly question will ever receive much illumination from large scale statistical investigations’ (see Stigler, 1942). In the 1950s the economist Aaron Director, together with a lawyer, Edward Levi, taught anti-trust at the University of Chicago. According to Posner (1979), Director formulated his ideas mainly orally. Numerous authors since then have further elaborated on Aaron Director’s core ideas and published them in scholarly journals. Bork (1954) elaborated on the often misunderstood aspects of efficiency resulting from vertical integration and brought together many of the schools’ insights in The Antitrust Paradox: A Policy at War with Itself (1978). (This book gives a complete and orthodox overview of the doctrine of the Chicago School.) The problem of tie-in-sales was analysed by Bowman (1957). Predatory pricing was investigated by McGee (1958), while another hot issue overwhelmed with misconceptions, namely vertical price fixing, was the topic of a paper by one of Chicago’s leading scholars in microeconomics, industrial organisation and law and economics, Telser (1960). A good survey of the issues involved and the economic forces at work is Reder (1982). The Chicago School’s point of departure can be found in neoclassical price theory. The confrontation between the classical, dogmatic approach to anti-trust law and the microeconomic angle of attack gave rise to an extremely rich, new efficiency theory. The Chicago approach to competition policy is not merely the result of the rejection of government intervention in the economy, although the opposite view often occurs. On the contrary, Director reached his conclusions by analysing competition problems through price theory. Unlike the economists following the S-C-P paradigm (the Harvard School), who examine competition problems on the basis of observable phenomena (empirical research) and industry tales instead of having recourse to an economic theory, Director sought an explanation for practices observed in real markets which tallied with the maximisation of profits, utility and welfare. Of course, if firms can engage in actions which are anti-competitive and profitable, they will do so. But already in 1964, Stigler showed that it was often more profitable to stay out of cartels than to form them. This conclusion, however, has been both confirmed (see Salant, Switzer and Reynolds, 1983), and rejected (see Deneckere and Davidson, 1984), indicating that one has to carefully investigate the nature of the interactions that takes place in industry, as is done in the game-theoretic tradition, discussed below. In the Chicago tradition, concentration mostly will be the result of efficiency, hence if antitrust authorities interfere with an existing market structure, they are likely to cause inefficiencies, and reduce rather than enhance welfare.
476
Antitrust Law
5300
One of the most important attacks on the S-C-P doctrine of conducting antitrust policies was given again by Stigler when investigating the role of barriers to entry. Often the Harvard tradition argued that fixed costs were seen to lead to scale economies on the one hand, but also to barriers to entry on the other. Stigler defines a barrier to entry as ‘a cost of producing (at some or every rate of output) that must be borne by a firm which seeks to enter the industry but is not borne by firms already in the industry’. Barriers to entry are present only if the costs for firms entering the market turn out to be higher than the costs for the existing firms. If, for example, it costs $10,000,000 to build the smallest possible efficient factory having an economic life of ten years, then the annual costs for a new entrant will be only $1,000,000. The existing firms will be confronted with the same annual costs, at least if it is assumed that they also intend to replace their factories. Accordingly, there is no cost disadvantage for the new entrant (see Posner, 1979; Spence, 1980, or Schmalensee, 1983) for initial ideas regarding the importance of sunk rather than fixed costs. These ideas were the fundamentals of what later on became the contestable market defence for ATT, and the subsequent new theories of industry structure by Baumol, Panzar and Willig (1982) and Sutton (1991). In fact, what turns out to be important for understanding market structure are not fixed but sunk costs. The latter are defined as non-recoupable costs, or outlays one has to make in order to get in business, but which are without value if one exits. Entrants will not be stopped if the fixed cost - the factory in the example above - can get a new destination or can be sold on a second-hand market (see Section 5 below). In short, the Chicago tradition then is the bundling of several ingredients, which taken together tell us that the monopoly problem is not all that important. First of all, as a stylised fact, monopolies (or strong market concentration for that matter) do not occur all that often. Moreover, if they are present, they are either the result of scale economies in production and/or distribution - and hence efficient - or the result of barriers to entry. But in the latter case, they are transitory, for the freedom of entry will induce the presence of other players in the market, which compete and hence limit the market power of the initial monopolist. Persistency of market power therefore can only be the result of government itself, by the fact that many of its regulatory policies establish legal barriers to entry, hence creating public monopolies. In terms of conduct, the often alleged malpractices also are explained by efficiency. Vertical restraints may provide the appropriate incentives for dealers to invest in quality of service or to appropriately advertise the product in its region. Others if allowed to deal in this region would free-ride on these efforts, the final result being that the initial dealer would no longer undertake the necessary efforts to maintain an high quality of service for the product (see also Telser, 1960). Commodity bundling also may be the result of efficiency
5300
Antitrust Law
477
considerations rather than trying to exploit monopoly power (see Kenney and Klein, 1983). From 1970 on, the influence of Chicago economics on US antitrust policy gradually increased. This has led, together with the renewed role of the private sector in the economy, to a different implementation of the law, in the sense that mergers or particular types of conduct have caused less problems for the firms involved. Such an evolution was bound to trigger the comment that Chicago economics is ideologically biased. In addition there is the belief held sometimes in Europe that the majority of the economics profession agrees with the characterisation of the Chicago School as an ideology. This is of course wrong, since what matters is the methodology to study antitrust issues along the lines of price theory, which was pioneered by the Chicago School and has currently been embraced by all scholars in industrial organisation as the starting point of every sound antitrust case. As such, the Chicago learning is well established both within the economic discipline of modern industrial organisation and antitrust practice, at least in the US, although it would be premature to claim that all of the US antitrust action is in line with the Chicago tradition (see Van den Bergh, 1997, and Section 7 below for a relativisation. Nonetheless, the Chicago School influences antitrust policy. The Merger Guidelines were revised several times (in 1982, 1984 and 1992) to take account of developments in economic thinking concerning the competitive effects of mergers. In the 1992 Guidelines there is no longer an explicit reference to the S-C-P paradigm; there is also explicit scope for an ‘efficiency defense’, which clearly reflects the influence of the Chicago School (see also Section 7 below). In Europe the same acceptance holds for the academic profession which has been very active in the field of industrial organisation, not the least through the EARIE (European Association for Reseach in Industrial Economics) conferences which celebrate their 25th edition, and for which there is no American counterpart. In antitrust policy however, the gap is substantial. This has led often to inconsistent treatment of one and the same phenomenon over a variety of industries (see again Van den Bergh, 1997). A real danger of the Chicago price theory tradition comes from the exageration of some theoretical concepts that do not apply to the real world very often. To some, contestability theory is such an example. In the US, it has been mistakenly applied, for example, in the airline mergers (see Utton, 1995). The result has been that it has been somewhat discredited. While in general thrust and effects, it is very much in the Chigaco School tradition, the major difference with mainstream Chicago concepts seems to lie in the lack of a positive inclination: the contestable market model serves a normative purpose in that it merely shows that there exists a yardstick market structure in which antitrust policies are useless even in the presence of monopoly. As will become clear, the assumptions needed to obtain this conclusion are so restrictive that
478
Antitrust Law
5300
the contestable market model cannot make claims to be descriptive or positive theory. In the theory of contestable markets, the fact that the market structure is concentrated says nothing, of itself, about the degree of efficiency. Even with a high degree of concentration, allocative efficiency is not excluded because potential entrants exercise a controlling discipline. Perfect contestability produces a similar outcome to perfect competition: prices are equal to marginal costs, as required by the welfare theorems, but without having a substantial number of competitors in the industry. The players necessary to guarantee this result are found outside the industry. In a perfectly contestable market, entry is completely free and withdrawal costs absolutely nothing. (Free entry does not imply that entry costs absolutely nothing, or that it is easy, but rather that the entrant has no relative disadvantages compared with participants who are already active in the market.) Besides lacking empirical support, many contributions have pointed out that the contestable market model is very particular, and that nearly every change of the assumptions leads to dramatically different outcomes (see, for example, the very early critical review article by Brock, 1983, or the discussion in Schwarz and Reynolds, 1983). For example, if some costs are sunk the incumbent has already paid for them, and will have written them off instantaneously as they are worth nothing if the activity is stopped. Potential entrants find it appropriate to judge the profitability of market entry on the basis of the post entry competition (which will determine the profitability) and the costs they still have to sink. If competition is hard, profits will be too low to cover these costs, and potential entry will never discipline the incumbents for it will not occur. Implicitly, the contestable market model by assuming zero sunk costs therefore assumes that investments can be redeployed in another activity (complete lack of asset specificity), or resold on a second-hand market that is not prone to failures (see, however, Akerlof, 1970, and Van Cayseele, 1993). Another example of the vulnerability of the conclusions with respect to small changes in the assumptions has been investigated in game theoretic detail by Van Cayseele and Furth (1996a, 1996b). In these articles, it is shown that if merely one assumption, namely that consumers react faster to lower prices than producers, is changed by the reverse assumption, the outcome of the contestable market model completely changes. Instead of predicting the perfectly competitive outcome for an industry in which firms compete with one another in prices, the monopoly outcome results. Other examples which follow a strict game-theoretic methodology show that one change in the assumptions may be sufficient to get drastically different outcomes (see Ausubel and Deneckere, 1987). There, the assumption that non-durable goods are involved is changed into the production of durable goods. While Coase (1972) had
5300
Antitrust Law
479
argued that durable good monopolists had no market power, the contestable market model with a duopoly in durable goods yields monopoly outcomes. From an academic viewpoint, the Chicago price theory tradition has been surpassed in the last decade by the contributions game theory made to the field of industrial organization. In the next section, we enter in detail into the gametheoretic contributions which are important in the area of antitrust economics. For the moment, it is important to stress that these newer contributions have shown that it is quite possible to explain certain mergers and particular types of conduct not as the result of efficiency, but from a clear pursuit of gaining or keeping market power. However, it would be untrue to say that the newer game-theoretic contributions are at odds with the Chicago tradition. On the contrary, from a methodological viewpoint this new approach has pursued with the same rigor as price theory the analytical approach to understanding the operations of firms in an industry. However, by allowing for a richer set of strategies it has been shown that some of the conclusions reached by the Chicago tradition could indeed be the outcome, but at the same time that under slightly different assumptions (which some will argue more closely to reality), quite different conclusions result. What certainly is taken for granted is that both the advocates of laissez-faire (no antitrust) as well as those in favour follow mathematical modelling approaches which allow sharp inroads into the problem, just as price theory pioneered by Director, Stigler and others a few decades earlier.
5. The New Industrial Economics: Game Theory and Transaction Cost Analysis Game theory offers a rigorous analytical framework - like price theory - to analyse the competition of firms. Game theory requires being explicit on the set of players (firms), on their strategies, and on the advantages these strategies can bring to them (payoffs). It offers solution concepts that take into account firstmover advantages and credible commitments that firms can take. As such it is said to reflect much more real-world competition than any other body of theory. A general introduction of the achievements game theory was able to accomplish for competition policy is provided by Phlips (1988, 1995). Jacquemin (1997) provides examples of the links that game theory has regarding both the goals of competition policies and the anti-competitive practices that are unconceavable with such policies. In addition to the many valuable insights received from the Chicago tradition, game theory especially has contributed by explicating carefully the relevant strategies and considerations that need to be taken into account as well as by pointing out that perfect information is not always prevalent. This has serious implications for the working of a market. In some cases, including a
480
Antitrust Law
5300
more full description of the strategic possibilities has led to a reversal of the conclusion: an insight found within the Chicago tradition was turned upside down. In other cases, the conclusions of the Chicago School have been confirmed, in a richer and more realistic economic environment. An important example for antitrust is horizontal mergers. Stigler had already argued that mergers for a market power motive would not be formed as it is more profitable to stay out such a merger than to join it. Paradoxically, Salant, Switzer and Reynolds (1983) show that with a linear demand curve, constant marginal costs and firms competing in quantities, at least 80 percent of the firms in an industry have to be included in the merger in order for it to be profitable. Clearly, these are not the mergers that will show up, for antitrust authorities would quickly rule them out on the basis of the creation of dominant positions. This would imply that mergers are not likely to form, unless some important efficiency gains in terms of, for instance, production or distribution costs are made. But these are the mergers that need to be approved from a welfare point of view, hence antitrust authorities only have to bother with clearly dominant positions. But the result depends on one critical assumption: the competition is in quantities rather than in prices. It was shown by Deneckere and Davidson (1984) that all mergers are profitable even if they do not yield efficiency improvements in the latter case. Hence the conclusions are turned upside down by merely the change of one assumption. This has led those critical of game theory to claim that any conclusion or its reverse can be proved, while the defenders of game theory claim that the advantages definitely outweigh this disadvantage (see, for instance, the discussion between Fisher, 1989 and Shapiro, 1989). The latter includes the fact that game theory requires one to explicate all the assumptions made also on behalf of the rival players (which was not always done by price theory), as well as the richness in terms of institutional detail and hence the realism game theory has added to economic models. In Sleuwaegen and Van Cayseele (1997) still another reason is given, namely the fact that as more game theoretic analysis of industries become available, it becomes possible to operate along a decision tree approach and to guide antitrust authorities as to whether a detailed investigation of the proposed operation is necessary. Finally, and as shown in a seminal article by Kamien and Zang (1990), game theory allows one to do more. In the just mentioned controversy between Salant, Switzer and Reynolds, on the one hand, and Deneckere and Davidson, on the other, the mergers under consideration are all given exogenously. But it is possible to endogenise the formation of mergers by considering different coalitions that can be formed, and hence reduce the number of conceivable mergers to those that are feasible. Similar game-theoretic exercises endogenise the strategies in which the firms will compete with one another, or even the moves, hence explaining who leads and who follows (see Hamilton and Slutsky, 1990). Another development which seriously attenuates the critique on game-
5300
Antitrust Law
481
theoretic models is the bounds approach by Sutton (1991) (see also Section 6 below). A final advantage of game theory is that, by its analysis of bounded rationality, it opens the way to approaches which hitherto remained outside the mainstream of microeconomics, by the fact that pure price theory does not offer much room for search and transaction costs phenomena. Nonetheless, transaction cost theory has a longstanding tradition in the law and economics of antitrust (see Williamson, 1975, 1979). The central idea in transaction cost economics is that the market is not entirely free in the sense that certain operations (transactions) are not entirely costless. As such, the transaction cost approach superimposes frictions upon microeconomic price theory. Seen in this light, transaction cost analysis is more a complement to than a substitute for price theory. The point of departure in Williamson’s analysis is not the subject matter of the sale/purchase transaction (goods or services) but the transaction or transfer system itself. The transaction is an exchange between two or more individuals whereby they transfer ‘property rights’ (that is, rights to dispose of scarce resources, which may be limited not only by other individuals’ ownership rights but also by rules of legal liability and the provisions of competition law). Transactions differ perceptibly so far as costs are concerned and these differences in transaction costs influence the choice of the right organisational form or ‘governance structure’. The transaction cost approach is thus concerned with the costs which are necessary to maintain the economic system. To put it briefly: markets and firms are regarded as alternative instruments for implementing transactions (see Williamson, 1985, 1986). Colloquially, managers speak about the ‘make or buy’ decision. Indeed, whether a transaction to acquire a good or service is carried out over the market or within the firm depends on the relative efficiency of these two institutions. A hierarchical form of organisation may be superior to a market-based solution. The relative efficiency of the two forms is determined on the one hand by the costs of entering into and carrying out agreements in a market, and on the other hand by the characteristics of the individuals who are affected by the transaction. As such, the origins of transaction cost economics go back at least to Coase (1937), who in his classic essay laid the foundations for the new institutional economics. Markets and firms are indeed institutional forms, and their existence and survival are explained out of economic efficiency. The use of one mode or the other for a particular type of transaction directly follows from the relative costs of operating over one system or the other. As such, the laws which regulate and interfere with these institutions will also be judged in the long run by economic efficiency. If legal rules make it more difficult to operate over a particular institution (for instance competition policies which forbid vertically integrated firms), that institution will lose appeal and vanish, together with the law that regulated it.
482
Antitrust Law
5300
Transactions differ from each other in a number of respects: the uncertainty to which the transactions are exposed, the frequency with which the transactions are repeated (once, occasionally, regularly) and the extent to which transactions must be supported by transaction-specific investments (‘asset specificity’). By asset specificity Williamson means the extent to which suppliers and customers must make specific investments in order to be able to carry out the transactions. Transaction-specific investments bind the supplier and the customer closely together. If the supplier cannot readily exploit his specific investments elsewhere and the purchaser, because of his specific investments, cannot readily place his order elsewhere, the supplier and the purchaser are bound to each other for a substantial period of time. This leads to situations in which market participants are very much dependent upon each other (‘small numbers exchange’). The importance of transaction costs depends on human factors such as the limited possibility to solve complex problems and ‘opportunism’. Opportunism follows straightforwardly out of the pursuit of self-interest in environments characterised by incomplete information or the lack of repeated transactions, making it simply not worthwhile to care for reputation. As already argued above, game theory has allowed the investigation of such moral hazard problems. And more recently game theory also has allowed the analysis of bounded rationality phenomena (see Young and Foster, 1991). Transaction cost economics has important implications for antitrust policy. Certain market structures might be the result of transaction cost efficiencies, not the strive for market power. A welfare-maximising anti-trust law then must take into account these efficiency aspects. In the context of the control of concentrations it is necessary to consider what transaction cost savings will be prevented by a merger prohibition and whether these (possible substantial) costs are compensated by the anticipated advantages of more intensive competition. Vertical integration or vertical restraints can be the result of complex negotiations aiming at the reduction of transaction costs. As a conclusion for this section, it is clear that game theory has entered the field of industrial economics to remain as a dominant supplier of tools to analyse sectors and industries. For the moment, the problem is not that the new industrial organisation is not very accurate but, on the contrary, that for nearly each different sector studied the assumptions and solution concepts of the models have to be adapted. This is of course mainly a problem for the laymen who lack the game theoretical knowledge to analyse industries, or to judge the quality of studies done by others. The plethora of models around does not make it easy to pick a model and be sure that it is appropriate for the sector under investigation. But things are changing quickly as, from the empirical side, the new empirical industrial organisation and the bounds approach are providing a workable synthesis.
5300
Antitrust Law
483
6. The New Empirical Industrial Organisation and the Bounds Approach The new empirical industrial organisation has tried to resolve the problem of indeterminacy in the new industrial economics, by leaving it open as to what kind of conduct prevails in an industry. The general idea is that industry structural elements can be measured and modelled, hence one starts from theoretical models of a sector. As such, conduct which is much harder to know ex ante is left open to be determined empirically. The divergence of industries necessarily calls for sector-specific models. Usually the fundamental ingredients are specifications of supply and demand, modified and augmented with industry-specific features. Estimation based on time series analysis allows the identification of market power, that is to separate the effects of cost changes from mark ups. The new empirical industrial organisation is a great leap forward for antitrust practitioners, as it allows the simulation of the effects of mergers and the detection of collusive behaviour. Models for an increasing number of industries become available, as we have witnessed since the pioneering studies applications to the cigarette industry (see Sullivan, 1985), automobile industry (see Berry, Levinsohn and Pakes, 1995; and Verboven, 1996), steel industry (see Baker, 1989), soft drinks (see Gasmi, Laffont and Vuong, 1992), and many others. The problem with this approach is that models do not already exist for every sector. Hence, an open industry in terms of publishing and communicating data might face a study which is at the disadvantage of the sector, whereas in other sectors collusion is much more important, but remains unknown. Moreover, often these studies will have to rely on historical data, hence it might not be appropriate to study a merger today in view of conduct a few decades ago. On the other hand, the pioneering studies by Panzar and Rosse (1987) and Porter (1983) offer many perspectives in that they have been applied successfully to many sectors without too much re-modelling. A similar effort to find robust results, that is results that can be applied to every industry under consideration is Sutton (1991). This approach is even more generally applicable, at the expense however of having to incorporate some degrees of freedom as to what can happen. Typically, one will only be able to say within which boundaries a sector will move, without being precise as to where it will be. Or, only an upper and lower bound to concentration will result. As such, this approach tries to provide the foundations for the S-C-P paradigm, but immediately shows how shaky the traditional Harvard approach was when it claimed it could make exact predictions regarding the impact of market structural changes such as concentrations. While some claim that many factors that are identified to be important in explaining market structure and the evolution of concentration could have been written down without all the theoretical efforts by Sutton, the old Harvard
484
Antitrust Law
5300
approach simply never has done it. Moreover, the explicit game-theoretic foundations used by Sutton illustrate the importance of adequate modelling of product differentiation, commitment, sunk costs and so on. It also shows the exact relation in which those factors relate to one another. Indeed, the Harvard approach mostly has looked for causal relations between variables that all are endogenous if one truly understand the dynamics of competition. This is mainly due to feedback effects of market performance variables, a fact well known in the European tradition on industrial organisation (see Jacquemin and De Jong, 1977).
7. The Influence of Economics on Antitrust Law In the last part of this contribution it will be investigated how far economic theory and concepts of industrial economics have had an influence on antitrust law. It seems fair to say that American antitrust law has been influenced by a constantly increasing and ever more penetrating use of economic theory, whereas the influence of economics on European competition law has remained rather modest. At present there are remarkable differences between American and European law with respect to the treatment of some hot issues in antitrust, such as predatory pricing and merger control. These differences may be attributed to at least two reasons. The main goal of European competition law (Articles 85-86 EC Treaty and Regulation 4064/89) has always been the promotion of market integration. A similar goal is absent in American antitrust law, since the latter rules came into being when a common market was already established. It was mainly political necessity, rather than economic theory, that made an active competition policy necessary in the eyes of the authors of the EC Treaty. The elimination of market compartmentalisation caused by restrictions on competition was necessary in order to achieve the central objective of integrating national markets. This aim of market integration is essential for an understanding of the principal characteristics of European competition law. The emphasis put on market integration has enabled European policymakers to avoid a profound debate about the values or objectives underpinning the competition rules of the EC Treaty. Consequently, the view of the Chicago School that productive and allocative efficiency are the only objectives which may be taken into account in interpreting and applying antitrust law could not get a firm basis in Europe. To a large extent, European competition law is at the same stage of development as American antitrust law was in the 1960s (see Van den Bergh, 1996). However, there are some first signs of a greater willingness by the European Commission to make use of economic theory (for example, with respect to the analysis of vertical restraints (see European Commission, 1997, pp. 19-31). It would, however, be wrong to label the latest developments in Europe as a victory for economic efficiency. Compared to American antitrust law European competition law still is less
5300
Antitrust Law
485
consistent with an efficiency based approach. Neither the European Commission nor the Court of Justice are sufficiently receptive to economic arguments, so that decisions and judgements are often formalistic and based on reiteration or expansion of early case law. 7.1 United States of America Although there may be disagreement as to the origins of the oldest competition legislation - the American Sherman Act of 1890 - it is clear that the Act was based not only on political objectives but also on the dominant economic theory at the end of the nineteenth century (see Sullivan, 1991). The economic objectives of the Sherman Act can be traced back to classical economics, which define competition as a process of rivalry taking place between large and small competitors in open and accessible markets. Consequently, the Sherman Act prohibits all ‘contracts, combinations and conspiracies’ which hinder trade, together with business conduct aimed at achieving a monopoly position by excluding competitors. In neoclassical economic theory the concept of ‘perfect competition’ was developed. Perfect competition is a situation in which the possibility of competitive behaviour in the Smithian sense is ruled out by definition. To some European authors the concept became a blueprint for competition policy (see, for example, Eucken, 1949), but the model was not used as a policy guideline in the USA. The same is true for the early theories of imperfect competition (Robinson, 1933, 1964) and monopolistic competition (Chamberlin, 1933), which did not have a clear influence on American antitrust policy either. The influence of economics on antitrust law increased dramatically, once the Harvard School had articulated the basic perceptions of industrial organisation theory in the well-known SCP paradigm and claimed to be able to explain the relationships among these three variables. This, together with the emergence of the new competitive ideal of workable competition had a clear influence upon competition policy. The concept of workable competition came about as a result of the publication, in 1940, of John M. Clark’s classic article. Clark denied that the ideal of perfect competition could serve as a blueprint for competition policy. Furthermore, Clark emphasised that, in the long run, market imperfections were not bound to be injurious per se. Not all market imperfections should be eliminated by competition policy, for market imperfections can neutralise each other (the antidote theory). Clearly, antitrust authorities will enjoy broad discretionary powers if competition policy must not eliminate all persistent market imperfections but should instead judge only to what extent an industry is workably competitive. Discretionary powers of antitrust authorities are further increased when antitrust law is also supposed to include non-economic objectives, as was the case with the Harvard School’s view in the 1950s-1960s. A complete and orthodox description of the Harvard
486
Antitrust Law
5300
views at that time is provided in Kaysen and Turner (1959). Kaysen and Turner distinguished no less than four objectives of competition policy: to achieve favourable economic results; to create and maintain competitive processes; to prescribe norms of ‘fair conduct’ and to restrict the growth of large firms. These objectives are partly inconsistent with each other and thus provide for large discretionary powers to be exercised by antitrust authorities. The Harvard analysis became the cornerstone of competition policy in the 1960s and remained so until the neoclassical and neoinstitutional approaches began to win the upper hand in the mid 1970s. Nowadays very few antitrust scholars in the United States believe that non-economic factors should pay any role whatsoever in antitrust analysis. In the light of the relationship between market structure, market conduct and market results, competition law became an instrument for generating optimal outcomes by directly influencing market structure (merger control). If prices increase as a result of market concentration, then mergers must be closely scrutinized. In the 1968 Merger Guidelines of the American Department of Justice it was stated that an analysis of market structure was fully adequate for showing that the effect of a merger, as spelled out in Section 7 of the Clayton Act, ‘may be substantially to lessen competition, or to tend to create a monopoly’ (US Department of Justice, 1968). The Department announced that its merger policy would focus on market structure ‘because the conduct of the individual firms in a market tends to be controlled by the structure of that market’. Following the Harvard views, only in exceptional circumstances would structural factors not alone be conclusive (for example in the case of conglomerate mergers). With respect to horizontal mergers, the 1968 Merger Guidelines used the CR 4 ratio as market concentration measure: when the shares of the four largest firms amounted to approximately 75 percent or more, the market was regarded as highly concentrated. The Department announced that mergers should be challenged when the market shares of both the acquiring firms and the acquired firms exceeded a certain threshold: for example, in highly concentrated markets mergers between firms both accounting for approximately 4 percent of the market would be challenged; in less highly concentrated markets a 5 percent market share for both the acquiring and the acquired firm was used as the relevant threshold (US Department of Justice, 1968). The Chicago School acquired a strong influence on American antitrust policy from the 1970s onwards and reached the apogee of its influence in the 1980s. A number of examples appropriately illustrate the altered judgement on forms of market conduct which, until the Chicago School emerged, seemed to cause competition problems but which, through the renewed application of price theory, no longer give rise to problems. The Harvard School was very critical of vertical restraints; the orthodox view proposed a strict ‘per se illegality’ for vertical price-fixing and tying (Kaysen and Turner, 1959, pp. 148-160). The Chicago revolution began when, in 1960, Telser published an
5300
Antitrust Law
487
article on vertical restraints which has since become a classic. In this essay the free-rider problem played a central role in explaining vertical price-fixing (see Telser, 1960, and Marvel and McCafferty, 1984, who added a quality certification argument). The free-rider rationale is not only used in the analysis of vertical price-fixing but has been extended by the Chicago School authors to other intra-brand restraints such as the reservation of exclusive sales territories and exclusive sales channels (selective distribution, franchising). The most far-reaching proposal of Chicago scholars was to introduce ‘per se legality’ for restricted distribution (Posner, 1981). Protection against free-riding may also explain interbrand restraints, such as exclusive dealing. Exclusive territories address the free-riding of one dealer on the efforts of another, whereas exclusive dealing addresses the free-riding of one manufacturer on the efforts of another (see Marvel, 1982). In deciding about the lawfulness of vertical restraints the American Supreme Court has been influenced by the Chicago analysis. The assessment of vertical restraints has wavered back and forth between the rule of reason and per se unlawfulness. In 1963 a majority of the Supreme Court held that vertical restraints did not necessarily violate the antitrust laws and were therefore subject to a rule of reason test (White Motor Co. v. United States). Four years later, the Supreme Court enunciated a clear-cut, but formalistic, distinction between restraints imposed by a manufacturer who retained ownership of the goods in question, and those imposed by a manufacturer after parting with ownership. If a manufacturer parts with ownership over his product or transfers risk of loss to another, he may not reserve control over its destiny or the conditions of its resale (United States v. Arnold, Schwinn & Co.). Then in 1977 the Supreme Court made clear that ‘departure from the rule-of-reason standard must be based upon demonstrable economic effect rather than … upon formalistic line drawing’. In so holding the Court drew also on the academic writings of the Chicago School. It would be premature, however, to consider the case-law of the American Supreme Court as a victory for the Chicago School analysis. The readiness of the American judiciary to apply the rule of reason does not extend to minimum vertical price-fixing. With respect to maximum resale prices the rule only recently shifted from a per se prohibition to the reasonableness standard (State Oil v. Kahn, Slip op. at 5). In the United States the Chicago learning has clearly influenced the analysis of predatory pricing. In the Matsushita case (in which American manufacturers of consumer electronic products accused Matsushita of combining with other Japanese manufacturers to monopolize the American market through predatory pricing), the Supreme Court quoted a number of publications by disciples of the Chicago view in support of its rejection of price-undercutting as a rational (that is, profit-maximising) economic strategy. The Supreme Court emphasised that a campaign of predatory pricing can be rational only if, after the elimination of the target, there remains sufficient monopoly power to raise prices and thus
488
Antitrust Law
5300
generate additional income. Given that in the Matsushita case it was improbable that the purpose of the predatory pricing could be achieved, the majority concluded that the price-undercutters ‘competed for business rather than to implement an economically senseless conspiracy’ (Matsushita Elec. Indus. Co. v. Zenith Radio Co.). In recent American case-law economic arguments are playing an ever more important role, but the Supreme Court seems no longer willing to blindly follow the Chicago approach. Antitrust defences based on Chicago ideas may be rejected using counter-arguments which are similarly economic in nature and largely based on criticisms towards the assumptions underlying the Chicago analysis. The Kodak case provides an interesting example (Eastman Kodak Co. v. Image Technical Services, Inc. et al.). Independent service organisations complained that Kodak had limited the availability of its proprietary spare parts, thus monopolising the market for the servicing of Kodak equipment. Kodak’s defence was primarily based on the argument that if there was competition in the primary market, then aftermarket power should have little adverse effect on consumers. The argument was similar to the Chicago School’s view that it is not possible for a dominant firm to achieve monopoly profits twice: the so-called leverage hypothesis was rejected already in the early days of the Chicago School (see Bowman, 1957). If a manufacturer raises the price of maintenance services, it can only do this - so Kodak argued - at the expense of lowering the initial purchase price of the equipment. The Supreme Court rejected this Chicago-inspired argument and demonstrated that consumers were not able to calculate lifetime cost with any accuracy, either because necessary information was not available to them or because of ‘bounded rationality’. Thus the Supreme Court made clear that the Chicago analysis of tying arrangements only holds under conditions of perfect information. Chicago theorists also exerted a clear influence upon American merger policy. The current 1992 Merger Guidelines are evidence that many concepts that started out as Chicago School concepts are now embraced by almost all of the US antitrust community. Throughout the Guidelines the analysis is focused on whether consumers or producers ‘likely would’ take certain actions, that is whether the action is in the actor’s economic interest. This reflects the concern to explain, rather than to merely describe, behaviour in (concentrated) markets, in order to be able to avoid inappropriate regulatory interventions. Intervention by the antitrust authorities is also geared to the goals of allocative efficiency: merger control should prevent that prices are raised above competitive levels for a significant period of time. Market power is defined accordingly. To create or enhance market power or facilitate its exercise, the merger must significantly increase concentration. The concentrated market must be properly defined and measured; the Guidelines pay considerable attention to the difficult problem of market definition. As a measure of market concentration the HHI index is used,
5300
Antitrust Law
489
instead of the CR4. If concentration increases significantly, the American antitrust agency will assess whether the merger raises concern about potential adverse competitive effects. It is stressed that market share and concentration data provide only the starting point for analyzing the competitive impact of a merger. Hasty conclusions from market structure of performance are thus overcome. A merger may diminish competition by enabling the firms selling in the relevant market more likely, more successfully or more completely to engage in coordinated interaction that harms consumers (tacit or express collusion). Mergers may also harm consumers if they create conditions conducive to reaching terms of coordination or conditions conducive to detecting and punishing deviations. If the merger raises significant competitive concerns, the antitrust agency will examine whether market entry may counteract the competitive effects of concern. At this point of the analysis the Chicago influence is obvious: Chicagoans stress that the possibility of market entry may prevent the post-merger firm from earning above-normal profits. Following this view, the Guidelines state that mergers in markets where entry is easy raise no antitrust concern. Entry is considered as ‘easy’ when it passes the tests of timeliness (entry must take place within a timely period), likelihood (entry must be profitable) and sufficiency (entry must be sufficient to return market prices to their pre-merger levels). The analysis of entry conditions will not yet complete the analysis. Efficiency gains of the merger will next be assessed. The Guidelines explicitly state that the primary benefit of mergers to the economy is their efficiency-enhancing potential, which can increase the competitiveness of firms and result in lower prices to consumers: ‘As a consequence, in the majority of cases, the Guidelines will allow firms to achieve available efficiencies through mergers’. Finally, it will be examined whether, but for the merger, either party to the transaction would be likely to fail, causing its assets to exit the market (failing company defense). The ultimate question whether the merger is likely to cause prices above competitive levels for a significant period of time will thus only be answered after an assessment of market concentration, potential adverse competitive effects, entry, efficiency and failure (US Department of Justice, 1992). 7.2 Europe Notwithstanding the fact that it is unlikely that the authors of the Treaty of Rome were aware of the concept of workable competition, many of the distinguishing features of European competition policy seem to fit into this theoretical framework. It is noteworthy that the European Court of Justice, in its leading Metro judgement, referred to the concept of workable competition as being the type of competition that was necessary to achieve the economic objectives of the EC Treaty (Metro v. SABA and Commission). The judgement was concerned with the lawfulness of selective distribution agreements. Once
490
Antitrust Law
5300
technical and luxury products are sold - for resale - only to recognised distributors, there can no longer be any question of a market which accords with the model of perfect competition. On the other hand, it is indeed possible to speak of workable competition. The European Court of Justice emphasised that price competition is not the only form of competition for wholesalers and retailers. It considered that it was in consumers’ interests for prices to be set at a certain level in order to be able to support a network of specialised dealers alongside a parallel system of dealers who themselves provide services and undertake other actions to keep distribution costs down. This choice is open to certain sectors in which high-quality, technically advanced and durable goods are produced and distributed. The manner in which the concept of workable competition acquired specific content can, by way of example, be further examined by studying present-day law in relation to selective distribution systems (for an overview, see Goyder, 1993). Provided the only criteria for selecting a distributor are objective, qualitative ones relating to his technical qualifications, his staff and his firm, and these criteria are determined uniformly for all distributors; and provided, furthermore, that they are applied in a non-discriminatory manner, the agreement is not regarded as restricting competition within the meaning of Article 85(1) EC Treaty. In order to establish the precise nature of such qualitative criteria for the selection of distributors, it is necessary to consider whether the characteristics of the product require a selective distribution system in order to maintain the quality and the proper use of the product. It is also necessary to examine to what extent these aims can already be accomplished by national regulations concerning access to the distributor’s profession or the conditions under which the products in question may be sold. Finally, one must answer the question of the extent to which the criteria thus determined are necessary in order to achieve the objective of improved quality. The European Commission has approved selective distribution systems for, for example, cars, television sets, watches and personal computers. It is evident that selective distribution agreements make resale to non-recognised dealers in other EC countries impossible, but the European Commission has nothing against this so long as exports within the selective distribution channels continue unhindered. By contrast, with the strict prohibition against absolute territorial protection in exclusive distribution agreements, increasing interbrand competition is balanced against the restraints inherent in intra-brand competition. Inter-brand competition guarantees consumers’ freedom of choice so long as access to the relevant market, or the competition within it, is not restricted to a significant extent by the cumulative effects of parallel networks or by similar agreements between competing producers or distributors. It is therefore necessary, when judging selective distribution systems, to take account of competition between competing systems of distribution. When selective distribution goes hand in hand with a quantitative restriction on
5300
Antitrust Law
491
recognised resellers the Commission will, as a rule, give full effect to the prohibition against cartels. The fact that the economic doctrine of the Chicago School has not influenced European competition law is clearly apparent from the decisions in AKZO and Tetra Pak II. The Court of Justice accepted a price-cost comparison as the yardstick by which to establish predatory pricing. Abuse of dominant position must be deemed to be present once prices fall below the level of average variable costs. According to the Court of Justice, a firm with a dominant position will always suffer losses if it charges such prices and it will have an interest in doing so only if it is aiming to exclude competitors in order to profit thereafter, by means of price increases, from the monopoly it has achieved. Furthermore, the Court of Justice considered that prices which are higher than average variable costs but lower than average total costs must be considered as unlawful to the extent that the fixing of prices at that level forms part of a strategy of excluding competitors. According to the Court of Justice, such prices can exclude from the market firms which, while just as efficient as the dominant firm, do not possess sufficient financial resources to enter such a price war. One can detect in this last argument the ‘deep pocket’ reasoning which has been discredited in the Chicago-oriented economic literature. In the event that the prices of the defendant firm are lower than average variable costs, there exists an irrefutable presumption of prohibited price-undercutting (predatory pricing). The European Court therefore adopts a stricter attitude towards price wars than the American judges do. Once prices are higher than average variable costs but lower than average total costs, supplementary evidence must be adduced in order to establish incontrovertibly the existence of a strategy aimed at the exclusion of competitors. From the Court’s further reasoning it seems that making threats, asking ‘unreasonably low prices’, maintaining artificially low prices over long periods and granting fidelity rebates can, together, provide the necessary supplementary evidence. In the AKZO case the Court relied heavily on the subjective evidence of intention on AKZO’s part (AKZO v. Commission). According to the Court, AKZO’s intention was clearly aimed at annihilating ECS (the target of the price war) because AKZO’s prices were not fixed in order to respond to competition from ECS but turned out in fact to be significantly lower. The weakest point both in the Commission’s reasoning and in that of the Court of Justice’s is that in neither of them was it adequately demonstrated that AKZO’s so-called predatory pricing could have succeeded. In the Chicago view an essential condition for considering predatory pricing as a rational competitive strategy is that the price-undercutter can recoup his losses after driving the target from the market. The longer the price-undercutting lasts, the larger the accumulated losses will be. Also, it will be very difficult or impossible to recoup the losses if potential new entrants to the market have to
492
Antitrust Law
5300
be borne in mind. Neither the Commission nor the Court of Justice gave sufficient consideration to these factors. In 1994, the European Court of First Instance had an opportunity to reconsider the position in Tetra Pak II, for the Commission’s finding that Tetra Pak had practised predatory pricing was specifically challenged by reference to the economic theory accepted in the most recent American case-law. Tetra Pak argued that, even if it had priced its products under cost, it could not have been indulging in predatory pricing because it had no reasonable hope of recouping its losses in the long term. The Court, however, upheld the Commission’s finding without any serious examination of this argument, holding that, where a producer charged AKZO-type loss-making prices, a breach of Article 86 EC Treaty was established ipso facto, without any need to consider specifically whether the company concerned had any reasonable prospect of recouping the losses which it had incurred (Tetra Pak International SA v. Commission). Finally, in the field of merger control the emphasis of the inquiry is on whether the concentration ‘creates or strengthens a dominant position’ (Reg. 4064/89). This clearly reflects the Harvard ideas that the structure of the market has an impact on the ultimate performance of the market. There is no explicit efficiency defence. Efficiencies are often seen as evidence of market power, rather than as benefits which may outweigh the anti-competitive consequences of mergers (see Neven, Nuttall and Seabright, 1993).
Bibliography on Antitrust Law (5300) Akerlof, George A. (1970), ‘The Market for “Lemons”: Quality Uncertainty and the Market Mechanism’, 84 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 488-500. Ausubel, Lawrence M. and Deneckere, Raymond J. (1987), ’One is Almost Enough for Monopoly’, 18 Rand Journal of Economics, 255-274. Bain, Joe S. (1951), ‘Relation of Profit Rate to Industry Concentration: American Manufacturing 1936-1940', 65 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 293-324. Bain, Joe S. (1956), Barriers to New Competition, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Bain, Joe S. (1968), Industrial Organisation, 2nd edn, New York, John Wiley and Sons. Baird, Douglas G., Gertner, Robert H. and Picker, Randal C. (1994), Game Theory and the Law, Cambridge and London, Harvard University Press. Baker, Jonathan B. (1989), ‘Identifying Cartel Policy under Uncertainty: the U.S. Steel Industry: 1933-1939', 32 Journal of Law and Economics, 547-576. Baumol, William J. (1982), ’Contestable markets: an Uprising in the Theory of Industry Structure’, 72 American Economic Review, 1-15. Baumol, William J., Panzar, John C. and Willig, Robert D. (1982), Contestable Markets and the Theory of Industrial Structure, Harcourt Brace Jovanovick, New York, 2nd edn, Orlando. Berry, Steven, Levinsohn, James and Pakes, Ariel (1995), ‘Automobile Prices in Market Equilibrium’, 63 Econometrica, 841-850.
5300
Antitrust Law
493
Bittlingmayer, George (1985), ‘Did Antitrust Policy Cause the Great Merger Wave?’, 28 Journal of Law and Economics, 77-118. Bork, Robert H. (1954), ‘Vertical Integration and the Sherman Act: The Legal History of an Economic Misconception’, 22 University of Chicago Low Review, 157 ff. Bork, Robert H. (1978), The Antitrust Paradox: A Policy at War with Itself, Basic Books, New York. Bowman, Ward S. (1957), ‘Tying Arrangements and the Leverage Problem’, 67 Yale Law Journal, 19 ff. Brock, William A. (1983), ‘Contestable Markets and the Theory of Industry Structure: A Review Article’, 91 Journal of Political Economy, 1055-1066. Carlton, Dennis W. and Perloff, Jeffrey M. (1994), Modern Industrial Organisation 2nd edn, New York, HarperCollins. Chamberlin, Edward H. (1933), The Theory of Monopolistic Competition, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Clark, John M. (1940), ’Towards a Concept of Workable Competition’, 30 American Economic Review, 242-243. Coase, Ronald (1937), ‘The Nature of the Firm’, 4 Economica, 386-405. Coase, Ronald (1972), ‘Durability and Monopoly’, 15 Journal of Law and Economics, 143-149. Collins, Norman R. and Preston, Lee E. (1969), ‘Price-Cost Margins and Industry Structure’, 51 The Review of Economics and Statistics, 271-286. Comanor, William S. and Wilson, Thomas A. (1967), ‘Advertising, Markets Structure and Performance’, 49 Review of Economics and Statistics, 423-440. Cournot, Auguste (1971), Researches into Mathematical Principles of the Theory of Wealth, New York, Augustus M. Kelly, p. 213. Original French title: Recherches sur les Principes Mathématiques de la Theorie des Richesses, in Journal des Savants, 1838. Cowling, Keith and Mueller, Dennis C. (1983), ‘The Social Costs of Monopoly Power in the French Economy: Some Tentative Estimates’, 32 Journal of Industrial Economics, 113-130. Davidson, Carl and Deneckere, Raymond (1986), ‘Long-Run Competition in Capacity, Short-Run Competition in Price, and the Cournot Model’, 17 Rand Journal of Economics, 404-415. De Bondt, Raymond and Van Cayseele, Patrick (1985), ‘Overheidsbeleid ten Aanzien van Industriële Vernieuwingsactiviteiten (Government Policy Towards Industrial Innovation)’, 49(3) Maandschrift Economie, 214-226. Deneckere, Raymond and Davidson, Carl (1984), ‘Horizontal Mergers and Collusive Behavior’, 2 International Journal of Industrial Organisation, 117-132. Domowitz, Ian, Hubbard, Glenn R. and Petersen, Bruce C. (1986), ‘Business Cycles and the Relationship Between Concentration and Price-Cost Margins’, 17 The Rand Journal of Economics, 1-17. Edgeworth, Francis Y. (1925), The Pure Theory of Monopoly, London, Macmillan. European Commission (1997), Green Paper on Vertical Restraints, COM (96) 7321 def. Eucken, Walter (1949), ‘Die Wettbewerbsordnung und ihre Verwirklichung’, 2 ORDO Jahrbuch für die Ordnung von Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft, 93 ff. Fisher, Franklin M. (1989), ‘Games Economists Play: A Non-cooperative View’, 20 Rand Journal of Economics, 113-124. Friedman, James W. (1984), Oligopoly Theory, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
494
Antitrust Law
5300
Fuchs, Victor R. (1961), ‘Integration, Concentration and Profits in Manufacturing Industry’, 75 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 278-291. Gasmi, Farid, Laffont, Jean-Jacques and Vuong, Quang H. (1992), ‘Econometric Analysis of Collusive Behavior in a Soft Drink Market’, 1 Journal of Economics and Management Strategy, 277-311. Goyder, Donald (1993), EC Competition Law, 2nd edn, Oxford, Clarendon Press. Hamilton, Jonathan and Slutsky, Steven (1990), ‘Endogenous Timing in Duopoly Games: Stackelberg or Cournot Equilibrium’, 2 Games and Economic Behavior, 29-46. Harberger, Arnold C. (1954),’ Monopoly and Resource Allocation’, 44 American Economic Review, 77-87. Hotelling, Harold (1928), ‘Stability in Competition’, 39 Economic Journal, 41-57. Jacquemin, Alexis P. (1997), ‘Industrial Organisation and Competition Policy: What are the Links?’, in van Bergeijk, Peter, Bovenberg, Land, Van Damme, Erik and van Sinderen, Jarig (eds), Economic Science and Practice, The Roles of Academic Economists and Policy-Makers, Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, 214 p. Jacquemin, Alexis P. and De Jong, Henry W. (1977), European Industrial Organisation, London, Macmillan, 269 p. Kamien, Morton and Zang, Israel (1990), ‘The Limits of Monopolisation Through Acquisition’, 105 The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 465-500. Kamerschen, David R. (1969), ‘The Determination of Profit Rates in “Oligopolistic” Industries’, 42 Journal of Business, 293-301. Kaysen, Carl and Turner, Donald F. (1959), Antitrust Policy: An Economic and Legal Analysis, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Kenney, Roy W. and Klein, Benjamin (1983), ‘The Economics of Block Booking’, 26 Journal of Law and Economics, 451-540. Kreps, David M. and Scheinkman, Jose A. (1983), ‘Quantity Pre-commitment and Bertrand Competition Yields Cournot Outcomes’, 14 Bell Journal of Economics, 326-337. Kwoka, John E. and White, Lawrence J. (1994), The Antitrust Revolution: The Role of Economics, New York, HarperCollins, 468 p. Lande, Robert H. (1982), ‘Wealth Transfers as the Original and Primary Concern of Antitrust: The Efficiency Interpretation Challenged’, 43 Hastings Law Journal, 67-151. Leibenstein, Harvey (1966), ‘Allocative Efficiency vs. “X-Efficiency”’, 56 American Economic Review, 392-415. Leibenstein, Harvey (1978), ‘“X-Inefficiency” Xists - Reply to an Xorcist’, 68 American Economic Review, 203-211. Lerner, Abba P. (1934), ‘The Concept of Monopoly and the Measurement of Monopoly Power’, 1 Review of Economic Studies, 157-175. Levine, David K. and Lippman, Steven A. (1995), The Economics of Information, Aldershot, Eward Elgar, p. 467. Levinson, Harry (1960), Post War Movements in Prices and Wages in Manufacturing Industries, Joint Economic Committee, Study of Income, Employment, and Prices, Study Paper No. 21, Washington, Government Printing Office. Marshall, Alfred (1920), Principles of Economics, 8th edn, London, Macmillan. Martin, Stephen (1993), Industrial Economics: Economic Analysis And Public Policy, New York, Macmillan, 623 p. Marvel, Howard P. (1982), ‘Exclusive Dealing’, 25 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-25. Marvel, Howard P. and McCafferty, S. (1984), ‘Resale Price Maintenance and Quality Certification’, 15 Rand Journal of Economics, 346-359.
5300
Antitrust Law
495
Mason, Edward S. (1949a), ‘Price and Production Policies of Large Scale Enterprises’, 29 American Economic Review, 61-74. Mason, Edward S. (1949b), ‘The Current State of the Monopoly Problem in the United States’, 62 Harvard law Review, 1265-1285. McGee, John S. (1958), ‘Predatory Price Cutting. The Standard Oil (N.J.) Case’, 1 Journal of Law and Economics, 137 ff. McNulty, Paul J. (1967), ‘A Note on the History of Perfect Competition’, 75 Journal of Political Economy, 395-396. Minhas, Bagicha Singh (1963), An International Comparison of Factor Costs and Factor Use, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 124 p. Neven, Damien J., Robin, Nuttall and Seabright, Paul (1993), Merger in Daylight. The Economics and Politics of European Merger Control, CEPR, London, 296 p. Novshek, William (1985), ‘Perfectly Competitive Markets as the Limits of Cournot Markets’, 35 Journal of Economic Theory, 72-82. Panzar, John C. and Rosse, James N. (1987), ‘Testing for Monopoly Equilibrium’, 35 Journal of Industrial Economics, 443-456. Phlips, Louis (1988), The Economics of Imperfect Information, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 281 p. Phlips, Louis (1995), Competition Policy: A Game-theoretic Perspective, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 272 p. Pindyck, Robert S. and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1993), Microeconomics, 2nd edn, New York, Macmillan. Porter, Robert H. (1983), ‘A Study of Cartel Stability: The Joint Executive Committee 1880-1886', 14 Bell Journal of Economics, 301-314. Posner, Richard A. (1979), ‘The Chicago School of Antitrust Analysis’, 127 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 925 ff, reprinted in 22 Corporate Practice Commentator, 583-610. Posner, Richard A. (1981), ‘The Net Step in the Antitrust Treatment of Restricted Distribution: Per Se Legality’, 48 University of Chicago Law Review, 6-26. Reder, Melwin W. (1982), ‘Chicago Economics: Performance and Change’, 20 Journal of Economic Literature, 1-38. Robinson, Joan (1964), The Economics of Imperfect Competition, London, Macmillan, p. 352. Salant, Stephen W., Switzer, Sheldon and Reynolds, Robert J. (1983), ‘Losses from Horizontal Merger, the Effects of an Exogenous Change in Industry Structure on Cournot-Nash Equilibrium’, 98 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 185-199. Scherer, Frederic M. and Ross, David (1990), Industrial Market Structure and Economic Performance, 3rd edn, Boston, Houghton Mifflin, 713 p. Schmalensee, Richard (1983), ‘Advertising and Entry Deterence: An Exploratory Model’, 91 Journal of Political Economy, 636-653. Schotter, Andrew R. (1994), Microeconomics: a Modern Approach, New York, HarperCollins College, p. 635. Schwarz, Marius and Reynolds, Robert J. (1983), ‘Contestable Markets: an Uprising in the Theory of Industry Structure: Comment’, 73 American Economic Review, 488-490. Schwartzman, David (1959),’ The Effects of Monopoly on Price’, 67 Journal of Political Economy, 352-362. Shapiro, Carl (1989), ‘The Theory of Business Strategy’, 20 Rand Journal of Economics, 125-137.
496
Antitrust Law
5300
Sleuwaegen, Leo and Van Cayseele, Patrick (1997), ‘Belgian Competition Policy, Some Facts and an Economic Analysis’, in Martin, S. (ed), Competition Policy in Europe, Amsterdam, North Holland, 185-204. Smets, Hilde and Van Cayseele, Patrick (1995), ‘Competing Merger Policies in a Common Agency Framework’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 425-441. Smith, Adam ([1776] 1937), An Enquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, New York, Modern Library Edition. Spence, A. Michael (1980), ‘Notes on Advertising, Economics of Scale, and Entry Barriers’, 95 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 493-507. Stigler, George J. (1942), ‘The Extent and Bases of Monopoly’, 32(2) American Economic Review, 1-22. Stigler, George J. (1968), The Organisation of Industry, Homewood, Ill., Irwin.. Stigler, George J. (1964), ‘A Theory of Oligopoly’, 72 Journal of Political Economy, 44-61. Stigler, George J. (1971), ‘The Theory of Economic Regulation’, 2 Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, 3-21 Stigler, George J. (1976), ‘The Xistence of X-Efficiency’, 66 American Economic Review, 213-216. Sullivan, Thomas E. (1991), The Political Economy of the Sherman Act. The First One Hundred Years, New York and Oxford, Oxford University Press. Sullivan, Daniel (1985), ‘Testing Hypotheses about Firm Behaviour in the Cigarette Industry’, 93 Journal of Political Economy, 586-598. Sutton, John (1990), ‘Explaining Everything, Explaining Nothing? Game Theoretic Models in Industrial Economics’, 34 European Economic Review, 505-512. Sutton, John (1991), Sunk Costs and Market Structure, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Telser, Lester G. (1960), ‘Why Should Manufacturers Want Fair Trade?’, 3 Journal of Law and Economics, 86-103. Tirole, Jean (1988), The Theory of Industrial Organisation, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. US Department of Justice (1968), Merger Guidelines, Trade Regulation Reports, CCH, 13, 101ff. US Department of Justice (1985), Vertical Restraints Guidelines, Washington. US Department of Justice (1992), Merger Guidelines, Washington. Utton, Michael A. (1995), Market Dominance and Antitrust Policy, Aldershot, Edward Elgar, 342 p. Van Cayseele, Patrick (1993), ‘Lemons, Peaches and Creampuffs, or the Economics of Second-hand Markets’, 38 Tijdschrift voor Economie en Management, 73-85. Van Cayseele, Patrick (1994), De Belgische Wet op de Mededinging in een Industrieel Economisch en Internationaal Juridisch Perspectief (The Belgian Law on Competition in a Industrial, Economic and International Legal Perspective), Antwerpen, Maklu, p. 152. Van Cayseele, Patrick (1996), ‘Industriële Economie, Toen en Nu (Industrial Economics, Then and Now)’, Maandschrift Economie, 5-24. Van Cayseele, Patrick (1998), ‘Market Structure and Innovation: A Survey of the Last Twenty Years’, De Economist, forthcoming. Van Cayseele, Patrick and Furth, Dave (1996a), ‘Bertrand-Edgeworth Duopoly with Buyouts or First Refusal Contracts’, 16 Games and Economic Behavior, 153-180. Van Cayseele, Patrick and Furth, Dave (1996b), ‘Von Stackelberg’s Equilibria for Bertrand-Edgeworth Duopoly with Buyouts’, 23 Journal of Economic Studies, 96-109.
5300
Antitrust Law
497
Van den Bergh, Roger (1996), ‘Modern Industrial Organisation versus Old-Fashioned European Competition Law’, 17 European Competition Law Review, 75-87. Van den Bergh, Roger (1997), Economische Analyse van het Mededingingsrecht. Een Terreinverkenning, 2nd edn, Arnhem, Gouda Quint. Verboven, Frank (1996), ‘International Price Discrimination in the European Car Market’, 27 Rand Journal of Economics, 240-268. Viscusi, W. Kip, Vernon, John M. and Harrington, Joseph E. (1995), Economics of Regulation and Antitrust, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 757 p. Weiss, Leonard W. (1963), ‘Average Concentration Ratios and Industry Performance’, 11 Journal of Industrial Economics, 237-254. Weiss, Leonard W. (1969), ‘Quantitative Studies of Industrial Organisation’, in Intriligator (ed), Frontiers of Quantitative Economics, Amsterdam, North-Holland. Weiss, Leonard W. (1989), Concentration and Price, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Williamson, Oliver (1975), Markets and Hierarchics: Analysis and Antitrust Implications, New York, The Free Press. Williamson, Oliver (1979),’ Assessing Vertical Market Restrictions: Antitrust Ramifications of the Transaction Cost Approach’, 127 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 953-993. Williamson, Oliver (1985), The Economic Institutions of Capitalism: Firms, Markets, Relational Contracting, New York, The Free Press. Williamson, Oliver (1986), Economic Organisation, Firms, Markets and Policy Control, New York, New York University Press. Worcester, Dean A. (1973), ‘New Estimates of the Welfare Loss to Monopoly in the United States 1956-1969', 40 Southern Economic Journal, 234-245. Young, H. Peyton and Foster, Dean (1991), ‘Cooperation in the Short and in the Long Run’, 3 Games and Economic Behavior, 145-156.
Cases US Eastman Kodak Co. v. Image Technical Services, Inc. et al., 112 S.Ct. 2072 (1992)) Matsushita Elec. Indus. Co. v. Zenith Radio Co.,475, pp. 597-598 (1968) State Oil v. Kahn, US 1997 WL 679424 (U.S. Nov. 4, 1997) United States v. Arnold, Schwinn & Co., 388 U.S. 365 (1967) White Motor Co. v. United States, 372 U.S. 253 (1963) EU AKZO v. Commission (1991), Case 62/86, ECR 3359 Metro v. SABA and Commission (1977) , Case 26/76, ECR 1875 Tetra Pak International SA v. Commission (1994), Case T-83/91, ECR II
5400 REGULATION OF NATURAL MONOPOLY Ben W.F. Depoorter Researcher Center for Advanced Studies in Law and Economics University of Ghent, Faculty of Law © Copyright 1999 Ben W.F. Depoorter
Abstract The concept of natural monopoly presents a challenging public policy dilemma. On the one hand a natural monopoly implies that efficiency in production would be better served if a single firm supplies the entire market. On the other hand, in the absence of any competition the monopoly holder will be tempted to exploit his natural monopoly power in order to maximize its profits. This chapter will take a closer look at the model of natural monopoly. It will address those areas where an unregulated natural monopoly is generally considered to be the cause of concern, before offering a brief overview of the regulatory process and some of its specific regulatory tools. It should be noted that this chapter mainly aims to provide an introduction to the vast literature on this topic, which has fascinated many economic and legal scholars over the years. JEL classification: K23, L90 Keywords: Cream Skimming, Price Regulation, Incentive Regulation, Contestable Markets, Public Ownership
1. The Natural Monopoly Model A natural monopoly exists in an industry where a single firm can produce output such as to supply the market at a lower per unit-cost than can two or more firms. The telephone industry, electricity and water supply are often cited as examples of natural monopolies. These industries face relatively high fixed cost structures. The costs necessary to produce even a small amount are high. In turn, once the initial investment has been made, the average costs decline with every unit produced. Competition in these industries is deemed socially undesirable because the existence of a large number of firms would result in needless duplication of capital equipment. The classic example might be that of two separate companies providing local water supplies, each constructing underground pipelines. 498
5400
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
499
In undergraduate textbooks one finds the natural monopoly condition linked to the issue of economies of scale. Traditionally, natural monopoly is often described as a situation where one firm may realize such economies of scale that it can produce the market’s desired output at an average cost which is lower than two firms could with smaller scale processes. The modern approach to defining natural monopoly was initiated by William J. Baumol (1977). In an industry where a single firm can produce output to supply the entire market at a lower per-unit cost than can two or more firms (subadditivity of the cost functions) or in an industry to which entrants are not ‘naturally’ attracted and are incapable of survival, even in the absence of predatory measures by the incumbent monopolist (sustainability of monopoly) the single firm is called a natural monopoly. The concept of subadditivity is a precise mathematical representation of the natural monopoly concept (Baumol, 1977) . If all potential active firms in the industry have access to the same technology, represented by a cost function c, then at an aggregate output x, the industry is a natural monopoly if c (x) < c (x1) + ... + for any set of outputs of x1, ..., xt such that
A cost function c is globally subadditive if for any non-negative output vectors x and y, c (x1 + y1, ..., xn + yn) < c (x1, ..., xn) + c (y1, ..., yn )
Given the production of a set N' 71, ..., n? of indivisible objects, the cost function is subadditive if c (S cT) < c (S) + c (T) for any disjoint subsets S and R (on the concept of subadditivity, see Baumol, 1977; Sharkey, 1982). There is a close relation between economies of scale and subadditivity. In a single-product firm economies of scale are a sufficient but not necessary condition for a natural monopoly. Production processes, although subadditive at output levels which exhibit economies of scale (decreasing average costs), may also be subadditive when exhibiting increasing average costs. In a multiproduct firm, for instance, economies of scope may create a natural monopoly although there are no economies of scale with regard to the production of the goods separately.
500
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
5400
Herein lies the difference between a strong and a weak natural monopoly (Gegax and Nowotny, 1993, p. 67). While strong natural monopolies exhibit decreasing average costs, the weak natural monopoly firm exhibits increasing average costs even though its costs are subadditive. The latter finds itself in a situation where it may not be able to prevent entry by other firms, for example when its monopoly position is non-sustainable. Since costs are subadditive, society might prefer a market consisting of only one firm rather than a multiplicity of firms producing the same output. Therefore, in the case of a weak natural monopoly it is often considered desirable that regulatory authorities bar entry into the market of the weak natural monopoly and in turn regulate prices. Graphically, a strong natural monopoly exists when the long-run average cost curve of a single firm is still declining at the point where it intersects the total market demand curve for the product. The D line on Figure 1 represents the demand curve, which is also the market-demand curve. A monopolist will supply the market with output at a price Po. The optimal scale of the firm is reached at point A in the figure. The market conditions, illustrated in Figure 1, allow for one firm to provide the entire market cheaper than could two or more firms. Suppose the market consists of four firms, each producing at an optimal level, where marginal revenue equals marginal costs. Thus, each firm produces a quantity of 1000. The total market demand curve determines price, which adds up to Px. At scale B, where the market is restructured into 4 firms, instead of one monopoly firm, each firm produces at a smaller scale. The total amount produced is unchanged but the average unit costs are higher at scale B. The market allows for one producer to generate total market demand at cheaper costs than can two or more equal producers. Figure 1
5400
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
501
A. Why Regulate Natural Monopoly? Many supposed natural monopolies are the subject of various types of regulation. As described above, under conditions of natural monopoly the market is best served when one firm supplies total market demand. Public interest theory claims to provide an explanation for government intervention in what may be considered a market imperfection. The need to avoid duplication of facilities, particularly fixed costs, would serve as a justification for traditional entry regulation. Consider in this respect the restructuring of the telecom industry in the United States that broke up the Bell system to AT&T, while forbidding Regional Bell Operating Systems to enter the lines of business assigned to AT&T in order to prevent destructive competition (Crandall, 1988). In Part A we will try to provide a brief insight into some other motives behind the regulation of natural monopolies. We refer to Chapter 5940 in this volume for a detailed review of the specifics of regulation of utilities and to Chapter 5000 for a general discussion of the various theories of regulation.
2. Allocative Inefficiency Under perfect competition prices of goods equal marginal cost, as firms engage in a competitive bidding process. Under conditions of monopoly, the profitmaximizing behavior of the incumbent firm will lead to a higher price charged to consumers and a lower output. It enables the seller to capture much of the value that would otherwise be attained by consumers. Monopoly pricing thus results in a wealth transfer from consumers of a product to the seller. At the higher price, at which the monopolist tries to maximize profits, a group of potential consumers will be excluded as they will not be able to afford the product at the higher (artificially set) price. Thus, monopoly leads to the classic case of the occurrence of dead weight losses: the part of the consumer surplus that the monopolist cannot appropriate but consumers lose. Now as a result of the monopoly pricing scheme, these consumers may be forced to consume more costly substitutes or less useful products, although society’s resources would be better used producing more of the good provided by the monopoly firm. Furthermore, the argument goes that by limiting output the monopolist underutilizes productive resources. The argument of the negative consequences of monopoly on economic welfare has been the subject of heavy debate. This article will not venture into the broad discussion of welfare economics, monopoly and distributive justice (for an introduction, see Tullock, 1967; Rahl, 1967; for case studies on the consequences of monopoly pricing and welfare, Albon, 1988). We can,
502
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
5400
however, focus on a few of the arguments concerning the case of natural monopoly which challenge the relevance of the alleged allocative inefficiency. The classic opposition to monopoly rents as opposed to everyday rent-seeking by the common man is that monopoly rents are the result of an artificial scarcity rather than a natural scarcity (Schap, 1985). The question arises whether the same really can be said about an unregulated natural monopolist. Early on, Posner (1969) rightly noted that market power in the latter case stems from cost and demand characteristics of the market, not from unfair or restrictive practices.
3. X-Inefficiency The condition of natural monopoly raises the question whether internal efficiency, cost minimization by the firm, is achieved under natural monopoly. Does a monopoly firm put its resources to the best possible use within the existing state of technology? Modern antitrust economists have used the term ‘X-Inefficiency’ to indicate the internal wastes that occur when a firm acquires monopoly power and is no longer pressured by strong competitors to keep its costs at the competitive minimum. Often-cited legendary examples are US Steel, General Motors, Sears, IBM and American Airlines. These giant firms, which once dominated their industries, are accused of falling victim to their own inefficiencies (Mueller, 1996). Empirical data suggest that the amount to be gained by increasing X-efficiency is significant (for a review, see Leibenstein, 1966). Generally, in a competitive market firms have an incentive to reduce costs, in order to obtain higher profits by selling at the same price or a price between the old price and the new cost level. Although cost reduction might be shortlived in a competitive situation, as competitors reduce their production costs and adjust their prices to those of their direct competitors, the concern for survival provides a firm in such a market with a strong incentive to minimize costs (Dewey, 1959). If a firm fails to anticipate or match the cost reductions of its competitors, it might suddenly find itself in a market dominated by its competitors. Where there are no significant entry barriers the threat of potential competition will hold price down to cost. Otherwise other firms will enter the market at the same scale of production, sell at a slightly lower price and capture the whole market for as long as it is profitable (for more on contestability, see Section 8). Also, it could be argued a monopoly firm has an even stronger incentive to minimize costs in order to gain maximized profits. Since the threat of a counter
5400
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
503
reaction to its pricing schemes is absent, it does not face the risk that the consequential benefits will only be short-lived.
4. Technological Progress Technological developments have been the drive behind the transformation of certain natural monopoly markets to more competitive outcomes. Most notably, this is the case for the more recent changes in the telecommunications industry, where the enhancement and development of microwave and satellite technology has come to provide a strong substitute for the traditional cable networks. The value of technical development should not be underestimated. Technological progress often reduces production costs or creates new products and has been of enormous importance to economic welfare. The classic argument goes that monopoly firms lack an efficient incentive to promote technical change and invest in expensive R&D programs. Allegedly, a monopoly firm would discourage progress. By virtue of its protected position it would not fear that a rival will promote products and production methods and would therefore not be driven to pioneering himself. Real-life observations regarding the introduction of new technology in monopoly firms seem to validate this criticism - witness the long life of equipment in telephone industries. This is often the case, regardless of whether the monopoly firm is conducted as a public or private monopoly (Dewey, 1959). Some empirical data suggests that small, profit-seeking firms are responsible for most major innovations (Scherer, 1984). However, there are strong arguments that provide indications that contradict the traditional allegations concerning the case of under-innovation under monopoly. Even when assuming that a monopoly firm will not introduce new products unless the cost of the new product is less than the marginal cost of the old (as sunk costs are bygones), there is no reason the same could not be said about competitive firms (Fellner, 1951). Furthermore, an important point has to be made. The fact that an industry is a monopoly does not mean than only one firm is pursuing research and development in its technology. Through the presence of external forces it is likely that the incumbent monopoly firm will feel the pressure to spend time and money on innovation, in order to safeguard its position (Posner, 1969). Certainly in an unregulated market, with free entry, successful research in the field of production methods could seriously threaten the position of natural monopoly firms. Although a natural monopolist is less concerned about survival, the possible threat of the introduction of new technology in substitute
504
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
5400
markets should provide monopoly firms with a strong incentive to anticipate such developments through R&D expenditure (this relates to the theory of contestable markets, see Section 8). At the other end of the spectrum Schumpeter (1950) holds that there is a positive relation between innovation and market power. A monopoly firm would be a strong instead of a poor innovator. Superior access to capital, the ability to pool risks and economies of scale in the maintenance of R&D laboratories are likely to advance industrial technology.
5. Cream-Skinning and Cross-Subsidization Because of social considerations, government may often feel the need to ensure the provision of certain products or services at a lower-than-cost price to some consumers. For instance, it is quite common that governments demand the provision of ‘universal services’ to consumers by telephone companies, the availability of minimum services at reasonable prices, even to small and distant communities where the small scale of operation may lead to very high costs, which often results in the occurrence of losses. The delivery of such services is often financed by obtaining higher profits on the sale of other products and services. This is termed cross-subsidization, referring to the practice where the difference between the price charged to the targeted consumers and the cost of supply might be funded by crosssubsidization from the prices paid by other consumers or, in a multiproduct firm by the purchases made for other products or services. When a firm, burdened with ‘universal service’ obligations of some sort, is not protected from price competition and free entry of competitors, it might not be able to maintain its position in the market as potential competitors will enter these market segments that are provided at prices well above cost. Creamskimming occurs when a supplier concentrates only on those areas of the market where the costs of supply are lowest, for instance because of geographical reasons (on cream-skimming in a natural monopoly market, see Zupan, 1990). Regulated firms on such a market, with universal services obligations, might find themselves in a possibly fatally detrimental situation, when competitors capture these low-cost/high-profit parts of the market which are crucial to recover losses made in the high cost market parts. Take the example of the US Postal Service. Without legislative protection, its uniform pricing scheme, according to which it charges the same price to deliver a letter anywhere in the United States regardless of distance and specific difficulties, would soon deprive it of its most profitable routes.
5400
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
505
Yet, the practice of cross-subsidization, when a company that supplies more than one product and uses the revenues from product A to recover a portion of the costs of product B, generates economic inefficiencies. Although benefits from economics of joint production might have to be sacrificed, in most cases the consumers of product A would be better off if the products were produced and priced separately, while the customers of good B are given incorrect price signals about the incremental costs of producing product B (Spulber, 1995). The cross-subsidization of loss-making services by taxing remunerative services has been demonstrated to lead to significant allocative inefficiencies (Brennan, 1991).
B. The Regulatory Process 6. Price Regulation Price control, although driven to the background in the years of deregulation, has been of increased importance in the recent trend of privatization in Europe. From a public interest perspective, price control should allow regulators to set prices at a level which induces allocative and productive efficiency. This part provides a brief, non-technical introduction to some of the tools governments have at their disposal to assure that firms meet consumer demand at efficient cost levels. For a more in-depth look at the different forms of price regulation and its analysis, reference is made to Chapter 5200, Price Regulation, which also deals with natural monopoly. Figure 2
506
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
5400
Marginal and Average Cost Pricing and Rate of Return Policy Without regulation, Qm in Figure 2 represents the profit-maximizing output of the monopolist and the demand, in turn, determines the market price Pm. The monopoly earns a positive economic profit represented by the area of the rectangle PmFGH. Welfare maximization to society as a whole is achieved at the quantity-price of P1 , Q1 . In other words, regulating authorities should set a price P1 (marginal cost pricing) in order to maximize economic welfare. However, at price P1 consumers will buy a quantity of Q1, whereas AC is NQ1, which is greater than the price P3. This will result in a total negative economic profit, shown by the area of the rectangle P1P2AM. In the long run, the monopoly firm will not stay in business. If the commodity or service provided is desirable, the only way to keep the monopoly firm in business is to provide a public subsidy to the amount of P1 P2 AM. The political problems associated with subsidization, its implementation and financing and the difficulties of calculating demand and MC have led to the application in the public utility field of average cost pricing. In Figure 2 such a price is P2, determined by the intersection of the demand and long-run AC curve. The output under average-cost pricing, Q2, is greater than the unregulated monopoly output of Qm. Also, part of the welfare costs arising from restricted output by an unregulated monopoly is eliminated. Expansion of output, from Qm to Q2 provides benefits to consumers that are greater than the additional costs. On the other hand, average cost pricing can hardly be deemed entirely satisfactory either. Under average cost pricing, when Q2 is produced, welfare losses are caused because at this point average costs (the AC curve) exceed marginal costs (MC). Graphically, the AMO triangle in Figure 2 represents this consequential welfare loss. When applying a rate-of-return policy, regulating agencies focus on the rate of return on invested capital (accounting profit) earned by a monopoly (fair rate of return) (Moorehouse, 1995). Allowing regulated firms to acquire a total sum that consist of annual expenditure plus a reasonable profit on capital investment, the so-called ‘fair’ rate of return, was constructed by American courts and the regulating bodies in order to meet constitutional demands of utilities to set prices on a ‘just and reasonable’ level. This can be formulated as E + ( r ·RB) where E represents the firms annual expenditure, r is the multiplier, representing the fair rate of return, and RB the rate (attributed value of the capital investment). If the realized rate of return is higher than what is considered to be a normal return, then the price must be above average cost. In a trial-and-error fashion regulators try to locate the price where profit is normal, for example, where price equals average cost.
5400
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
507
Allowing the regulated monopolist a fair rate of return creates various economic problems that have to be taken into account. Auditing costs involved in determining the firms capital base are considerable. Especially the determination of r, which should reflect a level of return that is satisfactory to attract investment, is problematic. Looking at other ‘comparable’ industries or applying the capital asset pricing model, where one looks at the returns obtained by investors from a portfolio of investments, as modified by the difference between the returns from shares in utilities and those from more general market shares, it is clear that these are imperfect methods for determining a rate of return that potential investors will demand from the regulated industry. Also, the perverse effects on incentives that occur when applying the standard rate of return policy are perhaps even more troublesome (Train, 1991). The regulated firm has an incentive to inflate its capital cost figures, since higher costs imply higher absolute returns (Baron and Taggart, 1977, on profitmaximizing behavior under rate of return regulation, see Hughes, 1990). If the regulator sets the fair rate of return above the cost of capital, the regulated firm is likely to utilize more capital than if it were unregulated. Thus, it might use inefficient high capital/labor ratios for its output. Also, average cost pricing diminishes the monopolist’s incentive to minimize costs. Figure 2 illustrates some of the consequences of this behavior. Inflation of costs shift the actual AC curve to AC'. At a price of P2 losses occur, therefore, regulators grant a price increase to cover the higher costs (point C). When implementing rate-of-return regulation the complexity accompanied with instituting and enforcing regulation schemes may often lead to delays in the regulatory response to changes in costs and other market conditions. When costs are fallingduring a certain period of time firms will benefit from these socalled regulatory lags, as they will be able to enjoy rates of return greater than those deemed ‘fair’ in the outcome of the regulatory proceedings. Several authors have argued in favor of regulatory lags:they would, at least temporarily, provide a way to allow regulated firms to profit from achieving lower costs (Baumol, 1967; Williamson, 1971; Bailey, 1973). However, if costs shift upwards, for instance due to factors external to the regulated firm, the opposite effect will occur and, the firm will incur costs that were not foreseen by the regulator. Also, because profit rates are restricted, the firm’s managers face the option of providing themselves with amenities in their salaries or the firm’s profits. Whether they do take advantage of this option in practice is largely dependent on whether they are externally controlled by reliable public officials, which in turn involves considerable monitoring costs.
508
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
5400
Price Discrimination Charging consumers different prices relative to what they are willing to pay, even though the costs of producing and supplying the goods or services are the same, has been demonstrated to enable allocative efficiency. With this technique, often referred to as Ramsey pricing, information on the priceelasticity of the different goods should allow for efficient price setting (the higher the price-elasticity, the closer the price needs to be set to marginal cost) (Ramsey, 1927). The objection often heard is that such a pricing scheme involves a wealth transfer from the consumer (consumer surplus) to the producer. Also, severe price discrimination, often termed predatory discrimination, is an effective method by which competition may be crushed out (see however for a detailed and comprehensive account McGee’s case study of the Oil of Indiana case, 1958). The classical analysis of price discrimination was set out by Pigou (1920). A distinction between three degrees of discrimination was made. The first degree involves a different price set for every unit purchased by every consumer, in such a way that virtually all the possible consumer surplus is obtained by the producer. Although this pricing mechanism can be efficient, as marginal decisions are made as marginal cost, it is often opposed on income distributional grounds: the transfer from consumer to producer. Second-degree price discrimination consists of pricing groups according to their willingness to pay, where all those with a demand price above a certain level are charged one price, while those with a lower demand price are charged a lower price. Third-degree price discrimination comes into effect when consumers are divided into separate groups, each group is charged a different monopoly price. This technique is of course strongly dependent on the possibility for the seller to identify groups in each specific case, which will vary according to market circumstances. In the telephone and electricity industries, for instance, the distinction is made between residential and commercial customers, who pay different prices (Hollas and Friedland, 1980; Primeaux and Nelson, 1980; Naughton, 1986; Eckel, 1987). Sometimes, sorting consumers by their willingness to pay can be achieved by requiring customers to tie (Cummings and Ruhter, 1979) or bundle (Adams and Yellen, 1976). In circumstances of uncertainty of demand, where prices must be established before demand is known, special distinctions, such as ‘saver-airfares’ requiring early bookings may be enforced on separate consumers (Leland and Meyer, 1976; Sherman and Visscher, 1982). Peak-Load Pricing When demand follows a periodic cycle, during which demand might be high at certain times and low at others, peak-load pricing might offer a way to achieve marginal cost pricing. As marginal cost generally rises with output,
5400
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
509
price variations will allow it to reflect the higher costs. This allows for the moderation of the demand cycle while establishing a more effective use of capacity (Crew, Fernando and Kleindorfer, 1995). Higher pricing during periods of peak demand might discourage use and save costly capacity, whilst lower prices when demand is low might encourage use of capacity that otherwise would have been left idle.
7. Incentive Regulation Many of the problems arising from the pricing models, such as the AverechJohnson model find their origin in the absence of incentives to operate at minimum cost levels. The motivation behind incentive regulation is to provide the firm with the motivation to behave more consistently with regard to the social optimum. Price-Cap Regulation or RPI-X Requiring the firm to increase its prices for each year within a given period by no more than the retail price index (RPI) minus a variable factor (X) which is the agency’s assessment of the firm’s cost-efficiency potential, price-cap regulation was found to be superior to the fair rate of return method both in terms of efficiency and administrative costs (Littlechild and Beesley, 1992). The system, as described above, would require less information from the firms to the regulating bodies, which would not only make this model less costly but also diminish the capture problems associated with rate of return regulation (for an overview, see Chapter 5200, Price Regulation).
C. Alternatives for Regulation The inefficiencies (Coase, 1959, Posner, 1969, 1975) and costs (Gerwig, 1962; Hahn and Hird, 1991) of the regulatory processes have been well documented over the years. Many scholars became dissatisfied with the public interest approach to regulation and looked for an alternative that would explain data that did not correspond with the normative approach to regulation. Capture theory, which holds that producers are the winners under most, began to shape (Jordan, 1972). A considerable body of literature, the economic theory of regulation, grew from this (Peltzman, 1976; Stigler, 1971, 1976; for an overview, see Viscusi, Vernon and Harrington, 1995).
510
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
5400
This in turn, has given rise to new, appealing theories where the approach is to have optimality induced without regulation, even in markets with one producer. Competition amongst numerous firms can be used to achieve optimality under natural monopoly conditions, where competition is held amongst firms that could produce. The argument goes that the pressure from potential producers will induce efficient pricing decisions by the natural monopolist.
8. Contestable Markets Building upon Demsetz’s ideas (1968) on the threat of potential competition as a disciplinary mechanism, the theory of contestable markets was further developed by Willig (1980) and Baumol, Panzar and Willig (1982) and applied to natural monopoly (Coursey, Issac and Smith, 1984). In a market where entry and exit are completely free and unconstrained, the threat of potential competition may hold price down to cost. When potential entrants exercise strong constraints on the behavior of the incumbent monopoly firm, the latter will be moved to pricing schemes closer to cost. Firms in a contestable market will not be able to gain pricing profits that exceed normal profits under competitive circumstances, as otherwise other firms will enter the market at the same scale of production, sell at a slightly lower price and capture the whole market for as long as it may be profitable, a practice often referred to as hitand-run entry and exit (Baumol, 1982). When entry is allowed, new firms will be able to enter the market of a Ramsey-pricing natural monopolist at a lower price (Faulhaber, 1975; Sharkey, 1982). Thus, when the nature of the market allows for only one firm to provide total demand, competition can assert itself by deciding which firm will obtain market domination. Contestability of a market would render regulation pure waste, as without regulation the monopoly would yield price efficiency. Instead, given this theory, when determining the proper form of regulation, governments should restrain from measures that obstruct potential entry and create an environment that promotes contestability. In other words, regulators should encourage rather than prevent entry into the natural monopoly market. However, in order for a market to be qualified as contestable various conditions, most notably the absence of any significant entry barriers, are demanded. Perfectly contestable markets are based on free entry - the firm does not have to incur any cost that is not also incurred by the incumbent natural monopolist - by entrepreneurs who do not face any disadvantages in relation to the incumbent monopolist. It assumes the possibility for the firms to freely exit, that is, potential recoupal of all costs incurred upon entering - minus
5400
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
511
depreciation. Also, the potential entrants must have access to equally efficient production technology as employed by the incumbent firm. Finally, the incumbent firm must not be able to adjust prices instantaneously when faced with the threat of entry. As a theoretical construction the theory of contestable market certainly has its merits. Indeed, a natural monopoly firm may not be immune to profitseeking hit and run entry (Faulhaber, 1975; Baumol, Bailey and Willig, 1977; Baumol, Panzar and Willig, 1982; Sharkey, 1982). However, it remains uncertain whether perfectly contestable markets do actually exist. The assumption which holds that an entrant can leave a market without costs when its presence is no longer profitable is rarely encountered in real-life economics (Waterson, 1988). Also, sunk costs, the difference between the ex ante opportunity cost of the funds and the value that could be recovered ex ante, have early on been demonstrated to deter entry (Eaton and Lipsey, 1978; Spence, 1977, 1980; Dixit, 1980). Cost curves reflecting large sunk fixed costs, already borne by the incumbent firm, place potential entrants in a disadvantaged situation. (Bailey and Panzar, 1981).
9. Entry Regulation and Auction Until 1968, the inevitability of regulation of natural monopoly was broadly accepted. It was Demsetz (1968) who argued that formal regulation, as described above, is uncalled-for where government can allow ‘rivalrous competitors’ to bid for the exclusive right to supply a good or service over the given ‘franchise period’. Monopoly pricing is prevented, as competition has asserted itself at the bidding stage. In other words, competition at the franchise stage will be sufficient to reduce the price below that of the monopoly profit maximizer. Therefore, a monopoly structure does not necessarily lead to monopoly behavior. Along the same lines we may situate Chadwick’s (see Crain and Eklund, 1976) historical reasoning in his investigation of water supply in London in the 1850s, where he advocates competition for the market rather than the costly and that time prevalent competition within the market. Successful and competitive bidding, in terms of prices and services offered, could initially eliminate the need for a principal-agent relationship (Chadwick, 1859). In certain cases, government might find it appropriate, most notably in the case of a natural monopoly, to limit the number of firms operating in a certain market. Bidding refers to a free and open right to supply the market, where the regulator announces that it will accept bids from all firms that are willing to provide the goods. Each bid could consist of the price that the firm would agree to charge consumers when awarded the franchise. In such a bidding process,
512
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
5400
price will eventually be bid down to a price at which the winning firm earns zero-profits. This will be the result of a repeated process where firms given the choice between zero profits from not winning the auction, and earning a small but positive profit by bidding below the lowest bid, will choose the latter. Even in the case where the bidding would be held at once, each firm would realize it could only win if it bids at a price that provides zero economic profit with least-cost production. (Coursey, Isaac and Smith, 1984; for a survey on the bidding process in the electricity industry, see Rozek, 1989; in cable television franchise allocation, see Zupan, 1989). This form of bidding, often referred to as Chadwick bidding, should be distinguished from auctions where the state is acting as a monopolist attempting to attain high prices, for instance when auctioning oil exploitation rights, instead of acting as a consumer agent (Posner, 1972; Waterson, 1988). At this point, reference should be made to recent proposals to have the auctions centered around an incentive contract, where the winner is consequentially bound to a desirable incentive arrangement (McAffee and McMillan, 1987; also Riordan and Sappington, 1987). However, the effective pursuit of economic welfare through the competitive awarding of monopoly franchises has its difficulties. Auction theory suggest that the quality of the winning bid only increases as the number of bidders increases (for a different view, see Bishop and Bishop, 1996). As has been demonstrated early on (see Williamson, 1976) in the cable television industry, the winner of a monopoly franchising procedure does not always fulfill the service contract as promised. Here, monitoring costs and the principle-agent problems should be taken into account. Government contracts are often won by bidding in terms that cannot be met (Sherman, 1989), the main reason being that the services are complicated and all eventualities cannot be anticipated fully when contracts are drawn up (see also the debate on the winner’s curse, Thaler, 1992). Also, once a firm has obtained the franchise for a certain period of time with exclusive information on costs, production processes and control over resources, future franchise biddings will be among unequals. Furthermore, it should be noted that costs and demand change over time in such a way that the price fixed in the franchise contract might not be optimal at a later point of time (Williamson, 1976). Contingency clauses, anticipating future events might offer a remedy, but are merely second best solutions, as they are bound to bring about considerable imperfections. Contractual stipulations, which specify the price movement in the event of price changes, demand information from a government which it simply does not have. Another type of contingency clause, the implementation of procedures by which to revise prices periodically, faces the same problem of asymmetry of information, as it provides the regulated firm with incentives to report smaller than real cost changes, for instance from
5400
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
513
technological progress (Train, 1991, p. 301). Reference can be made to the suggestion (Posner, 1992) to have repeated auctions held with short-term contracts for the winning firm. These short-time contracts will allow a better reflection of changes in cost and demand. However, it should be reminded that these auctions will only result in efficient price offerings if the incumbent firm has no other advantages with respect to the other firms involved in the franchise bid. Loeb and Magat (1979) propose an institutional arrangement consisting of a mixing of regulation and franchising, while supposedly eliminating the problems associated with both. As an alternative to rate-of-return regulation, they set forth a decentralized system of regulation in which the utility chooses its own price and where the regulatory agency subsidizes the utility on a per unit basis equal to the consumer surplus at the selected price. The classic opposition to subsidies, that revenues to provide a subsidy have to be collected elsewhere and that any subsidy policy as such brings along allocative inefficiencies, are countered by the introduction of a sale of the franchise which should reduce the net subsidy or, alternatively, the imposition on the utility of a lump-sum tax by the regulatory agency in order to recover part of the subsidy. Sharkey (1979), commenting on the Loeb-Magat (L-M) scheme, argues that such a policy might hold if conditions exist that the net subsidy paid to the utility is sufficiently small. Aside from imperfections of the regulatory bodies and the costs resulting from political manipulation, the L-M scheme is less convincing where one attaches more importance to the quality of service as opposed to the price. Nevertheless, as an alternative to rate of return regulation the L-M model has the advantage that the regulatory body does not need to obtain or verify information about the cost function of the utility and as such it has considerable merit (Sharkey, 1979). Moreover, experimental research on the behavioral robustness of the contestable market hypothesis has shown it to be promising (Coursey, et al., 1984; Harrison and McKee, 1985) especially in environments where the Bertrand-Nash assumption is satisfied (Harrison, 1987).
10. Public Ownership Another possible alternative to regulation is government ownership of enterprises that provide services under conditions of natural monopoly. Although one could argue that regulation occurs in its most severe and complete form under public ownership, its unique characteristics distinguish it from the broad range of traditional regulatory processes (Ogus, 1994). Instead of having a privately owned monopoly with profit-seeking shareholders one could institute a publicly owned enterprise with less concern about profits. This
514
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
5400
lack of profit-maximizing incentives in a public enterprise is sometimes thought to be beneficial, as it allows publicly responsible attention to nonfinancial goals and/or distributional goals (on the various possible reasons for state ownership, Ahoroni, 1986). The institutional framework of public ownership would provide a way to impose public interest prices and standards. This would allow the equation of prices to marginal cost, to have monopoly profits avoided, and so on. Half a century ago, government ownership of firms was thought of as the key solution to market imperfections, such as monopoly. Due to the failures of competition, the regulation during the Great Depression, the apparent success of Soviet industrialization and a misunderstanding of the consequences of political control over firms, the state took control of significant parts of production in the economy of many countries. In the last 29 years, a renewed faith in the market process induced governments in market economies throughout the world to privatize most of their sectors, including strategic ones such as steel, energy and telecommunications. The absence of a profit incentive under the institutional framework of public ownership had proven to be a high price to pay. In a public enterprise which lacks a group of residual profit-claiming shareholders, who emphasize fiscal goals and enforce efficient performance through management, economic efficiency is no longer guaranteed (Spann, 1977; Williamson, 1987; for a survey of economic performance under public ownership in the British fuel and power industry see Shepard, 1965). When assets are publicly owned, the public manager has relatively weak incentives to reduce costs or to improve quality or innovate, because he only gets a fraction of the return as a non-owner (Hart, Shleifer and Vishny, 1997; more on public managers, De Alessi, 1974, 1980). In private corporations, the shareholders’ ability to sell their vote or to vote out management creates incentives for management to serve the interests of the owner. The diffuse, non-transferable shareholding that characterizes government ownership reduces these incentives. Those in control of the enterprise pay less attention to the taxpaying shareholders and are more likely to succumb to more concentrated interest groups, such as suppliers, consumers, employees, and so on (Zeckhauser and Horer, 1989). The statutory monopoly will become the primary source of information about industry possibilities. The monopoly will not suffer as a competitive firm would when it is wrong, because regulators either cannot appreciate its errors completely or will forgive them. Regulatory agencies, distanced from the industry, might have a hard time to reflect the complexity of the industry. As regulators cannot evaluate all decisions, inefficient technologies may be chosen for years (Sherman, 1989).
5400
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
515
Also, the question remains what goals replace the profit incentive? Imposition of vague goals often results in diminished accountability which imposes the risk of inefficient results. Moreover, it should be noted that the absence of a profit incentive does not guarantee the absence of monopoly prices; these remain a possibility, for instance to make the life of managers easier, and so on. A public enterprise is often constrained by its budget. As it is required only to have a certain difference between total revenue and total costs, it may, especially when no stronger restrictions have been set out, seek to maximize its total expenditures or its revenue. In order to do this it may well follow a monopoly pricing rule. The US Postal Service can serve as an example of a public enterprise (since its 1970 charter) exhibiting such behavior, empirical evidence shows it has behaved as a cost or revenue maximizer for many years (Sherman, 1989, pp. 265-268). A publicly-owned firm with limited restrictions such as budget constraint has considerable managerial discretion, which often leads to the pursuit of various goals such as budget maximization (Niskanen, 1971; Crew and Kleindorfer, 1979), revenue maximization (Baumol, 1976) and the maximization of total output. The importance of innovation in market economies should not be disregarded. Voices as early as Marshall (1907), have argued that government is generally a poor innovator. The development and adoption of new technologies in telecommunications, that occurred shortly after the privatization of phone companies in the US, may serve as an example of the benefits of private ownership (Winston, 1998). In industries where innovation is crucial, the case for government provision is strained (Shleifer, 1998). Technology changes often have enormous impact on cost structures and may cause a natural monopoly market to move to a more competitive setting.
Selected Bibliography on Regulation of Natural Monopoly (5400) Abdel Khalik, A. Rashad (1988), ‘Incentives for Accruing Costs and Efficiency in Regulated Monopolies Subject to ROE Constraint’, 26 Journal of Accounting Research, 144-174. Adams, G. and Yellen, Janet L (1976), ‘Commodity Bundling and the Burden of Monopoly’, 60 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 475-98. Adie, Douglas K. (1985), ‘Abolishing the Postal Monopoly: A Comment’, 5 Cato Journal, 657-661. Ahoroni (1986), The Evaluation and Management of State-Owned Enterprises, Cambridge, MA, Ballinger Publishing Company. Albon, Robert P. (1988), ‘The Welfare Costs of the Australian Telecommunications Pricing Structure’, 64 Economic Record, 102-112. Antic Slavoljub (1994), ‘Alternativni Pristup Regulaciji Elektroprivrede (An Alternative Approach to
516
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
5400
the Electricity Sector Regulation)’, 3-4 Ekonomist, 197-204. Armstrong, Christopher and Nellis, Henry Vivian (1986),Monopoly’s Moment: The Organization and Regulation, Toronto, University of Toronto Press, 393 p. Atkinson, Scott E. and Halvorsen, Robert (1990), ‘Tests of Allocative Efficiency in Regulated Multi-product Firms’, 12(1) Resources and Energy, 65-77. Atkinson, Scott E. and Kerkvliet, Joe (1989), ‘Dual Measures of Monopoly and Monopsony Power: An Application to Regulated Electric Utilities’, 71 Review of Economics and Statistics, 250-257. Babilot, George, Frantz, Roger and Green, Louis (1987), ‘Natural Monopolies and Rent: A Georgist Remedy for X Inefficiency among Publicly Regulated Firms’, 46 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 205-217. Baca, Alvin (1987), ‘FERC $50 ERA: Issues in Natural Gas Regulation’, 27 Natural Resources Journal, 815-822. Bailey, Elisabeth E. (1973),Economic Theory of Regulatory Constraint, Lexington, MA, D.C. Health. Bailey, Elisabeth E. and Panzar John C. (1981), ‘The Contestabilty of Airline Markets, during the Transition to Deregulation’, 44 Law and Contemporary Problems, 125 ff. Baish, Richard O. (1987), ‘The Role of the California Public Utilities Commission in Western Gas’, 27 Natural Resources Journal, 805-810. Baldwin, John R. (1989), Regulatory Failure and Renewal: The Evolution of the Natural Monopoly Contract , Ottawa, Supply and Services Canada, 122 p. Barnes, David W. and Stout, Lynn A. (1992), Economic Foundations of Regulation and Antitrust Law, St Paul, MN, West Publishing. Baron, David P. and Besanko, David A. (1984a), ‘Regulation and Information in a Continuing Relationship’, 1(3) Information Economics and Policy, 267-302. Baron, David P. and Besanko, David A. (1984b), ‘Regulation, Asymmetric Information, and Auditing’, 15 Rand Journal of Economics, 447-470. Baumol, William J. (1967), ‘Reasonable Rules for Rate Regulation: Plausible Policies for an Imperfect World’, in Phillips A. and Williamsen O.E. (eds), Prices: Issues in Theory, Practice, and Public Policy, Philadelphia, University of Pennysylvania Press. Baumol, William J. (1976), Business Behaviour, Value and Growth, NY, Harcourt, Brace and World. Baumol, William J. (1977), ‘On the Proper Cost Tests for Natural Monopoly in a Multiproduct Industry’, 809 American Economic Review. Baumol, William J. (1982),’Contestable Markets: An Uprising in the Theory of Industry Structure’, 72 American Economic Review, 1982, 1-15. Baumol, W.J., Bailey, Elisabeth E. and Willig, R.D. (1977), ‘Weak Invisable Hand Theorems on Pricing and Entry in a Multiproduct Natural Monopoly’, 67 American Economic Review, 350365. Baumol, William J., Panzar, J. and Willig Robert (1982), Contestable Markets and the Theory of Industry Structure, New York, Harcourt Brace. Beesley, Michael E. (1997), Privatization, Regulation and Deregulation, London, New York, Routledge. Beesley, Michael E. and Littlechild, Stephen C. (1989), ‘The Regulation of Privatized Monopolies in the United Kingdom’, 20 Rand Journal of Economics, 454-472.
5400
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
517
Berg, Sanford V. and Tschirhart, John (1988), Natural Monopoly Regulation: Principles and Practice, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 564 p. Bernard, Jean Thomas and Cairns, Robert D. (1987), ‘On Public Utility Pricing and Forgone Economic Benefits’, 20 Canadian Journal of Economics, 152-163. Berry, S. Keith (1987a), ‘The Ratepayer and the Stockholder under Alternative Regulatory Policies: Comment’, 63 Land Economics, 201-205. Berry, S. Keith (1987b), ‘Rate of Return Regulation and Demand Uncertainty with a Symmetric Regulatory Constraint’, 31(2) American Economist, 8-12. Berry, S. Keith (1988), ‘The Allocation of Risk between Stockholders and Ratepayers in Regulated Utilities’, 64 Land Economics, 114-124. Besen, Stanley M. (1974), ‘The Economics of the Cable Television “Consensus”’, 17 Journal of Law and Economics, 39-51. Bishop, B. and Bishop, S. (1996), ‘When Two is Enough: Competition in Bidding Markets’, 1 European Competition Law Review, 3-6. Blackstone, Erwin A. and Fuhr, Joseph P., Jr (1989), ‘The Economics of Public Utility Regulation: Review Article’, 17(2) Atlantic Economic Journal, 68-73. Bold, Frederick C. (1987), ‘Responses to Energy Efficiency Regulations’, 8 Energy Journal, 111-123. Bowman, Ward S. (1966), ‘The New Haven, A Passenger Railroad for Nonriders’, 9 Journal of Law and Economics, 49-59. Boyes, William J. and McDowell, John M. (1989), ‘The Selection of Public Utility Commissioners: A Reexamination of the Importance of Institutional Setting’, 61 Public Choice, 1-13. Bradley, J.F. (1981), ‘Antitrust Policy under Regulation: Airline Mergers and the Theory of Contestable Markets’, 61 Boston University Law Review, 823 ff. Bradley, Ian and Price, Catherine Waddams (1991), ‘Partial and Mixed Regulations of Newly Privatized U.K. Monopolies’, in Weigel, Wolfgang (ed), Economic Analysis of Law - A Collection of Applications, Vienna, Österreichischer Wirtschaftsverlag, 212-220. Braeutigam, Ronald R. (1990), ‘Regulatory Reform: Lessons for Natural Gas Pipelines’, 8 Contemporary Policy Issues, 122-141. Braeutigam, Ronald R. and Hubbard, R. Glenn (1986), ‘Natural Gas: The Regulatory Transition’, in Weiss, Leonard W. and Klass, Michael W. (ed), Regulatory Reform: What Actually Happened, Boston, Little Brown, 137-168. Braeutigam, Ronald R. and Panzar, John C. (1989), ‘Diversification Incentives Under “Price-Based” and “Cost-Based” Regulation’, 20 Rand Journal of Economics, 373-391. Brennan, Timothy J. (1991), ‘Cross-Subsidization and Cost Misallocation by Regulated Monopolists’, 2 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 37-51. Broadman, Harry G. (1986), ‘Natural Gas Deregulation: The Need for Further Reform’, 5 Journal of Policy Analysis and Management, 496-516. Broadman, Harry G. and Kalt, Joseph P. (1989), ‘How Natural is Monopoly? The Case of Bypass in Natural Gas Distribution Markets’, 6 Yale Journal on Regulation, 181-208. Brown, Donald J. and Heal, Geoffrey M. (1987), ‘Ramsey Pricing in Telecommunications Markets with Free Entry’, in Crew, Michael A. (ed), Regulating Utilities in an Era of Deregulation, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 77-83. Brown, Lorenzo (1988), ‘Modelling Diversified Utilities and Cross Subsidization’, 10 Resources and
518
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
5400
Energy, 213-224. Buell, Stephen, G. and Guerard, John B., Jr (1985), ‘An Econometric Analysis of the Formal Regulatory Process’, in Brown, Roy Chamberlain (ed), Quantity and Quality in Economic Research, Lanham, University Press of America, Volume 1, 15-38. Bulcke, J. (1987), ‘Industrie en energie: 3. Electriciteit (Industry and Energy: Electricity)’, in X (ed), 18de Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Brussel 8 en 9 mei 1987, Sociaal-economische Deregulering, Brussel, V.E.H.U.B., 421-440. Bunn, Derek and Vlahos, Kiriakos (1989), ‘Evaluation of the Long-term Effects on UK Electricity Prices following Privatisation’, 10(4) Fiscal Studies, 104-116. Caillaud, Bernard (1990), ‘Regulation, Competition, and Asymmetric Information’, 52 Journal of Economic Theory, 87-110. Chadwick, Sir Edwin (1859), ‘Results of Different Principles of Legislation and Administration in Europe: Competition for the Field, as Compared with Competition Within the Field of Service’, 22 Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, 384-420. Chen, Andrew H. and Sanger, Gary C. (1985), ‘An Analysis of the Impact of Regulatory Change: The Case of Natural Gas Deregulation’, 20(1) Financial Review, 36-54. Chen, Paul (1990), ‘Prices vs. Quantities and Delegating Price Authority to a Monopolist’, 57 Review of Economic Studies, 521-529. Coase, Ronald H. (1961), ‘The British Post Office and the Messenger Companies’, 4 Journal of Law and Economics, 12-65. Coase, Ronald H. (1962), ‘The Interdepartment Radio Advisory Committee’, 5 Journal of Law and Economics, 17-47. Coase, Ronald H. (1970), ‘The Auction System and North Sea Gas: A Comment’, 13 Journal of Law and Economics, 45-47. Comanor, William S. and Mitchell, Bridger M. (1972), ‘The Costs of Planning: The FCC and Cable Television’, 15 Journal of Law and Economics, 177-206. Costello, Kenneth W. (1988), ‘The Struggle Over Electricity Transmission Access’, 8 Cato Journal, 107-124. Costello, Kenneth W. and Hemphill, Ross C. (1990), ‘Competitive Pricing in the Electric Industry’, 12(1) Resources and Energy, 49-63. Cote, Daniel O. (1989), ‘Firm Efficiency and Ownership Structure: The Case of U.S. Electric Utilities Using Panel Data’, 60 Annals of Public and Cooperative Economy, 431-450. Coursey, Don L., Isaac, R. Mark and Smith, Vernon L. (1984), ‘Natural Monopoly and Contested Markets: Some Experimental Results’, 27 Journal of Law and Economics, 91-113. Coursey, Don L., Isaac, R. Mark, Luke, M. and Smith, V.L.(1984), ‘Market Contestability in the Presence of Sunk (Entry) Costs’, 15 Rand Journal of Economics, 69-84. Cox, James C. and Isaac, R. Mark (1987), ‘Mechanisms for Incentive Regulation: Theory and Experiment’, 18 Rand Journal of Economics, 348-359. Crain, W. Mark and Ekelund, Robert B., Jr (1976), ‘Chadwick and Demsetz on Competition and Regulation’, 19 Journal of Law and Economics, 149-162. Crandall, Robert W. (1988), ‘Surprises from Telephone Deregulation and the AT&T; Divestiture’, 78 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 323-327. Crew, Michael A. (ed) (1985), Analyzing the Impact of Regulatory Change in Public Utilities, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books.
5400
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
519
Crew, Michael A. (ed) (1987), Regulating Utilities in an Era of Deregulation, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 201 p. Crew, Michael A. (ed) (1989), Deregulation and Diversification of Utilities, Dordrecht, Kluwer, 206 p. Crew, Michael A. (ed) (1991), Competition and the Regulation of Utilities, Dordrecht, Kluwer, 224 p. Crew M.A. and Kleindorfer, P.R. (1979), ‘Managerial Discretion and Public Utility Regulation, 84 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 236-53. Crew, Michael A. and Kleindorfer, Paul R. (1985a), ‘Governance Costs of Rate of Return Regulation’, 141 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 104-123. Crew, Michael A. and Kleindorfer, Paul R. (1985b), ‘Governance Structures for Natural Monopoly: A Comparative Institutional Assessment’, 14 Journal of Behavioral Economics, 117-140. Crew, Michael A. and Kleindorfer, Paul R. (1986), The Economics of Public Utility Regulation, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 304 p. Crew, Michael A. and Kleindorfer, Paul R. (1987), ‘Productivity Incentives and Rate-of-Return Regulation’, in Crew, Michael A. (ed), Regulating Utilities in an Era of Deregulation, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 7-23. Crew, Michael A. and Rowley, Charles K. (1988), ‘Toward a Public Choice Theory of Monopoly Regulation’, 57 Public Choice, 49-67. Crew, Michael A., Kleindorfer, Paul R. and Schlenger, Donald L. (1987), ‘Governance Costs of Regulation for Water Supply’, in Crew, Michael A. (ed), Regulating Utilities in an Era of Deregulation, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 43-62. Crew M.A., Fernando Chitru S. and Kleindorfer, P.R (1995), ‘The Theory of Peak-Load Pricing: A Survey’, 8 Journal of Regulating Economics, 215-248. Crockett, J.H., Jr (1976), ‘Differential Pricing and Inter-consumer Efficiency in the Electric Power Industry’, 7 Bell Journal of Economics, 293-298. Culbertson, William Patton, Jr (1977), ‘A Redistributive Effect of Natural Gas Price Regulation’, 16(4) Nebraska Journal of Economics and Business, 91-95. Cummings, F.J. and Ruchter, W.E. (1979), ‘The Northern Pacific Case’, 22 Journal of Law and Economics, 329-50. Dam, Kenneth W. (1965), ‘Oil and Gas Licensing and the North Sea’, 8 Journal of Law and Economics, 51-75. Dam, Kenneth W. (1970), ‘The Pricing of North Sea Gas in Britain’, 13 Journal of Law and Economics, 11-44. Dam, Kenneth W. (1971), ‘Implementation of Import Quotas: The Case of Oil’, 14 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-60. Dam, Kenneth W. (1974), ‘The Evolution of North Sea Licensing Policy in Britain and Norway’, 17 Journal of Law and Economics, 213-263. Dana, James D., Jr and Spier, Kathryn E. (1994), ‘Designing a Private Industry: Government Auctions with Endogenous Market Structure’, 53 Journal of Public Economics, 127-147. Danielsen, Albert L., Kamerschen, David R. and Keenan, Donald C. (1990), ‘Third Best Pricing Rules for Regulated Utilities’, 56 Southern Economic Journal, 628-638. De Alessi, Louis (1983), ‘Private Ownership and Limits to Retroactive Regulation of Utility Rates’,
520
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
5400
37 University of Miami Law Review, 433 ff. Debrock, Lawrence M. and Smith, J.L. (1983), ‘Joint Bidding, Information Pooling, and the Performance of Petroleum Lease Auctions’, 14 Bell Journal of Economics, 395-404. Delaney, J.B. and Honeycutt, T.C. (1976), ‘Determinants of Research and Development Activity by Electric Utilities: Comment’, 7 Bell Journal of Economics, 722-725. Della Valle, Anna P. (1988), ‘Short-run versus Long-run Marginal Cost Pricing’, 10 Energy Economics, 283-286. Demsetz, Harold (1968), ‘Why Regulate Utilities’, 11 Journal of Law and Economics, 55-65. Dewey, Donald (1959), Monopoly in Economics and Law, Chicago, Rand McNally, 328p. Doppegieter, J.J., Hamman, W.D. and Lambrechts, I.J. (1989), ‘Tariff Policies for Public Utilities: The Accounting Cost Approach’, 13(2) Journal for Studies in Economics and Econometrics, 49-57. Dixit, Avinash, (1980), ‘The Role of Investment in Entry-Deterrence’, 90 The Economic Journal, 95-106. Dreyfus, Daniel A. (1989), ‘Deregulation of Utilities: The Natural Gas Experience’, 24(2) Business Economics, 41-47. Eaton, B. Curtis and Lipsey, Richard G. (1978), ‘Freedom of Entry and the Existence of Pure Profit’, 88 The Economic Journal, p. 455-469. Eckel, Catherine C. (1987), ‘Customer Class Price Discrimination by Electric Utilities’, 39 Journal of Economics and Business, 19-33. Einhorn, Michael A. (1987), ‘Optimality and Sustainability: Regulation and Intermodal Competition in Telecommunications’, 18 Rand Journal of Economics, 550-563. Etzioni, Amitai (1986), ‘Does Regulation Reduce Electricity Rates? A Research Note’, 19(4) Policy Sciences, 349-357. Evans, Lewis and Garber, Steven (1988), ‘Public-Utility Regulators are only Human: A Positive Theory of Rational Constraints’, 78 American Economic Review, 444-462. Fabella, Raul V. (1989), ‘Monopoly Deregulation in the Presence of Tullock Activities’, 62 Public Choice, 287-293. Fanara, Philip, Jr and Sweet, David M. (1984), ‘What do Regulated Firms Maximize? Some Empirical Evidence from the Natural Gas Pipeline Industry’, 28(1) American Economist, 44-48. Fare, Rolf and Logan, James (1986), ‘Regulation, Scale and Productivity: A Comment’, 27 International Economic Review, 777-781. Fare, Rolf, Grosskopf, Shawna and Logan, James (1985), ‘The Relative Performance of Publicly Owned and Privately Owned Electric Utilities’, 26 Journal of Public Economics, 89-106. Faulhaber, G. (1975), ‘Cross-Susidization: Pricing in Public Enterprises’, 65 American Economic Review, 327-49. Fellner, William (1951), ‘The Influence of Market Structure on Technological Progress’, 65(4) The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 556-577. Ferris, Stephen P., Johnson, Dana J. and Shome, Dilip K. (1986), ‘Regulatory Environment and Market Response to Public Utility Rate Decisions’, 9 Journal of Financial Research, 313-318. Finsinger, Jörg and Vogelsang, Ingo (1981), ‘Alternative Institutional Frameworks for Price Incentive
5400
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
521
Mechanisms’, 34 Kyklos, 388-404. Fitzpatrick, Dennis B., Settle, John W. and Petry, Glenn H. (1988), ‘An Empirical Examination of Rate of Return Regulation in the Electric Utility Industry: 1971-1982'’, 40 Journal of Economics and Business, 27-44. Foreman Peck, J.S. (1987), ‘Natural Monopoly and Railway Policy in the Nineteenth Century’, 39 Oxford Economic Papers, 699-718. Fox, William F. and Hofler, Richard A. (1986), ‘Using Homothetic Composed Error Frontiers to Measure Water Utility Efficiency’, 53 Southern Economic Journal, 461-477. Fox-Penner, Peter S. (1990a), ‘Regulating Independent Power Producers: Lessons of the PURPA Approach’, 12(1) Resources and Energy, 117-141. Fox-Penner, Peter S. (1990b), ‘Cogeneration after PURPA: Energy Conservation and Industry Structure’, 33 Journal of Law and Economics, 517-552. Frech, H. Edward III and Decanio, Stephen J. (1993), ‘Vertical Contracts: A Natural Experiment in Gas Pipeline Regulation’, 149 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 370-392. Freeman, S. David (1986), ‘Electric Utility Conservation Programs: Progress and Problems: Comments’, in Sawhill, John C. and Cotton, Richard (eds), Energy Conservation: Successes and Failures, Washington, Brookings Institution, 160-162. Fuhr, Joseph P., Jr (1990), ‘Vertical Integration and Regulation in the Electric Utility Industry’, 24 Journal of Economic Issues, 173-187. Gathon, Henry Jean (1988), ‘La Distribution de l’Eau en Belgique: Prix, Coût et Efficacité (The Distribution of Water in Belgium: Price, Cost and Efficiency)’, 0(119) Cahiers Economiques de Bruxelles, 371-384. Geddes, R. Richard and Griffes, Peter H. (1990), ‘The Electric Utility Industry: New Challenges and Old Questions’, 12 Resources and Energy, 1-15. Gegax, Douglas and Nowotny, Kenneth (1993), ‘Competition and the Electric Utility Industry: An Evaluation’, 10(1) Yale Journal on Regulation, 63-87. Georgantzis, Nikolaos (1992), The Social Aspects of Telecommunications: Targeted Subsidies as a Means to Achieve Universal Basic Services, Report for the A-3 Unit (Economic Questions and Studies) of DG IV (Competition) of the European Comission. Gerber, David J. (1988), ‘Rethinking the Monopolist’s Duty to Deal: A Legal and Economic Critique of the Doctrine of “Essential Facilities”’, 74 Virginia Law Review, 1069-1113. Gerwig, Robert W. (1962), ‘Natural Gas Production: A Study of Costs of Regulation’, 5 Journal of Law and Economics, 69-92. Gilligan, Thomas W., Marshall, William J. and Weingast, Barry R. (1989), ‘Regulation and the Theory of Legislative Choice: The Interstate Commerce Act of 1887', 32 Journal of Law and Economics, 35-61. Goldberg, Victor P. (1971), ‘Marginal Cost Pricing, Investment Theory and CATV: Comment’, 14 Journal of Law and Economics, 513-516. Goldberg, Victor P. (1979), ‘Protecting the Right to be Served by Public Utilities’, 1 Research in Law and Economics, 145-156. Golec, Joseph (1990), ‘The Financial Effects of Fuel Adjustment Clauses on Electric Utilities’, 63 Journal of Business, 165-186. Gordon, Richard L. (1990), ‘Timidity in Electric Utility Deregulation’, 12(1) Resources and Energy, 17-32.
522
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
5400
Gormley, William, Hoadley, John and Williams, Charles (1983), ‘Potential Responsiveness in the Bureaucracy: Views of Public Utility Regulation’, 77 American Political Science Review, 704-717. Gort, Michael and Wall, Richard A. (1988), ‘Foresight and Public Utility Regulation’, 96 Journal of Political Economy, 177-188. Grandy, Christopher (1989), ‘Can Government be Trusted to Keep its Part of a Social Contract?: New Jersey and the Railroads’, 1825-1888, 5 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 249-269. Greenberg, Edward (1967), ‘Wire Television and the FCC’s Second Report and Order on CATV Systems’, 10 Journal of Law and Economics, 181-192. Griffin, James M. and Mayor, Thomas H. (1987), ‘The Welfare Gain from Efficient Pricing of Local Telephone Services’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 465-487. Hahn, Robert W. and Hird, John A. (1991), ‘The Costs and Benefits of Regulation: Review and Synthesis’, 8 Yale Journal on Regulation, 233-278. Harrison, G.W. (1987), ‘Experimental Evaluation of the Contestable Market Hypothesis’, in Bailey, E. (ed), Public Regulation, Cambridge, MA , MIT Press, 403p, 191-121. Harrison, G.W. and McKee, M. (1985), ‘Monopoly Behaviour, Decentralised Regulation and Contestable Markets: an Experimental Evaluation’, 16 Rand Journal of Economics, 51-69. Hart, Oliver, Shleifer, Andrei and Vishny, Robert W. (1997), ‘The Proper Scope of Government: Theory and Apllication to Prisons’, 112(4) Quarterly Journal of Economics, 1127-1161. Hartley, Peter and Trengove, Chris (1986), ‘Who Benefits from Public Utilities?’, 62 Economic Record, 163-179. Hayashi, Paul M., Sevier, Melanie and Trapani, John M. (1987), ‘An Analysis of Pricing and Production Efficiency of Electric Utilities by Mode of Ownership’, in Crew, Michael A. (ed), Regulating Utilities in an Era of Deregulation, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 111-136. Hazlett, Thomas W. (1986), ‘Private Monopoly and the Public Interest: An Economic Analysis of the Cable Television Franchise’, 134 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1335-1409. Hazlett, Thomas W. (1988), ‘Wiring the Constitution for Cable’, 12(1) Regulation, 30-34. Hazlett, Thomas W. (1990), ‘Duopolistic Competition in Cable Television: Implications for Public Policy’, 7 Yale Journal on Regulation, 65-119. Hazlett, Thomas W. (1995), ‘Predation in Local Cable TV Markets’, 40 Antitrust Bulletin, 609-644. Helbling, Hans H. and Turley, James E. (1975), ‘Oil Price Controls: A Counterproductive Effort’, 57(11) Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis Review, 2-6. Helm, Dieter (1988), ‘Regulating the Electricity Supply Industry’, 9(3) Fiscal Studies, 86-105. Henderson, J. Stephen (1986), ‘The Effect of Regulation on Nonuniform Electricity Price Schedules in the United States’, 29 Journal of Public Economics, 317-332. Hendricks, Walter (1975), ‘The Effect of Regulation on Collective Bargaining in Electric Utilities’, 6 Bell Journal of Economics, 451-465. Hillman, Jordan Jay and Braeutigam, Ronald R. (1989), Price Leval Regulation for Diversified Public Utilities: An Assessment, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 141p.
5400
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
523
Hilton, George W. (1966), ‘The Consistency of the Interstate Commerce Act’, 9 Journal of Law and Economics, 87-113. Hollas, Daniel R. and Friedland, Thomas S. (1980), ‘Price Discrimination in the Municipal Electric Industry’, 2 Research in Law and Economics, 181-198. Hollas, Daniel R. and Stansell, Stanley R. (1988a), ‘Regulation, Interfirm Rivalry, and the Economic Efficiency of Natural Gas Distribution Facilities’, 28(4) Quarterly Review of Economics and Business, 21-37. Hollas, Daniel R. and Stansell, Stanley R. (1988b), ‘An Examination of the Effect of Ownership Form on Price Efficiency: Proprietary, Cooperative and Municipal Electric Utilities’, 55(2) Southern Economic Journal, 336-350. Hotelling, Harold (1938), ‘The General Welfare in Relation to Problems of Taxation and Railway and Utility Rates’, 6 Econometrica, 242-269. Hovenkamp, Herbert J. (1988), ‘Regulatory Conflict in the Gilded Age: Federalism and the Railroad Problem’, 97 Yale Law Journal, 1017-1072. Huettner, David A. (1987), ‘The Effect of the Public Utility Regulatory Policy Act on the Electric Utility Industry’, in Pachauri, R.K. (ed), Global Energy Interactions, Riverdale, 189-203. Hughes, Joseph P. (1990), ‘Profit Maximizing Input Demand under Rate of Return Regulation: Pathological Substitution and Output Effects’, 12 Resources and Energy, 79-95. Isaac, R. Mark (1980), ‘Petroleum Price Controls when Information is a Joint Product’, 56 Land Economics, 181-187. Jacobson, Charles (1989), ‘Same Game, Different Players: Problems in Urban Public Utility Regulation, 1850-1987’, 26 Urban Studies, 13-31. Jarrell, Gregg A. (1978), ‘The Demand for State Regulation of the Electric Utility Industry’, 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 269-295. Jewkes, John (1958), ‘British Monopoly Policy 1944-56’, 1 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-19. Jones, Douglas N. (1988), ‘Regulatory Concepts, Propositions, and Doctrines: Casualties and Survivors’, 22 Journal of Economic Issues, 108-190. Jones, L.R. and Thompson, Frederick (1984), ‘Incremental vs. Comprehensive Reform of Economic Regulation: Predictable Outcomes and Unintended Consequences’, 43 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 1-17. Jordan, William A. (1972), ‘Producer Protection, Prior Market Structure and the Effects of Government Regulation’, 15 Journal of Law and Economics, 151-176. Jorgenson, Dale W. and Slesnick, Daniel T. (1987), ‘General Equilibrium Analysis of Natural Gas Price Regulation’, in Bailey, Elizabeth E. (ed), Public Regulation: New Perspectives on Institutions and Policies. MIT Press Series on the Regulation of Economic Activity, no. 14, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 153-190. Joskow, Paul L. (1974), ‘Inflation and Environmental Concern: Structural Change in the Process of Public Utility Price Regulation’, 17 Journal of Law and Economics, 291-327. Joskow, Paul L. and Schmalensee, Richard L. (1983), Markets for Power: An Analysis of Electric Utility, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 269 p. Jurewitz, John L. (1988), ‘Deregulation of Electricity: A View from Utility Management’, 6(3)
524
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
5400
Contemporary Policy Issues, 25-241. Kaplow, Louis (1993), ‘An Ex Ante Perspective on Deregulation, Viewed Ex Post’, 15(2) Resource and Energy Economics, 153-173. Kaufer, Erich (1985), ‘The Transaction Costs of Rate of Return Regulation: Comment’, 141 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 124-126. Kearl, J.R. (1983), ‘Rules, Rule Intermediaries and the Complexity and Stability of Regulation’, 22 Journal of Public Economics, 215-226. Kelly, Kevin et al. (1987), Some Economic Principles for Pricing Wheeled Power, Columbus, National Regulatory Research Institute, 361 p. Kelly, Suedeen G. (1987), ‘Regulatory Reform of the U.S. Natural Gas Industry: A Summing Up’, 27 Natural Resources Journal, 841-863. Kendrick, J.W. (1975), ‘Efficiency Incentives and Cost Factors in Public Utility Automatic Revenue Adjustment Clauses’, 6(1) Bell Journal of Economics, 299-313. Keshava, G.P. (1986), ‘A Review of the Theory of Electricity Pricing’, 34(2) Indian Economic Journal, 71-86. Kim, Jae Cheol and Ahn, Byong Hun (1990), ‘On the Economics of Cogeneration: Pricing and Efficiency in Government Owned Utilities’, 11 Energy Journal, 87-99. Kitch, Edmund W. (1968), ‘Regulation of the Field Market for Natural Gas by the Federal Power Commission’, 11 Journal of Law and Economics, 243-280. Kitch, Edmund W. (1972), ‘The Yellow Cab Antitrust Case’, 15 Journal of Law and Economics, 327-336. Kitch, Edmund W., Isaacson, Marc and Kasper, Daniel (1972), ‘The Regulation of Taxicabs in Chicago’, 14 Journal of Law and Economics, 285-350. Reprinted in Brookings Institute Reprint No. 255, 1972. Kling, Robert W. (1989), ‘General Equilibrium Effects of Regulation’, 33(2) American Economist, 53-59. Koller, Roland H. II (1973), ‘Why Regulate Utilities? To Control Price Discrimination’, 16 Journal of Law and Economics, 191-192. Kryzanowski, Lawrence and Jalilvand, Abolhassan (1986), ‘Statistical Tests of the Accuracy of Alternative Forecasts: Some Results for U.S. Utility Betas’, 21 Financial Review, 319-335. Laber, Gene (1988), ‘Regulators’ Decisions on Rates of Return: Recent Experience in the Telephone Industry’, 27(2) Quarterly Journal of Business and Economics, 3-22. Laffont, Jean-Jacques and Tirole, Jean (1986), ‘Using Cost Observation to Regulate Firms’,94 Journal of Political Economy, 614-641. Leland, H.E. and Meyer, R.A. (1976), ‘Monopoly Pricing Structures with Imperfect Information’, 7 Bell Journal of Economics, 449-62. Lerner, Abba P. (1964), ‘Conflicting Principles of Public Utility Price Regulation’, 7 Journal of Law and Economics, 61-70. Lesser, Jonathan A. (1989), ‘The Economics of Preference Power’, 12 Research in Law and Economics, 131-151. Lewis, Tracy R. and Sappington, David E.M. (1988), ‘Regulating a Monopolist with Unknown Demand and Cost Functions’, 19 Rand Journal of Economics, 438-457. Lewis, Tracy R. and Sappington, David E.M. (1988), ‘Regulating a Monopolist with Unknown Demand’, 78 American Economic Review, 986-998.
5400
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
525
Lewis, Tracy R. and Sappington, David E.M. (1989), ‘Regulatory Options and Price-Cap Regulation’, 20 Rand Journal of Economics, 405-416. Lipartito, Kenneth (1989), ‘System Building at the Margin: The Problem of Public Choice in the Telephone Industry’, 49 Journal of Economic History, 323-336. Littlechild S. and Beesley M. (1992), ‘The Regulation of Privatized Monopolies in the United Kingdom’, in Beesley, M., Privatization, Regulation and Deregulation, chapter 4, London and New York, Routledge. Loeb, Martin and Magat, Wesley A. (1979), ‘A Decentralized Method for Utility Regulation’, 22 Journal of Law and Economics, 399-404. Logan, John W., Masson, Robert T. and Reynolds, Robert J. (1989), ‘Efficient Regulation with Little Information: Reality in the Limit?’, 30 International Economic Review, 851-861. Lyon, Thomas P. (1990), ‘Natural Gas Policy: The Unresolved Issues’, 11(2) Energy Journal, 23-49. Macavoy, Paul W. (1971), ‘The Regulation-Induced Shortage of Natural Gas’, 14 Journal of Law and Economics, 167-199. Macavoy, Paul W., Spulber, Daniel F. and Stangle, Bruce E. (1989), ‘Is Competitive Entry Free? Bypass and Partial Deregulation in Natural Gas Markets’, 6 Yale Journal on Regulation, 209-247. Magat, Wesley A. (1976), ‘Regulation and the Rate and Direction of Induced Technical Change’, 7 Bell Journal of Economics, 478-496. Makhija, Anil K. and Spiro, Michael H. (1989), ‘Determinants of Earned Rates of Return on Equity of U.S. Electric Utilities, 1976-1984’, 30 Economic Letters, 367-371. Maloney, Michael T., McCormick, Robert E. and Tollison, Robert D. (1984), ‘Economic Regulation, Competitive Governments, and Specialised Resources’, 27 Journal of Law and Economics, 329-338. Mann, Patrick C. (1974), ‘User Power and Electricity Rates’, 17 Journal of Law and Economics, 433-443. Mann, Patrick C. (1979), ‘The Dynamics of Traditional Rate Regulation’, 1 Research in Law and Economics, 195-212. Marshall, Alfred (1907), ‘The Social Possibilities of Economic Chivalry’, 17 Economic Journal, 7-21. Marx, Jane (1986), ‘Regulation of Electric Utilities and Affiliated Coal Companies Determining Reasonable Expenses: Comment’, 26 Natural Resources Journal, 851-869. Mathios, Alan D. and Rogers, Robert P. (1989), ‘The Impact of Alternative Forms of State Regulation of AT&T; on Direct-Dial, Long-Distance Telephone Rates’, 20 Rand Journal of Economics, 437-453. Mayer, Robert N., Zick, Cathleen D. and Burton, John R. (1989), ‘Consumer Representation and Local Telephone Rates’, 23 Journal of Consumer Affairs, 267-284. Mayo, John W. and Flynn, Joseph E. (1988), ‘The Effects of Regulation on Research and Development: Theory and Evidence’, 61 Journal of Business, 321-336. McAffee, R.P. and McMillan, J. (1987), ‘Competition for Agency Contract’, 18 Rand Journal of Economics, 296-307. McConnell, Michael W. (1988), ‘Public Utilities’ Private Rights: Paying for Failed Nuclear Power’, 12(2) Regulation, 35-43.
526
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
5400
McGee, John S. (1958), ‘Predatory Price Cutting: The Standard Oil (N.J.) Case’, 1 Journal of Law and Economics, 137-169. McNicol, David L. (1979), ‘Price Discrimination and Peak-load Pricing Subject to Rate of Return Constraint’, 1 Research in Law and Economics, 213-238. Megdal, Sharon B. (1989), ‘On Regulation, Deregulation, and Economics’, 10(3) Energy Journal, 181-195. Melody, William H. (1989), ‘Efficiency and Social Policy in Telecommunication: Lessons from the U.S. Experience’, 23 Journal of Economic Issues, 657-688. Michaels, Robert J. (1989), ‘Reorganizing Electricity Supply in New Zealand: Lessons for the United States’, 7(4) Contemporary Policy Issues, 73-90. Millward, Robert and Ward, Robert (1987), ‘The Costs of Public and Private Gas Enterprises in Late 19th Century Britain’, 39 Oxford Economic Papers, 719-737. Minasian, Jora R. (1964), ‘Television Pricing and the Theory of Public Goods’, 7 Journal of Law and Economics, 71-80. Moorhouse, John C. (ed) (1986), Electric Power: Deregulation and the Public Interest, San Francisco, CA, Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy. Morrison, Steven A. and Winston, Clifford (1986), The Economic Effects of Airline Deregulation, Washington, Brookings Institution, 84 p. Mueller, Charles E. (1996), ‘Antitrust Overview’, Antitrust Law and Economics Review, <
>, last visited March, 1998. Munroe, Tapan (1987), ‘Electric Utility Competition: Lessons from Others’, 12(2) Journal of Energy and Development, 203-214. Naughton, Michael C. (1986), ‘The Efficiency and Equity Consequences of Two Part Tariffs in Electricity Pricing’, 68 Review of Economics and Statistics, 406-414. Naughton, Michael C. (1988), ‘The Determinants of Regulators’ Preferences: Discrimination in Electricity Pricing’, 17 Journal of Behavioral Economics, 279-294. Naughton, Michael C. (1989), ‘Regulatory Preferences and Two Part Tariffs: The Case of Electricity’, 55 Southern Economic Journal, 743-758. Nelson, Jon P. and Roberts, Mark J. (1989), ‘Ramsey Numbers and the Role of Competing Interest Groups in Electric Utility Regulation’, 29(3) Quarterly Review of Economics and Business, 21-42. Nelson, Jon P., Roberts, Mark J. and Tromp, Emsley P. (1987), ‘An Analysis of Ramsey Pricing in Electric Utilities’, in Crew, Michael A. (ed), Regulating Utilities in an Era of Deregulation, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 85-109. Nelson, Randy A. (1989), ‘The Effects of Competition on Publicly Owned Firms: Evidence from the Municipal Electric Industry in the U.S.’, 8 International Journal of Industrial Organization, 37-51. Nelson, Randy A. (1989), ‘The Effects of Regulation on Capacity Utilization: Evidence from the Electric Power Industry’, 29 Quarterly Review of Economics and Business, 37-48. Neufeld, John L. (1987), ‘Price Discrimination and the Adoption of the Electricity Demand Charge’, 47 Journal of Economic History, 693-709. Ng, Yew Kwang (1987), ‘Equity, Efficiency and Financial Viability: Public Utility Pricing with Special Reference to Water Supply’, 79 Australian Economic Review, 21-35. Niskanen, W.A., Jr (1971), Bureaucracy and Representative Government, Chicago, Aldine
5400
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
527
Atherthon. Niskanen, William A. (1986), ‘Natural Gas Price Controls: An Alternative View’, 10 Regulation, 46-50. Norton, Seth W. (1985), ‘Regulation and Systematic Risk: The Case of Electric Utilities’, 28(3) Journal of Law and Economics, 671-686. Norton, Seth W. (1987), ‘In Search of Regulatory Lag’, 26(4) Quarterly Journal of Business and Economics, 3-16. Norton, Seth W. (1988), ‘Regulation, the OPEC Oil Supply Shock, and Wealth Effects for Electric Utilities’, 26(2) Economic Inquiry, 223-238. Nowotny, Kenneth (1988), ‘Transmission Technology and Electric Utility Regulation’, 22 Journal of Economic Issues, 555-562. Odell, P. (1987), ‘The Deregulation of Oil: The International Oil Market Framework’, in X (ed), 18de Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Brussel 8 en 9 mei 1987, Sociaal-economische Deregulering, Brussel, V.E.H.U.B., 455-471. Ogus, Anthony (1994), Regulation: Legal Form and Economic Theory, Oxford, Clarendon, 380p. Oren, S.S. and Smith, S.A. (1981), ‘Criticial Mass and Tariff Structure in Electronic Communications Markets’, 12 Bell Journal of Economics, 467-487. Otsuka, Yasuji (1997), ‘A Welfare Analysis of Local Franchise and Other Types of Regulation: Evidence from the Cable TV Industry’, 11 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 157-180. Pace, Joe D. and Landon, John H. (1982), ‘Introducing Competition into the Electric Utility Industry: An Economic Appraisal’, 3 Energy Law Journal, 1-65. Panzar, John C. and Willig, Robert D. (1977), ‘Free Entry and the Sustainabilty of Natural Monopoly’, 8 The Bell Journal of Economics, 1-22. Park, Rolla Edward (1972), ‘Cable Television, UHF Broadcasting, and FCC Regulatory Policy’, 15 Journal of Law and Economics, 207-231. Patterson, Cleveland S. and Ursel, Nancy D. (1987), ‘Public Utility Equity Financing Practices: A Test of Market Efficiency’, in Crew, Michael A. (ed), Regulating Utilities in an Era of Deregulation, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 63-76. Paul, Chris and Schoening, Niles (1991), ‘Regulation and Rent-Seeking: Prices, Profits, and Third-Party Transfers’, 68 Public Choice, 185-194. Peltzman, Sam (1971), ‘Pricing in Public and Private Enterprises: Electric Utilities in the United States’, 14 Journal of Law and Economics, 109-147. Penn, David W. (1990), ‘Electric Supply Industry Regulation - Leadership or Retreat?’, 24 Journal of Economic Issues, 545-553. Pettway, Richard H. and Jordan, Bradford D. (1987), ‘APT vs. CAPM Estimates of the Return Generating Function Parameters for Regulated Public Utilities’, 10 Journal of Financial Research, 227-238. Pierce, Richard J., Jr (1983), ‘Reconsidering the Roles of Regulation and Competition in the Natural Gas Industry’, 97 Harvard Law Review, 345-385. Pierce, Richard J., Jr (1986), ‘A Proposal to Deregulate the Market for Bulk Power’, 72 Virginia Law Review, 1183-1235. Pigou, A.C. (1920), The Economics of Welfare, London, Macmillan. Poole, Robert W., Jr (ed) (1985), Unnatural Monopolies: The Case for Deregulating Public
528
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
5400
Untilities, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books, 224 p. Posner, Richard A. (1969), ‘Natural Monopoly and its Regulation’, 21 Stanford Law Review, 548-643. Posner, Richard A. (1972), ‘The Appropriate Scope of Regulation in the Cable Television Industry’, 3 Bell Journal of Economics, 98-129. Posner, Richard A. (1974), ‘Theories of Economic Regulation’, 5 Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, 335-358. Posner, Richard A. (1975), ‘The Social Costs of Monopoly and Regulation’, 83 Journal of Political Economy, 807-827. Posner, Richard A. (1992), Economic Analysis of Law, 4th edn, Boston, Little Brown. Primeaux, Walter J., Jr (1988), ‘What Can Regulators Regulate? The Case of Electric Utility Rates of Return’, 9(2) Managerial and Decision Economics, 145-152. Primeaux, W.J. and Nelson, R.A. (1980), ‘An Examination of Price Discrimination and Internal Subsidization of Electric Utilities’, 47 Southern Economic Journal, 84-99. Primeaux, Walter J., Jr et al. (1984), ‘Determinants of Regulatory Policies toward Competition in the Electric Utility Industry’, 43 Public Choice, 173-186. Quandt, Richard E. (1983), ‘Complexity in Regulation’, 22 Journal of Public Economics, 199-214. Raffiee, Kambiz and Wendel, Jeanne (1988), ‘The Effects of Alternative Regulatory Policies on Utility Investment Strategies’, 54 Southern Economic Journal, 840-854. Ramsey, F. (1927), ‘A Contribution to the Theory of Taxation’, 37 Journal of Economics, 47 ff. Rashid, Salim (1981), ‘Public Utilities in Egalitarian LDCs: The Role of Bribery in Achieving Pareto Efficiency’, 34 Kyklos, 448-460. Rassenti, S.J., Smith, Vernon L. and Bulfin, R.L. (1982), ‘A Combinatorial Auction Mechanism for Airport Time Slot Allocation’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 402-417. Reece, D.K. (1978), ‘Competitive Bidding for Offshore Petroleum Leases’, 9 Bell Journal of Economics, 369-384. Reece, D.K. (1979), ‘An Analysis of Alternative Bidding Systems for Leasing Offshore Oil’, 10 Bell Journal of Economics, 659-669. Riordan, Michael H. and Sappington, David E.M. (1987), ‘Awarding Monopoly Franchises’, 77 American Economic Review, 375-387. Rowley, Charles K. (1968), ‘Monopoly in Britain: Private Vice but Public Virtue?’, Moortgat and Wall Street, 37-68. Rowley, Charles K. (1969), ‘The Monopolies Commission and Rate of Return on Capital’, 79 Economic Journal, 42-65. Rowley, Charles K. (1971), ‘The Monopolies Commission and Rate of Return on Capital: A Reply’, 81 Economic Journal, 603-609. Rozek, Richard P. (1989), ‘Competitive Bidding in Electricity Markets: A Survey’, 10(4) Energy Journal, 117-138. Salaun, Fabienne (1990), ‘Privatisation et Reglementation: le Cas du British Gas (Privatization and Regulation: The Case of British Gas)’, 24 Economies et Sociétés, 453-469. Saltzman, Sidney and Schuler, Richard E. (1986), ‘Electricity’s Future: Sharpening the Debates’, in Saltzman, Sidney and Schuler, Richard E. (eds), The Future of Electrical Energy: A Regional
5400
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
529
Perspective, New York, Greenwood Press, 348-362. Samuels, Warren G. and Mercuro, Nicholas (1976), ‘Property Rights, Equity, and Public Utility Pricing’, in Trebing, H. (ed), New Dimensions in Public Utility Pricing, East Lansing, MI, MSU Public Utility Papers, Institute of Public Utilities, Michigan State University, 44-82. Sappington, David E.M. (1980), ‘Strategic Firm Behavior under a Dynamic Regulatory Adjustment Process’, 11 Bell Journal of Economics, 360-372. Schap, David (1985), ‘X-Inefficiency in a Rent-Seeking Society - A Graphical Analysis’, 25 Quarterly Review of Economics and Business, 19-27. Schap, David (1986), Municipal Ownership in the Electric Utility Industry, New York, Greenwood Press, 128 p. Schmidt, Ronald H. (1987), ‘Deregulating Electric Utilities: Issues and Implications’, Federal Reserve Bank of Dallas Economic Review, 213-226. Scholtes, Philippe R. (1990), ‘Dual v Uniform Prices: An Application’, 12(1) Energy Economics, 18-26. Schap, David (1985), ‘X-Inefficiency in a Rent-Seeking Society - A Graphical Analysis’, 25 Quarterly Review of Economics and Business, 19-27. Scherer, F.M. (1984), Innovation and Growth: Schumpeterian Perspectives, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Schumpeter, Joseph (1950), Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, 3rd edn, New York, Harper and Row. Seldon, Zena A. and Seldon, James R. (1984), ‘Natural Monopolies versus Desirable Monopolies and Regulation in the Public Interest: Two Quibbles and a Policy Note’, 23(2) Quarterly Journal of Business and Economics, 58-71. Sharkey, William W. (1979), ‘A Decentralized Method for Utility Regulation: A Comment’, 22 Journal of Law and Economics, 405-407. Sharkey, William W. (1982), The Theory of Natural Monopoly, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 229 p. Shepard, W.G. (1965), Economic Performance under Public Ownership, New Haven, CT, Yale University Press, 161p. Sherman, R. and Visscher M. (1982), ‘Non Price Rationing and Monopoly Price Structure when Demand is Schoastic’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 254-262. Sherman, Roger (1989), The Regulation of Monopoly, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 289p. Shleifer, Andrei (1985), ‘A Theory of Yardstick Competition’, 16 Rand Journal of Economics, 319-327. Shleifer, Andrei (1998), ‘State versus Private Ownership’, 12(4) Journal of Economic Perspectives, 133-150. Sibley, David (1989), ‘Asymmetric Information, Incentives and Price-Cap Regulation’, 20 Rand Journal of Economics, 392-404. Sing, Merrile (1987), ‘Are Combination Gas and Electric Utilities Multiproduct Natural Monopolies?’, 69 Review of Economics and Statistics, 392-398. Smith, Vernon L. (1987), ‘Currents of Competition in Electricity Markets’, 11(2) Regulation, 23-29. Spence, A. Michael (1975), ‘Monopoly, Quality and Regulation’, 6 Bell Journal of Economics,
530
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
5400
417-429. Spence, A. Michael (1976), ‘Product Selection, Fixed Costs, and Monopolistic Competition’, 43 Review of Economic Studies, 217-235. Spence, A. Michael (1977), ‘Nonprice Competition’, 67 American Economic Review, p. 255 - 259. Spence, A. Michael (1980), ‘Advertising, Economies of Scale and Entry Barriers’, 95 Quarterly Journal of Economics, p. 493 - 507. Spier, Kathryn E. and Dana, James D., Jr (1994), ‘Designing a Private Industry: Government Auctions with Endogenous Market Structure’, 53 Journal of Public Economics, 127-147. Spulber, Daniel F. (1986), ‘Second-Best Pricing and Cooperation’, 17 Rand Journal of Economics, 239-250. Spulber, Daniel F. (1995), ‘Deregulating Telecommunications, 12 The Yale Journal of Regulation, 26-68. Stewart, Marion B. (ed) (1987), Energy Deregulation and Economic Growth: Proceedings, New Brunswick, Rutgers, Bureau of Economic Research. Stigler, George J. (1958), ‘The Economics of Scale’, 1 Journal of Law and Economics, 54-71. Stigler, George J. and Friedland, Claire (1962), ‘What Can Regulators Regulate? The Case of Electricity’, 5 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-16. Stout, Lynn A. and Barnes, David D. (1992), Economic Foundations of Regulation and Antitrust Law, St Paul, MN, West Publishing. Strasser, Kurt A. and Kohler, Mark F. (1989), Regulating Utilities with Management Incentives: A Strategy for Improved Performance, Westport, CT, Greenwood, 197 p. Taggart, Robert A., Jr (1985), ‘Effects of Regulation on Utility Financing: Theory and Evidence’, 33 Journal of Industrial Economics, 257-276. Tam, Mo Yin S. (1988), ‘A Mechanism to Induce Ramsey Pricing for Natural Monopoly Firms’, 6 International Journal of Industrial Organization, 247-261. Tawada, Makoto and Katayama, Sei Ichi (1990), ‘On the Technical Efficiency under Regulation: A Case for the Japanese Electric Power Industry’, 41 Economic Studies Quarterly, 34-47. Teeples, Ronald, Feigenbaum, Susan and Glyer, David (1986), ‘Public versus Private Water Delivery: Cost Comparisons’, 14 Public Finance Quarterly, 351-366. Thompson, Howard E. (1987), ‘Regulatory Policy under Uncertainty: How Should the Earned Rate of Return for a Public Utility be Controlled?’, in Crew, Michael A. (ed), Regulating Utilities in an Era of Deregulation, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 25-41. Thompson, Howard E. (1991), Regulatory Finance: Finacial Foundations of Rate of Return Regulation, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 256 p. Tishler, Asher (1989), ‘The Response of Large Firms to Different Schemes of Time of Use Pricing when the Production Function is Quadratic’, 10(2) Energy Journal, 69-90. Train, Kenneth E. and Toyama, Nate (1989), ‘Pareto Dominance through Self-selecting Tariffs: The Case of TOU Electricity Rates for Agricultural Customers’, 10(1) Energy Journal, 91-109. Train, Kenneth E., McFadden, Daniel L. and Goett, Andrew A. (1987), ‘Consumer Attitudes and Voluntary Rate Schedules for Public Utilities’, 69 Review of Economics and Statistics, 383-391.
5400
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
531
Train, K.E. (1991), The Economic Theory of Natural Monopoly, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 338p. Trebing, Harry M. (1984), ‘Public Utility Regulation: A Case Study in the Debate over Effectiveness of Economic Regulation’, 18 Journal of Economic Issues, 223-250. Trebing, Harry M. (1986), ‘Apologetics of Deregulation in Energy and Telecommuniciations: An Institutionalist Assesment’, 20 Journal of Economic Issues, 613-632. Tullock, Gordon (1967), ‘The Welfare Costs of Tariffs, Monopolies and Theft’, 5 Western Economic Journal, 224 ff. Vermoes, J. (1987), ‘De Programmaovereenkomst: Regulering of Deregulering? (Program Contract: Regulation or Deregulation?)’, in X (ed), 18de Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Brussel 8 en 9 mei 1987, Sociaal-economische Deregulering, Brussel, V.E.H.U.B., 441-454. Vogelsang, Ingo (1988), ‘A Little Paradox in the Design of Regulatory Mechanisms’, 29 International Economic Review, 467-476. Vogelsang, Ingo and Finsinger, Jörg (1979), ‘A Regulatory Adjustment Process for Optimal Pricing by Multiproduct Monopoly Firms’, 10 Bell Journal of Economics, 157-171. Volkonskii, V.A. and Kuzovkin, A.I. (1987), ‘Marginal Costs and Optimal Electricity Tariffs’, 24 Matekon, 43-69. Wald, Patricia M. (1983), ‘Judicial Review of Economic Analysis’, 1 Yale Journal on Regulation, 43-62. Wall, Richard A. and Gort, Michael (1990), ‘An Empirical Test of Feedbacks in Public Utility Regulation’, 12(1) Resources and Energy, 107-116. Waterson, Michael (1984), ‘Issues in the Regulation of Cable TV’, 4 International Review of Law and Economics, 67-82. Waterson, Michael (1988), Regulation of the Firm and Natural Monopoly, Oxford, Blackwell, 164 p. Wattles, George M. (1973), ‘The Rates and Costs of the United States Postal Service’, 16 Journal of Law and Economics, 89-117. Williams, Philip L. (1987), ‘Competitive Aspects of Electronic Funds Transfer Systems: The Emerging Pattern of Point-of-Sale Networks’, 1 Australian Economic Review, 31-38. Williams, Philip L. (1995), ‘Interconnection Prices in Local Telephony: The Implications of Symmetry’, in X (ed), Bureau of Industry Economics, 1995 Industry Economics Conference, Papers and Proceedings, Canberra, AGPS. Williams, Philip L. and Lindsay, David (1995), ‘The Trade-Off Between Competition and Efficiency in Telecommunications: The Australian Experience’, in Richardson, Megan and Williams, Philip (eds), The Law and the Market: Essays in Honour of Maureen Brunt, Melbourne, The Federation Press. Williams, Stephen F. (1991), ‘Fixing the Rate of Return After Duquesne’, 8 Yale Journal on Regulation, 159 ff. Williamson, O.E. (1971), ‘Administrative Controls and Regulatory Behavior’, in Trebling H.M. (ed), Essays on Public Utility Pricing and Regulation, Institute of Public Utilities, East Lansing, Michigan, Michigan State University. Williamson, O.E. (1976), ‘Franchise Bidding for Natural Monopolies - In General and With Respect
532
Regulation of Natural Monopoly
5400
to CATV’, 7 Bell Journal of Economics, 73-104. Williamson, Oliver E. (1987), ‘Delimiting Antitrust’, 76 Georgetown Law Journal, 271-303. Wilson, James Q. and Richardson, Louise (1985), ‘Public Ownership vs. Energy Conservation: A Paradox of Utility Regulation’, 9(5) Regulation, 13-17. Wilson, Robert B. (1989), ‘Efficient and Competitive Rationing’, 57 Econometrica, 1-40. Wolff, Nancy (1987), Income Redistribution and the Social Security Program, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 181 p. Winston, Clifford (1998), ‘U.S. Industry Adjustment to Economic Deregulation’, 12(2) Journal of Economic Policy, 175-196. Woodbury, John R., Besen, Stanley M. and Fournier, Gary M. (1983), ‘The Determinants of Network Television Program Prices: Implicit Contracts, Regulation, and Bargaining Power’, 14 Bell Journal of Economics, 351-365. Worcester, D.A. Jr (1948), ‘Justifiable Price Discrimination under Conditions of Natural Monopoly: A Diagrammatic Representation’, 38(3) The American Econ. Review, 382-388. Yucel, Mine Kuban (1990), ‘A Dynamic Model of Natural Gas Deregulation’, 12(1) Energy Economics, 35-47. Zeckhauser, Richard J. and Horer, Murray (1989), ‘The Control and Performance of State-Owned Enterprises’, in MacAvoc, Paul. W. et al. (eds), Privatization and State-Owned Enterprises, Boston, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 340 p. Zupan, Mark A. (1989), ‘The Efficacy of Franchise Bidding Schemes in the Case of Cable Television: Some Systematic Evidence’, 32 Journal of Law and Economics, 401-456. Zupan, Mark A. (1990), ‘On Cream Skimming, Coase and the Sustainability of Natural Monopolies’, 22(4) Applied Economics, 487-492.
Other References Liebenstein, Harvey (1966), ‘Allocative Efficiency vs. X-Efficiency’, 56 American Economic Review. Thaler, Richard H. (1992), The Winner’s Curse: Paradoxes and Anomalies of Economic Life, Princeton, Princeton University Press. Rahl, J. (1967), ‘Distributive Justice’, in Lasslett P. and Runciman W. (eds) Philosophy, Politics and Society, Third Series, Yale, Yale University Press..
5500 LABOR LAW AND EMPLOYMENT REGULATION: GENERAL © Copyright 1999 Boudewijn Bouckaert and Gerrit De Geest
Bibliography Collected by the Editors Adams, Michael (1994), ‘Das Bundesarbeitsgericht und das Recht zur Täuschung (The Federal Labor Court and the Right to Deceive)’, April Zeitschrift für Wirtschaftsrecht, 499 ff. Adomeit, Klaus (1996), Regelungen von Arbeitsbedingungen und ökonomische Notwendigkeiten - Eine Untersuchung zu aktuellen Fragen des deutschen Tarifrechts (Regulations on the Conditions of Labour and Economic Constraints), München, Verlag Aktuell, Landsberg am Lech. Allen, Steven G. (1983), ‘Much Ado about Davis-Bacon: A Critical Review and New Evidence’, 26 Journal of Law and Economics, 707-736. Backhaus, Jürgen G. (1980), Arbeitsverhältnis und Beschäftigung, Politisch-ökonomische Analyse zur Bekämpfung der Arbeitslosigkeit (Labor Relations and Employment, A Political Economic Analysis of Actions against Unemployment), Frankfurt, Campus. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1996), ‘Participatory Management Within a Theory of the Firm’, 21 Journal of Corporation Law, 657 ff. Behrens, Peter (1989), ‘Die Bedeutung der ökonomischen Analyse des Rechts für das Arbeitsrecht (The Importance of Economic Analysis of Law for Labour Law)’, 20 Zeitschrift für Arbeitsrecht, 209-238. Bierman, Leonard (1985), ‘Judge Posner and the NLRB: Implications for Labor Law Reform’, 69 Minnesota Law Review, 881 ff. Boorman, S.A. (1975), ‘A Combinatorial Optimization Model for Transmission of Job Information through Contact Networks’, 6 Bell Journal of Economics, 216-249. Brandes, Wolfgang, Buttler, Friedrich, Dorndorf, Eberhard and Walwei, U. (1991), ‘Grenzen der Kündigungsfreiheit - Kündigungsschutz zwischen Stabilität und Flexibilität (Limits of the Freedom to Terminate Employment Contracts)’, in Semlinger, K. (ed.), Flexibilität des Arbeitsmarktes, Interessen, Wirkungen, Perspektiven, Frankfurt/Main und New York, Campus-Verlag, 111-131. Bruce, Christopher J. (1988), ‘The Adjudication of Labor Disputes as a Private Good’, 8 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-19. Bryn, Brenda Greenberg (1987), ‘Case Comment: Refusals to Cross Stranger Picket Lines and the Wealth Maximization Principle: An Economic Analysis of the Views of the NLRB and Judge Posner’, 41 University of Miami Law Review, 533 ff. Burkhauser, Richard V. (1990), ‘Morality and the Cheap: The Americans with Disability Act’, 13(2) Regulation, 47-56. Buttler, Friedrich and Walwei, U. (1990), ‘Effizienzwirkungen des Kündigungsschutzes (Impacts of Protection against Dismissal on Efficiency)’, 23(3) MittAB, 386-393. Culyer, A.J. (1973), The Economics of Social Policy, London, Martin Robertson, 268 p.
533
534
Labor Law and Employment Regulation: General
5500
Danzon, Patricia M. (1988), ‘The Political Economy of Workers’ Compensation: Lessons for Product Liability’, 78 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 305-310. Dau-Schmidt, Kenneth G. (1992), ‘A Bargaining Analysis of American Labor Law and the Search for Bargaining Equity and Industrial Peace’, 91 Michigan Law Review, 419 ff. Dau-Schmidt, Kenneth G. (1993), ‘Bargaining Theory and Canadian Labour Law’, in Kuttner, T. (ed.), 2 The Industrial Relations System: Proceedings of the XXIXth Conference of the Canadian Industrial Relations Association, 753 ff. Dau-Schmidt, Kenneth G. (1993), ‘Meeting the Demands of Workers Into the Twenty-First Century: The Future of Labor and Employment Law’, 68 Indiana Law Journal, 685 ff. Dau-Schmidt, Kenneth G. (1995), ‘The Labor Market Transformed: Adapting Labor and Employment Law to the Rise of the Contingent Workforce’, 52 Washington and Lee Law Review, 879 ff. Dau-Schmidt, Kenneth G. (1996), ‘Employment Security: A Comparative Institutional Debate’, 74 Texas Law Review. Desdentado, Aurelio and Almudena Duran (1996), Las Causas Económicas Para la Extinción Objetiva del Contrato de Trabajo. Un Análisis Jurídico y Económico (Objective Causes for Breach of Labour Contracts. An Economic and Legal Analysis), Relaciones Laborales. Dnes, Antony W. (1984), The Economic Consequences of Job Protection, Employment Research Centre Paper, Buckingham, Univ. of Buckingham Press, No. 1. Dorndorf, Eberhard (1989), ‘Arbeitsmarkttheorie und Arbeitsrechtswissenschaft, Analoge Probleme und Diskussionsschwerpunkte im Hinblick auf die Funktionsfähigkeit der Arbeitsmärkte (Theory of Labor Markets and Jurisprudence)’, in X. (ed.), Währungsreform und Soziale Marktwirtschaft, Arbeitstagung des Vereins für Socialpolitik in Freiburg 1988, Berlin, Duncker and Humblot. Dorndorf, Eberhard (1992), ‘Mehr Individualvertragsfreiheit im Arbeitsrecht? (More Freedom for Individual Employment Contracts?)’, in Däubler, Wolfgang, Bobke, Manfred and Kehrmann, Karl (ed.), Festschrift für Albert Gnade, Köln, Bund-Verlag. Dorndorf, Eberhard, Brandes, Wolfgang and Buttler, Friedrich (1991), ‘Grenzen der Kündigungsfreiheit - Kündigungsschutz zwischen Stabilität und Flexibilität (Limits of the Right to Terminate Employment Contracts)’, in Semlinger, K. (ed.), Flexibilität des Arbeitsmarktes, Interessen, Wirkungen, Perspektiven, Frankfurt/Main und New York, Campus-Verlag. Drukarczyk, Jochen (1986), ‘Zum Problem der “wirtschaftlichen Vertretbarkeit” von Sozialplänen (The Problem of “Economic Feasibility” of Social Compensation Plans)’, 39 Recht der Arbeit, 115-120. Dung, Tran Huu and Premus, Robert (1990), ‘Do Socioeconomic Regulations Discriminate against Small Firms?’, 56 Southern Economic Journal, 686-697. Ehrenberg, Ronald G. and Schumann, Paul L. (1982), ‘Compliance with the Overtime Pay Provisions of the Fair Labor Standards Act’, 25 Journal of Law and Economics, 159-181. Epstein, Richard A. (1983), ‘Common Law, Labor Law, and Reality: A Rejoinder to Professors Getman and Kohler’, 92 Yale Law Journal, 1435-1441.
5500
Labor Law and Employment Regulation: General
535
Epstein, Richard A. (1984), ‘Toward a Revitalization of the Contract Clause’, 51 University of Chicago Law Review, 703-751. Epstein, Richard A. and Paul, Jeffrey (1984), ‘Introduction’, 51 University of Chicago Law Review, 945-946. Erven, Bernard L. (1984), ‘Impact of Labor Laws and Regulations on Agricultural Labor Markets’, in Emerson, Robert D. (ed.), Seasonal Agricultural Labor Markets in the United States, Ames, Iowa State University Press, 376-405. Faure, Michael G. (1995), ‘Rechtseconomische Kanttekeningen bij de Deregulering van de Arbeidsomstandighedenwetgeving (A Law and Economics Note on Deregulation in Working Conditions Legislation)’, 10(5) Sociaal Recht, 140-149. Feinstein, Jonathan S. (1990), ‘Detection Controlled Estimation’, 33 Journal of Law and Economics, 233-276. Fenn, Paul T. and Whelan, Christopher J. (1982), ‘Remedies for Dismissed Employees in the U.K.: An Economic Analysis’, 2 International Review of Law and Economics, 205-225. Fischel, Daniel R. (1984), ‘Labor Markets and Labor Law Compared with Capital Markets and Corporate Law’, 51 University of Chicago Law Review, 1061-1077. Fischel, Daniel R. and Lazear, Edward P. (1986), ‘Comparable Worth and Discrimination in Labor Markets’, 53 University of Chicago Law Review, 891-918. Flanagan, Robert J. (1987), Labor Relations and the Litigation Explosion, Washington, Brookings Institution, 122 p. Fortin, Pierre (1980), Les Conditions Minimales de Travail: leurs Conséquences Economiques (The Fixation of Minimum Working Conditions: Their Economic Consequences), 35e congrès des relations industrielles, La détermination des conditions minimales de travail par l’État: une loi: son économie et sa portée. Fox, Alan (1974), Beyond Contract: Work, Power and Trust Relations, London, Faber and Faber, 408 p. Frank, Robert H. (1984), ‘Interdependent Preferences and the Competitive Wage Structure’, 15 Rand Journal of Economics, 510-520. Freeman, Andrew D. (1987), ‘Note: A Critique of Economic Consistency’, 39 Stanford Law Review, 1259-1270. Frisvold, George, Mines, Richard and Perloff, Jeffrey M. (1988), ‘The Effects of Job Site Sanitation and Living Conditions on the Health and Welfare of Agricultural Workers’, 70(4) American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 875-885. Genser, Bernd (ed.) (1987), Abfertigungsregeln im Spannungsfeld der Wirtschaftspolitik (Rules of Indemnification as a Current Problem in Economic Policy), Vienna, Manz, 272 p. Getman, Julius G. and Kohler, Thomas C. (1983), ‘The Common Law, Labor Law, and Reality: A Response to Professor Epstein’, 92 Yale Law Journal, 1415-1434. Gier, H.G. De (1991), ‘Heeft het Arbeidsrecht een Toekomst? Een Verhandeling over de Invloed van de Economie op het Arbeidsrecht (Does Labour Law have a Future? An Essay on the Influence of Economics on Labour Law)’, in Coljee, P.D., Franken, H., Heertje, A. and Kanning, W. (eds), Law and Welfare Economics, Amsterdam, VU Amsterdam, 101-113. Goldfarb, Robert S. and Heywood, John S. (1982), ‘An Economic Evaluation of the Service Contract Act’, 36 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 56-72.
536
Labor Law and Employment Regulation: General
5500
Goldin, Claudia (1988), ‘Maximum Hours Legislation and Female Employment: A Reassessment’, 96 Journal of Political Economy, 189-205. Goodwin, William B. and Carlson, John A. (1981), ‘Job Advertising and Wage Control Spillovers’, 16 Journal of Human Resources, 80-93. Grabenwarter, Christoph (1992), Ladenschlußrecht (Regulation of Shopping Hours), Vienna - New York. Groenewegen, John (1990), ‘Transactiekosten (Transactions Costs)’, Tijdschrift voor Politieke Economie, 50-76. Hanson, Charles G. (1987), ‘Economic Significance of British Labor Law Reform’, 6 Cato Journal, 851-868. Harrison, Jeffrey L. (1984), ‘The ‘New’ Terminable-at-Will Employment Contract: An Interest and Cost-Incidence Analysis’, 69 Iowa Law Review, 327-363. Hart, P.E. (ed.) (1986), Unemployment and Labour Markets Policies, Aldershot, Gower, 198 p. Hébert, Gérard (1986), ‘Les Normes du Travail à Caractère Economique au Canada et au Québec (Labor Rules of an Economic Nature in Canada and Quebec)’, 17 Revue générale de droit, 45-84. Hendricks, Walter (1977), ‘Regulation and Labor Earnings’, 8 Bell Journal of Economics, 483-496. Hill, Andrew D. (1987), ‘Wrongful Discharge’ and the Derogation of the At Will Employment Doctrine, Philadelphia, PA, University of Pennsylvania, Wharton School, Industrial Research Unit, 246 p. Hill, John K. and Pearce, James E. (1990), ‘The Incidence of Sanctions against Employers of Illegal Aliens’, 98 Journal of Political Economy, 28-44. Hirsch, Werner Z. and Rufolo, Anthony M. (1985), ‘Economic Effects of Residence Laws on Municipal Police’, 17 Journal of Urban Economics, 335-348. Holderbeke, F., Pernot, A. and Denys, J. (1987), ‘Inkomensvorming en Deregulering van de Arbeidsmarkt: 3. Arbeidsvoorwaarden (Income Formation and Deregulation of the Labour Market: Labour Conditions)’, in X (ed.), 18de Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Brussel 8 en 9 mei 1987, Sociaal-economische Deregulering, Brussel, V.E.H.U.B., 265-303. Holland, D.M. (1971), ‘An Evaluation of Tax Incentives for On-the-Job Training of the Disadvantaged’, 2 Bell Journal of Economics, 293-327. Isé, Sabrina and Perloff, Jeffrey M. (1995), ‘Legal Status and Earnings of Agricultural Workers’, 77 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 355-386. Johnson, George E. and Solon, Gary R. (1986), ‘Estimates of the Direct Effects of Comparable Worth Policy’, 76 American Economic Review, 1117-1125. Kessel, Reuben A. and Alchian, Armen A. (1959), ‘Real Wages in the North during the Civil War: Mitchell’s Data Reinterpreted’, 2 Journal of Law and Economics, 95-113. Koch, Harald (1981), ‘Die Ökonomie der Gestaltungsrechte. Möglichkeiten und Grenzen der ökonomische Analyse des Rechts am Beispiel von Kündiging und Anfechtung (The Economics of Dispositive Right. Possibilities)’, in Bernstein, H., Drobnig, U. and Kötz, H. (eds), Festschrift für Konrad Zweigert zum 70. Geburtstag, Tübingen, Mohr, 851-877. Kosters, Marvin H. (1988), ‘Mandated Benefits - on the Agenda’, 12(3) Regulation, 21-27.
5500
Labor Law and Employment Regulation: General
537
Kruse, Douglas L. (1990), ‘The Economic Implications of Employment Rights and Practices in the United States’, 14 Journal of Comparative Economics, 221-253. Kübler, Friedrich, Mendelson, Morris and Mundheim, Robert H. (1990), ‘Die Kosten des Bezugsrechts - Eine rechtsökonomische Analyse des Amerikanischen Erfahrungsmaterials (The Costs of the Subscription Right - A Legal Economic Analysis of the American Experience)’, Die Aktiengesellschaft, 461-475. Kuhn, Peter J. (1990), ‘Reply’, 80 American Economic Review, 290-297. Lande, Robert H. and Zerbe, Richard O., Jr (1985), ‘Reducing Unions’ Monopoly Power: Costs and Benefits’, 28 Journal of Law and Economics, 297-310. Reprinted in 29 Corporate Practice Commentator, 1987, 107-122. Lande, Robert H. and Zerbe, Richard O., Jr (1990), ‘More Lessons From Japan: End Industrywide Collective Bargaining ?’, 28 Asian Economic Journal. Landes, William M. (1968), ‘The Economics of Fair Employment Laws’, 76 Journal of Political Economy, 507-559. Lemley, Mark A. and Durie, Daralyn J. (1992), ‘The Antitrust Liability of Labor Unions for Anticompetitive Litigation’, 80 California Law Review, 757 ff. Linder, Mark (1987), ‘Employees Not-so-Independent Contractors and the Case of Migrant Farmworkers: a Challenge to the ‘Law and Economics’ Agency Doctrine’, 15 New York University Review of Law and Social Change, 435-475. Mendeloff, John M. (1986), ‘Regulatory Reform and OSHA Policy’, 5 Journal of Policy Analysis and Management, 440-468. Meyer, Dirk (1989), ‘Rent Seeking durch Rationalisierungsschutz oder die Wohlfahrtsverluste einer Kostensenkungssteuer (Rent Seeking through Regulations Protecting Human Capital from Devaluation Due to Technological Innovation)’, 35 Konjunkturpolitik, 188-1200. Miller, James C., III and Yandle, Bruce (eds) (1979), Benefit-Cost Analysis of Social Regulation, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research. Miyazaki, Hajime (1977), ‘The Rat Race and Internal Labor Markets’, 8 Bell Journal of Economics, 394-418. Moore, William J., Newman, Robert J. and Thomas, R. William (1974), ‘Determinants of the Passage of Right-To-Work Laws: An Alternative Interpretation’, 17 Journal of Law and Economics, 197-211. Myhrman, Johan (1981), ‘Kontraktsrätt och löntagarfonder (Contractual Rights and Labour Funds)’, 6 Ekonomisk Debatt. Nagel, Bernhard (1979), ‘Die Verlagerung der Probleme um die Unternehmensmitbestimmung auf das Informationsproblem (Transferring the Problems of Worker Participation to the Information Problem)’, BB, 1799-1804. Nagel, Bernhard (1982a), ‘Der Schutz von Arbeitsplätzen im Kartell- und Wettbewerbsrecht (Protection of Jobs in Anti-Trust and Competition Law)’, in Kittner (ed.), Arbeitsmarkt Ökonomische, Soziale und Rechtliche Grundlagen, Heidelberg, Müller Juristischer Verlag. Nagel, Bernhard (1982b), ‘Fusionskontrolle und Schutz von Arbeitsplätzen (Merger Control and Job Protection)’, Arbeit und Recht, 207-215. Nagel, Bernhard (1992), ‘Von der Lex Mercatoria zur Lex Laboris, zur Rechtlichen Bewältigung der Internationalen Arbeitsbeziehungen (Lex Mercatoria and Lex Laboris. On the Legal Analysis of International Work Relations)’, in Däubler, Wolfgang, Bobke, Manfred and Kehrmann, Karl (ed.), Festschrift für Albert Gnade, Köln, Bund-Verlag.
538
Labor Law and Employment Regulation: General
5500
O’Connor, Marleen A. (1991), ‘Restructuring the Corporation’s Nexus of Contracts: Recognizing a Fiduciary Duty to Protect Displaced Workers’, 69 North Carolina Law Review, 1189-1260. O’Connor, Marleen A. (1993a), ‘The Human Capital Era: Reconceptualizing Corporate Law to Faciliate Labor-Management Cooperation’, 78 Cornell Law Review, 899-965. O’Connor, Marleen A. (1993b), ‘A Socio-Economic Approach to the Japanese Corporate Governance Structure’, 50 Washington and Lee Law Review, 1529-1564. Palomba, Neil A. and Palomba, Catherine A. (1971), ‘Right-To-Work Laws: A Suggested Economic Rationale’, 14 Journal of Law and Economics, 475-483. Pardolesi, Roberto (1985), ‘Invalidità Temporanea del Dipendente, Illecito del Terzo Rivalsa’ del Datore di Lavoro (ovvero: l’analisi economica del diritto in cassazione) (Temporary Disability of Employees Tortious Conduct By Third Party Employer’s Remedies)’, 1 Foro Italiano, 2286-2291. Perloff, Jeffrey M. (1979), ‘Plumber and Electrician Licensing Laws’, 25(9) Construction Review, 4-11. Perloff, Jeffrey M. (1980), ‘The Impact of Licensing Laws on Wage Changes in the Construction Industry’, 23 Journal of Law and Economics, 409-428. Pethig, Rudiger (1986), ‘Eminent Domain: A New Industrial Policy Tool: Comment’, 142 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 44-51. Posner, Richard A. (1984), ‘Some Economics of Labor Law’, 51 University of Chicago Law Review, 988-1011. Poulmans, G. (1987), ‘Inkomensvorming en Deregulering van de Arbeidsmarkt: 1. Arbeidsflexibiliteit (Income Formation and Deregulation in the Labour Market: Flexibility)’, in X (ed.), 18de Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Brussel 8 en 9 mei 1987, Sociaal-economische Deregulering, Brussel, V.E.H.U.B., 229-248. Priest, W. Curtiss (1988), Risks, Concerns, and Social Regulation: Forces that Led to Laws on Health, Safety, and the Environment, Boulder, CO, Westview Press, 204 p. Pritchard, A.C. (1991), ‘Note: Government Promises and Due Process: An Economic Analysis of the ‘New Property’’, 77 Virginia Law Review, 1053-1090. Raday, Frances (1989), ‘Costs of Dismissal: An Analysis in Community Justice and Efficiency’, 9 International Review of Law and Economics, 181-207. Rees, Albert and Hamilton, Mary T. (1963), ‘Postwar Movements of Wage Levels and Unit Labor Costs’, 6 Journal of Law and Economics, 41-68. Rosen, Sherwin (1984), ‘Commentary: In Defense of the Contract at Will’, 51 University of Chicago Law Review, 983-987. Rowley, Charles K. (1984), ‘Towards a Political Economy of British Labor Law’, 51 University of Chicago Law Review, 1135-1160. Rubin, Paul H. (1990), Managing Business Transactions, New York, Free Press. Rubin, Paul H. and Kau, James B. (1981), ‘The Impact of Labor Unions on the Passage of Economic Legislation’, Journal of Labor Economics, 133-145. Ryan, Bernard (1994), ‘Law-and-Economics and Employment Law’, in Raes, Koen and Willekens, H. (eds), Economische Verklaringen van het Recht, Den Haag, VUGA, 109-131. Sadowski, Dieter (1988), ‘Währt ehrlich am längsten? Personalpolitik zwischen Arbeitsrecht und Unternehmenskultur (Is Honesty the Best Policy? Personal Management Between Labor Law
5500
Labor Law and Employment Regulation: General
539
and Corporate Culture)’, in Budäus, Dietrich, et al. (ed.), Betriebswirtschaftslehre und Theorie der Verfügungsrechte, Wiesbaden, Gabler, 219-238. Sadowski, Dieter and Kurth, Elke (1991), ‘Wettbewerbsverzerrung trotz Europäischen Arbeitsrechts? Ein Ökonomischer Vergleich des Arbeitnehmerschutzes beim Unternehmensverkauf in Deutschland und Großbritannien (Distortions of Competition Despite European Labor Law?)’, in Marr, R. (ed.), Eurostrategisches Personalmanagement, München und Mering, 423-446. Sagoff, Mark (1988), The Economy of the Earth: Philosophy, Law, and the Environment, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 271 p. Schröder, Michael (1997), Betriebliche Vollzugskosten der Arbeits- und Sozialgesetzgebung. Ein internationaler und intertemporaler Vergleich (Execution Costs of Labor and Social Laws), Frankfurt, Campus. Schwab, Stewart J. (1987), ‘Collective Bargaining and the Coase Theorem’, 72 Cornell Law Review, 245-287. Schwab, Stewart J. (1989a), The Economics Invasion of Labor Law Scholarship, Industrial Relations Research Association 41st Annual Proceedings. Schwab, Stewart J. (1989b), ‘Coase Defends Coase: Why Lawyers Listen and Economists Do Not’, 87 Michigan Law Review, 1171-1198. Schwab, Stewart J. (1994), ‘Employment Life Cycles and the Employment-At-Will Doctrine’, 20 Cornell Law Forum, 7-11. Schwab, Stewart J. (1995), ‘The Diversity of Contingent Workers and the Need for Nuanced Policy’, 52 Washington and Lee Law Review, 915-933. Schwab, Stewart J. (1996), ‘Wrongful Discharge Law and the Search for Third-Party Effects’, Texas Law Review, 74 ff. Shultz, George P. (1963), ‘Strategies for National Labor Policy’, 6 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-9. Smith, Robert S. (1979), ‘Compensating Wage Differentials and Public Policy: A Review’, 32 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 339-351. Sunstein, Cass R. (1984), ‘Rights, Minimal Terms, and Solidarity: A Comment’, 51 University of Chicago Law Review, 1041-1060. Tinbergen, J. (1982), ‘Kan de Economische Wetenschap Bijdragen tot de Ontwikkeling van het Recht? (Can the Economic Science Contribute to Legal Development?)’, in X (ed.), In Orde: Liber Amicorum Pieter Verloren van Themaat, Deventer, Kluwer, 295-300. Tollefson, John O. and Pichler, Joseph A. (1974), ‘A Comment on Right-To-Work Laws: A Suggested Economic Rationale’, 17 Journal of Law and Economics, 193-196. Trapani, John M., III (1986), ‘Eminent Domain: A New Industrial Policy Tool: Comment’, 142 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 39-43. Verkerke, J. Hoult (1995), ‘An Empirical Perspective on Indefinite Term Employment Contracts: Resolving the Just Cause Debate’, Wisconsin Law Review, 837-918. Verkuil, Paul R. (1983), ‘Whose Common Law for Labor Relations?’, 92 Yale Law Journal, 1409-1414. Vetter, Jan (1989), ‘Commentary: Searching for the Right Questions’, 75 Virginia Law Review, 285-294.
540
Labor Law and Employment Regulation: General
5500
Walwei, U. (1988), ‘Ökonomische Analyse arbeitsrechtlicher Regelungen am Beispiel des Kündigungsschutzes (Economic Analysis of Protection Against Dismissal as an Example for Worker Protection Laws)’, 63(6) WSI-Mitteilungen, 392-400. Walwei, U. (1989), Ansätze einer ökonomischen Analyse des Arbeitsrechts - Debatte um Deregulierung und Flexibilisierung des Arbeitsrechts aus ökonomischer Sicht (Economic Analysis of Labor Markets. The Debate on Deregulation and Flexibilization of the Labor Law), Arbeitspapiere aus dem Arbeitskreis Sozialwissenschaftliche Arbeitsmarktforschung (SAMF), 1989. Walwei, U. (1990), ‘Ökonomisch-rechtliche Analyse befristeter Arbeitsverhältnisse (Law and Economics of Temporary Employment)’, Arbeitspapiere aus dem Arbeitskreis Sozialwissenschaftliche Arbeitsmarktforschung (SAMF). Walwei, U. (1993), ‘Zum Regulierungsbedarf bei Zulassung privater Arbeitsvermittlung (On the Need for Regulation of Admission of Private Employment Agencies)’, 26(3) Mitteilungen aus der Arbeitsmarkt- und Berufsforschung, 285-293. Walwei, U. (1995), ‘Atypische Beschäftigungsformen, Kongruenz und Divergenz der Interessen (Non-typical Forms of Employment)’, in Keller, B. and Seifert, H. (eds), Atypische Beschäftigung. Verbieten oder gestalten?, Köln, 9-24. Walwei, U. (1996), ‘Befristung von Arbeitsverhältnissen, Mehr Beschäftigung durch weniger Kündigungsschutz? (Temporary Employment, More Emplyoment by Less Protection Against Dismissal?)’, in Montada, L. and Dieter, A., Gerechtigkeitsprobleme der Arbeitslosigkeit. Berichte aus dem Zentrum für Gerechtigkeitsforschung an der Universität Potsdam, Nr. 3, 127-154. Wielers, Rudi and Schippers, Joop J. (1998), ‘Labour Market Research: The Supremacy of Neoclassical Economic Theory’, in Evers, G., van Hees, B. and Schippers, Joop J. (eds), Work, Organisation and Labour in Dutch Society: A State of the Art of the Research, Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 37-61. X (1989), ‘Note: Employer Opportunism and the Need for a Just Clause Standard’, 103 Harvard Law Review, 510-529.
5510 LABOR CONTRACTS Ann-Sophie Vandenberghe Netherlands School for Social and Economic Policy Research Utrecht University © Copyright 1999 Ann-Sophie Vandenberghe
Abstract This chapter contains an overview of the literature on labor contracts. Four important aspects of the employment relationship will be discussed: matching of employer and employee, acquisition and retention of firmspecific human capital, earnings stability as insurance and the effort intensity of employees. These four important areas of the employment relationship are encountered by imperfections, mainly information problems and opportunistic behavior. Some labor market institutions, such as the design of a certain wage policy, can be explained as devices to overcome these imperfections. The employment contract can be viewed as a combination of explicit and implicit agreements. An explicit contract is legally enforceable. An implicit contract is an informal understanding which is too vague to be legally enforceable. In order to be of any value, the implicit contract must be selfenforcing. JEL classification: J41, K31 Keywords: Adverse Selection, Asymmetric Information, Efficiency Wage, Effort, Firm Specific Human Capital, Implicit Contracts, Opportunistic Behavior, Signaling
1. Introduction Job matching constitutes the process whereby heterogeneous workers are matched to heterogeneous jobs. This matching process consists of two steps: discovering appropriate individuals and providing the workers with specific skills (see Elliott, 1991, p. 292). The first step is to discover appropriate individuals and will be discussed in Section 2. The employer wants to find the ‘right’ kind of employee and the employee wants to find the ‘right’ kind of job. Information asymmetry and opportunistic behavior of one or both parties at the precontractual stage might result in a suboptimal match and in adverse selection. Some devices help parties to overcome those inefficiencies. In Section 3, the second step of the matching process or the investments in specific human capital by both employer and employee are considered. 541
542
Labor Contracts
5510
These investments are specific to the unique match between a firm and the worker and will be lost if the match is broken (see Becker, 1975; Parsons, 1986, p. 819). Therefore, compensation schemes might be adopted to prevent the employee from quitting soon after investments are made. Parties might also behave opportunistically as regards the division of the surplus resulting from investments in firm-specific training. Parties who anticipate the opportunistic behavior might refrain from investing in specific capital; this is the hold up problem. One role of the employment contract is to overcome the hold up problem by introducing wage rigidity. Another role of the employment contract, as will be shown in Section 4, is to enable firms to share the risks for uncertain income streams. This is at the heart of the implicit contract theory which also provides arguments for wage rigidity. In Section 5 an overview is given of the employment arrangements, mainly compensation plans, used to induce an employee to provide the optimal level of effort. Finally, some characteristics of the form of the employment contract will be explained; the employment contract is in general a long-term, incomplete and self-enforcing implicit contract.
2. Matching of Employer and Employee For markets to successfully promote mutually beneficial transactions, both buyers and sellers must have access to accurate information about the quality and price of the goods (Ehrenberg and Smith, 1997, p. 378). Translated to the labor market the employer wants to have information about the productivity level of the potential employee and his attachment to the job; the employee wants to have information about the pecuniary and non pecuniary job characteristics. Schäfer and Ott (1993) and De Geest (1994, pp. 167-189) summarize the law and economics literature on information production in the precontractual stage in general. De Geest, et al. (1999) apply the insights of the general analysis of information production to labor contract negotiations. In many cases the information is ‘asymmetric’ - that is, when one party knows more than the other about its intentions or performance under the contract. When information is asymmetric, opportunities for malpractice are enhanced. Applicants have incentives to overstate their productive capacities and employers have incentives to represent jobs as less demanding than they may actually be. As a result, mutually beneficial transactions may be ‘blocked’ and disallocation of the resource labour may be the result.
5510
Labor Contracts
543
It is interesting to look at some labor market institutions that remove the information asymmetry or reduce the inefficient consequences of it, on the employer’s side as well as on the employee’s side. Employer’s Side It is profitable for an employer to distinguish between high-productivity workers and low-productivity workers. How can the employer find out about a potential employee’s productivity? A mechanism by which employers and employees deal with the problem of asymmetric information is ‘signaling’. The concept of job market signaling was first developed by Spence (1973). He uses the term signals for those observable characteristics attached to the individual that are subject to manipulation by him. The costs of making the adjustments by manipulation are signaling costs. A signal is strong when the signaling costs are negatively correlated with the individual’s unknown productivity so that high-productivity persons are more likely to give the signal than low-productivity persons. Education might be a strong signal in labor markets. Prior to hiring, the employer not only wants to know the potential productivity but also whether the employee is likely to stay for a long term with the employer, especially when firm-specific investments will be made. Salop and Salop (1976) offer a sorting model of quit behavior. The rationale is that offered pay plans may induce signaling. Employees who choose to work under compensation plans with deterred payments, signal that they intend to stay for a longer time with the employer. ‘The essence of signaling ... is the voluntary revelation of truth about oneself in one’s behavior, not just one’s statements’ (Ehrenberg and Smith, 1997, p. 379). In many cases complete information revelation about the potential employee’s productivity is not possible at a reasonable cost; the information will remain partly asymmetric which may have inefficient consequences. An important consequence of the asymmetry of information at the precontractual stage is known as adverse selection. The adverse selection problem was discussed by Akerlof (1970) in the used car market. In the employment relationship the adverse selection problem arises when employers cannot devise a way to distinguish between groups of employee candidates with different levels of productivity at a reasonable cost. In that case, firms would be forced to assume that all applicants are ‘average’ and would pay them an average wage. Low-quality workers would profit as they are paid a wage above the value of their marginal productivity, where goodquality workers are underpaid. According to Weiss (1980) this will result in good-quality workers refraining from applying for the job; employees (as opposed to employers) know their productivity and will only accept wages that correspond with their productive endowments. Only the low-quality
544
Labor Contracts
5510
workers find it profitable to apply for the job. However, the employer can attract more high-quality employees by offering a higher wage. ‘Because reservation wages are positively correlated with labor endowments, if a firm were to cut the wage it offered, the workers that would be discouraged from applying to work for the firm would be the workers that the firm finds most desirable’Weiss, 1991, p. 15). This model is an efficiency-wage model, and the reason for paying above market wages is to avoid adverse selection; this will be done by enlarging the pool of applicants with good-quality workers. Discrimination might be another consequence of asymmetric information when screening and signaling are not perfect. Statistical discrimination might occur when the employer assigns group characteristics to people who may not be typical of the group. Employers who rely on false stereotypes will face adverse selection because they are not hiring the most productive workers. Chapter 5530 gives an overview of Employment Discrimination. Employee’s Side We now turn to the information shortage on the side of employees with respect to the job characteristics. The employer normally possesses more information about the job characteristics, but he will have the incentive to present the job as less demanding than it actually is. Economic theory, however, predicts that compensating wage differentials will be associated with various job characteristics. Positive differentials (higher wages) will accompany ‘bad’ characteristics, while negative differentials (lower wages) will be associated with ‘good’ ones (Ehrenberg and Smith, 1997, p. 251). A company offering a job with ‘bad’ characteristics with no compensating wage differentials would have trouble recruiting or retaining workers; the company would eventually be forced to raise its wages, even above the wage level offered by the company offering good characteristics. The prediction that there are compensating wage differentials was already proposed by Adam Smith in his The Wealth of Nations (1776). The prediction is only true under the assumption that workers want to maximize their utility, are informed of the job characteristics and perfect worker mobility (see, for example, Ehrenberg and Smith, 1997, chapter 8). When the assumptions are not fulfilled, regulation might discipline the employer. For an overview of Occupational Safety and Health Regulation see Chapter 5540.
3. Firm Specific Investments Many workers increase their productivity by learning new skills and perfecting old ones while on-the-job. Gary Becker (1975) was the first to formalize the distinction between two types of on the job training: general
5510
Labor Contracts
545
training that increases an individual’s productivity to many employers equally, and specific training that increases an individual’s productivity only at the firm in which he or she is currently employed. Future productivity can be improved only at a cost. These investment costs will only be incurred when there is a possibility to recoup the returns of investments. This necessitates that the employment relationship should endure for a sufficiently long period of time. Some arrangements of the employment relationship can be seen as incentives for the continuance of the relationship. The original theoretical literature in the area of human capital theory (Becker, 1975; Mincer, 1962; Oi, 1962; Parsons, 1972; Pencavel, 1972; and Salop, 1973) focused on the effect of firm specific human capital on firm compensation policies and the consequences for firm lay-off and quit experiences. General Training Because general training increases workers’ productivity in the firm providing it, as well as in many other firms, the prediction holds true that firms will not offer general training, or only if the employees bear the full cost of their training. However, general training is widely provided and paid for by employers in the actual labour market. A possible explanation is that the mobility of workers to work for another firm is sufficiently limited by the mobility costs, that is by the various costs employees must naturally bear in finding other offers and switching employer. In that way employers can obtain the returns of the training if they have paid for it. Specific Training Becker (1975) defines ‘completely specific’ training as training that has no effect on the productivity of trainees that would be useful in other firms. If training were completely specific, the wage that an employee could get elsewhere would be independent of the amount of training he had received. When a firm offers specific training, it has to decide how to structure wages during and after training so that it can recoup its investment. This will be explained with the two period example (this is essentially the model developed in Becker, 1975). Suppose the firm’s workers come to it with a marginal product of MP*, and they can obtain a wage of W* (=MP*) elsewhere. If they receive specific training in the first period of employment, their marginal product with the firm is reduced to MP0 (< MP*) during the training period but rises to MP1 (>MP*) in the post-training period. The difference between MP1 and MP* in the post-training period is called the post-training surplus. What is the optimal pay policy to be adopted by the firm? First, a firm is hurt by the departure of a trained employee because an equally profitable new employee could not be obtained and the firm’s
546
Labor Contracts
5510
training investments would be lost. Therefore the firm must offer a posttraining wage that is high enough to discourage its trained workers from quitting immediately after training (W1 > W*). But the firm incurred costs in the training period, which it wants to recoup. Therefore the post-training wage must be below MP1 (W1 < MP1) so that the firm is allowed to recoup investment costs. Where exactly within this range W1 will be depends on the mobility costs (job search costs, change of residence) of the trained employee. If these costs are high, then W1 need not be much above W* to induce those workers to stay with the firm in the post-training period. When employees are offered some of the return from training, the higher wage would make the supply of trainees greater than the demand, and rationing would be required. The final step is then to shift some training costs as well as returns to employees. This will be done by offering a wage below W* in the training period. Some of the training costs will be borne by the employer. Therefore the wage will be higher than MP0. If employees bore all the costs of specific training, then employers would have no investment to protect and would not be inhibited from firing employees after training. The optimal pay policy is one in which firms do not pay all training costs nor do they collect all the return, but they rather share both with the employees. In the efficiency-wage theory it is shown that high wages have a quitdeterring effect (Salop, 1973, 1979; Stiglitz, 1974). So employers pay an above market wage in order to prevent their specifically trained employees from quitting. But an element that also plays an important role in efficiency wage theories is unemployment. The basic idea is that employees are less likely to quit when their current wage is higher than what they can earn elsewhere and when the level of unemployment is higher. Hold-Up Problem Becker focused on the possibility of the employee to threaten in an opportunistic way to quit after the firm makes the specific investment unless the wage rate is adjusted upwards. Becker’s solution is a sharing of the costs and benefits of the specific investment via an initial lump-sum payment by the employee and a later higher-than-market wage. But as Klein, Crawford and Alchian (1978) show, this solution does not eliminate the bilateral opportunistic bargaining problem; the employer may later decrease the wage back to the competitive level or the employee may demand a higher wage to appropriate the partial specific investment by the employer. Williamson (1985) has termed this problem ‘hold-up’. By threatening to quit, an employee might bargain for a large share of the surplus in a way that the employer can only partly reap the returns of his specific investment. The employer will have to concede because if the employee quits, the employer cannot reap any returns at all. The same is true for the employee who has
5510
Labor Contracts
547
invested in specific training when the employer acts strategically by threatening to dismiss the employee. Parties might anticipate this opportunistic behavior and refrain from firm-specific investments. The investments in specific training will then be less than what is socially optimal. A solution put forward in the literature is a formal fixed-wage contract specifying a wage at the start of employment (Klein, Crawford and Alchian, 1978; Macleod and Malcomson, 1993; and Malcomson, 1997). When renegotiations are avoided through wage rigidity, the scope for opportunistic behavior will be smaller: ‘a contract that ensures a wage independent of the amount the firm invests insures those investments are efficient’ (Malcomson, 1997, p. 1933). However, a wage contract will not completely avoid the hold-up problem, especially when alternative market opportunities for one or both parties are considered. Due to macro shocks in product demand and firm-specific shocks, the alternative opportunities for one or both parties might be better than the existing wage contract. In order to avoid an inefficient separation, the wage must be adjusted. Those adjustments are normally not foreseen in the employment contract because the employment relationship is too complex and uncertain. Renegotiation is necessary and again the hold-up problem occurs. Renegotiation to prevent an inefficient separation when an outside option constraint binds may allow one party to capture part of the returns to specific investments made by the other. Anticipation of that means that the original investments may not be efficient. (Malcomson, 1997, p. 1943)
According to Teulings (1996) the solution is to delegate the power to renegotiate to centralized labour unions and employer organisations. Negotiations are then independent of the problems of the workplace and specific investments do not influence the decisions. In general the fear of opportunistic behavior leads to wage rigidity in long term explicit contracts where specific human capital is present. This argument is distinct from the argument for the existence of rigid long-term implicit labor contracts as a means of bearing risk. The use of the employment contract as an insurance contract will be discussed in the next section.
4. Insurance Contract Azariadis (1975) considers the risk-neutral firms to act both as employers and as insurers of homogenous, risk-averse laborers. The use of the employment contract as an insurance contract has been discussed in the implicit contract theory. The origins of implicit-contract theory lie in the belief that observed movements in wages and employment cannot be
548
Labor Contracts
5510
adequately explained by a competitive spot labor market in which wages are always equal to the marginal product of labor and the labor market is always in equilibrium. Instead, the observation in the labor market is that over the cycle wages are ‘rigid’ while employment varies. Basic ideas about implicitcontract models were originally proposed by Baily (1974), Gordon (1974) and Azariadis (1975). But the ideas spawned an enormous amount of literature. For surveys see Azariadis and Stiglitz (1983), Hart and Holmstrom (1986) and Rosen (1994). The earliest literature on implicit contracts exploits the insight by Knight (1921), who argued that inherently confident and venturesome entrepreneurs will offer to relieve their employees of some market risks in return for the right to make allocative decisions. The basic idea of implicit-contract theory is that in their dealings employers are less risk-averse than workers. One reason is that owners of capital who represent the employers can divide their capital among many different firms through the stock market, and by this diversification they obtain insurance against the risks faced by individual firms. On the other hand, for workers it is generally difficult to diversify assets which take the form of human capital because workers generally work for only one employer at the time. Risk-averse workers do not like fluctuations in their wages. But in a competitive labor market, fluctuations in the marginal product of labor would lead to fluctuations in the wage. However, the risk-averse employee is willing to pay for income certainty because it increases his utility. Due to the imperfect nature of insurance markets, workers who desire such an insurance coverage cannot get it on the insurance market. The employing firm, having more information than a separate insurer, is much better placed to undertake the insurance function, if compensated for it. The crucial feature of implicit-contract models is how risk is shared between workers and firms. Both parties to the employment relationship can be made better off by replacing a fluctuating wage with a fixed wage contract which has a slightly lower average value. So it appears that the implicit contract theory can explain wage stickiness, one of the stylized facts of the labor market. In the optimal contract, the wage is rigid and does not vary with the marginal revenue product of labor. The marginal revenue product is supposed to be high in good times and low in bad times. In that way the employment contract will include an insurance element, insuring workers against bad times by collecting premiums from them in good times. According to Azariadis (1987) an implicit contract is a complete description, made before the state of nature (good or bad) becomes known, of the labour services to be rendered unto the firm in each state of nature, and of the corresponding payments to be delivered to the worker. These types of risk sharing agreements are termed ‘implicit-contracts’ in the implicit contract theory. By ‘implicit’ we normally mean that something is
5510
Labor Contracts
549
understood to be the case. In the case of a contract, an implicit contract has connotations of an informal arrangement which is not written down. The converse of an implicit contract would then be an explicit contract in which everything that matters is clearly specified and written down. The use of the term ‘implicit contracts’ to denote risk-sharing contracts is rather confusing according to Bosworth, Dawkins and Stromback (1996, p. 280). It is not the implicit nature of the insurance contract that is the crucial feature of implicit contract theory, but it is the question how risk is shared between employer and employee. For that reason, ‘risk-sharing agreements’ would be a better term. It is, however, true that the risk-sharing agreement considered by the implicit contract literature is implicit. Indeed, we do not observe such risksharing contracts in the real world, so if they exist they must be implicit (see Manning, 1990, p. 65). The problem with contracts that are implicit (understood) compared to explicit (written) contracts, is that they are not enforceable by a third party, such as a court. One of the parties might breach the implicit risk sharing agreement; the employer can increase his profits by dismissing the worker whose marginal revenue product is below the fixed wage in the bad state of nature and replace him by a cheaper worker, and the employee has an incentive to quit when his marginal revenue product is higher than the fixed wage in the good state of nature. These implications can be avoided when the implicit contract is self enforcing through labor market institutions such as mobility costs (for example Baily, 1974) and reputation (for example Holmstrom, 1981; and Bull, 1987). The mechanism of self-enforcing implicit contracts will be further discussed in this contribution.
5. Employee’s Effort Level and Compensation Scheme The employment relationship can be thought of as a contract between a principal (the employer) and an agent (the employee). The employee is hired to help advance the employer’s objectives in return for receiving wages and other benefits. But workers are considered to be utility maximizers. They are primarily motivated by self interest and they seek to avoid unpleasant or otherwise costly activities. Which policies can employers devise in order to ensure the alignment of the agent’s interests with those of the principal and more specifically to induce a high level of effort from their employees? One way to motivate high levels of effort is to closely supervise employees. According to Alchian and Demsetz (1972), the essence of the firm is ‘the centralized contractual agent in a team productive process’. And one method of reducing shirking is for someone to specialize as a monitor to check the input performance of team members.
550
Labor Contracts
5510
While virtually all employees work under some form of supervision, close and detailed supervision or monitoring is costly. With imperfect monitoring and full employment, workers will choose to shirk, that is to provide a low level of effort. If supervision or monitoring is too costly, the employer can use various compensation plans to motivate the employee to work hard. A possible incentive-based pay scheme to motivate the employees is linking one’s pay to one’s output. Possible systems under which workers are paid for their output are piece-rate pay, payment by commission, gainsharing, profit-sharing, and bonus plans. Although such pay systems reduce the monitoring costs for the employer, in reality in most employment relationships employees are paid (at least partly) for their time. Output-based pay encounters difficulties of measurement of output. Such incentive contracts that are legally enforceable are limited by the practical difficulty of finding measures of employee performance that can be verified in court. Without such verifiability, contracts that make the wage conditional on output will not be legally enforceable (Macleod and Malcomson, 1987, 1989). Another problem is that a system of pay for performance places employees at a risk of having earnings that are variable over time. Such a system does not satisfy the desire of a risk averse employee (see Section 4 above contract) and the employee is only willing to accept the risk if this is offset by a higher expected income. At the heart of the principal-agent problem lies the inevitable trade-off between the provision of incentives to work hard and the sharing of risks. The challenge is to design an employment contract so that there are incentives to perform well, but without burdening the workers with too much risk (see for example Douma and Schreuder, 1998, 7.6). Given the difficulties with output-based pay plans, another method to increase the chances that the workers will not shirk their duties is to pay them a wage above the market wage. This method has been the object of the efficiency-wage theories. The reasons why higher wages are thought to generate greater productivity from given workers all relate to the commitment to the firm they build. Wages affect the productivity of individual workers by affecting whether workers are supportive or antagonistic to their employer. The main contributor to this line of investigation has been Akerlof (1984) in the context of ‘gift-exchange’ relationships. He argues that when firms pay ‘high’ wages they are in effect making a gift to the workers, which is reciprocated by the workers. They act in ways that benefit the firm even if they are not rewarded for those actions. However, the aspect of behavior that has been widely discussed as being affected by wages is the quality and intensity of work (effort level or productivity level). Employees realize that even though supervision may not be detailed enough to detect shirking with certainty, if they are caught
5510
Labor Contracts
551
cheating on their promises to work hard and are fired as a result, the loss of a job paying above market wages is costly. If an employee’s work is not diligent and he is fired, he faces the risk of earning a lower wage. The cost of earning less provides the incentive to work hard. Raising compensation above the level that workers can earn elsewhere has both benefits (less monitoring costs) and costs (higher wages) to the employer. While initial increases in pay may well serve to increase productivity and therefore the profits of the firm, after a point the costs to the employer of further increases will exceed the benefits. The above-market level at which the marginal revenues to the employer from a further pay increase equal the marginal costs is the level that will maximize profits. This has become known as the efficiency wage (Ehrenberg and Smith, 1997, p. 396). The wage premium that efficiency-wage employers must pay to discourage shirking depends upon the alternatives open to their employees. The prediction holds that there should be a negative association between average wage rates and unemployment rates across areas (see Ehrenberg and Smith, 1997, p. 582). Shapiro and Stigliz (1984) state in their shirking model that if all employers were to follow the strategy of raising wages, then the incentive not to shirk again disappears; the worst that can happen to a worker who shirks on the job is that he is fired, since he can be rehired (assuming there is no unemployment) at the same high wage. But as all firms raise their wages, supply of labor would exceed demand and unemployment would result. With unemployment, even if all firms pay the same wages, a worker has an incentive not to shirk. For, if he is fired, an individual will not immediately obtain another job. Lazear (1979) shows that it is beneficial to both employer and employee to arrange workers’ pay over time so that employees are ‘underpaid’ (less than their marginal productivity) early in their careers and ‘overpaid’ later on. Holding out payments until late in the individual’s lifetime alters the worker’s incentives to reduce his effort on the job. Workers are less likely to shirk their responsibilities because the penalties for being caught and fired are forfeiture of a late future award. Another form of worker motivation is the promotion tournament. Workers with high effort levels will be awarded with promotion. Promotion tournament models are given by Malcomson (1984, 1986) and Bhattacharya (1986). A contract to induce the employee to provide a certain effort level is often an understanding that cannot be enforced by third parties, such as courts. Such contracts are labelled ‘implicit contracts’. It is, for example, usually understood, but seldom explicitly expressed, that workers who provide a high effort level will be rewarded with a bonus. Implicit contracts are distinguished from explicit contracts which can be enforced by third parties. There is no use for parties explicitly to write down the required
552
Labor Contracts
5510
effort level of the employee in the employment contract because courts generally cannot verify information about the effort level of the employee. The worker’s effort and thus his output are modeled as nonverifiable (Carmichael, 1989).
6. Long-Term, Incomplete and Self-Enforcing Implicit Contract When the motivation for an employment contract is to regulate and divide the surplus of relation-specific investments, to ensure a certain income stream, and to provide incentives to the workers to work hard through deferred forms of pay, long-term employment relationships are in many instances conducive to economic efficiency (see Büchtemann and Walwei, 1996). Normally, long-term employment contracts are incomplete. A contract is incomplete when it does not specify each party’s obligations in every conceivable eventuality (Hart, 1987). The employment contract might be incomplete if parties are not able to foresee all future contingencies. If they envisage contingencies, it may just be too costly to write all those details into the contract. And even if they want to specify all those details in a contract, they may be unable to do so in such a way that a court can enforce their intentions because the necessary information cannot be verified by third parties, such as courts (see Malcomson, 1997, p. 1917). Even when legal enforcement is possible, it may be too costly. If parties do not write all their agreements explicitly down for the reasons just mentioned, they can still rely on an implicit type of long-term contract. For a review of long-term and incomplete contracts see Chapters 4100, Contractual Choice and 4200, Long-Term Contracts and Relational Contracts. It is fruitful to look at the employment contract as a combination of explicit and implicit agreements. An implicit agreement is an understanding that is not legally enforceable. We could think, for example, of the informal understanding between employer and employee that the employee will be rewarded when his effort level is high or when his attachment to the job is strong. Implicit contracts are not legally enforceable. This does not render the implicit agreement valueless. Implicit agreements will be made when parties can rely on self enforcement of the agreement. The basic idea of selfenforcing implicit contracts is that if both parties benefit from the continuance of the employment relationship, they will not cheat on their promises implicitly made. Self enforcing implicit contracts will exist only if upholding the agreement will generate a surplus for the two parties (MacLeod and Malcomson, 1987, 1989). The way in which the surplus is divided between the two parties is important, because this is what determines the form of the contract. Among others, Carmichael (1989) has summarized the potential sources for a surplus of self enforcing implicit contracts in the labor market.
5510
Labor Contracts
553
A first source for a surplus in the relationship is savings of direct mobility costs for each party. One of the earliest approaches (for example Baily, 1974) was to assume the existence of mobility costs for workers and costs for the employer of replacing workers. If employers profit more from the continued employment of their existing workforce than they could from hiring replacements, they will suffer losses, for example by failing to promote ‘good’ workers as promised and thereby inducing them to quit. Investment in specific human capital is a second source for a surplus. Terminating the contract is unattractive when it makes the investments disappear. Reputation is a third source for a surplus, as illustrated by Holmstrom (1981) and Carmichael (1984). If either employer or workers gain a reputation for breaking contracts when it is in their short term interest to do so, we might expect them to have difficulty in finding employers or workers to sign contracts with them in the future, that is they will acquire a bad reputation which is costly to them in the future. According to Bull (1987) strong reputation effects require that accurate information about breach of the agreement flows rapidly to a large portion of the labor market. It is unlikely that market-based or external reputation will, in many labor markets, be strong enough to support implicit agreements. While the market will not have timely, accurate information on the outcomes of trades within the firm, the information flows within the firms will be fast and accurate. It is these strong intrafirm reputations that will support implicit agreements. An unfair breach of a promise on the part of the employer could result in an unprofitable drop in the morale of the workforce. Efficiency wages can also do the trick. The employee will not quit when he will earn less elsewhere. If workers are receiving more from the existing relationship than they expect to receive elsewhere, they will automatically lose if they shirk on their duties and are fired as a consequence.
7. Conclusion It has been shown how parties to the employment contract cope with imperfections such as asymmetric information, uncertainty and opportunistic behavior with respect to different areas of the employment relationship. The employment contract has several roles or functions: to match employer and employee, to regulate and divide the surplus from relation-specific investments, to share risks and smooth the income stream and to induce a high effort level (Ehrenberg and Smith, 1997, p. 394). For many employees, setting a compensation policy consists of more than just ‘finding out’ the market wage for given jobs. Paying above-market wages might attract high-
554
Labor Contracts
5510
productivity workers, reduce the incentive of the employee to quit after receiving specific training and reduce the incentive to shirk. Risk-averse employees prefer certain income streams which leads to the rigid wage result of implicit contract theory; wages do not fluctuate in response to fluctuations in the firm’s output price. Rigid wages have also been proposed as a solution for the hold up problem. Besides explicit agreements, employers and employees exchange a set of informal, implicit promises regarding their current and future behavior. To make these implicit contacts self-enforcing there must be a surplus of the relationship and the challenge for employer and employee is to make arrangements concerning the division of the surplus.
Acknowledgements I would like to thank Gerrit De Geest and Jacques Siegers for helpful comments on the first draft. They are naturally not accountable for any remaining errors and shortcomings.
Bibliography on Labor Contracts (5510) Abowd, John M. and Card, David (1987), ‘Intertemporal Labor Supply and Long-Term Employment Contracts’, 77 American Economic Review, 50-68. Akerlof, George A. (1984), ‘Gift Exchange and Efficiency Wage Theory: Four Views’, 74 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 79-83. Antel, John J. (1985), ‘Costly Employment Contract Renegotiation and the Labor Mobility of Young Men’, 75 American Economic Review, 976-991. Arnott, Richard J., Hosios, Arthur J. and Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1988), ‘Implicit Contracts, Labor Mobility, and Unemploy ment’, 78 American Economic Review, 1046-1066. Azariadis, Costas (1987), ‘Implicit Contracts’, in Eatwell, John, Milgate, Murray and Newman, Peter (eds), The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, London, Macmillan, 733-737. Ball, Laurence (1987), ‘Externalities from Contract Length’, 77 American Economic Review, 615-629. Baron, David P. (1974), ‘Incentive Contracts and Competitive Bidding: Reply’, 64 American Economic Review, 1072-1073. Blaydon, Colin C. and Marshall, Paul W. (1974), ‘Incentive Contracts and Competitive Bidding: Comment’, 64 American Economic Review, 1070-1071. Canes, Michael E. (1975), ‘The Simple Economics of Incentive Contracting: Note’, 65 American Economic Review, 478-483. Cooper, Russell (1988), ‘Will Share Contracts Increase Economic Welfare?’, 78 American Economic Review, 138-154.
5510
Labor Contracts
555
Dana, James D., Jr and Spier, Kathryn E. (1993), ‘Expertise and Contingent Fees: The Role of Asymmetric Information in Attorney Compensation’, 9 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 349-367. Dau-Schmidt, Kenneth G. (1992), ‘A Bargaining Analysis of American Labor Law and the Search for Bargaining Equity and Industrial Peace’, 91 Michigan Law Review, 419 ff. Dau-Schmidt, Kenneth G. (1993a), ‘Bargaining Theory and Canadian Labour Law’, in Kuttner, T. (ed.), The Industrial Relations System: Proceedings of the XXIXth Conference of the Canadian Industrial Relations Association, 753 ff. Dau-Schmidt, Kenneth G. (1993b), ‘Meeting the Demands of Workers Into the Twenty-First Century: The Future of Labor and Employment Law’, 68 Indiana Law Journal, 685 ff. Dau-Schmidt, Kenneth G. (1995), ‘The Labor Market Transformed: Adapting Labor and Employment Law to the Rise of the Contingent Workforce’, 52 Washington and Lee Law Review, 879 ff. Dau-Schmidt, Kenneth G. (1996), ‘Employment Security: A Comparative Institutional Debate’, Texas Law Review. Dudley, Leonard (1986), ‘Implicit Labor Contracts and Public Choice: A General Equilibrium Approach’, 29 Journal of Law and Economics, 61-82. Dye, Ronald A. (1985), ‘Optimal Length of Labor Contracts’, 26 International Economic Review, 251-270. Flanagan, Robert J. (1984), ‘Implicit Contracts, Explicit Contracts, and Wages’, 74 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 345-349. Frech, H. Edward III (1985), ‘The Property Rights Theory of the Firm: Some Evidence from the U.S. Nursing Home Industry’, 141 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 146-166. Frech, H. Edward III, Borjas, George J. and Ginsburg, Paul B. (1983), ‘Property Rights and Wages: The Case of Nursing Homes’, 18(2) Journal of Human Resources, 231-246. Freeman, Smith (1977), ‘Wage Trends as Performance Displays Productive Potential: a Model and Application to Academic Early Retirement’, 8 Bell Journal of Economics, 419-443. Goldberg, Victor P. (1980), ‘Bridges Over Contested Terrain: Exploring the Radical Account of the Employment Relationship’, 1 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 249-274. Goldberg, Victor P. (1984), ‘A Relational Exchange Perspective on the Employment Relationship’, in Stephen, Frank H. (ed.), Firms, Organization and Labour: Approaches to the Economics of Work Organization, London, Macmillan, 127-145. Greene, Kenneth V. and Moulton, George D. (1986), ‘Municipal Employee Residency Requirement Statutes: An Economic Analysis’, 9 Research in Law and Economics, 185-204. Hall, Robert E. (1982), ‘The Importance of Lifetime Jobs in the U.S. Economy’, 72 American Economic Review, 716-724. Harris, Milton and Holmström, Bengt (1987), ‘On the Duration of Agreements’, 28 International Economic Review, 389-406.
556
Labor Contracts
5510
Harris, Milton and Raviv, Artur (1978), ‘Some Results on Incentive Contracts with Applications to Education and Employment, Health Insurance, and Law Enforcement’, 68 American Economic Review, 20-30. Hashimoto, Masanori and Yu, Ben T. (1980), ‘Specific Capital, Employment Contracts, and Wage Rigidity’, 11 Bell Journal of Economics, 536-549. Hertog, Johan A. and Kraamwinkel, Margriet M. (1991), ‘Pensioennadelen in Het Licht Van De Contracttheorie (Pension Disadvantages in the Light of Contract Theory)’, Economisch-Statistische Berichten, 908-912. Hirsch, Werner Z. (1989), ‘The Economics of Contracting Out: The Labor Cost Fallacy’, 40 Labor Law Journal, 536-542. Ichino, Pietro (1998), ‘Il Diritto del Lavoro e i Modelli Economici (Labour Law and Economic Models)’, Lavoro e Diritto, 309-322. Ickes, B.W. and Samuelson, Larry (1987), ‘Job Transfers and Incentives in Complex Organizations: Thwarting in the Ratchet Effect’, 18 Rand Journal of Economics, 275-286. Ioannides, Y.M. and Pissarides, C.A. (1983), ‘Wages and Employment with Firm-Specific Seniority’, 14 Bell Journal of Economics, 573-580. Klein, Benjamin (1984), ‘Contract Costs and Administered Prices: An Economic Theory of Rigid Wages’, 74 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 332-338. Kübler, Dorothea (1997), ‘Auctioning Off Labor Contracts: Legal Restrictions Reconsidered’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 63-74. Lazear, Edward P. (1984), ‘Incentives and Wage Rigidity’, 74 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 339-344. Lazear, Edward P. (1987), ‘Incentive Contracts’, in Eatwell, John, Milgate, Murray and Newman, Peter (eds), The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, London, MacMillan, 744-748. Lemley, Mark A. and Durie, Daralyn J. (1992), ‘The Antitrust Liability of Labor Unions for Anticompetitive Litigation’, 80 California Law Review, 757 ff. Lewis, Tracy R. (1980), ‘Bonuses and Penalties in Incentive Contracting’, 11 Bell Journal of Economics, 292-301. MacDonald, Glenn M. (1982), ‘Specific Investments and Nonlabor Income’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 225 ff. Magee, R.P. (1978), ‘Accounting Measurement and Employment Contracts: Current Value Reporting’, 9 Bell Journal of Economics, 145-158. Martin, Donald L. (1977), ‘The Economics of Employment Termination Rights’, 20 Journal of Law and Economics, 187-204. McCall, John, J. (1970), ‘The Simple Economics of Incentive Contracting’, 60 American Economic Review, 837-846. Murphy, Kevin J. (1986), ‘Incentives, Learning, and Compensation: A Theoretical and Empirical Investigation of Managerial Labor Contracts’, 17 Rand Journal of Economics, 59-76. Nogler, Luca (1992), ‘Una Ventata di Analisi Economica del Diritto in Tema di Contratto di Lavoro a Termine (Nota a Cass., sez. lav., 21 febbraio 1992, n. 2153, Matteucci c. Cassa risp. Città di Castello) (A Wave of Economic Analysis of Law on Forward Employment Contract)’, I Giustizia Civile, 2104-2105.
5510
Labor Contracts
557
Peltzman, Sam (1987), ‘Comment (on R. B. Freeman, ‘How Do Public Sector Wages and Employment Respond To Economic Conditions’)’, in Wise, D. (ed.), Public Sector Payrolls, Chicago, IL, University of Chicago Press. Petersen, Trond (1991), ‘Reward Systems and the Distribution of Wages’, 7(S) Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 130-158. Plaut, Steven E. (1986), ‘Implicit Contracts in the Absence of Enforcement: Note’, 76 American Economic Review, 257-258. Rasmusen, Eric and Zenger, Todd (1990), ‘Diseconomies of Scale in Employment Contracts’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 65-92. Roemer, J. (1979), ‘Divide and Conquer Microfoundations of a Marxian Theory of Wage Discrimination’, 10 Bell Journal of Economics, 695-705. Rosen, Sherwin (1982), ‘Authority, Control, and the Distribution of Earnings’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 311-323. Rubin, Paul H. and Shedd, Peter (1981), ‘Human Capital and Covenants Not to Compete’, 10 Journal of Legal Studies, 93-110. Schwab, Stewart J. (1987), ‘Collective Bargaining and the Coase Theorem’, 72 Cornell Law Review, 245-287. Schwab, Stewart J. (1992), ‘Union Raids, Union Democracy, and the Market for Union Control’, 22 University of Illinois Law Review, 367-416. Schwab, Stewart J. (1994), ‘Employment Life Cycles and the Employment-At-Will Doctrine’, 20 Cornell Law Forum, 7-11. Schwab, Stewart J. (1995), ‘The Diversity of Contingent Workers and the Need for Nuanced Policy’, 52 Washington and Lee Law Review, 915-933. Schwab, Stewart J. (1996), ‘Wrongful Discharge Law and the Search for Third-Party Effects’, Texas Law Review, 74 ff. Shadowen, Steve D. and Voytek, Kenneth (1984), ‘Note: Economic and Critical Analyses of the Law of Covenants Not To Compete’, 72 Georgetown Law Journal, 1425-1450. Simon, Herbert A. (1951), ‘A Formal Theory of the Employment Relationship’, 19 Econometrica, 293-305. Sklivas, S.D. (1987), ‘The Strategic Choice of Managerial Incentives’, 18 Rand Journal of Economics, 452-460. Spier, Kathryn E. and Dana, James D., Jr (1993), ‘Expertise and Contingent Fees: The Role of Asymmetric Information in Attorney Compensation’, 9 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 349-367. Taylor, John B. (1980), ‘Aggregate Dynamics and Staggered Contracts’, 88 Journal of Political Economy, 1-23. Topel, Robert H. and Welch, Finis (1986), ‘Efficient Labor Contracts with Employement Risk’, 17 Rand Journal of Economics, 490-507. Verkerke, J. Hoult (1995), ‘An Empirical Perspective on Indefinite Term Employment Contracts: Resolving the Just Cause Debate’, 61 Wisconsin Law Review, 837-918. Vogel, Kenneth R. (1983), ‘Analysis of Labour Contracts and their Administration Using Transaction Costs Economics’, 5 Law and Policy Quarterly, 129-152. Waldman, Michael (1984), ‘Job Assignments, Signalling, and Efficiency’, 15 Rand Journal of Economics, 255-267. Weitzman, Martin L. (1980), ‘Efficient Incentive Contracts’, 94 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 719-730.
558
Labor Contracts
5510
Weitzman, Martin L. (1984), The Share Economy. Conquering Stagflation, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 167 p. Williamson, Oliver E., Wachter, Michael L. and Harris, Jeffrey F. (1975), ‘Understanding the Employment Relation: The Analysis of Idiosyncratic Exchange’, 6 Bell Journal of Economics, 250-278. Willman, Paul (1982), ‘Opportunism in Labor Contracting: An Application of the Organizational Failures’ Framework’, 3 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 83-98.
Other References Akerlof, George A. (1970), ‘The Market for ‘Lemons’: Qualitative Uncertainty and the Market Mechanism’, 84 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 488-500. Alchian, Armen A. and Demsetz, Harold (1972), ‘Production, Information Costs, and Economic Organization’, 62 The American Economic Review, 777-795. Azariadis, Costas (1975), ‘Implicit Contracts and Underemployment Equilibria’, 83 Journal of Political Economy, 1183-1202. Azariadis, Costas and Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1983), ‘Implicit Contracts and Fixed-Price Equilibria’, 98 Quarterly Journal of Economics Supplement, 1-22. Baily, Martin N. (1974), ‘Wages and Employment under Uncertain Demand’, 41 Review of Economic Studies, 37-50. Becker, Gary S. (1962), ‘Investment in Human Capital: A Theoretical Analysis’, 70 Journal of Political Economy, S9-49. Becker, Gary S. (1975), Human Capital, 2nd edn, New York, National Bureau of Economic Research. Bhattacharya, Sudipto (1986), ‘Tournaments, Termination Schemes and Forcing contracts’, Bell Communications Research, Working Paper, December. Bosworth, Derek L., Dawkins, Peter J. and Stromback, Thorsten (1996), The Economics of the Labour Market, Harlow, Longman, 460 p. Büchtemann, Christoph F. and Walwei, Ulrich (1996), ‘Employment Security and Dismissal Protection’, in Schmid, Günther, O’Reilly, Jacqueline and Schönmann, Klaus (eds), International Handbook of Labour Market Policy and Evaluation, Cheltenham, Edward Elgar, 652-693. Bull, Clive (1987), ‘The Existence of Self Enforcing Implicit Contracts’, 102 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 147-159. Carmichael, H. Lorne (1984), ‘Reputations in the Labor Market’, 74 American Economic Review, 713-725. Carmichael, H. Lorne (1989), ‘Self Enforcing Contracts, Shirking, and Life Cycle Incentives’, 3 (4) Journal of Economic Perspectives, 65-83. De Geest, Gerrit (1994), Economische Analyse van het Contracten- en Quasi-Contractenrecht. Een Onderzoek naar de Wetenschappelijke Waarde van de Rechtseconomie (Economic Analysis of Contract Law and Quasi Contract Law. Research of the Scientific Value of Law and Economics), Antwerpen, Maklu, 568p. De Geest, Gerrit, Siegers, Jacques, Jaspers, Teun and Vandenberghe, Ann-Sophie (1999), ‘The Right to Lie: New Law and Economics versus Dutch Labour Law?’, in De Geest, Gerrit,
5510
Labor Contracts
559
Siegers, Jacques and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds), Law and Economics in the Labour Market, Cheltenham, Edward Elgar, forthcoming. Douma, Sytse W. and Schreuder, Hein (1998), Economic Approaches to Organizations, London, Prentice Hall, 238 p. Ehrenberg, Ronald G. and Smith, Robert S. (1997), Modern Labor Economics. Theory and Public Policy, Reading, MA, Addison-Wesley, 652 p. Elliott, Robert F. (1991), Labor Economics: A Comparative Text, London, McGraw-Hill, 536 p. Gordon, Donald F. (1974), ‘A Neo Classical Theory of Keynesian Unemployment’, 12(4) Economic Inquiry, 431-459. Hart, Oliver D. (1987), ‘Incomplete Contracts’, in Eatwell, John, Milgate, Murray and Newman, Peter (eds), The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, London, Macmillan, Volume 2, 752-759. Hart, Oliver D. and Holmstrom, Bengt (1986), ‘The Theory of Contracts’, in Bewley, Truman (ed.), Advances in Economic Theory, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Holstrom, Bengt (1981), ‘Contractual Models of the Labor Market’, 71 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 308-313. Klein, Benjamin, Crawford, Robert G. and Alchian, Armen A. (1978), ‘Vertical Integration, Appropriable Rents, and the Competitive Contracting Process’, 21 The Journal of Law and Economics, 297-326. Knight, Frank (1921) Risk, Uncertainty and Profit, Boston, Houghton Miffin. Lazear, Edward P. (1979), ‘Why is there Mandatory Retirement?’, 87 Journal of Political Economy, 1261-1284. Macleod, W. Bentley and Malcomson, James M. (1987), ‘Involuntary Unemployment in Dynamic Contract Equilibria’, 31 European Economic Review, 427-435. Macleod, W. Bentley and Malcomson, James M. (1989), ‘Implicit Contracts, Incentive Compatibility, and Involuntary Unemployment’, 57 Econometrica, 447-480. MacLeod, W. Bentley and Malcomson, James M. (1993), ‘Investments, Holdups, and the Form of Market Contracts’, 84 American Economic Review, 811-837. Malcomson, James M. (1984), ‘Work Incentives, Hierarchy, and Internal Labor Markets’, 92 Journal of Political Economy, 486-507. Malcomson, James M. (1986), ‘Rank Order Contracts for a Principal with Many Agents’, 53 Review of Economic Studies, 807-817. Malcomson, James M. (1997), ‘Contracts, Hold up, and Labor markets’, 35 Journal of Economic Literature, 1917-1957. Manning, A. (1990), ‘Implicit Contract Theory’, in Sapsford, David and Tzannatos, Zafiris (eds), Current Issues in Labour Economics, Basingstoke, Macmillan, 63-85. Mincer, Jacob (1962), ‘On-The-Job Training: Costs, Returns, and Some Implications’, 70 The Journal of Political Economy, 50-79. Oi, Walter Y. (1962), ‘Labor as a Quasi Fixed Factor’, 70 Journal of Political Economy, 538-555. Parsons, Donald O. (1972), ‘Specific Human Capital: An Application to Quit Rates and Layoff Rates’, 80 Journal of Political Economy, 1120-1143. Parsons, Donald O. (1986), ‘The Employment Relationship: Job Attachment, Work Effort, and the Nature of Contracts’, in Ashenfelter, Orley C. and Layard, Richard G., Handbook of Labor Economics, Amsterdam, North-Holland, Volume 2, 789-848.
560
Labor Contracts
5510
Pencavel, John H. (1972), ‘Wages, Specific Training, and Labor Turnover in U.S. Manufacturing Industries’, 13 International Economic Review, 53-64. Rosen, Sherwin (1994), Implicit Contract Theory, Aldershot, Edward Elgar, 467p. Salop, J. and Salop Steven C. (1976), ‘Self Selection and Turnover in the Labor Market’, 90 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 619-627. Salop, Steven C. (1973), ‘Wage Differentials in a Dynamic Theory of the Firm’, 6 Journal of Economic Theory, 321-344. Salop, Steven C. (1979), ‘A Model of the Natural Rate of Unemployment’, 69 The American Economic Review, 117-125. Schäfer, Hans-Bernd and Ott, Claus (1993), Lehrbuch der Ökonomischen Analyse des Zivilrechts (Handbook of the Economic Analysis of Civil Law), Berlin, Springer-Verlag, 2nd edn. Shapiro, Carl and Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1984), ‘Equilibrium Unemployment as a Worker Discipline Device’, 75 American Economic Review, 433-444. Smith, Adam (1776), The Wealth of Nations, Oxford, Clarendon. Spence, Michael (1973), ‘Job Market Signaling’, 87 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 355-374. Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1974), ‘Alternative Theories of Wage Determination and Unemployment in LDC’s: The Labor Turnover Model’, 88 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 194-227. Teulings, Coenraad N (1996), De Plaats van de Vakbeweging in de Toekomst (The Future Position of Labour Unions), Amsterdam, Welboom, 96p. Weiss, Andrew (1980), ‘Job Queues and Layoffs in Labor Markets with Flexible Wages’, 88 Journal of Political Economy, 526-538. Weiss, Andrew (1991), Efficiency Wages: Models of Unemployment, Layoffs, and Wage Dispersion, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 118 p. Williamson, Oliver E. (1985), The Economic Institutions of Capitalism: Firms, Markets, Relational Contracts, New York, Free Press.
5520 MINIMUM WAGE LEGISLATION Simon Deakin Reader in Economic Law and Assistant Director, ESRC Centre for Business Research, University of Cambridge
Frank Wilkinson Senior Research Officer, Department of Applied Economics and ESRC Centre for Business Research, University of Cambridge © Copyright 1999 Simon Deakin and Frank Wilkinson
Abstract Economists have traditionally been hostile to minimum wage legislation, seeing it as an unwarranted interference with the operation of the market and a cause of unemployment among the less skilled. Recent evidence from the USA and the UK claims to show, however, that employment rises when minimum wage laws are introduced and falls when such laws are repealed. A number of explanations have been offered for these findings, ranging from monopsony effects to labour market segmentation. There are trade-offs between short-run adjustment costs and long-run improvements to productivity and performance which are, however, difficult to assess. From the point of view of the economics of law, the minimum wage studies show how important empirical work is in testing and reshaping economic theory. JEL classification: K31, J38 Keywords: Unemployment, Household Poverty
1. Introduction Most developed economies (and many developing ones) set a legal minimum level to wages, either through statute or by giving legal force to the terms of collective agreements negotiated between employers and trade unions. Economists, however, have traditionally been hostile to minimum wage legislation and to labour standards more generally, seeing them as an unwarranted interference with the operation of the market and a cause of unemployment among the less skilled. Recent evidence from the USA and the UK claims to show, however, that employment rises when minimum wage laws are introduced (Card and Krueger, 1995) and falls when such laws are repealed (Dickens et al., 1993). The story of how these findings 561
562
Minimum Wage Legislation
5520
have been evaluated by the economics profession is of considerable interest in itself for what it tells us about the present state of economic theory and the way in which it intersects with the law.
2. The Traditional Neoclassical Account In the traditional neoclassical account of the labour market, competition between firms for labour, and between workers for jobs, ensures that wage rates for labour of comparable productivity are more or less equal throughout the market and beyond the power of any individual economic actor to affect. The movement of the market towards equilibrium acts as an implicit regulator of individual decisions on whether to trade and at what price. Firms which attempt to pay below the market rate risk losing their workers to competitors, in the same way that workers who attempt to force up wages above the competitive level risk losing their jobs as firms at the margin substitute labour for capital or cease to trade. Repeated empirical studies - surveys and case-studies of firms dating back to the first large-scale studies of low pay in Britain and the USA - have shown that, in reality, labour markets do not display these characteristics (see Nolan, 1983). Firms do not automatically adjust wages to changes in demand for labour, and there is considerable divergence in the pay and conditions offered by different employers to workers doing similar jobs. Neoclassical theory tries to explain away these findings by the argument that freely competitive markets tend towards equilibrium. Limitations upon the flow of information and upon the mobility and substitutability of factors of production are overcome in time by the unravelling of competitive market forces. The market itself is seen as a powerful force for equality: under conditions of perfect competition, equal pay for work of equal value would follow from the operation of supply and demand. Where apparent inequalities in pay persist, they are viewed as the result of pre-market factors: differences between individuals in terms of endowment and ability, differences in individuals’ ‘tastes’ for work, training or leisure, or differences in employers’ ‘tastes’ for discrimination (Becker, 1957). Regulation is also seen as an exogenous cause of inequality, preventing market clearing. Public choice theory regards labour legislation as the outcome of organised pressure-group activity (Heldman, Bennett and Johnson, 1981; Rowley, 1985). Trade unions, according to this point of view, are labour monopolists seeking to cartelise the labour market. By driving wages above the market or equilibrium rate, they depress demand for employment and divert resources into wasteful rent-seeking. The costs of trade union activity are borne by consumers, in the form of artificially high
5520
Minimum Wage Legislation
563
prices, and the unemployed, who are ‘priced out’ of work. Trade union legislation, by supporting collective bargaining and the right to strike, ensures that these inefficient monopoly practices are protected against the market forces which would otherwise drive them out (Posner, 1984). On similar grounds, it is predicted that minimum wage laws would have a disproportionately adverse impact on the young, those without formal training or qualifications, and those re-entering the labour market after a long absence (such as the long-term unemployed) (Minford, 1985).
3. Empirical Evidence The minimum wage has given rise to a vast empirical literature. Until recently, the consensus was that the introduction of a minimum wage and subsequent rises in its level would both almost certainly lead to increases in youth unemployment, and sometimes to increases in adult unemployment (Brown, Gilroy and Kohen, 1982). However, this conclusion rested mainly upon time-series studies using long-term aggregate data of teenage unemployment derived from a single source, the US Current Population Survey. Critics suggested that these studies could not be regarded as definitive since the estimated employment effects are small and also highly sensitive to the choice of sample period (Card, 1991). Case studies by Card, Katz and Krueger examining the implementation of minimum wage reforms in various US states in the late 1980s and early 1990s presented a different picture (see Card, 1991; Card, Katz and Krueger, 1993; Card and Krueger, 1995). The research took advantage of the opportunity for comparative study which arose from the variations in rates of increase between states, and by the decision of the US Congress in the late 1980s to raise the federal minimum wage after a period of several years when its nominal value remained constant and its real value declined. One study examined the effects of raising the minimum wage in California in 1987, comparing teenage employment rates with those in states which did not increase their minima at the same time. It was found that both the earnings and the employment of teenagers in California increased after the minimum wage was raised, despite over half the teenage employees in the state being affected, a very high compliance rate, and few exemptions being allowed in the legislation. Similarly, a study comparing New Jersey, which increased its minimum wage, with Pennsylvania, which did not, found evidence of increasing employment in the former state. An analysis of the implementation of changes in the federal law in the fast food industry in Texas, a sector employing mostly part-time workers and with labour turnover rates in excess of 300 percent per annum, found that most
564
Minimum Wage Legislation
5520
employers observed the new adult rates for the minimum wage but that few took advantage of the possibility of paying a teenage sub-minimum. Over 70 percent of the firms interviewed did not report responding to the new rates by either dismissing workers or cutting fringe benefits. In Britain during the same period, minimum wage regulation was being weakened as a consequence of legislation which cut back the powers of the Wages Councils (wage-setting bodies operating at industry level in certain sectors). After 1986 they were prevented from setting rates for younger workers and in 1993 their powers to set wages and conditions were completely removed. Prior to the 1986 Act it was ‘confidently postulated’ that the abolition of the Wages Councils would ‘serve to expand employment [and] offer competitive wages for the socially disadvantaged’ (Minford, 1985, p. 122). However, econometric studies found that employment in low-paying service sectors declined as a result of the decreasing effectiveness of the Wages Councils (Machin and Manning, 1994; Dickens et al., 1993). In a similar vein, studies of the UK Equal Pay Act 1970 found that while the legislation was responsible for a considerable narrowing of the male-female gap, this was accompanied without a fall in female employment levels (Zabalza and Tzannatos, 1985).
4. Alternative Theoretical Perspectives The US findings on the positive impact upon employment of minimum wage increases produced a stormy debate. Some critics argued against the use of a comparative case study methodology, while others sought to provide different explanations for the observed employment effects (see Keenan, 1995; Neumark and Wascher, 1995). However, when the findings are taken together with the British research which demonstrates the converse effect the negative consequences of weakening minimum wage enforcement - they can be seen to have far-reaching implications for the conventional understanding of how labour market regulation works. Under these circumstances, it is not surprising that attention has focused on alternative theoretical perspectives. One possibility which is compatible with orthodox neoclassical theory is that employers in low-wage sectors are monopsonists holding a degree of market power over their employees. This enables them to keep their wages below the equilibrium or external market rate. It would be in the interests of such employers to avoid taking on new employees at the market rate if they then felt obliged, on the grounds of equity, to raise the wages of their existing employees. Under such conditions, a limited rise in the minimum wage would necessarily lead to a rise in employment, as the higher wages
5520
Minimum Wage Legislation
565
attracted new recruits into the industry concerned. Too large a rise, on the other hand, would lead to unemployment, particularly where there were wide variations in the degree of monopsony power which individual firms possessed (Stigler, 1946). A more radical departure from the orthodox account is provided by theories of labour market segmentation. These focus on the link between low pay and industrial structure, and take a historical and institutional perspective which is to some degree compatible with theories of path dependence or institutional lock-in. It is argued that since low pay is concentrated in particular occupations and industries, pay inequality cannot be wholly explained by differences in the skill and quality of individual workers (Craig et al., 1982). Rather, low pay comes to be associated with jobs which are socially undervalued or which are performed by workers who are accorded a low labour market status. ‘Undervaluation’ is a consequence of a number of factors including employer strategies, differences in the effectiveness of worker organisation, and the division of labour within the household. For example, one effect of the sexual division of labour is that skills traditionally associated with women’s non-waged labour in the home, such as caring and cleaning, command lower pay in the labour market than other comparable ‘male’ skills. Linking women’s pay to skill levels is, in practice, highly problematic. Studies comparing male and female earnings across a range of occupations have suggested that as much as three quarters of the wage gap between men and women in comparable jobs could not be put down to skill-related factors (Horrell, Burchell and Rubery, 1989). A labour market segmentation perspective leads to a very different view of minimum wage legislation (Deakin and Wilkinson, 1992). Rather than it being an ‘artificial’ interference in the free market, it becomes just one form of regulation which, together with other conventions, norms and customary practices, governs the way in which labour is contracted. The case for legislation is that as a consequence of segmentation, certain groups in the labour market will not have access to voluntary means of labour organisation, such as collective bargaining or the protection of professional rules governing entry and access to jobs. Hence the industries in which low pay is endemic are those in which there are structural factors, such as ease of entry by both firms (the result of low capital requirements) and workers (the result of the failure to develop and enforce formal skills and qualification requirements), which impede the effective organisation of labour and hence the application of common terms and conditions. Although these sectors appear more than any other to resemble the neoclassical ‘norm’ of free competition, in fact they are the exception. The persistence of these conditions creates the basis for a fundamental disequilibrium: low pay is in effect a subsidy, enabling otherwise uncompetitive firms and industries to
566
Minimum Wage Legislation
5520
survive. Minimum wage regulation is therefore necessary in order to help create an environment in which firms compete not on the basis of low pay but instead through high labour quality and product and process innovation (Deakin and Wilkinson, 1999). Equally, placing a floor under wages can augment the purchasing power of workers and so underpin effective demand (Michie, 1987; Prasch, 1996). These macroeconomic effects have indeed been prominent among the justifications offered for the introduction of minimum wage regulation in most of the systems adopting it.
5. Dynamic Effects of Introducing and Raising the Minimum Wage The general case for retaining a minimum wage, if one is in place, is distinct from more specific arguments for and against introducing or reintroducing minimum wage regulation. A fundamental change of this kind in the regulatory framework may well have far-reaching effects which cannot be precisely predicted. Moreover, it is unlikely that the effects will all be in one direction. Although an argument can be made, as we have just seen, for long-term efficiencies arising from the presence of a statutory wage floor, these may have to be traded off against short-run adjustment costs as some enterprises go out of businesses and workers retrain. Other matters to be decided include the level at which the minimum wage is set, and the mechanism through which it is subsequently varied. Many of these issues have been the focus of intense debate in Britain since the election of a Labour government in 1997 which was committed to reintroducing minimum wage regulation after an interval of four years during which no minimum wages of any kind were in operation. The government-appointed Low Pay Commission (LPC), which reported in June 1998, recommended the introduction of a national minimum wage (previously minimum rates only had the force of law in certain industries) (LPC, 1998). The proposed rate was towards the lower end of the range put forward by advocates of the minimum wage, namely £3.60 per hour from April 1999, rising to £3.70 in June 2000. The £3.60 figure represented about 45 percent of median earnings and was expected to affect about 11 percent of the working population over the age of 20. Sixteen and 17 year olds were to be exempt and 18-20 year olds were to receive a lower rate of £3.20 per hour from April 1999, rising to £3.30 in June 2000. The Commission estimated that the effect of introducing these reforms would be to add 0.6 percent to the total national wage bill; the sectors most heavily affected would be cleaning, catering and security, while the groups to benefit most included women workers and homeworkers. The government accepted the
5520
Minimum Wage Legislation
567
Commission’s recommendations for adult workers but set the starting rate for 18-20 year olds at £3.00 per hour, rising to £3.20 by June 2000. The work of the UK Low Pay Commission represents an interesting example of the use of economic evidence to aid public policy. The Commission was sympathetic to the monopsony model, noting its implication that ‘moderate minima can be introduced without destroying jobs’ (LPC, 1998, p. 114), while at the same time noting the broader ‘undervaluation’ argument in particular as it applied to female labour (LPC, 1998, p. 115). It also considered that the introduction of a minimum wage could have an impact on industrial structure: Whatever the nature of the labour market, it is likely that a National Minimum Wage will have a greater effect on the structure of employment than on its level. Businesses which are inefficient or which produce low value-added goods may need to reorganise working practices. If the National Minimum Wage is properly enforced, business and employment are likely to transfer to more efficient firms or to those offering higher value-added products and services … minimum wages may cause a transfer of jobs between groups such as the substitution of more skilled for less skilled workers … . (LPC, 1998, 115)
It is debatable whether the level set by the Low Pay Commission is sufficiently high to realise these potentially beneficial effects of reintroducing a minimum wage. A minimum wage set at about 45 percent of median earnings is low by international standards (the minimum wage in France, for example, is 57 percent of the median), although it is higher than the US federal minimum. In setting the rate at a low level, the Commission may have minimised the short-run adjustment costs of low-paying employers, at the expense of forfeiting a longer run improvement in productivity and economic performance from this source. A significant feature of the new UK legislation is that no provision is made for automatic increases of the minimum wage in future years. In the USA, a similar lack of automatic uprating has led to stagnation and decline in the level of the federal minimum, and has turned the level of the minimum wage into a hotly debated political issue, so arguably increasing the scope for wasteful pressure group activity (Sachdev and Wilkinson, 1999). In France, by contrast, legislation embodies a formula whereby the ‘minimum growth wage’, the salaire minimum interprofessionel de croissance or SMIC, rises automatically with prices and with at least half the increase in the purchasing power of the average wage. This has ensured that, alone of minimum wage systems in western Europe, the SMIC has retained its real value since the mid-1980s (OECD, 1998, chapter 2).
568
Minimum Wage Legislation
5520
6. The Minimum Wage, Household Poverty and Work Incentives The minimum wage, it is sometimes said, disproportionately benefits households with more than one person in employment, some of whom are so-called ‘secondary’ earners (typically wives and children of a male ‘breadwinner’). In practice, the employment of ‘secondary’ earners is often essential to improving the living standards of multiple earner households. A more important objection is that minimum wage appears at first sight to offer no means of relieving poverty in households with no member in employment. In practice, however, the minimum wage may assist the unemployed by improving work incentives. This depends upon how the minimum wage interacts with the benefits system. The contribution of the minimum wage to alleviating poverty and inequality needs to be set in the context of other, complementary measures, in particular those operating through the social security system. The institutional choice here is whether to have a system based on wage-substitutes, such as an extended negative income tax, or whether to use the minimum wage in conjunction with social security benefits to provide incentives for the non-employed to re-enter the labour market at a wage level which makes it worth their while to work. In Britain, the former system was in operation between 1986 and 1997. Social security benefits were targeted on low-paid earners with families at the same time as the minimum wage was abolished. Because these benefits were (unavoidably) means tested, they were progressively withdrawn as earnings from wages increased, so extending the ‘poverty trap’ which reduces the incentive for workers to take better paid jobs or jobs involving longer hours (Deakin and Wilkinson, 1991). Moreover, since employers could reduce wage levels or at least avoid increasing them in the knowledge that the difference would be met by social security, the state was in a position of subsidising low-paying firms which were often among the least efficient in terms of productivity. This reinvention of the Speenhamland system (see Polanyi, 1944) soon led to huge increases in state expenditure on benefits for the low paid. After 1997, the election of a new government led to a change in emphasis. Benefits to the low paid were retained but restructured with the intention of building on the level set by the minimum wage rather than directly substituting for it. As part of these reforms, taxes and social security contributions for the lower paid were substantially reduced. The aim of the reforms was to ‘demonstrate the rewards of work over welfare’ (Treasury, 1998).
5520
Minimum Wage Legislation
569
7. Conclusion The recent debate over the minimum wage demonstrates the remarkably tenacious hold which orthodox neoclassical theory has over the economics profession, even when confronted with evidence which, to say the least, puts in doubt the predictive capacity of that theory. From the point of view of the economics of law, the minimum wage studies show how important empirical work is in testing and reshaping economic theory. The hostility of mainstream law and economics towards labour regulation, as exemplified by the symposium on labour market published in the University of Chicago Law Review in 1984, is just one of many instances in which apparently clear-cut normative conclusions were drawn from models which had only a weak link to real-world conditions. From an institutional perspective such as that which can be drawn from the theory of labour market segmentation, the effects of the minimum wage - in particular, the consequences of introducing or raising the minimum - can be seen to be highly complex. There are trade-offs between short-run adjustment costs and long-run improvements to productivity and performance which are, however, difficult to assess. This may lead us to conclude that while the economic analysis of labour standards may help improve our understanding of how such laws operate, in and of itself it does not provide clear normative guidance to policy makers. At the end of the day, the case for social policy interventions will continue to be made on broader, ethical grounds.
Bibliography on Minimum Wage Legislation (5520) Becker, G. (1957), The Economics of Discrimination, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Brown, C., Gilroy, G. and Kohen, A. (1982), 'The Effect of the Minimum Wage on Employment and Unemployment', 20 Journal of Economic Literature, 487-528. Brozen, Yale (1962), 'Minimum Wage Rates and Household Workers', 5 Journal of Law and Economics, 103-109. Brozen, Yale (1969), 'The Effect of Statutory Minimum Wage Increases on Teen-Age Employment', 12 Journal of Law and Economics, 109-122. Card, D. (1991), Do Minimum Wages Reduce Employment? A Case Study of California 1987-1989, NBER Working Paper, 3710. Card, D. and Krueger, A. (1995), Myth and Measurement - the New Economics of the Minimum Wage, Princeton, Princeton University Press. Card, D., Katz, L. and Krueger, A. (1993), An Evaluation of Recent Evidence on the Employment Effects of Minimum and Subminimum Wages, NBER Working Paper, 4528. Colberg, Marshall R. (1960), 'Minimum Wage Effects on Florida's Economic Development', 3 Journal of Law and Economics, 106-117.
570
Minimum Wage Legislation
5520
Cousineau, Jean-Michel (1991), 'L'Effet du Salaire Minimum sur le Chômage des Jeunes et des Femmes au Québec: une Réestimation et un Réexamen de la Question (The Impact of a Minimum Wage on Unemployment of Young People and Women in Quebec: A New Look at the Question)', 67 Actualité Economique, 144-165. Craig, C., Rubery, J., Tarling, R. and Wilkinson, F. (1982), Labour Market Structure, Industrial Organisation, and Low Pay, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. De Bruyne, G. (1987), 'Inkomensvorming en Deregulering van de Arbeidsmarkt: 2. Indexering (Income Formation and Deregulation in the Labour Market: Indexation)', in X (ed.), 18de Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Brussel 8 en 9 mei 1987, Sociaal-economische Deregulering, Brussel, V.E.H.U.B., 249-263. Deakin, Simon and Wilkinson, Frank (1991), 'Labour Law, Social Security and Economic Inequality', 15 Cambridge Journal of Economics, 125-148. Deakin, Simon and Wilkinson, Frank (1992), 'The Law and Economics of the Minimum Wage', 19 Journal of Law and Society, 379-392. Deakin, Simon and Wilkinson, Frank (1999), 'Labour Law and Economic Theory - a Reappraisal', in De Geest, Gerrit, Van den Bergh, R. and Siegers, Jacques J. (eds), Law and Economics and the Labour Market, Aldershot, Edward Elgar. Dickens, R., Gregg, P., Machin, S., Manning, A. and Wadsworth, J. (1993), 'Wages Councils - Was there a Case for Abolition?', 31 British Journal of Industrial Relations, 515-529. Fortin, Pierre (1980), Les Conditions Minimales de Travail: leurs Conséquences Économiques (The Fixation of Minimum Working Conditions: Their Economic Consequences), 35e Congrès des Relations Industrielles, La Détermination des Conditions Minimales de Travail par l'État: une Loi: son Économie et sa Portée. Hashimoto, Masanori (1987), 'The Minimum Wage Law and Youth Crimes: Time-Series Evidence', 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 443-464. Heldman, D., Bennett, J. and Johnson, M. (1981), Deregulating Labor Relations, Dallas, Fisher Institute. Horrell, S., Burchell, B. and Rubery, J. (1989), 'Unequal Jobs or Unequal Pay?', 20 Industrial Relations Journal, 176-191. Keenan, J. (1995), 'The Elusive Effects of the Minimum Wage', 33 Journal of Economic Literature, 1950-1965. Leffler, Keith B. (1978), 'Minimum Wages, Welfare, and Wealth Transfers to the Poor', 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 345-358. Low Pay Commission (1998), The National Minimum Wage. First Report of the Low Pay Commission, Cm 3976. Machin, S. and Manning, A. (1994), 'Minimum Wages, Wage Dispersion, and Employment: Evidence from UK Wages Councils', 47 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 319-329. Michie, Jonathan (1987), Wages in the Business Cycle: An Empirical and Methodological Analysis, Oxford, Basil Blackwell. Minford, P. (1985), Unemployment: Cause and Cure (2nd edn), Oxford, Basil Blackwell. Miyagiwa, Kaz (1989), 'Human Capital and Economic Growth in a Minimum Wage Economy', 30 International Economic Review, 187-202. Neumark, D. and Wascher, W. (1995), The Effect of New Jersey's Minimum Wage on Fast Food Employment: a Re-Evaluation Using Payroll Data, NBER Working Paper, 5224.
5520
Minimum Wage Legislation
571
Nolan, P. (1983), 'Labour Market Behaviour and the Firm', in Bain, G. (ed.), Industrial Relations in Britain, Oxford, Basil Blackwell. OECD (1998), Employment Outlook, Paris, OECD. Polanyi, K. (1944), The Great Transformation, New York, Rinehart & Winston. Posner Richard A. (1984), 'Some Economics of Labor Law', 51 University of Chicago Law Review, 988-1004. Prasch, R. (1996), 'In Defense of the Minimum Wage', 30 Journal of Economic Issues, 391-398. Rottenberg, Simon (ed.) (1981), The Economics of Legal Minimum Wages, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research. Rowley, Charles K. (1985), 'The Relationship between Economics, Politics and Law in the Formation of Public Policy', in Matthews, R.C.O. (ed.), Economy and Democracy, New York, St. Martin's Press. Rubin, Paul H. and Kau, James B. (1978), 'Voting on Minimum Wages: A Time Series Analysis', Journal of Political Economy, 337-342. Sachdev, Sanjiv and Wilkinson, Frank (1999), The Labour Market, the Minimum Wage, and the Low Pay Commission Report, CBR Working Paper, 110. Shaviro, Daniel N. (1997), 'The Minimum Wage, the Earned Income Tax Credit, and Optimal Subsidy Policy', 64 University of Chicago Law Review. Stigler, George J. (1946), 'The Economics of Minimum Wage Legislation', 36 American Economic Review, 358-365. Treasury (1998), The Modernisation of Britain's Tax and Benefit System. Number Three: The Working Families Tax Credit and Work Incentives, London, Her Majesty's Treasury. Trejo, Stephen J. (1991), 'The Effects of Overtime Pay Regulation on Worker Compensation', 81 American Economic Review, 719-740. Uri, Noel D. and Mixon, J. Wilson, Jr (1980), 'An Economic Analysis of the Determinants of Minimum Wage Voting Behavior', 23 Journal of Law and Economics, 167-177. Yaniv, Gideon (1994), 'Complaining about Noncompliance with the Minimum Wage Law', 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 351-362. Zabalza, A. and Tzannatos, T. (1985), Women and Equal Pay. The Effects of Legislation on Female Employment and Wages in Britain, Oxford, Basil Blackwell.
5530 EMPLOYMENT DISCRIMINATION Stewart J. Schwab Professor of Law Cornell University School of Law © Copyright 1999 Stewart J. Schwab
Abstract This chapter first discusses the multiple overlapping definitions of discrimination, including distinctions between group and individual discrimination and between segregation and discrimination in pay. It then summarizes the major economic models of discrimination, particularly Becker’s taste-for-discrimination model and statistical-discrimination models, as well as sorting and status-production models. The discussion focuses on the conditions under which markets will tend to eliminate discrimination, noting that this occurs in a more limited range of situations than commonly recognized. The chapter next surveys the economic role of anti-discrimination laws, evaluating arguments that the law speeds the journey to a non-discriminatory equilibrium and that the law breaks social norms perpetuating inefficient discrimination. Finally, it examines empirical studies of employment discrimination laws, including analyses of litigation trends and of the laws’ effects on labor markets. JEL classification: J15, J16, J70, J71, J78 Keywords: Discrimination; Statistical Discrimination; Status-Production Model
1. Scope of Law and Economics Analysis of Employment Discrimination The law and economics scholarship on employment discrimination examines the welfare consequences of the legal rules regulating employment discrimination. While substantial overlap exists, the inquiry is distinct from the efforts of labor economists to determine the extent of discrimination in labor markets. For recent surveys in this vein, see Darity and Mason (1998); Blau (1998). It is also distinct from the efforts of academic lawyers to describe and criticize employment discrimination laws. The major task of law and economics work surveyed here is to link the two inquiries by studying the effects of law on the labor market. This review limits itself to the literature on race and sex discrimination, ignoring the important areas of
572
5530
Employment Discrimination
573
age discrimination (see Posner, 1995, for an excellent overview of the issues), and disability discrimination.
2. Definitions of Discrimination The term ‘discrimination’ is elusive. A wine expert is admired for his discriminating taste, but an employer with a taste for racial discrimination is despised (see Cooter, 1994, p. 137). For an extensive discussion of various definitions of discrimination, see Kelman (1991). An overly broad definition would say that an employer discriminates whenever it distinguishes between two workers because they belong to different groups. To see that the definition is too broad, consider an employer who pays ‘highly productive’ workers more than ‘less productive’ workers. Although distinctions based on productivity (or, more broadly, merit) violate a policy of egalitarianism, they do not implicate traditional concerns of discrimination. One must be careful with the meaning of ‘productivity’ as well. Aigner and Cain (1977) define productivity in terms of physical output or actual job performance. They recognize that discrimination against, say, blacks, can always be explained away if their productivity includes antipathy they create in others unrelated to their output or performance. As a second attempt at definition, perhaps discrimination occurs whenever an employer treats equally productive workers differently because of any group characteristic other than, but perhaps related to, productivity. As Cooter (1994, p. 137) suggests, ‘discrimination in economic life usually consists in sorting people according to traits rather than productivity’. This definition, at least for law, is both too broad and too narrow. The definition is over broad because every distinction can be said to be based on a group characteristic, but only some group distinctions are discriminatory. The problem comes in separating invidious discrimination from appropriate (or benign, or merit-based, or non-problematic) distinctions. For example, an employer might distinguish between equally productive college and high school graduates, or between equally productive workers scoring 95 and 85 on a test, or between equally productive black and white workers. Only the last distinction is generally labeled discrimination, because it is based on a suspect or protected group. Anti-discrimination laws have prohibited employers from making distinctions on a number of characteristics, including race, color, sex, age, religion, national origin, age, sexual orientation, marital status and disability. In general, but not invariably, these are immutable characteristics over which the person has no control. Often they are irrelevant characteristics for proper or profit-maximizing employment decisions, but models of statistical discrimination wrestle with situations when these characteristics are correlated with productivity. Epstein (1992, p. 413) has
574
Employment Discrimination
5530
attacked as inherently arbitrary the labeling of certain distinctions as invidious discrimination. As he puts it, a ‘central part of [my] argument against Title VII was that there is no independent conception of which characteristics count as “merit” characteristics and which are invidious’. While difficult lines must be drawn (do distinctions based on beauty, obesity, or veteran’s status count as discriminatory?), the law has singled out a few distinctions as legally discriminatory, the most important being distinctions based on race and sex. Still, it is too narrow to define discrimination as occurring only when an employer treats two equally productive workers differently because of a protected characteristic. This definition matches the legal concept of ‘disparate treatment’ fairly closely. But the definition is narrower than one that focuses on effects. A worker in a protected group could be said to be discriminated against whenever he or she is treated differently than someone in another group on grounds other than productivity. This definition includes the legal concept of ‘disparate impact’. For example, employers often distinguish between workers on the basis of non-protected characteristics, such as education, test scores, or criminal convictions. While the anti-discrimination laws do not protect criminals or those with low education or test scores, the laws do forbid employers from distinguishing on such a trait if it has a disparate impact on racial or gender lines and the employer cannot demonstrate that the practice is job related and a business necessity. Some scholars, including Aigner and Cain (1977), have separated individual from group discrimination. They argue that individual or within-group discrimination is inevitable. As an example, they note that when college graduates are paid their average productivity and high school graduates paid their (lower) average productivity, some high-school graduates will be paid less than their individual productivity (and others paid more, although rarely will an individual complain about being overpaid). But no group discrimination exists. Similarly, they note that racial group discrimination might not occur even when black and white individuals of the same underlying ability are not paid equally, because the overpayment of some might cancel the underpayment of others. In their definition, then, discrimination only occurs when groups with the same average productivity receive different average pay. Anti-discrimination law, however, does not separate individual and group discrimination. An individual black who is treated worse than a white with the same productivity has a claim under the anti-discrimination laws, regardless of whether other blacks might be treated better than whites of corresponding ability. A final definitional complication is that some writers separate discrimination from segregation. For example, Becker (1971, p. 57) declared
5530
Employment Discrimination
575
that ‘[m]any serious errors have been committed because of a failure to recognize that market segregation and market discrimination are separate concepts’. Racial discrimination occurs when blacks earn less than whites of comparable productivity; racial segregation occurs when race affects job assignments by particular firms. Segregation without discrimination can occur when all-black firms pay workers the same as all-white firms of equal productivity. Discrimination without segregation occurs when blacks and whites of equal productivity work in the same firms but blacks are paid less. Segregation and discrimination can go together. Strauss (1991, p. 1635) has warned of the long-term dangers of ‘separate but equal’ segregation. Anti-discrimination laws prohibit employers both from discriminating in wages and from segregating their workforces.
3. Economic Models of Discrimination Economists have developed two prominent models of why employers discriminate - a taste model and a statistical discrimination model. Two other models - a sorting model and a status-production model - have appeared more recently. 3.1 Becker’s Taste for Discrimination Model In the 1950s, Becker ([1957] 1971) introduced the ‘taste for discrimination’ model that captures the intuitive notion of invidious discrimination. An employer has a taste for discrimination, according to Becker, when he acts ‘as if he were willing to pay something ... to be associated with some persons instead of others’ (Becker, 1971, p. 14). This definition is general enough to finesse the issue discussed above of which group distinctions are discriminatory, but Becker focused on race discrimination. Assume that group-W and group-B workers (to update Becker’s original notation of W and N) are equally productive, and that employers are willing to pay ‘d’ not to associate with B workers. In equilibrium, the market wage for W workers is w, equal to the marginal revenue product of W workers. The wage of B workers, however, is w - d. Under this model, in the short run black workers will receive a lower wage than white workers of equal productivity, and discriminatory firms will earn lower monetary profits than non-discriminatory firms. Becker also introduced variants of his model in which customers or employees had a taste for discrimination, meaning that they would demand lower prices or higher wages when associating with black employees. Profit-maximizing firms will respond by segregating their workforces. If enough non-discriminatory customers or employees exist, all-black or integrated firms can pay the same wages as all-white firms. If the taste for
576
Employment Discrimination
5530
discrimination is pervasive, however, black workers will be segregated and paid less. Many scholars have asserted that, under Becker’s model, in the long run competitive markets will eliminate firms with a taste for discrimination. Posner (1987), for example, has said that discrimination can persist only with some kind of market failure. The issue is more complex, however. The basic point, not fully realized in the literature, is that markets cater to tastes rather than drive them out. People willing to pay for the costs of apples, or safety, or discrimination, will have it provided to them. True, well-functioning markets confront actors with the full costs of their actions, and so only actors who value their taste more than it costs to produce will indulge. In this sense, markets discipline tastes. One cannot indulge the taste for discrimination or apples on a whim, but will have to pay for it. Further, the taste for discrimination in labor markets is tied to another product - profits for employers, wages and other working conditions for workers, and the physical product or service for customers. Markets will confront actors with the costs of tying. Discrimination will be tied to the product only for actors willing to pay for the joint good. But it seems wrong to say, in general, that competitive markets will drive out a taste. Rather, markets drive out tastes that people are not willing to pay for, and markets sustain tastes where value exceeds cost. The taste for discrimination differs from the taste for apples in one respect, in that it directly affects other market actors. A customer’s preference for red over green apples lowers the relative price of green apples, but the green apples do not care. A customer’s preference for white over black workers lowers the wage of black workers, and the black workers suffer lower utility. It may seem that a discriminatory taste imposes an externality on black workers. But this is not so. Externalities occur when the full costs of a market transaction are not borne by the decision makers. Here, however, the discriminatory customer faces higher prices passed on by the employer who hires a more expensive white workforce. Becker himself was more cautious, and claimed only that ‘under certain conditions’ would competitive markets eliminate discriminatory employers (1971, p. 45). A number of points - some pointing to market failure but others not - can be made that suggest that a taste for discrimination is consistent with competitive markets in the long run. First, production technology matters. If constant-returns-to-scale technology exists, so that one firm can expand indefinitely without increasing its average costs, then a single non-discriminating firm can undersell all others and produce the entire industry output (Becker, 1971, p. 44). But if costs rise with output, more than one firm is required to eliminate discrimination. If employer discrimination is pervasive, there may not be
5530
Employment Discrimination
577
enough non-discriminating firms to hire all the minority workers and eliminate the wage differential. Becker (1968, p. 210) has suggested that a shortage of entrepreneurial skill may prevent firms from fully eliminating discrimination, and thereby declared that ‘discrimination exists, and at times even flourishes, in competitive economies’. Donohue (1997, p. 180) is unconvinced by the shortage-of-entrepreneurs explanation. It did not take special skill to know that hiring low-wage black workers in the textile industry would be profitable - unless, as Donohue puts it, ‘the scarce skill was knowing how to do this without having one’s mill burned down by the Ku Klux Klan’. Second, a firm with a taste for nepotism, as Becker called it, will thrive in a competitive market. A nepotistic employer gains utility from hiring whites, as distinct from a discriminatory firm that loses utility from hiring blacks. An all-white nepotistic employer, then, has a (subjective) cost advantage over both non-discriminatory and discriminatory employers and thus could produce the entire output, assuming constant returns to scale (see Becker, 1971, p. 44 n.4; Goldberg, 1982). Donohue (1986, p. 1422) finds the nepotism theory unimportant, arguing that the basic assumption that favoritism rather than animus drives discrimination is ‘arbitrary and unrealistic’. Third, as mentioned above, employers willing to pay for their taste in discrimination with lower profits can remain competitive indefinitely. Two scenarios are imaginable here, the closely-held firm and the joint-stock company. An entrepreneur who works alongside his employees may dislike working with blacks, and thus prefer an 8 percent monetary return with an all-white workforce to a 10 percent monetary return with an integrated or all-black workforce. He will stay in business if he is willing to reject offers from non-discriminatory entrepreneurs willing to pay the full monetary value (10 percent return) for the firm. If only a few entrepreneurs with his discriminatory tastes exist, these few firms will be segregated with no market discrimination. If enough discriminatory entrepreneurs exist, discrimination against blacks as well as segregation will occur. The capital market will pressure discriminatory entrepreneurs to sell out, thereby capturing the high monetary return, and retire or go into another business that does not require association with blacks to make high profits. But this repeats the point that if entrepreneurs are willing to pay for their taste in discrimination, the market allows them to do so. The alternate scenario involves dispersed shareholders who do not physically associate with the firm. Some investors might willingly accept lower monetary returns in order to indulge in their taste for investing in discriminatory firms, increasing their overall return as they see it. This is the flip side to the South Africa divestiture movement of the 1980s, where investors willingly accepted lower returns by refusing to invest in firms involved in South African apartheid. If only a small number of investors act this way, segregation may occur without discrimination. If enough discriminatory investors are willing to accept lower monetary returns, they can permanently lower black wages.
578
Employment Discrimination
5530
Perhaps a more important explanation for long-run discrimination is that profit-maximizing employers in competitive markets will cater to the discriminatory tastes of employees or customers. If some customers will pay less for a product or service from a black employee, or some employees demand hire wages to work with blacks, black employees become less valuable. As Strauss (1991) has ably recounted, the result could be segregation or discrimination. The issue is analogous to the debate whether domestic labor standards are ineffective in the face of foreign competition. There, the assertion is that workers in developing countries willing to work in unsafe conditions or forego other benefits will undercut domestic workers with a taste for safety. While it is far from clear that cheap foreign labor even sets overall levels of compensation domestically (see Freeman, 1995), profit-maximizing domestic employers will provide benefits that workers are willing to pay for with reduced wages, even in the face of foreign workers with no taste for benefits. Analogously, workers with no taste for discrimination will not undercut workers willing to pay for their taste for discrimination. Other scholars point to market imperfections to explain the persistence of discrimination. Epstein (1992) blames governmental Jim Crow laws for maintaining discrimination. Like other governmental regulation that interferes with labor markets, these laws mandating segregation perpetuated discrimination. Critics of Epstein have noted that Jim Crow laws, while mandating segregated schools, busses, and marriages, almost never regulated labor markets (see Verkerke, 1992). Labor market impediments were far broader than mere governmental restrictions. Indeed, a debate in the literature is the degree to which discriminatory social norms can persist without government involvement. Becker (1971, pp. 46-47) pointed to monopolies as a market imperfection. He emphasized that one of the fruits of a product monopoly is the ability to indulge in a taste for discrimination in the labor market without suffering competitive harm. The firm will earn lower profits than if it hired the cheapest possible labor of a given quality, but can still earn above-average profits. Still, if the monopoly is transferable, a discriminating monopolist has pressure to sell out to those without a taste for discrimination. In other words, competitive capital markets as well as competitive product markets put pressure on discriminatory employers. In a somewhat different vein, Akerlof (1985) shows that discrimination can persist in competitive markets with transaction costs. Suppose some traders have a taste for discrimination against blacks while others do not, and that it takes time or money to distinguish discriminators from others.
5530
Employment Discrimination
579
Firms with black employees will miss out on some trades and be under a perpetual cost disadvantage. 3.2 Statistical Discrimination In Becker’s employer-taste-for-discrimination model, employers lose profits by discriminating, even if they gain in utility. The deviation from the profit-maximizing assumption was troubling. This deviation meant that competitive pressures might reduce or eliminate discrimination, although as discussed above, more or less ad hoc or secondary assumptions can explain the persistence of discrimination within the taste-for-discrimination model. As an empirical fact, the seeming persistence of discrimination cast doubt on Becker’s model. As Arrow (1972, p. 192) observed, only a poor model ‘predicts the absence of the phenomenon it was designed to explain’. Still, as Samuelson (1951, p. 323) put it in discussing labor market models, ‘In economics it takes a theory to kill a theory; facts can only dent the theorist’s hide’. In response to the shortcomings of the taste model, economists developed models of statistical discrimination as an application of the growing insights from limited-information theories (see Phelps, 1972; Arrow, 1973; Aigner and Cain, 1977). These models assume no prejudice or invidious motive by employers. Rather, employers use group characteristics as a cost-effective way of predicting individual worker attributes in a world of limited information. A profit-maximizing employer wants to hire the worker with the highest expected productivity for the going wage. But gathering information to predict individual productivity is costly. Rather than undertake an expensive inquiry into the quality of the high schools attended by job applicants, the employer might assume that on average blacks attend lower-quality high schools than do whites. Or, rather than undertake a lengthy interview, the employer might assume that a woman job applicant is more likely to quit than an otherwise similar man, or is likely to put a greater drain on the pension fund by living longer in retirement. These stereotypes are merely statistical correlations, hence the term statistical discrimination. Employers that rely on false stereotypes will face a competitive disadvantage similar to employers acting on a taste for discrimination, because they are not hiring the most productive workers. But some stereotypes are true, in the sense that the average differs by group even though the generalization does not apply to many members of the group. Profit-maximizing employers will statistically discriminate whenever the net gains from using the cheap but often-inaccurate proxy outweighs the net gains of more accurate but more costly individualized information. Statistical discrimination models, while differing in their precise formulations, show how individuals from disfavored groups can receive less
580
Employment Discrimination
5530
pay than individuals with identical ability but from favored groups. The stereotypes can arise from ‘innate’ differences between the groups (differences in longevity being one of the less controversial examples here, although even here some argue that women live longer than men because they have been excluded from high-stress jobs), stereotypes can also arise from invidious discrimination outside labor markets (for example, in education), or from the effects of prior labor market discrimination. In Aigner and Cain’s prominent early model, the group differences arose because an individual productivity test predicted white performance more accurately than black performance. Statistical discrimination can persist over time, for it is engaged in by profit-maximizing employers. Nevertheless, pressures exist to reduce statistical discrimination. Money can be made through developing low-cost tests and other methods of predicting individual worker ability that reduce the gains from blunt stereotyping. It might seem that statistical discrimination increases overall efficiency by allowing individual employers to maximize their individual profits. In a world of imperfect information, statistical discrimination indeed helps place workers in jobs where their expected productivity is most valued. But statistical discrimination, by tying individuals to group averages beyond their control, creates an externality that can thwart overall efficiency. Statistical discrimination uses average valuations, rather than marginal valuations which are necessary for efficient resource allocation. Individual incentives can be dulled. For example, in the Aigner-Cain model workers are paid a weighted average of their individual predicted productivity and their group average productivity. Workers in such a model invest too little in training, because they are not completely compensated for individual increases in productivity. As Lundberg and Startz (1983) show, statistical discrimination can exacerbate the distortions. While white workers with statistical discrimination will be encouraged to receive more training, this can be more than offset by the discouragement of blacks to receive training. One empirical problem with the Lundberg-Startz model is that the returns to education are higher for blacks than white, at least in recent years (see Donohue and Heckman, 1991b; Sunstein, 1991, pp. 29-30), contrary to the prediction that statistical discrimination will discourage blacks to acquire human capital. Statistical discrimination might also exacerbate labor-supply distortions, as shown by Schwab (1986). In his model, workers can work in an individualized market that recognizes individual productivity (self-employment being an obvious example) or in a ‘factory’ that recognizes only average worker ability. Suppose the more-productive workers in the individualized market are also more productive in the factory market. If so, some workers will inefficiently choose the individualized market even though they would produce more in the factory market, because they would
5530
Employment Discrimination
581
receive only the average factory wage. Now suppose factory employers learn one more thing about their workers, which is their group status, and productivity varies by group. Favored-group workers are encouraged to work more in the productive factory market, but disfavored-group workers are discouraged. Under plausible scenarios, the discouraged workers can outweigh the encouraged workers, reducing overall efficiency. For example, suppose employers statistically discriminate against women because of their greater average quit rate. This may inefficiently divert women toward selfor home-employment. If men are likely to remain employees in the outside labor market regardless of statistical discrimination (that is, men have a more inelastic labor supply), the discouragement of women will outweigh the encouragement of men. 3.3 Sorting Model In his important book advocating a repeal of employment discrimination laws, Epstein (1992) introduces a sorting and searching model that blends aspects of the statistical and taste models. For a sympathetic review, see Crespi (1992). Epstein argues that decentralized markets provide substantial protection against discrimination. Epstein contrasts the victims of violence and the victims of discrimination. Without strong laws against violence, people have to be on guard against violent people. That is why we lock our house even when 99 percent of our neighbors are friendly. Even if one pays off one violent person, others will arise. Once laws against violence are enforced, people can concentrate on finding people who make good offers. Even if 90 percent of the people refuse to deal with someone because of his race, he can concentrate on doing business with the remaining 10 percent. The bigots are powerless to block their mutually beneficial deals. Epstein recognizes, however, that competitive forces will not totally eliminate discrimination. Much of the remaining discrimination is an efficient response by firms to sorting problems. To have smooth workplace arrangements, firms must solve many collective goods problems. What type of firm atmosphere will exist, from type of piped-in-music to work intensity to degree of office talk? When workers have very different tastes, a firm has difficulty making a decision that will not anger many. ‘To the extent that individual tastes are grouped by sex, by age, by national origin - and to some extent they are’ says Epstein, smooth operation of the firm may call for sorting on these groups. Epstein recognizes that diversity, say in a sales staff, has benefits as well. Some profit-maximizing firms will opt for diversity, but others for homogeneity. For a related argument, see Cooter (1994, pp. 141-44).
582
Employment Discrimination
5530
3.4 Status-Production Model of Discrimination Becker’s taste model assumed rather simplistically that individual discriminators wanted to avoid associating with people with certain characteristics, and were willing to pay to indulge in this taste. The model ignored the fact that discriminatory whites were often willing to closely associate with blacks, so long as the relationship maintained hierarchy. A prime example was the common practice of whites employing black domestic workers in their homes. More importantly, the taste model gives no importance to group status. McAdams (1995) has developed a quite different model, which he labels a status-production model. The key element is that whites form a socially connected group that invests in elevating its self-esteem by subordinating blacks. The importance of group solidarity explains why whites will not deviate from the social norm by hiring blacks into important positions. Building on Akerlof’s (1985) model, McAdams posits that the deviator loses intra-group status, and that the group develops a secondary norm of shunning or otherwise punishing the deviator. Thus, the profit-maximizing entrepreneur calculates that he loses more than he gains by hiring the shunned but cheap blacks. The status-production model captures the virulent aspects of racism. Its vision of discrimination is more brutal than the prissier taste model, which seems to apply more ‘to a kind of tea party discrimination than to the blood and steel of the southern racial scene’ (Higgs, 1977, p. 9). As McAdams (1995, p. 1063) emphasizes, the model predicts that discrimination ‘will persist in the face of market competition’. It also explains why lower-class whites are most likely to discriminate, because they are least able to produce status in other ways. The status-discrimination model may well explain the Jim Crow South. More open to question is whether it captures the central features of discrimination today, particularly discrimination based on sex, age, or disability. Epstein (1995) has termed the status-production model a sideshow, applicable to government-sponsored discrimination of the Jim Crow South but little else. He suggests that the enforcement of discriminatory norms is impossible without violence. As he puts it, ‘[c]oercion is always the main event; status production is the side show’.
4. The Economic Role of Anti-Discrimination Laws One’s views on the need for and effectiveness of law depends greatly on one’s model of discrimination. The taste-for-discrimination model sees little need for law. Starting with the premise that markets would root out taste-based discrimination, early law and economics writers urged civil
5530
Employment Discrimination
583
rights advocates to rely on markets rather than laws (see Friedman, 1962; Demsetz, 1965). An exception to this early writing is Landes (1968). He posits that fair employment laws raise the cost of discrimination and thus, at the margin, will discourage employers from discriminating and will raise the black-white wage ratio. Posner (1987) complains that the anti-discrimination laws are often counter-productive. Profit-maximizing employers break down discriminatory barriers by hiring qualified blacks at their lower market wage rate, thereby obtaining a cost advantage over discriminatory employers. But the anti-discrimination laws prohibit an employer from paying unequal wages for equal work (indeed, a separate Equal Pay Act prohibits wage discrimination against women, in addition to the general anti-discrimination prohibition of Title VII). Anti-discrimination laws are less effective at finding employers liable when they refuse to hire minority workers at all. Thus, the laws penalize profit-maximizing employers who pay low wages to blacks, but in practice condone employers who refuse to hire blacks. Posner’s argument assumes that wage discrimination occurs within a firm, but this rarely happens. As Wright (1986) has shown, throughout this century employers rarely paid blacks less than whites for identical work within a firm, even when it was legal to do so. Rather, blacks were excluded from many high-paying jobs and industries. Even law and economics scholars more sympathetic to the basic thrust of anti-discrimination laws have worried about some of its perverse incentives. For example, Ayres and Siegelman (1996) warn that disparate impact litigation might induce employers to discriminate against minorities in hiring. Their conclusion runs counter to the usual assertion that disparate impact litigation (which focuses on the relative numbers of minority and majority workers) leads to hiring quotas by employers. But Ayres and Siegelman show that, in recent years, most disparate impact opinions involve firing cases rather than hiring cases. A firing disparate impact case is easier to show because the relevant pools exist within the firm (a greater fraction of black than white employees were terminated), whereas in a hiring case great debate concerns the appropriate pool to compare racial hiring patterns with (all workers? all skilled workers? all suburban workers?). The danger to employers, then, is that hiring large numbers of minorities opens them up to a disparate impact firing suit. For a related argument that anti-discrimination laws do not lead to quota hiring, see Issacharoff (1992, pp. 1238-1239). Other scholars looked with more sympathy on the efficiency justifications for anti-discrimination laws, even within the taste-based model. Donohue (1986) has argued that the laws speed up the market’s push towards non-discrimination. Employers with a taste for discrimination have higher costs than non-discriminatory employers. Anti-discrimination laws, to the
584
Employment Discrimination
5530
extent they are effective, impose additional costs on employers who discriminate and thus drive them from the market more rapidly. Posner (1987) criticized Donohue for ignoring the costs of government enforcement, arguing that government intervention could make the transition to non-discriminatory markets inefficiently quickly, just as a government mandate that shippers adopt a new, fuel-efficient technology would wastefully cause old ships to be scrapped too quickly. The market is best, asserted Posner, at both eradicating discrimination and determining the optimal timing in which to eradicate discriminate. Posner’s basic objection to Donohue’s argument was that Donohue argued that government intervention was efficient without pointing to some market failure, such as externalities, monopoly, or high information costs, that casts doubt on the market solution. Donohue, in response, rejected Posner’s analogy to shippers, because it implicitly assumed that shipping was in equilibrium when a new technology was discovered, while the existence of discriminatory employers shows that labor markets were not in equilibrium under the Becker model. Companies with outmoded machines cannot be suddenly made efficient by changing ownership, but companies with a taste for discrimination can be suddenly made more efficient by switching ownership, because the psychic costs of discrimination immediately disappear. Later, taking up more directly Posner’s challenge to point to the market failure, Donohue (1992) pointed to third-party moralists who abhor discrimination directed against others. Their preferences are not considered in the contracts between employers and black and white employees. Even if discriminating employers are willing to pay for their taste for discrimination in reduced profits, the outcome is not efficient because employers are ignoring the external harm their discrimination causes these moralists. Conducting a ‘thought experiment’, Donohue argued that if the average adult American were willing to pay $100 per year to keep Title VII, the resulting $17.5 billion benefits would outweigh a ‘middle-case’ estimate of its administrative and incentive costs. Donohue (1997, p. 28) has acknowledged that economists generally try not to rely on altruism or the preferences of moralists in making efficiency arguments. The status-discrimination model makes the sharpest efficiency justification for the anti-discrimination laws. In that model, employers are trapped by the fear of white stigma from integrating their workforces. As Lessig (1995) has put it, hiring blacks would mark an employer as having either a special greed for money or affection for blacks. The anti-discrimination laws put an important ambiguity in the decision; perhaps the employer hiring a black merely wants to obey the law. By altering the social meaning of discrimination, the anti-discrimination laws can break the
5530
Employment Discrimination
585
cartel-like solidarity among whites, just as anti-dueling laws ended an inefficient social practice in the previous century (see also McAdams, 1995). Even Epstein has recognized the usefulness of the anti-discrimination laws in ending rigidities in southern labor markets. As he puts it, ‘Title VII was heaven-sent’ (Epstein, 1992, p. 251). Epstein emphasizes that Title VII destroyed the web of indirect legal sanctions against firms trying to exploit the profit potential in discrimination, rather than merely alter private behavior. As he explains, in the pre-Title VII south it was all to easy for an all-white town board to lose a building application, or postpone a meeting to approve the sewage connection, of a firm that violated the segregation norms of the era. Epstein’s major point, however, is that much contemporary discrimination is efficient, as indicated in his sorting model and in some statistical discrimination models. He therefore concludes that continuance of the anti-discrimination laws imposes heavy costs that are no longer worth the gains. Other law and economics scholars have questioned the means rather than ends of anti-discrimination law. Cooter (1994), for example, has argued that the absolute regulatory prohibition against discrimination is an inefficient method of controlling discrimination. Cooter’s premise is that some discrimination is efficient and thus should not be prohibited, but that market imperfections may allow too much discrimination and perhaps justify intervention. Analogizing to the use of taxes or tradeable permits to control pollution, Cooter suggests that anti-discrimination laws should tax employers who employ too few blacks or women, or give employers tradeable rights, rather than prohibit discrimination altogether. A tax or tradeable rights regime can reach equivalent levels of discrimination, differing only in whether government officials adjust prices or quantities. Either method can enforce discrimination laws at lower cost than a flat prohibition, in part by allowing firms with especially high costs of complying (for example, few qualified minorities are in their particular pool) to hire fewer minorities. Strauss (1991) makes a similar argument, phrasing it as a preference for disparate impact analysis than disparate treatment analysis. Current disparate-treatment law prohibits firms from ever considering race in a decision. Strauss argues that this is costly to enforce because it requires extensive case-specific findings. Many cases of invidious discrimination go unchecked, while some cases of efficient discrimination (particularly efficient statistical discrimination) are banned. Far better, Strauss says, would be to require employers to pay a fine if they do not hire proportionately to the nationwide labor force. If a firm has correct bottom-line numbers, it can then make individual decisions to hire or fire without scrutiny by the anti-discrimination laws. In making this argument, Strauss uses an unconventional conception of disparate impact, because he would not require the government to point to a specific employment
586
Employment Discrimination
5530
practice, such as a test, that caused the firm to hire fewer blacks. In a similar vein, Mashaw (1991) has argued for racial quotas, with firms with a small percentage of blacks in their workforce being allowed to buy permits from firms with large black workforces. One problem with such tax, fine, or tradeable rights schemes is that the government needs detailed information to set the optimal tax rate. Enormous wasteful lobbying would occur by rent-seeking advocates seeking higher or lower rates or special exemptions. A greater problem is the symbolism of allowing trade in rights to discriminate, although this symbolism has been overcome in allowing tradeable pollution rights. Bell (1992, pp. 47-64) has savagely satirized the concept of tradeable rights. Bell calls his hypothetical Racial Preferencing Licensing Act a ‘legalized reincarnation of Jim Crow’. McCaffery (1993) has likewise advocated tax reform as a solution to sex discrimination. McCaffery sees extensive market failures that create disparities between men and women, including search costs and incomplete markets, but he emphasizes the failures from tax policy. The result of these market failures, he suggests, is that women have been given a stark choice: act like men and become highly committed to the paid labor force, or get out. The market has been dictating choices rather than accommodating them, as Epstein would see it. McCaffery advocates higher taxes on primary workers, typically married men, and lower taxes on secondary workers, typically married women. These changes could unravel the dynamic that leads to polarized options for women.
5. Empirical Studies of Employment Discrimination Law Unlike law and economics scholarship in many other areas, the scholarship in employment discrimination has gone beyond model building and has taken a serious empirical look at discrimination litigation and the effects of anti-discrimination law. The amount of employment discrimination litigation has exploded in the last quarter century. Between 1970 and 1989, employment discrimination case filings rose by 2,166 percent, compared to a rise of only 125 percent in the overall civil docket (Donohue and Siegelman, 1991). By 1995, employment cases (about 80 percent of which are discrimination cases) comprised 6.8 percent of the federal civil docket (Eisenberg and Clermont, 1995). Employment cases are less likely than other cases to privately settle out of court. Employees win only 26 percent of cases going to trial, significantly less than the 45 percent overall win rate by plaintiffs in federal civil litigation (Eisenberg and Clermont, 1995). Most employment-discrimination cases protest firings, not refusals to hire. The common image of discrimination is that employers reject black or
5530
Employment Discrimination
587
women job applicants or pay black or women workers less for the same work. Indeed, in the early years of Title VII litigation, most cases were hiring cases. By the 1980s, however, firing cases were six times more common than firing cases. Donohue and Siegelman (1991, p. 1015). An employer is thus far more likely to be sued when it terminates a minority worker than when it refuses to hire minority job applicants. This makes employers more reluctant to hire minorities in the first place. Paradoxically, societal success in overcoming discriminatory barriers may explain much of the rise in discrimination litigation (see Donohue and Siegelman, 1991, pp. 1006-1015). A worker is more likely to sue when rejected from a high-paying job than a low-paying job, because the payoff of a successful lawsuit increases while the costs of litigation vary little with pay. Further, lawsuits protesting discrimination are more likely as the workforce becomes more integrated, because it becomes easier to show that the rejected black or woman was treated less favorably than a white male. Thus, as women and blacks enter high-paying, integrated jobs, the number of discrimination lawsuits rises. In addition to long-term trends, discrimination lawsuits respond to business cycles. The number of lawsuits increases during recessions, damages for successful suits rise, but win rates fall (Donohue and Siegelman, 1993). The key link is that victims of discrimination receive higher damages the longer they are out of work. Moving beyond empirical studies of the litigation process, several studies have examined whether the anti-discrimination laws have improved black earnings. Such studies are notoriously tricky. Essentially, the researcher is trying to examine changes after a nationwide law goes into effect, when many other changes in society occur as well. In the case of the anti-discrimination laws, Title VII became effective in 1965, coinciding with important executive orders requiring affirmation action by government contractors, a new Voting Rights Act, continuation of the civil rights movement, and general social unrest. Smith and Welch (1989) have argued that federal anti-discrimination laws had little effect on black economic progress, because black/white earnings ratios had been steadily increasing since the 1940s. Better black education and migration from the south to higher-paying jobs in the north are the most important explanations for black economic progress, they suggest, neither of which is directly attributable to law. Donohue and Heckman (1991a) have contested this conclusion. As the title of their review article indicates, they find black economic progress to be episodic rather than continuous. The first period of progress occurred around World War II. The second critical episode was the period from 1964 to 1975, when the black/white earnings ratio increased from 0.62 to 0.72, with most of the progress coming in the South (Donohue and Heckman, 1991a, p.
588
Employment Discrimination
5530
1607). Black outflow from the south had slowed dramatically by 1965, and improvements in amount and quality of black schooling explain only part of the post-1965 jump in black earnings. Donohue and Heckman conclude that Title VII, along with other civil rights legislation of the period, had a positive impact on black/white earnings by shaking the economic and social taboos of the south that had prevented employers from hiring black workers. A particularly important example comes from the textile industry in South Carolina, as examined by Heckman and Payner (1989). Prior to 1965, few blacks were employed in the South Carolina textile industry, when black employment levels and wages suddenly rose. Shifts from agriculture and improved black education cannot explain the timing. The mid-1960s saw a tight labor market, making the underemployment of blacks particularly costly to employers. Heckman and Payner find quite plausible the story that in 1965 entrepreneurs ‘seized on the new federal legislation and decrees’ and began hiring black workers as they had wanted to do. Epstein (1992, p. 245) attributes the surge of black employment to the federal government’s attack on Jim Crow regulation, pointing out that South Carolina had a 1915 statute, not formally repealed until 1972, mandating segregation in textile factories. Verkerke (1992, p. 2091) responds that nearby southern states also had highly segregated textile factories but no express segregation law. Some intriguing studies have exploited changes in coverage of Title VII to measure its effectiveness. In 1972 Congress expanded the coverage of Title VII from employers with 25 employees to employers with 15. Chay (1998) has found that relative black employment and earnings rose in industries in the South with a high percentage of small employers, suggesting that the statute increased the relative demand for blacks. Bloch (1994) has also emphasized differences in coverage, noting that the most intensive enforcement of anti-discrimination policy is for federal contractors, followed by employers with 100 or more employees required to file detailed EEO-1 reports on their hiring practices, followed by employers with 15 or more employees who are subject to Title VII. While significant data problems exist, he shows that minorities appear to have greater representation in more-regulated firms. Welch (1989), as reported in Donohue (1989), likewise has found that employment of blacks and women has increased between 1966 and 1980 for EEO-1 reporting firms. Bloch warns, however, that this pattern does not necessarily show any aggregate increase in black employment or wages, and may represent only a shift in black employment from the uncovered to the covered sector. Most analysts agree that, after the 1965-75 surge, blacks have made far less economic progress since then, and that black earnings remain substantially less than for whites, even after adjusting for education and other productivity factors. The anti-discrimination laws seem to have had
5530
Employment Discrimination
589
little effect in the last twenty years (although it is always hard to disprove the negative assertion that the laws prevented a decline). Whether more vigorous enforcement of the anti-discriminations would help, or whether they have run their course and further progress must come in other directions, is unclear.
6. Special Issues in Sex Discrimination Laws Much of the general law and economics approach to employment discrimination applies equally to sex and age discrimination as well as race discrimination. Sex discrimination raises a number of special issues, however, and as Epstein (1992) has emphasized, the parallels between race and sex discrimination are imperfect at best. As Wasserstrom (1977) has ably explained, color-blindness is the eventual goal of the anti-discrimination laws, but sex-blindness is not. No employer could provide separate but equal bathrooms for blacks, but all large employers provide separate bathrooms for women. In addition, pregnancy and childbirth uniquely affect women workers. The economic models fit differently for race and sex discrimination. Becker’s taste for discrimination model is formulated generally enough to accommodate a preference against associating with women or blacks. It seems to fit well enough the fact that many bosses, co-workers, or customers prefer dealing with men (and, in other situations, dealing with women). Perhaps men gain status by maintaining group solidarity against women, but McAdams’s status-production model seems somewhat hollow when applied to sex discrimination. Statistical discrimination models, by contrast, often apply well to sex stereotypes. Epstein (1992, p. 65) has applied his sorting model to sex discrimination, emphasizing the divisions within the firm that can arise when women want part-time status. In Posner’s (1989) view, the economics of sex discrimination is distinctive because of the interdependence in utilities of men and women. Married couples have joint consumption and often act altruistically towards each other. Thus, for example, married women indirectly benefit if labor market discrimination increases husbands’ pay. Because racial intermarriage remains rare, blacks do not indirectly benefit when whites are favored. Anti-discrimination law has recognized differences between race and sex discrimination. Most important is the bona fide occupational qualification (bfoq) under Title VII, which applies to sex but not race distinctions. Title VII prohibits employers in any context from using race to sort workers, but allows employers to sort by sex if sex is a bona fide occupational qualification (bfoq). Thus, employers can have separate but equal bathrooms or grooming standards for men and women, but not for race.
590
Employment Discrimination
5530
Women tend to live longer than men. Many employers acted on this ‘true stereotype’ in constructing pension plans, using sex-based annuity tables that required women to make higher contributions for equivalent monthly pensions, or receive lower monthly pensions for equivalent contributions. The practice is a paradigmatic example of statistical discrimination. No malicious discrimination was intended, but employers were explicitly using sex as a proxy to predict longevity. Nevertheless, it is illegal. In two cases, Los Angeles Department of Water and Power v. Manhart and Arizona Governing Committee v. Norris, the Supreme Court prohibited employers from using sex-based tables in calculating individual contributions or benefits (although the Court allowed employers to consider the overall percentage of women in calculating whether overall contributions match benefits). The Court reasoned that the anti-discrimination laws demand fairness toward individuals before fairness to groups, and the sex-based classification involved group generalizations rather than ‘thoughtful scrutiny of individuals’. In short, the Court prohibited statistical discrimination even when ‘true’. An extensive law and economics commentary has criticized the pension decisions, arguing that employers should be allowed to consider sex in calculating pension contributions or benefits (see Kimball, 1979; Freed and Polsby, 1981; Benston, 1982; Epstein, 1992). They see employers or their insurance companies using sex classifications to solve an adverse selection problem. With unisex tables, women covered by a pension plan will receive six to twelve percent more than they contribute to the plan (Epstein, 1992, p. 323, citing Benston, 1982, p. 515). These distributional consequences reduce overall welfare, as plan participants begin ‘gaming’ the system. As Epstein points out, strategic considerations become largest when a husband and wife are each entitled to pension benefits. With unisex tables, the couple has an incentive to shift their benefits towards the wife by having the husband take a self-and-survivor annuity and the wife take an annuity for her life alone. Employers have an incentive against hiring women or toward dropping life-time pension benefits. Similar controversy arose over the issue of whether employers violated anti-discrimination laws by excluding pregnancy from health-insurance benefits or pregnancy leave from disability benefits. Epstein (1992, p. 32) emphasizes that pregnancy is a poor candidate for insurance, because it is largely a controlled event and thus a moral hazard problem is created by insuring its costs - women are more likely to become pregnant. Many European countries, concerned with low birth rates, regard this as a favorable aspect of insurance, and provide for pregnancy health costs (generally as part of national health insurance) and paid maternity leave with government programs. Indeed, whether childbirth benefits should be
5530
Employment Discrimination
591
provided through government programs or employer mandates is a good example of the tradeoffs articulated by Summers (1989). In a thoughtful article, Issacharoff and Rosenblum (1994) contrast the extensive European government benefits toward pregnancy with the limited employer mandates in the United States - essentially a non-discrimination command and an employee’s right to twelve weeks’ unpaid leave for childbirth. They propose a more extensive set of benefits modeled after unemployment insurance. In the early US pregnancy cases, the Supreme Court upheld employer benefit plans that excluded pregnancy. The Court reasoned that a classification between pregnant persons and other persons was not explicitly sex-based and therefore was not disparate treatment; and because the costs of providing health insurance was as great for women (even without pregnancy coverage) as for men, no disparate impact claim was made. Congress promptly reversed this holding with the Pregnancy Discrimination Act amending Title VII. Employers must treat pregnancy like any other disability. Posner (1989) notes that this compels employers to ignore the higher average cost of employing women, who are more likely to leave the workforce to have children. The consequence of ignoring these differences, Posner argues, is inefficient and may not benefit women as a whole. Women directly lose because employers have an incentive not to hire them. Applying his interdependence analysis, Posner argues that women as wives indirectly lose. The biggest losers are married but childless working women, because the wife and husband have lower wages than if employers could consider pregnancy and she will not gain from the higher fringe benefits. Donohue (1989) challenges Posner’s argument that statistical discrimination against women is socially efficient. Following the approach of Lundberg and Startz (1983) and Schwab (1986) discussed above, Donohue reiterates that while acting on statistical averages may maximize firm profits, it creates dynamic distortions. For example, if employers are reluctant to train women for top corporate positions because they tend to quit to have children, even women who plan to stay in the labor market have reduced incentives to invest in human capital. Donohue also more broadly challenges Posner’s interdependency thesis. Even if consumption is joint and women are altruistic, Donohue says, women may have different preferences and may want altruistically to spend more on their children than their husbands would wish. If sex discrimination lowers the economic power of women, their bargaining within a marriage is probably weakened. Sexual harassment continues to be a major issue in employment discrimination law, and the law and economics literature helps frame the issues. Hadfield (1995) has used an avowedly economic approach to define sexual harassment. Harassment occurs, under her test, whenever a woman is subjected to actions that a man is not that would cause the woman to alter
592
Employment Discrimination
5530
her behavior to avoid the actions if she could do so without cost. Hadfield emphasizes that many women are trapped (not at the margin) and thus must endure the harassment, but otherwise might refuse night shifts, overtime or travel assignments where harassment is likely. Whatever the definition, Posner (1989) notes that sexual harassment is not in the employer’s self interest, but often the costs of prevention are high. Just as other antisocial workplace behavior, such as embezzlement, is subject to public enforcement, so too should sexual harassment be - depending on the relative costs of public and private enforcement. Epstein (1992) agrees that prohibitions on sexual harassment are perhaps the easiest anti-discrimination prohibitions to justify, at least if the claims stay close to their tort roots. Verkerke (1995) has explored the standards upon which employers should be liable for sexual harassment by its employees. He argues first that employer liability for creating a sexually hostile environment should not differ from employer liability for other forms of discrimination, but rather should depend on creating the proper incentives for employers to acquire information about harassment. Conditional notice liability, whereby employers are not liable if they have ‘experimented’ in creating notice procedures and have not been notified of the harassment, may be most appropriate. But Verkerke emphasizes that the choices of liability standard require data currently not available.
Bibliography on Employment Discrimination (5530) Aigner, Dennis J. and Cain, Glen G. (1977), ‘Statistical Theories of Discrimination in Labor Markets’, 30 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 175-187. Akerlof, George (1985), ‘Discriminatory, Status-Based Wages Among Tradition-Oriented, Stochastically Trading Coconut Producers’, 93 Journal of Political Economy, 265-276. Arrow, Kenneth (1972), ‘Some Mathematical Models of Race Discrimination in the Labor Market’, in Pascal, Anthony (ed.), Racial Discrimination in Economic Life, Lexington, Lexington Books, 187-203. Arrow, Kenneth (1973), ‘The Theory of Discrimination’, in Ashenfelter, Orley and Rees, Albert (eds), Discrimination in Labor Markets, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 3-33. Ayres, Ian and Siegelman, Peter (1996), ‘The Q-Word as Red Herring: Why Disparate Impact Liability does not Induce Hiring Quotas’, 74 Texas Law Review, 1487-1526. Becker, Gary S. (1968), ‘Discrimination, Economic’, in Sills, David L. (ed.), International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences, vol. 4, New York, Macmillan and Free Press, 208-210. Becker, Gary S. (1971), The Economics of Discrimination, 2nd edn (1st edition 1957), Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Bell, Derrick (1992), Faces at the Bottom of the Well: The Permanence of Racism, New York, Basic Books.
5530
Employment Discrimination
593
Benston, George (1982), ‘The Economics of Gender Discrimination in Employee Fringe Benefits: Manhart Revisited’, 49 University of Chicago Law Review, 489-542. Blau, Francine D. (1998), ‘Trends in the Well-Being of American Women, 1970-1995', 36 Journal of Economic Literature, 112-165. Bloch, Farrell (1994), Antidiscrimination Law and Minority Employment: Recruitment Practices and Regulatory Constraints, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Chay, Kenneth Y. (1998), ‘The Impact of Federal Civil Rights Policy on Black Economic Progress: Evidence From The Equal Employment Opportunity Act of 1972', 51 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 608-632. Cooter, Robert (1994), ‘Market Affirmative Action’, 31 San Diego Law Review, 133-168. Crespi, Gregory S. (1992), ‘Market Magic: Can the Invisible Hand Strangle Bigotry?’, 72 Boston University Law Review, 991-1011. Darity, William A., Jr and Mason, Patrick L. (1998), ‘Evidence on Discrimination in Employment: Codes of Color, Codes of Gender’, 12 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 63-90. Demsetz, Harold (1965), ‘Minorities in the Marketplace’, 43 North Carolina Law Review, 271-297. Donohue, John J., III (1986), ‘Is Title VII Efficient?’, 134 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1411-1431. Donohue, John J., III (1989), ‘Prohibiting Sex Discrimination in the Workplace: An Economic Perspective’, 56 University of Chicago Law Review, 1337-1368. Donohue, John J., III (1992), ‘Advocacy versus Analysis in Assessing Employment Discrimination Law’, 44 Stanford Law Review, 1583-1614. Donohue, John J., III (1997), Foundations of Employment Discrimination Law, New York, Oxford University Press. Donohue, John J., III and Heckman, James J. (1991a), ‘Continuous versus Episodic Change: The Impact of Civil Rights Policy on the Economic Status of Blacks’, 29 Journal of Economic Literature, 1603-1643. Donohue, John J., III and Heckman, James J. (1991b), ‘Reevaluating Federal Civil Rights Policy’, 79 Georgetown Law Journal, 1713-1735. Donohue, John J., III and Siegelman, Peter (1991), ‘The Changing Nature of Employment Discrimination Litigation’, 43 Stanford Law Review, 983-1033. Donohue, John J., III and Siegelman, Peter (1993), ‘Law and Macroeconomics: Employment Discrimination Over the Business Cycle’, 66 Southern California Law Review, 709-765. Eisenberg, Theodore and Clermont, Kevin M. (1995), Judicial Statistical Inquiry Form, http://teddy.law.cornell.edu:8090/questata.htm. Epstein, Richard A. (1992), Forbidden Grounds: The Case Against Employment Discrimination Laws, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Epstein, Richard A. (1995), ‘The Status-Production Sideshow: Why the Antidiscrimination Laws Are Still a Mistake’, 108 Harvard Law Review, 1085-1109. Freed, Mayer G. and Polsby, Daniel D. (1981), ‘Privacy, Efficiency, and the Equality of Men and Women: A Revisionist View of Sex Discrimination in Employment’, 1981 American Bar Foundation Research Journal, 583-636. Freeman, Richard B. (1995), ‘Are Your Wages Set in Beijing?’, 9 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 15-32.
594
Employment Discrimination
5530
Friedman, Milton (1962), Capitalism and Freedom, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Goldberg, Matthew (1982), ‘Discrimination, Nepotism, and Long-Run Wage Differentials’, 97 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 307-319. Hadfield, Gillian K. (1995), ‘Rational Women: A Test for Sex-Based Harassment’, 83 California Law Review, 1151-1189. Heckman, James J. and Payner, Brook S. (1989), ‘Determining the Impact of Federal Antidiscrimination Policy on the Economic Status of Blacks: A Study of South Carolina’, 79 American Economic Review, 138-177. Higgs, Robert (1977), Competition and Coercion: Blacks in the American Economic, 1865-1917, New York, Cambridge University Press. Issacharoff, Samuel (1992), ‘Contractual Liberties in Discriminatory Markets’, 70 Texas Law Review, 1219-1259. Issacharoff, Samuel and Rosenblum, Elyse (1994), ‘Women and the Workplace: Accommodating the Demands of Pregnancy’, 94 Columbia Law Review, 2154-2221. Kelman, Mark (1991), ‘Concepts of Discrimination in “General Ability” Job Testing’, 104 Harvard Law Review, 1157-1247. Kimball, Spencer (1979), ‘Reverse Sex Discrimination: Manhart’, 1979 American Bar Foundation Research Journal, 85-139. Landes, William M. (1968), ‘The Economics of Fair Employment Laws’, 76 Journal of Political Economy, 507-552. Lessig, Lawrence (1995), ‘The Regulation of Social Meaning’, 62 University of Chicago Law Review, 943-1045. Lundberg, Shelly and Startz, Richard (1983), ‘Private Discrimination and Social Intervention in Competitive Labor Markets’, 73 American Economic Review, 340-347. Mashaw, Jerry L. (1991), ‘Implementing Quotas’, 79 Georgetown Law Journal, 1769-1775. McAdams, Richard H. (1995), ‘Cooperation and Conflict: The Economics of Group Status Production and Race Discrimination’, 108 Harvard Law Review, 1005-1084. McCaffery, Edward J. (1993), ‘Slouching Towards Equality: Gender Discrimination, Market Efficiency, and Social Change’, 103 Yale Law Journal, 595-675. Phelps, Edmund (1972), ‘The Statistical Theory of Racism and Sexism’, 62 American Economic Review, 659-661. Posner, Richard A. (1987), ‘The Efficiency and the Efficacy of Title VII’, 136 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 513-521. Posner, Richard A. (1989), ‘An Economic Analysis of Sex Discrimination Laws’, 56 University of Chicago Law Review, 1311-1335. Posner, Richard A. (1995), Aging and Old Age, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Schwab, Stewart (1986), ‘Is Statistical Discrimination Efficient?’, 76 American Economic Review, 228-234. Smith, James P. and Welch, Finis R. (1989), ‘Black Economic Progress After Myrdal’, 27 Journal of Economic Literature, 519-564. Samuelson, Paul A. (1951), ‘Economic Theory and Wages’, in Wright, David M. (ed.), The Impact of the Union, New York, Harcourt, Brace & Co., 312-342.
5530
Employment Discrimination
595
Strauss, David A. (1991), ‘The Law and Economics of Racial Discrimination in Employment: The Case for Numerical Standards’, 79 Georgetown Law Journal, 1619-1657. Summers, Lawrence H. (1989), ‘Some Simple Economics of Mandated Benefits’, 79 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 177-183. Sunstein, Cass R. (1991), ‘Why Markets Don’t Stop Discrimination’, 8 Social Philosophy and Policy, 22-37. Verkerke, J. Hoult (1992), ‘Free to Search’, 105 Harvard Law Review, 2080-2097. Verkerke, J. Hoult (1995), ‘Notice Liability in Employment Discrimination Law’, 81 Virginia Law Review, 273-385. Wasserstrom, Richard A. (1997), ‘Racism, Sexism, and Preferential Treatment: An Approach to the Topic’, 24 UCLA Law Review, 581-621. Welch, Finis (1989), ‘Affirmative Action and Discrimination’, in Shulman, Steven and Darity, William, Jr (eds), The Question of Discrimination, Middleton, CT, Wesleyan University Press. Wright, Gavin (1986), Old South, New South: Revolutions in the Southern Economy Since the Civil War, Baton Rouge, Louisiana State University Press.
5540 OCCUPATIONAL SAFETY AND HEALTH REGULATION Sidney A. Shapiro John M. Rounds Professor of Law University of Kansas © Copyright 1999 Sidney A. Shapiro
Abstract An employer will invest in safety and health precautions until the cost is more than the expense of paying higher wages, workers’ compensation, and other accident and illness costs. Employees receive additional protection because governments have chosen to augment these financial incentives with regulation. Studies indicate that all three approaches cause employers to invest in health and safety precautions, but the extent to which injuries and illnesses are reduced is difficult to verify and may be limited in numerous work situations. The literature has identified potential reforms, but the viability of key reforms is uncertain. Thus, labor markets, compensation and regulation are highly imperfect alternatives concerning the reduction of occupational accidents and illnesses. As a result, continued reliance on all three approaches is indicated. JEL classification: K31, K32 Keywords: Occupational Safety, Occupational Health, Occupational Risk, Workers’ Compensation
A. Introduction 1. Imperfect Alternatives Economic theory predicts that workers will demand additional wages, or a ‘wage premium’, to compensate them for workplace safety and health risks. Employers will respond by reducing such risks until it is less expensive to pay workers additional compensation than it is to invest in additional health or safety precautions. In this manner, labor markets should produce the abatement of some safety and health hazards, and workers should be compensated for the risks that remain. Since the early 1900s, governments have intervened to augment these labor market incentives. According to Darling-Hammon and Kniesner (1980), virtually every state in the United States enacted some quasi-administrative 596
5540
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
597
scheme to award compensation for workplace accidents between 1911 and 1920. Today all 50 states and the federal government administer such programs. In 1970, Congress enacted the Occupational Safety and Health Act (OSH Act) which established the Occupational Safety and Health Administration (OSHA) in the Department of Labor to regulate workplace conditions. States have the option to accept federal regulation of employers or to administer their own safety and health regulations subject to OSHA’s approval and supervision. Other countries have also implemented administrative regulation. These governmental efforts indicate a political judgment that labor markets produce insufficient protection for workers. This essay describes how economic theory explains the role of labor markets, compensation, and regulation in addressing occupational injuries and illnesses. I also report on studies that have tested the effectiveness of each of these methods, and I discuss reforms to improve the effectiveness of each approach. Readers seeking an overview of these issues can consult several books and articles. Chelius (1974), Oi (1974), Rea (1983), Viscusi (1983, 1992), Dickens (1984), Schroeder and Shapiro (1984) and Robinson (1991) offer general comparisons of the impact of labor markets, compensation and regulation on workplace safety and health. This chapter confirms Komesar’s (1994) insight about options for making society safer and healthier. When governments choose between market, compensation, and regulatory approaches, Komesar contends that ‘[t]he choice is always a choice among highly imperfect alternatives’. Labor markets, compensation, and regulation are ‘imperfect’ alternatives concerning the reduction of occupational accidents and illnesses because none of these alternatives is reliable. Instead, each is limited by significant constraints, which are explained below. Reformers seek to address these constraints, but the constraints are intractable in many instances. Thus, it appears to be necessary to rely on all three approaches, because no one (or even two) approaches is likely to produce an appropriate level of occupational safety and health. Together, however, labor markets, compensation and regulation can come closer to this elusive goal.
B. Labor Markets 2. Introduction Economic theory establishes that labor markets create several incentives for employers to reduce occupational safety and health risks. Economic studies confirm the existence of one such incentive: the demand by workers for additional compensation, or a ‘wage premium’, for exposure to safety risks.
598
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
5540
The adequacy of such wage premiums, however, is in dispute. Moreover, analysts generally concede that workers are unlikely to be compensated for most health risks. Governments have attempted to aid workers in obtaining additional compensation by promoting the distribution of information about workplace risks and by addressing workers’ lack of bargaining power.
3. Economic Theory An employer will determine whether to prevent workplace accidents or illnesses by comparing the cost of prevention with the cost of not taking such action. Employers that fail to reduce workplace hazards can expect to pay increased labor costs because workers will demand additional compensation for enduring occupational safety and health risks. For a given level of workers’ compensation, workers will demand a wage premium that compensates for any inadequacies in ex post compensation. In other words, assuming workers are fully informed about job risks, they will seek compensation equal to the expected cost of an injury or illness not covered by workers’ compensation. In addition, the employer may have to pay for the cost of recruitment and training of additional workers to replace those persons who are injured or killed and other related costs. To avoid these expenses, an employer will make safety and health improvements until the cost of additional precautions is more than paying wage premiums and other related costs. In this manner, labor markets should produce the abatement of some safety and health hazards and workers should be compensated (ex ante and ex post) for the risks that remain. The employer’s assumption of these costs will make the market for the employer’s product or service more efficient. Because the employer assumes these costs, the price of the product or service will reflect the cost to society of the production of the good or service, including the cost of occupational illnesses and injuries.
4. Empirical Evidence Studies by Viscusi (1983) and other analysts (listed and described by Viscusi) find that workers in risky jobs receive higher wages after controlling for education, experience, and other market characteristics. Viscusi estimates that average annual compensation for all job risks in the United States totals about $400. Similarly, Robinson (1991) estimates that workers exposed to significant risks of occupational injuries received annual wage premiums of about $300$500. This amounts to about a 5-8 percent increase above the earnings of unexposed blue-collar workers. Fishback (1986) cites empirical evidence that
5540
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
599
miners in the United States in the 1900s received risk compensation. Weiss, Maier and Gerking (1986) discovered risk compensation in Austrian labor markets. By comparison, Leigh (1991), who reviewed several prior studies, found that only variables which reflected job hazards resulting in death were associated with compensating wages, and that among studies using death rates, only some studies found evidence of wage premiums. Further, among studies finding evidence of such wages, the amount of compensation paid for the risk of death varied widely. Leigh’s own study found evidence of compensating wages based on Bureau of Labor Statistics fatality data, but he found no correlation based on workers’ compensation fatality data. A review by Dorman (1996) of the literature on compensating wages, including Leigh’s study, characterizes the evidence for wage premiums as ‘weak at best’.
5. Evaluation of Empirical Data The empirical evidence is mixed concerning the extent to which workers obtain wage premiums for dangerous work. Moreover, even when workers obtain compensating wages, there is an issue of the adequacy of the compensation. As the last section revealed, studies finding compensating wages indicate that workers receive only modest wage premiums. Even a small wage premium, however, is significant if workplace risks are not very large. For example, Viscusi (1983) concludes that once analysts take into account the nature of a risk and the population exposed to it, it is evident that workers are well paid for the risks that they face. According to Viscusi, ‘most’ of the ‘reasonable’ estimates indicate that workers demand between $3 and $7 million compensation for exposure to potentially fatal accidents. Workers, however, may receive less compensation than Viscusi estimates. First, if the risk of a fatal accident is greater than the data on which Viscusi relies, workers receive less compensation than he estimates. McGarity and Shapiro (1993, 1996) found that experts believe existing statistics understate the extent of workplace fatalities (and injuries) in the United States by an unknown and perhaps significant extent. Second, the amount of additional compensation that a worker will seek for hazardous work is a function of the worker’s knowledge and understanding of existing risks. Robinson (1991) cites survey data which reveal that workers’ knowledge is incomplete. He found, for example, that 33 to 50 percent of workers in occupations with high rates of disabling injuries and illnesses reported that they faced no significant safety or health hazards. Carmichael (1986) adds that because the dissemination of safety information in labor markets takes time, workers may lack adequate information when they seek a job. Oi (1974) notes, however, that full information by all workers is not
600
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
5540
necessary to obtain adequate compensating wages. What is important is that the marginal worker possess full information. Third, workers must be able to discern marginal differences in risks to bargain effectively for hazard pay. Yet, as Lave (1983), Dickens (1984) and McGarity and Shapiro (1993) discuss, such distinctions are especially difficult to make in the context of occupational illness, where huge uncertainties befuddle attempts to predict the precise effects of health risks on longevity and the quality of life once a disease has manifested itself. Further, as Dorman (1996) discusses, a worker’s evaluation of risk may be distorted by psychological effects in the way individuals process risk information. Studies in the psychological literature suggest that people do not process risk information in the rationale manner that economic theory assumes. For example, people engage in several forms of ‘bounded rationality’ which simplify and filter risk perceptions. Risk perceptions are also impacted by attitudes towards risk, such as the fact that persons tend to fear more acutely those risks they cannot control. Cognitive dissonance is another factor, because it induces people to ignore or alter their perceptions of risk in order to avoid unpleasant conflicts with established beliefs. Fourth, the additional compensation that a worker can obtain for hazardous work is a function of the worker’s bargaining power. Boden and Jones (1987) point out that estimates of wage differentials are substantially higher for unionized employees than for nonunionized employees. Moreover, Robinson (1991) cites data indicating that only poorly educated and low-skilled employees are likely to take dangerous jobs. His calculations reveal that hazardous jobs pay 20-30 percent less than safe employment after taking into account education and skill levels. He concludes that persons with training and education avoid such jobs because safer employment pays more, and that hazardous jobs are more likely to go to minority workers. Robinson found that Hispanic males were 80 percent more likely to suffer a disabling injury or illness than whites in California, and that black men were 40 percent more likely. McGarity and Shapiro (1993) argue that even educated and skilled workers may hesitate to leave dangerous jobs because the hazardous pay is inadequate. Such workers may be hesitant to change jobs because of the loss of health benefits, pension rights, and seniority, the expense and disruption of relocation, and the difficulty of becoming familiar with a new employer. Boden and Jones (1987) hypothesize that these reasons explain the relatively low wage premium received by asbestos installation workers who were familiar with the significant risks that they faced. A study by Kahn (1987) finds that occupational safety levels in nonunionized firms reflect only the preferences of workers with three or less years of job tenure, who are, he presumes, the most mobile workers in the firm.
5540
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
601
Dorman (1996) proposes that game theory be used to study the relationship of workers and employers concerning issues such as risk compensation. He argues that because game theory accounts for strategic behavior, it can clarify how cooperation and conflict inside a corporation impacts issues of public policy such as the protection of workers.
6. Reform Workers may be inhibited in obtaining wage premiums for workplace safety and health risks because of the lack of information or inadequate bargaining power. Analysts have discussed what steps governments can take to address these problems. Regulatory policies that increase workers’ access to risk information should improve market performance. Government action is likely to be necessary because, as Viscusi (1983) points out, the ‘aberrant characteristics of information as an economic good’ inhibit the creation of market arrangements to produce such information. OSHA’s hazardous communication standard is a good example of this type of government mandate. The regulation requires chemical manufacturers to provide a material safety data sheet, based on the available literature, for each hazardous product that they produce or use. The information is then made available to workers who are exposed to these products. Carle (1988) proposes improvements in OSHA’s regulation, while Viscusi (1983) supports additional regulation. He recommends that employers be required to apprise workers of the nature of the risks that they face, the risk level of the firm (death, injury and illness rates), its relative risk as compared to other firms in the industry, and other relevant risk information. The impact of additional information will depend on the ability of workers to use risk information. As noted in the last section, workers may have limited cognitive capacities or psychological defense mechanisms that impede rational use of risk information. Government can address these limitations by requiring that employers train workers to evaluate the information that they receive. A worker’s ability to obtain a wage premium is also dependent on the person’s bargaining power. Workers would have more bargaining power if they could not be fired for their refusal to undertake hazardous work. Rea (1983) reports that some Canadian provinces have given workers the right to refuse unsafe work. McGarity and Shapiro (1993) support similar reforms for the United States.
602
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
5540
C. Compensation 7. Introduction The wage premiums received by workers constitute ex ante compensation for occupational accidents and diseases. Workers also receive ex post compensation through workers’ compensation and tort law. Spieler (1994) provides a detailed description of the role of workers’ compensation in the United States. Prior to the early 1900s, workers could sue their employers for negligence if they were injured at work, but these tort suits were frustrated by a number of legal doctrines that prevented workers from recovering. According to Chelius (1976), many state legislatures had abolished some of these defenses prior to 1911. Recovery under the tort system remained inadequate, however, which prompted the passage of workers’ compensation laws. These laws discarded most of the remaining legal obstacles to recovery and, as a tradeoff, established two important limitations on workers. States prohibited workers from suing their employers under tort law, and they limited the types and amount of damages that workers could recover. Morgenstern (1982) has a general description of the role of compensation in other countries. Employers should respond to higher compensation costs by investing in safety and health improvements. Yet, analysts have been unable to establish a clear correlation between such higher costs and a reduction in workplace injuries and fatalities. Despite the lack of evidence, some analysts argue that workers’ compensation provides a significant incentive to make safety and health improvements, but other analysts dispute this conclusion. What is clear is that workers’ compensation fails to reimburse employees for accident and illness costs that are not paid by wage premiums. Government may improve the function of workers’ compensation by requiring employers to pay higher compensation, mandating that insurance rates more accurately reflect an employer’s safety experiences, or imposing a tax-based system of compensation.
8. Economic Theory An employer will determine whether to prevent workplace accidents or illnesses by comparing the cost of prevention with the cost of not taking such action. For risks that are not prevented, the employer will be responsible for paying workers’ compensation to injured or ill employers. A firm will invest in safety and health precautions until the cost is more than the cost of paying higher wages, workers’ compensation, and other accident and illness costs. If workers are fully compensated (ex post and ex ante) for the accidents and illnesses which are not prevented, the market for an employer’s product or
5540
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
603
services will be more efficient. The market is more efficient because the price of the product or service will include the cost of occupational accidents and illnesses associated with its production. In this manner, the price will reflect the actual cost to society of the production of the good or service. The actual cost to the firm of paying compensation, however, will depend on the nature of its insurance arrangements. Insurance arrangements can reduce a firm’s incentive to prevent future accidents and illnesses as explained below.
9. Empirical Evidence Although employers pay billions of dollars for workers’ compensation, analysts have been unable to verify that higher costs are associated with a reduction in workplace injuries. Some studies even find that higher costs are associated with an increase in injuries. The cost of workers’ compensation in the United States was about $62 billion in 1992 according to Boden (1995). Viscusi (1992) points to this cost as evidence that workers’ compensation is more influential than OSHA in promoting workplace safety because employers paid only about $10 million in OSHA fines in the same year. The empirical evidence, however, is equivocal concerning whether workers’ compensation induces employers to take safety precautions. Boden (1995) reviewed sixteen studies (which he lists and describes) which tested the relationship between an increase in workers’ compensation costs and workplace injuries, as measured by injury statistics or workers’ compensation claim rates. Most of the studies concluded that injuries increased or remained unchanged when benefit levels rose. A study by Moore and Viscusi (1989), however, concludes that the average fatality rate would have been 22 percent higher if there had been no workers’ compensation. By comparison, Butler and Worrall (1991) report that ‘virtually’ all studies of claim usage in workers’ compensation find that an increase in indemnity benefits increases workers’ compensation claim frequency.
10. Evaluation of Empirical Data Some analysts interpret the previous data as supporting the conclusion that workers’ compensation provides a significant incentive to make safety and health improvements. They argue that the data do not reveal this correlation because various actions by employees offset the reduction in compensation claims attributable to employer safety improvements. Other analysts argue that workers’ compensation does not create significant incentives for employers to
604
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
5540
invest in safety and health improvements because of the impact of insurance and other factors. The impact of workers’ compensation on occupational safety and health also depends on the extent to which workers are compensated for their injuries and illnesses. Despite the large cost of workers’ compensation, employers pay for only a portion of the cost of workplace accidents and for almost none of the cost of occupational illness.
11. Employee Behavior Employee behavior may explain why increases in workers’ compensation costs may not have produced lower injury rates. According to Butler and Worrall (1991), an increase in benefits will increase the propensity of workers to file claims for two reasons. When benefits are increased, workers are willing to undertake greater risk than previously and more injuries will occur. Also, workers have a greater incentive to file a claim for any given level of risk. Butler and Worrall characterize the former response as a ‘risk-bearing moral hazard’ and the latter behavior as a ‘claims-reporting moral hazard’. In addition, claims may increase because higher benefits induce additional fraud. The additional claims which result from these three types of behavior, if large enough, could offset any reduction in compensation claims attributable to employer safety or health improvements undertaken in response to increased compensation costs. According to the ‘risk-bearing moral hazard’ theory, workers are less vigilant and therefore suffer more (and more serious) injuries because higher benefits diminish the personal economic risks associated with such injuries. If such behavior offsets the impact of safety improvements by employers, as Fishback (1986, 1987), Lyttkens (1988), Moore and Viscusi (1990) and Butler and Worrall (1991) suggest, this theory would explain the positive relationship between increased workers’ compensation costs and injury rates. McGarity and Shapiro (1996) are skeptical of this explanation, however, because workers have strong economic and other incentives to avoid injuries. As discussed below, workers receive less, sometimes far less, than the actual costs of their injuries and illnesses. McGarity and Shapiro also doubt the idea that the prospect of money in the future will persuade a significant number of people to risk severe pain, hospitalization, dismemberment, and even death in the present. The second explanation of employee behavior focuses on the ‘claims reporting moral hazard’, which is also characterized as a ‘reporting’ effect. According to this explanation, higher workers’ compensation only increases the number of accident reports and not the absolute number of injuries. Since workers lose less income if they miss work, they may report more injuries and stay off work longer.
5540
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
605
Researchers have evaluated this second type of moral hazard by focussing on the link between workers’ compensation rates and events that should not be subject to a reporting effect. Some studies have focussed on the relationship between higher compensation rates and fatalities. Because fatalities are clearcut events, there should be no overreporting. Moore and Viscusi (1990) and Ruser (1993) found that increased benefits levels were associated with reduced fatality rates, but Butler (1983) discovered that benefit increases were associated with higher fatality rates. A study by Robertson and Keeve (1983) compared the impact of benefits levels on sprains and strains as compared to more ‘objective’ injuries, such as lacerations and fractures. This comparison revealed that reported injuries of both types increased with benefit levels, although the effect was stronger for sprains and strains. Kniesner and Leeth (1989) claim to establish the validity of the reporting theory based on a computer simulation. A study by Butler, Durbin and Helvacian (1996) attributed most of the significant increase in workers’ compensation claims for soft tissue injuries in the 1980s to moral hazard responses by employees and also by physicians. A physician in a health maintenance organization (HMO) may earn more by misclassifying a soft tissue injury as compensable in the workers’ compensation system, because this permits the physician to avoid a payment cap imposed by the employee’s health insurance company. Higher benefits might also induce more cases of fraud. For example, Staten and Umbeck (1986) propose that the practical need for administrators to screen compensation applicants on the basis of observable characteristics creates the potential that workers can manipulate the evidence at critical margins. They found evidence to support such a ‘signaling effect’ among air traffic controllers who sought compensation for stress-induced impairment. Burton (1992), however, concludes there is a ‘lack of supporting quantitative evidence’ and a ‘paucity of compelling qualitative analysis’ that significant fraud occurs.
12. Employer Behavior Moral hazard behavior may explain why analysts have had difficulty finding a correlation between higher compensation costs and a reduction in accidents and illnesses. Another explanation is that workers’ compensation does not create significant incentives for employers to invest in safety and health improvements. Employers may fail to take safety precautions in response to higher compensation costs for two reasons. First, workers’ compensation insurance accurately reflects an employer’s safety experience only for the largest firms. Second, there may be less expensive ways for employers to decrease compensation costs than to make safety and health improvements.
606
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
5540
Spieler (1994) explains that the price of workers’ compensation insurance does not reflect, or only partially reflects, the claims experience of most employers. The sensitivity of premiums to claims experience varies inversely with the size of the firm. The smallest firms, which constitute the majority of purchasers of all insurance, pay premiums that have no relationship to their actual claims experience. Because small firms have so few employees, insurance companies view their individual claims experience as too random to have any predictive value. Insurance companies therefore base the cost of insurance for small employers on the claims experience of a class of similar employers. Thus, small employers have only a weak economic incentive to take safety precautions because their actual claims experience will have little effect on their future premiums. Larger firms, which pay premiums based in part on claim losses, have a greater incentive to engage in injury prevention. The extent to which these firms are rated according to their claims experience depends on the credibility or predictive value of that experience. Only the largest employers are self-rated, which means they pay rates that are based entirely on their claims experience. These firms, and firms that selfinsure, therefore have the greatest economic incentive to reduce workplace risks. According to Victor (1982), however, the incentives for prevention are greater for self-rated firms in hazardous industries than for firms that selfinsure in the same industries. Analysts have compared the reduction in injuries at large and small firms to determine if there is an ‘experience-rating effect’. Some studies have found that higher compensation costs are associated with a decrease in injuries at large firms as compared to small firms, but other analysts have been unable to confirm this result. A study by Worrall and Butler (1988) revealed that reported injuries declined more at large firms than small ones when compensation costs increased. By comparison, Ruser (1985, 1991, found that higher benefits led to higher rates of nonfatal injuries at large and small firms, but that these effects were smaller for larger firms. Ruser considers this result as evidence that experience rating does matter, and that it counteracts other incentives for increased injuries. Another study by Ruser (1993) found an experience rating impact for injuries, but not for fatalities. Chelius and Smith (1983, 1993) were unable to verify an experience rating effect. Employers will not invest in safety or health improvements if there are lower cost methods to avoid compensation payments. The literature suggests that employers may have two such options. First, Spieler (1994) and Ison (1986) specify a number methods by which employers can discourage employees from filing claims or if claims are filed, from prevailing. Employers can pressure employees not to file claims, delay the
5540
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
607
completion of necessary paperwork, aggressively contest claims, and persuade employees who file claims to return to work prematurely. Second, as Spieler (1994) documents, employers have reacted to higher compensation costs by engaging in political activity to reduce future payments to workers. In response, states have reduced the level of benefits for some types of injuries, made other types of injuries noncompensable, limited allowable medical costs, capped physician fees, adopted administrative changes to make it easier to discontinue benefits to workers, and reduced lawyers’ fees. At the same time, however, states have also adopted various types of injury prevention and safety incentives or requirements. The literature does not indicate whether the net effect of these two types of actions has been to reduce or increase the incentive of employers to take safety precautions. The impact may vary from state to state depending, among other factors, on the relative political strength of employers and organized labor. Spieler also hypothesizes that employers may seek to reduce workers’ compensation payments by methods other than safety improvements because they ‘often perceive themselves as having less influence over the occurrence of injuries than they in fact have’. More generally, Veljanovski (1982) demonstrates that compensation systems will not produce optimal results under conditions when employers, as well as workers, have imperfect and asymmetrical information.
13. Adequacy of Compensation Analysts debate whether the cost of workers’ compensation creates an incentive for employers to reduce workplace accidents and illnesses. Even if it is assumed that such an incentive exists, spending on accident and illness prevention will not be optimal unless employers compensate employees for inadequacies in ex ante compensation. The evidence suggests however, that workers’ compensation does not reimburse workers for the costs of an injury or illness not covered by wage premiums. Schroeder and Shapiro (1984), Spieler (1994) and Boden (1995) establish that the states have established damage caps and other limitations that significantly restrict workers’ compensation for accidents. In most states, the level of compensation varies inversely with the seriousness of an injury. Compensation for temporary disabilities is controlled by statutory prescribed formulas that limit compensation to less than the direct wage losses of better paid employees. Compensation for permanent partial disability payments often does not equal the total wage loss of any employee. Compensation for fatalities is often less than for temporary and permanent disabilities. Furthermore,
608
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
5540
workers’ compensation does not include in damage calculations the loss of fringe benefits or nonpecuniary losses to workers and their families. Moreover, employers pay very little compensation for workplace-induced illness. Statistics cited by Weiler (1986) indicate that states compensate only 250 cancer cases per year as compared to the thousands of cancer fatalities that may be work related. Government studies cited in Schroeder and Shapiro (1984) indicate that only 2-3 percent of all workers’ compensation payments are for occupational disease. Schroeder and Shapiro and Barth (1984) hypothesize that several factors explain this low compensation rate. Workers and their physicians often fail to recognize that many illness are work-related. Moreover, employers are often successful in contesting those claims which are filed because of the difficulty of proving causation and because many states have restrictive standards for recovery. The few disease victims that do prevail face the same statutory limitations on compensation amounts that apply to injury victims. Even if more workers were compensated at higher rates, employers may still lack a strong economic incentive to invest in health precautions. A manager’s decision to invest in disease prevention is not based on current compensation expenses, which result from past actions, but on the likelihood that the investment will prevent future illness. Since occupational diseases are frequently characterized by long latency periods between exposure and disease onset, the manager can discount heavily the consequences and spend little or nothing on prevention. The manager’s decision to discount the costs of future illnesses may accurately reflect the current costs to the employer of future illnesses. A manager, however, may be tempted to discount the cost of future illnesses for another reason: any consequences for the employer will occur long after the manager has retired. Moreover, managers know that many workers will change jobs during the long latency period which frees the employer from paying compensation when the worker becomes ill.
14. Tort Compensation Few workers can seek additional compensation in a tort suit. Workers’ compensation laws in the United States almost always prohibit an employee from suing an employer for a tort remedy. As a result, a worker can seek a tort remedy only if some third party is responsible for an accident or illness. Viscusi (1989, 1991) reports that product liability claims for work-related injuries constitute about 13 percent of all product liability claims. After a detailed analysis of such law suits, he concludes that both workers’ compensation and tort liability have ‘important’ roles to play and that further research is necessary to understand the relationships of the two
5540
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
609
remedies. Boden and Jones (1987) found that the product liability compensation in asbestos cases ‘may’ provide substantial incentives for manufacturers to warn of future hazards, but that workers’ compensation provided ‘extremely’ low incentives for the control of asbestos. Schroeder and Shapiro (1984) believe few workers are likely to receive tort compensation for occupational illnesses. They list the array of legal hurdles that such workers must overcome. Moreover, Wiggins and Ringleb (1992) demonstrate that bankruptcy can be a viable shield from compensation payments in cases involving long-term hazards.
15. Workers’ Compensation Reform The government, as Phillips (1976) discusses, has three options to increase the financial incentive of employers to make safety and health improvements. First, it can require employers to pay higher amounts of workers’ compensation. Second, it can require insurance companies to base rates to a greater extent on the actual accident experience of employers. Finally, the government can impose a tax on employers that would reflect the costs associated with workplace accidents and illnesses. This last option is discussed in the next section. An increase in workers’ compensation payments should stimulate greater investment by employers in safety and health precautions, but an earlier discussion indicated that employers may not react in this manner. Moreover, there are significant practical and legal hurdles to adopting this reform in the United States. An increase in compensation would require action by 50 states and overcoming the opposition of employers who could expect to pay higher insurance costs. Greater reliance on experience rating should encourage employers to improve workplace safety and health because an employer’s insurance costs would be more closely tied to the firm’s actual safety and health record. Phillips (1976) discusses Ontario’s experience with a ‘penalty’ rating system that is intended to increase experience rating by insurance companies. Spieler (1994) explains that insurance companies in the United States have fought attempts to increase experience rating because it increases their costs. Governmental attempts to impose experience rating will therefore draw the political opposition of both insurance companies and high injury rate employers. Low injury rate employers, however, may support such changes. The previous reforms would improve how workers’ compensation functions to reduce workplace accidents. Most analysts agree with Lave (1983), however, that it ‘seems inconceivable’ that workers’ compensation can be reformed to handle occupational disease. Dewees and Daniels (1988) discuss the difficulties
610
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
5540
of designing a system that addresses the constraints, discussed earlier, which impair disease compensation.
16. Injury and Illness Taxes Instead of reforming workers’ compensation, many analysts have expressed interest in imposing injury and illness taxes. Analysts recommending imposition of an injury tax include Smith (1974, 1976), Nichols and Zeckhauser (1977), Mendeloff (1980), Rubin (1984), Sider (1984) and Sunstein (1990). Employers can be expected to oppose vigorously a new tax. This may explain why so few governments have tried this approach despite its theoretical attractiveness. An injury tax would have several advantages. It would create an additional incentive for employers to reduce workplace accidents and illnesses. Further, the amount that an employer would pay would be a function of its safety record. Thus, unlike workers’ compensation, an employer’s incentive to take safety precautions is not diluted because of the impact of insurance. As explained earlier, the cost of workers’ compensation insurance for many firms does not reflect, or does not fully reflect, their safety record. Finally, as compared to OSHA regulation, a tax is a more efficient method by which to reduce workplace risks. Under OSHA regulation, all employers must comply with the level of safety that OSHA specifies regardless of the cost of compliance. Under a tax approach, an employer would have the option of paying the tax if it was less expensive that the cost of abatement of a hazard. Shapiro and McGarity (1991) dispute that a tax would necessarily be more efficient than regulation. First, they contend that OSHA regulation is not as inefficient as the agency’s critics believe. They note that OSHA relies on performance standards, which permit an employer to choose the method of compliance, and on variances, which give employers with high costs additional time for compliance. Second, they predict that employers are likely to engage in the same types of tax avoidance as they now practice concerning other taxes. A tax approach can also be used for occupational disease, but calculation of an appropriate tax rate might not be possible. Dewees and Daniels (1988) caution that the determination of an appropriate exposure charge would be difficult because it would require information that is not readily available. An exposure charge based on health effects requires knowledge of a quantifiable dose-response function, which measures the number of workers likely to become ill at different levels of exposure. Dose-response estimates, however, are not available for most chemicals, and the estimates that are available often vary by several orders of magnitude. Barth (1984) and Viscusi (1984) would avoid this problem by financing compensation for employees with a broadbased tax levied on their employers. This approach, however, would not
5540
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
611
generate appropriate incentives for illness avoidance, because the tax would not be based on extent to which individual firms exposed workers to dangerous chemicals.
D. Regulation 17. Introduction Labor markets and compensation of injured and ill workers create financial incentives for employers to take safety and health precautions. Regulation offers a more direct means to accomplish the same result. Most of the literature on regulation addresses OSHA regulation in the United States. OSHA’s mandate is to ‘assure so far as possible every working man and woman in the Nation safe and healthful working conditions’. The OSH Act requires employers to comply with safety and health regulations, or ‘standards’, promulgated by OSHA. OSHA is authorized to inspect employers for potential violations and to assess civil penalties if violations are found. OSHA may also seek criminal penalties in limited circumstances if an employee has been killed. McGarity and Shapiro (1993) and Mendeloff (1980, 1988) generally summarize and evaluate OSHA’s role in promoting workplace safety and health. Wilson (1985) and Kelman (1981) compare OSHA regulation to regulation in Great Britain and Sweden respectively. Lanoie (1992a, 1992b) has analyzed the impact of occupational safety and health regulation in Canada.
18. Economic Theory An employer will make safety and health improvements until the cost of these precautions is more than the cost of paying additional wages, workers’ compensation premiums (if experience rated), and other related costs. If, however, such financial incentives fail, employers will underinvest in safety and health improvements. Such incentives can fail for the reasons discussed earlier, including the inability of workers to obtain full compensation for their injuries and illnesses from wage premiums and workers’ compensation. Regulators can address this shortfall by ordering employers to undertake safety and health precautions improvements up to the point where the costs of such improvements exceed their benefits. If benefits are measured as the value of the improvements to workers, administrative regulation will produce about the same level of investment in safety and health precautions as fully effective financial incentives. In other words, the government would order the same level of protection as would be produced if employers fully compensated workers for their injuries and illnesses.
612
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
5540
Although economic theory favors the use of such a cost-benefit approach, Congress has chosen another standard to control health and safety regulation in the United States. This standard requires OSHA to seek the level of protection for workers which is available from the ‘best-available technology’ (BAT). Once OSHA establishes that a workplace hazard is a ‘significant risk’, it must order an employer to reduce that risk to the extent that is ‘feasible’. A standard is feasible when it is technologically achievable and when employers can afford the cost of implementing it. A standard is not economically infeasible because it is financial burdensome or even because it threatens the survival of some firms in an industry. As discussed below, many analysts favor replacing this technology-based approach with a cost-benefit standard.
19. Empirical Evidence Analysts have attempted to confirm that OSHA’s activities have led to an improvement in workplace safety. They have isolated OSHA’s impact on fatality and injury rates in three types of studies. All three efforts have produced inconsistent results. Some studies have projected the trend of pre-OSHA injury rates and compared the projected results with the actual results. Smith (1976) compared the actual injury rates in several high-hazard industries that OSHA had targeted for enforcement with projected injury rates. The comparison revealed that actual rates were not significantly lower than projected rates. Mendeloff (1980), by comparison, found that the actual rates were significantly lower than the projected rates for several individual types of injuries in California. His study, however, found that OSHA had no impact on the aggregate injury rate for California and the nation. Curington (1986) likewise had mixed results. The frequency rate for all injuries in manufacturing industries in New York was no lower than the projected rate for such injuries, but there were reductions in injuries resulting from being struck by a machine (43.6 percent) and in the severity of all injuries (13.2 percent). Other studies have tested the correlation between aggregate industry level injury rates and OSHA inspection activity. For example, when Viscusi (1992) tested whether injury rates were affected by the frequency of OSHA inspections and penalties, he found that OSHA caused a 1.5-3.6 percent decrease in the lost workday rate. The ‘lost workday rate’ measures the number of days of work that an employee misses after an injury. Viscusi indicates that earlier studies by himself and others found no measurable correlation between the number of OSHA inspections and injury rates. Finally, some studies have sought a correlation between individual plant level injury data and an employer’s inspection experience. Gray and Scholz
5540
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
613
(1993) found that an inspection imposing a penalty reduced injuries by 22 percent and lost workdays by 20 percent in the following three years. Using the same methodology, Cooke and Gautschi (1981), Robertson and Keeve (1983), and Scholz and Gray (1990) found similar impacts, but Smith (1979), McCaffrey (1983), and Ruser and Smith (1991) found no association using a different testing technique. Other analysts have measured the relationship between OSHA inspection activity and compliance with OSHA safety regulations. Gray and Jones (1991a), for example, found a significant relationship between OSHA enforcement and compliance at individual plants. Bartel and Thomas (1985) also found that OSHA enforcement significantly increased compliance (by a total of 26 percent relative to no enforcement), but they found only a weak link between compliance and injury rates. Only a few analysts have attempted to confirm that OSHA’s activities have led to an improvement in workplace health. Gray and Jones (1991b) found that OSHA inspections reduced the exposure of workers to hazardous substances and increased compliance with health regulations.
20. Evaluation of Empirical Evidence Bartel and Thomas (1985) explain there are two conflicting explanations for the lack of empirical evidence that OSHA activity results in fewer workplace accidents and injuries. The ‘inefficacy’ explanation proposes that administrative regulation is unable to address many of the causes of workplace accidents. The ‘noncompliance’ explanation proposes that the OSHA lacks the resources to undertake effective enforcement. In addition, Mendeloff (1988) offers a theory for the lack of effective regulation of health risks, which is considered in the next section. The ‘inefficacy’ theory posits that administrative regulation does not increase workplace safety because there is a tenuous link between regulation and the causes of accidents. Administrative regulation focusses on making workplace equipment safer to use. Analysts argue, however, that the cause of most accidents is a complex interaction of labor, equipment and workplace environment. In light of this mismatch, Barcow (1980) predicts that OSHA may be incapable of preventing more than 25 percent of all workplace accidents. Moreover, Rea (1981) hypothesizes that moral hazard may reduce the level of safety because workers will attempt to substitute wages for safer jobs. Bartel and Thomas (1985) ask why Congress has failed to reform, or even eliminate, OSHA in light of its apparent inefficacy. They observe that OSHA regulations may give large firms a competitive advantage over their smaller rivals because the smaller firms are less able to afford expensive regulations.
614
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
5540
They hypothesize that larger firms support OSHA because the gains from this competitive advantage exceeds the costs of complying with OSHA regulations. Bartel and Thomas (1987) offer empirical evidence that larger firms have such a competitive advantage concerning OSHA regulations. Fuess and Loewenstein (1990) have similar evidence for coal mine regulation. Their study finds the imposition of expensive engineering controls shifted production to large mines by driving smaller, less safe mines out of business. Hughes, Magat and Ricks (1986), however, were unable to establish that OSHA’s cotton dust standards permitted large firms to gain in profitability at the expense of smaller producers. Similarly, Miller (1984) asks whether organized labor is rational in support of OSHA. He offers some empirical support for the proposition that engineering controls may increase the demand for labor. The ‘noncompliance theory’ proposes that OSHA lacks the statutory and budgetary authority to enforce its standards effectively. McGarity and Shapiro (1996) point out that OSHA inspections have had a greater impact on the injury rates of inspected firms than on aggregate injury rates. They also point out that the industries with the most significant decline in injuries and fatalities are the industries with the highest levels of enforcement. They attribute OSHA’s limited impact on aggregate injury rates to the fact that the agency’s limited resources do not permit it to inspect the vast majority of employers that it regulates.
21. Overregulation Causes Underregulation The previous theories address OSHA’s impact on workplace accidents. Mendeloff (1988) attempts to explain OSHA’s limited impact on occupational disease. He identifies OSHA’s mandate as the cause because it requires the strict regulation of toxic substances. The problem is that such ‘overregulation’ causes ‘underregulation’. Overregulation occurs when the costs of a regulation exceed its benefits. Underregulation occurs when the costs of additional regulation are less than the benefits. Mendeloff argues that strict regulation of toxic substances causes less protection of workers than the promulgation of more lenient regulations. Strict regulation protects workers less then more lenient regulations because of how employers react to each type of regulation. OSHA has been able to promulgate very few health regulations because employers vigorously resist overregulation. As a result, OSHA spends inordinate time and resources defending strict standards. Mendeloff proposes that OSHA could successfully promulgate more standards if it balanced costs and benefits. OSHA would be more successful because industry would be less likely to challenge more lenient regulations in court, and, if such regulations were challenged, OSHA would be more likely to prevail. In this manner, workers ultimately would receive more
5540
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
615
protection from a more lenient approach. Although each OSHA regulation would be less protective of workers, the sum total of protection for workers would be greater because the agency could promulgate more standards overall. McGarity and Shapiro (1993) and Shapiro and McGarity (1991) object that employers will oppose even lenient regulations. They offer evidence that employers gain financial benefits from delaying even modest health and safety regulations. If the problem is employer intransigence, McGarity and Shapiro propose that Congress changes OSHA’s statutory mandate to make it easier for OSHA to prevail when it is sued. McGarity and Shapiro (1993) and Shapiro and McGarity (1989) also propose rulemaking reforms that OSHA can undertake to speed up rulemaking and make it more rational. These include improving how OSHA sets its regulatory priorities and focussing on types of regulations that yield the greatest protection for workers.
22. Reform of OSHA’s Regulatory Standard Mendeloff proposes that OSHA should balance costs and benefits in health regulation because employers would be less likely to challenge more lenient regulation in court. Other analysts favor adoption of a cost-benefit standard for OSHA safety and health regulation because this approach is more consistent with economic theory. Economic theory favors a cost-benefit approach for regulation because it equates the marginal benefits of safety and health improvements with the marginal cost of such precautions. Besides Mendeloff, supporters of a cost-benefit approach include Viscusi (1983, 1992) and Sunstein (1990, 1996). More generally, Litan and Nordhaus (1986) propose that Congress establish a regulatory budget for OSHA and similar agencies which would establish caps for the regulatory costs that the agency could impose. Arguments that OSHA should be subject to a cost-benefit approach follow the arguments made in general for using cost-benefit analysis to specify the extent of safety, health and other social regulation. Sunstein (1990, 1996) and Breyer (1993) contain a useful statement of the general arguments. The primary benefit of the cost-benefit analysis is that it addresses safety and health risks in light of the fact that society will always have limited resources to spend on safety and health. Cost-benefit balancing promotes rationality by helping to ensure that those resources are spent in the most efficient manner possible. By comparison, critics find that OSHA regulations often impose costs that exceed benefits sometimes by hundreds of millions of dollars. For example, Morrall (1979) objects to OSHA’s noise regulation because it mandated the use of expensive engineering controls rather than much less expensive personal protection equipment such as ear plugs. Analysts have made similar criticisms of other workplace safety regulation. French
616
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
5540
(1988), for example, suggests that railroad safety regulation in the United States is inefficient because excessive burdens are imposed on firms. A second benefit of the cost-benefit approach is that it makes agencies more accountable to the public. Safety and health regulation will inevitably require tradeoffs among regulatory goals because of society’s limited resources. Without a cost-benefit approach, the public has difficulty learning about such tradeoffs. By comparison, a cost-benefit approach requires agencies to make these tradeoffs more explicit. A third advantage is that the cost-benefit approach responds to the problem of regulatory ‘perversity’. Critics of regulation, such as Sunstein (1997), warn that an attempt to reduce one safety or health risk can increase other safety or health risks. This would occur, for example, when the regulation of one chemical leads manufacturers to use more dangerous substitutes. More generally, Sunstein cites to an incipient literature that considers whether costly regulation increases risks because such regulations reduce wealth. This possibility is suggested by the fact that persons who are unemployed or poor tend to be more unhealthy and to live shorter lives. Cost-benefit analysis addresses this problem by requiring agencies to examine the ‘substitution risks’ that might result from a proposed regulatory action.
23. Support of OSHA’s Standard McGarity and Shapiro (1993, 1996) and Shapiro and McGarity (1991) defend the current technology-based approach to regulation. Their arguments, summarized below, follow the arguments made in general by Cranor (1993), McGarity (1991), Sagoff (1988) and others against using cost-benefit analysis to specify the extent of safety, health, environmental, and other social regulation. One criticism is that cost-benefit analysis is too unreliable to constitute an effective method to implement regulations. Critics point out that current risk assessment techniques do not have the power to permit precise calculations of the number of lives saved or injuries avoided, and that methods used to reduce these benefits to dollars amounts are highly contestable. As a result, the costbenefit approach ordinarily raises difficult methodological issues that are exceedingly expensive and time-consuming for agencies to resolve and defend in court. In comparison, a technology-based approach more simply sets industry-wide limitations on the basis of the level of precaution that the best performers in the industry are capable of achieving. Supporters of a technology-based approach also deny that it leads to the type of regulatory excesses identified by the supporters of the cost-benefit approach. As just noted, estimates of costs and benefits are highly imprecise. In light of this imprecision, critics of a cost-benefit approach are skeptical regarding
5540
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
617
claims that the cost of OSHA regulation greatly exceeds the benefits. A second criticism is that the cost-benefit approach is at its core ‘incoherent’ because it cannot yield a single numerical value. According to this argument, the general tendency of individuals to buy and sell goods for roughly the same price (the market price) does not apply when credible risks to health and safety are being traded. Instead, individuals are normally willing to sell the right to be free from increased mortality risks for considerable more money than they are willing to pay to reduce such risks. The reason is that most persons can demand more in a bargain in which they are asked to sacrifice something of great value, to which they have a right, than they can afford to pay for that same thing, if someone else has the right to take it from them. Thus, use of a ‘willingness to sell’ measure of the benefits of a safety or health regulation yields a different, and higher, value than use of a ‘willingness to buy’ measure of such benefits. Despite this incoherence, regulators must rely on a ‘willingness to buy’ measurement because it is the only one for which there are data. Estimates of wage premiums indicate how much workers are willing to pay for a safer workplace. When workers seek safer jobs, they will forfeit the wage premiums paid for riskier work. Critics also argue that reliance on a ‘willingness to buy’ measurement of the value of human life is ethically objectionable. This argument contends that poor people are not likely to sell the right to be safe for any less than a rich person would. By comparison, a person’s wealth will affect the amount that he or she can pay to purchase the right to be safe. A fourth criticism is that discounting future benefits to present value biases the cost-benefit approach against the prevention of occupational disease. Although employers must immediate pay for prevention, the benefits of such actions will not show up for years. The latency period for occupational disease is usually 20 or 30 years. As a result, the benefits of a regulation that would prevent such losses can be outweighed by even modest present costs. Supporters of a cost-benefit standard defend the use of a discount rate. They argue that if workers had the opportunity to spend money on prevention today, which would result in lower wages, in return for a lower probability of cancer 30 years later, the workers themselves could likely discount the future costs of the disease. In other words, individuals put different values on dying 30 years from now and dying today. Defenders also dispute that the use of discounting results in a lack of appropriate regulation. They assert that an investment in abatement should earn a sufficiently large return over 30 years to justify the protection of workers. When this is not true, evaluators should verify that they are using an appropriate discount rate. Finally, critics charge that use of a cost-benefit standard as the primary decision criterion effectively elevates economic efficiency to a ‘meta-value’ that trumps all other conflicting values. OSHA’s mandate, which reflects both
618
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
5540
economic and noneconomic considerations, rejects the idea that the maximization of material wealth is the only goal of a good society. Instead, it seeks to balance ‘efficiency’, ‘fairness’, and other important social values.
24. Reform of Enforcement An earlier discussion explained that empirical studies suggest OSHA inspection activity has not lead to a reduction in aggregate injury rates. One explanation is that many causes of workplace accidents cannot be addressed by safety regulations. Another explanation is that OSHA has insufficient resources to expand its successful enforcement efforts at some plants to most employers. The literature on enforcement focusses on how OSHA can promote greater compliance in light of its limited resources. Viscusi (1986a, 1986b) analyzes this issue in terms of an employer’s economic incentives to comply with OSHA regulations. Employers will comply when it cost less to make safety improvements than to risk an adverse OSHA inspection. The risk to an employer of an inspection is a function of the likelihood that the firm will be inspected and the penalties that the firm will suffer if violations are detected. These penalties include OSHA fines as well as any adverse effect on the employer’s reputation. If the employer’s reputation is adversely affected, there may be worker turnover, increased demands for wage premiums, or other adverse consequences. In light of these incentives, Viscusi proposes that OSHA can improve compliance by increasing the likelihood that the most dangerous workplaces are inspected and that large fines are assessed for serious violations. McGarity and Shapiro (1993) support these recommendations and amplify how they might be implemented. OSHA can increase the likelihood that it will find the most dangerous work conditions by focussing its inspection activity on the most dangerous employers and its individual inspections on identifying the most serious violations. Analysts, such as Bardach and Kagan (1982) and Howard (1994), have criticized OSHA for zealously enforcing detailed rules in circumstances where enforcement is counterproductive, unfair, or even nonsensical. OSHA, however, has a potential problem in using injury records to target inspections. Ruser and Smith (1988) show that using injury records to target inspections creates an incentive for employers to underreport injuries in high-hazard industries. If OSHA uses such records for purposes of targeting, it must audit employers to reduce underreporting. Fry and Lee (1989) propose that the ‘real teeth’ of OSHA citations may be the impact on the stock market value of a firm. They found that the announcement of fines produce an immediate and pronounced decline in the
5540
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
619
value of the firm subject to the penalties. They hypothesize the decline may reflect the additional costs a firm can expect such as the need to make safety improvements. Regulators might also enhance compliance with regulations by mandating that employers establish joint employer-employee health and safety committees to monitor workplace conditions. Such committees may improve safety by focussing the attention of employers and employees on workplace hazards, and by providing a forum for the exchange of information. These committees might be especially effective in the absence of a union to give workers a voice concerning safety issues. Spieler (1994) documents that a number of states have instituted such a requirement. Rea (1983) discusses Canadian laws which require such committees. He notes that because joint safety committees were already in existence in larger unionized establishments, the main impact of the legislation is to extend the practice to small firms and nonunionized work places. Walters and Haines (1988) found, however, that workers in Ontario had only weak links with their health and safety representatives, and few workers made use of this resource.
E. Conclusions 25. Market, Compensation and Regulatory Alternatives An employer will invest in safety and health precautions until the cost is more than the expense of paying higher wages, workers’ compensation, and other accident and illness costs. Employees receive additional protection because governments have chosen to augment these financial incentives with regulation. Economic theory would have governments order the same level of protection as would be produced if employers fully compensated workers for their injuries and illnesses and paid any additional accident and illness costs. In the United States, however, Congress has established a technology-based goal for OSHA, which requires the agency to seek the highest level of protection which is technologically feasible. Analysts have studied the impact of compensatory wages, workers’ compensation, and regulation on safety and health. These studies indicate that all three approaches promote investments in safety and health protection, but the extent of such improvement is difficult to verify and may be limited in numerous situations. There are various explanations for this lack of efficacy, some of which conflict, but all of which suggest that labor markets, compensation and regulation are impeded by significant constraints. Various reforms have been proposed to address these constraints, but the literature has not reached a consensus concerning some key proposals. In particular, there is a considerable debate concerning whether OSHA should be
620
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
5540
subject to a cost-benefit test. There is also a question of political viability concerning some reforms. In the United States, for example, reform of workers’ compensation requires action by all 50 states. This analysis confirms that labor markets, compensation, and regulation are highly imperfect alternatives concerning the reduction of occupational accidents and illnesses. It also suggests that it is necessary to rely on all three approaches. Each approach alone, even if reformed, is unlikely to produce an appropriate level of occupational safety and health. The combination of the three, by comparison, is more likely to move countries closer to this elusive goal.
Acknowledgments Professor Shapiro gratefully acknowledges the highly useful comments of two anonymous reviewers.
Bibliography on Occupational Safety and Health Regulation (5540) Barcow, Lawrence S. (1980), Bargaining for Job Safety and Health, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 158 p. Bartel, Ann P. and Thomas, Lacy Glenn (1985), ‘Direct and Indirect Effects of Regulation: A New Look at OSHA’s Impact’, 28 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-25. Bartel, Ann P. and Thomas, Lacy Glenn (1987), ‘Predation through Regulation: The Wage and Profit Effects of the Occupational Safety and Health Administration and the Environmental Protection Agency’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 239-264. Barth, Peter S. (1984), ‘A Proposal for Dealing with the Compensation of Occupational Diseases’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 569-586. Boden, Leslie I. (1995), ‘Workers’ Compensation in the United States: High Costs, Low Benefits’, 16 Annual Review Public Health, 208-218. Boden, Leslie I. and Jones, Carl Adaire (1987), ‘Occupational Disease Remedies: The Asbestos Experience’, in Bailey, Elizabeth E. (ed), Public Regulation: New Perspectives on Institutions and Policies, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 321-346. Burton, John F., Jr (1992), ‘Workers’ Compensation Costs, 1960 - The Increases, the Causes and the Consequences’, John Burton’s Workers’ Compensation Monitor, Mar.-Apr. 1993, 1-23. Butler, Richard J. (1983), ‘Wage and Injury Rate Response to Shifting Levels of Workers’ Compensation’, in Worrall, John D. (ed), Safety and The Workforce, Ithaca, NY, ILR Press, 61-86. Butler, Richard J. and Worrall, John D. (1991), ‘Claims Reporting and Risk Bearing Moral Hazard in Workers’ Compensation’, 63 Journal of Risk and Insurance, 191-204. Butler, Richard J., Durbin, David L. and Helvacian, Nurhan M. (1996), ‘Increasing Claims For Soft Tissue Injuries in Workers’ Compensation: Cost Shifting and Moral Hazard’, 13 Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 73-87. Carle, Susan D. (1988), ‘A Hazardous Mix: Discretion to Disclose and Incentives to Suppress Under
5540
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
621
OSHA’s Hazard Communication Standard’, 97 Yale Law Journal, 581-601. Carmichael, H. Lorne (1986), ‘Reputations for Safety: Market Performance and Policy Remedies’, 4 Journal of Labor Economics, 458-472. Chelius, James R. (1974), ‘The Control of Industrial Accidents: Economic Theory and Empirical Evidence’, 38(4) Law and Contemporary Problems, 700-729. Chelius, James R. (1976), ‘Liability for Industrial Accidents: A Comparison of Negligence and Strict Liability Systems’, 5 Journal of Legal Studies, 293-309. Chelius, James R. and Smith, Robert S. (1983), ‘Experience-Rating and Injury Prevention’, in Worrall, John D. (ed), Safety and The Workforce, Ithaca, NY, ILR Press, 128-137. Chelius, James R., and Smith, Robert S. (1993), ‘The Impact of Experience-Rating on Employer Behavior: The Case of Washington State’, in Durbin, David and Borba, Philip S. (eds), Workers’ Compensation Insurance: Claims Costs, Prices, and Regulation, Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 293-306. Cooke, William N. and Gautschi, Frederick H. (1981), ‘OSHA, Plant Safety Programs, and Injury Reduction’, 20 Industrial Relations, 245-257. Curington, William P. (1986), ‘Safety Regulation and Workplace Injuries’, 53 Southern Economic Journal, 51-72. Darling-Hammon, Linda and Kniesner, Thomas J. (1980), The Law and Economics of Workers’ Compensation, Santa Monica, Rand Institute for Civil Justice, 86 p. Dewees, Donald N. with Daniels, Ronald J. (1988), ‘Prevention and Compensation of Industrial Disease’, 8 International Review of Law and Economics, 51-72. Dickens, William T. (1984), ‘Occupational Safety and Health Regulation and Economic Theory’, in Darity, William, Jr (ed), Labor Economics: Modern Views, Boston, Kluwer-Nijhoff, 133-173. Dorman, Peter (1996), Markets and Morality: Economics, Dangerous Work, and The Value of Human Life, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 274 p. Fishback, Price V. (1986), ‘Workplace Safety during the Progressive Era: Fatal Accidents in Bituminous Coal Mining, 1912-1923', 23 Explorations in Economic History, 269-298. Fishback, Price V. (1987), ‘Liability Rules and Accident Prevention in the Workplace: Empirical Evidence from the Early Twentieth Century’, 16 Journal of Legal Studies, 305-328. French, Michael Thomas (1988), ‘An Efficiency Test for Occupational Safety Regulation’, 54 Southern Economic Journal, 675-693. Fry, Clifford L. and Lee, Insup (1989), ‘OSHA Sanctions and the Value of the Firm’, 24 Financial Review, 599-610. Fuess, Scott M., Jr and Lowenstein, Mark A. (1990), ‘Further Analysis of the Theory of Economic Regulation: The Case of the 1969 Coal Mine Health and Safety Act’, 28 Economic Inquiry, 354-389. Gray, Wayne B. and Jones, Carolyn Adaire (1991a), ‘Longitudinal Patterns of Compliance with Occupational Safety and Health Administration Health and Safety Regulations in the Manufacturing Sector’, 26 Journal of Human Resources, 1623-654. Gray, Wayne B. and Jones, Carolyn Adaire (1991b), ‘Are OSHA Health Inspections Effective?: A Longitudinal Study in the Manufacturing Sector’, 73 Review of Economics and Statistics, 1504-508. Gray, Wayne B. and Scholz, John T. (1993), ‘Does Regulatory Enforcement Work: A Panel Analysis of OSHA Enforcement’, 27 Law and Society Review, 177-213.
622
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
5540
Hughes, John S., Magat, Wesley A. and Ricks, William E. (1986), ‘The Economic Consequences of the OSHA Cotton Dust Standards: An Analysis of Stock Price Behavior’, 29 Journal of Law and Economics, 29-59. Ison, Terence B. (1986), ‘The Significance of Experience Rating’, 24 Osgoode Hall Law Journal, 723-742. Kahn, Shulamit (1987), ‘Occupational Safety and Workers Preferences: Is There a Marginal Worker?’, 69 Review of Economics and Statistics, 262-268. Kelman, Steven (1981), Regulating America, Regulating Sweden: A Comparative Study of Occupational Safety and Health Policy, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 270 p. Kniesner, Thomas J. and Leeth, John D. (1989), ‘Separating the Reporting Effects from the Injury Rate Effects of Workers Compensation Insurance: A Hedonic Simulation’, 42 Industrial and Legal Relations Review, 280-293. Lanoie, Paul (1992a), ‘The Impact of Occupational Safety and Health Regulation on the Risk of Workplace Accidents: Quebec, 1983-1987', 27 Journal of Human Resources, 642-660. Lanoie, Paul (1992b), ‘Safety Regulation and the Risk of Workplace Accidents in Quebec’, 58 Southern Economic Journal, 1950-1965. Lave, L.B. (1983), ‘Viscusi’s Risk by Choice: Regulating Health and Safety in the Workplace’, 14 Bell Journal of Economics, 607-610. Leigh, J. Paul (1991), ‘No Evidence of Compensating Wages for Occupational Fatalities’, 30 Industrial Relations, 382-395. Litan, Robert E. and Nordhaus, William D. (1986), ‘Regulatory Reform and OSHA Policy: Comments’, 5 Journal of Policy Analysis and Management, 467-481. Lyttkens, C.H. (1988), ‘Workers’ Compensation and Employees’ Safety Incentives in Sweden’, 8 International Review of Law and Economics, 181-185. McCaffrey, David P. (1983), ‘An Assessment of OSHA’s Recent Effects on Injury Rates’, 18 Journal of Human Resources, 131-146. McGarity, Thomas O. and Shapiro, Sidney A. (1993), Workers At Risk: The Failed Promise of the Occupational Safety and Health Administration, Wesport, Conn., Praeger, 362p. McGarity, Thomas O. and Shapiro, Sidney A. (1996), ‘OSHA’s Critics and Regulatory Reform’, 31 Wake Forest Law Review, 587-646 Mendeloff, John M. (1980), An Economic and Political Analysis of Occupational Safety and Health, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 219 p. Mendeloff, John M. (1988), The Dilemma of Toxic Substance Regulation: How Overregulation Causes Underregulation at OSHA, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 321 p. Miller, James C., III (1984), ‘Is Organized Labor Rational in Supporting OSHA?’, 50 Southern Economic Journal, 881-885. Moore, Michael J. and Viscusi, W. Kip (1989), ‘Promoting Safety Through Workers’ Compensation: The Efficacy and Net Wage Costs of Injury Insurance’, 20 Rand Journal of Economics, 499-515. Moore, Michael J. and Viscusi, W. Kip (1990), Compensation Mechanisms For Job Risks: Wages, Workers’ Compensation, and Product Liability, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press, 188 p. Morgenstern, Felice (1982), ‘Some Reflections on Legal Liability as a Factor in the Promotion of Occupational Safety and Health’, 121 International Labour Review, 387-398. Morrall, John F. (1979), ‘Exposure to Occupational Noise’, in Miller, James C. and Yandle, Bruce
5540
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
623
(eds), Benefit-Cost Analysis of Social Regulation: Case Studies from the Council on Wage and Price Stability, Washington, American Enterprise Institute, 33-58 Nichols, Albert, L. and Zeckhauser, Richard (1977), ‘Government Comes to the Workplace: An Assessment of OSHA’, 49 Public Interest, 39-69. Oi, Walter Y. (1974), ‘On the Economics of Industrial Safety’, 38(4) Law and Contemporary Problems, 669-699. Phillips, Jerry J. (1976), ‘Economic Deterrence and the Prevention of Industrial Accidents’, 5 Industrial Law Journal, 148-163. Rea, Samuel A., Jr (1981), ‘Workmen’s Compensation and Occupational Safety Under Imperfect Information’, 71 American Economic Review, 80-93. Rea, Samuel A., Jr (1983), ‘Regulation of Occupational Health and Safety’, in Dewees, D.N. (ed), Quality Regulation, Toronto, Butterworths, 109-140. Robertson, Leon S. and Keeve, A. Phillip (1983), ‘Worker Injuries: The Effects of Workers’ Compensation and OSHA Inspections’, 8 Journal of Health, Politics, and Law, 581-597. Robinson, James C. (1991), Toil and Toxics: Workplace Struggles and Political Strategies for Occupational Health, Berkeley, University of California Press, 226 p. Rubin, Jeffrey (1984), ‘Economic Incentives and Safety Regulation: An Analytical Framework’, 28(1) American Economist, 18-24. Ruser, John W. (1985), ‘Workers’ Compensation, Experience-Rating, and Occupational Injuries’, 16 Rand Journal of Economics, 498-503. Ruser, John W. (1991), ‘Workers’ Compensation and Occupational Injuries and Illnesses’, 9 Journal of Labor Economics, 325-351. Ruser, John W. (1993), ‘Workers’ Compensation and the Distribution of Occupational Injuries,’ 28 Journal of Human Resources, 593-618. Ruser, John W. and Smith, Robert S. (1988), ‘The Effect of OSHA Records-Check Inspections on Reported Occupational Injuries in Manufacturing Establishments’, 1 Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 415-435. Ruser, John W. and Smith, Robert S. (1991), ‘Reestimating OSHA’s Effects: Have the Data Changed?’, 26 Journal of Human Resources, 212-236. Scholz, John T. and Gray, Wayne B. (1990), ‘OSHA Enforcement and Workplace Injuries: A Behavioral Approach to Risk Assessment’, 3 Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 283-305. Schroeder, Elinor P. and Shapiro, Sidney A. (1984), ‘Responses to Occupational Disease: The Role of Markets, Regulation, and Information’, 72 Georgetown Law Journal, 1231-1309. Shapiro, Sidney A. and McGarity, Thomas O. (1989), ‘Reorienting OSHA: Regulatory Alternatives and Legislative Reform’, 6 Yale Journal on Regulation, 1-63. Shapiro, Sidney A. and McGarity, Thomas O. ( 1991), ‘Not So Paradoxical: The Rationale For Technology-Based Regulation’, Duke Law Journal, 729-752. Sider, Hal (1984), ‘Economic Incentives and Safety Regulation: An Analytical Framework’, 28(1) American Economist, 18-24. Smith, Robert S. (1974), ‘The Feasibility of an ‘Injury Tax’ Approach to Occupational Safety’, 38(4) Law and Contemporary Problems, 730-744. Smith, Robert S. (1976), The Occupational Safety and Health Act: Its Goals and Its Achievements, Washington, American Enterprise Institute, 104 p. Smith, Robert S. (1979), ‘The Impact of OSHA Inspections on Manufacturing Injury Rates’, 14 Journal of Human Resources, 145-170.
624
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
5540
Spieler, Emily (1994), ‘Perpetuating Risk? Workers Compensation and the Persistence of Occupational Injuries’, 31 Houston Law Review, 119-264. Staten, Michael and Umbeck, John (1986), ‘A Study of Signaling Behavior in Occupational Disease Claims’, 29 Journal of Law and Economics, 263-286. Veljanovski, Cento G. (1982), ‘The Employment and Safety Effects of Employers’ Liability’, 29 Scottish Journal of Political Economy. Victor, Richard B. (1982), Workers’ Compensation and Workplace Safety: The Nature of Employer Incentives, Santa Monica, CA, Institute for Civil Justice, Rand Corporation, 68 p. Viscusi, W. Kip (1983), Risk By Choice: Regulatory Health and Safety in the Workplace, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 200 p. Viscusi, W. Kip (1984), ‘Structuring an Effective Occupational Disease Policy: Victim Compensation and Risk Regulation’, 2 Yale Journal on Regulation, 53-81. Viscusi, W. Kip (1986a), ‘Reforming OSHA Regulation of Workplace Risks’, in Weiss, Leonard W. and Klass, Michael W. (ed), Regulatory Reform: What Actually Happened, Boston, Little Brown, 234-268. Viscusi, W. Kip (1986b), ‘The Structure and Enforcement of Job Safety Regulation’, 49(4) Law and Contemporary Problems, 127-150. Viscusi, W. Kip (1989), ‘The Interaction between Product Liability and Workers’ Compensation as Ex Post Remedies for Workplace Injuries’, 5 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 185-210. Viscusi, W. Kip (1991), ‘Product and Occupational Liability’,5(3) Journal of Economic Perspectives, 71-91. Viscusi, W. Kip (1992), Fatal Tradeoffs: Public and Private Responsibilities for Risk, New York, Oxford Press, 306 p. Walters, Vivienne and Haines, Ted (1988), ‘Workers’ Use and Knowledge of the “Internal Responsibility System”: Limits to Participation in Occupational Health and Safety’, 14 Canadian Public Policy, 411-423. Weiler, Paul (1986), Legal Policy for Workplace Injuries, Philadelphia, American Law Institute Project on Compensation and Liability for Product and Process Injuries, 141p. Weiss, Peter, Maier, Gunther and Gerking, Shelby (1986), ‘The Economic Evaluation of Job Safety: A Methodological Survey and Some Estimates for Austria’, 13 Empirica, 53-67. Wiggins, Steven N. and Ringleb, Al H. (1992), ‘Adverse Selection and Long Term Hazards: The Choice between Contract and Mandatory Liability Rules’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 189-215. Wilson, Graham, K. (1985), The Politics of Safety and Health: Occupational Safety and Health in the United States and Britain, New York, Oxford Press, 179 p. Worrall, John D. and Butler, Richard J. (1988), ‘Experience Rating Matters’, in Borba, Philip S. and Appel, David (eds), Workers’ Compensation Insurance Pricing: Current Programs and Proposed Reforms, Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 81-94.
5540
Occupational Safety and Health Regulation
625
Other References Bardach, Eugene and Kagan, Robert A. (1982), Going By The Book: The Problem of Regulatory Unreasonableness, Philadelphia, Temple University Press, 375 p. Breyer, Stephen (1993), Breaking The Vicious Circle: Toward Effective Risk Regulation, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 127 p. Cranor, Carl F. (1993), Regulating Toxic Substances: A Philosophy of Science and The Law, New York, Oxford Press, 252 p. Howard, Philip K. (1994), The Death of Common Sense: How Law is Suffocating America, New York, Random House, 202 p. Komesar, Neil K. (1994), Imperfect Alternatives: Choosing Institutions in Law, Economics, and Public Policy, Chicago, University of Chicago press, 287 p. McGarity, Thomas O. (1991), Reinventing Rationality: The Role of Regulatory Analysis in the Federal Bureaucracy, New York, Cambridge University Press, 384 p. Sagoff (1988), The Economy of the Earth: Philosophy, Law, and the Environment, New York, Cambridge University Press, 271 p. Sunstein, Cass R. (1990), After the Rights Revolution: Reconceiving the Regulatory State, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 284 p. Sunstein, Cass R. ( 1991), ‘Administrative Substance’, Duke Law Journal, 607-646. Sunstein, Cass R. (1996), ‘Legislative Forward: Congress, Constitutional Moments, and the Cost-Benefit State’, 48 Stanford Law Review, 247-309. Sunstein, Cass R. (1997), Free Markets and Social Justice, New York, Oxford Press, 407 p.
5550 COLLECTIVE BARGAINING AND WORKER PARTICIPATION © Copyright 1999 Boudewijn Bouckaert and Gerrit De Geest
Bibliography Collected by the Editors Adams, G.W. (1978), ‘Collective Bargaining by Salaried Professionals’, in Slayton, Philip and Trebilcock, Michael J. (eds), The Professions and Public Policy, Toronto, University of Toronto Faculty of Law. Albert, Michael and Hahnel, Robin (1991), The Political Economy of Participatory Economics, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 132 p. Backhaus, Jürgen G. (1980), ‘Wirtschaftliche Analyse der Entwicklungsmöglichkeiten mitbestimmter Wirtschaftssysteme (Economic Analysis of Co-Determination)’, in Kappler, Ekkehard (ed), Unternehmensstruktur und Unternehmensentwicklung, Freiburg, Rombach, 266-289. Backhaus, Jürgen G. (1987a), Mitbestimmung im Unternehmen, Göttingen, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 306 p. Reprinted in Co-Determination: A Legal and Economic Analysis. Backhaus, Jürgen G. (1987b), ‘The Emergence of Worker Participation: Evolution and Legislation Compared’, 21 Journal of Economic Issues, 895-910. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1996), ‘Participatory Management Within a Theory of the Firm’, 21 Journal of Corporation Law, 657 ff. Buxbaum, Hertig and Hirsch, Hopt (eds), European Economic and Business Law, Legal and Economic Analyses on Integration and Harmonization, Berlin, Walter De Gruyter, 401 p. Cohen, George M. and Wachter, Michael L. (1988), ‘An International Labor Market Approach to Labor Law: Does Labor Law Promote Efficient Contracting?’, Industrial Relations Research Association 41st Annual Proceedings, 243-250. Cohen, George M. and Wachter, Michael L. (1988), ‘The Law and Economics of Collective Bargaining: An Introduction and Application to the Problems of Subcontracting, Partial Closure, and Relocation’, 136 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1349 ff. Cohen, George M. and Wachter, Michael L. (1990), ‘Replacing Striking Workers: The Law and Economics Approach’, in X (ed), New York University Conference on Labor, 43rd Annual Proceedings, 109-125. Coljee, P.D. (1991), ‘Het Economisch Adviesrecht van de Ondernemingsraad, Quo Vadis? Artikel 25 WOR nader beschouwd (The Workers Council Economic Right of Advice, Quo Vadis?)’, in Coljee, P.D., Franken, H., Heertje, A. and Kanning, W. (eds), Law and Welfare Economics, Amsterdam, VU Amsterdam, 77-99. Crouch, Colin (1982), Trade Unions: The Logic of Collective Action, Glasgow, Fontana Paperbacks, 251 p. Currie, Janet and McConnell, Sheena (1994), ‘The Impact of Collective Bargaining Legislation on Disputes in the U.S. Public Sector: No Legislation May Be the Worst Legislation’, 37 Journal of Law and Economics, 519-547.
626
5550
Collective Bargaining and Worker Participation
627
Dau-Schmidt, Kenneth G. (1992), ‘A Bargaining Analysis of American Labor Law and the Search for Bargaining Equity and Industrial Peace’, 91 Michigan Law Review, 419 ff. Dau-Schmidt, Kenneth G. (1993a), ‘Meeting the Demands of Workers Into the Twenty-First Century: The Future of Labor and Employment Law’, 68 Indiana Law Journal, 685 ff. Dau-Schmidt, Kenneth G. (1993b), ‘Bargaining Theory and Canadian Labour Law’, in Kuttner, T. (ed), 2 The Industrial Relations System: Proceedings of the XXIXth Conference of the Canadian Industrial Relations Association, 753 ff. Debrock, Lawrence M. and Roth, Alvin E. (1981), ‘Strike Two: Labor-Management Negotiations in Major League Baseball’, 12 Bell Journal of Economics, 413-425. Detman, Julius G., Goldbergh, Stephen B. and Herman, Jeanne B. (1972), ‘The National Labor Relations Board Voting Study: A Preliminary Report’, 1 Journal of Legal Studies, 233-258. Eger, Thomas, Nutzinger, Hans G. and Weise, Peter (1993), ‘Eine ökonomische Analyse der mitbestimmten Unternehmung (An Economic Analysis of Codetermined Enterprise)’, in Ott, C. and Schäfer, H.-B. (eds), Ökonomische Analyse des Unternehmensrechts, Heidelberg, Physica, 78-116. Fried, Charles (1984), ‘Individual and Collective Rights in Work Relations: Reflections on the Current State of Labor Law and Its Prospects’, 51 University of Chicago Law Review, 1012-1040. Garello, Jacques, Lemennicier, Bertrand and Lepage, Henri (1990), Cinq Questions sur les Syndicats (Five Questions on Labor Unions)’, Paris, Presses Universitaires de France (PUF). Ginsburg, Douglas H. (1992), ‘A Property Rights Analysis of the Inefficiency of Investment Decisions by Labor Managed Firms: Comment’, 148 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 45 ff. Goldberg, Michael J. (1988), ‘The Propensity to Sue and the Duty of Fair Representation: A Second Point of View (Tactical Use of the Union’s Duty of Fair Representation: An Empirical Analysis)’, 41 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 456-461. Gunderson, Morley (1978), ‘Economic Aspects of the Unionization of Salaried Professionals’, in Slayton, Philip and Trebilcock, Michael J. (eds), The Professions and Public Policy, Toronto, University of Toronto Faculty of Law. Hansmann, Henry B. (1990), ‘When Does Worker Ownership Work? ESOPs, Law Firms, Codetermination, and Economic Democracy’, 99 Yale Law Journal, 1749-1816. Hedlund, Jeffrey D. (1986), ‘An Economic Case for Mandatory Bargaining over Partial Termination and Plant Relocation Decisions’, 95 Yale Law Journal, 949-968. Hendricks, Walter (1975), ‘The Effect of Regulation on Collective Bargaining in Electric Utilities’, 6 Bell Journal of Economics, 451-465. Hopt, Klaus J. (1994), ‘Labor Representation on Corporate Boards: Impacts and Problems for Corporate Governance and Economic Integration in Europe’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 203-214. Hutt, W.H. (1986), ‘The “Power” of Labour Unions’, in Anderson, Martin J. (ed), The Unfinished Agenda: Essays on the Political Economy of Government Policy in honour of Arthur Seldon, London, Institute of Economic Affairs, 39-63.
5550
Collective Bargaining and Worker Participation
628
Klemm, Günter (1983), Ökonomische Analyse von Streik und Ausperrung im Rahmen einer marktwirtschaftlichen Ordnung (Economic Analysis of Strike and Lock-out in the Context of a Market Economy), 214 p. Knight, Thomas R. (1988), ‘The Propensity to Sue and the Duty of Fair Representation: Reply’, 41 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 461-464. Lande, Robert H. (1996), ‘Anticonsumer Effects of Union Mergers: An Antitrust Solution’, 46 Duke Law Journal, 197 ff. Lande, Robert H. and Zerbe, Richard O., Jr (1985), ‘Reducing Unions’ Monopoly Power: Costs and Benefits’, 28 Journal of Law and Economics, 297-310. Reprinted in 29 Corporate Practice Commentator, 1987, 107-122. Lande, Robert H. and Zerbe, Richard O., Jr (1990), ‘More Lessons From Japan: End Industrywide Collective Bargaining?’, 28 Asian Economic Journal. Leef, G.C. (1990), ‘Legal Obstacles to a Market for Employee Representation Services’, 9 Cato Journal, 663-687. Leslie, Douglas L. (1989), ‘Multiemployer Bargaining Rules’, 75 Virginia Law Review, 241-278. Levin, William R. (1985), ‘The False Promise of Worker Capitalism: Congress and the Leveraged Employee Stock Ownership Plan’, 95 Yale Law Journal, 148-173. Livernash, E.R. (1963), ‘The Relation of Power to the Structure and Process of Collective Bargaining’, 6 Journal of Law and Economics, 10-40. Lurie, Melvin (1960), ‘Government Regulation and Union Power: A Case Study of the Boston Transit Industry’, 3 Journal of Law and Economics, 118-135. Meltzer, Bernard D. (1963), ‘Labor Unions, Collective Bargaining, and the Antitrust Laws’, 6 Journal of Law and Economics, 152-223. Möschel, Wernhard (1996), ‘Ist die Tarifautonomie noch Zeitgemäß? (Is the German System of Autonomous Wage Bargaining Still up to Date?)’, 45 Zeitschrift für Wirtschaftspolitik, 39-48. Nagel, Bernhard (1980), ‘Beschaffung und Weitergabe von Informationen durch Mitbestimmungsträger im Aufsichtsrat (Collection and Transmission of Information by Workers’ Representatives in the Board of Directors)’, in Diefenbacher and Nutzinger (eds), Frankfurt/M., Bern, Cirencester, 249-269. Nagel, Bernhard (1981), ‘Rechtsauslegung und Rechtssetzung zur Mitbestimmung (Interpretation of Law and Law Making Concerning Worker Participation)’, Blätter für Steuer-, Sozialversicherungs- und Arbeitsrecht, 344-350. Nagel, Bernhard (1982), ‘Zusammensetzung mitbestimmter Aufsichtsratsausschüsse und Unternehmensinteresse (Composition of the Board of Directors under Worker Participation and the Goals of the Firm)’, DB, 2677-2681. Nagel, Bernhard (1984a), ‘Informationsrechte und Mitbestimmungsträger nach dem Mitbestimmungsgesetz 1976 und dem Betriebsverfassungsgesetz (Rights on Information and Worker Participation according to the German Law of 1976)’, in Koubek and Schredelseker (eds), Information, Mitbestimmung und Unternehmenspolitik, Frankfurt/M., Cirencester. Nagel, Bernhard (1984b), ‘Informationsrechte und Informationspolitik in Mitbestimmten Unternehmen (Rights on Information and Information Policy in Firms under Worker Participation)’, in Diefenbacher and Nutzinger (eds), Mitbestimmung, Theorie, Geschichte, Praxis, Heidelberg, Müller Juristischer Verlag.
5550
Collective Bargaining and Worker Participation
629
Nagel, Bernhard (1988), Mitbestimmung und Grundgesetz (Worker Participation and the German Basic Law), Baden-Baden, Nomos. Nagel, Bernhard (1990), ‘Erosion der Mitbestimmung und EG- Kommissionsentwürfe zur Europa-AG (Erosion of Worker Participation)’, Arbeit und Recht, 205-213. Nagel, Bernhard (1991), ‘Der EG-Richtlinienentwurf zum Europäischen Betriebsrat (The EG-Guideline on the European Workers Committee)’, Arbeit und Recht, 161-172. Nagel, Bernhard (1996), ‘Wie effizient sind Tarifvertrag und Mitbestimmung? (How Efficient are Wage Agreements and Worker Participation?)’, 2 Gewerkschaftliche Monatshefte, 97-111. Nutzinger, Hans G. and Backhaus, Jürgen G. (eds) (1989), Codetermination: A Discussion of Different Approaches, Berlin, Springer, 309 p. Peltzman, Sam (1961), ‘The Relative Importance of Unionization and Productivity in Increasing Wages’, 12 Labor Law Journal. Rees, Albert (1959), ‘Do Unions Cause Inflation?’, 2 Journal of Law and Economics, 84-93. Rees, Albert (1963), ‘The Effects of Unions on Resource Allocation’, 6 Journal of Law and Economics, 69-78. Roe, Mark J. (1994), ‘German "Populism" and the Large Public Corporation’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 187-202. Sadowski, Dieter and Frick, Bernd (1990), ‘Betriebsräte und Gesetzesvollzug (Labor Representatives and Execution of Laws)’, 4 Zeitschrift für Personalforschung, 165-178. Sadowski, Dieter, Backes-Gellner, Uschi and Frick, Bernd (1995), ‘Betriebsräte in Deutschland, Gespaltene Rationalitäten? (Labor Representatives in Germany)’, 14 Jahrbuch für Neue Politische Ökonomie, 157-182. Schmidtchen, Dieter (1981), ‘Leitungspartizipation, Wettbewerb und Funktionsfähigkeit des Marktsystems (Management Participation)’, in Issing, D. (ed), Zukunftsprobleme der Sozialen Marktwirtschaft, Schriften des Vereins für Socialpolitik, N.F. Bd. 116, Berlin, Springer, 191 ff. Schwab, Stewart J. (1992), ‘Union Raids, Union Democracy, and the Market for Union Control’, 25 University of Illinois Law Review, 367-416. St. Antoine, Theodore J. (1989), ‘Commentary on "Multiemployer Bargaining Rules": The Limitations of a Strictly Economic Analysis’, 75 Virginia Law Review, 279-283. Steinherr, A. (1977), ‘On the Efficiency of Profit Sharing and Labor Participation in Management’, 8 Bell Journal of Economics, 545-555. Turnbull, Shann (1990), ‘Re-Inventing Corporations’, 2(4) Journal of Employee Ownership Law and Finance, 109-136. Translated into Czech and republished 1991, Podnikov Organizace, Prague. Turnbull, Shann (1991a), ‘Equitable Capitalism: Promoting Economic Opportunity Through Broader Capital Ownership’, in Stuart M. Speiser, Socialising Capitalism, New York, New Horizons Press, 97-113. Turnbull, Shann (1991b), ‘Re-Inventing Corporations’, 10(3) Human Systems Management, 169-186. Turnbull, Shann (1993a), ‘Flaws and Remedies in Corporatisation and Privatisation’, 12(3) Human Systems Management, 227-252. Turnbull, Shann (1993b), ‘Democratic Capitalism; Self-Financing Local Ownership and Control’, 12(4) Human Systems Management, 333-348.
630
Collective Bargaining and Worker Participation
5550
Turnbull, Shann (1994), Building a Stakeholder Democracy, Ambitions for our Future: Australian Views, Economic Planning Advisory Commission, Canberra, Australian Government Publishing Service. Turnbull, Shann (1997), ‘Stakeholder Co-orporation’, 29(3) Journal of Co-operative Studies, 18-52. Wachter, Michael L. and Cohen, George M. (1988), ‘The Law and Economics of Collective Bargaining: An Introduction and Application to the Problems of Subcontracting, Partial Closure, and Relocation’, 136 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1349-1417. Walters, Vivienne and Haines, Ted (1988), ‘Workers’ Use and Knowledge of the “Internal Responsibility System”: Limits to Participation in Occupational Health and Safety’, 14 Canadian Public Policy, 411-423. Watrin, Christian (1975), ‘Gesellschaftliches Eigentum und Arbeiterselbstverwaltung - ein Weg zur Humanisierung der Gesellschaft? (Collective Property and Workers Self-Government - The Road to a More Human Society?)’, 26 Ordo, 79-96. Watrin, Christian (1976), ‘Selbstverwaltete Unternehmen und Produktionsmitteleigentum (Labor Managed Enterprises and Private Property of Capital)’, in Watrin, Christian and Willgerodt, Hans (eds), Widersprüche der Kapitalismuskritik. Festgabe für Alfred Müller-Armack. Wirtschaftspolitische Chronik, Heft 2/3, 157-178. Weber, Arnold R. (1963), ‘The Structure of Collective Bargaining and Bargaining Power: Foreign Experiences’, 6 Journal of Law and Economics, 79-151. Weise, Peter, Nutzinger, Hans G. and Eger, Thomas (1993), ‘Eine ökonomische Analyse der mitbestimmten Unternehmung (An Economic Analysis of Codetermined Enterprise)’, in Ott, C. and Schäfer, H.-B. (eds), Ökonomische Analyse des Unternehmensrechts, Heidelberg, Physica, 78-116. Wolff, Christian (1989), ‘Comment: Share Ownership and Efficiency’, in Faure, Michael and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds), Essays in Law and Economics. Corporations, Accident Prevention and Compensation for Losses, Antwerpen, Maklu, 81-83. Zimarowski, James B. (1989), ‘A Primer on Power Balancing Under the National Labor Relations Act’, 23 University of Michigan Journal of Law Reform, 47-104.
5610 THE THEORY OF THE FIRM Nicolai J. Foss Department of Industrial Economics and Strategy Copenhagen Business School
Henrik Lando Department of Finance Copenhagen Business School
Steen Thomsen Institute of International Business Aarhus Business School © Copyright 1999 Nicolai J. Foss, Henrik Lando, and Steen Thomsen
Abstract This chapter is a survey of modern theories of the firm. We categorize these as belonging either to the principal-agent or the incomplete contracting approach. In the former category fall, for example, the Alchian and Demsetz moral hazard in teams theory as well as Holmstrøm and Milgrom’s theory of the firm as an incentive system. Belonging to the incomplete contracting branch are theories that stress the importance of the employment relationship (for example, Coase and Simon) as an adaptation mechanism, theories that stress the importance of ownership of assets for affecting incentives when contracts must be renegotiated (Williamson, Grossman and Hart, Hart and Moore), and some recent work on implicit contracts (Baker, Gibbons and Murphy). We argue that these different perspectives on the firm should be viewed as complementary rather than as mutually exclusive and that a synthesis seems to be emerging. JEL classification: K22, L22 Keywords: Principal-Agent Problems, Incomplete Contracts, Moral Hazard, Employment Relationship, Firm Ownership, Renegotiation
1. Introduction: The Emergence of the Theory of the Firm Along with households, firms have for a long time been a crucial part of the explanatory set-up of economics. For example, in basic price theory, firms are part of the apparatus that helps us trace out the effect on endogenous variables of changes in exogenous variables. But the explanatory atoms, firms and 631
632
The Theory of the Firm
5610
households, are not themselves treated in any detail. Thus, we have for a long time had an economics with firms, as it were; what was missing until the 1970s was an economics of firms. It is only relatively recently, in other words, that economists have felt the need for an economic theory addressing the reasons for the existence of the institution known as the (multi-person) business firm, its boundaries relative to the market, and its internal organization - to mention the issues that are generally seen as the main ones in the modern economics of organization (for example, Milgrom and Roberts, 1988; Hart, 1989; Holmström and Tirole, 1989). Although pioneering early work was done already by Frank Knight (1921) and Ronald Coase (1937), it was not until the mid 1970s that work really blossomed within the field, stimulated by advances in the economics of market failures, property rights, information and uncertainty which made possible a more rigorous understanding of the sources and nature of transaction costs and of the incentive properties of alternative types of economic organization. The work of Coase did not belong to this formal stream of work, and as late as in 1972, Coase lamented that his 1937 paper had been ‘much cited and little used’. However, at the time of Coase’s lamentation, serious work on the theory of the firm had begun to take off, notably with Williamson (1971) and Alchian and Demsetz (1972), two seminal contributions that helped found distinct perspectives within the modern economics of organization. It is fair to say that today organizational economics is one of the richest and most rapidly expanding fields in modern economics. It may seen as part of broader attempt (sometimes called ‘new institutional economics’) to move beyond the confines of the market institution and also inquire into the rationales and functioning of alternative institutions for resource allocation, generalizing standard neoclassical economics in the process (Arrow, 1987). The pure analysis of the market institution leaves almost no room for the firm (Debreu, 1959). Under the assumption of a perfect set of contingent markets, as well as certain other restrictive assumptions, the model describes how markets may produce efficient outcomes. The question how organizations should be structured does not arise, because market-contracting perfectly solves all incentive and coordination issues. By assumption, firm behaviour (profit maximization) is invariant to institutional form (for example, ownership structure). The whole economy can operate efficiently as one great system of markets, in which autonomous agents enter into very elaborate contracts with each other. However, by treating the firm itself as a black box, where internal structure, contracts, and so on disappear from the picture, there are many other issues that the theory cannot address. For example, the theory does not tell us why firms exist. As already indicated this is not a new recognition, but rather a basic point in Coase (1937). What Coase observed was indeed that, in the world of
5610
The Theory of the Firm
633
neoclassical price theory, firms have no reason to exist. According to the textbook, the decentralized price system is the ideal structure for carrying out economic coordination. Why then do we observe some transactions to be removed from the price system to the interior of organizations called firms? The answer, Coase reasoned, must be that there is a ‘cost to using the price mechanism’ (Coase, 1937, p. 390). Thus was born the idea of transaction costs: costs that stand separate from and in addition to ordinary production costs. Firm organization may avoid these costs, and exists for this reason. However, as is well-known, Coase’s insights were neglected for more than three decades. During the 1960s, standard neoclassical theory was criticized for ignoring conflicts of interest between owners and managers, a point reaching back to Berle and Means (1932) (Marris, 1964; Williamson, 1964). Thus, the standard theory assumed that profit maximization was the main objective of managers. At the same time, critics from behavioral studies attacked the assumption of perfect rationality. In their view, the existence of organizations such as firms was primarily a matter of economizing with bounded rationality (Simon and March, 1958; Cyert and March, 1963). A little later, Williamson (1971, 1975) following Coase (1937) questioned the view (which he called ‘technological determinism’) that technologies are determinative of economic organization. This did not, according to Williamson, explain why the services of production factors are coordinated in a firm rather than offered to the market by self-sufficient factor-owners. More or less simultaneously, Kenneth Arrow’s work on welfare economics and information (Arrow, 1969, 1974) emphasized various limitations of the market mechanism and argued that firms can be understood in terms of market failures which arise under conditions of externality, economies of scale and information asymmetries. All these influences and insights set up a rich agenda for research. Work on the theory of the firm (as it has been defined here) began to take off during the 1970s, notably with seminal contributions by Williamson (1971, 1975), Alchian and Demsetz (1972), Ross (1973), Arrow (1974), Jensen and Meckling (1976), and, from a rather different perspective, Nelson and Winter (1982), summarizing their work in the 1970s. It is fair to say that the emerging economics of organization is now one of the richest and most rapidly expanding fields in modern economics. It may be seen as part of broader attempt (sometimes called ‘new institutional economics’) to move beyond the confines of the market institution and also inquire into the rationales and functioning of alternative institutions for resource allocation, generalizing standard neoclassical economics in the process (Arrow, 1987). (In this connection, it should be mentioned that what we here call ‘the theory of the firm’ really is a general theory of economic organization that also include, for example, ‘intermediate forms’, such as franchising arrangements or joint ventures.)
634
The Theory of the Firm
5610
While there exist various streams of research, they share the basic principle that economic organization, including paradigmatically the choice between firm or market, will turn on the maximization of joint surplus from cooperation in production (Coase, 1960). Although modern theories of organization are partial equilibrium theories, and although they emphasize bilateral aspects of transactions, many of them have a foundation in general equilibrium theory, both historically and conceptually (Hart and Holmström, 1987; Guesnerie, 1994). While this may not be historically true of the contributions of, for example, Coase and Alchian and Demsetz, nevertheless the various approaches to the theory of the firm can be rationalized as different departures from the Arrow-Debreu model. This is the interpretation we adopt in the following. Since firms would not exist in a full and perfect information setting (implying perfect and costless contracting), one can understand the existence of firms as a consequence of one or more of the Arrow-Debreu assumptions not holding true. We focus on two basic Arrow-Debreu assumptions which we use to structure our account of the different theories of the firm. 1. The assumption of complete contracting: Agents can foresee all future contingencies and can costlessly write contracts which cover all contingencies. Thus, there are no incomplete contracts. 2. The assumption of symmetry information concerning ‘states of nature’. Thus, there are no principal-agent incentive problems. Accordingly, theories of the firm may roughly be classified in a rough way into two categories: (a) Incomplete contracting models which are founded on the assumption that it is costly to write elaborate contracts, and that there is therefore a need for ex post governance. The work of Williamson; Grossman, Hart and Moore; Coase; and Simon, as well as implicit contract-theories, and the theory of communication in hierarchies, belong to this category. (b) Principal-agent models which allow agents to write elaborate contracts characterized by ex ante incentive alignment under the constraints imposed by the presence of asymmetric information. The work of, for example, Alchian and Demsetz; Holmström; and Milgrom belong in this category. One way of interpreting this division of the literature is to say that they have concentrated on different kinds of the transaction costs that Coase (1937) identified but did not elaborate on. Clearly, these perspectives are complementary, and should be integrated. There are signs that this integration process is slowly beginning (for example, Holmström and Milgrom, 1994). However, in this paper we stick to the above dichotomization, and after
5610
The Theory of the Firm
635
surveying theories in each category we end up discussing prospects and criticisms. (For more on the disagreement between the two modeling strategies, see Tirole, 1994.)
2. Complete Contracting and Economic Organization: Principal-Agent Theories 2.1 General Aspects of Principal-Agent Theories Historically, principal-agent theories (or simply, agency theory) reach back to early debates on the shareholders-managers relation. Following the observation by Berle and Means (1932) that ownership of US firms had become separated from management and control, managerialist theories have modeled firm behavior as the maximization of managerial objectives (firm size, growth) under a profit constraint (Marris and Mueller, 1980; Williamson, 1964). Managerial objectives are believed to be variables like firm size or growth, partly because they are positively correlated with managerial compensation and power. The conflict of interest between owners and managers is but one example of an incentive or principal-agent conflict which arises in the context of firms and which may explain important aspects of their organization. During the 1970s formal agency theory blossomed (Ross, 1973 is an early contribution). In its paradigmatic version, the theory deals with a relationship between a principal (for example, the owner) and an agent (for example, the manager) who works on a well-defined task, although the model can be generalized to encompass, for example, many agents, hierarchical layers (for example, a middle-manager who is both agent and principal), and multiple tasks. Indeed, much of the formal agency work in the 1970s consisted in such extensions of the basic model (see Hart and Holmström, 1987). A basic assumption is that some information asymmetry exists between the two, so that the principal cannot directly observe the activities of the agent or that the agent knows some other aspect of the situation which is unknown to the principal. The literature makes a distinction between ‘hidden action’ and ‘hidden information’ models (Arrow, 1985a). The principal may, of course, infer something by observing output (for example, profits), but under uncertainty output is an imperfect signal of the agent’s actions. Under these conditions the first-best (output maximizing) contract would be to let the agent compensate the principal with a fixed lump-sum payment and to be awarded the residual; however, risk aversion on behalf of the agent may rule out this solution. Other solutions are possible but all entail cost. In practice it has been suggested that managers are disciplined (that is, induced to behave efficiently) by takeover threats (Manne, 1965; Jensen, 1986), product market competition
636
The Theory of the Firm
5610
(Hart, 1983), debt pressure (Jensen, 1986) and competitive managerial labor markets (Fama, 1980). 2.2 The Nexus of Contracts View Alchian and Demsetz (1972), Jensen and Meckling (1976),Barzel (1997) and, most forcefully, Fama (1980) and Cheung (1983) argue that from the perspective of economics, it is essentially misguided to draw a hard line between firms and markets. Although firms are surely legal entities, and although this of course has important economic consequences (for example, limited liability, the right to deduct input purchases from tax statements, infinite lifetime, and so on), that firms are nevertheless merely special kinds of market contracting. What may distinguish them relative to other market contracts lies primarily in the continuity of association among input owners. In Alchian and Demsetz’ formulation, the authority relation associated with the employment relationship is, for example, in no way the defining characteristic of the firm. An employer has no more authority over an employee than a customer over a grocer. Both the employer and the customer rely on their ability to punish ‘disobedience’ by firing, that is, by no longer dealing with their counterpart. A customer ‘firing’ a grocer is not in economic terms any different from an employer firing an employee, it is asserted. In short, the firm is nothing but a nexus of contracts, backed up by special legal status and characterized by continuity of association among input owners. We may talk about a nexus of contracts being more ‘firm-like’ when, for example, residual claimancy becomes more concentrated, but it is not in general productive to talk about ‘firms’ as distinctive entities. While there is much truth in the view that defining the exact firmenvironment boundary is theoretically problematic, it would seem that this view ‘underdetermines’ real world firms: authority does seem to have a real existence and firms seem to be characterized by more than their legal status, for example, some argue, by specific technologies. While we treat the first of these two issues later, we briefly consider the second one in the following section. 2.3 The Firm as a Solution to Moral Hazard in Teams (Alchian-Demsetz and Holmström) Alchian and Demsetz (1972) emphasize that the firm is indeed characterized by something more than legal status, namely the technology of team production, by which they mean production with inseparable individual production functions. This implies, they argue, that marginal products are costly to measure. This may create a free-rider problem since team production can be a cover for shirking. The solution to this problem is to appoint a monitor who is given the right to fire and hire members of the team, based on his observation of employees’ marginal products. Giving him rights to the residual
5610
The Theory of the Firm
637
income of the team furthermore means that he is given incentives to perform the efficient amount of monitoring. This arrangement results in the distribution of rights known as ‘the classical capitalist firm’ (Alchian and Demsetz, 1972). In a formal contribution, Holmström (1982) discusses the incentive problems of monitoring and possible solutions (abstracting from team synergies by assuming an additive production function). Under the assumption that the monitor is uninformed about individual effort levels under team production, Holmström demonstrates that only under restrictive assumptions will the monitor be able to induce efficient effort levels. He can do this by devising clever incentive mechanisms. Specifically, Holmström proves that in a team production situation with unobservable effort levels, the triple requirement of the incentive system of Nash equilibrium, budget balancing (that is, the revenues should be distributed among the team members by the incentive system) and Pareto optimality cannot be met. A budget-balancing incentive system cannot reconcile Nash equilibrium and Pareto optimality. This is simply because every team member equalizes marginal costs and benefits of additional effort: if one team member’s effort generates some extra revenue for the team, he should be given that revenue in order to be properly motivated - but this cannot be done for all team members under budget balancing. In this perspective, the central advantage of the firm is that third parties can inject capital whereby the employees as a group do not have to balance their budget. However, neither the theory of Alchian and Demsetz nor that of Holmström provides us with a theory of the boundary of the firm. The basic question why the incentive problems cannot be just as well solved in the market through contracting as within firms cannot be answered by their theory. Thus, in Alchian and Demsetz’s theory it is not clear why the monitor must be the employer of the firm where he performs his monitoring services. He could be the employee of a firm specialized in monitoring services. Moreover, why don’t the employees monitor each other? Is it really meaningless to speak of authority if the employer/monitor has the right to deprive the employee of the right to work with his tools and equipment to which the employee may be strongly specialized? Still, as will become clear, unmeasurability of individual effort and contribution can be made part of a theory which explains the boundary of the firm (this is done in the Holmström-Milgrom model). 2.4 The Firm as an Incentive System (Holmström and Milgrom) The connection between ownership and employment is examined by Holmström and Milgrom (1994) who stress the importance of viewing the firm as ‘a system’, specifically as a coherent set of complementary contractual arrangements which mitigate incentive conflicts. In their opinion, it is misleading to focus on a single aspect of the coherent whole: the firm is characterized by the employee not owning the assets, by the employee being
638
The Theory of the Firm
5610
subject to a ‘low-powered incentive scheme’ (Holmström and Milgrom, 1991) and by the employee being subject to the authority of the employer. These ‘incentive instruments’ are complementary: for example, in the presence of measurement costs (Barzel, 1997), it is important that a person who does not own the assets, which he uses, is not subject to high-powered incentives, since he is then likely to care too little for the assets. Likewise, low-powered incentives make it important for the employer to be able to exercise authority over the use of the employee’s time, since the employee will lack the proper incentive to be productive. Due to this complementarity it is logical that independent contracting has the exact opposite constellation of instruments from the employment relationship. The choice between the two different incentive systems depends importantly on the extent to which every dimension of a person’s contribution can be measured. When an important dimension is unmeasurable, it might be counterproductive to remunerate the person through a high-powered incentive scheme since the person is likely to allocate too little attention on the unmeasurable activity. Thus, according to Holmström and Milgrom lack of measurability is an important variable determining the size of the firm (see also Barzel, 1997). They cite empirical evidence that sales agents (the sum of whose productive contributions can be measured with relatively high accuracy) are independent and vice versa. It should be mentioned that the Holmström and Milgrom model also incorporates the importance of the allocation of property rights to physical assets in determining bargaining powers and hence incentives, as in the class of models we consider later, those associated with the work of Williamson and the Grossman-Hart-Moore model. Hence, it is not only a principal-agent but also an incomplete contracting theory, and perhaps a sign of an increasing awareness of the need to join ideas from the complete contracting tradition with ideas from the incomplete contracting tradition. We consider the latter next.
3. Incomplete Contracting Theories 3.1 General Aspects This section reviews theories that may be reconstructed as departing from the assumption of complete contracting. Thus, for different reasons, not all contingencies can be contractually covered. This makes it possible to theorize about authority and asset-ownership. The view of Coase (1937) and Simon (1951) that the essence of the firm is the employment contract and the associated authority relation also belongs to the incomplete contracting category. This is because it emphasizes the costs of entering into a comprehensive contract and the consequent need of adaptation to changing
5610
The Theory of the Firm
639
circumstances that are not covered by the contract. The work of Williamson and Grossman and Hart also belongs here, although their focus is somewhat different: they focus on the bargaining power that asset-ownership may provide in those situations in which contingencies arise that are not covered by the contract. 3.2 The Authority View: The Firm as an Employment Relation The view that the employment contract is the characteristic feature which defines the firm is generally associated with Coase (1937) and Simon (1951). From this point of view, the size of the firm (the boundaries of the firm) is determined by the number of employees of the firm. An employee is distinguished from an independent contractor by the nature of his contract: while the employee is subject to the authority of the manager of the firm, an independent contractor acts autonomously. Coase sees the advantage of establishing an employment contract, that is a semi-authoritarian (hierarchical) relationship, in the saving of transaction costs, not least the costs of haggling over the terms of the contract. The disadvantage that is also part of the hierarchical relationship is seen as ‘information overload’: as a company expands, the manager will find it difficult to direct the actions of all employees subject to his authority, because he will be incapable of gathering all relevant information. This helps establishing the location of the boundaries of the firm. Simon defines the employment relationship more closely and compares its efficiency with the efficiency of a contract written between two autonomous actors. The latter contract specifies the action to be performed in the future and its price while the employment contract specifies a range of acceptable orders and establishes the right of the employer and the duty of the employee to accept orders within this range. The advantage of the employment relationship lies in its flexibility. The action of the employee can be adapted to whatever state of nature will occur. Intuitively, the benefit of flexibility is greater the greater the uncertainty. On the other hand, Simon stresses that the employment relationship is to some extent reliant upon the employer’s reputation for not abusing his authority. The need for trusting the employer is less if the employee is nearly indifferent between different tasks. Simon’s theory was criticized by Williamson (1975) for favorably comparing the flexibility of a short-term (spot market) employment contract to the rigidity of a (long-term) non-contingent output contract . But conceivably the flexibility of an output contract could also be achieved by a series of spot market contracts. A modern formulation by Wernerfelt (1997) overcomes some of the objections that can be raised against a theory of the firm that builds on Simon’s theory. Wernerfelt thinks of governance mechanisms as institutional mechanisms (game forms) according to which players adapt to changes in the environment and communicate about these changes. His conjecture here is that
640
The Theory of the Firm
5610
different game forms will be systematically characterized by different levels of costs of making adaptations. For example, in the case of the hierarchy, the employer and the employee avoid the costs of negotiating either a very complex agreement or a series of short-term contracts. Instead, the parties negotiate a once-and-for-all wage contract. In this context, authority is simply an implicit contract which states that one of the parties should have the authority to tell the other what to do (as in Coase, 1937). This game form requires less bargaining over prices than the market game form. The employment relationship is hence a game form which parties decide to adhere to in order to save on communication (adaptation) costs. The agreement to play by the least costly adaptation mechanism is upheld by the parties’ concern for reputation in a repeated game. As in Coase (1937), the size of the firm is limited by administrative information overload. 3.3 The Firm as a Governance Mechanism (Williamson) In spite of the contributions mentioned above, Coase’s idea that transaction costs can sometimes be diminished by interacting within firms rather than across markets, has been difficult to develop theoretically. In the terms of Oliver Williamson, Coase’s basic story for long awaited its ‘operationalization’. In particular, the nature and determinants of transaction costs were not, according to Williamson, adequately identified in Coase’s work. In a string of contributions, Williamson (for example, 1971, 1975, 1985, 1996) has erected an impressive edifice on Coasian foundations. Thus, Williamson’s work incorporates ideas from the so-called behavioral theory of the firm (Cyert and March, 1963), the emphasis on operating with a broad notion of self-interested behavior (a broad utility function) in the managerialist school (Williamson, 1964), ideas on contract law, and elements of information economics (Arrow, 1969).The behavioral starting points in Williamson’s theorizing are, first, Herbert Simon’s concept of bounded rationality, which produces contractual incompleteness and a need for adaptive, sequential decision making, and, secondly, opportunism, defined as ‘self-interest seeking with guile’, which has the implication that contractual agreements need various types of safeguards, such as ‘hostages’ (for example, the posting of a bond with the other party). Williamson calls contractual arrangements and the safeguards they embody ‘governance structures’, and the basic idea is to assign transactions to alternative governance structures on the basis of their transaction properties. Given bounded rationality and uncertainty, these are determined by what has increasingly become the central character in Williamson’s analysis, namely asset-specificity. Assets are highly specific when they have value within the context of a particular transaction but have relatively little value outside the transaction. This opens the door to opportunism. If contracts are incomplete
5610
The Theory of the Firm
641
due to bounded rationality, they must be renegotiated as uncertainty unfolds, and if a party to the contract (say, a supplier firm) has incurred sunk costs in developing specific assets (including human capital), that other party can opportunistically appropriate an undue part of the investment’s pay-off (‘quasi-rents’) by threatening to withdraw from the relationship. According to Williamson, vertical integration, that is, concentration of ownership of the (alienable) assets involved in the relation rather than having them separately owned, does away with these problems, because it removes the incentive to opportunism. Williamson’s arguments for the relative benefits of vertical integration for some classes of transactions - those that are characterized by a high degree of asset-specificity - rely on organizational theory and law. Thus, he argues that internal organization is characterized by its own implicit contract law, what he calls ‘forbearance’. Whereas divisions will not normally be granted standing for a court, corporate headquarters and headquarters function as the firm’s ‘ultimate court of appeal’. For example, Williamson points out that disputes which arise within the firm, for example, between different divisions, may be easier to resolve than disputes arising between firms which sometimes require the use of the court- system (Williamson, 1996). 3.4 The Firm as an Ownership Unit (Grossman, Hart and Moore) Over the last decade Oliver Hart, John Moore and others have developed an ‘incomplete contracts’ or ‘property rights’ theory of the firm (Grossman and Hart, 1986; Hart and Moore, 1990; Hart, 1995) which draws on elements in Williamson’s work. As in Williamson’s work, a central assumption is that because of transaction costs/bounded rationality, contracts must necessarily be incomplete in the sense that the allocation of control rights cannot be specified for all future states of the world. The theory defines ownership as the possession of residual rights of control, that is, rights to control the uses of assets under contingencies that are not specified in the contract. As a result, the allocation of formal ownership rights will affect behavior and resource allocation. For example, agents will be less inclined to invest in specific assets if they do not own these and relevant complementary assets. In the Grossman-Hart-Moore theory a firm is defined as a collection of jointly-owned assets. The basic distinction between an independent contractor and an employee, that is to say, between an inter-firm and an intra-firm transaction, turns on who owns the physical assets which the person utilizes in his work. An independent contractor owns his tools, and so on, while an employee does not. Owning an asset is important if one undertakes a non-contractible investment which is specific to the asset; if one does not own the asset, one is subject to the hold-up threat by the owner. Hence, according to this theory, the person who is to make the most important (non-contractible) asset-specific investment should own the asset. Hiring an employee (making the
642
The Theory of the Firm
5610
product within the firm) means hiring someone who stands the risk of being held up by the firm since the manager can threaten to ‘fire him’ (that is, exclude him from the use of the assets of the firm). Hiring an independent contractor (buying in the market) means granting him some power to hold up the firm by quitting with his assets. The optimal size of the firm balances these two opposing forces. The Grossman-Hart-Moore theory was the first to provide a formal model that could explain both the advantages and the disadvantages of firm-organization, that is, a theory that could convincingly establish the boundaries of the firm. 3.5 Implicit Contracts When it is difficult to write complete state-contingent contracts, for example, when certain variables are either ex-ante unspecifiable or ex-post unverifiable, people often rely on ‘unwritten codes of conduct’, that is, on implicit contracts. These may be self-enforcing, in the sense that each party lives up to the other party’s (reasonable) expectations from a fear of retaliation and breakdown of cooperation. The basic idea in the implicit-contract theory of the firm is that implicit contracts may function differently within firms than between firms; a person is hired as an employee rather than as an independent contractor when coordinating with him requires an implicit contract that is easier to implement within the firm than in the market place. In a recent paper, Baker, Gibbons and Murphy (1997) emphasize that implicit contracts occur both within firms (in the employment relationship) and between firms (‘relational contracting’). The difference lies in the options which are open to the parties if the implicit contract breaks down. Contrary to an independent contractor, an employee cannot leave the relationship with the assets belonging to it. Specifically, in their model, independent contracting is defined by the feature that the supplier has the possibility to sell the finished product elsewhere, while firm-contracting is defined by the supplier (the employee) not owning the finished product and hence not having the option of leaving with the asset or the product. The strength of the threat to leave the relationship determines the implementability of implicit contracts. For example, if the market for the good is volatile, relational contracts are vulnerable since the supplier is tempted to break out from the implicit contract when the market price is high. If the supplier is a division within the firm, this option does not exist and the implicit contract which holds the (internal transfer) price constant may therefore be self-enforcing. The implicit-contract theory is linked with Williamson’s idea that dispute resolution is easier to carry out within a firm than between firms: Mechanisms for dispute resolution can be seen as part of the system of self-enforcing implicit contracting within a firm.
5610
The Theory of the Firm
643
3.6 The Firm as a Communication-Hierarchy Recent work on the ‘theory of communication in hierarchies’ is based on the idea, well-known from organization theory (for example, Simon and March, 1958), that one important function of the firm is to adapt to and process new information. In most versions, it builds rather directly on the early work by Marschak and Radner (1972), a classic contribution on team-theory that was published at about the same time that work on incentive alignment began to take off. This book pointed to a completely different approach to economic organization, one in which incentive conflicts were disregarded, or at least assumed to have been solved, and where coordination and communication were highlighted instead. For some time enthusiasm over the new theories of the firm that all centered on incentive conflicts swamped interest in team theory issues, but recently interesting work that focuses on coordination in a team theory framework has emerged (Arrow, 1985b; Aoki, 1986; Crémer, 1990; Radner, 1992, 1996; Bolton and Dewatripont, 1994; Casson, 1997). These writers view the firm as a communication network that is designed to minimize both the cost of processing new information and the costs of communicating this information among agents. Communication is costly because it takes time for agents to absorb new information sent by others, but time consumption may be reduced by specializing in the processing of particular types of information. In Bolton and Dewatripont’s (1994) model, for example, each agent handles a particular type of information, and the different types of information are aggregated through the communication network. When the benefits to specializing outweigh the costs of communication, teams (firmlike organizations) arise. It was mentioned earlier that team- theory has difficulty explaining the boundary of the firm. This applies also to the theory of the firm as a communication hierarchy. It does not explain why communication hierarchies cannot exist between firms. However, if this can be given an explanation, that explanation together with the theory of the firm as a communication hierarchy may constitute a theory of the firm.
4. Some Criticisms of the Modern Theory of the Firm It is hard to deny that the modern theory of the firm represents one of the important instances of scientific advance in economics during the last two decades. However, criticisms of the modern theory of the firm have been raised. For example, Milgrom and Roberts (1988, p. 450), two of the most important representatives of modern formal work on the theory of the firm, made the following prediction ten years ago:
644
The Theory of the Firm
5610
The incentive-based transaction costs theory has been made to carry too much of the weight of explanation in the theory of organizations. We expect competing and complementary theories to emerge - theories that are founded on economizing on bounded rationality and that pay more attention to changing technology and to evolutionary considerations.
In the following, we organize our brief discussion around Milgrom and Roberts’ points of critique. To put it in admittedly simplistic terms, almost all of the focus in the modern economics of organization has been on interaction characterized by incentive conflicts. Very much attention has been given to the hold-up problem and its ex-ante consequences. Coordination problems not involving incentive conflicts have been much less treated, although they are surely important in most firms. However, as already mentioned, one attempt to study the non-incentive aspects of economic organization is represented by team theory. This sort of work adds a sophisticated, formal treatment of some hitherto ill-treated phenomena to the modern economics of organization. The theory’s focus on communication channels, on delays in information transmission, on costs of communicating, etc. makes some sense out of, for example, the economic function of corporate culture (see also Crémer, 1990) (Kreps, 1990, makes an attempt to conceptualize corporate culture in an incomplete contract setting, where corporate culture has the function of signaling trustworthy behavior under unforeseen - and therefore non-contractible - contingencies). With respect to the challenge from such allegedly ‘softer’ issues, it is also worth noting that work on implicit contracts meets this challenge to some extent (see Baker, Murphy and Gibbons, 1997; Segal, 1996). Bounded rationality still awaits its formalization, which may prove important in the development of the theory of the firm. The relevance of ideas on bounded rationality is illustrated by a fundamental problem in much of the modern economics of organization: how are efficient types of organization selected in reality? It is a basic postulate of the modern economics of organization that real-world agents will indeed structure their dealings in accordance with the theory’s predictions (for example, Williamson, 1985). But how can this be justified? One idea has been to rely on (untheorized) selection forces that weed out ill-adapted types of economic organization. We now know that social selection forces cannot in general be relied upon to produce efficient results. The other main approach is to simply assert that agents can rationally calculate pay-offs associated with alternative types of economic organization (for example, firms v. markets) and choose the efficient one (technically, agents can perform dynamic programming) (Kreps, 1992). Now, this assertion may perhaps be hard to square with the basic assumption of incomplete contracts,
5610
The Theory of the Firm
645
which typically (but not necessarily) involves some notion of unforeseen contingencies. Such problems await the development of precise models of bounded rationality. A primary source of unforeseen contingencies in real world economies is changing technology. It has been a persistent critique that the modern economics of organization ‘neglects technology’. Moreover, a number of critics (for example, Demsetz, 1991; Winter, 1988) have argued that the differences in different firms’ productive capabilities have been suppressed in the modern economics of organization in favor of an overriding concern with incentives. While the firm cannot generally be described by a production function, neither should technology be ignored altogether. The critics emphasize that knowledge may be imperfect in the realm of production - that firms have ‘differential productive capabilities’ - and that this may influence economic organization.
5. Concluding Comments In this chapter, we have surveyed a number of streams of research that together constitute the modern theory of the firm, or, the economics of organization. The tenor of the discussion has been optimistic, and although we have acknowledged the existence of rather deep problems (Section 4), we believe that we are on the way to a coherent theory of the firm. Thus, an argument may be made that at least some of the streams of research that we have discussed are strongly complementary. Together they provide a coherent picture of the advantages and disadvantages of firm (or firm-like) organization. The perhaps dominant basic perspective on the firm in today’s economics is that of an ownership unit under incomplete contracts, as it has emerged from the work of Williamson and Hart. The complementary nature of different attributes of firm-organization of the firm has been pointed out by Holmström and Milgrom (1994). And given incomplete contracts, Baker, Gibbons and Murphy (1997) have explained how implicit contracting under certain conditions is more likely to emerge within than between firms. Moreover, these contributions blend ideas from both the principal-agent and the incomplete contracting modeling approaches. Therefore, one may argue that a synthesis is gradually emerging. However, as we indicated, even this synthesis is not complete: critics argue that the field still needs to provide more room for issues relating to bounded rationality, coordination that is not related to incentive conflicts, cognition, embeddedness and differential capabilities. As it stands, the formal theory of the firm still differs from the casual observation of real business firm as well as from the richness of Williamson’s comparative institutional analysis (Williamson, 1975,
646
The Theory of the Firm
5610
1985, 1996). This present lack of realism should be seen in a positive way, namely as an invitation to further research.
Acknowledgements We are grateful for helpful comments by two anonymous reviewers.
Bibliography on The Theory of the Firm (5610) Adelstein, Richard P. (1989), ‘Islands of Conscious Power: Louis D. Brandeis and the Modern Corporation’, 63 Business History Review, 614-656. Alchian, Armen A. (1977), ‘Some Economics of Property Rights’, in Alchian, Armand A., Economic Forces at Work, Indianapolis, Liberty Press. Alchian, Armen A. (1991), ‘Development of Economic Theory and Antitrust: A View From the Theory of the Firm’, 147 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 232-234. Alchian, Armand A. and Demsetz, H. (1972), ‘Production, Information Costs, and Economic Organization’, 62 American Economic Review, 772-795. Aoki, Masahiko (1984), The Cooperative Game Theory of the Firm, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Aoki, Masahiko (1986), ‘Horizontal vs Vertical Information Structure of the Firm’, 76 American Economic Review, 971-983. Aoki, Masahiko (1990), ‘Toward an Economic Model of the Japanese Firm’, 28 Journal of Economic Literature, 1-27. Aoki, Masahiko et al. (eds) (1989), The Firm as a Nexus of Treaties, London, Sage, 358 p. Arrow, Kenneth J. (1969), ‘The Organization of Economic Activity’, in Arrow, Kenneth J. (ed), The Economics of Information, Oxford, Basil Blackwell. Arrow, Kenneth J. (1974), The Limits of Organization, New York, W.W. Norton. Arrow, Kenneth J. (1985a), ‘The Economics of Agency’, in Pratt, John W. and Zeckhauser, Richard J., Principals and Agents: The Structure of Business, Boston, Harvard Business School. Arrow, Kenneth J. (1985b), ‘The Informational Structure of the Firm’,75 American Economic Review, 303-307. Arrow, Kenneth J. (1987), ‘Reflections on the Essays’, in Feiwel, George (ed), Arrow and the Foundations of Economic Policy, New York, New York University Press. Arrow, Kenneth J. (1991), ‘Scale Returns in Communication and Elite Control of Organizations’, 7(S) Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 1-6. Arruñada, Benito (1990), ‘Control y Propiedad: Límites al Desarrollo de la Empresa Española (Corporate Control and Ownership: Limits to it’s Growth in Spain)’, 687 Información Comercial Española - Revista de Economia, 67-88. Arruñada, Benitob (1991), ‘Market vs. Regulation in the Market for Corporate Control: Interactions Between Takeovers and Industrial Policiy in Spain’, in Pardolesi, Roberto and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds), Law and Economics: Some Further Insights, Milano, Giuffrè, 71-106.
5610
The Theory of the Firm
647
Arruñada, Benito (1993), ‘Pintando la Caja Negra: Notas a “La Empresa en el Análisis Económico” de V. Salas (Painting the black box: A Note on “The Firm in V. Salas’ Economic Analysis”)’, 57 Papeles de Economía Española, 156-169. Arruñada, Benito (1994), ‘El Reparto del Monopolio: Obreros y Empresarios en la Historia de Asturias (Sharing the Monopoly: Workers and Managers in the History of Asturias)’, in García Delgado, J.L. and Fernández de la Buelga, L. (eds), Economía y Empresa en Asturias: Homenaje al Marqués de Aledo, Madrid, Editioral Cívitas, 690-720. Averch, H. and Johnson, L.L. (1962), ‘Behaviour of the Firm under Regulatory Constraints’, 52 American Economic Review, 1052-1069. Backhaus, Jürgen G. (1987), ‘The Emergence of Worker Participation: Evolution and Legislation Compared’, 21 Journal of Economic Issues, 895-910. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1993a), ‘In Defence of the Shareholder Wealth Maximization Norm: A Reply to Professor Green’, 50 Washington and Lee Law Review, 1423 ff. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1993b), ‘Independant Directors and the ALI Corporate Governance Project’, 61 George Washington Law Review, 1034 ff. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1996), ‘Participatory Management Within a Theory of the Firm’, 21 Journal of Corporation Law, 657 ff. Baker, George, Gibbons, Robert and Murphy, Kevin J. (1997), Implicit Contracts and the Theory of the Firm, Working Paper. Barzel, Y (1997), Economic Analysis of Property Rights, 2nd edn, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Baumol, William J. (1982), ‘Contestable Markets: An Uprising in the Theory of Industry Structure’, 72 American Economic Review, 1-15. Baumol, William J., Panzar, J. and Willig Robert (1982), Contestable Markets and the Theory of Industry Structure, New York, Harcourt Brace. Baysinger, Barry D. and Butler, Henry N. (1985), ‘The Role of Corporate Law in the Theory of the Firm’, 28 Journal of Law and Economics, 179-191. Berle, A.A., Jr and Means, Gardiner C. (1932), The Modern Corporation and Private Property, New York, Macmillan. Bjuggren, Per-Olof and Skogh, Göran (eds) (1990), Företaget. En kontraktsekonomisk analys (The Firm. A Contractual Approach), Stockholm, SNS Publishing Company. Black, Robert A., Kreide, Rosalie S. and Sullivan, Mark (1988), ‘Critical Legal Studies, Economic Realism, and the Theory of the Firm’, 43 University of Miami Law Review, 343-360. Blegvad, Britt-Mari and Collin, Finn (eds) (1987), Virksomheden Mellem ¢konomi og Jura (The Firm between Law and Economics), Samfundslitteratur. Boardman, Anthony E. and Vining, Aidan R. (1991), ‘The Behavior of Mixed Enterprises’, 14 Research in Law and Economics, 223-250. Bolton, Patrick and Dewatripont, Mathias (1994), ‘The Firm as a Communication Network’, 115 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 809-839. Bond, Ronald S. and Greenberg, Warren (1976), ‘Industry Structure, Market Rivalry, and Public Policy: A Comment’, 19 Journal of Law and Economics, 201-204. Boudreaux, Donald J. and Holcombe, Randall G. (1989), ‘The Coasian and Knightian Theories of the Firm’, 10 Managerial and Decision Economics, 147-154. Bratton, William W., Jr (1989), ‘The New Economic Theory of the Firm: Critical Perspectives from History’, 41 Stanford Law Review, 1471-1527.
648
The Theory of the Firm
5610
Butler, Henry N. (1985), ‘Nineteenth-Century Jurisdictional Competition in the Granting of Corporate Privileges’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 129-166. Butler, Henry N. (1986), ‘General Incorporation in Nineteenth Century England: Interaction of Common Law and Legislative Processes’, 6 International Review of Law and Economics, 169-188. Butler, Henry N. and Ribstein, Larry E. (1988), ‘State Anti-Takeover Statutes and the Contract Clause’, 57 University of Cincinnati Law Review, 611 ff. Butler, Henry N. and Ribstein, Larry E. (1989), ‘The Contract Clause and the Corporation’, 55 Brooklyn Law Review, 767 ff. Butler, Henry N. and Ribstein, Larry E. (1990), ‘Opting Out of Fiduciary Duties: A Response to the Anti-Contractarians’, 65 Washington Law Review, 1 ff. Buxbaum, Richard M. (1984), ‘Corporate Legitimacy, Economic Theory, and Legal Doctrine’, 45 Ohio State Law Journal, 515-543. Cabrillo, Francisco (1993), ‘La Teoría Económica de la Reorganización de las Empresas en Quiebra (Economic Theory of the Reorganization of Bankrupty Firms)’, 58 Economistas, 62-67. Campbell, David (1990), ‘Adam Smith, Farrar on Company Law and the Economics of the Corporation’, 19 Anglo-American Law Review, 185-208. Campbell, David (1993), ‘Why Regulate the Modern Corporation? The Failure of Market Failure’, in McCahery, Joseph, Picciotto, Lol and Scott, Colin (eds), Corporate Accountability and Control, Oxford, Clarendon, 103-131. Carney, William J. (1987), ‘The Theory of the Firm: Investor Coordination Costs, Control Premiums and Ownership Structure’, 65 Washington University Law Quarterly, 1 ff. Carr, Jack L. and Mathewson, G. Frank (1990), ‘The Economics of Law Firms: A Study in the Legal Organization of the Firm’, 33 Journal of Law and Economics, 307-330. Casson, Mark (1997), Information and Organization, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Chapman, Bruce (1993), ‘Trust, Economic Rationality, and the Corporate Fiduciary Obligation’, 43 University of Toronto Law Journal, 547-588. Cheung, Steven N.S. (1983), ‘The Contractual Nature of the Firm’, 26 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-21. Coase, Ronald H. (1937), ‘The Nature of the Firm’, 4 Economica, 386-405. Reprinted in Kronman, Anthony T. and Posner, Richard A. (eds), The Economics of Contract Law, Boston, Little Brown, 1979, 31-32. Coase, Ronald H. (1960), ‘The Problem of Social Cost’, 3 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-44. Coase, Ronald H. (1972), ‘Industrial Organization: A Proposal for Research’, in Fuchs, Victor R. (ed), Policy Issues and Research Opportunities in Industry, Washington, National Bureau of Economic Research. Coase, Ronald H. (1988), The Firm, the Market and the Law, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 217 p. Coase, Ronald H. (1992), ‘Contracts and the Activities of Firms’, 34 Journal of Law and Economics, 451-452. Coelho, Philip R.P. (1975), ‘Externalities, Liability Separability and Resource Allocation: Comment’, 65 American Economic Review, 721-723. Coelho Philip R.P. (1976), ‘Pollution, Direct Controls, Regulation and the Size of the Firm: Comment’, 56 American Economic Review, 976-978.
5610
The Theory of the Firm
649
Coelho Philip R.P. and McClure, James E. (1987), ‘Barriers to Entry in the Market for Stud Services: Government and “Non-Profit” Institutions in Collusion’, 25 Economic Inquiry, 659-670. Coffee, John C., Jr (1990), ‘Unstable Coalitions: Corporate Governance As a Multi-Player Game’, 78 Georgetown Law Journal, 1495-1549. Crémer, Jacques (1990), ‘Common Knowledge and the Coordination of Economic Activities’, in Aoki, M., Williamson, Oliver E. and Gustafsson, Bo (eds), The Firm as a Nexus of Treaties, London, Sage. Cyert, Richard M. and March, James G. (1963), A Behavioral Theory of the Firm, Englewood Cliffs, NJ, Prentice-Hall. Davenport, Herbert Joseph (1913), The Economics of Enterprise, New York, Macmillan, 544 p. Debreu, Gerard. (1959), Theory of Value, New York, Wiley. Demsetz, H. (1983), ‘The Structure of Ownership and The Theory of the Firm’, 26 Journal of Law and Economics, 375-390. Demsetz, H. (1991), ‘The Theory of the Firm Revisited’, in Williamson, Oliver E. and Winter, Sydney G. (eds), The Nature of the Firm., Oxford, Blackwell. Demsetz, Harold (1983), ‘The Structure of Ownership and the Theory of the Firm’, 26 Journal of Law and Economics, 375-390. Demsetz, Harold (1988), ‘The Theory of the Firm Revisited’, 4 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 141-161. Dixit, Avanish K. and Pindyck, Robert S. (1994), Investment Under Uncertainty, Princeton, Princeton University Press. Dosi, Giovanni and Marengo, Luigi (1994), ‘Some Elements of an Evolutionary Theory of Organizational Competences’, in England, Richard W. (ed), Evolutionary Concepts in Contemporary Economics, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press. Easley, David and O’Hara, Maureen (1988), ‘Contracts and Asymmetric Information in the Theory of the Firm’, 9 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 229-246. Easterbrook, Frank H. (1991), ‘High Yield Debt as an Incentive Device’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 183-201. Easterbrook, Frank H. and Fischel, Daniel R. (1986), ‘Close Corporations and Agency Costs’, 38 Stanford Law Review, 271-301. Eisenberg, Melvin Aron (1990), ‘Bad Arguments in Corporate Law’, 78 Georgetown Law Journal, 1551-1558. Ekelund, Robert B., Jr and Tollison, Robert D. (1980), ‘Mercantilist Origins of the Corporation’, 11 Bell Journal of Economics, 715-720. Ekern, S. (1975), ‘On the Theory of the Firm in an Economy with Incomplete Markets: an Addendum’, 6 Bell Journal of Economics, 388-393. Ekern, S. and Wilson, R. (1974), ‘On the Theory of the Firm in an Economy with Incomplete Markets’, 5 Bell Journal of Economics, 171-180. Engel, David L. (1979), ‘An Approach to Corporate Social Responsability’, 32 Stanford Law Review, 1 ff. Fama, Eugene F. (1980), ‘Agency Problems and the Theory of the Firm’, 88 Journal of Political Economy, 288-307. Fama, Eugene F. and Jensen, Michael C. (1983), ‘Agency Problems and Residual Claims’, 26 Journal of Law and Economics, 327-349.
650
The Theory of the Firm
5610
Fama, Eugene F. and Jensen, Michael C. (1985), ‘Organizational Forms and Investment Decisions’, 14 Journal of Financial Economics, 101-119. Fishel, Daniel R. (1982), ‘The Corporate Governance Movement’, 35 Vanderbilt Law Review, 1259 ff. Frech, H. Edward III (1975), ‘Property Rights and Dynamic Inefficiency of Capitalism: Comment’, 83(1) Journal of Political Economy, 209-214. Frech, H. Edward III (1976), ‘Property Rights Theory of the Firm: Empirical Results from a Natural Experiment’, 84(1) Journal of Political Economy, 143-152. Frech, H. Edward III (1980a), ‘Blue Cross, Blue Shield and Health Care Costs: A Review of the Economic Evidence’, in Paul, Mark V. (ed), National Health Insurance: What Now, What Later, What Never, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 250-263. Frech, H. Edward III (1980b), ‘Managerial Incentives in Nonproprietary Institutions’, S.1 Research in Law and Economics, 46-49. Frech, H. Edward III (1980c), ‘The Property Rights Theory of the Firm and Competitive Markets for Top Decision-Makers’, 2 Research in Law and Economics, 49-63. Frech, H. Edward III (1980d), ‘Health Insurance: Private, Mutual or Government’, S.1 Research in Law and Economics, 61-73. Frech, H. Edward III (1985), ‘The Property Rights Theory of the Firm: Some Evidence from the U.S. Nursing Home Industry’, 141 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 146-166. Frech, H. Edward III (1988a), ‘Preferred Provider Organizations and Health Care Competition’, in Frech, H.E., III (ed), Health Care in America: The Political Economy of Hospitals and Health Insurance, San Francisco, Pacific Research Institute, 353-372. Frech, H. Edward III (1988b), Health Care in America: The Political Economy of Hospitals and Health Insurance, San Francisco, Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy. Frech, H. Edward III (1988c), ‘Introduction: The Political Economy of Health Care’, in Frech, H.E., III (ed), Health Care in America: The Political Economy of Hospitals and Health Insurance, San Francisco, Pacific Research Institute, 1-26. Frech, H. Edward III (1988d), ‘Monopoly in Health Insurance: The Economics of Kartell v. Blue Shield of Massachusetts’, in Frech, H.E., III (ed), Health Care in America: The Political Economy of Hospitals and Health Insurance, San Francisco, Pacific Research Institute, 293-322. Frech, H. Edward III and Comanor, William S. (1984), ‘Strategic Behavior and Antitrust Analysis’, 74(2) American Economic Review, 372-376. Frech, H. Edward III and Comanor, William S. (1987), ‘The Competitive Effects of Vertical Agreements: Reply’, 77(5) American Economic Review, 1069-1072. Frech, H. Edward III and Comanor, William S. (1993), ‘Predatory Pricing and the Meaning of Intent’, 38 Antitrust Bulletin, 293-308. Frech, H. Edward III and Ginsburg, Paul B. (1981), ‘Property Rights and Competition in Health Insurance: Multiple Objectives for Nonprofit Firms’,3 Research in Law and Economics, 155-171. Frech, H. Edward III and Mobley, Lee Rivers (1994), ‘Firm Growth and Failure in Increasingly Competitive Markets: Theory and Application to Hospital Markets’, 1(1) Journal of the Economics of Business, 77-94. Frech, H. Edward III and Mobley, Lee Rivers (1995), ‘Resolving the Impasse on Hospital Scale Economies: A New Approach’, 27 Applied Economics, 286-296.
5610
The Theory of the Firm
651
Frech, H. Edward III, Borjas, George J. and Ginsburg, Paul B. (1983), ‘Property Rights and Wages: The Case of Nursing Homes’, 18(2) Journal of Human Resources, 231-246. Frech, H. Edward III and Ginsburg, Paul G. (1980), ‘The Cost of Nursing Home Care in the United States: Government Financing, Ownership and Efficiency’, in Van Der Gaag, Jaques and Perlman, Mark (eds), Health, Economics and Health Economics: Proceedings of the World Congress on Health Economics, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 67-91. Frech, H. Edward III and Ginsburg, Paul G. (1981), ‘Property Rights and Competition in Health Insurance: Multiple Objectives for Nonprofit Firms’,3 Research in Law and Economics, 155-172. Frost, Christopher (1993), ‘Organizational Form, Misappropriation Risk and the Substantive Consolidation of Corporate Groups’, 44 Hastings Law Journal, 449 ff. Furubotn, Eirik G. and Pejovich, Svetozar (1973), ‘Property Rights, Economic Decentralization and the Evolution of the Yugoslav Firm, 1965-1972', 16 Journal of Law and Economics, 275-302. Gatignon, Hubert and Anderson, Erin (1988), ‘The Multinational Corporation’s Degree of Control over Foreign Subsidiairies: An Empirical Test of a Transaction Cost Explanation’, 4 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 305-336. Geddes, R. Richard (1997), ‘Ownership, Regulation, and Managerial Monitoring in the Electric Utility Industry’, 40 Journal of Law and Economics. Geddes, R. Richard and Crowley, Peter T. (1994), ‘Agency Costs and Governance in the United States Postal Service’, in Sidak, Gregory J. (ed), Governing the Postal Service, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research. Gifford, Adam, Jr (1991), ‘A Constitutional Interpretation of the Firm’, 68 Public Choice, 91-106. Grant, Wyn (1985), ‘Corporatism and the Public-Private Distinction’, in Lane, Jan-Erik (ed), State and Market. The Politics of the Public and the Private, London, Sage, 158-180. Grossman, Sanford J. and Hart, Oliver D. (1986), ‘The Costs and Benefits of Ownership: A Theory of Vertical and Lateral Integration.’, 94 Journal of Political Economy, 691-719. Guesnerie, Roger (1994), ‘The Arrow-Debreu Paradigm Faced with Modern Theories of Contracting’, in Werin, Lars and Wijkander, Hans (eds), Contract Economics, Oxford, Blackwell. Halpern, Paul J. and Turnbull, Stuart M. (1983), ‘Legal Fees Contracts and Alternative Cost Rules: An Economic Analysis’, 3 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-26. Hansmann, Henry B. (1985), ‘The Organization of Insurance Companies: Mutual versus Stock’, 1 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 125-153. Hansmann, Henry (1988), ‘Ownership of the Firm’, 4 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 267-305. Hansmann, Henry (1996), The Ownership of Enterprise, Cambridge, MA, Belknap of Harvard University Press. Hanson, Robert C. and Song, Moon H. (1995), ‘Managerial Ownership Change and Firm Value: Evidence from Dual-Class Recapitalizations and Insider Trading’, 18 Journal of Financial Research, 281-297. Hart, Oliver D. (1983), ‘The Market Mechanism as an Incentive Scheme’, 74 Bell Journal of Economics.
652
The Theory of the Firm
5610
Hart, Oliver D. (1988), ‘Incomplete Contracts and the Theory of the Firm’, 4 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 119-139. Hart, Oliver D. (1989), ‘An Economist’s Perspective on the Theory of the Firm’, 89 Columbia Law Review, 1757-1774. Hart, Oliver D. (1990), ‘Is “Bounded Rationality” an Important Element of a Theory of Institutions?’, 16 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 696-702. Hart, Oliver D. (1995), Firms, Contracts and Financial Structure, Oxford, Oxford Clarendon Press. Hart, Oliver D. and Holström, Bengt (1987), ‘The Theory of Contracts’, in Bewley, T (ed), Advances in Economic Theory. Fifth World Congress, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Hart, Oliver D. and Moore, John (1990), ‘Property Rights and the Nature of the Firm’, 98 Journal of Political Economy, 1119-1158. Hayek, Friedrich A. von (1948), Individualism and Economic Order, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Hermalin, Benjamin E. (1993), ‘Managerial Preferences Concerning Risky Projects’, 9 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 127-135. Hessen, Robert (1979), ‘A New Concept of Corporations: A Contractual and Private Property Model’, 30 Hastings Law Journal, 1327-1350. Holmström, Bengt (1979), ‘Moral Hazard and Observability’, 10 Bell Journal of Economics, 74-91. Holmström, Bengt (1982), ‘Moral Hazard in Teams’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 324-340. Holmström, Bengt and Milgrom, P. (1991), ‘Multitask Principal-Agent Analyses: Incentive Contracts, Asset Ownership, and Job Design’, 7 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 24-52. Holmström, Bengt and Milgrom, P. (1994), ‘The Firm as an Incentive System’, 84 American Economic Review, 972-991. Holmström, Bengt and Tirole, Jean (1989), ‘The Theory of the Firm’, in Schmalensee, Richard and Willig, Robert D. (eds), Handbook of Industrial Organization, Amsterdam, North-Holland, Vol. I. Hovenkamp, Herbert J. (1990), ‘Antitrust Policy, Federalism, and the Theory of the Firm: An Historical Perspective’, 59 Antitrust Law Journal, 75-91. Hurwicz, L. (1972), ‘On Informationally Decentralized Systems’, in McGuire, Charles B. and Radner, Roy (eds), Decision and Organization., Amsterdam, North-Holland. Jaffe, Austin J. and Nigh, Douglas (1987), ‘Cross-Cultural Attitudes Toward Property: Implications for International Management’, in X (ed), Proceedings of the Second International Conference of the Eastern Academy of Management, 77-82. Jensen, Michael C. (1986), ‘Agency Costs of Free Cash Flow, Corporate Finance and Takeovers’, 76 American Economic Review. Jensen, Michael C. and Meckling, W. (1976), ‘Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behaviour, Agency Costs, and Ownership Structure’, 3 Journal of Financial Economics, 305-360. John, George and Weitz, Barton A. (1988), ‘Forward Integration into Distribution: An Empirical Test of Transaction Cost Analysis’, 4 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 337-355. Johnsen, D. Bruce (1995), ‘The Quasi-Rent Structure of Corporate Enterprise: A Transaction Cost Theory’, 44 Emory Law Journal, 1277 ff.
5610
The Theory of the Firm
653
Joskow, Paul L. (1985), ‘Vertical Integration and Long-Term Contracts: The Case of Coal-Burning Electric Generating Plants’, 1 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 33-80. Jovanovic, Aleksandra (1993), Participativna ekonomija: Uticaj tipa svojine na ponasanje (efikasnost) preduzeca (Participatory Economics: Influence of a Property Form on Behaviour (Efficacy) of a Firm), Belgrade, Pravni Fakultet. Kahan, Marcel and Yermack, David (1996), ‘Investment Opportunities and the Design of Debt Securities’, forthcoming. Klein, Benjamin, Crawford, Robert G. and Alchian, Armand A. (1978), ‘Vertical Integration, Appropriable Rents, and the Competitive Contracting Process’, 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 297-326. Knight, Frank H. (1921), Risk, Uncertainty, and Profit, New York, Kelley. Kreps, David M. (1990), ‘Corporate Culture and Economic Theory’, in Alt, J. and Shepsle, K. (eds), Perspectives on Politive Political Economy, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Kreps, David M. (1992), ‘Static Choice in the Presence of Unforeseen Contingencies’, in Dasgupta, Partha S., Gale, David, Hart, Oliver and Maskin, Eric (eds), Economic Analysis of Markets and Games: Essays in Honour of Frank Hahn, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Kreps, David M. (1996), ‘Markets and Hierarchies and (Mathematical) Economic Theory’, 5 Industrial and Corporate Change, 561-595. Kroll, Heidi (1989), ‘Property Rights and the Soviet Enterprise: Evidence from the Law of Contract’, 13 Journal of Comparative Economics, 115-133. Landers, Jonathan M. (1975), ‘A Unified Approach to Parent, Subsidiairy and Affiliate Questions in Bankruptcy’, 42 University of Chicago Law Review, 589-652. Langbein, John H. and Posner, Richard A. (1980), ‘Social Investing and the Law of Trusts’, 79 Michigan Law Review, 72-112. Langlois, Richard N. (1998), ‘Capabilities and the Theory of the Firm’, in Foss, Nicolai J. and Loasby, Brian J. (eds), Capabilities, Coordination, and Economic Organisation: Essays in Honour of George B Richardson, London, Routledge. Levmore, Saul (1993), ‘Irreversibility and the Law: the Size of Firms and Other Organizations’, 18 Journal of Corporation Law, 333-358. Reprinted in Corporate Practice Commentator, 1994-1995, 527. Levmore, Saul and Kanda, Hideki (1994), ‘Explaining Creditor Priorities’, 80 Virginia Law Review, 2103-2154. Lewis, Tracy and Sappington, D. (1991), ‘Technological Change and the Boundaries of the Firm’, 81 American Economic Review, 887-900. Llebot Majo, José Oriol (1996), ‘Doctrina y Teoría de la Empresa en el Derecho Mercantil (Una Aproximación al Significado de la Teoría Contractual de la Empresa) (Doctrine and Theory of the Firm in Contract Law Approaching the Meaning of Corporate Contractual Theory)’, 210 Revista de Derecho Mercantil, 319-388. Loasby, Brian J. (1996), ‘The Organisation of Industry’, in Foss, Nicolai J. and Knudsen, Christian, Towards a Competence Theory of the Firm, London, Routledge. Macey, Jonathan R. (1988), ‘Ethics, Economics, and Insider Trading: Ann Rand Meets the Theory of the Firm’, 11 Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy, 785-804. Manne, Henry G. (1965), ‘Mergers and the Markets for Corporate Control’, 73 Journal of Political Economy, 110-120.
654
The Theory of the Firm
5610
Manne, Henry G. (1967), ‘Our Two Corporate Systems: Law and Economics’, 53 Virginia Law Review, 259-284. Marcus, Alan J. (1982), ‘Risk Sharing and the Theory of the Firm’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 369-378. Marris, R. (1964), The Economic Theory of Managerial Capitalism, Glencoe, IL, Free Press of Glencoe. Marris, R. and Mueller, Dennis C. (1980), ‘The Corporation, Competition and the Invisible Hand’, 18 Journal of Economic Literature, 32-63. Marschak, Jacob and Radner, Roy (1972), The Theory of Teams, New Haven, CT, Yale University Press. Maskin, Eric and Tirole, Jean (1996), Unforeseen Contingencies, Property Rights, and Incomplete Contracts, mimeo, Boston, MA, Harvard University. Masson, Robert T. and Madhavan, Ananth (1991), ‘Insider Trading and the Value of the Firm’, 39 Journal of Industrial Economics, 333-353. Masten, Scott E. (1984), ‘The Organisation of Production: Evidence from the Aerospace Industry’, 27 Journal of Law and Economics, 403-417. Masten, Scott E. (1988), ‘A Legal Basis for the Firm’, 4 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 181-198. Masten, Scott E., Meehan, James W., Jr and Snyder, Edward A. (1989), ‘Vertical Integration in the U.S. Auto Industry: A Note on the Influence of Transaction Specific Assets’, 12 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 265-273. Masten, Scott E., Meehan, James W., Jr and Snyder, Edward A. (1991), ‘The Costs of Organization’, 7 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 1-25. McNulty, Paul J. and Pontecorvo, G. (1983), ‘Mercantilist Origins of the Corporation: Comment’, 14 Bell Journal of Economics, 294-297. Means, Gardiner C. (1983), ‘Corporate Power in the Marketplace’, 26 Journal of Law and Economics, 467-485. Milgrom, P. and Roberts, John (1988), ‘Economic Theories of the Firm: Past, Present, and Future’, 21 Canadian Journal of Economics, 444-458. Milgrom, P. and Roberts, John (1992), Economics, Organization, and Management, New York, Prentice Hall. Miller, Gary J. (1992), Managerial Dilemmas, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1996), ‘Finance and the Firm’, 152 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 89-107. Moore, John (1992), ‘The Firm as a Collection of Assets’, 36 European Economic Review, 493-507. Nelson, Richard and Winter, Sidney (1982), An Evolutionary Theory of Economic Change, Cambridge, The Belknap Press. Nutzinger, Hans G. and Backhaus, Jürgen G. (eds) (1989), Codetermination: A Discussion of Different Approaches, Berlin, Springer, 309 p. O’Hara, Maureen (1981), ‘Property Rights and the Financial Firm’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 317-332. Panzar, John C. (1989), ‘Technological Determinants of Firm and Industry Structure’, in Schmalensee, Richard and Willig, Robert (eds), Handbook of Industrial Organization, Amsterdam, North Holland. Posner, Richard A. (1976), ‘The Rights of Creditors of Affiliated Corporations’, 43 University of Chicago Law Review, 499-526.
5610
The Theory of the Firm
655
Radner, Roy (1992), ‘Hierarchy: The Economics of Managing’, 30 Journal of Economic Literature, 1382-1415. Radner, Roy (1996a), ‘Bounded Rationality, Indeterminacy, and the Theory of the Firm’, 106 Economic Journal, 1360-1373. Radner, Roy (1996b), ‘Hierarchy: The Economics of Managing’, in Casson, Mark (ed), The Theory of the Firm, Cheltenham, Edward Elgar, 233-266 (previously published 1992). Ribstein, Larry E. (1987), ‘A Statutory Approach to Partner Dissociation’, 65 Washington University Law Quarterly, 357 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. (1988), ‘An Applied Theory of Limited Partnership’, 37 Emory Law Journal, 837 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. (1989), ‘Takeover Defenses and the Corporate Contract’, 78 Georgetown Law Journal, 71 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. (1991a), ‘A Theoretical Analysis of Professional Partnership Goodwill’, 70 Nebraska Law Review, 36 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. (1991b), ‘Limited Liability and Theories of the Corporation’, 50 Maryland Law Review, 80 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. (1992a), ‘Efficiency, Regulation and Competition: A Comment on Easterbrook & Fischel’, 87 Northwestern University Law Review, 254 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. (1992b), ‘Corporate Political Speech’, 49 Washington and Lee Law Review, 109 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. (1993a), ‘The Mandatory Rules of the ALI Code’, 61 George Washington Law Review, 984 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. (1993b), ‘Choosing Law by Contract’, 18 Journal of Corporation Law, 245 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. (1995a), ‘The Constitutional Conception of the Corporation’, 4 Supreme Court Economic Review, 95 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. (1995b), ‘Statutory Forms for Closely Held Firms: Theories and Evidence from LLCs’, 73 Washington University Law Quarterly, 369 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. and Adler, Barry E. (1989), ‘Debt, Leveraged Buyouts, and Corporate Governance’, Cato Policy Analysis, 120 ff. Richardson, G. (1972), ‘The Organisation of Industry’, 82 Economic Journal, 883-896. Richter, Rudolf (1991), ‘Institutionenökonomische Aspekte der Theorie der Unternehmung (Institutional Economics of the Theory of the Firm)’, in Ordelheide, D., Rudolph, B. and Büsselmann, E. (ed), Betriebswirtschaftslehre und Ökonomische Theorie, Stuttgart, Poeschel. Ricketts, Martin (1987), The New Industrial Economics: An Introduction to Modern Theories of the Firm, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 305 p. Ross, Stephen A. (1973), ‘The Economic Theory of Agency: The Principal’s Problem’, 63 American Economic Review, 134-139. Rubin, Paul H. (1978), ‘The Theory of the Firm and the Structure of the Franchise Contract’, 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 223-233. Sajó, András (1990), ‘Diffuse Rights in Search of an Agent: A Property Rights Analysis of the Firm in the Socialist Market Economy’, 10 International Review of Law and Economics, 41-59. Schanze, Erich (1981), ‘Der Beitrag von Coase zu Rechte und Ökonomie des Unternehmens (Coase’s Contribution to Law and Economics of Business Organizations)’,137 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 694-701.
656
The Theory of the Firm
5610
Schanze, Erich (1983), ‘Theorie des Unternehmens und Ökonomische Analyse des Rechts (Theory of the Firm and Economic Analysis of Law)’, in Boettcher, Erik, Herder-Dorneich, Philipp and Schenk, Karl-Ernst (eds), Jahrbuch für Neue Politische Ökonomie, Tübingen, Mohr, 161-180. Schanze, Erich (1986), ‘Potential and Limits of Economic Analysis: The Constitution of the Firm’, in Daintith, Terence and Teubner, Gunther (eds), Contract and Organisation. Legal Analysis in the Light of Economic and Social Theory, Berlin, Walter de Gruyter, 204-218. Schenk, Karl-Ernst (1978), ‘Grenzüberschreitende Unternehmensformen in den Ost-West-Wirtschaftsbeziehungen (Transnational Forms of Enterprises in East-West Economic Relations, with A. Wass von Czege)’, in Schiller, Karl (ed), Technolgietransfer durch Ost-West-Kooperation, Ökonomische Studien aus den Institut für Außenhandel und Überseewirtschaft, Bd. 27, Stuttgart/New York, 1-12. Schenk, Karl-Ernst (1978), ‘Ökonomische Theorie der Bürokratisch Organisierten Produktion (Economic theory of Bureaucratic Oorganized Production)’, in Helmstädter, E. (ed), Neuere Entwicklungen in den Wirtschaftswissenschaften, Schriften des Vereins für Socialpolitik, N.F., Bd. 98, Berlin, 591-608. Schenk, Karl-Ernst (1978), ‘Bürokratie und Wirtschaftsordnung - Endogene Faktoren für die Veränderung (Bureaucracy and Economic Order. Indigenous Factors of Change)’, 23 Hamburger Jahrbuch für Wirtschaft und Gesellschaftspolitik, 141-154. Schenk, Karl-Ernst (1996), ‘Genossenschaftsverbund und Netzwerk-Externalitäten (Confederations of Cooperatives and Network Externalities)’, in Bonus, H., Grossekettler, H., Großfeld, B. and Wagner, H. (eds), Humanität und Genossenschaften. Festschrift für Wilhelm Jäger, Münster, 157-167. Schmalensee, Richard L. and Willig, Robert (1989), Handbook of Industrial Organization, Volume I, North-Holland, Elsevier Science Publishers. Schüller, Alfred (1983), ‘Theorie der Firma und Wettbewerbliches Marktsystem (Theory of the Firm and Competitive Market System)’, in Schüller, Alfred (ed), Property Rights und ökonomische Theorie, München, Vahlen, 145-183. Schwab, Stewart J. (1993), ‘Coase’s Twin Towers: The Relation Between the Nature of the Firm and the Problem of Social Cost’, 18 Journal of Corporation Law, 359-370. Segal, Ilya R. (1996), Modeling the Managerial Task, California, Department of Economics, Berkeley. Siekmann, Hans (1996), ‘Corporate Governance und Öffentlich-Rechtliche Unternehmen (Corporate Governance and Public Enterprises)’, in Schenk, Karl-Ernst, Schmidtchen, Dieter, Streit and Manfred E. (eds), Vom Hoheitsstaat zum Konsensualstaat, Neue Formen der Kooperation zwischen Staat und Privaten Jahrbuch für Neue Politische Ökonomie 15, Tübingen, Mohr. Simon, Herbert A. (1951), ‘A Formal Theory of the Employment Relationship’, 19 Econometrica, 293-305. Simon, Herbert A. and March, James G. (1958), Organizations, New York, Wiley. Sklivas, S.D. (1987), ‘The Strategic Choice of Managerial Incentives’,18 Rand Journal of Economics, 452-460. Teece, David J., Pisano, Gary and Shuen, Amy (1997), ‘Strategic Management and Dynamic Capabilities’, in Foss, Nicolai J. (ed), Resources, Firms, and Strategies: A Reader in the Resource-Based Perspective, Oxford, Oxford University Press.
5610
The Theory of the Firm
657
Tirole, Jean (1986), ‘Hierarchies and Bureaucracies: On the Role of Collusion in Organizations’, 2 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 181-214. Tirole, Jean (1994), Incomplete Contracts: Where Do We Stand?, unpublished manuscript. Triantis, Alexander J. and George G. (1994), ‘Conversion Rights and the Design of Financial Contracts’, 72 Washington University Law Quarterly, 1231-1255. Triantis, George G. (1995), ‘Debt Financing, Corporate Decision Making and Security Design’, 26 Canadian Business Journal, 93-105. Triantis, George G. and Daniels, Ronald J. (1995), ‘The Role of Debt in Interactive Corporate Governance’, 83 California Law Review, 1073-1113. Turnbull, Shann (1994), ‘Stakeholder Democracy: Redesigning the Governance of Firms and Bureaucracies’, 23(3) Journal of Socio-Economics, 321-360. Turnbull, Shann (1995), ‘Innovations in Corporate Governance: The Mondragon Experience’, 3(3) Corporate Governance: An International Review, 167-180. Turnbull, Shann (1997), ‘Stakeholder Governance: A Cybernetic and Property Rights Analysis’, 5(1) Corporate Governance: An International Review, 11-23. Ulen, Thomas S. (1993), ‘The Coasean Firm in Law and Economics’, 18 Journal of Corporate Law, 301 ff. Vanberg, Viktor J. (1982), ‘Das Unternehmen als Sozialverband. Zur Sozialtheorie der Unternehmung und zur juristsichen Diskussion um ein neues Unternehmensrecht (The Firm as a Social Organization. The Social Theory of the Firm and the Legal Discussion on a New Law of Business Corporations)’, 1 Jahrbuch für Neue Politische Ökonomie, 276-307. Weisman, Dennis L. (1989), ‘Optimal Re-Contracting, Market Risk and the Regulated Firm in Competitive Transition’, 12 Research in Law and Economics, 153-172. Weiss, Elliott J. (1984), ‘Economic Analysis, Corporate Law, and the ALI Corporate Governance Project’, 70 Cornell Law Review, 1 ff. Wernerfelt, Birger (1997), ‘On the Nature and Scope of the Firm: An Adjustment-Cost Story’, 70 Journal of Business, 489-514. West, Richard R. (1984), ‘An Economist Looks at the ALI Propo sals’, 8 Delaware Journal of Corporate Law. Wiggins, Steven N. (1990), ‘The Comparative Advantage of Long-Term Contracts and Firms’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 155-170. Williams, Philip L. (1993), ‘Corporate Groups: the Management Dilemma’, in Gillooly, Michael (ed), The Law Relating to Corporate Groups, Sydney, The Federation Press. Williamson, Oliver E. (1964), The Economics of Discretionary Behavior, Englewood Cliffs, NJ, Prentice-Hall. Williamson, Oliver E. (1971), ‘The Vertical Integration of Production: Market Failure Considerations’, 61 American Economic Review, 112-123. Williamson, Oliver E. (1975), Markets and Hierarchies: Analysis and Antitrust Implication: A Study in the Economics of Internal Organization, New York, Free Press, 286 p. Williamson, Oliver E. (1981), ‘The Modern Corporation: Origins, Evolution, Attributes’, 19 Journal of Economic Literature, 1537-1568. Williamson, Oliver E. (1985), The Economic Institutions of Capitalism., New York, NY, Free Press. Williamson, Oliver E. (1988), ‘The Logic of Economic Organization’, 4 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 65-93.
658
The Theory of the Firm
5610
Williamson, Oliver E. (1996), The Mechanisms of Governance, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Winter, Ralph K., Jr (1977), ‘State Law, Shareholder Protection, and the Theory of the Corporation’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 251-292. Winter, Sidney G. (1988), ‘On Coase, Competence, and the Corporation’, 4 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 163-180. Wolff, Birgitta (1996), ‘Public-Private Partnerships (Public-Private Partnerships)’, in Schenk, Karl-Ernst, Schmidtchen, Dieter and Streit, Manfred E. (eds), Vom Hoheitsstaat zum Konsensualstaat, Neue Formen der Kooperation zwischen Staat und Privaten Jahrbuch für Neue Politische Ökonomie 15, Tübingen, Mohr.
5620 LIMITED LIABILITY William J. Carney James Howard Candler, Professor, Emory University, School of Law © Copyright 1999 William J. Carney
Abstract Limited liability has been known in Europe since at least the twelfth century, and developed later in England and throughout the developed world. Limited liability can be achieved by private contractual arrangements, by the use of limited liability forms of enterprise, by other statutory limits on liability, and by bankruptcy. The principal advantage of limited liability is in encouraging investment by passive investors in risky enterprises, particularly where these investors are poor monitors of managers. Joint and several liability is a particular deterrent to investment by wealthy investors, who are likely to bear all of the costs of judgment. Pro rata liability shifts collection costs from wealth investors who must seek contribution from other investors to judgment creditors, who must collect from all investors if they are to recover the entire judgment. It is generally agreed that in the context of contractual liability, the costs of limited liability on contract creditors will be fully internalized, as the cost of credit rises to reflect increased risk of firm bankruptcy shifted to these creditors. Determining the efficient rule in the context of tort liability is much more complex. While it is generally true that limited liability allows firms to become judgment proof and frustrate tort creditor recovery, this is only the beginning of the inquiry. First, tort creditors may benefit from efforts of contract creditors to minimize firm risk. Second, it is not clear that unlimited liability would deter risky firm activities if widely dispersed shareholders are poor monitors of risky firm activities, or if many tort liabilities are uncertain in their incidence and extent of harm. Third, it is not clear that shareholders are necessarily the superior risk-bearers where mass torts involve class actions where each claim is relatively small, if some shareholders would bear a large amount of liability. JEL classification: K22 Keywords: Limited Liability, Piercing the Veil, Bankruptcy, Shareholder Liability
1. Introduction This chapter reviews the literature on limited liability. This literature began in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries with a concern for agency costs rather than for the liability system. After a long hiatus, when it reemerged in the 659
660
Limited Liability
5620
1960s and 1970s it was concerned primarily with contract liability and with the role of limited liability in facilitating capital markets. It was only after the theoretical literature on limited liability on these topics was relatively well developed that attention turned to tort liability. This literature developed in tandem with the growth of tort actions in the United States for catastrophic liability - generally involving class actions on behalf of large classes of plaintiffs. It became clear with the development of such actions that actors had developed liability-limiting strategies that had the ultimate effect of frustrating the liability system (Dent, 1991; LoPucki, 1996; Roe, 1986; Ringleb and Wiggins, 1990). Because liability systems within societies tend to be unitary, empirical work has generally been difficult to undertake. There are a few examples of parallel systems of limited and unlimited liability, but the evidence on the effects of limited liability remains extremely limited.
2. The History of the Law of Limited Liability 2.1 Ancient Rome In ancient Rome many corporate entities were de facto rather than de jure, and liability remained unlimited (Gillman and Eade, 1995). This is attributed at least in part to the fact that most firms were not highly specialized, because pressure toward limited liability occurs with a separation of ownership and control (Gillman and Eade, 1995). While vicarious liability existed in Rome, it was strictly interpreted by limiting the agents’ authority, thus creating some de facto limited liability (Johnston, 1995). Further, the pater familias, the head of the principal economic unit in Rome, was liable for the debts of a slave or son only to the extent of the extent of the peculium, or sum entrusted to him (Johnston, 1995; Perrott, 1982). While Rome had well-developed notions of both corporate personality and limited liability, they were not related to each other (Perrott, 1982). 2.2 Medieval Italian and Continental Versions of Limited Liability Joint and several unlimited liability became the rule in Italian city-states as early as the twelfth and thirteenth centuries (Medici, 1982). As commerce expanded outside capital was required and outside investors who participated, either for interest or a share of profits, were liable only to the extent of their investment (Medici, 1982; Holdsworth, 1925). This form was widely adopted throughout the Mediterranean as the commenda for the maritime trade, and soon crossed over to inland undertakings (Medici, 1982; Perrott, 1982). The en commandite partnership was legalized in France in 1671, in Ireland in 1782, elsewhere on the Continent and in a few states in the USA in the early nineteenth century (Shannon, 1931), and in England in 1907 (Holdsworth,
5620
Limited Liability
661
1925). Limited liability also developed for limited liability companies, which in most instances lack transferable shares but have other corporate characteristics (Carney, 1995). Limited liability did not make its appearance in chartered companies until the 1780s when clauses were inserted in charters limiting the liability of shareholders to the amount represented by their shares. Previously shareholders’ liability had been unlimited, though the directors of the French East India Company appear to have had limited liability (Minchinton, 1982). In 1807 France provided limited liability for joint stock companies known as sociétés anonymes. Napoleonic conquests spread this form to a number of German provinces, Prussia, Italy, the Low Countries and Switzerland. Limited liability survived the fall of Napoleon with the adoption by various German states of local statutes modeled after the Code de Commerce; the French Code also constituted the basis of the provincial Italian legislation during the first half of the nineteenth century and of the Spanish Code of 1829 (Blumberg, 1986; Macharzina, 1982). 2.3 English Limited Liability: Seventeenth and Eighteenth Centuries Those forms of corporation that required no royal grant from the English Crown were treated as having limited liability for their members without an express grant (Anderson and Tollison, 1983). The limited partnership or commenda form never took hold in England (Perrott, 1982; Gillman and Eade, 1995). While Coke made claims for the crown that corporate status could only come from a royal grant, the facts were otherwise, and Chancellor Coke was forced to argue that corporations created without royal permission must have had a ‘lost grant’. Charters could be obtained by common law or Parliamentary Act as well as from the Crown (Minchinton, 1982). At one point, the default rule for chartered companies seemed to be limited liability (Holdsworth, 1925). Indeed, if members of these corporations were to be held personally liable, it required an act of Parliament (Anderson and Tollison, 1983; Blumberg, 1986; Holdsworth, 1925). On the other hand, shareholders were liable to pay any assessments levied against them by the corporation, and some creditors were able to obtain court orders requiring the corporation to make such assessments (Holdsworth, 1925). Some corporations solved this problem by contracts that prohibited such assessments (Holdsworth, 1925). Some of the initial companies grew from guilds where members began to do business as joint stock companies, with charters in the sixteenth century that recognized this, sometimes with limited liability (Perrott, 1982; Shannon, 1931; Holdsworth, 1925). There is a statist tradition that treats limited liability as a privilege granted by government to encourage certain forms of economic activity (Bainbridge, 1993). In one version, government wished to encourage private undertaking of projects that were too large for individuals (Sundow, 1982). Much of the focus of English legal history on this subject takes this view, and assumes that the basic rule is (should be?) unlimited shareholder liability. Much of this attitude
662
Limited Liability
5620
probably stems from the Bubble Act’s 1720 prohibition of trading in shares of unincorporated joint stock companies. But this did not end the use of unincorporated joint-stock associations; half of the companies formed in the eighteenth century after 1720 were unincorporated, and achieved de facto limited liability through the use of trusts and contract terms limiting creditors to corporate assets (Anderson and Tollison, 1983). Their charters also prohibited assessments in excess of the nominal value of the stock (Blumberg, 1986). Not only is the ‘privilege’ argument rejected by the historical evidence, but also by the economic evidence. The value that shareholders attach to limited liability will be a function of the probability of firm insolvency, which in the case of torts, will be a partial function of firm size. Thus, all other things being equal, limited liability with respect to torts will be of less value to shareholders of large firms than small firms (Horvath and Woywode, 1996). Since the likelihood that a firm will elect corporate status is positively related to its size, it appears that limited liability with respect to tort liability is an incomplete explanation for the use of the limited liability corporation (Forbes, 1986). 2.4 Nineteenth Century English Reforms The origins of a law and economics discussion of limited liability lie in England, but they center not on discussions of the efficiency of externalizing the costs of firm activities, but rather on the increasing agency costs of firms with passive investors and management separated from ownership. Adam Smith believed that the separation of ownership and control found in limited liability companies would only lead to managerial shirking, and that in general limited liability companies could only survive where they were granted monopolies, while noting their potential usefulness in businesses with largescale economies requiring large capital (an issue related less to limited liability than to transaction costs) (Smith, 1776). This debate continued among British economists throughout the late eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. Some writers were concerned that limited liability would reduce shareholder monitoring and lead to riskier choices by managers (Amsler, Bartlett and Bolton, 1981). John Stuart Mill expressed concern for the protection of small investors from fraud, while encouraging their investment of their savings in enterprise (Amsler, Bartlett and Bolton, 1981). Others report that the debate included discussions of the effects of externalizing the cost of failure on creditors, which would reduce capital available to business (Halpern, Trebilcock and Turnbull, 1980). Repeal of the Bubble Act in 1825 and adoption of a general incorporation law in 1844 were not responses to the need to limit liability, but to the growth in the number of unincorporated joint stock companies, suggesting that general incorporation laws occurred in England not primarily because of a felt need to limit liability, but to respond to the development of large companies that operated under the disabilities of not being recognized as entities in the courts
5620
Limited Liability
663
(Anderson and Tollison, 1983). The 1844 Act emphasized unlimited liability by requiring registered companies to publicize their members (Shannon, 1931). In the years following 1844, the debate about limited liability was carried on almost entirely in terms of partnership, rather than company law (Saville, 1956); those who opposed limited liability did so on the grounds that it would create excessive speculation, create difficulties in securing credit, and promote fraudulent investment schemes (Shannon, 1931). In the early 1850s pressure for limited liability came in part from philanthropists seeking a safe investment for the savings of working people (Saville, 1956). The main argument for adopting limited liability was that the 1844 Act had not succeeded in attracting investors to new businesses (Diamond, 1982). In particular, wealthy investors were discouraged from participation (Perrott, 1982). Yet some joint stock companies had thousands of investors (Blumberg, 1986; Hansmann and Kraakman, 1991). It was not until 1855 and 1856 that Parliament granted limited liability to members of registered joint stock companies. This led to an increase in the number of companies seeking registration (Shannon, 1931; Blumberg, 1986; Gillman and Eade, 1995). The 1855 legislation attempted to protect creditors with both publicity (filings and inclusion of ‘Ltd.’ in the company name) and minimum capital (Diamond, 1982). This pattern was followed throughout Europe. After the 1855 Act it was common for industrial companies to create shares with large amounts of uncalled capital in the event of liquidation until the 1890s, and this trend continued in some cases in British banking until the 1960s (Evans and Quigley, 1995). While England was more highly industrialized than the United States in the early nineteenth century, it lagged behind the United States in the development of limited liability. In 1885, 30 years after introducing limited liability, only 10 percent of the number of ‘important’ firms were incorporated in England. Forbes suggests English entrepreneurs found limited liability less useful than Americans, although he offers no explanation for why this should be so (Forbes, 1986). Another explanation for the late arrival of limited liability in England compared to the United States is the lack of jurisdictional competition of the kind that existed in the United States (Forbes, 1986). But by 1855 English firms were registering under both French and American laws, giving credence to the competition among jurisdictions explanation (Saville, 1956). 2.5 American Limited Liability The American colonies inherited the Bubble Act early in their history, but the Colonial legislatures were more willing to issue charters than Parliament, so the corporation, rather than the joint stock company, became the dominant American form of business entity (Blumberg, 1986). The earliest treatise stated that the fundamental rule of corporate law was limited liability (Hovenkamp, 1991). The New England states provided for unlimited liability until increased demand for corporate charters for manufacturing, coupled with competitive
664
Limited Liability
5620
pressure from other states, caused them to adopt limited liability between 1816 (New Hampshire) and 1847 (Rhode Island). While Massachusetts, the dominant industrial state, had granted eighteenth century charters providing for both limited and unlimited liability, in 1808 its first general statute provided for unlimited liability, which was not repealed until 1830 (Blumberg, 1986; Dodd, 1948; Forbes, 1986; Hovenkamp, 1991; Livermore, 1935). Massachusetts courts were hostile to this law, construing it narrowly as in derogation of the common law (Livermore, 1935). Massachusetts continued to grant limited liability only by special charter until 1839, when competitive pressures from other states forced the adoption of a general corporation law with limited liability (Livermore, 1935). While limited liability was the general rule in the United States after 1830, and in most cases before that date, there were a few exceptions. California’s constitutions of 1849 and 1879 imposed pro rata shareholder liability until 1931, and at one time six states imposed shareholder liability for unpaid wages, a law that survives in New York (Blumberg, 1986; Manne, 1967) and in Wisconsin (Wis. Stat. §180.0622(2)(b)). Both federal and state law imposed double liability for shareholders of banks from 1865 to 1932 (Blumberg, 1986; Macey and Miller, 1992). The rapid adoption of limited liability in the US for law and accounting firms when catastrophic liabilities appeared after the collapse of thrift institutions suggests that limited liability may be more directly caused by the prospect of catastrophic tort or regulatory liability than contract liability. On the other hand, limited liability for banking shareholders was introduced after the collapse of the U.S. banking industry in the early 1930s, although it was replaced with Federal deposit insurance and comprehensive monitoring of bank solvency by regulators. 2.6 Other Nations Virtually all nations seem to have developed the notion of limited liability for shareholders in stock corporations. This doctrine has extended to Asian nations that have adopted western legal forms. For example, Korea is a civil code country that provides for limited liability of shareholders (Kim, 1995). 2.7 Managers and Creditors Generally the subject of limited liability is addressed only in the context of shareholders, but it is important to recall that both managers and creditors of companies also benefit from limited liability. Generally managers will not be personally liable for the acts of their subordinates unless they actively participate in them, or sign corporate obligations in their personal capacity (Kraakman, 1984; Thompson, 1994). More recently, however, various regulatory statutes in the US have provided liability for managers for failure to supervise (Thompson, 1994). Creditors are generally not held liable for the obligations of their debtors (Easterbrook and Fischel, 1985). Some exceptions
5620
Limited Liability
665
have developed where creditors hold pledged shares as collateral (Evans and Quigley, 1995), foreclose on pledged property that is the source of liability (Dent, 1991), exercise such control over the debtor that the relationship can be more properly characterized as one of principal and agent, or of co-partners, or where it can be said that third parties have been deceived into believing one of these relationships existed (Lawrence, 1989).
3. The Role of Liability Rules Liability is generally viewed as a device for minimizing the social cost of private activities, and for forcing actors to internalize the full cost of their actions. An efficient liability system causes actors to consider the full cost of their actions. Limiting liability can thus be seen as subsidizing risky behavior and allowing some actors to externalize part of the costs of their actions. While corporations generate positive as well as negative externalities (Leebron, 1991) there is no way to measure the balance of these externalities under a regime of limited liability. Posner argues that the social losses of employees from injuries are too small to warrant inclusion in a calculation, and makes only a passing reference to other tort liabilities (Posner, 1992). While others have discussed the issue of other tort liabilities (see Section 15, below), only one author has discussed the efficiency issues connected to mass tort liabilities, which have raised the question of the efficacy of limited liability in the tort context. That article suggests that in many cases mass tort liability, which commonly occurs in the context of unforeseeable harms, is inefficient, because such actions cannot be deterred by liability rules (except perhaps at the expense of over deterrence) (Schwartz, 1985). If this is correct, then discussions of unlimited shareholder liability in the context of large, well-capitalized publicly-held corporations are moot, and the discussion should focus on closely-held firms, where the justifications for limited liability, in terms of capital markets, are much less persuasive.
4. Means of Achieving Limited Liability While most discussion of limited liability centers around use of the corporate form to produce limited liability for shareholders, other means are available. Lending rather than investing in equity in a firm also provides limited liability (Easterbrook and Fischel, 1985). Indeed, part of the English debate over limited liability centered on whether creditors could accept variable interest under usury laws and retain limited liability (Gillman and Eade, 1995). Creditors can, however, be held liable for firm debts under circumstances discussed in Section 2, above.
666
Limited Liability
5620
4.1 Express Contracts The oldest liability-limiting device is an express contract by which a creditor agrees to look only to the assets of a business firm. This was well known at common law in the joint stock association (Anderson and Tollison, 1983; Hessen, 1979). 4.2 Becoming Judgment Proof Securing assets with a friendly creditor can immunize them from seizure by other creditors. Debtors can sell assets to unrelated entities, which finance the purchase with issuance of their own securities, thus financing the debtor’s enterprise. Individuals can hold property in tenancies by the entirety that immunize them from seizure by creditors of individual owners, and some jurisdictions offer large exemptions from seizure by creditors (LoPucki, 1996). Owners can remove either themselves or their assets to foreign jurisdictions where enforcement is costly or impossible (Alexander, 1992; LoPucki, 1996; Grundfest, 1992). If shareholders were subject to unlimited liability, shares might only be owned by risk-preferrers (high rollers - Hansmann and Kraakman, 1992) or by foreign investors not readily subject to enforcement by local creditors (Grundfest, 1992). Recent developments in capital markets have permitted the securitizing of assets - that is, the separation of productive assets from an integrated firm into a separate entity that cannot be attacked as part of the bankruptcy of the risk-taking firm. This has the effect of making firms engaged in high-risk activities virtually judgment-proof (LoPucki, 1996). It is, of course, just a new variation on the use of corporate subsidiaries to achieve insulation of some assets from the risky activities of an integrated firm (Blumberg, 1986; Dent, 1991; Hansmann and Kraakman, 1991; Landers, 1975; Leebron, 1991; LoPucki, 1996; Presser, 1992; Ringleb and Wiggins, 1990; Roe, 1986). 4.3 Incorporation and the Use of Other Limited Liability Entities While limited liability for passive investors in partnerships (societas), recognized in Europe at an early date (Medici, 1982; Perrott, 1982; Shannon, 1931), was not generally recognized in common-law jurisdictions, New York adopted a limited partnership act in 1822 (Livermore, 1935). Most other US states did not follow this pattern until the promulgation of the Uniform Limited Partnership Act in the twentieth century. More recently, all American states have adopted limited liability company legislation (as European nations had done much earlier, Carney, 1995), and most have provided for limited liability for electing general partnerships (‘limited liability partnerships’). Some of these states have conditioned such limited liability on maintenance of liability insurance in specified minimum amounts. With these developments the partnership default rule of unlimited liability will occupy a very small niche in
5620
Limited Liability
667
the United States (Ribstein, 1992). The mixed form - the limited partnership, with investors having both unlimited personal and limited liability, may be explained by the ability of management to entrench itself from control changes, coupled with the greater flexibility and reduced bankruptcy costs that result from making fixed payment promises to limited partners rather than to outside creditors (Ribstein, 1988). 4.4 Subsidiaries and Enterprise Liability Incorporation has long been the predominant means of limiting liability. While this was not controversial for a long time, use of corporate subsidiaries has generated considerable commentary. While incorporation to protect the personal estates of passive individual investors has been accepted by many commentators as efficient, when a corporation subdivides its own activities into separate subsidiaries for the purpose of insulating corporate assets from the risk of particular activities, some commentators have argued that this is inefficient, because it allows corporations (not just individual investors) to externalize the costs of some risks (Blumberg, 1986; Dent, 1991; Leebron, 1991; LoPucki, 1997; Roe, 1986). As catastrophic liabilities for environmental disasters, product liabilities and other mass torts have increased, large corporations have resorted increasingly to the strategy of disaggregation through subsidiaries, which may not be an efficient arrangement of the firm, since integration through a firm rather than by contract previously appeared to be more efficient (Dent, 1991; Hansmann and Kraakman, 1991; Roe, 1986). On the other hand, if all corporate shareholders were to be subject to unlimited liability, corporations might spin off thinly capitalized high-risk subsidiaries to their individual shareholders as an evasion (Hansmann and Kraakman, 1991). Leebron, (1991) argues that this spin-off process would depend in part on the operational costs of separating integrated operations among entities, and the relative cost of insurance. One author has argued that limited liability was not designed to protect corporate shareholders; in the United States, at least, corporate power to own shares in other corporations followed limited liability (Landers, 1975). Following Modigliani and Miller, Leebron (1991) argues that there is no economic justification for letting pure conglomerates separate risky activities to further diversification, because individual shareholders can make their own diversification. Thompson (1994) argues that while credit markets will discipline many corporations that choose excessively risky activities, this is less obvious for subsidiaries, where parents are the suppliers of credit. Regardless of the arguments against honoring the corporate veil with parent-subsidiary corporations, changing basic liability rules in any society would require such radical changes as to make them highly unlikely (LoPucki, 1997). One article argues for a higher tax on profits that would be used to finance a subsidy to creditors to reduce managers’ preference for risky activities under limited liability (Banerjee and Besley, 1990).
668
Limited Liability
5620
5. Exceptions to Limited Liability: Lifting or Piercing the Veil Numerous countries have provided exceptions from limited liability where actions inconsistent with the separate personality of entity and owners have been taken (Presser, 1991). Germany has developed the doctrine of ‘lifting’ or ‘piercing’ the corporate veil to hold shareholders liable where there is misrepresentation to third parties or commingling of assets (Alting, 1995; Schiessl, 1986; Thümmel, 1978; Weber-Ray, 1995). Veil-piercing is far more likely in the closely-held corporation (including subsidiaries), where the justifications for limited liability are weaker, because of shareholder ability to monitor and participate in management (Easterbrook and Fischel, 1985; Klein and Zolt, 1995; Leebron, 1991). Indeed, veil-piercing is virtually non-existent in the large publicly-held corporation (Easterbrook and Fischel, 1985). On the other hand, the relative ability of close corporation shareholders to bear risk is much weaker (Leebron, 1991). Further, where a corporation dominates the management of another without a formal contract, the dominant shareholder may be liable for liabilities of the servient firm (Alting, 1995). Veil-piercing in the United States is often triggered by activities that can generally be characterized as fraudulent conveyances under English traditions (Clark, 1977, 1986; Presser, 1991) or by actions of a shareholder that create confusion in third parties about whether they are dealing with the shareholder or a corporation (Presser, 1991). In some jurisdictions undercapitalization alone may be sufficient to trigger unlimited shareholder liability. France provides for liability of managers to the corporation, its shareholders and creditors if managers act in violation of the company’s constitution or law (Perrott, 1982). Similar rules exist in the US (Krendl and Krendl, 1978; Presser, 1991) and in Korea (Kim, 1995). Many countries have provided for shareholder liability where a legally required minimum number of shareholders is not maintained, although this rule is disappearing in Europe pursuant to European Community directives. Where some defects in the incorporation process are accompanied by an active role on the part of shareholders and plaintiffs’ belief that they were dealing with a corporation, American courts will also hold shareholders personally liable (McChesney, 1993). In European jurisdictions inadequate capitalization alone may be sufficient to trigger shareholder liability (Presser, 1991; Alting, 1995), while in others some evidence of fraud, such as commingling of assets may be required (Alting, 1995; Dobson, 1986; Presser, 1991), while in others mere close relationships between parent and subsidiary corporations may lead to parent liability (Pardinas, 1991). Anglo-American jurisdictions also use the doctrine to impose liability on shareholders where third parties are confused about whether they are dealing with shareholders or an entity (Halpern, Trebilcock and Turnbull, 1980; Presser, 1991). Doctrines of piercing the corporate veil are less-developed
5620
Limited Liability
669
outside of common law countries, where notions of equity and agency are either non-existent or less well developed, and courts frequently have relied on notions of fraud or abuse of the purpose of the corporate form (Presser, 1991).
6. Statutory Limits on Liability Certain industries might not exist without special provision for limited liability. The US nuclear power industry, for example, needed the Price-Anderson Act, which limited liability in case of a nuclear accident, in order to raise capital. Other statutory compensation schemes, such as workers’ compensation statutes, and certain treaties, such as the Warsaw convention, which limits damages for airline passengers, also permit damage limitations (Coffey, 1994). In the case of new industries where potential liabilities, while huge, are uncertain, such limits may prove to be efficient, although it is difficult to know how such judgments could be made ex ante where individual losses are likely to be catastrophic, if they occur.
7. Bankruptcy Bankruptcy provides a means for limitation of liability (Easterbrook and Fischel, 1985; LoPucki, 1997). Limited liability for a firm, which limits investor risk to assets dedicated to the firm, is similar to a discharge in bankruptcy, which limits a debtor’s liability to current assets, thus protecting future assets (Posner, 1976). In bankruptcies involving corporations with subsidiaries, American courts may use the device of consolidating the assets and creditors’ claims of all the related corporations as a means of disregarding the separateness of corporate entities, and thus piercing corporate veils (Frost, 1993).
8. Limited Liability and the Supply of Capital The principal argument in favor of limited liability stems from the common law rule of liability for partners - joint and several liability - in which any one partner may be held liable for the entire amount of the firm’s debt (Livermore, 1935). This appears to be the general European rule as well (Medici, 1982). Under these conditions there are three economic arguments in favor of limited liability: (1) it fosters economic growth by encouraging investors to take risks; (2) it facilitates the efficient spreading of risks among corporations and their voluntary creditors; and (3) it avoids the enormous litigation costs that would be required for creditors to seek recovery from shareholders (Menell, 1990).
670
Limited Liability
5620
The first justification is treated in Sections 9 and 10; the second in Section 14 (limited liability in contract); and the third in Section 12.
9. Encouraging Risky Investments It has long been argued that joint and several unlimited liability would discourage wealthy investors from investing in risky enterprises, particularly when they intended to play a passive role where they could not monitor and supervise the firm’s risky activities (Blumberg, 1986; Diamond, 1982; Easterbrook and Fischel, 1985; Grossman, 1995; Halpern, Trebilcock and Turnbull, 1980; Hansmann and Kraakman, 1991; Leebron, 1991; Manne, 1967; Woodward, 1985). This is supported by one study that suggests that the choice of limited liability is positively correlated with the wealth of owners (Horvath and Woywode, 1996). 9.1 Encouraging Diversification by Wealthy Investors Limited liability permits the diversification which is necessary to risk minimization in a specialized firm, where passive investors specialize in risk-bearing, and not monitoring of management (Easterbrook and Fischel, 1985; Hovenkamp, 1991; Mitchell, 1989). Under joint and several liability, wealthy investors would be the first targets of firm creditors upon failure, and thus would be forced to forego the benefits of diversification in order to concentrate their investments to allow them to monitor effectively (Grossman, 1995; Hansmann and Kraakman, 1991; Hicks, 1982; Kraakman, 1984; Leebron, 1991; Manne, 1967). Indeed, diversification would increase the expected risk of wealthy shareholders; the maximum possible loss is invariant with diversification, but its probability increases with diversification (Leebron, 1991 Ribstein, 1991). One result of unlimited liability might be larger firms engaged in more diversified activities, to protect shareholders from personal losses (Presser, 1992; Roe, 1986). This diversification would, of course, be limited by the increasing agency costs associated with management of conglomerates, and the costs of using internal capital markets, with their limited monitoring ability, rather than external markets. Because such diversification and increase in size would convey more benefits on wealthy investors under a joint and several liability regime, the benefits of this strategy would not be symmetrically distributed across investors, which could lead to constituency effects, in which wealthy investors would specialize in owning large diversified firms. Such diversification at the firm level is generally inefficient because investors can home-make their own diversification, absent unlimited liability rules.
5620
Limited Liability
671
9.2 Reducing Shareholder Monitoring of Co-Owners A joint and several liability rule would force shareholders to monitor not only firm activities, but also the wealth of their fellow shareholders, which leads to excessive monitoring costs (Carr and Mathewson, 1988; Easterbrook and Fischel, 1985; Halpern, Trebilcock and Turnbull, 1980; Hansmann and Kraakman, 1991; Leebron, 1991; Woodward, 1985). The result would be higher costs and lower returns to equity, which would limit the supply of equity for industry (Carr and Mathewson, 1988). One article rejects this, arguing that shareholders would not need to increase monitoring of either firms or fellow shareholders, since share prices in efficient markets provide them with all required information (Meiners, Mofsky and Tollison, 1979). But other authors respond that joint and several liability of shareholders would destroy efficient capital markets, because the value of shares would be a function of the expected cash flows of the business and the wealth of each individual buyer, and of expected fellow shareholders (Easterbrook and Fischel, 1985, 1991; Halpern, Trebilcock and Turnbull, 1980).
10. Evidence on the Effects of Unlimited Shareholder Liability on Investment There is some evidence that unlimited liability, at least on a joint and several basis, would reduce the number of shareholders and thus the amount of capital contributed to firms. Both limited liability and unlimited liability banks co-existed in eighteenth and early nineteenth century Scotland. From the beginning of the nineteenth century the average size of the limited liability banks was ten times that of the unlimited liability banks, and when the unlimited liability banks were later given the choice of forms, all chose limited liability (Carr and Mathewson, 1988). Unlimited liability banks had lower levels of capital than limited liability banks in relation to total assets, and shareholders in unlimited liability banks earned higher returns (risk premiums) on their investments (Evans and Quigley, 1995). Depositors in eighteenth- and nineteenth-century Scottish unlimited liability banks were provided no information about the bank’s assets, but rather received a list of shareholders (Evans and Quigley, 1995). A study of German enterprises showed that limited liability firms tend to be larger than unlimited liability firms among start-ups (Horvath and Woywode, 1996). There is some evidence to the contrary. Evans and Quigley’s study showed that the majority of banking assets in Scotland were held by unlimited liability banks, which they explain as a function of depositor preference for unlimited liability banking and the higher shareholder returns available (Evans and Quigley, 1995). Outside banking, some English joint stock companies had thousands of stockholders; whether they would have had more as limited
672
Limited Liability
5620
liability corporations is not testable (Blumberg, 1986; Hansmann and Kraakman, 1991). Gilson (1991) reports that law firm size in the United States is invariant with the choice of liability rule, once tax considerations are eliminated. This result may have changed with the introduction of new limited liability forms more readily available to US law firms in the 1990s, which resulted from the catastrophic liability of some US lawyers in the wake of the failures of client financial institutions in the late 1980s (Hamilton, 1995). One modern anomaly occurred in the era of efficient capital markets: the American Express Company remained a joint stock company with unlimited shareholder liability until 1965. From its creation in 1850 until conversion to a limited liability corporation it had as many as 25,000 shareholders, with only one 10 percent shareholder. There was neither illiquidity nor perverse stock pricing (Grossman, 1995). This limited evidence, based on a company with pro rata shareholder liability, rejects the theories that an efficient capital market with diversified shareholders could not exist without limited liability, although it does not reject the theory that joint and several liability would preclude such markets (Grossman, 1995). The unanswered question is whether American Express faced serious expected risk of large contract liability (much less catastrophic tort liability) prior to its conversion. It seems unlikely that American Express had a high risk of tort liability; it provided financial services of a limited sort - at the time, primarily travelers’ checks and credit cards - so it produced no products capable of producing either strict product liability or mass tort liability. There was some risk of massive forgery of travelers’ checks that could have deterred investors. While it was sued for more than twice its net assets in 1963 in connection with its certification of soybean oil inventories, it is not clear that creditors or stockholders would have understood this risk in advance, nor is it clear how much had to do with its 1965 conversion to the limited liability form of corporation (Grossman, 1995).
11. The Effects of Pro Rata Liability on Investment Subsequent to the development of theories about the impact of joint and several liability the literature began to examine the effects of pro rata shareholder liability. While this rule does not appear to play a significant role today, there are companies limited by guarantee, which is a form of pro rata multiple liability. Subsequent to reform of English company law in the mid nineteenth century, many registered limited liability companies voluntarily provided multiple liability through assessable shares, and Scottish banks shifted to this form after 1879 (Evans and Quigley, 1995). Further, to the extent shareholders were personally liable in the early nineteenth century in the US, and in California until 1931 by statute (Blumberg, 1986), it was pro rata (Presser, 1992; Blumberg, 1986; Livermore, 1935; Macey and Miller, 1992). Similarly,
5620
Limited Liability
673
US bank stockholders were subject to pro rata double liability from 1865 to 1932 (Blumberg, 1986; Macey and Miller, 1992). 11.1 Effects of Pro Rata Liability on Wealthy Investors and Securities Markets Pro rata liability solves the problem of imposing disproportionate liability on wealthy investors. This reduces the need of wealthy investors to concentrate their investments so they can monitor them more closely (Grossman, 1995; Halpern, Trebilcock and Turnbull, 1980; Leebron, 1991). Pro rata liability also eliminates the cost of monitoring other shareholders’ wealth (Leebron, 1991). It also solves the problem of differential pricing of securities based on the expected losses of buyers with different wealth levels (Grossman, 1995; Hansmann and Kraakman, 1991; Leebron, 1991; Presser, 1992). By doing so, it solves the diversification problem for investors, because the probability of a wealth-erasing assessment would not increase with each single stock purchased. The differences between joint and several liability rules and pro rata rules may be exaggerated if a joint and several rule is coupled with a rule of contribution. Under these circumstances, a joint and several rule shifts the transaction costs of collection from corporate creditors to shareholders (Leebron, 1991). 11.2 Effects of Pro Rata Liability on the Market for Corporate Control A pro rata rule would discourage wealthy investors from investing in large blocks of risky companies and thus would reduce shareholder monitoring of management activities (Hansmann and Kraakman, 1991; Leebron, 1991; Ribstein, 1992). Under limited liability concentrated block ownership occurs where the payoffs from monitoring are greatest (Demsetz and Lehn, 1985). Modern arguments for pro rata liability in tort argue that diversification would remain at efficient levels with such a rule (Halpern, Trebilcock and Turnbull, 1980; Leebron, 1991). Hansmann and Kraakman argue that most liability would be borne either by wealthy investors or institutions. What they ignore is that such a rule could have the effect of discouraging the formation of investment pools from which judgments are easily collectible; the cost to investors of holding through mutual funds and collective pension plans could rise to the point where individual diversification through mutual funds becomes uneconomic (Leebron, 1991; Coffey, 1994; Thompson, 1994). Grundfest (1992) believes mutual funds would be able to avoid this problem by establishing themselves off-shore and using various hedging strategies involving derivatives.
674
Limited Liability
5620
12. Costs of Collection The costs of collecting judgments under a joint and several liability rule would be high, as firm creditors collected from wealthy shareholders who in turn would need to seek (probably incomplete) contribution from less wealthy shareholders (Woodward, 1985). While a pro rata liability rule would be less disruptive of capital markets, it would also be less effective in collecting damage awards for judgment creditors because of the presence of large numbers of small investors, where collection costs would be high. It would have the effect of transferring collection costs from shareholders to creditors (Leebron, 1991). This would weaken both the deterrent effect and compensation value of unlimited liability. Anglo-American courts of equity developed a relatively effective collection device, the creditors’ bill, which allowed all creditors to seek a determination of both corporate and shareholder pro rata liability, which was res judicata, even for nonresidents, as to all issues other than defenses personal to each shareholder, such as the number of shares held or one’s actual identity as a shareholder (Blumberg, 1986). Posey (1993) argues that the effects of limited liability on the ability of tort victims to recover is less obvious. With unlimited liability, a firm’s expenditures on prevention increase, thus reducing net assets (and increasing collection costs from shareholders). In the alternative, unlimited liability might reduce firm activity levels, and with it the stock of capital (and the ease of collection). Hansmann and Kraakman assert that for publicly held firms the increased transaction costs of unlimited liability under a pro rata rule are less than the increased costs of externalized liability under limited liability, but they offer no evidence to support this statement (Hansmann and Kraakman, 1991). Further, this conclusion assumes that companies should be strictly liable for unforeseeable accident costs - that such a rule is efficient - even where the costs to individual plaintiffs are small but the damages to a firm are catastrophic (although these authors do not discuss this issue). Leebron notes that the difference between joint and several liability with a right of contribution and pro rata liability is a question of who will bear the transaction costs of collection - individual wealthy shareholders or plaintiffs. Leebron also argues that because of this, which rule is better depends not on collection costs, but on which rule creates more shareholder monitoring, and believes that joint and several liability is superior in this respect. This analysis assumes that transaction costs of collection are ultimately not significant. At the same time, he concedes that for public corporations with many small shareholders, unlimited pro rata liability to tort victims may be pointless because of high collection costs, and that because of transaction costs, it is unclear what is the best rule (Leebron, 1991). Other authors argue that none of the policy arguments in favor of limited liability have any real application to closely held
5620
Limited Liability
675
firms where owners are also managers and thus can control their risks (Klein and Zolt, 1995).
13. Evidence about Joint and Several versus Pro Rata Liability American law provided experience with both pro rata and joint and several liability: both New York and California law provided for pro rata liability (Blumberg, 1986; Livermore, 1935). American banks from 1865-1932 provided for double pro rata shareholder liability. While American courts were innovative in enforcing this liability, the collection rate on shareholder assessments was only 50.8 percent. Macey and Miller regard this as a success, because it is probable that many shareholders were insolvent (Macey and Miller, 1992). Grundfest has argued that capital markets would respond to pro rata liability by generating a large number of investors who are attachment-proof to specialize in holding equity of risky companies. These will include foreign investors and individuals of modest means holding small amounts of equity, where collection costs will exceed the amount collected (Grundfest, 1992). They will also include separation of substantial assets from risky enterprises through leasing and thin capitalization (Lopucki, 1997; Note, 1994). Recent evidence from Germany, however, supports the hypothesis that for investors in large firms risk aversion (and the liability rule) does not influence the choice of firm (Horvath and Woywode, 1996).
14. Limited Liability in Contract Early literature concentrated on limited liability for contract obligations. It may be that these writers thought tort liability was trivial. It was only later that writers, recognizing that liabilities for mass torts that could bankrupt even large firms, turned to analysis of the impact of limited liability on tort risks. 14.1 The Theory of Limited Liability in Contract In a perfect capital market with zero transaction costs the value of the firm and its optimal investment policy would not be affected by the liability rule chosen. Unlimited liability would reduce creditors’ risks and the interest rates and other contractual protections demanded, and increase returns to shareholders to compensate for this risk (Halpern, Trebilcock and Turnbull, 1980). Firms that choose a limited liability regime will face higher borrowing costs (Anderson and Tollison, 1983; Posner, 1976), although it is argued that trade creditors typically fail to incur the transaction costs to investigate credit risk (Landers, 1967). In the case of one-shareholder corporations with little capital, creditors will either charge higher interest rates for risky loans or insist on personal
676
Limited Liability
5620
guarantees, so that credit terms are invariant to the liability rule (Ekelund and Tollison, 1980; Meiners, Mofsky and Tollison, 1979). If we introduce transaction costs, where lenders are uncertain about the extent of shirking and risky behavior by owners with limited liability they may increase interest costs to the point where owners prefer to finance without borrowings at the firm level (Eswaran and Kotwal, 1989). This analysis has been extended to stock insurance companies: if shareholder liability is limited, policyholders will presumably recognize the risk they bear and pay less for policies. Insurers can bond against risky investments by writing participation rights into insurance policies (Garven and Pottier, 1995). They can also submit to regulation that assures minimum capital and constrains risky investments. Under an unlimited liability regime, Leebron argues that shareholders would probably prefer to borrow using their interest in the firm as collateral, because they would each only be liable for their own borrowing (pro rata), while if the firm borrows, each would be liable for everyone’s borrowings (joint and several) (Leebron, 1991). Corporate borrowing with limited liability is equivalent to nonrecourse borrowing by shareholders who pledge their shares as collateral, but the transaction costs of such borrowing would be higher, because so many lenders would have to investigate the firm in markets with large numbers of potential lenders (Leebron, 1991). Limited liability creates a state of the world where the worst possible state of the world is known to all investors, both creditors and shareholders, while unlimited liability does not allow shareholders the same certainty (Leebron, 1991). The evidence from eighteenth- and nineteenth-century Scottish banking is consistent with this model. Shareholders in unlimited liability banks earned higher returns than shareholders in limited liability banks (Evans and Quigley, 1995). But despite such differences in returns, in small firms risk aversion leads to a preference for limited liability, especially as firm projects grow riskier, according to a study of German firms (Horvath and Woywode, 1996). 14.2 The Cost of Limited Liability in Contract There are at least three costs borne by firm owners for achieving limited liability, at least two of which apply to both contract and tort liability. First, under limited liability, voluntary creditors will impose higher costs on firms (see above). Second, in many legal regimes, tax costs will be higher for limited liability, because the entity may be treated as separate, although this is not a necessary condition for limited liability. In the United States the development of the Limited Liability Company and Limited Liability Partnership have eliminated the tax cost for closely held enterprises in recent years. Third, in most legal systems except the United States, forming a limited liability entity will subject the firm to extensive public disclosures (Horvath and Woywode, 1996). This apparently is designed to provide potential creditors with information about the firm’s capital where unlimited liability is not available.
5620
Limited Liability
677
While Posner argues that creditors are the most efficient risk-bearers (Posner, 1992), Easterbrook and Fischel (1991) reject this, arguing that the evidence is otherwise: creditors accept lower returns because they prefer less risk, presumably because they are not the least-cost monitors of firms. Johnsen argues that creditors accept lower returns because they monitor only the value of debtors’ assets in alternative and less specialized uses, rather than in the present use, which is left to shareholders (Johnsen, 1995). Recent literature on domination of large corporations by big banks in Germany and Japan has raised the question of whether at least some creditors are superior monitors of firms, but fails to bring any evidence to bear on the subject (Roe, 1994). Some authors treat small trade creditors as if they were involuntary creditors, because they face high transaction costs in assessing the riskiness of their credit extensions (Landers, 1967; Easterbrook and Fischel, 1985, 1991). These arguments ignore both the ability of trade creditors to monitor current payments on a monthly or more frequent basis and their ability to free ride on the negative covenants imposed by larger creditors with scale economies in negotiating credit contracts. Further, they ignore the ability of many trade creditors to bear risk by diversifying their customer base (Carney, 1990). The costs of limited liability imposed on creditors depend on capital structure; thus, secured creditors monitor assets, not firms, so their monitoring costs are not increased by limited liability (Ribstein, 1991; Johnsen, 1995). To the extent that limited liability imposes unmonitored risk on creditors, it has been suggested that increasing the tax on firm profits and paying subsidies to creditors can solve the risky behavior problem. The creditor subsidy will reduce interest costs to the firm, while raising managerial efforts, thus leaving managers better off, because managers exert less effort when liability is limited (Banerjee and Besley, 1990). A similar suggestion has been made with respect to the level of taxation of profits on US financial institutions, to reduce incentives to take risks (John, John and Senbet, 1991). The difficulty with these proposals is that profits taxes do not distinguish returns to risk from returns to superior management. 14.3 The Benefits of Limited Liability in Contract Many of the benefits of limited liability in contract are related to capital markets. With limited liability, investors have the ability to diversify their investments in shares of corporations. This is true in part because without limited liability, for a wealthy investor, each investment would increase the risk of being held personally liable for the debts of a failed firm (Blumberg, 1981; Carr and Mathewson, 1988; Diamond, 1982; Easterbrook and Fischel, 1985, 1991; Grossman, 1995; Halpern, Trebilcock and Turnbull, 1980; Leebron, 1991; Woodward, 1985). It is also true because it reduces the need for any
678
Limited Liability
5620
shareholder to monitor management for risky choices (Blumberg, 1986; Easterbrook and Fischel, 1985, 1991). It also seems likely that given modern techniques for reporting financial results of firms, that monitoring shareholder wealth is more costly than monitoring firm wealth. Evans and Quigley (1995) argued that unlimited liability was observed in Scottish banking at a time when it was cheaper to monitor shareholder wealth than bank solvency. Finally, limited liability reduces the transaction costs of collection.
15. Limited Liability in Tort Limited liability’s externalization creates three problems: (1) firms make excessively risky decisions because they do not consider externalized costs; (2) corporations fail to insure fully; and (3) product costs do not reflect full social costs (Dent, 1991; Leebron, 1991). Many authors apparently believed that the problem of tort liability under a limited liability system was not a serious one, either because they felt that other parts of the legal system had dealt with the principal forms of business accidents, through workers’ compensation, unemployment insurance and mandatory automobile insurance (Manne, 1967), or because they focused on the large publicly held corporation, where the risk that individual tort liability would bankrupt a firm seemed trivial. For this reason, much of the early literature focused on contract liability (Easterbrook and Fischel, 1985; Halpern, Trebilcock and Turnbull, 1980; Meiners, Mofsky and Tollison, 1979; Posner, 1976). The development of the mass tort, stemming either from industrial accidents or strict products liability, has changed the analysis (Hansmann and Kraakman, 1992; Leebron, 1991; Roe, 1986; Schwartz, 1985). 15.1 Externalizing the Costs of Torts The general wisdom states that with limited liability managers loyal to shareholders will select unduly risky projects, because the owners of the firm can externalize some of the social costs of their choices (Blumberg, 1986; Brander and Lewis, 1986; Hansmann and Kraakman, 1991; Leebron, 1991). This may be borne out by a study showing that limited liability firms have a higher incidence of bankruptcy than unlimited liability firms. At the same time, they appear to have higher growth rates - the reward for undertaking riskier projects (Horvath and Woywode, 1996). In oligopoly, the effect of limited liability may provide a signaling effect for firms that take on more debt - that they intend to pursue output strategies that raise returns in good states and lower returns in bad states (Brander and Lewis, 1986). The extent of any reductions in precautions may be a function of the profitability and wealth of the firm, however; the more profitable the firm, the more the owners have at risk, and the greater their precautionary expenses. But where firms are
5620
Limited Liability
679
marginally profitable, owner-managers may choose a lower level of precautions under limited liability (Craig and Theil, 1990). Generally the risk of bankruptcy is treated as a last-period problem; but if it is seen as an expected cost of a firm with positive cash flows, the incentive to take excessive risk may be less than static models would suggest (Suen, 1995). 15.2 The Impact of Agency Costs on Firm Risk-Taking Decisions Agency costs will also influence the amount of firm risk assumed. While firms may increase their risk where there is a unity of ownership and control, as in closely held owner-managed corporations, it is less obvious that this holds with public corporations. Managers of public corporations often hold large undiversified investments in firm-specific human capital, and often in the stock of the firm as well. They are also holders of large fixed claims on the firm in the form of salaries (Jensen and Meckling, 1976). As a result, they may be unduly careful in making choices for the firm, and may retain excess equity in the firm (LoPucki, 1997). Further, their primary concern will be with failure of the firm, because that will cost them their jobs. Easterbrook and Fischel (1985, 1991) argue that with unlimited liability managers will reject some positive net present value projects as too risky, but will accept all such projects under limited liability. Presser argues that such managers would seek to diversify (and perhaps expand) firm activities to reduce the risk of total loss (Presser, 1992). To alleviate the managerial risk-aversion problem, many compensation plans give managers some claim on the upper tail of expected outcomes. To the extent that managers assume unlimited liability as shareholders, the value of incentive compensation tied to stock is reduced, and managers may be excessively cautious (Hansmann and Kraakman, 1991). One benefit of limited liability thus is to neutralize some part of a manager’s risk aversion. Easterbrook and Fischel (1985) further argue that the moral hazard of engaging in overly risky activities under limited liability can also be dealt with through (1) minimum capital requirements; (2) mandatory insurance; (3) managerial liability; and (4) regulation of inputs. Minimum capital requirements are widely employed throughout Europe (Carney, 1997). They represent a relatively crude form of protection, since they are not related to either the riskiness of firm activities nor its capital structure. All states in the United States have moved away from such requirements, providing evidence that in a competitive market for corporate law, these requirements do not survive as efficient (Carney, 1995). Mandatory insurance and managerial liability are discussed in Sections 17 and 18, below. Direct regulation of inputs, such as regulation of nuclear plants, presents problems, in that regulators have weak incentives to balance costs and benefits (Easterbrook and Fischel, 1985). 15.3 The Effectiveness of Shareholders as Monitors of Risky Activities There is little discussion of the relative efficiency of shareholders, managers and creditors as monitors. While Posner (1992) argues that creditors are the
680
Limited Liability
5620
most efficient risk-bearers, Easterbrook and Fischel (1991) reject this, arguing that the evidence is otherwise: creditors accept lower returns because they prefer less risk, presumably because they are not the least cost monitors of firms. Manager liability suggests the function of tort law is deterrence, while shareholder liability suggests the function is loss-spreading (Thompson, 1994). In public corporations, at least, passive shareholders are entirely dependent on management for a flow of information about risk management, as well as all other details of operations (Arlen and Carney, 1992). Most writers believe that limited liability will reduce shareholder monitoring of managers. Easterbrook and Fischel (1985) believe that such monitoring will be replaced by creditor monitoring. Even with limited liability, firms subject to high agency costs (which presumably includes excessively risky behavior) generate large block owners better able to monitor (Demsetz and Lehn, 1985). With constant returns to monitoring managers, the incentive of shareholders is not affected directly by the liability regime, but if managerial effort were to vary with the liability regime, then different levels of shareholder monitoring would be efficient (Carr and Mathewson, 1988). While Hansmann and Kraakman concede that passive shareholders in large corporations are unlikely monitors of risk, they believe markets will perform this function, and that share prices will reflect managerial risk-taking. Ironically, they also argue that managers will not be excessively cautious under an unlimited liability regime because many large uninsured tortious activities create a risk of catastrophic loss only many years later and thus will be heavily discounted by today’s management (Hansmann and Kraakman, 1991). If this is true, it is not clear how markets will be able to provide effective monitoring. 15.4 Catastrophic Tort Liability Only one author has addressed the effect of unlimited liability on deterrence of catastrophic torts. Schwartz (1985) argues that to the extent many mass torts are not foreseeable, strict liability coupled with unlimited liability has no deterrent value. If this is so, the arguments in favor of unlimited liability in tort are thrown back on risk-spreading ability, where the evidence is thus far inconclusive. Where class action claims involve relatively small amounts per claimant and joint and several liability runs the risk of imposing most of the liability on a few wealthy shareholders, it may well be that leaving liability with the injured class places it with the group best able to bear it.
16. Limiting the Cost of Limited Liability in Tort The social costs of externalizing the costs of accidents through limited liability have been discussed in Section 15. This section examines the factors that may
5620
Limited Liability
681
limit the size of the externalized costs. Managers of large firms facing catastrophic mass tort liability typically do not seek liquidation, which might be in the shareholders’ interest, because it ends the firm and with it their employment. Indeed, managers engaging in activities likely to result in catastrophic liability should probably maximize current distributions to shareholders in order to reduce the pool of assests subject to creditor claims. Rather, managers facing such a last period problem may have imposed agency costs on shareholders when they have kept resources within firms and then acquiesced in reorganizations that give mass tort claimants significant ownership in the firm (Roe, 1986). While this creates an agency cost for shareholders, it ameliorates the effects of externalization of the cost of accidents for these firms. Ribstein argues that owners of limited liability enterprises internalize most costs of tort by virtue of the fact that voluntary creditors will either impose higher credit costs or force additional firm monitoring, or both. Because unsecured contract creditors are at risk of some loss (or loss sharing with tort creditors) in the case of tort liability, he argues that tort risk is sufficiently internalized that the benefits of limited liability outweigh its costs to involuntary creditors (Ribstein, 1991). Obviously this arrangement does not internalize the expected cost of accidents in excess of a firm’s unsecured assets. But to the extent that voluntary creditors insist that debtors carry tort insurance, at least some of these costs may also be internalized (Ribstein, 1991). Further, in close corporations, shareholders have significant personal investments to protect, and have incentives to insure to protect them (Ribstein, 1992).
17. The Benefits of Limited Liability in Tort 17.1 Shareholders as Inefficient Monitors of Risky Activities Ex Ante The capital market benefits discussed earlier apply equally to limited liability in tort. The exposure of railroads to heavy tort liability, in connection with large scale operations that could not be readily monitored by shareholders, was one of the original justifications for English limited liability rules in the nineteenth century (Blumberg, 1986). Shareholders in public corporations are often poor monitors of much tort liability, which depends on a constant and candid flow of information about agents’ behavior (Arlen and Carney, 1992). As specialists in providing capital, these passive investors lack the skills to be effective monitors, so their monitoring activities would be inefficient (Easterbrook and Fischel, 1995). With unlimited liability in tort, the relevant domain for monitoring by stockholders expands and agency costs increase (Orhnial, 1982). Imposing default liability on the monitor is consistent with the theory of imposing liability on the party who can avoid it most cheaply
682
Limited Liability
5620
(Ribstein, 1991). In large corporations, this will almost never be dispersed public shareholders. Limited liability eliminates the disincentive for wealthy investors to take large (perhaps controlling) ownership positions in risky firms, which increases shareholder monitoring where it is efficient (Hansmann and Kraakman, 1991). 17.2 Reducing Collection Costs of Judgments Limited liability also reduces the transaction costs of collecting judgments, by shifting some risk to plaintiffs. A system of pro rata liability would increase collection costs, but it would lead to incomplete collections because of the difficulties of obtaining jurisdiction over many individual shareholder defendants (Alexander, 1992; Grundfest, 1992; but see Hansmann and Kraakman, 1992a; Patterson, 1995). Grundfest argues that a class of attachment-proof investors would develop that would specialize in holding risky common stocks, which would arbitrage away any price differences between risky and less risky businesses that should send managers signals about behavior (Grundfest, 1992). But Grundfest’s argument ignores managers’ personal incentives to avoid risk, in order to protect their firm-specific human capital. Bainbridge argues that limited liability encourages investors to more fully capitalize firms, so that tort claimants are better off collecting from firm assets than bearing the transaction costs of collection from shareholders (Bainbridge, 1993). Bainbridge’s argument is stronger under a pro rata liability rule than a joint and several liability regime. 17.3 Incomplete Insurance Markets Easterbrook and Fischel suggest that limited liability was more important in the nineteenth century because insurance markets were less developed, but this ignores the more recent development of mass tort liability, where insurance markets are probably as incomplete as were nineteenth-century markets (Easterbrook and Fischel, 1985; Schwartz, 1985). One solution proposed for the problem of high collection costs under unlimited liability is to provide for personal liability of shareholders only when a corporation is uninsured against the risk, which would increase incentives to insure (Alexander, 1992; Dent, 1991; Leebron, 1991; Schwartz, 1985). The difficulty is that insurance markets are incomplete (Blumberg, 1986; Dent, 1991). The existence of insurance markets will depend on (i) information costs; (ii) moral hazard, (iii) adverse selection and (iv) ability to bear risk (Halpern, Trebilcock and Turnbull, 1980). Because many firms will fail because of systematic risk, insurers will be unable to diversify this risk (Easterbrook and Fischel, 1985; Halpern, Trebilcock and Turnbull, 1980; Leebron, 1991). Further, the potential for mass torts, which are uncertain in both their incidence and extent of liability, may make some activities uninsurable (Hansmann and Kraakman, 1991; Ribstein, 1991). Finally, because lower-risk firms will self-insure rather than purchase costly insurance, the insurance market will be dominated by higher-risk purchasers, raising insurance costs and causing even more firms to self-insure (Ribstein,
5620
Limited Liability
683
1992). Finally, firms cannot be expected to insure against remote risks to their full extent, in part because of bounded rationality (Schwartz, 1985). Mandatory insurance may create new moral hazard problems, encouraging managers to take risks, if insurers are not efficient monitors (Easterbrook and Fischel, 1985). Some manufacturing activities may create potential liabilities decades in the future, where managers will heavily discount the risk (Hansmann and Kraakman, 1991). Further, the high loading costs of insurance (as much as 25 percent) reduce its efficiency (Hansmann and Kraakman, 1991). If liability insurance were mandatory, it would create a new barrier to entry of small firms (LoPucki, 1997).
18. Substitutes for Shareholder Liability 18.1 Tort Creditor Superpriority One substitute for unlimited liability for shareholders is to provide tort creditors with greater priority in a bankruptcy system. Under US law, secured creditors have priority over tort creditors. Providing tort creditors with a priority over all voluntary creditors would shift risk from involuntary creditors to voluntary creditors (Buckley, 1986; Presser, 1992). While this would increase monitoring by creditors, their comparative advantage in monitoring for this kind of risk over shareholders is not always clear. One author suggests that contract creditors specialize in valuing firm assets in alternative uses, while shareholders capture the quasi-rents from the current firm-specific use (Johnsen, 1995). Whether credit terms would be set to reflect accurately the new risks that the firm’s owners (including creditors) could not escape is an empirical question, but the increasing use of public markets for borrowings in the US suggests that these markets might become efficient, so prices would accurately reflect risks. At the same time, securitization of financial assets enhances their availability to the same passive investors likely to hold stocks, which probably reduces any comparative advantages in monitoring formerly held by creditors. Leebron argues that tort victims might consent to the priority of secured creditors if the loan made additional assets available to satisfy their claim or provided increased creditor monitoring. If new funds are provided to operate the business by the loan, tort creditors will suffer if firm assets subsequently shrink (Leebron, 1991). 18.2 Lender Liability Another substitute for unlimited shareholder liability is to treat contract creditors as owners of the firm, and subject them to unlimited liability. Leebron argues that in many public corporations creditors can exercise more control than public shareholders, and are better able to diversify risk than tort victims. Further, private contract lenders (as opposed to bondholders) are superior
684
Limited Liability
5620
monitors when compared to tort victims (Leebron, 1991). Indeed, some creditors may well be superior monitors to public shareholders as well (Easterbrook and Fischel, 1985). At the very least, large creditors are in a position to monitor firms for adequate capitalization, and to adjust interest rates to create incentives to capitalize the firm (Ribstein, 1992). On the other hand, unlimited liability for creditors would exacerbate the stockholder-bondholder conflict, and because of liability for catastrophic torts, lenders’ negative covenants would be of less value (Leebron, 1991). 18.3 Managerial Liability To the extent that neither shareholders nor creditors are effective monitors of managers’ risky choices, one solution might be to make managers personally liable for corporate obligations. But managers, while perhaps best able to monitor themselves, are inefficient risk-bearers, so that imposing liability on them will lead to even more risk aversion in firm decisions than managers may now choose (Thompson, 1994). Further, their investments in firm-specific human capital are uninsurable (Easterbrook and Fischel, 1985). Apparently because of the large risk premiums that would be required to persuade managers to bear liabilities personally, Kraakman has argued that managerial liability does not provide enough additional deterrence over enterprise liability to offset the greater costs involved (Kraakman, 1984). In the context of deliberate torts such as securities fraud, it is precisely managerial liability - both civil and criminal - that is required to deter these actions, given the last period problems facing managers tempted to commit securities fraud (Arlen and Carney, 1992). Indeed, Kraakman also states that enterprise (limited) liability fails when costs are shifted to third parties through firm wrongdoing, and firms lack sufficient assets to respond in damages. But he also argues that imposing liability on managers while permitting indemnification provides managerial incentives to keep firms solvent and able to respond to judgments. Dual liability of firms and managers lessens the risk that penalties were set too low for either, because now two levels of decision-makers must calculate costs and benefits (Kraakman, 1984). If French managers violate the company’s constitution or law, they can be made personally liable to the company, its shareholders and creditors. France is thus in the forefront of the movement to extend the liability of management, and not simply of the membership (Perrott, 1982).
5620
Limited Liability
685
19. Risk-Bearing Ability and the Role of Insurance There is general consensus that diversified shareholders are superior risk-bearers to tort victims (Leebron, 1991; Menell, 1990; Murphy, 1995; Thompson, 1994). But some authors have argued that the risk-bearing superiority of shareholders is not obvious. Tort victims may be superior risk-bearers if they can obtain insurance more cheaply (Leebron, 1991) or if individual harms are small while corporate (and shareholder) liability is large, relative to wealth. The principal argument in favor of limited liability with respect to risk-bearing is that insurance markets are incomplete, and would not allow investors to insure against personal liability for corporate failures. The occurrence of corporate bankruptcies will be positively correlated with the business cycle, and with the systematic risk of shares. Because of this, insurers will find they cannot easily diversify such risk, and will decline to write such insurance (Halpern, Trebilcock and Turnbull, 1980). Further, there may be an adverse selection problem: shareholders will choose to insure only their risk attached to ownership of high beta companies. Because managers are undiversified, they have incentives to have firms insure against liability to protect the life of the firm (Thompson, 1994). Additional insurance caused by unlimited liability only serves to reduce the cost of accidents if insurance companies are efficient monitors, and can adjust premiums to reflect experience (Ribstein, 1992). The ability and incentives of insurers to monitor for risky activities may be limited in several ways. First, insurers will retain some ability to contest claims if contract conditions are violated. Second, experience-based rates are set ex post, so that rates will lag observation of risky behavior. Third, where an insured believes it is in the last period of insurance coverage, incentives to avoid higher premiums are eliminated (Price, 1995). While involuntary tort claimants cannot diversify their risk in the same way tortfeasors can because their entire future wealth and earning power may be at stake, they can insure against their loss (Leebron, 1991; Meiners, Mofsky and Tollison, 1979). Because potential victims can decide how much insurance they desire, forcing either corporations or shareholders to carry additional insurance may cause overinsurance, except for the fact that most individuals do not insure against pain and suffering (Hansmann and Kraakman, 1991), perhaps because this is a risk they are willing to bear (Leebron, 1991). Indeed, it is not clear such insurance is available to individuals, perhaps because no market for it has been demonstrated. Where tortfeasors are in risky industries or in cyclical industries, they may be more efficient risk-bearers than the tortfeasors or their shareholders because of their superior ability to purchase all-risk insurance (Ribstein, 1992). Analysis may also change when the corporation is closely held, so that tort victims may be better able to diversify and insure than shareholders. Similarly, where unlimited liability discourages diversification
686
Limited Liability
5620
and forces investors to hold fewer stocks to improve monitoring, the risk-bearing ability of shareholders declines (Thompson, 1994). Further, analysis may change if mass tort liability involves relatively small injuries to large numbers of victims, and the possibility of catastrophic shareholder liability. The nature of mass tort liabilities has been explored with respect to this issue by only one writer (Schwartz, 1985).
Bibliography on Limited Liability (5620) Adams, Michael (1991), ‘Eigentum, Kontrolle und Beschränkte Haftung (Property, Control and Limited Liability)’, in Ott, Claus and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (eds), Ökonomische Probleme des Zivilrechts, Berlin, Springer-Verlag, 193-225. Alexander, Janet Cooper (1992), ‘Unlimited Shareholder Liability Through a Procedural Lens’, 106 Harvard International Law Journal, 387-445. Alting, Carsten (1995), ‘Piercing the Corporate Veil in American and German Law - Liability of Individuals and Entities: A Comparative View’, 2 Tulsa Journal of Comparative and International Law, 187-251. Amsler, Christine E., Bartlett, Robin L. and Bolton, Craig J (1981), ‘Thoughts of Some British Economists on Early Limited Liability and Corporate Legislation’, 13 History of Political Economy, 774-793. Anderson, Gary M. and Tollison, Robert D (1983), ‘The Myth of the Corporation as a Creation of the State’, 3 International Review of Law and Economics, 107-120. Bainbridge, Stephen M (1993), ‘In Defense of the Shareholder Wealth Maximization Norm: A Reply to Professor Green’, 50 Washington and Lee Law Review, 1423-1446. Banerjee, Anindya and Besley, Timothy (1990), ‘Moral Hazard, Limited Liability and Taxation: A Principal-Agent Model’, 42 Oxford Economic Papers, 46-60. Blumberg, Phillip L (1986), ‘Limited Liability and Corporate Groups’, 11 Journal of Corporation Law, 573-631. Boyd, James and Ingberman, Daniel E (1996), ‘The Polluter Pays Principle: Should Liability be Extended when the Polluter Cannot Pay?’, 21 Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance. Brander, James A. and Lewis, Tracy R (1986), ‘Oligopoly and Financial Structure: The Limited Liability Effect’, 76 American Economic Review, 956-970. Brander, James A. and Spencer, Barbara J (1989), ‘Moral Hazard and Limited Liability: Implications for the Theory of the Firm’, 30 International Economic Review, 833-849. Buckley, Francis H (1986), ‘The Bankruptcy Priority Puzzle’, 72 Virginia Law Review, 1393-1470. Byam, John I (1982), ‘The Economic Inefficiency of Corporate Criminal Liability’, 73 Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 582-603. Carney, William J (1995), ‘Limited Liability Companies: Origins and Antecedents’, 66 University of Colorado Law Review, 855-880. Carr, Jack L. and Mathewson, G. Frank (1988), ‘Unlimited Liability as a Barrier to Entry’, 96 Journal of Political Economy, 766-784. Coffey, Michael P (1994), ‘Note: In Defense of Limited Liability - A Reply to Hansmann and Kraakman’, 1 George Mason Law Review, 59-91. Craig, Ben and Thiel, Stuart E (1990), ‘Large Risks and the Decision to Incorporate’, 42 Journal of Economics and Business, 185-194.
5620
Limited Liability
687
Demsetz, Harold (1986), ‘A Commentary on Liability Rules and the Derivative Suit in Corporate Law’, 71 Cornell Law Review, 352-356. Dent, George W., Jr (1991), ‘Limited Liability in Environmental Law’, 26 Wake Forest Law Review, 151-182. Diamond, Aubrey L (1982), ‘Corporate Personality and Limited Liability’, in Orhnial, Tony (ed), Limited Liability and the Corporation, London and Canberra, Croom Helm, 22-43. Dobson, Juan (1986), ‘“Lifting the Veil” in Four Countries: The Law of Argentina, England, France and The United States’, 35 International and Comparative Law Quarterly, 839-863. Dodd, E. Merrick (1948), ‘The Evolution of Limited Liability in American Industry: Massachusetts’, 61 Harvard International Law Journal, 1351-1379. Easterbrook, Frank H. and Fischel, Daniel R (1985), ‘Limited Liability and the Corporation’, 52 University of Chicago Law Review, 89-117. Ekelund, Robert B., Jr and Tollison, Robert D (1980), ‘Mercantilist Origins of the Corporation’, 11 Bell Journal of Economics, 715-720. Eswaran, Mukesh and Kotwal, Ashok (1989), ‘Why are Capitalists the Bosses?’, 99 Economic Journal, 162-176. Evans, Lewis T. and Quigley, Neil C (1995), ‘Shareholder Liability Regimes, Principal-Agent Relationships, and Banking Industry Performance’, 38 Journal of Law and Economics, 497-520. Fischel, Daniel R (1989), ‘The Economics of Lender Liability’, 99 Yale Law Journal, 131-154. Forbes, Kevin F (1986), ‘Limited Liability and the Development of the Business Corporation’, 2 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 163-177. Frost, Christopher (1993), ‘Organizational Form, Misappropriation Risk and the Substantive Consolidation of Corporate Groups’, 44 Hastings Law Journal, 449 ff. Garven, James R. and Pottier, Stephen W (1995), ‘Incentive Contracting and the Role of Participation Rights in Stock Insurers’, 62 Journal of Risk and Insurance, 253-270. Gillman, Max and Eade, Tim (1995), ‘The Development of the Corporation in England, with Emphasis on Limited Liability’, 22 International Journal of Social Economics, 20-32. Gilson, Ronald J (1991), ‘Unlimited Liability and Law Firm Organization: Tax Factors and the Direction of Causation’, 99 Journal of Political Economy, 420-428. Grossman, Peter Z (1995), ‘The Market for Shares of Companies with Unlimited Liability: The Case of American Express’, 24 Journal of Legal Studies, 63-85. Grundfest, Joseph A (1992), ‘The Limited Future of Unlimited Liability: A Capital Markets Perspective’, 102 Yale Journal on Regulation, 387-425. Halpern, Paul J., Trebilcock, Michael J. and Turnbull, Stuart M (1980), ‘An Economic Analysis of Limited Liability in Corporation Law’, 30 University of Toronto Law Journal, 117-150. Hansmann, Henry B. and Kraakman, Reinier H (1991a), ‘The Uneasy Case for Limiting Shareholder Liability in Tort’, 101 Yale Law Journal, 1879-1934. Hansmann, Henry and Kraakman, Reinier (1991b), ‘Toward Unlimited Shareholder Liability for Corporate Torts’, 101 Yale Law Journal, 1879-1934. Hansmann, Henry B. and Kraakman, Reinier H (1992a), ‘A Procedural Focus on Unlimited Liability’, 106 Harvard Law Review, 446-459. Hansmann, Henry B. and Kraakman, Reinier H (1992b), ‘Do the Capital Markets Compel Limited
688
Limited Liability
5620
Liability?’, 94 Yale Law Journal, 427-436. Hellwig, Martin F (1981), ‘Bankruptcy, Limited Liability, and the Modigliani-Miller Theorem’, 71 American Economic Review, 155-170. Hicks, John R (1982), ‘Limited Liability: The Pros and Cons’, in Orhnial, Tony (ed), Limited Liability and the Corporation, London and Canberra, Croom Helm, 11-21. Horvath, Michael T.K and Woywode, Michael J (1996), Entrepreneurs and the Choice of Limited Liability, Working paper No. 129, John M. Olin Program in Law and Economics, Stanford University Law School. John, Kose, John, Teresa and Senbet, Lemma W (1991), ‘Risk-Shifting Incentives of Depository Institutions: A New Perspective on Federal Deposit Insurance Reform’, 15 Journal of Banking and Finance, 895-915. Johnston, David (1995), ‘The Development of Law in Classical and Early Medieval Europe: Limiting Liability: Roman Law and the Civil Law Tradition’, 70 Chicago-Kent Law Review, 1515-1538. Katz, Wilbur G (1960), ‘Responsibility and the Modern Corporation’, 3 Journal of Law and Economics, 75-85. Kim, Sung Bae (1995), ‘A Comparison of the Doctrine of Piercing the Corporate Veil in the United States and in South Korea’, 3 Tulsa Journal of Comparative and International Law, 73-94. Klaus Macharzina (1982), ‘Corporate Forms and Limited Liability in German Company Law’, in Orhnial, Tony (ed), Limited Liability and the Corporation, London and Canberra, Croom Helm, 44-72. Kornhauser, Lewis A (1982), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Choice Between Enterprise and Personal Liability for Accidents’, 70 California Law Review, 1345-1392. Kraakman, Reinier H (1984), ‘Corporate Liability Strategies and the Costs of Legal Controls’, 93 Yale Law Journal, 857-898. Krendl, Kathy S. and Krendl, James R (1978), ‘Piercing the Corporate Veil: Focusing the Inquiry’, 55 Denver Law Journal, 1-59. Landers, Jonathan M (1967), ‘Another Word on Parents, Subsidiaries and Affiliates in Bankruptcy’, 43 University of Chicago Law Review, 527-540. Landers, Jonathan M (1975), ‘A Unified Approach to Parent, Subsidiary and Affiliate Questions in Bankruptcy’, 42 University of Chicago Law Review, 589-652. Lawrence, William H (1989), ‘Lender Control Liability: An Analytical Model Illustrated with Applications to the Relational Theory of Secured Financing’,62 Southern California Law Review, 1387-1447. Leebron, David W (1991), ‘Limited Liability, Tort Victims, and Creditors’, 91 Columbia Law Review, 1565-1650. Lehmann, Michael (1986), ‘Das Privileg der Beschränkten Haftung und der Durchgriff im Gesellschafts- und Konzernrecht. Eine Juristische und Ökonomische Analyse (The Privilege of Limited Liability and the Piercing of the Corporate Veil in Association and Trust Law)’, 3 Zeitschrift für Unternehmens- und Gesellschaftsrecht, 345-370. Livermore, Shaw (1935), ‘Unlimited Liability in Early American Corporations’, 43 Journal of Political Economy, 674-687. Llebot Majo, José Oriol (1996), ‘Doctrina y Teoría de la Empresa en el Derecho Mercantil (Una Aproximación al Significado de la Teoría Contractual de la Empresa) (Doctrine and Theory of the Firm in Contract Law: Approaching the Meaning of Corporate Contractual Theory)’, 210 Revista de Derecho Mercantil, 319-388.
5620
Limited Liability
689
LoPucki, Lynn M (1996), ‘The Death of Liability? A Systems/Strategic Analysis’, 106 Yale Law Journal, 1-92. Macey, Jonathan R. and Miller, Geoffrey P (1992), ‘Double Liability of Bank Shareholders: History and Implications’, 27 Wake Forest Law Review, 31-62. Macharzina, Klaus (1982), ‘Corporate Forms and Limited Liability in German Company Law’, in Orhnial, Tony (ed), Limited Liability and the Corporation, London and Canberra, Croom Helm, 44-72. Manne, Henry G. (1967), ‘Our Two Corporate Systems: Law and Economics’, 53 Virginia Law Review, 259-284. McChesney, Fred S. (1993), ‘Doctrinal Analysis and Statistical Modeling in Law: The Case of Defective Incorporation’, 71 Washington University Law Quarterly, 193-534. Medici, Maria Teresa Guerra (1982), ‘Limited Liability in Mediterranean Trade from the 12th to the 15th Century’, in Orhnial, Tony (ed.), Limited Liability and the Corporation, London and Canberra, Croom Helm, 122-136. Meiners, Roger E., Mofsky, James and Tollison, Robert D (1979), ‘Piercing the Veil of Limited Liability’, 4 Delaware Journal of Corporate Law, 351-367. Menell, Peter S (1990), ‘Legal Advising on Corporate Structure in the New Era of Environmental Liability’, Columbia Business Law Review, 399-413. Minchinton, Walter E (1982), ‘Chartered Companies and Limited Liability’, in Orhnial, Tony (ed), Limited Liability and the Corporation, London and Canberra, Croom Helm, 137-160. Mitchell, Lawrence E (1989), ‘Close Corporations Reconsidered’, 63 Tulane Law Review, 1143-1190. Murphy, N. Scott (1995), ‘Note: It’s Nothing Personal: The Public Costs of Limited Liability Law Partnerships’, 71 Indiana Law Journal, 201-233. Old, J.L (1985), ‘Some Economic Considerations of Limited Liability’, 19 Law Teacher, 84-89. Orhnial, Tony (1982), ‘Liability Laws and Company Finance’, in Orhnial, Tony (ed), Limited Liability and the Corporation, London and Canberra, Croom Helm, 179-190. Pardinas, Claudia M (1991), ‘The Enigma of the Legal Liability of Transnational Corporations’, 14 Suffolk Transnational Law Journal, 405-456. Patterson, Mark R (1995), ‘Is Unlimited Liability Really Unattainable?: of Long Arms and Short Sales’, 56 Ohio State Law Journal, 815-898. Paz-Ares, Cándido (1983), ‘Sobre la Infracapitazación de las Sociedades (Infracapitalization of Ventures)’, ADC, 1587-1639. Paz-Ares, Cándido (1994), ‘La Infracapitalización. Una Aproximación Contractual (A Contractual Approach to Infracapitalization)’, Rds. nº. extraordinario, 253-269. Perrott, David L (1982), ‘Changes in Attitude to Limited Liability - the European Experience’, in Orhnial, Tony (ed), Limited Liability and the Corporation, London and Canberra, Croom Helm, 81-121. Posey, Lisa Lipowski (1993), ‘Limited Liability and Incentives when Firms can Inflict Damages Greater than Net Worth’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 325-330. Posner, Richard A (1976), ‘The Rights of Creditors of Affiliated Corporations’, 43 University of Chicago Law Review, 499-526. Presser, Stephen B (1991), Piercing the Corporate Veil, Deerfield, Ill., Clark Boardman Callaghan.
690
Limited Liability
5620
Presser, Stephen B (1992), ‘Commentary: Thwarting the Killing of the Corporation: Limited Liability, Democracy, and Economics’, 87 Northwestern University Law Review, 148-179. Price, Andrew (1995), ‘Tort Creditor Superiority and Other Proposed Solutions to Corporate Limited Liability and the Problem of Externalities’, 2 George Mason Law Review, 439-476. Ribstein, Larry E (1988), ‘An Applied Theory of Limited Partnership’, 37 Emory Law Journal, 837 ff. Ribstein, Larry E (1991), ‘Limited Liability and Theories of the Corporation’, 50 Maryland Law Review, 80 ff. Ribstein, Larry E (1992), ‘The Deregulation of Limited Liability and the Death of Partnership’, 70 Washington University Law Quarterly, 417 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. and Kobayashi, Bruce H (1995), ‘Uniform Laws, Model Laws and Limited Liability Companies’, 66 University of Colorado Law Review, 947-999. Ringleb, Al H. and Wiggins, Steven N (1990), ‘Liability and Large-Scale, Long-Term Hazards’, 98 Journal of Political Economy, 574-595. Roe, Mark J (1986), ‘Corporate Strategic Reaction to Mass Tort’, 72 Virginia Law Review, 1-59. Roth, Günter H (1986), ‘Zur “Economic Analysis” der Beschränkten Haftung (On the “Economic Analysis” of Limited Liability)’, 3 Zeitschrift für Unternehmens- und Gesellschaftsrecht, 371-382. Roth, Günter H (1991), ‘Kommentar (Comment on Adams, Eigentum, Kontrolle und beschrän)’, in Ott, Claus and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (eds), Ökonomische Probleme des Zivilrechts, Berlin, Springer-Verlag, 226-233. Saville, John (1956), ‘Sleeping Partnerships and Limited Liability, 1850-1856', 8 Economic History Review, Second Series, 418-433. Schiessl, Maximilian (1986), ‘The Liability of Corporations and Shareholders for the Capitalization and Obligations of Subsidiaries under German Law’, 7 Journal of International Law and Economics, 480-506. Schwartz, Alan (1985), ‘Products Liability, Corporate Structure, and Bankruptcy: Toxic Substances and the Remote Risk Relationship’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 689-736. Shannon, Herbert A (1931), ‘The Coming of General Limited Liability’, 2 Economic History, 267-291. Siliciano, John A (1987), ‘Corporate Behavior and the Social Efficiency of Tort Law’, 85 Michigan Law Review, 1820-1864. Suen, Wing (1995), ‘Risk Avoidance under Limited Liability’, 65 Journal of Economic Theory, 627-634. Sundow, Gerardo (1982), ‘Some Reflections on Company Law in Europe’, in Orhnial, Tony (ed), Limited Liability and the Corporation, London and Canberra, Croom Helm, 73-80. Thompson, Robert B (1994), ‘Unpacking Limited Liability: Direct and Vicarious Liability of Corporate Participants for Torts of the Enterprise’, 47 Vanderbilt Law Review, 1-41. Thümmel, Hans (1978), ‘Piercing the Corporate Veil - Germany’, 6 International Business Law, 282-287. Walter, E. Minchinton (1982), ‘Chartered Companies and Limited Liability’, in Orhnial, Tony (ed), Limited Liability and the Corporation, London and Canberra, Croom Helm, 137-160. Weber-Ray, Daniela (1995), ‘Insolvency of a German Limited Liability Company: De Facto
5620
Limited Liability
691
Shareholders, Group Liability for Individual Shareholders’, 7 Pace International Law Review, 523-531. Woodward, Susan (1985), ‘Limited Liability in the Theory of the Firm’, 141 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 601-611. X (1994), ‘Note: Investor Liability: Financial Innovations in the Regulatory State and the Coming Revolution in Corporate Law’, 107 Harvard Law Review, 1941-1958.
Other References Arlen, Jennifer and Carney, William J (1992), ‘Vicarious Liability for Fraud on the Market: Theory and Evidence’, 1992 University of Illinois Law Review, 691-740. Carney, William J. (1990), ‘Does Defining Constituencies Matter?’, 59 University of Cincinatti Law Review, 385-424. Carney, William J (1997), ‘The Political Economy of Corporate Laws’, 26 Journal of Legal Studies, 303-329. Clark, Robert C (1977), ‘The Duties of the Corporate Debtor to its Creditors’, 90 Harvard Law Review, 505-562. Clark, Robert C (1986), Corporate Law, Boston, Little, Brown & Co. Demsetz, Harold and Lehn, Kenneth (1985), ‘The Structure of Corporate Ownership: Causes and Consequences’, 93 Journal of Political Economics, 1155-1177. Easterbrook, Frank H. and Fischel, Daniel R (1991), The Economic Structure of Corporate Law, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 40-62. Hamilton, Robert W (1995), ‘Registered Limited Liability Partnerships: Present at the Birth (Nearly)’, 66 University of Colorado Law Review, 1065-1103. Hessen, Robert (1979), In Defense of the Corporation, Stanford, Hoover Institution, 17-21. Holdsworth, W.S. (1925), A History of English Law, London, Methuen & Co. Ltd., Vol. VIII, 192-222. Hovenkamp, Herbert (1991), Enterprise and American Law, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 49-55. Jensen, Michael C. and Meckling, William H (1976), ‘Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behavior, Agency Costs and Ownership Structure’, 3 Journal of Financial Economics, 305-360. Johnsen, D. Bruce (1995), ‘The Quasi-Rent Theory of Corporate Enterprise: A Transaction Cost Theory,’ 44 Emory Law Journal, 1277-1356. Klein, William A. and Zolt, Eric M (1995), ‘Business Form, Limited Liability, and Tax Regimes: Lurching Toward a Coherent Outcome?’, 66 University of Colorado Law Review, 1001-1041. Posner, Richard A (1992), Economic Analysis of Law (5th edn), Boston, Little, Brown & Co., 393-398, 406-409. Roe, Mark J (1994), Strong Managers, Weak Owners: The Political Roots of American Corporate Finance, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press. Smith, Adam (1776) (Cannan, Edwin, ed., 1937), The Wealth of Nations, New York, Random House, 690-715.
5630 THE SEPARATION OF OWNERSHIP AND CONTROL Stephen G. Marks Professor, Boston University School of Law © Copyright 1999 Stephen G. Marks
Abstract The separation of ownership and control refers to the phenomenon associated with publicly held business corporations in which the shareholders (the residual claimants) possess little or no direct control over management decisions. This separation is generally attributed to collective action problems associated with dispersed share ownership. The separation of ownership and control permits hierarchical decision making which, for some types of decisions, is superior to the market. The separation of ownership and control creates costs due to adverse selection and moral hazard. These costs are potentially mitigated by a number of mechanisms including business failure, the market for corporate control, the enforcement of fiduciary duties, corporate governance oversight, managerial financial incentives and institutional shareholder activism. JEL classification: K22 Keywords: Separation of Ownership and Control, Corporate Law, Market for Corporate Control, Corporate Governance
1. Introduction The separation of ownership and control refers to the phenomenon associated with publicly held business corporations in which the shareholders (the residual claimants) possess little or no direct control over management decisions. Reference to the separation of ownership and control, and concern over its effect, go back at least to Adam Smith. In The Wealth of Nations, Smith (1776), writing about joint stock companies, stated: The directors of such companies ... , being the managers rather of other people’s money than of their own, it cannot well be expected that they should watch over it with the same anxious vigilance with which the partners in a private copartnery frequently watch over their own. Like the stewards of a rich man, they are apt to consider attention to small matters as not for their master’s honour, and very easily give themselves a dispensation from having it. Negligence and profusion, therefore,
692
5630
The Separation of Ownership and Control
693
must always prevail, more or less, in the management of the affairs of such a company. It is upon this account that joint stock companies for foreign trade have seldom been able to maintain the competition against private adventurers. (Book 5, Chapter 1, Part 3, Art. 1)
Modern interest in the separation of ownership and control is often associated with Berle and Means (1932) who documented the rise of the modern corporation in the United States. This chapter is organized as follows. Section 2 discusses the legal and economic factors that separate ownership and control. Section 3 lays out the economic benefits of this separation. Section 4 outlines the costs of the separation of ownership and control. Section 5 surveys the various mechanisms for mitigating the costs of the separation of ownership and control. Section 6 considers briefly the origins of these mechanisms. Section 7 summarizes. The examples and motivations will be taken from corporate law in the United States. This chapter will lay out some of the important issues and point the reader to some of the literature in this area as well as give some examples of the economic reasoning involving some of the issues.
2. Ownership and Control We can define the separation of ownership and control with reference to the owner managed firm. In such a firm, the owner/manager possesses two principal attributes. The owner/manager (1) makes management decisions of the firm and (2) has a claim to the profits of the firm. (These claims are sometimes called residual claims to reflect that they accrue after all costs and fixed claims have been satisfied.) In a large publicly-held corporation, the shareholders own residual claims but lack direct control over management decision making. Correspondingly, managers have control but possess relatively small (if any) residual claims. The lack of control by shareholders is generally attributed to what is variously called free-rider, collective action or coordination problems. Shareholders in a publicly held corporation typically have limited legal rights to control the corporation. Shareholders do not have the right to engage in any day-to-day management of the corporation. Nor are they able to direct policy or to set compensation. And although shareholders have the right to elect directors, the management controls the voting (proxy) machinery. Typically in the US, management may use corporate funds to solicit proxies while insurgents may use corporate funds only if successful. In spite of this, voting could be an effective instrument of control absent collective action problems. However, the existence of collective action problems greatly weakens and, in many cases, eliminates voting as an effective control mechanism. In order for
694
The Separation of Ownership and Control
5630
a shareholder to oust current management such a shareholder faces significant expected costs. The expected return on such an investment to the shareholder, however, is a small fraction of the total return and, more importantly, small relative to the costs incurred. As an example, suppose that a shareholder possesses one-hundredth of 1 percent of a corporation’s stock. Suppose that a change in management would be worth $10,000,000 to the corporation and thus $1000 to the shareholder. Let us suppose that the cost of a proxy solicitation is $100,000. Given these costs, a shareholder would be unwilling to engage in a proxy solicitation unless almost certain of winning. (In such a case, the expenses would be reimbursed.) What is the chance of winning? Consider the collective action problems facing the solicited shareholder. The likelihood that an individual shareholder’s vote will affect the outcome is so small that most shareholders will not take the considerable time and effort of reading and understanding the competing proxy solicitations. (This phenomenon is sometimes called rational apathy.) The result is that the chance that a challenger will win with even a meritorious position, is small. If the chances are, say, 10 percent then the expected gain to the would-be challenger is now $100. The expected costs are 90 percent the chance of failure) times the cost of solicitation. In our example, this expected cost is $90,000. Thus shareholders typically have little incentive to engage in such challenges even where the total expected gain of such an action is large relative to the costs.
3. The Benefits of the Separation of Ownership and Control The benefits of separating ownership and control come from the interaction of three factors. First, under certain conditions and for certain types of decisions, hierarchical decision making may be more efficient than market allocation. Second, due to economies of scale in both production and decision making, optimal firm size can be quite large. Third, optimal investment strategy requires investors to be able to diversify and pool and to be able to change their allocations in response to changing market conditions. Under some conditions, hierarchical decision making may be more efficient than market transactions. Both hierarchical structures and market structures impose transaction costs. For some types of transactions, market costs may be particularly high. If so, then hierarchical decision making may be more efficient. (see, among others, Coase, 1937 and Williamson, 1979). As an example, suppose that a firm is considering either purchasing or making an input product. Let us consider two types of costs. Production costs refer to the cost of making the good or to the purchase price if the good is purchased from an outside supplier. Transaction costs refer to the costs of negotiating the transaction. If the input good is a standardized good then it
5630
The Separation of Ownership and Control
695
makes sense for a firm to go to the market and simply buy the input. Since the good is standardized, production costs will be much lower to outside producers who already are producing the good than it will be to produce in-house. In addition, transaction costs will be lower through the market. The purchasing manager simply has to check a couple of prices and then make the purchase. The competitive market will constrain prices and make extensive negotiations unnecessary. In-house production, on the other hand, involves significant transaction costs including communication costs and agency costs. Thus it makes no sense to make the product in-house. Instead, suppose that the input product is a highly idiosyncratic custom design. Suppose that, because of the uniqueness of the input product, it will cost about the same to build the product in-house as to have someone else build it. In addition, the transaction costs of building it in-house are likely to be lower. Because of the idiosyncratic nature of the product, the amount of negotiation and dispute resolution between a buyer and an outside supplier will be very large. If the product is made in-house, management can communicate to the engineers and the production people what they want. Later, if redesign is necessary, this too can be ordered. (Such redesign negotiations with outside suppliers can be long and tense and can lead to disputes over pricing, delivery dates, and so on.) Although there are principal-agent problems associated with hierarchical decision making within the firm, being able to make command decisions may be much less time-consuming than the extensive negotiations required when dealing with an idiosyncratic product and outside suppliers. Since production costs are the same and the transaction costs are less, the company will likely decide to make the product rather than buy it on the market. (For a more detailed discussion of idiosyncrasy and contractual governance, see Williamson, 1979.) For many firms, the number of idiosyncratic inputs is large. An organizational form that combines hierarchical organization and large size with diversified and liquid investment may possess informational, transactional and productive efficiencies that make it superior to other organizational forms. The separation of ownership and control permits the existence of an organization with these characteristics. In cases where the benefits outweigh the costs (including agency costs) we would expect to see organizations in which ownership and control are separated (see also, Knight, 1921; Arrow, 1974; Chandler, 1977 and Fama and Jensen, 1983).
696
The Separation of Ownership and Control
5630
4. The Cost of the Separation of Ownership and Control Much attention has been focused on the costs of the separation of ownership and control and policies that do or might reduce these costs. In this section we will consider the framework for examining these costs and these policies. Section 5 will consider the costs and policies specifically. Adam Smith considered the separation of ownership and control to be problematic in that managers of such companies would lack the incentives to operate the corporation in the same manner as owner-managers and would thus operate the business in an inefficient manner. Following Adam Smith, Jensen and Meckling (1976) characterized the separation of ownership and control as an agency problem. In the agency approach, shareholders are modeled as principals and managers are modeled as agents. Agents, in this model, maximize personal utility. The issue is how to provide the agent with incentives to induce behavior beneficial to the principals, the shareholders. Agency analysis studies the costs of providing such incentives and the costs resulting from the extent to which agents will still deviate from the interests of the principal even in the presence of such incentives. The costs of the separation of ownership and control are thus the usual principal-agent costs: the monitoring expenditures by shareholders, the bonding expenditures by managers and the residual loss from the divergence of behavior (even with monitoring and bonding) from the ideal. Agency analysis was important first step for the study of the separation of ownership and control. Agency analysis treated managers as economic actors with utility functions distinct from those of their principals and thus formalized Adam Smith’s concern over managerial behavior. Agency analysis focused on incentive schemes by which managers’ objective functions could be more closely aligned with those of the principals. Such schemes require the ability to monitor and to reward performance. Ultimately, however, agency analysis proved to be an imperfect fit for the study of the separation of ownership and control. As Stiglitz (1989) has stated, the problem addressed by the principal-agent literature is ‘how one individual, the principal ... can design a compensation system ... which motivates another individual, his agent ... to act in the principal’s interest’. Embodied in this statement are two concepts that are at odds with current analyses of the separation of the ownership and control. First, modern analyses do not take as its ideal the notion that the shareholder should have the ability to monitor or control management. Indeed, policies that encourage shareholder control may undermine the benefits of the separation of ownership and control outlined above. Rather, much modern analysis has focused how actors other than shareholders may effectively monitor and constrain managerial behavior. These other actors include other stakeholders (such as bondholders), lawyers (in the prosecution of derivative and class action suits), regulatory authorities
5630
The Separation of Ownership and Control
697
(such as the SEC in the United States) and market participants (such as potential acquirers). Second, and perhaps more importantly, many modern analyses do not assume that it is socially desirable for managers to act in the best interests of their current principals. This is made clear in the following example. Suppose that a publicly-traded company has made an ore discovery. Immediate announcement of the discovery will increase share value by 10 percent. However, if the corporation delays its announcement by eight months, allowing it to buy up property surrounding the ore discovery site, then the share price will double. Finally suppose that this is an actively traded corporation and that it is certain that the shareholders eight months from now will be different from the current shareholders. If we were to require that management act as agents of current shareholders, an immediate announcement would be required. Most modern analyses would reach a different result (see below). Berle and Means (1932) suggested treating shareholders as investors who have no necessary claims to control: On the one hand, the owners of passive property, by surrendering control and responsibility over the active property, have surrendered the right that the corporation should be operated in their sole interest ... Neither the claims of ownership nor the those of control can stand against the paramount interests of the community.
Under this framework shareholders are just another set of investors. The issue thus becomes one of determining socially desirable policies for the governance of the corporation. The goals of such policies could include encouraging the efficient flow of investment funds into production and the efficient production and distribution of goods and services. This, in turn, requires a consideration of shareholder protection and looks to policies that provide managers with optimal incentives. Under this model, managers could have duties toward shareholders, but not exactly the same duties that would be suggested by the agency model. Such a model could also include considerations of social justice and could require duties towards other constituencies. As an example of an approach that eschews the strict agency framework, consider the argument by Easterbrook and Fischel (1982) that managerial resistance to takeovers is socially counterproductive. Under a strict agency approach management should resist takeovers in situations where resistance and subsequent bargaining would lead to a higher premium for the corporation’s shareholders. Easterbrook and Fischel argue that even if resistance produces a higher premium for the shareholders the result is socially inefficient. Gains to the target’s shareholders are offset by losses to the acquirer’s shareholders. In addition there are a number of deadweight losses
698
The Separation of Ownership and Control
5630
such as those flowing from bargaining breakdowns, dilution of managerial incentives for good management and discouragement of search. Analysis of the costs of the separation of ownership and control is a several step process involving (1) the articulation of societal goals, (2) the determination of how managerial behavior affects those goals and (3) the evaluation of institutional arrangements in terms of how they affect managerial behavior and at what cost. Broadly speaking, there are two reasons why managerial behavior might not conform to the ideal. The first is that managers might not have the incentives to do so. This is sometimes called the moral hazard problem. The second is that managers may not have the ability to do so (that is, managers may be incompetent). This is sometimes called the adverse selection problem. (see, for example, Ayres and Crampton, 1994 and Smith, 1996). In the following section I will consider some of the institutional mechanisms that mitigate the costs of the separation of ownership and control.
5. Mechanisms for Mitigating the Costs of the Separation of Ownership and Control The separation of ownership and control gives rise to costs in that managers may act in ways that are inefficient or antisocial. Scholars have explored a number of mechanisms that might give managers an incentive to better conform their behavior to the ideal and that might weed out incompetence. Many (but not all) of these mechanisms rely on actors other than the shareholders. I will group these mechanisms into the following six categories: (1) business failure, (2) the market for corporate control, (3) managerial duties, (4) direct managerial financial incentives, (5) corporate governance oversight and (6) shareholder empowerment. In what follows, I give a brief account of some of the issues and analyses that have arisen in the literature surrounding each mechanism. 5.1 Business Failure Even in the absence of any other mechanism we would expect business failure to eliminate incompetent managers and thus to mitigate problems of adverse selection. We might also expect business failure to constrain moral hazard. However, absent additional mechanisms to control moral hazard, a market that depended solely on business failure might simply eliminate certain types of otherwise efficient organizations. If managers are unable to credibly commit to behavior that benefits residual claimants, these claimants may be unwilling to make investments in organizations in which they lack direct control. As Akerlof (1970) has demonstrated, asymmetric information can result in the wholesale elimination of markets. In other words, absent other control mechanisms, large publicly owned corporations might not be viable.
5630
The Separation of Ownership and Control
699
In modern corporations, other mechanisms do exist to mitigate the problems of adverse selection and moral hazard. These are discussed in the following sections. Some of these mechanisms operate in conjunction with business failure. For example, managers of failing businesses may be replaced by outside directors or through the market for corporate control. This threat of removal mitigates the problem of moral hazard and removal itself mitigates the problem of adverse selection long before the corporation is actually allowed to fail. 5.2 The Market for Corporate Control Some scholars have argued that if a market for corporate control is allowed to function, directors will be forced to take action to maximize share value or risk a takeover and the resultant loss of job. The proper functioning of such a market reduces the costs of the separation of ownership and control because, even though shareholders lack direct control, managers will be forced by market pressures to act to maximize share price. In addition, incompetent managers will be removed through the takeover process. In this manner, the market for corporate control mitigates both moral hazard and adverse selection problems. (see, among others, Manne, 1965; Butler, 1989; Easterbrook and Fischel, 1991; Romano, 1992; Macey and Miller, 1995). Two interesting variants of this story are related to dividend policy and capital structure. Some scholars argue that a corporate policy of paying steady dividends, in spite of adverse tax consequences, signals to the market that the corporation will not squander free cash flows. The market recognizes this signal and elevates stock price. (Presumably, firms that did not engage in this practice would suffer from lower stock price and be subject to a takeover; see, for example Easterbrook, 1984a). Other scholars have suggested that capital structure can provide the same sorts of signals. A capital structure that is weighted towards debt creates an obligation on the part of management to pay out future cash flows. Again this reflects a commitment by management not to squander future cash flows. This commitment is valued by the market and is reflected by higher share prices. Corporations that do not make this commitment have depressed share prices and are subject to takeover. The takeover of corporations in leveraged transactions may represent the market for corporate control operating to impose these debt constraints (see, for example, Jensen, 1986). The notion that capital markets can help reduce costs of the separation of ownership and control is parasitic on the notion that managerial performance is reflected in stock price. The idea that stock prices reflect information is known as the Efficient Capital Market Hypothesis (ECMH) and it comes in three flavors. Weak-form efficiency occurs when stock prices reflect all past stock price information (if the market is weak-form efficient, then technical analysis is unavailing). Semi-strong-form efficiency occurs when stock prices
700
The Separation of Ownership and Control
5630
reflect all public information (if the market is semi-strong-form efficient then both technical and fundamental analysis is unavailing). Strong-form efficiency occurs when stock prices reflect all public and private, information. Empirical evidence seems to suggest that capital markets are semi-strong form efficient in the sense that it is not possible to make abnormal returns through either technical or fundamental analysis (see Brealey and Myers, 1991; Ross et al., 1993). Critiques of the market for corporate control as a mechanism for mitigating the costs of the separation of ownership and control have had to deal with the efficient market hypothesis. The critiques come in a variety of forms. Note that in order for the market for corporate control to be effective that (1) managerial incompetence or misbehavior must be correlated with takeover activity, and in order for this to occur it is necessary that (2) that there be a correlation between managerial incompetence or misbehavior and stock price. Various critiques of the market for corporate control attack one or both of the above correlations. For example, one critique attacks the notion that managerial behavior and stock price are highly correlated. Even if stock prices reflect fundamental values, the determinants of these values contain a large random element (that is, random events unrelated to managerial performance are a significant factor in success). This random element weakens the correlation between managerial performance and stock price. Another critique allows that while the efficient market hypothesis may be correct in that it prevents the extraction of abnormal profits, it nonetheless does not imply that stock prices reflect the fundamental values of the firm. For example, noise traders could randomly cause stocks to diverge from fundamental value. Again, this random element weakens the correlation between managerial performance and stock price (see, among others, Black, 1986 and Stout, 1988). Another set of critiques attacks the correlation between managerial activity and takeover activity. Under this critique, takeovers are the result not only of managerial incompetence or misbehavior but also of synergies, the accumulation of market power, expropriation (of creditors or of the government, vis à vis taxes, or of labor), of empire-building, and so on. All of these other reasons weaken the correlation between managerial performance and takeover activity. For evaluations of possible determinants of takeover activity, including some empirical studies, see, among others, Kaplan (1989), Lee (1992), Ippolito and James (1992) and Romano (1992). Other critiques focus on the observability of managerial performance by the market participants. If managerial performance is not observable, or is systematically misobserved, then the market is unable to correctly correlate managerial performance and stock price. One such critique focuses on the informational asymmetry between the market and management. Managers may simply have better information than the market but may have difficulty in conveying this message to the markets. A version of this story is known in the
5630
The Separation of Ownership and Control
701
literature as ‘signal jamming’ and involves the classic prisoner’s dilemma (see Fudenberg and Tirole, 1986). Consider a manager who has the choice between Strategy L (long term) and Strategy S (short term). Neither strategy is certain. Associated with each strategy are two outcomes, one better than the other, and two probabilities: Strategy S (Short term): Outcome S1 (0.2 probability): Short-term earnings = 10, earnings = 60 Outcome S2 (0.8 probability): Short-term earnings = 20, earnings = 80 Strategy L (Long term): Outcome L1 (0.5 probability): Short-term earnings = 10, earnings = 80 Outcome L2 (0.5 probability): Short-term earnings = 20, earnings = 100
Total discounted Total discounted
Total discounted Total discounted
In this example, Strategy L is clearly superior (the worst outcome under Strategy L is equal to Strategy S’s best outcome). Suppose, however, that the market cannot observe the chosen strategy or the expected total discounted earnings flowing therefrom. Rather, only current earnings are observable in the short term. Management chooses a strategy, short-term earnings are revealed, and, on the basis of these short-term earnings, the market values the shares. The market uses the short-term earnings as a signal for total discounted earnings. The signal the market uses depends on what firms in the market typically do. As an example, suppose that every other firm picks Strategy S. In this case, the market will associate short-term earnings of $20 with total discounted earnings of $80, and thus bid the short-term share price to $80. The market will associate short-term earnings of $10 with total discounted earnings of $60, and thus bid the short-term share price to $60. The manager in this environment faces the following choice: Strategy S (Short term): Outcome S1 (0.2 probability): Short-term earnings = 10, Market valuation = 60 Outcome S2 (0.8 probability): Short-term earnings = 20, Market valuation = 80 Expected Market Valuation = 76 Strategy L (Long term): Outcome L1 (0.5 probability): Short-term earnings = 10, Market valuation = 60 Outcome L2 (0.5 probability): Short-term earnings = 20, Market valuation = 80 Expected Market Valuation = 70 Note that the market is valuing solely on the short-term earnings signal. Instead, if every other firm adopted strategy L, the signals would be different:
702
The Separation of Ownership and Control
5630
Strategy S (Short term): Outcome S1 (0.2 probability): Short-term earnings = 10, Market valuation = 80 Outcome S2 (0.8 probability): Short-term earnings = 20, Market valuation = 100 Expected Market Valuation = 96 Strategy L (Long term): Outcome L1 (0.5 probability): Short-term earnings = 10, Market valuation = 80 Outcome L2 (0.5 probability): Short-term earnings = 20, Market valuation = 100 Expected Market Valuation = 90 This leads to the following prisoner’s dilemma. Every other firm:
Our Firm:
Strategy S
Strategy L
Strategy S
76
96
Strategy L
70
90
The dominant strategy for the firm, indeed for all firms, is to adopt the short-term strategy. It is interesting to note that in equilibrium, with all firms adopting the short-term strategy, the market indeed values shares correctly. In equilibrium, the market is not being fooled. Yet even though the market is not being fooled, and cannot be fooled in the long term, managers still have the incentive to adopt short-term strategies. In this model, a market for corporate control would drive managers to make inefficient decisions. As another example, consider a two-period model in which the present-value discounted revenues are as follows: Strategy S (Short term): PV of Period 1 revs = 100, PV of Period 2 revs = 100 Strategy L (Long term): PV of Period 1 revs = 80, PV of Period 2 revs = 130 Suppose that labor costs in period 1 are fixed by contract at 50 but that the period 2 labor bill will be renegotiated. Suppose that bargaining strengths of labor and management are equal so that second period revenues will be equally split between labor and shareholders. Thus the return to shareholders of Strategy S is 50 in both periods or a total of 100. Returns to shareholders of Strategy L is 30 in the first period and 65 in the second or a total return of 95. Thus share price is maximized by S, even though L produces more value. In this case, even though Strategy S benefits shareholders, it is socially inefficient. Again, the market for corporate control drives managers to make inefficient decisions.
5630
The Separation of Ownership and Control
703
It should be noted that market-induced myopia, though theoretically possible, is difficult to identify empirically due to the difficulty in establishing a benchmark. 5.3 The Specification and Enforcement of Managerial Duties Some scholars have viewed the establishment of managerial duties legislatively, administratively, judicially, or contractually, and then the establishment of an enforcement mechanism as a means of mitigating the costs associated with the separation of ownership and control (see, for example, Brudney, 1966). We can divide enforcement regimes into two general categories. The first is enforcement through private rights of action. Typically, in such a system, attorneys are provided incentives, through attorneys’ fees in derivative or class action suits, to prosecute cases in which directors violate their duties. Without the provision of attorneys’ fees, individual shareholders have little incentive to prosecute such cases themselves since they would bear all of the costs but receive a very small fraction of the benefit. The provision of attorneys’ fees solves this problem by creating large incentives for attorneys to prosecute these cases. In effect, such a system provides private attorneys general who operate to enforce managerial duties (see Romano, 1991). This system represents one in which someone other than shareholders (that is, attorneys) provides the enforcement mechanism (the shareholder is just a nominal presence). A number of duties are enforceable in this manner, such as, in the US, the duties of care and loyalty. The second enforcement mechanism is direct enforcement by the government. In the US, a number of duties are enforceable in this manner, including many duties created through the securities acts. Many duties are enforceable through both private and public enforcement. The following issues have occupied scholars who have studied this class of mechanisms. What is the optimal set of managerial duties? Should they be broad or narrow? To whom should duties be owed? Should duties be mandatory (state-imposed) or optional (contained in charter provisions)? Should enforcement be private (through derivative and class action suits) or public? Is enforcement effective? Who should be liable, managers, the corporation or both? As to private enforcement, what sort of incentives and disincentives should lawyers have to bring such suits? To what extent should managers be able to immunize themselves through insurance and indemnification? (In addition, there is a question as to the history and origins of the duties and whether the process of producing duties is a good one. I put this last question off to a later section since it relates to corporate law in general and not just to this particular mechanism.) As to the issue of which duties are best privately enforced and which are best publicly enforced, there is a large literature which is not limited to
704
The Separation of Ownership and Control
5630
corporate law. For example, Calabresi and Melamed (1972) and Cooter (1984) both discuss rationales for different enforcement regimes (see also Boston University Law Review (1996). In private enforcement, there exists a large literature on optimal incentives to sue which again is not limited to the corporate area (see, for example, Shavell, 1982). Specific to corporate law, there is much debate on whether private enforcement through derivative actions is effective (see, for example, Kraakman, Park and Shavell (1994). An additional enforcement issue which has been treated by law and economics scholars is whether liability should run to organizations, natural persons or both (see, for example, Arlen, 1994; Arlen and Kraakman, 1997). One important issue that has been addressed by law and economics scholars is whether duties should be mandatory or optional. Under an optional (opt-out) regime, the law would provide a standard set of duties that would be optimal for a large number of corporations. However, individual corporations would be allowed to opt out of these duties through provisions in the corporate charter. Under this view, the corporation is seen as a nexus of voluntary contracts designed to minimize agency costs. (This nexus of contracts view of the firm probably dates from Coase, 1937. See also Alchian and Demsetz, 1972; Jensen and Meckling, 1976; Klein, 1982; Cheung, 1983; Williamson, 1984; Butler, 1989; Butler and Ribstein, 1990; Easterbrook and Fischel, 1991). Proponents of the opt-out regime point out that the same set of provisions is unlikely to be optimal for every corporation. They also assert that the existence of relatively efficient markets for securities will create incentives for corporations to adopt provisions that are efficient. Those corporations with inefficient provisions will have depressed share prices and will invite takeovers. As such, the adoption of managerial duties by a corporation is similar to any other managerial decision. (For examples of analyses in support of an opt-out regime, see, Winter, 1977; Carlton and Fischel, 1983; Easterbrook and Fischel, 1982; Macey, 1984; Easterbrook, 1984, among others.) Proponents of mandatory managerial duties point to market failure. Consider the case for the mandatory provision of information. One argument is that efficient markets depend on the availability of information. Without a duty to disclose there will be an inadequate provision of information. Efficient charter provisions, including efficient disclosure provisions, are unlikely to be produced if the market for securities is inefficient. Thus efficient disclosure provisions are unlikely to be produced in an inefficient market and an efficient market is unlikely to develop absent efficient disclosure provisions (Joseph Heller referred to this type of situation as a Catch-22). Thus, the argument goes, mandatory disclosure provisions are necessary. A similar argument could be made for provisions (such as poison-pill provisions) that insulate management from the market. Again, efficient takeover provisions are unlikely to be produced in an inefficient market and an
5630
The Separation of Ownership and Control
705
efficient market is unlikely to develop absent efficient take-over provisions. Even if markets are relatively efficient, market forces may provide inadequate incentives. For example, Bebchuk (1989) argues that a charter amendment that redistributes corporate money to management would affect the probability of a takeover only marginally given that such transfers are probably small relative to corporate assets though large relative to individual assets. Other market failure critiques point to the public-goods nature of managerial duties. This argument asserts that a change in duties could have a large negative impact on the corporation. However, the impact on individual shareholders could be small due to small individual share holdings and thus it would not be worth the cost of resistance. For example, imagine a relaxation of the duty of loyalty. Such a change could result in large benefits for the manager by allowing the manager to expropriate a percentage of corporate wealth. Since the change is small to individual shareholders, such shareholders would not bother to resist. Share price could fall representing the amount that managers have taken. Such an expropriation could not be remedied through the market for corporate control since corporate wealth has already been removed from the corporation. Yet other critiques point to the lack of sophistication of shareholders. The previous story is enhanced, for example, if the change in the charter is relatively complex. An unsophisticated shareholder would then have to invest more heavily in order to understand and resist such a change. Another critique of the opt-out duties, attacks the wealth-maximization criterion. Under this critique, even if opt-out duties did result in efficiency, mandatory duties would be necessary to accomplish other societal goals such as distributive goals. Several empirical studies have attempted to determine whether corporate decisions to opt out of managerial duties are efficient. (For analyses in support of a mandatory regime see Bebchuk, 1989; Brudney, 1985, and Coffee, 1988, among others.) 5.4. Corporate Governance Structure and Oversight Under this rubric I include policies directed at the structure and procedures of the board of directors. Some important questions are: How should the board be selected? Who should be on the board of directors? Who should the board represent? What should be the goal of the board? How should the board be compensated? Boards of directors in US corporations are typically elected by shareholders. In Europe, there has been some experience with boards that represent other constituencies, such as labor. In addition, large share-holdings by banks in countries such as Germany and Japan have provided oversight by lenders. A body of literature examines the costs and benefits of these various representational schemes (see, for example, Aoki, 1984; Jensen and Meckling, 1979; Summers, 1980, and Williamson, 1984). Additionally there exists
706
The Separation of Ownership and Control
5630
literature as to whether boards, however chosen, have responsibilities narrowly to shareholders or broadly to the society as a whole. For example, Dodd (1932) has argued that managers have responsibilities to the community and not just to shareholders. Friedman (1970), on the other hand, has argued that the manager has a duty to maximize shareholder value subject only to legal and ethical constraints. Recently, the debate has been reenergized by the passage in several states of ‘other-constituency’ statutes. Proponents view these statutes as providing boards with the right to consider other constituencies, such as labor. Opponents view these statutes as merely providing cover for managerial entrenchment. An additional issue concerns the role of boards in active management and oversight. Some scholars have examined the separation of roles between the chairman of the board (oversight) and the chief executive officer (management). Others have examined the division between outside directors (oversight) and inside directors (management). In the US, boards are typically composed of inside and outside directors. Inside directors manage the day-to-day operations of the corporation. Outside directors provide oversight. Ideally, monitoring by outside directors could mitigate problems of moral hazard and adverse selection (see, for example, Weisbach, (1988). The reward structure for inside and outside directors differ markedly. For example, in the takeover context, both inside and outside directors stand to lose their jobs. However, whereas for the insider directors this loss is potentially great, including loss of a large income, important responsibilities, prestige and the like, for the outside director this involves the loss of a very part-time job and a very part-time salary. Thus the outside director has diminished incentives to oppose the takeover for personal reasons. Although outside directors may be more likely to act in the interests of the corporation, the position of outside directors is weakened, however, by the fact that such directors are typically chosen by inside directors and that their continued employment depends on getting along with the insiders. In addition, inside directors and outside directors often find their positions reversed with respect to other corporations. There is thus an incentive for mutual back-scratching. In addition, insider directors typically control the flow of information. This has led some commentators to be skeptical over the efficacy of this mechanism. Scholars and investors (particularly institutional investors) have made proposals for corporate governance reform that are designed to increase the independence and influence of outside directors. Plans for reform often include one or more of the following proposals: (1) increase the number of outside directors relative to inside directors (most proposals specify that outside directors should be in the majority); (2) remove inside directors from the process of nominating new directors; (3) remove inside directors from the
5630
The Separation of Ownership and Control
707
process of setting directorial compensation; (4) set a mandatory retirement age or term limits for directors; (5) prohibit interlocking directorship (where inside directors of one company are outside directors of another and vice versa, and (6) require that directors own stock in the company. (For additional analysis, see, among others, Mace, 1971; Jensen, 1993, and Lin, 1996.) 5.5 The Alignment of Direct Managerial Financial Incentives Through derivative financial instruments, particularly warrants, it may be possible to give managers greater incentives to maximize share value. To the extent that share price maximization is desirable this mechanism may reduce the costs associated with the separation of ownership and control. Note, however, that compensatory incentive mechanisms address primarily the problem of moral hazard, not adverse selection. Imagine, for example, a corporation whose shares are currently trading for $100. Suppose that at-the-money warrants are trading at $1. Now imagine the following compensation schemes. Scheme 1 pays the manager $200,000 cash per year. Scheme 2 pays the manager $100,000 cash plus $100,000 worth of restricted shares (that is, 1000 shares). The restricted shares cannot be traded for five years. Scheme 3 pays the manager $100,000 cash plus $100,000 worth of warrants (that is, 100,000 warrants). The warrants would be exercisable in five years. Each scheme provides the same value of compensation. However, the incentive effects are quite different. Under scheme 1, the manager is not required to take an equity interest in the corporation. Under scheme 2, the manager will have accumulated 5000 shares after five years. Under scheme 3, the manager will possess 500,000 warrants after five years. Imagine now that a takeover offer for the corporation develops involving a 100 percent premium. Under scheme 1, the manager has an incentive to resist the takeover even if the price is a good one since the manager will likely lose his or her job. Under scheme 2, the manager has something of an incentive to consider the opportunity of a good price since the manager will receive $500,000 in increased value for selling into the offer as opposed to resisting it. Under scheme 3, the share price is likely to dominate the managers thinking since the premium represents $50,000,000 to the manager. (Assume that the manager may exercise the warrants in a takeover situation.) To the extent that maximization of share price is a desired outcome this mechanism creates stronger incentives for managers than might otherwise exist. The warrant mechanism could be combined with corporate governance structures in order to create even stronger incentives. For example, one could imagine governance structures in which outside directors constituted a majority and in which outside directors were compensated exclusively through warrants. In such a case, outside directors would have small adverse incentives (since the salary is small) and significant correct incentives since their compensation would depend almost exclusive on share price performance.
708
The Separation of Ownership and Control
5630
One should note that warrants create asymmetric incentives. That is, they pay if share price is above the exercise price. However, the payoffs are the same (that is, zero) for all prices below the exercise price. Thus warrants could create incentives for inefficient risk-taking. Nevertheless, since cash compensation creates incentives for inefficiently risk-averse behavior it is not clear what the net effect of warrants would be (see, among others, Jensen and Murphy, 1990; Gilson, 1992; Milgrom and Roberts, 1992). 5.6 Shareholder Empowerment A number of scholars have made proposals to increase the power of shareholders over management. Shareholder empowerment as a mechanism for managerial control has a different emphasis from the previously discussed mechanisms in that those mechanisms relied on actors other than shareholders to restrain management. Those mechanisms sought to maintain the advantages of the separation of ownership and control while mitigating the costs. By contrast, shareholder empowerment reduces the separation and gives shareholders more say in management. Thus some of the critiques of these proposals point to the compromising of centralized management and reduction of the benefits that flow therefrom (see, for example, Boyer, 1993). Shareholder empowerment proposals seek to give public shareholders a greater voice in management by endowing them with greater rights to manage and by reducing the costs of involvement. An important subset of this research notes the increasing prominence of institutional investors in the securities markets and evaluates the costs and benefits of legal changes that would encourage greater activism by institutional investors. Current proxy regulation in the United States gives incumbent management a tremendous advantage over challengers to their authority. Very few matters are required to be put to the vote of shareholders. Managers can fund proxy battles out of the corporate treasury while challengers must incur the high costs themselves unless they ultimately prove successful. In addition, corporations have the ability to restrict voting rights in certain classes of shares (see, for example, Seligman, 1986). This system, combined with collective action problems (see Section 2 above), discourages challenges even where the total benefit of the challenge to the corporation is great compared to the costs. Some proposals for corporate reform would alter proxy rules to put more decisions in the hands of shareholders (that is, to provide for binding shareholder resolutions) and to change the cost structure to make challenges significantly cheaper, for example, by putting some of the resources of the corporation into the hands of shareholder challengers (see, among others, Bernstein and Fischer, 1940; Caplin, 1953; Eisenberg, 1970; Dent, 1989; Goforth, 1994; Smith, 1996). Evaluation of such proposals must trade the gains of greater managerial accountability against both the costs of increased use of corporate funds for such purposes and the cost of decreased centralization of management
5630
The Separation of Ownership and Control
709
decisionmaking. In the US, equity securities are held increasingly by institutions, i.e., pension funds, insurance funds and investment funds. Although any individual fund holds a small percentage of the shares of any given corporation, the holdings are significant enough to encourage some monitoring. In addition, a small number of funds could control enough of a corporation to possess significant voting power if their actions are coordinated (see, among others, Gilson and Kraakman, 1991, 1993a; Black, 1992a, 1992b; and Maug, 1997). In the US, laws exist which work to discourage cooperation among funds to exercise voting control. Some proposals have suggested reducing these barriers to cooperation in order to allow funds to exert control over management and thus to reduce the separation of ownership and control and thereby reduce the costs associated with the separation of ownership and control. Some of this scholarship has been comparative in nature, focusing on institutional ownership by banks in countries such as Germany and Japan (see, among others, Gilson and Roe, 1993). Skeptics of institutional monitoring point to a number of costs associated with institutional investor oversight. Fund managers are themselves agents whose interests are not aligned with their own investors. In addition, managers represent only some of the shareholders. Control and access to information may lead to insider trading and other abuses vis-à-vis other shareholders. Although fund managers may have incentives to cooperate with other fund managers in order to exercise control, they are also in competition. Strategic behavior may result in inefficient control. Some managers, particularly managers of government pension funds, may be susceptible to political influence. Debates over institutional investor voice involve assessing these costs (see, among others, Garten, 1992; Romano, 1993; Calio and Zahralddin, 1994; Bainbridge, 1993, 1995; Fisch, 1994; Utset, 1995).
6. Origins of the Mechanisms for Mitigating the Costs of the Separation of Ownership and Control In the United States, most of the mechanisms for mitigating the costs of ownership and control are regulated by state law. Some commentators have suggested that the optimal development of mechanisms has been impeded through the process of state competition for corporate charters. This has become known as the ‘race-to-the-bottom’ thesis. This has led some commentators to support a federal (that is, national) chartering of corporations and the development of a federal corporate law. Other commentators argue that jurisdictions that compete for charters will offer efficient corporate laws. Yet other scholars have applied public choice tools to explain the development of corporate law as the result of the interest group interaction (see Cary, 1974;
710
The Separation of Ownership and Control
5630
Dodd and Leftwich, 1980; Romano, 1985, 1994; Hovenkamp, 1988; Macey and Miller, 1987; Bebchuk, 1992; Bratton, 1994; and Ayres, 1995).
7. Summary Many of the issues in corporate law can be traced to the separation of ownership and control. This separation has made viable large, centrally-managed firms with diversified and liquid investors. It has provided the means for the efficient mobilization of large amounts of private capital towards productive uses. The same separation of ownership and control has created potential costs. Much of corporate law can be explained as mechanisms designed to mitigate these costs. Economic analysis of law, with its emphasis on incentive effects and on the costs and benefits that flow therefrom, provides an important tool for the analysis of corporate law and policy.
Selected Bibliography on the Separation of Ownership and Control (5630) Adams, Walter and Brock, James W. (1990), ‘Efficiency, Corporate Power, and the Bigness Complex’, 21 Journal of Economic Education, 30-50. Agrawal, Arun and Knoeber, Charles R. (1996), ‘Firm Performance and Mechanisms To Control Agency Problems Between Managers and Shareholders’, 31 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 377-397. Agrawal, Arun and Mandelker, G.N. (1987), ‘Managerial Incentives and Corporate Investment and Financing Decisions’, 42 Journal of Finance, 823-837. Agrawal, Arun and Mandelker, G.N. (1990), ‘Large Shareholders and the Monitoring of Managers: The Case of Antitakeover Charter Amendments’, 25 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 143-161. Agrawal, Arun and Nagarajan, N.J. (1990), ‘Corporate Capital Structure, Agency Costs and Ownership Control: The Case of All-equity Firms’, 45 Journal of Finance, 1325-1331. Agrawal, Arun and Walkling R. (1994), ‘Executive Careers and Compensation Surrounding takeover Bids’, 49 Journal of Finance, 985-1014. Agrawal, Arun, Makhija, A.K. and Mandelker, G.N (1991), ‘Executive Compensation and Corporate Performance in Electric and Gas Utilities: Some Empirical Evidence’, 20 Financial Management, 113-124. Akerlof, George A. (1970), ‘The Markets for ‘Lemons’: Qualitative Uncertainty and the Market Mechanism’, 84 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 488-500. Alchian, Armand A. and Demsetz, Harold (1972), ‘Production, Information Costs, and Economic Organization’, 62 American Economic Review, 777-795. Alchian, Armen A. (1965), ‘The Basis of Some Recent Advances in the Theory of Management of the Firm’, 14 Journal of Industrial Economics, 30-41. Alchian, Armen A. (1969), ‘Corporate Management and Property Rights’, in Manne, Henry G. (ed.), Economic Policy and the Regulation of Corporate Securities, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research.
5630
The Separation of Ownership and Control
711
Alfaro Aguila-Real, Jesús (1995), Interés Social y Derecho de Suscripción Preferente. Una aproximación económica (Economic Efficiency of a strict Construction of the ‘Interest of the Corporation’ Clause in Corporate Law), Madrid, Ed. Cívitas, 160 p. Amihud, Y. and Lev, B. (1981), ‘Risk Reduction as a Managerial Motive for Conglomerate Mergers’, 12 Bell Journal of Economics, 605-617. Andre, Thomas J., Jr (1990), ‘A Preliminary Inquiry into the Utility of Vote Buying in the Market for Corporate Control’, 63 Southern California University Law Review, 533 ff. Aoki, Masahiko (1984), The Cooperative Game Theory of the Firm, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Arlen, Jennifer H. (1994), ‘The Potentially Perverse Effects of Corporate Criminal Liability’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 833 ff. Arlen, Jennifer H. and Kraakman, Reinier H. (1997), ‘Controlling Corporate Misconduct: An Analysis of Corporate Liability Regimes’, 72 New York University Law Review, 687-779. Arlen, Jennifer H. and Weiss, Deborah (1995), ‘A Political Theory of Corporate Taxation’, 105 Yale Law Journal, 325 ff. Arrow, Kenneth J. (1974), The Limits of Organization, New York, Norton. Arruñada, Benito (1988), ‘Un Análisis Económico de la Regulación de la Sociedad anónima en España (An Economic Analysis of the Regulation of the Joint-Stock Society in Spain)’, 3 Anales de Estudios Económicos y Empresariales, 191-224. Arruñada, Benito (1990), Control y Regulación de la Sociedad Anónima (Control and Regulation of Joint-Stock Companies), Madrid, Alianza Editorial. Arruñada, Benito (1990b), ‘Control y Propiedad: Limites al Desarrollo de la Empresa Española (Corporate Control and Ownership: Limits to its Growth in Spain)’, 687 Información Comercial Española - Revista de Economia, 67-88. Arruñada, Benito (1992), ‘Critica a la Regulación de las Opas (A Critic on the Regulation of Takeovers)’, 203-4 Revista de Derecho Mercantil, 29-67. Arruñada, Benito (1992b), ‘La Conversión Coactiva de Acciones Comunes en Acciones sin Voto para Lograr el Control de las Sociedades Anónimas: De Cómo la Ingenuidad Legal Prefigura el Fraude (Mandatory Conversion of Common Shares into Non-Voting Shares to Reach Corporate Control over Joint-Stock Companies: How legal Simplicity Leads to Fraud)’, 71 Revista Española de Financiación y Contabilidad, 283-314. Arruñada, Benito and Paz Ares, Cándido (1995), ‘Conversion of Ordinary Shares into Non-Voting Shares’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics. Ayres, Ian (1991), ‘Back to Basics: Regulating How Corporations Speak to the Market’, 77 Virginia Law Review, 945 ff. Ayres, Ian (1995), ‘Supply-Side Inefficiencies in Corporate Charter Competition: Lessons From Patents, Yachting and Bluebooks’, 43 University of Kansas Law Review, 541 ff. Ayres, Ian and Crampton, Peter (1994), ‘Relational Investing and Agency Theory’, 15 Cardozo Law Review, 1033 ff. Bab, Andrew Laurance (1991), ‘Debt Tender Offer Techniques and the Problem of Coercion’, 91 Columbia Law Review, 846-890. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1993a), ‘In Defence of the Shareholder Wealth Maximization Norm: A Reply to Professor Green’, 50 Washington and Lee Law Review, 1423 ff. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1993b), ‘Independant Directors and the ALI Corporate Governance Project’, 61 George Washington Law Review, 1034 ff. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1995), ‘The Politics of Corporate Governance’, 18 Harvard Journal of Law
712
The Separation of Ownership and Control
5630
and Public Policy, 671 ff. Bajt, Aleksander (1968), ‘Property in Capital and in the Means of Production in Socialist Economics’, 11 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-4. Bargman, Diedre A. and Cox, Paul N. (1984), ‘Reappraising the Role of the Shareholder in the Modern Public Corporation: Weinberger’s Procedural Approach to Fairness in Freezeouts’, 1984 Wisconsin Law Review, 593 ff. Baysinger, Barry D. and Butler, Henry N. (1985), ‘Corporate Governance and the Board of Directors: Performance Effects of Changes in Board Composition’, 1 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 101-124. Baysinger, Barry D. and Zardkoohi, Asghar (1986), ‘Technology, Residual Claimants, and Corporate Control’, 2 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 339-349. Bebchuck, Lucian Arye (1989), ‘Limiting Contractual Freedom in Corporate Law: The Desirable Constraints on Charter Amendments’, 102 Harvard Law Review, 1820-1860. Bebchuck, Lucian Arye (1992), ‘Federalism and the Corporation: The Desirable Limits on State Competition in Corporate Law’, 105 Harvard Law Review, 1435 ff. Bebchuk, Lucian Arye and Kahan, Marcel (1990), ‘A Framework for Analyzing Legal Policy Towards Proxy Contest’, 78 California Law Review, 1071-1135. Berle, A.A., Jr and Means, Gardiner C. (1932), The Modern Corporation and Private Property, New York, MacMillan. Bernstein, Seldon E. and Fischer, Henry G. (1940), ‘The Regulation of the Solicitation of Proxies: some Reflections on Corporate Democracy’, 7 University of Chicago Law Review, 226 ff. Bhagat, Sanjai and Brickley, James A. (1984), ‘Cumulative Voting: The Value of Minority Shareholder Voting Rights’, 27 Journal of Law and Economics, 339-365. Biancala, Joseph (1990), ‘Defining the Proper Corporate Constituency: Asking The Wrong Question’, 59 University of Cincinnati Law Review, 425 ff. Bjuggren, Per-Olof (1989), ‘Ownership and Efficiency in Companies Listed on Stockhold Stock Exchange 1985', in Faure, Michael and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds), Essays in Law and Economics. Corporations, Accident Prevention and Compensation for Losses, Antwerpen, Maklu, 71-79. Black, Bernard (1992a), ‘Agents Watching Agents: The Promise of Institutional Investor Voice’, 39 UCLA Law Review, 811 ff. Black, Bernard (1992b), ‘The Value of Institutional Investor Monitoring: The Empirical Evidence’, 39 UCLA Law Review, 895 ff. Black, Bernard and Kraakman, Reinier H. (1996), ‘A Self-Enforcing Model of Corporate Law’, 109 Harvard Law Review, 1911-1979. Black, Fisher (1986), ‘Noise’, 41 Journal of Finance, 529 ff. Boardman, Anthony E. and Vining, Aidan R. (1989), ‘Ownership and Performance in Competitive Environments: A Comparison of the Performance of Private, Mixed, and State-owned Enterprises’, 32 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-33. Boyer, Allen (1988), ‘When it Comes to Hostile Tender Offers, Just Say No: Commerce Clause and Corporation Law in CTS Corp. v. Dynamics Corp. of America’, 57 Cincinatti Law Review, 539 ff. Boyer, Allen (1993), ‘Activist Shareholders, Corporate Directors, and Institutional Investment: Some Lessons from the Robber Barons’, 50 Washington and Lee Law Review, 977 ff. Bradley, Michael D. and Rosenzweig, Michael (1986), ‘Defensive Stock Repurchases and the
5630
The Separation of Ownership and Control
713
Appraisal Remedy’, 96 Yale Law Journal, 322-338. Bratton, William W., Jr (1993), ‘Confronting the Ethical Case Against the Ethical Case for Constituency Rights’, 50 Washington and Lee Law Review, 1449 ff. Bratton, William W., Jr (1994), ‘Corporate Law’s Race to Nowhere in Particular’, 44 University of Toronto Law Review, 401 ff. Brealey, Richard A. and Myers, Stewart C. (1991), Principles of Corporate Finance, New York, McGraw Hill. Brickley, James A., Bhagat, Sanjai and Lease, Ronald C. (1985), ‘The Impact of Long-range Managerial Compensation Plans on Shareholder Wealth’, 7 Journal of Accounting and Economics, 115-130. Brudney, Victor (1966), ‘Fiduciary Ideology in Transactions Affecting Corporate Control’, 65 Michigan Law Review, 259 ff. Brudney, Victor (1985), ‘Corporate Governance, Agency Costs, and the Rhetoric of Contract’, 85 Columbia Law Review, 1403-1444. Bundy, Stephen M. (1989), ‘Commentary: Rational Bargaining and Agency Problems’, 75 Virginia Law Review, 335-365. Butler, Henry N. (1989), ‘The Contractual Theory of the Corporation’, 11 George Mason Law Review, 99 ff. Butler, Henry N. and Ribstein, Larry E. (1990), ‘Opting Out of Fiduciary Duties: A Response to the Anti-Contractarians’, 65 Washington Law Review, 1 ff. Butler, Henry N. and Ribstein, Larry E. (1994), ‘Corporate Governance Speech and the First Amendment’, 43 University of Kansas Law Review, 163 ff. Calabresi, Guido and Melamed, A. Douglas (1972), ‘Property Rules, Liability Rules and Inalienability: One View of the Cathedral’, 85 Harvard Law Review, 1089-1128. Reprinted in Ackerman, Bruce A. (ed.) (1975), Economic Foundations of Property Law, Boston, Little Brown, 31-48. Calio, Joseph Evan and Zahralddin, Rafael Xavier (1994), ‘The Securities and Exchange Commissions 1992 Proxy Amendments: Questions of Accountability’, 14 Pace International Law Review, 459 ff. Campbell, David (1990), ‘Adam Smith, Farrar on Company Law and the Economics of the Corporation’, 19 Anglo-American Law Review, 185-208. Campbell, David (1995), ‘Review of R. Tomasic and S. Bottomley, Directing the Top 500', 4 Social and Legal Studies, 428-432. Campbell, David (1996), ‘Review of B. Fisse and J. Braithwaite, Corporations, Crime and Accountability’, 5 Social and Legal Studies, 549-554. Caplin, Mortimer M. (1953), ‘Shareholder Nominations of Directors: A Program for Fair Corporate Suffrage’, 39 Virginia Law Review, 141 ff. Carlton, Denis and Fischel, Daniel R. (1983), ‘The Regulation of Insider Trading’, 35 Stanford Law Review, 857 ff. Carney, William J. (1988), ‘Controlling Management Opportunism in the Market for Corporate Control: An Agency Cost Model’, 64 Wisconsin Law Review, 385-433. Cary, William L. (1974), ‘Federalism and Corporate Law: Reflections Upon Delaware’, 83 Yale Law Journal, 663 ff. Chandler, Alfred (1977), The Visible Hand, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Charensky, Steven S. (1994), ‘Shareholders, Managers, and Corporate R&D; Spending: An Agency Cost Model’, 10 Santa Clara Computer and High Tech. Law Journal, 299-346. Cheung, Steven N.S. (1983), ‘The Contractual Nature of the Firm’, 26 Journal of Law and
714
The Separation of Ownership and Control
5630
Economics, 1-21. Choi, Dosoung, Kamma, Sreenivas and Weintrop, Joseph (1989), ‘The Delaware Courts, Poison Pills, and Shareholder Wealth’, 5 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 375-393. Clarckson, Kenneth W. and Martin, Donald L. (eds) (1979), The Economics of Nonproprietary Institutions (Supplement 1 to Research in Law and Economics), Greenwood, JAI Press, 330 p. Clark, William A.V. (1988), ‘Production Costs and Output Qualities in Public and Private Employment Agencies’, 31 Journal of Law and Economics, 379-393. Coase, Ronald H. (1937), ‘The Nature of the Firm’, 4 Economica, 386-405. Reprinted in Kronman, Anthony T. and Posner, Richard A. (eds) (1979), The Economics of Contract Law, Boston, Little Brown, 31-32. Coffee, John C., Jr (1984), ‘Market Failure and the Economic Case for A Mandatory Disclosure System’, 70 Virginia Law Review, 717-754. Coffee, John C., Jr (1986), ‘Shareholders Versus Managers: The Strain in the Corporate Web’, 85 Michigan Law Review, 1-109. Coffee, John C., Jr (1988), ‘No Exit?: Opting Out, the Contractual Theory of the Corporation, and the Special Case of Remedies’, 53 Brooklyn Law Review, 919 ff. Coffee, John C., Jr (1989), ‘The Mandatory/Enabling Balance in Corporate Law: An Essay on the Judicial Role’, 89 Columbia Law Review. Coffee, John C., Jr (1993), ‘New Myths and Old Realities: The American Law Institute Faces the Derivative Action’, 48 Journal of Business Law, 1407 ff. Coffee, John C. (1994), Transfers of Control and the Quest for Efficiency: Can Delaware Law Encourage Efficient Transactions While Chilling Inefficient Ones?, Working Paper based on a lecture given on 10/28/94. Conard, A.F. (1988), ‘Beyond Managerial Capitalism: Investor Capitalism?’, 72 University of Michigan Journal of Law Reform, 117-178. Cooter, Robert (1984), ‘Prices and Sanctions’, 84 Columbia Law Review, 1523 ff. Cooter, Robert D. and Rubin, Edward L. (1988), ‘Orders and Incentives as Regulatory Methods: The Expedited Funds Availability Act of 1987', 35 UCLA Law Review, 1115-1186. Cox, James D. (1984), ‘Compensation, Deterrence, and the Market as Boundaries for Derivative Suit Procedures’, 52 George Washington Law Review, 745-788. Cutler, David M. and Summers, Lawrence H. (1988), ‘The Costs of Conflict Resolution and Financial Distress: Evidence from the Texaco-Pennzoil Litigation’, 19 Rand Journal of Economics, 157-172. Daines, Robert M. and Hanson, Jon D. (1992), ‘The Corporate Law Paradox: The Case for Restructuring Corporate Law, a Review Essay on The Economic Structure of Corporate Law, by Easterbrook and Fischel’, 102 Yale Law Journal, 577-637. Dallas, Lynne L. (1988), ‘Two Models of Corporate Governance: Beyond Berle and Means’, 72 University of Michigan Journal of Law Reform, 19-116. De Alessi, Louis (1973), ‘Private Property and Dispersion of Ownership in Large Corporations’, 28 Journal of Finance, 839-851. Demsetz, Harold and Lehn, Kenneth (1985), ‘The Structure of Corporate Ownership: Causes and Consequences’, 93 Journal of Political Economy, 1155-1177. Dennis, Roger J. (1987), ‘Mandatory Disclosure Theory and Management Projections: A Law and Economics Perspective’, 46 Maryland Law Review, 1197 ff.
5630
The Separation of Ownership and Control
715
Dent, George W., Jr (1989), ‘Toward Unifying Ownership and Control in the Public Corporation’, 65 Wisconsin Law Review, 881-924. Dodd, E. Merrick (1932), ‘For Whom are Corporate Managers Trustees?’, 45 Harvard Law Review, 1145 ff. Dodd, Peter and Leftwich, Richard (1980), ‘The Market for Corporate Charters: ‘Unhealthy Competition’ vs. Federal Regulation’, 53 Journal of Business, 1-41. Dunbar, Frederick C., Juneja, Vinita M. and Martin, Denise N. (1995), Shareholder Litigation: Deterrent Value, Merit, and Litigants, Options, New York, Law Journal Seminars Press. Easterbrook, Frank H. (1984a), ‘Two Agency-Cost Explanations of Dividends’, 74 American Economic Review, 650-659. Easterbrook, Frank H. (1984b), ‘Managers’ Discretion and Investors’ Welfare: Theories and Evidence’, 9 Delaware Journal of Corporate Law, 540-571. Easterbrook, Frank H. and Fischel, Daniel R. (1982), ‘Corporate Control Transactions’, 91 Yale Law Journal, 698 ff. Easterbrook, Frank H. and Fischel, Daniel R. (1983), ‘Voting in Corporate Law’, 26 Journal of Law and Economics, 395-427. Easterbrook, Frank H. and Fischel, Daniel R. (1984), ‘Mandatory Disclosure and the Protection of Investors’, 70 Virginia Law Review, 669-715. Easterbrook, Frank H. and Fischel, Daniel R. (1989), ‘The Corporate Contract’, 89 Columbia Law Review, 1416 ff. Easterbrook, Frank H. and Fischel, Daniel R. (1991), The Economic Structure of Corporate Law, Boston, Harvard Univ Press. Eckel, Catherine C. and Vermaelen, Theo (1986), ‘Internal Regulation: The Effects of Government Ownership on the Value of the Firm’, 29 Journal of Law and Economics, 381-403. Eisenberg, Melvin Aron (1970), ‘Access to the Corporate Proxy Machinery’, 83 Harvard Law Review, 1489 ff. Eisenberg, Melvin Aron (1989), ‘The Structure of Corporation Law’, 89 Columbia Law Review, 1461 ff. Fama, Eugene F. (1980), ‘Agency Problems and the Theory of the Firm’, 88 Journal of Political Economy, 288 ff. Fama, Eugene F. and Jensen, Michael C. (1983a), ‘Separation of Ownership and Control’, 26 Journal of Law and Economics, 301-325. Fama, Eugene F. and Jensen, Michael C. (1983b), ‘Agency Problems and Residual Claims’,26 Journal of Law and Economics, 327-349. Fisch, Jill E. (1994), ‘Relationship Investing: Will it Happen? Will it Work?’, 55 Ohio State Law Journal, 1009-1048. Fischel, Daniel R. (1978), ‘Efficient Capital Market Theory, the Market for Corporate Control and the Regulation of Cash Tender Offers’, 57 Texas Law Review, 1-46. Friedman, Milton (1970), ‘The Social Responsibility of Business is to Increase its Profits’, 13/9/1970 The New York Times. Frost, Christopher (1992), ‘Running the Asylum: Governance Problems in Bankruptcy Reorganizations’, 34 Arizona Law Review, 89 ff. Fudenberg, Drew and Tirole, Jean (1986), ‘A “Signal-Jamming” Theory of Predation’, 17 Rand Journal of Economics, 366 ff. Garten, Helen A. (1992), ‘Institutional Investors and the New Financial Order’, 44 Rutgers Law
716
The Separation of Ownership and Control
5630
Review, 585 ff. Garth, Bryant G., Nagel, Ilene H. and Plager, Sheldon J. (1985), ‘Empirical Research and the Shareholder Derivative Suit: Toward a Better Informed Debate’, 48(3) Law and Contemporary Problems, 137-159. Geddes, R. Richard (1997), ‘Ownership, Regulation, and Managerial Monitoring in the Electric Utility Industry’, 40 Journal of Law and Economics. Geddes, R. Richard and Crowley, Peter T. (1994), ‘Agency Costs and Governance in the United States Postal Service’, in Sidak, Gregory J. (ed.), Governing the Postal Service, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research. Gilson, Ronald J. (1992), ‘Executive Compensation and Corporate Governance, An Academic Perspective’, 24 Annual Institute on Securities Regulation. Gilson, Ronald J. and Kraakman, Reinier H. (1984), ‘The Mechanisms of Market Efficiency’, 70 Virginia Law Review, 549-644. Gilson, Ronald J. and Kraakman, Reinier H. (1991a), ‘Corporate Governance and Portfolio Performance: An Agenda for Institutional Investors’, Director’s Monthly, 1-4. Gilson, Ronald J. and Kraakman, Reinier H. (1991b), ‘Reinventing the Outside Director: An Agenda for Institutional Investors’, 43 Stanford Law Review, 863-906. Gilson, Ronald J. and Kraakman, Reinier H. (1993), ‘Investment Companies as Guardian Shareholders: The Place of the MSIC in the Corporate Governance Debate’, 45 Stanford Law Review, 985-1010. Gilson, Ronald J. and Roe, Mark J. (1993), ‘Understanding the Japanese Keiretsu: Overlaps Between Corporate Governance and Industrial Organization’, 102 Yale Law Journal, 871 ff. Goforth, Carol (1994), ‘Proxy Reform as a Means of Increasing Shareholder Participation in Corporate Governance: Too Little, But Not Too Late’, 43 American University Law Review, 379-465. Gordon, Jeffrey N. (1989), ‘The Mandatory Structure of Corporate Law’, 89 Columbia Law Review, 1549-1598. Green, Ronald M. (1993), ‘Shareholders as Stakeholders: Changing Metaphors of Corporate Governance’, 50 Washington and Lee Law Review, 1409-1421. Greenwood, Daniel J.H. (1996), ‘Fictional Shareholders: For Whom Are Corporate Managers Trustees, Revisited’, 69 University of Southern California Law Review, 1021-1104. Grossman, Sanford J. and Hart, Oliver D. (1980), ‘Takeover Bids, the Free-Rider Problem, and the Theory of the Corporation’, 11 Bell Journal of Economics, 42-64. Györffy, Gabor (1995), ‘The Structure of Fiduciary Relationship: Its Relevance to Nonprofit Governances and Regulation’, in Bouckaert, Boudewijn and De Geest, Gerrit (eds), Essays in Law and Economics II: Contract Law, Regulation, and Reflections on Law and Economics, Antwerpen, Maklu, 193-216. Hansmann, Henry B. (1988), ‘Ownership of the Firm’, 4 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 267-304. Hansmann, Henry B. (1990), ‘When Does Worker Ownership Work? ESOPs, Law Firms, Codetermination, and Economic Democracy’, 99 Yale Law Journal, 1749-1816. Hindley, Brian (1970), ‘Separation of Ownership and Control in the Modern Corporation’, 13 Journal of Law and Economics, 185-221. Holderness, Clifford G. (1990), ‘Liability Insurers as Corporate Monitors’, 10 International Review of Law and Economics, 115-129. Hovenkamp Herbert J. (1988), ‘The Classical Corporation in American Legal Thought’, 76 George
5630
The Separation of Ownership and Control
717
Washington Law Review, 1593-1688. Hu, Henry T.C. (1990), ‘Risk, Time, and Fiduciary Principles in Corporate Investment’, 38 UCLA Law Review, 277-390. Hwang, Chun-Sin and Kan, Steven S. (1994), Principles of Economics, Cooperating for Mutual Prosperity and Progress (in Chinese), Published by the authors and distributed by Shin Lu Bookstore, Taipei. Hwang, Chun-Sin and Kan, Steven S. (1995), ‘Democracy and the Principle for the Division of Labor in Government Organization (in Chinese)’, in Chien, Sechin Y.S. and Tai, Terence H. (eds), Philosophy and Public Norms, Taipei, Academia Sinica, Sun Yat-sen Institute for Social Sciences and Philosophy, 163-200. Ippolito, Richard A. and James, William H. (1992), ‘LBOs Reversions and Implicit Contracts’, 67 Journal of Finance, 139 ff. Itoh, Hideshi (1992), ‘Cooperation in Hierarchical Organizations: An Incentive Perspective’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 321-345. Janjigian, Vahan and Bolster, Paul J. (1990), ‘The Elimination of Director Liability and Stockholder Returns: An Empirical Investigation’, 13 Journal of Financial Research, 53-60. Jensen, Michael C. (1986), ‘Agency Costs and Free Cash Flow, Corporate Finance, and Takeovers’, 76 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 323-329. Jensen, Michael C. (1993), ‘The Modern Industrial Revolution, Exit, and the Failure of Internal Control Systems’, 48 Journal of Finance, 831 ff. Jensen, Michael C. and Meckling, William H. (1976), ‘Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behaviour, Agency Costs and Ownership Structure’, 3 Journal of Financial Economics, 305-360. Jensen, M and Meckling, W. (1979), ‘Rights and Production Functions: An Application to Labor-Managed Firms and Co-determination’, 52 Journal of Business, 469 ff. Jensen, Michael C. and Murphy, Kevein M. (1990), ‘Performance Pay and Top-Management Incentives’, 98 Journal of Political Economy, 225 ff. Jensen, Michael C. and Murphy, Kevin J. (1990), ‘CEO Incentives - It’s Not How Much You Pay, But How’, 68 Harvard Business Review, 138 ff. Johnson, K.C. (1985), ‘Golden Parachutes and the Business Judgment Rule: Toward a Proper Standard of Review’, 94 Yale Law Journal, 909-928. Joskow, Paul L. (1988), ‘Asset Specificity and the Structure of Vertical Relationship: Empirical Evidence’, 4 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 95-117. Kabir, R., Cantrijn, D. and Jeunink, A. (1997), ‘Takeover Defenses, Ownership Structure and Stock Returns in the Netherlands: An Empirical Analysis’, 18 Strategic Management Journal, 97-109. Kan, Steven S. and Hwang, Chun-Sin (1994), Principles of Economics: Cooperating for Mutual Prosperity and Progress (in Chinese), Published by the authors and distributed by Shin Lu Bookstore, Taipei. Kan, Steven S. and Hwang, Chun-Sin (1996), ‘A Form of Government Organization from the Perspective of Transaction Cost Economics’, 7 Constitutional Political Economy, 197-220. Kaplan, Steven E. (1989), ‘The Effects of Management Buyouts on Operating Performance and Value’, 24 Journal of Financial Economics, 217 ff. Klausner, Michael and Kahan, Marcel (1995), ‘Corporate Contracting: Standardization, Innovation and the Role Contracting Agents’, 48 Stanford Law Review.
718
The Separation of Ownership and Control
5630
Klein (1982), ‘The Modern Business Organization: Bargaining Under Constraints’, 91 Yale Law Journal, 1521 ff. Klein, Benjamin (1983), ‘Contracting Costs and Residual Claims: The Separation of Ownership and Control’, 26 Journal of Law and Economics, 367-374. Klein, Benjamin (1988), ‘Vertical Integration as Organizational Ownership: The Fisher Body-General Motors Relationship Revisited’, 4 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 199-213. Knight, Frank H. (1921), Risk, Uncertainty, and Profit, New York, Houghton Mifflin Co. Knoeber, Charles R. and Flath, David J. (1985), ‘On Managerial Shareholding’, 34 Journal of Industrial Economics, 93-99. Knoeber, Charles R. and Thurman, Walter N. (1994), ‘Testing the Theory of Tournaments: An Empirical Analysis of Broiler Production’, 12 Journal of Labor Economics, 155-179. Kornhauser, Lewis A. and Revesz, Richard L. (1994), ‘Multidefendant Settlements under Joint and Several Liability: The Problem of Insolvency’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 517-542. Kraakman, Reinier H. (1984), ‘Corporate Liability Strategies and the Costs of Legal Controls’, 93 Yale Law Journal, 857-898. Kraakman, Reinier H., Park, Hyun and Shavell, Steven (1994), ‘When are Shareholder Suits in Shareholders’ Interests?’, 82 Georgetown Law Journal, 1733-1775. La Porta, Rafael, Lopez de Silanes, Florencio, Shleifer, Andre and Vishny, Robert W. (1996), Law and Finance, National Bureau of Economic Research, No. 5661. Lambert, Richard A. and Larcker, D. (1985), ‘Golden Parachutes, Executive Decision-making and Shareholder Wealth’, 7 Journal of Accounting and Economics, 179-204. Lashbrooke, E.C., Jr (1995), ‘The Divergence of Corporate Finance and Law in Corporate Governance’, 46 South Carolina Law Review, 449-469. Lee, D. Scott (1992), ‘Management Buyout Proposals and Inside Information’, 67 Journal of Finance, 106 ff. Lehn, Kenneth (1988), ‘Majority-Minority Relationships - An Economic View’, 13 Canada-United States Law Journal, 135-141. Levin, William R. (1985), ‘The False Promise of Worker Capitalism: Congress and the Leveraged Employee Stock Ownership Plan’, 95 Yale Law Journal, 148-173. Lien, Da Hsiang Donald (1990), ‘Competition, Regulation and Bribery: A Note’, 11 Managerial and Decision Economics, 127-130. Lin, Laura (1996), ‘The Effectiveness of Outside Directors as a Corporate Governance Mechanism: Theories and Evidence’, 90 Northwestern University Law Review. Lipton, Martin (1987), ‘Corporate Governance in the Age of Finance Corporatism’, 136 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1-72. Lipton, Martin and Rosenblum, Steven A. (1991), ‘A New System of Corporate Governance: The Quinquennial Election of Directors’, 58 University of Chicago Law Review, 187-253. Llebot Majo, Jos Oriol (1996), ‘El Sistema de la Responsabilidad de los Administradores, Doctrina y Jurisprudencia (Manager’s Liability System, Doctrine and Jurisprudence)’, Revista de Derecho de Sociedades. Lynk, William J. (1981), ‘Regulatory Control of the Membership of Corporate Boards of Directors: The Blue Shield Case’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 159-173.
5630
The Separation of Ownership and Control
719
Lynk, William J. (1994), ‘Property Rights and the Presumptions of Merger Analysis’, 39 Antitrust Bulletin, 363 ff. Macavoy, Paul W. et al. (1989), Privatization and State-Owned Enterprises: Lesson, Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 360 p. Mace, Myles L. (1971), Directors, Myth and Reality, Boston, Harvard Business School. Macey, Jonathan R. (1984), ‘From Fairness to Contract: The New Direction of the Rules Against Insider Trading’, 13 Hofstra Law Review, 9-64. Macey, Jonathan R. (1991), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Various Rationales for Making shareholders the Exclusive Beneficiaries of Corporate Fiduciary Duties’, 21 Stetson Law Review, 23 ff. Macey, Jonathan R. and McChesney Fred S. (1985), ‘A Theoretical Analysis of Corporate Greenmail’, 95 Yale Law Journal, 13-61. Macey, Jonathan R. and Miller, Geoffrey P. (1987), ‘Toward an Interest Group Theory of Delaware Corporate Law’, 65 Texas Law Review, 469-523. Macey, Jonathan R. and Miller, Geoffrey P. (1991a), ‘The Plaintiffs’ Attorney’s Role in Class Action and Derivative Litigation: Economic Analysis and Recommendations for Reform’, 58 University of Chicago Law Review. Macey, Jonathan R. and Miller, Geoffrey P. (1991b), ‘The Fraud-on-the-Market Theory Revisited’, 77 Virginia Law Review, 1001-1016. Macey, Jonathan R. and Miller, Geoffrey P. (1995), ‘Corporate Governance and Commercial Banking: A Comparative Examination of Germany, Japan and the United States’, 48 Stanford Law Review, 73-112. Macho-Stadler, I. and Pérez-Castrillo, J. David (1991), ‘Double Risque Moral et Delegation (Double Moral Hazzard and Delegation)’, 57(3) Recherches Economiques de Louvain, 277-296. Macho-Stadler, I. and Pérez-Castrillo, J. David (1992), ‘Le Règle de la Dérogation dans une Rélation d’Agence (Derogation Rule in an Agent-Principal Relationship)’,102-103 Économie et Prévision, 67-77. Macho-Stadler, I. and Pérez-Castrillo, J. David (1993), ‘Delegar o Centralizar? Qu‚ dice la Economía de la Información? (What Economics of Information Say about Delegation and Decentralization?)’, 52 Cuadernos Económicos de ICE, 25-46. Macho-Stadler, I. and Verdier, T. (1989), ‘Aspectos Estrategicos de la Separación Accionista-Gestor (Strategic Aspects between Corporate Ownership and Control)’, 2(3) De Economía Pública, 25-44. Mahoney, Paul G. (1987), ‘Mandatory Disclosure as a Solution to Agency Problems’, 54 University of Chicago Law Review, 1441-1483. Malatesta, Paul H. and Walkling, Ralph A. (1989), ‘Poison Pill Securities: Stockholder Wealth, Profitability and Ownership Structure’, 25 Journal of Financial Economics. Manne, Henry G. (1964), ‘Some Theoretical Aspects of Share Voting: An Essay in Honor of Merle, Adolf A.’, 64 Columbia Law Review, 1427-1444. Manne, Henry G. (1965), ‘Mergers and the Market for Corporate Control’, 73 Journal of Political Economy, 110-120. Manne, Henry G. (1966), ‘In Defence of Insider Trading’, 44 Harvard Business Review, 113-122. Mark, Gregory A. (1995), ‘Realms of Choice: Finance Capitalism and Corporate Governance. A Review Essay on Mark J. Roe’s Strong Managers, Weak Owners’, 95 Columbia Law Review, 969-999.
720
The Separation of Ownership and Control
5630
Marris, R. (1964), The Economic Theory of Managerial Capitalism, New York, Free Press. Maug, Ernst (1996), ‘Boards of Directors and Capital Structure: Alternative Forms of Corporate Restructuring’, 3 Journal of Corporate Finance, April 1997. Maug, Ernst (1997), ‘Large Shareholders as Monitors: Is There a Trade Off Between Liquidity and Control?’, 53 Journal of Finance.. McChesney Fred S. (1989), ‘Economics, Law, and Science in the Corporate Field: A Critique of Eisenberg’, 89 Columbia Law Review, 1530-1548. Mercuro, Nicholas, Sourbis, Haralambos and Whitney, Gerald (1992), ‘Ownership Structure, Value of the Firm and the Bargaining Power of the Manager’, 59(2) Southern Economic Journal, 273-283. Milgrom, Paul R. (1988), ‘Employment Contracts, Influence Activities and Efficient Organization Design’, 96 Journal of Political Economy, 517 ff. Milgrom, Paul R. and Roberts, John (1990), ‘Bargaining Costs, Influence Costs, and the Organization of Economic Activity’, in Alt, J. and Shepsle, K. (eds), Perspectives on Politive Political Economy, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Milgrom, Paul R. and Roberts, John (1992), Economics, Organization and Management, Englewood Cliffs, NJ, Prentice-Hall. Miller, Geoffrey P. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1993), ‘Corporate Stakeholders: A Contractual Perspective’, 43 University of Toronto Law Journal, 401 ff. Miller, Geoffrey P. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1995), ‘Corporate Governance and Commercial Banking: A Comparative Examination of Germany, Japan and the United States, 1995, Stanford Law Review, 73 ff. Mitchell, Lawrence E. (1992), ‘A Theoretical and Practical Framework for Enforcing Corporate Constituency Statutes’, 70 Texas Law Review, 579-644. Mofsky, James and Rubin, Robert D. (1983), ‘Introduction: A Symposium on the ALI Corporate Governance Project’, 97 University of Miami Law Review, 169-185. Moore, Andrew G.T., II (1994), ‘Shareholder Rights Still Alive and Well in Delaware: The Derivative Suit: A Death Greatly Exaggerated’, 38 Saint Louis University Law Journal, 947-965. Murdock, Charles W. (1990), ‘The Evolution of Effective Remedies for Minority Shareholders and Its Impact upon Valuation of Minority Shares’, 65 Notre Dame Law Review, 425-489. Murphy, Kevin J. (1985), ‘Corporate Performance and Managerial Renumeration: An Empirical Analysis’, 11 Journal of Accounting and Economics, 11-42. Newcomb, R. Link (1987), ‘The Limitation of Directory Liability: A Proposal for Legislative Reform’, 66 Texas Law Review, 411-452. O’Connor, Marleen A. (1993), ‘How Should we Talk about Fiduciary Duty? Director’s Conflict-of-Interest Transactions and the ALI’s Principles of Corporate Governance’, 61 George Washington Law Review, 954-983. Olivella, O. (1990), ‘Una Introducción a la Delegación como Mecanismo de Compromiso (An Introduction to Delegation as a Commitment Device)’, 7(2) Economía Pública, 37-52. Olivella, O. (1995), ‘Information Structures and the Delegation of Monitoring’, 39 Annales d’Économie et de Statistique, 1-32. Painter, Richard W. (1994), ‘The Moral Interdependence of Corporate Lawyers and Their Clients’, 67 Southern California Law Review, 507-584. Palmiter, Alan R. (1989), ‘Reshaping the Corporate Fiduciary Model: A Director’s Duty of
5630
The Separation of Ownership and Control
721
Independence’, 67 Texas Law Review, 1351-1464. Portellano, Pedro (1996), Deber de Fidelidad de los Administradores de Sociedades Mercantiles y Oportunidades de Negocio (Fidelity Commitment of Corporation Managers and Bussiness Oportunities), Madrid, Editorial Cívitas. Porter, Philip K. and Scully, Gerald W. (1987), ‘Economic Efficiency in Cooperatives’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 489-512. Posner, Richard A. (1976), ‘The Rights of Creditors of Affiliated Corporations’, 43 University of Chicago Law Review, 499-526. Pound, John (1989), ‘Shareholder Activism and Share Values: The Causes and Consequences of Countersolicitations against Management Antitakeover Proposals’, 32 Journal of Law and Economics, 357-379. Preite, Disiano (1988), La Destinazione dei Risultati nei Contratti Associativi (The Destination of the Results in Partnership Contracts), Milano, Giuffrè, 456 p. Radner, Roy (1974), ‘A Note of Unanimity of Stockholders’ Preferences among Alternative Production Plans a Reformulation of the Ekern-Wilson Model’, 5 Bell Journal of Economics, 181-184. Repetti, James R. (1992), ‘Corporate Governance and Stockholder Abdication: Missing Factors in Tax Policy Analysis’, 67 Notre Dame Law Review, 971-1035. Ribstein, Larry E. (1989), ‘Takeover Defenses and the Corporate Contract’, 78 Georgetown Law Journal, 17 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. (1992a), ‘Corporate Political Speech’, 49 Washington and Lee Law Review, 109 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. (1992b), ‘Efficiency, Regulation and Competition: A Comment on Easterbrook and Fischel’, 87 Northwestern University Law Review, 254 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. (1993), ‘The Mandatory Rules of the ALI Code’, 61 George Washington Law Review, 984 ff. Roe, Mark J. (1991), ‘A Political Theory of American Corporate Finance’, 91 Columbia Law Review, 10-67. Romano, Roberta (1985), ‘Law as a Product: Some Pieces of the Incorporation Puzzle’, 1 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 225-283. Romano, Roberta (1991), ‘The Shareholder Suit: Litigation without Foundation?’, 7 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 55-87. Romano, Roberta (1992), ‘A Guide to Takeovers: Theory, Evidence and Regulation’, 9 Yale Journal of Regulation, 119 ff. Romano, Roberta (1993), ‘Public Pension Fund Activism in Corporate Governance Reconsidered’, 93 Columbia Law Review, 795 ff. Romano, Roberta (1994), The Genius of American Corporate Law, Washington, DC, The AEI Press. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1991), ‘Risk Taking and Ruin: Bankruptcy and Investment Choice’, 20 Journal of Legal Studies, 277-310. Ross, Stephen A. (1977), ‘The Determination of Financial Structure: the Incentive-Signalling Approach’, 8 Bell Journal of Economics, 23-40. Ross, Stephen A. et al. (1993), Corporate Finance, Irwin/McGraw-Hill Series in Finance, Insurance, and Real Estate, Homewood/New York, Irwin/McGraw. Ruder, David S. (1983), ‘Protections for Corporate Shareholders: Are Major Revisions Needed?’, 37 University of Miami Law Review, 243 ff. Ryan, Patrick J. (1991), ‘Strange Bedfellows: Corporate Fiduciaries and the General Law Compliance
722
The Separation of Ownership and Control
5630
Obligation in Section 2.01(a) of the American Law Institute’s Principle of Corporate Governance’, 66 Washington Law Review, 413-502. Sadat-Keeling, Leila (1984), ‘The 1983 Amendments to Shareholder Proposal Rule 14A-8: A Retreat from Corporate Democracy?’, 59 Tulane Law Review, 161-198. Schleifer, A. and Vishny, Robert W. (1996), A Survey of Corporate Governance, NBER, 5554 Working Paper. Schott, Kenneth E. (1983), ‘Corporation Law and the American Law Institute Corporate Governance Project’, 35 Stanford Law Review, 927-948. Schwartz, Alan (1985), ‘Products Liability, Corporate Structure, and Bankruptcy: Toxic Substances and the Remote Risk Relationship’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 689-736. Schwartz, Alan (1988), ‘The Sole Owner Standard Reviewed’, 17 Journal of Legal Studies, 231-235. Schwartz, Donald E. (1984), ‘Federalism and Corporate Governance’, 45 Ohio State Law Journal, 545-590. Seligman, Joel Stock (1986), ‘Equal Protection in Shareholder Voting Rights: The One Common Share, One Vote Controversy’, 54 George Washington Law Review, 687 ff. Shavell Steven (1982), ‘The Social Versus the Private Incentive to Bring Suit in a Costly Legal System’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 333 ff. Shleifer, Andrei and Vishny, Robert W. (1986), ‘Large Shareholders and Corporate Control’, 94 Journal of Political Economy, 461-488. Shleifer, Andrei and Vishny, Robert W. (1986b), ‘Greenmail, White Knights, and Shareholders’ Interest’, 17 Rand Journal of Economics, 293-309. Sidak, J. Gregory and Woodward, Susan (1991), ‘Takeover Premiums, Appraisal Rights, and the Price Elasticity of a Firm’s Publicly Traded Stock’, 25 Georgia Law Review, 783 ff. Slagter, Wiek J. (1988), Macht en Onmacht van de Aandeelhouder (Shareholders Lack of Power), Deventer, Kluwer, 47 ff. Slagter, Wiek J. (1989), Schaarse Rechten. Afscheidscollege Rotterdam (Scarce Rights), Deventer, Kluwer, 42 ff. Smart, Christopher J. (1988), ‘Takeover Dangers and Non-Shareholders: Who Should be our Brothers’ Keeper?’, Columbia Business Law Review, 301-339. Smith, Adam (1776), The Wealth of Nations. Smith, Gordon G. (1996), ‘Corporate Governance and Managerial Incompetence: Lessons From Kmart’, 14 North Carolina Law Review, 1037 ff. Ståhl, Ingemar (1976), ‘Ígande och Makt i Féretagen - en Debattinledning, Nationalek Onomiska Féreningens Férhandlingar (Ownership and Power in the Firms - An Introduction to Debate, the Economics Association’s Negotiations)’, 1 Ekonomisk Debatt. Stano, Miron (1976), ‘Monopoly Power, Ownership Control, and Corporate Performance’, 7 Bell Journal of Economics, 672-679. Stano, Miron (1978), ‘Executive Ownership Interests and Corporate Performance’, 42 Southern Economic Journal, 272-278. Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1989), ‘Principal and Agent’, in Eatwell, John, Milgate, Murray and Newman, Peter (eds.) (1989), The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, London, MacMillan . Stout, Lynn A. (1988), ‘The Unimportance of Being Efficient: An Economic Analysis of Stock Market Pricing and Securities Regulation’, 87 Michigan Law Review, 613-709. Summers (1980), ‘Worker Participation in the U.S. and West Germany: A Comparative Study from
5630
The Separation of Ownership and Control
723
an American Perspective’, 28 American Journal of Comparative Law, 367 ff. Triantis, Alexander J. and George G. (1994), ‘Conversion Rights and the Design of Financial Contracts’, 72 Washington University Law Quarterly, 1231-1255. Triantis, George G. (1992), ‘Secured Debt under Conditions of Imperfect Information’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 225-258. Triantis, George G. (1993), ‘A Theory of the Regulation of Debtor-in-Possession Financing’, 46 Vanderbilt Law Review, 901-935. Triantis, George G. (1994), ‘A Free-Cash-Flow Theory of Secured Debt and Creditor Priorities’, 80 Virginia Law Review, 2155-2168. Triantis, George G. (1995), ‘Debt Financing, Corporate Decision Making and Security Design’, 26 Canadian Business Journal, 93-105. Triantis, George G. (1996), ‘The Interplay between Liquidation and Reorganization in Bankruptcy: The role of Screens, Gatekeepers and Guillotines’, 16 International Review of Law and Economics, 101-119. Triantis, George G. and Daniels, Ronald J. (1995), ‘The Role of Debt in Interactive Corporate Governance’, 83 California Law Review, 1073-1113. Turnbull, Shann (1997), Evolution of Business and the Corporate Structure, Corporate Directors’ Diploma Course, University of New England, Armidale, Australia, Topic 1.1. Utset, Manuel (1995), ‘Towards a Bargaining Theory of the Firm’, 80 Cornell Law Review, 540 ff. Vanecko, Robert G. (1992), ‘Regulations 14A and 13D and the Role of Institutional Investors in Corporate Governance’, 87 Northwestern Law Review, 376-421. Watts, Ross L. and Zimmerman, Jerold L. (1983), ‘Agency Problems, Auditing, and the Theory of the Firm: Some Evidence’, 26 Journal of Law and Economics, 613-633. Weisbach, Michael S. (1988), ‘Outside Directors and CEO Turnover’, 20 Journal of Financial Economics, 431 ff. Weiss, Elliott J. and White, Lawrence J. (1987), ‘Of Econometrics and Indeterminacy: A Study of Investors’ Reactions to ‘Changes’ in Corporate Law’, 75 California Law Review, 551-607. Williamson, Oliver E. (1963), ‘Managerial Discretion and Business Behaviour’, 53 American Economic Review, 1032-1057. Williamson, Oliver E. (1976), ‘The Economics of Internal Organization: Exit and Voice in Relation to Markets and Hierarchies’, 66 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 369-377. Williamson, Oliver E. (1979), ‘Transaction-Cost Economics: The Governance of Contractual Relations’, 22 Journal of Law and Economics, 233-261. Williamson, Oliver E. (1983), ‘Organization Form, Residual Claimants, and Corporate Control’, 26 Journal of Law and Economics, 351-366. Williamson, Oliver E. (1984), ‘Corporate Governance’, 93 Yale Law Journal, 1197-1230. Winter, Ralph A. (1981), ‘Majority Choice and the Objective Function of the Firm under Uncertainty: Note’, 12 Bell Journal of Economics, 335-337. Winter, Ralph K., Jr (1977), ‘State Law, Shareholder Protection, and the Theory of the Corporation’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 251-292. Winter, Ralph K., Jr (1988), ‘On Protecting The Ordinary Investor’, 63 Washington Law Review, 881-902. X. (1996), ‘Symposium: The Intersection of Tort and Criminal Law’, 76 Boston University Law
724
The Separation of Ownership and Control
5630
Review. Yablon, Charles M. (1992), ‘Book Review of The Corporate Lawyer and Executive Pay: In Search of Excess, by Graef Crystal’, 92 Columbia Law Review, 1867-1906. Zalecki, Paul H. (1993), ‘The Corporate Governance Roles of the Inside and Outside Directors’, 24 University of Toledo Law Review.
5640 THE MARKET FOR CORPORATE CONTROL (INCLUDING TAKEOVERS) George Bittlingmayer Professor of Management Graduate School of Management University of California, Davis © Copyright 1999 George Bittlingmayer
Abstract Mergers, acquisitions and takeovers often imply dramatic changes for employees, competitors, customers and suppliers. Not surprisingly, the market for corporate control has generated controversy and is frequently regulated by law or business custom. Though transfers of control take place in many countries, explicit and public struggles for control occur most frequently in the US and UK. During most of the twentieth century, critics of mergers and acquisitions in the US pointed to the danger of monopoly and increased concentration. Partly in response to the emergence of new control transactions such as the hostile takeover and leveraged buyout, more recent criticism has focused on the consequences for corporate productivity, profitability and employee welfare. Subject to qualifications, the market for corporate control reallocates productive assets - in the form of going concerns - to the highest bidder. In cases where the bidder uses his own money or acts on behalf of the bidding firm’s shareholders, the asset goes to the highest value use. In cases where managers of the bidding firm are able to serve their own interests rather than the interests of shareholders, the market for corporate control plays a paradoxical role. It simultaneously provides (1) a means by which managers may acquire companies using other people’s money and (2) a means by which they may themselves be disciplined or displaced. JEL classification: G3, K2, L2, L4, L5 Keywords: Corporate Control, Mergers, Acquisitions, Takeovers, Securities Regulation, Antitrust, Corporate Law
1. Introduction The shareholders of the modern, publicly held corporation buy and sell their shares freely, though ordinarily in small quantities and without major consequence for the corporation itself. Occasionally, a new owner - typically
725
726
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
5640
another firm - will acquire a large fraction of a corporation’s shares, elect a new board of directors, replace or absorb its top management, and alter its methods of doing business. Consequently, when a substantial fraction of shares does change hands - through a negotiated acquisition, market purchase or tender offer - the new owner often expects to gain. What the acquirer expects to gain and what the acquirer actually receives have been the subject of a long-standing, lively and often acrimonious debate. During most of the twentieth century, merger, acquisition and the control of corporations in the United States were intimately related with the twin problems of monopoly and the concentration of economic power. The acquisition of a substantial stake in a corporation by another entity - whether another corporation, a bank or other financial intermediary - appeared to pose a threat to some part of the non-corporate sector, typically small business, labor or consumers. By mid-century, corporate control and the transfer of that control began to raise other policy issues besides the threat of corporate power. Academic attention, for example, turned to possible strategic or financial objectives in mergers and acquisitions, or to managers’ hunger for more turf. This shift came about partly because stricter antitrust laws had ruled out traditional monopoly explanations. In addition, the merger waves of the 1960s and the 1980s witnessed the emergence of hostile tender offers, new and controversial forms of debt financing, and new control transactions such as the leveraged buyout. Frequently, the acquisitions wrought dramatic and far-reaching changes in the marketplace and in the lives of employees. Acquired firms, even in cases involving hostile takeovers, came increasingly from the ranks of America’s largest corporations. Scholarly discussion and public debate covered a wide territory, but focused in large part on mergers and takeovers as a solution to mismanagement. In fact, the widespread restructuring that followed many acquisitions, leveraged buyouts and other transactions helped in large measure to rekindle interest in the problems raised by the ‘separation of ownership and control’. Subsidiary questions concerned the effects of changes in state and federal takeover policy; the degree to which stock prices represented the underlying asset value of takeover targets; and the effects of takeovers and mergers on wages, investment, and research and development. The transfer of corporate control in other developed countries, in particular Western Europe and the Far East, has been less dramatic and less controversial than in the United States. One might argue that these other countries do not need an active market for corporate control. Large financial intermediaries, in particular banks, monitor corporate performance more closely and exert a greater influence than they do in the US, in particular when a corporation gets into trouble. Major financial institutions may also see their own interests better
5640
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
727
served by continuity. The impact of the state on mergers, though still powerful, has been more subtle than in the US, perhaps reflecting a lower level of concern with monopoly and the concentration of business. Finally, business in other developed countries makes less intensive use of the stock market as a source of finance than do American corporations, further limiting the scope for a market for corporate control. So, while the control of corporations and the transfer of control is a worldwide phenomenon, the use of explicit, market-based mechanisms is most advanced and most conspicuous in the United States.
2. Types of Control Transactions An acquirer can gain of control of a large fraction of a corporation’s shares using the following methods, either singly or in combination. Open Market Purchase. This involves purchase of shares on an exchange. In the absence of any regulation, an acquirer will take pains to conceal his intentions and purchase as many shares as possible before the news leaks out. Since 1934, American law has required the disclosure of 10 percent ownership, and with the passage of the 1970 Amendment to the Williams Act, 5 percent ownership. This regulation effectively forces an acquirer to show his hand. Even without regulation, the attempt to gain control of a corporation without arousing suspicion and without increasing the stock price of the target firm is likely to prove difficult. Block Purchase. A shareholder may purchase a large block of shares in a negotiated acquisition. Large blocks, especially those that confer the right to elect the board, typically trade at a premium to small blocks sold on an exchange, presumably because of the value of control. Tender Offer. A potential acquirer may issue a tender offer - promising to pay a fixed amount per share for shares submitted by stockholders, subject to specified conditions. This price is typically greater than the market price. A tender offer may be made for only some fraction of the shares outstanding, it is likely to expire at some point, and the actual transaction may be made contingent on a minimum number of shares being tendered. The terms may be for cash or securities, and the offer may be made with or without the consent of the target management and board. If management is opposed, and especially if it offers active resistance, the offer is viewed as ‘hostile’. An acquirer will often first buy a relatively cheap ‘toe-hold’ on the open market and then follow up with a tender offer. In the US, tender offers are subject to federal securities laws. Negotiated Purchase. Often, the acquirer deals directly with the management and board of the target firm and negotiates the terms of an acquisition. This method usually involves the transfer of all outstanding shares of the target, for
728
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
5640
either cash or securities. It may also involve other terms, such as employment contracts for the management of the acquired firm, provision for a ‘break-up fee’ if the company to be acquired backs out, or so-called lock-up agreements conferring on the acquirer the right to purchase shares. The transfer of control over shares is typically but one step in a longer negotiated transaction that includes the ultimate formal absorption of the acquired firm through merger. Proxy Contest. Typically, shareholders of a publicly held corporation may delegate their vote. Small shareholders and institutions who do not wish to take an active role typically delegate their vote to management. (In some countries the proxies of small shareholders may be held by a large bank, with the bank itself being a substantial shareholder.) A group of dissident shareholders may stage a proxy contest, by which the group solicits proxies from other shareholders. With sufficient votes, such a group is able to change the composition of the board and ultimately effectuate changes in the management of the corporation. A group of insurgent shareholders will typically hold a fraction of outstanding shares in order to certify their seriousness and to capitalize on any gain in share value from a successful effort. In American practice, the acquirer is usually another publicly-held firm, and the transaction results in the merger of two publicly-held firms. Increasingly, however, acquirers take minority positions for longer periods of time. Partial acquisitions without any immediate plans for merger have had a longer tradition in Europe. Recent American practice has also seen the rise of leveraged buyouts (LBOs) and management buyouts (MBOs). In a leveraged buyout, a private firm uses borrowed funds to make a tender offer that - if successful - would give the acquirer sufficient votes to ‘take the firm private’. The acquirer is then free to effectuate changes in the board and management, or require that top managers increase their equity stake. A management buyout typically involves the same substitution of debt for widely held public equity as an LBO, but the transaction takes place at the initiative of management, and management takes on a large stake in the remaining equity of the private firm. Finally, corporations often repurchase their own shares on the open market or by means of a tender offer or block purchase, with the intention of influencing the balance of control (Gilson, 1986, Part III; Brudney and Chirelstein, 1987, Part IV; Weston, Kwang and Hoag, 1990, chs. 18-19).
3. Explanations for Mergers and Acquisitions The transfer of control through merger and acquisition emerged at the end of the nineteenth century and is linked, at least in time and quite likely in substance, with the development of the modern corporation. Early American
5640
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
729
economists regarded the growth of firms such as Standard Oil, US Steel and DuPont through merger as largely natural and efficiency-enhancing. The emergence through merger of large industrial firms in the UK and continental Europe generated largely similar reactions. Subsequent generations of economists, in particular in the US, came to view merger largely in terms of monopoly, perhaps because the development of economic theory seemed to leave little choice. For a good deal of the twentieth century, economic explanations for merger focused on the interaction of monopoly and scale economies, with scale economies playing a paradoxical role. If scale economies did not exist, that is, if a single large firm could not produce more cheaply than two or more smaller ones, then the motive for a merger of two firms in the same or related line of business could only be monopoly. If scale economies did exist and a larger firm was more efficient, then the large firm would take over the whole business and set its price above marginal cost but below the level that would lead to significant entry. Either way, the acquisition of one firm by another was linked with monopoly. Stigler’s (1950) influential analysis of ‘Oligopoly and Monopoly by Merger’ appealed to the ‘survivor principle’ to argue that economies of scale were unimportant. He explained the emergence of large firms at the turn of the century and again in the 1920s as grabs for monopoly power facilitated by the growth of the stock market, which allowed firms to capitalize monopoly rents. It is worth noting that the textbook models of competition and monopoly both assume a unitary, profit-maximizing firm. Those models have little to say about the mechanisms by which a group of individuals control a corporation, how the effectiveness of that control varies according to the concentration of stockholdings and the identity of stockholders, or how optimal control mechanisms might vary by type of business or over the life-cycle of the business. Regardless of the intellectual origins, the concern with possible monopoly motives and monopoly effects of mergers and acquisitions ultimately moved beyond horizontal mergers (involving firms making identical products or very close substitutes) to vertical mergers (involving merger of successive levels of production, such as cement and concrete) and even to conglomerate mergers (involving mergers of firms in unrelated businesses). However, the arguments and evidence supporting a monopoly explanation were particularly weak in the last case. Beginning in the 1960s, the economic literature turned to a number of other, non-monopoly explanations. These new explanations struck one of several broad themes. Acquisitions may allow the implementation of managerial knowledge across businesses; they may allow firms to implement strategic goals; they may promote financial synergies such as diversification or the use of increased leverage; they may allow managers to indulge their appetites for more control using other people’s money; and, paradoxically, they may be the mechanism by which new owners can impose much-needed
730
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
5640
discipline on managers. The last explanation gained more and more adherents during the 1980s, when an increasing number of mergers were financed by debt and resulted in a leveraging up of the corporate sector. According to Jensen’s (1986) ‘free cash-flow’ theory, companies with excess cash are likely to undertake negative net present value projects. For example, oil companies flush with cash from high oil prices may drill negative net present value oil wells and engage in dubious diversification efforts instead of returning cash to shareholders. An acquisition financed with debt forces the new management to generate cash and reject dubious projects. According to oral tradition, the ‘free cash-flow’ explanation originated with the colorful 1980s takeover king, T. Boone Pickens. Gilson (1986, Part II), Scherer and Ross (1990, pp. 159-167), Weston, Kwang and Hoag (1990, ch. 10), and Carlton and Perloff (1994, pp. 36-40) offer surveys of possible explanations for mergers and acquisitions.
4. Manne and Corporate Control Though control transactions have a long history in fact and in law, the academic literature on the ‘market for corporate control’ and indeed the term itself begin with Henry Manne (1965). His analysis focused on control transactions that would address the problem of poor management, and he introduced a number of enduring themes. He viewed the competition for corporate control as encompassing (1) proxy fights, (2) direct purchase of shares and (3) merger. Manne also argued that control of the corporation was a valuable asset, he suggested that many mergers took place because the bidder valued that asset, and he advanced the idea of a ‘positive correlation between corporate managerial efficiency and the market price of shares’ (Manne, 1965, p. 112). He also viewed proxy fights as needlessly cumbersome and expensive, a conclusion shared by much subsequent commentary. Direct purchase of shares (open market purchases, block purchases, and tender offers) and merger differ in one important respect. Direct purchase does not require approval of the target management. In a merger that requires board approval, management would typically demand some compensation for its consent to be displaced. ‘When we find incumbents recommending a control change, it is generally safe to assume that some side payment is occurring’ (Manne, 1965, p. 118). He also observed that firms in the same industry are likely to be well situated to discover mismanagement and act on that knowledge by proposing merger, thus weakening the case for the stringent horizontal merger policy practiced in the 1960s. Consistent with Manne’s original approach, the subsequent literature has included negotiated merger among the panoply of control transactions that includes open market purchases, tender offers and control block purchases.
5640
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
731
Doing so recognizes that many mergers take place under the threat of takeover or because the merger itself amounts to a takeover with side payments to secure the cooperation of target management. Though control of managers has become an important theme in discussions of the market for corporate control, it bears emphasis that other mechanisms exist that also promote efficient operation of a corporation. Jensen and Meckling (1976) argue that managers act as agents of shareholders and that shareholders have an incentive to use resources efficiently to monitor managers. In common with the textbook model of the profit-maximizing firm, their model views shareholders as unitary agents and neglects the issue of incentives in the case of widely held corporations. As Manne himself observed, ‘the separation of ownership and control’ deals with the problem faced by diffuse ownership. ‘So long as we are unable to discern any control relationship between small shareholders and corporate management, the thrust of Berle and Means’s famous phrase remains strong’ (Manne, 1965, p. 112). Even in the case of the diffusely held corporation, however, various influences tend to promote efficient management. Competition in product markets imposes discipline on management because inefficiency may lead to the ultimate demise of a firm. State law allows shareholders to vote for directors, and these in turn are responsible for the appointment and dismissal of top management. States with corporate laws that encourage or allow inefficient management will not get their share of new incorporations. The job market for managers will penalize those who do not perform well. Finally, managers may own a large fraction of outstanding shares, which will tend to align their interests with those of shareholders. Clearly, none of these and other possible forces is perfect. The workings of competition in the product market may be slow; shareholders may not have the incentives or abilities to assess corporate performance and the need for a new board of directors; states will still be able to retain and compete for established corporations that management controls by means of relatively small ownership stakes; entrenched top management may not care about moving to another job; and large shareholdings are the exception rather than the rule. Even jointly, then, these other disciplinary mechanisms may fail to protect shareholders.
5. Overview of Regulation A variety of laws affect mergers and the market for corporate control. These include the law of corporations, antitrust policy and securities regulation. In the United States, corporate law is largely a creature of the individual states. About half of all large, publicly-held corporations choose Delaware, a small, east-coast state, and the remainder tend to gravitate toward large states such as New York,
732
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
5640
California, Illinois and Pennsylvania. The states compete to grant corporate charters and to attract the fees and legal business that comes with them. Indeed, critics charge that this competition is a ‘race to the bottom’, with the states offering insufficient protection to shareholders and overly generous protection to managers. The influence of state corporate law on corporate control runs deep. State law affects the voting rights of shareholders, the duties of corporate directors, and the defensive tactics available to target management, for example. This influence over the mechanics of control ultimately affects the value of control. In contrast to state law, the influence of American federal law is less direct, though perhaps no less important. Early federal law focused on antitrust, which limited mergers, acquisitions, cross-holdings of stock and interlocking directorates. The federal role increased dramatically with the 1934 Securities Exchange Act, and with subsequent legislation, notably the 1968 Williams Act, which imposed disclosure requirements on acquisitions above threshold levels and restricted the terms of a tender offer. Federal securities law also governs proxy fights and communication among shareholders. Finally, Federal law restricts the stock holdings of banks, mutual funds and other financial intermediaries, with subtle but arguably powerful consequences for corporate control. In the late 1980s, the regulatory initiative passed back to the individual states, which passed antitakeover legislation when the federal government did little to restrict a wave of takeovers. In contrast to early state initiatives to control the takeover process, the courts gave their approval. Indeed, this last development illustrates one of the recurrent themes in the American approach to corporate control, namely regulatory competition between the federal government, the judiciary and the states (particularly Delaware). The other constant theme in America is the hostility toward concentrated power (Roe, 1994; Romano, 1987; Pound, 1992b, 1993).
6. Early Corporation Policies and Their Effects The federal government may interfere with the transfer of control on various grounds. Chief among these is alleged monopoly, which has played an important role since 1890, when the modern corporation was in its infancy. The original trusts enabled a trustee to hold and control shares of several corporations, thus facilitating coordinated operation of several nominally independent enterprises. The device was pioneered by Standard Oil in 1882 but other groups of firms soon adopted the form. More broadly, a variety of related cooperative forms, also called ‘trusts’, emerged over the following two decades.
5640
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
733
These included cartels, pools, holding companies, ‘communities of interest’ (later termed ‘interlocking directorates’) and merged firms. The chief chartering states (notably New Jersey and Delaware) shaped and accelerated this development by allowing corporations to buy each other’s stock and by permitting merger. Both measures facilitated the conversion of possibly illegal ‘trusts’ into statutorily sanctioned forms. In contrast, populist states and the federal government responded to the widespread cartelization with ‘anti-trust’ statutes, in particular the 1890 Sherman Antitrust Act. It bears emphasis that most commentary at the time regarded the various trust forms as different manifestations of the same underlying phenomenon - a single ‘trust and corporation problem’. According to early Supreme Court interpretation, notably E.C. Knight (1895), the new antitrust law applied only to cartels. Cartels implied an agreement to restrain interstate trade. Acquisition and merger, in contrast, involved the purchase and sale of corporate shares created under state law and no agreement to restrain trade. This odd legal situation - cartels always illegal, merger always OK - laid the basis for the Great Merger Wave of 1898-1902, including the formation or growth through merger of firms such as US Steel, DuPont and American Tobacco, as well as the conversion of the Standard Oil Trust into a holding company. Some very dramatic takeover struggles took place in that era, notably the fight between railroad magnates Hill and Harriman for control of the Northern Pacific in 1901. The aims and effects of these early innovations in corporate control - the classic trusts and the holding companies and merged firms that replaced them - were controversial at the time and have remained controversial to the present day. Modern business historians, notably Chandler (1977), view the early acquisitions and mergers as part of the process by which ‘the visible hand’ of management was substituted for the invisible hand of arms-length market agreements, allowing greater efficiency in management. Modern legal historians have tended to view the cartels as, at best, mixed blessings (Hovenkamp, 1991; Freyer, 1992). Economists since mid-century have followed Stigler’s (1950) analysis - discussed above - which emphasized the formation of monopolies through merger. Scherer and Ross (1990, ch. 5), who share this view, provide a representative treatment from the perspective of the late twentieth century. One approach, which was popular early on only to be rejected in favor of the monopoly view, has recently experienced a revival. Early economists defended both the cartels and the mergers that often replaced them as efficient responses to the problems posed by high fixed costs, in particular the danger of ‘cutthroat competition’. In more recent work, Bittlingmayer (1982, 1983, 1985) and Telser (1987, ch. 2) rely on the theory of cooperative games, in particular the theory of the core, to explain the widespread use of cooperative forms including merger in many industries marked by high fixed costs and fluctuating demand.
734
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
5640
On this view, a competitive equilibrium is not possible with an ‘empty core’, leaving cartelization, tacit collusion, merger or single-firm monopolization as the only alternatives. This squares the circle, explaining how the early ‘trusts’ could have been both collusive and more efficient than the businesses they replaced. On all three views of the late nineteenth- and early twentieth-century mergers - managerial, monopoly and empty core - the market for control provided a mechanism by which previously independent units achieved coordinated action. The managerial view also allows the possibility that merger facilitated the transfer of new, more efficient managerial methods and comes closest to embodying modern notions about the function of the market for corporate control.
7. The Emergence of Merger and Corporate Control as Policy Issues Effective federal intervention in mergers and acquisitions began with President Theodore Roosevelt’s celebrated ‘trust-busting’. In response to the Great Merger Wave, 1898-1902, Roosevelt filed Northern Securities (1904), a case that originated in the battle for control of the Northern Pacific. His intention was to force a revision of merger policy. In a 5-4 decision, the Supreme Court reversed itself and placed merger under direct federal control. At the same time, Roosevelt established the Bureau of Corporations (the Federal Trade Commission’s predecessor) and the Antitrust Division of the Department of Justice. After a brief lull, Roosevelt used the government’s new powers under the Sherman Act in late 1906 and 1907 in an aggressive effort to divest some of the most notorious ‘trusts’, including John D. Rockefeller’s Standard Oil, American Tobacco and DuPont. These attacks were controversial and potentially immense if carried to their logical conclusion, since thorough ‘trust-busting’ would have meant a costly and protracted dismemberment of perhaps half of US industry. Indeed, public commentary at the time blamed Roosevelt’s ‘trust-busting’ for the Panic of 1907, which was marked by a remarkably steep decline in stock prices and output. A similar discussion flared up during the less dramatic bear market and recession that surrounded President William Howard Taft’s (1909-1913) attempt to break up US Steel. Though historians of the Progressive Era are aware of this controversy, economists have largely ignored it. Bittlingmayer (1993, 1996) has recently offered new supporting evidence, in particular a negative correlation between antitrust enforcement and changes in stock prices and output. Despite sporadic and controversial successes and continued anti-big-business rhetoric, the federal government eventually abandoned the aim of divesting the large corporations formed in the 1898-1902 merger wave. Arguably, attempts to do so had proven too costly. However, big business and
5640
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
735
in particular bank control of big business remained unpopular, and political attention turned to the later topic. The Pujo ‘Money Trust Investigations’ of 1912 drove banks off the boards of directors, thus undermining the role of banks as monitors of corporate performance (Roe, 1994, pp. 33-35). In recent work, Cantillo (1996) reports that the forced departure of banks from corporate boards depressed stock values of the affected corporations. Arguably, the erosion of bank power over corporations set the stage for management self-dealing and the emergence of alternative methods of disciplining management. The political controversy surrounding the corporation was suppressed during the First World War and, after a brief flurry of anti-business sentiment following the war, suppressed again during the 1920s. The administration of President Calvin Coolidge (1923-1929) deliberately attempted to scale back enforcement of the antitrust laws, especially the laws against merger. In an echo of experience at the turn of the century, this period of extraordinarily lax merger enforcement again coincided with a large wave of mergers. General Motors, Curtiss-Wright, General Mills and many other companies grew substantially during this period. The high-growth and new technology industries of the era - automobiles, aviation, food processing, radio, motion pictures and electric utilities - experienced particularly extensive consolidation through acquisition and merger. Corporate growth and the booming stock market of the 1920s also contributed to the growth of the modern managerial firm, that is, a large firm owned by many small shareholders but run by professional managers. It was precisely this emerging ‘separation of ownership and control’ that Berle and Means (1932) criticized only a few years later in their classic, The Modern Corporation and Private Property. The 1920s merger wave ended after the October 1929 stock crash. Perhaps the crash and 1930 recession ended the merger wave. This would be consistent with the view that merger waves are speculative phenomena or that merger waves are caused by business booms. Alternatively, and of some importance for our assessment of merger and takeover activity, and of the effects of swings in government policy, the boom and crash may have reflected swings in merger and antitrust policy under Presidents Coolidge (1923-1929) and Herbert Hoover (1929-1933). Coolidge’s administration, which was widely regarded as being aggressively ‘pro-business’, filed very few merger cases and almost none against mergers involving publicly traded firms. Outside observers, among them America’s leading economist at the time, Irving Fisher, regarded Hoover as simply continuing a policy favorable toward merger. This was a plausible inference in part because Hoover had been Coolidge’s Secretary of Commerce. However, it has only recently come to light that Hoover in fact viewed the merger wave with suspicion, and that Hoover’s attorney general announced a radical shift in antitrust policy in the middle of the October 1929 crash. The Hoover administration soon implemented a more restrictive policy, that
736
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
5640
included a resumption of merger case filings (Bittlingmayer, 1993). Experience in 1929 is consistent with the evidence from the Panic of 1907, and with the October 1987 crash, discussed below.
8. The New Deal and its Aftermath The presidency of Franklin Delano Roosevelt (1933-1945) left its mark on regulations affecting the market for corporate control, as it did on many other areas of economic life. However, most of the New Deal’s explicit legal and regulatory changes affected the market for control indirectly - by requiring disclosure of stock ownership, placing restrictions on proxy contests (originally a matter of state law only), and by restricting the stockholdings of financial intermediaries. Especially at the end of the 1930s, political attention turned again to the ownership and control of business. Though New Deal legislation contained few specific provisions dealing with the market for corporate control, the potential for federal intervention increased sharply. For example, the single most important piece of federal takeover legislation, the Williams Act, discussed below, was passed in 1968. It was an amendment to the 1934 Securities Exchange Act. Ultimately, the potential influence of federal legislation was also felt at the state level, because key states of incorporation, such as Delaware, defended their positions against federal encroachment. The danger to them stemmed from latent Securities and Exchange Commission powers under 1930s legislation, and from the possibility that Congress might extend that legislation. Other legislation from the New Deal had more direct effects on stock ownership. For example, the 1940 Investment Company Act, which was drafted by the newly founded Securities and Exchange Commission at the direction of Congress, limits mutual fund holdings of stock (Roe, 1994, p. 103). The connection between corporate control and the monopoly problem surfaced again after the Second World War. Based on a relatively small merger wave, and a concern about a ‘rising tide of concentration’, Congress passed the 1950 Celler-Kefauver Amendment to the Clayton Act, thus closing the so-called asset loophole. The 1914 Clayton Act had prohibited anticompetitive acquisitions of stock, but left acquisitions of asset untouched. As a consequence of the new law, and new Supreme Court interpretations in the late 1950s and 1960s, horizontal merger policy became very restrictive. Horizontal mergers involving market shares of as little as 5 and 10 percent were largely ruled out, and even vertical mergers came under attack. Conglomerate mergers - mergers of unrelated businesses - were not entirely immune because of ‘reciprocity’ and ‘potential competition’ theories, but did enjoy a relatively safe harbor.
5640
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
737
Not surprisingly, though mergers of all types continued to occur, the 1960s experienced an upsurge of conglomerate mergers. With hindsight many of these seem ill-advised. Why they occurred remains unclear. Antitrust policy favored them, but it did not compel them. Perhaps restrictions on the ownership of corporations by banks and other intermediaries and the development in state corporate law of the business judgment rule that gave wide discretion to managers and directors facilitated the formation of inefficient conglomerates. The origin of the conglomerates remains a riddle. The 1980s and 1990s wave of mergers, acquisitions and restructurings quite likely had their origins in changed state and federal policies. The Supreme Court declared restrictive state antitakeover laws unconstitutional in 1982, and the federal government reversed course under the Reagan administration and practiced a relatively permissive merger policy. In addition, the development of new forms of financing, notably high-yield ‘junk’ bonds, probably contributed to the increase in merger activity, though their emergence may have been as much an effect as a cause of the high level of restructuring. The consequences for American business were substantial. Table 1 shows that over half of a sample of large firms in existence in December 1981 became the targets of takeover attempts or themselves undertook defensive restructuring during the following eight years. These changes generated a political reaction that is not surprising in hindsight. The states enacted new antitakeover laws that passed muster at the Supreme Court. In a sequence of events reminiscent of the Panic of 1907 and the 1920s boom and crash, the US Congress briefly considered federal antitakeover legislation that is implicated as a precipitating factor in the October 1987 crash (Mitchell and Netter, 1989). On the other hand, the American political process has tolerated well into the 1990s a pace of mergers, acquisitions and restructuring that would have been unimaginable in earlier decades.
738
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
5640
Table 1 Frequency of takeover and restructuring over 1982-1989 for 1,064 large US firms in existence December 1981 Category Number Percentage Percentage of of firms of firms market value Friendly takeover target 286 26.9 13.6 Successful 268 25.2 13.0 Unsuccessful 18 1.7 0.6 Hostile takeover target 243 22.8 23.4 Successful 85 8.0 7.3 Unsuccessful 35 3.3 2.2 Unsuccessful followed by 87 8.1 7.0 friendly takeover Unsuccessful followed by 36 3.4 6.9 restructuring Defensive asset restructuring 78 7.3 11.8 Asset restructuring 64 6.0 9.0 Financial recapitalization 14 1.3 2.8 Remainder of sample 457 43.0 51.2 Total sample 1064 100.0 100.0 Source: Mitchell and Mulherin (1996, Table 2).
9. The Regulation of Takeovers The emergence of the unsolicited, often unfriendly and sometimes hostile takeover in the 1950s and its subsequent growth sparked various attempts at regulation. Though intensively studied, many aspects of takeover regulation remain controversial to the present day. Should acquirers be forced to disclose their holdings? Disclosure raises the cost of the shares purchased and may give target management warning and an opportunity to mount a defense. On the other hand, knowledge that a bidder is acquiring shares may allow target management to encourage an auction for the asset at stake, namely control of the corporation. Should tender offers be open for a fixed period of time? A long open period again allows target management to mobilize a defense, but it may also encourage others to enter the bidding. Should non-tendering shareholders have options other than forced sale at a price below the tender-offer price? Such a forced sale may compel shareholders to part with their shares for a price less than their valuation or the true value, but a price equal to or greater than the tender dilutes shareholder incentives to tender in the first place.
5640
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
739
9.1 Regulation of Takeovers by Exchanges Though not well known, US stock exchanges themselves placed limits on takeovers in the 1950s and sixties. The New York Stock Exchange required listed firms to keep open offers for their own and other firms’ shares at least ten, but preferably thirty, days, and tendered shares had to be taken up on a pro-rata rather than a first-come-first-serve basis (NYSE Company Manual, 1963, pp. A179-A180). The American Stock Exchange apparently had a similar informal policy (Fleischer and Mundheim, 1965, p. 330, n. 24). Such policies were limited in scope, however, because the NYSE and AMEX had no power over non-listed firms. 9.2 The Williams Act Passed in July 1968, the Williams Act stipulated that tendering shareholders had the right to withdrw their tendered shares during the first seven days, and after 60 days it required pro-rationing of tendered shares, and specified that increased offers applied retroactively to shares tendered in response to earlier offers. It also stipulated that acquirers that had bought 10 percent of outstanding shares on the open market disclose their acquisitions to the US Securities and Exchange Commission, though this added little to existing disclosure requirements. The 1970 Amendment lowered the disclosure requirement to 5 percent. Effects of the Williams Act A number of studies, among them Smiley (1975), Jarrell and Bradley (1980), Guerin-Calvert, McGuckin and Warren-Boulton (1987), and Asquith, Bruner and Mullins (1983) found that target firms experienced higher abnormal stock returns after passage of the Williams Act. Some of these early studies also investigated bidder returns and found that they were lower after passage of the act, suggesting that the legislation increased returns to target shareholders at the expense of bidding shareholders. Moreover, Schipper and Thompson (1983b) found that bidders who were engaged in merger programs experienced stock price declines with the passage of the Williams Act. Given the higher target premia and the lower bidder returns, the law arguably reduced the number of takeovers, though that proposition has not been tested. It is also unclear from this evidence whether the aggregate gains to all shareholders (all potential bidders and targets) were positive or negative. Other, more recent work even casts doubt on the conclusion that the Williams Act raised takeover premia and hindered the market for corporate control. Franks and Harris (1989) found that UK takeover premia also increased after 1968 in the absence of similar legislation. Nathan and O’Keefe (1989) place the increase in takeover premia at 1973-74, well after passage of the law.
740
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
5640
9.3 First-Generation State Takeover Laws The increased use of the hostile or unfriendly takeover had repercussions at the state level in the passage of so-called first-generation takeover statutes. Virginia led the way in 1968, the year Congress passed the Williams Act. By 1979, every state with a substantial share of corporate headquarters or a substantial share of incorporations had passed an antitakeover statute (Smiley, 1981). Romano (1985) documents the spread of these laws. The Illinois law, for example, prohibited acquisition of any firm with substantial assets in Illinois unless a state official approved. Jarrell and Bradley (1980) and Smiley (1981) found that these laws lowered takeover activity. However, the Illinois statute and with it most of the first-generation statutes were declared illegal in Edgar v. Mite 457 U.S. 624 (1982) because they interfered with interstate commerce. 9.4 Second-Generation State Takeover Legislation The states responded to Mite with statutes more narrowly focused on corporate law, the traditional prerogative of the states. Not surprisingly, states that were leaders in the adoption of first generation statutes were also more likely to adopt a second generation statute (Romano, 1987, p. 114). These laws fell into three categories. For example, Indiana passed a ‘control share acquisition’ statute stipulating that the shares of acquirer cannot be voted without the authorization of the target’s board of directors or shareholders not affiliated with the bidder. A second set of states, following Maryland’s lead, passed ‘fair-price’ provisions that stipulate a minimum price in a two-tier takeover bid (involving an initial price for tendered and accepted shares, and a second price for any remaining shares in any ‘back-end’ transaction such as merger, liquidation, and so on). A third set of states adopted ‘freeze-out’ laws that restrict the ability of an acquirer to effectuate a business combination (merger) with the target firm unless the bidder obtains prior approval from the board of directors. The new laws were generally upheld. One line of studies found significant negative, though generally small, effects on the share prices of companies incorporated in states adopting such takeover amendments. These include Schumann (1988) for New York, Ryngaert and Netter (1988, 1990) for Ohio, Sidak and Woodward (1990) for Indiana, and Szewcsyk and Tsetsekos (1992) for Pennsylvania. On the other hand, Romano (1987) finds no effects in Connecticut, Missouri and Pennsylvania, and Margotta, McWilliams and McWilliams (1990) conclude that the Ohio law had no effect. Similarly, Pugh and Jahera (1990) found no effects in Ohio, Indiana, New York and New Jersey, and Jahera and Pugh (1991) find no effect from the introduction of an antitakeover law in Delaware, the major state of incorporation. To resolve these findings, Karpoff and Malatesta (1989) examine all second-generation of laws passed from 1982 through 1988 and find small but statistically significant negative effects of about -0.3 percent on average upon
5640
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
741
publication of the first newspaper article that reported on the upcoming legislation. Surprisingly, Karpoff and Malatesta found that corporations headquartered but not incorporated in a state passing an antitkakeover law experienced similar stock-price declines. In their view, passage of a law reflects a state’s willingness to help corporations doing business there to defend themselves against takeover. They also find that companies without takeover provisions in their corporate charters experienced significant negative effects, while those with such provisions did not. Surprisingly, a recent study by Comment and Schwert (1995) find little effect of these state laws and firm-level antitakeover measures on the firm-level probability of a takeover. They found that the monthly rate of takeover offers for firms listed on the New York Stock Exchange (NYSE) and the American Stock Exchange (Amex) was typically below 1 percent from 1975 through the mid 1980s. That rate increased above 1 percent in the late 1980s and early 1990s, and then declined below 0.5 percent in the early 1990s. (Note that a takeover rate of 0.5 or 1 percent per month implies a substantial cumulative risk of takeover over several years.) Comment and Schwert found that for a sample of over 20,000 firm-years covering January 1977 through January 1991, the existence of a state control share or business combination law had, if anything, a positive effect on takeover probability. However, the existence of such laws was related to the adoption of poison pills. The use of a poison pill in turn, taking into account other factors, including the existence of a state antitakeover law, did lower the likelihood of takeover. Comment and Schwert conclude that not state laws, but rather the adoption of firm-level antitakeover defenses and changing financial conditions may explain the decline in takeovers. The demise of the junk-bond market, a demise that arguably had political origins, may also have played a role. 9.5 The Politics of Takeover Legislation Roe (1990, 1993, 1994) argues that political forces hinder effective control by shareholders in the United States. For example, the distinctively American opposition to centralized power has kept banks weak and prevented them from playing an active role in the oversight of large corporations. Similarly, the law places limits on financial intermediaries, including investment and insurance companies. Along similar lines, Pound (1992a) argues that the political reaction to takeovers will channel the struggle over corporate control from takeovers to shareholder activism. Clearly, mergers and takeovers generate forceful and volatile political reactions because of the dramatic way they create winners and losers. Jarrell (1992) chronicles the interaction of state law, Supreme Court decisions and firm-level defensive tactics during the 1980s.
742
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
5640
10. Stock-Price Effects of Corporate Control Transactions The stock-price effects of corporate control transactions have been intensively studied. Acquired firms typically experience dramatic increases in their share prices, while the share prices of acquiring firms show little effect on average. Unfortunately, the method is based on short-term stock reactions to the announcement of a merger or tender offer and does not yield direct information about the long-term effects of such transactions on variables of underlying interest such as managerial efficiency. 10.1 Acquired Firms The early survey by Jensen and Ruback (1983) report average returns to US targets of 30 percent for tender offers, 20 percent for mergers and 8 percent for proxy contests. Franks and Harris (1989) find similar gains in the UK. Focusing only on tender offers, Jarrell and Poulson (1987) find returns to targets of 19 percent in the 1960s, 35 percent in the 1970s and 30 percent in the early 1980s. These studies routinely adjust for general changes in the market. In all of these cases, whether merger or tender offer, some of the gains may well have been anticipated. Consequently, these numbers probably understate the stock market gains to acquired firms or targets. In addition, systematic variation occurs across acquisition types. A recent study by Comment and Schwert (1995) investigates the determinants of the takeover premia in a sample of 648 successful takeovers. They found that high sales growth, low market-to-book ratio, the existence of multiple bidders, the use of cash and the use of a tender offer were associated with a higher merger premium. The existence of a poison pill and the existence of a ‘control share’ law also increased the premium. The substantial increase in the stock value of acquired firms is open to various interpretations. If stock markets are efficient, the joint increase in value of the acquired firm and the bidder should reflect the expected value of future increases in joint profitability. As discussed below, bidder stock prices remain essentially unchanged with a merger announcement. Consequently, the increase in value of acquired firm measures the total joint gains, under the assumption of market efficiency. If this interpretation is correct, from where does the extra expected profitability stem? Early work attempted to distinguish prospective monopoly gains from prospective efficiency gains. Given the very stringent horizontal merger policy of the 1960s and 1970s, large monopoly gains were unlikely. In those instances in which an arguably anticompetitive merger did take place, however, the stock prices of rivals to the merging firms should have gone up. (It must be noted though that even this inference may be incorrect if the announcement of a merger in an industry signals that other firms in that industry are ‘in play’.) Stillman (1983) found that rivals’ stock prices did not
5640
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
743
increase in a sample that examined mergers that were subsequently challenged on antitrust grounds. Eckbo (1983), in contrast, found that for a sample of subsequently challenged mergers, the stock prices of rivals increased at the announcement, but that they did not decline when the merger was challenged and actually increased when the challenging agency was the DOJ. Taken together, the results offer little support for the monopoly view, even for these sorts of restricted samples of horizontal mergers. Though monopoly seems largely ruled out, a number of other possible sources of increased expected profitability remain. One line of commentary argues that the expected gains measured by stock price changes came from various ‘stakeholders’. These include workers, suppliers and even bondholders (in the case of mergers that involve increased leverage). This line of inquiry has received at best only very limited support from the data. However, one party may have been hurt by the increased leverage. Since payments on interest are tax deductible, one possible source of gains is the reduced payments going to yet another possible ‘stakeholder’, the US Treasury. In response to the conglomerate mergers of the 1960s and 1970s, some researchers briefly speculated about risk reduction as a motive for merger. Today, most commentary views this possibility skeptically since investors can achieve risk reduction directly through portfolio diversification. Another strand of commentary rejects the assumption of efficient markets. Kraakman (1988) suggests that the shares of target firms may be discounted below their true, efficient-market value. Hence, stock-price gains may overstate the true expected gains in efficiency. In a similar vein, some commentary has argued that the merger gains come from slashing various current expenses that the stock market does not fully value: investment in physical plant, research and development, and the expertise of middle management. Market analysts and investors are fooled by the boost in short-term profits that result when these items are cut and they undervalue the future returns from these expenditures. Other points also deserve mention. The size of the premium depends on the fraction of shares acquired. Bradley, Desai and Kim (1988) found that the supply of tendered shares has an upward slope - an increase of ten percentage points in the fraction of shares acquired resulted in a 1.7 percent increase in the merger premium. Hence, the premia in mergers and tender offers may simply reflect the higher price necessary to elicit a greater supply. Furthermore, control itself may have value even if the transaction does not result in any efficiencies. Consistent with this, control-share blocks trade at a premium. The possibility that a bid reveals previously private information about the value of the target is unlikely since blocked bids result in stock prices that revert to their old values.
744
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
5640
10.2 Bidding Firms Jensen and Ruback (1983) found that bidders on average experienced no net gain or loss as the result of merger activity. More recent work by Bradley, Desai and Kim (1988) and studies surveyed by Jarrell, Brickley and Netter (1988) found steadily decreasing returns to bidders from decade to decade from the 1960s through the 1980s. A changing regulatory environment more favorable to targets, the increased use of defenses that raise target premia, and greater competition for targets in a stronger merger market may explain this shift in financial gains. However, these results were still consistent with the notion that the market expects some bidders to increase and others to decrease corporate performance. An intriguing study by Lehn and Mitchell (1990), ‘Do Bad Bidders Become Good Targets?’, found that bidders whose stock prices declined upon the announcement of their bid were subsequently more likely to become targets of bids themselves. Arguably, then, the market for corporate control may be a two-edged sword. On the one hand, it allows managers to indulge their penchant for acquiring businesses they are not able to manage well and to pay too much when they do so, but, on the other hand, it also provides the ultimate corrective. Clearly, however, this corrective force has recent origins since mergers, takeovers and LBOs of large firms emerged only in the 1980s and 1990s. Morck, Shleifer and Vishny (1990) present similar results, showing the bidder returns are lower when a firm diversifies, when it buys a rapidly growing target and when it has performed poorly before the acquisition. Lang, Stulz and Walkling (1991) find that bidders with large cash flow and low ‘q’ (the ratio of stock value to replacement cost) experience negative returns.
11. Economic Causes and Effects of the Market for Corporate Control At the firm level, attempts to predict merger and takeover candidates have met with only modest success. For the US, Palepu (1986) found that firms are more likely to be acquired if they have had low stock returns, low growth and low leverage, and if they belonged to an industry with a history of recent acquisitions. However, the explanatory power of the model was low. Intriguingly, and not surprising on the efficient-market view, investing in likely targets would not have yielded abnormal positive returns. Though work on the US supports the view that poor performance leads to takeover, a recent study of the UK by Franks and Mayer (1996) found little evidence that targets of hostile bids performed poorly prior to the bid. Since even well-managed firms become targets, it seems unlikely that poor performance by itself would be a reliable precursor to takeover.
5640
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
745
Plant-, division- and firm-level studies appear to support the view that mergers improve performance, on average, though the results are not uniform. The study by Ravenscraft and Scherer (1987) based on Federal Trade Commission Line of Business data seemed to suggest that bidders purchased units with good performance and lowered their return. However, their sample was largely composed of acquisitions made in the 1960s and 1970s, that is, during the conglomerate merger wave. Lichtenberg’s (1992) study of plant-level ownership changes made in the 1970s and early 1980s found that plants with low productivity were more likely to change hands and that, having changed hands, they experienced increases in productivity. Other work based on relatively recent periods seems to confirm the impression that transfers of control raise productivity and profits. Palepu (1990) found that LBO firms experience increases in productivity and operating performance. Healy, Palepu and Ruback (1992) studied the post-acquisition performance of 50 large US mergers. They found increases in productivity and a strong relationship between the original stock price increase at the merger announcement and subsequent operating cash flow changes. It bears emphasis that plant- or firm-level increases in productivity may represent only part of the contribution of mergers and acquisitions to economic well being. A healthy merger market gives entrepreneurs incentives to establish new business since they know that those businesses, once up and running, will find a ready market. It is possible that the market for corporate control performs this function even in the absence of any identifiable short-term increase in productivity linked with a transfer of control. Though the effect of the market for corporate control on managerial efficiency has received the bulk of attention, it seems likely that we would still have mergers and acquisitions even in a world where the incentives of managers and stockholders were well aligned. The variation in merger intensity across industries suggests that merger and acquisition activity result from other factors, though what those factors are remains unclear. Gort (1969) explains the cross-industry variation with an ‘economic disturbance’ theory of merger. He finds that industries with high rates of growth and industries with a large fraction of ‘technical personnel’ - which he viewed as proxies for disturbances - had higher rates of merger. In more recent work, Mitchell and Mulherin (1996) find that 1980s takeover and acquisition activity clustered over time in particular industries. In addition, they find that deregulation, dependence on energy and a low ratio of R&D to sales were correlated with greater takeover and restructuring activity at the industry level. The last result, which contrasts with Gort’s finding for technical personnel, is probably attributable to the increased use in the 1980s of high-yield or ‘junk’ bond financing, which requires tangible assets - that is, not intangible R&D - as backing. Arguably,
746
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
5640
all three variables - deregulation, energy dependence and susceptibility to junk-bond financing - are proxies for shocks. Another line of work views merger as the response to endogenous industry forces or endogenous characteristics. Telser (1987) posits that firms have differential success in their innovative efforts, that merger provides a mechanism by which successful innovations can be applied across firms and that merger has advantages over other methods of transferring information. This prediction explains Gort’s results discussed above, as well as Telser’s results that industry merger and growth rates are positively related. Bittlingmayer (1996) advances a ‘merger as investment’ explanation, according to which acquisition and merger are firm-level alternatives to new investment in tangible and intangible capital. At the industry level, merger intensity depends on the need to replace or augment the stock of capital assets and the degree to which independent development of assets and subsequent acquisition and merger provide a cheaper solution than development of assets within the firm. This explanation emphasizes the link between merger, that is, changes in the scope of a firm, and the theory of the firm. Bittlingmayer found that industry merger intensity was related to industry investment and growth of value-added per employee in the US, and to investment and productivity growth in Germany, offering indirect support for the view that the same factors drive merger and investment.
12. Concluding Comments The purchase of corporate control by an individual, corporation or financial institution undoubtedly arises for a number of reasons. According to a former General Electric executive, GE chairman Jack Welch enjoys socializing with entertainers. That preference and Welch’s effective control over GE as long as it remains one of the best managed corporations in the US may very well explain why GE owns the National Broadcasting Company (NBC). Undoubtedly, some of General Electric’s other acquisitions have had more traditional strategic origins. Acquisitions by other companies may have been undertaken to improve the management of the acquired firm. Against this background, it would be difficult to conclude that the market for corporate control serves shareholders - and ultimately, the cause of economic efficiency - in each and every instance. Not just common sense but the record of the conglomerate merger wave of the 1960s supports a split verdict. However, if one accepts the view that the modern corporation has allowed substantial efficiencies in the organization and financing of business, and that the corporation gets things right on average and in the long run, it seems likely that - taking the good with the bad - the market for corporate control has aided the cause of efficiency. Perhaps the most suggestive evidence on the possible role of an active market in mergers and acquisitions comes from the historical
5640
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
747
correlation between merger activity and economic growth - at the turn of the century, in the 1920s, the 1960s and again the 1980s and 1990s. Economists have typically assumed causation runs from business booms to merger, but it also seems possible that mergers and acquisitions are among the means by which industrial economies come to use resources more efficiently. The importance of mergers, acquisitions and the market for corporate control is reflected in the volatile, often contradictory political reaction to them. Until the 1960s, discussion of mergers and acquisitions was dominated by the monopoly problem and the power of the corporation. Concern about the monopoly problem was probably overstated and seems to have been a pretext to slow the pace of economic change. Since the 1960s, the focus of discussion has shifted partly to the effects on employees and others connected with acquired corporations, reflecting the increase in hostile takeovers and radical restructuring. Ironically, restructuring was probably more severe because other, related political pressures had undermined effective control by shareholders, increasing the gap between potential and actual corporate performance, and thus increasing the extent of changes that were likely to ensue when a change in control did take place. Effective control mechanisms are the public’s best protection against substantial changes stemming from an unrestricted market for corporate control. Economists, lawyers and business historians have only slowly come to appreciate the consequences of legal intervention in the market for corporate control, and the subtle but powerful interplay between business, the presidency, the legislature and the courts. The initial effort to outlaw the trusts at the end of the nineteenth century hastened the growth of large firms through merger because the courts were reluctant to bring merger under the Sherman Act. Cartels were illegal but merger was not. Public opinion and public policy also opposed effective control by financial intermediaries, and state competition for corporate charters may have undermined effective control of corporations by shareholders. Episodes of lax merger policy stimulated merger waves, and the political reaction against those merger waves brought them to abrupt halts at the turn of the century and again in the 1920s. The effort to outlaw horizontal merger in the 1950s and 1960s aided the formation of inefficient conglomerates, a process no doubt hastened by other restrictions on effective shareholder control such as a cumbersome proxy machinery and limits on stock ownership. The states reacted to acquisitions of the 1960s with blatantly protectionist antitakeover laws, and the Supreme Court reacted by declaring those laws illegal. The Reagan administration’s laissez-faire antitrust policies and reluctance to cater to political pressure in the face of the resulting 1980s takeover wave led states to adopt and the Supreme Court ultimately to approve a new generation of more subtly crafted antitakeover measures.
748
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
5640
Three areas of research deserve more attention. First, what have been the effects of mergers, acquisitions and takeovers on economic efficiency? The existing evidence, based on plant-, division- or company-level data, is unlikely to capture the total effects. To put the matter differently, what would have been the effects on the efficiency of existing firms and on the formation of new firms of a complete ban on mergers? Second, what is the most efficient level of defense against an unwanted takeover? Some analysts say that no defense serves shareholders best, while others believe even aggressive measures serve shareholders. The socially optimal takeover defense deserves more attention. Finally, how will the political economy of takeover regulation change against the background of increasing public ownership of stocks, the internationalization of equity markets and greater use of equity markets worldwide?
Bibliography on The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers) (5640) Adams, Michael (1989), ‘Der Markt für Unternehmenskontrolle und sein Missbrauch (The Market of Corporate Control and Its Abuse)’, Die Aktiengesellschaft, 333-338. Adams, Michael (1990), ‘Höchststimmrechte, Mehrfachstimmrechte und sonstige wundersame Hindernisse auf dem Markt für Unternehmenskontrolle (Maximum Voting Right, Multiple Voting Right, and some Wonderfull Obstacles from the Market of Corporate Control)’, 35 Die Aktiengesellschaft, 63-78. Agrawal, Arun and Mandelker, G.N. (1987), ‘Managerial Incentives and Corporate Investment and Financing Decisions’, 42 Journal of Finance, 823-837. Agrawal, Arun and Mandelker, G.N. (1990), ‘Large Shareholders and the Monitoring of Managers: The Case of Antitakeover Charter Amendments’, 25 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 143-161. Agrawal, Arun and Mandelker, G.N. (1992), ‘Shark Repellents and the Role of Institutional Investors in Corporate Governance’, 13 Managerial and Decision Economics, 15-22. Agrawal, Arun and Nagarajan, N.J. (1990), ‘Corporate Capital Structure, Agency Costs, and Ownership Control: The Case of All-Equity Firms’, 45 Journal of Finance, 1325-1331. Agrawal, Arun and Walkling R. (1994), ‘Executive Careers and Compensation Surrounding takeover Bids’, 49 Journal of Finance, 985-1014. Agrawal, Arun, Jaffe, J. and Mandelker, G.N. (1992), ‘The Post-Merger Performance of Acquiring Firms: A Re-examination of an Anomaly’, 47 Journal of Finance, 1605-1621. Allen, J.W., Lummer, S.I., McConnell, J.J. and Reed, D.K. (1995), ‘Can Takeover Losses Explain Spin-Off Gains’, 30 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 465-485. Ambrose, B.W. and Megginson, W.L. (1992), ‘The Role of Asset Structure, Ownership Structure, and Takeover Defenses in Determining Acquisition Likelihood’, 27 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 575-589. Amihud, Yakov, Lev, Baruch and Travlos, Nickolaos G. (1990), ‘Corporate Control and the Choice of Investment Financing: The Case of Corporate Acquisitions’, 45 Journal of Finance, 603-616.
5640
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
749
Arruñada, Benito (1991), ‘Market vs. Regulation in the Market for Corporate Control: Interactions Between Takeovers and Industrial Policiy in Spain’, in Pardolesi, Roberto and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds), Law and Economics: Some Further Insights, Milano, Giuffrè, 71-106. Arruñada, Benito (1988a), ‘Tiburones y Sanguijuelas en la Plaza de la Lealtad (Sharks and Spongers in the Stockmarket)’, 2123 Boletín del ICE, 771-772. Arruñada, Benito (1988b), ‘Un Análisis Económico de la Regulación de la Sociedad Anónima en España (An Economic Analysis of the Regulation of the Joint-Stock Society in Spain)’, 3 Anales de Estudios Económicos y Empresariales, 191-224. Arruñada, Benito (1990a), ‘Control y Propiedad: Límites al Desarrollo de la Empresa Española (Corporate Control and Ownership: Limits to its Growth in Spain)’, 687 Información Comercial Española - Revista de Economia, 67-88. Arruñada, Benito (1990b), Control y Regulación de la Sociedad anónima (Control and Regulation of Joint-Stock Companies), Madrid, Alianza Editorial. Arruñada, Benito (1992a), ‘Tiburones Sólo en el Diccionario (Sharks only in the Dictionary)’, 56 Boletín del Círculo de Empresarios, 15-30. Arruñada, Benito (1992b), ‘Crítica a la Regulación de las Opas (A Critic on the Regulation of Takeovers)’, 203-4 Revista de Derecho Mercantil, 29-67. Arruñada, Benito (1992c), ‘La Conversión Coactiva de Acciones Comunes en Acciones sin voto para Lograr el Control de las Sociedades Anónimas: De cómo la ingenuidad legal prefigura el fraude (Mandatory Conversion of Common Shares into Non-Voting Shares to Reach Corporate Control over Joint-Stock Companies: How legal Simplicity Leads to Fraud)’, 71 Revista Española de Financiación y Contabilidad, 283-314. Arruñada, Benito (1992d), ‘¿Hacia un “mercado único” de control societario? (Towards a Common Market of Corporate Control)’, 703 Información Comercial Española, 144-170. Arruñada, Benito and Paz Ares, Cándido (1995), ‘Conversion of Ordinary Shares into Non-Voting Shares’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics. Asquith, P. (1983), ‘Merger Bids, Uncertainty and Stockholder Returns’, 11 Journal of Financial Economics, 51-83. Asquith, P., Bruner, Robert F. and Mullins, David W., Jr (1983), ‘The Gains to Bidding Firms from Merger’, 11 Journal of Financial Economics, 121-139. Auerbach, Alan J. (ed) (1991), Corporate Takeovers, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 354 p. Austensmith, D. and Obrien, P.C. (1992), ‘Takeover Defenses and Shareholder Voting’, 59 Economica, 199-219. Bagnoli, Mark and Lipman, B. L. (1996), ‘Stock Price Manipulation Through Takeover Bids’, 27 Rand Journal of Economics, 124-147. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1986), ‘State Takeover and Tender Offer Regulations Post-MITE: The Maryland, Ohio and Pennsylvania Attempts’, 90 Dickinson Law Review, 731 ff. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1990), ‘Exclusive Merger Agreements and Lock-Ups in Negotiated Corporate Acquisitions’, 75 Minnesota Law Review, 239 ff. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1991), ‘The Short Life and Resurrection of SEC Rule 19c-4', 69 Washington University Law Quarterly, 565 ff. Reprinted in 1992 Securities Law Review 377. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1992a), ‘Interpreting Nonshareholder Constituency Statutes’, 19 Pepperdine Law Review, 971 ff. Reprinted in 34 Corporate Practice Commentator 641, 1993.
750
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
5640
Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1992b), ‘Redirecting State Takeover Laws at Proxy Contests’, 68 Wisconsin Law Review, 1071 ff. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1994), ‘Revisiting the One-Share/One-Vote Controversy: The Exchanges’ Uniform Voting Rights Policy’, 22 Securities Regulation Law Journal, 175 ff. Bannister, James, W. and Riahi-Belkaoui, Ahmed (1992), ‘Cash Flow, Earnings, and Corporate Control’, 18 Managerial Finance, 14-30. Barclay, Michael J. and Holderness, Clifford G. (1991), ‘Negotiated Block Trades and Corporate Control’, 46 Journal of Finance, 861-878. Baysinger, Barry D. and Butler, Henry N. (1985), ‘Antitakeover Amendments, Managerial Entrenchment, and the Contractual Theory of the Corporation’, 71 Virginia Law Review, 1257-1303. Beatty, Anne (1994), ‘An Empirical Analysis of Corporate Control Tax and Incentive Motivations for Adopting Leveraged Employee Stock Ownership Plans’,15 Managerial and Decision Economics, 299-315. Bebchuck, Lucian Arye (1985), ‘Toward Undistorted Choice and Equal Treatment in Corporate Takeovers’, 98 Harvard Law Review, 1693-1808. Bebchuck, Lucian Arye (1986), ‘The Case for Facilitating Competing Tender Offers’, 2 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 253-271. Bebchuck, Lucian Arye (1988), ‘The Sole Owner Standard for Takeover Policy’, 17 Journal of Legal Studies, 197-229. Bebchuck, Lucian Arye (1989), ‘Takeover Bid Below The Expected Value of Minority Shares’, 24 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 171-184. Bebchuck, Lucian Arye (1994), ‘Efficient and Inefficient Sales of Corporate Control’, 109 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 957-993. Bebchuk, Lucian Arye and Kahan, Marcel (1990), ‘A Framework for Analyzing Legal Policy Towards Proxy Contest’, 78 California Law Review, 1071-1135. Berger, P.G. and Ofek, E. (1991), ‘Bustup Takeovers of Value-Destroying Diversified Firms’, 51 Journal of Finance, 1175-1200. Berkovitch, Elazar and Khanna, Naveen (1990), ‘How Target Shareholders Benefit from Value-Reducing Defensive Strategies in Takeovers’, 45 Journal of Finance, 137-156. Berkovitch, Elazar and Narayanan, M.P. (1993), ‘Motives for Takeovers: An Empirical Investigation’, 28 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 347-362. Berkovitch, Elazar, Bradley, Michael D. and Khanna, Naveen (1989), ‘Tender Offer Auctions, Resistance Strategies, and Social Welfare’, 5 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 395-412. Berle, Adolph A. and Means, Gardiner C. (1932), The Modern Corporation and Private Property, New York, Macmillan. Bhagat, Sanjai and Jefferis, R.H. (1991), ‘Voting Power in the Proxy Process - The Case of Antitakeover Charter Amendments’, 30 Journal of Financial Economics, 193-225. Bhagat, Sanjai, Brickley, James A. and Loewenstein, Uri (1987), ‘The Pricing Effects of Interfirm Cash Tender Offers’, 42 Journal of Finance, 965-986. Bhagat, Sanjai, Shleifer, Andrei and Vishny, Robert W. (1990), ‘Hostile Takeovers in the 1980s - The Return to Corporate Specialization’, 1 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 1-84. Bittlingmayer, George (1982), ‘Decreasing Average Cost and Competition: A New Look at the Addyston Pipe Case’, 25 Journal of Law and Economics, 201-229.
5640
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
751
Bittlingmayer, George (1983), ‘Price-Fixing and The Addyston Pipe Case’, 5 Research in Law and Economics, 57-130. Bittlingmayer, George (1985), ‘Did Antitrust Policy Cause the Great Merger Wave?’, Journal of Law and Economics, 77-118. Bittlingmayer, George (1989a), ‘The Economic Problem of Fixed Costs and What Legal Research Can Contribute’, 14 Law and Social Inquiry, 739-762. Bittlingmayer, George (1989b), ‘Shareholder Heterogeneity and the Gains from Merger’, in Faure, Michael and Van Den Bergh, Roger (eds), Essays in Law and Economics. Corporations, Accident Prevention and Compensation for Losses, Antwerpen, Maklu, 49-70. Bittlingmayer, George (1992), ‘Stock Returns, Real Activity, and the Trust Question’, 47 Journal of Finance, 1701-1730. Bittlingmayer, George (1993), ‘The Stock Market and Early Antitrust Enforcement’, Journal of Law and Economics, 1-32. Bittlingmayer, George (1996), ‘Merger as a Form of Investment’, 49 Kyklos, 127-153. Bittlingmayer, George (1997), ‘Antitrust and Business Activity: The First Quarter Century’, Business History Review. Black, Bernard and Kraakman, Reinier H. (1996), ‘A Self-Enforcing Model of Corporate Law’, 109 Harvard Law Review, 1911-1979. Blair, Margaret, M. (1991), ‘Who’s In Charge Here? How Changes in Corporate Finance Are Shaping Corporate Governance’, 9 Brookings Review, 8-13. Blair, Margaret, M. (1995), ‘Rethinking Assumptions Behind Corporate Governance’, 38 Challenge, 12-17. Blair, Margaret, M. (1995), Ownership and Control: Rethinking Corporate Governance for the Twenty-First Century, Washington, Brookings Institution. Blair, Margaret, M. (1996), Wealth Creation and Wealth Sharing: A Colloquium on Corporate Governance and Investments in Human Capital, Washington, Brookings Institution. Blair, Margaret, M. and Girish, Uppal (1993), The Decade Handbook, Washington, Brookings Institution. Boot, Arnoud, W.A. (1992), ‘Why Hang on to Losers? Divestitures and Takeovers’, 47 Journal of Finance, 1401-1423. Booth, Richard A. (1989a), ‘The Problem with Federal Tender Offer Law’, 77 California Law Review, 707-776. Booth, Richard A. (1989b), ‘State Takeovers Statutes Revisited’, 88 Michigan Law Review, 120 ff. Born, Jeffrey, A., Trahan, Emery A. and Faria, Hugo J. (1993), ‘Golden Parachutes: Incentive Aligners, Management Entrenchers, or Takeover Bid Signals?’, 16 Journal of Financial Research, 299-308. Borstadt, Lisa, F. and Zwirlein, Thomas J. (1992), ‘The Efficient Monitoring Role of Proxy Contests: An Empirical Analysis of Post-Contest Control Changes and Firm Performance’, 21 Financial Management, 22-34. Boukema, C.A. (1991), ‘Economische en Juridische Aspecten van Hoofdstuk I Fusiecode (Economic and Legal Aspects of Chapter I Dutch Merger Rules)’, in Coljee, P.D., Franken, H., Heertje, A. and Kanning, W. (eds), Law and Welfare Economics, Amsterdam, VU Amsterdam.
752
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
5640
Bowers, Helen, M. and Moore, Norman H. (1995), ‘Market Valuation of Excess Pension Assets: Evidence from the Market for Corporate Control’, 62 Journal of Risk and Insurance, 214-229. Braakman, A.J. (1988), ‘Europees Kartelrecht als Strijdmiddel bij Overnames (European Anti-trust Law as Takeover Combat Mechanism)’, 73 Economisch-Statistische Berichten, 854-858. Bradford, C. Steven (1990), ‘Stampeding Shareholders and Other Myths: Target Shareholders and Hostile Tender Offers’, 15 Journal of Corporation Law, 417-464. Bradley, Michael and Schipani, CA (1989), ‘The Relevance of the Duty of Care Standard in Corporate Governance’, 75 Iowa Law Review in Frech, H.E. (ed.), Regulating Doctors’ Fees: Competition, Benefits, and Controls under Medicare, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute, 1-74. Bradley, Michael D. (1980), ‘Interfirm Tender Offers, and the Market for Corporate Control’, 53 Journal of Business, 345-376. Bradley, Michael, Desai, Anand and Kim, Han J. (1988), ‘Synergistic Gains from Corporate Acquisitions and Their Division Between the Stockholders of Target and Acquiring Firms’, 21 Journal of Financial Economics, 3-40. Brickley, James A. and James, Christopher M. (1987), ‘The Takeover Market, Corporate Board Composition, and Ownership Structure: The Case of Banking’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 161-180. Brous, P.A. and Kini, O. (1993), ‘A Reexamination of Analysts Earnings Forecasts for Takeover Target’, 33 Journal of Financial Economics, 201-255. Brown, David T. and Ryngaert, Michael (1991), ‘The Mode of Acquisition in Takeovers: Taxes and Asymmetric Information’, 46 Journal of Finance, 653-669. Browne, Lynn E. and Rosengren, Eric S. (1987), ‘Are Hostile Takeovers Different?’, in Browne, Lynn E. and Rosengren, Eric S. (ed.), The Merger Boom: Proceedings of a Conference Held at Melvin Village, New Hampshire, October 1987, Boston, Federal Bank of Boston, 199-229. Brudney, Victor and Chirelstein, Marvin A. (1987), Corporate Finance, Mineola, NY, Foundation Press. Buckley, Francis H. (1990), ‘When the Medium is the Message: Corporate Buybacks as Signals’, 65 Indiana Law Journal, 493-547. Butler, Henry N. (1989), ‘State Takeover Legislation, the Market for Corporate Charters, and the Scope of Federal Intervention: A Comment on Hitzeman, Indiana’s Control Share Acquisition Statute’, 27 American Business Law Journal, 291-305. Butler, Henry N. and Ribstein, Larry E. (1988), ‘State Anti-Takeover Statutes and the Contract Clause’, 57 University of Cincinnati Law Review, 611 ff. Butler, Henry N. and Ribstein, Larry E. (1989), ‘The Contract Clause and the Corporation’, 55 Brooklyn Law Review, 767 ff. Buxbaum, Hertig and Hirsch, Hopt (eds) (1996), European Economic and Business Law, Legal and Economic Analyses on Integration and Harmonization, Walter De Gruyter; Berlin, 401 p. Buxbaum, Richard M. (1985), ‘The Internal Division of Powers in Corporate Governance’, 73 California Law Review, 1671-1734. Byttebier, Koen (1995), ‘Hostile Take-Overs: Economic (Dis)Functions and Legal Policy Questions’, in Bouckaert, Boudewijn and De Geest, Gerrit (eds), Essays in Law and Economics II: Contract Law, Regulation, and Reflections on Law and Economics, Antwerpen, Maklu, 77-134.
5640
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
753
Campbell, David (1990), ‘Adam Smith, Farrar on Company Law and the Economics of the Corporation’, 19 Anglo-American Law Review, 185-208. Cantillo, Miguel Simon (1996), The Rise and Fall of Bank Control in the United States: 1890-1939, Berkeley, University of California. Carlton, Dennis W. and Perloff, Jeffrey M. (1994), Modern Industrial Organization, Harper Collins Publishers. Carney, William J. (1980), ‘Fundamental Corporate Changes, Minority Shareholders and Business Purposes’, 5 American Bar Foundation Research Journal, 69 ff. Carney, William J. (1983), ‘Shareholder Coordination Costs, Shark Repellents and Takeout Mergers: The Case Against Fiduciary Duties’, 8American Bar Foundation Research Journal, 341 ff. Carney, William J. (1984), ‘Toward a More Perfect Market for Corporate Control’, 9 Delaware Journal of Corporate Law, 593 ff. Carney, William J. (1986), ‘Two-Tier Tender Offers and Shark Repellents’, 4(2) Midland Corporate Finance Journal, 48 ff. Carney, William J. (1988), ‘Controlling Management Opportunism in the Market for Corporate Control: An Agency Cost Model’, 44 Wisconsin Law Review, 383 ff. Castanias, Richard, P. and Helfat, Constance E. (1992), ‘Managerial and Windfall Rents in the Market for Corporate Control’, 18 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 153-184. Caswell, Julie A. (1984), ‘’An Institutional Perspective on Corporate Control and the Network of Interlocking Directorates’, 18 Journal of Economic Issues, 619-626. Caves, Richard E. (1989), ‘Mergers, Takeovers, and Economic Efficiency: Foresight vs. Hindsight’, 7 International Journal of Industrial Organization, 151-174. Caves, Richard E. (1990), ‘Lessons from Privatization in Britain: State Enterprise Behavior, Public Choice, and Corporate Governance’, 13 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 145-169. Cebenoyan, A.S, Papaioannou, G.J. and Travlos, Nickolaos G. (1992), ‘Foreign Takeover Activity in the United-States and Wealth Effects for Target Firm Shareholders’, 21 Financial Management, 58-68. Chandler, Alfred D., Jr (1977), The Visible Hand: The Managerial Revolution in American Business, Belknap Press. Chaplinsky, S. and Neihaus, G. (1994), ‘The Role of ESOPS in Takeover Contests’, 49 Journal of Finance, 1451-1470. Chapman, Bruce (1993), ‘Trust, Economic Rationality, and the Corporate Fiduciary Obligation’, 43 University of Toronto Law Journal, 547-588. Chatterjee, Sayan (1992), ‘Sources of Value in Takeovers: Synergy or Restructuring-Implications for Target and Bidder Firms’, 13 Strategic Management Journal, 267-286. Chernow, Ron (1990), The House of Morgan, New York, Touchstone. Choi, Dosoung (1991), ‘Toehold Acquisitions, Shareholder Wealth, and the Market for Corporate Control’, 26 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 391-407. Chowdhry, Bhagwan and Jegadeesh, N. (1994), ‘Pre-tender Offer Share Acquisition Strategy in Takeovers’, 29 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 117-129. Chowdhry, Bhagwan and Nanda, Vikram (1993), ‘The Strategic Role of Debt in Takeover Contests’, 48 Journal of Finance, 731-745.
754
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
5640
Claassen, E.M. (1993), ‘Cleaning the Balance Sheets of Commerical Banks in Eastern Europe and Their Role in Corporate Governance’, 129 Weltwirtschaftliches Archiv - Review of World Economics, 600-609. Coffee, John C., Jr (1984), ‘Regulating the Market for Corporate Control: A Critical Assessment of the Tender Offer’s Role in Corporate Governance’, 84 Columbia Law Review, 1145-1296. Coffee, John C., Jr (1987), ‘Are Hostile Takeovers Different? Discussion’, in Browne, Lynn E. and Rosengren, Eric S. (ed.), The Merger Boom, Boston, Federal Bank of Boston, 230-242. Coffee, John C. (1990), ‘Unstable Coalitions - Corporate Governance as a Multi-player Game’, 78 Georgetown Law Journal, 1495-1549. Coffee, John C., Lownstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1988), Knights, Raiders and Targets: The Impact of the Hostile Takeover, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Cohen, Lloyd R. (1990), ‘Why Tender Offers? The Efficient Market Hypothesis, the Supply of Stock, and Signaling’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 113-143. Cohen, Lloyd R. (1991), ‘Holdouts and Free Riders’, 20 Journal of Legal Studies, 351-362. Collins, Daniel, W. and Deangelo, Linda (1990), ‘Accounting Information and Corporate Governance: Market and Analyst Reactions to Earnings of Firms Engaged in Proxy Contests’, 13 Journal of Accounting and Economics, 213-247. Comment, Robert and Schwert, G. William (1995), ‘Poison or Placebo? Evidence on the Deterrence and Wealth Effects of Modern Antitakeover Measures’,39 Journal of Financial Economics, 3-43. Conyon, Martin and Leech, Dennis (1994), ‘Top Pay, Company Performance and Corporate Governance’, 56 Oxford Bulletin of Economics and Statistics, 229-247. Corry, Jospeh, C. (1990), ‘Accounting Aspects of Takeovers’, 72 Management Accounting, 47-51. Cosh, A.D., Hughes, A. and Singh, A. (1989), ‘Institutional Investment, Mergers and the Market for Corporate Control’, 7 International Journal of Industrial Organization, 73-100. Craig, Lee A. and Knoeber, Charles R. (1992), ‘Manager Shareholding, the Market for Managers, and the End Period Problem: Evidence from the U.S. Whaling Industry’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 607-627. Cramton, Peter and Schwartz, Alan (1991), ‘Using Auction Theory to Inform Takeover Regulation’, 7 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 27-53. Curtis, C., T. (1990), ‘The Takings Clause and Regulatory Takeovers of Banks and Thrifts’, 27 Harvard Journal On Legislature, 367-390. Curzan, Myron, P. and Pelesh, Mark L. (1980), ‘Revitalizing Corporate Democracy: Control of Investment Managers’ Voting on Social Responsibility Proxy Issues’, 93 Harvard Law Review, 670-700. Daily, Catherine, M. and Dalton, Dan R. (1994), ‘Corporate Governance and the Bankrupt Firm: An Empirical Assessment’, 15 Strategic Management Journal, 643-654. Dann, Larry, Y. and Deangelo, Harry (1983), ‘Standstill Agreements, Privately Negotiated Stock Repurchases, and the Market for Corporate Control’, 11 Journal of Financial Economics, 275-300. Dann, Larry, Y. and Deangelo, Harry (1988), ‘Corporate Financial Policy and Corporate Control: A Study of Defensive Adjustments in Asset and Ownership Structure’, 20 Journal of Financial Economics, 87-127.
5640
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
755
Davis, Gerald, F. (1991), ‘Agents Without Principles? The Spread of the Poison Pill Through the Intercorporate Network’, 36 Administrative Science Quarterly, 583-613. Davis, Gerald, F. and Stout, Suzanne K. (1992), ‘Organization Theory and the Market for Corporate Control: A Dynamic Analysis of the Characteristics of Large Takeover Targets, 1980-1990', 37 Administrative Science Quarterly, 605-633. Davis, Gerald, F. and Thompson, Tracey A. (1994), ‘A Social Movement Perspective on Corporate Control’, 39 Administrative Science Quarterly, 141-173. De Angelo, Linda, E. (1988), ‘Managerial Competition, Information Costs, and Corporate Governance: The Use of Accounting Performance Measure in Proxy Contests’, 10 Journal of Accounting and Economics, 3-36. Deangelo, Harry, Deangelo, Linda and Rice, Edward M. (1984), ‘Going Private: Minority Freezeouts and Stockholder Wealth’, 27 Journal of Law and Economics, 367-401. Demsetz, H. (1986), ‘Corporate Control, Insider Trading, and Rates of Return’, 76 American Economic Review, 313-316. Demsetz, H. and Lehn, Kenneth (1985), ‘The Structure of Ownership: Causes and Consequences’, 93 Journal of Political Economy, 1155-1177. Denis, David, J. (1992), ‘Corporate Investment Decisions and Corporate Control: Evidence from Going-Private Transactions’, 21 Financial Management, 80-94. Denis, Debra K. and McConnell, John J. (1986), ‘Corporate Mergers and Security Returns’,16 Journal of Financial Economics, 143-187. Dennis, R. and Honabach, D.R. (1992), ‘Corporate Governance Theory in the 1990s - Introduction’, 44 Rutgers Law Review, 533-554. Dewatripont, M. (1993), ‘The Leading Shareholder Strategy, Takeover Contest and Stock Price Dynamics’, 37 European Economic Review, 983-1004. Dewenter, K.L. (1995), ‘Does the Market React Differently to Domestic and Foreign Takover Announcements - Evidence from the United States Chemical and Retail Industries’, 37 Journal of Financial Economics, 421-441. Diacon, S.R. and O’Sullivan, N. (1995), ‘Does Corporate Governance Influence Performance - Some Evidence From U.K. Insurance Companies?’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 405-424. Dodd, Peter (1986), ‘The Market for Corporate Control: A Review of the Evidence’, in Stern, Joel M. and Chew, Donald H. (eds), The Revolution in Corporate Finance, Oxford, Blackwell. Dodd, Peter and Warner, Jerold (1983), ‘On Corporate Governance: A Study of Proxy Contests’, 11 Journal of Financial Economics, 401-438. Dyl, Edward, A. (1989), ‘Agency, Corporate Control and Accounting Methods - the LIFO-FIFO Choice’, 10 Managerial and Decision Economics, 141-145. Easterbrook, Frank H. and Fischel, Daniel R. (1981), ‘The Proper Role of a Target’s Management in Responding to a Tender Offer’, 91 Harvard Law Review, 1161-1201. Easterbrook, Frank H. and Fishel, Daniel R. (1982), ‘Corporate Control Transactions’, 91 Yale Law Journal, 698-737. Eckbo, B. Espen (1983), ‘Horizontal Mergers, Collusion, and Stockholder Wealth’, 11 Journal of Financial Economics, 241-273. Eckbo, B. Espen, Giammarino, R.M. and Heinkel, R. (1990), ‘Asymmetric Information and the Medium of Exchange in Takeovers - Theory and Tests’, 3 Review of Financial Studies, 651-675. Elhauge, Einer Richard (1992), ‘The Triggering Function of Sale of Control Doctrine’, 59 University of Chicago Law Review, 1465 ff.
756
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
5640
Elhauge, Einer Richard (1993), ‘Toward a European Sale of Control Doctrine’, 41 American Journal of Comparative Law, 627 ff. Epstein, Richard A. (1985), ‘The Pirates of Pennzoil: A Comic Opera Made Possible by a Grant from the Texaco Corporation’, 9(6) Regulation, 18-2442. Estes, Robert, M. (1977), ‘The Emerging Solution to Corporate Governance’, 55 Harvard Business Review, 20-164. Estes, Robert, M. (1980), ‘Corporate Governance in the Courts’, 58 Harvard Business Review, 50-64. Fairburn, James (1992), ‘Japanese Takeovers: The Global Contest for Corporate Control’, 66 Business History Review, 248-249. Fama, Eugene F. (1980), ‘Agency Problems and the Theory of the Firm’, 88 Journal of Political Economy, 288-307. Reprinted in Jensen, Michael C. and Smith, Clifford W. Jr (eds), The Modern Theory of Corporate Finance, McCraw-Hill, 1984. Ferguson, Michael F. (1994), ‘Ownership Structure, Potential Competition, and the Free Rider Problem in Tender Offers’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 35-62. Filer, John E., Kenny, Lawrence W. and Morton, Rebecca B. (1991), ‘Voting Laws, Educational Policies, and Minority Turnout’, 34 Journal of Law and Economics, 371-393. Firth, Michael (1979), ‘The Profitability of Takeovers and Mergers’, 89 Economic Journal, 316-328. Fischel, Daniel R. (1978), ‘Efficient Capital Market Theory, the Market for Corporate Control and the Regulation of Cash Tender Offers’, 57 Texas Law Review, 1-46. Fishman, Michael J. (1988), ‘A Theory of Preemptive Takeover Bidding’, 19 Rand Journal of Economics, 88-101. Fitzsimons, Peter G. (1997), ‘Takeovers and Efficiency in the Context of Concentrated Shareholdings: The Case of New Zealand’, 15 Companies and Securities Law Journal, 4-15. Fizel, John, L. and Louie, Kenneth K.T. (1990), ‘CEO Retention, Firm Performance and Corporate Governance’, 11 Managerial and Decision Economics, 167-176. Fleischer, Arthur, Jr and Mundheim, Robert H. (1965), ‘Corporate Acquisitions by Tender Offer’, 115 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 317-370. Fogg, Joseph, G. III (1985), ‘Takeovers: Last Chance for Self-Restraint’, 63 Harvard Business Review, 3040 ff. Franks, Julian and Harris, Robert S. (1989), ‘Shareholder Wealth Effects of Corporate Takeovers: The U.K. Experience 1955-1985', 23 Journal of Financial Economics, 225-249. Franks, Julian and Mayer, Colin (1990), ‘Takeovers: Capital Markets and Corporate Control: A Study of France, Germany and the UK’, 0(10) Economic Policy: A European Forum, 189-231. Franks, Julian and Mayer, Colin (1996), ‘Hostile Takeovers and the Correction of Managerial Failure’, 43 Journal of Industrial Economics, 229-259. Frech, H.E. III (1978), ‘Is Corporate Ownership Divorced from Control?’, in Johnson, M.B. (ed.), The Attack on Corporate America: The Corporate Issues Sourcebook, New York, McGraw-Hill. Freyer, Tony Allan (1992), Regulating Big Business: Antitrust in Great Britain and America, 1880-1990, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
5640
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
757
Garcia De Enterria, Javier (1995), ‘El Control del Poder societario en la Gran Empresa y la Función Disciplinar de las OPAS (Corporate Control of Large Companies and the Disciplinary Role of Takeovers)’, 47 Revista de Derecho Bancario y bursatil, 665-689. Garcia De Enterria, Javier (1996), La Opa Obligatoria (Mandatory Takeovers), Madrid, Editorial Cívitas, 324 p. Geddes, R. Richard (1997), ‘Ownership, Regulation, and Managerial Monitoring in the Electric Utility Industry’, 40 Journal of Law and Economics. Gibbs, P.A. (1993), ‘Determinants of Corporate Restructuring - The Relative Importance of Corporate Governance, Takeover Threat, and Free Cash Flow’, 14 Strategic Management Journal, 51-68. Gilson, Ronald J. (1981), ‘A Structural Approach to Corporations: The Case against Defensive Tactics in Tender Offers’, 33 Stanford Law Review, 933-944. Gilson, Ronald J. (1986), The Law and Finance of Corporate Acquisitions, Mineola, NY, Foundation Press. Gilson, Ronald J. (1992), ‘The Political Ecology of Takeovers - Thoughts on Harmonizing the European Corporate Governance Environment’, 61 Fordham Law Review, 161-192. Gilson, Ronald J. and Kraakman, Reinier H. (1989), ‘Delaware’s Intermediate Standard for Defensive Tactics: Is There Substance to the Proportionality Rule?’, 44 The Business Lawyer, 247-274. Gilson, Ronald J. and Kraakman, Reinier H. (1990), ‘What Triggers Revlon?’, 25 Wake Forest Law Review, 37-59. Gilson, Ronald J. and Kraakman, Reinier H. (1991), ‘Reinventing the Outside Director: An Agenda for Institutional Investors’, 43 Stanford Law Review, 863-906. Gilson, Ronald J. and Kraakman, Reinier H. (1993), ‘Investment Companies as Guardian Shareholders - The Place of the MSIC in the Corporate Governance Debate’, 45 Stanford Law Review, 985-1010. Gilson, Ronald J. and Roe, Mark J. (1993), ‘Understanding the Japanese Keirstsu - Overlaps Between Corporate Governance and Industrial Organization’, 102 Yale Law Journal, 871-906. Gilson, Stuart C. (1990), ‘Bankruptcy, Boards, Banks, and Blockholders: Evidence on Changes in Corporate Ownership and Control when Firms Default’, 27 Journal of Financial Economics, 355-387. Ginsburg, Douglas H. and Robinson, John F. (1986), ‘The Case Against Federal Intervention in the Market for Corporate Control’, 4 Brookings Review, 534-551. Gitelman, Steven (1987), ‘Beyond CTS: A Limited Defense of State Tender Offer Disclosure Requirements’, 54 University of Chicago Law Review, 1161-1204. Giuffra, Robert J., Jr (1986), ‘Investment Bankers’ Fairness Opinions in Corporate Control Transactions’, 96 Yale Law Journal, 119-141. Gokhale, Jagadeesh, Groshen, El and Neumark, D. (1995), ‘Do Hostile Takeovers Reduce Extramarginal Wage Payments’, 77 Review of Economics and Statistics, 470-485. Gordon, Jeffrey N. (1991), ‘Corporations, Markets, and Courts’, 91 Columbia Law Review, 1931-1988. Gordon, Jeffrey N. and Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1986), ‘Takeover Defense Tactics: A Comment on Two Models’, 96 Yale Law Journal, 295-321. Gordon, Lilli, A. and Pound, John (1990), ‘ESOPs and Corporate Control’, 27 Journal of Financial Economics, 525-555.
758
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
5640
Gordon, Lilli, A. and Pound, John (1993), ‘Information, Ownership Structure, and Shareholder Voting: Evidence from Shareholder-sponsored Corporate Governance Proposals’, 48 Journal of Finance, 697-718. Gort, Michael (1969), ‘An Economic Disturbance Theory of Mergers’, 83 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 624-642. Gorton, Gary and Rosen, Richard (1995), ‘Corporate Control, Portfolio Choice, and the Decline of Banking’, 50 Journal of Finance, 1377-1420. Grabowski, Richard, Mathur, Ike and Rangan, Nanda (1995), ‘The Role of Takeovers in Increasing Efficiency’, 16 Managerial and Decision Economics, 211-223. Greenaway, David (1995), ‘Policy Forum - Corporate Governance’, 105 Economic Journal, 676-677. Griffin, James M. and Wiggings, Steven N. (1992), ‘Takeovers: Managerial Incompetence or Managerial Shirking?’, 30 Economic Inquiry, 355-370. Grossman, Sanford J. and Hart, Oliver D. (1980), ‘Takeover Bids, the Free-Rider Problem, and the Theory of the Corporation’, 11 Bell Journal of Economics, 42-64. Grossman, Sanford J. and Hart, Oliver D. (1988), ‘One Share-One Vote and the Market for Corporate Control’, 20 Journal of Financial Economics, 175-202. Guerin-Calvert, Margaret E., McGuckin, Robert H. and Warren-Boulton, Frederick R. (1987), ‘State and Federal Regulation in the Market for Corporate Control’, 32 Antitrust Bulletin, 661-691. Hackl, Jo Watson and Testani, Rosa Anna (1988), ‘Second Generation State Takeover Statutes and Shareholder Wealth: An Empirical Study’, 97 Yale Law Journal, 1193-1231. Haddock, David D., Macey, Jonathan R. and McChesney, Fred (1987), ‘Property Rights in Assets and Resistance to Tender Offers’, 73 Virginia Law Review, 701-746. Hahn, Dieter (1990), ‘Takeover Rules in the European Community: An Economic Analysis of Proposed Takeover Guidelines and Already Issued Disclosure Rules’, 10 International Review of Law and Economics, 131-148. Hancock, G.D. (1992), ‘Battles for Control: An Overview of Proxy Contests’, 18 Managerial Finance, 59-76. Harrington, Joseph E., Jr and Prokop, J. (1993), ‘The Dynamics of the Free-Rider Problem in Takeovers’, 6 Review of Financial Studies, 851-882. Harris, Ellie, G. (1990), ‘Antitakeover Measures, Golden Parachutes, and Target Firm Shareholder Welfare’, 21 Rand Journal of Economics, 614-625. Harris, Ellie, G. (1994), ‘Why One Firm is the Target and Other the Bidder in Single-Bidder Synergistic Takeovers’, 67 Journal of Business, 263-280. Harris, Milton and Raviv, Artur (1988), ‘Corporate Governance: Voting Rights and Majority Rules’, 20 Journal of Financial Economics, 203-235. Harris, Milton and Raviv, Artur (1988), ‘Corporate Control Contests and Capital Structure’, 20 Journal of Financial Economics, 55-86. Hart, Oliver D. (1995), ‘Corporate Governance: Some Theory and Implications’, 105 Economic Journal: The Journal of the Royal Economic Society, 678-689. Healy, Paul M., Palepu, Krishna G. and Ruback, Richard S. (1992), ‘Does Corporate Performance Improve After Mergers?’, 31 Journal of Financial Economics, 135-175. Hermann, Werner and Santoni, G. J. (1989), ‘The Cost of Restricting Corporate Takeovers: A Lesson from Switzerland’, 71 Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis Review, 3-11.
5640
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
759
Hersch, Philip L. and McDougall, Gerald S. (1992), ‘Separation of Ownership from Control and the Demand for Corporate Aircraft’, 44 Journal of Economics and Business, 223-236. Herzel, Leo (1990), ‘Corporate Governance Through Statistical Eyes’, 27 Journal of Financial Economics, 581-593. Hill, Alfred (1957), ‘The Sale of Controlling Shares’, 70 Harvard Law Review, 986-1039. Hirschey, Mark (1986), ‘Mergers, Buyouts and Takeouts’, 76 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 317-322. Hirschleifer, David and Titman, Sheridan (1990), ‘Share Tendering Strategies and the Success of Hostile Takeover Bids’, 98 Journal of Political Economy, 295-324. Hitt, Michael, A., Hoskisson, Robert E., Johnson, Richard A. and Moesel, Douglas D. (1996), ‘The Market for Corporate Control and Firm Innovation’, 39 Academy of Management Journal, 1084-1119. Högholm, Kenneth (1994), Essays in the Market for Corporate Control, Helsinki, Swedish School of Economics and Business Administration. Holl, Peter (1973), ‘Control Type and the Market for Corporate Control in Large U.S. Corporations’, 25 Journal of Industrial Economics, 259-273. Holl, Peter and Pickering, J.F. (1991), ‘Takeovers and Other Influences on Economic Performance A Plant Level Analysis’, 23 Applied Economics, 1779-1788. Hopt, Klaus J. (1984), ‘New Ways in Corporate Governance: European Experiments with Labor Representation on Corporate Boards’, 82 Michigan Law Review, 1338-1363. Hopt, Klaus J. (1994), ‘Labor Representation on Coporate Boards: Impacts and Problems for Corporate Governance and Economic Integration in Europe’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 203-214. Hoskisson, Robert E. and Turk, Thomas A. (1990), ‘Corporate Restructing: Governance and Control Limits of the Internal Capital Market’, 15 Academy of Management Review, 459-477. Hoskisson, Robert E., Johnson, Richard A. and Moesel, Douglas D. (1994), ‘Corporate Divestiture Intensity in Restructuring Firms: Effects of Governance, Strategy, and Performance’, 37 Academy of Management Journal, 1207-1251. Hovenkamp Herbert J. (1991), Enterprise and American Law, 1836-1937, Cambridge (MA), Harvard University Press. Husson, B. (1987), Le Prise de Contrôle d’Entreprises (Takeovers), Paris, Presses Universitaires de France (PUF). Ikenberry, David and Lakonishok, Josef (1993), ‘Corporate Governance through the Proxy Contest: Evidence and Implications’, 66 Journal of Business, 405-435. Israel, Ronen (1991), ‘Capital Structure and the Market for Corporate Control: The Defensive Role of Debt Financing’, 46 Journal of Finance, 1391-1409. Jahera, John S., Jr and Pugh, William N. (1991), ‘State Takeover Legislation: The Case of Delaware’, 7 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 410-428. James, Christopher M. (1984), ‘An Analysis of the Effect of State Acquisition Laws on Managerial Efficiency: The Case of the Bank Holding Company Acquisitions’, 27 Journal of Law and Economics, 211-226. Jarrell, Gregg A. (1985), ‘The Wealth Effects of Litigation by Targets: Do Interests Diverge in a Merger?’, 28 Journal of Law and Economics, 151-179. Jarrell, Gregg A. (1992), ‘The 1980s Takeover Boom and Government Regulation’, 15 Regulation, 44-53.
760
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
5640
Jarrell, Gregg A. and Bradley, Michael D. (1980), ‘The Economic Effects of Federal and State Regulations of Cash Tender Offers’, 23 Journal of Law and Economics, 371-407. Jarrell, Gregg A. and Poulsen, Annette B. (1987), ‘Shark Repellents and Stock Prices: The Effects of Antitakeover Amendements since 1980', 19 Journal of Financial Economics, 127-168. Jarrell, Gregg A., Brickley, James A. and Netter, Jeffrey M. (1988), ‘The Market for Corporate Control: The Empirical Evidence since 1980', 2 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 49-68. Jenkinson, T. and Mayer, Colin (1992), ‘The Assessment - Corporate Governance and Corporate Control’, 8 Oxford Review of Economic Policy, 1-10. Jennings, R.H. (1994), ‘Intraday Changes in Target Firms Share Price and Bid-Ask Quotes Around Takeover Announcements’, 17 Journal of Financial Research, 255-270. Jennings, R.H. and Mazzeo, M.A. (1993), ‘Competing Bids, Target Management Resistance, and the Structure of Takeover Bids’, 6 Review of Financial Studies, 883-909. Jennings, Richard W. (1956), ‘Trading in Corporate Control’, 44 California Law Review, 1-39. Jensen, Michael C. (1984), ‘Takeovers: Folklore and Science’, 6 Harvard Business Review, 109-121. Jensen, Michael C. (1986), ‘Agency Costs and Free Cash Flow, Corporate Finance, and Takeovers’, 76 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 323-329. Jensen, Michael C. (1988), ‘Takeovers: Their Causes and Consequences’, 2 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 21-48. Jensen, Michael C. (1989), ‘The Takeover Controversy: Analysis and Evidence’, in Coffee, John, Lowenstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (eds), Takeovers and Contests for Corporate Control, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Jensen, Michael C. and Meckling, W. (1976), ‘Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behavior, Agency Costs and Owership Structure’, 3 Journal of Financial Economics, 305-360. Reprinted in Jensen, Michael C. and Smith, Clifford W. Jr (eds), The Modern Theory of Corporate Finance, McCraw-Hill, 1984. Jensen, Michael C. and Ruback, Richard S. (1983), ‘The Market for Corporate Control: The Scientific Evidence’, 11 Journal of Financial Economics, 5-50. Johnson, Lyman and Mylon, David (1989), ‘Missing the Point About State Takeover Statutes’, 87 Michigan Law Review, 846-857. Kabir, R., Cantrijn, D. and Jeunink, A. (1997), ‘Takeover Defenses, Ownership Structure and Stock Returns in the Netherlands: An Empirical Analysis’, 18 Strategic Management Journal, 97-109. Kackl, Jo Watson and Testani, Rosa Anna (1988), ‘Note: Second Generation State Takeover Statutes and Shareholder Wealth: An Empirical Study’, 97 Yale Law Journal, 1193 ff. Kahan, Marcel (1992), ‘Securities Laws and the Social Costs of “Inaccurate” Stock Prices’, 42 Duke Law Journal, 977-1044. Kahan, Marcel (1993), ‘Sales of Corporate Control’, 9 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 368-379. Kahan, Marcel (1994), ‘Paramount or Paradox: The Delaware Supreme Court’s Takeover Jurisprudence’, 19 Journal of Corporation Law, 583 ff. Kahan, Marcel and Bebchuk, Lucian Arye (1989), ‘Fairness Opinions: How Fair Are They and What Can Be Done About It?’, Duke Law Journal, 27 ff. Reprinted in 32 Corporate Practice Commentator, 1990, p. 1.
5640
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
761
Kahan, Marcel and Bebchuk, Lucian Arye (1990), ‘A Framework for Analyzing Legal Policy Towards Proxy Contests’, 78 California Law Review, 1071 ff. Kahan, Marcel and Klausner, Michael (1993), ‘Anti-Takeover Provisions in Bonds: Bondholder Protection or Management Entrenchment’, 40 UCLA Law Review, 931 ff. Reprinted in 35 Corporate Practice Commentator 575, 1994. Kahan, Marcel and Klausner, Michael (1996), ‘Lockups and the Market for Corporate Control’, Stanford Law Review. Kamien, Morton I. and Zang, Israel (1993), ‘Monopolization by Sequential Acquisition’, 9 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 205-229. Kamin, Jacob Y. and Ronen, Joshua (1978), ‘The Effects of Corporate Control on Apparent Profit Performance’, 45 Southern Economic Journal, 181-191. Kang, Jun-Koo (1993), ‘The International Market for Corporate Control: Mergers and Acquisitions of U.S. Firms by Japanese Firms’, 34 Journal of Financial Economics, 345-371. Kang, Jun-Koo and Shivdasani, A (1995), ‘Firm Performance, Corporate Governance, and Top Executive Turnover in Japan’, 38 Journal of Financial Economics, 29-58. Karpoff, Jonathan M. and Malatesta, Paul H. (1989), ‘The Wealth Effects of 2nd-Generation State Takeover Legislation’, 25 Journal of Financial Economics, 291-322. Katz, Wilbur G. (1957), ‘The Sale of Corporate Control’, 38 Chicago Bar Record, 376-380. Kester, W. Carl (1991), Japanese Takeovers: The Global Contest for Corporate Control, Boston, Harvard Business School. Kester, W. Carl (1991), ‘Global Players, Western Tactics, Japanese Outcomes: The New Japanese Market for Corporate Control’, 33 California Management Review, 58-70. King, Mervyn and Röell, Ailsa (1988), ‘The Regulation of Takeovers and the Stock Market’, National Westminster Bank Quarterly Review, 2-14. Klausner, Michael and Kahan, Marcel (1993), ‘Antitakeover Provisions in Bonds: Bondholder Protection or Management Entrenchment?’, 40 UCLA Law Review, 931 ff. Klausner, Michael and Kahan, Marcel (1996), ‘Lockups and the Market for Corporate Control’, 48 Stanford Law Review. Knoeber, Charles R. (1986), ‘Golden Parachutes, Shark Repellents, and Hostile Tender Offers’, 76 American Economic Review, 155-167. Kornhauser, Lewis A. and Gordon, J. (1986), ‘Takeover Defense Tactics: A Comment on Two Models’, 96 Yale Law Journal, 295 ff. Kraakman, Reinier H. (1988), ‘Taking Discounts Seriously: The Implications of ‘Discounted’ Share Prices as an Acquisition Motive’, 88 Columbia Law Review, 891-941. Kraakman, Reinier H. (1990), ‘Discounted Share Prices as a Source of Acquisition Gains’, in Bebchuk, L. (ed.), Corporate Law and Economic Analysis, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 29-73. Kyle, Albert S. and Vila, Jean-Luc (1991), ‘Noise Trading and Takeovers’, 22 Rand Journal of Economics, 54-71. Laffont, Jean-Jacques and Tirole, Jean (1988), ‘Repeated Auctions of Incentive Contracts, Investment, and Bidding Parity with an Application to Takeovers’, 19 Rand Journal of Economics, 516-537. Lang, Larry H.P., Stulz, Rene M. and Walkling, Ralph A. (1991), ‘A Test of the Free Cash Flow Hypothesis: The Case of Bidder Returns’, 29 Journal of Financial Economics, 315-335.
762
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
5640
Lawriwsky, Michael, L. (1984), ‘Some Tests of the Influence of Control Type on the Market for Corporate Control in Australia’, 32 Journal of Industrial Economics, 277-291. Lease, Ronald C., McConnell, J.J. and Mikkelson, Wayne, H. (1983), ‘The Market Value of Control in Publicly-Traded Corporations’, 11 Journal of Financial Economics, 439-471. Leech, Dennis (1987), ‘Corporate Ownership and Control: A New Look at the Evidence of Berle and Means’, 39 Oxford Economic Papers, 534-551. Leech, Noyes (1956), ‘Transactions in Corporate Control’, 104 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 725-839. Lehn, Kenneth and Mitchell, Mark L. (1990), ‘Do Bad Bidders Become Good Targets?’, 98 Journal of Political Economy, 372-398. Lehn, Kenneth, Netter, Jeffrey and Poulsen, Annette B. (1990), ‘Consolidating Corporate Control: Dual-Class Recapitalizations versus Leveraged Buyouts’, 27 Journal of Financial Economics, 557-580. Lemieux, Pierre (1991), Apologie des Sorcières Modernes (An Apology of Modern Witches), Paris, Belles Lettres. Levmore, Saul (1982), ‘Monitors and Freeriders in Commercial and Corporate Settings’, 92 Yale Law Journal, 49-83. Levmore, Saul (1987), ‘A Primer on the Sale of Corporate Control (Book Review Essay)’, 65 Texas Law Review, 1061-1070. Levy, David T. and Reitzes, James D. (1992), ‘Anticompetitive Effects of Mergers in Markets with Localized Competition’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 427-440. Lichtenberg, Frank, R. (1992), Corporate Takeovers and Productivity, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Linn, Scott, C. and McConnell, J.J. (1983), ‘An Empirical Investigation of the Impact of “Antitakeover” Amendments on Common Stock Prices’, 11 Journal of Financial Economics, 362-400. Lipton, Martin and Rosenblum, Steven A. (1991), ‘A New System of Corporate Governance: The Quinquennial Election of Directors’, 58 University of Chicago Law Review, 187-253. Loderer, Claudio and Martin, Kenneth J. (1990), ‘Corporate Acquisitions by Listed Firms: The Experience of a Comprehensive Sample’, 19 Financial Management, 17-33. Loderer, Claudio and Martin, Kenneth J. (1992), ‘Postacquisition Performance of Acquiring Firms’, 21 Financial Management, 69-79. Lutter, Marcus and Wahlers, Henning W. (1989), ‘Der Buyout: Amerikanische Fälle und die Regeln des Deutschen Rechts (The Buyout: American Cases and the German Rules)’, 34 Die Aktiengesellschaft, 1-17. Luttmann, Ruth (1992), ‘Changes of Corporate Control and Mandatory Bids’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 497-516. Macey, Jonathan R. (1986), ‘Takeover Defense Tactics and Legal Scholarship: Market Forces versus the Policymaker’s Dilemma’, 96 Yale Law Journal, 342-352. Macey, Jonathan R. (1988), ‘State Anti-Takeover Legislation and the National Economy’, 64 Wisconsin Law Review, 467 ff. Macey, Jonathan R. and McChesney, Fred S. (1985), ‘A Theoretical Analysis of Corporate Greenmail’, 95 Yale Law Journal, 13-61.
5640
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
763
Machlin, Judith, C., Choe, Hyuk and Miles, James A. (1993), ‘The Effects of Golden Parachutes on Takeover Activity’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 861-876. MacMinn, Richard, D. and Cook, Douglas O. (1991), ‘An Anatomy of the Poison Pill’, 12 Managerial and Decision Economics, 481-487. Madden, Gerald, P. (1981), ‘Potential Corporate Takeovers and Market Efficiency: A Note’, 36 Journal of Finance, 1191-1197. Malatesta, Paul H. (1983), ‘The Wealth Effect of Merger Activity and the Objective Functions of the Merging Firms’, 11 Journal of Financial Economics, 155-181. Malatesta, Paul H. and Walkling, Ralph A. (1988), ‘Poison Pill Securities: Stockholder Wealth, Profitability, and Ownership Structure’, 20 Journal of Financial Economics, 347-376. Maloney, Michael T. and McCormick, Robert E. (1988), ‘Excess Capacity, Cyclical Production, and Merger Motives: Some Evidence from the Capital Markets’, 31 Journal of Law and Economics, 321-350. Manne, Henry G. (1962), ‘The Higher Criticism of the Modern Corporation’, 62 Columbia Law Review, 399-432. Manne, Henry G. (1965), ‘Mergers and the Market for Corporate Control’, 73 Journal of Political Economy, 110-120. Manne, Henry G. (1967), ‘Cash Tender Offers for Shares: A Reply to Chairman Cohen’, Duke Law Journal, 231-253. Manne, Henry G. (1984), ‘In Defense of the Corporate Coup’, 11 Northern Kentucky Law Review, 513-518. Margotta, Donald G., McWilliams, Thomas P. and McWilliams, Victoria B. (1990), ‘An Analysis of the Stock Price Effect of the 1986 Ohio Takeover Legislation’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 235-251. Marr, M. Wayne, Mohta, Sanjeev and Spivey, Michael F. (1993), ‘An Analysis of Foreign Takeovers in the United States’, 14 Managerial and Decision Economics, 285-294. Martin, Kenneth J. and McConnell, J.J. (1991), ‘Corporate Performance, Corporate Takeovers, and Management Turnover’, 46 Journal of Finance, 671-687. Mathur, Ike and De, Soumendra (1989), ‘A Review of the Theories of and Evidence on Returns Related to Mergers and Takeovers’, 15 Managerial Finance, 1-11. Mathur, Ike, Rangan, Nanda, Chhachhi, Indudeep and Sundaram, Sridhar (1994), ‘International Acquisitions in the United States: Evidence From Returns to Foreign Bidders’, 15 Managerial and Decision Economics, 107-118. Matsusaka, J.G. (1993), ‘Takeover Motives during the Conglomerate Merger Wave’, 24 Rand Journal of Economics, 357-379. Maule, C.J. (1969), ‘Antitrust and the Takeover Activity of American Firms in Canada: A Rejoinder’, 12 Journal of Law and Economics, 419-424. Maule, C.J. (1970), ‘Antitrust and the Takeover Activity of American Firms in Canada: A Final Comment’, 13 Journal of Law and Economics, 261 ff. McCardle, Kevin, F. and Viswanathan, S. (1994), ‘The Direct Entry versus Takeover Decision and Stock Price Performance’, 67 Journal of Business, 1-43. McChesney, Fred S. (1986), ‘Assumptions, Empirical Evidence and Social Science Theory’, 96 Yale Law Journal, 339-341. McEachern, William A. (1978), ‘Corporate Control and Growth: an Alternative Approach’, 26 Journal of Industrial Economics, 257-266. McGee, Robert W. (1977), ‘Planning a Tax-Free Corporate Reorganization: Selecting the One Best Suite to a Client’s Needs’, Taxation for Lawyers, 36-41.
764
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
5640
McGee, Robert W. (1988), ‘Mergers and Acquisitions: An Economic and Legal Analysis’, 22(3) Creighton Law Review, 665-693. McGee, Robert W. (1989), ‘Ethical Issues in Acquisitions and Mergers’, 25(5) Mid-Atlantic Journal of Business, 19-39. McGee, Robert W. (1990), ‘The Economic Effects of Antitakeover Gimmicks: An American View’, 10(3) Economic Affairs, 14-20. McGee, Robert W. (1992), ‘Ethical Issues in Acquisitions and Mergers’, in McGee, Robert W. (ed.), Business Ethics and Common Sense, Westport, Quorum Books, 167-185. McGee, Robert W. and Block, Walter E. (1990), ‘Information, Privilege, Opportunity and Insider Trading’, 10(1) Northern Illinois University Law Review, 1-35. McGee, Robert W. and Block, Walter E. (1992), ‘Insider Trading’, in McGee, Robert W. (ed.), Business Ethics and Common Sense, Westport, Quorum Books, 219-229. McKee, David L. (ed.) (1989), Hostile Takeovers: Issues in Public and Corporate Policy, New York, Greenwood Press, 179 p. McWilliams, V.B. (1990), ‘Managerial Share Ownership and the Stock Price Effects of Antitakeover Amendment Proposals’, 45 Journal of Finance, 1627-1640. Megginson, W.L. (1990), ‘’Restricted Voting Stock Acquisition Premiums, and the Market Value of Corporate Control’, 25 Financial Review, 175-198. Mehran, Hamid (1992), ‘Executive Incentive Plans, Corporate Control, and Capital Structure’, 287 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 539-560. Meier-Schatz, Christian (1987), ‘Unternehmenszusammenschlüsse Mittels Übernahmeangebot (Mergers by Takeover Bid)’, 39 Wirtschaft und Recht, 16-39. Mikkelson, Wayne, H. and Partch, M. Megan (1989), ‘Managers’ Voting Rights and Corporate Control’, 25 Journal of Financial Economics, 263-290. Miller, Geoffrey P. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1988), ‘Trans-Union Reconsidered’,, 98 Yale Law Journal, 127 ff. Miller, Geoffrey P. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1988), ‘Bank Failures, Risk Monitoring, and the Market for Corporate Control’, 88 Columbia Law Review, 1153 ff. Millstein, Ira M. and Bicks, Robert (1977), ‘Antitrust Aspects of Takeovers and Mergers - the Hart Scott Rodino Antitrust Improvement Act of 1976’, 32 Business Lawyer, 1517-1532. Mitchell, Mark L. and Mulherin, J. Harold (1989), ‘The Stock Price Response to Pension Terminations and the Relation of Terminations with Corporate Takeovers’, 18 Financial Management, 41-56. Mitchell, Mark L. and Mulherin, J. Harold (1996), ‘The Impact of Industry Shocks on Takeover and Restructing Activity’, 41 Journal of Financial Economics, 193-229. Mitchell, Mark L. and Netter, Jeffrey (1989), ‘Triggering the 1987 Stock Market Crash: Antitakeover Provisions in the Proposed House Ways and Means Tax Bill?’, 24 Journal of Financial Economics, 37-68. Mnookin, Robert H. and Wilson, Robert B. (1989), ‘Rational Bargaining and Market Efficiency: Understanding Pennzoil v. Texaco’, 75 Virginia Law Review, 295-334. Morck, Randall, Shleifer, Andrei and Vishny, Robert W. (1988), ‘Management Ownership and Market Valuation: An Empirical Analysis’, 20 Journal of Financial Economics, 293-315. Morck, Randall, Shleifer, Andrei and Vishny, Robert W. (1988), ‘Characteristics of Targets of Hostile and Friendly Takeovers’, in Auerbach, Alan J. (ed.), Corporate Takeovers: Causes and Consequences, Chicago, IL, University of Chicago Press, 101-129.
5640
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
765
Morck, Randall, Shleifer, Andrei and Vishny, Robert W. (1989), ‘Alternative Mechanisms for Corporate Control’, 79 American Economic Review, 842-852. Morck, Randall, Shleifer, Andrei and Vishny, Robert W. (1990), ‘Do Managerial Objectives Drive Bad Acquisitions?’, 45 Journal of Finance, 31-48. Mueller, Dennis C. (1995), ‘Corporate Takeovers and Productivity’, 50 Journal of Finance, 383-387. Mukherjee, Tarun, K. and Verla, Oscar (1992), ‘Corporate Behavior After the Proxy Contest for Control: The Short, Intermediate and Long Term’, 18 Managerial Finance, 77-97. Murray, Louis, C. (1991), ‘A Study on the Wealth Effects of Irish Takeovers and Mergers’, 12 Managerial and Decision Economics, 67-72. Nagarajan, S. (1995), ‘On the Generic Efficiency of Takeovers Under Incomplete Information’, 65 Journal of Economic Theory, 522-556. Nathan, Kevin, S. and O’Keefe, Terrence B. (1989), ‘The Rise in Takeover Premiums: An Exploratory Study’, 23 Journal of Financial Economics, 101-109. New York Stock Exchange (1963), Company Manual, Published for the NYSE by Commerce Clearing House. Niden, D.M. (1993), ‘An Empirical Examination of White Knight Corporate Takeovers - Synergy and Overbidding’, 22 Financial Management, 28-45. Nyberg, S. (1995), ‘Reciprocal Shareholding and Takeover Deterrence International’, 13 Journal of Industrial Organization, 355-372. Palepu, Krishna, G. (1986), ‘Predicting Takeover Targets: A Methodological and Empirical Analysis’, 8 Journal of Accounting and Economics, 3-35. Palepu, Krishna, G. (1990), ‘Consequences of Leveraged Buyouts’, 27 Journal of Financial Economics, 247-262. Pelikan, Pavel (1989), ‘Evolution, Economic Competence, and the Market for Corporate Control’, 12 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 279-303. Perkins, Rosewell, B. (1995), ‘Corporate Governance in the New Russia’, 14 International Financial Law Review, 12-15. Persons, J.C. (1994), ‘Signaling and Takeover Deterrence with Stock Repurchases - Dutch Auctions Versus Fixed Price Tender Offers’, 49 Journal of Finance, 1373-1402. Pickens, T. Boone, Jr (1988), ‘Takeovers: A Purge of Poor Managements’, 77 Management Review, 52-55. Png, Ivan Paak-Liang and Hirshleifer D. (1990), ‘Facilitation of Competing Bids and the Price of a Takeover Target’, 2 Review of Financial Studies, 587-606. Pontiff, Jeffrey, Shleifer, Andrei and Weisbach, Michael S. (1990), ‘Reversions of Excess Pension Assets After Takeovers’, 21 Rand Journal of Economics, 600-613. Pound, John (1987), ‘The Effects of Antitakeover Amendments of Takeover Activity: Some Direct Evidence’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 353-367. Pound, John (1988a), ‘The Information Effects of Takeover Bids and Resistance’, 22 Journal of Financial Economics, 207-227. Pound, John (1988b), ‘Proxy Contests and the Efficiency of Shareholder Oversight’, 20 Journal of Financial Economics, 237-265. Pound, John (1989), ‘Shareholder Activism and Share Values - The Causes and Consequences of Countersolicitations Against Management Antitakeover Proposals’, 32 Journal of Law and Economics, 357-379.
766
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
5640
Pound, John (1992a), ‘On the Motives for Choosing a Corporate Governance Structure: A Study of Corporate Reaction to the Pennsylvania Takeover Law’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 656-672. Pound, John (1992b), ‘Beyond Takeovers: Politics Comes to Corporate Control’, 70 Harvard Business Review, 83-93. Pound, John (1993), ‘The Rise of the Political Model of Corporate Governance’, 68 New York University Law Review, 1003-1071. Pound, John, Lehn, Kenneth and Jarrell, Gregg A. (1986), ‘Are Takeovers Hostile to Economic Performance?’, 10(1) Regulation, 25-56. Prokesch, Steven, H (1993), ‘Corporate Governance’, 71 Harvard Business Review, 10 ff. Pugh, W.N. and Jahera, John S., Jr (1990), ‘State Antitakeover Legislation and Shareholder Wealth’, 13(3) Journal of Financial Research, 221-231. Ramseyer, J. Mark (1987), ‘Takeovers in Japan: Opportunism, Ideology and Corporate Control’, 35 UCLA Law Review, 1-64. Ravenscraft, David J. and Scherer, Frederic M. (1987), Mergers, Sell-offs, and Economic Efficiency, Washington, Brookings Institution. Reuber, Grant L. (1969), ‘Antitrust and the Takeover Activity of American Firms in Canada: A Further Analysis’, 12 Journal of Law and Economics, 405-417. Reuber, Grant L. (1970), ‘Antitrust and the Takeover Activity of American Firms in Canada: A Reply’, 13 Journal of Law and Economics, 257-259. Rhodes, M.J. (1991), ‘The White Knight Privilege in Litigated Takeovers - Leveling The Playing Field in Discovery’, 43 Stanford Law Review, 445-473. Ribstein, Larry E. (1989), ‘Takeover Defenses and the Corporate Contract’, 78 Georgetown Law Journal, 71 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. (1992), ‘Efficiency, Regulation and Competition: A Comment on Easterbrook and Fischel’, 87 Northwestern University Law Review, 254 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. (1993), ‘The Mandatory Rules of the ALI Code’, 61 George Washington Law Review, 984 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. and Adler, Barry E. (1989), ‘Debt, Leveraged Buyouts, and Corporate Governance’, Cato Policy Analysis, 120 ff. Rietkerk, G. (1988), ‘Bestuursonvriendelijke Onderneming: een Countervailing Power. Een Economische Analyse (Management Unfriendly Take-over: A Countervailing Power. An Economic Analysis)’, 66 De Naamloze Vennootschap, 45-54. Roe, Mark J. (1990), ‘Political and Legal Restraints on Ownership and Control of Public Companies’, 27 Journal of Financial Economics, 7-41. Roe, Mark J. (1993), ‘Takeover Politics’, in Blair, Margaret, M. (ed.), The Deal Decade, Washington, DC, Brookings Institution. Roe, Mark J. (1994), Strong Managers, Weak Owners: The Policital Roots of American Corporate Finance, Princeton, Princeton University Press. Roll, Richard (1986), ‘The Hubris Hypothesis of Corporate Takeovers’, 59 Journal of Business, 197-216. Roll, Richard (1987), ‘Empirical Evidence on Takeover Activity and Shareholder Wealth’, in Copeland, T.E. (ed.), Modern Finance and Industrial Economics: Papers in, New York, Blackwell. Romano, Roberta (1985), ‘Law as a Product: Some Pieces of the Incorporation Puzzle’, 1 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 225-283. Romano, Roberta (1987), ‘The Political Economy of Takeover Statutes’, 73 Virginia Law Review, 111-199.
5640
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
767
Romano, Roberta (1993), ‘Public Pension Fund Activism in Corporate Governance Reconsidered’, 93 Columbia Law Review, 795-853. Ronen, Joshua (1988), ‘Sale of Controlling Interest: A Financial Economic Analysis of the Governing Law in the United States and Canada’, 13 Canada-United States Law Journal, 263-298. Rosenbaum, Robert D. and Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1988), ‘The Corporate Takeover Game and Recent Legislative Attempts to Define Insider Trading’, 26 American Criminal Law Review, 229 ff. Ryan, Patrick J. (1989), ‘Corporate Directors and the “Social Costs” of Takeovers - Reflections on the Tin Parachute’, 64 Tulane Law Review, 3-70. Ryngaert, Michael (1988), ‘The Effect of Poison Pill Securities on Shareholder Wealth’, 20 Journal of Financial Economics, 377-417. Ryngaert, Michael (1989), ‘Firm Valuation, Takeover Defenses and the Delaware Supreme Court’, 18 Financial Management, 20-28. Ryngaert, Michael and Netter, Jeffry M. (1988), ‘Shareholder Wealth Effects on the Ohio Antitakeover Law’, 4 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 373-383. Ryngaert, Michael and Netter, Jeffry M. (1990), ‘Shareholder Wealth Effects of the 1986 Ohio Antitakeover Law Revisited: Its Real Effects’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 253-262. Salancik, Gerald, R. and Meindl, James R. (1984), ‘Corporate Attributions as Strategic Illusions of Management Control’, 29 Administrative Science Quarterly, 238-254. Santerre, Rexford E. and Neun, Stephen P (1993), ‘’Corporate Control and Performance in the 1930s’, 31 Economic Inquiry, 466-480. Saul, Ralph, S. (1985), ‘Hostile Takeovers: What Should be Done?’, 63 Harvard Business Review, 18-24. Scherer, Frederic M. (1986), ‘Takeovers: Present and Future Dangers’, 4 Brookings Review, 15-20. Scherer, Frederic M. (1988), ‘Corporate Takeovers: The Efficiency Arguments’, 2 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 69-82. Scherer, Frederic M. and Ross David (1990), Industrial Market Structure and Economic Performance, Third Edition, Boston, Houghton Mifflin. Schipper, Katherine and Thompson, Rex (1983a), ‘Evidence on the Capitalized Value of Merger Activity for Acquiring Firms’, 11 Journal of Financial Economics, 85-119. Schipper, Katherine and Thompson, Rex (1983b), ‘The Impact of Merger-Related Regulations on the Shareholders of Acquiring Firms’, 21 Journal of Accounting Research, 184-221. Schnitzer, Monika (1995), ‘Breach of Trust in Takeovers and the Optimal Corporate Charter’, 43 Journal of Industrial Economics, 229-259. Schnitzer, Monika (1996), ‘Hostile Versus Friendly Takeovers’, 63 Economica, 37-55. Schranz, Mary, S. (1993), ‘Takeovers Improve Firm Performance: Evidence from the Banking Industry’, 101 Journal of Political Economy, 299-326. Schüller, Alfred (1979), ‘Eigentumsrechte, Unternehmenskontrollen und Wettbewerbsordnung (Property Rights, Corporate Control and Competition)’, 30 Ordo: Jahrbuch für die Ordnung von Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft, 325-364. Schumann, Laurence (1988), ‘State Regulation of Takeovers and Shareholder Wealth: The Case of New York’s 1985 Takeover Statutes’, 19 Rand Journal of Economics, 557-567. Schüttrumpf, Veit-G. (1995), ‘Comment: Hostile Takeovers: Some Reasons for the Different Legal Solutions and Some Thoughts about the Role of German Banks’, in Bouckaert, Boudewijn and De
768
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
5640
Geest, Gerrit (eds), Essays in Law and Economics II: Contract Law, Regulation, and Reflections on Law and Economics, Antwerpen, Maklu, 135-143. Schwartz, Alan (1986a), ‘Bebchuck on Minimum Offer Periods’, 2 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 271-277. Schwartz, Alan (1986b), ‘Search Theory and the Tender Offer Auction’, 2 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 229-253. Schwartz, Alan (1988), ‘The Fairness of Tender Offer Prices in Utilitarian Theory’, 17 Journal of Legal Studies, 165-196. Schwartz, Alan (1989), ‘Defensive Tactics and Optimal Search’, 5 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 413-424. Sercu, P. and Van Hulle, C. (1995), ‘On the Structure of Take-over Models and Insider-Outsider Conflicts in Negotiated Take-overs’, 19 Journal of Banking and Finance, 11-14. Sercu, P. and Vanhulle, C. (1995), ‘Financing Instruments, Security Design, and the Efficiency of Takeovers - A Note’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 373-393. Servaes, Henri (1991), ‘Tobin’s Q and the Gains from Takeovers’, 46 Journal of Finance, 409-419. Servaes, Henri (1994), ‘Do Takeover Targets Overinvest’, 7 Review of Financial Studies, 253-277. Seward, J.K. and Walsh, J.P. (1996), ‘The Governance and Control of Voluntary Corporate Spin-Offs’, 17 Strategic Management Journal, 25-39. Sheard, Paul (1989), ‘The Main Bank System and Corporate Monitoring and Control in Japan’, 11 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 399-422. Shivdasani, A (1993), ‘Board Composition, Ownership Structure and Hostile Takeovers’, 16 Journal of Accounting and Economics, 167-198. Shleifer, Andrei and Summers, Larry (1988), ‘Breach of Trust in Hostile Takeovers’, in Auerbach, Alan J. (ed.), Corporate Takeovers: Causes and Consequences, Chicago, IL, University of Chicago Press. Shleifer, Andrei and Vishny, Robert W. (1986), ‘Large Shareholders and Corporate Control’, 94 Journal of Political Economy, 461-488. Shleifer, Andrei and Vishny, Robert W. (1988), ‘Value Maximization and the Acquisition Process’, 2 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 7-20. Shleifer, Andrei and Vishny, Robert W. (1990), ‘The Takeover Wave of the 1980s’, 249 Science, 745-749. Shleifer, Andrei and Vishny, Robert W. (1991), ‘Takeovers in the 60s and the 80s - Evidence and Implications’, 12 Strategic Management Journal, 51-59. Shute, Laurence (1985), ‘J.M. Clark on Corporate Concentration and Control’, 19 Journal of Economic Issues, 409-418. Sidak, J. Gregory and Woodward, S. (1990), ‘Corporate Takeovers, the Commerce Clause, and the Efficient Anonimity of Shareholders’, 84 Northwestern University Law Review, 1092-1118. Simon, Carol J. (1989), ‘The Effect of the 1933 Securities Act on Investor Information and the Performance of New Issues’, 79 American Economic Review, 295-318. Sklar, Martin (1988), The Corporate Reconstruction of American Capitalism, 1890-1916: The Market, the Law, and Politics, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
5640
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
769
Slovin, Myron B. and Sushka, Marie E. (1993), ‘Ownership Concentration, Corporate Control Activity, and Firm Value: Evidence from the Death of Inside Blockholders’, 48 Journal of Finance, 1293-1321. Smiley, Robert H. (1975), ‘The Effect of the Williams Amendement and Other Factors on Transactions Costs in Tender Offers’, 3 Industrial Organization Review, 138-145. Smiley, Robert H. (1981), ‘The Effect of State Securities Statutes on Tender Offer Activity’, 19 Economic Inquiry, 426 ff. Smith, Craig, B. and Furlow, Clark W. (1988), Guide to the Takeover Law of Delaware, Washington, DC, Corporate Practice Series. Smith, E.D. and Salamon, Gerald L. (1979), ‘Corporate Control and Managerial Misrepresentation of Firm Performance’, 10 Bell Journal of Economics, 319-328. Smith, Richard L. and Kim, Joo-Hyun (1994), ‘The Combined Effects of Free Cash Flow and Financial Slack on Bidder and Target Stock Returns’, 67 Journal of Business, 281-310. Spindler, Gerald (1997), ‘Deregulierung des Aktienrechts? (Deregulation of Mandatory Corporate Law in Germany)’, 2 Die Aktiengesellschaft. Sridharan, Uma and Reinganum, Marc R. (1995), ‘Determinants of the Choice of the Hostile Takeover Mechanism: An Empirical Analysis of Tender Offers and Proxy Contests’, 24 Financial Management, 57-67. Stano, Miron (1976), ‘Monopoly Power, Ownership Control, and Corporate Performance’, 7 Bell Journal of Economics, 672-679. Stapleton, R.C. (1975), ‘Some Aspects of the Pure Theory of Corporate Finance: Bankruptcies and Take-Overs: Comment’, 6 Bell Journal of Economics, 708-710. Stigler, George J. (1950), ‘Monopoly and Oligopoly by Merger’, 40 American Economic Review, reprinted in Stigler, George J. (1968), The Organization of Industry, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1972), ‘Some Aspects of the Pure Theory of Corporate Finance: Bankruptcies and Take-Overs’, 3 Bell Journal of Economics, 458-482. Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1975), ‘Some Aspects of the Pure Theory of Corporate Finance: Bankruptcies and Take-Overs: Reply’, 6 Bell Journal of Economics, 711-714. Stillman, Robert (1983), ‘Examining Antitrust Policy toward Horizontal Mergers’, 11 Journal of Financial Economics, 225-240. Stone, Christopher, D. (1980), ‘The Place of Enterprise Liability in the Control of Corporate Conduct’, 90 Yale Law Journal, 1-77. Stout, Lynn A. (1988), ‘The Unimportance of Being Efficient: An Economic Analysis of Stock Market Pricing and Securities Regulation’, 87 Michigan Law Review, 613-709. Stout, Lynn A. (1990), ‘Are Takeover Premiums Really Premiums? Market Price, Fair Value, and Corporate Law’, 99 Yale Law Journal, 1235-1296. Stout, Lynn A. (1997), ‘How Efficient Markets Undervalue Stocks: CAPM and ECMH in a World of Uncertainty and Disagreement’, 18 Cardozo Law Review. Stulz, René M. (1988), ‘Managerial Control of Voting Rights: Financing Policies and the Market for Corporate Control’, 20 Journal of Financial Economics, 25-54. Stulz, Rene M., Walkling R. and Song, Moon H. (1990), ‘The Distribution of Target Ownership and the Division of Gains in Successful Takeovers’, 45 Journal of Finance, 817-833. Sunder, Shyam (1980), ‘Corporate Capital Investment, Accounting Methods and Earnings: A Test of the Control Hypothesis’, 35 Journal of Finance, 553-565.
770
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
5640
Szewczyk, Samuel, H and Tsetsekos, George P. (1992), ‘State Intervention in the Market for Corporate Control: The Case of Pennsylvania Senate Bill 1310', 31 Journal of Financial Economics, 3-23. Telser, Lester G. (1987), A Theory of Efficient Cooperation and Competition, Cambridge, New York and Melbourne, Cambridge University Press. Thompson, S. and Wright, M (1995), ‘The Role of Restructuring Transactions’, 105 Economic Journal: The Journal of the Royal Economic Society, 690-703. Thompson, S., Wright, M and Robbie, K. (1992), ‘Buy-Outs, Divestment, and Leverage-Restructuring Transactions and Corporate Governance’, 8 Oxford Review of Economic Policy, 58-69. Timonen, Pekka (1997), Määräysvalta, Hinta ja Markkinavoima - Julkisesti Noteeratun Yrityksen Määräysvallan Siirtymisen Oikeudellinen Sääntely (Control, Price and Market Power - The Judicial Regulation of Transfers of Control in Quoted Companies). Treynor, Jack, L. (1993), ‘The Value of Control’, 49 Financial Analysts Journal, 6-9. Triantis, George G. (1996), ‘The Interplay between Liquidation and Reorganization in Bankruptcy: The Role of Screens, Gatekeepers and Guillotines’, 16 International Review of Law and Economics, 101-119. Tripp, Malcolm A. (1984), ‘Note: Access, Efficiency, and Fairness in Dirks v. SEC’, 60 Indiana Law Journal, 535-557. Vahcic, A. (1989), ‘Capital Markets, Management Takeovers and Creation of New Firms in a Reformed Self-Managed Economy - Some Lessons from the Nova-Gorica (Yugoslavia) Experiment’, 33 European Economic Review, 456-465. Van Gerven, Yves (1991), ‘Regulering van Vijandige Overnames. De Amerikaanse Ervaring (Regulation of Hostile Takeovers: The American Experience)’,Rechtskundig Weekblad, 791-833. Van Hulle, C., Vermaelen, T. and De Wouters, Paul (1991), ‘Regulation,Taxes and the Market for Corporate Control in Belgium’, 15 Journal of Banking and Finance, 1143-1170. Van Nuys, Karen (1993), ‘Corporate Governance through the Proxy Process: Evidence from the 1989 Honeywell Proxy Solicitation’, 34 Journal of Financial Economics, 101-132. Wade, James, O’Reilly, Charles A., III and Chandratat, Ike (1990), ‘’Golden Parachutes: CEOs and the Exercise of Social Influence’, 35 Administrative Science Quarterly, 587-603. Walsh, J.P. and Kosnik, Rita D. (1993), ‘Corporate Raiders and Their Disciplinary Role in the Market for Corporate Control’, 36 Academy of Management Journal, 671-700. Weidenbaum, Murray L. and Chilton, Kenneth W. (eds) (1988), Public Policy toward Corporate Takeovers, New Brunswick, NJ, Transaction, 176 p. Weisbach, Michael S. (1993), ‘Corporate Governance and Hostile Takeovers’, 16 Journal of Accounting and Economics, 199-208. Weiss, Elliott J. (1981), ‘Social Regulation of Business Activity: Reforming the Corporate Governance System to Resolve an Institutional Impasse’, 28 UCLA Law Review, 343-437. Werden, Gregory J. and Froeb, Luke M. (1994), ‘The Effects of Mergers in Differentiated Products Industries: Logit Demand and Merger Policy’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 407-426. Weston, Fred J., Kwang, Chung S. and Hoag, Susan E. (1990), Mergers, Restructuring, and Corporate Control, Englewood Cliffs, NJ, Prentice-Hall.
5640
The Market for Corporate Control (Including Takeovers)
771
Williamson, Oliver E. (1983), ‘Organization Form, Residual Claimants, and Corporate Control’, 26 Journal of Law and Economics, 351-366. Williamson, Oliver E. (1988), ‘Corporate Finance and Corporate Governance’, 43 Journal of Finance, 567-591. Winsen, Joseph K. (1982), ‘Regulation of Trading in Corporate Equity: Constraints on Takeovers’, Nov Companies and Securities Law Journal, 91-115. Wintrobe, Ronald (1987), ‘The Market for Corporate Control and the Market for Political Control’, 3 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 435-448.
5650 INSIDER TRADING Stephen M. Bainbridge Professor, UCLA School of Law © Copyright 1999 Stephen M. Bainbridge
Abstract Insider trading is one of the most controversial aspects of securities regulation, even among the law and economics community. One set of scholars favors deregulation of insider trading, allowing corporations to set their own insider trading policies by contract. Another set of law and economics scholars, in contrast, contends that the property right to inside information should be assigned to the corporation and not subject to contractual reassignment. Deregulatory arguments are typically premised on the claims that insider trading promotes market efficiency or that assigning the property right to inside information to managers is an efficient compensation scheme. Public choice analysis is also a staple of the deregulatory literature, arguing that the insider trading prohibition benefits market professionals and managers rather than investors. The argument in favor of regulating insider trading traditionally was based on fairness, which predictably has had little traction in the law and economics community. Instead, the economic argument in favor of mandatory insider trading prohibitions has typically rested on some variant of the economics of property rights in information. JEL classification: K22, G30, G38 Keywords: Property Rights, Securities Regulation, Insider Trading, Securities Fraud
1. Introduction The law of insider trading is one way society allocates the property rights to information produced by a firm. In the United States, early common law permitted insiders to trade in a firm’s stock without disclosure of inside information. Over the last three decades, however, a complex federal prohibition of insider trading emerged as a central feature of modern US securities regulation. Other countries have gradually followed the US trend, although enforcement levels continue to vary substantially from country to country. Prohibiting insider trading is usually justified on fairness or equity grounds. Predictably, these arguments have had little traction in the law and economics community. At the same time, however, that community has not coalesced 772
5650
Insider Trading
773
around a single view of the prohibition; instead, competing economic arguments produced an extensive debate that is still active. Those law and economics scholars who favor deregulation of insider trading typically argue that efficiency is the sole basis for analyzing a legal regime, and that the prohibition lacks any rational economic basis. Those who favor regulating insider trading typically respond either by rejecting the claim that efficiency is the controlling criterion or by attempting to show that the prohibition is justifiable on efficiency grounds. Most observers of the literature likely would conclude that neither side has carried the field, but that the argument in favor of regulation probably is winning at the moment.
A. Overview of US Insider Trading Law Because the vast bulk of law and economics scholarship on insider trading refers to United States law, a brief overview of the current state of that law seems appropriate. Insider trading, generally speaking, is trading in securities while in possession of material nonpublic information. Under current United States law, there are three basic theories under which trading on inside information becomes unlawful. The disclose or abstain rule and the misappropriation theory were created by the courts under Section 10(b) of the Securities Exchange Act of 1934 and Rule 10b-5 thereunder. Pursuant to its rule-making authority under Exchange Act Section 14(e), the Securities and Exchange Commission (SEC) adopted Rule 14e-3 to proscribe insider trading involving information relating to tender offers. (Insider trading may also violate other statutes, such as the mail and wire fraud laws, which are beyond the scope of this chapter.)
2. The Disclose or Abstain Rule The modern federal insider prohibition began taking form in SEC v. Texas Gulf Sulphur Co. TGS, as it is commonly known, rested on a policy of equality of access to information. Accordingly, under TGS and its progeny, virtually anyone who possessed material nonpublic information was required either to disclose it before trading or abstain from trading in the affected company’s securities. If the would-be trader’s fiduciary duties precluded him from disclosing the information prior to trading, abstention was the only option. In Chiarella v. United States and Dirks v. SEC, the United States Supreme Court rejected the equal access policy. Instead, the Court made clear that liability could be imposed only if the defendant was subject to a duty to disclose prior to trading. Inside traders thus were no longer liable merely because they
774
Insider Trading
5650
had more information than other investors in the market place. Instead, a duty to disclose only arose where the inside traders breached a pre-existing fiduciary duty owed to the person with whom they traded. (Chiarella; Dirks, pp. 653-655). Creation of this fiduciary duty element substantially narrowed the scope of the disclose or abstain rule. But the rule remains quite expansive in a number of respects. In particular, it is not limited to true insiders, such as officers, directors and controlling shareholders, but picks up corporate outsiders in two important ways. Even in these situations, however, liability for insider trading under the disclose or abstain rule can only be found where the trader - insider or outsider - violates a fiduciary duty owed to the issuer or the person on the other side of the transaction. First, the rule can pick up a wide variety of nominal outsiders whose relationship with the issuer is sufficiently close to the issuer of the affected securities to justify treating them as ‘constructive insiders’, but only in rather narrow circumstances. The outsider must obtain material nonpublic information from the issuer. The issuer must expect the outsider to keep the disclosed information confidential. Finally, the relationship must at least imply such a duty. If these conditions are met, the putative outsider will be deemed a ‘constructive insider’ and subjected to the disclose or abstain rule in full measure (see Dirks, p. 655 n.14). If they are not met, however, the disclose or abstain rule simply does not apply. The critical issue thus remains the nature of the relationship between the parties. Second, the rule also picks up outsiders who receive inside information from either true insiders or constructive insiders. There are a number of restrictions on tippee liability, however. Most important for present purposes, the tippee’s liability is derivative of the tipper’s, ‘arising from his role as a participant after the fact in the insider’s breach of a fiduciary duty’ (ibid. p. 659). As a result, the mere fact of a tip is not sufficient to result in liability. What is proscribed is not merely a breach of confidentiality by the insider, but rather a breach of the duty of loyalty imposed on all fiduciaries to avoid personally profiting from information entrusted to them (see ibid. pp. 662-664). Thus, looking at objective criteria, a court must determine whether the insider personally will benefit, directly or indirectly, from his disclosure. So once again, a breach of fiduciary duty is essential for liability to be imposed: a tippee can be held liable only when the tipper has breached a fiduciary duty by disclosing information to the tippee, and the tippee knows or has reason to know of the breach of duty.
5650
Insider Trading
775
3. The Gap-Fillers Chiarella created a variety of significant gaps in the insider trading prohibition’s coverage. Consider this standard law-school hypothetical: Law Firm is hired by Raider Corp. to represent it in connection with a planned takeover bid for Target Co. Alex Associate is one of the lawyers assigned to the project. Before Raider Corp. publicly discloses its intentions, Associate purchases a substantial block of Target stock. Under the disclose or abstain rule, he has not violated the insider trading prohibition. Whatever the scope of the duties he owed Raider Corp., he owed no duty to the shareholders of Target Co. Accordingly, the requisite breach of fiduciary duty is not present in his transaction. Rule 14e-3 and the misappropriation theory were created to fill this gap.
4. Rule 14e-3 Rule 14e-3 was the SEC’s immediate response to Chiarella. The rule prohibits insiders of the bidder and target from divulging confidential information about a tender offer to persons who are likely to violate the rule by trading on the basis of that information. The rule also, with certain narrow and well-defined exceptions, prohibits any person who possesses material information relating to a tender offer by another person from trading in target company securities if the bidder has commenced or has taken substantial steps towards commencement of the bid. Note that the rule’s scope is very limited. One prong of the rule (the prohibition on trading while in possession of material nonpublic information) is not triggered until the offeror has taken substantial steps towards making the offer. More important, both prongs of the rule are limited to information relating to a tender offer. As a result, most types of inside information remain subject to the duty-based analysis of Chiarella and its progeny.
5. Misappropriation The misappropriation theory grew out of then-Chief Justice Burger’s dissent in Chiarella. As an employee of a financial printer, Chiarella had access to tender offer documents being prepared for takeover bidders. Although Chiarella owed no duties to the investors with whom he traded, he did owe a duty of confidentiality to his employer and thereby to the bidders. Chief Justice Burger argued that Chiarella’s misappropriation of material nonpublic information that
776
Insider Trading
5650
had been entrusted to his employer was a sufficient breach of duty to justify imposing Rule 10b-5 liability (Chiarella v. U.S., 240-243, (Burger, C.J., dissenting)). Although Justices Blackmun, Brennan and Marshall supported the Chief Justice’s argument, the majority declined to reach the misappropriation question because that theory of liability had not been presented to the jury. The Second Circuit nevertheless adopted the misappropriation theory as a basis for inside trading liability in U.S. v. Newman, 664 F.2d 12 (2nd Cir. 1981), and followed it in a number of subsequent decisions; see, for example, U.S. v. Chestman, U.S. v. Carpenter SEC v. Materia. Like the traditional disclose or abstain rule, the misappropriation theory requires a breach of fiduciary duty before trading on inside information becomes unlawful. It is not unlawful, for example, for an outsider to trade on the basis of inadvertently overheard information (SEC v. Switzer). The fiduciary relationship in question, however, is a quite different one. Under the misappropriation theory, the defendant need not owe a fiduciary duty to the investor with whom he trades. Nor does he have to owe a fiduciary duty to the issuer of the securities that were traded. Instead, the misappropriation theory applies when the inside trader violates a fiduciary duty owed to the source of the information. Had the misappropriation theory been available against Chiarella, for example, his conviction could have been upheld even though he owed no duties to those with whom he traded. Instead, the breach of the duty he owed to Pandick Press would have sufficed. After two Circuit Courts of Appeals rejected the misappropriation theory, the United States Supreme Court took a case raising the theory’s validity (see U.S. v. O’Hagan, also concluding that the SEC lacked authority to adopt Rule 14e-3; U.S. v. Bryan). James O’Hagan was a partner in the Minneapolis law firm of Dorsey & Whitney. In July 1988, Grand Metropolitan PLC (Grand Met), retained Dorsey & Whitney in connection with its planned takeover of Pillsbury Company. Although O’Hagan was not one of the lawyers on the Grand Met project, he learned of their intentions and began buying Pillsbury stock and call options on Pillsbury stock. When Grand Met announced its tender offer in October, the price of Pillsbury stock rose to nearly $60 per share. O’Hagan then sold his Pillsbury call options and common stock, making a profit of more than $ 4.3 million. Following a SEC investigation, O’Hagan was indicted on various charges. The most pertinent charges for our purposes are: (1) O’Hagan violated 1934 Act Section 10(b) and Rule 10b-5 by trading on misappropriated nonpublic information; and (2) O’Hagan violated 1934 Act Rule 14e-3 by trading while in possession of nonpublic information relating to a tender offer. The Supreme Court upheld O’Hagan’s conviction on both counts. With respect to the misappropriation charge, the Court validated the theory as being designed to ‘protect the integrity of the securities markets
5650
Insider Trading
777
against abuses by “outsiders” to a corporation who have access to confidential information that will affect the corporation’s security price when revealed, but who owe no fiduciary or other duty to that corporation’s shareholders’.
B. The Argument for Deregulation Henry Manne’s book Insider Trading and the Stock Market must be ranked among the truly seminal events in the economic analysis of corporate law (Manne, 1966a). It is only a slight exaggeration to suggest that Manne stunned the corporate law academy by daring to propose the deregulation of insider trading. The traditionalists’ response was immediate and vitriolic (see, for example, Schotland, 1967; Mendelson, 1969; see also Manne, 1970). In the long run, however, Manne’s daring was vindicated in at least one important respect. Although it is hard to believe at this remove, corporate law was regarded as moribund during much of the middle part of this century. Manne’s work on insider trading played a major role in ending that long intellectual drought by stimulating interest in economic analysis of corporate law. Whether one agrees with Manne’s views on insider trading or not, one must give him due credit for helping to stimulate the outpouring of important law and economics scholarship in corporate law and securities regulation during the 1980s and 1990s. Manne identified two principal ways in which insider trading benefits society and/or the firm in whose stock the insider traded. First, he argued that insider trading causes the market price of the affected security to move toward the price that the security would command if the inside information were publicly available. If so, both society and the firm benefit through increased price accuracy. Second, he posited insider trading as an efficient way of compensating managers for having produced information. If so, the firm benefits directly (and society indirectly) because managers have a greater incentive to produce additional information of value to the firm.
6. The Effect of Insider Trading on the Price of Securities There is general agreement that both firms and society benefit from accurate pricing of securities. The ‘correct’ price of a security is that which would be set by the market if all information relating to the security had been publicly disclosed. Accurate pricing benefits society by improving the economy’s allocation of capital investment and by decreasing the volatility of security prices. This dampening of price fluctuations decreases the likelihood of individual windfall gains and increases the attractiveness of investing in
778
Insider Trading
5650
securities for risk-averse investors. The individual corporation also benefits from accurate pricing of its securities through reduced investor uncertainty and improved monitoring of management’s effectiveness. Although US securities laws purportedly encourage accurate pricing by requiring disclosure of corporate information, they do not require the disclosure of all material information. Where disclosure would interfere with legitimate business transactions, disclosure by the corporation is usually not required unless the firm is dealing in its own securities at the time. When a firm lawfully withholds material information, its securities are no longer accurately priced by the market. If the undisclosed information is particularly significant, the error in price can be substantial. In the famous Texas Gulf Sulphur case, for example, TGS discovered an enormously valuable mineral deposit in Canada. When the deposit was discovered, TGS common stock sold for approximately $18 per share. By the time the discovery was disclosed, four months later, the price had risen to over $31 per share. One month after disclosure, the stock was selling for approximately $58 per share (SEC v. Texas Gulf Sulphur Co.). Pricing errors of this magnitude eliminate the benefits of accurate pricing. However, requiring TGS to disclose what it knew would have reduced the value of the information and thus the incentive to discover it. Manne essentially argued insider trading is an effective compromise between the need for preserving incentives to produce information and the need for maintaining accurate securities prices. Manne offered the following example of this alleged effect: A firm’s stock currently sells at $50 per share. The firm has discovered new information that, if publicly disclosed, would cause the stock to sell at $60. If insiders trade on this information, the price of the stock will gradually rise toward but will not reach the ‘correct’ price. Absent insider trading or leaks, the stock’s price will remain at $50 until the information is publicly disclosed and then rapidly rise to the correct price of $60. Thus, insider trading acts as a replacement for public disclosure of the information, preserving market gains of correct pricing while permitting the corporation to retain the benefits of nondisclosure (Manne, 1966a, pp. 80-90) Texas Gulf Sulphur provides anecdotal evidence for this effect. The TGS insiders began active trading in its stock almost immediately after discovery of the ore deposit. During the four months between discovery and disclosure, the price of TGS common stock gradually rose by over $12. Arguably, this price increase was due to inside trading. In turn, the insiders’ profits were the price society paid for obtaining the beneficial effects of enhanced market efficiency. Despite this and similar anecdotes, empirical justification for the deregulatory position remains scanty. Early market studies indicated insider trading had an insignificant effect on price in most cases (Schotland, 1967, p. 1443). Subsequent studies suggested the market reacts fairly quickly when
5650
Insider Trading
779
insiders buy securities, but the initial price effect is small when insiders sell (Finnerty, 1976). In an important study, Givoly and Palmon (1985) found that while transactions by insiders were followed by a strong price effect, identifiable insider transactions were only rarely based on exploitation of nonpublic information. If they are correct, then the market efficiency rationale for deregulation loses much of its force: insider trading simply is not communicating inside information to the market. These and similar studies are problematic, however, because they relied principally (or solely) on the transactions reports corporate officers, directors, and 10 percent shareholders are required to file under §16(a). Because insiders are unlikely to report transactions that violate rule 10b-5, and because much illegal insider trading activity is known to involve persons not subject to the §16(a) reporting requirement, conclusions drawn from such studies may not tell us very much about the price and volume effects of illegal insider trading. Accordingly, it is significant that a more recent and widely-cited study of insider trading cases brought by the SEC during the 1980s found that the defendants’ insider trading led to quick price changes (Meulbroek, 1992). That result supports Manne’s empirical claim, subject to the caveat that reliance on data obtained from SEC prosecutions arguably may not be conclusive as to the price effects of undetected insider trading due to selection bias, although Meulbroek’s study addressed that concern by segmenting the sample into subsets, one of which was less likely to be contaminated by selection bias, and finding that the results did not differ significantly across the subsets. Finally, the SEC’s chief economist has reached the perhaps debatable conclusion that pre-announcement price and volume run-ups in takeovers are most likely attributable to factors other than insider trading (Rosenbaum and Bainbridge, 1988, p. 235). In theory, of course, the supply/demand effects of insider trading should have only a minimal impact on the affected security’s price. A given security ‘represents only a particular combination of expected return and systematic risk, for which there is a vast number of substitutes’ (Gilson and Kraakman, 1984, p. 630). The correct measure for the supply of securities is not simply the total of the firm’s outstanding securities, but the vastly larger number of securities with a similar combination of risk and return. Therefore, the supply/demand effect of a relatively small number of insider trades should not have a significant price effect. The price effect of undisclosed insider trading is an example of what Gilson and Kraakman (1984, p. 630) call the ‘derivatively informed trading mechanism’ of market efficiency. Derivatively informed trading affects market prices through a two-step mechanism. First, those individuals possessing material nonpublic information begin trading. Their trading has only a small effect on price. Some uninformed traders become aware of the insider trading
780
Insider Trading
5650
through leakage or tipping of information or through observation of insider trades. Other traders gain insight by following the price fluctuations of the securities. Finally, the market reacts to the insiders’ trades and gradually moves toward the correct price. The problem is that while derivatively informed trading can affect price, it functions slowly and sporadically. Given the inefficiency of derivatively informed trading, the market efficiency justification for insider trading loses much of its force.
7. Insider Trading as an Efficient Compensation Scheme Even Manne (1966a, p. 110) admitted that price effect is not a strong argument against a bar on insider trading. Instead, Manne’s deregulatory argument rested mainly on the claim that allowing insider trading was an effective means of compensating entrepreneurs in large corporations. Manne (1966b, p. 116) distinguished corporate entrepreneurs from mere corporate managers. The latter simply operate the firm according to predetermined guidelines. Because the firm and the manager know what the manager will do and what his abilities are, salary is an appropriate method of compensation. By contrast, an entrepreneur’s contribution to the firm consists of producing new valuable information. The entrepreneur’s compensation must have a reasonable relation to the value of his contribution to give him incentives to produce more information. Because it is rarely possible to ascertain the information’s value to the firm in advance, predetermined compensation, such as salary, is inappropriate for entrepreneurs.
8. Insider Trading as Entrepreneurial Compensation Manne (1966a, pp. 116-119) asserted insider trading is an effective way to compensate corporate agents for innovations. The increase in the price of the security following public disclosure provides an imperfect but comparatively accurate measure of the value of the innovation to the firm. The entrepreneur can recover the value of his discovery through buying the firm’s securities prior to disclosure and selling them after the price rises. (Manne, 1970) later implicitly retreated from the distinction between entrepreneurs and managers, which vitiated some of the criticisms directed at his thesis. Because Manne did not retreat from the more general claim that insider trading was an efficient compensation scheme, most of the criticisms discussed in the next section remained viable.) Carlton and Fischel (1983, pp. 869-871) suggested a further refinement of Manne’s compensation argument. They likewise believed advance payment
5650
Insider Trading
781
contracts fail to compensate agents for innovations. The firm could renegotiate these contracts later to account for innovations, but renegotiation is costly and thus may not occur frequently enough to provide appropriate incentives for entrepreneurial activity. Carlton and Fischel suggested that one of the advantages of insider trading is that an agent revises his compensation package without renegotiating his contract. By trading on the new information, the agent self-tailors his compensation to account for the information he produces, increasing his incentive to develop valuable innovations. Because insider trading provides the agent with more certainty of reward than other compensation schemes, it also provides more incentives.
9. Evaluating the Compensation Thesis In evaluating compensation-based justifications for deregulating inside trading, it is crucial to determine whether the corporation or the manager owns the property right to the information in question. Some of those who favor deregulating insider trading deny that the property rights of firms to information produced by their agents include the right to prevent the manager from trading on the basis of that information. In contrast, those who favor regulation contend that when an agent produces information the property right to that information belongs to the principal. Where the property right to agent-produced information should be assigned is a question deferred to Section 20 below. This section focuses on the contention by those who favor regulating insider trading that it is an inefficient form of compensation. Manne (1966b, pp. 117-119) rejected contractual and bonus forms of compensation as inadequate incentives for entrepreneurial inventiveness on the ground that they fail to accurately measure the value of the innovation to the firm. Some contend, however, that insider trading is not any more accurate. They assert, for example, that even assuming the change in stock price accurately measures the value of the innovation, the insider’s compensation is limited by the number of shares he can purchase. This, in turn, is limited by his wealth. As such, the insider’s trading returns are based not on the value of his contribution, but on his wealth. Another objection to the compensation argument is the difficulty of restricting trading to those who produced the information. Where information is concerned, production costs normally exceed distribution costs. As such, many firm agents may trade on the information without having contributed to its production. A related objection is the difficulty of limiting trading to instances in which the insider actually produced valuable information. In particular, why should
782
Insider Trading
5650
insiders be permitted to trade on bad news? Allowing managers to inside trading reduces the penalties associated with a project’s failure because trading managers can profit whether the project succeeds or fails. If the project fails, the manager can sell his shares before that information becomes public and thus avoid an otherwise certain loss. The manager can go beyond mere loss avoidance into actual profitmaking by short selling the firm’s stock. Easterbrook (1981) focused on the contingent nature of insider trading as a ground for rejecting compensation-based arguments. Because the agents trading returns cannot be measured in advance, neither can the true cost of his reward. As a result, selection of the most cost-effective compensation package is made more difficult. Moreover, the agent himself may prefer a less uncertain compensation package. If an agent is risk averse, he will prefer the certainty of $100,000 salary to a salary of $50,000 and a 10 percent chance of a bonus of $500,000 from insider trading. Thus, the shareholders and the agent would gain by exchanging a guaranteed bonus for the agents promise not to trade on inside information (see also Levmore, 1982). As with the market efficiency argument, little empirical evidence supports or counters the compensation argument. The only useful empirical evidence is Givoly and Palmon’s (1985) finding that while insiders do earn abnormal returns from trading in their firm’s securities, these abnormal returns are based on the insiders’ superior assessment of their firm’s status and not on exploitation of inside information. If so, the compensation argument rests on fundamentally flawed assumptions.
10. Public Choice Some critics of the insider trading prohibition contend that the prohibition can be explained by a public choice-based model of regulation in which rules are sold by regulators and bought by the beneficiaries of the regulation. This section focuses on slightly different, but wholly compatible, stories about insider trading told by Dooley (1980) and Haddock and Macey (1987). One explains why the SEC wanted to sell insider trading regulation, while the other explains to whom it has been sold.
11. The Sellers’ Story Dooley (1980) explained the federal insider trading prohibition as the culmination of two distinct trends in the securities laws. First, as do all government agencies, the SEC desired to enlarge its jurisdiction and enhance
5650
Insider Trading
783
its prestige. Administrators can maximize their salaries, power and reputation by maximizing the size of their agency’s budget. A vigorous enforcement program directed at a highly visible and unpopular law violation is surely an effective means of attracting political support for larger budgets. Given the substantial media attention directed towards insider trading prosecutions, and the public taste for prohibiting insider trading, it provided a very attractive subject for such a program. Second, during the prohibition’s formative years, there was a major effort to federalize corporation law. In order to maintain its budgetary priority over competing agencies, the SEC wanted to play a major role in federalizing matters previously within the state domain. Regulating insider trading was an ideal target for federalization. Rapid expansion of the federal insider trading prohibition purportedly demonstrated the superiority of federal securities law over state corporate law. Because the states had shown little interest in insider trading for years, federal regulation demonstrated the modernity, flexibility and innovativeness of the securities laws. The SEC’s prominent role in attacking insider trading thus placed it in the vanguard of the movement to federalize corporate law and ensured that the SEC would have a leading role in any system of federal corporations law.
12. The Buyers’ Story Haddock and Macey (1987) argue that the insider trading prohibition is supported and driven in large part by market professionals, a cohesive and politically powerful interest group, which the current legal regime effectively insulates from insider trading liability (see also Macey, 1991). Only insiders and quasi-insiders such as lawyers and investment bankers have a greater degree of access to nonpublic information that might affect a firm’s stock price than do market professionals. By basing insider trading liability on breach of fiduciary duty, and positing that the requisite fiduciary duty exists with respect to insiders and quasi-insiders but not with respect to market professionals, the prohibition protects the latter’s ability to profit from new information about a firm. Market professionals benefit in a variety of ways from the present ban. When an insider trades on an impersonal secondary market, the insider takes advantage of the fact that the market maker’s or specialist’s bid-ask prices do not reflect the value of the inside information. Because market makers and specialists cannot distinguish insiders from non-insiders, they cannot protect themselves from being taken advantage of in this way. When trading with insiders, the market maker or specialist thus will always be on the wrong side of the transaction. If insider trading is effectively prohibited, however, the
784
Insider Trading
5650
market professionals are no longer exposed to this risk. Professional securities traders likewise profit from the fiduciary duty-based insider trading prohibition. Because professional investors are often active traders, they are highly sensitive to the transaction costs of trading in securities. Prominent among these costs is the specialist’s and market-maker’s bid-ask spread. If a ban on insider trading lowers the risks faced by specialists and market makers, some portion of the resulting gains should be passed on to professional traders in the form of narrower bid-ask spreads. Analysts and traders are further benefited by a prohibition on insider trading, because only insiders are likely to have systematic advantages over market professionals in the competition to be the first to act on new information. Market professionals specialize in acquiring and analyzing information. They profit by trading with less well-informed investors or by selling information to them. If insiders can freely trade on nonpublic information, however, some portion of the information’s value will be impounded into the price before it is learned by market professionals, which will reduce their returns (Haddock and Macey, 1987). Circumstantial evidence for Haddock and Macey’s thesis is provided by SEC enforcement patterns. The frequency of insider trading prosecutions rose dramatically after the US Supreme Court’s decision in Chiarella v. U.S., 445 U.S. 222 (1980), which held that insider trading is only unlawful if the trader violated a fiduciary duty owed to the party with whom he trades. Strikingly, however, in the years immediately prior to Chiarella, enforcement proceedings often targeted market professionals. After Chiarella, market professionals were rarely charged (Dooley, 1995, pp. 832-834).
C. The Argument for Regulation Efficiency-based arguments for regulating insider trading (as opposed to those grounded on legislative intent, equity, or fairness) fall into three main categories: (1) insider trading harms investors and thus undermines investor confidence in the securities markets; (2) insider trading harms the issuer of the affected securities; and (3) insider trading amounts to theft of property belonging to the corporation and therefore should be prohibited even in the absence of harm to investors or the firm. This section considers these arguments seriatim.
5650
Insider Trading
785
13. Does Insider Trading Injure Investors? Insider trading is said to harm the investor in two principal ways. Some contend that the investor’s trades are made at the ‘wrong price’. A more sophisticated theory posits that the investor is induced to make a bad purchase or sale. Neither argument proves convincing on close examination. An investor who trades in a security contemporaneously with insiders having access to material nonpublic information likely will allege injury in that he sold at the wrong price; that is, a price that does not reflect the undisclosed information. If a firm’s stock currently sells at $10 per share, but after disclosure of the new information will sell at $15, a shareholder who sells at the current price thus will claim a $5 loss. The investor’s claim, however, is fundamentally flawed. It is purely fortuitous that an insider was on the other side of the transaction. The gain corresponding to shareholder’s ‘loss’ is reaped not just by inside traders, but by all contemporaneous purchasers whether they had access to the undisclosed information or not (Bainbridge, 1986, p. 59). To be sure, the investor might not have sold if he had had the same information as the insider, but even so the rules governing insider trading are not the source of his problem. The information asymmetry between insiders and public investors arises out of the federal securities laws’ mandatory disclosure rules, which allow firms to keep some information confidential even if it is material to investor decision making. Unless immediate disclosure of material information is to be required, a step the law has been unwilling to take, there will always be winners and losers in this situation. Irrespective of whether insiders are permitted to inside trade or not, the investor will not have the same access to information as the insider. It makes little sense to claim that the shareholder is injured when his shares are bought by an insider, but not when they are bought by an outsider without access to information. To the extent the selling shareholder is injured, his injury thus is correctly attributed to the rules allowing corporate nondisclosure of material information, not to insider trading. A more sophisticated argument is that the price effects of insider trading induce shareholders to make poorly advised transactions. In light of the evidence and theory recounted above in Section 6, however, it is doubtful whether insider trading produces the sort of price effects necessary to induce shareholders to trade. While derivatively informed trading can affect price, it functions slowly and sporadically (Gilson and Kraakman, 1984, p. 631). Given the inefficiency of derivatively informed trading, price or volume changes resulting from insider trading will only rarely be of sufficient magnitude to induce investors to trade. Assuming for the sake of argument that insider trading produces noticeable price effects, however, and further assuming that some investors are misled by
786
Insider Trading
5650
those effects, the inducement argument is further flawed because many transactions would have taken place regardless of the price changes resulting from insider trading. Investors who would have traded irrespective of the presence of insiders in the market benefit from insider trading because they transacted at a price closer to the ‘correct’ price; that is, the price that would prevail if the information were disclosed (Dooley, 1980, pp. 35-36; Manne, 1966b, p. 114). In any case, it is hard to tell how the inducement argument plays out when investors are examined as a class. For any given number who decide to sell because of a price rise, for example, another group of investors may decide to defer a planned sale in anticipation of further increases.
14. Does Insider Trading Undermine Investor Confidence? In the absence of a credible investor injury story, it is difficult to see why insider trading should undermine investor confidence in the integrity of the securities markets. Instead, any anger investors feel over insider trading appears to arise mainly from envy of the insider’s greater access to information. The loss of confidence argument is further undercut by the stock market’s performance since the insider trading scandals of the mid-1980s. The enormous publicity given those scandals put all investors on notice that insider trading is a common securities violation. At the same time, however, the years since the scandals have been one of the stock market’s most robust periods. One can but conclude that insider trading does not seriously threaten the confidence of investors in the securities markets. Macey (1991, p. 44) contends that the experience of other countries confirms this conclusion. For example, Japan only recently began regulating insider trading and its rules are not enforced. The same appears to be true of India. Hong Kong has repealed its insider trading prohibition. Both have vigorous and highly liquid stock markets.
15. Does Insider Trading Injure Issuers? Unlike tangible property, information can be used by more than one person without necessarily lowering its value. If a manager who has just negotiated a major contract for his employer then trades in his employer’s stock, for example, there is no reason to believe that the managers conduct necessarily lowers the value of the contract to the employer. But while insider trading will not always harm the employer, it may do so in some circumstances. Specifically, there are four significant potential harms connected with insider
5650
Insider Trading
787
trading that are worth considering. First, insider trading may delay the transmission of information or the taking of corporate action. Second, it may impede corporate plans. Third, it gives managers an incentive to manipulate stock prices. Finally, it may injure the firm’s reputation.
16. Delay Insider trading becomes a plausible source of injury to the firm if it creates incentives for managers to delay the transmission of information to superiors. Decision making in any entity requires accurate, timely information. In large, hierarchical organizations, such as publicly traded corporations, information must pass through many levels before reaching senior managers. The more levels, the greater the probability of distortion or delay intrinsic to the system. This inefficiency can be reduced by downward delegation of decision making authority, but not eliminated. Even with only minimal delay in the upward transmission of information at every level, where the information must pass through many levels before reaching a decision maker, the net delay may be substantial. If a manager discovers or obtains information (either beneficial or detrimental to the firm), he may delay disclosure of that information to other managers so as to assure himself sufficient time to trade on the basis of that information before the corporation acts upon it. As noted, even if the period of delay by any one manager is brief, the net delay produced by successive trading managers may be substantial (see Haft, 1982, pp. 1053-1060; but see Macey, 1991, pp. 36-37). Unnecessary delay of this sort harms the firm in several ways. The firm must monitor the manager’s conduct to ensure timely carrying out of his duties. It becomes more likely that outsiders will become aware of the information through snooping or leaks (Easterbrook, 1981). Some outsider may even independently discover and utilize the information before the corporation acts upon it. Although delay is a plausible source of harm to the issuer, its importance is easily exaggerated. The available empirical evidence scarcely rises above the anecdotal level, but does suggest that measurable delay attributable to insider trading is rare (Dooley, 1980, p. 34). Given the rapidity with which securities transactions can be conducted in modern secondary trading markets, moreover, a manager need at most delay corporate action long enough for a five minute telephone conversation with his stockbroker. Even if the manager wished to cover his tracks by trading through an elaborate network of off-shore shell corporations, very little delay is entailed once the network is up and running. Delay (either in transmitting information or taking action) also often will be readily detectible by the employer. Finally, and perhaps most importantly,
788
Insider Trading
5650
insider trading may create incentives to release information early just as often as it creates incentives to delay transmission and disclosure of information.
17. Interference with Corporate Plans Trading during the planning stage of an acquisition is the paradigm example of how insider trading may affect corporate plans. If the managers charged with overseeing the acquisition buy shares in the target, the price of the target’s shares may rise, making the takeover more expensive. Price and volume changes caused by their trading also might tip off others to the secret, interfering with the bidder’s plans, as by alerting the target to the need for defensive measures. The trouble with this argument, of course, is its dependence upon price and volume effects. As the theory and empirical evidence recounted above in Section 6 suggest, price or volume changes resulting from insider trading may raise the marginal cost of corporate plans but will only rarely pose significant obstacles to carrying corporate plans forward. The risk of premature disclosure poses a more serious threat to corporate plans. The issuer often has just as much interest in when information becomes public as it does in whether the information becomes public. Suppose Target, Inc., enters into merger negotiations with a potential acquirer. Target managers who inside trade on the basis of that information will rarely need to delay corporate action in order to effect their purchases. Having made their purchases, however, the managers now have an incentive to cause disclosure of Target’s plans as soon as possible. Absent leaks or other forms of derivatively informed trading, the merger will have no price effect until it is disclosed to the market, at which time there usually is a strong positive effect. Once the information is disclosed, the trading managers will be able to reap substantial profits, but until disclosure takes place, they bear a variety of firm-specific and market risks. The deal, the stock market, or both may collapse at any time. Early disclosure enables the managers to minimize those risks by selling out as soon as the price jumps in response to the announcement. If disclosure is made too early, a variety of adverse consequences may result. If disclosure triggers competing bids, the initial bidder may withdraw from the bidding or demand protection in the form of costly lock-ups and other exclusivity provisions. Alternatively, if disclosure does not trigger competing bids, the initial bidder may conclude that it overbid and lower its offer accordingly. In addition, early disclosure brings the deal to the attention of regulators and plaintiffs’ lawyers sooner than necessary. An even worse case scenario is suggested by the classic insider trading case, SEC v. Texas Gulf Sulphur Co. In TGS, insiders who knew of a major ore
5650
Insider Trading
789
discovery traded over an extended period of time. During that period the corporation was attempting to buy up the mineral rights to the affected land. Had the news leaked prematurely, the issuer at least would have had to pay much higher fees for the mineral rights, and may well have lost some land to competitors. Given the magnitude of the strike, which eventually resulted in a 300-plus percent increase in the firm’s market value, the harm that would have resulted from premature disclosure was immense. Although insider trading probably only rarely causes the firm to lose opportunities, it may create incentives for management to alter firm plans in less drastic ways to increase the likelihood and magnitude of trading profits. For example, trading managers can accelerate receipt of revenue, change depreciation strategy, or alter dividend payments in an attempt to affect share prices and insider returns (Brudney, 1979). Alternatively, the insiders might structure corporate transactions to increase the opportunity for secret-keeping. Both types of decisions may adversely affect the firm and its shareholders. Moreover, as Levmore (1982, p. 149) suggests, this incentive may result in allocative inefficiency by encouraging overinvestment in those industries or activities that generate opportunities for insider trading. Easterbrook (1981, p. 332) identifies a related perverse incentive created by insider trading. Managers may elect to follow policies that increase fluctuations in the price of the firm’s stock. ‘They may select riskier projects than the shareholders would prefer, because if the risks pay off they can capture a portion of the gains in insider tradings and, if the project flops, the shareholders bear the loss.’ In contrast, Carlton and Fischel (1983, pp. 874-876) assert that Easterbrook overstates the incentive to choose high-risk projects. Because managers must work in teams, the ability of one or a few managers to select high-risk projects is severely constrained through monitoring by colleagues. Cooperation by enough managers to pursue such projects to the firm’s detriment is unlikely because a lone whistle-blower is likely to gain more by exposing others than he will by colluding with them. Further, Carlton and Fischel argue managers have strong incentives to maximize the value of their services to the firm. Therefore they are unlikely to risk lowering that value for short-term gain by adopting policies detrimental to long-term firm profitability. Finally, Carlton and Fischel alternatively argue that even if insider trading creates incentives for management to choose high-risk projects, these incentives are not necessarily harmful. Such incentives would act as a counterweight to the inherent risk aversion that otherwise encourages managers to select lower risk projects than shareholders would prefer. Carlton and Fischel are correct that shareholders may prefer higher-risk projects. Because shareholders hold residual claims, they will prefer that the firm invest in projects with a significant upside potential. This is true even if
790
Insider Trading
5650
such ventures pose a substantial risk because shareholders earn no return until all prior claims are paid. However, shareholders would not approve high-risk projects where the increased risk is not matched by a commensurate increase in potential return. Allowing insider trading may encourage management to select negative net present value investments, not only because shareholders bear the full risk of failure, but also because failure presents management with an opportunity for profit through short-selling. As a result, shareholders might prefer other incentive schemes.
18. Manipulation Manipulation of stock prices, as a form of fraud, harms both society and individuals by decreasing the accuracy of pricing by the market. Some of those who favor regulation of insider trading argue that if managers are permitted to trade on inside information they have a strong interest in keeping the stock pricing stable or in moving it in the correct direction while they are trading. Therefore, they have a strong incentive to use manipulative practices (see, for example, Schotland, 1967, pp. 1449-1450). Manne (1970, p. 575) acknowledged that manipulation is harmful and that manipulation of stock prices would cease if insider trading could be effectively eliminated because nobody would then benefit from it. Manne’s principal response to the manipulation argument is not that it is wrong, but that the costs of producing perfect compliance with a prohibition against insider trading are unacceptably high. Like most arguments in this debate, the thrust of the manipulation rationale depends on whose estimate of the costs is correct.
19. Injury to Reputation Suppose that insider trading was shown to harm not the issuer, but the issuer’s shareholders. It has been said that insider trading by corporate managers may ‘cast a cloud on the corporation’s name, injure stockholder relations and undermine public regard for the corporation’s securities’ (Diamond v. Oreamuno; compare Macey, 1984, pp. 42-43; discussing threat of reputational injury posed for the Wall Street Journal when one of its reporters traded on confidential information. But see Freeman v. Decio, arguing that injury to reputation is ‘speculative’.) Reputational injury of this sort translates into direct financial injury, by raising the firm’s cost of capital, if investors demand a premium (by paying less) when buying stock in a firm whose managers inside trade.
5650
Insider Trading
791
Because shareholder injury is a critical underlying premise of the reputational injury story, however, this argument would appear to collapse at the starting gate. As we have seen, it is very hard to create a plausible shareholder injury story. As such, the reputational injury story must turn to more generalized notions of fairness. At this stage in the analysis, virtually all commentators make one of two moves. One group tries to find sources of unfairness unrelated to the question of shareholder injury, while the other simply asserts that insider trading is not unfair absent a credible story of investor injury. The former move fails. As Bainbridge (1986, pp. 56-61) argues, insider trading is not unfair to investors in any meaningful sense of the term (see also Easterbrook, 1981, pp. 323-330; Macey, 1991, pp. 23-31). Some contend that the latter move also fails precisely because most people do not examine the problem dispassionately. Even though insider trading is not actually unfair, the reputational injury story may remain viable if most investors believe it to be unfair. This perception of unfairness most likely proceeds from resentment of the insider’s informational advantage, which suggests that it may be based on envy as much as on fairness norms. As an advertising slogan once put it, however, image is everything. If one’s definition of efficiency takes into account seemingly irrational preferences, perhaps a prohibition of insider trading can be justified as a means of avoiding this sort of reputational injury. Whether efficiency should include such preferences is a question beyond the scope of this essay. Assuming the validity of the reputational injury story, arguendo, the reputational impact of insider trading probably is minimal in most cases. The principal problem is the difficulty investors have in distinguishing those firms in which insider trading is frequent from those in which it is infrequent. If they are unable to do so, individual firms are unlikely to suffer a serious reputational injury in the absence of a truly major scandal.
20. Insider Trading as Theft: A Property Rights Analysis There is an emerging consensus that the federal insider trading prohibition is most easily justified as a means of protecting property rights in information (see, for example, U.S. v. Chestman; Bainbridge, 1993, pp. 21-23; Dooley, 1995, pp. 820-823; Easterbrook, 1981; Macey, 1984). For an argument that the property rights approach has explanatory as well as justificatory power, see Bainbridge (1995, pp. 1256-1257). In contrast, for a vociferous critique of the law and economics literature on insider trading generally and the property rights approach in particular, see Karmel (1993).
792
Insider Trading
5650
There are essentially two ways of creating property rights in information: allow the owner to enter into transactions without disclosing the information or prohibit others from using the information. In effect, the federal insider trading prohibition vests a property right of the latter type in the party to whom the insider trader owes a fiduciary duty to refrain from self-dealing in confidential information. To be sure, at first blush, the insider trading prohibition admittedly does not look very much like most property rights. Enforcement of the insider trading prohibition admittedly differs rather dramatically from enforcement of, say, trespassing laws. The existence of property rights in a variety of intangibles, including information, however, is well-established. Trademarks, copyrights, and patents are but a few of the better-known examples of this phenomenon. In context, moreover, even the insider trading prohibition’s enforcement mechanisms are not inconsistent with a property rights analysis. Where public policy argues for giving someone a property right, but the costs of enforcing such a right would be excessive, the state often uses its regulatory powers as a substitute for creating private property rights. Insider trading poses just such a situation. Private enforcement of the insider trading laws is rare and usually parasitic on public enforcement proceedings (Dooley, 1980, pp. 15-17). Indeed, the very nature of insider trading arguably makes public regulation essential precisely because private enforcement is almost impossible. The insider trading prohibition’s regulatory nature thus need not preclude a property rights-based analysis. The rationale for prohibiting insider trading is precisely the same as that for prohibiting patent infringement or theft of trade secrets: protecting the economic incentive to produce socially valuable information. (An alternative approach is to ask whether the parties, if they had bargained over the issue, would have assigned the property right to the corporation or the inside trader. For a hypothetical bargain-based argument that the property right would be assigned to the corporation in the lawyer-corporate client context, see Bainbridge (1993, pp. 27-34).) As the theory goes, the readily appropriable nature of information makes it difficult for the developer of a new idea to recoup the sunk costs incurred to develop it. If an inventor develops a better mousetrap, for example, he cannot profit on that invention without selling mousetraps and thereby making the new design available to potential competitors. Assuming both the inventor and his competitors incur roughly equivalent marginal costs to produce and market the trap, the competitors will be able to set a market price at which the inventor likely will be unable to earn a return on his sunk costs. Ex post, the rational inventor should ignore his sunk costs and go on producing the improved mousetrap. Ex ante, however, the inventor will anticipate that he will be unable to generate positive returns on his up-front costs and therefore will be deterred
5650
Insider Trading
793
from developing socially valuable information. Accordingly, society provides incentives for inventive activity by using the patent system to give inventors a property right in new ideas. By preventing competitors from appropriating the idea, the patent allows the inventor to charge monopolistic prices for the improved mousetrap, thereby recouping his sunk costs. Trademark, copyright, and trade secret law all are justified on similar grounds. This argument does not provide as compelling a justification for the insider trading prohibition as it does for the patent system. A property right in information should be created when necessary to prevent conduct by which someone other than the developer of socially valuable information appropriates its value before the developer can recoup his sunk costs. Insider trading, however, often does not affect an idea’s value to the corporation and probably never entirely eliminates its value. Legalizing insider trading thus would have a much smaller impact on the corporation’s incentive to develop new information than would, say, legalizing patent infringement. The property rights approach nevertheless has considerable justificatory power. Consider the prototypical insider trading transaction, in which an insider trades in his employer’s stock on the basis of information learned solely because of his position with the firm. There is no avoiding the necessity of assigning the property right to either the corporation or the inside trader. A rule allowing insider trading assigns the property right to the insider, while a rule prohibiting insider trading assigns it to the corporation. From the corporation’s perspective, we have seen that legalizing insider trading would have a relatively small effect on the firm’s incentives to develop new information. In some cases, however, insider trading will harm the corporation’s interests and thus adversely affect its incentives in this regard. This argues for assigning the property right to the corporation, rather than the insider. Those who rely on a property rights-based justification for regulating insider trading also observe that creation of a property right with respect to a particular asset typically is not dependent upon there being a measurable loss of value resulting from the asset’s use by someone else. Indeed, creation of a property right is appropriate even if any loss in value is entirely subjective, both because subjective valuations are difficult to measure for purposes of awarding damages and because the possible loss of subjective values presumably would affect the corporation’s incentives to cause its agents to develop new information. As with other property rights, the law therefore should simply assume (although the assumption will sometimes be wrong) that assigning the property right to agent-produced information to the firm maximizes the social incentives for the production of valuable new information.
794
Insider Trading
5650
Because the relative rarity of cases in which harm occurs to the corporation weakens the argument for assigning it the property right, however, the critical issue may be whether one can justify assigning the property right to the insider. On close examination, the argument for assigning the property right to the insider is considerably weaker than the argument for assigning it to the corporation. As we have seen, some have argued that legalized insider trading would be an appropriate compensation scheme. In other words, society might allow insiders to inside trade in order to give them greater incentives to develop new information. As we have also seen, however, this argument appears to founder on grounds that insider trading is an inefficient compensation scheme. Even assuming that the change in stock price that results once the information is released accurately measures the value of the innovation, the insider’s trading profits are not correlated to the value of the information. This is so because his trading profits are limited not by the value of the information, but by the amount of shares the insider can purchase, which in turn depends mainly upon his ex ante wealth or access to credit. A second objection to the compensation argument is the difficulty of restricting trading to those who produced the information. The costs of producing information normally are much greater than the costs of distributing it. Thus, many firm employees may trade on the information without having contributed to its production. The third objection to insider trading as compensation is based on its contingent nature. If insider trading were legalized, the corporation would treat the right to inside trade as part of the manager’s compensation package. Because the manager’s trading returns cannot be measured ex ante, however, the corporation cannot ensure that the manager’s compensation is commensurate with the value of her services. The economic theory of property rights in information thus cannot justify assigning the property right to insiders rather than to the corporation. Because there is no avoiding the necessity of assigning the property right to the information in question to one of the relevant parties, the argument for assigning it to the corporation therefore should prevail.
D. Open Questions If the property rights justification for regulating insider trading is accepted, several questions remain open. Among these are: (1) Should the insider trading prohibition apply to all confidential information relating to the firm, or only to information whose use by an insider poses some serious threat of injury to the corporation? (2) Should the insider trading regulatory scheme consist of a
5650
Insider Trading
795
mandatory prohibition or a default rule? (3) In the United States, the regulatory purview of the federal securities laws is normally regarded as being limited to issues of disclosure and fraud. Questions of theft and fiduciary duty are usually relegated to state law. Why is insider trading an exception to that scheme? We consider these questions seriatim.
21. Scope of the Prohibition In Diamond v. Oreamuno the New York (state) Court of Appeals concluded that a shareholder could properly bring a derivative action against corporate officers who had traded in the corporations stock. The court explicitly relied on a property rights-based justification for its holding: ‘The primary concern, in a case such as this, is not to determine whether the corporation has been damaged, but to decide, as between the corporation and the defendants, who has a higher claim to the proceeds derived from exploitation of the information.’ Critics of Diamond have frequently pointed out that the corporation could not have used the information at issue in that case for its own profit. The defendants had sold shares on the basis of inside information about a substantial decline in the firm’s earnings. Once released, the information caused the corporation’s stock price to decline precipitously. The information was thus a historical accounting fact of no value to the corporation. The only possible use to which the corporation could have put this information was by trading in its own stock, which it could not have done without violating the antifraud rules of the federal securities laws. The Diamond case thus rests on an implicit assumption that, as between the firm and its agents, all confidential information about the firm is an asset of the corporation. Critics of Diamond contend that this assumption puts the cart before the horse: the proper question is to ask whether the insiders use of the information posed a substantial threat of harm to the corporation. Only if that question is answered in the affirmative should the information be deemed an asset of the corporation (see, for example, Freeman v. Decio). Proponents of a more expansive prohibition might respond to this argument in two ways. First, they might reiterate that, as between the firm and its agents, there is no basis for assigning the property right to the agent. See above, Section 20. Second, they might focus on the secondary and tertiary costs of a prohibition that encompassed only information whose use posed a significant threat of harm to the corporation. A regime premised on actual proof of injury to the corporation would be expensive to enforce, would provide little certainty or predictability for those who trade, and might provide agents with perverse incentives.
796
Insider Trading
5650
22. Mandatory or Default Rules For law and economics supporters of the insider trading prohibition, an interesting question is whether the corporate employer should be allowed to authorize its agents to inside trade. Because most property rights are freely alienable, treating confidential information as a species of property suggests that the information’s owner is presumptively entitled to decide whether someone may use it to inside trade. In other words, the insider trading prohibition arguably should be treated as simply a special case of the laws against theft. Another way of phrasing the question is to ask whether the prohibition of insider trading should be a default or a mandatory rule. Default rules in corporate law are analogous to alienable property rights. Just as shareholders generally are protected by the doctrine of limited liability unless they give a personal guarantee of the corporation’s debts, patentholders have exclusive rights to their inventions unless they authorize another’s use by granting a license. Continuing the analogy, mandatory rules in corporate law are comparable to inalienable property rights. Just as corporate law proscribes vote buying, the law prohibits one from selling one’s vote in a presidential election. So phrased, the insider trading problem becomes a subset of one of the fiercest debates in the corporate law academy; namely, the extent to which mandatory rules are appropriate in corporate law. A detailed analysis of this debate is beyond this chapter’s scope. Accordingly, it perhaps suffices to observe that the question of whether the insider trading prohibition should be cast as an alienable or an inalienable property right remains open (see generally Fischel, 1984; Macey, 1984; Ule, 1993).
23. How Should Insider Trading be Regulated? Even among those who agree that insider trading should be regulated on property rights grounds, there is no agreement as to how insider trading should be regulated. Bainbridge (1995, pp. 1262-1266) contends that the federal Securities and Exchange Commission has a comparative advantage in prosecuting insider trading questions, which justifies treating the prohibition as a matter of concern for the federal securities laws. Macey (1991, pp. 40-41) agrees that insider trading is difficult to detect and, moreover, that centralized monitoring of insider trading by the SEC and the self-regulatory organizations within the securities industry may be more efficient than private party efforts to detect insider trading. He nevertheless draws a distinction between SEC monitoring of insider trading and a federal prohibition of insider trading. Macey contends that the SEC should monitor insider trading, but refer detected
5650
Insider Trading
797
cases to the affected corporation for private prosecution. A third option, favored by some commentators, would be to leave insider trading to state corporate law, just as is done with every other duty of loyalty violation and, accordingly, divest the federal SEC of any regulatory involvement. Although this debate has considerable theoretical interest, it is essentially mooted by the public choice arguments recounted in Section 10 above. There is no constituency that would support repealing the federal insider trading prohibition, while proposals to do so would meet strong opposition from the SEC and its securities industry constituencies that benefit from the current prohibition.
24. Some Suggestions for Further Empirical Research Those who approach the insider trading proposition assuming that the property right to inside information belongs to managers in the absence of a compelling reason for assigning it to firms will necessarily draw different conclusions than those who start out with the opposite assumption. Unfortunately, in the absence of decisive empirical evidence, the insider trading debate turns on who gets to choose the null hypothesis - the proposition that the other side must refute - and on that issue there is unlikely to be agreement. The problem is that serious empirical research on insider trading is obviously impeded by the subject matters illegality. The two principal sources of raw data for US transactions are insider stock transaction reports filed under Securities Act Section 16(a) and case files of actions brought under Securities Exchange Act Rules 10b-5 and 14e-3. The first option is unattractive for two reasons: (1) only a small percentage of individuals with access to inside information are obliged to file under Section 16(a); and (2) it seems unlikely that insiders would knowingly report the most interesting transactions - those that violate Rules 10b-5 or 14e-3. The second option is unattractive because of the potential for selection bias. Many insider trading cases result from computer analysis of stock market activity. As such, empirical studies of SEC case files will be inherently biased towards cases in which insider trading conincident with noticeable price or volume effects. A third option is cross-cultural studies, focusing on stock markets operating in countries where insider trading is either legal or not vigorously prosecuted. One must be careful, of course, to ensure that focusing on only one aspect of cross-cultural comparisons does not invalidate the results. Having said all of that, there remain several areas in which further empirical research might be helpful. First, the data on the price and volume effects of insider trading remain confused. Further research on this issue seems
798
Insider Trading
5650
warranted. A related area of research would focus on the incentive effects of insider trading by corporate managers. Is there any empirical basis for the compensation argument? Second, it would be helpful to gather better data on the effect of insider trading on investor confidence. Here is one area in which cross-cultural comparisons are both promising and yet fraught with danger. As Macey (1991, p. 44) observes, Japan only recently began regulating insider trading and its rules are not enforced. Hong Kong has repealed its insider trading prohibition. Yet, both have vigorous and highly liquid stock markets. The question is to what extent the Japanese and Hong Kong experiences are relevant to an understanding of US capital markets. Assuming the validity of such comparisons, however, studying the effects of insider trading regulation (or the lack thereof) on other markets would be instructive with respect to the panoply of questions relating to investor confidence and injury.
Acknowledgments Although any remaining errors are my sole responsibility, I wish to thank Mitu Gulati and William Klein, both Professors of Law at UCLA, Lisa Meulbroek, Associate Professor at the Harvard Business School, and Thomas Ulen, Professor of Law and Economics at the University of Illinois, as well as the two anonymous referees, for helpful comments on earlier drafts. I also wish to thank my research assistant, Bradley Cebeci, for his excellent work in helping to assemble the bibliography.
Bibliography on Insider Trading (5650) Agrawal, Arun and Jaffe, J. (1995), ‘Does Section 16b Deter Insider Trading by Target Managers?’, 39 Journal of Financial Economics, 295-319. Aldave, Barbara Bader (1988), ‘The Insider Trading and Securities Fraud Enforcement Act of 1988: An Analysis and Appraisal’, 52 Albany Law Review, 893-921. Aldave, Barbara Bader and Carroll, Peter G. (1988), ‘The Misappropriation Theory: Carpenter and its Aftermath’, 49 Ohio State Law Journal, 373-391. Allen, Franklin and Gale, Douglas (1992), ‘Stock-Price Manipulation’, 5 Review of Financial Studies, 503-529. Allen, Steven A. (1990), ‘The Response of Insider Trading to Changes in Regulatory Standards’, 29 Quarterly Journal of Business and Economics, 47-78. Allen, William R. (1993), ‘Professor Schepple’s Middle Way: On Minimizing Normativity and Economics in Securities Law’, 56 Law and Contemporary Problems, 175-184. Anabtawi, Icman (1989), ‘Note: Toward a Definition of Insider Trading’, 41 Stanford Law Review, 377-399.
5650
Insider Trading
799
Anderson, Alison Grey (1982), ‘Fraud, Fiduciaries, and Insider Trading’, 10 Hofstra Law Review, 341-377. ArruÁada, Benito (1990), Control y Regulación de la Sociedad anónima (Control and Regulation of Joint-Stock Companies), Madrid, Alianza Editorial. Arshadi, Nasser and Eyssell, Thomas H. (1995), ‘On Corporate Governance: Public Corporations, Corporate Takeovers, Defensive Tactics, and Insider Trading’, 4 Financial Markets, Institutions, and Instruments, 74-103. Ausubel, Lawrence M. (1990), ‘Insider Trading in a Rational Expectations Economy’, 80 American Economic Review, 1022-1041. Back, Kerry (1992), ‘Insider Trading in Continuous Time’, 5 Review of Financial Studies, 387-409. Back, Kerry (1993), ‘Asymmetric Information and Options’, 6 Review of Financial Studies, 435-472. Baesel, Jerome B. and Stein, Garry R. (1979), ‘The Value of Information: Inferences from the Profitability of Insider Trading’, 4 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 553-571. Bagnoli, Mark and Khanna, Naveen (1992), ‘Insider Trading in Financial Signaling Models’, 47 Journal of Finance, 1905-1934. Baiman, Stanley and Verrecchia, Robert E. (1996), ‘The Relation among Capital Markets, Financial Disclosure, Production Efficiency, and Insider Trading’, 34 Journal of Accounting Research, 1-22. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1985), ‘Note: A Critique of the Insider Trading Sanctions Act of 1984', 71 Virginia Law Review, 455-498. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1986), ‘The Insider Trading Prohibition: A Legal and Economic Enigma’, 38 University of Florida Law Review, 35-68. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1993), ‘Insider Trading Under the Restatement of the Law Governing Lawyers’, 19 Journal of Corporate Law, 1-40. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1995), ‘Incorporating State Law Fiduciary Duties into the Federal Insider Trading Prohibition’, 52 Washington and Lee Law Review, 1189 ff. Reprinted in 38 Corporate Practice Commentator, 1996, 1. Barry, John F. III (1981), ‘The Economics of Outside Information and Rule 10b-5', 129 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1307-1391. Bauman, Todd A. (1984), ‘Comment: Insider Trading at Common Law’, 51 University of Chicago Law Review, 838-867. Bebchuck, Lucian Arye and Fershtman, Chaim (1993), ‘The Effects of Insider Trading on Insiders’ Effort in Good and Bad Times’, 9 European Journal of Political Economy, 469-481. Bebchuck, Lucian Arye and Fershtman, Chaim (1994), ‘Insider Trading and the Managerial Choice among Risky Projects’, 29 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 1-14. Beck-Dudley, Caryn L. and Stephens, Alan A. (1989), ‘The Efficient Market Theory and Insider Trading: Are we Headed in the Right Direction?’, 27 American Business Law Journal, 441-465. Beeson, John R. (1996), ‘Rounding the Peg to Fit the Hole: A Proposed Regulatory Reform of the Misappropriation Theory’, 144 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1077-1148. Benesh, Gary A. and Pari, Robert A. (1987), ‘Performance of Stocks Recommended on Basis of Insider Trading Activity’, 22 Financial Review, 145-158.
800
Insider Trading
5650
Bernardo, Antonia Eugenio (1991), An Integrated Analysis of Insider Trading, Executive Compensation, and Corporate Investment, Stanford University, unpublished Ph.D. dissertation. Bernhardt, Dan, Hollifield, Burton and Hughson, Eric (1995), ‘Investment and Insider Trading’, 8 Review of Financial Studies, 501-543. Bhattacharya, Uptal and Spiegel, Matthew (1991), ‘Insiders, Outsiders, and Market Breakdowns’, 4 Review of Financial Studies, 255-282. Biais, Bruno and Hillion, Pierre (1994), ‘Insider and Liquidity Trading in Stock and Options Markets’, 7 Review of Financial Studies, 743-780. Botha, D. (1991), ‘Aspects of Capital Market Efficiency and Statutory Regulation of Insider Trading in South Africa’, 15 Journal for Studies in Economics and Econometrics, 57-69. Bowles, Roger A. (1991), ‘Comment (on Fenn, McGuire and Prentice, Insider Trading Regulation after 1992)’, in Weigel, Wolfgang (ed), Economic Analysis of Law - A Collection of Applications, Vienna, Sterreichischer Wirtschaftsverlag, 143-145. Boyle, James (1992), ‘A Theory of Law and Information: Copyright, Spleens, Blackmail, and Insider Trading’, 80 California Law Review, 1413-1540. Briggs, Thomas W. (1992), ‘Insider Trading and the Prospective Investor after the Chestman Decision’, 20 Securities Regulation Law Journal, 296-312. Brown, Keith C., Harlow, W.V. and Tinic, Seha M. (1988), ‘Risk Aversion, Uncertain Information, and Market Efficiency’, 22 Journal of Finance and Economics, 355-385. Brudney, Victor (1979), ‘Insiders, Outsiders and Informational Advantages under the Federal Securities Laws’, 93 Harvard Law Review, 322-376. Campbell, David (1996), ‘Why Insider Dealing Is Wrong’, 16 Legal Studies, 185-199. Carbone, Paolo (1991), ‘Nuovi Illeciti attinenti alla Negoziazione di “Valori mobiliari”. Profili della Disciplina. Spunti Critici (New Torts Concerning Securities Exchange. Outlines of the Rules. Critical Hints)’, 5 Il Foro Italiano, 466-490. Carbone, Paolo (1993), Tutela Civile del Mercato e Insider Trading (Private Law Protection of the Market and Insider Trading), Padova, CEDAM. Carlton, Dennis W. and Fischel, Daniel R. (1983), ‘The Regulation of Insider Trading’, 35 Stanford Law Review, 857-895. Carney, William J. (1987), ‘Signalling and Causation in Insider Trading’, 36 Catholic University Law Review, 863-898. Chowdhry, Bhagwan and Nanda, Vikram (1991), ‘Multimarket Trading and Market Liquidity’, 4 Review of Financial Studies, 483-511. Cleeton, David L. and Reeder, Paul A. (1987), ‘Stock and Option Markets: Are Insider Trading Regulations Effective?’, 27 Quarterly Review of Economics and Business, 63-76. Colvin, Oliver Perry (1991), ‘A Dynamic Definition of and Prohibition Against Insider Trading’, 31 Santa Clara Law Review, 603-640. Conard, Alfred F. (1992), ‘Enterprise Liability and Insider Trading’, 49 Washington and Lee Law Review, 913-955. Cook, William J. (1992), ‘From Insider Trading to Unfair Trading: Chestman II and Rule 14e-3', 22 Stetson Law Review, 171-208. Corgill, Dennis S. (1996), ‘Insider Trading, Price Signals, and Noisy Information’, 71 Indiana Law Review, 355-417.
5650
Insider Trading
801
Cornell, Bradford and Sirri, Erik R. (1992), ‘The Reaction of Investors and Stock Prices to Insider Trading’, 47 Journal of Finance, 1031-1059. Cox, James D. (1986a), ‘Insider Trading and Contracting: A Critical Response to the ‘Chicago School’’, Duke Law Journal, 628-659. Cox, James D. (1986b), ‘Insider Trading Regulation and the Production of Information: Theory and Evidence’, 64 Washington University Law Quarterly, 475-505. Cox, James D. (1988), ‘Choices: Paving the Road Toward a Definition of Insider Trading’, 39 Alabama Law Review, 381-397. Cox, James D. (1990), ‘An Economic Perspective of Insider Trading Regulation and Enforcement in New Zealand’, 4 Canterbury Law Review, 268-283. Damodaran, Aswath and Liu, Crocker H. (1993), ‘Insider Trading as a Signal of Private Information’, 6 Review of Financial Studies, 79-119. Datta, Sudip and Iskandar-Datta, Mai E. (1996), ‘Does Insider Trading Have Information Content for the Bond Market?’, 20 Journal of Banking and Finance, 555-575. De Grauwe, Paul (1987), ‘Financial Deregulation in Developing Countries’, 32 Tijdschrift voor Economie en Management, 381-401. Dedek, Oldrich (1994), ‘Insider Trading, Investor Protection and an Orderly Capital Market: Lessons for the Czech Republic’, 3 Prague Economic Papers, 201-215. Demsetz, Harold (1986), ‘Corporate Control, Insider Trading, and Rates of Return’, 76 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 313-316. Dennert, Jörgen (1991), ‘Insider Trading’, 44 Kyklos, 181-202. Dennis, Roger J. (1988), ‘This Little Piggy Went to Market: The Regulation of Risk Arbitrage after Boesky’, 52 Albany Law Review, 841-892. Dinehart, Stephen J. (1986), ‘Insider Trading in Futures Markets: A Discussion’, 6 Journal of Futures Markets, 325-333. Dooley, Michael P. (1980), ‘Enforcement of Insider Trading Restrictions’, 66 Virginia Law Review, 1-89. Dooley, Michael P. (1995), The Fundamentals of Corporation Law, Mineola, NY, Foundation Press. Doorenbos, D.R. and Roording, J.F.L. (1990), ‘Rechtseconomie en Strafrecht: een Rechtseconomische Analyse van de Bestrijding van Misbruik van Voorwetenschap bij de Handel in Effecten (Law and Economics and Criminal Law: A Law and Economics Analysis of Insider Trading in Securities)’, 39 Ars Aequi, 733-742. Douglas, Norman S. (1988), ‘Insider Trading: The Case Against the “Victimless Crime”’,23 Financial Review, 127-142. Dunleavy, Patrick S. (1986), ‘Leveraged Buyout, Management Buyout, and Going Private Corporate Control Transactions: Insider Trading or Efficient Market Economics’, 14 Fordham Urban Law Journal, 685-722. Dutta, Prajit K. and Madhavan, Ananth (1995), ‘Price Continuity Rules and Insider Trading’, 30 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 199-221. Dyer, Boyd Kimball (1992), ‘Economic Analysis, Insider Trading, and Game Markets’, 1992 Utah Law Review, 1-66. Easterbrook, Frank H. (1981), ‘Insider Trading, Secret Agents, Evidentiary Privileges, and the Production of Information’, 1981 Supreme Court Review, 309-365. Easterbrook, Frank H. and Fischel, Daniel R. (1984), ‘Mandatory Disclosure and the Protection of Investors’, 70 Virginia Law Review, 669-715. Elitzur, R. Ramy and Yaari, Varda (1995), ‘Executive Incentive Compensation and Earnings
802
Insider Trading
5650
Manipulation in a Multi-Period Setting’, 26 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 201-219. Elliot, John E., Morse, Dale and Richardson, Gordon (1984), ‘The Association Between Insider Trading and Information Announcements’, 15 Rand Journal of Economics, 521-536. Engelen, Peter-Jan (1996), ‘De Regelgeving omtrent Handel met Voorkennis: een Juridisch-Economische Benadering (The Legal Rules on Insider Trading: a Legal and Economic Approach)’, 51(24) Weekberichten, Kredietbank, 1-7. Translated and reprinted as ‘La Reglementation en Matière de Delit d’Initie: une Approche Economico-Juridique’, 51(24) Bulleting Hebdomadaire, Kredietbank, 1-7. Engelen, Peter-Jan (1997a), In Defense of Insider Trading, Working Paper, University of Antwerp (UFSIA), Department of Business Economics, No. 97-247. Engelen, Peter-Jan (1997b), ‘Is the Enforcement of Insider Trading Regulation Enforceable?’, 5 European Journal of Crime, Criminal Law and Criminal Justice, 105-111. Engelen, Peter-Jan (1997c), ‘In Defense of Insider Trading. An Economic Analysis of Belgian Insider Trading Regulation’, 156 Cahiers Economiques de Bruxelles, 349-372. Epstein, Richard A. (1995), Simple Rules for a Complex World, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Estrada, Javier (1994), ‘Insider Trading: Regulation, Deregulation, and Taxation’, 5 Swiss Review of Business Law, 209 ff. Estrada, Javier (1995), ‘Insider Trading: Regulation, Securities Markets, and Welfare Under Risk Aversion’, 35 Quarterly Review of Economics and Finance, 421-449. Eyssell, Thomas H. (1991), ‘Corporate Insiders and the Death of the Firm: Evidence on the Incidence of Insider Trading in Corporate Dissolutions’, 26 Financial Review, 517-533. Eyssell, Thomas H. and Reburn, James P. (1993), ‘The Effects of the Insider Trading Sanctions Act of 1984: The Case of Seasoned Equity Offerings’, 16 Journal of Financial Research, 161-170. Fenn, Paul T., McGuire, Alistair and Prentice, Dan (1991), ‘Insider Trading Regulation after 1992: An Economic Analysis’, in Weigel, Wolfgang (ed), Economic Analysis of Law - A Collection of Applications, Vienna, Sterreichischer Wirtschaftsverlag, 135-141. Ferreira, Eurico J. (1995), ‘Insider Trading Activity, Different Market Regimens, and Abnormal Returns’, 30 Financial Review, 193-210. Filbeck, Greg and Mullineaux, Donald J. (1995), ‘Insider Trading and Regulation: A Look at Bank Holding Companies’, 19 Journal of Economics and Finance, 71-84. Finnerty, Joseph E. (1976), ‘Insiders and Market Efficiency’, 31 Journal of Finance, 1141-1148. Fisch, Jill E. (1991), ‘Start Making Sense: An Analysis and Proposal for Insider Trading Regulation’, 26 Georgia Law Review, 179-251. Fischel, Daniel R. (1984), ‘An Economic Analysis of Dirks v. Securities and Exchange Commission’, 13 Hofstra Law Review, 127-146. Fischer, Paul E. (1992), ‘Optimal Contracting and Insider Trading Restrictions’, 47 Journal of Finance, 673-694. Fishman, Michael J. and Hagerty, Kathleen M. (1992), ‘Insider Trading and the Efficiency of Stock Prices’, 23 Rand Journal of Economics, 106-122. Fitzsimons, Peter G. (1995), ‘Enforcement of Insider Trading Laws by Shareholders in New Zealand: An Analysis and Proposals for Reform’, 3 Waikato Law Review, 101-125.
5650
Insider Trading
803
Fortin, Rich and Michelson, Stuart (1995), ‘Option Introduction and Insider Trading in the NASDAQ/NMS Equity Market’, 19 Journal of Economics and Finance, 31-50. Fox, Merritt B. (1992), ‘Insider Trading in a Globalizing Market: Who Should Regulate What?’, 55 Law and Contemporary Problems, 263-302. Fox, Merritt B. (1994), ‘Insider Trading Deterrence Versus Managerial Incentives: A Unified Theory of Section 16(b)’, 92 Michigan Law Review, 2088-2203. Fried, Jesse M. (1997), ‘Towards Reducing the Profitability of Corporate Insider Trading’,, 70 Southern California Law Review. Friedman, Howard M. (1982), ‘Efficient Market Theory and Rule 10b-5 Non-Disclosure Claims: A Proposal for Reconciliation’, 47 Missouri Law Review, 745-762. Garten, Helen A. (1987), ‘Insider Trading in the Corporate Interest’, 1987 Wisconsin Law Review, 573-640. Georgakopoulos, Nicholas L. (1990), ‘Classical and Cross Insider Trading: Variations on the Theme of Rule 10b-5', 28 American Business Law Journal, 109-144. Georgakopoulos, Nicholas L. (1993), ‘Insider Trading as a Transaction Cost: A Market Microstructure Justification and Optimization of Insider Trading Regulation’, 26 Connecticut Law Review, 1-51. Gerson, Philip (1970), ‘Comment: Section 16(b): Re-evaluation is Needed’, 25 University of Miami Law Review, 144 ff. Gilson, Ronald J. and Kraakman, Reinier H. (1984), ‘The Mechanisms of Market Efficiency’, 70 Virginia Law Review, 549-644. Givoly, Dan and Palmon, Dan (1985), ‘Insider Trading and the Exploitation of Inside Information: Some Empirical Evidence’, 58 Journal of Business, 69-87. Glosten, Lawrence R. (1989), ‘Insider Trading, Liquidity, and the Role of the Monopolist Specialist’, 62 Journal of Business, 211-235. Goelzer, Daniel L. and Berueffy, Max (1988), ‘Insider Trading: The Search for a Definition’, 39 Alabama Law Review, 491-530. Goldie, Raymond and Ambachtsheer, Keith (1981), ‘The Battle of Insider Trading vs. Market Efficiency: Comment’, 7 Journal of Portfolio Management, 88 ff. Good, Coni Rae (1984), ‘Comment: An Examination of Investment Analyst Liability Under Rule 10b-5', Arizona State Law Journal, 129-159. Gosnell, Thomas, Keown, Arthur J. and Pinkerton, John M. (1992), ‘Bankruptcy and Insider Trading: Differences between Exchange-Listed and OTC Firms’, 47 Journal of Finance, 349-362. Grossman, Sanford J. (1986), ‘An Analysis of the Role of ‘Insider Trading’ on Futures Markets’, 59S Journal of Business, 129-146. Guo, Enyang Sen, Nilanjan and Shome, Dilip K. (1995), ‘Analysts’ Forecasts: Low-Balling, Market Efficiency, and Insider Trading’, 30 Financial Review, 529-539. Gupta, Atul and Misra, Lalatendu (1988), ‘Illegal Insider Trading: Is it Rampant before Corporate Takeovers’, 23 Financial Review, 453-464. Gupta, Atul and Misra, Lalatendu (1989), ‘Public Information and Pre-Announcement Trading in Takeover Stocks’, 41 Journal of Economics and Business, 225-233. Haddock, David D. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1986a), ‘Controlling Insider Trading in Europe and America: The Economics of the Politics’, in Graf Von Der Schulenburg, J.-Matthias and Skogh, Göran (eds), Law and Economics and The Economics of Legal Regulation, Dordrecht, Kluwer, 149-167.
804
Insider Trading
5650
Haddock, David D. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1986b), ‘A Coasian Model of Insider Trading’, 80 Northwestern University Law Review, 1449-1472. Haddock, David D. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1987), ‘Regulation on Demand: A Private Interest Model, with an Application to Insider Trading Regulation’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 311-352. Haft, Robert J. (1982), ‘The Effect of Insider Trading Rules on the Internal Efficiency of the Large Corporation’, 80 Michigan Law Review, 1051-1071. Hanson, Robert C. and Song, Moon H. (1995), ‘Managerial Ownership Change and Firm Value: Evidence from Dual-Class Recapitalizations and Insider Trading’, 18 Journal of Financial Research, 281-297. Harp, Hilary (1984), ‘Note: Insider Trading After Dirks v. SEC’, 18 Georgia Law Review, 593-638. Hauch, Jeanne M. (1987), ‘Note: Insider Trading by Intermediaries: A Contract Remedy for Acquirer’s Increased Costs of Takeovers’, 97 Yale Law Journal, 115-134. Heinkel, Robert and Kraus, Alan (1987), ‘The Effect of Insider Trading on Average Rates of Return’, 20 Canadian Journal of Economics, 588-611. Heller, Harry (1982), ‘Chiarella, SEC Rule 14e-3 and Dirks: “Fairness” versus Economic Theory’, 37 The Business Lawyer, 517-558. Herzel, Leo and Katz, Leo (1987), ‘Insider Trading: Who Loses?’, 165 Lloyds Bank Review, 15-26. Hetherington, J.A.C. (1967), ‘Insider Trading and the Logic of the Law’, 1967 Wisconsin Law Review, 720-737. Hiler, Bruce A. (1984), ‘Dirks v. SEC: A Study in Cause and Effect’, 43 Maryland Law Review, 292-341. Hirschey, Mark and Zaima, Janis K. (1989), ‘Insider Trading, Ownership Structure, and the Market Assessment of Corporate Sell-Offs’, 44 Journal of Finance, 971-980. Hirschey, Mark Slovin, Myron B. and Zaima, Janis K. (1990), ‘Bank Debt, Insider Trading, and the Return to Corporate Selloffs’, 14 Journal of Banking and Finance, 85-98. Hirschleifer, David (1971), ‘The Private and Social Value of Information and the Reward to Incentive Activity’, 61 American Economic Review, 561 ff. Horman, Timothy J. (1996), ‘In Defense of United States v. Bryan: Why the Misappropriation Theory is Indefensible’, 64 Fordham Law Review, 2455-2506. Jaffe, Jeffrey F. (1974a), ‘The Effect of Regulation Changes on Insider Trading’, 5 Bell Journal of Economics, 93-121. Jaffe, Jeffrey F. (1974b), ‘Special Information and Insider Trading’, 47 Journal of Business, 410-428. Jagannathan, Ravi and Palfrey, Thomas R. (1989), ‘Effects of Insider Trading Disclosures on Speculative Activity and Future Prices’, 27 Economic Inquiry, 411-430. Jarrell, Gregg A. and Poulsen, Annette B. (1989), ‘Stock Trading Before the Announcement of Tender Offers: Insider Trading or Market Anticipation?’, 5 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 225-248. Jennings, Marianne Moody and Hudson, Carl D. (1989), ‘The Ultimate Inside Information: Financial Institutions and Auditors as a Control of Market Response to Clients’ Securities Offerings’, 42 Arkansas Law Review, 467-518. Jennings, R.W. and Smith, R.B. (1976), ‘Insider Trading and the Analyst’, 5 Institutional Securities Regulation, 261 ff. John, Kose, John, Teresa and Lang, Larry H.P. (1991), ‘Insider Trading around Dividend
5650
Insider Trading
805
Announcements: Theory and Evidence’, 46 Journal of Finance, 1361-1389. John, Kose, John, Teresa and Mishra, Banikanta (1990), ‘Information Content of Insider Trading around Corporate Announcements: The Case of Capital Expenditures’, 45 Journal of Finance, 835-855. Johnson, Dana J., Serrano, Jan M. and Thompson, G. Rodney (1996), ‘Seasoned Equity Offering for New Investment and the Information Content of Insider Trading’, 19 Journal of Financial Research, 91-103. Jun, Meeka (1993), ‘New Capital Markets and Securities Regulations in Hungary: A Comparative Analysis of the Insider Trading Regulations in Hungary and the United States’, 19 Brooklyn Journal of International Law, 1047-1100. Kabir, R. (1990), Security Market Regulation: An Empirical Investigation of Trading Suspension and Insider Trading Restriction, Maastricht, Datawyse. Kabir, R. and Vermaelen, T. (1996), ‘Insider Trading Restrictions and the Stock Market : Evidence from the Amsterdam Stock Exchange’, 40 European Economic Review, 1591-1603. Kahan, Marcel (1992), ‘Securities Laws and the Social Costs of “Inaccurate” Stock Prices’, Duke Law Journal, 977-1044. Karjala, Dennis S. (1982), ‘Statutory Regulation of Insider Trading in Impersonal Markets’, 1982 Duke Law Journal, 627-649. Karmel, Roberta S. (1993), ‘The Relationship Between Mandatory Disclosure and Prohibitions Against Insider Trading: Why a Property Rights Theory of Inside Information is Untenable’, 59 Brooklyn Law Review, 149-174. Kelly, William A., Jr, Nardinelli, Clark and Wallace, Myles S. (1987), ‘Regulation of Insider Trading: Rethinking SEC Policy Rules’, 7 Cato Journal, 441-448. Keown, Arthur J. and Pinkerton, John M. (1981), ‘Merger Announcements and Insider Trading Activity: An Empirical Investigation’, 36 Journal of Finance, 855-869. Kerr, Halbert S. (1980), ‘The Battle of Insider Trading vs. Market Efficiency’, 6 Journal of Portfolio Management, 47-50. Kidd, Ronald F. (1993), ‘Insider Trading: The Misappropriation Theory Versus an ‘Access to Information’ Perspective’, 18 Delaware Journal of Corporate Law, 101-137. King, Raymond D. and O’Keefe, Terrence B. (1986), ‘Lobbying Activities and Insider Trading’, 61 Accounting Review, 76-90. Kitch, Edmund W. (1980), ‘The Law and Economics of Rights in Valuable Information’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 683-723. Kitch, Edmund W. (1995), ‘The Theory and Practice of Securities Disclosure’, 61 Brooklyn Law Review, 761 ff. Klein, Spencer Derek (1988), ‘Insider Trading, SEC Decision-Making, and the Calculus of Investor Confidence’, 16 Hofstra Law Review, 665-704. Klock, Mark (1994), ‘Mainstream Economics and the Case for Prohibiting Inside Trading’,10 Georgia State University Law Review, 297-335. Kraakman, Reinier H. (1991), ‘The Legal Theory of Insider Trading Regulation in the United States’, in Hopt, K. and Wymeersch, E. (eds), European Insider Dealing, Butterworths, London, 39-54. Kripke, Homer (1985), ‘Manne’s Insider Trading Thesis and Other Failures of Conservative Economics’, 4 Cato Journal, 945-957. Kyle, Albert S. (1985), ‘Continuous Auctions and Insider Trading’, 53 Econometrica, 1315-1335.
806
Insider Trading
5650
Laffont, Jean-Jacques and Maskin, Eric S. (1990), ‘The Efficient Market Hypothesis and Insider Trading on the Stock Market’, 98 Journal of Political Economy, 70-93. Langevoort, Donald C. (1982), ‘Insider Trading and the Fiduciary Principle: A Post-Chiarella Restatement’, 70 California Law Review, 1-53. Langevoort, Donald C. (1984), ‘The Insider Trading Sanctions Act of 1984 and its Effect on Existing Law’, 37 Vanderbilt Law Review, 1273-1298. Langevoort, Donald C. (1990), ‘Investment Analysts and the Law of Insider Trading’, 76 Virginia Law Review, 1023-1054. Langevoort, Donald C. (1993), ‘Fraud and Insider Trading in American Securities Regulation: Its Scope and Philosophy in a Global Marketplace’, 16 Hastings International and Comparative Law Review, 175-187. Langevoort, Donald C. (1995), ‘Words from On High about Rule 10b-5: Chiarella’s History, Central Bank’s Future’, 20 Delaware Journal of Corporate Law, 865-897. Lee, Moon H. and Bishara, Halim (1985), ‘Securities Regulation and Market Efficiency’, 5 International Review of Law and Economics, 247-254. Lee, Wayne Y. and Solt, Michael E. (1986), ‘Insider Trading: A Poor Guide to Market Timing’, 12 Journal of Portfolio Management, 65-71. Leland, Hayne E. (1992), ‘Insider Trading: Should it be Prohibited?’, 100 Journal of Political Economy, 859-887. Levmore, Saul (1982), ‘Securities and Secrets: Insider Trading and the Law of Contracts’, 68 Virginia Law Review, 117-160. Levmore, Saul (1988), ‘In Defense of the Regulation of Insider Trading’, 11 Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy, 101-109. Lin, Ji-Chai and Howe, John S. (1990), ‘Insider Trading in the OTC Market’, 45 Journal of Finance, 1273-1284. Liu, Pu, Smith, Stanley D. and Syed, Azmat A. (1992), ‘The Impact of the Insider Trading Scandal on the Information Content of the Wall Street Journal’s “Heard on the Street”’, 15 Journal of Financial Research, 181-188. Loh, Charmen (1992), ‘Poison Pill Securities: Shareholder Wealth and Insider Trading’, 27 Financial Review, 241-257. Long, D. Michael and Rao, Spuma (1995), ‘The Wealth Effects of Unethical Business Behavior’, 19 Journal of Economics and Finance, 65-73. Lorie, James H. (1980), ‘Insider Trading: Rule 10b-5, Disclosure and Corporate Privacy: A Comment’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 819-822. Lorie, James H. and Niederhoffer, Victor (1968), ‘Predictive and Statistical Properties of Insider Trading’, 11 Journal of Law and Economics, 35-53. Lundholm, Russell J. (1988), ‘Price-Signal Relations in the Presence of Correlated Public and Private Information’, 26 Journal of Accounting Research, 107-118. MacCabruni, Franco (1995), ‘Insider Trading e Analisi Economica del Diritto (Insider Trading and Economic Analysis of Law)’, 1 Giurisprudenza Commerciale, 598-622. Macey, Jonathan R. (1984), ‘From Fairness to Contract: The New Direction of the Rules Against Insider Trading’, 13 Hofstra Law Review, 9-64. Macey, Jonathan R. (1988), ‘Ethics, Economics, and Insider Trading: Ann Rand Meets the Theory of the Firm’, 11 Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy, 785-804. Macey, Jonathan R. (1988b), ‘From Judicial Solutions to Political Solutions: The New, New Direction of the Rules Against Insider Trading’, 39 Alabama Law Review, 355-380. Madura, Jeff and Wiant, Kenneth J. (1995), ‘Information Content of Bank Insider Trading’, 5 Applied
5650
Insider Trading
807
Financial Economics, 219-227. Manne, Henry G. (1966a), Insider Trading and the Stock Market, New York, Free Press,189ff. Manne, Henry G. (1966b), ‘In Defence of Insider Trading’, 44 Harvard Business Review, 113-122. Manne, Henry G. (1967), ‘Insider Trading and the Administrative Process’, 35 George Washington Law Review, 473-511. Manne, Henry G. (1970), ‘Insider Trading and the Law Professors’, 23 Vanderbilt Law Review, 547-590. Manne, Henry G. (1987), ‘Insider Trading and Property Rights in New Information’, in Dorn, James A. and Manne, Henry G. (eds), Economic Liberties and the Judiciary, Fairfax, George Mason University Press, 317-327. Mannolini, Justin J. (1996), ‘Insider Trading: The Need for Conceptual Clarity’, 14 Company and Securities Law Journal, 151-156. Manove, Michael (1989), ‘The Harm from Insider Trading and Informed Speculation’, 104 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 823-845. Marinelli, Arthur J., Jr (1988), ‘Liability for Insider Trading: Expansion of Liability in Rule 10b-5 Cases’, 22 Akron Law Review, 45-60. Masson, Robert T. and Madhavan, Ananth (1991), ‘Insider Trading and the Value of the Firm’, 39 Journal of Industrial Economics, 333-353. McGee, Robert W. (1992), Business Ethics and Common Sense, Westport, Quorum Books, 302 p. McGee, Robert W. and Block, Walter E. (1989), ‘Information, Privilege, Opportunity and Insider Trading’, 10 Northern Illinois University Law Review, 1-35. Mellett, Marc (1996), ‘Is There Life After Bryan?: The Validity of Rule 10b-5's Misappropriation Theory’, 34 Duquesne Law Review, 1057-1082. Mendelson, Morris (1969), ‘Book Review: The Economics Board of Insider Trading Reconsidered’, 117 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 470-492. Meulbroek, Lisa K. (1992), ‘An Empirical Analysis of Illegal Insider Trading’, 47 Journal of Finance, 1661-1699. Miller, Geoffrey P. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1990), ‘Good Finance, Bad Economics: An Analysis of the Fraud on the Market Theory’,, 42 Stanford Law Review, 1059-1092. Miller, Geoffrey P. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1991), ‘The Fraud on the Market System Revisited’, 77 Virginia Law Review, 1001-1016. Miller, Joseph E., Jr (1994), ‘SEC v. Peters: Stabilizing the Regulation of Tender Offer Insider Trading without a Fiduciary Duty’, 71 Denver University Law Review, 783-799. Milton, Elisabeth A. (1984), ‘Note: The Supreme Court’s Highwire Act: Balancing SEC Enforcement and Market Efficiency in Dirks v. SEC’, 45 University of Pittsburg Law Review, 923-947. Mirman, Leonard J. and Samuelson, Larry (1989), ‘Information and Equilibrium with Inside Traders’, 99 Economics Journal, 152 ff. Mitchell, Lawrence E. (1988), ‘The Jurisprudence of the Misappropriation Theory and the New Insider Trading Legislation: From Fairness to Efficiency and Back’, 52 Albany Law Review, 775-839. Mitchell, P.L. (1982), Directors’ Duties and Insider Dealing, London, Butterworths. Mofsky, J.S. (1972), ‘SEC Financial Requirements for Broker-Dealers: Economic Implications of Proposed Revisions’, 47 Indiana Law Journal, 232-248.
808
Insider Trading
5650
Morgan, Richard J. (1987), ‘Insider Trading and the Infringement of Property Rights’, 48 Ohio State Law Journal, 79-116. Netter, Jeffrey M., Poulsen, Annette B. and Hersch, Philip L. (1988), ‘Insider Trading: The Law, the Theory, the Evidence’, 6 Contemporary Policy Issues, 1-13. Nicodano, Giovanna (1992), Corporate Information Sales and Market Liquidity: A Property Right Approach to Insider Trading, published Working Paper, Centre for Economic Policy Research, European Science Foundation. O’Brien, Stephen J. (1995), Illegal Insider Trading, Mergers, and Market Efficiency, unpublished Ph.D. dissertation, University of North Carolina. Ocana, Carlos (1995), ‘Mergers and Takeovers in Spain: Empirical Evidence on Abnormal Returns and Insider Trading’, Journal of Business Accounting and Finance. O’Connor, Marleen A. (1989), ‘Toward a More Efficient Deterrence of Insider Trading: The Repeal of Section 16(b)’, 58 Fordham Law Review, 309-381. Odaiyappa, Ramasamy and Nainar, S.M. Khalid (1992), ‘Economic Consequences of SFAS No. 33 An Insider Trading Perspective’, 67 Accounting Review, 599-609. Okamoto, Karl Shumpei (1992), ‘Rereading Section 16(b) of the Securities Exchange Act’,27 Georgia Law Review, 183-251. Painter, W.H. (1965), ‘Inside Information: Growing Pains for the Development of Federal Corporation Law under Rule 10b-5, 65 Columbia Law Review, 1361-1393. Penman, Stephen H. (1982), ‘Insider Trading and the Dissemination of Firms’ Forecast Information’, 55 Journal of Business, 479-503. Penman, Stephen H. (1985), ‘A Comparison of the Information Content of Insider Trading and Management Earnings Forecasts’, 20 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 1-17. Pfeil, Ursula C. (1996), ‘Finanzplatz Deutschland: Germany Enacts Insider Trading Legislation’, 11 American University Journal of International Law and Policy, 137-193. Pitt, Harvey L. and Shapiro, Karen L. (1988), ‘The Insider Trading Proscriptions Act of 1987: A Legislative Initiative for a Sorely Needed Clarification of the Law Against Insider Trading’, 39 Alabama Law Review, 415-437. Pitt, Harvey L., Hardison, David B. and Shapiro, Karen L. (1987), ‘Problems of Enforcement in the Multinational Securities Market’, 375 University of Pennsylvania Journal of International Business, 452 ff. Posner, Richard A. (1992), Economic Analysis of Law (4th edn), Boston, Little Brown., §14.9, 417-418. Raad, Elias and Wu, H.K. (1995), ‘Insider Trading Effects on Stock Returns Around Open-Market Stock Repurchase Announcements: An Empirical Study’, 18 Journal of Financial Research, 45-57. Rider, Barry A. (1977), ‘Should Insider Trading be Regulated? Some Initial Considerations’, 94 South African Law Journal, 79-101. Rochet, Jean-Charles and Vila, Jean-Luc (1994), ‘Insider Trading without Normality’, 61 Review of Economic Studies, 131-152. Rosenbaum, Robert D. and Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1988), ‘The Corporate Takeover Game and Recent Legislative Attempts to Define Insider Trading’, 26 American Criminal Law Review, 229 ff. Rozeff, Michael S. and Zaman, Mir A. (1988), ‘Market Efficiency and Insider Trading: New Evidence’, 61 Journal of Business, 25-44. Saari, Christopher P. (1977), ‘Note: The Efficient Capital Market Hypothesis, Economic Theory and
5650
Insider Trading
809
the Regulation of the Securities Industry’, 29 Stanford Law Review, 1031-1076. Salbu, Steven R. (1990), ‘A Legal and Economic Analysis of Insider Trading’, 8 Business and Professional Ethics Journal, 2 ff. Salbu, Steven R. (1992a), ‘Differentiated Perspectives on Insider Trading: The Effect of Paradigm Selection on Policy’, 66 St. John’s Law Review, 373-405. Salbu, Steven R. (1992b), ‘Regulation of Insider Trading in a Global Market Place: A Uniform Statutory Approach’, 66 Tulane Law Review, 837-869. Salbu, Steven R. (1992c), ‘The Misappropriation Theory of Insider Trading: A Legal, Economic and Ethical Analysis’, 15 Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy, 223-253. Salbu, Steven R. (1993), ‘Tipper Credibility, Noninformation Tippee Trading, and Abstention from Trading: An Analysis of Gaps in the Insider Trading Laws’, 68 Washington Law Review, 307-350. Sampaio E Mello, Antonio (1989), ‘Insider Trading and Dealer Pricing’, 13 Economia (Portuguese Catholic University), 163-177. Samuelson, S.S. (1988), ‘The Prevention of Insider Trading: A Proposal for Revising Section 16 of the Securities Exchange Act of 1934', 25 Harvard Journal on Legislature, 511-531. Sanders, Ralph W., Jr and Zdanowicz, John S. (1992), ‘Target Firm Abnormal Returns and Trading Volume around the Initiation of Change in Control Transactions’, 27 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 109-129. Schäfer, Hans-Bernd and Ott, Claus (1992), ‘Economic Effects of EEC Insider Trading Regulation Applied to Germany’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 357-375. Schnitzlein, Charles R. (1996), ‘Call and Continuous Trading Mechanisms under Asymmetric Information: An Experimental Investigation’, 51 Journal of Finance, 613-636. Schotland, Roy A. (1967), ‘Unsafe at Any Price: A Reply to Manne, “Insider Trading and the Stock Market”’, 53 Virginia Law Review, 1425-1478. Schulte, David J. (1985), ‘Note: The Fraud on the Market Theory: Efficient Markets and the Defenses to an Implied 10b-5 Action’, 70 Iowa Law Review, 975-993. Schwert, G. William (1996), ‘Markup Pricing in Mergers and Acquisitions’, 41 Journal of Financial Economics, 153-192. Scott, David F., Jr and Petty, J. William (1973), ‘An Analysis of Corporate Insider Trading Activity’, 26 Journal of Economics and Business, 19-24. Scott, Kenneth E. (1980), ‘Insider Trading: Rule 10b-5, Disclosure, and Corporate Privacy’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 801-818. Scribner, Douglas G. (1994), ‘When Greed is No Longer Good: An Analysis of the Policy Considerations Underlying Rule 10b-5's Misappropriation Theory’, 26 University of Toledo Law Review, 205-235. Seligman, Joel, Stock (1985), ‘The Reformulation of Federal Securities Law Concerning Nonpublic Information’, 73 Georgetown Law Journal, 1083-1140. Seyhun, H. Nejat (1986), ‘Insiders’ Profits, Costs of Trading, and Market Efficiency’, 16 Journal of Financial Economics, 189-212. Seyhun, H. Nejat (1988a), ‘The Information Content of Aggregate Insider Trading’, 61 Journal of Business, 1-24. Seyhun, H. Nejat (1988b), ‘The January Effect and Aggregate Insider Trading’, 43 Journal of
810
Insider Trading
5650
Finance, 129-141. Seyhun, H. Nejat (1992a), ‘Why Does Aggregate Insider Trading Predict Future Stock Returns?’, 107 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 1303-1331. Seyhun, H. Nejat (1992b), ‘The Effectiveness of the Insider Trading Sanctions’, 35 Journal of Law and Economics, 149-182. Shin, Hyun Song (1141), ‘Measuring the Incidence of Insider Trading in a Market for State-Contingent Claims’, 1153 Economic Journal. Shin, Jhinyoung (1996), ‘The Optimal Regulation of Insider Trading’, 5 Journal of Financial Intermediation, 49-73. Silver, Carole B. (1985), ‘Penalizing Insider Trading: A Critical Assessment of the Insider Trading Sanctions Act of 1984', 1985 Duke Law Journal, 960-1025. Stout, Lynn A. (1988), ‘The Unimportance of Being Efficient: An Economic Analysis of Stock Market Pricing and Securities Regulation’, 87 Michigan Law Review, 613-709. Stout, Lynn A. (1990), ‘Are Takeover Premiums Really Premiums? Market Price, Fair Value, and Corporate Law’, 99 Yale Law Journal, 1235-1296. Strickler, Jeffrey P. (1985), ‘Inside Information and Outside Traders: Corporate Recovery of the Outsider’s Unfair Gain’, 73 California Law Review, 483-524. Sunder, Shyam (1992), Insider Information and its Role in Security Markets, published Working Paper, Carnegie-Mellon University, Graduate School of Industrial Administration. Syed, Azmat A., Liu, Pu and Smith, Stanley D. (1989), ‘The Exploitation of Inside Information at the Wall Street Journal: A Test of Strong Form Efficiency’, 24 Financial Review, 567-579. Thel, Steve (1991), ‘The Genius of Section 16: Regulating the Management of Publicly Held Companies’, 42 Hastings Law Journal, 391-503. Thompson, A.R. and Ward, M.J.D. (1995), ‘The Johannesburg Stock Exchange as an Efficient Market: A Review’, 19(Nov) Journal for Studies in Economics and Econometrics, 33-63. Thurber, Stephen (1994), ‘The Insider Trading Compensation Contract as an Inducement to Monitoring by the Institutional Investor’, 1 George Mason University Law Review, 119-134. Titus, Robert B. and Carroll, Peter G. (1986), ‘Netting the Outsider: The Need for a Broader Restatement of Insider Trading Doctrine’, 8 Western New England Law Review, 127-155. Tripp, Malcolm A. (1985), ‘Note: Access, Efficiency, and Fairness in Dirks v. SEC’, 60 Indiana Law Journal, 535-557. Trivoli, George William (1980), ‘How to Profit from Insider Trading Information’, 6(summ) Journal of Portfolio Management, 51-56. Trueman (1983), ‘Motivating Management to Reveal Inside Information’, 38 Journal of Finance, 1253 ff. Ulen, Thomas S. (1993), ‘The Coasean Firm in Law and Economics’, 18 Journal of Corporate Law, 301 ff. Vaahtoranta, Tapani (1988a), ‘Setting the Agenda for Legislative Reform: Some Fallacies, Anomalies and Other Curiosities in the Prevailing Law of Insider Trading’, 39 Alabama Law Review, 399-413. Vaahtoranta, Tapani (1988b), ‘A Note on Insider Trading: An Example of How Not To Make Law’, 39 Alabama Law Review, 349-354.
5650
Insider Trading
811
Vaahtoranta, Tapani (1996), ‘The German Securities Trading Act 1994: A Ban on Insider Trading and An Issuer’s Affirmative Duty to Disclose Material Nonpublic Information’, 30 International Lawyer, 555-558. Vaahtoranta, Tapani and Michener, Ron (1994), ‘The Political Economy of Insider Trading Laws’, 84 American Economic Review, 164-168. Wang, George (1985), ‘Dirks v. SEC: An Outsider’s Guide to Insider Trading Liability Under Rule 10b-5', 22 American Business Law Journal, 569-582. Wang, William K.S. (1981), ‘Trading on Material Nonpublic Information on Impersonal Stock Markets: Who is Harmed, and Who Can Sue Whom Under SEC Rule 10b-5?’, 54 Southern California Law Review, 1217-1321. Wang, William K.S. (1982), ‘Post-Chiarella Developments in Rule 10b-5', 15(4) Review of Securities Regulation, 956-965. Wang, William K.S. (1983), ‘Recent Developments in the Federal Law Regulating Stock Market Inside Trading’, 6 Corporation Law Review, 291-328. Reprinted in Bloomenthal, H. (ed.) (1984), Securities Law Review, 219-256. Reprinted in slightly different form as chapter two of Steinberg, M. (ed) (1988), Contemporary Issues in Securities Regulaties, 59-99. Wang, William K.S. (1987), ‘The ‘Contemporaneous’ Traders Who Can Sue an Inside Trader’, 38 Hastings Law Journal, 1175-1194. Wang, William K.S. (1988), ‘A Cause of Action for Option Traders Against Insider Option Traders’, 101 Harvard Law Review, 1056-1060. Wang, William K.S. (1991), ‘ITSFEA’s Effect on Either an Implied Cause of Action for Damages by Contemporaneous Traders or an Action for Damages or Rescission by the Party in Privity with the Inside Trader’, 16 Journal of Corporation Law, 445-490. Reprinted in Langevoort, Donald (ed.) (1993), Securities Law Review, 427-472. Wang, William K.S. and Steinberg, Marc I. (1996), Insider Trading, Boston, Little Brown. Wihlborg, Clas G. and (1990), ‘The Incentive to Acquire Information and Financial Market Efficiency’, 13 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 347-365. Winslow, Donald Arthur and Anderson, Seth C. (1993), ‘From “Shoeless” Joe Jackson to Ivan Boesky: A Sporting Response to Law and Economics Criticism of the Regulation of Insider Trading’, 81 Kentucky Law Journal, 295-321. Wolfson, Nicholas (1987), ‘Comment: Civil Liberties and Regulation of Insider Trading’, in Dorn, James A. and Manne, Henry G. (eds), Economic Liberties and the Judiciary, Fairfax, George Mason University Press, 329-334. Wolfson, Nicholas (1988), ‘Trade Secrets and Secret Trading’, 25 San Diego Law Review, 95-124. Wu, H.K. (1968), ‘An Economist Looks at Section 16 of the Securities and Exchange Act of 1934’, 68 Columbia Law Review, 260-269. X (1976), ‘Note: Framework for the Allocation of Prevention Resources with a Specific Application to Insider Trading’, 74 Michigan Law Review, 975-1022. X (1976), ‘Note: Economic Analysis of Section 16(b) of the Securities Exchange Act of 1934’, 18 William and Mary Law Review, 389-428. X (1987), ‘Note: Private Causes of Action for Option Investors Under SEC Rule 10b-5: A Policy, Doctrinal, and Economic Analysis’, 100 Harvard Law Review, 1959-1978. X (S.B.) (1985), ‘Note: A Critique of the Insider Trading Sanctions Act of 1984’, 71 Virginia Law Review, 455-498.
812
Insider Trading
5650
Cases SEC v. Texas Gulf Sulphur Co., 401 F.2d 833 (2d Cir. 1968), cert. denied, 394 U.S. 976 (1969). Diamond v. Oreamuno, 248 N.E.2d 910, 912 (N.Y. 1969) Freeman v. Decio, 584 F.2d 186, 194 (7th Cir. 1978) Chiarella v. United States, 445 U.S. 222 (1980) U.S. v. Newman, 664 F.2d 12 (2d Cir. 1981) Dirks v. SEC, 463 U.S. 646 (1983) SEC v. Switzer, 590 F. Supp. 756, 766 (W.D. Okla. 1984) SEC v. Materia, 745 F.2d 197 (2d Cir. 1984), cert. denied, 471 U.S. 1053 (1985) U.S. v. Carpenter, 791 F.2d 1024 (2d Cir. 1986) aff’d on other grounds 484 U.S. 19 (1987) U.S. v. Chestman, 947 F.2d 551 (2d Cir. 1991) (en banc), cert. denied, 112 S.Ct. 1759 (1992) U.S. v. Bryan, 58 F.3d 933 (4th Cir. 1995) U.S. v. O’Hagan, 92 F.3d 612 (8th Cir. 1996)
5660 REGULATION OF THE SECURITIES MARKET Edmund W. Kitch Professor University of Virginia Law School © Copyright 1999 Edmund W. Kitch
Abstract Securities regulation is a field that covers the interaction between the law and the securities industry. This includes many different topics, some addressed by some form of public law, some by private law and some by industry agreements, practices and customs. The literature on these numerous different topics is large and diffuse. Two exceptions are the literature on insider trading (Chapter 5650) and on the market for corporate control (Chapter 5640). An unresolved issued is what impact differences in legal regimes governing the securities industry actually have on the behavior of securities markets. The American laws of securities regulation have been viewed as (1) protecting investors, (2) increasing market efficiency, (3) completing organization of the market ‘firm’, (4) capturing wealth for some members of the industry and (5) affecting competition in the industry. The American literature on securities regulation has centered on two themes. One is the role and meaning of efficiency in the context of securities markets and their regulation. The second is the nature of the remedies for fraud or misrepresentations in connection with securities transactions. JEL classification: K22 Keywords: Investors, Firms, Fraud, Misrepresentation, Securities Transactions
1. Introduction There are many different interrelationships between securities markets and the law. For instance, securities are themselves contracts which create property rights. Participants in the securities markets buy and sell securities under the terms of specialized contracts. A principal concern of the law is fraud, deception and manipulation in securities markets, behavior that may be subject to private tort remedies, administrative penalties and criminal sanctions. Private organizations such as exchanges play an important role in organizing securities markets and regulating their participants. Securities markets are subject to some level of supervision and control by a public 813
814
Regulation of the Securities Market
5660
office or commission. The contract rights traded on securities markets may be issued by public or private bodies, or they may simply be, as is the case for exchange traded derivatives, obligations of the exchange clearing house itself. Because securities regulation encompasses so many disparate topics, the literature addresses numerous aspects of the legal rules and regulations which apply to the activity of issuing and trading securities without a focus on any particular issues. Two notable exceptions are the extensive literatures on insider trading, covered in Chapter 5650, and on takeovers and the market for corporate control in Chapter 5640. This chapter sketches out other topics related to the regulation of securities markets. The literature on securities regulation is diffuse and unfocused because securities regulation is understood as a field of public law that cuts across every aspect of the securities industry. Issues that in another industry would be private law issues of contract, property or tort, or matters that would be addressed by industry custom or practice, are issues of public law in securities regulation. For instance, the legal response to fraud or misrepresentation is a central preoccupation of the field of securities regulation, but is this response best analyzed and understood as an issue relating to the law’s general response to false statements in different contexts, or is the law of securities fraud a distinctive and different area, with its own unique problems and legal responses? It is interesting to speculate as to why insider trading and the market for corporate control have attracted a much more intensive and focused academic interest. The law of insider trading in securities regulation has presented a distinctive legal response to the issue of the right of persons to act on the basis of the information which they possess. The general approach of the law has been to permit persons to use their own heads for their own advantage. The traditional exceptions have been in the case of narrow categories of confidential, technical or marketing information or in the presence of specific contractual restraints, and then only in the form of private remedies for the person injured by the misuse of the information. In the securities regulation area, the US has pioneered (and exported to the rest of the world) legal rules that have made the use of material non-public information in securities markets a crime, as well as providing administrative sanctions and private remedies. The market for corporate control has attracted attention because it is a device by which the control of important economic institutions can be wrested from one incumbent management and transferred to another. Only because the tender offer procedures used to accomplish this are subject to
5660
Regulation of the Securities Market
815
securities regulations is the market for corporate control a securities regulation topic. In any jurisdiction, the law governing the issuance of and trading in securities is a mix of public laws and regulations, requirements of private industry organizations, industry custom and private contractual arrangements. The portion that is generated privately in the form, for instance, of industry agreements, customs and practices, is often difficult for scholars to access. The portion that is generated publicly will be more easily accessible in the form of published laws, regulations and regulatory and judicial decisions, and thus is more likely to be made the subject of academic description and analysis. In all jurisdictions the public portion will, like the part of an iceberg that is above the water, tell only a part of the story. The United States is a jurisdiction that imposed public regulation on securities markets at a relatively early date. In the first part of the twentieth century most states adopted what were called ‘Blue Sky Laws’ which subjected brokers and dealers to public oversight and required that securities be registered with a public agency before they were sold. Then in 1933 and 1934, partly in response to the market crash of 1929 and the ensuing Great Depression, the United States Congress created a national regulatory agency with similar powers. The national securities laws, in turn, have been the subject of a substantial US literature. Most of this literature has been descriptive, but much was at least implicitly normative. All of it assumed, usually implicitly, that markets were regulated in order to produce better economic results. A relatively small portion of the literature has used explicit economic analysis. Thus the line between the ‘law and economics literature’ on securities regulation and the ‘other’ literature on securities regulation is blurred. In recent decades, a central issue for many jurisdictions has been whether or not the US regulation is a desirable normative baseline for reform of the regulation of securities markets. The US consensus view - both academic and as expressed by US political and industry representatives - has been that it does. This view has been adopted to a greater or less extent in many different jurisdictions. The two major non-US markets - the United Kingdom and Japan - have pursued distinctive approaches. The UK in particular has had considerable success in building a London-based global securities market using a regulatory approach that self-consciously rejects many features of the US model. The bibliography that follows this article illustrates the disparate range of topics that can be thought to fall within the economic analysis of securities regulation. The remainder of this entry offers some thoughts on the problem of how to define the field, how to evaluate the regulation, and the present state of the literature.
816
Regulation of the Securities Market
5660
2. The Jurisdiction of the US Securities and Exchange Commission One way to delineate the varied topics that fall within securities regulation is simply to describe the matters that are within the jurisdiction of the United States Securities and Exchange Commission. The Securities and Exchange Commission administers the provisions of four securities statutes. The Securities Act of 1933, The Securities Exchange Act of 1934, The Investment Company Act of 1940, the Investment Advisor’s Act of 1940, and the Trust Indenture Act of 1939. The most important and far-reaching of these statutes is the Securities and Exchange Act of 1934, which, among many other things, created the Securities and Exchange Commission as an independent federal agency. The Securities and Exchange Act covers the following aspects of the securities industries. (1) Self-regulatory organizations or SROs, including all exchanges and the National Association of Securities Dealers (NASDA), (2) licensing of brokers and dealers, (3) margin credit, (4) manipulation of securities markets, (5) information reporting by issuers of securities, (6) solicitation of proxies by issuers of securities, (7) position reporting by officers and five percent shareholders, (8) position reporting by holders of large positions in securities markets, (9) misrepresentation, deception or insider trading in connection with the purchase or sale of a security, and (10) tender offers. A common structural feature of the statute is to require that the regulated entity (exchange, broker, dealer, issuer, and so on) be registered, and to give the Securities Exchange Commission discretion to control what the registered entity can, cannot and must do. The Securities Act of 1933 requires that public offerings of securities by issuers and issuer affiliates must be registered with the Securities and Exchange Commission. The Investment Advisor’s Act is a licensing statute for persons who offer investment advice to the public. The Investment Company Act of 1940 gives the Commission authority to regulate the structure and activities of investment companies, more commonly known as mutual funds. The Trust Indenture Act regulates some of the terms of the indentures that set the terms of bonds sold in public offerings. In the US, in addition to the Securities and Exchange Commission, the Commodities Futures Trading Commission (CFTC) regulates the futures markets, whose activities have expanded from trading in future contracts on agricultural commodities to trading in futures on securities indexes. The CFTC is a successor institution to an agency within the Department of Agriculture of the federal government that regulated the futures exchanges at a time when they dealt exclusively in agricultural commodities.
5660
Regulation of the Securities Market
817
3. The Functions of Securities Regulation Another way to look at regulation of securities markets is to look at the functions that are performed by the legal arrangements related to securities markets. This view of the subject is more appropriate for a comparative analysis, since it is not dependent on the particular provisions of any one country’s legal arrangements. 3.1 Functions of ‘Exchanges’ Securities markets existed before there was any explicit body of laws called ‘securities regulation’. These markets were based on private arrangements, backed up by the willingness of courts to enforce contracts and provide remedies for fraud. The core private arrangement was the Exchange, consisting of both a place where trading took place and set of understandings among its members. This private organization would be governed by a governing board, selected by its members. The Exchange performed a number of different functions. (a) Limited access to trading facility The exchanges required pre-clearance of the persons allowed to trade on the exchange, usually in the form of permitting only members to trade on the exchange. This procedure reduced the need for any one member of the exchange to be concerned about the identity and trust worthiness of any particular counter party. (b) Standardized trading rules The exchanges established standardized trading rules, governing such questions as standard units of trading, pricing increments, time of trading, delivery and payment procedures, and so on. This standardization made it possible for the transacting parties to focus on only one variable of the transaction - the price. (c) Clearing procedures The exchange would specify the rules relating to the obligations of the parties to an exchange contract to carry out the contract by delivery of the security and of payment. To facilitate the process, the exchange might operate a clearing office. (d) Exclusive roles for members The exchange may specify specialized roles for certain members, and specify in what roles members may act. For instance certain members may be allowed to function only as dealers, making a market in securities, and others only as brokers representing customers. Or the exchange may designate certain members as monopoly dealers or specialists for particular securities. (e) Dispute resolution Because it is important for traders on the exchange to know what their assets and obligations are as quickly as possible, exchanges provide for the resolution of disputes about trades outside the courts through a system of exchange sponsored arbitration. This avoids the problem of the
818
Regulation of the Securities Market
5660
uncertainty created by lengthy court proceedings, and forecloses the ability of parties to argue that any contract is unenforceable under public policy relating to gambling or other matters. (f) Exclusive rights in information The trading activity on exchanges generates information about the value of securities, information which is itself valuable. The exchange regulates access to that information and may attempt to exploit its value through, for instance, charges for access to the information. (g) Listing Requirements In order to ensure that securities trading on the exchange meet some minimum procedural and quality requirements, the exchanges set requirements for ‘listing’ a security on the exchange. This listing procedure was particularly important in connection with newly offered issues, since approval for listing helps the issuer’s underwriters sell the new issue to the public. These listing requirements set minimum size requirements (to ensure that there is a sufficient float of outstanding shares to make regular exchange trading possible), and specify requirements for information preparation and disclosure. These listing requirements often include the requirement that financial data be audited by recognized professional accountants. Even an entirely privately structured securities market will implicate the law of fraud. Legal systems usually provide both civil and criminal remedies for fraud. The existence of securities markets creates the possibility of generating large profits by the dissemination of false information. The law of fraud operates to deter this behavior. The fraud problem is, experience has shown, particularly acute in the case of equity securities. Because equities have no contractually fixed rights, but are simply a claim on the residual values of an enterprise, their value depends upon estimates about the future value of the enterprise, and the market’s estimate of that future value can be affected by false but credible information. Thus a fraud perpetrator can profit hugely by providing favorable but false information, and selling shares into the market at the inflated price. Such events, which are a recurrent aspect of the existence of securities markets, lead to demands, including demands by those involved in the securities industry itself, that the enforcement authorities and the courts take action.
3.2 Expanded Functions of Modern Securities Regulation Modern securities regulation has expanded far beyond the core functions of enforcing contracts and property rights and providing civil and criminal remedies for intentional fraud. These expanded functions include the following.
5660
Regulation of the Securities Market
819
1. Licensing of participants in the activity. A government agency may take over, in whole or in part, the function of licensing participants in the industry. Even though exchanges have membership restrictions, the exchanges will not reach participants in the trading that occurs off the exchanges. A government agency may be in a better position to screen applicants due to access to confidential government information and enforcement powers that can be used to deter false applications. Such licensing may also function to restrict non-exchange trading and strengthen the role of the exchanges, and to restrict competition in some or all parts of the industry. 2. The activities of exchanges may become subject to supervision by a government agency. This supervision helps to overcome the perception that exchanges are being operated only for the benefit of their members, to the detriment of the public, the customers for exchange services. 3. The regulation may attempt to control the use of leverage and trading in various types of derivative securities in order to reduce market fluctuations and the threat of insolvency of market participants when fluctuations occur. 4. Issuers of publicly traded securities and their managers may be made subject to direct regulation relating to issues such as the voting rights of securities holders, information disclosure, prohibition of insider trading, recovery of short-swing profits, and accounting and auditing procedures. 5. Securities laws may provide enhanced civil remedies, a variety of administrative remedies, and criminal penalties. These remedies may be enforced by criminal prosecutors, a specialized agency, or private parties, or by a combination of any of the three.
4. What Difference does the Modern Regulation Make? An important but largely unaddressed question about particular regimes of securities regulation is what actual effects they have on the markets to which they apply. For instance, what differences are there between the American securities markets after 1934, subject to national regulation, and the American securities markets before national regulation was imposed? What differences are there between the American securities markets, subject to American regulation, and the UK or Japanese securities markets, subject to different regulation? It is easy enough to observe various differences in the regulation, such as the comparative frequency of private, class-action damage actions based on Rule 10b-5 in the United States and the absence of a similar litigation in other countries. But do the differences in regulation
820
Regulation of the Securities Market
5660
have an impact on the way in which the markets behave, and if so, are those differences that have any economic or social importance? The proponents of national securities regulation in the US had a clear view on this question. In their view, the US stock market crash of 1929 was an important causal factor of the depression of the 1930s. The argument, most graphically set out by Galbraith (1955) at a later date, was that the stock market had been overvalued. As buyers and sellers became aware of this overvaluation, stock market prices fell. The fall in prices of securities caused a drop in personal wealth. The drop in personal wealth caused people to reduce their spending. This reduction in spending caused a reduction in demand, which caused producers to cut prices, cut production, and reduce employment. This caused a further fall in the value of their securities, which set off the whole downward spiral again. In addition, the reduced consumption of the unemployed fed the cycle. Thus the objective of the national securities acts of the 1930s was to force companies to provide accurate, if not pessimistic, information about their value and to reduce speculative excesses in securities markets. The legislative history of the acts shows that this view played an important role in the arguments for the regulation. This view of the role of the securities markets in the 1930s’ depression has been discredited. First, the magisterial monetary history of Friedman and Schwartz (1963) argued with considerable power that the depression had its genesis not in the securities markets but in the monetary policies of the Federal Reserve Board, which shrank the US money supply at a sharp and unprecedented rate. Second, the market crash of 1987, which was as large as the 1929 crash in percentage terms, but which was accompanied by monetary ease rather than monetary tightening, did not lead to any significant contraction in economic activity. The securities markets of 1929 were not a speculative cesspool whose rot spread to the large economy, rather they were an accurate predictor of the impending economic decline. The opposite view, that differences in the structure of securities regulation make no difference, is suggested by the work of finance economists. Finance is the part of economics focused on the study of financial markets. Finance economists have found that securities markets are efficient. Indeed, they have not identified any securities markets that are not efficient. This suggests that whatever differences there are in the regulation of securities markets, the differences are unimportant since all markets are efficient, and efficiency is the paramount normative criterion that an economic institution should meet. However, this result is an artifact of the unusual way in which finance economists define efficiency. They define efficiency in terms of the properties of the price series generated by
5660
Regulation of the Securities Market
821
securities markets. They have found that the price series generated by securities markets are random, and they equate this property with efficiency. In normal usage, efficiency is the property of a process in which the outputs generated from the inputs are maximized. Since securities markets make use of many different inputs, and their outputs affect many different aspects of the economy, it is difficult to determine whether particular arrangements are efficient in this sense. George Stigler, in pioneering work, attempted to determine whether the passage of the 1933 Securities Act had had a favorable impact on buyers of public offerings made under the provisions of the act. The question he asked was: have buyers who purchased the post-act regulated offerings done better than the buyers who purchased unregulated offerings? He studied a sample of pre-act offerings, comparing the returns to buyers of securities in public offerings with the return to buyers of a diversified portfolio of securities in the market at the same time. He then studied a similar sample of post-act offerings, making the same comparison. He found that the returns (as compared to the market) of the pre- and post-act buyers were the same. Thus purchasers protected by the regulation were no better off than they were before the act was passed. These findings suggested that the regulation did not help the purchasers of securities (Stigler, 1964). However, Stigler did find that the variance of the results was greater in the pre-act period. Stigler’s basic results were subsequently replicated in Jarrell (1981) and Simon (1989). Friend and Herman (1964) were highly critical of the Stigler study, and argued that this reduction in variance was a desirable effect, because it reduced the risk of investing in offerings subject to the act. Missing from this exchange was any analysis of whether securities regulation could or should be expected to either (1) improve the returns available to investors or (2) reduce the risk of a group of investments as a class. The idea that securities regulation could or should improve the returns obtained by investors is particularly improbable. The return that investors obtain will be the result of (1) the quality of the investment and (2) the price. The price, in turn, will be determined by the competition of investors to purchase the investment. To the extent that securities regulation is effective in making it easier and less risky to value the investment, that will increase the competition to purchase it and drive the price up. Any gain (less the costs of complying with the regulation) will be captured by the seller of the investment, not the buyer. Securities regulation can, on the other hand, reduce the riskiness of a the class of investments that investors are permitted to buy. For instance, if securities regulation permitted only conservative investments to be offered - say, for instance, only government bonds - then the investment risk would be reduced. But would that be a good thing? The reduction in risk would be achieved at the cost of suppressing the
822
Regulation of the Securities Market
5660
opportunity for risky investments that would be socially productive. The securities markets are themselves institutions that enable investors to assume risk by diversifying their portfolios. In the securities markets investments can be acquired in small amounts tailored to preserve the diversification of the buyer’s portfolio. The debate about the significance of the finding that the 1933 Securities Act reduced the variance of the buyer’s returns took precisely this form. Friend and Herman, and later Seligman (1982), argued that this was a good thing. Stigler argued that it was simply the result of raising the costs of making public offerings, and that the effect of raising the cost was to cut out the riskier offerings.
5. The Goals of the Regulation Further efforts to identify what impact different systems of securities regulation have on securities markets should be informed by an effort to first identify the impact which securities regulation is thought to have. There are numerous different goals or objectives that have been identified with securities regulation. The principal goals are: 5.1 Investor protection The most commonly asserted objective of securities regulation is the protection of investors. However, what this ‘protection’ constitutes is never spelled out. Given that investment transactions involve the transfer of money between consenting adults for a product that is not socially harmful, it is difficult to identify what the regulation is protecting investors from. The simple idea that the regulation will protect investors by providing them with higher returns is, as has already been discussed, implausible on its face. A more sophisticated variant of the theme of investor protection is that the purpose of the regulation is to protect investors in order to help issuers and securities salesman sell securities to the public. The public resists buying securities because of fears that any particular issue may be fraudulent. Potential buyers have to invest real resources to protecting themselves against fraud. The regulation, by providing an effective deterrent against fraud, reduces this cost for buyers and makes it possible to sell securities at higher prices, helping issuers and the securities industry. Whether or not contemporary securities regulation actually achieves a reduction in the amount of fraud is unclear. First of all, securities fraud has always been subject to criminal and civil remedies. Second, buyers are not helpless. They can, for instance, deal with established firms with good reputations for honesty and integrity, diversify their portfolios, and insist upon and examine carefully information about the investment. The
5660
Regulation of the Securities Market
823
additional strategy of contemporary securities regulation is to add a network of advance licensing procedures. It is made a crime to attempt to sell securities without a license, and it is made a crime to offer securities that have not been registered with public officials. Can this licensing network screen out the potential fraudulent actors? Or is it inevitably overwhelmed by the administrative routine and volume of paper work, so that even scam artists can obtain the required licenses, and use them to increase the credibility of their offering? American newspapers regularly report enormous swindles involving the sale of fraudulent securities. In the US there has been a persistent problem with ‘Penny Stock’ frauds, operated out of high pressure sales offices called ‘boiler rooms’ because of the selling heat put on the salesmen. These frauds are usually conducted by licensed securities salesman employed by licensed securities firms, and offer their victims the opportunity for quick profits in stocks that at least superficially appear to have satisfied regulatory requirements. In spite of the fact that regulators have made control of penny stock frauds an enforcement priority, and in spite of the fact that federal statues have been extensively amended to make penny stock scams more difficult to operate, they appear to continue to flourish. It is not particularly plausible that criminal activity can be reduced by requiring criminals to register with the government before they commit the crime. A sales practice permitted by US securities regulation but not permitted in many other jurisdictions such as the UK is cold calling. This is the practice of calling potential investors at their homes and inducing them to invest over the phone. This is a sales technique used by boiler room sales operations, and also used by large and established US brokerage houses. A ban on cold calling confines securities salesman to their existing customer base and persons who affirmatively seek out the services of the securities salesman. The very fact that the potential investor knows enough to seek out the securities salesman ensures that the investor has at least some knowledge of securities markets. Another view of investor protection is that securities regulation helps sophisticated investors help themselves. By requiring that material information be made available to investors, the regulation makes it possible for sophisticated investors to analyze the information and separate the good investments from the bad ones. It is not clear, however, why sophisticated investors need the help of regulation to get this information. Any potential investor can require, as a condition of investing, that he or she be provided with specified information. And providing the requested information fraudulently has always been a crime.
824
Regulation of the Securities Market
5660
5.2 Efficiency Beginning around 1980 there appeared in the literature an argument by scholars trained in law and economics that the purpose and effect of securities regulation is to make securities markets specifically, and capital markets generally, more efficient. The style of this argument echoed the many arguments in the law and economics literature that the common law is efficient. Here the argument was applied to a scheme of statutory regulation. The argument was that securities regulation required the production of more public information by firms than they would provide in an unregulated market. Because information is valuable to actors other than the firm itself, an unregulated firm would produce less information than would be produced by an unregulated firm motivated only by its own interests. This increased information results in more accurate pricing of securities, and contributes to more accurate or correct economic decisions throughout the economy, with a consequent increase in economic output by the whole society or perhaps, even, the world (Easterbrook and Fischel, 1984, 1991; Gilson and Kraakman, 1984; Kahan, 1992; Langevoort, 1992). Needless to say, this story has a happy and reinforcing congruence with the view of the financial economists that securities markets are efficient, even though they use efficiency in a quite different sense. It is a story that purports to explain why securities markets have the properties they have been found to have. This Panglossian story is based only on the stated aspiration of the securities laws: to require the production of all information material to investors. It is not based on an examination of the actual information contained in the disclosure documents produced under the securities laws, on any analysis of whether the information they contain is in fact the information required to increase the accuracy of pricing decisions, or on any explanation of how the regulators could identify what that information is. It depends on the simple argument that more information always leads to better decisions, no matter what the information is, and ignores the fact that the production of information itself has costs, which in a complete efficiency analysis must be balanced against any benefits resulting from its production. I, for instance, have pointed out that not only are there the direct administrative costs of collecting, organizing and presenting the information, which may be different information than the firm would otherwise collect, but that making the information public has direct costs to the firm because it will affect the actions of competitors and others, and that the risk of harm is increased the more economically (and hence competitively) relevant the information is (Kitch, 1995).
5660
Regulation of the Securities Market
825
5.3 Complete the organization of the market ‘firm’ Another perspective is to view the public and private aspects of securities regulation as a combined effort to create competitive market institutions which will attract securities business. This aspect of securities regulation has been more prominent in recent years as US and UK firms and regulators have adjusted their regulation in order to attract or keep business from each other and other jurisdictions. Or, to take another example, in the United States exchange-traded derivatives regulated by the CFTC compete with over- the-counter derivatives which are largely unregulated. Many users prefer the exchange-traded derivatives because of their transparency, the ease of entering and leaving positions, and the elimination of counter party risk through the exchange clearing house. Other users prefer over the counter derivatives because of their confidentiality, and the fact that the terms of the contract can be customized. These two markets, one regulated by the CFTC and the other largely unregulated, compete. In this view, the public, regulatory aspects are designed to deal with coordination problems that face the individual securities firms. The government agency helps the private firms coordinate the basic structure and organization of the markets so that the markets are attractive to potential customers. A public agency, unlike private firms, can impose collective solutions and engage in coordination relatively free of antitrust scrutiny. The principal feature of securities regulation that is inconsistent with this view of its function is that most of its provisions are mandatory. Buyers and sellers are not permitted to choose whether or not they wish to enter into a transaction subject to the regulation. If the transaction falls within the regulation it applies. If the regulation was in fact designed to increase the attractiveness of the market to the transacting parties, it would not need to force unwilling parties to accept its costs and benefits. Recently, a number of US scholars have argued that securities regulation should, at least to a greater extent than it does now, permit party choice. For instance Roberta Romano has argued that the ‘Delaware model’ of US corporate law competition should be extended to securities regulation, and that issuers should be permitted to choose the jurisdiction whose securities laws would apply to their securities. This would force regulators, just like issuers, to compete for investors. In the case of the regulators, this competition would be a competition to offer a regime of securities regulation that enhances the value of the securities offered under it (Romano, 1998; see also Choi and Guzman, 1996; Mahoney, 1997). 5.4 Capture Wealth Public choice analysis has also been applied to the securities laws, most notably in the area of insider trading (see Chapter 5650, Section 10; Phillips
826
Regulation of the Securities Market
5660
and Zecher, 1981). The public choice analysis views the securities laws as the product of political competition among groups whose wealth is affected by the provisions of the laws. Macey and Miller (1991a) have suggested, for instance, that the blue sky laws originated with concern on the part of bankers, who viewed securities as competition for deposit dollars. The passage of the securities laws in the 1930s moved the important decisions about securities regulation to the federal level. As long as currency exchange controls made it difficult for US businesses to access foreign capital markets, the national legislators and SEC Commissioners had a monopoly on the terms and conditions imposed on access to securities markets. This gave the national politicians considerable leverage to extract concessions from the industry. 5.5 Protect the Industry from Competition The view that securities regulation is a device for organizing the industry into a cartel has had considerable influence in the area of securities regulation (Baxter, 1970). In the 1970s this led to an attack under the antitrust laws on the New York Stock Exchange fixed commissions. The Exchange, as part of its membership rules, had required that members adhere to specified minimum commissions. These antitrust actions were unsuccessful (Gordon v. New York Stock Exchange, 422 US 659 (1975)). However, Congress amended the Securities and Exchange Act in 1975 to change provisions in the act that sanctioned fixed commissions, and the SEC abolished them as of May 1, 1975. Subsequently, commission rates have dropped significantly. However, turnover rates increased even more, leading to an increase in industry income. This ‘big bang’ strategy was subsequently followed in the UK (Poser, 1991), and in other countries. At the same time, Congress empowered the SEC to engage in form of central planning for the securities industry by a series of statutory amendments designed to spur the creation of a ‘National Market System’. It is fair to say that in spite of its enhanced statutory powers, the SEC’s planning has not played an important role in the subsequent evolution of the industry (Macey and Haddock, 1985; Poser, 1991). Recently, Christie and Schultz (1994) reported that market makers on the National Market System of the NASDA (the ‘NASDAQ’ market) never quoted prices in 1/8ths in many important stocks. This was suggested as evidence that the market makers were colluding to keep the spread from falling below 1/4th of a dollar (Dutta and Madhavan, 1997). These findings have led to civil and administrative actions, a reorganization of the NASDA and its affiliated NASDAQ market, and the introduction of quotations in 1/64ths on that market.
5660
Regulation of the Securities Market
827
6. The Literature A principal concern of the law and economics literature on securities markets has been the role and meaning of the concept of efficiency in this area (Gordon and Kornhauser, 1985; Lee and Bishara, 1985; Stout, 1988, 1995; Wang, 1986). This is a discussion that has been made more confusing by the special meaning that the finance economists have given the term efficiency, and it is the financial economists’ concepts of efficiency that have been the focus of the discussion. There has not been even a preliminary examination of the question of what characteristics or regulatory structure would make a securities market more efficient in the usual sense of that term. Most writing in the securities area in the United States has focused on the remedies for fraud. The private cause of action which arises in the United States under section 10(b)-5 of the 1934 Securities and Exchange Act is a distinctive feature of US securities law. This cause of action exists for misrepresentations that are unintentional, and can be enforced by a class action composed of all those who purchased after the misrepresentation without a showing that the members of the class relied on the misrepresentation. Some writers are of the view that this cause of action is an important incentive to insure the accuracy of statements made by market actors. Others view the cause of action skeptically, and express the concern that the threat of 10(b)-5 simply operates to increase the cost of providing information and to enrich lawyers (Alexander, 1991; Arlen and Carney, 1992; Carney, 1989). Since a similar cause of action is not available in other jurisdictions, it might be possible to demonstrate differences between the behavior of US and non-US markets resulting from this difference in legal remedies.
Bibliography on Regulation of the Securities Market (5660) Adams, Michael (1994), ‘Macht von Banken und Versicherungen - Wettbewerb im Finanzdienstleistungssektor-, Stellungnahme zur öffentlichen Anhörung des Deutschen Bundestages - Ausschuß für Wirtschaft -, 8. Dezember 1993 (Power of Banks and Insurances)’, Zeitschrift für Bank- und Börsenrecht, 77-86. Alexander, Janet Cooper (1991), ‘Do the Merits Matter? A Study of Settlements in Securities Class Actions’, 43 Stanford Law Review, 497-598. Alfaro Aguila-Real, Jesús (1995), Interés Social y Derecho de Suscripción Preferente. Una Aproximación Económica (Economic Efficiency of a Strict Construction of the ‘Interest of the Corporation’ Clause in Corporate Law), Madrid, Ed. Cívitas, 160 p. Arlen, Jennifer H. and Carney, William J. (1992), ‘Vicarious Liability for Fraud on Securities Markets: Theory and Evidence’, University of Illinois Law Review, 691-740. Reprinted in
828
Regulation of the Securities Market
5660
Andersen, Jensen and Mortensen (eds) (1993), Governance by Legal and Economic Measures, Copenhagen, Gad. Arrow, Kenneth J. (1964), ‘The Role of Securities in the Optimal Allocation of Risk Bearing’, 31 Review of Economic Studies, 91-96. Arruñada, Benito (1990a), Control y Regulación de la Sociedad Anónima (Control and Regulation of Joint-Stock Companies), Madrid, Alianza Editorial. Arruñada, Benito (1990b), ‘La Regulación de la Información Empresarial (Regulation of Corporate Information)’, 51 Boletín del Círculo de Empresarios, 11-42. Arruñada, Benito (1992a), ‘Crítica a la regulación de las Opas (A Critic on the Regulation of Takeovers)’, 203-4 Revista de Derecho Mercantil, 29-67. Arruñada, Benito (1992b), ‘La Conversión Coactiva de Acciones Comunes en Acciones sin voto para Lograr el Control de las Sociedades Anónimas: De Cómo la Ingenuidad Legal Prefigura el Fraude (Mandatory Conversion of Common Shares into Non-Voting Shares to Reach Corporate Control over Joint-Stock Companies: How Legal Simplicity Leads to Fraud)’, 71 Revista Española de Financiación y Contabilidad, 283-314. Arruñada, Benito and Paz Ares, Cándido (1995), ‘Conversion of Ordinary Shares into Non-Voting Shares’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 351-392. Ayres, Ian (1991), ‘Back to Basics: Regulating How Corporations Speak to the Market’, 77 Virginia Law Review, 945-999. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1991), ‘The Short Life and Resurrection of SEC Rule 19c-4', 69 Washington University Law Quarterly, 565 ff. Reprinted in 1992 Securities Law Review 377. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1994), ‘Revisiting the One-Share/One-Vote Controversy: The Exchanges’ Uniform Voting Rights Policy’, 22 Securities Regulation Law Journal, 175-219. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1995), ‘Securities Act Section 12(2) After the Gustafson Debacle’, 50 Business Lawyer, 1231-1271. Banoff, Barbara Ann (1984), ‘Regulatory Subsidies, Efficient Markets, and Shelf Registration: An Analysis of Rule 415', 70 Virginia Law Review, 135-185. Barclay, Michael J. and Holderness, Clifford G. (1992), ‘The Law and Large Block Trades’, 35 Journal of Law and Economics, 265-294. Baxter, William F. (1970), ‘NYSE Fixed Commission Rates: a Private Cartel Goes Public’, 22 Stanford Law Review, 675-712. Beaver, William H. (1980), ‘The Nature of Mandated Disclosure’, in Posner, Richard A. and Scott, Kenneth E. (eds), Economics of Corporation Law and Securities Regulation, Boston, Little Brown. Benston, George J. (1973), ‘Required Disclosure and the Stock Market: An Evaluation of the Securities Exchange Act of 1934', 63 American Economic Review, 132-155. Benston, George J. (1976), Corporate Financial Disclosure in the U.K. and the U.S.A., Farnborough, Hants, Saxon House. Berglof, Erik (1994), ‘A Control Theory of Venture Capital Finance’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 247-267. Booth, Richard A. (1994), ‘The Uncertain Case for Regulating Program Trading’, 1994 Columbia Business Law Review, 1-71. Bradford, C. Steven (1996), ‘Transaction Exemptions in the Securities Act of 1933: An Economic Analysis’, 45 Emory Law Journal, 591-672.
5660
Regulation of the Securities Market
829
Butler, Henry N. and Ribstein, Larry E. (1994), ‘Corporate Governance Speech and the First Amendment’, 43 University of Kansas Law Review, 163-206. Carney, William J. (1989), ‘The Limits of the Fraud on the Market Doctrine’, 44 Business Lawyer, 1259-1292. Choi, Stephen J. and Guzman, Andrew T. (1996), ‘The Dangerous Extraterritoriality of American Securities Law’, 17 Northwestern Journal of International Law and Business, 207-241 Christie, W. and Schultz, P. (1994), ‘Why do Nasdaq Market Makers Avoid Odd-eighth Quotes?’, 49 Journal of Finance, 1813-1860. Cochrane, James L. (1994), ‘Are US Regulatory Requirements for Foreign Firms Appropriate?’, 17 Fordham International Law Journal, 58-67. Coffee, John C. (1984), ‘Market Failure and the Economic Case for a Mandatory Disclosure System’, 70 Virginia Law Review, 717-753. Corgill, Dennis S. (1993), ‘Securities as Investments at Risk’, 67 Tulane Law Review, 861-954. Reprinted 26 Securities Law Review, 1994. Cox, James D. (1993), ‘Regulatory Competition in Securities Markets: an Approach for Reconciling Japanese and United States Disclosure Philosophies’, 16 Hastings International and Comparative Law Review, 149-173. Cox, James D. (1996), ‘Just Desserts for Accountants and Attorneys after Bank of Denver’, 38 Arizona Law Review, 519-545. Reprinted in 29 Securities Law Review, 427. Cox, James D. (1997), ‘The Fundamentals of an Electronic-Based Federal Securities Act (Markets and Information Gathering in an Electronic Age, Securities Regulation in the 21st Century)’, 75 Washington University Law Quarterly, 857-886. Cox, James D. (1997), ‘Making Securities Fraud Class Actions Virtuous (Rule 23: Class Actions at the Crossroads)’, 39 Arizona Law Review, 497. Dennis, Roger J. (1988), ‘This Little Piggy Went to Market: The Regulation of Risk Arbitrage After Boesky’, 52 Albany Law Review, 841-892. Dietl, Helmut and Picot, Arnold (1995), ‘Information (De-)Regulation of Capital Markets from the Viewpoint of New Institutional Economics’, 30 Hitotsubashi Journal of Commerce and Management, 29-46. Dutta, Prajit K. and Madhavan, Ananth (1997), ‘Competition and Collusion in Dealer Markets’, 52 Journal of Finance, 245-276. Easterbrook, Frank H. and Fischel, Daniel R. (1984), ‘Mandatory Disclosure and the Protection of Investors’, 70 Virginia Law Review, 669-715. Easterbrook, Frank H. and Fischel, Daniel R. (1991), Mandatory Disclosure’, Chapter 11 of The Economic Structure of Corporate Law, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Fanto, James A. (1996), ‘The Absence of Cross-Cultural Communication: SEC Mandatory Disclosure and Foreign Corporate Governance’, 17 Northwestern Journal of International Law & Business, 119-206. Fischel, Daniel R. (1987), ‘Organized Exchanges and the Regulation of Dual Class Common Stock’, 54 University of Chicago Law Review, 119-152. Fischel, Daniel R. and Ross, Robert R. (1991), ‘Should the Law Prohibit ‘Manipulation’ in Financial Markets?’, 105 Harvard Law Review, 503-553. Fox, Merritt B. (1984), ‘Shelf Registration, Integrated Disclosure, and Underwriter Due Diligence: An Economic Analysis’, 70 Virginia Law Review, 1005-1034.
830
Regulation of the Securities Market
5660
Friedman, Howard M. (1982), ‘Efficient Market Theory and Rule 10b-5 Non-Disclosure Claims: A Proposal for Reconciliation’, 47 Missouri Law Review, 745-762. Friedman, Milton and Schwartz, Anna J. (1963), A Monetary History of the United States, 1867-1960, Princeton, Princeton University Press. Friend, Irwin and Herman, Edward S. (1964), ‘The SEC through a Glass Darkly’, 37 Journal of Business, 382-405. Friend, Irwin and Westerfield, Randolph (1975), ‘Required Disclosure and the Stock Market’, 65 American Economic Review, 467-472. Galbraith, John Kenneth (1955), The Great Crash, 1929, Boston, Houghton Mifflin. Georgakopoulos, Nicholas L. (1995), ‘Frauds, Markets, and Fraud-on-the-Market: The Tortured Transition of Justifiable Reliance from Deceit to Securities Fraud’, 49 University of Miami Law Review, 671-730. Gilson, Ronald J. and Kraakman, Reinier H. (1984), ‘The Mechanisms of Market Efficiency’, 70 Virginia Law Review, 549-644. Gilson, Ronald J. and Kraakman, Reinier H. (1993), ‘Investment Companies as Guardian Shareholders: The Place of the MSIC in the Corporate Governance Debate’, 45 Stanford Law Review, 985-1010. Gordon, Jeffrey N. (1988), ‘Ties That Bond: Dual Class Common Stock and the Problem of Shareholder Choice’, 76 California Law Review, 1-85. Gordon, Jeffrey N. and Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1985), ‘Efficient Markets, Costly Information, and Securities Research’, 60 New York University Law Review, 761-849. Grundfest, Joseph A. (1990), ‘Internationalization of the World’s Securities Markets: Economic Causes and Regulatory Consequences’, 4 Journal of Financial Services Research, 349-378. Grundfest, Joseph A. (1994), ‘Disimplying Private Rights of Action under the Federal Securities Laws: the Commission’s Authority’, 107 Harvard Law Review, 961-1024. Reprinted in 27 Securities Law Review 199. Grundfest, Joseph A. (1995), ‘Why Disimply?’, 108 Harvard Law Review, 727-747. Haddock, David D. (1989), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Brady Report: Public Interest, Special Interest, or Rent Extraction?’, 74 Cornell Law Review, 841-864. Haddock, David D. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1987), ‘Regulation on Demand: A Private Interest Model, with an Application to Insider Trading Regulation’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 311-352. Harding, Don (1982), ‘Implications of the Efficient Market Hypothesis for Securities Regulation’, in Cranston, Ross and Schick, Anne (eds), Law and Economics, Canberra, Australian National University, 129-144. Hasabrouck, J. and Sofianos, G. (1993), ‘The Trades of Market Makers: An Empirical Analysis of NYSE Specialists’, 48 Journal of Finance, 1565-1593. Hertig, Gerard (1994), ‘Imperfect Mutual Recognition for EC Financial Services’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 177-186. Hilke, John C. (1991), ‘Mandatory Government Investment “Advice”: the Effects on Investors of State Merit Regulation of Mutual Funds and Common Stocks’, 14 Research in Law and Economics, 113-190. Hu, H. (1989), ‘Swaps, the Modern Process of Financial Innovation and the Vulnerability of a Regulatory Paradigm’, 138 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 333-435. Ingram, Robert W. and Chewning, Eugene G. (1983), ‘The Effect of Financial Disclosure Regulation on Security Market Behavior’, 58 Accounting Review, 562-580.
5660
Regulation of the Securities Market
831
Jaffe, Jeffrey F. (1974), ‘The Effect of Regulation Changes on Insider Trading’, 5 Bell Journal of Economics, 93-121. Jarrell, Gregg A. (1981), ‘The Economic Effects of Federal Regulation of the Market for New Security Issues’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 613-675. Jarrell, Gregg A. (1984), ‘Change at the Exchange: The Causes and Effects of Deregulation’, 27 Journal of Law and Economics, 273-312. Johnson, David B. (1994), ‘Property Rights to Investment Research: the Agency Costs of Soft Dollar Brokerage’, 11 Yale Journal on Regulation, 75-113. Kahan, Marcel (1992a), ‘Securities Laws and the Social Costs of ‘Inaccurate’ Stock Prices’, 41 Duke Law Journal, 977-1044. Kahan, Marcel (1992b), ‘Games, Lies and Securities Laws’, 67 New York University Law Review, 750-800. Reprinted in 26 Securities Law Review 127, 1994. Kahan, Marcel (1995), ‘The Qualified Case Against Mandatory Terms in Bonds’, 89 Northwestern University Law Review, 565-622. Kahan, Marcel and Tuckman, Bruce (1993), ‘Do Bondholders Lose from Junk Bond Covenant Changes’, 66 Journal of Business, 499-516. Kanda, Hideki (1992), ‘Debtholders and Equityholders’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 431-448. Kidwell, David S., Marr, M. Wayne and Thompson, G. Rodney (1987), ‘Shelf Registration: Competition and Market Flexibility’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 181-206. Kitch, Edmund W. (1984), ‘A Federal Vision of the Securities Laws’, 70 Virginia Law Review, 857-873. Kitch, Edmund W. (1992a), ‘The Securities Exchange Commission’, in Newman, Peter, Milgate, Murray and Eatwell, John (eds), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Money and Finance, London, Macmillan. Kitch, Edmund W. (1992b), ‘Manipulation’, in Newman, Peter, Milgate, Murray and Eatwell, John (eds), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Money and Finance, London, Macmillan. Kitch, Edmund W. (1995), ‘The Theory and Practice of Securities Disclosure’, 61 Brooklyn Law Review, 763-887. Kitch, Edmund W. (1996a), ‘Competition Between Securities Markets: Good or Bad?’, in Oditah, Fidelis (ed.), The Future for the Securities Market: Legal and Regulatory Aspects, Oxford, Clarendon, 233 ff. Kitch, Edmund W. (1996b), ‘Gustafson v. Alloyd Co.: An Opinion That Did Not Write’, 99 Supreme Court Review, 99-124. Klausner, Michael (1994), ‘Letting Banks Trade CRA Obligations Would Offer Market-Based Efficiencies’, American Banker. Kornhauser, Lewis A. and Gordon, J. (1985), ‘Efficient Markets, Costly Information, and Securities Research’, 60 New York University Law Review, 761-849. Kripke, Homer (1975), ‘Can the SEC Make Disclosure Policy Meaningful’, 31 Business Lawyer, 293-317. Kripke, Homer (1979), The SEC and Corporate Disclosure: Regulation in Search of a Purpose, New York, Law and Business Inc. Langevoort, Donald C. (1985), ‘Information Technology and the Structure of Securities Regulation’, 98 Harvard Law Review, 747-804.
832
Regulation of the Securities Market
5660
Langevoort, Donald C. (1992), ‘Theories, Assumptions, and Securities Regulation: Market Efficiency Revisited’, 140 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 851-920. Reprinted 25 Securities Law Review, 581 (1993). Langevoort, Donald C. (1994), ‘The Reform of Joint and Several Liability under the Private Securities Litigation Reform Act of 1995: Proportionate Liability, Contribution Rights and Settlement Effects’ (Symposium on the Private Securities Litigation Reform Act of 1995)’, 51 Business Lawyer, 1157-1175. Langevoort, Donald C. (1996a), ‘Capping Damages for Open-Market Securities Fraud (Symposium: Securities Litigation, The Fundamental Issues)’, 38 Arizona Law Review, 639664. Langevoort, Donald C. (1996b), ‘Selling Hope, Selling Risk: Some Lessons for Law from Behavioral Economics about Stockbrokers and Sophisticated Customers’, 84 California Law Review, 627 ff. Langevoort, Donald C. (1997), ‘Organized Illusions: A Behavioral Theory of Why Corporations Mislead Stock Market Investors (and Cause Other Social Harms)’, 146 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 101-172. Lax, David A. (1989), ‘Commentary: Market Expectations of Bargaining Inefficiency and Potential Roles for External Parties in Disputes Between Publicly Traded Companies’, 75 Virginia Law Review, 367-381. Levmore, Saul (1984), ‘Efficient Markets and Puzzling Intermediaries’, 70 Virginia Law Review, 645-667. Lorie, James H. and Hamilton, Mary T. (1973), The Stock Market: Theories and Evidence, Homewood, IL, Richard D. Irwin. Loss, Louis (1961), Securities Regulation, Boston, Little Brown. Loss, Louis (1983), Fundamentals of Securities Regulation, Boston, Little Brown. Loss, Louis and Seligman, Joel, (1989, with current supplementation), Securities Regulation, Boston, Little Brown (II Vols.). Macey, Jonathan R. and Haddock, David D. (1985), ‘Shirking at the SEC: The Failure of the National Market System’, 1985 University of Illinois Law Review, 315-362. Macey, Jonathan R. and Miller, Geoffrey P. (1991), ‘The Fraud-on-the-Market Theory Revisited’, 77 Virginia Law Review, 1001-1016. Macey, Jonathan R., Marr, M. Wayne and Young, S. David (1991), ‘The Glass Steagall Act and the Riskiness of Financial Intermediaries’, 14 Research in Law and Economics, 19-30. Macey, Jonathan R., Miller, Geoffrey P., Mitchell, Mark L. and Netter, Jeffrey M. (1991), ‘Lessons from Financial Economics: Materiality, Reliance, and Extending the Reach of Basic v. Levinson’, 77 Virginia Law Review, 1017-1049. Mahoney, Paul G. (1995a), ‘Is There a Cure for ‘Excessive’ Trading?’ (Response to an Article by Lynn A. Stout)’, 81 Virginia Law Review, 713. Mahoney, Paul G. (1995b), ‘Mandatory Disclosure as a Solution to Agency Problems’, 62 University of Chicago Law Review, 1047-1112. 28 Securities Law Review, 105. Mahoney, Paul G. (1997a), ‘Technology, Property Rights in Information, and Securities Regulation (Markets and Information Gathering in an Electronic Age, Securities Regulation in the 21st Century)’, 75 Washington University Law Quarterly, 815-848. Mahoney, Paul G. (1997b), ‘The Exchange as Regulator (Symposium: The Allocation of Government Authority)’, 83 Virginia Law Review, 1453-1500. Manne, Henry G. (1969), Economic Policy and the Regulation of Corporate Securities, Washington, American Enterprise Institute.
5660
Regulation of the Securities Market
833
McGee, Robert W. (ed.) (1989), Commentaries on the Law of Accounting and Finance, Dumont, NJ, Dumont Institute. McGee, Robert W. (1992), ‘Ethical Issues in Acquisitions and Mergers’, in McGee, Robert W. (ed.), Business Ethics and Common Sense, Westport, Quorum Books, 167-185. Miller, Geoffrey P. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1990), ‘Good Finance, Bad Economics: An Analysis of the Fraud on the Market Theory’, 42 Stanford Law Review, 1059-1092. Miller, Geoffrey P. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1991a), ‘Origin of the Blue Sky Laws’, 70 Texas Law Review, 347 ff. Miller, Geoffrey P. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1991b), ‘The Fraud on the Market System Revisited’, 77 Virginia Law Review, 1001-1016. Miller, Geoffrey P., Litt, David, Macey, Jonathan R. and Rubin, Edward L. (1990), ‘Politics, Bureaucracies, and Financial Markets: Bank Entry Into Commercial Paper Underwriting in the United States and Japan’, 139 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 369-453. Miller, Geoffrey P., Macey, Jonathan R., Netter, Jeffrey and Mitchell, Mark L. (1991), ‘Lessons From Financial Economics: Materiality, Reliance, and the Utility of Empirical Methodology in Extending the Reach of Basic V. Levinson’, 77 Virginia Law Review, 1017-1049. Mofsky, J.S. (1972), ‘SEC Financial Requirements for Broker-Dealers: Economic Implications of Proposed Revisions’, 47 Indiana Law Journal, 232-248. Nielsen, Niels Chr. (1993), ‘Minoritetsaktionærbeskyttelse - Eller et Velfungerende Market for Virksomhedskontrol (Minority Protection or a Well-functioning Market for Corporate Control)’, Revision og Regnskabsvæsen. Nielsen, Niels Chr. and Ebbesen, Jan (1993), ‘Stemmelofter - En¢konomisk analyse af den retlige analyse (Restrictions on Voting Rights, An Economic Analysis of the Legal Analysis)’, 6 Juristen, 251-264. Palmer, Matthew S.R. (1986), ‘The Economics of Law: the Sharebrokers Act 1908', 16 Victoria University of Welington Law Review, 277-301. Phillips, S. and Zecher, R. (1981), The SEC and the Public Interest, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Pille, G. (1987), ‘Financiële Instellingen en Markten: 2. Secundaire Effectenmarkt (Financial Institutions and Markets: Secundary Securities Market)’, in X (ed.), 18de Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Brussel 8 en 9 mei 1987, Sociaal-economische Deregulering, Brussel, V.E.H.U.B., 649-663. Pitt, Harvey L., Hardison, David B. and Shapiro, Karen L. (1987), ‘Problems of Enforcement in the Multinational Securities Market’, 9 University of Pennsylvania Journal of International Business Law, 375-452. Poser, Norman S. (1981), ‘Restructuring the Stock Market. A Critical Look at the SEC’s National Market System’, 56 New York University Law Review, 883-958. Poser, Norman S. (1991), International Securities Regulation, Boston, Little Brown. Posner Richard A. and Scott Kenneth E. (eds) (1980), Economics of Corporation Law and Securities Regulation, Boston, Little Brown. Prasad, Ravi (1995), ‘Review of Licensing Regime for Security Advisers’, Office of Regulation Review. Ribstein, Larry E. (1991), ‘Private Ordering and the Securities Laws: The Case of General Partnerships’, 41 Case Western Reserve Law Review, 1-64.
834
Regulation of the Securities Market
5660
Ribstein, Larry E. (1992), ‘Efficiency, Regulation and Competition: A Comment on Easterbrook and Fischel’, 87 Northwestern University Law Review, 254-286. Ribstein, Larry E. (1994), ‘Form and Substance in the Definition of a ‘Security’: The Case of Limited Liability Companies’, 51 Washington and Lee Law Review, 807-841. Romano, Roberta (1989), ‘The Politics of the Brady Report: A Comment. (Symposium on the Regulation of Secondary Trading Markets: Program Trading, Volatility, Portfolio Insurance, and the Role of Specialists and Market Makers)’, 74 Cornell Law Review, 865-872. Romano, Roberta (1991), ‘The Shareholder Suit: Litigation Without Foundation’, 7 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 55. Romano, Roberta (1996), ‘A Thumbnail Sketch of Derivative Securities and Their Regulation’, 55 Maryland Law Review, 1-83. Romano, Roberta (1997), ‘The Political Dynamics of Derivative Securities Regulation’, 14 Yale Journal on Regulation, 279-383. Romano, Roberta (1998), ‘Empowering Investors: A Market Approach to Securities Regulation’, 107 Yale Law Journal, 2359-2430. Russo, Thomas A. and Wang, William K.S. (1972), ‘The Structure of the Securities Market - Past and Future’, 41 Fordham Law Review, 1-42. Saari, Christopher P. (1977), ‘Note: The Efficient Capital Market Hypothesis, Economic Theory and the Regulation of the Securities Industry’, 29 Stanford Law Review, 1031-1076. Samuelsson, Per (1991), Information och Ansvar. Om B¢rsbolagens Ansvar (Information and Remedies. Listed Companies and Their Responsibility for False and Misleading Information in the Stock Market), Stockholm, Norstedt. Scholes, Myron S. (1972), ‘The Market for Securities: Substitution versus Price Pressure Effects and the Effects of Information on Share Prices’, 45 Journal of Business, 179-211. Schwert, G. William (1977), ‘Public Regulation of National Securities Exchanges: A Test of the Capture Hypothesis’, 8 Bell Journal of Economics, 128-150. Schwert, G. William (1981), ‘Using Financial Data to Measure Effects of Regulation’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 121-158. Reprinted in Posner, Richard A. and Scott, Kenneth E. (eds), Economics of Corporation Law and Securities Regulation, Boston, Little Brown. Seidman, L.R. (1991), ‘SEC Rule 144A: The Rule Heard Round the Globe - Or the Sounds of Silence?’, 47 Business Lawyer, 333-354. Seligman, Joel (1982), The Transformation of Wall Street: A History of the Securities and Exchange Commission and Modern Corporate Finance, Boston, Houghton Mifflin. Seligman, Joel (1983), ‘The Historical Need for a Mandatory Corporate Disclosure System’, 9 Ijournal of Cooporation Law, 1-61. Seligman, Joel (1995), ‘The Obsolescence of Wall Street: A Contextual Approach to the Evolving Structure of Federal Securities Regulation’, 93 Michigan Law Review, 649-702. Sevic, Zeljko (1994a), Pravni Status Centralne Banke u Savremenoj Trzisnoj Privredi (Status of the Central Bank in a Contemporary Market Economy), Belgrade, Faculty of Law, University of Belgrade. Sevic, Zeljko (1994b), Komisioni Posao u Bankarskom Pravu (Undisclosed Agency Operations Commission Transactions in the Banking Law), Belgrade, Cigoja-stampa.
5660
Regulation of the Securities Market
835
Sevic, Zeljko (1996), Centralna banka: Polozaj - Organizacija - Funkcije (Central Bank: Position - Organization - Functions), Belgrade, Cigoja-stampa. Simon, Carol J. (1989), ‘The Effect of the 1933 Securities Act on Investor Information and the Performance of New Issues’, 79 American Economic Review, 295-318. Slain, John J. and Kripke, Homer (1973), ‘The Interface between Securities Regulation and Bankruptcy: Allocating the Risk of Illegal Securities Issuance between Securityholders and the Issuer’s Creditors’, 48 New York University Law Review, 261-300. Stigler, George J. (1964), ‘Public Regulation of the Securities Market’, 37 Journal of Business, 117-142. Stout, Lynn A. (1988), ‘The Unimportance of Being Efficient: An Economic Analysis of Stock Market Pricing and Securities Regulation’, 87 Michigan Law Review, 613-709. Stout, Lynn A. (1990), ‘Are Takeover Premiums Really Premiums? Market Price, Fair Value, and Corporate Law’, 99 Yale Law Journal, 1235-1296. Stout, Lynn A. (1995a), ‘Betting the Bank: How Derivatives Trading Under Conditions of Uncertainty Can Increase Risks and Erode Returns in Financial Markets’, 21 Journal of Corporate Law, 53. Stout, Lynn A. (1995b), ‘Are Stock Markets Costly Casinos? Disagreement, Market Failure, and Securities Regulation’, 81 Virginia Law Review, 611-712. Stout, Lynn A. (1995c), ‘Agreeing to Disagree Over Excessive Trading’, 81 Virginia Law Review, 751-755. Stout, Lynn A. (1996), ‘Insurance or Gambling? Derivatives Trading in a World of Risk and Uncertainty’, 39 Brookings Review. Stout, Lynn A. (1997), ‘Technology, Transactions Costs, and Investor Welfare: Is a Motley Fool Born Every Minute?’, 75 Washington University Law Quarterly, 791-813. Thel, Steve (1990), ‘The Original Conception of Section 10(b) of the Securities Exchange Act’, 42 Stanford Law Review, 385-464. Reprinted 23 Securities Law Review, 85. Thel, Steve (1991), ‘The Genius of Section 16: Regulating the Management of Publicly Held Companies’, 42 Hastings Law Journal, 391-503. Thel, Steve (1995), ‘$850,000 in Six Minutes - the Mechanics of Securities Manipulation’, 79 Cornell Law Review, 219-298. Turnbull, Shann (1974), ‘Making the Securities Industry a Growth Business’, Feb. Australian Stock Exchange Journal, 34-40. Turnbull, Shann (1975), ‘Fading Out with a Profit-Planned Corporate Obsolescence’, 55 The Canadian Forum, 14-16. Turnbull, Shann (1985), ‘Trusteeship as a Technique For Sustainable Industrialisation’, in Gandhi, Marg (ed.), Gandhi Peace Foundation, New Delhi, 7,8 & 9, 634-643. Vaahtoranta, Tapani (1996), ‘The German Securities Trading Act 1994: A Ban on Insider Trading and An Issuer’s Affirmative Duty to Disclose Material Nonpublic Information’, 30 International Lawyer, 555-558. Wang, William K.S. (1986), ‘Some Arguments that the Stock Market is not Efficient’, 19 U.C. Davis Law Review, 341-402. Wang, William K.S. (1988), ‘Is a Seller’s Rule 10b-5 Cause of Action Automatically Transferred to the Buyer?’, Columbia Business Law Review, 129-148. Reprinted in Thompson, Robert (ed.) (1991), 33 Corporate Practice Commentator, 41-64.
836
Regulation of the Securities Market
5660
Whincop, Michael J. (1996a), ‘Due Diligence in SME Fundraising: Reform Choices, Economics and Empiricism’, 20 University of New South Wales Law Journal, 433-464. Whincop, Michael J. (1996b), ‘Insider Trading, Property Rights and Market Microstructure: The Case of Primary Securities Markets Transactions’, 7 Journal of Banking and Finance Law and Practice, 212-232. Young, S. David (1988), ‘The Economic Theory of Regulation: Evidence from the Uniform CPA Examination’, 63 Accounting Review, 283-291.
5700 INSURANCE REGULATION Seth J. Chandler Professor of Law,University of Houston Law Centre © Copyright 1999 Seth J. Chandler
Abstract This chapter summarizes the economic understanding of insurance regulation with a focus on solvency regulation, underwriting regulation, contract regulation and competition law exemptions. Insurance industry solvency regulation is viewed as a solution to a collective action problem that might otherwise induce insurers to take excessive risk. The chapter analyzes the economics of regulations addressing adverse selection, including traditional doctrines of warranty and misrepresentation as well as recent laws relating to genetic testing. Traditional doctrines examined from an economic perspective include contra proferentum, ‘extra-contractual damages’ and resolution of conflict of interest problems arising out of typical liability insurance policies. Competition law exemptions are seen as perhaps an overly broad vehicle to foster the economies of scale in production of information needed to prevent adverse selection and insolvency. JEL classification: K20, K29 Keywords: Insurance Regulation, Solvency Regulation, Underwriting Regulation, Adverse Selection, Genetic Testing, Warranty, Misrepresentation, Competition Law, Contra Proferentum, Contract Remedies
A. Introduction and Scope Note In almost all jurisdictions, government heavily regulates the business of insurance. To varying degrees in different states and nations, it uses its legislative and judicial branches to regulate solvency, underwriting practices and contract structure. It likewise often distinguishes the business of insurance from other businesses regarding the extent to which separate enterprises must behave competitively rather than cooperatively. While economics-oriented scholarship has not yet spanned the breadth of these varying forms of insurance regulation or plumbed the intricacies of every doctrine thereunder, an increasing mass of literature has begun to review these regulatory practices. This entry seeks to develop the main contours of the existing body of research. It should be noted that several critical topics are addressed only briefly in this chapter. The focus is on insurance regulation through legislative action and 837
838
Insurance Regulation
5700
judicial rulings as it has developed in the United States. The chapter does not discuss purely legal analyses of insurance regulation or analyses that draw on other disciplines such as political philosophy, nor does it discuss purely economic analyses of the insurance industry, including the extensive empirical work in the field. Rather, the focus is on analyses that have attempted to bring the tools of economic analysis to bear on the laws regulating insurance. Economic analysis of laws requiring purchase of insurance is addressed in a separate chapter.
B. Solvency Regulation 1. Traditional Economic Understanding Economic theory has often understood efforts by government to monitor and regulate the solvency of insurers as a solution to a collective action problem not unlike that arising with banks and other financial intermediaries (Winter, 199b). Insureds in this view are analogous to fixed-debt investors putting money into insurers who reinvest that money and return sums to the insured in the event certain events come to pass (Hansmann, 1985). This beneficial intermediation of investment requires an expectation by the investor/insured that the insurer will actually be able to pay those sums when the events occur at some point in the relatively near future (property/casualty insurance) or in the distant future (life insurance). Given the incentive of insurer/owners with limited liability to invest in high risk ventures, however, the likelihood of repayment is hardly assured. This incentive exists because insurer/owners capture all the upside of a favorable materialization of the risk while they are able to shift part of the downside of an unfavorable materialization onto the investor/insureds. While economic theory suggests that investor/insureds may be able to constrain this ‘agency cost’ or ‘moral hazard’ by use of monitored conditions in contracts (Smith and Warner, 1979; Mayers and Smith, 1981) or through bonding (mutual ownership) (Fama, 1980) few individual investor/policyholders can structure the complex arrangements needed to achieve this end. Free ridership problems hinders groups of investor/policyholders from coalescing to accomplish this aim. These problems are particularly weighty with respect to insurance because non-payment to the investor/insured occurs after the insured has suffered an often catastrophic loss at times when prompt payment is particularly valuable. It is this understanding of the insurance industry that motivates the predominant regulatory structure: governments intervene by licensure and public insurance mechanisms often known as ‘guaranty funds’ that provide at least partial indemnity to selected policyholders of an insolvent, licensed insurer (Winter, 1991b). The licensure mechanism generally imposes severe
5700
Insurance Regulation
839
punishment for sale of insurance without a license and conditions licensure on regulation and monitoring of insurer finances. The public insurance mechanism transfers the risk that this system will fail in the case of a particular insurer away from the individual insured to a collective of all insurers and, derivatively, their insureds, although this backup form of risk transfer, if effective, minimizes the incentive of insured/policyholders to monitor insurer solvency. Although this mode of regulation is prevalent throughout the world, different systems of shared sovereignty differentially allocate responsibility for solvency regulation. In the United States, a complex system exists under which, for most insurers, each of the states may regulate the solvency of insurers ‘doing business’ in that state. Regulations need not be consistent among the states (Lewis and Coates, 1991). The danger of excessive regulation posed by this system, particularly with respect to sophisticated insureds, is tempered, however, by two co-existing alternative forms of insurance regulation: captive regulation and surplus lines regulation. So-called captive insurers have their access restricted to relatively sophisticated policyholders capable of banding together to monitor the insurer. With some exceptions, they are generally regulated only by one state even when policies are sold outside that state. Surplus lines insurers, instead of being regulated by all states into which the insurer is admitted to do business, likewise have their solvency seriously regulated by only one of the states. With surplus lines insurers, however, states in which these insurers do business without a license may nonetheless regulate their market conduct. Moreover, most states make their own regulated surplus lines brokers responsible for appropriate investigations and disclosures with respect to the solvency of the surplus lines insurers. These alternative modes of insurance regulation in which a home state has greater responsibility for solvency regulation of the insurer, res embles, in certain respects, that applying in the European Community (Hogan, 1995).
2. Recent Economic Analysis of Solvency Regulation Economic scholarship regarding the laws governing insurance regulation is divided into two categories: studies of rules relating premium revenue to surplus and studies of price regulation. 2.1 Rules Relating Premium Revenue to Surplus Either through the so-called Kenney Rule or its more modern equivalent via the ‘IRIS’ system of insurance solvency monitoring used in much of the United States, most jurisdictions attempt to enhance solvency by restricting the ratio between the volume of premiums an insurer can write in some given period and
840
Insurance Regulation
5700
its stock of capital surplus. The notion is that restrictions on the rate at which a financial intermediary such as an insurer can engage in new borrowing decreases the likelihood of insolvency and preserves the ability of monitoring agencies to provide early warning of problems (Mayerson, 1969). Several scholars have challenged this implementation of solvency regulation by arguing that it creates or exacerbates positive feedback cycles in insurance pricing and availability (Winter, 1988, 1991b; Gron, 1994a, 1994b).These instabilities hamper the economy. The Winter model assumes that this method of regulation creates a topology known as a ‘fold catastrophe’. Winter argues that the regulatory constraint establishes a peculiar short-run supply curve for insurance which, when coupled with a relatively inelastic demand curve for insurance, can establish a dynamic relationship between surplus and insurance price. This dynamic process, while often equilibrating insurance markets in a relatively smooth fashion, can also lead to almost instantaneous increases in insurance price and a correlative decrease in insurance supplied - a phenomenon last observed in the late 1970s and early 1980s. 2.2 Price Regulation Other scholars have considered the economic effects of government price regulation. This regulation may occur either through the direct setting of a price for various forms of insurance or by constraining the prices an insurer may charge to some range. By requiring that rates be ‘adequate’, insurers are protected from ‘trembling hand’ instabilities (Selten, 1975) in the system whereby the perhaps irrational decision of one insurer to underprice insurance can drive out more rational insurers and lead to the collapse of an insurance system (Kimball, 1992). While history suggests that fear of insurance underpricing is not irrational, the ability of pricing regulation to combat insolvency is questionable. If insurers compete, suppression of price competition merely bolsters non-price competition in areas such as marketing (Stigler, 1968). It lowers consumer welfare because consumers no longer get the product they desire most. The loss to the United States economy from this non-price competition was estimated in 1980 at $1 billion (Frech and Sambrone, 1980). Moreover, to the extent the insurers do not compete, price regulation based on assuring an adequate return may deter efficient methods of production by insurers. Price regulation is also troublesome to the extent that permitted rates do not encompass those which would clear the market. If permitted rates fall below the market clearing rate, insurance shortages may exist that harm insureds and insurers alike (Winter, 1991a). While the existence of legal ‘black markets’ such as the surplus lines market and the captive market may reduce the impact of the distortions and hardships created thereby, the transaction costs associated with purchase of these sorts of policies, coupled with their limited availability,
5700
Insurance Regulation
841
renders these alternatives at best only a partial cure. If permitted rates stay atop the market clearing rate, a deadweight loss occurs resulting from a reduction in profitable transfers of risk. Insurers, under such a system, obtain economic rents. Costs incurred by insurer in obtaining or preserving such a hospitable regulatory state may also constitute economic waste.
C. Underwriting Regulation 3. Adverse Selection with Costly Sorting Adverse selection, the tendency of persons with private and accurate beliefs about their high risk to transfer risk more extensively than persons with low risk or without private and accurate beliefs, is the central economic problem of insurance contracting. Unchecked adverse selection can destroy an insurance market and the benefit conferred thereby (Akerlof, 1970). The law has thus developed various mechanisms to support ‘underwriting’, the process of curbing the ‘asymmetric information’ between insured and insurer that causes adverse selection. Doctrines such as representation and warranty have been central in this effort. These mechanisms have long come in occasional tension with concerns regarding insurer power and the misallocation of risk that results when these doctrines are interpreted by imperfect courts. These tensions have led only to adjustments to the central legal doctrines. In recent years, however, it has become increasingly common for laws in support of private adverse selection control to collide with other social goals such as wealth redistribution or antidiscrimination entitlements. Accordingly, the law of underwriting has, in recent years, undergone significant chance. As shown by Borenstein (1989), Rea (1992) and others, when individuals with different expected losses are ‘pooled’ and charged the identical premium, the result is a loss that depends on the elasticity of demand for insurance. In general, however, the loss results from (1) the consumption of insurance by high-risk insureds beyond the point where the marginal value they attach to risk transfer equals the marginal cost of their risk transfer and (2) the consumption of insurance by low-risk insureds in an amount less than that where the marginal value they attach to risk transfer equals the marginal cost of their risk transfer. Although, as noted by Rea (1992) and Chamberlain (1985), this efficiency loss from pooling should perhaps be offset by the gain that pooling - which itself amounts to insurance of a particular ‘commodity’ price - creates for those who, at some earlier position (Harsanyi, 1967) behind a ‘veil of ignorance’ (Rawls, 1971), do not know their risk class and are unable to adjust measured indicia of their expected loss.
842
Insurance Regulation
5700
Separation of otherwise pooled classes is generally considered to be efficient when the cost of the separating program is less than the gains resulting from enhanced allocative efficiency through pricing that more closely reflects the marginal costs of risk transfer posed by each potential insured. Separation thus becomes more sensible as the (1) cost of the developing and implementing the separation algorithm decreases; (2) the homogeneity of expected losses posed by the separated risk classes increases; and (3) the elasticity of demand for insurance increases. Reduction of the cost of a separation program in turn depends on (a) technological advances in testing, (b) reduction of variable costs by administration of binary tests only to those likely to be in the numerically smaller of the two separated classes, and (c) legal rules supporting separation. As also shown by Schmalensee (1984), Borenstein (1989) and Rea (1992), however, low-risk individuals and insurers may develop a separation program even when these efficiency conditions are not met. The low-risk insureds, this argument contends, fail to take into account the interests of the high-risk insureds in not implementing a testing program that, while it restores allocative efficiency, ends the cross-subsidization they enjoyed under pooling. Coasean bargaining by the high-risk insureds to pay off the low-risk insureds not to be tested is even more difficult than usual here, because, almost by definition, the high-risk insureds do not know the identity of the low-risk insureds. The unregulated market equilibrium in favor of separation is also troubling, as suggested by Abraham (1986), because it favors separation techniques that examine readily ascertainable characteristics such as race or gender that may have no causal relationship to expected loss but that bear a statistical correlation with the difficult-to-observe factors that indeed determine loss. In theory, the unregulated market equilibrium described above operates by establishing different pricing terms for identical contracts and achieves separation through verification mechanisms that reliability and validly classify individuals by risk. A second mechanism described first by Rothschild and Stiglitz (1976) and explicated by various scholars (Rasmusen, 1994) achieves separation by having insurers offer a menu of contracts with varying shortfalls in the indemnity to be paid - and commensurately lower prices. This menu of contracts induces only low-risk insureds (who know themselves to be low risk) to purchase the most incomplete contracts. The mechanism saves the cost of verification but results in inefficiently low levels of risk transfer to the low-risk insureds.
4. Classification of Legal Responses to the Problem of Adverse Selection Legal responses to the tensions between adverse selection control and other goals, such as non-discrimination, differ in the way that they control the
5700
Insurance Regulation
843
problem of ‘error’ and in the zones of legality they establish according to classification cost and classificatgion benefit. One prevailing response is ‘libertarian’, to give the insurer and insured complete freedom to use whatever classification devices they choose. Perhaps hoping that the market will punish inaccurate classifiers, the government itself makes no effort to control error. The government likewise fails to evaluate whether the classification method employed is inefficient, either classifying too coarsely or too finely. In some ways, this response, which at least prevents the possibility of government-created error in classification, has been the prevailing legal response in the United States and elsewhere for many years. Laws that focus primarily on error control represent a second response mode to the tension between adverse selection control and other goals. Laws, for example, that prohibit classification for automobile insurance based on marital status of the driver or that prohibit different health insurance charges for disabled individuals absent ‘sound actuarial principles’ for doing so exemplify this sort of law. Such laws act as a safeguard against the cooperative behavior generally permitted in the insurance industry by prohibiting ‘irrational’ collective discrimination by insurers against disfavored groups. They fail, however, either to require classification in this way or, apparently, to prohibit overly coarse classification in which separated groups have apparently different expected losses but in which that difference is actually caused by an underlying variable that greater classification expense would have revealed. Such laws likewise generally fail to criticize insurance classifications that result in reasonably accurate separation of applicants into groups with equivalent expected losses but that do so too finely through testing methods that are so costly as to make the whole classification enterprise inefficient. A third response mode makes classification impermissible, except when it is extremely fine, even where the cost of fine separation exceeds the economic benefit. Laws generally prohibiting use of gender as a basis for classifying individuals for life insurance or annuity policies exemplify this mode of response (Arizona Governing Committee v. Norris, 1983). In the western world, gender correlates with life expectancy and it is unclear whether many other underlying variables that determine expected life expectancy may be ascertained at any reasonable cost. Gender is nonetheless sometimes prohibited as a classification device. Laws of this sort protect both against ‘irrational’ collective discrimination but also against the ‘accident’ of certain variables that correlate with expected losses being cheaper to observe that others that actually determine expected loss. They also may serve as a safeguard against the perpetuation of irrational collective prejudices whose existence is difficult to prove. A fourth response (‘non-actuarialism’) is to prohibit classification even if it is efficient and even if it is accurate. Laws barring use of race for classifying
844
Insurance Regulation
5700
applicants for life insurance and annuities exemplify such laws. Such laws redistribute wealth according to political and social preferences apart from notions of economic efficiency. Interestingly, laws that implement the ‘efficiency concept’ described above - do not appear yet to exist, although, as noted below, restrictions on use of genetic information may fall into this category of regulation. This absence of ‘efficient actuarialism’ from the law as it actually exists may in part be due to the extraordinarily high legal and administrative costs that would be incurred in determining accurately whether any particular classification system met the efficiency standard.
5. Traditional Regulation via Legal Doctrines of Misrepresentation and Warranty As part of a libertarian impulse, the law has long facilitated separation and the economic benefits it often entails by permitting the insurer to investigate the risk characteristics of a potential insured even where this investigation probes generally private information about the insured. Moreover, subject to recent restraints on use of cheap observables such as race or gender, the law has not intervened in insurer’s selection of characteristics used to determine expected loss, even where this selection - often done in concert - causes substantial loss to identifiable social groups. Pre-contractual investigations of all potential insureds can, in many instances, be quite costly. The doctrines of warranty and representation represent potentially cheaper vehicles to create symmetric information and thereby reduce adverse selection. Under both doctrines, the insured is given an opportunity prior to contract formation to make statements that, if true, demonstrate a lower risk and thereby lower premiums in the event a contract is formed. The insured accepts some penalty in the event that some subset of otherwise insurable events come to pass and the statements made prior to contract formation turn out to have been false to some pre-specified extent as determined by some post-event investigation. The economic concept behind both warranty and representation is to restructure the ‘game’ being played by the insured and insurer into one where the insured’s dominant strategy is to reveal truthfully all private information about his risk and therefore to render the information symmetrical. The success of this concept becomes more likely as (a) the amount of the potential penalty increases, (b) the scope of the subset of events triggering the potential penalty increases, (c) the degree of falsity required to trigger the penalty decreases; and (d) the likelihood that falsity will be detected increases. The joint benefit to both insurer and insured increases as the expected cost of this post-event
5700
Insurance Regulation
845
determination decreases. Measurements of this expected cost should reflect both the cost of the investigation itself and the risk cost imposed on the insured as the result of a determination that is either incorrect or that occurs absent truly asymmetric belief structures. The traditional doctrine of warranty is a structure that results in strong inducements to tell the truth but creates substantial costs. Under a polar version of the traditional doctrine, the penalty (defeasance of an otherwise existing insurance obligation) is exacted whenever any claim for insurance benefits arises and any statement made by the insured is shown to have been false to any degree. Thus, with warranty, a claim for insurance is defeated by the making of even minimally false statements even when the complete truth would not have lowered the premium for a policy providing indemnity only for the event that actually occurred. Because warranty bars claims even when the insured cannot be shown to have known that the statement was false, the doctrine protects the insurer (and, in a competitive market, insureds) from statements that the insured in fact knew to be false in conditions where the insurer cannot prove that knowledge. The downsides of the warranty mechanism include the frequent investigations into the truthfulness of pre-contractual statements and the undesirable transfer of risk to the insured in situations where belief structures were indeed symmetric but the insured was careless in his pre-contractual statements. The doctrine of representation represents another method of controlling adverse selection. Although many variants of the doctrine exist, it may generally be idealized as a rule under which the insured is penalized (defeasance of an otherwise existing insurance obligation) whenever the insured knowingly made a false statement, a claim for insurance benefits arise, and the premium for a policy providing indemnity for the event that in fact occurred would have been materially higher had the insured been truthful. Since fewer events trigger an inquiry into the truthfulness of pre-contractual statements and since exaction of the penalty depends on the insured’s being shown to have knowingly lied, the expected penalty for false statements is less than that under traditional warranty. The incentive to be truthful and the correlative reduction in adverse selection may be tempered as well. On the other hand, representation rather than warranty lowers expected investigation costs and substantially reduces the chance of imposing a penalty on the insured in situations where beliefs were truly symmetric. During the early nineteenth century, many American and English courts saw considerable virtue in a legal regime where warranties were unfettered in their ability to control adverse selection (Horwitz, 1992). In recent years, however, legal authorities, apparently believing representation either to be a superior vehicle for controlling adverse selection or in an effort at protecting insureds from the costs of warranty, have generally imposed a preference for
846
Insurance Regulation
5700
representation, at least in situations where the legal status of pre-contractual statements has been ambiguous. Some legislatures have thus enacted statutes that deem statements to be representations absent clear statements to the contrary. Others have enacted ‘contribute to cause’ statutes that permit penalization of the insured only where the premium for a policy providing indemnity for the event that in fact occurred would have been materially higher had the insured been truthful. Few jurisdictions have considered a contribute to cause standard coupled with a significant penalty (beyond mere defeasance of otherwise existing contractual obligations) for discovery of a material falsehood, although such a mechanism with low policing costs and high penalties would fit well with economic theory regarding control of illegal behavior (Polinsky and Shavell, 1979). Also reducing the efficacy of the pre-contractual statement mechanism, though arguably decreasing its undesirable side effects, has been the doctrine of incontestability. Incontestability, which acts as a kind of statute of limitations against insurer defenses of misrepresentation of breach of warranty, generally addresses situations where there is a high risk of an erroneous determination that a pre-contractual statement was false: the insured is dead and thus unable to testify regarding knowledge of falsity or falsity itself against a life insurer seeking to avoid an indemnity obligation. Thus, at least for the subset of risk factors that the insurer could reasonably have determined by an investigation either before the contract or during some period of time (1 or 2 years) after formation of the contract, the law refuses to let post-event investigations result in a penalty to the insured (Simpson v. Phoenix Mutual Life Insurance Company, 1969). Laws reducing the penalty for false statements likewise potentially weaken the use of post-event investigations as an underwriting tools for controlling adverse selection. These laws reduce, however, the costs associated with erroneous determinations of falsity and determinations of falsity in the face of symmetric beliefs. Legislative distrust of the market’s determination of optimal methods of adverse selection control may explain statutes limiting the penalty for false declarations of age on a life insurance policy to a reduction in the indemnity equal to the difference between the face amount of the policy and the amount of insurance that could have been purchased for the same premium had the insured been truthful about age. Similar judicial distrust of the market may explain occasional rulings limiting the penalty for false representations to a reduction in indemnity equal to that which the insured would have been entitled to had it told the truth in the application process.
5700
Insurance Regulation
847
6. Genetic Testing Legal support for both investigatory and post-event methods of separation has recently collided with the growing interest in acquisition of information regarding the genetic make-up of individuals. The result has been the emergence of new laws or ‘voluntary’ agreements on the part of insurers restricting use of genetic information. The Health Insurance Portability and Accountability Act of the United States, laws recently passed in several American states, and laws enacted in Austria and Belgium, all restrict the ability of insurers either to investigate genetic information or to rely on traditional doctrines such as representation with respect to genetic information. Indeed, the Belgian law would appear to prohibit even voluntary disclosure of favorable genetic information. Insurers in Australia, France, the Netherlands, Norway and Switzerland have restricted use of genetic information through industry trade associations. Most scholars who have examined ‘genetic information privileging laws’ from an economic perspective have been critical of these efforts. They fear it will lead to serious problems of adverse selection in health and life insurance (Christianson, 1996; Pokorski, 1995, 1997). Those with privileged information of a genetic defect that increases the probability of early death but without other symptomatic manifestation might, for example, purchase large amounts of life insurance, knowing it to be a tremendous investment under those circumstances. The investment could be liquidated prior to death through viatical settlements and accelerated death benefit provisions now becoming more prevalent within insurance policies. Similarly, those with knowledge of a genetic predisposition to debilitating illnesses such as Alzheimer’s disease might stock up on long-term disability insurance. Others, however, have suggested that permitting insurance underwriting to deter genetic testing may lead to delayed diagnosis and treatment of disease. The harm caused thereby outweighs dislocations to the insurance market caused by privileging genetic information (McGoodwin, 1996). The economic component of this argument rests, however, on the value to the insured (and perhaps related parties) regarding foreknowledge of genetic defect. Moreover, this argument for privileging genetic information has greater weight with respect to health insurance and possibly long-term care insurance than it does for life insurance. With respect to the latter, it is hard to develop a traditional economic argument supporting genetic privileging laws, except perhaps one that sees the prohibition as the solution to a collective action problem under which individuals with ‘good genes’ would benefit from testing by costly methods even when the harm done to those with bad genes, coupled with the cost of testing, outweighed the total benefit created by the classification scheme.
848
Insurance Regulation
5700
Still others (Rothstein, 1993, 1997; Stone, 1996; Jacobi, 1997) have argued that genetic testing poses a perilous dilemma for a system that relies heavily on private risk-based insurance for basic health insurance. If genetic tests are not privileged, few will take them and those who do may find themselves denied financial access to good health care. If genetic tests are not privileged, the private insurance market is seriously endangered. An intriguing escape from the dilemma is suggested by one scholar, however, who proposes to bar individuals from undergoing genetic tests absent prior purchase of insurance to indemnify the insured for the higher health or life insurance premiums that would result from a finding of defect (Tabarrok, 1994). Such a system might itself be subject to some adverse selection, however. People rationally suspecting a genetic defect based either on family history or testing not covered by the law (such as testing in a foreign nation), would purchase this bundle of genetic testing and ‘insurance premium insurance’ with greater frequency than those without suspicion.
D. Contract Regulation 7. Introduction Two significant themes pervade regulation of insurance conflicts: the first is the extent to which government intervention is desirable to protect the insured from the presumed power of the insurer; a second is the extent to which government intervention is desirable to protect non-parties to the transaction from the coalition created by insurer and insured.
8. Insured Protection 8.1 Contra Proferentum Construing ambiguous contracts against the drafter, usually the insurer, has long been part of American insurance law. One economic theory for understanding this doctrine of ‘contra proferentum’ sees it as beneficially internalizing the social costs fostered by ambiguity. Imposing a ‘penalty’ for ambiguous drafting in the form of expanding the enforceable promises made by the drafter or contracting the conditions protecting the drafter theoretically induces the drafter to avoid ambiguity. An overlapping economic theory sees contra proferentum as correcting information problems in the insurance market: interpreting ambiguities in the contract in favor of the insured provides the insured with the optimal expected coverage; the insurer’s foreknowledge of
5700
Insurance Regulation
849
the doctrine insures that the insured pays the correct premium for the expanded coverage (Abraham, 1996). While the theory behind contra proferentum, so stated, may not be particularly controversial, its application in sculpting existing insurance law is. To begin with, if the non-drafting party can understand the terms of the contract without incurring significant cost, as is the case when the insured is sophisticated or a ‘repeat player’ in the transactional form, the assignment of liability to the drafting party appears arbitrary. Indeed, under such circumstances the labeling of one party as ‘the drafter’ appears arbitrary as well. Many courts nonetheless hold the doctrine still to apply in this circumstance (Ostrager and Newman, 1995). This arbitrariness might be tempered, to be sure, if the parties were costlessly able to reallocate the private burdens of ambiguity through the insurance contract itself, but impasse costs, bargaining costs, and the risk that a court would not recognize the reallocation of risk would hinder such a cure (Rappaport, 1995). Second, while the burdens of ambiguity fall substantially on society in the form of higher dispute resolution costs, the benefits of the doctrine accrue largely to the non-drafting party (at least in the case of ambiguity unrecognized by the drafter). The doctrine thus creates a disincentive for non-drafting parties to become educated and, indeed, creates a possible incentive for non-drafting parties to prefer contracts that have unrecognized ambiguities. Moreover, some have argued that the doctrine of contra proferentum discourages innovative terms in contract drafting because new terms are subject to the doctrine whereas old terms, already having been interpreted by the courts, are better understood (Goetz and Scott, 1985). The social costs of ambiguity - more judicial disputes - are thus not reduced as much as might initially be thought by the existing judicial doctrine of contra proferentum. Examination of contract terms by government officials before litigation arises, though creating its own difficulties, may thus have some place in an economic theory of insurance regulation. Scholars have also profitably used the tools of economics to classify the variants of contra proferentum found in American courts. Professor Abraham, for example, drawing on traditional law and economics scholarship, describes the optimal degree of clarity as one that would minimize the sum of maldrafting costs (uncertainty, unwarranted reliance) plus maldrafting avoidance costs (lawyer time and lengthier policies, Rappaport, 1995; Abraham, 1996). Negligence-like regimes are those in which contra proferentum is invoked only where the degree of clarity created by the drafter falls short of the optimal level. Strict liability regimes are those in which contra proferentum is invoked whenever an ambiguity is found. Drawing on recent scholarship regarding contract default rules (Ayres and Gertner, 1989), Abraham further classifies legal regimes regarding contra proferentum as penalty or majoritarian-oriented. ‘Majoritarian’ approaches alter the terms of a contract deemed ambiguous (by one of the above measures) to that which a
850
Insurance Regulation
5700
majority of policyholders would prefer - and be willing to pay for. Penalty approaches alter the terms of the contract to that which the policyholder would prefer if the expanded coverage were provided for free. While negligence/majoritarian approaches to the doctrine of contra proferentum have some appeal, the popular strict liability/penalty approach has the virtue of avoiding expensive fact-finding on issues that courts are unlikely to resolve correctly much more often than chance. 8.2 Extracontractual Damages A significant development in American insurance law has been the willingness of courts and legislatures to grant insureds injured by breach of an insurance contract damages in excess of that which would have been paid by the insurer had it honored its contractual obligations. These ‘extra-contractual damages’ have been controversial since their inception, have been the subject of some retrenchment in recent years (Macintosh, 1994), and have the subject of considerable economic analysis. There are two sorts of arguments made for augmenting damages for breach of an insurance contract. One, not the subject of examination in this entry, rests on the general inadequacy of traditional contract damages and applies those grounds in the insurance arena (Sebert, 1986). A second type of argument justifying extracontractual damages is that otherwise the winning strategy for insurers is frequent ‘opportunistic breach’ with respect to meritorious claims. This strategy is particularly effective against those who show no signs of sophistication and with respect to smaller claims (Abraham, 1986). Economic arguments in favor of extracontractual damages generally rest on forms of information failure. Unsophisticated insureds, often ignorant of their actual rights under the policy, particularly as expanded by doctrines such as contra proferentum, fear that if they sue and lose they will be out significant time and money. Attorneys are unlikely to correct any misinformation because insureds have imperfect access to the legal marketplace even for advice (Curtis, 1986). Moreover, even insureds accessing the legal market are likely to stall there because attorneys will have difficulty cheaply determining the merits of the insured’s case, particularly where the insurer has failed to create a detectable pattern signaling wrongful denials. And even an attorney determining that the case has merit will be unlikely to bring it because of the small rewards relative to the cost of the case. The reward is small because the insurer pays only what it owed in the first place, plus any positive difference between court-system interest rates and the money earned by holding on to the money, plus some attorneys fees, possibly including those of the insured (Jerry, 1986). According to this theory, the ‘equilibrium’ under a legal regime denying extracontractual damages is for the insurer to breach frequently and the insured frequently to do nothing about it. The consequence is lesser entry into insurance
5700
Insurance Regulation
851
transactions and less risk transfer than desirable. Extracontractual damages thus creates a Pareto superior contract as a default rule (Perlstein, 1992). Against this theory rests a basic question: if extracontractual damages are so superior why do they not exist in a competitive insurance market absent legal intervention? If insureds operating in a competitive insurance market really felt it were necessary and desirable to have extracontractual damages, some sort of mechanism would be built in to the contract, such as a formula damage clause for some subset of failures by the insurer timely to pay a meritorious claim. Yet such a system was seldom if ever seen. In part, economic critics of extracontractual damages say, this absence may exist because the harmful reputation an insurer would acquire through consistent bad faith denials of a claim would lead to market punishment at least as harsh as any the legal system could provide. And even if the market failed, public regulators and licensure mechanisms could succeed. It may not exist because insurers and insureds know that the legal system would be unable to distinguish ‘bad faith’ breach from simple mistake. This inability would lead to precisely what has occurred: perversions of desired coverages, induced breach (Richmond, 1994; Schmidt, 1994), and needlessly higher premiums for insureds. And it may be absent in part because the legal market functions better than proponents of extracontractual damages assert (Sykes, 1994a). Awards of legal fees to prevailing parties substantially correct the attorney incentive problems without resort to radical reformulation of contract law. The ability of some insureds to ‘sell’ their rights against insurers in a competitive market to others whose need for funds is less immediate may sometimes hinder the ability insurers would otherwise possess to force cheap settlements out of insureds. Finally, some economic scholars have argued that (ex ante) insureds subject to suffering a catastrophic loss of an irrepaceable commodity want less than full compensation for their financial loss rather than the extra compensation provided by much current law on extra-contractual damages (Cook and Graham, 1977; Fenn, 1987). This attack on extracontractual damages is not without problems. Deterrence of opportunistic breach through reputational injury rests on the dubious ability of the market accurately to distinguish breach from lawful claims denial. Public regulators are often underfunded, incompetent or captured by insurers. The competitive market that supposedly exists in fact consists of insurers who may lawfully collude. An award of simple legal fees to prevailing insureds may not entice attorneys uncertain of their clients’ prospects. The supposed cure of the insurer’s ability to exploit the weakness of an insured through assignment of claims relies on markets that seldom exist precisely because such transactions are often difficult and, in some instances, illegal (State Farm Fire and Casualty Co. v. Gandy, 1996).
852
Insurance Regulation
5700
8.3 Conflicts of Interest in Liability Insurance Policies Protection of the insured is likewise illustrated by judge-made law in the United States governing conflicts of interest created by the contract between a liability insurer and its insured over private settlement of legal actions brought against the insured. The conflict, which resembles that arising in the corporate context between various forms of claimants against corporate assets, arises from the extraordinarily complex decomposition of responsibility liability insurance policies almost always create. The responsibilities created by typical liability insurance policies in conjunction with legal doctrine may be crudely represented by positions along three not entirely orthogonal axes. One axis distinguishes responsibility for ‘discharge’ payments such as settlements and judgments made to reduce the liability of the insured from ‘defense’ payments made on behalf of the insured in defending against claims of liability. Certain discharge payments such as those that ‘exhaust’ certain limits of the policy may eliminate future defense obligations of the insurer. This feature of conventional liability insurance contracts effectively gives the insurer a ‘put’ on future defense obligations provided it can completely discharge its insured’s liability to one potential victim of the insured. Thus, a conflict occasionally arises between insurers, who want to exercise this put (at a price negotiated with a victim of the insured) and an insured, who does not want to take on defense responsibilities even when the insurer’s failure to exercise the put increases at least one insured’s expected payments in discharging liabilities to various victims (Texas Farmers Ins. Co. v. Soriano, 1994). The law is not yet well developed on whether the insurer will be permitted unfettered discretion in exercising its apparent contractual authority in this area. One axis that creates frequent conflicts distinguishes responsibility for ‘discharge’ payments made to reduce the liability of the insured based on the amount of the payment in question. Often, the insured takes the first level of responsibility pursuant to deductible or ‘self-insured retention’ provisions in its policy. A primary insurer will often take the next level of responsibility up to some policy limit, but with payments thereunder reducing its responsibility for certain other judgments against the insured and, potentially, litigation expenses in other cases. An excess insurer may take the next level of responsibility up to some policy limit, with the insured having responsibility for judgments beyond the final layer of excess. All of these responsibilities can be shifted in whole or in part to reinsurers. To the extent that litigation strategies, such as reactions to settlement offers, can shape the probability distribution of future discharge and defense obligations, which distribution in turn determines the expected loss from the case suffered by each party, the decomposition along this axis creates conflicts of interest among the various parties regarding litigation strategy (Chandler, 1993; Sykes, 1994a, 1994b; Silver and Syverud, 1995; Pryor, 1997).
5700
Insurance Regulation
853
In the absence of clear language to the contrary in the insurance contract, courts typically react to this conflict by simplifying the decomposition in a way somewhat analogous to a judically-imposed corporate restructuring. In the face of an opportunity to settle for some ‘reasonable amount’ with the plaintiff, the insurer that fails to tender the requisite amount or who acts in bad faith with respect to settlement of the case, is held to ‘own’ all layers above the one it nominally owns by contract. The faulty layer is thus liable directly to the victim for judgments piercing that layer or, through subrogation and other mechanisms, to higher layers who discharged the responsibilities that would have been theirs absent the fault of a lower layer (Stuhr, 1992). And, in most American jurisdictions, this liability exists even where the higher layer would not actually have the resources to pay the judgment. Economic theory might well view this restructuring as one vehicle (among others) for correcting inefficient behavior through internalizing of the costs created when parties in control of litigation strategy are otherwise able to foist the costs of certain strategies on to others. The restructuring often induces insurers with settlement responsibility to make decisions that maximize the joint wealth of insurer and insured, thereby leading to optimal consumption of liability insurance. The problem, as noted by two scholars (Sykes, 1994a; Logue, 1994), occurs when the higher layer (usually the insured) would not have the financial resources to pay the judgment. Under these circumstances, the conventional legal rule induces settlements that fail to maximize joint wealth, which in turn leads to underconsumption of liability insurance, which in turn leads to undercompensation of victims. A minority legal doctrine has recently re-emerged that limits the liability of the faulty layer to no more than the higher layers would actually have been able to pay. While this ‘Michigan rule’ may cure the distortions in the settlement process caused by the traditional legal decomposition of responsibility, it may create other problems such as undercompensation of victims and underdeterrence of wrongful conduct. Whatever the merits of the various rules, however, there is always the theoretical possibility of Coasean bargaining to restore efficiency (Sykes, 1994b) but it is unlikely to be particularly useful here given (a) the high costs of bargaining in this extraordinarily complex field and (b) a likely judicial reluctance to accept private party modification of legal rules. Interestingly, consonant with economic theory, liability insurance contracts tend not to grant the insurer authority to settle cases without trial absent the consent of the insured when the insured’s reputation and future income depend on exoneration from the allegations made in the lawsuit (Mayers and Smith, 1981). Courts, concerned about the major change in expected discharge responsibilities created by such a provision, generally refuse, however, to imply it into contracts otherwise silent on the matter (Dear v. Scottsdale Insurance Company, 1997; McKinley, Moody and Barlow, 1997). Insurers and insureds
854
Insurance Regulation
5700
protect against exploitation of this consent clause by frequently providing that a settlement held up by the insured’s non-consent re-layers discharge responsibilities such that the insured takes on responsibility for discharge payments in excess of the amount of the rejected settlement (Rauch et al., 1986). A third axis in which conflicts of interest arises surrounds the liability insurance contract’s decomposition of responsibility for various types of events. The insurer, for example, generally has discharge obligations arising out of liability from negligence but generally does not have discharge obligations arising out of more serious types of fault. This conflict leads to an intricate ballet of litigation strategies and counterstrategies described well by one recent scholar (Pryor, 1997). In essence, however, the injured party may ‘underlitigate’ the dispute in an effort both to induce the insurer to incur heightened expected defense and discharge obligations, which increase may be partly appropriated by the injured party through offering to withdraw the triggering underlying dispute against the insured in exchange for a payment mostly from the insurer.
9. Public Protection 9.1 Anti-Diminution In the past, some liability or indemnity insurers sought to reduce the amount they paid victims of their insureds based on the insolvency of their insureds. The insurers’ theory was that their own liability derived from actual payment or the possibility of payment by the insured, which possibility was reduced by the insured’s insolvency. ‘Anti-diminution laws’, or ‘bankruptcy provisions’ now frequently prohibit this practice (Jerry, 1987) and are a classic example of insurance regulation acting to the detriment of the insured and in favor of the public at large. Assuming with Huberman that an insured’s utility of wealth is constant below some ‘insolvency’ level, but that the indemnity owed as a function of insured loss does not have to be non-decreasing, an insured would prefer a policy whose indemnity obligation disappeared above some threshhold level of loss to a policy that had some constant upper limit regardless of the amount of the loss. Indemnity obligations on the part of the insurer that fail to increase the utility of the insured in the event of some serious adverse increase needlessly decrease wealth in all other states by increasing the actuarially justified premium owed by the insured for the insurance. And, indeed, during the early years of indemnity/liability insurance, such ‘diminution clauses’ existed in insurance policies. The problem with such ‘diminution clauses’ is that they result in inadequate compensation to victims of the insured and exacerbate the moral hazard problem caused by the existence of insurance (Shavell, 1986). Many American states now require that insurance policies not diminish on account of the
5700
Insurance Regulation
855
insolvency of the insured. 9.2 Treatment of Proceeds in Insolvency The conflict between the interests of the insured and those of potential stranger victims of the insured shows itself again in the legal treatment of liability insurance proceeds upon the insolvency of the insured. Treating these proceeds as property of the estate and thus available to all creditors of the insured, including contract creditors, has the potential generally to enrich the insured by permitting it to borrow at lower interest rates, which inures to the benefit of the insured in the event a subsequent insolvency does not occur. Treating the proceeds as dedicated to the victims of conduct covered by the insurance policy, as the law now often does, means that uncovered claimants such as contract creditors or victims of tortious conduct excluded from the insurance policy’s indemnity obligations must look solely to the insured’s non-insurance assets in the event of an insolvency. This treatment thus has the potential to increase the interest rate the insured must pay. This result likewise may occur where the proceeds of the policy are nominally part of the insured’s estate but where the law permits victims of conduct covered by the insurance policy to ‘cut through’ and bargain with the insurer for a direct payment in exchange for a reduction of the claim against the insured. 9.3 Extreme Conduct Limitations Government limitations on the ability of insureds to protect themselves against liability either for their intentional misconduct to others or for conduct deemed appalling or sadistic enough to be worthy of ‘punitive’ or ‘exemplary’ damages further illustrates intervention in the market to protect potential victims of the insured’s and insurer’s cooperation (Chandler, 1996). Generally, these limitations restrict coverage for appalling conduct. Other times, however, notably in the area of automobile insurance, government requires coverage for appalling conduct so as not to defeat a ‘compulsory insurance’ regime (State Farm Fire and Casualty Co. v. Tringali, 1982). Many commentators applaud limitations on the insurability of punitive damages or damages for intentional conduct on grounds that such restrictions prevent undesirable moral hazard (Ellis, 1982). These efforts generally fail to confront the questionable need for such governmentally imposed constraints, however, given the ability of insurers who fear moral hazard and who will pay the price for failure to control it on their own through exclusions and conditions in the insurance contract. One explanation is that the refusal to enforce contracts permitting indemnification for severely deviant conduct lets insurers and insureds, apparently confused at the time of contracting, ‘come to their senses’. Such a legally created ‘reprieve’ from a faulty contract may be particularly important given the possibility that indemnity for punitive damages
856
Insurance Regulation
5700
will increase the frequency of wrongful behavior by insureds and the frequent inability of the law, even with punitive damages, to restore their victims to the status quo ex ante. This argument explanation draws support from simulations conducted by one scholar suggesting that few rational contracting parties would want to provide indemnity for conduct grossly below an efficient level of care, even with court systems prone to error (Chandler, 1996). Perhaps the simplest explanation made with respect to the non-insurability of punitive damages is that deterrence models are irrelevant to punitive damages and that punishment is destroyed where punishment is indemnified (Ellis, 1982).
E. Competition Law Exemptions In the United States and in Europe, insurers have been exempt from many ‘competition’ or ‘antitrust’ laws prohibiting forms of cooperative behavior by distinct insuring entities. In the United States, this exemption occurs via the McCarran-Ferguson Act (15 United States Code § 1011-15) insulating insurers from most of federal antitrust laws, and by ‘mini McCarran-Ferguson Acts’ enacted by some states insulating insurers to varying degrees from the states’ own laws barring combinations and conspiracies in restraint of trade. In Europe, it occurs via Commission Regulation promulgated in 1992 under Article 85(3) of the Treaty of Rome. This regulation generally permits certain cooperative practices in the ‘insurance sector’ such as cooperation with respect to establishment of premiums, standard policy forms and coverages that might otherwise be prohibited by Article 85(1) of the Treaty and the regulations thereunder. An economic theory has emerged to justify this departure from the general notion that competition rather than cooperation maximizes welfare: the significant economies of scale in production of information needed to prevent adverse selection and insolvency (Achampong, 1991; Danzon, 1992; Macey and Miller, 1993b). Without significant data on the experience of policyholders, it becomes difficult reliably to model the expected loss posed by individual policyholders and therefore accurately to establish actuarially sound premiums. Individual insurers, even large insurers operating multiple lines in many jurisdictions, may lack adequate internal historic data to perform the necessary analyses with confidence. Some have argued that this inability extends even to projections of future losses on future policies. Collective analysis on this point should thus be exempt from antitrust scrutiny (Danzon, 1992). Advocacy of cooperation rather than competition in the business of insurance extends to collective drafting of policy forms. Without common forms, the data needed to make reliable predictions would be ‘noisy’ and thus less amenable to accurate, fine-grained statistical analysis (Macey and Miller,
5700
Insurance Regulation
857
1993a, 1993b). Consumers are thought better able to shop when policies have only a few varying parameters, such as price. Uniformity in policy provisions thus actually favors competition, this argument proceeds. Moreover, reinsurance, which serves an economically beneficial specialization function, would be hampered were collective policy forms barred and certain lines of insurance made more custom and less of a ‘commodity’ (Ayres and Siegelman, 1989). Two other economic arguments also frequent debates about application of competition laws to the insurance industry. First, scholars such as Bork (1978) generally question whether collusive behavior between entities should ever be illegal so long as the law would permit those entities to merge. Limited cooperation between competitors might well be better than the elimination of competition through merger (Bork, 1978). Exemption from competition laws thus fosters the existence of numerous small insurers and, derivatively, competition (Danzon, 1992). Second, and somewhat relatedly, some scholars have suggested that legally supported cooperation helps prevent ‘cut-throat’ or ‘anarchic’ competition that, at least historically, appears to have jeopardized the solvency of insurers (Carlson, 1979; McDowell, 1987). Several scholars have noted, however, the scope of the American exemption from competition laws is considerably broader than the arguable economic justification (Achampong, 1991; Macey and Miller, 1993a) Collective data gathering would almost certainly be protected by modern interpretations of existing American competition laws, even were the McCarran-Ferguson Act not in place. Moreover, a need for collective data gathering would not seem to justify collective data analysis, nor would it justify collective pricing of insurance policies, both of which are frequently permitted in the United States though practiced somewhat less frequently than in years past. Moreover, if there are economies of scale in data collection, it is not clear why for insurance but not for other industries the law would ‘prop up’ small companies operating at less than an efficient scale by permitting them to collude with each other in a way other than lawful merger or joint research permitted for all industries under federal laws enacted in the 1980s. This critique would appear to be supported by empirical research suggesting that the economies of scale in the insurance industry are limited and that many insurers could survive at the minimum efficient scale (Geehan, 1986; Joskow, 1992). It has also been suggested that the collusive rating practices facilitated by the exemption from competition laws induces sloppy and inefficient cost control measures by insurers (Angoff, 1988). Finally, collective data gathering may trap underwriting practices in some local optimum whereas the greater experimentation facilitated by barring collusion might lead to more accurate methods of assessing policyholder risk. Interestingly, the more recent regulations of the European Community appear to echo at least some of these criticisms of the broad American exemption from competition laws. Under Regulation 3932/92, for example,
858
Insurance Regulation
5700
collaborative compilation of statistics on expected losses is permitted as is statistical analysis of that data. Collective determinations of actual premiums, after expense loading and other cost factors are taken into account, is prohibited, however. Obligations among competitors to adhere to a joint pricing mechanism are void. While development of common policy forms and coverages are permitted, insurers are not permitted to enter into contracts with each other than would compel use of these forms and coverages.
F. Conclusion Sensible regulation of insurance requires an understanding of a broad span of economics including finance theory, price theory, game theory, dynamics, international trade and econometrics as well as ancillary subjects such as statistical and information theory. It also requires an understanding of jurisprudential issues such as the appropriate specificity of rules, the appropriate centralization of legal authority across networked cultures, the appropriate allocation of law-making authority between legislature and judiciary, and the costs of various forms of dispute resolution. While the broad contours of insurance regulation have been profitably and extensively examined using tools from each of these disciplines separately, and while this entry evidences some considerable progress in a more interdisciplinary approach, many of the intricacies of legal doctrine that determine the actual course of insurance transactions remain unconquered by the powerful combination of law and economics.
Bibliography on Insurance Regulation (5700) Abraham, Kenneth S. (1985), ‘Efficiency and Fairness in Insurance Risk Classification’, 71 Virginia Law Review, 403-451 Abraham, Kenneth S. (1986), Distributing Risk: Insurance, Legal Theory and Public Policy, New Haven, Yale University Press. Abraham, Kenneth S. (1991), Environmental Liability Insurance Law, Prentice Hall Law and Business. Abraham, Kenneth S. (1996), ‘A Theory of Insurance Policy Interpretation’, 95 Michigan Law Review, 531-569. Achampong, Francis (1991), ‘The McCarran-Ferguson Act and the Limited Insurance Antitrust Exemption: An Indefensible Aberration’, 15 Seton Hall Legislative Journal, 141-169. Akerlof, George (1970), ‘The Market for Lemons: Quality Uncertainty and the Market Mechanism’, 84 Quarterly Journal of Economics; 488-500. Angoff, Jay (1988), ‘Insurance Against Competition: How the McCarran-Ferguson Act Raises Prices
5700
Insurance Regulation
859
and Profits in the Property-Casualty Insurance Industry’, 5 Yale Journal on Regulation, 397-415. Ayres, Ian and Siegelman, Peter (1989), ‘The Economics of the Insurance Antitrust Suits: Towards an Exclusionary Theory’, 63 Tulane Law Review, 971-997. Borenstein, Severin, (1989), ‘The Economics of Costly Risk Sorting in Competitive Insurance Markets’, 9 International Review of Law and Economics 25-39. Carlson, Larry D. (1979), ‘The Insurance Exemption from the Antitrust Laws’, 57 Texas Law Review 1127 ff. Chamberlain, John R. (1985), ‘Assessing the Fairness of Insurance Classifications’, 7 Research in Law and Economics, 65-87. Chandler, Seth J. (1993), ‘Reconsidering The Duty to Settle’, 42 Drake Law Review, 741-806. Chandler, Seth J. (1996), ‘The Interaction of the Tort System and Liability Insurance Regulation: Understanding Moral Hazard’, 2 Connecticut Insurance Law Journal, 91-177. Christianson, David J. (1996), ‘Genetic Testing: Risk Classification and Adverse Selection’, 15 Journal of Insurance Regulation, 75-79. Cook, P.J. and Graham, D.A. (1977), ‘The Demand for Insurance and Protection: The Case of Irreplaceable Commodities’, 91 Quarterly Journal of Economics,143-156. Crocker, Keith J. and Snow, Arthur (1986), ‘The Efficiency Effects of Categorical Discrimination in the Insurance Industry’, 94 Journal of Political Economy, 321-344. Cummins, J. David (1988), ‘Risk-Based Premiums for Insurance Guaranty Funds’ 43 Journal of Finance, 823-839. Curtis, Linda (1986), ‘Damage Measurements for Bad Faith Breach of Contract: An Economic Analysis’, 39 Stanford Law Review, 161-185. Danzon, Patricia M. (1992), ‘The McCarran-Ferguson Act: Anticompetitive or Procompetitive’, Regulation, Spring 38-47. Ellis, Dorsey D. (1982), ‘Fairness and Efficiency in the Law of Punitive Damages’, 56 Southern California Law Review, 1-78. Fama, Eugene F. (1980), ‘Agency Problems and the Theory of the Firm’, 88 Journal of Political Economy, 288 ff. Fenn, Paul (1987), ‘Evaluating Irreplaceable Loss: Some Implications for Insurance and Liability Rules’, 12 Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance,158-167. Finsinger, Jorg and Pauly, Mark (1992), ‘Reserve Levels and Reserve Requirements for Profit-maximizing Insurance Firms’, in Dionne, George and Harrington, Scott E. (eds), Foundations of Insurance Economics, Boston, Kluwer. Finsinger, Jörg, Hammond, Elizabeth and Trapp, Julian (eds) (1985), Insurance: Competition or Regulation?, London, The Institute for Fiscal Studies. Frech, H.E. and Samprone, Joseph C. (1980), ‘The Welfare Loss of Excess Nonprice Competition: The Case of Property-Liability Insurance Regulation’ 23 Journal of Law and Economics, 429-440. Geehan, Randall (1986), ‘Economies of Scale in Insurance: Implications for Regulation’, in: Wasow, Bernard and Hill, Raymond D. (eds), The Insurance Industry in Economic Development, New York, New York University Press, 137-159. Goetz, Charles J. and Scott, Robert E. (1985), ‘The Limits of Expanded Choice: An Analysis of the Interactions Between Express and Implied Contract Terms’, 73 California Law Review, 261-322.
860
Insurance Regulation
5700
Gron, Anne (1994a), ‘Evidence of Capacity Constraints in Insurance Markets’, 37 Journal of Law and Economics, 349-377. Gron, Anne (1994b), ‘Capacity Constraints and Cycles in Property-Casualty Insurance Markets’, 25 RAND Journal of Economics, 110-127. Hansmann, Henry (1985), ‘The Organization of Insurance Companies: Mutual versus Stock’, 1 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization 125-153. Hogan, Arthur M.B. (1995), ‘Regulation of the Single European Insurance Market’, 13 Journal of Insurance Regulation, 329-358. Huberman, Gur, Mayers, David and Smith, Clifford W. (1983), ‘Optimal Insurance Policy Indemnity Schedules’, 14 Bell Journal of Economics, 415-425. Jacobi, John V. (1997), ‘The Ends of Health Insurance’, 30 University of California Davis Law Review 311-404. Jerry, Robert H., II (1986), ‘Remedying Insurer’s Bad Faith Contract Performance: A Reassessment’, 18 Connecticut Law Review, 271-321. Jerry, Robert H., II (1987), Understanding Insurance Law, § 95c, New York, Matthew Bender. Jones, Brian A. (1996), ‘Insurance Regulation in the European Union’, 47 Federation of Insurance and Corporate Counsel Quarterly, 75-93. Joskow, Paul L. (1992), ‘Cartels, Competition and Regulation in the Property-Liability Insurance Industry’ in Dionne, Georges and Harrington, Scott E. (eds), Foundations of Insurance Economics, Boston, Kluwer. Kimball, Spencer L. (1961), ‘The Purpose of Insurance Regulation: A Preliminary Inquiry in The Theory of Insurance Law’, 41 Minnesota Law Review 471-524. Kimball, Spencer L. and Denenberg, Herbert S. (eds) (1969), Insurance, Government, and Social Policy, Homewood, IL, Richard D. Irwin. Logue Kyle D. (1994), ‘Solving the Judgment-Proof Problem’, 72 Texas Law Review, 1345-1394. Macey, Jonathan R. and Miller, Geoffrey, P. (1993a), ‘The McCarran-Ferguson Act of 1945: Reconceiving the Federal Role in Insurance Regulation’, 68 New York University Law Review, 13-88. Macey, Jonathan R. and Miller, Geoffrey P. (1993b), Costly Policies: State Regulation and Antitrust Exemption in Insurance Markets, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute Press. Macintosh, Kerry L. (1994), ‘Gilmore Spoke too Soon: Contract Rises from the Ashes of the Bad Faith Tort’, 27 Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review, 483 ff. Mayers, David and Smith, Clifford W., Jr (1981), ‘Contractual Provisions, Organizational Structure, and Conflict Control in Insurance Markets’, 54 Journal of Business, 407-434. Mayerson, Allen L. (1969), ‘Ensuring The Solvency of Property and Liability Insurance Companies’ in: Kimball, Spencer L. and Denenberg, Herbert S. (eds), Insurance, Government, and Social Policy, Homewood, IL, Richard D. Irwin. McDowell, Banks (1987), ‘Competition as a Regulatory Mechanism in Insurance’, 19 Connecticut Law Review, 287-310. McGoodwin, Wendy L. (1996), ‘Genetic Testing: A Tool for Doctors, not for Insurers’, 15 Journal of Insurance Regulation, 71-74. Perlstein, Barry (1992), ‘Crossing The Contract-Tort Boundary: An Economic Argument for the Imposition of Extracompensatory Damages for Opportunistic Breach of Contract’, 58 Brooklyn Law Review, 877-911.
5700
Insurance Regulation
861
Pokorski, Robert J. (1995), ‘Genetic Information and Life Insurance’, Nature, July 6, 1995, 13-14. Pokorski, Robert J. (1997), ‘Insurance Underwriting in the Genetic Era’, 60 American Journal on Human Genetics, 205-216. Pryor, Ellen S. (1997), ‘The Stories We Tell: Intentional Harms and the Quest for Insurance Funding’, 75 Texas Law Review, 1721-1764. National Association of Insurance Commissioners (1996), ‘Report of the NAIC Genetic Testing Working Group’, 15 Journal of Insurance Regulation, 7-65. Rappaport, Michael B. (1995), ‘The Ambiguity Rule and Insurance Law: Why Insurance Contracts Should not be Construed Against the Drafter’, 30 Georgia Law Review 171-257. Raviv, Artur (1992), ‘The Design of an Optimal Insurance Policy’ in: Dionne, George and Harrington, Scott E. (eds), Foundations of Insurance Economics, Boston, Kluwer. Rea, Samuel A., Jr (1992), ‘Insurance Classifications and Social Welfare’, in Dionne, Georges (ed.), Contributions to Insurance Economics, Boston, Kluwer. Rea, Samuel A., Jr (1993), ‘The Economics of Insurance Law’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 145-162. Rothschild, Michael and Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1976), ‘Equilibrium in Competitive Insurance markets: An Essay on the Economics of Imperfect Information’, 90 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 629-649. Rothstein, Mark A. (1993), ‘Genetics, Insurance and the Ethics of Genetic Counseling’, 3 Molecular Genetic Medicine, 159-177. Rothstein, Mark A. (1997), ‘Genetic Secrets: A Policy Framework’, in Rothstein, Mark A. (ed.), Genetic Secrets: Protecting Privacy and Confidentiality in the Genetic Era, New Haven, Yale University Press. Schmalensee, Richard (1984), ‘Imperfect Information and the Equitability of Competitive Prices’, 99 Quarterly Journal of Economics 441-460. Sebert, John A., Jr (1986), ‘Punitive and Nonpecuniary Damages in Actions Based Upon Contract: Toward Achieving The Objective of Full Compensation’,33 University of California Los Angeles (UCLA) Law Review 1565-1678. Shavell, Steven (1986), ‘The Judgment Proof Problem’, 6 International Review of Law and Economics, 45-58. Shavell, Steven (1987), An Economic Analysis of Accident Law, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Silver, Charles and Syverud, Kent (1995), ‘The Professional Responsibilities of Insurance Defense Lawyers’, 45 Duke Law Journal 255-363. Smith, Clifford W. and Warner, Jerold B. (1979), ‘On Financial Contracting: An Analysis of Bond Covenants’, 7 Journal of Financial Economics, 117-161. Stigler, George J. (1968), ‘Price and Nonprice Competition’, 76 Journal of Political Economy, 149 ff. Stone, Deborah A. (1996), ‘The Implications of the Human Genome Project for Access to Health Insurance’, in The Human Genome Project and the Future of Health Care, Indiana University Press. Sykes, Alan O. (1994a), ‘Bad Faith: Refusal to Settle by Liability Insurers: Some Implications of the Judgment-Proof Problem’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 77-110. Sykes, Alan O. (1994b), ‘Judicial Limitations on the Discretion of Liability to Settle or Litigate: An Economic Critique’, 72 Texas Law Review 1345-1374.
862
Insurance Regulation
5700
Sykes, Alan O. (1996), ‘Bad Faith Breach of Contract by First-Party Insurers’, 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 405-444. Tabarrok, Alexander (1994), ‘Genetic Testing: an Economic and Contractarian Analysis’, 13 Journal of Health Economics, 75-91. Van Den Berghe, Lutgart (1990), ‘(De)Regulation of Insurance Markets’ in Louberge, Henri (ed.), Risk, Information and Insurance: Essays in the Memory of Karl H. Borch, Boston, Kluwer, 199-220. Winter, Ralph A. (1988), ‘The Liability Crisis and the Dynamics of Competitive Insurance Markets’, 5 Yale Journal on Regulation, 455-499. Winter, Ralph A. (1991a), ‘Solvency Regulation and the Property-Liability “Insurance Cycle”’, 29 Economic Inquiry, 458-71. Winter, Ralph A. (1991b), ‘The Liability Insurance Market’, 5 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 115-136. Wortham, Leah (1986), ‘The Economics of Insurance Classification: The Sound of One Invisible Hand Clapping’, 47 Ohio State Law Journal, 835-890.
Other References Ayres, Ian and Gertner, Robert (1989), ‘Filling Gaps in Incomplete Contracts: An Economic Theory of Default Rules’, 99 Yale Law Journal, 87-130. Bork, Robert H. (1978), The Antitrust Paradox: A Policy At War With Itself, New York, Basic Books. Harsanyi, John (1967), ‘Games with Incomplete Information Played by “Bayesian” Players I: The Basic Model’, 14 Management Science, 159-182. Horwitz, Morton J. (1992), The Transformation of American Law, New York, Oxford University Press. Howard, Lisa S. (1996), ‘Genetic Testing Debate Starts to Bubble in U.K.’, National Underwriter, August 5, 45-46. Kimball, Spencer L. (1992), Cases and Materials on Insurance Law, Boston, Little Brown. Lewis, Stephen and Coates, Katherine (1991), ‘European Perception of U.S. State Regulation’, in Semaya, Francine and Vitkowsky, Vincent J. (eds), The State of Insurance Regulation, Chicago, American Bar Association. Ostrager, Barry R. and Newman, Thomas R. (1995), Handbook of Insurance Coverage Disputes, New York, Prentice Hall Law and Business, §1.03. McKinley, Hall F., III, Moody, G. Randall and Barlow, Peter B. (1997), ‘Issues in the Selection of Counsel and Control of Litigation when the Insured has a Self-Insured Retention’, 32 Tort and Insurance Law Journal, 769-786. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1979), ‘The Optimal Tradeoff Between the Probability and Magnitude of Fines’, 69 American Economics Review, 880 ff. Rasmusen, Eric (1994), Games and Information: An Introduction to Game Theory, 2nd edn, Cambridge, MA, Blackwell. Rauch, Michael, et al. (1986), ‘Settlement of Professional Liability Claims’, in Professional Liability Insurance for Attorneys, Accountants, and Insurance Brokers 1986, New York, Practicing Law Institute. Rawls, John (1971), A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, MA, Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
5700
Insurance Regulation
863
Richmond, Douglas R. (1994), ‘The Two-Way Street of Insurance Good Faith: Under Construction, but Not Yet Open’ 28 Loyola University Chicago Law Journal 95-140. Riegel, Robert (1916), ‘Fire Insurance Rates: Problems of Cooperation, Classification, Regulation’, 30 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 704-737. Schmidt, Stephen R. (1994), ‘The Bad Faith Setup’, 29 Tort and Insurance Law Journal 705-739. Selten, Reinhard (1975), ‘Re-examination of the Perfectness Concept for Equilibrium Points in Extensive Games’, 4 International Journal of Game Theory, 25-55. Sankey, Keith (1997), ‘UK: Insurers Measure Up Genes’, Reinsurance, April 30, 1997. Stuhr, V. Eileen (1992), ‘Excess Carrier Tort Suits: Are Primary Insurers Up The Canal Without a Paddle?’, 29 Houston Law Review, 661-717.
Cases Arizona Governing Committee v. Norris (1983), 463 United States Reports 1073-1011. Dear v. Scottsdale Insurance Co. (1997), 947 Southwestern Reporter (Second Series) 908-919. Simpson v. Phoenix Mutual Life Insurance Co. (1969), 24 New York Reporter (Second Series) 262-268. State Farm Fire and Casualty Co. v. Gandy (1996), 39 Texas Supreme Court Journal 696-719. State Farm Fire and Casualty Co. v. Tringali (1982), 686 Federal Reporter (Second Series) 821-825. Texas Farmers Ins. Co. v. Soriano (1994), 881 Southwestern Reporter (Second Series) 312-318.
5810 MARRIAGE CONTRACTS Antony W. Dnes Associate Dean (Research) University of Hertfordshire, England. © Copyright 1999 Antony W. Dnes
Abstract This chapter is an examination of the incentive structure set up by the law of marriage and divorce. Two forms of opportunistic behaviour are of particular interest: the ‘greener-grass’ effect and the ‘Black-Widow’ effect. There is a case for seriously considering expectation damages as a basis for post-divorce support obligations and asset division. The current focus of marital law on a mixture of needs-based and contractual elements in divorce settlements is vulnerable to the charge that behaviour is encouraged in both males and females that is predatory in nature. The contractual uncertainty that follows from this may well deter some good quality marriages that might otherwise occur. JEL classification: K12 Keywords: Family, Remedies, Needs, Opportunism, Breach of Contract
1. Introduction The growth of divorce, reduction in rates of marriage, growth of co-habitation, and similar trends in western society have all caused concern in recent years. Families are less stable and this has implications for the welfare of children. From an economic perspective, a major issue is the incentive structure set up by the law of marriage and divorce. The dependency and vulnerability of one marriage partner to opportunistic behaviour by the other is foreseeable under current laws, opportunism being defined as self-seeking with guile (definition of Williamson, 1985, p. 47). This chapter is specifically concerned with the extent to which laws may have set up incentives encouraging divorces that would otherwise be avoided and discouraging marriages that might otherwise have occurred Two adverse incentives are of particular interest. Financial obligations may create incentives for a high-earning partner to divorce a low-earning, or possibly simply ageing, spouse if the law does not require full compensation of lost benefits. Elsewhere, I have called this the ‘greener-grass’ effect (Dnes, 1978). Under current social conditions and present marital law, the 864
5810
Marriage Contracts
865
greener-grass effect will typically induce wealthy men to abandon poorer wives. There could also be an incentive for a dependent spouse to divorce if payments based on dependency allow the serial collection of marital benefits without regard to the costs imposed on the other party. I call the second adverse incentive the ‘Black-Widow’ effect (Dnes, op cit.). Under current conditions, Black Widows are likely to be women with relatively poor husbands in marriages where the husband cannot transfer benefits to deter her exit.
2. Marriage as a Long-Term Contract A useful starting point is to think of marriage as a contract between two parties and divorce as resulting from breach of contract, although it should be noted that marriage predated the development of contract. A purely contractual starting point would be modern, although contractual elements are present in the case law (Lloyd Cohen, 1987, p. 270). A contractual approach is also capable of considerable sophistication and it is unhelpful to dismiss it out of hand, particularly where inherently economic issues like asset division are at stake. Becker was a pioneer among economic theorists of marriage and is often regarded as a bête noir by writers hostile to economics-based approaches to the family. Becker’s work is admirable but was not focused on opportunism. It has lead to more recent bargaining theories of the family. The interested reader may see Becker (1974a) and Becker (1991) to inspect the origins of economic analysis of the family. Lloyd Cohen (1987) describes marriage as an unusual contract in which the parties exchange promises of spousal support, where the value of the support is crucially dependent on the attitude with which it is delivered. In a traditional marriage, many of the domestic services provided by the wife occur early in the marriage, whereas the support offered by the male will grow in value over the longer term. The opportunities of the parties may change so that one of them has an incentive to breach the contract. Divorce imposes costs on both parties, equal to at least the cost of finding a replacement spouse of equivalent value (in contract terms this cost is technically a measure of expectation damages, that is the replacement cost of the anticipated spousal support). Cohen argues that the risks and costs of being an unwilling party to divorce are asymmetrically distributed: the husband might be tempted to take the wife’s early services and dump her to enjoy his later income without her (the ‘greener-grass’ effect), and she will tend to be worth less on the remarriage market than a male of similar age (Lloyd Cohen, 1987, p. 278). Why do people marry? There are both psychic and instrumental benefits to marriage.
866
Marriage Contracts
5810
The willingness of someone to commit themselves to oneself is evidence of worthiness of such love, and marriage gives a means of protecting long-term investments in marital assets. According to Cohen the spouses may be regarded as ‘unique capital inputs in the production of a new capital asset, namely ‘the family’. In particular, children are shared marital outputs. Another instrumental gain is the provision of insurance: parties give up their freedom to seek new partners, if their prospects improve, for a similar commitment from a spouse, which is rational if the gains from marriage exceed the cost of losing freedom to separate (see Posner, 1992). The gains from marriage reflect surpluses that can be seen as appropriable and may tempt a spouse to opportunistic behaviour, comparable to the incentives in more regular long-term contracts (see Klein, Crawford and Alchian, 1978). Cohen also draws attention to the role of marriage-specific investments like the effort expended on raising children, or the prospect of losing association with one’s children, as ‘hostages’ that may suppress opportunistic exit from the marriage. Cohen favours the preservation of restraints on opportunistic divorce, which he sees as requiring understanding that marriage is a long-term contractual relationship. The ‘wrong’ judicial approach to obligations like long-term support can lead to too much or too little divorce. This observation brings in the idea of an optimal level of divorce, which might be encapsulated in a rule like ‘let them divorce when the breaching party (the one who wants to leave, or who has committed a “marital offence”) can compensate the victim of breach’. (I pursue the idea of optimal breach further below.) A contractual focus on marriage is of value but the underlying view of the marriage contract needs to be sophisticated. Marriage contracts revolve around direct and instrumental benefits, bargaining influences (Lundberg and Pollak, 1996), shared goods, long-term marriage-specific investments, incentives for due performance and incentives for opportunism. These factors are of considerable consequence. If the law covering the financial obligations attached to divorce fails to suppress opportunism, then people will be hurt: fewer marriages will occur than otherwise and there may be less investment in marriage-specific activities like child raising. People will not be certain of obtaining predictable returns on marital investments.
3. Efficient Marital Breach Breach of contract may be optimal, providing compensation is paid to the breached-against party for lost expectation. Awarding ‘expectation damages’ is indeed the standard remedy for breach among commercial parties, and has the characteristic of placing the parties in the position they would have been in
5810
Marriage Contracts
867
if the contract had been completed (see Dnes, 1996). The common law may be considered efficient (wealth maximizing for the parties) in awarding expectation damages for breach. One would not insist on specific performance of a commercial contract. However, so as not to over-insure the victim of breach there is an important requirement for the victim to take any steps possible to mitigate the loss. Later in this chapter I shall show that a sophisticated view of the marriage contract, drawing on modern ideas of long-term relational contracting could give a useful direction to policy. For the moment, I examine a more limited, classical form of contract. Marriage vows would be taken quite literally and promises would be seen as binding. For example, a traditionalist view of the marriage contract is as an exchange of lifetime support for the wife, in which she shares the standard of living (‘output’) of the marriage, for domestic services such as housekeeping and child rearing. The classical-contract view could easily include less traditionalist frameworks. Breach of contract by one party would allow the other to reclaim lost expectation subject to an obligation to mitigate losses. All the traditional marital offences, such as adultery, unreasonable behaviour and abandonment, would be relevant to a divorce system based on classical breach of contract, in determining who had breached. Equally, no-fault divorce would be consistent with the notion of efficient breach as it would simply represent either (i) a decision by one party to breach the marital contract and pay damages, or (ii) a mutual decision to end the contract with a negotiated settlement. Consider a lengthy marriage that ends in divorce. The parties met when they left university. After working for some years the wife gave up work to have children and care for them. When the youngest child started school, she returned to work but at a lower wage than previously. After 20 years of marriage, the husband petitions for divorce on the grounds of separation. Their housing and other assets have always been held jointly. The husband would be expected to share property and income to maintain the standard of living his ex-wife would have enjoyed for the remainder of the marriage. Expectation damages are identical to the minimum sum that he would have to pay to buy from her the right to divorce her, if divorce were only available by consent. (He might have to pay up to his net benefit from divorcing if this were higher and his ex-wife were able to hold out.) The court would assess what that standard of living was and determine who had breached the contract. The breaching partner would not generally be difficult to detect if attention is focused, as is common across the law, on proximate causes. The fact that the divorced wife gave up work for a while or now earns less than might have been the case without child-care responsibilities is immaterial in finding expectation damages: broadly, if it can be judged that
868
Marriage Contracts
5810
she would have enjoyed the use of a large house and of other assets and available monetary sums, she would be awarded the assets and income to support that lifestyle. Her own income would contribute to that expectation, as would her own share of the house and other assets. The divorcing husband would be expected to contribute from his income and his share of the assets to provide that support for his ex-wife, regardless of the impact on his own lifestyle or on any subsequent marriage partner. Any common-law or statutory requirement to maintain the standard of living of the children of the marriage could be dealt with separately by the court, although the requirement would probably be met by maintaining expectation in the example. Following the principle of loss mitigation, if separation from allows the former wife to increase her income or assets in some way, or there are opportunities to avoid losses (including opportunities for remarriage) those amounts should be deducted from the settlement. In addition, if she contrived an apparent breach, for example by pursuing oppressive forms of behaviour, the husband could excuse his breach under the doctrine of duress (other classical contract doctrines would also be needed, for example misrepresentation, but do not seem central to the issues at this point). Without such safeguards, couples might be careless in preserving the marriage. With these qualifications, expectation damages would ensure that only efficient breach occurred, that is when someone’s gain from the divorce exceeded the compensation needed to put the other party, as far as money could, in the same position as before. From a traditionalist perspective, the approach would give security to a woman contemplating an investment in home-making rather than labour-market activities - although it is actually supportive of a wide range of possible marriage types. Under a classical-contracting approach, the courts would recreate the expected living standard of the victim of breach of the marital contract by adjusting the property rights and incomes of the parties at divorce. Fault would matter to the extent that the court would need to establish who was the breaching party but this would not rule out no-fault divorce (actually, unilateral breach where one party wishes to leave the marriage without citing marital offences and can divorce the other party against his or her will). It would only be irrelevant in a system of mutual consent, where both parties negotiated a settlement stating that neither was at fault; where bargaining would safeguard expectations. The classical-contracting approach preserves incentives for the formation of traditional families, if that were considered important. Any costs incurred by the victim of breach in raising children would be more than compensated since expectation normally exceeds such costs. The parties would only enter the marriage and incur costs (possibly as opportunities forgone, which we discuss further below) if they expected their personal welfare to be higher - hence, expectation exceeds (reliance) costs.
5810
Marriage Contracts
869
Classical contracting is also consistent with the simultaneous existence of separate legal obligations for the maintenance of children. However, it would only be consistent with a literal interpretation of the clean-break principle favoured in much recent family law if sufficient property rights can be transferred to avoid the need for subsequent periodical payments. A classical-contract view would not be consistent with views emphasizing the sanctity of marriage, which insists upon specific performance. No more difficulty should arise in family law than in commercial law in carrying out calculations of expectation damages. Typically, both parties will be at a mature stage of their lives where their lifestyles are reasonably foreseeable. It would be harder to calculate alternatives like reliance damages (see below). The courts might well discover they faced a great deal of argument over who had caused the breach. There might also be a tendency to apply rigid views of what constituted a party’s reasonable expectation in a marriage, although, historically, there has been more of a problem of discretion and inconsistency in the case law on long-term support of ex-wives. Other criticisms of an expectation-damages approach tend to be based on sectional views of social welfare. Thus, the arguments of feminists may be used to reject the idea of divorce rules that reinforce the dependency of women on men. Some liberals (for example, Kay, 1987) argue for measures to increase equality between males and females in their social roles. Others (for example, Gilligan, 1982) argue that men and women are different (women’s art, women’s ways of seeing, women’s writing, and so on). Recent moves in divorce law to compensate women for forgoing career opportunities, or to ‘rehabilitate’ them have been sympathetically received by these groups. Such moves focus on opportunity cost and amount to using restitutionary or possibly reliance standards of compensation.
4. The Reliance Approach In The Limits of Freedom of Contract, Michael Trebilcock (1993) contrasts an analysis of the financial consequences of divorce based on classical-contract ideas with contemporary trends towards compensating opportunity costs. Trebilcock argues strongly for an expectation-damages approach to marital breakdown, particularly because this will suppress opportunistic abandonment of dependent spouses. According to Trebilcock, the feminist dilemma is that divorce laws that are protective of women legitimize the subordinate role of women in society, whereas treating the divorcing couple as equals ignores the
870
Marriage Contracts
5810
labour-market disadvantages that domestic specialization confers on many divorcing women. What would happen if we compensated the abandoned spouse (usually the woman) or the woman choosing to leave the marriage, for the opportunity cost of marrying? Opportunity cost comprises the value of alternative prospects she gave up. In contract terms, this amounts to awarding reliance damages: the opportunity cost has become akin to wasted expenditure and the suggested rule seeks to put her in the position she would have been in had the marriage never taken place (the status quo ante). Reliance draws attention to the loss of career opportunities for many women either on entering marriage or in stopping work to have children. An economically strong woman leaving a marriage might receive nothing under this approach, if she could be shown to have lost nothing through marriage. This form of compensation should strictly provide the difference between what has been obtained up to the point of divorce and what the lost opportunity might reasonably be expected to have provided over some targeted period of time. The court would be required to examine and adjust the property rights of the divorcing spouses to put the divorcing woman in the financial position she could claim marriage prevented her from attaining. The suggested operation of this standard is not strictly equivalent to the use of reliance damages, either in contract (when this occurs) or in tort, because there is no suggestion that the payment of reliance damages should be linked to breach of contract: the adjustment is usually simply to be made for the benefit of an economically weakened divorcing woman (or comparable male cases if they emerged, for example where he had given up work to carry out child care). Equally, there is no reason in principle why reliance damages could not be linked to breach of contract, either in the sense of marital offences (substantial breach) or simply as a decision by one party to leave the marriage. Trebilcock points out that the reliance approach is harsh in its treatment of divorcing women with poor pre-marriage career prospects, for example, the waitress who marries a millionaire. Such cases would receive very little compensation for marital breakdown. Reliance damages were rejected in 1980 by the English Law Commission as requiring too much speculation about what might have been. In comparison, expectation damages require less speculation: comparisons are not in the distant past and it is usually reasonably clear by the time of divorce how the standard of living would have developed. Nonetheless, reliance does have its supporters among some economics of law practitioners, notably in the valuation of the loss of a housewife’s services in fatal-accident cases and in establishing a bare incentive for investment in
5810
Marriage Contracts
871
household production. (On accident valuation, see Knetsch, 1984.) In the case of a fatal accident, the wife is lost and in some jurisdictions the husband claims her opportunity cost of participating in the marriage as an alternative to claiming her replacement cost (that is, hiring a housekeeper). The reasoning is that the benefits to them both of her forgoing that opportunity must have been at least equal to the opportunity cost (for example wage in paid employment) or she would not have given up the opportunity. The advantage to the professional-class bereaved husband is that compensation will typically be higher. Although reliance damages would tend to be lower than expectation damages, assuming the marriage increased each party’s expected welfare, incentives for investments in domestic services would be preserved. A woman contemplating marriage-specific investments in child care by giving up labour-market opportunities (the reliance) for example, is better off in the marriage with those investments and is at least as well off if it all goes wrong. Therefore, the incentive remains for traditional marriages in which the woman exchanges domestic services for long-term support. The reliance approach could therefore easily support a public-policy objective of preserving traditional family lifestyles, which may not be appreciated by some of its supporters. Equally, one could support investments by males in child care by establishing their right to reliance damages upon divorce. Reliance damages will not be associated with efficient breach. Taking a contractual view first, if reliance damages are owed for breach of contract, a party may breach when the net benefit to them before damages is exceeded by the loss to the other party (opportunistic breach). This is because they only have to pay for reliance, which is normally less than expectation, so the socially suboptimal breach confers a private net advantage to the breaching party. In a system awarding reliance damages for breach of contract, we would expect additional, opportunistic divorces compared with an expectation standard. Women’s marriage-specific investments tend to be made early in marriage, and their remarriage opportunities are poorer than men’s owing to the different operation of ageing processes, demographic factors and the fact that the children of an earlier marriage will be a financial burden on a new husband. Men therefore would be more likely to divorce their wives (the ‘greener-grass effect’) and the increase in opportunistic divorces would tend to harm the interests of women on balance. Under a system awarding reliance damages for breach, we could expect a great deal of judicial effort to go into establishing fault (in the sense of who breached the marriage contract) just as under an expectation standard. If less
872
Marriage Contracts
5810
were at stake because reliance is normally less than expectation, there would be a lower incentive to pursue disputes and there might be fewer resources devoted to such conflict. However, the main driving force is that a finding of fault will result in a large bill under both standards so the difference is unlikely to be great. In a system awarding reliance damages of right to a divorcing party regardless of the cause of breach (typically an award to a wife - but possibly a husband - who has specialized in child care) there may also be an incentive for opportunism of a different kind. The problem is not peculiar to the reliance standard but affects all non-fault standards, for example, consider an award from a spouse divorced against his or her will under the Matrimonial and Family Proceedings Act 1984. The apparently vulnerable wife (or husband) might decide to divorce when the net gain from divorce including the reliance award exceeds her (or his) expected net benefit from the marriage continuing, which is a form of inefficient breach. This problem could not happen under a more contractual approach, because a decision to end the marriage would be breach of contract and would attract a damages penalty rather than an award. The practical problem here is that the woman in the example will either not care (on financial grounds) whether the marriage survives, or may feel she will be better off without it. The law will have effectively written an insurance contract that perversely influences behaviour: a case of moral hazard. This type of opportunism (the ‘Black-Widow’ effect) would lead to the prediction that divorces initiated by women would increase whenever such specified damages were introduced. The reliance approach could encourage opportunistic behaviour and would encounter problems of definition and calculation of the status quo ante. It is not kind to divorced women who start out with poor career prospects. Like the expectation standard, reliance implies no special status for any particular family asset: houses, pensions, and anything else, are all candidates for trading off with the aim of achieving the targeted level of support for a party. Reliance could be criticized for introducing a tort focus into the financial obligations of divorce, treating decisions to invest in domestic services as like sustaining injury, and carrying the implication that home building and child raising are activities with no benefits for the domesticated provider. As with expectation damages, a reliance approach could be operated around a separate system of child-support obligations.
5810
Marriage Contracts
873
5. Restitutionary Damages Carbone and Brinig (1991) identify a modern development in divorce law that they describe as a restitution approach. In a US context, they argue that academic analysis has been led by developments in the courts, which have increasingly emphasized settlements that repay lost career opportunities, particularly in the context of a wife’s domestic support of her husband and children during periods that allowed for the development of business capital, and other contributions to a spouse’s career (see, for example, Jamison v. Churchill Truck Lines, 632 S.W. 2d. 34, 3536 (Missouri Ct. App. 1982), awarding part of business for domestic contributions; see also Carbone, 1990; Krauskopf, 1980, 1989, and O’Connell, 1988). Restitution might be considered appropriate when a wife supports her husband through college: if they later divorce, the question is whether it is right that he should keep all the returns on this human-capital investment. The canonical example would be where the wife undertakes the child care so that her husband can develop his professional or business life. Restitution is often cited as an appropriate remedy in contract law when not returning money paid out by the victim of breach would lead to unjust enrichment of the breaching party. Restitution is ideologically acceptable to cultural feminists who wish to emphasize the repayment of sacrifices. A restitution approach is distinct from a reliance approach, although both often emphasize the same life choices, for example the opportunity forgone for a separate career. Under a restitution approach, compensation is in the form of a share in the market gain supported by the (typically) wife’s supportive career choice, for example a share in the returns to a medical degree, or a share of the business. Restitution is therefore only possible where measurable market gains have resulted from the ‘sacrifice’. The reliance approach, in contrast, is based on measuring the value of the opportunity forgone, for example estimating the value of continuing with a career instead of leaving work to raise children - an input rather than output measure. Reliance puts the victim of breach in the same position as if the contract had not been made, whereas restitution puts the breaching party in the same position as if the contract not been made (Farnsworth, 1990, p. 947). Restitution damages may be difficult to calculate. Who can really say how much a wife’s contribution was to a husband’s obtaining a medical training? Under a tort-style ‘but-for’ test, perhaps a case could be made that all of his earnings (and assets bought with income) belong to her. Yet, the ex-wife must have got something from the marriage, that is, was not supporting him purely
874
Marriage Contracts
5810
for the later return on his income. How much should we offset? Another problem might be negative restitution, where a party can show that the other spouse held them back and was a drain rather than an asset (the ‘Mayor of Casterbridge effect’). In practice, interest in restitution awards arises in US states with no-fault divorce and community-property rules, as a basis for obtaining alimony for an abandoned wife. Restitution will probably be kinder to divorcing women who had poor career prospects before entering the marriage. From an efficiency angle, restitution damages suffer from all of the problems already cited for reliance: the difficulties are logically identical. In a contractual setting (using restitution as a remedy for breach) restitution damages will lead to inefficient breach as liability for damages will again be too low. There will be too much breach (divorce) compared with expectation damages as restitution will normally be less than expectation damages (as long as the victim of breach expected more from the marriage than the returns reflected in the victim’s investment in the breaching party’s career). The higher level of opportunistic divorce will be to the disadvantage of women, if earlier comments about the differential effects of age on remarriage prospects for males and females hold true. Outside of a contractual setting, if support payments are set by statute for ex-spouses regardless of fault, there will be an incentive for opportunistic breach by the party for whom the restitution payment plus other expected benefits from divorce exceed the expectation within the marriage (the Black-Widow effect exactly as above, with restitution substituted for reliance). Compared with reliance damages, the level of divorce could be higher or lower under a restitution standard. This is because there is no necessary connection between the value of investment in the other spouse’s career and a person’s own alternative career prospects. Therefore, reliance can be greater or less than restitution (measured as the market return on the investment in the other spouse’s career). The restitution standard will give the incentive necessary to bring forth investments in domestic activities, particularly child raising. This would operate a little differently from the reliance standard. A person contemplating marriage-specific investments in child care by giving up labour-market opportunities would be entitled to compensation for each such investment decision. Therefore, the incentive remains for traditional marriages. As with expectation damages, a restitution approach could be operated around a separate system of child-support obligations.
5810
Marriage Contracts
875
6. Partnership, Property Rights and Rehabilitation There is a trend towards the use of a partnership model in some jurisdictions, notably where community-property is the norm in marriage. Singer (1989) argues that post-divorce income disparity between ex-spouses is the result of joint decisions and that the higher income is strictly joint income (which could carry over to property bought from income). Singer also points out that the equal division of property and income would meet demands for compensation for lost career opportunities, and could further the aims of ‘rehabilitating’ an abandoned spouse. According to Carbone and Brinig (1991), Singer’s analysis uses conventional justifications for post-divorce support without identifying the links between them, fails to determine initial property rights and does not achieve a precise calculation. Singer actually has a spuriously precise system of sharing the joint income for a number of years (she suggests one year of post marriage support for each year of marriage). A partnership model is possibly consistent with an updated contractual model of marriage. There is some evidence that divorcing couples do see themselves as jointly owning at least their assets, that is, their expectations are built around partnership. Weitzman (1981a) found that 68 percent of women and 54 percent of men in her sample of divorcees in Los Angeles County, California believed ‘a woman deserved alimony if she helped her husband get ahead because they are really partners in his work’. This was similar to the proportion supporting alimony on the grounds of the need to maintain small children. Davis, Cretney and Collins (1994) note the prevalence of the presumption of an equal split in their discussion of ‘folk myths’ associated with divorce. Without repeating the detailed analysis of earlier sections, I note that, unless rehabilitation, or equal shares, are the parties’ expectations from marriage, the model could lead to inefficient breach. In turn this can give rise to incentives for opportunistic behaviour, including the greener-grass and the Black-Widow effects, which reflect the adverse incentive effects from using less-than-expectation damages. If the true expectation of the dependent party went beyond equal shares or temporary support plus rehabilitation then a move from expectation damages to rehabilitation would encourage breach of contract by the non-dependent party.
876
Marriage Contracts
5810
7. Need A focus on meeting post-divorce housing and other needs, particularly of the spouse with childcare responsibilities, is the dominant element operating several jurisdictions (for example , England and some US states). In such law, need is the starting point, and the majority of cases do not reveal sufficient family resources to go much beyond the allocation of housing to the spouse with responsibility for care of the children, particularly as the clean-break principle favours transferring assets in lieu of periodical payments. There is no necessary inconsistency between a contractual view and needs-based awards, as meeting the needs of the children of the marriage and a breached-against spouse could be the remedy for breach of the marriage contract. However, the welfare consequences of the standard are not encouraging. If we assume that meeting need is a minimal expectation in marriage, need awards for breach would be less than or equal to expectation damages and excessive breach would occur: the by now familiar greener-grass effect as (most likely) husbands find they are not expected fully to compensate abandoned wives for removing the husband’s high, late career earnings. Also, if, as is the case, need awards are not linked to substantial breach, the Black-Widow effect can follow, if the value of a need award plus the expectation from the changed situation (possibly, re-marriage, cohabitation, or single status) exceeds the expectation from the current marriage. There is a direct analogy with the fourth condition above. Needs-based awards of spousal support do meet a concern that people should not be trapped into unhappy marriages. ‘Fault served to restrain men from leaving or flouting their marital obligations too egregiously, but it also left women with little bargaining power within the relationship. Women ... could not leave ... without facing financial ruin’ (Carbone and Brinig, 1991, p. 997). However, from the perspective of maximizing the sum of benefits from a marriage, it is impossible to justify the removal of costs for one person when this will impose similar or greater costs upon another: that would amount to ‘taking sides’. Furthermore, the possibility of inducing the Black-Widow effect might encourage some men to avoid marriage altogether, which is generally a problem when contracts cannot be secured against opportunism: a form of long-term, dynamic inefficiency (see Dnes, 1995). The argument that public policy requires men rather than women to bear the financial costs of divorce is vulnerable to the observation that it is difficult to distinguish between the unhappy divorcing wife and the opportunistically divorcing wife. The weight of the criticism in this paragraph could be undermined by finding that there is
5810
Marriage Contracts
877
typically a heavy spillover effect (externality) from the unhappiness of one marriage partner to the welfare of other parties, for example onto children.
8. Revising the Contract Approach to Marriage The problems following from avoiding the use of expectation damages, or of separating awards from the issue of breach of contract are that (i) generally, breach will be inefficient, and (ii) breach may be opportunistic (exploitative). However, the problems with expectation damages in marriage contracts are that (i) implications of lifetime support appear to militate against a modern emphasis on independence in life, and (ii) protracted arguments over the identification of breach would be costly, which is particularly relevant when the court system is run largely from public funds. The problems of identifying breach are at least as severe if non-expectation standards (for example reliance) are used. Would a more sophisticated view of the marriage contract resolve any of these issues? The movement away from highly restrictive divorce laws coupled with lifetime support obligations towards wives was followed by the evolution of liberal laws characterized often by needs-based, discretionary systems of property adjustment and spousal support. The social norms surrounding marriage have clearly changed over time, in particular towards favouring serial marriages and cohabitation. A number of points stand out. One is that marriage rates are falling, cohabitation rates are rising, and divorce rates are rising in many countries, which suggests that the current legal view of marriage does not correspond with the wishes of the population at large. A second important point is that liberalization in a sense allows people to change their minds as circumstances change and to revise the marriage contract. Consequently we need to ask whether a more flexible view of marriage is useful and what the limits to it would be. The history of marital law, showing an evolving view of the nature of the marriage contract that has been heavily shaped by surrounding social norms, is consistent with modern views of ‘relational’ contracts shaped by a surrounding mini-society of norms (relational contracting is explored in Macneil, 1978; Williamson, 1985 and Macaulay, 1991). One possibility might be to encourage the use of clearer marriage contracts with the possibility of enforceable modifications that might be a substitute for divorce. The literature on contract modifications is extremely pessimistic over the prospect of welfare gain from enforcing mutually agreed and compensated modifications (see Jolls, 1997, and Dnes, 1998). This is because of the difficulty of distinguishing between genuinely beneficial revisions and those resulting
878
Marriage Contracts
5810
from opportunistic behaviour, which can amount to duress. Consider the difficulty in marriage contracts in distinguishing between a genuine modification (because a party now has improved prospects) and the case where a party threatens to make their spouse’s life hell unless certain terms are agreed. Contract modifications will not set up incentives for opportunism if, in the context of unforeseen events, (i) it is not clear who is the lowest-cost bearer of the risk, (ii) the events were judged of too low a value to be worth considering in the contract, or (iii) it was infeasible for either party to bear the risk (as explained fully in Dnes, 1995, p. 232). Generally, the view that supporting all modifications is desirable because there appears to be a short-term gain is unsound: there may be undesirable long-term instability as a result, as already noted in the previous subsection, since fewer people will make contracts if it is difficult to protect them from opportunism. The idea that modifications can be legally supported when events unfold for which it would not have been clear early on who should have benefitted or borne a fresh cost does give a clue to a rôle for the court. It can determine whether some change was foreseeable and whether the attendant risk would have been clearly allocated, for example, one’s wife’s aging is not a reason for scooting off without compensating her, on the other hand mutually tiring of each other would have been hard to allocate to one party. Generally, the main focus of the law can be expected to remain the division of benefits and obligations on divorce, that is, the ending of a contract and move to new circumstances for the parties. A more appropriate fundamental model of the marriage contract would be as a relational contract. Macneil (1978) has suggested that complex long-term contracts are best regarded ‘in terms of the entire relation, as it has developed [over] time’. Special emphasis is placed on the surrounding social norms rather than on the ability of even well-informed courts to govern the relationship (Macneil calls governance that emphasizes third-party interpretation ‘neoclassical’ contracting). An original contract document (for example marriage vows) is not necessarily of more importance in the resolution of disputes than later events or altered norms. Courts are likely to lag behind the parties’ practices in trying to interpret relational contracts. A relational contract is an excellent vehicle for thinking of the fundamental nature of marriage but it may be of limited help in designing practical solutions to divorce issues unless it is possible to fashion legal support for the relational contracting process. Crucially though, the idea emphasizes flexibility. It is a fascinating mental experiment to put the idea of flexibility together with the persistent caution of this article over the dangers of creating incentives for opportunistic behaviour. Many of the problems associated with the division of
5810
Marriage Contracts
879
marital assets arise because social norms change (for example the wife has no entitlement to life-time support) but the individual marriage partners fail to match the emerging marital norm (for example a homely wife married in 1966 is much more likely to have specialized in domestic services). Therefore, a possible approach to divorce law is to use expectation damages to guard against opportunism but to allow the interpretation of expectation to be governed by differing ‘vintages’ of social norms. As an example, the courts could take a retrospective view of the expectations associated with each decade. Consideration could also be given to making pre-nuptial, and post-nuptial, agreements between spouses legally binding. Modern marriages might be allowed to choose between several alternative forms of marital contract (for example traditional, partnership, or implying restitutionary damages on divorce). Providing expectations are clarified, inefficient and opportunistic breach could be broadly suppressed. Such a system could operate around a statutory obligation to meet the needs of children, which providing it does not overcompensate the parent with care should be neutral towards incentives.
9. Conclusions and Summary There is a case for seriously considering expectation damages as a basis for post-divorce support obligations and asset division. The foundation for this conclusion is the incentive for opportunistic behaviour set up by the use of reliance, restitution, partnership, rehabilitation and need approaches to post-divorce liabilities. The current focus of marital law is vulnerable to the charge that behaviour is encouraged in both males and females that is predatory in nature. The contractual uncertainty that follows from this may well deter some good quality marriages that might otherwise occur. Problems arise because a marriage partner can leave without meeting obligations incurred early on in the marriage, that is, will not be forced to pay expectation damages. Under the greener-grass incentive, a husband (usually) will leave the marriage if the gains in a new marriage or from single status exceed his gains in the first marriage, when he knows he will not have to compensate his first wife for the full loss of her married lifestyle. The Black Widow effect is similar but refers to cases where (typically) a female would find that a divorce award means she is better off leaving a first husband and possibly moving to a new relationship even when this would have lower net benefits for her in the absence of the award.
880
Marriage Contracts
5810
The contractual view of marriage ultimately explored in this article is different from classical commercial contract law. Different vintages and varieties of marriage need to be recognized. In particular, partners in traditional and non-traditional marriages could be contractually protected against exploitation by recognizing the variety of promises they received. The approach is also consistent with a separate system of liability for support for children and with avoiding having the state pick up the bill for failed marriages.
Acknowledgements I wish to thank the Lord Chancellor’s Department in England for supporting parts of the research associated with this paper, and to thank participants at the June 1997 Lord Chancellor’s Department Economists’ Forum for helpful comments on an earlier draft. I also wish to thank everyone at the Private Enterprise Research Center, Texas A&M University, where I wrote part of this paper, for their kind hospitality and helpful discussions. The paper is developed from an earlier report (Dnes, The Division of Marital Assets Following Divorce with Particular Reference to Pensions, Research Report 7/97, Lord Chancellor’s Dept, 1997) and a journal article (Dnes, 1998).
Bibliography on Marriage Contracts (5810) Allen, Douglas W. (1990), ‘An Inquiry Into the State’s Role in Marriage’, 13 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 171-191. Bayles, Michael D. (1989), ‘Marriage as a Bad Business Deal: Distribution of Property on Divorce’, 17 Florida State University Law Review, 95-106. Becker, Gary S. (1973), ‘A Theory of Marriage: Part 1', 81 Journal of Political Economy, 813-846. Becker, Gary S. (1974a), ‘On the Relevance of the New Economics of the Family’, 64 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 317-319. Becker, Gary S. (1974b), ‘A Theory of Social Interactions’, 82 Journal of Political Economy, 1063-1093. Becker, Gary S. (1976), The Economic Approach to Human Behavior, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 314 p. Becker, Gary S. (1985), ‘Human Capital, Effort, and the Sexual Division of Labor’, 3(S) Journal of Labor Economics, 33 ff. Becker, Gary S. (1988), ‘Family Economics and Macro Behavior’, 78 American Economic Review, 1-13.
5810
Marriage Contracts
881
Becker, Gary S. (1991), A Treatise on the Family, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 288 p. Becker, Gary S. and Murphy, Kevin M. (1988), ‘The Family and the State’, 31 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-18. Becker, Gary S., Landes, Elisabeth M. and Michael, Robert T. (1977), ‘An Economic Analysis of Maritial Instability’, 85 Journal of Political Economy, 1141-1187. Ben-Porath, Y. (1980), ‘The F-Connection: Families, Friends and Firms and the Organization of Exchange’, 6 Population Development Review, 1-30. Bennett, Belinda (1991), ‘The Economics of Wifing Services: Law and Economics on the Family’, 18 Journal of Law and Society, 206-218. Bishop, William, ‘’Is He Married?’ Marriage as a Market Signal’, in Knetsch, Jack L. (ed.), Economic Aspects of Family Law, Toronto, Butterworths. Bolin, Kristian (1994), ‘The Marriage Contract and Efficient Rules for Spousal Support’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 493-502. Bonus, Holger (1991), ‘Schöne Müllerin. Heiratsmarkt, Vor- und Nachteile der Ehe aus ökonomischer Sicht (Advantages and Disadvantages of Marriage from the Economist’s Viewpoint)’, 12 Wirtschaftswoche, 44-49. Borenstein, Severin and Courant, Paul N. (1989), ‘How To Carve a Medical Degree: Human Capital Assets in Divorce Settlements’, 79 American Economic Review, 992-1009. Bradshaw, J. and Millar, J. (1991), Lone Parent Families in the UK, Department of Social Security Research Report, No.6. Brinig, Margaret F. (1990), ‘Rings and Promises’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 203-215. Brinig, Margaret F. (1993), ‘The Law and Economics of No-Fault Divorce’, 27 Family Law Quarterly, 453-470. Brinig, Margaret F. (1994a), ‘Comment on Jana Singer’s Alimony and Efficiency’, 83 Georgetown Law Journal, 2461-2479. Brinig, Margaret F. (1994b), ‘Status, Contract and Covenant’, 79 Cornell Law Review, 1573-1602. Brinig, Margaret F. and Alexeev, Michael V. (1991), ‘Legal Rules, Bargaining and Transactions Costs: The Case of Divorce’, in Nagel, Stuart and Mills, Miriam K. (eds), Systematic Analysis in Dispute Resolution, New York, Quorum Books, 91-105. Brinig, Margaret F. and Alexeev, Michael V. (1993), ‘Trading at Divorce: Preferences, Legal Rules and Transaction Costs’, 8 Ohio State Journal on Dispute Resolution, 279-297. Brinig, Margaret F. and Alexeev, Michael V. (1995), ‘Fraud in Courtship: Annulment and Divorce’, 2 European Journal of Law and Economics, 45-63. Brinig, Margaret F. and Carbone, June R. (1988), ‘The Reliance Interest in Marriage and Divorce’, 62 Tulane Law Review, 855-905. Brinig, Margaret F. and Crafton, Steven M. (1994), ‘Marriage and Opportunism’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 869-894. Broude, Donna L. (1986), ‘The Effect of the Tax Reform Act of 1984 on Divorce Financial Planning’, 21 Journal of Family Law, 283-300. Cabrillo, Francisco (1996), Matrimonio, Familia y Economía (Marriage, Family and Economics), Madrid, Minerva Ediciones. Cabrillo, Francisco (1996b), Matrimonio, Familia y Economia, Madrid, Minerva Ediciones.
882
Marriage Contracts
5810
Carbone, June R. (1990), ‘Economics, Feminism, and the Reinvention of Alimony: A Reply to Ira Ellman’, 43 Vanderbilt Law Review, 1463-1501. Carbone, June R. and Brinig, Margaret F. (1991), ‘Rethinking Marriage: Feminist Ideology, Economic Change, and Divorce Reform’, 65 Tulane Law Review, 954-1010. Cass, Ronald A. (1987), ‘Coping With Life, Law, and Markets: A Comment on Posner and the Law-and-Economics Debate’, 67 Boston University Law Review, 73-97. Chami, Ralph and Fischer, Jeffrey (1996), ‘Altruism, Matching and Nonmarket Insurance’, 34 Economic Inquiry, 630-647. Cheung, Steven N.S. (1972), ‘The Enforcement of Property Rights in Children, and the Marriage Contract’, 82 Economic Journal, 641-657. Cohen, Jane Maslow (1987), ‘Posnerism, Pluralism, Pessimism’, 67 Boston University Law Review, 105-175. Cohen, Lloyd R. (1987), ‘Marriage, Divorce, and Quasi-Rents; or, ‘I Gave Him the Best Years of My Life’’, 16 Journal of Legal Studies, 267-303. Dnes, Antony W. (1998) The Division of Marital Assets, 25 Journal of Law and Society, 336-64. Fair, R.C. (1978), ‘A Theory of Extramarital Affairs’, 86 Journal of Political Economy, 45-61. Freiden, A. (1974), ‘The United States Marriage Market’, 82(S) Journal of Political Economy, 34-53. Friedman, Lawrence M. and Percival, Robert V. (1976), ‘Who Sues for Divorce? From Fault through Fiction to Freedom’, 5 Journal of Legal Studies, 61-82. Fuchs, Maximilian (1979), ‘Die Behandlung von Ehe und Scheidung in der ‘Ökonomischen Analyse des Rechts’ (The Treatment of Marriage and Divorce in the ‘Economic Analysis of Law’)’, 7 Zeitschrift für das gesamte Familienrecht, 553-557. Grossbard, Amyra (1978), ‘Towards a Marriage between Economics and Anthropology and a General Theory of Marriage’, 68 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 33-37. Grossbard-Shechtman, Amyra (1984), ‘A Theory of Allocation of Time in Markets for Labour and Marriage’, 94 Economic Journal, 863-882. Horton, Paul and Alexander, Lawrence (1986), ‘Freedom of Contract and the Family: A Skeptical Appraisal’, in Peden, Joseph R. and Glahe, Fred R. (eds), The American Family and the State, San Francisco, Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy, 229-255. Hudson, P. and Lee, W. (1990), Women’s Work and the Family Economy in Historical Perspective. Hutchens, Robert M. (1979), ‘Welfare, Remarriage and Market Search’, 69 American Economic Review, 369-379. Keeley, Michael C. (1977), ‘The Economics of Family Formation’, 15 Economic Inquiry, 238-250. King, Allan G. (1982), ‘Human Capital and the Risk of Divorce: An Asset in Search of a Property Right’, 49 Southern Journal of Economics, 536-541.
5810
Marriage Contracts
883
Knetsch, J. (1984), ‘Some Economic Implications of Marital Property Rules’, 34 University of Toronto Law Journal, 263 ff. Kornhauser, Lewis A. and Mnookin, Robert H. (1979), ‘Bargaining in the Shadow of the Law: the Case of Divorce’, 88 Yale Law Journal, 950 ff. Krauskopf, J. (1980), ‘Recompense for Financing Spouse’s Education’ 28 Kansas Law Review, 379 ff. Krauskopf, J. (1989), ‘Theories of Property Division/spousal Support: Searching for Solutions to the Mystery’, 23 Family Law Quarterly, 253 ff. Landes, Elisabeth M. (1978), ‘The Economics of Alimony’, 7 Journal of Legal Studies, 35-63. Lemennicier, Bertrand (1980), ‘La Spécialisation des Rôles Conjugaux, les Gains du Mariage et la Perspective du Divorce (Specialization of Conjugal Role, Marital Gains, and Perspective of Divorce)’, Consommation. Lemennicier, Bertrand (1982), ‘Les Déterminants de la Mobilité Matrimoniale (The Determinants of Matrimonial Mobility)’, Consommation. Lemennicier, Bertrand (1988), Le Marché du Mariage et de la Famille (The Marriage Market and the Family), Paris, Presses Universitaires de France (PUF), Collection Libre Echange. Lemennicier, Bertrand (1990), ‘Bioéthique et liberté (Bio-Ethics and Liberty)’, 13 Droits: Revue Française de Théorie Juridique, 111-122. Lemennicier, Bertrand and Garboua, Levy (1981), ‘L’Arbitrage Autarcie-Marché: une Explication du Travail Féminin (Arbitration Autarchy-Market: An Explanation of Female Work)’, Consommation. Lichtenstein, Norman B. (1985), ‘Marital Misconduct and the Allocation of Financial Resources at Divorce: A Farewell to Fault’, 51 UMRC Law Review, 1-18. Lundberg, S. and Pollak, R. (1996), ‘Bargaining and Distribution in Marriage’ 10 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 139 ff. Lundberg, S., Pollak, R. and Wales, T. (1995), Do Husbands and Wives Pool Their Resources? Evidence from the UK Child Benefit, Manuscript, Economics Dept., Washington University, Seattle. Manser, Marilyn and Brown, Murray (1980), ‘Marriage and Household Decision-Making: A Bargaining Analysis’, 21 International Economic Review, 31-44. McGee, Robert W. (1998), ‘Polygamy’, in X. (ed.), Magill’s Legal Guide, Pasadena, CA, Salem Press. Michael, R. (1979), ‘Determinants of Divorce’, in Garboua, Levy (ed.), Sociological Economics, London, Sage. O’Connell, M. (1988), ‘Alimony after No-fault: A Practice in Search of a Theory’, 23 New England Law Review, 437 ff. Olsen, Frances E. (1983), ‘The Family and the Market: A Study of Ideology and Legal Reform’, 96 Harvard Law Review, 1497-1578. Pahl, J. (1989), Money and Marriage.
884
Marriage Contracts
5810
Papps, Ivy (1980), For Love or Money? A Preliminary Economic Analysis, London, Institute of Economic Affairs, 63 p. (Hobart Paperback No.86). Parisi, Francesco (1998), ‘Family Law and Successions’, in Mattei, Ugo (ed.), Introduction to Italian Law, Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers. Parisi, Francesco and Posner Richard A. (1997), International Library of Critical Writings in Europe, Volume III: Other Areas of Private and Public Law, London, Edward Elgar. Pask, E. Diane, McCall, M.L., Brown C.L., Bruce, Christopher J., Hass, C.A. and Vallance, D.P. (1989), How Much and Why?, Calgary, Canadian Research Unit for Law and the Family, 202 p. Pennington, Joan (1989), ‘The Economic Implications of Divorce for Older Women’, 23 Clearinghouse Review, 488-493. Peters, H. Elizabeth (1986), ‘Marriage and Divorce: Informational Constraints and Private Contracting’, 76 American Economic Review, 437-454. Pollak, Robert A. (1985), ‘A Transaction Cost Approach to Families and Households’, 23 Journal of Economic Literature. Polsby, Daniel D. and Zelder, Martin (1994), ‘Risk-Adjusted Valuation of Professional Degrees in Divorce’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 273-285. Posner, Richard A. (1989), ‘The Ethics and Economics of Enforcing Contracts of Surrogate Motherhood’, 6 Journal of Contemporary Health Law and Policy, 21-31. Posner, Richard A. (1992), Sex and Reason, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Ramseyer, J. Mark (1996), Odd Markets In Japanese History: Law and Economic Growth, New York, Cambridge University Press. Riboud, M. (1988), ‘Altruisme au Sein de la Famille, Croissance Economique et Démographie (Altruism in the Family, Economic Growth and Demography)’, 39 Revue Economique. Schultz, Theodore W. (ed.) (1974), Economics of the Family: Marriage, Children and Human Capital, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 584 p. Singer, J. (1989), ‘Divorce Reform and Gender Justice’, 67 North Carolina Law Review, 1103 ff. Smith, I. (1997), ‘Explaining the Growth of Divorce in Great Britain’, 44 Scottish Journal of Political Economy, 519 ff. Smith, Vernon L. (1974), ‘Economic Theory and Its Discontents’, 64 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 320 ff. Sofer, C. (1985), La Division du Travail entre Hommes et Femmes (The Division of Labour Between Men and Women), Paris, Economica. Stake, Jeffrey E. (1992), ‘Mandatory Planning for Divorce’, 45 Vanderbilt Law Review, 397-454. Stout, Lynn A. (1981), ‘Note: The Case for Mandatory Separate Filing By Married Persons’, 91 Yale Law Journal, 363-382. Tsaoussis-Hatzis, Aspasia (1999), ‘Changes in Greek Marriage and Divorce Law: The Impact of the Family Law Reform of 1983', in Miller, Robin R. and Browning, Sandra Lee, Till Death Do Us Part: A Multicultural Anthology on Marriage, Greenwich, JAI Press.
5810
Marriage Contracts
885
Tsaoussis-Hatzis, Aspasia (1999b), The Social and Economic Consequences of the Greek Divorce Law Reform of 1983, Ph.D. Thesis, University of Chicago Law School. Weiss, Yoram and Willis, Robert J. (1985), ‘Children as Collective Goods and Divorce Settlements’, 3 Journal of Labor Economics, 268-292. Weitzman, Lenore J. (1981a), The Marriage Contract: Spouses, Lovers and the Law, New York, Free Press, 536 p. Weitzman, Lenore J. (1981b), ‘The Economics of Divorce: Social and Economic Consequences of Property, Alimony and Child Support Awards’, 28 UCLA Law Review, 1181-1268. Weitzman, Lenore J. (1985), The Divorce Revolution: the Unexpected Consequences for Women and Children in America, New York, NY, Free Press. Wishik, Heather Ruth (1986), ‘Economics of Divorce: An Explanatory Study’, 20 Family Law Quarterly, 79-107. Zelder, Martin (1993), ‘Inefficient Dissolutions as a Consequence of Public Goods: The Case of No-Fault Divorce’, 22 Journal of Legal Studies, 503-520.
Other References Davis, G., Cretney, S. and Collins, J. (1994), Simple Quarrels, Oxford, Oxford Clarendon Press. Dnes, Antony W. (1995), ‘The Law and Economics of Contract Modifications: the Case of Williams v. Roffey’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 225-240. Dnes, Antony W. (1996), Economics of Law, London, Sweet & Maxwell. Farnsworth, E.A. (1990), Contracts (2nd edn), Boston, Little Brown. Gilligan, C. (1982), In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development, Boston, MA, Harvard Univ Press. Jolls, Christine (1997), ‘Contracts as Bilateral Commitments: A New Perspective on Contract Modification’, 26 Journal of Legal Studies, 203-237. Kay, H. (1987), ‘Equality and Difference: A Perspective on No-fault Divorce and its Aftermath’, 56 University of Cincinnati Law Review, 1 ff. Klein, Benjamin, Crawford, Robert G. and Alchian, Armand A. (1978), ‘Vertical Integration, Appropriable Rents, and the Competitive Contracting Process’,21 Journal of Law and Economics, 297-326. Macaulay, Stewart (1991), ‘Long-term Continuing Relations: The American Experience Regulating Dealerships and Franchises’, in Joerges, Ch. (ed.), Franchising and the Law, 179 ff. MacNeil, Ian R. (1978), ‘Contracts: Adjustment of Long-Term Economic Relations Under Classical, Neoclassical, and Relational Contract Law’, 72 Northwestern University Law Review, 854-905.
886
Marriage Contracts
5810
Trebilcock, Michael (1993), The Limits of Freedom of Contract, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Williamson, Oliver E. (1985), The Economic Institutions of Capitalism, New York, NY, Free Press.
5820 SEXUAL REGULATION © Copyright 1999 Boudewijn Bouckaert and Gerrit De Geest
Bibliography Collected by the Editors Brinig, Margaret F. (1990), ‘Rings and Promises’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 203-215. Brinig, Margaret F. (1995), ‘A Maternalistic Approach to Surrogacy’, 81 Virginia Law Review, 2377-2399. Gohmann, Stephan F. and Ohsfeldt, Robert L. (1994), ‘U.S. Senate Voting on Abortion Legislation: A More Direct Test for Ideological Shirking’, 16 Research in Law and Economics, 175-196. McGee, Robert W. (1998), ‘Polygamy’, in X. (ed.), Magill’s Legal Guide, Pasadena, CA: Salem Press. Posner Richard A. (1992), Sex and Reason, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Ramseyer, J. Mark (1991), ‘Indentured Prostitution in Imperial Japan: Credible Commitments in the Commercial Sex Industry’, 7 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 89-116. Stout, Lynn A. (1981), ‘Note: The Case for Mandatory Separate Filing By Married Persons’, 91 Yale Law Journal, 363-382. Stout, Lynn A. (1992), ‘Strict Scrutiny and Social Choice: An Economic Inquiry Into Fundamen Tal Rights and Suspect Classifications’, 80 Georgetown Law Journal, 1787-1834. Zelder, Martin (1993), ‘Incompletely Reasoned Sex: A Review of Posner’s Somewhat Misleading Guide to the Economic Analysis of Sex and Family Law’, May Michigan Law Review, 1584-1608.
887
5830 GIFTS, WILLS AND INHERITANCE LAW Pierre Pestieau CREPP, Université de Liège and CORE, Université Catholique de Louvain © Copyright 1999 Pierre Pestieau
Abstract This chapter provides a survey of recent theoretical and empirical work on bequeathing from the viewpoint of both economics, and law and economics. We focus on the interaction between individuals’ preferences, legal and fiscal institutions and bequeathing. Two conclusions emerge. First, it appears clearly that the level, the pattern and the timing of bequests depend on both the preferences of the donors and the type of regulation and taxation imposed on inheritance. Second, and conversely, the desirability of such taxation and regulation depends closely on the type of bequests (voluntary or involuntary) that one observes in a given country in a given period. JEL classification: D30, D64, D91, H24 Keywords: Bequests, Inheritance, Gift, Estate Duty
1. Introduction In this chapter, we want to focus on rather recent literature that studies the interaction between preferences, institutions and bequests. More explicitly, we want to convey the now well established idea that the level, the timing and the pattern of bequests is the outcome of the underlying preferences of the bequeathing parents on the one hand and the prevailing legal and fiscal institutions constraining bequests on the other. To do so, we start with the setting in which bequeathing is effected, that is, the complex network of family relations. The family is indeed the locus of various transfers and exchanges, either in competition with, or as a complement to, the state or the market. Admittedly, the distinction between exchange and transfer within the family is not all that clear-cut. Even though ‘pure’ transfers do not imply explicit counterparts, the simple fact that they bring utility to the donor makes them less free than it might seem. Our concern here is with the legal regulation and fiscal treatment of exchanges or transfers between parents and children, which may be monetary or in kind. In addition to wealth transfers such as bequests and gifts, there is also the education that parents provide to their offspring through an investment in both time and money, not to mention the transmission of intangible social 888
5830
Gifts, Wills and Inheritance Law
889
capital. There are also different types of assistance, often in the form of services: these may be descending (providing accommodation or care to grandchildren) or ascending (care, visits or accommodating elderly parents). Even though we focus here on the most traditional type of intergenerational transfers, that is, bequests, all the other types play an important role, either as a complement or as a means of exchange. We survey recent work on the desirability of estate or inheritance taxation and of legal constraints imposed upon bequeathing. To deal with this issue, we introduce a taxonomy of the main types of bequests and models of inheritance developed by economists over the last decades. Each of these models, which focus on specific motivations for wealth transmission, is characterized by the kind of relations existing within the family, the structure of preferences, the type of information held by each member of the family and, of course, his or her own characteristics such as ability or life expectancy. It will become apparent that this taxonomy is very different from the popular image of inheritance and that the economic approach does not follow the same track as the one adopted by other social scientists (Masson, 1995). More importantly, we will point out the multiple and divergent implications that each of these types of inheritance may have when assessing the desirability of fiscal and legal regulation of inheritance.
2. Taxonomy of Bequests Inherited wealth is generally quite unequally distributed (a great deal more than income). In countries like France, it accounts for a large part of all wealth possessed (generally estimated at 40 percent) and represents the largest descending monetary transfer, three times as much as wealth received in the form of inter vivos gifts, for example. Although the inheritor may very well not know the motivations behind the decision to leave him or her a bequest, it is clear that they may be diverse and sometimes contradictory. In fact, there exist three large categories of inheritance: -
-
-
accidental, or unplanned, bequests, characterized not primarily by the desire to transmit wealth to offspring, but by precaution or consumption deferred over an uncertain life span; voluntary, or planned, bequests, falling into different categories depending on the motives for the transmission. They range from pure altruism to paternalistic behavior all the way to the most self-interested strategic exchange. capitalist, or entrepreneurial, bequests, which are the outcome of accumulation for its own sake.
890
Gifts, Wills and Inheritance Law
5830
Our taxonomy of bequests is based on two dividing lines: the consumer’s horizon and the concern for family. Accidental bequests are typically limited to the consumer’s life cycle. Voluntary bequests are essentially based on family considerations. Capitalist bequests commonly have a horizon that extends well beyond the lifetime of the wealth holder; they are not primarily motivated by family considerations even though the dynastic family is used as the channel allowing for the perennity of the estate. These distinctions may sound superfluous. Yet, as we hope to make clear, they are of crucial importance. The implications and consequences that a bequest may have for the level and structure of estate duties (for example) largely depend on the category it belongs to. 2.1 Accidental Bequests Even if parents accumulate wealth only in provision for their old age, as the theory of the life cycle claims, and have no particular desire to leave something to their children, the latter will probably still receive an inheritance. This kind of bequest, termed accidental, is generally associated with the concepts of precautionary savings and deferred consumption. It owes its existence to three factors: the uncertainty over one’s life span, the imperfection of capital markets (pertaining to, for example, annuities or housing) and the impossibility of leaving a negative inheritance. In a world of certainty, savings would be adjusted to match the needs of the life cycle only; if annuities were available at an actuarially fair rate, one could protect oneself against the risk of an excessively long and penniless existence. Under these conditions, there seems to be no purpose in leaving a bequest that is of no particular use in itself. To illustrate the accidental bequest (see, for example, Davies, 1981), let us take the case of a couple of retirees who are entitled only to a small pension and have not taken out annuities. Anticipating a long and comfortable retirement, they have accumulated financial and real estate assets that they hope to live on. They subsequently die in a car accident, leaving their children an inheritance they were not counting on. All things being equal, the accidental inheritance is larger should death occur at the moment in the life cycle when wealth is at its peak, usually at the end of the person’s working life. In this type of inheritance, there is no exchange or altruism between parents and children. The children inherit only because their parents did not live as long as they had expected to and had not invested their savings in a life annuity. One could raise the question of why annuity markets are not well developed. There might be no demand for them because of some social norms. In France, for example, buying annuities is viewed as an act of distrust toward one’s children. This leads to another point about accidental bequests. Suppose that parents are altruistic toward their children but would not leave them anything
5830
Gifts, Wills and Inheritance Law
891
if fair annuities were available, because their children are well-provided for through the secular growth in wages. In the absence of annuities, these parents know that some bequest will inevitably be left and may find this highly desirable. 2.2 Voluntary Bequests In accidental bequests, neither the presence of children nor even of heirs is required. Voluntary bequests, on the other hand, depend on the presence of children. It was long held that intentional bequests were the norm and, even more so, were motivated by altruism. The anthropology and sociology of the family have since taught us, however, that many different forms of voluntary bequests and family models exist. At one extreme, there is the family in which solidarity and generosity prevail, while, at the other extreme, there is the model of give and take in which exchange is sometimes equitable and sometimes not. We will move gradually from pure altruism to strategic exchange, which gives rise to an arrangement rather unfavorable to children. Altruistic Bequests The stereotyped representation of inheritance clearly corresponds to the model based on pure altruism; that is, parental love and filial piety (classical references are Becker, 1974, 1975, 1989, 1991; Becker and Tomes, 1979, 1986; and Barro, 1974). When making decisions on consumption and savings, parents take into account their children’s preferences while anticipating their income and future needs. Their utility function implies that, in the absence of constraints, they will attempt to distribute their incomes and those of their children over time so as to smooth out the consumption of both parties. The concept of smoothing is already present in the life cycle hypothesis, where the consumption path is independent of the income path, but it is here extended to the infinite duration of a dynasty (smoothing is clearly limited by the constraint of nonnegative bequests when children are wealthier than their parents). In this context, parents have two ways of raising their children’s resources: human capital (education) transfers increase their wages and nonhuman transfers, their financial wealth. The parents choose the amount they wish to invest in their children’s education and that to be given them in the form of inter vivos gifts or bequests. Their sole objective is to ensure that consumption will be divided fairly either between them and their children or among the children. Insofar as the return on education is variable - at first it is a great deal higher than that of financial assets, before it diminishes - parents cover educational costs until the return on education is equal to that of physical assets; thereafter, they make inter vivos gifts or bequests so as to maximize the utility of the extended family. Choices such as these have immediate implications. If inequalities of talents or fortune exist between parents and children or between children themselves, intergenerational transfers will be tuned so as to reduce them if not eliminate
892
Gifts, Wills and Inheritance Law
5830
them entirely. Let us take the case of two brothers: one is gifted and will have no problem acquiring a top-flight education, while his brother, unable to obtain qualifications of any kind, will be forced to take a menial job. In an altruistic environment, the latter should receive a great deal more from his parents than his brother; however, it is probable that, strictly in terms of education costs, the opposite will be true. In a model where differences in talent are contingent on circumstances and where the brothers enjoy the same standard of living thanks to their parents’ compensatory transfers, the members of the following generation all start from the same position. Thus, if parents are not prevented from exercising free choice for reasons connected to their wealth, altruism or luck itself, there should be great social stability within the dynasty. Intrafamily transfers insure each member against the vagaries of fate or nature. Yet, there are limits to parental choice; problems of incentives, moral hazard and adverse selection cannot be avoided. In making their transfers, parents would like to be sure that their children really need them and will not rely on them to the extent of shirking responsibility for the rest of their lives (see Bruce and Waldman, 1990; Linbeck and Weibull, 1988; Cremer and Pestieau, 1993, 1996; Richter, 1992). But it is often argued that even though parents cannot forgo problems linked to asymmetric information, they are in a much better position than the government. This relative superiority of the parents is often viewed as a key argument against any public interference with private intergenerational transfers. Moreover, parents may not be able to transfer as much as they might wish. In this case, they will give priority to investments in human capital, where the return is greater than that on physical investments. The latter will thereby not be able to perform their role as buffers, and parent-child as well as child-child inequalities may subsist. Note that altruism in the neoclassical sense of the term is not to be confused with generosity or disinterest. Quite often, one makes a distinction between altruistic households, which leave positive (operative) bequests, and those which are constrained by the nonnegativity constraint on bequests (if they could, they would force their children into giving them resources) and thus do not leave any. One cannot say that the former are more altruistic than the latter. Paternalistic Bequests The paternalistic bequest shares the same bloodline as the altruistic (see Blinder, 1974, 1976a; Modigliani and Brumberg, 1954). Paternalistic parents also accumulate savings with the intention of transmitting them to their children. Yet, the amount and structure of the bequest are based not on their children’s preferences, but rather on their idea of what is good for their children, or uniquely on the pleasure they might derive from giving. One often refers to the bequest-as-consumption model because bequest appears in the parents’ utility function as any other consumption goods. Although it is
5830
Gifts, Wills and Inheritance Law
893
possible for paternalistic and altruistic bequests to coincide, generally speaking, this is not the case. Paternalistic bequests might consist of assets that the heir does not really need, such as family possessions bequeathed inopportunely, that is, without the economic situation of the children being taken into account. A variant of the paternalistic bequest, put forward in particular by Modigliani (1986), assumes that the amount of the bequest does not depend on the absolute amount of the family’s resources, but rather on its relative value within the generation to which it belongs, the idea being that a family’s consumption needs tend to increase with economic growth from one generation to the next. Retrospective Bequests We now come to a category of models that share a number of common features: (i) the bequest is motivated by altruism that is labeled ad hoc relative to pure altruism à la Barro-Becker; (ii) information is limited and the forecast imperfect, so parents decide to leave their children a bequest commensurate to what they themselves received; (iii) the implicit rule ‘Do unto your children as you would have liked your parents to have done unto you’ is rooted in social norms of deferred reciprocity, as if bequests were made to one’s children in return for inheritance received from one’s parent. This social, or rather family, norm is related to what sociologists call habitus. Usually these models are cast in a three-generation setting and lead to social optimality if not the Golden Rule. However, this optimal equilibrium is not a market one but one that is based on a commitment to a perennial norm. Even though this commitment is Pareto optimal, one cannot exclude the possibility of rupture in the intergenerational social compact. Bevan (1979), Bevan and Stiglitz (1979), Cigno (1995), and Cox and Stark (1994) have developed models for this category of bequests. Bequests Based on Pure Exchange Intergenerational exchange was common in traditional societies. Parents took care of their children until they reached adulthood and promised to leave them an inheritance (often their work tools). In exchange, children promised to look after their parents once they reached old age, or even earlier in the event of failing health. This type of bequest, known as bequest-as-exchange, is still practiced in rural areas and is related to the old-age security hypothesis that is used to explain fertility. There are a wide variety of bequest-as-exchange models; they have in common that parents care about some service or action undertaken by their children especially to secure old-age needs, and that the education and bequests are the payment for this service or this action. They differ in the nature of what is exchanged, in the timing of the exchange and in the enforcement mechanism (courts, altruism, economic punishment or rewards). Why not always rely on the market? When the market option is rejected, it is primarily because of higher transaction costs. The family is capable of carrying out the tasks of
894
Gifts, Wills and Inheritance Law
5830
middlemen or insurers much more cheaply than commercial companies. In addition, family members have more complete information on the risk of illness or death when financing retirement and on individual talents and motivations when financing education. In the traditional family, for instance, the weight of custom and geographic immobility helped ensure that these engagements were honored. In Kotlikoff and Spivak (1981), exchange leads to an annuity-type contract; in Cox (1987), one has an exchange of services; in Cox (1990), one finds a scheme of loans by parents that are mutually advantageous; Desai and Shah (1983) study the old-age security hypothesis within traditional families. In the same vein, Stark (1995), Becker (1993) and Cremer and Pestieau (1993) have introduced the idea of ‘preference shaping’ through education as a means to facilitate and secure exchange in general and support in particular. They consider a two-stage model. In the first stage, parents attempt to inculcate values in their children; in the second, when those values (guilt for misbehavior) have been imparted, children are ready to trade attention for bequests in terms that are quite favorable to their parents. The exchange-bequest models are most often cast in a setting implying efficient, if not fair, allocations between parents and children. Such a setting mimics that of a competitive market economy. In a quite distinct stream of literature, one finds the dissonant view of Buchanan (1983) who focuses on the rent-seeking aspect of inheritance. He argues that this represents a substantial source of wasteful investment and a significant economic inefficiency (this view is disputed by Anderson and Brown, 1985). Strategic Bequests In the modern family, it is easy and unfortunately common for children not to come to the aid of their elderly parents. However, filial ingratitude is hardly a new phenomenon. Two famous literary representations come to mind. The misfortunes of Shakespeare’s King Lear are well known, but Balzac’s Père Goriot experienced a hardly less tragic fate: ‘He had given his heart and soul for twenty years, his fortune in one day. When the lemon had been squeezed dry, his daughters dropped the peel at the corner of the street.’ These two works show why more than one parent has eschewed premature bequeathing. This leads us quite naturally to a particular type of bequest, the strategic bequest, which in many respects belongs to the bequest-as-exchange category. It is one of the ways of enforcing exchange within the family when there is a time lag between the giving and the receiving and there is no credible recourse to the legal power of the courts and the state (see Bernheim, Schleifer and Summers, 1985. There are other bequest-as-exchange models with strategic features, although less pronounced; see, for example, Cox, 1987.) The model poses in a family with two children. Each child wants to receive as large an inheritance as possible; at the same time, spending time with aging
5830
Gifts, Wills and Inheritance Law
895
parents is costly (at least beyond a certain threshold) in terms of forgone leisure or earnings in the market. The game follows a precise chronology. First, the parents make a commitment as to the total amount of the bequest and to a rule whereby this amount will be divided up according to the level of attention provided by each child. For these promises to be credible, the commitment must be binding. Thereafter, the children do not cooperate with each other and each gives his parents the amount of attention he considers optimal given the inheritance he will derive from it. Following the death of both parents, the inheritance is divided as stipulated. It is clear that the trump card in this game is held by the parents. Operating according to the adage ‘divide and conquer’, they extract the maximum from each of their children under the threat of disinheriting them. 2.3 Capitalist Bequests The term capitalist, or entrepreneurial bequests evokes the image of the entrepreneur found in Ricardo (1817) and classical economists in general (see also Moore, 1979): an austere individual infused with the Weberian Protestant ethic, investing everything he earns and extending the influence of his decision making beyond his own existence. While accidental inheritance touches all classes of society, this type concerns only the well-to-do. (For an empirical test, see Arrondel and Lafferère, 1996, who distinguish the behavior of wealthy households from that of the ‘top-heavy’ ones.) The famous American billionaire Howard Hughes, who left behind a vast financial empire but no direct heir upon his death a couple of decades ago, comes to mind. This is the prototype of wealth so great that it may not be consumed in a single lifetime. It has an existence of its own that in a way exceeds its owner’s control. Even access to the annuity market and knowledge of one’s lifespan would not change the situation in the least. Parents in possession of such wealth, even those devoid of any concern for their family, have no choice but to bequeath it, most likely to their children in societies where the latter may not be disinherited. In any event, there will be an estate whether there are children or not. Such is the example of Alfred Nobel, who left his wealth not to his family but to the well-known Nobel Foundation. So far, we have focused on one factor: the very impossibility of spending an excessive amount of wealth in one generation (this applies to the 1 percent richest families, who, in most countries, possess nearly one-quarter of all wealth). There is another motivation in capitalist bequest: the desire to leave a perennial trace, a financial or industrial dynasty. One thus thinks of individuals such as John D. Rockefeller. Children and grandchildren are then needed not so much out of altruism, but as a necessary means of perpetuation. There is a formal analogy between this type of bequest and those left out of altruism in the Becker-Barro model.
896
Gifts, Wills and Inheritance Law
5830
Lying behind these types of bequests is a whole range of behavior, all the way from pure altruism to selfish manipulation and absolute indifference to the children. From a normative point of view, many will prefer altruistic behavior, but in reality, one finds a little of everything (reality is not as schematic as our categories). What might the interest of this typology be? Is it important to know if certain types of behavior become more frequent and others less so in different times and places? (For the empirical evidence concerning the relative importance of these types of inheritance, see Arrondel, Masson and Pestieau, 1997, and Bernheim, 1991.) Might the likely shift in behavior in the direction of exchange and strategic attitudes be indicative of a change in values? This is not our most immediate concern. We are more interested in the different types of inheritance because each has specific implications for the desirability of adopting particular legal or fiscal regulation of giving and bequeathing. Taking an example from a purely economic viewpoint, taxing accidental bequests is harmless because it has no disincentive effect on that type of saving. The other types of bequests, on the other hand, can be badly affected by taxation. As stated, this is a purely economic viewpoint. One might object from another viewpoint that any inheritance taxation, regardless of the motivation, involves a repugnant confiscatory aspect. We now turn to this debate.
3. Taxing Bequests 3.1 Two Polar Views (for a presentation of these and other views, see Erreygers, 1997; Masson and Pestieau, 1994) Debate over inheritance and its legitimacy has often focused on whether it should be taxed. Quite often, among political scientists and philosophers more than economists, one finds two extreme positions. The first argues that taxing inheritance would allow society to move toward more equality, especially equality of starting conditions in life, without disrupting economic incentives, particularly those concerning work and saving. This position, which can be labeled as one of minimal liberty, assumes that a person has no right at all to decide what should happen with his or her property after his or her death; in this view, property rights do not include a natural right to bequest (see, for example, Haslett, 1994). The second position argues that taxing inheritance is not only illegitimate but destructive because it disrupts the delicate framework of incentives that regulate economic activities. This second position is notably advocated by Bracewell-Milnes (1989) and by the Public Choice school’s founders, James Buchanan and Gordon Tullock (see Buchanan, 1983, and Tullock, 1971). Tullock’s paper was followed by a number of interesting comments ( Greene, 1973; Koller, 1973; Ireland, 1973) and a reply by Tullock
5830
Gifts, Wills and Inheritance Law
897
(1973). Following this view, every person has the right to decide what should happen with his or her property after his or her death. Accordingly, the right of bequest is a natural right. Quite clearly these two positions are fostered by different attitudes toward liberty and equality. They are concerned with basic principles and not with the actual implications for distributive justice and economic efficiency. Put another way, the first position postulates rather than demonstrates that a 100 percent tax on inheritance has no inefficiency effects and leads to a more equal distribution of wealth and eventually of income. The second position, on the contrary, finds any tax on bequests not only repugnant but inoperable as a means of redistributing wealth. The majority of thinkers, and particularly of economists, tend to take a middle position between the two extremes. 3.2 The Middle Position: A Trade-Off Between Equity and Efficiency The position generally taken on this issue of inheritance taxation is one of pragmatism. Making explicit the objectives of taxing authorities, inheritance taxation is deemed desirable if it can achieve some redistribution across and within generations without hurting production and growth. Actually, the extent of taxation will depend on the trade-off between equity and efficiency and this is an empirical and not an ideological matter. If, for example, it can be shown that equity can be achieved without much efficiency cost, then taxation of bequests and inter vivos gifts is desirable. The taxonomy of bequests above is very useful in coping with this issue. Indeed, wealth-transfer taxation will have allocative (efficiency) and redistributive (equity) implications that depend heavily on the type of bequest. We start with the redistributive implications. The clear dividing line on this matter is between (unconstrained) altruistic bequests and all others. In an altruistic world consisting of identical (dynastic) families, we should let the pater familias redistribute resources across and within generations. Estate taxation is then undesirable. However, if income differences are wider across families than within families, there arises a delicate trade-off between two types of redistribution: public and private. The case for estate taxation is enhanced if between-families inequality is higher than within-family inequality and if the efficiency cost of public redistribution is not much higher than that of private redistribution. This is true only of altruistic bequests. For all other types of bequests, estate taxation is always desirable on redistribution grounds. Let us now turn to efficiency considerations and analyze the allocative effects of a distortionary estate tax. We assume that the government runs a balanced budget and that the tax revenue is spent on public goods that enter agents’ utility in an additive way. In other words, we focus on just the uncompensated price effect of wealth-transfer taxation. In the altruistic model, when bequests are operative before and after the tax change, estate taxation
898
Gifts, Wills and Inheritance Law
5830
discourages capital accumulation. (Bernheim and Bagwell, 1988 argue that, with pure altruism and marriage, we are all interconnected through bequests and this makes all taxes nondistortionary. They use this overall neutrality argument to emphasize the limits of altruism.) In the case of accidental bequests, estate taxation has no effect on saving. In the other models, bequest-as-consumption or bequest-as-exchange, taxing bequest is equivalent to taxing a particular type of future consumption. Does that mean that basically it is not desirable to tax wealth transfer ? Not at all. Even when such a tax has a depressive effect on the capital-labor ratio, it can still increase welfare, granted that the overall economy is dynamically inefficient - namely, there is too much capital. Further, even with dynamic efficiency, the desirability of a wealth-transfer tax is a general equilibrium matter that ought to be dealt with in the framework of optimal taxation theory. This section, as well as the current state of the literature on estate taxation, may leave the reader with the impression that the issue is so complicated that nothing can be said. Our own reading of the theoretical literature on inheritance taxation and of the empirical literature on the relative importance of alternative forms of bequests is that progressive inheritance taxation is desirable for both efficiency and equity reasons. The problem, if any, is one of compliance. In open economies with mobility of financial capital, the implementation of inheritance taxation is very difficult. All OECD countries collect less than 0.5 percent of their tax revenues through inheritance taxation in spite of rather high statutory rates.
4. Freedom of Bequeathing 4.1 Equal Division: Some Evidence The debate over the treatment of intergenerational transfer is not restricted to the issue of taxation; for taxation is only one way to restrict the freedom of bequeathing. In fact, one source of debate has been the opposition between the Anglo-Saxon view and the Napoleonic view of inheritance. The first implies freedom of bequests, the only restriction being estate taxation (the tax base is the total amount of the estate left by the deceased, and the tax liability is independent of the number or quality of heirs). Note that when there is no will, equal sharing is the rule. The latter implies equal sharing of the estate among children, but for a limited part that the deceased can allocate freely by writing a will. Within the framework, one has a so-called inheritance tax, whereby the tax base is the amount received by each heir and the rates depend on the degree of consanguinity. These different legal regimes can play an important rule in shaping wealth distribution. It is therefore interesting to see their actual implications by comparing the French and the American situations. Let us consider the US
5830
Gifts, Wills and Inheritance Law
899
estates cases. Tomes (1981, 1988a and 1988b), whose work is based on heirs’ declarations, concludes that exact equality is achieved in one-fifth of the cases and ‘approximate’ equality in less than half. Other authors, who confine themselves to information contained in probate records, find a much greater incidence of equal sharing. In families with two children, for example, exact equality is observed in approximately 70 percent of the cases (63 percent in Menchik, 1980a; 87 percent in Menchik, 1988; 81 percent in Bennett, 1990; 63 percent in Jouflaian, 1993; 69 percent in Wilhem, 1996) versus only 22 percent in Tomes. Moreover, primogeniture represents less than 10 percent of the cases, and the frequency of equal sharing is higher among wealthy households. Finally, the transmission of an indivisible professional asset often leads to unequal sharing only if there is no other wealth that can compensate children left out of the professional bequest. There is thus hardly any doubt that equal sharing is the most frequent official practice in the US. Does that mean that making equal estate sharing mandatory in the US would not be binding for most households and would thus have no consequence? Not necessarily. As the strategic bequest model shows, what matters is the threat of disinheritance, even though the final outcome is equal sharing. In France, less than 8 percent of the estates are unequally divided (see Arrondel and Laferrère, 1992). These cases concern mainly the rich (contrary to the situation in the US) and the self-employed with many children and an illiquid or indivisible bequest (professional assets, real estate). Moreover, inheritance shares remain generally equal, the redistribution among siblings being achieved mainly through previous gifts (80 percent of the cases). It remains to determine whether unequal shares compensate the less-privileged child. There is some evidence in the US that girls, assumed to receive less education or to care more for parents, are slightly advantaged (Menchik, 1980a, 1980b; Bennett, 1990). Otherwise, evidence is mixed. Tomes (1981, 1988a, 1988b) finds significant compensatory effects, but other authors (Menchik, 1988; Wilhem, 1996) do not find any significant correlation between children’s observable characteristics and the relative amount of inheritance received. This ambiguous conclusion is also drawn for France by Arrondel and Lafferère (1992). Indeed, the French or American studies (apart from Tomes’s) can explain when unequal estate division occurs, but not the rationale underlying the distribution. 4.2 Inheritance Rules: Motivations and Implications Inheritance rules are not necessarily imposed by law. In this matter as in many others, tradition and custom are a much more effective way to regulate bequeathing. Bergstrom (1996), for example, refers to several anthropological studies that examine particular rules such as ‘partible patrilineal inheritance’ in central Tibet, whereby ‘in families that had male offspring, inheritance was
900
Gifts, Wills and Inheritance Law
5830
in principle divided equally among them; in families that had no sons, inheritance was passed to a daughter’. Certainly there are many rules besides those of traditional equal division and (male) primogeniture. Each of them, enforced by law or by tradition, has or had a reasonable explanation and interesting implications. For example, as shown by Brenner (1985), the equal-division rule was imposed in the English Middle Ages during a rather short period characterized by ‘the mistreatment of both stepchildren by step-parents and younger children by their older brothers and sisters’ (p. 96). Cyrus Chu (1991) explains the practice of primogeniture in education in imperial China: the whole family pooled its money to subsidize just one child for his human capital investment in the hope he would move up the social ladder and bring honor and prestige to the family (see also Van de Gaer and Crisologo, 1999, who study inheritance rules in the Philippines). The economists are, however, much more interested in the implications than in the historical cause of alternative inheritance rules. A number of scholars (Stiglitz, 1969; Pryor, 1973; Blinder, 1973, 1976b; Atkinson, 1980; Davies, 1982; Laitner, 1988, 1991; Van de Gaer, 1997) have thus studied the expected effects of alternative inheritance rules combined with marriage patterns on the distribution of wealth. Not surprisingly, in these models, where compensatory bequests are assumed away, random marriage and equal division are strong factors of wealth equality. In all this investigation, fertility is assumed fixed. It is, however, interesting to note that fertility can be affected by inheritance rules. The French case is enlightening in that respect. Until the Revolution, each region had its own customs. As shown by Rosental (1991), fertility was much higher in regions subject to primogeniture than in regions subject to equal division. In the latter, the only way to avoid splitting a family’s property was to have at most two children. 4.3 Wills and Strategic Bequests Quite interesting in the debate over the freedom of bequests is the fact that the alternative positions range from one giving all the power to the parent-donor to one implying a confiscatory 100 percent inheritance tax. One can view the practice of many countries, that is, imposing an effectively small inheritance tax along with mandatory equal estate division among children, as an intermediate position that limits the discretionary power of parents. In a society where equal estate sharing is the rule, there is less risk of opportunism on the side of the testator. In fact, with such a rule, there is little room for wills. Empirically, there are fewer wills in countries such as France and Germany where the equal division rule applies, than in the US or the UK where there is full freedom of bequest. As pointed out by De Geest (1995) in reviewing literature on the economics of wills, ‘Much remains to be said about
5830
Gifts, Wills and Inheritance Law
901
the forms of opportunism which testaments can prevent as well as create’ (p. 13). In the models of strategic bequests discussed above, the testator fully uses the possibility of opportunism that is given to him or to her by the legal practice of wills. Accordingly, the testament is not the outcome of a contract; it can be revoked at any time, and its content can even be kept secret. Not only the testament can be kept secret, but also the size of the estate. Note that in Bernheim, Schleifer and Summers (1985), the outcome is efficient even though the testator gets all the trade surplus. Yet, this only works if the inheritance rules and the size of the estate are known by the competing heirs. It would be an interesting avenue for future research to study the economics of wills through the alternative models of strategic and exchange bequests. When equal division is imposed, there is no room for strategic bequests and it is not even certain that the outcome is efficient. In a number of papers (Cremer and Pestieau, 1996), it appears clearly that the only way to induce children to perform and not to shirk responsibility while waiting for an inheritance is to allow their parents the possibility of disinheriting them. At equilibrium, there is no disinheriting but its threat is necessary. In these models, one sees that mandatory equal division is clearly a source of inefficiency or, to put it otherwise, that freedom of bequeathing is a factor of efficiency.
5. Conclusion In this chapter, we have presented a number of alternative models of inheritance and then discussed the implications of each of them for the desirability of inheritance taxation. It appears that the dividing line is clearly between models with altruistic bequests that are fully operative and all the other inheritance models. In a number of countries, the debate on inheritance taxation and on the freedom of bequeathing is lively. The practical problem inherent in inheritance taxation is that whatever the quality of arguments presented in favor of such a taxation, in the reality it brings little revenue to the state regardless of the statutory rates. In all OECD countries, inheritance and gifts taxation represents less than 1 percent of all public revenues. Yields are not only low, but often deemed unfair. After all, estate taxation is often called ‘the tax on sudden death’. The issue of whether bequeathing should be constrained is of a slightly different nature. It is interesting to remember that at one point in its history equal sharing was imposed in the UK because there were too many cases of unfair treatment of stepchildren (see, Brenner,1985). Equal sharing avoids that kind of inequity, but, at the same time, it prevents parents from compensating their children for unequal incomes or opportunities. One has the feeling that, in a number of countries, the trend is now in favor of increasing freedom of
902
Gifts, Wills and Inheritance Law
5830
bequeathing. This hopefully implies an increasing trust in the judgment and the maturity of individuals in dealing with the intergenerational distribution of resources.
Acknowledgments I wish to thank Gerrit De Geest, Marty Crowe, and an anonymous referee for helpful comments and suggestions.
Bibliography on Gifts, Wills and Inheritance Law (5830) Anderson, Gary M. and Brown, P.J. (1985), ‘Heir Pollution: A Note on Buchanan’s “Law of Succession” and Tullock’s “Blind Spot”, 5 International Review of Law and Economics, 15-23. Arrondel, L. and Lafferère, A. (1992), ‘Les Partages Inégaux des Successions entre Frères et Soeurs’, 250 Economie et Statistique, 29-42. Arrondel, L. and Lafferère, A. (1996), Succession Capitaliste et Succession Familiale, mimeo. Arrondel, L., Masson, Alison and Pestieau P. (1997), ‘Becquests and Inheritance: Empirical Issues and French Evidence’, in Erreygers, G. and Vandevelde, T. (eds), Is Inheritance Justified?, Berlin, Springer Verlag. Atkinson, Anthony B. (1980), ‘Inheritance and the Distribution of Wealth’, in Hughes, G.A. and Heal, Geoffrey M. (eds), The Public Policy and the Tax System, London, George Allen and Unwin, 36-66. Barro, Robert J. (1974), ‘Are Government Bonds Net Wealth?’, 82 Journal of Political Economy, 1095-1117. Becker, Gary S. (1974), ‘A Theory of Social Interactions’, 82 Journal of Political Economy, 1063-1093. Becker, Gary S. (1975), ‘Human Capital and the Personal Distribution of Income: An Analytic Approach’, Woytinsky Lecture 1967, Human Capital, New York, Columbia University Press, 94-144. Becker, Gary S. (1989), ‘On the Economics of the Family: Reply to a Skeptic’, 79 American Economic Review, 514-518. Becker, Gary S. (1991), A Treatise on the Family, Cambridge, Harvard University Press. Becker, Gary S. (1993), ‘The Economic Way of Looking at Behavior’, 101 Journal of Political Economy, 385-409. Becker, Gary S. and Tomes, Nigel (1979), ‘An Equilibrium Theory of the Distribution of Income and Intergenerational Mobility’, 87 Journal of Political Economy, 1153-1189. Becker, Gary S. and Tomes, Nigel (1986), ‘Human Capital and the Rise and Fall of Families’, 4(2) Journal of Labor Economics, 1-39. Bennett, S.K. (1990), Economic and Non-Economic Factors Motivating Bequest Patterns, mimeo. Bergstrom, T. C. (1996), ‘Economics in a Family Way’, 34 Journal of Economic Literature, 1903-1934.
5830
Gifts, Wills and Inheritance Law
903
Bernheim, B. Douglas (1991), ‘How Strong are Bequest Motives? Evidence Based on Estimates of The Demand for Life Insurance and Annuities’, 99 Journal of Political Economy, 899-927. Bernheim, B. Douglas and Bagwell, Kyle (1988), ‘Is Everything Neutral?’, 96 Journal of Political Economy, 308-338. Bernheim, B. Douglas, Schleifer, A. and Summers, Lawrence H. (1985), ‘The Strategic Bequest Motive’, 93 Journal of Political Economy, 1045-1076. Bevan, D.L. (1979), ‘Inheritance and the Distribution of Wealth’, 46 Economica, 1153-1189. Bevan, D.L. and Stiglitz, J.E. (1979), ‘Intergenerational Transfers and Inequality’, 1 Greek Economic Journal, 8-26. Blinder, Alan S. (1973), ‘A Model of Inherited Wealth’, 88 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 608-626. Blinder, Alan S. (1974), Towards an Economic Theory of Income Distribution, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Blinder, Alan S. (1976a), ‘Intergenerational Transfers and Life Cycle Consumption’, 66 American Economic Review, 87-93. Blinder, Alan S. (1976b), ‘Inequality and Mobility in the Distribution of Wealth’, 29 Kyklos, 607-638. Bracewell-Milnes, Barry (1989), The Wealth of Giving: Every One in his Inheritance, London, Institute of Economic Affairs. Brenner, Gabrielle A. (1985), ‘Why did Inheritance Laws Change?’, 5 International Review of Law and Economics, 91-106. Brenner, Reuven (1985), Betting on Ideas, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Brinig, Margaret F. (1994), ‘Finite Horizons: The American Family’, 2 International Journal of Children’s Rights, 293-315. Brinig, Margaret F. (1996), ‘The Family Franchise, Elderly Parents and their Adult Siblings’, 1996 Utah Law Review, 393-425. Brough, Wayne T. (1990), ‘Liability Salvage - by Private Ordering’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 95-111. Bruce, Neil and Waldman, Michael (1990), ‘The Rotten Kid Theorem Meets the Samaritan’s Dilemma’, 105 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 1165-1182. Buchanan, James M. (1983), ‘Rent Seeking, Noncompensated Transfers, and Laws of Succession’, 26 Journal of Law and Economics,71-85. Cabrillo, Francisco (1996), Matrimonio, Familia y Economía (Marriage, Family and Economics), Madrid, Minerva Ediciones. Chami, Ralph (1996), ‘King Lear’s Dilemma: Precommitment versus the Last Word’, 52 Economics Letters, 171-176. Chami, Ralph and Fischer, Jeffrey (1996), ‘Altruism, Matching and Nonmarket Insurance’, 34 Economic Inquiry, 630-647. Cigno, Alessandro (1995), Saving, Fertility and Social Security in the Presence of Self-Enforcing Intrafamily Deals, mimeo. Cox, Donald (1987), ‘Motives for Privates Transfers’, 96 Journal of Political Economy, 508-546. Cox, Donald (1990), ‘Intergenerational Transfers and Liquidity Constraints’, 104 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 187-217. Cox, Donald and Stark, Oded (1994), ‘Intergenerational Transfers and the Demonstration Effect’,
904
Gifts, Wills and Inheritance Law
5830
mimeo. Cremer, H. and Pestieau P. (1993), ‘Education for Attention: a Nash Bargaining Solution to the Bequest-as-Exchange Model’, 48 Public Finance, 85-97. Cremer, H. and Pestieau P. (1996), ‘Bequests as a Heir Discipline Device’, 9 Journal of Population Economics, 405-414. Cremer, H., Kessler, Daniel and Pestieau P. (1991), ‘Intergenerational Transfers within the Family’, 58 European Economic Review, 359-375. Cyrus, Chu C.Y. (1991), ‘Primogeniture’, 99 Journal of Political Economy, 78-99. Davies, J.B. (1981), ‘Uncertain Lifetime, Consumption and Dissaving in Retirement’, 89 Journal of Political Economy, 561-577. Davies, J.B. (1982), ‘The Relative Impact of Inheritance and Other Factors on Economic Inequality’, 97 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 471-498. De Geest, Gerrit (1995), ‘Contracting by Way of Non-Simultaneous Assent: An Economic Analysis of Irrevocable Offers, Clauses for the Benefit of a Third Party, Assignments and Testaments’, in Bouckaert, Boudewijn and De Geest, Gerrit (eds), Essays in Law and Economics II: Contract Law, Regulation, and Reflections on Law and Economics, 1-27. Desai, M. and Shah, A. (1983), ‘Bequest and Inheritance in Nuclear Families and Joint Families’, 50 Economica, 193-202. Erreygers, G. (1997), ‘Views on Inheritance in the History of Economic Thought’, in Erreygers, G. and Vandevelde, T. (eds), Is Inheritance Justified?, Berlin, Springer Verlag. Erreygers, G. and Vandevelde, T. (1997), Is Inheritance Justified?, Berlin, Springer Verlag. Garcimartin Alférez and Francisco Javier (1995), ‘El Régimen Normativo de las Transacciones Privadas Internacionales: una Aproximación Económica (The Regulation of International Private Transactions: an Economic Approach)’, 2 Revista Española de Derecho Internacional, 99-111. Greene, Kenneth V. (1973), ‘Inheritance Unjustified?’, 16 Journal of Law and Economics, 417-419. Haslett, D. W. (1994), Capitation with Morality, Oxford, Clarendon Press. Hirsch, Adam J. and Wang, William K.S. (1992), ‘A Qualitative Theory of the Dead Hand’, 68 Indiana Law Journal, 1-58. Ireland, Thomas R. (1973), ‘Inheritance Justified: A Comment’, 16 Journal of Law and Economics, 421-422. Joulfaian, D. (1993), The Distribution and the Division of Bequests in the U.S.: Evidence from the Collation Study, mimeo. Koller, Roland H. II (1973), ‘Inheritance Justified: A Comment’, 16 Journal of Law and Economics, 423-424. Kotlikoff, L.J. and Spivak, Avia (1981), ‘The Family as an Incomplete Annuities Market’, 89 Journal of Political Economy, 372-391. Laitner, J. (1988), ‘Bequests, Gifts and Social Security’, 55 Review of Economic Studies, 275-299. Laitner, J. (1991), ‘Modeling Marital Connections among Family Lines’, 99 Journal of Political Economy, 1123-1141. Linbeck, A. and Weibull, Jürgen W. (1988), ‘Altruism and Time Consistency: the Politics of Fait Accompli’, 96 Journal of Political Economy, 1165-1182. Masson, Alison (1995), ‘L’Héritage au Sein des Transfers entre Générations: Théorie, Constat, Perspective’, in Attias-Donfut, Cl. (ed.), La Solidarité entre Générations, Paris, Nathan.
5830
Gifts, Wills and Inheritance Law
905
Masson, Alison and Pestieau P. (1994), ‘L’Héritage et l’Etat’, in Pestieau P. (ed.), Héritage et Transmission Intergénérationelles, Bruxelles, De Boeck Université, 15-44. Menchik, Paul (1980a), ‘Primogeniture, Equal Sharing and the U.S. Distribution of Wealth’, 94 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 299-316. Menchik, Paul (1980b), ‘Effect of Material Inheritance on the Distribution of Wealth’, in Smith, J.D. (ed.), Modelling the Distribution and Intergenerational Transmission of Wealth, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 159-185. Menchik, Paul (1988), ‘Unequal Estate Division: is it Altruism, Reverse Bequests, or Simply Noise?’, in Kessler, D. and Masson, A. (eds), Modelling the Accumulation and Distribution of Wealth, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 105-116. Modigliani, Franco (1986), ‘Life Cycle, Individual Thrift, and the Wealth of Nations’, 76 American Economic Review, 297-313. Modigliani, Franco and Brumberg, R. (1954), ‘Utility Analysis and the Consumption Function: an Interpretation of Cross-Section Data’, in Kurihana, K.K. (ed.), Post-Keynesian Economics, New York, Rutgers University Press, 388-436. Moore, B.J. (1979), ‘Life Cycle Saving and Bequest Behavior’, 1 Journal of Post Keynesian Economics, 78-99. Ott, Claus (1995), ‘Comment on Contracting by Way on Non-Simultaneous Assent in the German Civil Code’, in Bouckaert, Boudewijn and De Geest, Gerrit (eds), Essays in Law and Economics, 29-33. Posner Richard A. (1992), Economic Analysis of Law (4th edn), Boston, Little Brown. Posner, Eric A. (1997), ‘Altruism, Trust, and Status in the Law of Gifts and Gratuitous Promises’, Wisconsin Law Review, forthcoming. Pryor, F.L. (1973), ‘Simulation of the Impact of Social Economic Institutions on the Size Distribution of Income and Wealth’, 63 American Economic Review, 50-72. Ricardo, D. (1817), Principles of Political Economy and Taxation, London, Murray. Richter, Wolfram F. (1992), Bequeathing Like a Principal, University of Dortmund, mimeo. Rosental, P.A. (1991), ‘Practiques Successorales et Fécondité: l’Effet du Code Civil’, 100 Economie et Prévision, 231-238. Schäfer, Hans-Bernd and Struck, Gerhard (1983), ‘Schlammbeseitigung auf der Bundesstrasse. Geschäftsführung ohne Auftrag, Deliktsrecht, negatorische Haftung. Ökonomische Analyse des Rechts (The Case of the Mud Removal at the Federal Highway)’, in Walz, W. Rainer and Rascher-Friesenhausen, Hein (eds), Sozialwissenschaften im Zivilrecht: Fälle und Lösungen in Ausbildung und Prüfung, 119-132. Shammas, Carole, Salmon, Marylynn and Dahlin, Michel (1987), Inheritance in America from Colonial Times to the Present, New Brunswick, Rutgers University Press. Stake, Jeffrey E. (1990), ‘Darwin, Donations, and the Illusion of Dead Hand Control’, 64 Tulane Law Review, 705-781. Stark, Oded (1995), Altruism and Beyond, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Stiglitz, J.E. (1969), ‘Distribution of Income and Wealth Among Individuals’, 37 Econometrica, 382-397. Tomes, Nigel (1981), ‘The Family, Inheritance and the Intergenerational Transmission of Inequality’, 89 Journal of Political Economy, 928-958. Tomes, Nigel (1982), ‘On the Intergenerational Savings Function’, 34 Oxford Economic Papers, 108-134. Tomes, Nigel (1988a), ‘Inheritance and Inequality within the Family: Equal Division among Unequals,
906
Gifts, Wills and Inheritance Law
5830
or Do the Poor Get More?’, in Kessler, D. and Masson, A. (eds), Modelling the Accumulation and Distribution of Wealth, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 79-104. Tomes, Nigel (1988b), ‘The Intergenerational Transmission of Wealth and the Rise and Fall of Families’, in Kessler, D. and Masson, A. (eds), Modelling the Accumulation and Distribution of Wealth, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 147-165. Tullock, Gordon (1971), ‘Inheritance Justified’, 14 Journal of Law and Economics, 465-474. Tullock, Gordon (1973), ‘Inheritance Rejustified’, 16 Journal of Law and Economics, 425-428. Van de Gaer, D. (1997), ‘Remarks on Inheritance and Marriage’, KUL, unpublished manuscript. Van de Gaer, D. and Crisologo, L. (1999), ‘Population Growth and Customary Law on Land: The Case of Cordillera Villages in the Philippines’, Economic Development and Cultural Change, Forthcoming. Wilhem, M.O. (1996), ‘Bequest Behavior and the Effect of Heirs’ Earnings: Testing the Altruistic Model of Bequests’, 86 American Economic Review, 874-892.
5840 RENTING Werner Z. Hirsch Professor of Economics University of California, Los Angeles © Copyright 1999 Xerner Z. Hirsch
Abstract Landlord-tenant law can be grouped into three major classes - rent control, habitability, and anti-discrimination laws. At times, two or three such laws are in effect at the same time and even may be supplemented by some additional laws needed to assure their effectiveness. When that happens, as in the case where a jurisdiction has both rent control and habitability laws, landlords can find their financial future at risk. The reason is that virtually all landlord-tenant laws, intended to protect the interest of tenants, impose costs on landlords. The more such laws are enforced, the heavier the burdens on landlords, and the more limited the latters’ rights and opportunities to manage their enterprise. Moreover, both deductive and inductive studies suggest that some of the landlord-tenant laws, while burdening landlords, are of little, and at times no, help to tenants, though tenants may deserve protection. JEL classification: 619, 717, 722, 916, 917, 932, K11, K23 Keywords: Renting, Landlord-Tenant Relations, Rent Control, Habitability Laws, Housing Codes, Housing Discrimination Laws
1. Introduction Renting involves a temporary exchange of rights to occupy and make use of real property - unimproved and improved - in return for a fee, that is a rent payment. While the property may be used for agricultural, industrial, commercial or residential purposes, the law has taken special interest in residential property for a number of reasons. Housing provides shelter which is a necessity, and therefore has inelastic demand; it takes a long time to build new housing, and therefore it has inelastic short-run supply; it is one of the largest, if not the largest, budget item of most families; and it has many intangible characteristics which determine its quality, including spatial location and fixity, durability, age, size and appointments. This review, therefore, will focus on what law and economics has contributed to the understanding, regulation, and evaluation of landlord-tenant relations and particularly the laws’ side effects. 907
908
Renting
5840
Three classes of laws regulating landlord-tenant relations will be reviewed rent control laws and, in conjunction with them, vacancy decontrol, no-fault eviction and anti-conversion laws since they tend to be associated with rent control, habitability laws and anti-discrimination laws.
A. Economic Theory of Rental Housing Markets 2. Housing Market Theory Nowhere is housing a single market in the neoclassical sense. In fact it is a set of submarkets which differ in their location, housing type, tenure, quality and other aspects (Smith, et al., 1988, p. 30). They also differ in terms of the jurisdiction’s tenure strategy, that is, private versus public ownership of residential rental housing. This strategy is well documented for Australia, Germany, Holland, New Zealand, Sweden, Switzerland and the United Kingdom (Kemeny, 1995, pp. 75-129). Renting in a number of countries has also been discussed by Harloe (1985) and Emms (1990). Power (1993) has reviewed renting in five European countries. From these and other studies it is clear that the distinguishing characteristics of housing in general, and rental residential housing in particular, are many. Some are responsible for governments all over the world frequently interceding in the relations between landlords and tenants. For example, the fact that both the supply of and demand for rental housing tend to be inelastic can lead to sharp rent increases during market adjustments, which interested parties often proclaim to constitute rent gouging (a terms basically devoid of economic content). In order to analyze rental housing in general and the effects upon it of landlord-tenant laws in particular, economists have developed special methods of inquiry. One involves housing stock models and the other flow models which use hedonic price analysis (Kain and Quigley, 1970; Rosen, 1974; Barnett, 1979; Quigley, 1979). Hedonic price analysis also has been applied to estimate the effects of certain landlord-tenant laws (Hirsch, 1981; Hirsch and Law, 1979; Rydell et al., 1981; Marks, 1984) . Hedonic price analysis looks at housing as a complex commodity composed of a host of housing services flowing from the existing housing stock with the number of housing service units determining its quality. The housing services of a dwelling include location, heat, air conditioning, size, appointments, and so on, each valued and consumed by residents. Although the flow of housing services is not well-defined and its quantity hard to ascertain and to price, the monthly rent can be considered the product of the number of housing-service units times the unit’s price. The hedonic price approach supposes that the
5840
Renting
909
various housing characteristics of a dwelling have distinguishable values to residents. Thus, the hedonic housing price function estimates the marginal market prices consumers are willing to pay for each housing characteristic. Information from this function can be used to combine any set of measured characteristics into a one-dimensional measure of the value of the total flow of housing services from dwellings in a specific housing market. This approach has major beneficial applications to the analysis of landlord-tenant laws. It allows looking at rent as the product of the number of housing service units and the price of a unit, providing useful insight into the effect, for example, of a rent control law. Thus, even if rent control succeeds in reducing rent, hedonic housing price analysis permits the estimation of the percentage associated with lower housing service unit prices as well as that associated with the reduced number of housing service units. The latter testifies to the extent to which housing quality has diminished as a result of rent control (Rydell et al., 1981). In a similar manner, with the help of hedonic price methods, it becomes possible to determine what, if any, effect a habitability law has had on housing quality and the price of housing service units (Hirsch, Hirsch and Margolis, 1975).
3. Housing Market Models Economists have developed a number of specific rental housing models, which fall into the following categories: 1. Perfectly competitive static stock models which treat rental housing as a homogeneous commodity, thereby neglecting such characteristics as location, quality, size, and so on. 2. Perfectly competitive static flow models which assume the existence of an unobservable homogeneous commodity, that is, housing services (Muth, 1983 and Olsen, 1988). Rental housing has a variety of housing characteristics, each of which has quantitative and qualitative dimensions. This characteristics approach of Rosen (1974) involves a model of demand, supply and competitive market equilibrium. Each housing unit has a vector of n objectively measurable characteristics. A bundle of such characteristics constitutes a housing unit which has a price in the housing market. In a competitive market, such bundles and their prices indicate the implicit prices of characteristics, defined as hedonic prices. Multiple regression analysis can estimate these hedonic prices. Many of these models assume a group of households and firms to be confined to the rental market, ownership housing to be a substitute for rental housing with the price of ownership housing given, and rather static circumstances which do not identify how quality changes come about, that is, whether through maintenance, rehabilitation, conversion, and so on (Arnott, 1995).
910
Renting
5840
3. Perfectly competitive flow models with select dynamic features. For example, a housing model by Sweeney (1974b) incorporates a number of dynamic features and also explicitly allows quality differentiation. In this model a landlord owning a durable housing unit of a given quality makes, for instance, maintenance decisions. Based on information on rent-quality relationships and the rate at which the housing unit deteriorates subject to maintenance levels, the landlord selects the maintenance expenditure level which maximizes the discounted present value of net revenues from his housing unit. The model allows for construction and abandonment of housing, and a model by Arnott (1987) allows for demolition followed by construction of rentals. 4. Imperfectly competitive flow models which recognize imperfections due to location, heterogeneity of housing units, neighborhood effects, search costs and imperfections in capital markets. Two major classes of such models exist. One is a monopolistically competitive model derived from search-based matching models (Diamond, 1984). Tenants’ tastes guide the search for rentals. In an imperfect market, searchers finding the exact housing unit they desire can end up paying a rent above that commanded by rather similar rental units. Should landlords recognize this fact, they could charge a price above marginal cost. Yet, should there be free entry and exit, profits would decline, possibly to zero, and vacancies result. A second class of models can be referred to as contract models where market imperfections result from asymmetric information (Hubert, 1990). For example, there can be reliable and unreliable tenants, whose identity landlords discover only after occupancy has commenced. Unreliable tenants will move frequently and, in the absence of widespread information about their behavior, impose heavy costs on landlords. 5. Political-economic models theorize about the probability of a jurisdiction enacting landlord-tenant laws (Fallis, 1988). Such models take cognizance of the fact that landlord-tenant relations are significantly affected by the relative size, wealth, and political activity of the two groups to a bargain. Landlords in many communities tend to be richer but fewer in number than are tenants. But in addition to tenants, there are also homeowners. Whether their economic interest is more attuned to tenants or landlords is not altogether clear (Arnott, 1995). A model by Epple (1994) explicitly recognizes that a community has permanent and temporary residents, each with different interests. Neither group, however, knows the size of the other. Yet, homeowners are not incorporated into the model.
5840
Renting
911
B. Rent Control Laws 4. Legal Analysis In many countries governments have enacted laws that regulate the rents landlords may charge residential tenants for their property and services. The avowed purpose has been to protect tenants from unwarranted rent increases, particularly if they might force them to vacate the premises. Most of these controls were enacted in times of severe housing shortages, mainly during wartime and periods of hyperinflation. The relation between rent control and inflation has been explored by St. John (1996). Controls are of two types - first generation or hard controls, that is, virtual rent freezes, and second generation or soft controls which can allow for automatic rent increases (tied, for example, to the rate of inflation), cost passthroughs, vacancy decontrol, and so on. Rent freezes were imposed on many American and European cities during World War II. Some, including New York, retained these controls long into the post-war period. For example, in the United Kingdom, rent control was enacted by Parliament shortly after the outbreak of World War II (Hirsch, 1981) and Turner (1988). The Rent and Mortgage Interest Restrictions Act of 1939 applied to rent controls as well as to security of tenure. Rents were fixed at September 1939 levels. Also a number of major cities in developing countries have first generation types of rent controls, although they differ in detail and enforcement Malpezzi (1993). During runaway inflation of the 1970s, many local jurisdictions in the United States imposed rent control, including about 100 municipalities in the State of New Jersey alone. In California, when real estate prices skyrocketed in the late 1970s and the electorate passed a revenue limitation measure (Proposition 13), the measure’s sponsors promised to reduce rents. When rents were not lowered, a number of local jurisdictions (including the cities of Los Angeles, San Francisco, Oakland, Berkeley, and Santa Monica, and the County of Los Angeles) adopted rent control ordinances. Also, about one third of cities in California had rent control ordinances in effect on mobile home parks. Moreover in the mid 1970s all Canadian provinces introduced rent control, though only four have retained them (Arnott, 1995). In 1995, residential housing under rent control is estimated to fall between 10-15 percent (Arnott, 1995). In the United States, rent control has typically been justified by local government entities as an exercise of their police power. In the 1920s, the United States Supreme Court held that the use of state police power to enact rental controls was consistent with the due process clauses of the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments of the United States Constitution only if utilized in response to a housing ‘emergency’ (Block v. Hirsch, 1921). In recent years,
912
Renting
5840
however, for some courts a crisis or extremely exigent circumstances are no longer required to justify rent control. For example, the California Supreme Court, in Birkenfeld v. City of Berkeley (1976, p. 129), declared that it ‘is now settled California law that legislation regulating prices or otherwise restricting contractual or property rights is within the police power if its operative provisions are reasonably related to the accomplishments of a legitimate governmental purpose.’ Thus, in the United States, the court’s inquiry in rent control cases is generally whether the ordinance reasonably relates to a legitimate purpose. The more important question of whether the measure will, in fact, achieve its stated objective of controlling rents is typically not reviewed by the courts. This is the traditional dichotomy between procedural and substantive due process, and it is this approach that ignores the value of economic analysis. The fact that rent controls may actually make a housing problem worse often appears irrelevant to a court’s view of a rent control ordinance. As long as the enacting body could reasonably conclude that the measure is related to a legitimate purpose, the measure is likely to be upheld, even if it is counterproductive (Palos Verdes Shores Mobile Estates, Ltd. v. City of Los Angeles, 1983). American courts have two further concerns. In order not to be confiscatory on its face, a rent control ordinance must permit the regulatory board to grant across-the-board increases based upon classification enumerated by the board or statute. Alternatively, the rent control ordinance must institute a unit-by-unit procedure that will operate without what the court considers to be an unreasonable delay. There is also a constitutional requirement for a ‘just and reasonable’ return, a difficult concept. A requirement of recent vintage and to be discussed below is the ‘nexus’ test. Rent control laws differ in stringency and tightness, depending on their coverage and pass-through provisions, the basis on which and manner in which permissible rent increases are calculated, the ease with which landlords can hope to get such increases, and whether the laws allow for vacancy decontrol, demolition of buildings, and use change. Stringent ordinances cover all premises, whereas the less stringent ones exempt single dwellings, luxury apartments, and apartment houses with fewer than four or three units. Also, the less stringent ordinances permit the cost for major repair and minor improvements to be passed on to tenants. Great differences also exist in the manner in which allowable rent increases are set and enforced. In the most extreme case, there can be rent freezes and even rollbacks to an earlier date. Most laws provide a formula by which annual ‘general adjustments’ are made: some stipulate a fixed annual percentage increase, while others tie increases to changes in the cost of living. Since rents are more in line with market rent under vacancy decontrol, total decontrol should be easier in its presence than in its absence. However, discrimination can result against groups of tenants that have low turnover rates (that is, senior citizens).
5840
Renting
913
Rent control is not unique to the United States. For example, in the United Kingdom, rent control has had a long history going back to 1939. The Rent Acts of 1965 and 1977 focused on ‘fair rents’ and allowed tenants to apply to a rent officer (with a right to appeal to a rent assessment committee) for determination of what is a fair rent for the relevant premises. In making the assessment, regard is to be had to the age, character, locality and state of repair of the premises, and also to the provision (if any) of furniture. This determination was to be made on the assumption that in the locality demand does not exceed supply, that is, the market is in equilibrium. While the legislation does not prescribe how this determination is to be made, the favored method had been to look for rents for equivalent premises in comparable jurisdictions. While possibly generating horizontal equally, the method does not assure that the rent is appropriate. This determination of fair rent has been costly to administer and has resulted in a large amount of litigation (Ogus, 1994). In recognizing its harmful effects in a White Paper of 1987, rent controls were abolished by the Housing Act of 1988. The end of fair rents in the United Kingdom has been examined by Davy (1992) and Lee (1992).
5. Economic Analysis: General Remarks Rent control laws have in common that they reduce the freedom of landlords to set rent levels and diminish the range of rents and property types that can feasibly be offered tenants. As a consequence, opportunities for mutually beneficial trades between landlords and tenants are reduced. Such laws amount to price control and result in distributional and efficiency consequences commonly associated with such controls. An exercise in positive economics reveals a host of effects on rental housing supply, property values, maintenance and housing quality, new construction and conversion, availability of rentals, potential mismatch of rental units to households and reduced housing mobility. Moreover, distributional effects occur, not only between landlords and tenants, but also among tenant groups with differing income, gender, race and age characteristics. It is helpful to recognize that rent control laws can apply to two major classes of property ownership. Rent control of apartments, unless they are furnished, involve single ownership, that is land as well as improvements are owned by one and the same party. The second class involves divided ownership which occurs when the improvements are owned by one party and the land on which they are placed are owned by another. Examples are housing condominiums and cooperatives as well as mobile home parks on leased land. In relation to an appraisal of effects of rent control, the two ownership patterns differ.
914
Renting
5840
Arnott recognizes, and our review confirms, that there are few empirical studies of first generation rent control in Europe at least in the English-language literature (Arnott, 1995, p. 102). Moreover, there are relatively few contributions that pertain to countries other than the United States. Exceptions are some papers on Canada (Arnott and Johnston, 1981; Smith and Tomlinson, 1981; Marks, 1984; Fallis and Smith, 1985); Germany (Börsch-Supan, 1986); Hong Kong (Cheung, 1975, 1979); Israel (Anas and Cho, 1988; Werczberger, 1988) and United Kingdom (Coleman, 1988; Ogus, 1994).
6. Economic Analysis: Rent Control of Single Ownership Property First-generation or hard rent control laws, that involve a virtual rent freeze, have usually been subjected to what Arnott (1995) refers to as ‘Textbook Analysis.’ This analysis makes use of the first model discussed earlier, that is, a perfectly competitive static stock model. It focuses on rent and availability of rental housing. When, for example, inflation raises the cost of providing rental housing, controls prevent landlords from passing on cost increases to tenants. Figure 1
Using a housing stock model in Figure 1 the two axes are rent (R) and number of dwellings (Q). Before the imposition of rent control on apartments, at equilibrium, the number of dwelling units was Q1 and the market-clearing rent was R1. As a result of, for example, increases in the price of input factors (whether repair and maintenance costs, utilities, or property taxes), the supply function shifts to the left (S2). Without a change in demand, a new equilibrium would be reached at Q2 and R2. Rent control would prohibit landlords from
5840
Renting
915
charging the rent that they would otherwise have sought; that is, their rent will be below R2. In the most extreme case where no rent increase is permitted, landlords would supply Q1 - Q3 fewer dwellings than would be demanded in the short run. In the long run, rent control is likely to have a chilling effect on investors and therefore curtail the supply of housing. Thus, cumulative declines in low-cost dwellings could be anticipated, accompanied by housing shortages. Empirical estimates of the long-run price elasticity of rental housing supply related to land prices in large US metropolitan areas suggest it to be about +0.20 (Hirsch, 1981). Thus, a 10 percent increase in the price of land per year would tend to increase rents by 6.5 percent. If no rent increases were permitted, supply would be reduced by 2.4 percent of low-cost housing units, and if only half of that increase were permitted, the shortage would be 1.2 percent. The effects of rent control can also be examined from the demand side, where the rental housing demand function shifts to the right. If we assume that, in the short run, the supply of low-cost housing rental units cannot change, a new equilibrium would be reached at a higher rent and number of dwelling units. Rent control does not permit this new price for housing units to be obtained, and a shortage of dwelling units will result. Landlords not permitted to raise rents may reduce repair and maintenance, and thereby the quality of housing. Or they may withdraw dwellings from the market by converting apartments into condominiums, convalescent homes, homes for the aged, or cooperatives. Some may even abandon their properties because of the artificial imbalance between costs and rent. The magnitude of the likely rental housing shortage can be estimated with the aid of income elasticities for low-cost rentals. An econometric study estimated it to be about +0.98 for 1974-75 (Hirsch, 1981, p. 293). In an uncontrolled rental market, in the presence of an annual per capita income increase of 8 percent, for example, and on the assumption that the short-run supply of low-cost housing does not increase, annual rent increases of about 8.0 percent could be expected. If rent control were to be imposed and were to permit no increase whatsoever, an 8.0 percent shortage of low-cost rental units would develop. If, on the other hand, rent increases were held to half the expected 8.0 percent, or 4.0 percent per annum, a shortage of about 4.0 percent would result. These shortages would be cumulative as long as income increases over time. The textbook analysis has been effectively summarized by Arnott (1995). Accordingly, when rents are capped below market-clearing levels, tenants in rent-controlled apartments benefit. The longer the occupancy, the greater the benefit. The below-market rents induce excess demand for housing and in turn a mismatch of apartments to households; reduced mobility of tenants and therefore the labor force; and grey- or black-market phenomena, for example, ‘key money’. Furthermore, landlords incur lower returns on their investment
916
Renting
5840
and a corresponding decline in property values. They tend to reduce repair and maintenance, convert to non-controlled land uses and desist from adding apartments. When the analysis applies the second model, that is, a perfectly competitive flow model, one can show that one effect of the reduced rents takes the form of a reduction in the number of housing service units, that is, quality of apartments provided. Empirical methods permit an estimation of the relative importance of changes in the number of housing service units provided, that is, quality of apartments, compared to housing service unit prices. If the main concern is with rent control’s effect on housing quality, a housing flow model, using hedonic housing price functions, is appropriate. A theoretical model by Frankena (1975) (the second type discussed earlier) separates the effect of rent control on the number of housing service units from that on the unit’s price. Frankena does so by examining the effect of rent control as a ceiling on rent (or, equivalently, revenue) per dwelling as opposed to a ceiling on price per housing service unit. His model leads to a kinked supply curve when rent control takes the form of a revenue constraint, as shown in Figure 2. Figure 2
The horizontal axis measures housing service units. Equilibrium price and quantity occur at p0 and q0, respectively, in the absence of controls. If rent control limits revenue per dwelling to price-quantity combinations along the rectangular hyperbola ASSR2, then the effective supply curve will become SASSR2. In this diagram, equilibrium occurs at a lower quality level (q1), but at a higher price per housing service unit (p1). Increased demand, then, will lead to even
5840
Renting
917
more deterioration of quality. Rydell et al. (1981) built a model that permits the estimation of both the price and the quality effects of rent control. They relied on the housing-services approach in which the variable of interest is a composite of the housing commodity’s desirable attributes. If landlords charge the market rent for a dwelling with a certain quantity of housing services, a reduction in rents means that the landlords are now not being paid for all the services they supply. For example, if the rent declines by 5 percent, the landlord will be receiving payment for only 95 percent of what he offers. The landlord then will be tempted to reduce the quantity of services to only those for which he is paid. This is done for the least cost through less maintenance resulting in deterioration, which, of course, is the result predicted by Frankena. It was projected that, after rent control had been in effect in Los Angeles for four years, the rents of controlled dwellings would be about 4 percent lower than they would have been if rent control had not been in force. Likewise, after four years, the price of rental housing services was estimated to be 3.2 percent lower than it would have been without rent control, and the quantity of rental housing service units was 1.5 percent lower (Rydell et al., 1981, p. VI). A 1991 paper projected the effect of rent control on housing service units and their prices for eight years (Rydell et al., 1991). It confirms that rent control of the sort enacted by Los Angeles in the late 1970s would confer its benefits early and extract its costs late. The early effects of rent control were exclusively housing service price reductions, whereas, as time passed, landlords reduced the level of rental housing services in line with the rent they were permitted to charge. Thus, controls would reduce benefits to renters and also reduce supply. If the rent-control ordinance were tightened, it would accelerate those reductions without providing proportionate increases in benefits to the renters. The long-term effect of rent control on rental housing quality was estimated by Mengle (1983). His study of eight large cities estimated that the presence of rent control was associated in 1974 with a 7.4 percent decrease in housing quality, while three years later it was associated with a 13.9 percent decrease. For indigent black tenants, the deterioration was 18.6 percent in 1974 and 26.6 percent in 1977. The deterioration was particularly serious for indigent aged tenants. Thus, in 1979 in the presence of rent control, the housing quality of all tenants had declined by 14.5 percent, of aged tenants 60 years and over by 17.3 percent, and of indigent tenants 60 years and over by 23.0 percent. Tenant gains and landlord losses that result from rent control have been compared by Rydell et al. (1991, p. 618). Gains are defined as net rent reductions after deterioration minus loss in consumer surplus due to reduced housing and rent control fees levied on tenants. Losses are the decrease in revenue due to rent reductions and decline in housing stock plus landlords’ rent control fees, minus reduced maintenance expenditures. The paper makes use
918
Renting
5840
of the Marshallian consumer surplus concept and assumes a constant elasticity aggregate demand function with an 0.7 price elasticity. It concludes that the present value of landlord losses exceeds the present value of tenant gains, pointing to two reasons - (1) housing benefit losses to tenants due to quality declines outstrip landlords’ savings from under-maintenance and (2) burden of rent control fees. In order to estimate the overall effect of rent control, a rent capitalization framework can be used. In it, the expected future flow of revenues from rental properties determines their values, which, in turn, depend on supply and demand conditions and their modification by a changing legal environment (Hirsch, 1987b). An econometric study of nine middle-sized cities in Los Angeles Country, California estimated that rent control was associated with an annualized decline in property values of between 7.3 percent and 11.9 percent, ceteris paribus. The effect of rent control was also examined by Albon and Stafford (1990). The third model, that is, a perfectly competitive flow model with dynamic features and explicit quality differentiation, also has been applied to a second-generation rent control analysis. In its simple form it has dynamic features, allows for quality differentiation and articulates specific provisions of rent control laws. A more complicated model by Sweeney (1974b) has been discussed before. It has been expanded to allow for rent control leading to demolition of existing buildings, followed by construction of new ones (Arnott, Davidson and Pines, 1983).
7. Economic Analysis: Rent Control of Divided Ownership Property Rent control under divided asset ownership has especially extensive effects. Here are some of the reasons: improvements, whether condominiums or mobile homes, are of no residential use without the land on which they are placed. Thus, land and improvements that jointly provide residential shelter are complementary goods. The tenant-owned condominium apartment or mobile home has a negative cross-price elasticity of demand for the stream of housing services associated with the stream emanating from the land on which the improvement is placed. Consequently, a decrease in rent for fee simple condominium or mobile home park land should increase the demand for condominium apartments or mobile homes, thus causing their prices to rise. In short, capping rents of land on which condominiums or mobile homes are placed will lead to an increase in their value, and thereby yield tenants a windfall profit which accrues in addition to benefits from reduced rents. Owners of condominium apartments and mobile homes benefit from unearned appreciated values of their assets.
5840
Renting
919
A capitalization model can be used to analyze, for example, the effect of changes in the rents for mobile home pads on mobile home values. Since the supply of mobile homes is assumed to be inelastic at any point in time, in this model prices are basically demand determined in the short run. P = f(U,V,W,C)
(1)
where P is the sales price of a mobile home or its assessed valuation; U is the flow of housing services derived from the home; V is the price per constant quality unit of pad services; W is the price per constant quality unit of alternative housing, mainly apartments; and C is the cost of transporting and installing the mobile home (Hirsch, 1988). The price of a mobile home unit is assumed to be inversely related to (C), the costs of transporting the home and installing it in a park. A home already located in a mobile home park should be relatively more expensive than a comparable one in a showroom, since for the former the costs of transportation and installation are absent. Mobile home prices should be positively related to the flow of housing services (U). The amount of housing services is an increasing function of a number of physical characteristics of mobile home units, including size, quality, and amenities contained in the coach. It is likely that consumers of mobile homes have a negative cross-price elasticity of demand for home services with respect to services of pads (V). Consequently, any decrease in the rent for pads should increase the demand for homes, causing their prices to rise. Two econometric studies have applied the capitalization model to estimate the effect of rent control on the value of mobile homes. One covers the State of California in 1984-86, where about 39 percent of all mobile homes were in rent control communities. Sales prices were on average about $8,800 or 32 percent higher in communities which had imposed rent control on mobile home park rents (Hirsch and Hirsch, 1988). A second econometric study pertains to a particular mobile home park in Ocean City, California in 1987-92. It found that during 1986-92, sales prices of mobile homes under rent control were $3,531 higher than those in uncontrolled markets (Hirsch, 1995). When under divided asset ownership income from one asset is capped, the landlord’s profit will be negatively affected in at least three ways - first, the annual rent savings benefiting tenants are losses incurred by landlords. Secondly, the lower rent adjustment resulting from rent control will be capitalized into lower prices potential buyers are willing to pay for the land on which the condominium or mobile home is placed. Thirdly, there is the damaging effect of rent control on risks perceived by potential buyers of the land. Because of heightened risks, potential park buyers will use a higher interest rate which they apply to capitalized expected rents into land values. The higher the risk, the lower the prices they are willing to pay for the land.
920
Renting
5840
8. Distributional Effects The issue of equity has been argued from two different points of view. One view holds that in a search for equity, macroeconomic instruments must be relied upon. It recognizes that while some equity in housing consumption is important, governments can pursue an income distribution policy which can make housing policies inefficient and even inequitable (Aaron and von Furstenberg, 1971; Kain, 1974). The second view distinguishes between general and specific egalitarianism, that is, the general fairness of the income distribution, and concern that all citizens have a minimum amount of essential commodities, including housing (Tobin, 1970). Specific egalitarianism requires an interest in the level of housing services accruing to indigents, minorities and the aged, even if an optimal income distribution were to prevail. An evaluation of equity aspects of landlord-tenant laws clearly is based on the specific egalitarian view, without necessarily determining an optimal housing service level. Whenever a government caps rents, distributional effects are likely to occur. In the case of single, undivided property ownership, forcing a landlord to charge rents which are below the market-clearing rent will cause his property to decline in value. The capitalization formula presented earlier gives expression to such an outcome. Inequities tend to occur also among tenants. For example, sitting tenants tend to benefit from reduced rents. As a result, there exist fewer rental opportunities for new tenants, who may be requiring apartments because of changes in their place of work, family circumstances, student status, and so on. The longer tenants stay after rent control is enacted, the more they benefit. In particular, gains accrue to senior citizens since they tend to stay put. Landlords whose rents are controlled tend, whenever possible, to seek new tenants who are good credit risks. In the case of apartments, landlords prefer small families, whose members are not destructive, for example, young professionals. As a consequence, tenants who are poor, have young children and have large families are less likely to gain access to vacated apartments. The long-term effects of rent control of apartments in Santa Monica, CA are well-documented in a California Court of Appeal ruling (Santa Monica Beach Ltd. v. The Superior Court of Los Angeles County, 1996, pp. 2155-2156). The following ten year effects of rent control found the City’s stock of rental housing units declined by nearly 5 percent and ... low-income rental units [by] 12 percent ... notwithstanding that, during the same period, the rental housing supply and the number of low-income rental units increased in all comparable non-rent-controlled Southern California cities. The City also lost 285 ‘very low-income’ rental units, the largest ‘exodus of economically disadvantaged renters’ from any comparable Southern California city. At the same time, the
5840
Renting
921
City experienced a 37 percent increase in the proportion of households with very high incomes (while the proportion of very high-income households dropped by more than 8 percent in Los Angeles County as a whole). ... In addition, rental housing in Santa Monica has become ‘increasingly unavailable’ to young families, with the number of family households with children declining by 1,299, a 6 percent drop during a period when no comparable non-rent-controlled Southern California city lost young family households. ... female-headed households with children under 18 in Santa Monica fell by more than 27 [percent], despite an increase in such households in Los Angeles County as a whole. ... Santa Monica’s elderly population ... declined by 1.7 [percent] [while] ... the elderly population of Los Angeles County rose by more than 15 [percent] over the same decade. The distributional effects of controls under divided property ownership are even more pronounced and widespread. With the help of the capitalization model it can be shown that the more onerous and continuous the rent control and therefore the greater the difference between the controlled and market clearing rent - the greater the home sales price appreciation. In addition to these distributional effects on landlords and tenants, certain tenant classes will be particularly effected. For example, the heightened resale prices of homes placed in parks and the absence of park spaces hurts young families and transient workers especially. At the same time, sitting tenants, many advanced in age, are prime beneficiaries.
9. Constitutionality - Is There a Taking? In the United States, the constitutionality of rent control, particularly of mobile home parks, has been of concern to the court in recent years. The issue involves The Takings Clause of the Fifth Amendment which provides: ‘[N]or shall private property be taken for public use, without just compensation.’ This Clause generally requires just compensation where the government authorizes a physical occupation of property. But where the Government merely regulates the property’s use, compensation is required only if considerations such as the regulations’ purpose or the extent to which it deprives the owner of the property’s economic use suggests that the regulation has unfairly singled out the property owner who bears a burden that should be borne by the public as a whole. The US Supreme Court has last ruled in 1992 on the constitutionality of rent control of property under undivided ownership. However, in 1996 a California Court of Appeal in Santa Monica Beach Ltd. v. Superior Court of Los Angeles County (1996) ruled rent control of apartments in Santa Monica, California unconstitutional. The alleged reason is that Santa Monica’s rent
922
Renting
5840
control law has failed to mitigate the effects of a growing shortage of housing units by assisting the poor, minorities, students, young families and senior citizens and, to the contrary, it has made things worse’. Thus, it did not meet the ‘nexus test’, to be discussed below. The US Supreme Court has ruled on the constitutionality of rent control of property under divided ownership. Some of the characteristics of mobile home rent control may make it particularly vulnerable to running foul of the Takings Clause. Courts have employed several tests in determining whether a government action or regulation effects an unconstitutional taking of property without just compensation, typically focusing their inquiry upon: (1) the character of the government action; (2) whether the property owner has been denied his or her reasonable investment expectations; (3) the economic impact of the action on the claimants; (4) whether the action gives rise to a permanent, physical occupation of the claimant’s property; and (5) whether the action substantially advances legitimate state interests. Until 1992, courts evaluating challenges to mobile home rent control ordinances typically focused on the fourth of these factors. Should mobile home park owners be able to characterize the intrusion created by an ordinance as a permanent physical occupation, their challenges could succeed. The leading case, adopting the position that mobile home rent control constitutes a permanent physical occupation and is, therefore, a taking, is Hall v. City of Santa Barbara (1986). Owners of a mobile home park challenged a mobile home park rent control ordinance by arguing that the ordinance transferred to each tenant a possessory interest in the land on which their mobile home was located. They claimed that the transfer was reflected in the facts that the prices for mobile homes in the park had shot up dramatically after the ordinance was enacted, and that many homes in the park were selling for above their bluebook value. A federal Court of Appeal citing, Loretto v. Teleprompter Manhattan CATV Corp. (1982), for the proposition that a permanent physical occupation of property is a government action of such a unique character that it is a taking without regard to the other factors that a court might ordinarily examine, concluded that the ordinance interfered with the park owner’s property rights as described in Loretto and therefore constituted a physical taking. Specifically, the court found that the ordinance directs the landlord to give tenants a lease, a recognized estate in land, lasting indefinitely. Moreover, the landlords’ residual rights in the property are largely at the mercy of his tenants: he loses practically all right to decide who occupies the property, and on what terms. If a tenant moves, the tenant alone decides who will be his successor by selecting the buyer for his rental unit; the landlord has no say as to who will live on the property, now or in the future. Moreover, because of the way the ordinance is alleged to operate, the tenant is able to derive an economic benefit from the statutory leasehold by capturing
5840
Renting
923
the rent control premium when he sells his mobile home. In effect, the tenant is given an economic interest in the land that he can use, sell or give away at his pleasure; this interest (or its monetary equivalent) is the tenant’s to keep or use, whether or not he continues to be a tenant. Moreover, the court is concerned that the ordinance has ‘eviscerated’ the property rights of the park owners, stating: as the Santa Barbara ordinance is alleged to operate, landlords are left with the right to collect rents while tenants have practically all other rights in the property they occupy. As we read the Supreme Court’s pronouncements, this oversteps the boundaries of mere regulation and shades into permanent occupation of the property for which compensation is due. (Hall v. City of Santa Barbara, 1986, pp. 2, 4)
Some state courts, particularly in California, have rejected the Hall position for two reasons: (1) mobile home rent control merely regulates the relationship between landlords and tenants, much like ordinary (apartment) rent control, and does not cause a permanent physical occupation of park owners’ property, and (2) the original price of the regulated pad was artificially high (as a result of monopolistic aspects of the market) so that resulting recalibration of the prices of both goods may be seen as a restoration of the equilibrium a free market would have reached. Such a restoration is not a taking. While it did not adopt the California courts’ approach, the US Supreme Court specifically rejected the Hall approach in Yee v. City of Escondido (1992), holding that a mobile home rent control ordinance without a vacancy decontrol provision did not effect a physical taking. The Court held unanimously that a physical taking can occur only when the government requires that the landowner submit to a physical occupation of his or her land. Yet the Escondido ordinance did not impose such a requirement, because a park owner could choose to evict all tenants and change the use of his or her land. It merely established the terms of the landlord-tenant relationship for those landowners who chose to devote their property to mobile home parks. Even as it rejected the argument that the Escondido mobile home rent control ordinance effected a physical taking, the Yee Court may have opened the door to challenges to mobile home rent control ordinances as regulatory takings. The Court implicitly invited such challenges by noting that the plaintiffs’ argument was ‘perhaps within the scope of our regulatory taking cases’ (Yee, 1992, p. 165). The Court also stated that rent controls ‘are analyzed by engaging in the “essentially ad hoc, factual inquiries” necessary to determine whether a regulatory taking has occurred’ (Yee, 1992, p. 166). Also, commenting on the plaintiffs’ argument that the Escondido ordinance transferred wealth from landlords to incumbent mobile home owners, the Court stated that:
924
Renting
5840
This effect might have some bearing on whether the ordinance causes a regulatory taking, as it may shed some light on whether there is a sufficient nexus between the effect of the ordinance and the objectives it is supposed to advance. See Nolan v. California Coastal Commission, supra, at 834-835, 97 L.Ed.2d 677, 107 S.Ct. 3141. But it has nothing to do with whether the ordinance causes a physical taking. (Yee, 1992, p. 167)
Finally, in response to plaintiffs’ argument that the Escondido ordinance effected a physical taking because it deprived landlords of the ability to choose their incoming tenants, the Court stated: This effect may be relevant to a regulatory taking argument, as it may be one factor a reviewing court would wish to consider in determining whether an ordinance unjustly imposes a burden on petitioners that should ‘be compensated by the government, rather than remaining disproportionately concentrated on a few persons.’ [Citation]. But it does not convert regulation into the unwanted physical occupation of land. (Yee, 1992, p. 167)
With each of these statements, the Court hinted that a regulatory takings challenge might succeed where the physical takings challenge failed. As the Yee Court suggested with its citation of Nollan v. California Coastal Commission (1987), a challenge to a mobile home rent control ordinance as a regulatory taking could be based on the fifth of the five Takings Clause factors: whether the ordinance substantially advances a legitimate state interest. As is set forth in Nollan, this test requires more than just a rational basis for the state’s action. For the action to pass constitutional muster, there must also be an essential nexus between the stated ends of the state action and the means employed. An argument that mobile home rent control is a regulatory taking could be based on the absence of a substantial nexus between mobile home rent control and the objectives it is supposed to advance. For example, if the objective of rent control is to alleviate a housing shortage and economic theory suggests, and empirical evidence confirms, such an outcome to be unlikely, a regulatory taking would have occurred. In a more recent decision, the US Supreme Court appears to have added a further requirement to the nexus test. In Dolan v. City of Tigard (1994) the Court added a ‘rough proportionality requirement’. It held that the city’s exactions for flood control purposes and a pedestrian bicycle path were unconstitutional. Although both were legitimate public purposes, and there was a significant nexus between these ends and the exactions required by the city, the degree of the required exactions was disproportionate to the impact that the planned land development would have on problems addressed by the exactions. In short, it failed the ‘rough proportionality’ test. There is still the question to
5840
Renting
925
what extent Dolan is applicable beyond the context of exactions required for permit approval, for example, rent control.
C. Laws Complementing Rent Control Rent control laws, particularly those of the first generation, often create conditions that appear to require follow-up legislation. They include vacancy decontrol, just-cause eviction laws and anti-conversion and anti-demolition laws.
10. Vacancy Decontrol Laws All over the world rent controls, once imposed, have been politically difficult to lift. Obstacles to terminating rent control are particularly formidable after controlled rents have fallen substantially below market levels. In order to avoid this situation, some jurisdictions allow vacancy decontrol of the following major types: once the tenant vacates the premises, the landlord can charge higher rents, for example, whatever rent the market will bear and (1) the premises remain decontrolled or (2) rent control is reconstituted at the higher rent. Some jurisdictions prescribe by how much rents can increase once premises have been vacated. Particularly the first type of decontrol would allow market forces to correct the disequilibrium created by rent control. The result would be particularly favorable under divided property ownership, for example, when the tenant sells the mobile home or condominium (Hirsch and Hirsch, 1988). Vacancy decontrol of mobile home parks, in particular, raises the question of who gains and who loses. While the unearned windfall profits of sitting tenants will clearly be reduced, the effect on new tenants requires analysis, specifically whether potential mobile home buyers will be better off with or without decontrol. Using a simple supply-demand housing stock model, controls can be shown to limit quantity supplied. With rent control, the supply curve moves up and prices increase. With vacancy decontrol, the supply curve shifts down. If vacancy decontrol results in an increased quantity, then the price will necessarily fall. While new purchasers clearly benefit in terms of lower initial prices, they are worse off due to pad rents starting at a higher level. This will lower the demand curve for mobile homes, but it would be hard to imagine a shift that lowered it enough to get a new equilibrium at a lower number of units. Sitting mobile home owners will generally be worse off due to the change. With permanent controls, they are free to sell the future rights to the controlled land rents, but lose this option with vacancy decontrol. They lose by
926
Renting
5840
the price decrease if they sell and by a lesser amount if they stay. For those planning to stay indefinitely, there is only a minor impact.
11. Just-Cause Eviction Laws In the presence of vacancy decontrol, landlords have a strong incentive to create circumstances conducive to tenants vacating their premises. To counteract these tendencies, jurisdictions often enact just-cause eviction laws, which enumerate the specific causes which allow eviction. Causes include among others, failure to pay rent, disorderly conduct, willful damage to premises, and so on (New Jersey Stat., 1974). Some states have attempted to apply such laws solely to senior citizens (California Assembly A.B.1202, 1974). The effect of a just-cause eviction law is to increase the security of tenancy. The demand function for apartments with just-cause eviction guarantees is higher, that is, further to the right, than that without such guarantees, ceteris paribus. Thus, the law by protecting tenants enhances their utility. But while just-cause eviction laws increase the welfare of tenants, they also impose costs on landlords. Specifically, such laws reduce landlords’ rights and thereby flexibility, and place greater risk upon them. Moreover, legal costs are likely to increase. As a consequence, the rental housing supply function shifts to the left in the presence of just-cause eviction laws, ceteris paribus. Depending on the relative shifts of the demand and supply functions, three different outcomes are possible. In the most likely case, the cost to the landlord of operating under a just-cause eviction law are higher than is the law’s value to tenants; the result can be fewer dwellings. In a second case, the cost to the landlord is smaller than the increased value to the tenant. The result usually will be more dwellings, however, at a higher rent. In a further case, law-induced benefit and cost increases are about equal with all parties left in the same welfare situation as before.
12. Anti-Conversion and Anti-Demolition Laws To protect tenants from landlords circumventing rent control laws, some jurisdictions have enacted anti-conversion and anti-demolition laws. The former prevent apartment house owners from converting properties into condominiums, cooperatives, or convalescence homes. While these laws protect tenants, they interfere with landlords’ rights to seek the most efficient and profitable use of their property. Thereby they can create inefficiencies as well as inequities, particulary when they prohibit ownership of residential rental property to go out of the housing business.
5840
Renting
927
D. Habitability Laws Habitability laws (or housing codes) compel landlords to make sure that a rental meets minimum standards of habitability, that is, is not substandard housing.
13. Legal Analysis Laws regulating landlord-tenant relations historically favored landlords over tenants. Specifically, the doctrine of caveat emptor was applied to relieve landlords of responsibility for warranting that a building rented for residential purposes was fit for that purpose at the inception of the tenancy. Landlords had no responsibility for a building to remain habitable during the term of tenancy. Repair of damage caused by ordinary wear and tear was considered the tenant’s responsibility. In 1826, the doctrine of constructive eviction was first recognized in the United States (Dyett v. Pendleton, 1826). Grounds for constructive eviction, which permitted the tenant to surrender possession and vacate premises, were the covenant of habitability and the covenant of quiet enjoyment. The covenant of habitability required the premises to be delivered in tenantable fit or suitable condition. Concerned that the only relief for tenants was to vacate the premises, some state statutes and court decisions in the post-World War II period modified the doctrine of constructive eviction. In so doing, the doctrine of caveat emptor was reinterpreted in relation to the rights and obligations of landlords and tenants. In light of the complexity of rental housing and the inequality of bargaining power in present-day society, a move towards the doctrine of caveat venditor occurred. As a result, an implied warranty of habitability in urban rental leases evolved (Markovits, 1976; Schwallie, 1990). In the mid-1970s two parallel developments occurred in the United Kingdom and the United States. In 1975 the Law Commission (Law Com. No. 67) handed to the Lord High Chancellor its proposed Codification of the Law of Landlord and Tenant. He in turn laid this Report on Obligations of Landlords and Tenants before Parliament Law Commissioners (1975). The Report proposes inter alia that particular obligations of landlords and tenants be divided into two classes - mandatory obligations that cannot be varied or excluded, and variable obligations that can be varied or excluded by agreement of the parties. The important mandatory obligations included the tenant’s right to exclusive possession of the premises and their quiet enjoyment; the tenant’s mandatory obligation was to pay rent, to protect the premises and to disclose his identity; as well as the landlord’s obligations to disclose his identity. The Law Commission also recommended that tenancy for a term of less than seven years be governed by an overriding covenant obliging the landlord
928
Renting
5840
to repair the structure and interior of a dwelling. In tenancies of a furnished dwelling for a term not exceeding 20 years there should be an implied, but variable, covenant by the landlord to keep the entirety of the premises in repair. In tenancies over 20 years and in the absence of expressed agreement, the entire responsibility for repairs of the premises should be imposed on the tenant. In 1976, the American Law Institute adopted Restatement of the Law: Property 2d - Landlord and Tenant (American Law Institute, 1976). According to the document’s section on habitability, a court could hold that a landlord had breached a covenant of habitability even though he had an agreement with a tenant on a month-to-month basis that clearly indicated that both landlord and tenant were fully aware of housing code violation. Remedies available to tenant include rescission, damages, rent abatement and rent withholding. Moreover, tenants are protected against retaliatory eviction. The United Kingdom has various laws providing for compulsory improvements and repair. For example, the Housing Act of 1974 in Part VIII provides powers to compel landlords to provide a bathroom and other standard amenities on request from a tenant (Haden, 1978). This requirement, which had existed since 1964, was intended by the 1974 Act to include repairs associated with the provision of standard amenities, and also to permit local authorities to act without a formal request from a tenant. In response to representation from a tenant, local authorities inform the owner and then inspect the premises and finally prepare a schedule of work and an estimate of costs. Under certain circumstances steps are initiated by the local authority as a result of house-to-house inspection. At any time within six weeks, the owner may appeal to the county court on the ground that the notice is invalid, for example that the expense involved is unreasonable or that the standard of repairs required is unreasonable in relation to the age, character and locality of the house. Once the notice has become operative, the owner has a further six months to decide whether or not to serve a purchase notice on the local authority. If no action of any kind has been taken by the owner on the expiration of the six month period, the local authority may then serve a formal reminder asking whether the owner intends to carry out the work. Should this not produce a satisfactory response, the local authority may then serve further notice stating that it intends to carry out the work in default and, after a further 21 days, may do so. Alternatively, it may wait until the full 12 months have expired and then act in default, though it must still give the owner 21 days notice of its intention to do so. In either instance, the cost of the work may then be recovered from the owner, subject to further provision of an appeal against the amount claimed. Procedures for compelling owners to carry out repairs on their property have been successfully instituted under the Public Health Act of 1936 and 1961. Large authorities are reported to issue hundreds or thousands of formal and informal notices per year under these statutes, compared to tens or hundreds
5840
Renting
929
under the Housing Act. Compulsory repair under the Public Health Act requires a finding of a statutory nuisance. As such it must either be prejudicial to the health of an occupier of the house in question, or a nuisance that is a danger or an annoyance to adjoining occupiers or other people in the area. It appears that the Public Health Act has been mainly used to require owners to remedy relatively inexpensive defects. By means of housing codes, many large American cities have shifted to the landlord the responsibility for repairing leased premises and maintaining them in habitable condition. Toward this end in the United States, for example, three remedies were developed - repair-and-deduct, rent withholding and receivership, with the first two often supplemented by retaliatory eviction laws, designed to protect tenants from eviction by former landlords for complaining about housing code violations. The implied warranty of habitability has been used as a defense in action of eviction, if the tenant is able to show that a ‘substantial’ violation of the housing code existed during the period rent was withheld. In addition, the tenant may take affirmative action against the landlord for breach of contract, though remaining liable for the reasonable value of the use of the premises. Of the three remedies listed, receivership is potentially the most costly to the landlord. It results in a complete stoppage of rental income to him, since all tenants in the building, not only aggrieved ones, pay rents into escrow. Moreover, the landlord loses control over his building altogether. Instead, control is temporarily transferred to a receiver, who may be enthusiastic about fixing up the building, possibly even above minimum standards established by housing codes. The repair decisions are thus made without due consideration of their potential profitability. Finally, contrary to most repair-and-deduct and withholding actions, receivership is usually initiated by government, which has vast resources behind it. It must be remembered that these laws were designed to protect tenants in view of their unequal bargaining power as well as their inability to effectively inspect a dwelling in the light of its structural and technological complexity. The unequal bargaining power issue affects mainly poor tenants and, in particular, members of minority groups. The great complexity of today’s rental housing is of concern to all tenants, though the rich can quite readily cope with complexity. In response to both conditions, courts have extended warranties of habitability to leases of rental housing. Concerning inequality in bargaining power, Judge Skelly Wright has argued in Javins v. First National Realty Corporation (1970, p. 1071) The inequality in bargaining power between landlord and tenant has been well documented. Tenants have very little leverage to enforce demands for better housing. Various impediments to competition in the rental housing market, such as
930
Renting
5840
racial and class discrimination and standardized form leases, mean that landlords place tenants in a take it or leave it situation. The increasingly severe shortage of adequate housing further increases the landlord’s bargaining power and escalates the need for maintaining and improving the existing stock. Finally, the findings by various studies of the social impact of bad housing has led to the realization that poor housing is detrimental to the whole society, not merely to the unlucky ones who must suffer the daily indignity of living in a slum.
In connection with the complexity of today’s dwellings which affects everybody, including the richest tenants, Judge Skelley Wright has stated in Javins v. First National Realty Corporation (1970, p. 1073): the increasing complexity of today’s dwellings renders them much more difficult to repair than the structures of earlier times. In a multiple dwelling repair may require access to equipment and areas in the control of the landlord. Low and middle income tenants, even if they were interested in making repairs, would be unable to obtain any financing for major repairs since they have no long-term interest in the property. ... The tenant must rely upon the skill and bona fides of his landlord at least as much as a car buyer must rely upon the car manufacturer. In dealing with major problems, such as heating, plumbing, electrical or structural defects, the tenant’s position corresponds precisely with the ‘ordinary consumer’ who cannot be expected to have the knowledge or capacity or even the opportunity to make adequate inspection of mechanical instrumentalities, like automobiles, and to decide for himself whether they are reasonably fit for the designed purposes.
14. Economic Analysis: Short-Term Welfare Effects By 1972 about half the states in the United States had a habitability law. Moreover, a number of local jurisdictions enacted such laws. An example is the City of Los Angeles with its Habitability Enforcement Program (Los Angeles City Ordinance 171074, 1996). While many legislators and judges are likely to agree that provision of habitable rental housing is a socially desirable goal, a crucial issue is whether enacting habitability laws is likely to have socially desirable effects, especially on indigent and minority tenants. The outcome depends to a large extent on whether landlords can pass on significant parts of their increased maintenance and repair costs to their tenants. In the early 1970s, this issue began to be researched, first by applying economic theory and later by carrying out econometric studies. Ackerman (1971, p. 1093) reasoned that ‘when code enforcement is seriously pursued, market forces will generally prevent landlords from passing on their increased
5840
Renting
931
costs through rent increases’. In opposition to this position, Komesar (1973, p. 475, 1187) argued that in many housing markets landlords were unlikely to be able to pass on their cost increases. An econometric study attempted to empirically estimate the effects of various habitability laws not only on cost but also on demand functions of rental housing (Hirsch, Hirsch and Margolis, 1975). In this manner an understanding of the welfare-effects of such laws became possible. Habitability laws have forced landlords to improve repair and maintenance of their dwellings and thereby improve the welfare of their tenants. It is clear that the cost to landlords increases in the presence of habitability laws. However, it is less clear on a priori grounds, whether and, if so, to what extent the well-being of tenants increases, let alone whether tenants’ welfare increases exceed landlords’ losses. One reason why tenants’ welfare may not increase relates to tenants’ preferences. There can be instances, admittedly not too many, where tenants prefer to live in substandard housing as long as their rent is commensurately low. Whether, on balance, the gains of tenants exceed the costs of landlords is affected by the relative importance of those tenants who are forced against their will to live in improved housing at higher cost. Some econometric studies have attempted to estimate the welfare effects of repair-and-deduct, rent-withholding, and receivership laws, respectively (Hirsch, Hirsch and Margolis, 1975). The econometric analysis uses hedonic price methods, and includes habitability laws among the explanatory variables in the rental housing demand and supply equations. The extent to which the demand and supply functions shift upward in the presence of a particular habitability law can be estimated, and so can the resulting change in consumers’ surplus. If such laws are enforced and lead to improved repair and maintenance, the tenants’ wellbeing will be enhanced and the demand function will shift upward. On the supply side, habitability laws can affect maintenance and repair decisions, and, as a result, they can increase landlords’ costs. In consequence, they can make the supply function shift upward. Welfare conclusions can be derived by comparing the magnitude of the vertical shifts of these demand and supply functions. Using a hedonic price approach, an econometric study found that, of the three types of habitability laws, in 1974-75 only receivership had a statistically significant effect on both the demanders and suppliers of low-cost rental housing in 34 large metropolitan areas with more than 1/4 of the United States population. Receivership laws were found to be associated with a statistically significant increase in rental expenditures incurred by indigent tenants, which, however, was not matched by benefits. Costs exceeded benefits by a factor of three and the consumer’s surplus declined by more than 10 percent (Hirsch, 1981, p. 272). Thus, although habitability laws were designed to improve the welfare of indigent tenants, in the sample studied they had failed to do so. Receivership laws may even have been counterproductive.
932
Renting
5840
An econometric analysis of black and aged indigent tenants, respectively, reveals that habitability laws affect them differently. For black indigents, again the vertical shift of the supply function related to a receivership law is more than three times that of the demand function and the difference again is statistically significant (Hirsch, 1983, p. 128). Yet, for aged indigents, the vertical shifts of the two functions are about of equal size. In short, for black indigents, receivership laws were counterproductive, while for aged indigents they were of no consequence. Why are habitability laws inconsequential or even counterproductive? One reason is that these regulations are not accompanied by an increase in the indigents’ purchasing power which should have permitted them to pay for improved housing. Without income transfers, habitability laws can be counterproductive. Schwallie (1990, p. 525) recently concluded that the implied warranty of habitability and habitability laws incorporating this warranty have often failed indigent tenants. The main reason is that ‘the warranty of habitability results in scarcer, more expensive housing for the poor. Moreover, the quality of low-rent housing is a consequence of inadequate demand due to the low incomes of renters...’. The effects of making the implied warranty of habitability compulsory on repairs, maintenance and safety and on equity have been discussed by Singer (1993, pp. 756-759).
15. Economic Analysis: Alternatives Consistent with the objectives of habitability laws, housing subsidy laws for rental housing meeting minimum standards have been enacted. When subsidies go directly to landlords, and only to those who meet minimum quality conditions, improved housing is assured. Moreover, the entire subsidy is then used for housing. In the United States, one such program is Sections 501 and 504 of the Housing and Urban Development Act of 1970, often referred to as a housing-allowance program. Under it, tenants who meet an income test are paid a rent subsidy as long as they do not live in substandard housing. The rent subsidy amounts to the difference between the rent payments and 25 percent of the tenant’s income. Such an earmarked subsidy is very different from a general welfare payment that can be used by recipients for whatever purpose they choose. Whenever the income elasticity of rental housing is smaller than one, and there exists evidence that this is the case for indigents, an earmarked subsidy is to be preferred (de Leeuw, 1971). As tenants receive such a rent subsidy, their housing demand function shifts to the right. Depending on the demand and supply elasticities and the nature of the demand function shift (that is, whether it is parallel or not), part, all, or none of the subsidy will be shifted
5840
Renting
933
to landlords in the form of rent changes.
16. Economic Analysis: Long-Term Welfare Effects Beyond short-run welfare effects of habitability laws, there exist also long-run effects, particularly in terms of housing stock deterioration. If such laws reduce dilapidation, upper income groups who by and large can assure themselves of habitable housing are little affected. The benefits to low and low-middle income groups are less clear. While the result is an increase in the supply of habitable rentals, their demand will also increase. There is some empirical evidence regarding the effectiveness of habitability laws in reducing substandard housing. An econometric study of the relation between habitability laws and two different measurements of dilapidation in the United States in 1960-75 produced the following results: among the different habitability laws receivership laws have the greatest effect on housing quality. In their presence, renter-occupied dilapidated and deteriorating housing units declined on average by 12.4 percent (Hirsch and Law, 1979). The law’s effect was even more pronounced if substandard housing is defined as housing lacking some or all plumbing facilities. By this measure, substandard housing declined by an average of 17.0 percent. It would be a mistake, however, to look upon a decline in substandard rental housing as an unmitigated gain. In fact, in the absence of substandard housing, options for indigent tenants are reduced. Some tenants are likely to end up in over-crowded standard units, or even homeless.
E. Laws Complementing Housing Codes Landlords may be tempted to evict tenants who invoke habitability laws. For such cases, anti-retaliatory eviction laws exist in some jurisdictions and they can be supplemented by anti-speedy eviction laws.
17. Anti-Retaliatory Eviction Laws Such laws, designed to protect tenants from being penalized by their landlords for complaining about housing code violations, can be looked upon as a means to assure tenants continued occupancy for a specified period. Already in the mid-1970s, about half the states in the US had such laws, usually with a 3-6 month rent freeze. Determination of the landlord’s motive is of critical importance.
934
Renting
5840
In terms of economic effects, anti-retaliatory eviction laws can be viewed as miniature, temporary rent control laws which preserve the existing rent status quo in the face of a changed buyer-seller relationship. The force of the rebuttable or conclusive presumption tends to deter landlords from raising rents for the statutory period, while operating and maintenance costs increase. The temporary and rather limited scope of retaliatory eviction laws is unlikely to cause many landlords to abandon their property. However, when the landlord feels legally ‘safe’ in raising rents, the increase may be larger than would have been the case otherwise.
18. Anti-Speedy Eviction Laws In the United States, for a long time the judicial process of ejecting a tenant was heavily burdened with procedural complexities and of slow pace. During the middle and end of the nineteenth century, legislation was enacted to provide a more efficient remedy through the institution of special summary proceedings for landlords seeking to evict tenants. The new proceedings were to prevent landlords from taking the law into their own hands through self-help. In the recent past, laws to rein in the use of summary proceedings and self-help have been enacted. Under a summary eviction law procedure, a basic pattern followed in most states is that upon a judgment for the landlord, in the absence of an appeal, a writ of restitution will be issued. Then, after a short period, the sheriff will execute the writ by evicting the tenant. However, in some states a concern for the wellbeing of the tenant and a desire to mitigate the harshness of an eviction has led to the adoption of legislation which permits a court to delay the enforcement of the writ of restitution. The major mitigating circumstance is that the tenant cannot find alternative housing. In many states, the courts recognize some variation of the common law right to self-help by landlords. The minimal conditions are a clear right to possession by the landlord without use of unreasonable force in retaking possession. Generally, peaceable entry in the absence of the tenant will be recognized as a legitimate exercise of the landlord’s authority. However, an increasing number of states have abrogated this common law right to self-help. They have recognized the existence of a tort claim by the tenant against the landlord who enters to retake the premises, even with reasonable force. One group of states permits a tenant a tort cause of action against the landlord for removal of the tenant without resort to judicial process, if the removal is against the will of the tenant. A second group expressly bars any use of self-held by the landlord, permitting the tenant a cause of action for the mere act of entry by the landlord in an attempt to remove the tenant. An example is
5840
Renting
935
California (Jordan v. Talbot, 1961). Analysis of the economic effects of anti-speedy eviction laws can be similar to that of habitability laws. Both types of speedy eviction impose burdens on tenants while benefiting landlords; laws modifying or negating them should result in upward shifts of the rental housing demand and supply functions. If the vertical shift of the demand function in the presence of anti-speedy eviction laws exceeds that of the supply function, and the difference is statistically significant, welfare is enhanced, and vice versa. An econometric study of black indigent tenants indicates that laws reining in landlords’ use of self-help measures may be socially desirable (Hirsch, 1983).
F. Anti-discrimination Laws Housing discrimination is said to exist when members of one or more groups, commonly defined by race, gender, age, religion, or family status, are denied housing that is available to other groups, regardless of formal qualifications. Not only does discrimination violate concepts of fairness, but it can also result in many social and economic side effects.
19. Racial Discrimination: Legal Analysis Countries have enacted a variety of laws to combat housing discrimination. Discrimination on the basis of race has played a major role in the history of the United States. A housing discrimination survey of 25 large metropolitan areas with central city populations in excess of 100,000 and where at least 12 and 7 percent of the population was black or Hispanic, respectively (Turner, 1991, pp. 3-17) produced the following findings. In the United States in 1989 black and Hispanic renters faced a 39 and 36 percent probability, respectively, of being denied information about housing availability, and a 17 and 16 percent probability, respectively, of being told that the advertised unit is no longer available even though it was available to comparable whites. For blacks and Hispanics the index of unfavorable treatment in completing the renting transaction was 44 and 42 percent, respectively. Since the end of the Civil War in the United States, a number of affirmative steps have been taken to combat discrimination. In terms of housing activities, Section 1982 of the Civil Rights Act of 1866 together with its interpretation by the US Supreme Court in Jones v. Alfred H. Mayer Co. (1968) was first. Next came the Fair Housing Act of 1968 and Fair Housing Amendments Act of 1988.
936
Renting
5840
For housing, one of the most important acts is that of 1968 which is often referred to as the ‘Fair Housing Act’. It prohibits discrimination based on race, color, religion, sex, and national origin in the sale or rental of most housing. While it covers a host of activities related to real estate and housing, it includes real estate brokers, apartment owners and extends to federally owned and operated dwellings and dwellings provided by federally insured loans and grants. Title VIII prohibits such discriminatory activities as refusal to rent a dwelling; terms, conditions, or privileges of renting dwellings; indicating preferences or limitations in advertising; and so on.
20. Racial Discrimination: Economic Analysis Racial housing discrimination appears to exist in many countries with racially diverse populations (Page, 1995). In many Western countries, especially the United States, such discrimination has been on the decline. Economists have been interested in the reasons responsible for housing discrimination and how anti-discrimination laws affect them, and welfare effects of anti-discrimination laws. A number of theories have been advanced to explain the existence of rental housing discrimination and the resulting segregation by race. They include the aversion theory (Muth, 1970), racial prejudice theory (Becker, 1957; Bailey, 1959), and amenity theory (Yinger, 1976). Effects of race discrimination which have been explored include segregation, employment opportunities, crime, drug use, homelessness, and so on (Sander, 1988). Laws prohibiting racial discrimination in rental housing impose on landlords costs which often can be sufficient to persuade them not to engage in this practice. If this is the case, these laws can do more than merely contribute to fairness. Since racial housing discrimination is inefficient, as it restricts the housing choices of minority families and their efficient access to housing, employment, and educational opportunities, these laws also enhance efficiency.
21. Age Discrimination: Legal Analysis In the United States until recently little attention was paid to housing discrimination of age groups. Even as late as 1971, the US Supreme Court in Graham v. Richardson (1971) included among ‘suspect’ categories requiring strict scrutiny only race, national origin and alienage. Recently, state legislatures and courts, as well as local governments, have shown concern about housing discrimination against families with children. By 1981 nine states and the District of Columbia had enacted laws dealing with age discrimination in
5840
Renting
937
housing, and many courts began to interpret discrimination laws to cover age. For example, the California Supreme Court, in Marina Point, Ltd. v. Wolfson (1982) interpreted the California Civil Rights Act as preventing housing discrimination against children. The court also found that the strongest basis for this position rested upon California’s Unruh Civil Rights Act (1982) which provides that ‘[a]ll persons ... are entitled to ... full and equal accommodations in all business establishments’. California courts have interpreted the phrase ‘business establishments’ to include housing. Comprehensive federal legislation only arrived with enactment of the Fair Housing Amendments Act of 1988. It prohibits landlords to refuse to rent or show a house or apartment to a family with children younger than 18, or to require such a family to pay higher rent, impose restrictions or create unfair barriers not required of someone without children. However, under some circumstances, families with children can be excluded, for example, in ‘housing for older persons’. There are two classes of such housing: (1) ‘62 or over housing’, if all tenants in the housing complex are 62 years or older, and (2) ‘55 or over housing’, if at least 80 percent of all units in the complex have at least one occupant 55 years or older and there exist significant facilities and services to meet the needs of older people. Major concerns have been voiced concerning the facilities and services requirement of ‘55 or over housing’, mainly its vagueness (California Senate Select Committee on Mobile Homes, 1989). Fear has been expressed about the potential for litigation and cost of providing appropriate facilities and services for senior citizens, particularly since approximately 60 percent of the more than 5,000 mobile home parks in California in 1988 had adult-only restrictions (California Senate ..., 1989, p. 13). Thus, age discrimination laws relating to housing have been directed mainly at tenants with children and at senior citizens. The interests of these two classes of tenants can be in serious conflict. Senior citizens favor a tranquil life which often becomes difficult with young children as close neighbors. Thus, some mobile home parks are dedicated to senior citizens. Young families, like all families, want to be free to live wherever they choose. Arguments in opposition to anti-age discrimination laws were advanced, for example, in Flowers v. John Burham & Co (1971) where a California appellate court determined that, because of children’s ‘independence, mischievousness, boisterousness and rowdyism’, age discrimination within housing was not arbitrary discrimination. Also, the dissent in Marina Point Ltd. v. Wolfson (1982) argued that regulations regarding children are reasonable and rationally related to the services performed by the landlord when it has been determined that the apartment complex has been constructed for all-adult housing and its facilities are ill-adapted for use by children. Thus, landlords are faced with two costs associated with the Wolfson decision: Not only will landlords be
938
Renting
5840
prohibited to choose tenants on the basis of whether or not they have children, but they will also be forced to incur expenses to alter their premises to accommodate children. Arguments in favor of such laws include the serious impact on family stability as well as a deep psychological effect on children. Moreover, since many minority families have many children, child discrimination might be disguised racial discrimination and no doubt contributes to such discrimination.
22. Age Discrimination: Economic Analysis The conflict that can arise when children and senior citizens are housed in great proximity can be looked upon as an externality problem. In the abstract, price discrimination can help solve this conflict. Depending on each market’s demand, either families with children or senior citizens would be forced to pay higher rents, which in some instances could be prohibitive. Clearly such a resolution of the conflict is likely to run into political opposition. Furthermore, traditional economic theory tends to indicate that landlords in highly competitive housing markets will seldom, if ever, refuse to rent to families with children. In such a setting, a landlord could satisfy his distaste for families with children at the expense of a higher vacancy rate. Therefore, housing markets with age discrimination probably contain elements of monopoly. The landlord has some locational monopoly as well as some market power due to any unique characteristics his building may have. More important, exclusionary maximum density zoning laws and slow growth policies of local governments, combined with a growing demand for housing rentals, have tended to widen the gap between the quantity of dwellings supplied and those demanded. While rents should have adjusted to this situation and helped to close these gaps, in reality price adjustment in the housing market has been slow. This result is due to institutional features, as well as the existence of long-term leases. Microeconomic analysis of welfare effects can utilize a demand and supply housing stock model. Since children impose costs on landlords, for example, for heightened repair and maintenance, the supply curve shifts upward as the number of children increases. With children affecting negatively the utility of some tenants, their demand function will shift downward. The welfare effect of such laws depends on the relative importance of tenants who enjoy children in their building compared to those who are ill-affected and if so by how much.
5840
Renting
939
G. Policy Implications 23. Policy Implications Many countries have a host of landlord-tenant laws and there exists an extensive legal, economic and law and economics literature on the subject. By far the greatest interest has been shown in rent control. Until recently virtually all appraisals of its effects on society were negative, perhaps for two reasons economists’ misgivings about any form of price control and excessive focus on first generation, hard rent controls analyzed by perfectly competitive, static economic housing models. A few voices have recently been heard claiming that analyses of second generation controls which recognize the imperfection of housing markets are much less conclusive. Arnott (1995, p. 118) concludes, ‘the case against second-generation rent control is so weak that economists should at least soften their opposition to them’. However, Arnott concedes that ‘[E]ven if the optimal rent control package would be beneficial, the actual ... package thrown up by the political process may be harmful’ (p. 109). Habitability laws are also common to many countries, although in only a few instances have their welfare implications been subjected to careful economic analysis. Some deductive and one econometric study in the United States raise serious doubts about their desirability. Anti-discrimination laws have also become common all over the world as society is seeking to free itself from race and age discrimination in rental housing. While society has good reason to oppose housing discrimination, and anti-race discrimination laws tend to be socially desirable, the efficacy of anti-age discrimination laws is less clear. The reason is that both young and old families have valid claims. The former lay claim to their right to live wherever they want, and the latter to the quiet enjoyment of their homes and surroundings. Additionally, and perhaps most importantly, law and economics should not look at the various laws in isolation. All too often jurisdictions have enacted a number of laws, for example, rent control laws with anti-conversion and anti-demolition provisions together with habitability laws. The former prevent landlords from using their best judgment in deciding on rent levels and on the best use of their property, thereby reducing their investment’s profitability and their ability to preserve housing quality. Yet, habitability laws compel them to provide tenants with habitable housing. In the extreme case, thus, landlords find themselves between a rock and a hard place. In conclusion, this review of renting confirms the judgement of Williamson (1996) that law and economics is a success story. This assessment is clearly correct in so far as Renting is concerned. Contributions to tools of economic analysis, legal thought and public policy have had a major impact and proved
940
Renting
5840
valuable.
Bibliography on Renting (5840) Aaron, Henry F. and von Furstenberg, George M. (1971), ‘The Inefficiency of Transfer in Kind : The Case of Housing Assistance’, 9 Western Economic Journal, 184-191. Ackerman, Bruce A. (1971), ‘Regulating Slum Housing Markets on Behalf of the Poor: Of Housing Codes, Housing Subsidies and Income Redistribution Policy’, 80 Yale Law Journal, 1093-1197. Albon, Robert P. (1978), ‘Rent Control, a Costly Redistributive Device? the Case of Canberra’, 54 Economic Record, 303-313. Albon, Robert P. (1979), ‘The Value of Tenancies Due to Rent Control in Post War New South Wales’, 18 Australian Economic Papers, 222-228. Albon, Robert P. (ed.) (1980), Rent Control Costs and Consequences. Essays on the History, and the Economic and Social Consequences of Rent Control in Australia and Overseas, St. Leonards, Center for Independent Studies. Albon, Robert P. (1982), ‘Lawyers and the Rental Market for Housing: a Critical Appraisal or A Conversation Between Two Academics in a Hotel Bar’, in Cranston, Ross and Schick, Anne (eds), Law and Economics, Canberra, Australian National University, 105-111. Albon, Robert P. and Stafford, David C. (1987), Rent Control, London, Croom Helm, 128p. Albon, Robert P. and Stafford, David C. (1990), ‘Rent Control and Housing Maintenance’, 27 Urban Studies, 233-240. Alston, Richard M., Kearl, J.R. and Vaughan, Michael B. (1992), ‘Is There a Consensus Among Economists in the 1990s?’, 82 American Economic Review, 203-209. Anas, Alex and Cho, Joong Rae (1988), ‘A Dynamic, Policy-Oriented Model of the Regulated Housing Market: The Swedish Prototype’, 18 Regional Science and Urban Economics, 201-231. Anas, Alex et al. (1987), The Economics of a Regulated Housing Market, Stockholm, Swedish Council for Building Research, 114 p. Appelbaum, R.P. and Gilderbloom, John I. (1990), ‘The Redistributional Impact of Modern Rent Control’, 22 Environment and Planning, 601-614. Arnault, E. Jane (1975), ‘Optimal Maintenance under Rent Control with Quality Constraints’, 3(2) American Real Estate and Urban Economics Association Journal, 67-82. Arnott, Richard J. (1979), Rent Controls and Housing Maintenance, mimeo, Queens University. Arnott, Richard J. (1987), ‘Economic Theory and Housing’, in Mills, Edwin S. (ed.), Handbook of Regional and Urban Economics, Vol. 2, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 959-988. Arnott, Richard J. (1989), ‘Housing Vacancies, Thin Markets, and Idiosyncratic Tastes’, 2 Journal of Real Estate Finance and Economics, 5-30. Arnott, Richard J. (1995), ‘Time for Revisionism on Rent Control?’, 9 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 99-120. Arnott, Richard J. and Johnston, Nigel (1981), Rent Control and Options for Decontrol in
5840
Renting
941
Ontario, Toronto, Ontario Economic Council. Arnott, Richard J. and Mintz, Jack M. (eds) (1987), Rent Control: The International Experience. Proceedings of a Conference Held at Queen’s University, 31 August-4 September 1987, Kingston, Queen’s University, John Deutsch Institute for the Study of Economic Policy, 176 p. Arnott, Richard J., Davidson, Russell and Pines, David (1983), ‘Housing Quality, Maintenance, and Rehabilitation’, 50 Review of Economic Studies, 467-494. Baar, Kenneth K. (1987), ‘Peacetime Municipal Rent Control Laws in the United States: Local Design Issues and Ideological Policy Debates’, in Van Vliet, William, et al. (eds), Housing and Neighborhoods: Theoretical and Empiric, London, Greenwood Press, 257-276. Baird, Charles W. (1980), Rent Control: The Perennial Folly, San Francisco, Cato Institute, 101 p. Bailey, Martin J. (1959), ‘Note on the Economics of Residential Zoning and Renewal’, 35 Land Economics, 288-290. Barnett, Lance C. (1979), Using Hedonic Indices to Measure Housing Quality, Santa Monica, Rand Corporation. Basu, Kaushik (1989), ‘Technological Stagnation, Tenurial Laws, and Adverse Selection’, 79 American Economic Review, 251-255. Becker, Gary (1957), The Economics of Discrimination, Chicago, Chicago University Press, 59 p. Berger, Curtis J. (1983), ‘Commentary on Redistribution of Income through Regulation in Housing’, 32 Emory Law Journal, 733-744. Bernhardt, Robin M. (1987), ‘A Misapplication of the Sherman Act to Rent Control: Fisher v. City of Berkeley’, 24 San Diego Law Review, 181-197. Block, Walter E. and Olson, Edgar (eds) (1981), Rent Control. Myths and Realities. International Evidence of the Efects of Rent Contol in Six Contries, Vancouver, Fraser Institute, 335 p. Börsch-Supan, Axel (1986), ‘On the West German Tenants’ Protection Legislation’, 142 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 379-404. Bull, Clive and Tedeshi, Piero (1989), ‘Optimal Probation for New Hires’, 145 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 627-642. California Senate Select Committee on Mobile Homes (1989), Hearings on Effect of 1988 Federal Fair Housing Amendments Act on Mobile Home Parks, Feb. 14, Sacramento, CA. Cheung, S.N.S. (1975), ‘Roofs or Stars: The Stated Intents and Actual Effects of a Rent Ordinance’, 8 Economic Inquiry, 1-21. Cheung, Steven N.S. (1979), ‘Rent Control and Housing Reconstruction: The Postwar Experience of Prewar Premises in Hong Kong’, 22 Journal of Law and Economics, 27-53. Cirace, John (1989), ‘Response: Housing Market Instability and Rent Stabilization’, 54 Brooklyn Law Review, 1275 ff. Clark, William A.V. and Heskin, Allan D. (1982), ‘The Impact of Rent Control on Tenure Discounts and Residential Mobility’, 58 Land Economics, 109-117. Coleman, David (1988), ‘Rent Control: The British Experience and Policy Response’, 1 Journal of Real Estate Finance and Economics, 233-255. DaSalvo, Joseph S. (1971), Reforming Rent Control in New York City: Analysis of Housing
942
Renting
5840
Expenditures and Market Rentals, Regional Science Association Papers and Proceedings, No. 27. Davy, M (1992), ‘A Farewell to Fair Rents’, 1992 Journal of Social Welfare and Family Law, 497-502. de Leeuw, F. (1971), ‘The Demand for Housing: A Review of Cross-Section Evidence’, 53 Review of Economics and Statistics, 1-10. Diamond, Peter (1984), ‘A Search-Theoretic Approach to the Microfoundations of Macroeconomics’, The Wicksell Lectures, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Downs, Anthony (1988), Residential Rent Controls: An Evaluation, Washington, Urban Land Institute. Emms, Peter (1990), Social Housing: A European Dilemma?, Occasional Paper, Bristol, School for Advanced Urban Studies. Epple, Dennis (1994), ‘Rent Control With Reputation: Theory and Evidence’, 24 Regional Science and Urban Economics. Epstein, Richard A. (1982), ‘Notice and Freedom of Contract in the Law of Servitudes’, 66 Southern California Law Review, 1353-1368. Epstein, Richard A. (1988), ‘Rent Control and the Theory of Efficient Regulation’, 54 Brooklyn Law Review, 741-774. Epstein, Richard A. (1989), ‘Rent Control Revisited: One Reply to Seven Critics’, 54 Brooklyn Law Review, 1281-1304. Fallis, George (1988), ‘Rent Control: The Citizen, the Market, and the State’, 1 Journal of Real Estate Finance and Economics, 309-320. Fallis, George and Smith, Lawrence B. (1985a), ‘Rent Control in Toronto: Tenant Rationing and Tenant Benefits’, 11 Canadian Public Policy, 543-550. Fallis, George and Smith, Lawrence B. (1985b), ‘Price Effects of Rent Control on Controlled and Uncontrolled Rental Housing in Toronto: A Hedonic Index Approach’, 18 Canadian Journal of Economics, 652-659. Fallis, George and Smith, Lawrence B. (1988), ‘Uncontrolled Prices in a Controlled Market: The Case of Rent Controls’, 78 American Economic Review, 193-200. Fischel, William A. (1991), ‘Exploring the Kozinski Paradox: Why is More Efficient Regulation a Taking of Property?’, 67(3) Chicago-Kent Law Review, 865-912. Fishback, Price V. (1992), ‘The Economics of Company Housing: Historical Perspectives from the Coal Fields’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 346-365. Flath, David (1980), ‘The Economics of Short-Term Leasing’, 18 Economic Inquiry, 247-259. Frankena, Mark W. (1975), ‘Alternative Models of Rent Control’, 12 Urban Studies, 303-308. Fraser Institute (1975), Rent Control: A Popular Paradox, Vancouver, BC, The Fraser Institute. Friedman, Milton and Stigler, George J. (1946), Roofs or Ceilings?, Irvington-on-Hudson, Foundation of Economic Education. Fu, Yuming (1993), Three Essays in Real Estate Economics, Ph.D. dissertation, University of British Columbia. Gilderbloom, John I. (1983), ‘The Impact of Moderate Rent Control in New Jersey: An Empirical Study of 26 Rent Controlled Cities’, 7 Journal of Urban Analysis, 135-154. Goetz, Charles J. (1984), ‘Wherefore the Landlord-Tenant Law ‘Revolution’? - Some Comments’, 69 Cornell Law Review, 592-603.
5840
Renting
943
Grossman, Sanford J. and Hart, Oliver D. (1986), ‘The Costs and Benefits of Ownership: A Theory of Vertical and Lateral Integration’, 94 Journal of Political Economy, 691-719. Grossman, Sanford J. and Linneman, Peter (1989), ‘Equity and Efficiency Aspects of Rent Control: An Empirical Study of New York City’, 26 Journal of Urban Economics, 54-74. Gyourko, Joseph, Peter (1989), ‘Equity and Efficiency Aspects of Rent Control: An Empirical Study of New York City’, 26(1) Linneman Journal of Urban Economics, 54-74. Haden, T. (1978), Compulsory Repair and Improvement, Oxford, Center for Socio-Legal Studies. Harle, Jakob S. (1986), ‘Challening Rent Control: Strategies for Attack’, 34 UCLA Law Review, 149-174. Harloe, Michael (1985), Private Rented Housing in the United States and Europe, London, Routledge. Heady, Earl (1947), ‘Economics of Farm Leasing’, 29 Journal of Farm Economics, 659-678. Hirsch, Werner Z. (1980), ‘Habitability Laws and the Welfare of Indigent Tenants’, 63 Review of Economics and Statistics, 263-274. Hirsch, Werner Z. (1981), ‘Landlord-Tenant Relations Law’, in Burrows, Paul and Veljanovski, Cento G. (eds), The Economic Approach to Law, London, Butterworths, 277-306. Hirsch, Werner Z. (1982), ‘Landlord-Tenant Relations Law’, in Burrows, P. and Veljanovski, C.G. (eds), The Economic Approach to Law, London, Butterworth, 290 p. Hirsch, Werner Z. (1983), ‘Effects of Habilability and Anti-Speedy Eviction Laws on Black and Aged Indigent Tenant Groups: An Economic Analysis’, 3 International Review of Law and Economics, 121-135. Hirsch, Werner Z. (1984), ‘Comment: From ‘Food for Thought’ to ‘Empirical Evidence’ About Consequences of Landlord-Tenant Laws’, 69 Cornell Law Review, 604 ff. Hirsch, Werner Z. (1987a), ‘Landlord-Tenant Laws and Indigent Black Tenants’, 10 Research in Law and Economics, 129-141. Hirsch, Werner Z. (1987b), Rental Housing Data Base, State of California Dept. of Real Estate. Hirsch, Werner Z. (1988), ‘An Inquiry into Effects of Mobile Home Park Rent Control’, 24 Journal of Urban Economics, 212-226. Hirsch, Werner Z. (1995), Effects of Controlling Rent Under Divided Property Ownership, Symposium on Native Hawaian Land Rights, Eminent Domain and Regulatory Takings, Honolulu, HI. Hirsch, Werner Z. and Law, Cheung Kwok (1979), ‘Habitability Laws and the Shrinkage of Substandard Rental Housing Stock’, 16 Urban Studies, 19-28. Hirsch, Werner Z., Hirsch, Joel G. and Margolis, S. (1975), ‘Regression Analysis of the Effects of Habitability Laws Upon Rent: An Empirical Observation on the Ackerman-Komesar Debate’, 63 California Law Review, 1095-1143. Hirsch, Werner Z. and Hirsch, Joel G. (1988), ‘Legal-Economic Analysis of Rent Controls in A Mobile Home Context: Placement Values and Vacancy Decontrol’, 35 UCLA Law Review, 399-466. Hohm, Charles F. (1983), ‘The Reaction of Landlords to Rent Control’, 11 American Real Estate and Urban Economics Association Journal, 504-520.
944
Renting
5840
Hubert, Franz (1990a), Tenure Security for Tenants, Working Paper, Berlin, Freie Universität, Oct. Hubert, Franz (1990b), Long-Term Rental Contracts, Working Paper, Berlin, Freie Universität, Aug. Igarashi, Masahiro and Arnott, Richard (1994), ‘Rent Control, Mismatch Costs, and Search Efficiency’, 24 Regional Science and Urban Economics. Jaffe, Austin J. (1989), ‘Concepts of Property, Theories of Housing, and the Choice of Housing Policy’, 4 Netherlands Journal of Housing and Environmental Research, 311-320. Jaffe, Austin J. (1995), ‘On the Role of Transaction Costs and Property Rights in Housing Markets’, Housing Studies. Jaffe, Austin J. and Berjum, H. (1989), ‘Landlord-Tenant Contracts in Sweden and the United States: A Test of Alternative Models of Housing’, 6 Scandinavian Housing and Planning Research, 67-81. Johnson, Alex M., Jr (1988), ‘Correctly Interpreting Long-Term Leases Pursuant to Modern Contract Law: Toward a Theory of Relational Leases’, 74 Virginia Law Review, 751-808. Johnson, George W. (1988), ‘Introduction: Is the United States Supreme Court Ready for the Question?’, 54 Brooklyn Law Review, 729-739. Johnson, M. Bruce (1983), ‘Commentary on Redistribution of Income through Regulation in Housing’, 32 Emory Law Journal, 761-766. Johnson, Omotunde E.G. (1972), ‘Economic Analysis: the Legal Framework and Land Tenure Systems’, 15 Journal of Law and Economics, 259-276. Kain, John F. (1974), ‘What should Housing Policy be?’, Journal of Finance, 683-698. Kain, John F. and Quigley, John M. (1970), ‘Measuring the Value of Housing Quality’, 65 Journal of the American Statistical Association, 532-548. Kaish, Stanley (1981), ‘What is “Just and Reasonable” in Rent Control? Why Historic Cost is More Rational than Current Value’, 40 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 129-137. Keating, W. Dennis (1983), Rent Control in California: Responding to the Housing Crisis, Berkeley, Institute of Governmental Studies, University of California Policy Seminar. Keating, W. Dennis (1987), ‘Landlord Self-Regulation: New York City’s Rent Stabilization System 1969-85', 31 Journal of Urban and Contemporary Law, 77-134. Kemeny, Jim (1995), From Public Housing to the Social Markets: Rental Policy Strategies in Comparative Perspective, London, Routledge. Kiefer, David (1980), ‘Housing Deterioration, Housing Codes and Rent Control’, 17 Urban Studies, 53-62. Kochanowski, Paul S. (1980), ‘The Rent Control Choice: Some Empirical Findings’,6 Policy Analysis, 171-186. Komesar, N.K. (1973), ‘Return to Slumville: A Critique of the Ackerman Analysis of Housing Code Enforcement and the Poor’, 82 Yale Law Journal, 1175-1193. Korngold, Gerald (1990), ‘Resolving the Flaws of Residential Servitudes and Owners Association: For Reformation Not Termination’, 66 Wisconsin Law Review, 513-535. Kristof, Frank S. (1975), ‘Rent Control within the Rental Housing Parameters of 1975', 3(3) American Real Estate and Urban Economics Association Journal, 47-60. Lee, R. (1992), ‘Rent-Control - The Economic Impact of Social Legislation’, 12 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 543 ff.
5840
Renting
945
Lett, Monica R. (1976a), Rent Control: Concepts, Realities, and Mechanisms, New Brunswick, NJ, Center for Urban Policy Research. Lett, Monica R. (1976b), ‘Rent Control: The Potential for Equity’, 4(1) American Real Estate and Urban Economics Association Journal, 57-81. Loikkanen, Heikki A. (1985), ‘On Availability Discrimination under Rent Control’, 87 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 500-5840. Lowry, Ira S. (ed.) (1970), Rental Housing in New York City, Vol. 1, Confronting the Crisis, Research Memo, New York, NY, RAND Institute, No. RM-6190-NYC. Luger, Michael I. (1986), ‘The Rent Control Paradox: Explanations and Prescriptions’, 16(3) Review of Regional Studies, 25-41. Malpezzi, Stephen (1993), ‘Can New York and Los Angeles Learn From Kumasi and Bangalore? Costs and Benefits of Rent Controls in Developing Countries’, 4 Housing Policy Debate, 589-626. Marcuse, Peter (1979), Rental Housing in the City of New York: Supply and Condition 1975-1978, New York, City of New York Dept. of Housing Preservation and Development. Markovits, Richard S. (1976), ‘The Distributive Impact, Allocative Efficiency, and Over-all Desirability of Ideal Housing Codes: Some Theoretical Clarifications’, 89 Harvard Law Review, 1815-1846. Marks, Denton (1983), ‘Public Choice and Rent Control’, 11(3) Atlantic Economic Journal, 63-69. Marks, Denton (1984a), ‘The Effect of Rent Control on the Price of Rental Housing: An Hedonic Approach’, 60 Land Economics, 81-94. Marks, Denton (1984b), ‘The Effects of Partial Coverage Rent Control on the Price and Quantity of Rental Housing’, 16 Journal of Urban Economics, 360-369. Marks, Denton (1986), ‘The Effect of Rent Control on the Price of Rental Housing: Reply’, 62 Land Economics, 106-109. Marks, Denton (1988), ‘More on Rent Control: A Response to Yang and Dennis, Public Choice and Rent Control’, 16(2) Atlantic Economic Journal, 78-79. Mengle, David L. (1983), Rent Control and Housing Quality: An Empirical Analysis of the Effect of Second Generation Rent Controls on the Quality of Rental Housing, Ph.D. dissertation, John M. Olin Center, Harvard Law School. Miron, J.R. (1990), ‘Security of Tenure, Costly Tenants and Rent Regulation’, 27 Urban Studies, 167-183. Moorhouse, John C. (1972), ‘Optimal Housing Maintenance Under Rent Control’, 39 Southern Economic Journal, 93-106. Moorhouse, John C. (1987), ‘Long-Term Rent Control and Tenant Subsidies’, 27 Quarterly Review of Economics and Business, 6-24. Muller, R. Andrew (1989), The Experience With Reng Regulation in Canada, Research Report, McMaster University, Program for Quantitative Studies in Economics and Population, No. 244. Muth, Richard P. (1970), ‘The Ghetto in the Local Housing Market’, in Crecine, John P. (ed.), Financing the Metropolis, Beverly Hills, Sage, 449 ff. Muth, Richard P. (1983), ‘Redistribution of Income through Regulation in Housing’, 32 Emory Law Journal, 691-720. Nguyen, Trien T. and Whalley, John (1986), ‘Equilibrium Under Price Controls With Endogenous Transactions Costs’, 39 Journal of Economic Theory, 290-300.
946
Renting
5840
O’Flaherty, Brendan (1993), Grates, Bus Terminals, and Shelters Around the World: The Economics of Homelessness in Six Cities, mimeo, Columbia University. Ogus, Anthony (1994), Regulation: Legal Form and Economic Theory, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 298-300. Olsen, Edgar (1988), ‘What do Economists Know About the Effect of Rent Control on Housing Maintenance?’, 1 Journal of Real Estate Finance and Economics, 295-307. Olsen, Edgar (1990), What is Known about the Effects of Rent Controls?, Consulting Report for U.S. Dept. of Housing and Urban Development, Contract Number, No. NA 90-7272. Olsen, Edgar O. (1972), ‘An Econometric Analysis of Rent Control’, 80 Journal of Political Economy, 1081-1100. Ontario Ministry of the Attorney General, Commission of Inquiry Into Residential Tenancies (1987), Report of the Commission of Inquiry Into Residential Tenancies, Toronto, Queens Printer for Ontario, Vol. II. Page, Marianne (1995), ‘Racial and Ethnic Discrimination in Urban Housing Markets: Evidence from a Recent Audit Study’, 38 Journal of Urban Economics, 183-206. Pena, Daniel and Ruiz Castillo, Javier (1984), ‘Distributional Aspects of Public Rental Housing and Rent Control Policies in Spain’, 15 Journal of Urban Economics, 350-370. Power, Ann (1993), Hovels to High Rise: State Housing in Europe Since 1850, London, Routledge. Priemus, Hugo (1981), ‘Rent and Subsidy Policy in the Netherlands During the Seventies’, 1 Urban Law and Policy, 299-355. Quigley, John H. (1979), ‘What have we learned about Urban Housing Markets?’, in Mieszkowski, Peter and Straszheim, Mahlon (eds), Current Issues in Urban Economics, Baltimore, Johns Hopkins University Press, 391-429. Quigley, John M. (1990), ‘Does Rent Control Cause Homelessness? Taking the Claim Seriously’, 9 Journal of Policy Analysis and Management, 89-93. Raymon, Neil (1983), ‘Price Ceilings in Competitive Markets with Variable Quality’, 22 Journal of Public Economics, 257-264. Roistacher, Elizabeth A. (1972), The Distribution of Tenant Benefits Under Rent Control, Ph.D. dissertation, University of Pennsylvania. Rosen, Sherwin (1974), ‘Hedonic Prices and Implicit Markets: Product Differentiation in Pure Competition’, 82 Journal of Political Economy, 34-55. Rydell et al. (1981), The Impact of Rent Control on the Los Angeles Housing Market, Santa Monica, CA, RAND Corporation, N-1747-LA. Rydell et al. (1991), ‘Analyzing Rent Control: The Case of Los Angeles’, 29 Economic Inquiry, 601-625. Sander, Richard H. (1988), ‘Individual Rights and Demographic Realities: The Problem of Fair Housing’, 82 Northwestern Law Review, 874-882. Santerre, Rexford E. (1986), ‘The Effect of Rent Control on the Price of Rental Housing: Comment’, 62 Land Economics, 104-105. Schwallie, Daniel P. (1990), ‘Note: The Implied Warranty of Habitability as a Mechanism for Redistributing Income: Good Goal, Bad Policy’, 40 Case Western Reserve Law Review, 525 ff. Shulman, David (1981), ‘Real Estate Valuation under Rent Control: The Case of Santa Monica’, 9(1) American Real Estate and Urban Economics Association Journal, 38-53. Siegan, Bernard H. (1983), ‘Commentary on Redistribution of Income through Regulation in Housing’, 32 Emory Law Journal, 721-731.
5840
Renting
947
Singer, Joseph (1993), Property Law, Boston, MA, Little Brown. Skelley, Christine (1992), Rent Control and Complete Contract Equilibria, mimeo. Smith, Lawrence B. and Tomlinson, P. (1981), ‘Rent Controls in Ontario: Roofs or Ceilings?’, 9 American Real Estate and Urban Economics Association Journal, 93-114. Smith, Lawrence B., Tomlinson, P., Rosen, Kenneth T. and Fallis, George (1988a), ‘Recent Developments in Economic Models of Housing Markets’, 26 Journal of Economic Literature, 29-64. Smith, Lawrence B., Tomlinson, P., Rosen, Kenneth T. and Fallis, George (1988b), ‘An Economic Assessment of Rent Controls: The Ontario Experience’, 1 Journal of Real Estate Finance and Economics, 217-231. Smith, Richard A. (1989), ‘The Effects of Local Fair Housing Ordinances on Housing Segregation’, 48 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 219-230. St. John, Michael (1996), ‘Inflation and Rent Control’, WMA Reporter, 27-32. Stake, Jeffrey E. (1988), ‘Toward an Economic Understanding of Touch and Concern’, Duke Law Journal, 925-974. Stegman, Michael (1988), Housing and Vacancy Report: New York City, 1987, New York (NY), City of New York Dept. of Housing Preservation and Development. Sternlieb, George (1976), Urban Housing Dilemma: The Dynamics of New York City’s Rent Controlled Housing, New Brunswick (NJ), Center for Urban Policy Research. Struyk, Raymond J. (1988), ‘The Distribution of Tenant Benefits from Rent Control in Urban Jordan’, 64 Land Economics, 125-134. Sweeney, James L. (1974a), ‘Quality, Commodity Hierarchies and Housing Markets’, 42 Econometrica, 147-167. Sweeney, James L. (1974b), ‘A Commodity Hierarchy Model of the Rental Housing Market’, 1 Journal of Urban Economics, 288-323. Symposium (1983), ‘Redistribution of Income Through Regulation in Housing’, 32 Emory Law Journal, 767-819. Symposium (1988), ‘Rent Control and the Theory of Efficient Regulation’, 54 Brooklyn Law Review, 729-739. Tobin, James (1970), ‘On Limiting the Domain of Inequality’, 13 Journal of Law and Economics, 263-277. Turner, Bengt (1988), ‘Economic and Political Aspects of Negotiated Rents in the Swedish Housing Market’, 1 Journal of Real Estate Finance and Economics, 257-276. Turner, Margery (1988), Rent Control and the Availability of Affordable Housing in the District of Columbia: A Delicate Balance, Report prepared for the District of Columbia’s Dept. of Consumer and Regulatory Affairs, Washington, DC, The Urban Institute. Turner, Margery (1991), Housing Discrimination Study - Synthesis, Washington, DC, U.S. Dept. of Housing and Urban Development. Vitaliano, Donald F. (1985), ‘The Short run Supply of Housing Services under Rent Control’, 22 Urban Studies, 535-542. Vitaliano, Donald F. (1986), ‘Measuring the Efficiency Cost of Rent Control’, 14(1) American Real Estate and Urban Economics Association Journal, 61-71. Weber, Shlomo and Weismeth, Hans (1987), ‘Contract Equilibrium in a Regulated Rental Housing Market’, 21 Journal of Urban Economics, 59-68. Weibull, Jürgen W. (1983), ‘A Dynamic Model of Trade Frictions and Disequilibrium in the Housing Market’, 85 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 373-392.
948
Renting
5840
Weitzman, Phillip (1985), ‘Economics and Rent Regulation: A Call for a New Perspective’, 13 New York University Review of Law & Social Change, 975-988. Werczberger, Elia (1988), ‘The Experience with Rent Control in Israel: From Rental Housing to Condominiums’, 1 Journal of Real Estate Finance and Economics, 277-293. Wheaton, William (1990), ‘Vacancy, Search, and Prices in a Housing Market Matching Model’, 98 Journal of Political Economy, 1270-1292. Williamson, Oliver E. (1996), Revisiting Legal Realism: The Law, Economics and Organizational Perspective, Working Paper, Center for the Study of Law and Society, Berkeley, No. 95-12, 3. Willis, Kenneth G., Malpezzi, Stephen and Tipple, A. Graham (1990), ‘An Econometric and Cultural Analysis of Rent Control in Kumasi, Ghana’, 27 Urban Studies, 241-257. X (1988), ‘Note: Reassessing Rent Control: Its Economic Impact in a Gentrifying Housing Market’, 101 Harvard Law Review, 1835-1855. Yang, Chin Wei and Dennis, Enid (1984), ‘Elasticities and Rent Control Revisited’, 12(4) Atlantic Economic Journal, 59-61. Yinger, John (1976), ‘Racial Prejudice and Racial Residential Segregation in an Urban Model’, 3 Journal of Urban Economics, 383-406.
Cases and Legislation Age Discrimination Act of 1975, 42 U.S.C. §§6101-6107 (1976 and Supp. II 1978). American Law Institute (1976), Restatement of the Law: Property 2d-Landlord and Tenant. Birkenfeld v. City of Berkeley (1976), 17 Cal. 3d at 169-172, 550 P.2d at 1029-1032 Cal. Rptr. Block v. Hirsch (1921), 256 U.S. , 135-156. California Assembly (1973-1974 Regular Session), A.B. 1202 Dolan v. City of Tigard (1994), 512 U.S. 129 L.Ed. 304, 317, 114, S.Ct. 2309. Dyett v. Pendleton (1826 N.Y.), 8 Cow, 727. Fair Housing Amendments Act of 1988, Pub.L. No. 100-430, 102 Stat. 1625. Fair Housing Act, 42 U.S.C. §3601-3631 (1976 and Supp. II 1978). Fair Housing Act of 1968, 42 U.S.C.A. §3601 et. seq. Flowers v. John Burham & Co. (1971), 21 Cal. App. 3d 700, 98 Cal. Rptr. 644. Graham v. Richardson (1971), 403 U.S. 365. Hall v. City of Santa Barbara (1986), United States Court of Appeals, Ninth Circuit, No. 85-5838, August. Housing and Urban Development Act of 1970, Pub. L. No. 91-609, §§501, 504, 84 Stat. at 1784 and 1786 (1970). Housing: The Government’s Proposals, 1987 (Cm. 214). Javins v. First National Realty Corporation (1970), 428 F2d 1071, DC Cir. Jones v. Alfred H. Mayer Co. (1968), 392 U.S. 409. Jordan v. Talbot (1961), 55 C2d 597,12 Cal. Reptr. 488,361 P.2d 20. Law Commissioners, Codification of the Law Landlord and Tenant (1975), Law Com. No. 67. Los Angeles, Cal. (1996), Ordinance 171074 (March 6). Loretto v. Teleprompter Manhattan CATV Corp. (1982), 458 U.S. 419, 734, Ed. 2d 868, 102 S.Ct. 3164.
5840
Renting
949
Marina Point Ltd. v. Wolfson (1982), 30 Cal. 3d 721, 640 P.2d 114. 180 Cal. Rptr. 446, cert. Denied, 1035 S.Ct. 129. New Jersey Stat. Ann. (West Supp. 1974) §2A. 18-53. Nolan v. California Coastal Commision (1987), 483 U.S. 825, 834-837, 974, Ed. 2d 677, 107 S.Ct. 3141. Palos Verdes Shores Mobile Estates, Ltd. v. City of Los Angeles (1983), 142 Cal. App. 3d 362, 190 Cal. Rptr. 866. Rent Act 1965, s. 27 (I): Rent Act 1977, s. 70(I). Santa Monica Beach Ltd. v. The Superior Court of Los Angeles County (1996), 42 Cal. App. 4th 1228. Title VIII of the Civil Rights Act of 1968, 42 U.S.C. §3601-3631. Unruh Civil Rights Act (1982), Cal. Civ. §Code 51 West. Yee v. City of Escondido (1992), 503 U.S. 519, 522-523.
5850 REGULATION OF BANKING AND FINANCIAL MARKETS Dirk Heremans Professor of Monetary Economics at the Center for Economic Studies, and of Law and Economics at the Law School of the Catholic University of Leuven © Copyright 1999 Dirk Heremans
Abstract The dynamic evolution of the financial system is stirring up the regulatory debate. Recent theoretical insights in the role of financial intermediaries and banks shed new light on the role of financial regulation. Information asymmetries, adverse selection and moral hazard problems help to explain the need for investors’ protection and the occurrence of systemic crises that may endanger financial stability. Lender of last resort interventions and deposit insurance are to be complemented by incentive compatible capital adequacy rules in an efficient corporate governance perspective. The balance between market and government is shifting, replacing structural by prudential measures, eventually moving towards worldwide regulation. JEL classification: 310, 311, 312, 314, 430, 619 Keywords: Regulation, Banking, Insurance, Financial Markets, Financial Crisis, Corporate Governance
1. Introduction Recently no longer irresponsible macroeconomic policy of governments but rather excessive risk taking by financial intermediaries is becoming the major factor explaining the occurrence of financial crises. Hence, it is the regulation of banking and financial markets that is becoming the major challenge for public authorities as due to increased competition the borders between financial institutions are fading, financial innovations are multiplying off balance sheet activities, and internationalization is rendering control by national authorities more and more difficult. According to an International Monetary Fund study by Lindgren, Garcia and Saal (1996), since 1980 about 133 IMF member countries have experienced significant banking sector problems of which 36 countries had to face real financial crises.
950
5850
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
951
The major goal of regulation in economic life in general, however, traditionally consists in protecting the (uninformed) consumers against a variety of market imperfections. Problems of market failures also apply to the financial sector and the banking system in particular. The goal of banking regulation and supervision is often explicitly stated as to prevent banks from assuming unacceptably high risks which may endanger the interests of creditors, that is, deposit holders and savers in general. Government intervention may also aim at the advancement of other policy objectives: that is, to encourage particular activities in the industrial, the agricultural sector or in the social field. In the financial sector the government intervenes in credit markets to subsidize or guarantee lending for industry, agriculture, housing and other activities regarded as beneficial to the economy. Often specialized financial intermediaries are sponsored by governments to make home mortgages accessible to borrowers or to grant cheap investment credits to particular sectors of the economy. It may be observed all over the world that compared to other sectors of the economy a much more elaborate system of regulatory interventions has been set up in the financial sector. Hence, the question arises what is specific to the financial sector in order to warrant such extensive regulation and supervision. First, it is held that special protection has to be provided to the consumer due to the fiduciary nature of most financial products and services. Being in essence future markets, financial markets are unavoidably characterized by risk and uncertainty, what is also reflected in financial assets as the intertemporal assets traded in these markets. Consumers have to be protected from excessive prices and opportunistic behavior by the suppliers of financial services. Second, money, a special commodity with vital transaction functions in the economy, is at the core of the financial system. As a consequence monetary and financial stability has become even the overriding goal of financial regulation. Specific concern for the stability of the financial sector is warranted due to external effects. Financial markets and institutions are much more interconnected and characterized by ‘herd behavior’ than is the case in other sectors of the economy. Bankruptcy of one institution may easily spill over to others and endanger the whole financial system. The elaborate financial regulating system that has resulted in the aftermath of the economic depression of the 1930s, which was attributed to a financial crisis, has recently been questioned for various reasons. First, the traditional public interest view of regulation has been challenged by the public choice approach. The latter view observes that in reality regulation often fails to serve the public interest. Regulators are ‘captured’ by the regulated firms through lobbying in order to protect the business interests, often at the expense of the consumer. In particular, firms have an interest in limiting competition by restricting entry into their markets through regulatory
952
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
5850
barriers. It is observed that the ‘capture theory’ applies even more to the financial sector, where unbridled competition is seen as a major threat to the primary goal of stability of the financial system. Hence, according to Van Cayseele (1992), the emphasis has been more on stability than on efficiency by limiting competition. As a result the financial sector more than other sectors of the economy has been hit by the deregulation wave. Second, the regulation debate has recently received renewed interest in the economic literature by new insights from developments in the field of information economics. Financial markets in particular are seen as imperfect by definition characterized by asymmetric information, agency problems and moral hazard. Markets are powerful coordination mechanisms, yet they do not operate perfectly and cannot do so. However, government intervention does not provide better coordination and therefore need not replace market mechanisms. Government policies in the first instance have to create a framework for satisfactory market operation, and only in the second instance do they have to prevent and limit the consequences of some negative aspects of the operation of the market mechanism. Hence, a delicate balance has to be struck between the discipline of the market and coordination by government actions. Moreover, the dynamic evolution of the financial system constantly presents new challenges to the regulatory debate. Government measures to protect the consumer such as deposit insurance coverage have in turn created new moral hazard problems. They diminish the incentives for markets to discipline the banks and induce excessive risk taking as has been documented recently, for example in the widespread Savings and Loans crises in the US. Hence, in order to complement market discipline a regulatory dialectic has developed in which deposit insurance has become a major modern driving force behind the supervision and regulation of banks. In this evolutionary process there are no definite nor universal recipes to be found and the balance between market and government may shift over time. Rather than discussing ad hoc regulatory policies, it is important to specify the general principles that have to determine the right balance between market and government coordination. Therefore before moving into specific regulatory issues such as regulatory instruments and regulating authorities, a more fundamental analysis of the role and the nature of the financial system is in order.
2. The Nature of the Financial System According to economic analysis financial markets by definition are imperfect. Financial intermediaries find there origin precisely in these market
5850
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
953
imperfections.They may provide a market solution to the market failures and in this respect may be an alternative for government intervention. First, more than other economic activities financial operations are concerned with the future, and hence are characterized by risk and uncertainty. The key services of the financial system in the process of allocating funds between savers and borrowers consist in trading risk and liquidity. As a consequence, expectations play a major role in the pricing of financial assets. However, given the often limited amount of information available price developments are difficult to predict. As new information becomes available market parties adjust suddenly and collectively (so-called herd behavior) their price expectations. Together with low transaction costs in financial markets, it explains the high volatility and inherent instability of financial markets. Second, asymmetric information problems arise when market parties have different information. Hence, one party may not have enough information about the other party to make accurate decisions. It certainly applies to financial markets where one party often has superior information about the risk being transacted than the other party, for example an investor knows more about the riskiness of his investment than the money lender. Asymmetric information hampers the well-functioning of markets. It creates problems of adverse selection before the transaction is entered into, and of moral hazard after the transaction has taken place. Adverse selection arises as due to incomplete information the lender cannot accurately distinguish good risk applicants from bad-risk applicants before making an investment. Thereby a so-called ‘lemon-premium’ will increase the loan rate, so that only risky projects will be funded. Moral hazard costs, incurred by the lender in verifying that borrowers are using their funds as intended, further raise the loan rate. In the process financial intermediaries arise as they specialize in information on borrowers and solve these asymmetric information problems. The key services provided by financial institutions then consist in collecting and communicating information on debtors and on financial assets. The principal-agent relationship of creditors with financial institutions, however, involves similar information problems. How can the lender (the principal) make sure that the agent (the financial intermediary) acts in his interest? For example, depositors lack information regarding the riskiness of the bank’s portfolio. Should these financial intermediaries which provide market solutions to market imperfections, in turn not be subject to government regulation and supervision? Third, financial markets and financial institutions tend to be more interdependent than is the case for other sectors of the economy. Events in one financial market or institution may have important external affects on the rest of the financial system and on the whole economy. Together with the important potential for ‘herd behavior’ it explains the occurrence of so-called system risks.
954
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
5850
Finally, at the heart of the financial system lies a special commodity: money. The proper functioning of money depends upon price stability. As there is a link between prices and money in circulation, there is a need to keep money creation under control. Money creation, however, is profitable, so that it may not be taken for granted that an unregulated money supply will lead to a sufficient stable price level. As money is created by the banking sector a special need for controlling these specialized intermediaries may arise.
3. Information Failures and the Need for Financial Regulation Mainly due to information-asymmetries financial markets do not operate perfectly. In reallocating funds between market parties an agency problem arises between the lender (principal) and the borrower (agent), since the latter has private information about the potential return and risk of his investment project. Hence, optimal debt contracts typically include extra costs, a so-called external finance premium, that are incurred. They consist of costs incurred in screening loan applicants and monitoring the behavior of borrowers and include a premium for credit risk. These are dead-weight costs associated with the agency problem and are more particularly due to problems of adverse selection and moral hazard as explained before. Solutions for these information failures may be provided by the market itself, mainly by financial intermediation, or may require government intervention. Instead of individual investors having to perform a variety of screening and monitoring functions that are complex and time-consuming, financial intermediaries arise. They specialize in these information functions and may benefit thereby from scale economics, reducing the cost of production of information, that is the external financing costs. As is argued by several authors, for example Dewatripont and Tirole (1994), in the exercise of these information functions there may be a ‘natural monopoly’ in that their duplication by several parties is technically wasteful. However, the main reason for the existence of financial intermediaries depends on their ability to overcome free rider problems in the production of information, due to problems of non-appropriability of information. Information has public good characteristics in that information is often non-rivalrous, meaning that one person’s use of information does not diminish its availability for others to use. Moreover, because the transmission of information has become so cheap, it may be expensive to exclude some people from this information. The non-excludability of people who do not pay for it, creates a free rider problem. It prevents the market from producing enough information to eliminate all the asymmetric information. The undersupply of
5850
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
955
information in the market may require regulatory intervention by the government to disclose information. In financial markets large numbers of savers have little incentive to devote resources to screen and monitor investors. Financial intermediaries on the contrary will have an incentive to invest in information and to act as delegated monitors for many individual savers who deposit their funds with the intermediary, if they can obtain extra profits from the production of information, as is argued by Hubbard (1996, p. 203). Banks play a special role as financial intermediaries in this respect by reallocating funds from small uninformed savers to small and medium-size investors, whose creditworthiness is often difficult to evaluate. Individual savers are faced with difficult information problems as the use of their funds involves a lot of ‘private’ information. When banks give private loans, instead of buying market paper, they invest in information on credit risks. According to Mishkin (1997), banks are able to profit from the information they produce and to avoid the free rider problems by primarily making private loans. These loans are not traded, so that other investors cannot gain a free ride on the intermediary’s screening and monitoring efforts by observing what the bank is doing and bid up the loan’s price to the point where the bank receives no compensation for its production of information. Hence, banks generally benefit from higher intermediation margins compared to external finance premiums in financial markets. By giving private loans banks are also able to better discipline the behavior of investors and to avoid risks of moral hazard. This monitoring function proves to be more difficult in case of market financing, for example by the emission of corporate bonds. These distinctions lie at the heart of the controversy between the so-called banking financing model, that is predominant in continental Europe, versus the market financing model of business investments in the Anglo-Saxon world. It may help to explain differences in choices made by banking legislation among countries. The role of markets and financial intermediaries in the provision of information implies that the need for government intervention is essentially of a complementary nature. First, in financial markets regulation is needed to the extent that no solutions for information failures are provided by financial intermediaries. This is the domain of financial market regulation. Second, financial intermediaries alleviate information problems, but their operation creates in turn similar information and monitoring problems. This has to be solved by regulation and supervision of financial institutions. The case for government interventions in the operation of financial markets mainly rests upon asymmetric information problems that create risks of fraud, negligence, incompetence, and so on. Financial services in this respect are seen as credence goods whose quality it is difficult to establish. However,
956
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
5850
information problems may be alleviated by private production and selling of information. For example, rating agencies screen and monitor the creditworthiness of bond issuers in the financial market. Because of the public good nature of information and the free rider problem linked to it, financial intermediaries are not able to solve completely these information problems. Additional public policy is needed therefore, in particular in retail markets. Hence, traditionally the main motive for regulatory intervention is found in the need to protect the consumer against information related failures. Timely and accurate information disclosure is needed to enable market participants to make prudent financial decisions, for example regulation requires lenders to provide borrowers a meaningful disclosure of credit terms. Information disclosure rules may also aim at ensuring equal treatment for all financial customers. Financial institutions on the one hand help to alleviate information problems in financial markets. On the other hand a substantial part of financial assets issued by financial institutions are information intensive. This applies in particular to banks where depositors are not informed about the quality and risk of the asset portfolio. Information asymmetries create problems of moral hazard as financial institutions may take actions that are not in the interest of investors, for example banks may have incentives to make high yielding but very risky loans. Moreover a free rider problem arises as large numbers of investors have little incentive to devote resources to the monitoring of financial institutions. In particular, bank debt is primarily held by small unsophisticated depositors who have little incentive to perform various monitoring functions. However, these costs of moral hazard may also be reduced and financial institutions be disciplined by the nature of the debt claims they issue. By issuing short-term debt claims as the banks do, their behavior will be disciplined by the threats that savers may withdraw their funds on short notice. If, however, such short-term debt claims are insured, as is the case for deposit insurance, moral hazard problems may even increase. Only uninsured creditors who cannot run, as is the case when banks issue a certain amount of subordinated debt, will have incentives to monitor risk taking by banks. Government regulation and supervision is needed to provide additional ways to reduce the costs of moral hazard to individual savers. These failures in market discipline can be best counteracted by requiring that financial information should be disclosed promptly and be accurate. This can also be achieved by increasing incentives for responsible performance for bankers and bank shareholders, for example by augmenting their stake in the bank by capital adequacy rules requiring to invest more of their own funds.
5850
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
957
4. Financial Stability and the Need for Regulation Stability is traditionally an important concern in the financial sector. The characteristics of the financial sector are such that individual problems may easily spill over and endanger the whole financial system. Hence, failures in the operation of the financial sector not only have consequences for individual investors and savers but stock market crashes, bank failures and other financial disasters may endanger the health of the whole economy. Financial operations are characterized by risk and uncertainty. In particular information problems arise as explained before. As a result financial decision making depends heavily upon expectations. It is also characterized by herd behavior. Market parties adjust suddenly and collectively their expectations leading to high volatility in financial markets. Moreover, compared to other sectors of the economy, financial markets are much more interdependent. This is witnessed by very tight interconnections in the interbank market. Events in one financial market or institution may then have important effects on the rest of the financial system. Failure in one market or institution may create a financial panic and end up in a systemic crisis. Due to ever increasing international capital mobility it may become a worldwide financial crisis. Banks specifically are faced with a two-sided asymmetric information problem. On the asset side borrowers may fail on their repayment obligations. Depositors, however, cannot observe these credit risks. The quality of the loan portfolio is private information acquired while evaluating and monitoring borrowers. On the liabilities side savers and depositors may withdraw their funds on short notice. Banks, however, cannot observe the true liquidity needs of depositors. This is private information. A true liquidity risk arises when depositors collectively decide to withdraw more funds than the bank has immediately available. It will force the bank to liquidate relatively illiquid assets probably at a loss. A liquidity crisis may then endanger also the solvability of the bank and eventually lead to bankruptcy. As Dewatripont and Tirole (1994) observe, the providers of funds are not able to assess the value of the bank’s underlying assets. As a result bad news, whether true or false, may provoke a withdrawal of funds. Moreover, as deposits are repaid in full on a first-come-first-served basis until the liquid assets are exhausted, depositors have an incentive to act quickly. A ‘bank run’ may occur when enough savers lose confidence in the soundness of a bank. Moreover, bad news about one bank can snowball and have a contagion effect on other banks. A bank failure could eventually trigger a signal on the solvency of other banks. Even if these banks are financially healthy the information about the quality of the loan portfolio underlying the deposits is private, so that depositors may also lose confidence and withdraw their funds.
958
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
5850
As is documented by Paroush (1988) domino effects lead to a widespread loss of confidence in the banking system and create a ‘financial panic’. Financial market failures and instability eventually leading to a systemic crisis not only affect individual savers and depositors, but the health of the whole economy. Public policy intervention then is not only a microeconomic question of protecting individual savers and investors, but becomes a macroeconomic issue. Government concern about the health of the financial system is mainly motivated by the negative macroeconomic externalities from bank failures and financial panics. These impair the ability of the financial markets and intermediaries to provide the key services of risk sharing, liquidity and information when faced with economic disturbances. Financial crises undermine the efficiency with which resources in the economy are allocated as, for example, companies have difficulty raising capital for investment and job creation. The collapse of financial institutions in general may have important costs of debt deflation on effective aggregate demand in the economy, as is extensively documented by Hubbard (1991). Because of the banks’ importance it is in particular important to maintain the health of the banking industry. The severity of the Great Depression of the 1930s is often linked to the breakdown of the banking system’s ability to provide financial services. As explained before, banks are very important in reducing information costs in the economy. Insolvency of banks is costly because information on borrowers is then lost. It hurts in particular the ability of less well known borrowers to obtain loans. Moreover, banks play an essential role in the payments system and in the creation of money. As argued by Mishkin (1997) bank failures could cause large and uncontrollable fluctuations in the quantity of money in circulation. The negative impact of banking problems on economic growth, the government budgets, the balance of payments and foreign exchange rates are further documented in an IMF study by Lindgren, Garcia and Saal (1996). Systemic risks are more difficult to deal with than the previous individual risks for depositors and savers. Of course government intervention aiming at the protection of depositors and investors by reducing information costs will also stabilize their behavior and reduce the danger of major financial instability. Also at the international level the timely dissemination of accurate financial information may be in order. The question arises whether additional government intervention may be necessary. This applies especially to ex post interventions when a financial crisis has occurred. Liquidity crisis may be overcome by monetary authorities acting as a lender of last resort and providing additional liquidity. However, this may lead in turn to a moral hazard problem. Financial institutions anticipating the bail-out possibility by monetary authorities may behave in a riskier way. Hence, the
5850
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
959
lender of last resort certainly does not have to intervene for financial problems that do not contain the danger of leading to a systems crisis. For an international financial crisis the question arises as to the need of an international lender of last resort. Finally, ensuring a stable payments system has been a principal concern of public policy. Therefore financial regulation in a wider perspective contains also a whole framework for controlling the volume of money in circulation, that is a whole set of monetary policy instruments. Normally a stable and sound financial system is a condition for an efficient monetary policy. Therefore in financial law specific regulations determine for instance which institutions can offer deposit accounts. However, in the short run conflicts may also arise between money supply control and the provision of additional liquidity under the lender of last resort function.
5. Regulatory Instruments To maintain the health of the financial system governments have developed a whole range of regulatory instruments. They have placed different degrees of emphasis upon the various objectives at different times and have used different regulatory tools to achieve them. The different regulatory and policy measures are classified in Table 1 according to the following criteria. First, following Baltensperger (1990) public authorities may limit themselves to ex post interventions, offering protection to customers and financial intermediaries in the case of impending insolvency. They may also act in a preventive way by controlling the levels of risk assumed and reducing the probability of insolvency and illiquidity. Second, the safety and stability of the financial system may be enhanced by structural limitations of competition and market forces. Instead of these structural measures more weight is given to market efficiency by resorting to a whole set of prudential measures. Third, regulatory measures may focus on the macroeconomic concerns of systemic risk, or directly aim at microeconomic consumer protection. However, both are interrelated as the avoidance of consumer risks also limits systemic risks and vice-versa. Historically, the overriding reason for government intervention has been the desire to avoid systemic risk, mainly by ex post rescue operations of financial intermediaries. Preventive measures were mostly of a structural nature by limiting competition. The focus on market efficiency and individual consumer protection by deposit insurance and prudential measures is of a more recent date. Structural and prudential regulation often involve a whole set of different public regulatory measures which differ from country to country. They are
960
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
5850
stylized in Table 1 and further commented upon in the next sections. Protective interventions in the form of the lender of last resort and deposit insurance provisions do not involve such extensive regulation. Central banks can significantly limit the occurrence of systemic crises by their role as a ‘lender of last resort’. Central banks have been set up to control liquidity provision in the economy. They are the ultimate source of credit to which financial institutions can turn during a panic. By providing liquidity as a bankers’ bank they can stop the contagious transmission of financial problems among financial intermediaries. Table 1 Protective systems (ex post) Preventive measures (ex ante)
Lender of last resort Deposit insurance
Structural
Restrictions on entry and on business activities - product line restrictions - geographic restrictions Regulation of interest rates
Prudential
Portfolio restrictions and supervision - capital adequacy standards - asset restrictions and diversification rules - liquidity adequacy requirements Disclosure standards and reporting requirements Conduct and conflict rules Inspection and bank examination
As pointed out in Herring and Litan (1995, pp. 51-55), in some countries central banks under certain conditions also guarantee the settlements risk involved in the funds transfer system. By bearing the risk of non-payments by participants they take the systemic risk out of the payments system. The same role may also be taken up by private clearing houses, which have developed to
5850
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
961
handle larger value payments transactions. These clearing houses additionally use forms of private regulation such as capital standards, limits on the amount of debt and so on, to reduce default risk. The problem, however, is that these private intermediaries do not have sufficient means to cope with economy-wide shocks, for example serious disturbances that affect the members as a whole. There are several difficulties with the lender of last resort function. First, interventions must be carried out swiftly in a credible way. Credit should only be advanced to solvent financial intermediaries using the good, but illiquid, assets as collateral. They should not be used to bail out insolvent institutions, often at a high cost for taxpayers. However, it may not be easy in practice to distinguish between problems of liquidity and insolvency. Second, lender of last resort interventions may conflict with monetary policy objectives. In order to avoid a systemic crisis central banks may extend liquidity and fuel inflationary pressures. Inflation may structurally weaken the financial sector and its capacity to absorb shocks, thereby increasing the probability of a systemic crisis. In addition public authorities also intervene by guaranteeing some financial liabilities and by directly protecting investors through ‘deposit insurance’. Insurance arrangements contain the promise that if a financial institution fails, the investors will be reimbursed for the funds lost. They directly aim at individual investors protection, in particular the small depositors who are unable to determine the quality of the banks assets. Indirectly they also reduce the threat of a systemic crisis. This is achieved not by bailing out individual financial institutions, but by reducing incentives for bank runs by depositors and by containing the risk of contagion among financial institutions (see Diamond and Dybvig, 1983). Deposit insurance was already introduced in the 1930s in the US in order to stabilize the financial system in the aftermath of the Great Depression. Other countries have since followed, legislating a variety of deposit insurance schemes. Deposit insurance systems differ according to their public or private organization, compulsory or voluntary participation, fee structure, degree of coverage, funding provisions, etc. The question arises whether government intervention may not be limited to these protective policies. Why do public authorities resort to more extensive public regulation of the financial system? According to Herring and Litan (1995) further government regulation has to be explained by the potential high costs and moral hazard problems that these protective policies may entail. The lender of last resort prevents failures of financial institutions, in particular when they are considered to be ‘too big to fail’. In their IMF study Lindgren, Garcia and Saal (1996) document that the ‘too-big-to-fail’ doctrine has been prevalent in many countries, also in major industrial countries, for example recently in France and Japan, where it has prevented the closure of major commercial banks. Also in the US the practice in case of distress of merging
962
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
5850
banks rather than closing them relies upon this philosophy. When the government provides such a safety net it tempts financial institutions to pursue high risk investment strategies at the expense of the government. Also, when they are covered by deposit insurance, depositors have less incentive to monitor and discipline financial institutions. Hence, government safety nets help solve risk problems only by creating other problems. Instead of spending substantial amounts of GNP on rescuing ex post ailing financial institutions, preventive government interventions by regulation and supervision may be in order to counter ex ante these moral hazard effects.
6. Structural Regulation In order to limit the threat of systemic risks government intervention in the financial sector traditionally consisted in regulatory measures aiming at limiting competition and at restricting the operation of market forces. Unbridled competition was seen as a major threat to the stability of the financial sector. As listed in Table 1, structural regulation mainly involves restrictions on entry and on business activities, and often includes various measures of interest rate regulation. It was mainly in the aftermath of the Great Depression, which found its origin in a stock market crash, that it was deemed necessary to introduce structural restrictions on the scope of permissible activities of the different financial institutions. Before the crisis commercial banks acted as securities market financial institutions as well as depository institutions. They had an incentive to take on more risky activities in financial markets and earn investment banking fees, the risk being shifted in part to the depositors. In order to limit these risky activities and to reduce the risk of contagion within the financial system, after the crisis these activities were legally separated in many countries. In the US the separation of the banking and securities industries was legislated in the well-known Glass-Steagall Act. Besides bank investments in industrial firms, their real estate investments and insurance activities were also also often regulated. Frequently the ownership of financial institutions and non-financial firms was separated, and the investments of industrial firms in banks limited. However, these additional restrictions were aimed at limiting the concentration of power. For similar reasons also branching restrictions could be imposed. In the US in particular banks were geographically limited and were not allowed to open branches in other states and to engage in interstate banking. Since the 1970s the debate over retaining these restrictions has been reopened and limits have faded significantly. First, it was observed that some countries such as Germany had maintained a system of universal banking, in
5850
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
963
which banks were allowed to participate heavily in non-financial activities. Did this so-called bank intermediation model not present certain advantages for the economy? Giving a role to commercial banks in corporate finance may improve information gathering and the monitoring of loans, thereby reducing problems of adverse selection and moral hazard in core banking. Moreover, the restrictions also shielded the investment banking industry in many countries from competition. As a result of this recent debate, in its banking directives the European Community adopted the universal bank model. Second, the increased affiliation with commercial companies, however, remains a controversial issue. It may stretch the safety net meant only for bank depositors to protect other commercial operations, and induces more risky behavior. Also the risk of contagion increases as shocks in the industrial sector may more easily spread to financial institutions. Third, the combination of banking and insurance within the same financial institution has been permitted mainly in European countries. It raises, however, similar regulatory issues of conflicts of interests. Fourth, domestic branching restrictions by limiting the concentration of power may lower the cost of providing risk sharing, liquidity and information services. However, they increase the exposure of banks to credit risk by reducing their ability to diversify assets. In the meantime banks have spread worldwide so that it increasingly becomes difficult to maintain these restrictions. The European Community in its banking directives has resolutely opened up the opportunities for European-wide banking through the single bank license. Interest rates are important instruments of monetary policy. Hence, governments traditionally have intervened in the price formation in money and capital markets by regulating interest rates. Interest rate ceilings and other pricing rules, however, were also introduced to limit competition between banks and between banks and other financial institutions. Limiting price competition in financial markets would also reduce risk taking and moral hazard problems for financial institutions. Imposing interest rate ceilings such as regulation Q in the past in the US would then lower the cost of funds, enhance profits and reduce the likelihood of bank runs. Recently many of these anti-competitive regulatory measures have been removed. It was observed that they did not contribute to financial stability in the long run. They resulted in disintermediation as funds could be more profitably directly invested in and obtained from financial markets. Also many financial innovations were introduced to circumvent these restrictive regulations. In the trade-off between safety, stability and efficiency the present regulatory environment gives more weight to competition and efficiency. Instead of structurally limiting competition and the operation of market forces, regulation is taking more and more the form of prudential measures which may better serve the interest of the customers.
964
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
5850
7. Prudential Regulation Prudential control is exercised first at the market entry stage by ‘chartering’, that is the obligation to file an application for a charter. To obtain a license the owners have to supply sufficient equity capital. A minimum of capital is required as a cushion against losses. The chartering of new financial institutions is also subject to a screening of the proposed managers to prevent undesirable people from controlling them. According to Mishkin (1997) an adverse selection problem arises as financial activities may attract entrepreneurs wishing to engage in speculative activities. A central instrument of prudential control consists in capital adequacy rules. Equity capital provides the necessary cushion against losses, since shareholders may want to benefit from the leverage effect and to increase their return on equity by providing as little capital as necessary. Only in well capitalized institutions, however, do the shareholders have enough incentives to monitor their financial health. When financial institutions hold a large amount of equity capital, they have more to lose in case of failure so that they will pursue less risky activities. Capital requirements may take different forms. Traditionally they are calculated as a fixed percentage of the assets to limit the leverage ratio. Since these do not sufficiently reflect the differences in risk taking, default-risk-based capital requirements have been developed. Under the auspices of The Bank for International Settlements a risk-asset ratio, the so-called Cooke-ratio, that reflects ratios of capital to risk-weighted assets has been introduced. Recently additional risk-based capital requirements, so-called Capital Adequacy Directives, that take into account off-balance sheet activities and deal with market risk, have been devised. As is argued by Herring and Litan (1995, pp. 55-58) sound capital standards are important to offset the moral hazard created by government safety nets for depositors and other creditors. If capital regulation were perfect, no other regulatory interventions would be needed against the danger of moral hazard. Financial intermediaries could then be shut down and creditors reimbursed just before insolvency of the intermediary. In practice, however, regulators face delays in taking appropriate action, moreover the measuring of risk and the valuation of assets and capital proves to be difficult. Hence, other regulatory tools are necessary to backstop capital regulation. Besides structural interventions whereby financial institutions are not allowed to engage in certain activities, such as investments in common stocks by banks, the imposition of quantitative limits on certain asset holdings has more the character of prudential regulation. By ‘portfolio diversification rules’ such as limiting the amount of loans in particular categories or to individual borrowers the risk profile of banks can be reduced.
5850
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
965
Cash reserve requirements are often imposed as a measure to enhance liquidity adequacy. By providing the necessary liquidity for deposit withdrawals they increase confidence with depositors and reduce the threat of bank runs. In situations of collective withdrawals of deposits, however, they turned out to be largely insufficient to avoid a bank panic. Nowadays changes in required reserves have developed to an instrument that is used primarily for controlling the quantity of money and credit creation. By regular examination and inspection regulators may limit the moral hazard problems. They have to control whether the financial institutions are complying with the capital requirements and the restrictions on asset holding. A supervisory structure has to be set up in which bank examiners make periodic, but also unannounced visits to the financial intermediaries. Recent prudential measures such as ‘disclosure requirements’ tend to emphasize the disciplining of financial institutions by the market rather than by regulators. Generally, providing appropriate and timely disclosure of financial conditions of companies may help to reduce stock price volatility and excessive speculation. In particular, disclosure of financial conditions of financial institutions not only increases the ability but also gives incentives to investors to monitor the performance and the risk-profile of financial intermediaries. Recently the Basle Committee issued recommendations to banks to disclose their trading and derivatives activities. Also by discouraging shareholders and managers from excessive risk taking, public disclosure reduces the threat of systemic crises. Some degree of market discipline is also restored by recent developments such as market value accounting. Finally, many other regulatory measures are imposed that primarily aim at consumer protection. Consumers have to be protected against excessive prices from opportunistic behavior by producers of financial services and other participants in financial markets. In this respect regulation is no longer concerned with systemic stability, but with the integrity and efficiency of the financial markets. In the US traditionally antitrust regulation has been an important instrument to guarantee fair prices to consumers. With the advent of the European-wide financial market and the mergers it will entail, competition law may also play a larger role in Europe. Opportunistic behavior is often made possible by asymmetric information. In securities markets corporate officials and owners are better informed about the fortunes of their companies. Hence, other investors are protected by insider trading regulations. Certain financial products are sometimes very complicated such as insurance, pension plans and long-term securities. In order to avoid that some buyers of these products are misled standardized disclosure rules may be imposed, reporting requirements and supervision of these financial institutions by regulators may be in order.
966
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
5850
8. Regulatory Structure It follows from the previous discussion that the need for government intervention as well as the choice of regulatory instruments depend on the threat of the occurrence of systemic crises and on the need for individual investors’ protection. The occurrence of these risks may differ among financial institutions. Hence the need for regulating the different types of financial institutions depends on the specific activities they engage in. In particular the danger of systemic risk is seen as justifying a larger role for government. In this respect the activities of the different financial institutions may be compared according to three criteria: first the risks involved that may lead to their failure; second the interconnections among intermediaries determining the contagion affect; and finally their importance for the whole financial system and the real economy. According to these criteria, it is held by Mayer and Neven (1991) that deposit taking, which is the core of banking, has been found to be especially vulnerable to systemic risk. First, the maturity transformation sets the banks apart from other financial intermediaries. The mismatch between the maturities of their assets makes them vulnerable to decisions by depositors to withdraw their funds. As the liquidation value of their investments is often smaller this may amplify withdrawals to a bank run. Second, important interconnections in bank relations means that even healthy banks are exposed to failures elsewhere in the banking system. The externalities involved may lead to a contagious collapse of the whole banking system. Third, the costs to the economy of bank failures may be huge. Banks play a crucial role in the payments system and in refinancing other financial intermediaries. Failures have wider ramifications on the rest of the financial system and on the real economy. One may point also to the danger that a banking crisis causes large and uncontrollable fluctuations in the quantity of money and credit. Hence, the case for banking regulation not only arises from the need of depositors’ protection, but more urgently from the systemic risk of the collapse of the whole financial system. The question arises whether failures of other financial institutions present the same dangers of systemic crises. Also investment firms are subject to interconnections that can lead to a contagious loss of confidence. This is especially the case for market making functions. There are, however, according to Herring and Litan (1995, pp. 72-73), key distinctions between banks and investment firms that make a contagious transmission of shocks a less serious concern for systemic risk. First, the nature of customer relations, debt contracts and maturity of assets involve less liquidity risk. The funds of investors are kept in accounts that are segregated from the institutions own assets what is not the case in banking. Debt contracts by securities firms typically do not guarantee rates of return and are not redeemable at par, so that customers have little to gain from a run on
5850
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
967
securities firms that are in difficulty. The portfolio of investment firms also typically consists of marketable securities that can easily be evaluated and transferred in the event of a failure. Second, the role of securities houses in intermediating funds from savers to investors in many countries is much less crucial. Hence, their failure is much less likely to cause significant harms to the economy. Therefore the need for regulation of investment firms is less compelling. However, there remain sound reasons for regulation. The activities of investment firms involve information asymmetries and may require regulation to protect investors against fraud and incompetence. In this respect the regulation of portfolio managers has an affinity with the regulation of (free) professions. In addition capital requirements similar to those for banks may be imposed in order to avoid undermining confidence in the functioning of markets in the event of a steep decline in asset prices. In the insurance sector important interconnections exist through the important role of reinsurers. In principle an insurance crisis may emerge when many or all of the reinsurers simultaneously cut off reinsurance coverage, so that primary insurers eventually have to cut back on the availability of insurance. In practice major shocks in the insurance market have not entailed such a collapse. Even if this might be called a systemic insurance risk, insurance companies are not involved in payments and liquidity functions, so that the consequences for the whole financial system and the real economy would not be so dramatic as for a banking crisis. Protection of the individual consumer against asymmetric information problems, however, may be more compelling than in the rest of the financial sector. The reason is that those insurance contracts generally are complicated, and involve not only financial but also more technical actuarial risks. The elaborate financial regulatory system is continuously questioned at various levels.
9. Deregulation and the Regulatory Crisis In the last decades awareness has grown that regulation not only entails benefits, but also imposes substantial costs on the economy. In this respect the traditional public interest view of regulation has been challenged by the new public choice approach. It implies the need for an evaluation of the externalities and the incidence of regulatory measures. Structural regulation that limits market competition may eventually convey benefits to private financial institutions, by protecting them against outside competition and by promoting confidence in financial intermediaries. However, by restricting market entry it may involve substantial welfare costs to society. In this respect regulators may be ‘captured’ by the regulated firms through
968
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
5850
lobbying in order to protect their business interests at the expense of the consumer. Other types of regulation impose additional costs on the financial intermediaries when they have to adjust to the regulatory standards. The foregone earnings due to high capital requirements or to required cash reserves may be considered as a tax on financial institutions. By increasing the intermediation cost they lead to disintermediation. Financial institutions often respond by changing their activities and by introducing financial innovation in an attempt to circumvent the regulatory restrictions. In particular off-balance sheet transactions, which may be a multiple of traditional balance sheet activities have multiplied banking risks. Moreover, they also involve severe information problems as to measurement and valuation of these risks. As regulators respond by introducing new regulation it may leads to a regulatory dialectic. The dynamics of regulation boils down to a continuous tension between the desire for a stable financial system and an economic efficient system. The recent shift towards prudential regulatory measures is to be considered as an attempt to solve this tension. The discussion, however, remains as to the level of regulatory restrictions required. It pertains to the perception of the fragility of the financial system. Based upon empirical evidence Benston and Kaufman (1995) observe that the worries about contagion are often unfounded and that there is no reason to claim that banking is more fragile. Hence, a combination of minimum capital requirements with a system of structured early intervention would be sufficient to avoid a systemic crisis. The question, however, arises whether the empirical evidence is not biased by the high regulatory burden in the past? Will deregulation not give incentives for higher risk strategies and enhance systemic risk? In fact the debate boils down to finding the difficult balance between security and risk. As explained before, information asymmetries in financial markets create problems of moral hazard. Financial intermediaries may have incentives to take more risk than is in the interest of individual savers and depositors. Government regulation and intervention may be in order to reduce the costs of moral hazard to individual customers. When the government, however, provides a safety net through regulatory measures such as deposit insurance and the lender of last resort, it gives incentives to financial institutions to pursue high risk investment strategies. According to the free banking school these moral hazard problems are better solved by suitable private sector instruments of internal and external disciplining of bank management together with the promotion of competition of banks. Banks will be disciplined by markets as deposit-holders have incentives to monitor the behavior of banks. There is no need for independent supervisory authorities. Contrary to this view, however, a free rider problem
5850
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
969
arises in markets in case of a large number of investors who have little incentive to devote resources to the monitoring of financial institutions. Certain episodes such as the Savings and Loan Crisis in the last decade in the US teach that moral hazard remains a difficult regulatory concern. Taxpayers had to bear collectively the huge cost of the deposit insurance bail-out. Deposit insurance undermined the incentives for saving banks to pursue prudent policies as they reduce the need for individual savers to monitor bank management. In addition Hubbard (1996, p. 386) argues that the regulator’s incentives differed from those of tax payers. Regulatory supervision became lax at the first sign of trouble as regulators did not want troubled intermediaries to fail. These experiences are currently shaping the regulatory reform of financial institutions. Proposals have been launched to reform deposit insurance in various directions: from reducing the level of deposit insurance coverage and risk-based pricing of deposit insurance to private deposit insurance. The undesired risk incentives of the safety net has also to be reduced by supplementary prudential regulation such as capital adequacy and liquidity requirements.
10. The Changing Nature of Regulation Recently a debate has been launched about the regulatory structure. The rising tide for market solutions implies an increasing role for self-regulation and private regulatory bodies. Self-regulation will arise when clubs can be formed. Clubs are professional organizations which regulate the behavior of members. Self-regulation has the advantage of flexibility but the danger of capture by members. Also outside private agencies, such as rating agencies may discipline risk behavior as the rating of an intermediary affects its funding costs. However, private regulatory failures may occur due to a collective action problem. As a result of this debate, it is increasingly argued that the control of risks, remains in first instance the task of individual institutions or of clubs of institutions. The role of the government then has to be limited to supervising these private regulatory systems. In the same vein the traditional debate between rules versus discretion is taking a different direction. Whereas rules can be crude and not adapted to the situation at hand, discretion makes it a largely political matter. As argued by Horvitz (1995) the need for discretion may be reduced, while allowing for reasonably flexible regulation by a graduated system of interventions and controls. In the US it works through the operation of various trigger points as banks approach the critical area of balance sheet ratios. In this respect the
970
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
5850
recent Basle Agreements are being criticized as not providing such a graduated response. Moreover, the present system relying predominantly upon institutional regulation is being questioned. Banks, securities firms, insurance companies are being regulated and supervised by different regulatory bodies. In fact systemic stability is seen as requiring the application of different rules to different financial institutions. Institutional regulation becomes difficult to implement when the different financial intermediaries widen the scope of their financial activities, for example when universal banks engage in securities activities. Maintaining institutional regulation and subjecting universal banks to stricter capital requirements or providing a safety net also for their securities activities conflicts with competitive neutrality of regulation. Similar issues arise for financial conglomerates. A level playing field may be promoted and regulatory efficiency maintained by introducing a system of functional regulation. Regulation by function is likely to emerge and regulation by institution to decline in the future as the distinction between banks and other financial intermediaries is fading. More fundamentally the philosophy of regulation is analytically being reexamined in the new institutional economics literature. A strong analogy is pointed out between banking regulation and loan agreement covenants in ‘corporate governance’. By relying upon contract theory the analysis of financial regulation is becoming a true interdisciplinary law and economics endeavor. According to Richter (1990) the complex ongoing business relationships between savers, borrowers and financial institutions can be analyzed as a relational contract. By its nature it is an incomplete contract as analyzed by Hart (1994) that eventually may be in need of further regulation. In repeat business transactions one may relay upon private contract enforcing mechanisms such as reputation, for example. Individual monitoring in banking, however, suffers from a collective action problem. Dewatripont and Tirole (1994, pp. 117-118) argue that unsophisticated and small claimholders suffer from information asymmetries and have little incentive to invest in monitoring due to a free rider problem. Active representation of depositors must be provided by organizing ‘delegated’ monitoring. However, if no mechanism of private representation is or can be set up, regulation may be needed. It may take the form of private regulation by an independent supervisory or regulatory firm. Public regulation of banks is a very complex matter and therefore should limit itself to a complementary role by light-handed regulation. More specifically, regulation must focus upon altering incentives, for example for shareholders to discipline managers through higher capital requirements. It should not impose rigid regulatory schemes to all intermediaries, but introduce a number of options from which financial institutions should be allowed to make a selection. To summarize the
5850
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
971
arguments, financial regulation has to be devised within the framework of an efficient governance of financial intermediaries. The trend clearly is towards a more comprehensive approach to risk management, stressing the importance of internal governance and the role of market discipline.
11. The International Dimension The globalization of financial markets constitutes a major challenge to the regulation of financial activities and institutions which continues to be carried out by national governments. It creates several problems for which solutions are not easy to implement. First, due to the growing interdependence in international financial markets financial difficulties experienced in one country can easily spill over to other countries. A systemic crisis in one country and the failure of its authorities to deal with it appropriately may lead to a global banking crisis. Second, regulation can be considered as a tax and can have an impact on the international competitiveness of financial institutions. Different regulatory regimes may also create barriers for firms in cross-border trade in financial services. For instance, different capital requirements create an unlevel playing field between financial institutions of different countries. Third, financial institutions may attempt to avoid more stringent domestic regulation by locating abroad. Regulatory arbitrage impairs the effectiveness of regulation and the ability of different countries to maintain their own regulatory framework. Regulatory competition may eventually lead to a downward regulatory spiral. As is demonstrated in a game-theoretic framework by taking into account the special informational characteristics of financial products and the role of reputation in the banking industry (see Van Cayseele and Heremans, 1991) there may, however, be limits to this process. In particular in retail markets where financial integration is far less complete there remain upward regulatory pressures. Countries will be able to maintain regulatory measures as a signal of quality differentiation provided that they are valued by customers. The concern for the distortion of international competition certainly has been a major driving force behind attempts towards worldwide solutions for financial regulation. Recent international financial crises are increasing the urge for an international approach. International market integration also helps to explain the recent shift of emphasis from structural towards prudential regulation. Through efforts of international coordination an answer is sought for the questions of what should be the right of access to foreign markets, and whose rules should apply in international financial services. In this respect a tendency is observed to give branches and subsidiaries of foreign banks the same treatment as domestic banks. For cross-border transactions of financial
972
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
5850
intermediaries it is proposed (for example, by Hubbard, 1996, p. 426) that they should be monitored by the home country. Regulation and coordination can be limited as banks should be allowed to develop their own risk-assessment procedures which should only be subject to regulatory review. Taking into account the concern for the threat of complete deregulation, however, stronger forms of international harmonization are also being envisaged. The European Union has linked policies of mutual recognition and home country control rules with agreements on minimum standards of conduct. The Basel Committee on Banking Supervision has laid down common bank capital rules. These minimum standards, continue to be enforced by individual countries. They are, however, being criticized (for example by Herring and Litan, 1995) for their arbitrariness and potential inflexibility. In the face of the possibility of a worldwide systemic crisis the lender of last resort function still remains largely the endeavor of national central banks. Whether emergency liquidity assistance should be provided not only for banks but also for other financial intermediaries, and whether the lender of last resort function should be provided at the international level, remain heavily debated issues. Finally, faced with the increasing need for worldwide regulation, an agreement that extends beyond the Basle countries on a set of minimum capital standards, as Goldstein (1997) has argued for, may be eventually attained. But international cooperation beyond these minimal standards, remains a difficult issue. In particular, faced with the fragmented supervision by many agencies to be multiplied by the number of countries, the prospects for international cooperation to reinforce supervision remain bleak. These difficulties to agree on the international dimension of financial regulation and supervision are enhancing the overall trend towards greater emphasis on discipline by the market rather than by regulators.
Acknowledgements The author gratefully acknowledges the comments made by P. Van Cayseele, M. De Broeck, Y. Maes, P. Maenhout and an unknown referee. Helpful logistical support was provided by M. De Houwer and J. Janssens. All remaining errors are the responsibility of the author.
5850
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
973
Bibliography on Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets (5850) Abraham, J.P. (1981), ‘De Overheidstussenkomst in het Financiewezen: Effectief? Efficiënt? (Government Intervention in Finance: Effective? Efficient?)’, 12-13 Bank-en Financiewezen, 17-39. Adams, Michael (1994a), ‘Die Usurpation von Aktionärsbefugnissen mittels Ringverflechtung in der ‘Deutschland - AG’ - Vorschläge für Reformen im Wettbewerbs-, Steuer- und Unternehmensrecht’, Die Aktiengesellschaft, 148-156. Adams, Michael (1994b), ‘Beseitigung der Steuerlich bedingten Machtzentralisierung bei Versicherungsunternehmen durch Einführung eines ‘Qualifizierten Kontos’, 15 Zeitschrift für Wirtschaftsrecht, 1434-1437. Adams, Michael (1994c), ‘Macht von Banken und Versicherungen - Wettbewerb im Finanzdienstleistungssektor-, Stellungnahme zur öffentlichen Anhörung des Deutschen Bundestages - Ausschuß für Wirtschaft -, 8. Dezember 1993 (Power of Banks and Insurances)’, Zeitschrift für Bank- und Börsenrecht, 77-86. Altman, Edward I. and Nammacher, S.A. (1987), ‘Anatomy and Portfolio Strategies of the High Yield Debt Market’, in Copeland, T.E. (ed.), Modern Finance and Industrial Economics: Papers in Honor of J. Fred Weston, 168-199. Aronowitz, Daniel (1991), ‘Retracing the Antitrust Roots of Section 1972 of the Bank Holding Company Act’, 44 Vanderbilt Law Review, 865-898. Arvan, Lanny and Brueckner, Jan K. (1986), ‘Efficient Contracts in Credit Markets Subject to Interest Rate Risk: An Application of Raviv’s Insurance Model’, 76 American Economic Review, 259-263. Baltensperger, Ernst (1976), ‘The Borrower-Lender Relationship, Competitive Equilibrium, and the Theory of Hedonic Prices’, 66 American Economic Review, 401-405. Baltensperger, Ernst (1990), ‘The Economic Theory of Banking Regulation’, in Furubotn, Eirik and Richter, R. (eds), The Economics and Law of Banking Regulation, Occasional Papers, vol. 2, Winter 1989/90, Germany, Saarbrucken, University of Saarlandes, Center for the Study of the New Institutional Economics. Baltensperger, Ernst and Dermine, J. (1987), ‘Banking Deregulation’, Economic Policy: A European Forum, 61-109. Barth, James R., Cordes, Joseph J. and Yezer, Anthony M.J. (1986), ‘Benefits and Costs of Legal Restrictions on Personal Loan Markets’, 29 Journal of Law and Economics, 357-380. Baxter, William F. (1983), ‘Bank Interchange of Transactional Paper: Legal and Economic Perspectives’, 26 Journal of Law and Economics, 541-588. Benston, George J. and Kaufman, George G. (1995), ‘Is the Banking and Payment System Fragile?’, in Benink, H.A. (ed.), Coping with Financial Fragility and Systemic Risk., Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers. Benston, George J. et al. (1986), Perspectives on Safe and Sound Banking: Past Present and Future, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 358 p. Black, Fisher, Miller, Merton H. and Posner, Richard A. (1978), ‘An Approach to the Regulation of Bank Holding Companies’, 51 Journal of Business, 379-412. Bowles, Roger A. and Phillips, Jennifer (1976), ‘Judgments in Foreign Currencies: An Economist’s View (Notes of Cases)’, 39 Modern Law Review, 196-201. Bowles, Roger A. and Whelan, Christopher J. (1979), ‘Judgments in Foreign Currencies: Extension of the Milangos Rule (Notes of Cases)’, 42 Modern Law Review, 452-459.
974
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
5850
Bradley, Michael D. and Jansen, Dennis W. (1986), ‘Deposit Market Deregulation and Interest Rates’, 53 Southern Economic Journal, 478-489. Bratton, William W., Jr (1984), ‘The Economics and Jurisprudence of Convertible Bonds’, Wisconsin Law Review, 667 ff. Bundt, Thomas and Keating, Barry (1988), ‘Depository Institution Competition in the Deregulated Environment: The Case of the Large Credit Union’, 20 Applied Economics, 1333-1342. Burnham, James B. (1990), ‘The Government Securities Act of 1986: A Case Study of the Demand for Regulation’, 13(2) Regulation, 78-84. Buss, James A. and Buss, William E. (1981), ‘A Note on the Economic Impact from the Financed Capitalist Plan’, 3 Research in Law and Economics, 227-239. Buxbaum, Hertig and Hirsch, Hopt (eds) (1991), European Economic and Business Law, Legal and Economic Analyses on Integration and Harmonization, Berlin, Walter De Gruyter, 401 p. Cable, John (1985), ‘Capital Market Information and Industrial Performance: The Role of West German Banks’, 95 Economic Journal, 118-132. Chen, Andrew H. and Merville, Larry J. (1986), ‘An Analysis of Divestiture Effects Resulting from Deregulation’, 41 Journal of Finance, 997-1010. Cosentino, Fabrizio (1990), ‘Il Contratto di Servizio delle Cassette di Sicurezza: Clausole di Limitazione della Responsabilità della Banca e Dichiarazione di Valore (The Contract for Services Related to Safety Deposit Boxes: Exemption Clauses for the Bank and Statement of Value)’, 1 Foro Italiano, 1292-1298. Dale, Richard (1984), The Regulation of International Banking, Cambridge, Woodhead-Faulkner. Dale, Richard (ed.) (1986), Financial Deregulation: The Proceedings of a Confe, Cambridge, Woodhead-Faulkner. Dauw, C. (1987), ‘Financiële Deregulering en Financiering der Investeringen (Financial Deregulation and Financing of Investment)’, in X (ed.), 18de Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Brussel 8 en 9 mei 1987, Sociaal-economische Deregulering, Brussel, V.E.H.U.B., 695-730. Demuth, Christopher C. (1986), ‘The Case against Credit Card Interest Rate Regulation’, 3 Yale Journal on Regulation, 201-242. Dewatripont, M. and Tirole, Jean (1994), The Prudential Regulation of Banks, Cambridge, MA and London, MIT Press. Diamond, D.W. and Dybvig, P.H. (1983), ‘Bank Runs, Deposit Insurance and Liquidity’, 91 Journal of Political Economy, 401-417. Drukarczyk, Jochen (1987a), ‘Ökonomische Analyse der Rechtsprechung des BGH zur Sittenwidrigkeit von Sanierungskrediten (Economic Analysis of the Jurisprudence of the Bund)’, in X (ed.), Kapitalmarkt und Finanzierung, Jahrestagung des Vereins für Socialpolitik in München, 379-397. Drukarczyk, Jochen (1987b), Unternehmen und Insolvenz - Zur effizienten Gestaltung des Kredisicherungs- und Insolvenzrechts (Entrepreneurship and Insolvency - On the Efficient Shape of Safeguarding of Credits Law and Insolvency Law), Wiesbaden, Gabler, 424 p. Drukarczyk, Jochen (1987c), ‘Kreditsicherheiten und Insolvenzverfahren (Collateralized Debt and Insolvency Proceedings)’, 8 Zeitschrift für Wirtschaftsrecht, 205-217.
5850
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
975
Drukarczyk, Jochen (1988), ‘Zum Verhältnis von Markt und Regulierung in einem Neuen Insolvenzrecht - Besprechung des Ersten Berichts der Kommission für Insolvenzrecht (The Relation of Market and Regulation in the New Bankruptcy Law - Discussion of the first report by the “Kommission für Insolvenzrecht”)’, 1 DBW, 3-25. Drukarczyk, Jochen (1989), ‘Insolvenzrecht als Versuch Marktkonformer Gestaltung von Verwertungsentscheidungen und Verteilungsregeln (Bankruptcy law as an Attempt to Organize Insolvency Proceedings in Line with Market Rules)’, 10 Zeitschrift für Wirtschaftsrecht, 341-351. Drukarczyk, Jochen (1992a), ‘Insolvenzrechtsreform, Reformkonzeptionen und aktueller Stand (Reform of the Bankruptcy Law, Concepts of Reform and State of the Art)’, 52 DBW, 161-183. Drukarczyk, Jochen (1992b), ‘Mobiliargesicherte Gläubiger, Verfahrensbeitrag im Insolvenzverfahren und Kreditkonditionen (Secured Creditors, Contributions to Bankruptcy Proceedings and Credit Terms)’, 46 WM, 1136-1144. Drukarczyk, Jochen (1993), ‘Soll das Insolvenzrecht eine Reorganisation zulassen? (Should Bankruptcy Law Allow Reorganization?)’, in Gerke, W. (ed.), Planwirtschaft am Ende Marktwirtschaft in der Krise? Festschrift für Wolfram Engels, Stuttgart, Poeschel, 109-137. Drukarczyk, Jochen (1994a), ‘Kapitalerhaltungsrecht, Überschuldung und Konsistenz - Besprechung der Überschuldungs-Definition in BGH WM 1992, 1650 (Capital maintenance, overindebtedness and consistency - Discussion of the Statutory Definition of Overindebtedness by the German Supreme Court)’, 48 WM, 1737-1746. Drukarczyk, Jochen (1994b), ‘Überschuldung, Zur Konstruktion eines Insolvenztatbestandes im Spannungsfeld von Kapitalerhaltungsrecht und Kreditmarkt (Overindebtedness, Construction of an Insolvency Trigger Given the Constraints of Capital Maintenance and Credit Markets)’, in Ballwieser, W., Bücking, H.-J., Drukarczyk, J. and Schmidt, R.H. (eds), Bilanzrecht und Kapitalmarkt. Festschrift für Adolf Moxter, Düsseldorf, 1231-1258. Drukarczyk, Jochen (1995a), ‘Gesellschafterdarlehen, Rechtsprechungsgrundsätze des BGH und § 32a GmbHG - Einige Kritische Anmerkungen (Proprietors’ Loans, Principles of Jurisdiction of the German Supreme Court and § 32a GmbHG - Critical Comments)’, in Elschen, R., Siegel, Th. and Wagner, F.W. (eds), Unternehmenstheorie und Besteuerung. Festschrift für Dieter Schneider, Wiesbaden, Gabler, 173-202. Drukarczyk, Jochen (1995b), ‘Verwertungsformen und Kosten der Insolvenz (Asset Use and Bankruptcy Costs)’, 1 BFuP, 40-58. Duttle, Josef (1986), Ökonomische Analyse dinglicher Sicherheiten - Die Reform der Mobiliarsicherheiten und Probleme ihrer Behandlung in insolvenzrechtlichen Verfahren (Economic Analysis of Collateral Securities - The Reform of Personal Securities and Problems of their Treatment in Bankruptcy Proceedings), Dissertation, Marchal und Matzenbacher, Wissenschaftsverlag, Krefeld, 1986. Edwards, Linda N. and Edwards, Franklin R. (1974), ‘Measuring the Effectiveness of Regulation: The Case of Bank Entry Regulation’, 17 Journal of Law and Economics, 445-460. Eisenbeis, Robert A. (1988), ‘Expanding Banking Powers: The Present Debate’, 7 Cato Journal, 763-769.
976
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
5850
Ekelund, Robert B., Jr, Hébert, Robert F. and Tollison, Robert D. (1989), ‘An Economic Model of the Medieval Church: Usury as a Form of Rent Seeking’, 5 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 307-331. England, Catherine (1988), ‘Agency Costs and Unregulated Banks: Could Depositors Protect Themselves?’, 7 Cato Journal, 771-797. Fama, Eugene F. (1965), ‘Random Walks in Stock Market Prices’, 21 Financial Analysts Journal, 55-99. Fama, Eugene F. (1970), ‘Efficient Capital Markets: A Review of Theory and Empirical Work’, 25 Journal of Finance, 383-417. Fazio, Antonio and Capriglione, Francesco (1983), ‘Governo del Credito e Analisi Economica del Diritto (Governing Credit and Economic Analysis of Law)’, 1 Banca, Borsa, e Titoli di Credito, 310-346. Fischel, Daniel R. (1989), ‘The Economics of Lender Liability’, 99 Yale Law Journal, 131-154. Fischel, Daniel R., Rosenfield, Andrew M. and Stillman, Robert (1987), ‘The Regulation of Banks and Bank Holding Companies’, 73 Virginia Law Review, 301-338. Fischer, Thomas G., Gram, William H., Kaufman, George G. and Mote, Larry R. (1984), ‘The Securities Activities of Commercial Banks: A Legal and Economic Analysis’, 51 Tennessee Law Review, 467 ff. Flood, Mark D. (1990), ‘On the Use of Option Pricing Models to Analyze Deposit Insurance’, Jan/Feb Review, Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis, 19-35. Flood, Mark D. (1992), ‘The Great Deposit Insurance Debate’, July/Aug Review, Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis, 51-77. Flood, Mark D. (1993), ‘Deposit Insurance Problems and Solutions’, Jan/Feb Review, Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis, 28-34. Flood, Mark D. (1994), ‘Market Structure and Inefficiency in the Foreign Exchange Market’, 13 Journal of International Money and Finance, 131-158. Fox, Eleanor M. (1987), ‘Chairman Miller, the Federal Trade Commission, Economics, and Rashomon’, 50(4) Law and Contemporary Problems, 33-55. Frieder, Larry A. (1988), ‘The Interstate Banking Landscape: Legislative Policies and Rationale’, 6(2) Contemporary Policy Issues, 41-66. Furnish, Dale Back and Boyes, William J. (1982), ‘Usury and the Efficiency of Market Control Mechanisms: A Comment on ‘Usury in English Law’‘, 1 Arizona Journal of International and Comparative Law, 61-81. Gilson, Ronald J. and Kraakman, Reinier H. (1984), ‘The Mechanisms of Market Efficiency’, 70 Virginia Law Review, 549-644. Goldstein, M. (1997), The Case for an International Banking Standard., Washington, DC, Institute for International Economics. Golembe, Carter H. (1989), ‘Long term Trends in Bank Regulation’, 2 Journal of Financial Services Research, 171-183. Goodman, Laurie S. (1986), ‘The Interface between Technology and Regulation in Banking’, in Saunders, Anthony and White, Lawrence J. (eds), Technology and the Regulation of Financial Markets, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books, 181-186. Gorinson, Stanley M. (1983), ‘Depository Institution Regulatory Reform in the 1980s: The Issue of Geographic Restrictions’, 28 Antitrust Bulletin, 227-254.
5850
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
977
Gottfries, Nils Torsten and Palmer, Edward (1989), ‘Regulation, Financial Buffer Stocks, and ShortRun Adjustment: An Econometric Case Study of Sweden, 1970-82, 33 European Economic Review, 1545-1565. Haraf, William S. (1988), ‘Bank and Thrift Regulation’, 12(3) Regulation, 50-56. Haraf, William S. (1988), ‘Toward a Sound Financial System’, 7 Cato Journal, 677-681. Hart, O. (1994), Firms, Contracts and Financial Structure, Oxford, Oxford Clarendon Press. Herring, Ronald J. and Litan, Robert E. (1995), Financial Regulation in the Global Economy, Washington, Brookings Institution. Herrmann, Harald (1976), ‘Die Grundsätze ordnungsgemäßer Buchführung im Licht einer entscheidungswissenschaftlichen Rechtstheorie (The Generally Accepted Principles of Book-Keeping in the Light of a Decision Theory of Law)’, Zeitschrift für Unternehmens- und Gesellschaftsrecht, 203-238. Herrmann, Harald (1987), ‘Vertrags- und wettbewerbsrechtliche Grenzen der Zinsanhebung beim Hypothekenkredit (Limits of Interest Adaptation Clauses in Contract Law and the Law of Competition)’, Wertpapiermitteilungen, 1029-1062. Herrmann, Harald (1989), ‘Handelsbilanzrechtliche Probleme des Quasi-Eigenkapitals in der GmbH und KG (Problems of the Accounting Law of Mezzanine Financing in the Closed Corporation and the Limited Partnership)’, in Albers, S., Herrmann, H., Kahle, E., Kruschwitz, C. and Perlitz, M. (eds), Elemente Erfolgreicher Unternehmenspolitik in Mittelständischen Unternehmen, Stuttgart, 301-322. Herrmann, Harald (1993), ‘Kreditvertragsrecht und Funktionsfähiger Wettbewerb im Neuen Bundesgebiet (Law of Borrowing and Workable Competition in the Ex-GDR)’, 14 Zeitschrift für Wirtschaftsrecht, 54-63. Herrmann, Harald (1996), ‘Quasi-Eigenkapital im Kapitalmarkt- und Unternehmensrecht.-Ein deutsch-amerikanischer Rechtsvergleich und Beitrag zum Internationalen Wirtschaftsrecht (Mezzanine Financing in the Law of Securities Regulations and in the Law of Corporations. An Analysis of German-American Comparative Law and of International Commerce Law)’, 17 Recht des internationalen Wirtschaftverkehrs. Hertig (1991), ‘Considerations Supplémentaires à Propos de la Fécision CS’, Revue Suisse de Droit des Affaires, 155-159. Hertig, Gerard (1994), ‘La Diligence des Banques: les Règles de Conduite vis-à-vis des Clients, Aspects de Droit Public, Revue de droit Suisse’, in Helbing and Lichtenhahn (eds), 249-358. Hertig, Gerard (1994), ‘Imperfect Mutual Recognition for EC Financial Services’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 177-186. Horvitz, P. (1995), ‘Banking Regulation as a Solution to Financial Fragility’, in Benink, H.A. (eds), Coping with Financial Fragility and Systemic Risk, Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 175-186. Hubbard, R. Glenn (1991), Financial Markers and Financial Crises, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Hubbard, R. Glenn (1996), Money in the Financial System and the Economy, Reading, MA, Addison-Wesley Longman, 2nd edn. Huerta De Soto, Jesús (1994), ‘Banque Central ou Banque Libre: Le Debat Theorique sur les Reserves Fractionaires’, 5(2-3) Journal des Economistes et des Etudes Humaines, 379-391.
978
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
5850
Huerta De Soto, Jesús (1995), ‘A Critical Analysis of Central Banks and Fractional-Reserve Free Banking from the Austrian Perspective’, 8(2) Review of Austrian Economics, 25-38. Huerta De Soto, Jesús (1996), ‘New Light on the Prehistory of the Theory of Banking and the School of Salamanca’, 9(2) Review of Austrian Economics, 59-61. Huertas, Thomas (1988), ‘Can Banking and Commerce Mix?’, 7 Cato Journal, 743-762. Jackson, Howell E. (1993), ‘The Superior Performance of Savings and Loan Associations with Substantial Holding Companies’, 22 Journal of Legal Studies, 405-456. Jafee, Jeffrey F. and Long, J.B., Jr (1972), ‘Corporate Investment under Uncertainty and Pareto Optimality in the Capital Markets’, 3 Bell Journal of Economics, 151-174. Jensen, Michael C. (1969), ‘Risk, the Pricing of Capital Assets, and the Evaluation of Investment Portfolios’, 42 Journal of Business, 167-247. Joffrion, Theresa and Rose, Peter S. (1987), ‘Savings and Loans’ Response to Deregulation: Evidence from Multivariate Models and a National Survey’, 6 Housing Finance Review, 17-38. Johnsen, D. Bruce (1992), ‘The Incentive Effects of Soft Dollar Brokerage’, in Lehn, Kenneth and Kamphuis, Robert (eds), Modernizing US Securities Regulations: Economic and Legal Perspectives, Homewood, IL, Business One Irwin, 511-519. Johnsen, D. Bruce (1994), ‘Property Rights to Investment Research: The Agency Costs of Soft Dollar Brokerage’, 11 Yale Journal on Regulation, 75-113. Johnson, Harry G. (1972), ‘The International Monetary System and the Rule of Law’, 15 Journal of Law and Economics, 277-292. Jones, Lawrence D. (1993), ‘Deficiency Judgments and the Exercise of the Default Option in Home Mortgage Loans’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 115-138. Jonung, Lars (1978), ‘The Legal Framework and the Economics of Private Bank Notes in Sweden, 1831-1902', in Skogh, Göran (ed.), Law and Economics. Report from a Symposium in Lund, Lund, Juridiska Föreningen, 185-202. Junod, Charles-André (1988), ‘L’Indexation des Crédits Hypothécaires Pourrait-elle à la Fois Améliorer le Fonctionnement du Marché du Logement et Servir de Correctif à l’Inflation? (Could the Indexation of Mortgage-debt Improve the Operation of the Housing Market)’, 40 Wirtschaft und Recht, 88-123. Kane, Edward J. (1986), ‘Technology and the Regulation of Financial Markets’, in Saunders, Anthony and White, Lawrence J. (eds), Technology and the Regulation of Financial Markets, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books, 187-193. Kane, Edward J. (1988), ‘Interaction of Financial and Regulatory Innovation’, 78 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 328-334. Kane, Edward J. (1989), ‘Changing Incentives Facing Financial Services Regulators’, 2 Journal of Financial Services Research, 265-274. Keeley, Michael C. and Furlong, Frederick T. (1986), ‘Bank Regulation and the Public Interest’, 0(2) Federal Reserve Bank of San Francisco Economic Review, 55-71. Kessel, Reuben A. and Truman, A. Clark (1976), ‘A Study of Expectational Errors in the Money and Capital Markets, 1921- 1970', 19 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-15. Kitch, Edmund W. (1981), ‘Discussion of Some Implications of the United States Constitution for Accounting Institution Alternatives’, 19 Journal of Accounting Research.
5850
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
979
Kitch, Edmund W. (1990), ‘The Framing Hypothesis: Is It Supported by Credit Card Issuer Opposition to a Surcharge on a Crash Price?’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 217-233. Kitch, Edmund W. (1995), ‘The Theory and Practice of Securities Disclosure’, 61 Brooklyn Law Review, 761 ff. Klausner, Michael (1991), ‘An Economic Analysis of Bank Regulatory Reform: The Financial Institutions Safety and Consumer Choice Act of 1991', 69 Washington University Law Quarterly, 695 ff. Klausner, Michael (1995a), ‘Market Failure and Community Investment: A Market-Oriented Alternative to the Community Reinvestment Act’, 143 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1561 ff. Klausner, Michael (1995b), ‘Regulation of Banks’, in Morrison, Alan (ed.), Introduction to American Law, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Kohl, Helmut, Kübler, Friedrich, Walz, W. Rainer and Wüstrich, Wolfgang (1974), ‘Abschreibungsgesellschaften, Kapitalmarkteffizienz und Publizitätszwang - Plädoyer für ein Vermögensanlagegesetz (Tax Shelter Companies, Efficiency of Capital Marke)’, 138 Zeitschrift für das gesamte Handels- und Wirtschaftsrecht, 1-49. Koller, Ingo (1981), ‘Die Verteilung des Scheckfälschungsrisikos zwischen Kunde und Bank (The Division of the False Cheque Risk Between Client and Bank)’, 27 Neue Juristische Wochenschrift, 2433 ff. Langbein, John H. and Posner Richard A. (1976), ‘Market Funds and Trust-investment Law’, 2 American Bar Foundation Research Journal, 1 ff. Langbein, John H. and Posner Richard A. (1977), ‘Market Funds and Trust-investment Law II’, 3 American Bar Foundation Research Journal. Leland, Hayne E. and Pyle, D.H. (1977), ‘Information Asymmetries, Financial Structure and Financial Intermediation’, 32 Journal of Finance, 371-387. Lesser, William and Madhavan, Ananth (1987), ‘Economic Impacts of a National Deposit Law: Cost Estimates and Policy Questions’, 21 Journal of Consumer Affairs, 122-140. Levmore, Saul (1981), ‘Bank Trust Departments and “Float” Revenue’, 98 Banking Law Journal, 817-837. Lindgren, James, Garcia, G. and Saal, M.I. (1996), Bank Soundness and Macroeconomic Policy, Washington, DC, International Monetary Fund. Litan, Robert E. (1985), ‘Evaluating and Controlling the Risks of Financial Product Deregulation’, 3 Yale Journal on Regulation, 1-52. Llewellyn, David T. (1991), ‘Capital Regulatory Convergence: The Basle Regime’, in Weigel, Wolfgang (ed.), Economic Analysis of Law - A Collection of Applications, Vienna, Österreichischer Wirtschaftsverlag, 146-162. Macey, Jonathan R. and Miller, Geoffrey P. (1990), ‘Good Finance, Bad Economics: An Analysis of the Fraud-on-the-Market Theory’, 42 Stanford Law Review, 1059-1092. Magoulas, Georgios and Fritz, Jost (1985), ‘Oikonomike Analyse tou Dikaiou - Provlemata ton Katanalotikon Pistoseon se Allodapous Ergazomenous kai Symbole sten Ermeneia tes 138 GermAK (Problems of Consumer Credit to Alien Workers and a Contribution to the Interpretation of 138 of the German Civil Code)’, 6 Scientific Review of the Thessaloniki Bar Association, 206-217. Mayer, Colin and Neven, D. (1991), ‘European Financial Regulation: a Framework for Policy Analysis’, in Giovannini, Alberto and Mayer, C. (eds), European Financial Integration, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
980
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
5850
McGee, Robert W. (ed.) (1998), Commentaries on the Law of Accounting and Finance, Dumont, NJ, Dumont Institute. Meier-Schatz, Christian (1989), ‘Europäische Harmonisierung des Gesellschafts- und Kapitalmarktrechts (European Harmonization of Company and Capital Market Law)’, 41 Wirtschaft und Recht, 84-110. Meigs, A. James (1988), ‘Evolution in Banking’, 7 Cato Journal, 799-802. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1985), ‘Interstate Banking in the Court, 1985’, 40 Supreme Court Review, 179 ff. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1986a), ‘Interstate Branching and the Constitution’, 41 Business Lawyer, 337 ff. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1986b), ‘Public Policy Implications of Legislation Limiting the Growth of Interstate Banks’, Federal Reserve Bank of Chicago, Proceedings of a Conference on Bank Structure and Competition 602, 602 ff. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1987), ‘The Future of the Dual Banking System,’, 53 Brooklyn Law Review, 1 ff. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1992), ‘Legal Restrictions on Bank Consolidation: An Economic Analysis’, 77 Iowa Law Review, 1083 ff. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1993a), ‘Comments on Calomiris, Structural Change in Banking 226’, in Klausner, M. and White, L. (eds), Structural Change in Banking, Homewood, IL, Richard D. Irwin, 566p. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1993b), ‘Drunken Sailors on a Sinking Ship? the Rehnquist Court and the Bank Failure Problem, 1993´, Public Interest Law Review, 83 ff. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1993c), ‘Comment (on Universal Banks and Financial Stability)’, 19 Brooklyn International Law Journal, 197 ff. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1994), ‘Politics of Deposit Insurance Reform: The Case of Argentina, Federal Reserve Bank of Chicago, Proceedings of a Conference on Bank Structure and Competition (republished as “Políticas de Reforma de Seguro de Depósito. El Caso de la Argentina”, in Revista de Derecho Bancario y de la Actividad Financiera, Año 4, Enero-diciembre 1994, No. 19/24, pp. 221-239)’, 473 Argentine Journal. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1996a), ‘Comments on Rajan and James, Universal Banking: Financial System Design Reconsidered’, in Saunders, A. and Walter, I. (eds), Universal Banking, Homewood, IL, Irwin, 330-333. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1996b), Decisionmaking at the Bank of Japan: A Legal-Economic Analysis, Draft. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1996c), ‘The Role of a Central Bank in a Bubble Economy’, Cardozo Law Review. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1996d), ‘Is Deposit Insurance Inevitable? the Case of Argentina’, in Bandhari, Jagdeep and Sykes, Alan (eds), International Law and Economics. Reprinted in International Review of Law and Economics. Miller, Geoffrey P. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1988), ‘Bank Failures, Risk Monitoring, and the Market for Corporate Control’, 88 Columbia Law Review, 1153 ff. Miller, Geoffrey P. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1991), ‘America’s Banking System: The Origins and Future of the Current Crisis’, 69 Washington University Law Quarterly, 769 ff. Miller, Geoffrey P. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1992a), ‘Double Liability of Bank Shareholders: History and Implications’, 27 Wake Forest Law Review, 31 ff.
5850
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
981
Miller, Geoffrey P. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1992b), ‘Nondeposit Deposits and the Future of Bank Regulation’, 91 Michigan Law Review, 237 ff. Miller, Geoffrey P. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1992c), ‘Bank Failure: The Politicization of A Social Problem’, 45 Stanford Law Review, 289 ff. Miller, Geoffrey P. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1992d), ‘Toward Enhanced Consumer Choice in Banking: Uninsured Depository Facilities As Financial Intermediaries for the 1990s, 1991', New York University Annual Survey of American Law, 865 ff. Miller, Geoffrey P. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1992e), Banking Law and Regulation. Miller, Geoffrey P. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1993a), ‘The Community Reinvestment Act: An Economic Analysis’, 79 Virginia Law Review, 291 ff. Miller, Geoffrey P. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1993b), ‘Double Liability of Bank Shareholders: A Look At the New Data’, 28 Wake Forest Law Review, 933 ff. Miller, Geoffrey P. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1993c), ‘Firrea and the Desirability of Early Closure: A View of the Kaye, Scholar Case From the Perspective of Bank Regulatory Policy’, 66 University of Southern California Law Review, 1115 ff. Miller, Geoffrey P., Litt, David, Macey, Jonathan R. and Rubin, Edward L. (1990), ‘Politics, Bureaucracies, and Financial Markets: Bank Entry into Commercial Paper Underwriting in the United States and Japan’, 139 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 20 ff. Miller, Merton H. and Modigliani, Franco (1958), ‘The Cost of Capital, Corporate Finance and the Theory of Finance’, 48 American Economic Review, 261 ff. Miller, Stephen M. (1988), ‘Counterfactual Experiments of Deregulation on Banking Structure’, 28(4) Quarterly Review of Economics and Business, 38-49. Mishkin, F. (1997), The Economics of Money Banking and Financial Markets, Reading, MA, Addison-Wesley. Mochizuki, Hiroshi and Murate, Satoshi (1987), ‘The Impact of Deregulation on Financial Markets in the United States and Japan: Is the Market Always Right?’, in Finn, Richard B. (ed.), U.S.-Japan Relations: A Surpising Partnership, New Brunswick, Transaction Books, 97-108. Möschel, Wernhard (1972), ‘Das Wirtschaftsrecht der Banken. Die Währungs-, Bankaufsichts-, Kartell- und EWG-rechtliche Sonderstellung der Kreditinstitute (Banking Law)’, in X. (ed.), Schriftenreihe Wirtschaftsrecht und Wirtschaftspolitik, Band 29, Frankfurt. Reprint in Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft, Baden-Baden, forthcoming. Möschel, Wernhard (1975a), ‘Kreditwirtschaft und Bereichsausnahme nach § 102 GWB (Credit Markets and Areas Exempt from Competition under § 102 GWB [German Antitrust Law])’, 139 Zeitschrift für das Gesamte Handels- und Wirtschaftsrecht, 347-361. Möschel, Wernhard (1975b), ‘Bankenrecht und Wirtschaftsordnung (Law of Banking and Economic Order)’, BB, 1025-1030. Möschel, Wernhard (1990), Internationaler Freihandel in Bankdienstleistungen, in Festschrift für Ernst Steindorff (International Free Trade in Banking Services), Berlin, Springer. Möschel, Wernhard (1993), ‘Privatisierung der Sparkassen. Zu den jüngsten Vorschlägen der Monopolkommission (The Privatization of Savings Banks)’, WM, 93-99. Mulherin, J. Harold and Muller, Walter J., III (1987), ‘Volatile Interest Rates and the Divergence of Incentives in Mortgage Contracts’, 3 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 99-115.
982
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
5850
Myhrman, Johan, Hörngren, Lars, Viotti, Staffan and Eliasson, Gunnar (1987), Kreditmarknadens Spelregler (The Rules of the Game on the Credit Market), Stockholm, SNS Publishing Company. Neave, Edwin H. (1989), ‘Canada’s Approach to Financial Regulation’, 15 Canadian Public Policy, 1-11. Ng, Kenneth (1988), ‘Free Banking Laws and Barriers to Entry in Banking, 1838-1860', 48 Journal of Economic History, 877-889. O’Driscoll, Gerald P., Jr (1976), ‘The American Express Case: Public Good or Monopoly?’, 19 Journal of Law and Economics, 163-175. O’Driscoll, Gerald P., Jr (1986), ‘Deregulation and Monetary Reform’, Federal Reserve Bank of Dallas Economic Review, 19-31. O’Driscoll, Gerald P., Jr. (1988), ‘Deposit Insurance in Theory and Practice’, 7 Cato Journal, 661-675. Ordover, Janusz A. and Weiss, Andrew (1981), ‘Information and the Law: Evaluating Legal Restrictions on Competitive Contracts’,71 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 399-404. Ott, Claus and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (1991), ‘Ökonomische Auswirkungen der EG-Insider-Regulierung in Deutschland (Economic Consequences of the EG Insider Regulation in Germany)’, Zeitschrift für Bankrecht und Bankwirtschaft, 226-241. Pacolet, J. (1987), ‘Financiële Instellingen en Markten: 1. Deposito-Instellingen (Financial Institutions and Markets: Depository Institutions)’, in X (ed.), 18de Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Brussel 8 en 9 mei 1987, Sociaal-economische Deregulering, Brussel, V.E.H.U.B., 623-647. Paroush, P. (1988), ‘The Domino Effect and the Supervision of the Banking Systems’, 43 Journal of Finance, 1207-1218. Peltzman, Sam (1965), ‘Entry in Commercial Banking’, 8 Journal of Law and Economics, 11-50. Peltzman, Sam (1965), ‘Bank Entry Regulation: Its Impact and Purpose’, Dec. National Banking Review. U.S. Treasury, Studies in Banking Competition and the Banking Structure, Washington, 1966 Peltzman, Sam (1968), ‘Bank Stock Prices and Effects of Regulation of the Banking Structure’, Oct. Journal of Business. Peltzman, Sam (1969), ‘The Banking Structure and the Transmission of Monetary Policy’, June Journal of Finance. Peltzman, Sam (1970), ‘Capital Investment in Commercial Banking and Its Relationship to Bank Portfolio Regulation’, Jan./Feb. Journal of Political Economy. Peltzman, Sam (1972), ‘The Costs of Competition: An Appraisal of the Hunt Commission Report’, Nov. Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking. Peltzman, Sam (1979), ‘Comment (on R. Schotland, ‘Conflicts of Interest Within the Financial Firm: Regulatory Implications’)’, in Edwards, F. (ed.), Issues In Financial Regulation, New York, McGraw-Hill. Peltzman, Sam (1984), ‘Comment (on “Bank Market Structure and Competition: A Survey”)’, 16 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking. Pettway, Richard H., Tapley, T. Craig and Yamada, Takeshi (1988), ‘The Impacts of Financial Deregulation upon Trading Efficiency and the Levels of Risk and Return of Japanese Banks’, 23 Financial Review, 243-268.
5850
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
983
Pinto, Arthur R. (1989), ‘The Third Abraham L. Pomerantz Lecture the First Amendment and Government Regulation of Economic Markets: The Nature of the Capital Markets Allows a Greater Role for the Government’, 55 Brooklyn Law Review, 77 ff. Pollefliet, E. (1988), ‘1992: Regulering of Deregulering van de Financiële Sector? (1992: Regulation or Deregulation of the Financial Sector?)’, 42 Economisch en Sociaal Tijdschrift, 631-654. Pyle, D.H. (1974), ‘The Losses on Savings Deposits from Interest Rate Regulation’, 5 Bell Journal of Economics, 614-622. Ramseyer, J. Mark (1995), ‘Explicit Reasons for Implicit Contracts: The Legal Logic To the Japanese Main Bank System’, in Masahiko, Aoki and Patrick, Hugh T. (eds), The Japanese Main Bank System: Its Relevance For Developing and Transforming Economies, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 231 ff. Ramseyer, J. Mark (1991), ‘Legal Rules in Repeated Deals: Banking in the Shadow of Defection in Japan’, 20 Journal of Legal Studies, 91 ff. Rasmusen, Eric (1988), ‘Mutual Banks and Stock Markets’, 31 Journal of Law and Economics, 395-421. Richter, Rudolf (1990), ‘Banking Regulations as Seen by the New Institutional Economics’, in Furubotn, Eirik and Richter, R. (eds), ‘The Economics and Law of Banking Regulation’, Occasional Papers, vol.2, Germany, Saarbrucken, University of Saarlandes, Center for the Study of the New Institutional Economics, 135-160. Richter, Rudolf (1991), ‘Bankenregulierung aus der Sicht der Neuen Institutionenökonomik (Regulation of Banks from the Viewpoint of the New Institutional Economics)’, in Siebke, J. (ed.), Finanzintermediation, Bankenregulierung und Finanzmarktintegration, Berlin, Duncker and Humblot, 43-64. Rieber, Michael (1967), ‘Bids Bid Patterns and Collusion in the Auction Market for Treasury Bills’, 10 Journal of Law and Economics, 149-168. Roe, Mark J. (1991), ‘A Political Theory of American Corporate Finance’, 91 Columbia Law Review, 10-67. Rubinstein, M.E. (1973), ‘Jan Mossin’s Theory of Financial Markets’, 4 Bell Journal of Economics, 693-699. Salyzyn, Vladimir (1962), ‘Limitations on Asset Acquisition and the Competition for Savings Deposits’, 5 Journal of Law and Economics, 93-102. Saunders, Anthony, Strock, Elizabeth and Travlos, Nickolaos G. (1990), ‘Ownership Structure, Deregulation, and Bank Risk Taking’, 45 Journal of Finance, 643-654. Schäfer, Hans-Bernd and Ott, Claus (1991), ‘Ökonomische Auswirkungen der EG-Insider-Regulierung in Deutschland (Economic Effects of the EU Insider Regulation)’, 3 Zeitschrift für Bankrecht und Bankwirtschaft, 226 ff. Schanze, Erich (1977), ‘Anlegerschutz bei Aktienfonds, Das Indexfonds-Konzept (Shareholder Protection)’, 22 Die Aktiengesellschaft, 102-107. Schanze, Erich (1986), Investitionsverträge im Internationalen Wirtschaftsrecht (Investment Contracts in International Economic), Frankfurt a.M., Metzner, 305 p. Schmidt, Reinhard H. and Koch, Hans-Dieter (1981), ‘Ziele und Instrumente des Anlegerschutzes (Goals and Means of Investor Protection)’, 33(3) Betriebswirtschaftliche Forschung und Praxis, 29-48. Schmidt, Reinhard H., Ballwieser, W., Böcking, H.-J. and Drukarczyk, Jochen (1994),Bilanzrecht und Kapitalmarkt, Festschrift zum 65. Geburtstag von Adolf Moxter (Accounting Law and Capital Markets), Düsseldorf.
984
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
5850
Sevic, Zeljko (1994a), Komisioni Posao u Bankarskom Pravu (Undisclosed Agency Operations Commission Transactions in the Banking Law), Belgrade, Cigoja-stampa. Sevic, Zeljko (1994b), Pravni status Centralne Banke u Savremenoj Trzisnoj Privredi (Status of the Central Bank in a Contemporary Market Economy), Belgrade, Faculty of Law, University of Belgrade. Sevic, Zeljko (1995), ‘Svojinski Oblici i Efikasnost Funkcionisanja Bankarskog Sistema (Property Forms and the Banking System Efficiency)’, 9 Pravni zivot, 647-660. Sevic, Zeljko (1996a), ‘Odnos Centralne Banke i Izvrsne Vlasti (Relationship between the Central Bank and Executive Power)’, 1-2 Jugoslovensko Bankarstvo, 29-36. Sevic, Zeljko (1996b), Law and Economics I: Ekonomska Analiza Prava Svojine u Tranziciji (Law and Economics I: Economic Analysis of the Property Rights in Transition), Pravni zivot. Sevic, Zeljko (1996c), ‘Bankarstvo i Bankarsko Pravo: Neka Otvorena Pitanja Samostalnosti Bankarskog Prava (Banking and Banking Law: Some Open Questions on Banking Law Independence)’, 51(11-12) Finansije, 964-977. Sevic, Zeljko (1996d), Centralna Banka: Polozaj - Organizacija - Funkcije (Central Bank: Position - Organization - Functions), Belgrade, Cigoja-stampa. Sevic, Zeljko and Sevic, Aleksandar (1997), ‘Centralna Banka i Finansijska Trzista (Central Bank and Financial Markets)’, 27(1-2) Jugoslovensko Bankarstvo, 28-34. Shughart, William F., II (1988), ‘A Public Choice Perspective of the Banking Act of 1933', 7 Cato Journal, 595-613. Shull, Bernard (1983), ‘The Separation of Banking and Commerce: Origin, Development, and Implications for Antitrust’, 28 Antitrust Bulletin, 255-279. Skogh, Göran (1976), ‘Ett Alternativ till den Föreslagna Konsumentkreditlagen (An Alternative to the Proposed Consumer Credit Law)’, Svensk Juristtidning, 542-547. Smith, Bruce D. (1988), ‘Legal Restrictions, “Sunspots”, and Peel’s Bank Act: The Real Bills Doctrine Versus the Quantity Theory Reconsidered’, 96 Journal of Political Economy, 3-19. Smith, Vernon L. (1976), ‘The Borrower-Lender Relationship’, 66 American Economic Review, 406-407. Spierings, Renee (1990), ‘Reflections on the Regulation of Financial Intermediaries’, 43 Kyklos, 91-109. Stout, Lynn A. (1988), ‘The Unimportance of Being Efficient: An Economic Analysis of Stock Market Pricing and Securities Regulation’, 87 Michigan Law Review, 613-709. Stout, Lynn A. (1995a), ‘Agreeing to Disagree over Excessive Trading’, 81 Virginia Law Review, 751 ff. Stout, Lynn A. (1995b), ‘Betting the Bank: How Derivatives Trading Under Conditions of Uncertainty Can Increase Risks and Erode Returns in Financial Markets’, 21 Journal of Corporate Law, 53 ff. Stout, Lynn A. (1995c), ‘Are Stock Markets Costly Casinos? Disagreement, Market Failure, and Securities Regulation’, 81 Virginia Law Review, 611 ff. Stout, Lynn A. (1996), ‘Insurance or Gambling? Derivatives Trading in a World of Risk and Uncertainty’, 39 Brookings Review. Takigawa, Yoshio (1986), ‘Deregulation of Interest Rate and Bank Rate Policy’, 0(32) Kobe University Economics Review, 121-137. Terberger, Eva (1994), ‘Kommentar zu Picot, Arnold/Dietl, Helmut, Informations (de-)Regulierung am Kapitalmarkt aus Institutionenökonomischer Sicht (New Institutional Economics and the (De-)Regulation of Insider Trading)’, 13 Jahrbuch für Neue Politische Ökonomie, 143-148.
5850
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
985
Terberger, Eva (1995), ‘Bankenaufsicht (Regulation of Banks)’, in Gerke, Wolfgang and Steiner, Manfred (eds), Handwörterbuch des Finanz- und Bankwesens, Band 6, 2. Aufl., Stuttgart, 151-163. Thomson, James B. and Todd, Walker F. (1990), ‘Rethinking and Living with the Limits of Bank Regulation’, 9 Cato Journal, 579-600. Thurow, Lester C. (1985), ‘The Politics of Deregulation and Evolution of the Major Banks and the Financial Intermediaries in the U.S.A.’, 3 Review of the Economic Conditions in Italy, 353-362. Triantis, George G. (1986), ‘Allocation of Losses from Forged Indorsements on Checks and the Application of Section 3-405 of the Uniform Commercial Code’, 39 Oklahoma Law Review, 669-668. Tseng, Wang-Run (1996), ‘Capital Structure and the Regulation of Disclosure’, 25(4) National Taiwan University Law Journal, 279-317. Van Cayseele, Patrick (1992), ‘Regulation and Financial Market Integration’, in Steinherr, A. (ed.), The New European Financial Market Place, London and New York, Longman, 68-78. Van Cayseele, Patrick and Heremans, Dirk (1991), ‘Legal Principles of Financial Market Integration in 1992: An Economic Analysis’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 83-99. Van den Bergh, P. (1987), ‘Deregulering van de Internationale Financiële Stromen en Valutastelsel (Deregulation of the International Financial Flaws and Exchange System)’, XXX18de Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Brussel 8 en 9 mei 1987, Sociaal-economische Deregulering, 845-878. Varela, Oscar and Olson, Richard E. (1986), ‘A General Equilibrium Analysis of Financial Regulation’, 30 Journal of Public Economics, 329-340. Wall, Richard A. and Gort, Michael (1988), ‘Financial Markets and the Limits of Regulation’, 9(1) Managerial and Decision Economics, 65-73. Walz, W. Rainer (1993), ‘Ökonomische Regulierungstheorie vor den Toren des Bilanzrechts (Economic Theory of Regulation and Accounting Law)’,82 Zeitschrift für Betriebswirtschaftliche Forschung. Walz, W. Rainer (1996), ‘Rechtspolitik und Betriebswirtschaftslehre angesichts der Internationalisierung des Bilanzrechts (Legal Policy, Business Administration, and the Internationalization of Accounting Law)’, in Sadowski, D., Czap, H. and Wächter, H. (eds), Regulierung der Unternehmenspolitik. Methoden und Kritik der betriebswirtschaftlichen Rechtsanalyse, Wiesbaden, Gabler, 23-49. Wehrt, Klaus (1991), ‘Die BGH-Urteile zur Tilgungsverrechnung - Nur die Spitze des Eisbergs, Der korrekt abgerechnete Hypothekenbankkredit (The Judgements of the German Supreme Court Concerning the Reimbursement of Wrongly Calculated Interest Payments, a Critical Economic Review)’, 24 Betriebs-Berater, 1645-1655. Wehrt, Klaus (1994), ‘Zur Zinsfälligkeitsabrede, die eine Unterjährige Zahlungsverpflichtung Enthält, Anmerkung zum BGH-Urteil vom 5.10.93 - XI ZR 35/93 (An Interest Clause which Fixes the Periods for the Interest Payments, a Remark to a Judgement of the German Supreme Court)’, 3 Juristenzeitung, 155-157.
986
Regulation of Banking and Financial Markets
5850
Wehrt, Klaus (1994), ‘Die wettbewerbliche Funktion transparenter Zinsfälligkeitsabreden (The Competitive Function of Transparent Interest Clauses)’, 2 Zeitschrift für Bankrecht und Bankwirtschaft, 161-171. Wehrt, Klaus (1997), ‘Vorfälligkeitsentschädigung und Wettbewerb, Mögliche wettbewerbliche Auswirkungen der Rechtsprechung zur vorzeitigen Ablösung von Festzinsdarlehen (Possible Competitive Effects of the Jurisdiction According the Prepayment of Mortgages)’, 1 Zeitschrift für Bankrecht und Bankwirtschaft. Weisbrod, Steven R. (1988), ‘Regulation of International Banking: A Review Essay’, 22 Journal of Monetary Economics, 347-352. West, Richard R. (1973), ‘Bond Ratings, Bond Yields and Financial Regulation: Some Findings’, 16 Journal of Law and Economics, 159-168. White, Lawrence J. (1986), ‘The Partial Deregulation of Banks and Other Depository Institutions’, in Weiss, Leonard W. and Klass, Michael W. (eds), Regulatory Reform: What Actually Happened, Boston, Little Brown, 169-209. White, Lawrence J. (1990), ‘The S&L Debacle: How it Happened and Why Further Reforms are Needed’, 13(1) Regulation, 11-16. X (1985), ‘Note: Consumer Protection and Payment Systems: Policy for the Technological Era’, 98 Harvard Law Review, 1870-1889. Zdrahal, Peter (1991), ‘Comment (on Llewellyn, Capital Regulatory Convergence)’, in Weigel, Wolfgang (ed.), Economic Analysis of Law - A Collection of Applications, Vienna, Österreichischer Wirtschaftsverlag, 164-166.
Other References Heremans, Dirk (1981), ‘The Complementary Nature of Competition and Regulation in the Financial Sector’, in Verheirstraeten, A. (ed.), Competition and Regulation in Financial Markets, London, Macmillan, 32-34. Heremans, Dirk (1991), ‘Hervorming van de Beursmarkt in België. Kon het Niet Eenvoudiger en Efficiënter’, in Schrans, G. and Wymeersch, E. (eds), Financiële Herregulering in België (Reform of the Stock Market. Financial Regulation in Belgium), Antwerpen, Kluwer Rechtswetenschappen 171-182. Heremans, Dirk (1993), ‘Economic Aspects of the Second Banking Directive and of the Proposal for a Directive on Investment Services in the Securities Field’, in Stuyck, J. (ed.), Financial and Monetary Integration in the European Community. Legal, Institutional and Economic Aspects, Deventer, Kluwer, 37-55. Heremans, Dirk (1994), ‘Economic Aspects of the Banking and Investment Services Directive in a European Economic Area’, in Stuyck, J. and Looijestijn-Clearie, A. (eds), The European Economic Area EC-EFTA, Deventer, Kluwer, 105-117. Heremans, Dirk and Cousy, Herman (1996), Financial Markets and Insurance, Essays in Law and Economics III, Antwerpen, Maklu Publishers, 277 p.
5860 REGULATION OF THE LEGAL PROFESSION Frank H. Stephen and James H. Love University of Strathclyde, Glasgow, United Kingdom © Copyright 1999 Frank H. Stephan and James H. Love
Abstract This chapter reviews the contribution which economists, and others using economic modes of reasoning, have made to the analysis of the regulation of law firms. It particularly focuses on the analysis of self-regulation by the profession. The chapter begins by rehearsing the traditional cartel argument against self-regulation and its links with the modern private interest theory of regulation via capture theory. This is contrasted with the market failure view of regulation which in the context of the professions focuses on the information asymmetry between the professional and the client. There is then a brief discussion of the merits of self-regulation and inter-profession competition before turning to an examination of the instruments by which professional regulation is exercised: control of entry, control of advertising or other means of competition, control of fee levels, control of fee contracts and control of organisational form. In this context, prominence is given to recent empirical studies which test the effects of these regulatory controls or their removal. The focus throughout is on what the economics literature has had to say on the regulation of the practice of law. Thus more general treatments of the economics of the law firm are not discussed. JEL classification: L12, L43, L44, L84, L51, M37 Keywords: Legal Profession, Regulation, Advertising, Entry Restrictions, Fee Levels, Fee Contracts, Empirical Studies
1. Introduction In most jurisdictions one or more of the following is regulated in some manner: a. the provision of advice about the law for financial reward; b. the use of specific professional titles indicating expertise in legal matters; c. the right to appear on behalf of one of the parties before the courts. Whilst ultimately governed by statute and subject to oversight by some public official (judge, civil servant or politician) this regulation is frequently enforced and delimited by the profession itself (see further below). This article reviews the contribution which economists, and others using economic modes
987
988
Regulation of the Legal Profession
5860
of reasoning, have made to the analysis of such regulatory regimes. We begin by rehearsing the traditional cartel argument against self-regulation and its links with the modern private interest theory of regulation via capture theory. This is contrasted with the market failure view of regulation which in the context of the professions focuses on the information asymmetry between the professional and the client. There is then a brief discussion of the merits of self-regulation and inter-profession competition before turning to an examination of the instruments by which professional regulation is exercised: control of entry, control of advertising or other means of competition, control of fee levels, control of fee contracts and control of organisational form. In this context we give prominence to recent empirical studies which test the effects of these regulatory controls or their removal. The focus throughout is on what the economics literature has had to say on the regulation of the practice of law. Thus more general treatments of the economics of the law firm are not discussed.
A. Regulation of Professions, Capture and Cartels 2. Economists’ Views Economists, traditionally, have been highly critical of many aspects of professional regulation and self-regulation in particular (see, for example, Arnauld, 1972; Arnauld and Friedland, 1977; Benham and Benham, 1975; Faure et al., 1993; Friedman and Kuznets, 1945; Kessel, 1958; Lees, 1966; Leffler, 1978). Self-regulation is characterised as, potentially, having the effect of a cartel: by controlling entry to the market and setting an agreed price above the competitive price, members of the profession earn economic rents. Restrictions on advertising and prohibitions on using fee-levels to attract business restrain competition from ‘breaking out’ between existing suppliers. It has been argued that restricting fee competition, particularly by publishing mandatory or recommended fee scales, reduces competition and innovation and is against the public interest (Arnauld, 1972; Arnauld and Friedland, 1977; Domberger and Sherr, 1989; Monopolies and Mergers Commission, 1970; Van den Bergh and Faure, 1991). Whilst the earlier literature was written from a price theory/industrial organisation perspective, more recently critics have adopted a capture theory or public choice perspective (Van den Bergh and Faure, 1991; Faure, 1993; Van den Bergh, 1993). This is not surprising since in the development of the private interest theory of regulation from capture theory Posner (1974) made a direct link with the theory of cartels. Indeed, self-regulation has been described as the ultimate form of regulatory capture (Kay, 1988). From this perspective the regulation of markets for professional services is seen to arise or at least is sustained because it is in the interests of
5860
Regulation of the Legal Profession
989
the members of the profession. It legitimises or enforces their cartel-like behaviour.
3. Market Failure and Information Asymmetry An older, though nowadays less fashionable, view of regulation is that it arises from a public interest in remedying market failure (Noll, 1989). Notwithstanding the origins or motivations underlying regulation, many would argue that there is a potential market failure in many professional markets. The particular market failure that applies to professional markets in general, and the markets for legal services in particular, is that of information asymmetry. The asymmetry is between the professional on the one hand and the client on the other. For most clients legal services are credence goods (Darby and Karni, 1973) as opposed to search or experience goods. The client is usually less well informed about the nature of legal problems and their remedies than the lawyer and often relies on the lawyer to define the problem in the first place as well as recommending a course of action and implementing it (but see further below). Quinn (1982) distinguishes between two roles: the agency function (defining the client’s needs and selecting appropriate strategies) and the service function (using technical expertise to implement the chosen strategy). Normally in the legal context the lawyer performs both functions. Thus there is a potentially severe principal-agent problem (potentially encompassing supplier-induced demand). The lawyer as agent has a pecuniary interest in recommending expensive strategies which he/she will be paid to implement. This demands some protection for the (infrequent) consumer of personal professional services (see, for example, Arruñada, 1996; Dingwall and Fenn, 1987; Evans and Trebilcock, 1982; Faure, 1993; Faure et al., 1993; Federal Trade Commission, 1984; Helligman, 1993; Herrmann, 1993; Kritzer, 1990; Levmore, 1993; Matthews, 1991; Smith and Cox, 1985; Sykes, 1993; Wolfram, 1984). Under these conditions the market will fail to produce the socially optimum quantity of the professional service. Protection of consumers frequently takes the form of regulation of the profession and its markets. In certain circumstances, contingent fee contracts may mitigate or overcome some aspects of this problem (see further Part E below). It is important to recognise that the informational asymmetry identified here does not apply to all clients of lawyers. Many commercial clients are repeat purchasers in the market for legal services. Therefore they are able to acquire experience and knowledge of the market which reduces the asymmetry between lawyer and client. They are less in need of the agency function than infrequent purchasers. Furthermore in the case of repeat purchasers, lawyers must be aware of the loss of future business from behaving opportunistically. They must also be aware of reputational effects which may arise from social networks even
990
Regulation of the Legal Profession
5860
where individual consumers are not repeat purchasers. Thus the information asymmetry argument does not carry over to all segments of the market for legal services (Hudec and Trebilcock, 1982; Trebilcock, 1982). It has its principal relevance in the market for private clients and small businesses. Thus although the information asymmetry argument is now well recognised its application must be sensitive to the circumstances of the market concerned. Recently, Emons (1997) has analysed a model of behaviour in a credence good market where, essentially, the service function cannot be provided separately from the agency function. He describes this as a situation of ‘profound economies of scope between diagnosis and treatment’. Consumers attempt to infer sellers incentives from observation of market data. The analysis demonstrates that market equilibria inducing non-fraudulent behaviour can exist. The information asymmetry between professional and client also gives rise to another potential source of market failure due to the client’s inability to judge, ex ante, the quality of the professional. In the extreme this can give rise to a ‘lemons’ problem (Akerlof, 1970). The use of licensing to avoid this problem is analysed in Leland (1979). The author concludes that the optimal supply of quality will not be produced in a market with asymmetry between client and supplier and that minimum quality standards may solve the problem. Clearly it will be in the interests of the profession to avoid a ‘lemons’ problem arising. However, Leland’s analysis suggests that if the setting of minimum standards is by the professional group itself it is likely to be set too high.
4. Professional Self-Regulation Dingwall and Fenn (1987) consider a number of possible responses to the information asymmetry problem. First, society could subsidise high quality suppliers to ensure that they remain in the market. Secondly, penalties could be imposed on those suppliers who do not meet some quality threshold. Thirdly, entry to the market could be restricted to those meeting some minimum standard. They consider the first implausible since it does not guarantee that the higher quality service will actually be supplied. The second and third response requires a regulatory agency which must avoid capture and be able to do what the individual client cannot: assess quality and signal it to potential consumers. Self-regulation can do the latter but runs the risk of being the ultimate form of regulatory capture. However, they argue that if self-regulation was so problematic why does it persist in most jurisdictions? If it were inefficient someone would benefit from its removal otherwise democracy itself would be inefficient. Dingwall and Fenn (1987) see self-regulation as arising from the social institution of trust: a social contract between society and the profession
5860
Regulation of the Legal Profession
991
mitigates the moral hazard problem arising from the information asymmetry. However, they recognise that safeguards are required, particularly to ensure that the profession does not operate as a cartel. They also feel that the various professions will act as watchdogs on each other. The case for self-regulation has been examined in detail also in Ogus (1995). He points to a number of reasons why self-regulation might be preferred to regulation by some body external to the profession. In particular, self-regulation may reduce the cost of the regulator acquiring information and makes adjustments to regulations easier. These benefits need to be compared to the potential efficiency losses due to the potential for cartel-like behaviour. Curran (1993) reports J.C. Miller, Chairman of the Federal Trade Commission in the Reagan administration, making similar arguments for self-regulation (Miller, 1983). Even where regulation by a professional body is deemed an appropriate solution Ogus (1995) has argued that the public interest would be protected best by having a number of professional bodies in competition with each other. As implied in the foregoing, in many jurisdictions the regulation of a profession is in the hands of the members of the profession itself, either nationally or locally. This is usually the case with the legal profession (Arruñada, 1996; Curran, 1993; Dingwall and Fenn, 1987; Evans and Trebilcock, 1982; Faure, 1993; Federal Trade Commission, 1984; Finsinger, 1993; Helligman, 1993; Herrmann, 1993; Lees, 1966; Ogus, 1993; Pashigian, 1979; Stephen, 1994; Stephen and Love, 1996; Stephen, Love and Paterson, 1994; Van den Bergh, 1993). A more formal treatment of professional self-regulation is provided in Shaked and Sutton (1981a) which examines the effects on welfare of a self-regulating profession and also the effect on welfare of the existence of a lower quality para-profession. Shaked and Sutton (1982) focuses on the perceived quality of a profession and the availability of information. In particular, information available to consumers is related to the size of the profession: a larger profession increases the heterogeneity of information available to consumers and increases the demand at a given price. A small profession (whose quality is higher) will produce less information and reduce demand. Thus increased quality may be associated with lower price. In this work the motive force comes from the consumer side.
5. Alternatives to Self-Regulation Regulation may not be the only solution to the information asymmetry problem. Independent rating agencies have been suggested as a solution or the use of repeat purchasers to perform the agency function on behalf of infrequent purchasers (Stephen, Love and Paterson, 1994; Stephen and Love, 1996). Others suggest that competition will generate its own quality signals (Klein and
992
Regulation of the Legal Profession
5860
Leffler, 1981; Leffler, 1978). Fama and Jensen (1983a, 1983b) and Carr and Mathewson (1990) suggest that the existence of partnerships with unlimited liability signals the quality of legal advice to consumers because each partner is willing to risk his/her wealth on the competence of the other partners (see further below for the development of this argument). Even if the information asymmetry problem is large its removal via professional self-regulation may introduce other, greater, distortions (Curran, 1993).
6. Deregulation of Professional Service Markets In both academic and policy discussion there has been a gradual shift against regulation, a shift which has quickened in pace in recent years. Markets for legal services have been the subject of varying degrees of deregulation in USA, Europe and elsewhere (see, for example, Bowles, 1994; Cox, 1989; Curran, 1993; Domberger and Sherr, 1987; Faure, 1993; Federal Trade Commission, 1984; Helligman, 1993; Herrman, 1993; Ogus, 1993; Paterson and Stephen, 1990; Shinnick, 1995; Stephen and Love, 1996; and Scottish Home and Health Department, 1989). In several jurisdictions there have been proposals by government to remove the general exemption of professions from anti-trust or restrictive practices legislation. However, not all such attempts have reached the statute book (for example England and Wales, Ireland, Scotland, Spain).
7. Instruments of Self-Regulation The current state of the discussion in the conceptual literature is such that although some authors recognise the potential problem arising from the asymmetry of information between client and professional, considerable scepticism remains on whether traditional self-regulation is a solution to the problem or a source of even greater welfare loss. The remainder of this paper considers that part of the literature which examines the instruments used by self-regulatory bodies for the legal profession to regulate the market. In particular, we emphasise empirical studies of regulation and de-regulation. The lack of discussion in the economics literature on some aspects of self-regulatory systems such as complaints procedures, controls on quality of training and requirements for continuing professional development and so on is reflected in their absence in what follows. Commentators (Cox, 1989; Curran, 1993; Domberger and Sherr, 1987, 1989; Evans and Trebilcock, 1982; Faure, 1993; Finsinger, 1993; Federal Trade Commission, 1984; Scottish Home and Health Department, 1989; Stephen, 1994; Stephen and Love, 1996; Stephen, Love and Paterson, 1994;
5860
Regulation of the Legal Profession
993
Van den Bergh, 1993) have identified a number of instruments typically used by self-regulators of the legal profession which may work against the public interest: (i) restrictions on entry; (ii) restrictions on advertising and other means of promoting a competitive process within the profession; (iii) restrictions on fee competition; and (iv) restrictions on organisational form. A separate although connected literature has developed on restrictions on the nature of fee contracts between lawyers and clients. This particularly focuses on contingent fee contracts (see, for example, Clermont and Currivan, 1973; Dana and Spier, 1993; Danzon, 1983; Fisher, 1988; Gravelle and Waterson, 1993; Halpern and Turnbull, 1981; Hay, 1996; Kritzer, et al., 1984; Lynk, 1990; Miceli, 1994; Miceli and Segerson, 1991; Rickman, 1994; Rubinfeld and Scotchmer, 1993; Schwartz and Mitchell, 1970; Smith, 1992; Thomason, 1991; Watts, 1994). We now discuss each of these methods of self-regulatory control in turn.
B. Entry Restrictions 8. Entry to the Profession Economists (for example Friedman and Kuznets, 1945; Leffler, 1978) have criticised restrictions on entry to a profession or restrictions on providing a particular service by persons not recognised by a particular professional body. This can undoubtedly lead to supply shortages and hence the earning of substantial economic rents by members the profession. However, it not only requires a monopoly right for the profession over a particular service but also numerical restrictions on entry to the profession. Thus an excess demand for the services of the profession is maintained. The monopoly right ensures that an adjustment in supply from outside the profession cannot take place in response to the profession’s high incomes. In the most famous study, Friedman and Kuznets (1945) estimated economic rents of 15-110 percent being earned by professionals in the US during the 1929-36 period. This is the global effect of self-regulation and is not solely attributable to entry restrictions. Entry to the legal profession has continued to grow (for Europe see Bowles, 1994; Faure, 1993; Helligman, 1993; Herrmann, 1993; Ogus, 1993) for USA see Curran (1993) and Lueck, Olsen and Ransom (1995). Indeed as Curran (1993) points out the American Bar Association has been less successful than its medical counterpart in limiting the growth of the profession. It has not regulated the numbers qualifying to practice in the same way as the American Medical Association. Of course, established members of the profession may have an interest in encouraging an expansion of new entry to the lower reaches of the profession as this might reduce the salaries paid to new entrants due to excess supply. However, this argument only holds so long as the new entrants
994
Regulation of the Legal Profession
5860
to the profession are unable to provide the basis for an increase in the number of law firms and thus compete away the rents earned by existing firms. However, the absence of severe restrictions on entry to the profession in general does not necessarily imply competition in specific service markets. Professional service markets, particularly of a personal nature, tend to be spatially localised. What may be important are geographical restrictions on movement which imply barriers to entry into specific service markets for existing members of the profession. In a number of jurisdictions lawyers may only appear before courts in the local area to whose bar they have been admitted (USA, Belgium, Germany, for example). In the case of legal advice, even when there are no formal restrictions on practising in a given locality, other restrictions on behaviour such as prohibiting advertising may raise the cost of entry (through an inability to quickly generate goodwill) and thus constitute a barrier to entering a specific spatial market. Alternatively prohibitions on ‘undercutting’ or ‘supplanting’ existing suppliers may reduce the incentive to enter a local market where rents are being earned. Thus, although there may be no formal barriers to entering a local market, such markets may not be contestable.
9. Empirical Studies of Entry to the Profession Economists’ empirical studies of the effects of such mobility restrictions for the legal profession are restricted to the USA. They find, for example, that lack of reciprocity between state bar associations leads lower numbers of practising lawyers and higher lawyer incomes (Holen, 1965; Kleiner, Gay and Green, 1982; Pashigian, 1977). However, a recent empirical study by Lueck, Olsen and Ransom (1995) finds little support for the view that licensing restrictions affect the price of legal services. Their evidence suggests that it is what they describe as ‘market forces’ which are most important. Licensing restrictions are proxied by requirements to pass a state bar exam, state bar exam pass rates, state residency requirements and requirement of an ABA recognised law school degree. Although they find that there is a relationship between state lawyer density, state bar exam pass rates and the requirement of an ABA recognised degree the effect is in the opposite direction to that hypothesised by the capture theory, that is, the lower the pass rate the higher is lawyer density, and the latter is higher in states requiring an ABA recognised degree. Although the authors argue that their evidence runs counter to the implications of the capture theory they do find that the higher are state bar exam pass rates the lower are lawyer fees.
5860
Regulation of the Legal Profession
995
10. Professional ‘Monopoly Rights’ The preceding paragraphs have focused on controls on entry to the legal profession itself. Often, as discussed above, this has been accompanied by the exclusive rights given to the legal profession over certain services. Many writers commenting on the regulatory regimes governing the legal profession draw attention to ‘monopoly rights’ in certain areas of work and criticise this on a priori grounds. However, little empirical work has been done by economists to estimate the effects of professional monopoly rights and the existence of para-professions. This may be due, in part, to the absence of data sets which allow variations in such monopoly rights either over time or location to be studied. Even during the current deregulation wave there has been little empirical work estimating the effects of relaxing monopoly rights. Para-professions sometimes exist alongside professions with the right to provide services which overlap with some of those provided by a profession. There has been limited analysis of profession/para-profession interaction. Shaked and Sutton (1981a) examines the effects on welfare of the existence of a lower quality para-profession operating alongside a self-regulating profession. Shaked and Sutton (1981b) looks at the viability of a para-profession when there are consumers with different incomes but identical preferences. In this context the para-profession’s viability depends on the relative sizes of the two income groups of consumers. A series of studies of the deregulation of legal services in England and Wales between 1985 and 1992 which focuses on conveyancing (title transfer) services provides some limited insights on the relaxation of a profession’s monopoly rights and the impact of a para-profession. Until the mid-1980s solicitors had the exclusive right to provide conveyancing services for financial reward. This monopoly was revoked in 1985 and by 1987 the first licensed conveyancers (non-solicitors licensed to provide these services) were offering services in competition with solicitors in some areas of the country (Stephen and Love, 1996; Stephen, Love and Paterson, 1994). Paterson et al. (1988) report that solicitors surveyed in 1986 were reducing fees in anticipation of licensed conveyancer entry. Later surveys, however, provide a more complex picture of the effects of entry. Survey data for 1989 revealed solicitors’ conveyancing fees in a sample of locations where licensed conveyancers had entered as compared to those where there were no licensed conveyancers were lower (Love et al., 1992) and were less likely to involve price discrimination (Stephen et al., 1993). These results appear to support the conventional view that monopoly rights will operate to the disadvantage of clients of lawyers. A subsequent survey conducted in 1992 and covering the same locations as the earlier surveys produced results less conducive to the traditional economic view. Both the conveyancing fees of solicitors in markets where there were
996
Regulation of the Legal Profession
5860
licensed conveyancers and those of licensed conveyancers had risen between 1989 and 1992 by more than those in markets where there were no licensed conveyancers; in addition licensed conveyancers’ feeing practices were more like those of solicitors than before (Stephen, Love and Paterson, 1994). There is the suggestion that the threat of entry is a more powerful restraint on solicitors’ behaviour than actual entry. Stephen and Love (1996) have sought to explain these results by the fact that licensed conveyancers produce a limited range of services and therefore have the same interest as lawyer conveyancers in maintaining high fees and also that the risks to licensed conveyancers are greater than those of solicitors. These results should caution against the assumption that multiple professional bodies will necessarily be to the benefit of consumers. However, the limited effects of removing a monopoly in a restricted field, as in this case, may not carry over to a more general removal of monopoly rights.
C. Restrictions on Advertising 11. Professional Advertising and Competition The second tool used by self-regulated professions has been the restriction or total ban on advertising by members of the profession. This has often been accompanied by restrictions on other aids to competition such as quoting of fees in advance of carrying out the work and so on (Cox, 1989; Curran, 1993; Domberger and Sherr, 1987, 1989; Evans and Trebilcock, 1982; Faure, 1993; Federal Trade Commission, 1984; Finsinger, 1993; Helligman, 1993; Herrman, 1993; Ogus, 1993; Paterson and Stephen, 1990; Scottish Home and Health Department, 1989; Shinnick, 1995; Stephen, 1994; Stephen and Love, 1996; Stephen, Love and Paterson, 1994). During the recent deregulation wave, restrictions on lawyer advertising have been relaxed to varying degrees in different jurisdictions. These deregulatory moves have been prompted by court decisions, consumer lobby pressure and activities of competition authorities. Economic analysis of restrictions on advertising by professionals has been carried out from an economics of information perspective based on the insights of Stigler’s (1961) analysis. Stigler argued that producer advertising was equivalent to a large amount of search by a large number of consumers. Consequently it reduced price dispersions and enhanced competition. Writers on the professions therefore argued that restrictions on advertising by professions imposed by self-regulatory bodies were designed to reduce competition by increasing the cost of consumer search (see for example, Benham and Benham, 1975). Removal of such restrictions would enhance competition and be in the interests of efficiency. In the 1960s and 1970s severe
5860
Regulation of the Legal Profession
997
restrictions on advertising by lawyers was quite widespread (see for example, Federal Trade Commission, 1984; Cox, 1989; Monopolies and Mergers Commission, 1976; and contributions to Faure et al., 1993). Such severe restrictions still applied in Belgium and Germany until recently. (Faure, 1993; Herrmann, 1993). It is frequently asserted by critics of professional advertising that advertising will drive down the quality of services provided. Economists have examined the relationship between advertising and quality. Rogerson (1988) shows formally that even if price can communicate no information directly about quality, it can do so indirectly because price serves as a positive signal of quality when price advertising is allowed. Price advertising is therefore welfare enhancing because it improves consumer choice. A problem arises, however, if price advertising is undertaken exclusively, or at least principally, by low-price/low-quality suppliers. Price advertising therefore becomes an adverse signal on quality. This is a general argument, and does not depend on price being a clear signal on quality. Rizzo and Zeckhauser (1992) point out that consumers who are unable to assess quality ex ante (and possibly even ex post) and who observe a low price for a non-standardised service may assume that more knowledgeable purchasers have assessed the service as being of low quality. Professionals are keen to avoid such adverse signals on quality, and so Rizzo and Zeckhauser conclude that price advertising will be uncommon in most professions. Thus not only may advertising have an effect on quality, perceptions of quality may have an effect on the form of advertising chosen by professionals.
12. Empirical Studies of Lawyer Advertising An extensive empirical literature has developed on the restriction of advertising of professional services and what happens to fee levels when such restrictions are relaxed. A review of this literature is presented in Love and Stephen (1996). The general thrust of the evidence from this literature is that restrictions on advertising increase the fees charged for the profession’s services and that the more advertising there is the lower are fees. The one study contradicting this result is Rizzo and Zeckhauser (1992). Love and Stephen (1996) note a number of limitations to these studies. The empirical studies of advertising by members of the legal profession find that law firms which advertised charged, on the whole, lower fees than those that did not advertise (Cox, DeSerpa and Canby, 1982; Federal Trade Commission, 1984; Schroeter, Smith and Cox, 1987; Love et al., 1992; Stephen, 1994). Domberger and Sherr (1987, 1989) found that conveyancing fees in England and Wales had fallen since advertising and fee quoting had been permitted. Schroeter, Smith and Cox (1987), Love et al. (1992) and
998
Regulation of the Legal Profession
5860
Stephen (1994) found that the more advertising by lawyers there was in a locality the lower were the fees charge by all lawyers in the locality (at least for certain transactions). Stephen et al. (1992) found that that price discrimination by solicitors was lower the more advertising there was in a market. However, Love et al. (1992) for England and Wales and Stephen (1994) for Scotland found that this result was only valid for some forms of lawyer advertising. The other studies did not distinguish between different forms of advertising. The hypothesis that non-price advertising will be much more common than price-advertising is supported by evidence from the legal profession in the UK and in the USA. Stephen, Love and Paterson (1994) show that within two years of advertising being permitted, the percentage of English solicitors’ firms which had advertised within the six months prior to an extensive survey was 46 percent; but only 2 percent of firms had advertised the price of any service. Six years later (in 1992), the proportion of advertising firms had risen to 59 percent, but price advertising was carried out by just 4 percent of firms. In Scotland, Stephen (1994) estimates that within three years of being permitted to do so, over half of Scottish solicitors’ firms engaged in advertising, but less than 3 per cent advertised the price of any service. The Federal Trade Commission (1984) study of attorney advertising found similar low levels of price advertising across US states. Empirical work on the quality of legal services in the presence of lawyer advertising does not present such a clear-cut view as that on fees. Love and Stephen (1996) point out that there are variations in how quality is measured in these studies. Muris and McChesney (1979) find that high advertising legal clinics provided better quality services than traditional legal firms for a sample transaction. However, since advertising only enters their analysis indirectly it is difficult to judge the implications for policy on advertising. Murdock and White (1985) conclude that advertisers are more likely to be low quality firms. Thomas (1985) argues that such a conclusion is not warranted by Murdock and White’s evidence. Cox, Schroeter and Smith (1986) find that quality is lower in those localities with greater lawyer advertising but find no statistically significant differences in the quality of work produced by advertisers and non-advertisers. Domberger and Sherr (1989) found that quality (measured by time taken) rose as a consequence of liberalisation of rules on advertising and competition in England and Wales.
5860
Regulation of the Legal Profession
999
D. Regulation of Fees 13. Scale Fees The third weapon in the armoury of the self-regulating profession is the regulation of fees. Traditionally fees have been subject to control by the profession itself, by the courts or by the state through mandatory fee schedules. In some jurisdictions these mandatory scales have been transformed into recommendations. During the recent deregulation wave even these recommendations have been swept away and replaced by the market. Most self-regulatory bodies, however, have retained powers to punish those who charge ‘excessively’ low fees for bringing the profession into disrepute. In Germany fees are still determined by State regulation (Herrmann, 1993). In Belgium and the Netherlands a recommended fee schedule is produced by the profession and in Belgium there is a recommended minimum (Faure, 1993; Helligman, 1993). A recommended scale is still produced by the solicitors’ professional body in Ireland for conveyancing work (Shinnick, 1995) and one was in operation in Scotland until 1985 (Stephen and Love, 1996). The corresponding schedule was withdrawn in England and Wales in 1974, although Domberger and Sherr, 1992) argue that it still influenced feeing practices until the mid-1980s. Observers of professional self-regulation are highly critical of scale fees: In general, we regard a collective obligation not to compete in price, or a restriction collectively imposed which discourages such competition, as being one of the most effective restraints on competition. The introduction of price competition in the supply of a professional service where it is not at present permitted is likely to be the most effective single stimulant to greater efficiency and to innovation and variety of service and price that could be applied to that profession. (Monopolies and Mergers Commission, 1970, p. 78, see also Arnauld, 1972; Arnauld and Friedland, 1977, and Domberger and Sherr, 1989, 1992)
However, economists are generally sceptical about the ability of cartels to avoid their members selling output at prices below those agreed by the cartel. This practice has become known in the economics literature as ‘chiselling’ (see, for example, Cohen and Cyert, 1965, pp. 245-246). As has been pointed out many times (for example Stigler, 1966; Layard and Walters, 1978) the ability of a cartel to enforce its rules is inversely related to the number of members. Professional ‘cartels’ have many members. Scale fees are often ‘recommended’ (Monopolies and Mergers Commission, 1970, pp. 21, 22; Arnauld, 1972, p. 498; Shinnick, 1995) rather than
1000
Regulation of the Legal Profession
5860
mandatory or State-enforced charges. It is often argued that even where they are ‘mere’ recommendations they have the effect of raising fees: There appears to us to be little difference between so-called mandatory and recommended scales in their practical effect ... although disciplinary action could not be taken specifically for breach of a recommended scale, the fact that the fees charged were not in accordance with the scale might in some circumstances be quoted in support of a charge of breach of some other rule .... such that the established practitioner would not depart more readily from a ‘recommended’ scale than from a mandatory scale. (Monopolies and Mergers Commission, 1970, p. 22, see also Arnauld, 1972, p. 498)
14. Empirical Studies of Fee Schedules In contrast to the considerable empirical research on the role of advertising (as discussed above) there would appear to have been little on the impact or effectiveness of recommended fee scales. This is somewhat surprising given the conflicting a priori positions taken by commentators on professional regulation and the writers of general treatises on microeconomics. Arnauld and Friedland (1977) examined the relationship between the incomes of a sample of lawyers and (inter alia) the minimum fee recommended (where there was one) for a simple transaction for a sample of lawyers in California and Pennsylvania. They found that lawyer income rose as the recommended fee rose. It should be noted that the dependent variable here is lawyer income not the fee for the standard transaction. For this to imply that fees also rose, demand for the standard transaction must be inelastic. Arnauld and Friedland, however, argue that the influence of fee schedules on prices may be even greater than they demonstrate because high prices may induce entry which will moderate the effect on lawyer incomes. Strikingly, they also suggest that there may be widespread cheating on the fee schedule. There is some limited evidence that such ‘cheating’ on recommended fee schedules for lawyers does exist. Stephen (1993) reports evidence from a sample of solicitors’ conveyancing bills for 1984, when a scale of recommended fees was in force, that more than 40 percent of these solicitors charged conveyancing fees below that recommended by the Law Society of Scotland. Furthermore, statistically significant geographical patterns were identified in the determinants of these fees even although the fee schedule applied to all Scottish solicitors. However, this evidence must be qualified by the fact that large numbers of solicitors failed to co-operate in this study suggesting that the data analysed may not be representative of all solicitors.
5860
Regulation of the Legal Profession
1001
Stronger evidence of chiselling is presented in Shinnick (1995). This paper examines the conveyancing fees of a large sample of Irish solicitors. At the time at which the survey was carried out the Incorporated Law Society of Ireland, the self-regulatory body for solicitors in Ireland, published a recommended scale of fees for conveyancing which applied throughout the country. Considerable variation from the recommended fee was found. Econometric tests reject the hypothesis that a single fee is charged throughout Ireland, indicating that this variation was not random. The limited empirical evidence available suggests that the strong conclusions on scale fees arrived at on the basis of a priori reasoning by academic observers and competition authorities reported above may not have empirical support.
E. Restrictions on Fee Contracts 15. Contingency Fees In many jurisdictions lawyers’ fees are regulated by prohibiting certain forms of fee contract between lawyer and client. In particular, lawyers may be prohibited from entering into contingent-fee contracts with clients. Under such contracts the lawyer’s fee is contingent on the outcome of the case. The most common form of contingent fee contract is that used between lawyer and plaintiff in many civil cases in the United States. If the case is lost the lawyer receives no fee but if it is won the lawyer receives a percentage of the damage award to the client. Such contingent-fee contracts are prohibited in many European jurisdictions (see Faure, 1993; Helligman, 1993; Herrmann, 1993; Rickman, 1994) but changes are taking place (see, for example, Gravelle and Waterson, 1993; Rickman, 1994) and Lord Chancellor’s Department, 1998, on the introduction of conditional fees with a speculative mark-up in England and Wales). Lynk (1990) has argued that contingency fees are an interesting issue for two reasons: their economic characteristics and their public policy implications. Their economic characteristics have been studied to examine whether they encourage lawyers to invest more or fewer hours in a case; the incentive to settle out of court; and various aspects of the principal agent problem between client and lawyer. The public policy issues focus on whether contingent fees increase the volume of litigation and whether they improve access to justice by removing wealth barriers. Both sets of issues have featured in the literature. A number of authors have used the insight from the agency literature that tying the agent’s remuneration to the outcome is optimal to advocate the superiority of contingency fees in increasing the lawyer’s effort (Danzon, 1983; Halpern and Turnbull, 1981; Hay, 1996; Rickman, 1994; Schwartz and Mitchell, 1970).
1002
Regulation of the Legal Profession
5860
The incentive properties of contingent-fee contracts and hourly contracts more generally have been analyzed by many writers (Clermont and Currivan, 1973; Dana and Spier, 1993; Danzon, 1983; Fisher, 1988; Gravelle and Waterson, 1993; Halpern and Turnbull, 1981; Hay, 1996; Kritzer et al., 1985; Lynk, 1990; Miceli and Segerson, 1991; Rickman, 1994; Rubinfeld and Scotchmer, 1993; Schwartz and Mitchell, 1970; Smith, 1992; Swanson, 1991; Thomason, 1991).
16. Settlement Conflicts In many jurisdictions a fundamental argument put against contingency fees is that they conflict with the principle that lawyers should not have an interest in the cases which they handle (see for example, Rickman, 1994; Faure, 1993 and Helligman, 1993). Such a situation can produce a conflict of interest between client and lawyer over when to settle. In particular, whether the plaintiff in a tort case should accept an out of court settlement rather than go to court. This argument neglects the fact that such a conflict of interest can still exist under the conventional hourly-fee system; it is simply that the lawyer’s private interest is reversed. Under an hourly-fee system the lawyer earns more the greater the number of hours put into the case. It will thus be attractive to the lawyer to continue the case provided that the hourly rate is greater than the opportunity cost of the lawyer’s effort, that is, if super-normal profits are being made. Consequently, the lawyer has an interest in convincing the client to continue the case, ceteris paribus, rather than settle (Johnson, 1981). The opposite may be true under a contingency fee. Here the lawyer receives a predetermined share of any damages awarded but bears all costs incurred on behalf of the client. Thus when a pre-trial offer is made by the defendant to settle out of court the interests of the plaintiff and the plaintiff’s lawyer can conflict (Gravelle and Waterson, 1993; Johnson, 1981; Miller, 1987; Rickman, 1994; Schwartz and Mitchell, 1970; Swanson, 1991; Watts, 1994). Indeed, the higher the offer the more likely the interests of plaintiff and lawyer are to conflict under a contingent-fee system (Gravelle and Waterson, 1993). The foregoing analysis implicitly assumes that the client relies totally on the lawyer’s decision over settlement and that the lawyer is motivated by pure self-interest. Gravelle and Waterson (1993) allow for the variation of this assumption by incorporating a parameter in their model which varies as the client is better informed or as the lawyer is more altruistic. They find that the more informed the client is (or the more altruistic the lawyer is) the less likely a given offer will be accepted pre-trial under a contingency fee. Indeed, if the lawyer is more altruistic than selfish the probability of pre-trial settlement will be lower under a contingency fee than under an hourly fee. This result emphasises the crucial importance of the asymmetric information issue in
5860
Regulation of the Legal Profession
1003
determining the choice of fee contract. Well-informed clients are likely to prefer an hourly rate. Furthermore, the more imbued with a client service ethic lawyers are (the more altruistic) the more suitable is the hourly-fee contract to the client’s interest. There is some limited empirical evidence supporting this result in that Kritzer (1990) reports that for a sample of tort and contract cases where the plaintiff was an organisation 81 percent of the fee contracts were on an hourly basis whilst when the plaintiff was an individual 59 percent of the fee contracts were on a contingency basis. It is to be expected that organisations are more likely to be experienced litigants than individuals. Returning to the more standard setting where the lawyer is assumed to be self-interested, Gravelle and Waterson’s (1993) result is somewhat modified if the context is changed slightly and bargaining introduced to the model (Rickman, 1994; Swanson, 1991). Under these circumstances, it is argued that with the contingency fee contract the lawyer has a greater incentive to bargain hard. The lawyer’s behaviour may be affected in ways other than hours at a given effort level. Consequently even a relatively selfish lawyer settling out of court may improve the client’s award as against that attainable under an hourly fee contract where the incentive to bargain hard is less.
17. Volume of Litigation It is frequently argued by those supporting the ban on contingency fees in European jurisdictions that permitting contingency fees will increase the volume of litigation. The higher volume of litigation in the US where contingency fees are permitted is often cited in support of this view. However most of the economic modelling suggests the opposite conclusion (Clermont and Currivan, 1973; Dana and Spier, 1993; Danzon, 1983; Halpern and Turnbull, 1981; Miceli, 1994; Miceli and Segerson, 1991; Rubinfeld and Scotchmer, 1993). Miceli (1994) examines the impact of contingent fees on the pursuit of frivolous cases and finds no support for the view that contingent fees will encourage frivolous suits. Gravelle and Waterson (1993) develop a model in which both the probability of accident and the probability of settlement are endogenous. Thus they extend the model beyond the decision to litigate or settle given that an accident has occurred to one where the care taken by potential tortfeasors is influenced by the nature of contracts between potential victims and their lawyers and thus post-accident behavior. They find that the effect of a switch from hourly fee to a contingency fee has an ambiguous effect on the volume of litigation in this model and on welfare.
1004
Regulation of the Legal Profession
5860
18. Access to Justice A number of authors argue that a benefit of contingency fees is that risk averse or wealth-constrained victims of torts who under an hourly fee contract may be unwilling to pursue a claim will now do so because the risk is shifted to their lawyer. Some predict a consequent increase in the volume of litigation under contingency fees (Miceli and Segerson, 1991; Rubinfeld and Scotchmer, 1993) but Dana and Spier (1993) suggest that to the extent that victims may be overoptimistic about their chance of success contingency fees may actually reduce the number of suits. Neither of these views takes account of the deterrence (or otherwise) effects of a change from hourly to contingent contracts as predicted by Gravelle and Waterson (1993). However, it would seem that victims are likely to be better off one-way-or-another under contingency fees even although the overall welfare effects may be ambiguous.
F. Restrictions on Organizational Form 19. Choice of Organizational Form Thus far in this paper we have discussed the relationship between lawyer and client abstracting from the organisational form through which lawyers provide their services. We have focused on lawyer-client relations and relations between the profession as a whole and others in society. In most jurisdictions lawyers provide their services to the public through ‘firms’. However the nature and form of these law firms is regulated in many jurisdictions. Lawyers are not free in their choice of organizational form. Some organizational forms are prohibited. In this section we evaluate the economic rationale for such regulation of organizational form. We begin by considering the factors which might influence a lawyer’s choice of organizational form. Increases in firm size can be justified on a number of grounds. The most general of these is that economies of scale can be captured the greater the output of the firm. Every introductory textbook in economics lists sources of economies of scale. Principal among these are those emanating from specialization of labor and more efficient use of capital. The former of these may apply to legal services but the latter is more doubtful, at least where it is physical capital that is involved. The physical capital requirements of legal services are quite small and are likely to involve limited economies of scale. Legal services are essentially human (rather than physical) capital intensive. Provision of legal services through group practice allows specialization of lawyers in particular aspects of law, therefore, lowering the cost of providing
5860
Regulation of the Legal Profession
1005
services. Practices of lawyers with different specialties have the further benefit of risk spreading. Different specialties may face different business cycles and thus fluctuations in specialist income may be smoothed across the group. Furthermore, economies of scope may exist when a client has a range of legal service needs which can be serviced by specialists within the firm or when a legal problem has dimensions involving a range of specialties. Economies of scope are available to the sole practitioner but in the multi-lawyer firm they are combined with economies of specialization. The more complex the issues the more likely that specialists will dominate because the benefits of economies of specialization outweigh the economies of scope to the sole practitioner. Economies of scope or benefits from risk sharing in the multi-lawyer specialist firm will lead to multi-lawyer firms dominating. Similar arguments apply where the specialists involved are outside the legal profession in what is often referred to as multi-disciplinary practice (MDP). It has often been argued that clients would benefit from economies of scope where a professional firm included lawyers, accountants, surveyors and so on; so-called ‘one stop shopping’. We do not discuss this issue further here but a general discussion of the issue in a different context may be obtained from Smith and Hay (1997). Thus far we have only considered production costs. We have not considered agency costs which may arise from the asymmetry of information between client and lawyer. The analysis here may be helped by using Quinn’s (1982) distinction between the agency function and the service function discussed earlier in this paper. Earlier we pointed to the moral hazard problem that arises after a lawyer performs the agency function in diagnosing a client’s legal problem and recommending a course of action. This arises because it is assumed that the same lawyer will perform the consequent service function. The agency cost increases when it is recognized that there are economies of specialization. Many circumstances will arise under which the lawyer performing the agency function is not the least cost supplier of the service function required. This may be particularly so in the sole practitioner firm. In a multi-lawyer firm it is, perhaps, more likely that there will be a specialist within the firm who is the least-cost provider of the service function. The probability of this being so may increase the more lawyers there are in the firm. However, the fewer the number of partners and the more specialized the service function required the more likely that the firm will not be the least-cost supplier. This may even be the more so if the firm is an MDP. Nevertheless, it is likely that the lawyer performing the agency function will pass the client to a specialist within the firm: first, because the lawyer providing the agency function will share in the income of the firm generated from the provision of the specialized services; secondly, because recommending the client to another firm may mean that the client’s future business will also be lost.
1006
Regulation of the Legal Profession
5860
In many jurisdictions there are restrictions on the organisational forms which can be adopted by providers of legal services. Traditionally these restrictions appear to have been motivated by a desire to keep at arm’s length commercial or profit considerations on the part of lawyers, reflecting the agency problem which has been a central consideration throughout this paper. Thus for many years lawyers in most jurisdictions could only operate as sole practitioners or in partnerships with other lawyers and could not incorporate (see Bishop, 1989; Faure, 1993; Helligman, 1993; Herrmann, 1993; Ogus, 1993; Prichard, 1982, and Quinn, 1982). Furthermore, in the UK and Ireland providers of legal services are divided into two distinct professions with their own professional bodies and self-regulatory functions: solicitors and barristers (in Scotland known as advocates). Until 1990 in the UK only barristers (advocates) could appear before the higher courts and they could only take instructions from a solicitor and not directly from a client (see Bowles, 1994, and Ogus, 1993). There is a limited economic literature which examines such restrictions on organisational form. We first examine the issues surrounded the divided profession before moving on to the issue of firm size and organisational form.
20. A Divided Profession In England and Wales, Northern Ireland and Scotland (each of which is a separate legal jurisdiction) as well as the Republic of Ireland and certain states in Australia, what is elsewhere a single legal profession is split into two branches: solicitors and barristers (in Scotland, advocates). Solicitors provide legal advice to the public on the whole range of legal matters and have rights of audience in the lower courts. Barristers have rights of audience in the higher courts and provide consultancy services to solicitors. The rules governing each of the professions prohibits its members from practising as members of the other profession. Judges (as opposed to magistrates) are drawn almost exclusively from the ranks of barristers (advocates) (Bishop, 1989; Bowles, 1994; Ogus, 1993; Shinnick, 1995). Although rights of audience in the higher courts in Scotland and England and Wales have changed recently as a consequence of legislation to allow solicitors who meet certain tests of experience in advocacy in the lower courts to appear in the higher courts, there has been no move to fuse the professions. From an economic perspective the question is whether the division into two professions is efficiency enhancing or is a mere restrictive practice. It should be noted that specialisation in advocacy may exist within a fused profession. Within law firms some practitioners may specialise in court advocacy while others specialise in diagnosis and case management. Some firms may specialise in advocacy, particularly in the criminal field. Outside the criminal field in-house advocates may lack expertise in a particular area of law
5860
Regulation of the Legal Profession
1007
in spite of having enhanced advocacy skills. The issue then becomes whether or not any benefits from formally separating the roles outweigh the costs. Bishop (1989) analyses the separation into two professions as a prohibition on vertical integration between successive stages in a production process: the preparation of a case and its prosecution through advocacy in the courts. He argues along lines similar to those of Quinn (1982) that the conflict between the agency function and the service function is particularly severe due to the large benefits which accrue from specialisation in trial advocacy. The existence of a cadre of specialist consultants and litigators (barristers/advocates) removes the temptation to supply higher cost in-house advocacy. Not only this, it may provide competition in the downstream market. Thus one benefit of a divided profession is that the client gets higher quality advocacy than would be available from an in-house advocate. However, this benefit is not costless. Bishop argues that the cost will be the dead-weight loss to sophisticated buyers of legal services who do not require the intermediation of a solicitor. An additional cost might be the differential transaction costs associated with employing both solicitor and barrister rather than two solicitors within the same firm. This would be the case if economies of scope existed when the two legal advisors were from the same firm/office. An evaluation of the division in the profession cannot be resolved on these a priori arguments. It is a question of the relative magnitudes of the costs and benefits. However, their empirical measurement is fraught with difficulty. Ogus (1993) clearly doubts that the balance lies in favour of division but adduces additional points against division. If, he argues, division were efficient, why is it that when fusion is not prohibited we invariably observe fusion. Further, enforced division removes choice from informed consumers who might prefer lower quality but cheaper in-house advocacy to high quality but high price external advocacy. On the other hand Bishop points out that in some Australian states where there is fusion there is de facto separation as some specialist pleaders operate, in effect, as barristers. Bishop (1989) also discusses external effects which have a bearing on the division issue. The first of these is that the division into two specialist branches allows more effective policing of lawyer misbehaviour (particularly in the case of barristers) due to a ‘club’ effect. This reduction in dishonesty will benefit future honest litigants because it will reduce the cost of achieving justice. However the implication is that Bishop regards the division of the professions as an expensive means of achieving this benefit. The division may also allow the monitoring of the performance of the members of each profession by the members of the other. A further external effect is public capital formation through the production of high quality precedent. The existence of highly specialised and qualified advocates should produce better argued cases and more valuable precedent. Furthermore the recruitment of the judiciary from the
1008
Regulation of the Legal Profession
5860
ranks of the best of these specialist advocates, not only ensures that those recruited to the bench have proven their worth as trial lawyers but should further ensure high quality precedents. A final external effect identified by Bishop (1989) is a lowering of the cost of judicial administration. Here the main beneficiary is not the client but the trial judge. Poor advocacy places a burden on the trial judge to ensure that the decision reached is not influenced by inadequate advocacy. With highly specialised and skilled advocates this problem does not arise. Barristers also act as gatekeepers to the courts. They ensure that cases are sifted and well-prepared before reaching the court thus reducing the cost of adjudication. Similar external effects are adduced by Arruñada (1996) in his examination of Spanish Notaries. It is not easy to find empirical evidence to test propositions like those of Bishop. He cites the former Chief Justice of the United States, Warren Burger, in support of the higher quality of advocacy and the higher quality of the judiciary in England as compared to the US. However, Bishop does not regard this testimony as determinative. He then discusses at length the spontaneous evolution of barrister-like specialists in Australian states where there is de jure a fused profession. The final sources of evidence cited by Bishop are the extensive use of English precedents throughout the common-law world and the choice of London and English law to settle international legal issues. Both of these might be seen as suggesting a higher quality of legal services resulting from specialisation in the branches of the profession. Notwithstanding the above arguments Bishop does concede that it will only be where the stakes are high that the higher cost of specialisation may be worth incurring implying that rights of audience in lower courts should not be restricted to specialist advocates.
21. Sole Practitioners, Partnerships and Incorporation A more common organizational restriction in many jurisdiction is that providers of legal services must operate as independent providers or in partnership with other qualified lawyers. Even where incorporation is permitted restrictions are frequently imposed maintaining unlimited liability and that the directors of the firm must all be lawyers (see Bishop, 1989; Faure, 1993; Helligman, 1993; Herrmann, 1993; Ogus, 1993; Prichard, 1982, and Quinn, 1982). However, some US states permit incorporation under limited liability (Carr and Mathewson, 1988). Fama and Jensen (1983a, 1983b) have argued that professional partnership accompanied by unlimited liability is a solution to the moral hazard problem posed by the asymmetry between client and professional. The willingness of one professional to risk his or her wealth by entering into such a partnership with another professional signals to clients the trustworthiness of members of the
5860
Regulation of the Legal Profession
1009
partnership and provides a guarantee that there will be mutual monitoring among partners. Stephen and Gillanders (1993) present evidence that little mutual monitoring takes place within UK law firms and that ex ante screening of prospective partners is likely to dominate ex post monitoring. The persistence of sole practitioner firms in legal practice also seems to run counter to this signalling function of partnership: around 50 percent of law firms in the US are sole practitioners and around 40 percent of solicitors’ firms in England and Wales. However, Carr and Mathewson (1990) point out that the proportion of sole practitioner firms in the US has been declining for a number of years. Carr and Mathewson (1990) model the choice of organisational form for law firms in a competitive market subject to information asymmetries. They conclude that ‘partnerships dominate solo lawyers when client cases are large and the detection of chiselling is low’ (p. 328). They also point out that for large corporations it may pay to have in-house counsel to monitor legal services. However, they find that limited liability becomes attractive as it reduces the cost of capital to partnerships. In Carr and Mathewson (1988) they argue that the increased cost of capital when unlimited liability is small leads to inefficiently small law firms where complex cases are involved. They find empirical support for this conclusion from differences in law firm size across US states being related to whether or not limited liability is available. Their regressions support the view that law firm size rises where limited liability is permitted. Gilson (1991) suggests that the relationship runs in the opposite direction because of the tax advantages of incorporation: large firms derive a greater tax advantage from incorporation. Carr and Mathewson (1991) respond that their empirical results allow for a distinction between incorporation and limited liability since not all corporate law firms enjoy limited liability.
G. Conclusion 22. Summing Up This chapter has reviewed the extensive economic literature on the regulation of the legal profession. The case for regulation has been seen to be based on the moral hazard problem which arises from the information asymmetry between the lawyer and the infrequent user of legal services. The justification for self-regulation is seen to be based on reducing the costs of regulation. Nevertheless, much of the literature on self-regulation sees it working in the interests of the members of the profession by raising fees and professional incomes. A number of instruments through which self-regulation operates to restrict competition were identified. Theoretical work by economists tends to point to
1010
Regulation of the Legal Profession
5860
these working in the interests of the profession and against the interests of clients. The empirical literature testing such predictions is limited but produces mixed support for the theoretical predictions. For example, whilst there is some support from aggregate data for the view that restrictions on entry to the legal profession lead to higher incomes for lawyers, the microeconometric evidence on the effect of restrictions on fees runs counter to theory. The evidence from the removal of the conveyancing monopoly in England and Wales is at least ambiguous. Similarly, the limited empirical evidence on recommended scale fees for solicitors suggests significant deviations from these scales. The evidence on the effects of restrictions on advertising tends to support the theory, although it has been suggested that when different types of advertising are considered the evidence is less unambiguous. On the issues of contingent fees and restrictions on organisational form the empirical evidence is very limited. This survey of the literature suggests a need for more empirical studies. The theoretical literature, on the whole, suggests fairly strong recommendations to policymakers regarding self-regulation. On the other hand, the limited empirical evidence does not always support such strong theoretical predictions. More evidence would clarify whether the conflict arises from the limitations of the current evidence or from the theory.
Acknowledgements The authors would like to acknowledge constructive comments made by three referees and the editors on an earlier draft of this survey. We also benefited from comments made when aspects of this work were presented at Universidad de Valencia and the Lord Chancellor’s Department Economics Forum. The usual disclaimer applies.
Bibliography on Regulation of the Legal Profession (5860) Arnauld, R.J. (1972), ‘Pricing Professional Services: A Case Study of the Legal Services Industry’, 33 Southern Economic Journal. Arnauld, R.J. and Friedland, Thomas S. (1977), ‘The Effect of Fee Schedules on the Legal Services Industry’, XII Journal of Human Resources. Arruñada, Benito (1996), ‘The Economics of Notaries’, 3 European Journal of Law and Economics, 5-37. Benham, Lee and Benham, Alexandra (1975), ‘Regulating Through the Professions: A Perspective on Information Control’, 18 Journal of Law and Economics, 421-447. Bishop, William (1989), ‘Regulating the Market for Legal Services in England: Enforced Separation of Function and Restrictions on Forms of Enterprise’, 52 Modern Law Review, 326-351.
5860
Regulation of the Legal Profession
1011
Bowles, Roger A. (1994), ‘The Structure of the Legal Profession in England and Wales’, 10 Oxford Review of Economic Policy, 18-33. Bowles, Roger A. and Phillips, Jennifer (1977), ‘Solicitors’ Renumeration: A Critique of Recent Developments in Conveyancing’, 40 Modern Law Review, 639-650. Bowles, Roger A. and Skogh, Göran (1989), ‘Reputation, Monitoring and the Organisation of the Law Firm’, in Faure, Michael and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds), Essays in Law and Economics. Corporations, Accident Prevention and Compensation for Losses, Antwerpen, Maklu, 33-47. Calvani, Terry, Langenfeld, James and Shuford, Gordon (1988), ‘Attorney Advertising and Competition at the Bar’, 41 Vanderbilt Law Review, 761-788. Carr, Jack L. and Mathewson, G. Frank (1988), ‘Unlimited Liability as a Barrier to Entry’, 96 Journal of Political Economy, 766-784. Carr, Jack L. and Mathewson, G. Frank (1990), ‘The Economics of Law Firms: A Study in the Legal Organization of the Firm’, 33 Journal of Law and Economics, 307-330. Carr, Jack L. and Mathewson, G. Frank (1991), ‘Unlimited Liability and Law Firm Organization: Tax Factors and the Direction of Causation’, 99 Journal of Political Economy, 426-428. Charette, Frédérick (1992), ‘Libéraliser la Publicité des Avocats: Fondements et Conséquences (Liberalizing Lawyers’ Advertising: Foundations and Consequences)’, 71 Canadian Bar Review, 508-551. Clermont, K.N. and Currivan, J.D. (1973), ‘Improving on the Contingent Fee’, 63 Columbia Law Review, 529-639. Coffee, John C., Jr (1987), ‘The Regulation of Entrepreneurial Litigation: Balancing Fairness and Efficiency in the Large Class Action’, 54 University of Chicago Law Review, 877-937. Cox, Steven R. (1989), ‘Advertising Restrictions among Professionals: Bates v. State Bar of Arizona (1977)’, in Kwoka, J. and White, L. (eds), The Antitrust Revolution: The Role of Economics, Glenview, IIL, Scott Foresman. Cox, Steven R., DeSerpa, Allan C. and Canby, William C., Jr (1982), ‘Consumer Information and the Pricing of Legal Services’, 30 Journal of Industrial Economics, 305-318. Cox, Steven R., Schroeter, John R. and Smith, Scott L. (1986), ‘Attorney Advertising and the Quality of Routine Legal Services’, 2 Review of Industrial Organization, 340-354. Curran, Christopher (1993), ‘The American Experience with Self-Regulation in the Medical and Legal Professions’, in Faure, Michael, Finsinger, Jorg, Siegers, Jacques and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds), Regulation of Professions, Antwerpen, Maklu, 47-87. Dana, James D., Jr and Spier, Kathryn E. (1993), ‘Expertise and Contingent Fees: The Role of Asymmetric Information in Attorney Compensation’, 9 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 349-367. Danzon, Patricia M. (1983), ‘Contingent Fees for Personal Injury Litigation’, 14 Bell Journal of Economics, 213-224. Darby, Michael R. and Karni, Edi (1973), ‘Free Competition and the Optimal Amount of Fraud’, 16 Journal of Law and Economics, 111-126. Dingwall, R. and Fenn, Paul T. (1987), ‘A Respectable Profession? Sociological and Economic Perspectives on the Regulation of Professional Services’, 7 International Review of Law and Economics, 51-64. Domberger, Simon and Sherr, Avrom (1981), ‘Economic Efficiency in the Provision of Legal Services: The Private Practitioner and the Law Centre’, 1 International Review of Law and Economics,
1012
Regulation of the Legal Profession
5860
29-49. Domberger, Simon and Sherr, Avrom (1987), ‘Competition in Conveyancing: An Analysis of Solicitors’ Charges 1983-85´, 8(3) Fiscal Studies, 17-28. Domberger, Simon and Sherr, Avrom (1989), ‘The Impact of Competition on Pricing and Quality of Legal Services’, 9 International Review of Law and Economics, 41-56. Domberger, Simon and Sherr, Avrom (1992), ‘Price Discrimination in Conveyancing: A Reply to Our Critics’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 103-107. Emons, Winand (1997), ‘Credence Goods and Fraudulent Experts’, 28 Rand Journal of Economics, 107-119. Evans, R.G. and Trebilcock, Michael J. (eds) (1982), Lawyers and the Consumer Interest: Regulating the Market for Legal Services, Toronto, Butterworths. Fama, Eugene F. and Jensen, Michael C. (1983a), ‘Separation of Ownership and Control’, 26 Journal of Law and Economics, 301-325. Fama, Eugene F. and Jensen, Michael C. (1983b), ‘Agency Problems and Residual Claims’, 26 Journal of Law and Economics, 327-349. Faure, Michael (1993), ‘Regulation of Attorneys in Belgium’, in Faure, Michael, Finsinger, Jorg, Siegers, Jacques and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds), Regulation of Professions, Antwerpen, Maklu. Faure, Michael, Finsinger, Jorg, Siegers, Jacques and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds) (1993), Regulation of Professions, Antwerpen, Maklu. Federal Trade Commission (1984), Improving Consumer Access to Legal Services, Report of Staff of the Federal Trade Commission, Cleveland, Nov. 1984. Finsinger, Jorg (1993), ‘Attorneys: Summary of the Cross National Comparison’, in Faure, Michael, Finsinger, Jorg, Siegers, Jacques and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds), Regulation of Professions, Antwerpen, Maklu. Fisher, Joseph M. (1988), ‘Contingent and Noncontingent Attorney’s Fees in Personal Injury Cases’, 6 Contemporary Policy Issues, 108-121. Friedman, Milton and Kuznets, S. (1945), Income from Independent Professional Practice, New York, National Bureau of Economic Research. Gilson, Ronald J. (1991), ‘Unlimited Liability and Law Firm Organization: Tax Factors and the Direction of Causation’, 99 Journal of Political Economy, 420-428. Gravelle, Hugh S.E. and Waterson, Michael (1993), ‘No Win, No Fee: Some Economics of Contingent Legal Fees’, 103(420) Economic Journal, 1205-1220. Gross, Leonard E. (1986), ‘Contractual Limitations on Attorney Malpractice Liability: An Economic Approach’, 75 Kentucky Law Journal, 793 ff. Halpern, Paul J. and Turnbull, Stuart M. (1981), ‘An Economic Analysis of Legal Fee Contracts’, in Evans, R.M. and Trebilcock, Michael J. (eds), Lawyers and the Consumer Interest, Toronto, Butterworths. Hay, Bruce L. (1996), ‘Contingent Fees and Agency Costs’, 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 503-533. Hazard, Geoffrey C., Jr, Pearce, Russell G. and Stempel, Jeffrey W. (1983), ‘Why Lawyers Should be Allowed to Advertise: A Market Analysis of Legal Services’, 58 New York University Law Review, 1084-1113. Helligman, K. (1993), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Regulation of Lawyers in the Netherlands’, in Faure, Michael, Finsinger, Jorg, Siegers, Jacques and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds), Regulation of Professions, Antwerpen, Maklu. Herrmann, H. (1993), ‘Regulation of Attorneys in Germany: Legal Framework and Actual Tendencies
5860
Regulation of the Legal Profession
1013
in Deregulation’, in Faure, Michael, Finsinger, Jorg, Siegers, Jacques and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds), Regulation of Professions, Antwerpen, Maklu. Holen, Arlene S. (1965), ‘Effects of Professional Licensing Arrangements on Interstate Labor Mobility and Resource Allocation’, 73 Journal of Political Economy, 492-498. Hudec, Albert J. and Trebilcock, Michael J. (1982), ‘Lawyer Advertising and the Supply of Information in the Market for Legal Services’, 20 University of Western Ontario Law Review, 53-99. Johnson, E. (1981), ‘Lawyer’s Choice: A Theoretical Appraisal of Litigation Investment Decisions’, 15 Law and Society Review. Julin, J.R. (1980), ‘The Legal Profession: Education and Entry’, in Blair, Roger D. and Rubin, Stephen (eds), Regulating the Professions: A Public-Policy Symposium, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (1989), ‘Legal Advice about Information to Present in Litigation: Its Effects and Social Desirability’, 102 Harvard Law Review, 565-615. Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (1992), ‘Private versus Socially Optimal Provision of Ex Ante Legal Advice’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 306-320. Kay, John A. (1988), ‘The Forms of Regulation’, in Seldon, Arthur (ed), Financial Regulation - or Over-Regulation, Institute of Economic Affairs, 33-42. Kessel, Reuben A. (1958), ‘Price Discrimination in Medicine’, 1 Journal of Law and Economics, 20-53. Klein, Benjamin and Leffler, Keith B. (1981), ‘The Role of Market Forces in Assuring Contractual Performance’, 89 Journal of Political Economy, 615-641. Kleiner, Morris M., Gay, Robert S. and Greene, Karen (1982), ‘Barriers to Labor Migration: The Case of Occupational Licensing’, 12 Industrial Relations, 383-391. Kritzer, Herbert M. (1990), The Justice Broker: Lawyers and Ordinary Litigation, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Kritzer, Herbert M., Felstiner, William L.F., Saret, A. and Trubeck, David M. (1985), ‘The Impact of Fee Arrangement on Lawyer Effort’, 251 Law and Society Review. Kritzer, Herbert M., Sarat, Austin, Trubek, David, Bumiller, Kristin and McNichol, Elizabeth (1984), ‘Understanding the Cost of Litigation: The Case of the Hourly-Fee Lawyer’, 3 American Bar Foundation Research Journal, 559-604. Lees, D.S. (1966), The Economic Consequences of the Professions, London, Institute of Economic Affairs, 48 ff. Leffler, Keith B. (1978), ‘Physician Licensure: Competition and Monopoly in American Medicine’, 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 165-186. Leland, Hayne E. (1979), ‘Quacks, Lemons, and Licensing: A Theory of Minimum Quality Standards’, 87 Journal of Political Economy, 1325-1346. Levmore, Saul (1993), ‘Commissions and Conflicts in Agency Arrangements: Lawyers, Real Estate Brokers, Underwriters, and Other Agents’ Rewards’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 503-539. Lord Chancellor’s Department (1998), Access to Justice with Conditional Fees, London, Lord Chancellor’s Department. Love, James H. and Stephen, Frank H. (1996), ‘Advertising, Price and Quality in Self-regulating Professions: A Survey’, 3 International Journal of the Economics of Business, 227-247. Love, James H., Stephen, Frank H., Gillanders, Derek D. and Paterson, Alan A. (1992), ‘Spatial Aspects of Deregulation in the Market for Legal Services’, 26 Regional Studies, 127-147.
1014
Regulation of the Legal Profession
5860
Lueck, Dean, Olsen, Reed and Ransom, Michael (1995), ‘Market and Regulatory Forces in the Pricing of Legal Services’, 7(1) Journal of Regulatory Economics, 63-83. Lynk, William J. (1990), ‘The Courts and the Market: An Economic Analysis of Contingent Fees in Class-Action Litigation’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 247-260. Matthews, Robin C.O. (1991), ‘The Economics of Professional Ethics: Should the Professions be more like Businesses?’, 101 Economic Journal, 737-750. McChesney, Fred S. (1982), ‘Team Production, Monitoring, and Profit Sharing in Law Firms: An Alternative Hypothesis’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 379-393. McChesney, Fred S. and Muris, Timothy J. (1979), ‘The Effects of Advertising on the Quality of Legal Services’, 65 American Bar Association, 1503-1503. Miceli, Thomas J. (1994), ‘Do Contingent Fees Promote Excessive Litigation?’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 211-224. Miceli, Thomas J. and Segerson, Kathleen (1991), ‘Contingent Fees for Lawyers: The Impact on Litigation and Accident Prevention’, 20 Journal of Legal Studies, 381-399. Miller, Geoffrey P. and Macey, Jonathan R. (1996), ‘Reflections on Professional Responsibility in a Regulatory State’, 63 George Washington Law Review. Miller, James C., III (1983), ‘The FTC and Voluntary Standards: Maximizing the Net Benefits of Self-Regulation’, 4 Cato Journal, 897-903. Mitchell, Daniel J.B. and Schwart, M.L. (1972), ‘Theoretical Implications of Contingent Legal Fees’, 12 Quarterly Review of Economics and Business, 69-76. Monopolies and Mergers Commission (1970), A Report on the General Effect on the Public Interest of Certain Restrictive Practices so far as they prevail in relation to the Supply of Professional Services, Cmnd 4463, HMSO. Monopolies and Mergers Commission (1976), Services of Solicitors in England and Wales in Relation to Advertising, HC 457, London, HMSO. Morgan, Thomas D. (1977), ‘The Evolving Concept of Professional Responsibility’, 90 Harvard Law Review, 702 ff. Murdock, G.W. and White, Jim (1985), ‘Does Legal Service Advertising Serve the Public’s Interest? A Study of Lawyer Ratings and Advertising Practices’, 8 Journal of Consumer Policy, 153-165. Mureiko, William R. (1989), ‘Note: A Public Goods Approach to Calculating Reasonable Fees Under Attorney Fee Shifting Statutes’, Duke Law Journal, 438 ff. Muris, Timothy J. and McChesney, Fred S. (1979), ‘Advertising and the Price and Quality of Legal Services: The Case for Legal Clinics’, 1 American Bar Foundation Research Journal, 179-207. Noll, Roger G. (1989), ‘Economic Perspectives on the Politics of Regulation’, in Schmalensee, R. and Willig, R. (eds), Handbook of Industrial Organization II, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 12531287. Ogus, Anthony I. (1993), ‘Regulation of the Legal Profession in England and Wales’, in Faure, Michael, Finsinger, Jorg, Siegers, Jacques and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds), Regulation of Professions, Antwerpen, Maklu. Ogus, Anthony I. (1995), ‘Rethinking Self-Regulation’, 15 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies. Pashigian, B. Peter (1979), ‘Occupational Licensing and the Interstate Mobility of Professionals’, 22 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-25. Pastor, Santos (1990), ‘El Análisis Económico del Acceso a la Justicia (The Economics of Access to Justice)’, 687 Información Comercial Española, 23-42.
5860
Regulation of the Legal Profession
1015
Paterson, Alan A. and Stephen, Frank H. (1990), The Market for Conveyancing in Scotland: Solicitors’ Responses to Competition through Advertising and Fee Quotations, Scottish Office Central Research Unit Paper, Dec. 1990. Paterson, Alan A., Farmer, Lindsay, Stephen, Frank H. and Love, James H. (1988), ‘Competition and the Market for Legal Services’, 15 Journal of Law and Society. Paz-Ares, Cándido (1994), ‘Seguridad Jurídica y Sistema Notarial (Certainty in the Law and the Notarial System)’, in X (ed), El Libro Colectivo de la Répública, Madrid, 73-134. Igualmente Publicado el Iuris 1, 1994, pp. 351-372. Paz-Ares, Cándido (1995), El Sistema Notarial. Una Aproximación Económica (An Economic Approach to The Notarial System), Madrid. Posner, Richard A. (1974), ‘Theories of Economic Regulation’, 5 Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, 335-358. Prichard, J. Robert S. (1982), ‘Incorporation by Lawyers’, in Evans, R.M. and Trebilcock, Michael J. (eds), Lawyers and the Consumer Interest, Toronto, Butterworths. Quinn, Jack (1982), ‘Multidisciplinary Services and Preventive Regulation’, in Evans, R.M. and Trebilcock, Michael J. (eds), Lawyers and the Consumer Interest, Toronto, Butterworths. Ramseyer, J. Mark (1986), ‘Lawyers, Foreign Lawyers, and Lawyer-Substitutes: The Market for Regulation in Japan’, 27 Harvard International Law Journal, 499-986. Rickman, Neil (1994), ‘The Economics of Contingent Fees in Personal Injury Litigation’, 10 Oxford Review of Economic Policy, 34-50. Rizzo, John A. and Zeckhauser, Richard J. (1992), ‘Advertising and the Price, Quantity and Quality of Primary Physician Services’, 28 Journal of Human Resources, 381-421. Rogerson, William P. (1988), ‘Price Advertising and the Deterioration of Product Quality’, 55 Review of Economic Studies, 215-229. Rowley, Charles K. (1989), ‘Competition and the Right to Justice’, 1(1) Legal Services Record, 11 ff. Rowley, Charles K. (1992), The Right to Justice: The Political Economy of Legal Services in the United States, Aldershot, Edward Elgar. Rubinfeld, Daniel L. and Scotchmer, Suzanne (1993), ‘Contingent Fees for Attorneys: An Economic Analysis’, 24 Rand Journal of Economics, 343-356. Schroeter, John R., Smith, Scott L. and Cox, Steven R. (1987), ‘Advertising and Competition in Routine Legal Services Markets: an Empirical Investigation’,36 Journal of Industrial Economics. Schwartz, Murray L. and Mitchell, Daniel J.B. (1970), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Contingent Fee in Personal Injury Litigation’, 22 Stanford Law Review, 1125-1162. Scottish Home and Health Department (1989), The Legal Profession in Scotland, Edinburgh. Shaked, Avner and Sutton, John (1981a), ‘The Self-Regulating Profession’, 47 Review of Economic Studies, 217-234. Shaked, Avner and Sutton, John (1981b), ‘Heterogeneous Consumers and Product Differentiation in a Market for Professional Services’, 15 European Economic Review, 159-177. Shaked, Avner and Sutton, John (1982), ‘Imperfect Information, Perceived Quality and the Formation of Professional Groups’, 27 Journal of Economic Theory, 170-181. Shinnick, Edward (1995), The Market for Legal Services in Ireland, paper presented at Irish Economic Association conference. Smith, B.L. (1992), ‘Three Attorney Fee-Shifting Rules and Contingency Fees: Their Impact on
1016
Regulation of the Legal Profession
5860
Settlement Incentives’, 90 Michigan Law Review, 2154-2189. Smith, Janet Kiholm and Cox, Steven R. (1985), ‘The Pricing of Legal Services: A Contractual Solution to the Problem of Bilateral Opportunism’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 167-183. Spier, Kathryn E. and Dana, James D., Jr (1993), ‘Expertise and Contingent Fees: The Role of Asymmetric Information in Attorney Compensation’, 9 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 349-367. Stephen, Frank H. (1993), ‘Effects of Deregulation in Professional Service Markets: Scottish Conveyancing Markets 1984-1989', 9 Strathclyde Papers in Economics. Stephen, Frank H. (1994), ‘Advertising, Consumer Search Costs and Prices in a Professional Service Market’, 26 Applied Economics, 1994 ff. Stephen, Frank H. and Gillanders, Derek D. (1993), ‘Ex Post Monitoring versus Ex Ante Screening in the New Institutional Economics’, 149 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics. Stephen, Frank H. and Love, James H. (1996), ‘Deregulation of Legal Services Markets in the UK: Evidence from Conveyancing’, 4 Hume Papers on Public Policy, 53-66. Stephen, Frank H. et al. (1992), ‘Testing for Price Discrimination in the Market for Conveyancing Services’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 397-404. Stephen, Frank H. et al. (1993), ‘A Critical Assumption in Testing for Price Discrimination in the Market for Conveyancing Services’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 109-111. Stephen, Frank H., Love, James H., Gillanders, Derek D. and Paterson, Alan A. (1993), ‘Deregulation and Price Discrimination in the Conveyancing Market’, 14 Managerial and Decision Economics, 365-375. Stephen, Frank H., Love, James H. and Paterson, Alan A. (1994), ‘Deregulation of Conveyancing Markets in England and Wales’, 15 Fiscal Studies, 102-118. Stigler, George J. (1961), ‘The Economics of Information’, 69 Journal of Political Economy, 213-225. Swanson, Timothy M. (1991), ‘The Importance of Contingency Fee Arrangements’, 11 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies. Sykes, Alan O. (1993), ‘Some Thoughts on the Real Estate Puzzle: Comment (Commissions and Conflicts in Agency Arrangements: Lawyers, Real Estate Brokers, Underwriters, and Other Agents’ Rewards)’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 541-551. Thomas, R. William (1985), ‘Legal Service Advertising - A Comment on the Paper by Murdock and White’, 8 Journal of Consumer Policy, 165-167. Thomason, Terry (1991), ‘Are Attorneys Paid What They’re Worth? Contingent Fees and the Settlement Process’, 20 Journal of Legal Studies, 187-223. Trebilcock, Michael J. (1982), ‘Competitive Advertising’, in Evans, R.M. and Trebilcock, Michael J. (eds), Lawyers and the Consumer Interest, Toronto, Butterworths. Van den Bergh, Roger (1993), ‘Self-Regulation in the Medical and Legal Professions and the European Internal Market in Progress’, in Faure, Michael, Finsinger, Jorg, Siegers, Jacques and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds), Regulation of Professions, Antwerpen, Maklu. Van den Bergh, Roger and Faure, Michael G. (1991), ‘Self Regulation of the Professions in Belgium’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 165-182. Veljanovski, Cento G. and Whelan, Christopher J. (1983), ‘Professional Negligence and the Quality of Legal Services - An Economic Perspective’, 46 Modern Law Review, 700-718.
5860
Regulation of the Legal Profession
1017
Watts, Alison (1994), ‘Bargaining through an Expert Attorney’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 158-186. Wolfram, Charles W. (1984), ‘The Second Set of Players: Lawyers, Fee Shifting, and the Limits of Professional Discipline’, 47(1) Law and Contemporary Problems, 293-320.
Other References Akerlof, George (1970), ‘The Market for “Lemons”: Quality Uncertainty and the Market Mechanism’, 84 Journal of Political Economy, 488 - 500. Cohen, Kalman J. and Cyert, Richard M. (1965), Theory of the Firm: Resource Allocation in a Market Economy, Englewood Cliffs, Prentice Hall. Layard, P. Richard G. and Walters, Alan A. (1978), Micro-Economic Theory, Maidenhead, McGraw-Hill. Smith Howard and Hay, Donald A. (1997), ‘Competition in Retailing: One Stop Shopping’, 189 Applied Economics Discussion Paper Series, Institute of Economics and Statistics, University of Oxford. Stigler, George J. (1966), The Theory of Price, New York, Macmillan.
5870 THE REGULATION OF MEDICAL PROFESSIONS Reed Neil Olsen Department of Economics, Southwest Missouri State University © Copyright 1999 Reed Neil Olsen
Abstract This chapter reviews two areas of the medical regulation literature; the licensing of medical professionals and medical malpractice. The licensing literature draws upon a more general literature which explains the existence of regulation as reflecting the interests of either (1) the regulated profession, (2) the public, or (3) a combination of both the public and the profession. The major contribution of the licensing literature has been to empirically test these theories, finding mixed support for all three theories; its major weakness is the lack of empirical studies which explicitly test the third theory. The medical malpractice literature also draws upon a more general theory, hypothesizing that malpractice liability deters negligent treatment. The major contribution is empirical and focuses on two areas: (1) describing the recent existence and extent of the widely perceived medical malpractice ‘crisis’, which has led researchers to advocate diverse reforms of the system and (2) describing and estimating the effectiveness of actual malpractice reforms. The major weakness of the literature is the failure to consider, based upon historical antecedents, that no crisis might exist but that increased medical liability is simply an efficient response to changes in medical practice. JEL classifications: K13, I18 Keywords: Medical Licensing, Medical Malpractice, Malpractice Reform, Malpractice Crisis
1. Introduction This review on the regulation of medical professions discusses only two of the major areas where researchers have investigated, theoretically and empirically, the impact of regulation of the medical professions, the licensing of medical professions and medical malpractice law. Although not addressed in this review, a wide and diverse literature on other aspects of the regulation of medical professions certainly exists (for example, the impact of capital constraint, or Certificate of Need, regulation, see Joskow, 1981; for a general overview of the wider literature see Feldstein, 1988 and Phelps, 1992). Although the law and economics literature has made major contributions to 1018
5870
The Regulation of Medical Professions
1019
both of these two topics, there exists very little overlap between the two areas in either theoretical or empirical studies. The literature on professional licensing relies upon a wider literature, explaining the existence of regulation in general, for its theoretical base. From this literature, three explanations for professional licensure emerge: (1) the capture theory, which assumes that professionals ‘capture’ regulation and use it to deter entry and increase their incomes; (2) the public interest theory, which assumes that professional licensure is used in the public interest in order to insure the quality of professional services; and (3) the political economy theory, which assumes that both professional interests and public interests may simultaneously have an impact upon the existence and nature of licensing for health care professionals. The remainder of the professional licensing literature is focussed on attempts to empirically assess the validity of these three theories. Although most empirical researchers conclude that the data support the capture theory a careful reading of their findings actually reveals that such support is inconsistent at best. Thus, although medical licensure is sometimes found to deter entry and enhance the income of medical professionals, at other times it does not have such an impact. The inconsistent support for the capture theory, combined with a few studies which directly test both the public interest theory and the political economy theory, lend support to the political economy theory. The theoretical literature on medical malpractice is also based upon a wider literature dealing with tort law generally rather than medical malpractice specifically. This literature focusses on the impact that malpractice liability has upon the efforts, or precautions, that medical professionals take in order to avoid medical accidents which may result from their treatment of patients. As with tort law in general, the major aim of medical malpractice is, theoretically, to deter medical professionals from shirking on such precaution. In the section on medical malpractice, this general theoretical literature is discussed in more detail, as are the extensions of the literature for medical malpractice, specifically. Although the medical malpractice literature has made some original contributions to the theoretical literature, the main focus of the malpractice literature, similar to the professional licensing literature, has been on empirical studies. One of the main areas where the field of law and economics has contributed has been in studying, empirically, the medical malpractice ‘crisis’ which arose in the US and other developed nations in the past 20 to 30 years. As detailed below, during this time period the liability of medical professionals has increased dramatically and has led to the common conclusion that the malpractice system itself is inefficient and in need of reform. The review below critically assesses the validity of this common conclusion and suggests that some caution must be taken given the nature of the data to be found in the
1020
The Regulation of Medical Professions
5870
literature and, especially, the common lack of a historical perspective concerning malpractice liability. The final area of concern in the literature, also addressed below, is medical malpractice reform. Naturally, given the common assumption that a crisis exists in medical malpractice, much of the literature focusses on the need for reform of the malpractice system. Some of this literature is theoretical in nature, discussing the types of reforms that would be most likely to move the system away from the crisis and towards a more efficient system. Some, perhaps a majority, focus on detailing the actual reforms that have been enacted, mostly by the US and entirely at the state level, and estimating their effectiveness in reducing the malpractice liability of medical professionals.
A. The Licensing of Medical Professions 2. General Remark The literature on the licensing of medical professions fits into a larger literature on regulation in general and the licensing of all professionals in specific. These literatures have a common theoretical background which explains the existence, and persistence, of regulation. A brief summary of this theoretical literature is included below in order to provide a framework for the subsequent discussion of the empirical literature on licensing medical professions. Thus, the major contribution of the literature on medical licensure has not been theoretical but empirical. The extensive literature which investigates the impact of licensure upon markets for medical services is synthesized below. Finally, conclusions about findings gleaned from the empirical literature and directions for future research are given in the final section.
3. Theoretical Background Three general theories have been used to explain the existence of regulations limiting professional licensure of the medical professions: the capture theory, the public interest theory, and a more general, political economy theory. Although these theories are well known in the economics literature, a brief overview of each is included both for background and to clarify the testable hypotheses flowing from each theory. In its simplest form, the capture theory is a straightforward application of self-interest. Medical professionals ‘capture’ the regulations governing licensure and structure them to limit the supply of medical professionals and thereby increase their incomes (Coase, 1974; Friedman, 1962; Moore, 1961;
5870
The Regulation of Medical Professions
1021
Posner, 1974; and Stigler, 1971). As a result, the capture theory predicts that licensure should decrease the supply of medical professionals, increase the prices charged by medical professionals, and increase existing medical professionals’ incomes. Of course, regulatory capture may be attempted by coalitions of professionals within a given profession to the detriment of both the public and non-coalition professionals. For example, regulations may be structured to benefit physicians in certain specialties. In these cases, incomes of only coalition professionals would be expected to rise. In contrast, the public interest theory suggests that professional licensure occurs due to some market ‘failure’ and that its intent is to increase societal welfare. Unlike the capture theory, the public interest theory does not yield clear cut, tractable hypotheses that can be readily tested. For example, predictions from the public interest theory vary dependent upon the type of market failure. Thus, the first step is to accurately identify the relevant market failure being addressed. Researchers have commonly presumed that consumers of professional services, due to the complex nature of the service and uncertainty about the efficacy of competent service, lack complete information about the quality of such services (for example, Arrow, 1963). Hence, the public interest theory asserts that professional licensing corrects this market deficiency by ensuring that medical professionals are of a sufficiently high and standard quality. However, even if such informational asymmetries exist for professional services, the public interest theory still does not yield clean, testable hypotheses. For example, Leland (1979) shows that the impact of quality standards (that is, professional licensing) is dependent upon the cost function for quality. If higher quality applicants can meet the quality standard at lower cost, quality will rise as will market price and professional income. However, if higher quality applicants have a higher cost of meeting the standards, quality, prices and income will all fall. Thus, to be able to predict the impact of professional licensure one must also know its impact on quality. Unfortunately, data on quality are notoriously difficult to obtain. As a result, most researchers interpret the lack of anti-competitive effects as support for the public interest theory (for example, Holen, 1965; Maurizi, 1974; Shepard, 1978; and Noether, 1986). To be clear, anti-competitive effects are those which are predicted by the capture theory - decreased supply of professionals, higher prices, and higher incomes for professionals. In contrast to both capture and public interest theories, the political economy theory entertains the possibility that both the public and medical professionals have an impact on the existence and the form of medical professional licensure regulations (Becker, 1983; Peltzman, 1976, and Stigler, 1971). Thus, the political economy theory is basically a theory of checks and balances. Since all have an impact on the regulatory outcome, medical
1022
The Regulation of Medical Professions
5870
professionals cannot monolithically shape regulations merely to suit their self-interest, their ability to do so is tempered by the competing self-interest of the ‘public’. In fact, Becker (1983) demonstrates that regulators would have a predisposition to enact regulations that are in the public’s (society’s) interest. However, this predisposition is tempered by other factors such as the dispersion or concentration of the affected parties. Thus, the political economy theory predicts that medical professionals will sometimes, but not always, be able to use licensure to limit supply and increase prices and incomes.
4. Empirical Studies Before summarizing the empirical literature one must briefly discuss the nature of medical licensure regulation and how licensure is measured in the empirical studies. There are several common requirements for a medical professional to receive a license to practice. For example, it is common to require that professionals obtain a given education at an approved educational facility. Likewise, many medical professions require candidates for licensure to pass either state or national licensure exams. As can be seen below in the discussion of the empirical literature, the difficulty of the licensure exam as measured by its pass rate (or failure rate) in a given jurisdiction is commonly used to evaluate the impact of the exam requirement on market conditions. Educational and exam requirements are the most common licensure requirements. Some jurisdictions, however, waive educational and exam requirements for certain professionals, most commonly those who have obtained a license to practice in another jurisdiction. Some empirical studies estimate the impact that such rules, known as reciprocity, have on market conditions as well. Licensure requirements, of course, vary by jurisdiction and by profession. Though beyond the scope of this article, a full examination of the history of licensing for medical professionals can provide insight into the issues of primary concern to the literature discussed in this article. For example, licensing for health care professionals, as with many other professions, has most often either been proposed by the regulated professionals themselves or the licensing has had the support of the regulated professionals. In fact, physician licensure only became truly effective and widely applied jurisdictionally with the formation beginning in the late 1800s of effective national and state medical associations who could push for licensure (Shryock, 1967; Starr, 1982; Frech, 1996). Such an impetus for licensing, though most often combined with the regulated professionals publicly arguing that licensing served the public interest by protecting the public against low quality professionals, lends implicit support to the capture theory discussed above.
5870
The Regulation of Medical Professions
1023
For a summary of the history of licensure in the nursing profession see White (1980, 1983, 1987). The empirical literature also discusses current licensing regulations and the history of licensing regulations for other medical professions such as dentists (Shepard, 1978; Boulier, 1980), physicians (Kessel, 1958; Shryock, 1967; Leffler, 1978; Rizzo and Zeckhauser, 1990; Frech, 1974, 1996), optometrists (Benham and Benham, 1975) and physical therapists (Sass and Nichols, 1996). Other studies discuss licensing in general or for a number of different professions (Moore, 1961; Holen, 1965; Starr, 1982; Pashigian, 1979; Frech, 1996). A careful review of the literature yields no consistent picture of the impact that medical licensure has on income, prices, supply, or the quality of medical professionals. Early studies in this area focused on estimating the return to medical education under the assumption that higher than average returns to medical education, as opposed to other types of education, would be an indication of monopoly rents obtained through the capture of licensure. Friedman and Kuznets (1945), for example, compared the incomes of physicians to dentists, and found that physicians had average incomes 32.5 percent greater than dentists. According to their calculations only approximately half of this increased income could be a result of extra training requirements for physicians. As a result, they concluded that barriers to entry must explain the remainder of the differential returns. Early studies by Sloan (1970) and Fein and Weber (1971) also found higher than average returns to medical education and reached similar conclusions. However, Lindsay (1971, 1973) demonstrated that these empirical studies overestimated the returns to medical education. Lindsay noted that medical professionals were characterized not only by higher than average income but also by higher than average weekly hours worked. For example, during the period of the Fein and Weber (1971) study, 1966, physicians worked an average of 62 hours per week. As a result, estimates of the returns to medical education must be decreased to offset the disutility of working longer hours. Lindsay (1973) corrected for the hours worked bias for the time periods covered by all three of the earlier studies and found, as would be expected, much smaller differential returns to medical education. In some cases, he found negative differential returns, dependent upon the discount rate chosen, to medical education. Hence, Lindsay’s results seriously question the conclusions of earlier studies that entry barriers provided by, among other factors, medical licensure had led to higher than average returns. Leffler (1978) also noted that the differential returns to medical education were overestimated not only because of an hours worked bias but also because of the increased expected mortality of physicians, progressive income taxation, and ‘differential probabilities of conscription taxation’ (Leffler, 1978, p. 167). After adjusting for these factors, Leffler found much lower differential returns
1024
The Regulation of Medical Professions
5870
to medical education. Leffler did find positive differential returns, again dependent upon the discount rate, in some years, particularly the late 1960s and early 1970s. However, he attributed these returns to transitory demand shocks rather than entry barriers. Other studies have estimated hours adjusted rates of return to medical education with more recent data (Burstein and Cromwell, 1985; Marder and Willke, 1991) and have found positive differential rates of return. For example, Burstein and Cromwell (1985) found internal rates of return, hours adjusted, equalling about 12 percent for physicians and dentists from 1970 to 1980. Likewise, Marder and Willke (1991) found estimated internal rates of return, hours adjusted, by physician specialty in 1987 and found that such returns varied from a low of 1.5 percent for Pediatrics to a high of 58 percent for Pathology (where hours adjustment increased the rate of return) and 3.7 percent for General Practice. Thus, even though rates of return to medical education are not as high as estimated originally, substantial returns do exist especially for some medical specialties. In addition to studies which focused on estimating the differential return to medical education, other studies have estimated the impact that licensure has on the medical professional’s income directly. For example, early studies on professional licensure by Holen (1965), Benham, Maurizi and Reder (1968) and Maurizi (1974) suggested that licensure (as measured by licensure exam difficulty) was used to increase the incomes of professionals. The support for this conclusion was, however, mixed in these studies. For example, Benham, Maurizi and Reder found licensure to have a positive and significant impact on dentist’s income. Licensure, however, was found to have a negative, and sometimes significant, impact on physicians’ incomes. In addition, the studies used small samples of older aggregate data, rather than recent individual data. Further, neither Holen nor Maurizi attempted to control for the possibility that other demand or supply variables had a significant impact on professional income. Considerable overlap exists in many studies estimating the impact of professional licensure. Both Holen and Maurizi, for example, tested the impact of licensure regulations from multiple professions, including both medical and non-medical professions. Maurizi tested the impact of regulations from 18 different professions including eight medical professions (chiropodists, chiropractors, dentists, registered nurses, optometrists, osteopaths, pharmacists, and physicians). Additional studies of the impact of medical licensure on professional income also yielded mixed results. For example, Shepard (1978) found that lack of reciprocity between jurisdictions significantly limited the number of dentists and, as a result, increased average income for dentists. Shepard, however, used state level aggregate data for a single year (1970) which limits
5870
The Regulation of Medical Professions
1025
the validity of the results. White (1980) found that mandatory licensing for nurses had a small, but positive, impact on nurses’ incomes when first introduced in the 1950s. However in later years, after licensing had had more time to affect incomes, White found that mandatory licensing had no significant impact on nurses’ incomes. Pashigian (1980) found that licensing in a number of occupations, including physicians, dentists, optometrists, pharmacists, nurses and other allied health occupations, restricted the mobility of licensed professionals, all else being equal, but did not significantly raise incomes (for similar work, see Pashigian, 1979). Noether (1986) found that entry restrictions for foreign medical school graduates increased average physician income during the early 1960s. However, Noether’s data indicate that entry restrictions have not been effective since 1965 in increasing physicians’ incomes. She attributes this result to the increased ability of foreign medical school graduates to enter the US market. In a study of physical therapy licensure, Sass and Nichols (1996) found that licensure actually caused a decrease in professional wages and, presumably, in income as well. Licensure in the Sass and Nichols study is somewhat different than is measured in most other empirical studies of medical licensure. Rather than focussing on licensure conditions which limit the entry of professionals, Sass and Nichols focus on states with direct access laws (that is, laws which allow physical therapists to treat patients without referrals from physicians). Although physical therapists have lobbied in favor of direct access laws, Sass and Nichols found that direct access has the impact of lowering therapist wages and, presumably, income as well. Leffler (1978) found that physicians in states which rejected national physician licensure exams in favor of state licensure exams had higher average incomes. Leffler’s state level data comes from the 1960s and early 1970s. At that time, 41 states allowed physician candidates for licensure to take either a standardized national exam or an exam specific to the given state. Nine states, however, did not allow candidates the option of taking the national exam but required passage of the state exam for licensure. Requiring the state exam for licensure reduced the mobility of professionals from other states and, according to the capture theory, would be expected to increase physicians’ incomes. As a result, Leffler concluded that some evidence existed that local state coalitions of physicians used licensure in order to increase incomes. The fact that only nine of the 50 states required candidates to take the state exam indicates, however, that physician capture of licensure occurred only in a few states. Further, Leffler found direct evidence that states who accepted the national exams did so as a result of consumer, rather than physician, demand for licensure. Some evidence does exist indicating that medical licensure has a positive impact on prices charged by medical professionals. Kessel (1958) examined
1026
The Regulation of Medical Professions
5870
pricing of physician services and found evidence that suggested that physicians practiced price discrimination. More importantly, Kessel provided evidence that local medical societies, who controlled licensure, used licensure to force local physicians to keep prices high and comply with price discrimination practices. The major problem with Kessel’s study is his reliance upon ad hoc data. As a result, Kessel could only detail efforts by some local medical societies to force physicians to comply with local pricing rules. In fact, Kessel’s study focused on opposition by local medical societies to prepaid health plans and the physicians who contracted with such plans. He argued that opposition to prepaid plans resulted because they did not generally allow price discrimination by patient income. Kessel’s ad hoc empirical evidence, then, focused on demonstrating that local medical societies often denied licensure, or attempted to deny licensure, to physicians affiliated with such plans. Given the nature of Kessel’s ad hoc data, though, he could not estimate whether or not anti-competitive efforts by local medical societies were actually successful in raising prices or promoting price discrimination. In fact, the ad hoc data which Kessel used demonstrated that in some instances efforts to deny licenses to non-complying physicians failed. Studies by Benham and Benham (1975) and Haas-Wilson (1986) on eyeglasses and Shepard (1978) and Boulier (1980) on dental services provided some evidence that professional licensure increases prices. These studies do have some weaknesses. Only Haas-Wilson and Boulier used individual data. Haas-Wilson’s results were strong only when she considered the cumulative effects of several regulations. Boulier did not measure licensing restrictions directly but, rather, found state variations in individual fees which could not be explained by other variables included as controls in the regressions. The possibility of omitted variables limits the validity of his study. Shepard’s study is the most convincing but suffers because he looked at the impact that licensing has on average prices rather than individual dentist’s prices and because he uses only state aggregate, rather than individual, data. Next, consider the impact that medical licensure has on the quantity of professionals in a given market. As noted above, both Shepard (1978) and Noether (1986) found that licensure reduced the number of professionals in a market, Shepard with dentists and Noether with physicians. Noether found that entry restrictions significantly limited the ability of foreign medical school graduates to enter the US market which, in turn, positively affected physician incomes in the US However, she also found that the effectiveness of such entry restrictions have deteriorated over time to the point where their impact was largely non-existent by the early 1980s. White (1980), in his study of licensing for nurses, found that licensure either had a positive impact on employment of nurses, as it did in early years of licensure, or else had no significant impact on employment, as it did in later years. Svorny (1987), using aggregated state level data from 1965, found that licensure decreased the number of physicians per
5870
The Regulation of Medical Professions
1027
capita. Finally, consider the impact that professional licensure has on the quality of professional services. Studies of quality almost universally suffer from one overwhelming weakness; quality is difficult to measure. Regardless of this practical difficulty, several studies have attempted to estimate the impact that professional licensure has on the quality of professional services. Haas-Wilson (1986) generally found that regulations in optometry had no significant impact on quality as measured by the thoroughness of the eye exam. Carroll and Gaston (1981) found scattered support for their conclusion that licensure resulted in decreased quality for several professions. Their results were strongest for dentistry, although the variable they used to measure the quality of a dentist’s services - how long a patient must wait to receive an appointment rather than by a direct measure of the effectiveness of the dentist’s services - is questionable at best. In contrast, Feldman and Begun (1985) considered the impact of a number of different licensing regulations for optometry and found that regulation increased the quality of services as measured by the length of the eye exam and its thoroughness.
5. Conclusions The review of the empirical literature reveals that medical licensure does, for certain medical professions, in some jurisdictions, or during some periods of time, have the anti-competitive impacts predicted by the capture theory. At times and for certain professions, medical licensure limits the number of professionals in a market with resultant upward pressure upon prices of professional services and professional incomes. It is not surprising, then, that many of the empirical studies on medical licensure have concluded that their empirical results tend to support the capture theory. However, taking a broader overview of the entire empirical literature, one finds that at other times or for other medical professions, anti-competitive effects are not present. The same inconsistent picture holds when examining the impact that medical licensure has upon the quality of medical services. Sometimes, licensure increases quality, as predicted by the public interest theory, but at other times or for other medical professions it does not. The fact that no consistent picture of the impact that professional licensure has on supply, prices, income or quality of medical professionals emerges when reviewing the empirical literature seriously weakens support for both the capture theory and the public interest theory. The inconsistent impact of medical licensure actually lends support to the political economy theory of licensure where both medical professionals and the public are expected to have an impact on licensure. The political economy theory predicts, as noted above,
1028
The Regulation of Medical Professions
5870
that professionals will sometimes, but not always, have the ability to capture licensure to serve their own best interests. At other times, or for other professions, licensure will be used to serve the best interests of the public. Although most empirical studies of medical licensure conclude that their results support the capture theory, a few studies have taken an explicit look at the political economy theory. For example Leffler (1978), in his study of physician licensure, sets up a model to explicitly test the political economy theory. Leffler found evidence supporting consumer demand for physician licensure as well as significant pressure by physicians using licensure in an attempt to raise their incomes. Again, that neither physicians nor consumers are always successful in their attempts to use licensure gives support to the political economy theory of licensure. Likewise, Graddy (1991) found support for public interest and legislative forces, as well as interest group pressure in her study of state occupational regulations. Thus, the most serious failing of the medical licensure literature is the axiomatic approach of many researchers - assuming that the capture theory is correct and, not surprisingly, concluding that their own evidence, even though it is often only weakly supportive, supports the simple capture theory. As can be seen, a wealth of empirical studies have been done which look at the impact of licensure for a number of different medical professions. Only a few studies, though, have been done which seriously consider, or test for, the possibility that licensure has a more complex explanation. The major area where future research, mostly empirical, would be most profitable lies in testing these more complex explanations for medical licensure.
B. Medical Malpractice 6. General Remarks In the past 30 years, medical malpractice has consistently been of interest to a wide variety of groups, including but not limited to the law and economics literature. The intense interest in medical malpractice in the past three decades has been a result of the widespread perception that the malpractice system, previously working smoothly, experienced periodic crises beginning in the 1960s and extending into the 1970s and 1980s (for example, Danzon, 1985a, 1988; Sloan, Bovbjerg and Githens, 1991; Weiler, 1991). The perceived crisis in medical malpractice has generated an extensive literature in a number of diverse areas. The major areas where law and economics has contributed to the literature on medical malpractice are discussed in more detail in the following sections. For example, the law and economics literature has made a large contribution in developing the theoretical justification for the existence of
5870
The Regulation of Medical Professions
1029
medical malpractice law. However, empirical studies have been, perhaps, the most significant contribution of law and economics to the medical malpractice literature. These studies have focussed on two main areas. First, a number of studies detail the nature and extent of the ‘crisis’ in medical malpractice liability and the malpractice insurance market. Second, given the common conclusion that medical malpractice is in crisis, a number of studies focus on medical malpractice reform. Some of these studies are theoretical in nature, arguing for a particular type of reform as that best able to correct perceived deficiencies in the medical malpractice system. Others attempt to measure the impact that US legislative reforms passed at the state level have had upon the medical malpractice system. Most, although not all, of the focus in the literature has been on US medical malpractice law which leaves other malpractice systems as fruitful areas for future research.
7. The Theory of Medical Malpractice The theoretical justification for medical malpractice law fits into a larger law and economics literature discussing the existence and economic efficiency of tort law. In addition to this more general theoretical framework, the literature has also developed some theory specific to medical malpractice. Medical malpractice law, and tort law generally, hold health care providers to a court-determined legal standard of care which, if violated, establishes the negligence of the provider. Negligence will, in turn, establish the liability of the physician, or other health care provider, for any resultant injuries suffered by the patient (see Keeton, et al., 1989, for a complete discussion of the law of torts). Tort law, generally, and medical malpractice law, specifically, serves two primary purposes. First, they compensate injured parties for losses caused by negligent accidents. Second, the threat of liability for negligence induces potential injurers to take precaution against potential harm (Brown, 1973; Landes and Posner, 1980, 1984; Cooter and Ulen, 1986; and Posner, 1986a). The medical malpractice literature tends to focus on the incentives created by medical malpractice law, known as the deterrence effect, rather than upon the compensation of negligent accidents although, certainly, exceptions exist (for example, Shavell, 1978). The larger law and economics literature does address the issue of compensation as it is related to involuntary insurance against adverse outcomes. That is, higher average compensation levels will, all else being equal, induce potential injurers such as physicians to increase the price of their services to all patients. The increased compensation is, in effect, an implicit insurance contract against the risk of potential malpractice injuries. This larger literature generally argues that from the point of view of optimal
1030
The Regulation of Medical Professions
5870
insurance, which is defined to be that level of insurance which a fully informed consumer would choose to buy himself, full compensation levels lead to higher levels of implicit insurance than is optimal (see Epstein, 1980; Priest, 1985, 1987; Schwartz, 1988; and Viscusi, 1991). With respect to deterrence, the theoretical literature attempts to determine whether or not negligence, or other alternative liability rules, will lead to optimal or efficient deterrence. Optimal deterrence occurs when the liability rule gives each party (that is, both health care provider and patient) an incentive to take actions, or precautions, which minimize the total costs of the medical injuries, including the expected accident costs of the injuries themselves, the costs of preventing such injuries and the administration costs associated with the malpractice system (Calabresi, 1970). Brown (1973) and others (for example, Landes and Posner, 1980, 1984; Cooter and Ulen, 1986; and Posner, 1986a) have shown that tort liability rules can be used to force both parties (that is, in medical malpractice both provider and patient can take actions to avoid harm from treatment) to consider the full potential loss and, hence, to take the optimal level of precaution. Unfortunately this result is only valid under very limiting conditions; the courts and both parties must have full and costless information. When information is costly to obtain and, hence, incomplete, tort law does not necessarily result in optimal deterrence (Cooter and Ulen, 1986; Haddock and Curran, 1985; Kolstad, Ulen, and Johnson, 1990; Shavell, 1987; and White 1989). Even though the theoretical literature on medical malpractice draws upon the general theoretical background of tort law, described above, the medical malpractice literature goes beyond this general theoretical framework, although not always by using formal, mathematical models of deterrence. For example, a number of researchers have addressed the issue of which liability rule, out of all possible liability rules, results in optimal deterrence for cases of medical malpractice (for example, Shavell, 1978; Danzon, 1985c). Currently, as noted above, medical malpractice uses some form of the negligence liability rule where the courts establish a legal standard of precaution against which a provider’s actual precaution is measured in order to determine negligence and liability. Alternatives to a negligence liability rule, such as a strict liability rule or a no-fault rule, could be used to determine liability (see Shavell, 1978; Danzon, 1985c; Epstein, 1978, 1988; Weiler, 1991). In contrast to a negligence rule, a strict liability rule does not compare a defendant’s level of precaution to a legal standard. Rather, as long as the accident or injury was caused by the medical treatment, the defendant is found liable for the costs of such accidents. Theoretically, the major advantage of strict liability is that it reduces the costs of the legal system because only causation must be demonstrated rather than, as in the case of negligence rules, both causation and negligence. However, determining causation for medical
5870
The Regulation of Medical Professions
1031
injuries is problematic as adverse medical outcomes routinely happen because of prior medical conditions. In medical malpractice, unlike other torts, causation is often determined to exist when an adverse outcome occurs and the defendant is found negligent. Hence, a finding of negligence is often required to prove causation which obviates the cost advantages of strict liability. Similar problems exist relative to no-fault proposals for medical malpractice because no-fault rules generally require proof of causation as well (Shavell, 1978; Epstein, 1978, 1988; Danzon, 1985c). Thus, medical malpractice gives health care providers an incentive to avoid negligent injuries caused by medical treatment. Under ideal conditions, medical malpractice results in optimal deterrence. However, since conditions are not, realistically, ideal, some thought, as noted above, has been given to alternatives to the negligence standard set up by medical malpractice, such as strict liability and no-fault rules. However, there is another, useful, way to look at medical malpractice. For example, Posner (1986a, 1981) has proposed that the law, especially common law, can be best understood as a method of achieving societal efficiency (that is, maximizing the wealth of society). Under Posner’s efficiency theory of the law, legal rules do not necessarily result in perfectly optimal, or first-best, outcomes. Rather, the law is seen as a system for achieving the best possible, or second-best, outcomes given the constraints faced in the real world (for example, costly and, hence, incomplete information). Given the efficiency theory of the law, it is useful to look at medical malpractice as an efficient, albeit imperfect, system. Somewhat surprisingly few researchers have attempted to examine medical malpractice from this viewpoint, especially in any formal sense. A number of researchers have, though, loosely noted that medical malpractice may either be efficient or not as inefficient as its harshest critics have claimed (for example, Frech, 1978). Even so, a number of these researchers continue by proposing reforms that, they suggest, will improve the malpractice system implying, at the very least, that malpractice has not yet reached its second best optimum (for example, Danzon, 1985). Thus, one of the flaws in the theoretical literature on medical malpractice remains an insistence that medical malpractice law is inefficient. As shown in the next section, the persistence of the view that malpractice is inefficient can be, for the most part, traced to the widespread perception in the literature that the medical malpractice system is in ‘crisis’.
8. The Medical Malpractice Crisis Perhaps more than any other event, significant changes in the medical malpractice insurance market during the past few decades have prompted the view of a malpractice system in crisis. For example, available evidence
1032
The Regulation of Medical Professions
5870
indicates that during most of the 1950s the market for medical malpractice insurance was quite stable with malpractice insurance being so unimportant that insurance agents typically sold medical malpractice policies to physicians along with their home and auto insurance (Sloan Bovbjerg and Githens, 1991). Beginning in the 1960s, however, malpractice insurance premiums rose dramatically, over 500 percent in the 1960s (Sloan, Bovbjerg and Githens, 1991; Posner, 1986) and by the mid 1970s a full blown ‘crisis’ was thought to have developed (Danzon, 1985a,1985b; Sloan, Bovbjerg and Githens, 1991; Robinson, 1986a). Not only did insurance premiums rise dramatically but in some states, most notably New York and California, malpractice insurance was not available at any price as insurance carriers left the states. Increases in malpractice insurance premiums continued into the 1980s. By some estimates, premiums increased as much as 45 percent from 1982 to 1984 (US GAO, 1986). Of more importance, medical malpractice premiums, which in the 1950s represented less than 1 percent of a physician’s total costs (Sloan, Bovbjerg and Githens, 1991), had risen to 9 percent of their total costs by 1984 (US GAO, 1986). The empirical medical malpractice literature gives insight into why malpractice premiums rose at such dramatic rates during this time period. Essentially, as with all insurance premiums, the root cause of increased premiums can be traced to increased average benefits paid by insurers. Three variables affect the average benefits paid by medical malpractice insurers. The frequency of malpractice claims measures how often, usually on a per capita or per physician basis, malpractice claims are being filed. The probability of malpractice claims measures the likelihood, most often measured by the ratio of paid claims to total claims for a period, that the physician will lose a given malpractice case. Malpractice severity simply measures the average size of the awards paid by defendants and their insurance companies for cases they lose. As malpractice frequency, probability, or severity rise the cost of providing insurance coverage increases and companies react by increasing malpractice insurance premiums (Olsen, 1996). A good part of the empirical malpractice literature has focused on estimating these three variables. The literature demonstrates that, not surprisingly, during the same decades that malpractice insurance premiums rose dramatically so did malpractice frequency, probability and severity. For example, although claim frequency remained stable from the 1950s through the early 1960s (AMA, 1969), by 1968 claim frequency had risen 76 percent from its earlier level (Danzon, 1985a). From the mid 1960s to the mid to late 1980s, claim frequency rose on average 7 to 10 percent annually. In general, however, claim frequency showed modest increases in the 1960s, rapid increases in the early 1970s, a leveling off in the mid 1970s, and more modest increases in the late 1970s and early 1980s (Danzon, 1985; Olsen, 1996; US Department of Health and Human Services, 1987).
5870
The Regulation of Medical Professions
1033
The available evidence, although somewhat sparse, indicates that malpractice probability also increased during this same time period. For example, some researchers estimate that plaintiffs won only 24 percent of malpractice cases in the mid 1960s which increased to as much as 53 percent by the mid 1980s (Peterson, 1987). Although Peterson’s estimates of malpractice probability only used data gathered from a few metropolitan areas, other estimates agree that by the mid 1980s malpractice probability had risen to approximately 50 percent (US GAO, 1987; Weiler, 1991). One of the major areas of concern in the literature has been the large increases in the average size of paid malpractice claims (malpractice severity) over the past three decades. From 1960 to 1984, for example, average malpractice awards in some areas rose from 10 to 14 percent annually on average (Peterson, 1987; also see Weiler, 1991 and Danzon, 1985b). Although average awards grew at rates exceeding 10 percent annually, median awards grew at much more modest rates, as low as 4 to 5 percent annually (Peterson, 1987; Weiler, 1991; Danzon, 1985b). Lower growth rates for median, as compared to average, awards indicate that much of the increase in average awards is due to a small number of cases with extremely large awards while most cases had much more modest increases. In addition, briefly compare the changes in malpractice frequency, probability, and severity noted above to changes in other areas of personal injury litigation. For the most part only product liability consistently demonstrated increases in frequency, probability and severity comparable to those discussed above for malpractice. For example, the number of product liability cases rose 16 percent on an average annual basis from 1975 to 1989 (Viscusi, 1991). Though Viscusi’s data is expressed as the number of claims filed, rather than as a frequency, it still gives an indication that product liability claims rose at large rates during the 1970s and 1980s. In support of this view, Peterson’s (1987) data indicates that product liability cases, as a percent of total cases in two locales, Cook County, Illinois and San Francisco, rose from 3 to 5 percent annually from 1960-64 to 1980-84. During the same time period, malpractice cases as a percent of total cases rose from 2 to 5 percent. Other types of personal injury cases, actually fell relative to total cases (for example, work injury and auto injury cases). Danzon’s (1985a) data from the 1970s has comparable findings as well. Similar to the frequency of cases, Peterson (1987) finds that product liability severity is comparable to malpractice severity, rising at fairly large rates (6 -11 percent) annually from the mid 1960s to the mid 1980s while average severity for other types of personal injury cases were much more modest (for example, annual increases of 2-5 percent for work injury claims; 4 to 5 percent for auto injury claims). Peterson (1987) finds similar trends for probability for these other types of injury claims.
1034
The Regulation of Medical Professions
5870
The above empirical evidence is gathered from US data. The literature does, however, give evidence that similar trends for medical malpractice frequency, probability and severity exist in other developed countries. For example, Dewees, Trebilcock and Coyte (1991), compared the US to Canada and found a number of similarities. Just as with the US, Canada experienced relatively stable malpractice frequency and severity during the 1950s. Thereafter, malpractice frequency and severity rose at much higher rates. From 1971 to 1990 average annual growth rates in Canadian frequency and severity were 6.1 percent and 9.6 percent respectively. Although Canadian growth rates are similar to US growth rates, US malpractice frequency during these years was consistently 8-10 times as large as Canadian malpractice frequency (Dewees, Trebilcock and Coyte, 1991). However, the average size of malpractice awards were fairly similar during this time period in the two countries, with a few years where malpractice severity was actually higher in Canada than in the US (Dewees, Trebilcock and Coyte, 1991). Likewise, a similar trend was found in the United Kingdom where both severity and frequency rose at about 17 percent on average annually from the mid 1970s to the mid to late 1980s. Unfortunately, the United Kingdom data presented by Dewees, Trebilcock and Coyte only allow comparison to their US and Canadian data for growth rates, but not for levels, of malpractice frequency and severity. Danzon (1990b) had similar findings in her comparison of the US to Canada, Australia, and the United Kingdom. In fact, Danzon found that growth rates in malpractice severity were substantially higher, on an average annual basis, in the UK and Canada than in the US However, she found similar growth rates in malpractice frequency (averaging about 10 percent annually) in all three countries. However, US levels of malpractice frequency were 5 to 6 times that of Canadian malpractice frequency even though, similar to Dewees, Trebilcock and Coyte (1991), levels of average severity in the two countries were quite similar. She also found that UK levels of malpractice frequency were one fifth to two thirds of the US levels, dependent upon the region of the country. Thus, the widespread belief in the existence of a medical malpractice crisis hinges upon two crucial empirical observations. First, it hinges upon the view that prior to the 1960s, the medical malpractice system was working smoothly with few cases and, more importantly, no significant growth in the frequency, severity, or probability of medical malpractice (for example, Danzon, 1985a, p. 2). Second, the belief in the malpractice crisis also relies upon the wellestablished facts, as detailed above, that all of these measures increased dramatically after the mid 1960s and that such growth continued in the 1970s and 1980s. Although the latter view is well established empirically, the former is not. Olsen (1996) uses available historical data to demonstrate that medical malpractice cases were not rare events prior to the 1950s as has been assumed
5870
The Regulation of Medical Professions
1035
by most studies of medical malpractice. More importantly, Olsen (1996) demonstrates that growth rates in malpractice frequency and severity over most of the US history from 1820 on were comparable to more recent growth rates (see also DeVille, 1990; Sandor, 1957; Sadusk, 1956). Hence, these data suggest that if a medical malpractice crisis does exist, it has been an ongoing crisis for more than 150 years. Of course, the possibility exists that there is no malpractice crisis, but that the malpractice system is simply responding to changing variables in an efficient manner. Frech (1978) identified this as a possibility in his early commentary on medical malpractice. Few researchers, as noted in the previous section, take into account the possibility that the malpractice system is working efficiently. The failure to even consider, let alone investigate, this possibility is the most glaring deficiency in the medical malpractice literature. In recent work, Olsen (1997a, 1997b) has begun to address this deficiency, both by considering the possibility that the malpractice system is efficient and by empirical testing of that hypothesis. Similar to Grady (1988), Olsen posits that increased technology and, especially, the increased physician productivity (that is, an increased ability of physicians to avoid medical injuries) that has historically been linked with increased technology, explains much of the historical increases of medical malpractice liability. In fact, Olsen (1997a) finds that such increased physician productivity has historically been correlated with increased liability, as would be efficient according to standard tort models (according to the deterrence hypothesis discussed above, it is efficient to give more productive physicians, those who can have a larger impact on medical injuries, per unit of input, a correspondingly larger incentive to avoid shirking on the use of those inputs). Likewise, Olsen (1997b) formally tests this hypothesis, relying on data from the 1980s, and finds further support for the hypothesis that malpractice law is efficient, imposing higher malpractice liability for physicians who are more productive at avoiding medical injuries (for example; more experienced physicians, board certified physicians, and so on). Another possibility worthy of mention, though rarely considered in the literature, which might explain the medical malpractice ‘crisis’ is that the low levels of physician liability existing prior to the 1960s might actually have been too low, resulting from physician capture of licensure and the consequent use of licensure to deny expert witness testimony in malpractice cases. A number of researchers detail the emergence of this phenomenon (Kessel, 1958; Starr, 1982; DeVille, 1990), which made it much more difficult for plaintiffs to prove malpractice against physicians. However, beginning in the 1960s it became much easier to obtain expert witness testimony against plaintiff physicians, partially due to the erosion of the locality rule (which limited expert witnesses to the those practicing in the plaintiff physician’s locale, where local medical societies had more control over physicians) and partially due to erosions in the ability of local medical societies to discipline such ‘unethical’ practices as the
1036
The Regulation of Medical Professions
5870
offering of expert witnesses (see Danzon, 1985; Weiler, 1991 and Olsen, 1997a).
9. Medical Malpractice Reform Regardless of whether a malpractice crisis actually existed or not, the widespread perception of a crisis led to public policy pressure (which continues to the present) to reform medical malpractice law in the US (Sloan, Bovbjerg and Githens, 1991; US Congress Senate, 1969). Although a near consensus existed regarding the need for reform, no consensus existed on the appropriate nature of medical malpractice reform. For example, some in the law and economics literature have proposed a move toward a contractual basis for medical malpractice liability (Epstein, 1976, 1978, 1986; Robinson, 1986b; and Havighurst 1983, 1986). Others have suggested that medical malpractice should adopt a no-fault liability system similar to worker’s compensation or no-fault automobile insurance (Weiler, 1991; Abramson, 1990; Johnson, et al., 1989; AMA, 1987; Danzon, 1985). Siliciano (1991) has argued that malpractice law should be reformed so as to hold providers of care to the poor to a lower standard of negligence. Dewees, Trebilcock and Coyte (1991) presents evidence that suggests that increased medical malpractice frequency, severity, and probability in Canada are only partially explained by changes in the Canadian legal environment. As a result, they suggest that US type tort reforms are unlikely to have much of an impact on malpractice in Canada and recommend that a wider view of malpractice be taken where reduction in malpractice liability could be attained through amelioration of other factors which they claim have contributed more to the ‘crisis’ (for example, a general increase in the willingness to litigate, the impact that increased medical technology has on patients’ unrealistic perceptions of favorable outcomes, and so on). Grady (1988) argues that the medical malpractice crisis has been caused, not by changes in the legal environment per se, but by increased technology. Grady distinguishes between two types of precaution, durable and nondurable precaution. Durable precaution is defined as precaution which has a long life and, therefore, need not be used repetitively (for example, Grady’s example is that of a dialysis machine). Nondurable precaution, often used as complements with durable precaution, do not have a long life and must, therefore, be used repetitively (for example, the medical technician must check that the dialysis machine is properly connected and running correctly). Grady makes two points relative to durable and nondurable precaution. First, increased technology tends to increase the harm associated with failures to take nondurable precautions (not paying attention has more potential harm when driving a semi-truck than when driving a wagon). Second, courts hold
5870
The Regulation of Medical Professions
1037
defendants strictly liable for failures to use nondurable precaution even though this is not optimal due to the positive costs associated with remembering to use the nondurable precaution. These two aspects together, Grady claims, explain much of the medical malpractice crisis. Hence, in order to reform the malpractice system, one must change legal rules dealing with nondurable precaution where the standard of care is non-optimal rather than focussing on legal rules (such as the doctrine of informed consent and revision of the locality rule) which many commentators see as responsible for the malpractice crisis. Olsen (1997b) investigates the impact of various physician characteristics upon physician liability, measuring physician liability by the likelihood of the physician losing a malpractice suit (an estimate of malpractice probability) and the size of the judgement awarded for paid malpractice claims (an estimate of malpractice severity). Olsen finds that physician characteristics, such as board certification, which tend to increase the productivity of a physician’s time, also tend to increase physician liability, all else equal. To the extent that the increased physician productivity associated with such variables is associated with increased technology, Olsen’s findings tend to support Grady’s contention that technological innovations lie at the heart of the historical increases in physician malpractice liability (see Olsen, 1997a for further evidence supporting Grady’s claim). However, as noted above and in contrast to Grady, Olsen’s findings are supportive of the hypothesis that medical malpractice law is efficient. Obviously, if medical malpractice law is already working relatively efficiently, no need exists for medical malpractice reform. Regardless of the widespread prescriptions for malpractice reform, actual public policy towards malpractice reform either passed by US state legislatures or found in US state and federal courts’ common law precedents have, in general, either explicitly rejected or have not even considered the proposed reforms discussed above. For example, courts have actually limited the ability of the parties to freely contract out of current medical malpractice liability rules (see Tunkl v. Regents of the University of California, 383 P.2d 441, Cal. 1963). Only two states, Florida and Virginia, have replaced medical malpractice liability with a no-fault liability system and then only for infants who suffer neurological trauma during birth (Weiler, 1991; Epstein, 1988; Tedcastle and Dewar, 1988). Rather than wholesale changes in the medical malpractice system, US courts and legislatures have, instead, focussed on reforms whose apparent intent is to diminish the perceived crisis by reducing malpractice frequency, severity, and probability. A few of the more popular US reforms, for example, include limiting plaintiff attorney fees, shortening the statute of limitations for malpractice claims, offsetting malpractice awards when plaintiffs have insurance which pays for injuries (collateral source rule), payment limits on malpractice awards, periodic payment of awards, arbitration, sometimes mandatory, of claims, and pre-trial screening of malpractice claims to establish
1038
The Regulation of Medical Professions
5870
merit (Olsen, 1996; Weiler, 1991; AMA, 1989; Bovbjerg, 1989; Danzon, 1985b). Malpractice reform of this nature has been extensive in the US, although carried out solely, to date, at the state level. For example, by 1989 states had, on average, passed 5 of the 10 most common reforms (Olsen, 1996). Much of the empirical research in the literature attempts to measure the impact of such reforms on medical malpractice frequency, severity and probability. At the same time, such research also measures the impact that other legal, social, or demographic variables have upon medical malpractice. Some of the earliest work assessing the impact of US malpractice reforms was done by Danzon (1984, 1985, 1986). Using US state level data from the 1970s she found that only a few of the malpractice reforms, dollar limitations on awards and the mandatory offset of collateral benefits (for example., from health insurance) had a significant negative impact on medical malpractice severity (Danzon, 1984). None of the other malpractice reforms that she tested had a significant impact on either frequency or severity. Further, she found no significant impact from any of the reforms upon frequency. Danzon did, however, find other variables that had a significant impact upon the frequency and severity of medical malpractice claims. For example, she found that urbanization was the most powerful explanatory variable. Further, pro-plaintiff laws passed prior to the 1970s were found to have a significant positive impact on both frequency and severity. In contrast to Danzon, Sloan (1985) estimated the impact that various factors, including malpractice reforms, had upon malpractice insurance premiums (see also Viscusi and Born, 1995). Malpractice insurance premiums reflect, albeit imperfectly, increased malpractice frequency and severity through increased average benefits paid by insurers. Similar to Danzon, Sloan found that malpractice reforms generally had little impact upon malpractice insurance premiums. He found that only pre-trial screening panels had a significant and negative impact on premiums while reforms requiring binding arbitration had a significant positive impact on premiums. In contrast to Danzon, who found that increased lawyer density had no significant impact on either frequency or severity, Sloan found that lawyer density had a significant positive impact on malpractice premiums. Danzon (1986) attributes this discrepancy between the two studies to Sloan’s failure to include urbanization as a control variable in his study. As Danzon (1984, 1986) notes, urbanization is likely to capture a number of relevant factors besides lawyer density which may also have a positive impact on malpractice frequency and severity and, eventually, upon malpractice insurance premiums as well. Danzon (1986) updated her earlier study, which had only used data from the 1970s, incorporating data from 1975 to 1984. As she notes, one of the weaknesses of both Danzon (1984) and Sloan (1985) is that the data used in these two studies come only from the 1970s, Danzon’s from 1975 through 1978 and Sloan’s from 1974 to 1978. However, the majority of the malpractice
5870
The Regulation of Medical Professions
1039
reforms were either passed or became effective after 1975. Hence, much of the data from these studies came from periods before the reforms were effective. Of more importance, as Danzon (1986) notes, it is plausible that the impact of the reforms would only occur with some lag after implementation, especially when estimating the impact of such reforms upon malpractice insurance premiums. Danzon’s (1986) update of her earlier work, using an expanded data set to capture any lagged effect of the malpractice reforms, found both similarities and differences as compared to her previous empirical estimates. For example, similar to her earlier study, urbanization was positively related to both malpractice frequency and severity. However, urbanization was negatively related to the percentage of paid claims which Danzon interprets to mean that urban areas have a higher than average number of non-meritorious malpractice claims. Consistent with her earlier study, lawyer density was found to have no impact upon either malpractice frequency or severity. In contrast to the earlier study, Danzon (1986) found several malpractice reforms which tended to reduce malpractice frequency including decreases in the number of years before reaching the statute of limitations (that is, a reduction in the number of years during which claims can be filed) and mandatory collateral source rules. In contrast, laws permitting voluntary binding arbitration had the impact of increasing claim frequency. Similar to her earlier study, dollar limitations on malpractice awards and the mandatory offset of collateral benefits were found to reduce malpractice severity by approximately 23 percent for the former and 11-18 percent for the latter. The allowance of voluntary binding arbitration was also found to reduce average severity by about 20 percent. However, as noted above, since arbitration increased the frequency of malpractice cases, these two effects tend to offset each other. Besides their impact upon malpractice frequency and severity, malpractice reforms have also been found to affect the decisions that plaintiffs and/or defendants face, once a claim has been filed. A malpractice claim can, ultimately, be dropped by the plaintiff, settled (which is a decision made by both parties), or continue to trial. In fact, in some states the decision becomes more complex since voluntary binding arbitration is offered as a fourth possibility. To the extent that malpractice reforms affect these decisions, the reforms will have an indirect impact on malpractice although not upon malpractice frequency (because the decision to file a claim occurs prior to the time when these decisions are made). The earliest studies in this area, malpractice claim disposition, were also done by Danzon (Danzon, 1980; Danzon and Lillard, 1983). The major difference between these two studies is that the later study uses a more recent data set and a statistical technique which attempts to correct for potential selection bias. This later study (Danzon and Lillard, 1983) found that some malpractice reforms had a significant impact on the decisions to drop, settle,
1040
The Regulation of Medical Professions
5870
or go to trial and, also, upon the dollar amount of verdicts for those cases going to trial. For example, they found that limitations on attorney’s fees caused plaintiffs to drop 5 percent more cases and decrease the proportion of cases litigated all the way to a verdict by 1.5 percent. Likewise, for settled cases, attorney fee limitations reduced the settlement size by 9 percent. For cases going to verdict, a mandatory collateral source offset rule reduced dollar awards by 15 percent. The impact of a number of reforms intended to reduce awards, such as dollar limits on the award and periodic payment of the award, were considered together and found to lead to a 30 percent reduction in average awards at verdict. Hughes (1989), using data from the late 1970s, also corrected for potential selection bias and corrected the potential bias introduced by the inaccurate measurement of malpractice reforms used by earlier claim disposition studies. Such studies had measured malpractice reforms by whether a given state had adopted a reform and not whether the adopted reform applied to a given claim. Hughes correctly noted that only claims filed after adoption of a given reform were affected by the reform even though the earlier studies had assumed that all claims closed after the adoption of a given reform, regardless of the date of filing, were affected by the reform. Correcting for these problems, he found that most of the malpractice reforms had no significant impact on the probability of settling a malpractice claim. Only limitations on lawyer fees and a collateral source offset rule significantly increased the probability of settling the claim. Hughes found that malpractice reforms had a much stronger impact on the decision to drop a malpractice claim. In fact, five of the eight reforms he considered, including limitations on awards and periodic payment of awards, increased the probability that the plaintiff would drop the case. Although Hughes did not measure the impact that reforms had on average awards, an increase in the tendency to drop cases would be expected to reduce average awards, all else equal. Using more recent data from the 1980s in addition to data from the 1970s, Sloan, Mergenhagen and Githens (1989) also estimated the effectiveness of the malpractice reforms in reducing malpractice liability. Similar to Hughes (1989), they used claims level data and could not, as a result, estimate the impact of malpractice reforms on claim frequency. They did, however, estimate the impact of malpractice reforms on both malpractice probability (that is, the probability that a claim would be paid) and severity (that is, the size of the award for paid claims). Similar to other researchers, they also found that malpractice reforms had an inconsistent impact. For example, limitations on awards were found to significantly reduce severity, as found by earlier researchers. Likewise, mandatory collateral source offset rules tended to reduce severity as well. Few of the rest of the reforms considered had a significant impact on severity. The only malpractice reform found to have a statistically significant impact on probability was the statute of limitations, where an increase in the number of years a plaintiff was allowed to file a claim increased the probability of payment.
5870
The Regulation of Medical Professions
1041
Zuckerman, Koller and Bovbjerg (1990) estimated the impact that tort reforms had upon medical malpractice insurance premiums, frequency and severity. Again, they found that malpractice reforms had an inconsistent impact on malpractice insurance premiums. The only reforms which significantly lowered premiums were those which limited the size of awards or those which limited the statute of limitations (Viscusi and Born, 1995, had similar findings with respect to malpractice premiums). None of the malpractice reforms were found to decrease frequency. Similar to other studies, Zuckerman, Koller and Bovbjerg also found that limitations on awards, collateral source offset rules and limitations on attorney fees tended to reduce malpractice severity. Synthesizing the empirical work estimating the impact of malpractice reforms, it becomes clear that not all reforms have a consistent impact on provider liability or insurance premiums. Reforms such as limitations on awards, collateral source rules, and shortened statute of limitations have had the most consistent impact on such liability. Most other reforms have only occasionally been found to have an impact on the medical malpractice liability of health care providers. There are several public policy implications that may be gleaned from this empirical evidence. For example, if one takes the view that a crisis exists and needs amelioration, the empirical evidence highlights the types of reforms that would have the most probability of decreasing malpractice liability. Of course, as Hughes and Snyder (1989) illustrate, some care must be taken when making such public policy decisions. Care must be taken because the impact of the reforms is, theoretically, quite complex. For example, a reform may have the impact of decreasing severity, but changes in severity theoretically also have two competing impacts upon the frequency of claims. First, decreases in average awards give potential plaintiffs less incentive to file claims. However, decreases in average awards increases the incentive of potential defendants to be negligent which, in turn, increases the number of potential claims. As a result, predicting the impact of a given reform upon malpractice liability, ex ante, is problematic. Finally, given that neither malpractice cases nor large growth rates in malpractice liability are recent phenomena, as many in the literature assume to be the case, public policymakers must carefully consider whether the medical malpractice crisis is real or illusory. Most reforms, as outlined above, have little consistent impact on malpractice liability. One possible explanation for this is that the reforms, although intended to reduce liability, have not been well enough constructed to actually have that impact. Another possible explanation, though, is that the common law efficiently takes into account malpractice reform in the long run. That is, the law is flexible enough to overcome inefficient efforts to reduce malpractice liability. This area is, as noted above, one where much additional research must be done before being able to come to any firm conclusions. However, it is an area which must be investigated in
1042
The Regulation of Medical Professions
5870
order to ‘round out the circle’ of the medical malpractice literature (Calabresi, 1978).
10. Conclusions Theoretically, health care providers are found liable for negligence under medical malpractice law in order to optimally deter them from negligent treatment. Although the literature, as noted above, consistently assumes that medical malpractice fails to meet the goal of optimal deterrence because of imperfections in the legal system, it also consistently notes that such deterrence is a valid and necessary public policy goal. More than any other event, increased health care provider liability over the past three decades has resulted in the common perception that the medical malpractice system is both imperfect and in need of reform. Some care, however, must be taken in this conclusion as recent evidence indicates that, contrary to the common perception, substantial growth rates in health care provider liability for malpractice is not new phenomena nor limited to the US Much, if not most, of the literature on medical malpractice has focussed on either the need for, and the most efficient type of, malpractice reform or the impact that existing reforms have had on medical malpractice. Little of the literature has, however, seriously considered the possibility that malpractice reform is neither necessary nor optimal. Given the questionable basis for the common conclusion that malpractice reform is necessary, that a smoothly working malpractice system has suddenly gone into crisis, the possible efficiency of medical malpractice, at least on a second-best level, must be seriously evaluated by researchers. Common medical malpractice reforms in the US have had an inconsistent affect on medical malpractice liability. Some reforms, such as limitations on awards, collateral sources rules, and shortening the statute of limitations, have been found to have a fairly consistent impact on malpractice liability. Other reforms have been found, though, to either have no significant impact or an inconsistent impact on malpractice liability. As noted in the previous section, the inconsistent impact of reforms intended to reduce malpractice liability may mean, as some researchers have suggested, that more care should be paid to the nature of malpractice reform. However, it may also be the case that the reforms are ineffective because the law (for example, judges and juries) is flexible enough to obviate the reforms and still impose increased liability on health care providers. Again, this may be an efficient response to changes in medical relationships, leading one to again conclude that future research is needed which considers the possibility that current increased levels of liability are simply an efficient response to changing circumstances. Thus, a need exists for a better theoretical understanding of what changes would cause an efficient
5870
The Regulation of Medical Professions
1043
increase in malpractice liability for health care providers. One possible change which might efficiently lead to increased provider liability is the increased technological ability of medicine to provide efficacious treatment that has, especially, occurred in the last three decades simultaneous with the recent increase in malpractice liability (see Graddy, 1991 and Olsen, 1997a, 1997b for discussions on the impact of increased technology on medical malpractice).
Bibliography on The Regulation of Medical Professions (5870) Abramson, Elliott M. (1990), ‘The Medical Malpractice Imbroglio: A Non-Adversarial Suggestion’, 78 Kentucky Law Journal, 293 ff. Arnould, Richard J. and Van Vorst, Charles B. (1985), ‘Supply Responses to Market and Regulatory Forces in Health Care’, in Meyer, Jack A. (ed.), Incentives vs. Controls in Health Policy: Broadening the Debate, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 107-131. Arrow, Kenneth J. (1963), ‘Uncertainty and the Welfare Economics of Medical Care’, 53 American Economic Review, 941-973. Benham, Lee (1991), ‘Licensure and Competition in Medical Markets’, in Frech, H.E. (ed.), Regulating Doctors’ Fees: Competition, Benefits, and Controls under Medicare, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute. Benham, Lee and Benham, Alexandra (1975), ‘Regulating Through the Professions: A Perspective on Information Control’, 18 Journal of Law and Economics, 421-447. Benham, Lee, Maurizi, A. and Reder, M.W. (1968), ‘Migration, Location and Remuneration of Medical Personel: Physicians and Dentists’, 50 Review of Economics and Statistics, 332-347. Berlant, J.L. (1975), Profession and Monopoly: A Study of Medicine In The United States and Great Britain, Berkeley, University of California Press. Boulier, Bryan L. (1980), ‘An Empirical Examination of the Influence of Licensure and Licensure Reform on the Geographical Distribution of Dentists’, in Rottenberg, Simon (ed.), Occupational Licensure and Regulation, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute. Bovbjerg, Randall R. (1989), ‘Legislation on Medical Malpractice: Further Developments and a Preliminary Report Card’, 22 U.C. Davis Law Review, 499 ff. Burstein, P.L. and Cromwell, J. (1985), ‘Relative Incomes and Rates of Return for US Physicians’, 4 Journal of Health Economics, 63-78. Calabresi, Guido (1977), ‘The Problem of Malpractice: Trying to Round out the Circle’, 27 University of Toronto Law Journal, 131-141. Calabresi, Guido (1978), ‘The Problem of Malpractice - Trying to Round out the Circle’, in Rottenberg, S. (ed.), The Economics of Medical Malpractice, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 233-243. Carroll, Sidney L. and Gaston, Robert J. (1981), ‘Occupational Restrictions and the Quality of Service Received: Some Evidence’, 48 Southern Economic Journal, 959-975. Chollet, Deborah J. (1985), ‘Liability Rules and Health Care Costs’, in Baily, Mary Ann and Cikins, Warren I. (eds), The Effects of Litigation on Health Care Costs, Washington, Brookings Institution, 22-27.
1044
The Regulation of Medical Professions
5870
Conrad, Douglas A. and Watts, Carolyn A. (1981), ‘A Note on Measuring the Extent of Competition in the Physicians’ Services Market: An Alternative Approach’,3 Research in Law and Economics, 241-249. Coyte, Peter C., Dewees, Donald N. and Trebilcock, Michael J. (1990), ‘Medical Malpractice in Canada, 1971-1987', 15 Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance, 55-80. Danzon, Patricia. (1980), The Disposition of Medical Malpractice Claims, The RAND Corporation, Report R-2622-HCFA. Danzon, Patricia M. (1984), ‘The Frequency and Severity of Medical Malpractice Claims’, 27 Journal of Law and Economics, 115-148. Danzon, Patricia M. (1985a), Medical Malpractice: Theory, Evidence, and Public, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 264 p. Danzon, Patricia M. (1985b), ‘The Medical Malpractice System: Facts and Reforms’, in Baily, Mary Ann and Cikins, Warren I. (eds), The Effects of Litigation on Health Care Costs, Washington, Brookings Institution, 28-35. Danzon, Patricia M. (1985c), ‘Liability and Liability Insurance for Medical Malpractice’, 4 Journal of Health Economics, 309-331. Danzon, Patricia M. (1986), ‘The Frequency and Severity of Medical Malpractice Claims: New Evidence’, 49(2) Law and Contemporary Problems. Danzon, Patricia. (1988), ‘Medical Malpractice Liability’, in Litan, R. and Winston, C. (eds), Liability: Perspectives and Policy, Washington, Brookings Institute Danzon, Patricia M. (1990a), ‘Alternative Liability Regimes for Medical Injuries’, 15 Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance, 3-21. Danzon, Patricia M. (1990b), ‘The “Crisis” in Medical Malpractice: A Comparison of Trends in the United States, Canada, the United Kingdom and Australia’, 18(1-2) Law, Medicine and Health Care, 48 ff. Danzon, Patricia M. (1991), ‘Liability for Medical Malpractice’, 5(3) Journal of Economic Perspectives, 51-69. Danzon, Patricia M. (1994), ‘The Swedish Patient Compensation System: Myths and Realities’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 453-466. Danzon, Patricia M. (1997), ‘Tort Liability: A Minefield for Managed Care?’, 16 Journal of Legal Studies, 491-519. Danzon, Patricia M. and Lillard, Lee A. (1983), ‘Settlement out of Court: The Disposition of Medical Malpractice Claims’, 12 Journal of Legal Studies, 345-377. Danzon, Patricia M., Pauly, Mark V. and Kingston, Raynard S. (1990), ‘The Effects of Malpractice Litigation on Physicians’ Fees and Income’, 80 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 122-127. Devany, Arthur S., Gramm, Wendy L., Saving, Thomas R. and Smithson, Charles W. (1982), ‘The Impact of Input Regulation: The Case of the US Dental Industry’, 25 Journal of Law and Economics, 367-381. Dewees, Donald N., Trebilcock, Michael, J. and Coyte, Peter C. (1991), ‘The Medical Malpractice Crisis: A Comparative Empirical Perspective’, 54(1) Law and Contemporary Problems, 217-251. Dolan, A.K. (1980), ‘Occupational Licensure and Obstruction of Change in the Health Care Delivery System: Some Recent Developments’, in Blair, Roger D. and Rubin, Stephen (eds), Regulating the Professions: A Public-Policy Symposium, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Dranove, David, Shanley, Mark and White, William D. (1993), ‘Price and Concentration in Hospital Markets: The Switch from Patient-Driven to Payer-Driven Competition’, 36 Journal of Law and
5870
The Regulation of Medical Professions
1045
Economics, 179-204. Eisenberg, Barry S. (1980), ‘Information Exchange among Competitors: The Issue of Relative Value Scales for Physicians’ Services’, 23 Journal of Law and Economics, 441-460. Elhauge, Einer Richard (1994), ‘Allocating Health Care Morally’, 82 California Law Review, 1449 ff. Elhauge, Einer Richard (1996), ‘The Limited Potential of Medical Technology Assessment’, 82 Virginia Law Review. Epstein, Richard (1976), ‘Medical Malpractice: The Case for Contract’, 76 American Bar Foundation Research Journal, 87 ff. Epstein, Richard (1978), ‘Medical Malpractice: its Cause and Cure’, in Rottenberg, S. (ed.), The Economics of Medical Malpractice, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research. Epstein, Richard A. (1986), ‘Medical Malpractice, Imperfect Information, and the Contractual Foundation for Medical Services’, 49(2) Law and Contemporary Problems, 201-212. Epstein, Richard A. (1988), ‘Market and Regulatory Approaches to Medical Malpractice: The Virginia Obstetrical No-Fault Statute’, 74 Virginia Law Review, 1451-1474. Evans, R.G. (1976), ‘Does Canada have too many Doctors? - Why Nobody Loves an Immigrant Physician’, 11 Canadian Public Policy, 147-159. Evans, R.G., Parish, E.M.A. and Sully, F. (1973), ‘Medical Productivity, Scale Effects and Demand Generation’, 6 Canadian Journal of Economics, 376-393. Fein, Rashi (1967), The Doctor Shortage: An Economic Diagnosis, Washington, Brookings Institution, 199 p. Fein, Rashi and Weber, Gerald I. (1971), Financing Medical Education, An Analysis of Alternative Policies and Mechanisms, New York, Carnegie Commission on Higher Education and the Commonwealth Fund. Feldman, P.H. (1980), ‘The Impact of Third-Party Payment on Professional Practice: Lessons from the Medical Profession’, in Blair, Roger D. and Rubin, Stephen (eds), Regulating the Professions: A Public-Policy Symposium, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Feldman, Roger and Begun, James W. (1985), ‘The Welfare Costs of Quality Changes Due to Professional Regulation’, 34 Journal of Industrial Economics, 17 ff. Feldstein, Martin S. (1970), ‘The Rising Price of Physicians’ Services’, 52 Review of Economics and Statistics, 121-133. Feldstein, P.J. (1977), Health Associations and the Demand for Legislation, Cambridge, MA, Ballinger. Feldstein, Paul J. (1988), Health Care Economics, New York, Delmar Publishers, 634 p. Fine, Max W. and Sunshine, Jonathan H. (1986), ‘Malpractice Reform through Consumer Choice and Consumer Education: Are New Concepts Marketable?’, 49(2) Law and Contemporary Problems, 213-222. Frech, H. Edward III (1974), ‘Occupational Licensure and Health Care Productivity: The Issues and the Literature’, in Rafferty, John A. (ed.), Health, Manpower and Productivity, Lexington, Lexington Books, chapter 6, 119-142. Frech, H. Edward III (1976), ‘Property Rights Theory of the Firm: Empirical Results from a Natural Experiment’, 84 Journal of Political Economy, 143-152. Frech, H. Edward III (1977), ‘The Economics of Medical Malpractice: Commentary’, in Rottenberg,
1046
The Regulation of Medical Professions
5870
Simon (ed.), The Economics of Medical Malpractice, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 280-288. Frech, H. Edward III (1978), ‘Commentary’, in Rottenberg, S. (ed.), Occupational Licensure and Regulation, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 280-288. Frech, H. Edward III (1980a), ‘Market Power in Health Insurance: Effects on Insurance and Medical Markets’, 18(1) Journal of Industrial Economics, 55-72. Frech, H. Edward III (1980b), ‘Health Insurance: Private, Mutual or Government’, S.1 Research in Law and Economics, 61-73. Frech, H. Edward III (1980c), ‘Blue Cross, Blue Shield and Health Care Costs: A Review of the Economic Evidence’, in Paul, Mark V. (ed.), National Health Insurance: What Now, What Later, What Never, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 250-263. Frech, H. Edward III (1981), ‘The Long-Lost Free Market in Health Care: Government and Professional Regulation in Medicine’, in Olson, Mancur (ed.), A New Appraoch to the Economics of Health Care, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 44-66. Frech, H. Edward III (1984a), ‘Competition in Medical Care: Research and Policy’, 5 Advances in Health Economics and Health Services Research, 1-27. Frech, H. Edward III (1984b), ‘The Social Benefits of Price Competition in Medicine’, 28(1) Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 40-48. Frech, H. Edward III (1985a), ‘Le Système Américain de Securité Sociale (The United States Health Care System)’, in X (ed.), O— Vont les Systèmes de Santé? Les Carrefours de l’Industrie Pharmaceutique, Paris, Publications Essentielles, 25-30. Frech, H. Edward III (1985b), ‘The Property Rights Theory of the Firm: Some Evidence form the US Nursing Home Industry’, 141 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 146-166. Frech, H. Edward III (1987), ‘Comments on Antitrust Issues’, 7 Advances in Health Economics and Health Services Research, 263-267. Frech, H. Edward III (1988), ‘Introduction: The Political Economy of Health Care’, in Frech, H.E., III (ed.), Health Care in America: The Political Economy of Hospitals and Health Insurance, San Fransisco, Pacific Research Institute, 1-26. Frech, H. Edward III (1988b), ‘Review of the Health Economy by Victor Fuchs’, 95(6) Journal of Political Economy, 1337-1340. Frech, H. Edward III (1988c), ‘Monopoly in Health Insurance: The Economics of Kartell v. Blue Shield of Massachusetts’, in Frech, H.E., III (ed.), Health Care in America: The Political Economy of Hospitals and Health Insurance, San Fransisco, Pacific Research Institute, 293-322. Frech, H. Edward III (1988d), ‘Preferred Provider Organizations and Health Care Competition’, in Frech, H.E., III (ed.), Health Care in America: The Political Economy of Hospitals and Health Insurance, San Fransisco, Pacific Research Institute, 353-372. Frech, H. Edward III (1990), ‘The United States (Health Care System)’, in Rosa, Jean-Jacques (ed.), Advances in Health Economics and Health Services Research, 43-76. Frech, H. Edward III (1991a), ‘Overview of Policy Issues’, in Frech, H.E., III (ed.), Regulating Doctor’s Fees: Competition, Benefits and Controls under Medicare, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 1-34. Frech, H. Edward III (1991b), Regulating Doctor’s Fees: Competition, Benefits and Controls under Medicare, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research.
5870
The Regulation of Medical Professions
1047
Frech, H. Edward III (ed.) (1991c), Health Economics Worldwide, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers. Frech, H. Edward III (1992), ‘Review of Serious and Unstable Condition: Financing America’s Health Care, by Henry J. Aaron’, 30 Journal of Economic Literature, 2165-2166. Frech, H. Edward III (1993), ‘What Can Reform Achieve in Health Care Cost-Containment: Commentary’, in Helms, Robert B. (ed.), American Health Policy: Critical Issues for Reform, Wadhington, American Enterprise Institute, 298-302. Frech, H. Edward III (1993b), ‘Health Insurance: Designing Products to Reduce Costs’, in Duetsch, Larry L. and Cliffs, Englewood (eds), Indusrty Studies, New York, Prentice Hall, 307-323. Frech, H, Edward III (1993c), ‘Economie de la Santé’, 103(2) Revue d’Economie Politique, 609-611. Frech, H.E. III (1996), Competition and Monopoly in Medical Care, Washington, DC, The AEI Press, 191 p. Frech, H. Edward III and Ginsburg, Paul G. (1975), ‘Imposed Health Insurance in Monopolistic Markets, A Theoretical Analysis’, 13(1) Economic Inquiry, 55-70. Frech, H. Edward III and Ginsburg, Paul G. (1978a), Public Insurance in Private Medical Markets: Some Problems of National Health Insurance, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research. Frech, H. Edward III and Ginsburg, Paul G. (1978b), ‘Competition Among Health Insurers’, in Greenberg, Warren (ed.), Competition in the Health Care Sector: Past, Presence and Future, Washington, Federal Trade Commission, 210-237. Reprinted by Aspen Systems, Germantown, MD. Frech, H. Edward III and Ginsburg, Paul G. (1980), ‘The Cost of Nursing Home Care in the United States: Government Financing, Ownership and Efficiency’, in Van Der Gaag, Jaques and Perlman, Mark (eds), Health, Economics and Health Economics: Proceedings of the World Congress on Health Economics, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 67-91. Frech, H. Edward III and Ginsburg, Paul G. (1981), ‘Property Rights and Competition in Health Insurance: Multiple Objectives for Nonprofit Firms’,3 Research in Law and Economics, 155-172. Frech, H. Edward III and Ginsburg, Paul G. (1988), ‘Competition Among Health Insurers, Revisited’, 13(2) Journal of Health Politics, Policy and Law, 279-291. Reprinted Greenberg, Warren, Competition in the Health Care Sector: Ten Years Later, Durham, NC, Duke University Press, pp. 57-70. Frech, H. Edward III and Mobley, Lee Rivers (1994), ‘Firm Growth and Failure in Increasingly Competitive Markets: Theory and Application to Hospital Markets’, 1(1) Journal of the Economics of Business, 77-94. Frech, H. Edward III and Mobley, Lee Rivers (1995), ‘Resolving the Impasse on Hospital Scale Economies: A New Approach’, 27 Applied Economics, 286-296. Frech, H. Edward III and Woolley, Michael J. (1989), ‘How Hospitals Compete: A Review of Literature’, 2 Journal of Law and Public Policy, 57-80. Frech, H. Edward III and Woolley, Michael J. (1992), ‘Consumer Information, Price and Nonprice Competition Among Hospitals’, in Frech, H.E., III and Zweifel, Peter (eds), Health Economics Worldwide: Proceeding of the Second World Congres on Health Economics, Dordrecht, Kluwer, 217-244.
1048
The Regulation of Medical Professions
5870
Frech, H. Edward III and Zweifel, Peter (1991), ‘Preface’, in Frech, H.E. III and Zweifel, Peter (eds), Health Economics Worldwide: Proceeding of the Second World Congres on Health Economics, Dordrecht, Kluwer, 7-8. Frech, H. Edward III, Borjas, George J. and Ginsburg, Paul B. (1983), ‘Property Rights and Wages: The Case of Nursing Homes’, 18(2) Journal of Human Resources, 231-246. Friedman, Milton (1962), ‘Occupational Licensure’ in Capitalism and Freedom, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Friedman, Milton and Kuznets, S. (1945), Income from Independent Professional Practice, New York, National Bureau of Economic Research. Goldberg, Victor P. (1975), ‘Some Emerging Problems of Prepaid Health Plans in the Medi-Cal System’, 1 Policy Analysis, 55-68. Goldberg, Victor P. and Auger, Richard (1974), ‘Prepaid Health Plans and Moral Hazard’, 22 Public Policy, 353-397. Goldsmith, Art (1989), ‘Dental Hygienists’ Wages: The Role of Human Capital and Institutional Factors’, 29(2) Quarterly Review of Economics and Business, 56-67. Graddy, Elizabeth (1991), ‘Toward a General Theory of Occupational Regulation’, 72 Social Science Quarterly, 676-695. Grady, Mark F. (1988), ‘Why Are People Negligent?: Technology, Nondurable Precautions, and the Medical Malpractice Explosion’, 82 Northwestern University Law Review, 293 ff. Gravelle, Hugh S.E. (1990), ‘Medical Negligence: Evaluating Alternative Regimes’, 15 Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance, 22-26. Haas-Wilson, Deborah (1986), ‘The Effect of Commercial Practice Restrictions: The Case of Optometry’, 29 Journal of Law and Economics, 165-186. Hall, Thomas D. and Lindsay, Cotton M. (1980), ‘Medical Schools: Producers of What? Sellers to Whom?’, 23 Journal of Law and Economics, 55-80. Havighurst, Clark C. (1983), ‘Decentralizing Decision Making: Private Contract versus Professional Norms’, in Meyer J. (ed.), Market Reforms in Health Care. Havighurst, Clark C. (1986), ‘Private Reform of Tort-Law Dogma: Market Opportunities and Legal Obstacles’, 49 Law and Contemporary Problems, 143 ff. Holen, Arlene S. (1965), ‘Effects of Professional Licensing Arrangements on Interstate Labor Mobility and Resource Allocation’, 73 Journal of Political Economy, 492-498. Hughes, James W. (1989), ‘The Effect of Medical Malpractice Reform Laws on Claim Disposition’, 9 International Review of Law and Economics, 57-78. Hughes, James W. and Savoca, Elizabeth (1997), ‘Measuring the Effect of Legal Reforms on the Longevity of Medical Malpractice Claims’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 261-273. Hughes, James W. and Snyder, Edward A. (1989a), ‘Evaluating Medical Malpractice Reforms’, 7(2) Contemporary Policy Issues, 83-498. Hughes, James W. and Snyder, Edward A. (1989b), ‘Policy Analysis of Medical Malpractice Reforms: What Can We Learn from Claims Data?’, 7 Journal of Business and Economic Statistics, 423-431. Hunsaker, Ann T. (1985), ‘The Federal Government’s Perspective on Litigation and Health Care Costs’, in Baily, Mary Ann and Cikins, Warren I. (eds), The Effects of Litigation on Health Care Costs, Washington, Brookings Institution, 11-21. Johnson, K., Phillips, C., Orentlicher, D. and Hatlie, M. (1989), ‘A Fault-Based Administrative Alternative for Resolving Medical Malpractice Claims’, 42 Vanderbilt Law Review, 1365 ff.
5870
The Regulation of Medical Professions
1049
Joskow, Paul L. (1981), Controlling Hospital Costs: The Role of Government Regulation, Cambridge, MIT Press, 211 p. Kendall, M.C. (1978), ‘Expectations, Imperfect Markets, and Medical Malpractice Insurance’, in Rottenberg, S. (ed.), The Economics of Medical Malpractice, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research. Kessel, Reuben A. (1958), ‘Price Discrimination in Medicine’, 1 Journal of Law and Economics, 20-53. Kessel, Reuben A. (1970), ‘The A.M.A. and the Supply of Physicians’, 35 Law and Contemporary Problems, 267-283. Kessel, Reuben A. (1972), ‘Higher Education and the Nation’s Health: A Review of the Carnegie Commission Report on Medical Education’, 15 Journal of Law and Economics, 115-127. Leffler, Keith B. (1978), ‘Physician Licensure: Competition and Monopoly in American Medicine’, 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 165-186. Lindsay, Cotton M. (1971), ‘Measuring Human Capital Returns’, 79 Journal of Political Economy, 1195-1215. Lindsay, Cotton M. (1973), ‘Real Returns to Medical Education’, 8 Journal of Human Resources, 331-348. Lynk, William J. (1988), ‘Physician Price Fixing under the Sherman Act: An Indirect Test of the Maricopa Issues’, 7 Journal of Health Economics, 95-109. Marder, William D. and Willke, Richard J. (1991), ‘Comparisons of the Value of Physician Time by Specialty’, in Frech, H.E. (ed.), Regulating Doctors’ Fees: Competition, Benefits, and Controls under Medicare, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute. Maurizi, Alex R. (1974), ‘Occupational Licensing and the Public Interest’, 82 Journal of Political Economy, 399-413. McCoid, Allan H. (1959), ‘The Care Required of Medical Practitioners’, 12 Vanderbilt Law Review, 549-632. Mennemeyer, S.T. (1978), ‘Really Great Returns to Medical Education?’, 13 Journal of Human Resources, 75-90. Metzloff, Thomas B. (1988), ‘Researching Litigation: The Medical Malpractice Example’, 51(4) Law and Contemporary Problems, 199-241. Moore, Thomas G. (1961), ‘A Theory of Professional Licensing’, 4 Journal of Law and Economics, 93-117. Newhouse, Joseph P., Williams, Albert P., Bennett, Bruce W. and Schwartz, William B. (1982), ‘Does the Geographical Distribution of Physicians Reflect Market Failure?’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 493-505. Noether, Monica (1986), ‘The Effect of Government Policy Changes on the Supply of Physicians: Expansion of a Competitive Fringe’, 29 Journal of Law and Economics, 231-262. Olsen, Reed Neil (1996), ‘The Reform of Medical Malpractice Law: Historical Perspectives’, 55 The American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 257-275. Olsen, Reed Neil (1997a), ‘The Efficiency of Medical Malpractice Law: A New Appraisal’, 19 Research in Law and Economics. Olsen, Reed Neil (1997b), The Efficiency of Medical Malpractice: Theory and Empirical Evidence, Working Paper, Department of Economics, Southwest Missouri State University. Pashigian, B. Peter (1979), ‘Occupational Licensing and the Interstate Mobility of Professionals’, 22 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-25.
1050
The Regulation of Medical Professions
5870
Pashigian, B. Peter (1980), ‘Has Occupational Licensing Reduced Geographical Mobility and Raised Earnings?’, in Rottenberg, Simon (ed.), Occupational Licensure and Regulation, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute. Peterson, Michael (1987), Civil Juries in the 1980s: Trends in Jury Trials and Verdicts in California and Cook County, Illinois, The RAND Corporation, Report R-3466-ICJ. Phelps, Charles E. (1992), Health Economics, New York, HarperCollins Publishers, 559 p. Porter, John E. (1985), ‘The Effects of Litigation on Health Care Costs: A Congressional Perspective’, in Baily, Mary Ann and Cikins, Warren I. (eds), The Effects of Litigation on Health Care Costs, Washington, Brookings Institution, 36-42. Posner, James R. (1986a), ‘Trends in Medical Malpractice Insurance, 1970-1985', 49(2) Law and Contemporary Problems, 37-156. Psacharopoulos, G. (1975), Earnings and Education in OECD Countries, Paris, OECD. Quam, Lois (1990), ‘Comment: Medical Malpractice in Canada, 1971-1987', 15 Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance, 81-83. Reder, M.W. (1976a), ‘Medical Malpractice: An Economist’s Viewpoint’, 2 American Bar Foundation Research Journal, 511-563. Reder, Melvin W. (1976b), ‘An Economic Analysis of Medical Malpractice’, 5 Journal of Legal Studies, 267-292. Resta, Giorgio (1996), ‘Scarsit… delle Risorse e Funzione Allocativa del Diritto: il Caso dei Trapianti d’Organo (Scarsity of Resources and Allocative Function of the Law: the Case of Organ Transplants)’, Rivista Critica del Diritto Privato, 111-159. Rizzo, John A. and Zeckhauser, Richard J. (1990), ‘Advertising and Entry: The Case of Physician Services’, 98 Journal of Political Economy, 476-500. Robinson, Glen O. (1986a), ‘The Medical Malpractice Crisis of the 1970's: A Retrospective’, 49(2) Law and Contemporary Problems, 5-35. Robinson, Glen O. (1986b), ‘Rethinking the Allocation of Medical Malpractice Risks between Patients and Providers’, 49(2) Law and Contemporary Problems, 173-199. Rottenberg, Simon (ed.) (1978), The Economics of Medical Malpractice, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 293 p. Sass, Tim R. and Nichols, Mark W. (1996), ‘Scope-of-Practice Regulation: Physician Control and the Wages of Non-Physician Health-Care Professionals’, 9 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 61 ff. Schwartz, Gary T. (1991), ‘Products Liability and Medical Malpractice in Comparative Context’, in Huber, Peter W. and Litan, Robert E. (eds), Liability Maze: The Impact of Liability Law on Innovation and Safety, Washington, Brookings Institute, 28-80. Schwartz, Gary T. (1994), ‘A National Health Program: What its Effect would be on American Tort Law and Malpractice Law’, 79 Cornell Law Review, 1339-1381. Shavell, Steven (1978), ‘Theoretical Issues in Medical Malpractice’, in Rottenberg, Simon (ed.), The Economics of Medical Malpractice, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 35-64. Shepard, Lawrence (1978), ‘Licensing Restrictions and the Cost of Dental Care’, 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 187-201. Siliciano, John A. (1991), ‘Wealth, Equity, and the Unitary Medical Malpractice Standard’, 77 Virginia Law Review, 439-487. Sloan, Frank A. (1970), ‘Lifetime Earnings and Physicians’ Choice of Specialty’, 24 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 47-56. Sloan, Frank A. (1985), ‘State Responses to the Malpractice Insurance "Crisis" of the 1970s: An Empirical Assessment’, 9 Journal of Health Politics, Policy, and Law, 629 ff.
5870
The Regulation of Medical Professions
1051
Sloan, Frank A. and Bovbjerg, Randall R. (1989), Medical Malpractice: Crises, Response, and Effects, Washington, Health Insurance Association of America. Sloan, Frank A. and Steinwald, Bruce (1980), ‘Effects of Regulation on Hospital Costs and Input Use’, 23 Journal of Law and Economics, 81-109. Sloan, Frank A., Bovbjerg, Randall R. and Githens, P.B. (1991), Insuring Medical Malpractice, New York, NY, Oxford University Press. Sloan, Frank A., Entman, Stephen S., Reilly, Bridget A., Glass, Cheryl A., Hickson, Gerald B. and Zhang, Harold H. (1997), ‘Tort Liability and Obstetricians’ Care Levels’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 245-260. Sloan, Frank A., Mergenhagen, Paula M. and Bovbjerg, Randall R. (1989), ‘Effects of Tort Reforms on the Value of Closed Medical Malpractice Claims: A Microanalysis’, 14(4)6636 Journal of Health Politics, Policy and Law. Svorny, Shirley V. (1987), ‘Physician Licensure: A New Approach to Examining the Role of Professional Interests’, 25 Economic Inquiry, 497-509. Symposium, Medical Malpractice (1976), 1975(6) Duke Law Journal, 1179-1468. Symposium (1986), ‘Medical Malpractice: Can the Private Sector Find Relief?’, 49(2) Law and Contemporary Problems, 1-348. Symposium, Medical Malpractice (1991), 54(1) Law and Contemporary Problems. Tedcastle, T.R. and Dewar, M.A. (1988), ‘Medical Malpractice: A New Treatment for an Old Illness’, 16 Florida State University Law Review, 537-590. Venezian, E.C., Nye, B.F. and Hofflander, A.E. (1989), ‘The Distribution of Claims for Professional Malpractice: Some Statistical and Public Policy Aspects’, 56 Journal of Risk and Insurance, 686-701. Viscusi, W. Kip and Born, Patricia (1995), ‘Medical Malpractice Insurance in the Wake of Liability Reform’, 24 Journal of Legal Studies, 463-490. Weiler, Paul C. (1991), Medical Malpractice on Trial, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 240 p. Weiler, Paul C., Hiatt, Howard, H., Newhouse, Joseph P., Johnson, William G., Brennan, Troyen A. and Leape, Lucian L. (1993), A Measure of Malpractice: Medical Injury, Malpractice Litigation, and Patient Compensation, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 178 p. Weingast, Barry R. (1980), ‘Physicians, DNA Research Scientists, and the Market for Lemons’, in Blair, Roger D. and Rubin, Stephen (eds), Regulating the Professions: A Public-Policy Symposium, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. White, Michelle J. (1994), ‘The Value of Liability in Medical Malpractice’, 13(4)7587 Health Affairs. White, William D. (1978), ‘The Impact of Occupational Licensure of Clinical Laboratory Personnel’, 13 Journal of Human Resources, 91-102. White, William D. (1979), ‘Dynamic Elements of Regulation: The Case of Occupational Licensure’, 1 Research in Law and Economics, 15-33. White, William D. (1980), ‘Mandatory Licensure of Registered Nurses: Introduction and Impact’, in Rottenberg, Simon (ed.), Occupational Licensure and Regulation, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute. White, William D. (1983), ‘Labor Market Organization and Professional Regulation: A Historical Analysis of Nursing Licensure’, 7 Law and Human Behavior, 167-170. White, William D. (1987), ‘The Introduction of Professional Regulation and Labor Market Conditions Occupational Licensure of Registered Nurses’, 20 Policy Sciences, 27-51. X (1974), ‘Note: Restrictive Licensing of Dental Paraprofessionals’, 83 Yale Law Journal, 806-826.
1052
The Regulation of Medical Professions
5870
Zuckerman, Stephen, Bovbjerg, Randall R. and Sloan, Frank A. (1990), ‘Effects of Tort Reforms and Other Factors on Medical Malpractice Insurance Premiums’, 27 Inquiry, 167-182. Zuckerman, Stephen, Koller, Christopher F. and Bovbjerg, Randall R. (1986), ‘Information on Malpractice: A Review of Empirical Research on Major Policy Issues’, 49(2) Law and Contemporary Problems, 85-111.
Other References American Medical Association (1969), Professional-Liability Survey Chicago: American Medical Association (1963), Reprinted in Medical Malpractice: The Patient vs. the Physician, US Congress, Senate, Washington, DC, Government Printing Office. American Medical Association (1987), Report of the Specialty Society Medical Liability Project. A Proposed Alternative to the Civil Justice System for Resolving Medical Liability Disputes: A Fault-Based, Administrative System, Chicago, American Medical Association. American Medical Association (1989), AMA Tort Reform Compendium, Chicago, American Medical Association. Becker, Gary (1983), ‘A Theory of Competition Among Pressure Groups for Political Influence’, 98 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 371 ff. Brown, John P. (1973), ‘Toward an Economic Theory of Liability’, 2 Journal of Legal Studies, 323 ff. Calabresi, Guido (1970), The Costs of Accidents: A Legal and Economic Analysis, New Haven, Yale University Press, 340 ff. Coase, Ronald (1974), ‘The Choice of the Institutional Framework: A Comment’, 17 The Journal of Law and Economics, 493 ff. Cooter, Robert and Ulen, Thomas (1986), ‘An Economic Case for Comparative Negligence’, 61 New York University Law Review, 1067 ff. DeVille, Kenneth A. (1990), Medical Malpractice in Nineteenth-Century America: Origins and Legacy, New York, New York University Press, 319 ff. Epstein, Richard (1980), Modern Products Liability Law, London, Quorum Books, 210 ff. Giesen, Dieter (1988), International Medical Malpractice Law: A Comparative Study of Civil Liability Arising from Medical Care, London, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers. Haddock, David and Curran, Christopher (1985), ‘An Economic Theory of Comparative Negligence’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 49 ff. Keeton, Page, Keeton, Robert E., Sargentich, Lewis D. and Steiner, Henry J. (1989), Cases and Materials on Tort and Accident Law, St. Paul, Minnesota, West Publishing Company, 1318 ff. Kolstad, Charles D., Ulen, Thomas S. and Johnson, Gary V.(1990), ‘Ex Post Liability for Harm vs. Ex Ante Safety Regulation: Substitutes or Complements?’, 80 American Economic Review, 888 ff. Landes, William and Posner, Richard (1980), ‘Joint and Multiple Tortfeasors: An Economic Analysis’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 517 ff. Landes, William and Posner, Richard (1984), ‘The Positive Economic Theory of Tort Law’, 15 Georgia Law Review, 851 ff. Leland, Hayne E. (1979), ‘Quacks, Lemons, and the Market Mechanism: A Theory of Minimum
5870
The Regulation of Medical Professions
1053
Quality Standards’, 87 Journal of Political Economy,1328-1346. Peltzman, Sam (1976), ‘Toward a More General Theory of Regulation’, 19 Journal of Law and Economics, 211-244. Posner, Richard (1974), ‘Theories of Economic Regulation’, 5 Bell Journal of Economics, 335-58. Posner, Richard (1981), ‘A Reply to Some Recent Criticisms of the Efficiency Theory of the Common Law’, 9 Hofstra Law Review, 775 ff. Posner, Richard (1986b), The Economic Analysis of Law, Boston, Little, Brown and Company, 666 ff. Priest, George L. (1985), ‘The Invention of Enterprise Liability’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 461 ff. Priest, George L. (1987), ‘The Current Insurance Crisis and Modern Tort Law’, 96 Yale Law Journal, 1521 ff. Sadusk, Joseph F. (1956), ‘Analysis of Professional Factors in Medical Malpractice Claims’, 161 Journal of the American Medical Association, 442-447. Sandor, Andrew A. (1957), ‘The History of Professional Liability Suits in the United States’, 163 Journal of the American Medical Association, 459-466. Sanger, E.F. (1879), ‘Report on Malpractice’, 100 Boston Medical and Surgical Journal, 41-50. Schwartz, Alan (1988), ‘Proposals for Products Liability Reform: A Theoretical Synthesis’, 97 Yale Law Journal, 353 ff. Shavell, Steven (1987), Economic Analysis of Accident Law, Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 312 ff. Shryock, Richard H. (1967), Medical Licensing in America, 1650-1965, Baltimore, The Johns Hopkins Press. Starr, Paul (1982), The Social Transformation of American Medicine, New York, Basic Books, Inc., 514 ff. Stigler, George J. (1971), ‘The Theory of Economic Regulation’, 2 Bell Journal of Economics, Spring, 3-21. US Congress Senate (1969), Medical Malpractice, Patient vs. the Physician 91st Congress, 1st Session, Washington, DC, Government Printing Office. US Department of Health and Human Services (1987), Report of the Task Force on Medical Liability and Malpractice, Washington, DC, Government Printing Office. US General Accounting Office (1986), Medical Malpractice Insurance Costs Increased but Varied among Physicians and Hospitals, Washington, DC, US General Accounting Office. US General Accounting Office (1987), Medical Malpractice: Characteristics of Claims Closed in 1984, Washington, DC, US General Accounting Office. Viscusi, W. Kip (1991),Reforming Products Liability, Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press, 270 ff. Werthman, Barbara (1984), Medical Malpractice: How Medicine is Changing the Law, Lexington, D.C. Heath and Company. White, Michelle (1989), ‘An Empirical Test of the Comparative and Contributory Negligence Rules in Accident Law’, 20 Rand Journal of Economic, 308 ff.
1054
The Regulation of Medical Professions
Cases Tunkl v. Regents of the University of California (1963), 383 P.2d 441, Cal.
5870
5880 THE PHARMACEUTICAL INDUSTRY Patricia M. Danzon The Wharton School - University of Pennsylvania © Copyright 1999 Patricia M. Danzon
Abstract The pharmaceutical industry raises unique economic questions because of three related features. First, the high rate of R&D, technical change and importance of patent protection raise important positive and normative questions related to industry structure, prices, profits and public policy. Second, the industry is heavily regulated in all major functions. Early regulatory requirements focused on safety and efficacy. More recently, prices, promotion and expenditures are increasingly regulated, arising out of policy concerns to control spending under social insurance programs. Optimal policies must consider trade-offs between control of moral hazard, assuring access to medical care and preserving incentives for innovation. Third, major drugs are global products and the costs of R&D are global joint costs. This creates incentives for national free-rider strategies, whereas socially optimal policies should consider cross-national spillovers and optimal price differentials. Existing literature provides a framework and some empirical evidence on some of these issues, but many questions remain unanswered. JEL classification: L1, L4, L5, I11, L65, K32 Keywords: Pharmaceutical Industry, Regulation, Anti-trust, Health Care, R&D, Insurance
1. Introduction The pharmaceutical industry is of interest to the field of law and economics for two, related, reasons. First, the usual issues of structure, conduct and performance when applied to the pharmaceutical industry must take into account its unusually high rate of R&D, which implies a high rate of technical change, critical importance of patent protection, potential for market power and novel price and product competitive strategies. This raises interesting positive and normative issues related to prices, profits and public policy. Second, the industry is heavily regulated in all major functions. Much of the early regulation and early economic literature focused on regulation related to safety and efficacy. Because pharmaceuticals may entail 1055
1056
The Pharmaceutical Industy
5880
significant risks to health as well as potential benefits, all industrialized countries require that new drugs meet certain safety standards as a condition of market access. Since the 1960s some countries, including the US and the UK, also require evidence of efficacy; regulate the conduct of R&D; monitor manufacturing processes for quality; and restrict promotion and advertising, both to physicians and to consumers. In the 1980s and 1990s, the focus of most new regulation in most countries has been related to control of costs, through regulation of manufacturer prices, insurance reimbursement, and/or total expenditures. These policies arise out of concern to constrain health spending under public insurance schemes which pay for a large fraction of pharmaceutical expenditures. Insurance coverage tends to make demand less price-elastic, increasing consumption volume and use of more costly drugs. The controls adopted by public and private insurers have significant effects on both the demand and supply sides of the market and on the nature of competition. This in turn affects returns to and incentives for R&D and consumer welfare. A growing literature examines both positive and normative issues raised by these cost control regulations. This literature has certainly increased our understanding of these regulations but many questions remain unanswered. The effects of such regulation are profound and multi-dimensional even within a single country, affecting consumption patterns, productivity, R&D and hence the supply of future technologies. Moreover, research-based pharmaceuticals are global products that are diffused worldwide through licensing arrangements or, increasingly, through local subsidiaries of multinational corporations. The profitability of pharmaceutical R&D thus depends on worldwide sales and on policies adopted in many national markets. Each country faces an incentive to adopt the regulatory policies that best control its pharmaceutical budget in the short run, free-riding on others to pay for the joint costs of R&D, and ignoring cross-national spillovers of national regulatory policies through parallel trade and international price comparisons. But although policies remain national, the industry is global and market segmentation is breaking down. This requires a global perspective on both positive and normative analysis. The future structure of the industry, as it adapts to changing technology and regulation, is another interesting question with no certain answers. The emerging technologies of biotechnology and genomics are transforming the nature of R&D and comparative advantage within the industry. Small firms play an increasingly important role in the development of new drugs and new R&D technologies. Biotechnology and gene therapy have raised important safety and ethical issues for regulation. The alliances that link biotech firms with each other and with large pharmaceutical companies raise interesting questions related to agency and the nature of the firm.
5880
The Pharmaceutical Industry
1057
The primary focus of this survey is the recent literature on measurement of prices, profits, and cost of R&D, and on these new regulatory initiatives. A previous survey article on the political economy of the pharmaceutical industry (Comanor, 1986) reviewed the early literature on industry structure, pricing and effects of regulation, focusing almost exclusively on US regulations governing safety and efficacy in the 1960s and 1970s and related literature. Scherer (1993) focuses on issues related to pricing, profits and technical progress. Material covered in these earlier reviews is briefly reviewed here. The focus here is inevitably on US issues and evidence, given the dominance of US-based literature and firms in this industry. However, regulatory issues and evidence from other countries are included where possible. The focus on issues raised by regulation and policy is made without apology (for a contrary view, see Comanor, 1986). Regulation of safety, efficacy and quality fundamentally affect the industry’s cost structure and the nature of competition, while regulation of price, reimbursement and promotion affect demand and profitability. By any measure, regulation has been and remains a critical factor that shapes this industry and must be central to any realistic analysis of the industry.
2. Safety and Efficacy Regulation: Costs and Benefits Much of the early literature on the pharmaceutical industry grew out of the major regulatory initiatives adopted in the US in 1962. Under the 1938 Food, Drug and Cosmetics Act, any firm seeking to market a new chemical entity (NCE) was required to file a new drug application (NDA) to demonstrate that the drug was safe for use as suggested in proposed labeling. The Food and Drug Administration (FDA) had 180 days to reject the NDA. Congressional hearings on the industry were initiated in the late 1950s, arising out of concerns about prices, excess profits and promotion. Legislation was precipitated by the thalidomide tragedy. The drug thalidomide was still under review in the US but had been marketed in several countries of Europe, causing birth defects in hundreds of babies. The 1962 Kefauver-Harris Amendments to the 1938 Act strengthened safety requirements, extending FDA regulation to cover clinical testing and manufacturing facilities. More controversial, the Amendments also added the requirement that drugs show proof of efficacy, which usually requires double blind, randomized controlled trials of the drug relative to placebo; removed the time limit (previously 180 days) within which the FDA could reject an NDA; restricted manufacturers’ promotion to approved indications; and required that all promotional material must include a summary of side-effects and contraindications. The UK tightened safety regulations in 1964 and added efficacy requirements in 1971; some other countries
1058
The Pharmaceutical Industy
5880
followed suit. However others, such as France and Japan, retained much looser efficacy requirements (Thomas, 1996). The presumption underlying the requirements for proof of efficacy was that asymmetric information prevented physicians and consumers from making accurate evaluations, leading to wasted expenditures on ineffective drugs and enabling companies to use product innovation as an obstacle to price competition. However, the extent of the market failure was a matter of assumption, not evidence, and the added requirements clearly entailed additional costs. These costs include the real resource costs of larger and longer clinical trials and increased delay in bringing new drugs to market, which entail foregone benefits to consumers and foregone revenue to manufacturers. Higher fixed costs of R&D raise the threshold of the expected revenue needed to break even on developing a new drug, leading to higher break-even prices, ceteris paribus. Some drugs would be totally eliminated by the new, higher threshold, including some with potential positive net benefits to consumers (assuming some Type II errors by regulatory bodies), particularly for relatively rare diseases with small potential market size. The Orphan Drug Act of 1982 attempts to remedy the latter problem; however, this addresses only the smallest markets and by the imperfect means of granting market exclusivity. 2.1 Costs of Regulation An extensive literature has attempted to quantify the social and private costs and benefits of regulatory requirements for proof of efficacy, in particular, the 1962 US Amendments. Most research has focused on costs, in particular, the decline in the number of new drug introductions, longer delays for NCEs that ultimately do reach the market, higher input cost and capitalization cost per successful NCE due to larger and longer clinical trials, and shortened period of patent life - all of which coincided with the 1962 Amendments. Measurement of benefits has been even more elusive, because it requires comparing the actual rate of new drug introductions to the counterfactual rate that would have occurred, had the Amendments not been passed. Grabowski, Vernon and Thomas (1978) report that the number of NCEs fell from 233 in the five-year period 1957-1961 to 93 in 1962-1966 and 76 in 1967-1971. Some decline would be consistent with the intent of the legislation, if some of the prior introductions were ineffective. However, the percentage of total ethical drug sales accounted for by new NCEs declined roughly in proportion to the number of drugs, from 20.0 percentage in 1957-1961 to 5.5 percent in 1967-1971. This tends to refute the argument that only the most insignificant drugs were eliminated. Several studies (Baily, 1972; Peltzman, 1973; Wiggins, 1981) have attempted to estimate the contribution of the Amendments to this dramatic
5880
The Pharmaceutical Industry
1059
decline in new drug introductions. Bailey (1972) estimates a production function of new drugs and concludes that input costs per NCE increased more than three-fold after 1962. Peltzman estimates a demand pull model to predict new drugs for the post-1962 period based on pre-1962 relationships. He attributes all the difference between predicted and actual number of NCEs to regulation. However, this is an assumption rather than a tested proposition since he does not explicitly control for other possible contributing factors. Grabowski, Vernon and Thomas (1978) attempt to identify the marginal contribution of regulation, controlling for other possible contributing factors, including the depletion of new product opportunities; the thalidomide tragedy that may have made manufacturers and physicians more risk averse, hence reduced demand for new drugs; and pharmacological advances that may have raised R&D costs independent of regulation. Their strategy is to compare trends in NCE discoveries in the US relative to the UK, an appropriate comparator country because of its strong and successful research-based pharmaceutical industry. This provides a quasi-natural experiment because the UK did not adopt efficacy requirements until 1971 and its 1963 safety requirements were statistically unrelated to the flow of new discoveries. Grabowski et al. find that research productivity, defined as number of NCEs per (lagged) R&D expenditure, declined sixfold between 1960-61 and 1966-1970 in the US, compared to a threefold decline in the UK, and that the 1962 US Amendments increased the cost per new NCE by a factor of 2.3. They conclude that these differentials are plausibly attributable to regulation, since the UK would have been equally affected by exogenous changes in scientific opportunities and testing norms and by any thalidomide-related change in demand. Using the UK as a benchmark provides a conservative estimate because changes in the US, as the largest single pharmaceutical market, would influence incentives for innovative R&D for all firms, regardless of country of domicile, and hence could have contributed to the decline in discovery rates in the UK. Several studies have examined the role of regulation in increasing delay for drugs that ultimately do reach the market. Dranove and Meltzer (1994) estimate that the average time from a drug’s first worldwide patent application to its approval by the FDA rose from 3.5 years in the 1950s to almost 6 years in the 1960s and 14 years in the mid-1980. Wardell (1973) and Wardell and Lasagna (1975) report that the US lagged behind each major European country in new drug introductions for various new drugs sold in the US in the late 1960s. Comparing the US and Britain for the period 1962-1971, they find that more drugs were launched earlier in Britain than the US. The US had 59 product-years of prior availability compared to 120 in Britain. Of single country drugs, 77 were exclusive to Britain while
1060
The Pharmaceutical Industy
5880
21 were confined to the US. The authors attributed these differences to the increased stringency of FDA regulations. Other studies provide further support for the hypothesis that the 1962 Amendments delayed the introduction of new drugs into the US. Grabowski and Vernon (1978) compare introduction dates in the US and the UK for drugs discovered in the US between 1960 and 1974. The proportion of drugs introduced first in the US declined significantly between the periods 1960-1962 and 1972-1974, while the proportion introduced later in the US increasing significantly. The authors conclude that increased regulatory scrutiny in the US caused multinational companies to introduce new products abroad before their US launch. Similarly, Grabowski (1980) finds that many more drugs were introduced first in Europe despite most being discovered in US research laboratories or by US-based firms, with the lag increasing over time. Wiggins (1981) extends the evidence by using differences in average FDA approval times across therapeutic categories. He finds large and significant effects of the 1962 Amendments, particularly on R&D cost per new product introduced, with some additional depressing effect on research expenditures and significant variation across therapeutic categories. However, in a study of new product introductions between 1956 and 1976, by therapeutic category, he finds that the overall decline is dominated by a few therapeutic classes for which regulatory stringency appears to be less important than other, non-regulatory factors in the decline in new product introductions. The cost in foregone consumer welfare from delay or elimination of new drugs remains a current issue for different reasons in different countries. In the US, concern has focused on regulatory delay in approval of promising therapies for life-threatening diseases and other conditions that lack effective alternative therapies, such as AIDS. The economic argument is that the costs of delay are higher, hence the optimal risk-benefit trade-off is different if no alternative therapy exists. Since the mid-1970s the FDA has attempted to accelerate approval of such critical drugs, under pressure from Congress, consumer groups and the pharmaceutical industry. Early studies (by, for example, Wiggins, 1981) concluded that the drug lag for ‘important therapeutic advances’ was similar to that for all new chemical entities. More recently, Dranove and Meltzer (1994) conclude that, beginning in the 1950s, more important drugs - especially drugs that proved to be successful in the marketplace - have been developed and approved more rapidly than less important drugs. This differential appears to reflect actions of drug companies as much as regulatory priority setting. Moreover, for their period 1950-1986 the trend towards longer average development and approval times implied that even drugs two standard deviations above the mean level of importance took longer to reach the market. One interesting feature of the
5880
The Pharmaceutical Industry
1061
Dranove and Meltzer study is the use of a comprehensive set of ex post measures of drug importance, including citations in medical textbooks, in medical journals, and in subsequent patent applications; the extent of worldwide introduction; and US sales. To the extent that these ex post measures of importance are noisy measures of ex ante forecasts of importance, their estimates of differential delay are understated. These findings that, since the 1962 Amendments, delay in approval for important drugs has increased less than for more minor drugs, and that firm strategies can significantly influence delay, implies that estimates of the average drug lag due to the 1962 Amendments may overestimate the social costs of the regulation-induced delay. On the other hand, if it is costly for firms to accelerate approval, then the measure of total social costs should include these added expenditures as well as the pure delay-induced costs. The fact that approval time continued to lengthen through the 1980s and that this is not confined to the US suggests either that other countries have experienced similar regulatory factors or that other factors such as common clinical factors may play an important role. Recent evidence suggests some convergence. Although Dranove and Meltzer (1994) find that approval times have lengthened in the US, their data indicate some narrowing of the gap between the US and other countries at the end of their period. Schweitzer, Schweitzer and Guellec (1996), using a sample of drugs approved in the US between 1970 and 1988, conclude that there were no significant differences in approval between the US and the G-7 countries, but that Switzerland was consistently quicker. These different findings may reflect differences in time period, methodology or sample. They may also reflect real changes in firms’ optimal timing of launch in different countries. In particular, with increasing interdependence between markets, due to parallel trade and regulatory use of international price comparisons, the incentive of firms is to delay launch in countries with relatively low prices that may become a ceiling for prices in other countries. More on this below. 2.2 Benefits of Regulation Of course, regulatory control may also benefit consumers, by reducing the risk that harmful or useless drugs are admitted to the market. The production of safety and efficacy information is a public good which may be underprovided by the market. For safety, liability may provide an alternative corrective to regulation. For efficacy, the market may acquire information over time, but learning by experience may entail a welfare loss. The optimal regulatory policy would set safety and efficacy standards to achieve the optimal balance between costs and benefits. The only study that has attempted to estimate both the benefits and costs of efficacy regulation is Peltzman’s (1973) study of the effects of the 1962
1062
The Pharmaceutical Industy
5880
US Amendments. Peltzman attempts to estimate the benefits of regulation by examining the rate of growth of market shares of new drugs before and after the Amendments. He concludes that the benefits were minimal and were far outweighed by the costs, which he estimates as foregone consumer surplus due to the reduced flow of NCEs which he attributes entirely to regulation. These conclusions depend critically on the methods for estimating costs and benefits, which have been questioned (for example, Temin, 1980). In particular, if consumer learning is slower or less accurate than assumed, Peltzman’s estimates understate the benefits of regulation. Conversely, Peltzman’s estimates of costs may be overstated by ascribing the decline in NCEs solely to the regulation. Nevertheless, this is an important study because it offers a theoretical and empirical framework for evaluating the overall net benefits of efficacy requirements in a particular country. The more numerous studies of cross-national differences in regulatory approval times and number of drugs admitted cannot provide the basis for policy implications because cross-national comparisons can only meaningfully be made for drugs that are approved in all comparison countries, which is a relatively small fraction of all drugs; because delay may reflect corporate strategies in additional to regulatory constraints; and because the delay may yield benefits in risk reduction or reduced wasteful expenditure on ineffective drugs. Thus delay and other regulatory costs cannot alone define the optimal extent and form of regulatory control, which remains an unresolved issue. Nevertheless, recent efforts to harmonize regulatory requirements across countries should reduce the expense and delay of new drug approval and yield net social benefits. The information generated by conduct of clinical trials is a public good, as is regulatory review of the evidence assuming similar standards. In 1995 the European Union established the European Medicines Evaluation Agency (EMEA) as the required approval route for biotech products and as an optional route for other innovative products. The EMEA’s goal is to review submissions within 365 days. An alternative is single country approval under the same rules, with reciprocity to other EU countries subject to objection. Competition between these alternative routes may stimulate efficiency. National systems remain for products that seek approval in only a single country. Harmonization between Europe, the US and Japan has been achieved on some issues but remaining differences still require country-specific trials and approval. 2.3 R&D Cost per New Chemical Entity The research-based pharmaceutical industry invests a higher percentage of sales in R&D than most other industries (US CBO, 1994). The R&D/sales ratio for the US research-based industry has increased from 11.9 percent in
5880
The Pharmaceutical Industry
1063
1980 to 21.2 percent in 1997 (PhRMA, 1997). However, because of the long lag between R&D and sales, a point-in-time R&D/sales ratio is downward biased as an estimate of the fraction of total costs that is accounted for by R&D. The sales in the denominator pertain to several cohorts of drugs currently on the market, whose R&D occurred many years earlier; conversely, the R&D expenditure in the numerator aggregates the one-year expenditures for several different cohorts that will generate sales over several future decades. To estimate R&D as a fraction of total cost, the stream of costs over the life cycle of a drug, from discovery through launch and sales, must be expressed in discounted present value at a common date. Applying this calculation to the date of launch, R&D accounts for roughly 30 percent of total costs (Danzon, 1997). The appropriate methodology for measuring the R&D cost per new drug approved was pioneered by Hansen (1979), using company-specific data for a cohort of drugs. DiMasi et al. (1991) extend this approach to estimate R&D costs for drugs introduced from 1980 through 1984. The average successful NCE incurred $73m. of preclinical testing expense and $53m during clinical testing, excluding amortization of failures and cost of capital. These out-of-pocket expenses have increased over time, partly due to increasingly stringent regulation and increased targeting of chronic conditions that require longer trials. Since only 23 percent of the drugs entering human trials reached market launch, the costs of the failures (‘dry holes’) must be amortized across the successful compounds to yield the out-of-pocket cost per successful new drug. Grabowski, Vernon and Thomas (1978) report that the success rate of drugs entering clinical trials declined from one in three in the 1950s to less than one in ten after 1962. The final adjustment is to add the cost of foregone interest on capital between the time of investment outlay and market launch, which is approximately twelve years. This includes ten years from beginning trials to filing for an NDA and an additional two or more years for regulatory review. Assuming a 9 percent real cost of capital, this foregone interest accounts for roughly half of the total estimated pre-tax cost per successful NCE of $231m. in 1987 dollars (DiMasi et al.,1991). The US Congress OTA (1993) updated this to $359m before tax in 1993 dollars. Di Masi et al. (1991) estimate that a one year reduction in NDA review time would reduce the total cost by 19 percent. This large effect reflects the high capitalization cost of delay added after all investments has been incurred. Note that this measure of delay cost does not include the foregone revenue to the originator firm because delay shortens effective patent life. An alternative, not mutually exclusive view of the rise in R&D cost per new drug is the dramatic decrease in productivity of R&D expenditures over time. Henderson and Cockburn (1996) report that in 1971, member firms of the US Pharmaceutical Manufacturers’ Association spent about $360m on
1064
The Pharmaceutical Industy
5880
R&D, compared to $8.9 billion in 1991, an increase of over 2300 percent in constant 1991 dollars. Over the same period, the output of important patents (those granted in two of the three major world markets, the US, Europe and Japan) fell, while the number of drugs discovered per year remained approximately constant. They conclude that this increase in cost cannot be explained by shifts in the distribution of R&D across therapeutic categories. The possibility of bias due to shifts in the location of R&D - as foreign firms shift a larger share of the R&D to the US - is not explored. These estimates of costs per new drug and regulation-induced delay must be viewed as ex post averages that reflect the endogenous decisions made by firms, given the constraints imposed by regulation, technology and market opportunities. Firms can influence the out-of-pocket costs and duration of R&D by their selection of drug candidates, rejection rates on questionable leads, and development strategies. For example, pursuing certain trials simultaneously rather than in sequence saves time but entails out-of-pocket expense that could have been averted by a sequential strategy. Size of clinical trials may be influenced by the tolerance for risk of finding statistically insignificant effects. Thus the observed average cost per NCE presumably reflects the subset of drug candidates and strategies that were expected to yield revenues sufficient to cover costs. The striking rise in real R&D expenditures in the 1970s and 1980s is consistent with rational behavior in the face of rising out-of-pocket and delay costs only if technological and market opportunities were also expanding. More recently, manufacturers have become more aggressive at screening out less promising candidates early in the development process, as regulation and competition have reduced expected revenues in recent years and possibly reduced expected prices of late arrivals in a therapeutic class. Thus changes in cost per NCE reflect firms’ optimizing responses to changes in market opportunities, as well as technological and regulatory shifts. Henderson and Cockburn (1996) point out that if R&D entails wasteful, competitive investments as firms race against each other in substantially similar research, then the reported average cost per drug overstates the true R&D expense required in a more ideal competitive environment. On the other hand, if there are significant spillovers across projects within and between firms, then the average observed cost understates the resource requirement for a single firm to develop a new drug. Using detailed data from individual firms, they conclude that the evidence is more consistent with the spillover hypothesis and find no evidence to support the racing hypothesis. This is consistent with qualitative evidence that R&D spending and employment changes slowly, driven by heterogeneous firm capabilities and the evolution of scientific opportunities. However, as the authors note, these conclusions are tentative because they depend on the use of patents as
5880
The Pharmaceutical Industry
1065
a measure of innovative output. Moreover, the assumed lag structure permits testing of only one specific model of racing behavior. On the other hand, their study makes no attempt to measure potential benefits to consumers that should be offset against any additional cost of duplicative R&D, if the existence of competing drugs on the market lowers prices. More on this below. The evidence from Dranove and Meltzer (1994) provides further support for the proposition that R&D costs and delay are at least partly endogenous. Their conclusion that pharmaceutical manufacturers, rather than the FDA, are more responsible for relative acceleration of important drugs rests upon evidence that acceleration is observed during the 1950s, before the lengthy approval process was initiated and accelerated development is a worldwide phenomenon. Once market importance is controlled for, scientific importance does not appear to be associated with accelerated review, which might suggest no independent role for regulation, after controlling for the role of manufacturers. However, in reality, interaction of manufacturers and regulators is important but difficult to separate empirically. Future studies may find a greater contribution by the FDA, at least for drugs to treat highly visible, life-threatening diseases such as AIDs. For countries other than the US there are no methodologically comparable estimates of R&D cost per successful NCE, correctly calculated to include the amortized cost of dry holes and capitalization cost. However, even if a cross-national comparison of R&D cost per NCE using comparable methodology were available, causal inference would be difficult for several reasons. First, with the harmonization of regulatory requirements firms increasingly conduct multi-national trials for global drugs. If country-specific studies reflect only the costs incurred in each country, all cost estimates are likely to be downward biased and relative costs will be upward biased in the countries where a disproportionate share of R&D is undertaken, particularly the US. Second, cross-national comparisons of R&D costs may be subject to sample selection bias because the mix of drugs that is approved differs greatly across countries. This reflects not only differences in regulatory stringency but also medical norms, local supply characteristics, pricing environments and other factors that affect costs and expected revenues and hence influence the portfolio of drugs that firms submit for approval. For example, a country with less stringent efficacy requirements might have a lower ratio of dry holes to successful NCEs, ceteris paribus, hence lower total cost per new drug approved. However, this would reflect differences in drug characteristics, in addition to the pure differential cost for a standardized cohort of drugs.
1066
The Pharmaceutical Industy
5880
2.4 Cost of Capital Several studies have attempted to estimate the pharmaceutical industry’s cost of capital, as a critical input in estimates of the cost and profitability of R&D. The cost of capital determines the interest cost on R&D funds invested and the discounted present value of life-time revenue flows. Using standard finance models such as the capital asset pricing model (CAPM), the conclusion is generally that the pharmaceutical industry is of average risk, with a beta approximately equal to one, a nominal cost of capital of roughly 15 percent or 10 percent in real terms in 1990 (for example, Grabowski and Vernon, 1993; Myers and Shyam-Sunder, 1996 and references cited therein). Although the industry is often perceived as highly risky because the success of any individual drug candidate is highly uncertain, such risks are readily diversifiable. However, Myers and Shyam-Sundar (1996) point out the sequential nature of investment in R&D amplifies risk. Investing in R&D is equivalent to investing in compound lotteries and compound call options. Both beta and the opportunity cost of capital are higher for early stage R&D projects than for later stages. By implication, the average cost of capital is higher for small companies, that have several early-stage projects but no final products, than for large companies that have a diversified portfolio of products at various stages of the life cycle of development and commercialization.
3. Patents The purpose of patent protection is to grant the originator firm a period market exclusivity that provides an opportunity to charge a price above marginal cost in order to recover the investment in R&D. In theory, the socially optimal patent term is defined by trading off the marginal utility gain from stimulating the development of innovative products against the loss from suboptimal consumption that results if patents lead to prices in excess of marginal cost. The optimal patent term may thus differ between countries. In pharmaceuticals, as in other industries, the period of effective market exclusivity may be much less than the nominal patent term because of entry of slightly differentiated products that are close substitutes. However, patent protection does block entry of generically equivalent imitator versions of the same compound until patent expiration. For pharmaceuticals, the value of patent protection is further constrained by two factors. First, the effective patent life is truncated by the delay between patent filing and product launch, which is particularly long for pharmaceuticals due to the lengthy process of drug development and regulatory approval described earlier. For example, with a nominal patent
5880
The Pharmaceutical Industry
1067
term of 20 years, the mean duration of 12 years from discovery research to product launch would leave an effective patent life of only eight years. In the US, the 1984 Patent Term Restoration and Competition Act grants to innovator firms an extension of patent term for up to five years, to offset the loss due to regulatory delay. However, as a quid pro quo, the 1984 Act expedited post-patent entry by generic manufacturers, by granting them access to the active ingredient before the actual patent expiry, and by regulating market access with an Accelerated New Drug Application (ANDA) that requires only a showing of bioequivalence to the originator product, without new trials. This 1984 Act has greatly accelerated generic entry after patent expiry in the US. Similar measures have been proposed for the EU but so far have not been adopted. The extent of generic penetration and the speed of generic erosion of originator market share differ significantly across countries and over time, depending on policies adopted by regulators and third party payers. Studies of generic penetration and effects on brand pricing strategies are discussed below. Second, in most countries drugs are reimbursed by publicly financed health or social insurance schemes. Insurance coverage tends to reduce demand elasticity, which could increase market power, ceteris paribus. Offsetting this, most public and private insurers have adopted controls on price, reimbursement, volume or total expenditures on drugs, in order to constrain manufacturers’ exploitation of this inelastic demand and to constrain insurance-induced overuse (moral hazard) on the part of patients and of providers, who may use prescription drugs to enhance demand for their own services (Danzon and Liu, 1996). Regulation designed to control costs can significantly limit and even nullify the value of patents to originator firms. Weak patent protection and associated copying of innovator drugs by local firms, particularly in developing countries, has been an important issue in international trade negotiations. In the Uruguay round of GATT, participating countries agreed to a 20 year patent life from date of application. However, because drugs already in the pipeline were exempted from the new rules, this provision would not grant patent protection to new drugs reaching the market for several years in countries that newly granted intellectual property protection. Differences between countries in patent protection would matter less if markets were fully separable, such that the effect of weak patent protection in one country affected only that country. However for pharmaceuticals there are important market spillovers for two reasons. First, pharmaceutical R&D is a global joint cost of serving all countries in which a drug is marketed. The incentives for investment in global products thus depends on total global revenues. This gives each country an incentive to free-ride, waiting
1068
The Pharmaceutical Industy
5880
for others to pay the joint costs. Second, the ability of producers of global drugs to segment markets along national lines and charge different prices, is breaking down as a result of parallel trade and regulatory use of foreign prices to set domestic prices. The EU Court of Justice, in Merck v. PrimeCrown (1996) upheld the right of parallel importers to import pharmaceuticals from one EU member state in which a product had no patent protection to another EU country in which the product was under patent protection. With parallel trade, the weak patent protection in one country effectively spills over to other countries, undermining the ability of the manufacturer to realize the value of the patent in countries that respect patents. The same effect occurs if the government in a country with patents regulates domestic prices based on prices in other countries that do not recognize intellectual property. The theory of Ramsey pricing (Ramsey, 1927) provides the theoretically optimal set of price differentials for pricing to cover joint costs when consumers differ in their ability or willingness to pay. The use of Ramsey pricing to set optimal cross-national differences in prices is discussed in (Danzon, 1997a, 1997b). However, Ramsey pricing sets optimal price differentials, taking demand elasticities as given. But demand elasticities for individual products depend on patent structure. Thus in a full social optimum, the differentials in both patent terms and prices would be simultaneously determined. This simultaneous determination of cross-national differences in patent terms and prices for global products such as pharmaceuticals is an interesting issue for future work.
4. Pricing: Competition and Regulation The pharmaceutical industry is structurally competitive, with low overall concentration. Although concentration within specific therapeutic categories is greater, the market is contestable in the long run, however, since there are no barriers to entering the process of research and discovery by established or new firms, as evidenced by the large number and high rate of turnover of start-up companies. It is incorrect to infer that entry would take 12 years (the mean time from discovery to approval for new drugs). Competitive entry is initiated long before a promising innovative compound for a new indication or with a new mode action reaches the market. Competitor firms can obtain information on the drug candidates under development by other firms in the industry, from patent filings and regulatory filings with the FDA. The techniques of rational drug design make it increasingly easy for competitors to develop similar but chemically distinct compounds to a promising new compound under development. Thus the pioneer may not necessarily be the first to reach the market and even if it is, follower compounds that are close
5880
The Pharmaceutical Industry
1069
therapeutic substitutes now enter the market within months. The SSRIs (selective seratonin reuptake inhibitors) and statins (HMG CoAse Reductase inhibitors) illustrate the rapid speed of imitative entry. To the extent that market power exists, it results largely from legal restrictions and other institutional factors. The role of patents in intentionally restricting competition has already been described. In addition, in most industrialized countries the demand for ethical drugs is channeled by legislation through physicians and other licensed professionals who are authorized to prescribe drugs. This separation of decision maker from payer makes demand less elastic, if physicians are uninformed about drug prices or, even if informed, are imperfect agents for patients. Insurance coverage further reduces price sensitivity. Traditional insurance that reimburses for the price of the drug, net of a fixed co-payment fee per script or a small co-insurance percentage, reduces demand elasticity in familiar ways. To offset this, both private and public insurers increasingly use strategies designed to make physicians more cost-conscious with respect to price and volume of prescriptions. Since most insurers outside the US are public or quasi-public bodies, these cost control strategies have the effect of regulation. An important consequence of this vital role of physicians and insurance coverage in influencing demand for drugs is that demand conditions differ across countries and over time, as medical reimbursement and insurance systems change. Thus any analysis of the form and extent of competition in the pharmaceutical industry is context-dependent and must take into account institutional arrangements in the local medical and insurance markets. 4.1 Pricing and Competition in Unregulated Markets The early literature provides interesting evidence on competition in relatively free markets because insurance coverage and regulatory controls were less widespread. In the 1960s and 1970s, US patients paid directly out-of-pocket for most outpatient drugs, with minimal insurance coverage. Nevertheless, opinion in the economic and policy literature was divided on the competitive effect of closely substitutable drugs and hence on the effects of the 1962 Amendments. Some view the development of closely substitutable ‘me-too’ products as waste that is costly to consumers, on the theory that the rapid introduction of new products, protected by patents, leads to increased product differentiation and higher prices (see, for example, Comanor, 1964 and Temin, 1980). This theory predicts that the 1962 Amendments, by requiring proof of efficacy and restricting drug advertising, should increase price competition. The alternative view is that the extent of price competition depends positively on the number of close therapeutic substitutes, in which case the existence of close substitutes may benefit consumers. To assess the impact of the 1962 US Amendments on prices, Peltzman (1973) examines average price changes in a time series
1070
The Pharmaceutical Industy
5880
analysis from 1952 to 1962 and a cross sectional analysis for the three years preceding the 1962 regulations. He finds no evidence that the number of NCEs had any net inflationary impact on drug prices, even under the strong assumption that innovation offers no net therapeutic benefit. He concludes that, if anything, the 1962 Amendments accelerated the rate of drug price inflation and added to the annual cost of drugs to consumers. Several subsequent studies tend to confirm that the development of new, closely substitutable drugs does not limit price competition. In a study of launch prices of new drugs introduced between 1958 and 1975, Reekie (1978) found that new drugs that offer significant therapeutic advance were priced above existing drugs but tended to lower price over time, whereas imitators were priced lower initially but tended to increase prices. This pattern, of a skimming strategy for innovative drugs and a penetration strategy for imitators was confirmed by Lu and Comanor (1998) using data for 144 new drugs launched in the US between 1978 and 1987. The penetration strategy is consistent with a multiperiod model with interrelated demand and imperfectly informed buyers, in which sellers offer a low initial price to encourage use and build reputation. Imitative products optimally set even lower initial launch prices and raise prices over time (Schmalensee, 1982). Most of these studies predate the application of managed care principles to pharmacy benefits in the US in the 1980s and 1990s, which has significantly affected demand for pharmaceuticals. Pharmacy benefit managers (PBMs) typically establish formularies of preferred drugs, which are selected on the basis of price and cost-effectiveness. Incentives and other inducements are offered to patients, physicians and pharmacists to use preferred drugs. Such strategies increase the cross-price elasticity of demand between therapeutic substitutes and are particularly powerful between generic equivalents (see below). For therapeutic substitutes, the use of formularies, physician monitoring and other strategies enables PBMs to shift market share between therapeutically similar, single source drugs, thereby increasing the demand elasticity facing manufacturers of on-patent drugs. Because of their ability to shift market share and hence make demand more elastic, PBMs have been able to negotiate discounts averaging 20-25 percent off the list price that is charged to the unmanaged, retail pharmacy sector (Boston Consulting Group, 1993). Evidence that new drugs are being launched at lower list prices than established drugs in the same product class and that the discount is greater, the greater the number of existing drugs in the product class (Boston Consulting Group, 1993) suggests that price sensitivity is spilling over to the unmanaged market.
5880
The Pharmaceutical Industry
1071
The future form of discounting and related competitive strategies in the US is uncertain because of litigation and growing legislative constraints initiated by retail pharmacists, who have not been offered discounts for patented drugs on the same terms as PBMs because individual retail pharmacists cannot - and arguably should not attempt to - shift market share between therapeutic substitutes (Danzon, 1997a). Pharmacists countrywide filed a massive series of antitrust claims against drug manufacturers, alleging collusive pricing and price discrimination (Scherer, 1996). This litigation explicitly excluded off-patent, multisource drugs, for which pharmacists do receive discounts because their legal authorization to substitute generic equivalents enables them to shift market share between multisource drugs. The recent partial settlement of this litigation and the pharmacists’ success in obtaining passage of anti-discount pricing legislation in several states, may reduce the practice of discounting and possibly reduce price competition more generally. The effect on profitability is theoretically ambiguous: while individual firms presumably perceived discounting to be in their short-run interests, the long-run effects, once discounting became an industry-wide strategy, could have been negative. However, since managed care has irreversibly changed the price-sensitivity and sophistication of purchasers, legal impediments to discounting will not simply return the status quo ante. Drug manufacturers are developing innovative competitive strategies, including risk-sharing contracts, but it is too soon to predict future developments. 4.2 Generics Generic substitution programs are used by HMOs and most pharmacy benefit managers in the US and in some other countries, notably the UK, Canada, Germany and other countries that use reference price reimbursement (see below). The main strategy is to limit reimbursement for multisource drugs to the price of a low or moderately priced generic. The patient must pay the difference if a higher priced drug, usually the originator brand, is dispensed. In the US most states have overturned their anti-substitution legislation and now authorize pharmacists to dispense a generic of their choice unless the physician explicitly notes that the brand is required. Since pharmacists capture the difference between the reimbursement price and the acquisition cost, pharmacists have strong incentives to select a relatively cheap generic, rather than a more expensive generic or brand. Thus for the manufacturer of multisource products, the primary customer is the pharmacist whose demand is highly price elastic. The cost and delay for generics entering the market was greatly reduced in the US by the 1984 Drug Price Competition and Patent Term Restoration Act, which reduced testing requirements and granted earlier access to essential data for generics, in return for extended patent life of originator drugs to compensate for time lost due to regulatory approval requirements.
1072
The Pharmaceutical Industy
5880
Several studies have examined the effects of the 1984 Act on generic entry and, more generally, the effect of generics on prices, promotional activity and market shares of brand drugs. The differences between the studies probably reflects changes in market conditions, as more states relaxed their anti-substitution laws in the 1970s and 1980s, the 1984 Act, and the growth of managed care in the 1980s and 1990s. Frank and Salkever (1992) provide a formal derivation of the conditions under which generic entry can lead to price increases for brand name drugs. Drawing on the observation made in several studies, that the prescription drug market consists of at least two segments, price-sensitive consumers and brand loyal consumers who are less price sensitive, they show that one plausible condition under which entry may increase brand prices is that entry makes the reduced form demand for the originator (after taking into account response of generics) less elastic. Viewing promotion and price as simultaneous choice variables, they also develop the conditions under which brand advertising may decrease while brand prices increase. Caves, Whinston and Hurwitz (1991) analyze post-patent pricing and promotion for 30 drugs whose patents expired between 1976 and 1987. They find small decreases in brand price following generic entry, with slightly greater effects in the hospital market than in the retail sector, as expected given the wider prevalence of formularies in hospitals at that time. However, their empirical specification includes therapeutic class-specific time effects, in addition to linear and quadratic time variables, which may capture some of the patent expiration effects. Caves, Whinston and Hurwitz (1991) also find significant reduction in brand promotion even before patent expiration. The net effect of less promotion and lower generic prices is that quantity sold does not increase significantly after patent expiration, implying ambiguous welfare effects. They conclude that a significant component of promotion of branded drugs is of the ‘market expansion’ variety, which reduces the extent to which these activities can be viewed as limiting generic competitors. Grabowski and Vernon (1992), using data on patent expirations that spanned the 1984 Act, find that some brand prices increased after generic entry and that generic prices were significantly inversely related to number of generic competitors. A safe conclusion is that none of these studies find strong brand price reductions following generic entry, whereas number of generic entrants has strong downward pressure on generic price. All of these studies underestimate generic penetration in the 1990s, which has greatly accelerated due to the growth of managed care and, possibly, patent expirations for more significant drugs with larger potential markets. For recent patent expirations, the brand drug typically loses over
5880
The Pharmaceutical Industry
1073
half the market in less than a year, compared to five years or more found in previous studies. Thus the ability of brand advertising to build brand loyalty (for example, Caves, Whinston and Hurwitz, 1991) has apparently diminished significantly. This experience underscores the point that conclusions on competition are context-specific, depending on the time period, insurance arrangements and resulting incentives for physicians, pharmacists and patients, which interact to determine demand elasticities and hence optimal manufacturer pricing strategies. None of these studies formally examine the role of pharmacists in drug demand and generic switching. Masson and Steiner (1985) show that for a sample of 37 multisource drugs in 1980, pharmacists obtained the generic at an average price 45 percent lower than the brand, but the difference at retail was only 24.3 percent, because the pharmacist retained a higher average absolute margin on the generics. Similarly, Grabowski and Vernon (1996) show that for 15 drugs whose patents expired between 1984 and 1987, the average absolute margin was roughly 40 percent higher on the generic. Caves, Whinston and Hurwitz (1991) find that pharmacists were quite conservative in exercising their right to substitute a generic, even where authorized. However, the recent gain in market share of generics suggests that this has changed as a result of the growth of managed pharmacy benefits and the associated pressure on pharmacy margins and reimbursement incentives that are designed to make pharmacists highly price sensitive in their choice between drugs. Alexander, Flynn and Linkins (1994) attempt to estimate aggregate demand elasticities using country-level data for seven countries pooled over the period 1980-1987. They use a two-stage procedure. Price is treated as endogenous and estimated in the first stage, with a labor cost index included as an identifying variable. The second stage equation regresses Quantity on this predicted price variable and measures of income, physicians per capita, fixed country effects and a time trend. The resulting elasticity estimate of !2.8 is implausibly large, since it implies even higher product-specific elasticities. It is probably upward biased (in absolute value) due to spurious negative correlation induced by imputing quantity by dividing total expenditures by an estimate of average price that is at best very rough. Since labor cost is presumably highly correlated with income per capita, it is unclear whether the system is identified. Finally, since prices were regulated in five of the seven countries, the assumption that prices are endogenously determined by manufacturers is questionable. Other studies have generally estimated much lower aggregate demand elasticities (less than !1.0 in absolute value). These studies are reviewed in Anessi (1997).
1074
The Pharmaceutical Industy
5880
4.3 Price Change The pharmaceutical industry has been under considerable attack in the US for rates of price increase in the late 1980s that appeared to exceed general inflation. Accurate measurement of price levels and intertemporal price change is particularly problematic, however, in industries with rapid technological change, including pharmaceuticals. Suslow (1996) uses hedonic methods to estimate a quality-adjusted measure of price change for anti-ulcerants. She concludes that unadjusted price indexes that fail to adjust for quality improvements are upward biased. Griliches and Cockburn (1994) demonstrate the upward bias in the official US producer price index for pharmaceuticals that results from treating generics as new drugs, rather than as new versions of old drugs. Berndt, Griliches and Rosett (1993) show that lags in updating the market basket used in official price indexes led to official estimates of price growth being upward biased by as much as 50 percent in the US. Danzon and Kim (1996), using data from seven countries for the period 1981-1992, show that biases differ across countries, depending on the form and effects of regulation, the role of generics and the structure of the official index (fixed or chained weights). For example, the upward bias from treating generics as new drugs rather than modifications of old drugs is greatest in the US, where generics have a relatively large market share, relatively low prices and negative price change over time. 4.4 Regulation of Prices, Reimbursement and Expenditures As noted earlier, to the extent that market power exists in the pharmaceutical industry, it derives partly from the legal grant of monopoly through patent protection. The inelastic nature of demand may be exacerbated by comprehensive insurance coverage, which has provided a rationale for regulation of prices, volumes and/or expenditures in most countries with public and social insurance systems. An extensive literature has addressed the general question of optimal insurance coverage under conditions of moral hazard. Because insurance tends to undermine cost-consciousness of patients and providers in their use of medical services, including drugs, optimal insurance policies include some contractual terms to control insurance-induced overuse (moral hazard). Although early insurance theory typically focuses on consumer co-payment (for example, Pauly, 1968; Zeckhauser, 1971), in the case of medical insurance the optimal trade-off between control of moral hazard and financial protection may yield co-payments that are optimally too low to provide much incentive. Forms of provider cost-sharing may therefore be preferred (Ellis and McGuire, 1991). In the case of drugs, optimal insurance coverage should also take into account the effects of current prices and volumes on incentives for R&D.
5880
The Pharmaceutical Industry
1075
In practice, the cost control strategies applied to drugs by private and public insurers differ across countries and continually evolve over time. A limited literature addresses the positive issue of measuring the effects of different insurance and regulatory structures on prices, drug expenditures and drug use. Harder to measure - and an important topic for future research - are effects of regulatory strategies on health benefits for current patients, on manufacturers’ incentives to invest in innovative R&D, and hence effects on future patients. Under direct price regulatory schemes, such as France and Italy, the manufacturer must obtain approval of the price of a new drug before it can be reimbursed by the social insurance system. Subsequent price changes must also be approved and price decreases may be mandated. The criteria used for setting prices include cost, comparison with existing drugs and international price comparisons. The 1989 EU Transparency Directive requires that such criteria be ‘transparent’ and neutral with respect to country of origin, but interpretation inevitably permits significant discretion. In practice, such systems are widely alleged to be used to pursue industrial policy goals, granting higher prices for products that are locally produced. Danzon and Percy (1996) develop a model showing that such biased regulation creates incentives for manufacturers to distort production efficiency and incur excessively high costs - for example, construction of an excessive number of production plants - in order to obtain higher prices. Other countries, including Germany, the Netherlands and New Zealand have established reference price systems that limit the reimbursement price for drugs in designated groups. Manufacturers remain free to charge more than the reference price; however, since the patient must pay the difference, demand is highly elastic above the reference price, leading most manufacturers to drop their prices to the reference price. Zweifel and Crivelli (1996) analyse reference pricing using a duopoly model; Danzon and Liu (1996) develop a model with physicians as imperfect agents and monopolistic competition between suppliers. The empirical analysis shows that reference pricing significantly reduced price levels and the rate of price increase, which is consistent with independent rather than collusive pricing by manufacturers. Branded drugs suffered a loss in market share despite a reduction in relative price under reference pricing. Prices of non-reference priced drugs increased, as predicted by an optimal life-cycle pricing strategy with reduced economic life and possibly with market segmentation (Danzon and Liu, 1996). The effect of reference price systems on the quality of care for patients and on R&D incentives for manufacturers depends critically on the criteria used to cluster drugs, since reference pricing induces competition primarily between drugs in the same cluster. In particular, if on-patent drugs are
1076
The Pharmaceutical Industy
5880
clustered with older drugs for which patents have expired, reference pricing tends to undermine the ability of innovator firms to recoup the costs of R&D while under patent protection. At the limit, if a new drug is reimbursed at a reference price rate determined by the supply price of a generic version of an old molecule and this price reflects the marginal cost of production, the incentive for innovative R&D would be seriously undermined. In theory, of course, since reference price limits apply only to reimbursement, patients should be willing to pay the differential if the new drug truly offers greater therapeutic benefits. However, physicians may be reluctant to take the time to explain the options, risks and benefits. In the case of Germany, the legal requirement that physicians explain to the patient why a more expensive drug is needed would impose a time cost on physicians that is not reimbursable but has a significant opportunity cost. Thus physician response plausibly contributes to the observed high demand elasticity at prices above the reference price. Price controls alone do not control drug expenditure growth, which is driven largely by the introduction of new, higher priced drugs that are or are perceived to be more effective. In 1993, therefore, Germany adopted a global limit on drug spending, with physicians at risk for the first DM280m of any overrun and the pharmaceutical industry at risk for the next DM280m overrun. This strategy dramatically reduced expenditures (Munnich and Sullivan, 1994). Danzon and Liu (1996) provide a theoretical and empirical analysis that distinguishes effects of reference pricing and drug budgets, using data from the period 1986-1994. They show that if physicians were perfect agents for patients, drug budgets should have no effect. In fact, the sharp spending cut reflected a reduction in number of prescriptions and substitution of older, cheaper drugs for newer, more expensive drugs that can only be plausibly explained by physicians’ concern for their own income. In response to the 1993 drug budgets, manufacturers cut prices of on-patent drugs by more than the mandatory 5 percent price roll-back, consistent with a significant drop in demand and increase in demand elasticity. Schulenburg et al. (1994) report that the referrals to specialists and hospitals increased in response to the drug budgets, plausibly because inpatient drugs were not included. Thus the net budget saving was much less than the saving in outpatient drug costs. Under the UK Prescription Price Regulation Scheme (PPRS), manufacturers are permitted to set prices of patented drugs, subject to the constraint that the rate of return on capital invested in the UK fall within a range, currently 17-21 percent. Each company negotiates with the government for a company-specific return of rate that depends on such factors as contribution to the economy. Prices of off-patent drugs are regulated. Standard theory predicts that pure rate of return regulation induces excessive capital investments and lower productivity (Averch and
5880
The Pharmaceutical Industry
1077
Johnson, 1962). However, in an empirical study of the effects of such biased regulatory schemes in the UK, France and Italy on labor and total factor productivity, Danzon and Percy (1996) find that although the rate of growth of capital and labor in the UK pharmaceutical industry has been high, relative to other UK industry and relative to pharmaceuticals in other countries, it has not been biased towards capital relative to labor, possibly because the permitted rate of return may depend on employment growth. Moreover, the UK has experience relatively high productivity growth, compared to other regulated and unregulated countries. Price regulation in most countries has been effective in controlling prices but not expenditures. Several cross-national price comparisons show that drug prices are significantly lower in France and Italy, which have strict price regulation, than in the US or Germany (for example, BEUC, 1989; Farmindustria, 1993). However, Danzon and Kim (1998) show that the measured differentials can vary significantly, depending on the sample of drugs used, the index number methodology used, including unit for measuring price and weights. Most international comparisons have been undertaken for regulatory purposes, have been biased by use of very small, non-random samples including only branded drugs, and have not adhered to standard index number methods (for example, GAO, 1992, 1994). For example, the exclusive focus on branded drugs tends to bias comparisons in favor of countries with strict price regulation. Regulation and competition are to some degree substitutes: less regulated markets tend to have higher brand prices but larger generic market shares and lower priced generics, plausibly because substantial brand mark-ups and cross-price elasticity of demand are necessary conditions to attract significant generic entry. The increasing use of international price comparisons, particularly for comparing prices across countries of the EU, imply that these methodological issues are of prime policy importance. The failure of price controls to constrain expenditure growth has prompted several countries to adopt controls on volume or expenditures. Germany’s national drug budget, described above, has evolved in 1997 into physician-specific drug spending targets with financial penalties for significant overruns. The UK has indicative drug budgets for general practitioners that, so far, are merely advisory and lack direct financial consequences (except for fundholding physicians who voluntarily assume financial risk for a broad range of services including drugs). France negotiates revenue caps with individual companies; prices are rolled back if volume and hence total revenue exceed the target level. Many issues related to costs and benefits of these evolving regulatory strategies require further analysis. The evidence from Germany shows that placing physicians at financial risk is a potent weapon to limit drug
1078
The Pharmaceutical Industy
5880
spending. However, it is a blunt weapon because physician budgets cannot be perfectly risk-adjusted to reflect differences in patient characteristics. Such caps therefore create incentives for cream skimming and/or service restrictions for sick patients. Limits confined to drug spending create no incentive for efficient substitution between drugs and other medical services, outpatient versus inpatient care, and so on. Cost-effective substitution between services is essential to achieve the maximum value from total health expenditures, but physicians cannot be expected to have the information or time required to evaluate alternative treatment regimens for specific patient conditions. In addition, in the longer run, regulatory systems that penalize physicians for prescribing costly new drugs could significantly reduce incentives for R&D. In response to the cost-increasing effects of new technologies, there is a growing interest by governments and other payers in the use of technology assessment, including cost-effectiveness analysis, to evaluate new drugs. Although so far no country requires evidence of cost-effectiveness for registration, an increasing number of countries consider economic factors as a condition of reimbursement. Australia and the province of Ontario in Canada were the first require data on cost-effectiveness in reimbursement decisions. France and the UK encourage the provisions of such data, as do many private insurers in the US (Elixhauser, Luce and Steiner, 1995). Since the conclusions from a cost-effectiveness study are highly sensitive to - and only as good as - the methodology and data employed in the study, there have been several attempts to establish guidelines for such studies (Drummond, 1994, 1996). Thus whereas the key research issue of the 1960s and 1970s was the design of market access controls, to appropriately balance reduction in risks to health and safety against delay in market access, the key issue in the 1990s is the design of price regulatory strategies that provide an optimal trade-off between control of drug spending, access for patients to new, more advanced therapies, incentives for optimal use of drugs relative to other medical services and long-run incentives for manufacturers to develop new drugs for the future.
5. Profitability and Rates of Return The pharmaceutical industry has been under frequent attack for apparently high profits. (The term ‘profit’ is used to denote a return in excess of a normal return on capital invested.) Accurate measurement of profits is not easy in any industry. It is particularly problematic in the case of pharmaceuticals because of the length of product life and because of the importance of investments in intangible R&D and promotional capital. Both
5880
The Pharmaceutical Industry
1079
of these investment flows are expensed on accounting statements but, from an economic perspective, are more correctly viewed as investments with a multi-year payout over the market life of a drug. Several approaches have been used to measure profitability. The Lerner index of price relative to marginal production cost suggests high profitability. The ratio of the price of originator drugs relative to generic price several years after patent expiration (a rough measure of marginal cost) is roughly 5 (Caves, Whinston and Hurwitz, 1991). However, this probably overstated the Lerner index at earlier points of the life cycle for this cohort of drugs, since the price of originator drugs tended to rise in real terms with age in the US in the 1980s (Danzon and Kim, 1996). More fundamentally, a Lerner index based on short-run marginal production cost at a single point in time in one country is not a good indicator of the conceptually correct measure, which compares the discounted present value of global revenues over the full life cycle, relative to total costs including investments in R&D and promotion. A second approach to profitability measurement attempts to adjust reported rates of return on book value of capital to take account of intangible capital of R&D and promotion. Standard accounting practices treat investments in R&D and promotion as current expenses rather than as investments in intangible capital, leading to systematic upward bias in accounting rates of return for industries with relatively high intangible investments. Clarkson (1996) illustrates the effects of these adjustments for firms in fourteen industries for the period 1980-1993. Before adjustment, the average accounting rate of return on equity for the fourteen industries is 12.3 percent; the pharmaceutical industry has the highest return of 24.4 percent. After adjustment for intangible capital, the average is 10.2 percent compared to 13.3 percent for pharmaceuticals, which is less than the adjusted return for petroleum, computer software and foods. The most reliable approach to measuring the rate of return to investment in a cohort of drugs uses discounted cash flow estimates of the costs and returns for that cohort. Grabowski and Vernon (1990, 1996) estimate the returns on R&D for new drugs introduced in the 1970s and in 1980-1984, respectively. The cost estimates include dry holes and interest cost of funds, based on data gathered from individual firms. Market sales data for the US are used to project a sales profile over an economic life of over 20 years. Foreign sales are estimated using a foreign sales multiplier. Applying a contribution margin to net out direct costs then yields a life-cycle profile for net revenue, which is discounted to present value using a 10.0-10.5 percent real cost of capital. Grabowski and Vernon conclude that drug introductions in the 1970s on average earned a return roughly equal to their cost of capital. The later cohort on average yielded a positive net present value of $22.2m, or an internal rate of return of 11.1 percent, compared to the 10.5
1080
The Pharmaceutical Industy
5880
percent cost of capital. Given the margin of error in estimating several of the key parameters, the hypothesis of a normal rate of return cannot be rejected. The returns distribution across drugs is highly skewed, such that only the top 30 percent of drugs cover the average R&D cost. Grabowski and Vernon (1996) use simulation analysis to show that an important implication of this skewed distribution of returns is that regulatory strategies that target these ‘blockbuster’ drugs could significantly reduce expected average returns and hence reduce incentives for R&D. By contrast, a competitive strategy that permits high prices for patented drugs but then promotes generic competition after patent expiry has a much less negative effect on incentives for R&D, because a given loss in sales revenue is more heavily discounted if it occurs late rather than early in the product life cycle. While the basic point is important and correct, the magnitude of the revenue loss from targeting blockbuster drugs may be sensitive to the assumption that R&D cost per drugs is uniform whereas the distribution of revenues is highly skewed. To the extent that firms can anticipate the different market potential of different drugs and incur higher R&D costs for drug candidates with potentially greater returns, the cost distribution may roughly mirror the returns distribution, such that the distribution of net revenues is less skewed than the distribution of gross revenues. Using similar methodology, a smaller sample (1981-1983 drug introductions) and different parameter values, the US OTA (1993) concluded that the average NCE in this period earned excess returns of $36m over the average R&D cost. Again, no confidence interval is reported and conclusions are sensitive to several important assumptions. Moreover, even if the drugs introduced in the 1980s did earn abnormal returns, the experience of the 1990s cohort of drugs is likely to be less favorable, because of the growth of managed care in the US, increased regulatory stringency in many foreign markets, and more rapid generic erosion of post-patent market shares in several major markets, including the US, Germany and the UK. Although the rapid growth in R&D investment - indeed any investment - by the pharmaceutical industry in the 1980s implies that at least normal and possibly above-normal returns were anticipated, such growth would also be consistent with expanding technological possibilities. Although this cohort rate-of-return approach is the only valid approach to measuring profitability, it is vulnerable to the fundamental objection that, if estimated returns either exceed or fall short of normal levels, this reflects either measurement error on the part of researchers or market disequilibrium that is probably already being corrected by competitive entry, such that the analyst’s estimate is obsolete before it is made. Since there are no significant barriers to entry to research activities, if pharmaceutical R&D were to generate persistently excessive returns, competitive entry would occur as
5880
The Pharmaceutical Industry
1081
long as expected profits exceed the cost of capital. Dissipation of excess profits could take the form of price competition but could also include undertaking more or riskier R&D that targets new therapeutic areas with little prior experience. This competitive adjustment process may not be smooth or instantaneous, because market and regulatory conditions, including insurance reimbursement systems, are continually changing; market entry through new R&D may take time and the actual realization of returns may be different from that anticipated when an R&D investment is initiated. In general, a reasonable assumption is that competitive entry to exploit R&D opportunities will tend to restore expected profitability to normal levels if anticipated profits are above normal. The more important policy question is whether the resulting rate of introduction of new drugs and mix of innovative vs. imitative drugs is socially optimal. In other words, changes in the regulatory and reimbursement environment may affect profitability in the short run. But in the long run, the rate and mix of R&D adjusts such that normal returns are realized on average. Whether the resulting R&D expenditures entail significant duplicative investment is an important issue. Henderson and Cockburn (1996) provide some evidence against this idea, but not a definitive rejection. The current trend of payers to demand evidence of cost-effectiveness relative to existing drugs as a condition for reimbursement above existing drugs, reinforces incentives for manufacturers to target R&D towards innovative therapies and away from imitative drugs. Of course, the great uncertainty ex ante as to the ultimate therapeutic value of new drugs and the speed of approval implies that ex post realizations may still yield some me-too drugs. Even the optimal number of me-toos is uncertain, given their value as a competitive constraint and sometimes as a source of significant improvements for some subsets of patients.
6. Industry Structure and Productivity: Regulation or Technology? Government regulation has had a significant impact on industry structure. In the US, the 1938 Federal Food, Drug, and Cosmetic Act restricted the sale of some drugs to prescription, leaving only less potent drugs available for direct over-the-counter (OTC) demand by consumers. The fact that insurance coverage is restricted in many countries to prescription drugs and that physician agency is an issue only for prescription drugs has distinguished the prescription sector from the OTC sector. The 1962 Amendments, enacted to promote safety and efficacy, further differentiated the research-based industry. Several studies have examined the effects of regulation and other factors on industry structure and economies of scale in R&D. Temin (1980)
1082
The Pharmaceutical Industy
5880
examines the impact of regulatory and technological change on the structure of the US pharmaceutical industry using firm level data from 1948 to 1973. Major technological advances in the postwar period dramatically increased the number and therapeutic potential of new drugs. Temin finds that the size of drug firms increased dramatically during this period with much of the growth concentrated in large rather than small firms. Grabowski and Vernon (1976, 1977) suggest that regulation-induced increases in cost and risks of R&D create scale economies that result in the concentration of innovation in large firms. They also hypothesize that this concentration would lead to higher market shares and higher prices for drugs that do obtain FDA approval, due to the reduction in the number of close competitors. Their empirical findings support the first hypothesis, showing an increasing proportion of innovations concentrated in large firms and increasing concentration ratios of innovational output. However, they find no evidence to support the second hypothesis: concentration of sales in the industry did not increase and competition from generic and non-patented products prevented prices from rising. The relationship between research productivity and firm size is further examined by Thomas (1990). Despite the decline in the annual number of NCE introductions following the 1962 Amendments, levels of real R&D expenditures rose each year from 1960 to 1980. Thomas shows that the decline in NCE introductions around 1962 was concentrated in the smallest firms, many of which dropped out of innovation. Using productivity trends in the UK as a control to isolate the effects of regulation in the US, Thomas estimates the ‘direct effects’ of regulation on individual firms and the ‘indirect effects’ resulting from the asymmetric impact of the regulation on small and large firms. In contrast to Grabowski and Vernon, he concludes that the sales gains due to reduced competition from smaller firms more than offset the reduction in research productivity for large firms. Thomas (1996) extends the argument that strict safety and efficacy regulation in the US and UK led to a shakeout of smaller, less innovative firms and concentration of innovative effort in larger firms. This, together with relatively free pricing policies, may have contributed to the preeminence of these two countries in developing innovative products, by forcing the development of the necessary skills. Thomas argues that the much less stringent efficacy regulation in France and Japan has sheltered weak domestic firms and hence contributed to the failure of these countries to develop skills necessary to compete in the global pharmaceutical marketplace. The price regulatory systems in these two countries, which depress prices over the life of a drug, create incentives for firms to focus R&D efforts on a large number of new drugs in order to get frequent price increases, rather than invest in fewer, truly innovative drugs that achieve global penetration (Danzon, 1997).
5880
The Pharmaceutical Industry
1083
More recently, the structure of the pharmaceutical industry has been undergoing fundamental change. Horizontal mergers have combined some of the largest firms, ostensibly to further exploit potential economies of scale, scope and risk-pooling. Other large firms have integrated forward into distribution, with the acquisition of pharmacy benefit management companies. The stated rationale for this strategy is to gain access to information and possibly leverage to gain sales advantage. The long-term value of both the horizontal and vertical integration strategies remains to be determined, compared to the alternative of devoting the same resources to R&D. It is also plausible that the optimal strategy is different for different firms, depending on their other assets and capabilities. At the same time, the biotechnology revolution has dramatically increased the importance of small firms in discovery research and related development of new tools for enhancing R&D productivity, for example, through rational drug design. In the 1980s a very small number of successful biotech firms developed their functional scope to become fully integrated pharmaceutical companies, similar in structure to the traditional chemical-based firms. However, theory and evidence for the 1990s indicate a higher degree of specialization and mutual dependence between small and large firms. Most small firms now specialize in discovery, relying on large firms for development and marketing expertise where regulatory interactions and economies of scale play a greater role. Conversely, although large firms still have in-house R&D activities, they also draw extensively on discoveries - tools and target compounds - that are in-licensed from smaller firms. The extent and form of alliances between small firms, particularly biotech, and large firms varies, in part reflecting the particular expertise of large firms. However there is virtually universal recognition that small firms have a key role to play and that most large firms cannot compete effectively in the R&D race without taking advantage of the developments offered by small firms. An important implication of this mutual dependence is that it is now almost impossible - and perhaps a meaningless task - to attempt to estimate returns to scale in R&D productivity. Since all firms draw on technologies developed by other firms through licensure and other sharing arrangements, any attempt to allocate specific new drugs to specific firms in order to count the number of new drugs per firm is at risk of error because most drug innovation employs inputs developed by several other firms, in addition to the firm that ultimately takes it through the regulatory process.
1084
The Pharmaceutical Industy
5880
7. Promotion and Advertising 7.1 Information or Persuasion? The pharmaceutical industry’s large expenditures on advertising and promotion have been controversial in both the economic literature and the policy debate, with concern over both magnitude and form. Critics question the social value of these large promotional expenditures and charge that they lead to increased market power and higher prices. The alternative view is that promotion provides information to physicians and consumers which is necessary for the effective use of the products. Considerable research has focused on determining the competitive effect of promotional expenditures in the pharmaceutical industry. An early proponent of the anti-competitive hypothesis, Walker (1971) argues that large promotion expenditures raise entry barriers and increase market power, by requiring new entrants to make large outlays in order to attract attention to new products. The alternative view is that advertising may enhance competition by facilitating the introduction of new products and new firms. Schwartzman (1975) finds that more innovative firms spend larger sums on promotion. Telser (1975) finds that the extent of new entry into a therapeutic class is positively related to promotional intensity. However, this positive correlation between research and selling intensity, at the level of either the firm or the therapeutic class, does not prove that the effect of advertising is to enhance competition. Clearly the two may be simultaneously determined and both causally related to such unobservable factors as technological advance and market potential. Leffler (1981) estimates a model across therapeutic categories with selling effort as the dependent variable and the number of new products introduced as the primary explanatory variable. He finds a significant positive effect which he interprets as suggesting that informative advertising of pharmaceuticals may be substantial. He also finds evidence, however, that advertising of established pharmaceutical products accomplishes ‘reminder’ and ‘habit-formation’ purposes by finding significant coefficients on variables which indicate therapeutic categories in which he hypothesizes that the returns from noninformative, repetitive advertising are relatively high. These results suggest that the impact of advertising is multidimensional and that the net effect on competition may differ, depending on the circumstances. The distinction drawn by Leffler between the ‘persuasion’ and ‘information’ roles of pharmaceutical promotion is extended by Hurwitz and Caves (1988) in a study of promotional expenditures for a sample of drugs that went off-patent and their generic competitors. Their interest is in the scope of rent-seeking in manufacturers’ promotion outlays. They note that
5880
The Pharmaceutical Industry
1085
the social costs generated by rent-seeking behavior must be weighed against the efficiency advantages of sellers as suppliers of product information demanded by buyers. Their results indicate that the leader’s (the original patent holder) market share increases significantly with its own sales promotion, independent of the amount of goodwill generated before it went off-patent, although these past investments are also important. In addition, the leader’s share diminishes with generic outlays. The leader’s price premium significantly increases the generics’ share of advertising, although the implied sensitivity is small in the short run. They conclude that there are both information and rent-seeking functions of pharmaceutical promotion. Beales (1996) uses the FDA policy restricting manufacturer advertising of unapproved indications as a natural experiment to test the importance of pharmaceutical marketing as a source of information for physicians. He analyzes the impact of promotional activity following FDA approval of second indications for existing drugs on the share of patients treated with the newly approved product, the total fraction of patients treated with drug therapy, and the average price level. He finds some evidence that seller-provided information after approval results in increased market share for the new indication as well as lower average price per prescription of other products in the market, suggesting an increase in consumer benefits from increased manufacturer-provided information. However, it is difficult to differentiate between the impact of FDA approval itself and the impact of promotional expenditures in this study. 7.2 Regulation of Promotion and Advertising Several countries have adopted regulations designed to discourage promotion. The UK PPRS limits the promotional expenditure that can be deducted as a cost in calculating the net rate of return. The provisions of the German global drug budgets, that place the pharmaceutical industry at financial risk for budget overruns (after the share paid by physicians), are designed to discourage promotional effort. Similarly, the French revenue caps for individual pharmaceutical firms severely reduce the incentive for incremental promotional effort that would lead to a budget overrun for the firm. In the US, since 1962 the FDA has imposed strict limits on content of promotional material to physicians and consumers. More recently, the growth of managed care has fundamentally changed the nature of marketing of pharmaceuticals. The autonomy of the physician has been reduced, with power shifting to payers or their agents, in the form of pharmacy benefit managers or pharmaceutical and therapeutics committees that make formulary decisions. This shift in the primary ‘customer’ from the physician to a cost-conscious decision maker has been accompanied by a dramatic
1086
The Pharmaceutical Industy
5880
increase in the importance of cost-effectiveness analysis, to demonstrate that a particular drug is more cost-effective than the alternatives. The available evidence on use of cost-effectiveness analysis by managed care organizations is summarized in Elixhauser, Luce and Steiner (1995). In response to this trend, the FDA has proposed regulations that would require that a pharmaceutical firm’s cost-effectiveness claims be supported by ‘sound’ analysis. If this requirement is defined as requiring a double blind, randomized clinical trial between the two drugs under comparison, it raises many of the same issues that were debated at the time of the 1962 efficacy requirements. In particular, are the gains from reducing the risk of misleading claims outweighed by the costs of the added regulatory requirements? These costs would include higher out-of-pocket costs for firms that would ultimately be passed on to consumers; delay and foregone benefits to consumers if the diffusion of new drugs is delayed; and a reduction in the number of drugs that are worth developing. Again, some might argue that elimination of me-too drugs would, on balance, benefit consumers but, as discussed earlier, both theory and evidence on this point remain inconclusive. However, it seems likely that as purchasers are increasingly either a managed care regime in the US or sophisticated, cost-conscious institutional buyers in other countries, that firms will face strong incentives to eliminate drugs that are clearly going to be pure me-toos at an early stage in the R&D process. The case for a regulatory requirement for randomized controlled trials (RCTs) before cost-effectiveness claims can be made seems weaker than the case for RCTs for efficacy. The information on both costs and effects produced from RCTs is of dubious value as evidence of cost-effectiveness in practice because trials do not mirror actual practice. Strict protocols are applied to the selection of participating patients, to assure compliance and follow up all questionable outcomes. The result is that neither costs nor effects of controlled trials reflect those that would be realized in actual practice by a particular patient, group of patients or health plan. Moreover, the evidence (Elixhauser, Luce and Steiner, 1995) suggests that managed care plans are quite skeptical of cost-effectiveness claims made by manufacturers. Similar conclusions surely apply to government regulators that review such claims for public insurances. Nevertheless, there appears to be a strong case for encouraging competition in the provision of information on cost-effectiveness of pharmaceuticals, including the development of guidelines for the conduct of such studies.
5880
The Pharmaceutical Industry
1087
8. Conclusions The economics literature on the pharmaceutical industry has made many valuable contributions, in framing some of the important issues and providing useful - although rarely definitive - empirical evidence. Nevertheless, we still lack complete answers to some of the basic questions raised by policymakers and academics. If the moral hazard effects of insurance justify some forms of control, which forms provide the best trade-offs between reasonable control of costs, access for patients, incentives for efficient mix of medical services and incentives for innovative R&D? Is there a case for separate regulation of promotional activity for pharmaceuticals, distinct from that applied to other consumer products? If so, what forms of regulation of promotional activities yield the greatest net social benefits, and how does this differ between prescription and over-the-counter medications? These are only some of the interesting questions that remain to be explored.
Bibliography on The Pharmaceutical Industry (5880) Alexander, Donald, Flynn, Joseph E. and Linkins, Linda A. (1994), ‘Estimates of the Demand for Ethical Pharmaceutical Drugs Across Countries and Time’, 26 Applied Economics, 821-826. Anessi Pessina, Eugenio (1997), The Effect of User Charges on the Utilization of Prescription Medicines in the Italian National Health Service, Unpublished Doctoral Dissertation, Philadelphia, The Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania. Averch, Harvey and Johnson, Leyland (1962), ‘Behavior of the Firm under Regulatory Constraint’, 52 American Economic Review, 1052-1069 Baily, Martin N. (1972), ‘Research and Development Costs and Returns: The U.S. Pharmaceutical Industry’, 80 Journal of Political Economy, 70-85. Beales, J. Howard, III (1996), ‘New Uses for Old Drugs’, in Helms, Robert B. (ed.), Competitive Strategies in the Pharmaceutical Industry, Washington, DC, The American Enterprise Institute Press 281-305. Berndt, Ernst R. and Greenberg, Paul (1996), ‘Price Growth of Prescription Pharmaceutical Preparations: An Update and Explanation’, in Helms, Robert B. (ed.), Competitive Strategies in the Pharmaceutical Industry, Washington, DC, The American Enterprise Institute Press, 35-48. Berndt, Ernst R., Griliches, Zvi and Rosett, Joshua G. (1993), ‘Auditing the Producer Price Index: Micro Evidence from Prescription Pharmaceutical Preparations’, 11 Journal of Business and Economic Statistics, 251-264. BEUC (1989), Drug Prices and Drug Legislation in Europe, Brussels. Boston Consulting Group (1993), The Changing Environment for U.S. Pharmaceuticals. Caves, Richard E., Whinston, Michael D. and Hurwitz, Mark A. (1991), ‘Patent Expiration, Entry, and Competition in the U.S. Pharmaceutical Industry’, Brookings Papers on Economic Activity: Microeconomics, 1-66.
1088
The Pharmaceutical Industy
5880
Clarkson, Kenneth W. (1996), ‘The Effects of Research and Promotion on Rates of Return’, in Helms, Robert B. (ed.), Competitive Strategies in the Pharmaceutical Industry, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute Press, 238-268. Comanor, William S. (1964), ‘Research and Competitive Product Differentiation in the Pharmaceutical Industry in the United States’, 31 Economica, 372-384. Comanor, William S. (1986), ‘The Political Economy of the Pharmaceutical Industry’, 24 Journal of Economic Literature, 1178-1217. Danzon, Patricia M. (1996), ‘The Uses and Abuses of International Price Comparisons’, in Robert B. (ed.), Competitive Strategies in the Pharmaceutical Industry, Washington, DC, The American Enterprise Institute Press, 85-106. Danzon, Patricia M. (1997a), Price Regulation in the Pharmaceutical Industry: National vs. Global Interests, Washington, DC, The American Enterprise Institute Press. Danzon, Patricia M. (1997b), ‘Price Discrimination for Pharmaceuticals: Welfare Effects in the US and the EU’, 4 International Journal of the Economics of Business, 301-322. Danzon, Patricia M. (1998), ‘The Economics of Parallel Trade’, 13(3) PharmacoEconomics, 1-12. Danzon, Patricia M. and Kim, Jeong (1996), ‘International Price Comparisons for Pharmaceuticals’, Working Paper, Philadelphia, University of Pennsylvania, The Wharton School. Danzon, Patricia M. and Liu, Hong (1996), ‘Reference Pricing and Physician Drug Budgets: The German Experience in Controlling Pharmaceutical Expenditures’, Working Paper, Philadelphia, University of Pennsylvania, The Wharton School. Danzon, Patricia M. and Percy, Allison (1996), ‘The Effects of Price Regulation on Productivity in Pharmaceuticals’, in Robert Lipsey (ed.), Studies in Income and Wealth, National Bureau of Economic Research, forthcoming. DiMasi, Joseph A., Bryant, N.R. and Lasagna, Louis (1991), ‘New Drug Development in the United States from 1963 to 1990’, 50(5) Clinical Pharmacology and Therapeutics. DiMasi, Joseph A., Hansen, Ronald W., Grabowski, Henry G. and Lasagna, Louis (1991), ‘The Cost of Innovation in the Pharmaceutical Industry’, 10 Journal of Health Economics, 107-142. Dranove, David and Meltzer, David (1994), ‘Do Important Drugs Reach the Market Sooner?’ 25 Rand Journal of Economics, 402-423. Drummond, Michael F. (1994), ‘Guidelines for Pharmaoeconomic Studies: The Way Forward’, 6 Pharmacoeconomics, 493-497. Drummond, Michael F. (1996), Experimental versus Observational Data in the Economic Evaluation of Health Care Technologies, University of North Carolina. Elixhauser, Anne, Luce, Bryan R. and Steiner, Claudia A. (1995), Cost Effectiveness Analysis, Medical Technology Assessment, and Managed Care Organizations, Bethesda, MD, MEDTAP International Inc.. Ellis, Randall and McGuire, Thomas (1991), ‘Optimal Payment Systems for Health Services’, 10 Journal of Health Economics. Farmindustria (1993), Indicatori Farmaceutici, Rome, Farmindustria. Frank, Richard G. and Salkever, David S. (1992), ‘Pricing, Patent Loss and the Market for Pharmaceuticals’, Southern Economic Journal, 165-79. Grabowski, Henry G. (1980), Drug Regulation and Innovation.
5880
The Pharmaceutical Industry
1089
Grabowski, Henry G., Vernon, John M. and Thomas, Lacy G., II (1978), ‘Estimating the Effects of Regulation on Innovation: An International Comparative Analysis of the Pharmaceutical Industry’, 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 133-163. Grabowski, Henry G. and Vernon, John M. (1976). ‘Structural Effects of Regulation on Innovation in the Ethical Drug Industry’, in Masson, R.T. and Qualls, P.D. (eds), Essays on Industrial Organization in Honor of Joe S. Bain, Cambridge, MA, Lippincott, Ballinger 181-205. Grabowski, Henry G. and Vernon, John M. (1977). ‘Consumer Protection Regulation in Ethical Drugs’, 67 American Economic Review, 359-64. Grabowski, Henry G., Vernon, John M. and Thomas, Lacy Glenn (1978), ‘Estimating the Effects of Regulation on Innovation: An International Comparative Analysis of the Pharmaceutical Industry’, 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 133-163. Grabowski, Henry G. and Vernon, John M. (1990), ‘A New Look at the Returns and Risks to Pharmaceutical R&D’, 36 Management Science, 804-821. Grabowski, Henry G. and Vernon, John M. (1992), ‘Brand Loyalty, Entry and Price Competition in Pharmaceuticals after the 1984 Act’, 35 Journal of Law and Economics, 331-350. Grabowski, Henry G. and Vernon, John M. (1993), ‘Returns to R&D on New Drug Introductions in the 1980's’, in Helms, Robert B. (ed.), Conference on Competitive Strategies in the Pharmaceutical Industry, Washington, DC, The American Enterprise Institute Press. Grabowski, Henry G. and Vernon, John M. (1996), ‘Prospects for Returns to Pharmaceutical R&D under Health Care Reform’, in Helms, Robert B. (ed.), Competitive Strategies in the Pharmaceutical Industry, Washington, DC, The American Enterprise Institute Press194-207. Griliches, Zvi and Cockburn, Iain (1994), ‘Generics and New Goods in Pharmaceutical Price Indexes’, 84 American Economic Review, 1213-1232. Hansen, Ronald W. (1979), ‘The Pharmaceutical Development Process: Estimates of Current Development Costs and Times and the Effects of Regulatory Changes’, in Chien, R.I. (ed.), Issues in Pharmaceutical Economics, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. 151-187. Henderson, Rebecca and Cockburn, Iain (1996), ‘The Determinants of Research Productivity in Ethical Drug Discovery’, in Helms, Robert B. (ed.), Competitive Strategies in the Pharmaceutical Industry, Washington, DC, The American Enterprise Institute Press, 167-193. Hurwitz, Mark A. and Caves, Richard E. (1988), ‘Persuasion or Information? Promotion and the Shares of Brand Name and Generic Pharmaceuticals’, 31 Journal of Law and Economics, 299-320. Leffler, Keith B. (1981), ‘Persuasion or Information? The Economics of Prescription Drug Advertising’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 45-74. Lu, John and Comanor, William (1998), ‘Strategic Pricing of Pharmaceuticals’, Review of Economics and Statistics, forthcoming. Masson, Alison and Steiner, Robert L. (1985), Generic Substitution and Prescription Drug Prices: Economic Effects of State Drug Product Selection Laws, Washington, DC, Bureau of Economics, Federal Trade Commission. Munnich, Frank E. and Sullivan, K. (1994), ‘The Impact of Recent Legislative Change on Germany’, 6(Suppl.1) PharmacoEconomics, 11-16.
1090
The Pharmaceutical Industy
5880
Myers, Steward C. and Shyam-Sunder, Lakshmi (1996), ‘Measuring Pharmaceutical Industry Risk and the Cost of Capital’, in Helms, Robert B. (ed.), Competitive Strategies in the Pharmaceutical Industry, Washington, DC, The American Enterprise Institute Press, 208-237. Pauly, Mark V. (1968). ‘The Economics of Moral Hazard’, 58 American Economic Review, 231-237. Peltzman, Sam (1973), ‘An Evaluation of Consumer Protection Legislation: The 1962 Drug Amendments’, 8 Journal of Political Economy, 1049-1091. Pharmaceutical Research and Manufacturers of America (PhRMA) (1997), 1997 Industry Profile, Washington, DC. Ramsey, Frank P. (1927), ‘A Contribution to the Theory of Taxation', 37 Economic Journal’, 47-61. Reekie, W. Duncan (1978), ‘Price and Quality Competition in the United States Drug Industry’, 26 Journal of Industrial Economics, 223-237. Scherer, Frederic M. (1993), ‘Pricing, Profits and Technological Progress in the Pharmaceutical Industry’, 7 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 97-115. Scherer, Frederic M. (1996), ‘How U.S. Antitrust Can Go Astray: The Brand Name Prescription Drug Litigation’, 4 International Journal of the Economics of Business, 239-256. Schmalensee, Richard (1982), ‘Product Differentiation Advantages of Pioneering Brands’, 72 American Economic Review, 349-365. Schulenburg, Mathias V.D. and Schöffski, O. (1993), Implications of the Structural Reform of Healthcare Act on the Referral and Hospital Admission Practices of Primary Care Physicians, Hanover, University of Hanover, Institute of Insurance Science. Schulenburg, J. Matthias Graf Von Der and Schöffski, Oliver (1994), ‘Transformation des Gesundheitswesens im Spannungsfeld zwischen Kostendämpfung und Freiheit, Eine ökonomische Analyse des veränderten Überweisungs- und Einweisungsverhaltens nach den Arzneimittelregulierungen des GSG (Transformation of the Health Care System, An Economic Analysis of the Changes in Referrals and Hospital Admissions after the Drug Budget of the Health Care Reform Act of 1992)’, in Oberender, P. (ed.), Probleme der Transformation im Gesundheitswesen, Baden-Baden, Nomos, 45-81. Schwartzman, David (1975), The Expected Return from Pharmaceutical Research, Washington, DC, The American Enterprise Institute Press. Schweitzer, Stuart O., Schweitzer, Maurice E. and Guellec, Marie S. (1996), ‘Is There a U.S. Drug Lag? The Timing of New Pharmaceutical Approvals in the G-7 Countries and Switzerland’, 53 Medical Care Research and Review, 162-178. Suslow, Valerie Y. (1996), ‘Measuring Quality Change in the Market for Anti-Ulcer Drugs’, in Helms, Robert B. (ed.), Competitive Strategies in the Pharmaceutical Industry, Washington, DC, The American Enterprise Institute Press, 49-72. Telser, Lester (1975), ‘The Theory of Supply with Applications to the Ethical Pharmaceutical Industry’, 18 Journal of Law and Economics, 449-478. Temin, Peter (1980), Taking Your Medicine: Drug Regulation in the United States, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Thomas, Lacy Glenn, II (1990), ‘Regulation and Firm Size: FDA Impacts on Innovation’, 21 RAND Journal of Economics, 497-517.
5880
The Pharmaceutical Industry
1091
Thomas, Lacy Glenn, II (1996), ‘Industrial Policy and International Competitiveness in the Pharmaceutical Industry’, in Robert B. Helms (ed.), Competitive Strategies in the Pharmaceutical Industry, Washington, DC, The American Enterprise Institute Press, 107-129. US Congress, Office of Technology Assessment (OTA) (1993), Pharmaceutical R&D: Costs, Risks and Rewards, Washington, DC, Government Printing Office. US Congressional Budget Office (CBO) (1994), An Analysis of the Administration’s Health Proposal, Washington, DC, Government Printing Office. US General Accounting Office (GAO) (1992), Prescription Drugs: Companies Typically Charge More in the United States than in Canada, Washington, DC, Government Printing Office. US General Accounting Office (GAO) (1994), Prescription Drugs: Companies Typically Charge More in the United States than in the UK, Washington, DC, Government Printing Office. Walker, Hugh E. (1971), Market Power and Price Levels in the Ethical Drug Industry, Bloomington, University of Indiana Press. Wardell, William M. (1973), ‘Introduction of New Therapeutic Drugs in the United States and Great Britain: An International Comparison’, 14 Clinical Pharmacology Therapeutics, 773-790. Wardell, William M. and Lasagna, Louis (1975), Regulation and Drug Development, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute Press. Wiggins, Steven N. (1981), ‘Product Quality Regulation and New Drug Introductions: Some New Evidence from the 1970s’, 63 Review of Economics and Statistics, 615-619. Zeckhauser, Richard (1971), ‘Medical Insurance: A Case Study of the Trade-Off Between Risk Spreading and Appropriate Incentives’, 2 JET, 10-26. Zweifel, Peter and Crivelli, Lucien (1996), ‘Price Regulation: Lessons from Germany’, 9 Journal of Regulatory Economics.
5890 FRANCHISE CONTRACTS Antony W. Dnes The Nottingham Trent University © Copyright 1999 Antony W. Dnes
Abstract Theoretical and empirical work on franchising has developed from agency theory and from ideas about asset specificity and opportunism associated with transactions-cost analysis. I begin by considering some traditional arguments about the capital-structure function of franchising. Next, I consider agency and transaction-cost theoretical explanations of franchising. An interesting special case is where the franchisor also runs company stores. Econometric work supports the view that franchise contracts protect against reciprocal opportunism. I also examine several arguments concerning the possible nature of ‘hostages’ in franchise contracts. JEL classification: K23, L22 Keywords: Franchising, Agency, Search Theory, Hostages
1. Introduction Franchising is an organizational form lying between markets and hierarchies, and can follow either a business-format or a simpler dealership model. It is a symbiotic relationship between businesses (Schanze, 1991). Business-format franchising, in which the franchisor supplies a brand name and also a model business for the franchisee to copy, is the growing sector of franchising and covers businesses like vehicle rental and fast-food restaurants. Many of the differences between business-format franchising and dealerships (for example, cars or petroleum) are disappearing over time as manufacturers provide a wide range of support for their dealers. Theoretical and empirical work on franchising has developed from agency theory and from ideas about asset specificity and opportunism associated with transaction-cost analysis. I begin by considering some traditional arguments about the capital-structure function of franchising. Next, I consider agency and transaction-cost theoretical explanations of franchising. An interesting special case is where the franchisor also runs company stores. Econometric work supports the view that franchise contracts protect against reciprocal opportunism. I also examine several arguments concerning the possible nature of ‘hostages’ in franchise contracts.
1092
5890
Franchise Contracts
1093
2. Franchising as a Method of Raising Capital An early argument is that firms franchise to raise capital for expansion (Caves and Murphy, 1975). Rubin (1978) argues that this makes no sense unless we assume that the franchisor is more risk averse than the franchisee, which is implausible. Even if franchisors could not use normal capital markets, they could sell shares in a portfolio of all outlets. The shares would diversify risk for the buyers but impose no costs on the franchisor. Franchisees would pay less for undiversified investments if they are risk averse, which implies smaller returns for franchisors. Any capital-market advantages from franchising must come from shifting risk to the franchisee, which only makes sense if the franchisor is the more risk averse. Rubin’s argument that capital raising does not explain franchising depends upon an assumption of zero transaction costs. Franchising can be a capital issue under less restrictive assumptions. However, empirical work generally supports organizational costs rather than capital-market influences as the driving force behind franchising. Lafontaine (1992) discovered that increases in the capital cost of opening stores reduced the proportion of franchised outlets, which is contrary to the capital-raising story.
3. Franchising as a Problem of Monitoring and Control Rubin explains the features of franchising in terms of solving monitoring problems. In retail networks where the satellite business is remote from the head office monitoring is difficult and it pays to develop an incentive system that encourages the avoidance of shirking. A profit-sharing agreement gives the franchisee sufficient residual profits to make shirking too costly. The franchise chain will show more total profit if shirking is controlled. Franchisors will not pay any more profit to franchisees than is necessary to remove the incentive to shirk. A competitive supply of prospective franchisees should be willing to pay lump sums equal to the difference between franchise profits and what they could earn as managers in similar occupations. We do not usually observe franchise contracts of this kind. Instead franchisees pay a lump-sum initial fee, and a continuing royalty payment related to sales, in return for residual profits. The most plausible explanation is that the franchisee requires protection against poor post-contract performance by the franchisor. The franchisor’s duties cover such things as providing managerial support and the monitoring of standards of operation throughout the franchise system. Monitoring of the system is necessary to control a classic externality problem: if one franchisee allows quality to deteriorate, he benefits by the full amount of the savings from reduced quality but incurs only part of
1094
Franchise Contracts
5890
the costs as other franchisees will suffer some of the loss of business. This type of externality is described by Mathewson and Winter (1985) as horizontal free riding. The theory generates several predictions. Increasing the geographical density of outlets should make operating company stores more attractive. Also, franchisors should buy back their outlets as their chains become more mature, the density of outlets increases, and distance-related monitoring costs become lower per outlet. Buy-backs are observed in mature chains. Much econometric work supports the importance of geographical density in explaining franchising (Lafontaine, 1992; Brickley and Dark, 1987; Norton, 1988). Lafontaine also finds evidence that increases in the importance of the franchisor’s inputs increase the royalty, which supports the view that franchise contracts are partly constructed to control the franchisor’s opportunism.
4. Modelling Franchising as an Agency Relationship Mathewson and Winter (1985) argue that horizontal externalities are not necessary to explain franchise contracts. Monitoring difficulties arise for the franchisor even when there is only one territory. However, vertical externality (chiselling on the franchisor’s standards) is an ever-present problem. Risk aversion on the part of the franchisee is also not a sufficient condition for the emergence of a franchise contract. The franchisor could impose a large penalty if the franchisee were caught cheating, making the franchisee’s income the same across different demand conditions and giving a pure risk-sharing contract with no profit-sharing. However, the penalty may be infeasible owing to wealth constraints affecting the franchisee and this gives profit sharing. In their model local demand at a franchised outlet is subject to uncertainty and may take a high or low state. The franchisor cannot costlessly identify any ruling state of demand. The franchisee has better local information and may attempt to reduce the quality of his effort in high demand states and try to pass off the resulting low output as due to a low demand state, reflecting a problem of franchisee moral hazard. The franchise contract specifies the franchise fee schedule (lump sum plus royalty) plus the quality of the franchisee’s input in good and bad demand states. Mathewson and Winter agree with Rubin that the first-best contract between franchisor and franchisee would lease the brand name in return for a lump-sum payment. The franchisor would be encouraged by the incentive of maximizing the fee to find the joint-profit-maximizing monitoring arrangements. Each franchisee would pay a fee conditional on the value of the brand name and therefore dependent on the optimal amount of monitoring, and could enforce the contract ex post.
5890
Franchise Contracts
1095
If it is infeasible to cover all aspects of the franchise relationship in an explicit contract, profit-sharing emerges. In their basic model, Mathewson and Winter attribute this to a constraint on the wealth of franchisees that prevents them from sinking large investments into franchises. This empirically relevant constraint makes franchisors rely on rewards rather than the penalty of termination to maintain franchisees’ standards. An incentive-compatibility constraint in their model ensures that the profit accruing to the franchisee from correctly declaring the better demand state and applying the correct effort level exceeds the profit from wrongly declaring the poor state and adjusting effort downward. A participation constraint ensures that the contract gives sufficient profit for the franchisee to pay a royalty fee. Mathewson and Winter derive the franchise fees, franchise effort in each state, the level of brand-name investment by the franchisor (including advertising) and the frequency of monitoring. The removal of the wealth constraint from the model opens up the possibility that franchisees could post bonds to guarantee good performance. Mathewson and Winter agree with Rubin that bond posting is problematic as the franchisor might behave opportunistically. The expected value of the lump sum must be less than the profits accruing to the franchisor from the proper delivery of services. Otherwise, there will be an incentive for the franchisor to abscond with the lump sum, possibly by contriving some reason for contract termination. The royalty, or its equivalent, is always the engine for rent extraction.
5. The Organizational Mix ‘Dual distribution’ is an important phenomenon. Gallini and Lutz’s (1992) model shows that both dual distribution and the use of a sales royalty may be methods by which a new franchisor signals the profitability of the franchise chain by making franchisor returns dependent on the revenues of company stores. Consider the case where a franchisor with a fixed number of outlets knows that demand is favourable so that stores should be unusually profitable. The problem is to convey this information in a credible manner to prospective franchisees. The high-profit franchisor chooses the proportion of company stores, the lump sum and the royalty to establish a separating equilibrium defining a contract that a low-profit franchisor would never offer. A separation constraint ensures that a low quality franchisor will always make more profit from truthfully declaring quality and franchising all stores, compared with emulating the dual-distribution strategy of the high-profit franchisor. A number of predictions may be made on the basis of signalling theory, but they are not supported by empirical work. To take one as an example, the high profitability of some franchises would be recognized over time and there would be no need for franchisors to operate company stores as a signal. We should see
1096
Franchise Contracts
5890
mature franchise chains concentrating on franchising, rather than the operation of company stores. Whilst there is possibly some support for this hypothesis, for example Martin (1988) observes that older units are often franchised, economists often observe a buy-back phenomenon (Thompson, 1994) as the chain matures. Lafontaine (1993) reports econometric results showing no support for a range of hypotheses suggesting that franchisors use their organizational mix as a method of signalling.
6. A Search Theory of Franchising Minkler (1992) has suggested that franchising is a device through which the franchisor gathers and uses local information. The theory is Austrian in character and emphasizes the key role played by information in the competitive process. There is a dark side to franchising in Minkler’s approach: franchisees are useful temporary tools, rather as in some of the small-business literature (Hoy, 1994; Bates, 1995). According to agency-based theories of franchising distance of the satellite business from the mother company, which makes monitoring more difficult, should be associated with an increased reliance on franchising. However, Minkler cites examples where franchised and company stores operate in close proximity to each other. For example, in Sacramento, California, 34 Taco Bell restaurants covered a 30-mile radius, of which seven were company owned. Minkler argues that franchisors draw on the local knowledge of franchisees, which concerns local tastes and market conditions. The franchisor might be unable to direct the satellite business, even if monitoring costs were zero, because of ignorance. Franchising allows the use of the trade mark to be exchanged for the franchisee’s local entrepreneurship, which is defined as noticing and acting upon opportunities. The franchisee’s local entrepreneurship reduces the cost of search for new business. How reasonable is the search-cost theory? Empirical work by Minkler shows that older outlets are more likely to be franchised than newer ones, which is consistent with the theory and with Martin’s (1988) results, although it is not consistent with Thompson (1994). A problem is that the buy-back phenomenon is consistent with many theories: for example older stores may be easier to monitor owing to experience effects unconnected with distance. It is difficult to imagine an empirical test to distinguish Minkler’s theory from others.
5890
Franchise Contracts
1097
7. Vertical Restrictions and Franchising Within the mainstream industrial-organization literature there are papers which show that a firm with monopoly power supplying an intermediate product into a competitive industry has an incentive to exercise vertical control if downstream input substitution is possible. Vertical restrictions principally comprise refusal to supply, tied-in sales, and exclusive-dealing contracts. The arguments of several economists that there are efficiency reasons for all of these practices are reflected in the specialist economic analysis of franchising, and in the benign view taken by European competition law towards franchising (Dnes, 1991c). For example, against simple claims that a monopolist could foreclose a downstream market by refusing to supply unless buyers were tied into a restrictive contract, it may be argued that it is profitable to allow access to inputs at monopoly prices to more efficient downstream firms. Although, to be fair, some recent analysis has revealed conditions under which refusal to supply (Bolton and Whinston, 1993) is a credible policy committing a firm to compete aggressively in the downstream market and deterring entry. Analyses of franchising based on monopoly-power explanations of vertical restrictions are typically less general than theories based on the economics of organization. As a very simple example of lack of generality, note that monopoly-power theories of vertical restrictions usually deal with product franchises, when most business-format franchises are based on services, and would seem to have relevance only for brand-and-trade-name franchising. The relevance of the market-power approach is further questioned by a lack of supporting empirical evidence: for example Lafontaine (1992) found that the proportion of franchised outlets decreased as franchisor input sales increased. Blair and Kaserman (1982) formulate a two-period model that does represent the franchise contract as a mixture of vertical controls. The model predicts use of both a lump sum and a royalty whenever the franchisor’s and franchisee’s discount factors diverge (reflecting perceptions of uncertainty). Blair and Kaserman avoid regarding individual controls like resale price maintenance (RPM) and franchise fees as perfect substitutes for one another. In general, franchising firms use a mix of contractual devices and cannot be indifferent between them. Blair and Kaserman suggest there may be complementarity between monopoly-power and organizational explanations of common features of franchised businesses. A franchisor with the relatively lower discount factor would not be able to extract all the expected downstream rent from the franchisee. Thus, post-contract tensions would arise as the franchisor saw franchisees enjoying super-normal profits. If franchisor uncertainty over forecasts fell over time, mature franchise chains would open more company stores. Blair and Kaserman also suggest that the franchisor can practice
1098
Franchise Contracts
5890
post-contract opportunism. The franchisor must promise the franchisee a normal return on investment. Afterwards, however, the franchisor may be able to increase his share of sales revenue without provoking the franchisee to close down (if there were worse losses from closing). The franchisor may use strategies like forcing, where quotas push sales past the point of profit maximization for the franchisee. Blair and Kaserman share some of the concerns over franchisor and franchisee incentive compatibility shown in the organizational literature and are not solely motivated by traditional market-power issues. Efficiency-based explanations of vertical restrictions are descended from Telser’s (1960) analysis of RPM. A retailer could provide service levels like advice and product demonstrations only to find that consumers made use of these and then bought the product at a low price from a no-frills retailer. There is a free-rider problem among retailers implying that no retailer would provide services. If service levels matter in promoting sales for the manufacturing and retailing industries combined, and are not separable, a means like RPM must be found to defeat free riding. Marvel (1982) explains exclusive dealing, which is a common feature of franchising, in a similar fashion. When a manufacturer with a valuable brand supplies an outlet it endorses the retailer’s business and centralized advertising may promote the retailer’s sales more generally. Marvel argues that exclusive dealing prevents retailers from diverting business to other brands and wasting advertising. Klein and Saft (1985) examine tied-in sales and argue that franchisors use these either to control the quality of the final service, or to measure the sales of franchisees. Where the franchisee cannot substitute away from the input, a mark-up on a tie-in is equivalent to a fixed percentage sales royalty if price is predictable. Tie-ins may also develop where the franchisor wishes to ensure that franchisees use inputs of specific quality. Rather than monitoring the required technical properties of more generic inputs, the franchisor has the much simpler problem of ascertaining whether anything else was used.
8. Hostages in Franchise Contracts Transaction-cost analysis shows that franchise contractual provisions that are often regarded as unfair in the law have important implications for efficiency (Klein, 1995). Fully contingent, costlessly enforceable, explicit contracts are not usually feasible. Uncertainty implies a large number of possible contingencies and some aspects of contractual performance are difficult to measure. Individuals have an incentive to renege on agreements and hold-up any contracting partner who has made specific investments by taking advantage of unspecified or unenforceable aspects of contracts. Full vertical integration
5890
Franchise Contracts
1099
between trading partners will not always be observed: for example integration of human capital is outlawed by the prohibition of slavery. One method of safeguarding performance is for a potential cheater to post a bond (a ‘hostage’) possibly in an implicit form if the cheater is required to make an investment in a highly specific form with a very low salvageable value. In both cases, the same purpose is served. Franchise contracts typically require franchisees to pay lump-sum fees to franchisors and to make highly specific investments in equipment. The franchisor usually takes the right to terminate the contract at will if the franchisee is not maintaining quality standards. For any hostage to be effective it must set the franchisee’s expected gain from cheating equal to zero. This implies that hostages will be worth much more than the actual gain when monitoring costs are positive. Cheating by the franchisor is controlled by possible increases in operating costs. A franchisor known to appropriate hostages opportunistically would lose franchisees and find it hard to recruit new ones, forcing him to use more costly organizational forms. As long as the franchisee’s bond is greater than the franchisee’s expected gain from cheating and is less than the cost penalty imposed on the franchisor on moving to some other organizational form, a hostage can support their relationship. The hostage is a low-cost substitute for costly monitoring and enforcement devices. Of particular interest is Klein’s argument that the franchisor’s contractual right to terminate the contract at will (for good cause) supports a number of hostages. Given termination at will, the common requirement that franchisees lease their properties from the franchisor can be explained. The franchisee could be forced to move premises and sacrifice valuable leasehold improvements, which would revert to the franchisor as lessor. This gives the franchisor a hostage with which to control franchisee behaviour and enables monitoring to be reduced with an associated cost saving. In recent years Klein has moved to the view that the rents attached to the non-salvageable investment should be the focus in valuing the franchisee’s potential loss, at least in cases where there are no binding legal constraints on the franchisor’s behaviour. It is important to recognize the rich variety of devices used to support contracts. The use of restrictive covenants in franchise agreements can also be explained in terms of hostages. Covenants usually prevent a franchisee from competing in a market area for some period after leaving the franchise system, implying that the non-availability of an alternative rent stream is used to constrain the franchisee’s behaviour: that is, he cannot cheat and leave for better pastures. A new franchisee’s future level of skill is not known but if he becomes highly adept at his business, he might be tempted to set up on his own. A covenant prevents the franchisee from simply removing the franchisor’s investment in his training. Also, termination by the franchisor can cause the loss of the hostage.
1100
Franchise Contracts
5890
Williamson (1985) makes some suggestions concerning likely hostage selection. Implicit hostages are less vulnerable to opportunistic appropriation by trading partners compared with pecuniary hostages. A hostage can be selected to be unattractive to its holder. An ideal hostage is like an ‘ugly princess’: the medieval king with two equally cherished daughters would be wiser posting the ugly one as a hostage, as she is less likely to be appropriated by the captor. A number of common observations emerge from studying franchisees’ contracts (Dnes, 1993d). Franchising increases the specificity of investment for the satellite business, compared with independent operation, for example leasehold improvements are trademarked and hard to adapt to other uses. Also, lump-sum fees are typically small in relation to sunk investment for the franchisee and appear to be linked to the franchisor’s costs of establishing the franchisee (training and launch advertising). The implicit aspects of contracts are important and show adjustments that favour the interests of both franchisees and franchisors. The feasibility of placing disciplinary hostages with franchisors is qualified by the explicit and implicit details of franchise contracts, which often set out conditions under which the franchisor must buy-back assets in the event of termination. Statute law in some countries, like the USA, also makes it difficult to call in a hostage for disciplinary reasons. Principles of common law, such as the prohibition against penal damages for breach of contract, may also make disciplinary hostages illegal in an Anglo-American setting. It is not surprising that franchisees are careful to avoid hostage penalties in their contracts: investments in such things as leasehold improvements are not ugly princesses but are of potential direct value to the franchisor. There are several questions about the real-world feasibility of disciplinary hostages, regardless of whether these are measured as rent streams or as the book value of sunk investments. Sunk investment by the franchisee may well have mainly a screening function, serving to demonstrate confidence in his own competence.
9. Conclusions The last decade has witnessed progress in the scientific understanding of franchising. Several theories have been constructed to explain franchising, most of which emphasize savings of monitoring costs in an agency framework. Details of the theories show how opportunism on the part of both franchisors and franchisees may be controlled. In separate developments, writers have argued that franchisors recruit franchisees to reduce information-search costs, or that they signal franchise quality by running company stores.
5890
Franchise Contracts
1101
Empirical studies tend to support theories emphasizing opportunism on the part of franchisors and franchisees. Thus, elements of both agency approaches and transaction-cost analysis receive support. The most robust finding is that franchising is encouraged by factors like geographical dispersion of units, which increases monitoring costs. Other key findings are that small units and measures of the importance of the franchisee’s input encourage franchising, whereas increasing the importance of the franchisor’s centralized role encourages the use of company stores. In many key respects, in result although not in principle, transaction-cost analysis and agency analysis are just two different languages describing the same franchising phenomena.
Bibliography on Franchise Contracts (5890) Adams, Michael (1988), ‘Franchising - A Case of Long-Term Contracts: Comment’, 144 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 145-148. Barron, John M. and Umbeck, John R. (1984), ‘The Effects of Different Contractual Arrangements: The Case of the Retail Gasoline Markets’, 27 Journal of Law and Economics, 313-328. Bates, T. (1995), ‘A Comparison of Franchise and Independent Small Business Survival Rates’, 7 Small Business Economics, 377-388. Bays, Carson W. (1989), ‘Tying Arrangements Should be Per Se Legal’, 26 American Business Law Journal, 625-663. Bays, Carson W. (1990), ‘Balancing the Benefits and Costs of the Tying Prohibition’, 28 American Business Law Journal, 161-167. Blair, R.D. and Kaiserman, D.L. (1982), ‘Optimal Franchising’, 48 Southern Economic Journal, 494-505. Bolton, P. and Whinston, M. (1993), ‘Incomplete Contracts, Vertical Integration and Supply Constraints’, 60 Review of Economic Studies, 121-148. Brickley, James A. and Dark, Frederick N. (1987), ‘The Choice of Organizational Form: The Case of Franchising’, 18 Journal of Financial Economics, 401-420. Brickley, James A., Dark, Frederick H. and Weisbach, Michael S. (1991), ‘The Economic Effects of Franchise Termination Laws’, 34 Journal of Law and Economics, 101-132. Caves, Richard E. and Murphy, William F., II (1975), ‘Franchising: Firms, Markets and Intangible Assets’, 42 Southern Economic Journal, 572-586. Dnes, Anthony W. (1989a), ‘Avis Rent A Car: a Case Study in Franchising’, in Moutinho, L. (ed.), Cases in Marketing Management, London, Reading, MA, Addison-Wesley, 207-215. Dnes, Anthony W. (1989b), ‘Franchising and Privatization: Issues and Options’, Paper D140, Centre of Policy Studies, Monash University. Dnes, Anthony W. (1991a), ‘Franchising’, in Parker, D. and Burton, J. (ed.), Studies in Business and Management. Dnes, Anthony W. (1991b), ‘The Economics of Franchising and its Regulation’, in Joerges, Christian (ed.), Franchising and the Law: Theoretical and Comparative Approaches in Europe and the United States, Baden Baden, Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft, 133-142. Dnes, Anthony W. (1991c), ‘Franchising, Natural Monopoly and Privatization’, in Veljanovski, C.
1102
Franchise Contracts
5890
(ed.), Regulators and the Market, London, Institute for Economic Affairs, 210-233. Dnes, Anthony W. (1992a), ‘Franchising’, in Eatwell, John, Milgate, Murray and Newman, Peter (eds.), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Money and Finance, London, Macmillan. Dnes, Anthony W. (1992b), ‘“Unfair” Practices and Hostages in Franchise Contracts’, 148 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 484-504. Dnes, Anthony W. (1992c), Franchising: a Case-study Approach, Avebury. Dnes, Anthony W. (1993a), ‘Bidding for Commercial Broadcasting’, 40(1) Scottish Journal of Political Economy, 104-115. Dnes, Anthony W. (1993b), ‘Franchising Passenger Rail’, 40(4) Scottish Journal of Political Economy, 420-433. Dnes, Anthony W. (1993c), ‘On the Wrong Tracks: the Government’s Proposal for Franchising Passenger Rail’, 40 Hume Occasional Paper, Edinburgh. Dnes, Anthony W. (1993d), ‘A Case-Study Analysis of Franchise Contracts’, 22 Journal of Legal Studies, 367-393. Dnes, Anthony W. (1994), ‘The Scope of Chadwick’s Bidding Scheme’, 150 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 524-536. Dnes, Anthony W. (1995a), ‘Avis Rent A Car: Targeting a Franchise System’, in Moutinho, L. (ed.), Cases in Marketing Management, 2nd edn, Reading, MA, Addison-Wesley. Dnes, Anthony W. (1995b), ‘Franchising and Privatization’, Private Sector, World Bank. Reprinted Viewpoint: Franchising and Privatization, 43 World Bank Note, April 1995. Dnes, Anthony W. (1996), ‘The Economics of Franchise Regulation and Contracts’, 152 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 1-28. Gallini, Nancy T. and Lutz, Nancy A. (1992), ‘Dual Distribution and Royalty Fees in Franchising’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 471-501. Goldberg, Victor P. (1979), ‘Law and Economics of Vertical Restrictions: A Relational Perspective’, 58 Texas Law Review, 91-129. Hadfield, Gilliam K. (1990), ‘Problematic Relations: Franchising and the Law of Incomplete Contracts’, 42 Stanford Law Review, 927-992. Hoy, F. (1994), ‘The Dark Side of Franchising or Appreciating Flaws in an Imperfect World’, 12 International Small Business Journal, 26-38. Inaba, Frederick S. (1980), ‘Franchising: Monopoly by Contract’, 47 Southern Economic Journal, 65-72. Joerges, Christian (1991), ‘The Economics of Franchising and its Regulation’, in X (eds), Franchising and the Law: Theoretical and Comparative Approaches in Europe and the United States, Baden Baden, Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft. Kaufmann, Patrick J. and Lafontaine, Francine (1994), ‘Costs of Control: The Source of Economic Rents for McDonald’s Franchisees’, 37 Journal of Law and Economics, 417-453. Klein, B. (1995), ‘The Economics of Franchise Contracts’, 2 Journal of Corporate Finance: Contracting, Governance and Organization, 9-38. Klein, Benjamin and Saft, Lester F. (1985), ‘The Law and Economics of Franchise Tying Contracts’, 28 Journal of Law and Economics, 345-361. Kneppers-Heynert, E.M. (1988), Een Economische en Juridische Analyse van Franchising tegen de Achtergrond van een Property Rights- en Transactiekosten Benadering (An Economic and Legal Analysis of Franchising in the Light of a Property and Transaction Costs Approach), Groningen, Van Denderen (diss. Groningen), 268 p.
5890
Franchise Contracts
1103
Lafontaine, F. (1992), ‘Agency Theory and Franchising: some Empirical Results’, 23 Rand Journal of Economics, 263-283. Lafontaine, Francine (1993), ‘Contractual Arrangements as Signaling Devices: Evidence from Franchising’, 9 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 256-289. Martin, Robert E. (1988), ‘Franchising and Risk Management’, 78 American Economic Review, 954-968. Marvel, H. (1982), ‘Exclusive Dealing’, 25 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-25. Mathewson, G. Frank and Winter, Ralph A. (1985), ‘The Economics of Franchise Contracts’, 28 Journal of Law and Economics, 503-526. Minkler, A. (1992), ‘Why Firms Franchise: A Search Cost Theory’, 148 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 240-259. Muller Graff, Peter Christian (1988), ‘Franchising: A Case of Long-term Contracts’, 144 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 122-144. Norton, S.W. (1988), ‘An Empirical Look at Franchising as an Organizational Form’, 61 Journal of Business, 197-218. Norton, Seth W. (1989), ‘Franchising, Labor Productivity, and the New Institutional Economics’, 145 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 578-596. Rubin, Paul H. (1978), ‘The Theory of the Firm and the Structure of the Franchise Contract’, 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 223-233. Sass, T.R. and Gisser, M. (1989), ‘Agency Cost, Frim Size, and Exclusive Dealing’, 32 Journal of Land of Economics, 381-399. Schanze, E. (1991), ‘Symbiotic Contracts: Exploring Long-term Agency Structures’, in Joerges, Ch. (ed.), Franchising and the Law: Theoretical and Comparative Approaches in Europe and the United States, Baden-Baden, Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft, 27-103. Telser, L. (1960), ‘Why should Manufacturers want Fair Trade?’, 3 Journal of Law and Economics, 86-105. Thompson, R.S. (1994), ‘The Franchise Life Cycle: a Contractual Solution to the Pensrose Effect?’, 24 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 207-218. Veljanovski, C. (1991), ‘Franchising, Natural Monopoly and Privatization’, in Regulators and the Market, London, Institute of Economic Affairs. Wegener, Morten (1996), ‘Franchising i EU-konkurrenceretten (Franchising in Perspective of the EU-Law of Competiton)’, Forthcoming Report Winter. Wiggins, Steven N. (1988), ‘Franchising - A Case of Long-term Contracts: Comment’, 144 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 149-151. Williamson, Oliver E. (1985), The Economic Institutions of Capitalism: Firms, Markets, Relational Contracting, New York, Free Press, 450 p.
5900 TRANSPORTATION © Copyright 1999 Boudewijn Bouckaert and Gerrit De Geest
Bibliography Collected by the Editors Acker, Mary H. (1985), ‘Assessing the Impact of Regulation of Trucking Firms’, 11 Eastern Economic Journal, 135-143. Ayres, Ian (1988), ‘Determinants of Airline Carrier Conduct’, 8 International Review of Law and Economics, 187-202. Babcock, Michael W. and German, H. Wade (1984), ‘The Impact of Deregulation on Rail TOFC Carloadings’, 20 Logistics and Transportation Review, 205-212. Bailey, Elizabeth E. (1985), ‘Airline Deregulation in the United States: The Benefits Provided and the Lessons Learned’, 12(2) International Journal of Transport Economics, 119-144. Bailey, Elizabeth E. and Williams, Jeffrey R. (1988), ‘Sources of Economic Rent in the Deregulated Airline Industry’, 31 Journal of Law and Economics, 173-202. Barla, Philippe and Perelman, Sergio (1989), ‘Technical Efficiency in Airlines under Regulated and Deregulated Environments’, 60 Annals of Public and Cooperative Economy, 103-124. Barnekov, Christopher C. (1987), ‘The Track Record’, 11(1) Regulation, 19-27. Beesley, Michael E. and Glaister, Stephen G. (1983), ‘Information for Regulating: The Case of Taxis’, 93 Economic Journal, 594-615. Beilock, Richard (1985), ‘Are Truckers Forced to Speed?’, 21 Logistics and Transportation Review, 277-291. Beilock, Richard and Freeman, James (1987), ‘The Effect on Rate Levels and Structures of Removing Entry and Rate Controls on Motor Carriers’, 21 Journal of Transport Economics and Policy, 167-188. Beneish, Messod D. (1991), ‘The Effect of Regulatory Changes in the Airline Industry on Shareholders’ Wealth’, 34 Journal of Law and Economics, 395-430. Bennett, Randall W. and Boyer, Kenneth D. (1990), ‘Inverse Price/Quality Tradeoffs in the Regulated Airline Industry’, 24 Journal of Transport Economics and Policy, 35-47. Benson, Bruce L. (1984), ‘Spatial Price Theory and an Efficient Congestion Toll Established by the Free Market"’, 22 Economic Inquiry, 244-252. Reprinted in Greenhut, Melvin L. and Norman, George (eds) (1995), The Economics of Location, Vol. II, London, Edward Elgar Publishing, 172-180. Benson, Bruce L. (1985), ‘Free Market Congestion Tolls: A Correction’, 23 Economic Inquiry, 361-362. Benson, Bruce L. (1994), ‘Are Public Goods Really Common Pools: Considerations of the Evolution of Policing and Highways in England’, 39 Economic Inquiry, 249-271. Blair, Roger D., Kaserman, David L. and McClave, James T. (1986), ‘Motor Carrier Deregulation: The Florida Experiment’, 68 Review of Economics and Statistics, 159-164. Blair, Roger D., Kaserman, David L. and McClave, James T. (1987), ‘Competition on Trial: Florida Deregulates Trucking’, 30(4) Challenge, 60-64.
1104
5900
Transportation
1105
Blauwens, Gust and Van De Voorde, Eddy (1986), ‘Onderzoek naar de Economische Kost van de Regulering van het Goederenvervoer in België (An Investigation of the Economic Cost of the Regulation of the Transport of Goods in Belgium)’, 40 Economisch en Sociaal Tijdschrift, 575-592. Blauwens, Gust and Van De Voorde, Eddy (1988), ‘Deregulering en de Vraag naar Luchtvervoer (Deregulation and the Demand for Air Transport)’, 32 Tijdschrift voor Economie en Management, 127-142. Blonk, W.A.G. (1987), ‘Vervoer (Transport)’, in X (ed.),18de Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Brussel 8 en 9 mei 1987, Sociaal-economische Deregulering, Brussel, V.E.H.U.B., 543-560. Blumestock, James W. and Thomchick, Evelyn A. (1986), ‘Deregulation and Airline Labor Relations’, 22 Logistics and Transportation Review, 389-403. Bohlander, George W. and Farris, Martin T. (1984), ‘Collective Bargaining in Trucking: the Effects of Deregulation’, 20 Logistics and Transportation Review, 223-238. Bongaerts, Jan C. and Van Schaik, A.S. (1984), ‘The Demand for Regulation: The Case of Dutch Inland Shipping’, 4 International Review of Law and Economics, 199-212. Borenstein, Severin and Zimmerman, Martin B. (1988), ‘Market Incentives for Safe Commercial Airline Operation’, 78 American Economic Review, 913-935. Bourbeau, Robert (1983), Les Accidents de la Route au Québec 1926-1978: Etude Démographique et Epidémiologique (Road Accidents in Quebec, 1926-1978: A Demographic and Epidemiologic Study), Montréal, Presses de l’Université de Montréal. Boyer, Kenneth D. (1987), ‘The Costs of Price Regulation: Lessons from Railroad Deregulation’, 18 Rand Journal of Economics, 408-416. Boyer, Marcel and Dionne, Georges (1985), ‘Sécurité Routière: Responsabilité pour Négligence et Tarification (Road Safety: Responsibility for Negligence and Pricing)’, 18 Canadian Journal of Economics, 814-830. Boyer, Marcel, Dionne, Georges and Vanasse, Charles (1991), ‘Infractions au Code de la Sécurité Routière, Infractions au Code Criminel et Gestion Optimale de la Sécurité Routière (Infractions to the Road Safety Code, Infractions to the Criminal Code and Optimal Management of Road Safety)’, 67 L’Actualité Economique, 279-305. Breen, Denis A. (1977), ‘The Monopoly Value of Household-Goods Carrier Operating Certificates’, 20 Journal of Law and Economics, 153-185. Bruning, Edward R. and Tehranian, Hassan (1988), ‘Stock Market Reactions to Motor Carrier Regulatory Reform’, 15 International Journal of Transport Economics, 7-27. Buckley, Patricia (1982), ‘The Deregulation of Urban Taxicab Markets: A Note’, 26 American Economist, 73-76. Button, Kenneth J. (1989a), ‘Economic Theories of Regulation and the Regulation of the United Kingdom’s Bus Industry’, 34 Antitrust Bulletin, 489-515. Button, Kenneth J. (1989b), ‘Liberalising the Canadian Scheduled Aviation Market’, 10(4) Fiscal Studies, 19-52. Button, Kenneth J. (1990), Airline Deregulation: International Experiences, New York, New York University Press, 191 p. Button, Kenneth J. and Swann, Dennis (1989), ‘European Community Airlines Deregulation and Its Problems’, 27 Journal of Common Market Studies, 259-282. Card, David (1986), ‘The Impact of Deregulation on the Employment and Wages of Airline Mechanics’, 39 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 527-538.
1106
Transportation
5900
Caves, Douglas W., Christensen, Laurits R. and Swanson, Joseph A. (1981), ‘Economic Performance in Regulated and Unregulated Environments: A Comparison of U.S. and Canadian Railroads’, 66 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 559-581. Caves, Douglas W., Christensen, Laurits R., Tretheway, Michael W. and Windle, Robert J. (1987), ‘An Assessment of the Efficiency Effects of U.S. Airline Deregulation via an International Comparison’, in Bailey, Elizabeth E. (ed.), Public Regulation: New Perspectives on Institutions and Policies. MIT Press Series on the Regulation of Economic Activity, no. 14, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 285-320. Coase, Ronald H. (1961), ‘The British Post Office and the Messenger Companies’, 4 Journal of Law and Economics, 12-65. Colegate, Raymond (1986), ‘Airline Deregulation in the United States Eight Years On: Review Article’, 9 World Economy, 441-444. Cordes, Joseph J. and Goldfarb, Robert S. (1983), ‘Alternate Rationales for Severence Pay Compensation under Airline Deregulation’, 41 Public Choice, 351-369. Cordes, Joseph J., Goldfarb, Robert S. and Johnson, Richard L. (1989), ‘Design and Implementation of Job Loss Compensation Provisions: Lessons from the Airline Deregulation Experience’, 16 International Journal of Transport Economics, 35-55. Cosentino, Fabrizio (1992), ‘Trasporto di Merci su Strada e Limitazione della Responsabilità : Osservazioni in Chiave di Analisi Economica del Diritto (Nota a Corte costit., 22 novembre 1991, n. 420, Soc. Dafne et Cloe c. Autotrasp. bestiame Melano) (Carriage of Goods by Road and Limitation of Liability: Remarks from the Point of View of the Economic Analysis of Law)’, 1 Il Foro Italiano, 647-655. Crew, Michael A. and Kleindorfer, Paul R. (eds) (1991), Competition and Innovation in Postal Services, Dordrecht, Kluwer, 304 p. Crum, Michael R. (1989), ‘U.S. Transportation Management Developments since Deregulation’, 16 International Journal of Transport Economics and Policy, 263-295. Daicoff, Darwin W. (1988), ‘Deregulation and Motor Carrier Safety’,24 Logistics and Transportation Review, 175-184. Dardis, Rachel, Garkey, Janet and Zhang, Zhiming (1989), ‘Deregulation of Trucking in the United States - Implications for Consumers’, 12 Journal of Consumer Policy, 19-38. Daughety, Andrew F. and Nelson, Forrest D. (1988), ‘An Econometric Analysis of Changes in the Cost and Production Structure of the Trucking Industry, 1953-1982', 70 Review of Economics and Statistics, 67-75. Davidson, Wallace N., II, Chandy, P.R. and Walker, Mike (1984), ‘The Stock Market Effects of Airline Deregulation’, 23(4) Quarterly Journal of Business and Economics, 31-45. Davies, David G. (1977), ‘Property Rights and Economic Efficiency - the Australian Airlines Revisited’, 20 Journal of Law and Economics, 223-226. Dawson, D.A. and Parent, L.P. (1987), ‘Positive Steps in Transport Deregulation the Prairies’, 13(1) Canadian Public Policy, 86-96. Derthick, Martha and Quirck, Paul J. (1985), ‘Why the Regulators Chose to Deregulate’, in Noll, Roger G. (ed.), Regulatory Policy and the Social Sciences, Berkeley, University of California Press, 200-231. Dionne, Georges and Gagne, Robert (1988), ‘Models and Methodologies in the Analysis of Regulation Effects in Airline Markets’, 15 International Journal of Transport Economics, 291-312.
5900
Transportation
1107
Dively, Dwight (1984), ‘Applications of Regulatory Theory to the Trucking Industry’, 6 Research in Law and Economics, 211-226. Dnes, Anthony W. (1996), ‘The Future of the British Post Office’, 3(3) European Journal of Law and Economics, 162-173. Dodgson, J.S. and Katsoulacos, Y. (1988), ‘Quality Competition in Bus Services: Some Welfare Implications of Bus Deregulation’, 22 Journal of Transport Economics and Policy, 263-281. Douglas, George W. and Miller, J.C. (1974), Economic Regulation of Domestic Air Transport: Theory and Policy, Washington, Brookings Institution. Dunbar, Frederick C. and Mehring, Joyce S. (1990), ‘Coal Rail Prices during Deregulation: A Hedonic Price Analysis’, 26 Logistics and Transportation Review, 17-34. Eads, George C. (1983), ‘Airline Competitive Conduct in a Less Regulated Environment: Implications for Antitrust’, 28 Antitrust Bulletin, 159-184. Eckert, Ross D. and Hilton, George W. (1972), ‘The Jitneys’, 15 Journal of Law and Economics, 293-325. Evans, Andrew (1988), ‘Hereford: A Case Study of Bus Deregulation’, 22 Journal of Transport Economics and Policy, 283-306. Findlay, Christopher C. (1985), ‘Effects of Australian International Air Transport Regulation’, 34 Journal of Industrial Economics, 199-216. Forsyth, Peter (1984), ‘Airlines and Airports: Privatisation, Competition, and Regulation’, 5(1) Fiscal Studies, 61-75. Frankel, E.G. (1986), ‘Economic and Commercial Implications of the U.S. Shipping Act of 1984', 22(2) Logistics and Transportation Review, 99-114. Frankena, Mark W. and Pautler, Paul A. (1986), ‘Taxicab Regulation: An Economic Analysis’, 9 Research in Law and Economics, 129-165. Frew, James R. (1981), ‘The Existence of Monopoly Profits in the Motor Carrier Industry’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 289-315. Friedlaender, Ann F. and De Neufville, Richard (1979), ‘The Political Rationality of Federal Transportation Policy’, 1 Research in Law and Economics, 97-114. Gagne, Robert and Dionne, Georges (1988), ‘Qu’en est-il des Rendements d’Echelle dans les Industries Quebecoises et Ontariennes de Transport par Camion (What is True About the Economics of Scale in the Quebec and Ontario Trucking Industry)’, 64 L’actualité Economique, 380-395. Gallick, Edward C. and Sisk, David E. (1987), ‘A Reconsideration of Taxi Regulation’, 3 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 117-128. Gantner, Manfred (1988), ‘Die neue Luftverkehrsordnung der Europäischen Gemeinschaft und ihre Auswirkungen auf die Austrian Airlines und die EG-Integrationspolitik (New European Community Air Transport Regulation and its Impact on Austrian Airlines and Integration Policies)’, 14 Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft, 337-357. Garrod, P.V. and Miklius, W. (1987), ‘“Captive Shippers” and the Success of Railroads in Capturing Monopoly Rent’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 423-442. Gaudry, Marc (1977), ‘Quelques Problèmes de Tarification du Transport des Voyageurs à Montréal (Some Tarification Problems Regarding Public Transit in Montreal)’, III Canadian Public Policy, 307-314. Gaudry, Marc (1986), Un abrégé de DRAG, un Modèle de la Demande Routière, des Accidents et de leur Gravité, appliqué au Québec de 1956 à 1982 (A Summary of DRAG, a Model of Road
1108
Transportation
5900
Demand and of Accidents and their Seriousness, Applied to Quebec from 1956 to 1982), Montréal, Centre de recherche sur les transports. Gaudry, Marc (1995), Sur une Application à la Région Métropolitaine de Montréal des Recommandations de la Commission Royale sur le Transport des Voyageurs au Canada (Of an Application to the Montreal Metropolitan Area of the Recommendations of the Royal Commission on Public Transit in Canada), Montréal, Centre de recherche sur les transports. Gaudry, Marc, Fournier, François and Simard, Robert (1995), DRAG-2, un Modèle Econométrique Appliqué au Lilométrage, aux Accidents et à leur Gravité au Québec - Synthèse des Résultats (DRAG-2, An Econometric Model Applied to Mileage and to Accidents and their Seriousness in Quebec - Summary of Results), Québec, Sociéte de l’assurance automobile du Québec. Gil, Avishai (1990), ‘Air Transport Deregulation and its Implications for Flight Attendants’, 129 International Labour Review, 317-331. Gillen, David W., Oum, Tae Hoon and Tretheway, Michael W. (1988), ‘Entry Barriers and Anticompetitive Behaviour in a Deregulated Airline Market: The Case of Canada’, 15 International Journal of Transport Economics, 29-41. Gillen, David W., Oum, Tae Hoon and Tretheway, Michael W. (1989), ‘Privatization of Air Canada: Why it is Necessary in a Deregulated Environment’, 15 Canadian Public Policy, 285-299. Giordano, James N. (1989), ‘A Trucker’s Dilemma: Managerial Behavior under an Operating Ratio Standard’, 10 Managerial and Decision Economics, 241-251. Golbe, Devra L. (1983), ‘Product Safety in a Regulated Industry: Evidence from the Railroads’, 21 Economic Inquiry, 39-52. Graham, David R., Kaplan, Daniel P. and Sibley, David S. (1983), ‘Efficiency and Competition in the Airline Industry’, 14 Bell Journal of Economics, 118-138. Greenhut, John, Norman, George and Greenhut, Melvin L. (1991), ‘Financial-Economic Aspects of Airline Deregulation’, 18 International Journal of Transport Economics, 3-30. Grimm, Curtis M. and Smith, Ken G. (1986), ‘The Impact of Rail Regulatory Reform on Rates, Service Quality, and Management Performance: A Shipper Perspective’, 22 Logistics and Transportation Review, 57-68. Grimm, Curtis M., Corsi, Thomas M. and Jarrell, Judith L. (1989), ‘U.S. Motor Carrier Cost Structure under Deregulation’, 25 Logistics and Transportation Review, 231-249. Guria, Jagadish C. (1988), ‘Effects of the Recent Road Transport Deregulation on Rail Freight Demands in New Zealand’, 15 International Journal of Transport Economics, 169-187. Guria, Jagadish C. (1989), ‘An Assessment of the Effects of Road Freight Transport Regulations in Developing Countries’, 16 International Journal of Transport Economics, 237-262. Gwilliam, Ken M. (1989), ‘Setting the Market Free: Deregulation of the Bus Industry’, 23 Journal of Transport Economics and Policy, 29-43. Harbeson, Robert W. (1969), ‘Toward Better Resource Allocation in Transport’, 12 Journal of Law and Economics, 321-338. Hardaway, Robert M. (1985), ‘Comment: Transportation Deregulation (1976-1984): Turning the Tide’, 14 Transport Law Journal, 101 ff.
5900
Transportation
1109
Harmatuck, Donald J. (1991), ‘Economies of Scale and Scope in the Motor Carrier Industry: An Analysis of the Cost Functions of Seventeen Large LTL Common Motor Carriers’, 25 Journal of Transport Economics and Policy, 135-151. Harper, Donald V. and Johnson, James C. (1987), ‘The Potential Consequences of Deregulation of Transportation Revisited’, 63 Land Economics, 137-146. Hayashi, Paul M. and Trapani, John M. (1983), ‘An Analysis of the Objectives of Domestic Airline Firms under CAB Regulation’, 15 Applied Economics, 603-617. Heywood, John S. and Peoples, James H., Jr (1994), ‘Deregulation and the Prevalence of Black Truck Drivers’, 37 Journal of Law and Economics, 133-155. Hirsch, Barry T. (1988), ‘Trucking Regulation, Unionization, and Labor Earnings: 1973-1985', 23 Journal of Human Resources, 296-319. Hwang, Ming Jeng and Mann, Patrick C. (1987), ‘Deregulation and Efficiency in the Rail Industry’, 15(2) Atlantic Economic Journal, 47-52. Jaffer, Sue M. and Thompson, David J. (1986), ‘Deregulating Express Coaches: A Reassessment’, 7(4) Fiscal Studies, 45-68. Janis, Russell A. (1986), ‘A Law and Economics Study of Rail Freight Rate Regulation: Traditional Standards, Ramsey Prices, and a Case of Neither’, 15 Transport Law Journal, 31 ff. Jansonius, John V. and Broughton, Kenneth E. (1984), ‘Coping with Deregulation: Reduction of Labor Costs in the Airline Industry’, 19 Journal of Air Law and Commerce, 501-593. Johnson, Nancy Brown, Sambharya, Rakesh B. and Bobko, Philip (1989), ‘Deregulation, Business Strategy, and Wages in the Airline Industry’, 28 Industrial Relations, 419-430. Jordan, William A. (1986), ‘Results of U.S. Airline Deregulation: Evidence from the Regulated Canadian Airlines’, 22 Logistics and Transportation Review, 297-337. Jordon, William D. (1979), ‘Airline Performance under Regulation: Canada vs. the United States’, 1 Research in Law and Economics, 35-79. Kahn, Alfred E. (1988), ‘Surprises of Airline Deregulation’, 78 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 316-322. Kahn, Alfred E. (1988), ‘I Would do it Again’, 12(2) Regulation, 22-28. Keasey, K. and Mulley, C. (1986), ‘Deregulation and Privatisation of Local Buses in the United Kingdom’, 13 International Journal of Transport Economics, 153-175. Keeler, Theodore E. (1986), ‘Public Policy and Productivity in the Trucking Industry: Some Evidence on the Effects of Highway Investments, Deregulation, and the 55MPH Speed Limit’, 76 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 153-158. Keeler, Theodore E. (1989), ‘Deregulation and Scale Economies in the U.S. Trucking Industry: An Econometric Extension of the Survivor Principle’, 32 Journal of Law and Economics, 229-253. Kim, Moshe (1984), ‘The Beneficiaries of Trucking Regulation, Revisited’, 27 Journal of Law and Economics, 227-241. Kitch, Edmund W. (1972), ‘The Yellow Cab Antitrust Case’, 15 Journal of Law and Economics, 327-336. Kling, Robert W. (1988), ‘Trucking Deregulation: Evolution of a New Power Structure’, 22 Journal of Economic Issues, 1201-1211. Kyle, Reuben, II and Phillips, Laurence T. (1985), ‘Airline Deregulation: Did Economists Promise Too Much or Too Little?’, 21 Logistics and Transportation Review, 3-25.
1110
Transportation
5900
Lee, Tenpao, Kim, Tae Kyun and Baumel, C. Phillip (1988), ‘Impact of Deregulation on the Financial Performance of the Class I Railroads: Heuristic Models of Pooled Time Series and Cross Sectional Data’, 24 Logistics and Transportation Review, 281-296. Lee, Tenpao, Kim, Tae Kyun and Baumel, C. Phillip (1989), ‘Impact of Deregulation on the Financial Performance of the Class I Railroads: Errata’, 25 Logistics and Transportation Review, 91-94. Levine, Michael E. (1975), ‘Regulating Airmail Transportation’, 18 Journal of Law and Economics, 317-359. Levine, Michael E. (1981), ‘Revisionism Revised? Airline Deregulation and the Public Interest’, 44(1) Law and Contemporary Problems, 179-195. Levine, Michael E. (1987), ‘Airline Competition in Deregulated Markets: Theory, Firm Strategy, and Public Policy’, 4 Yale Journal on Regulation, 393-494. Lewisch, Peter (1989), Erwerbsfreiheit und Bedarfsprüfung (The Freedom to Earn One’s Living as Subjected to Regulations Concerning Needs), Vienna, Marktwirtschaftliche Schriften des Carl Menger Institutes, 47 p. Lewisch, Peter (1991), ‘The Political Economy of Barriers to Entry: The Example of the Amendment for Taxicab Regulation in Austria’, in Weigel, Wolfgang (ed.), Economic Analysis of Law - A Collection of Applications, Vienna, Österreichischer Wirtschaftsverlag, 222-234. MacDonald, James M. (1989), ‘Railroad Deregulation, Innovation, and Competition: Effects of the Staggers Act on Grain Transportation’, 32 Journal of Law and Economics, 63-95. McCarthy, Patrick S. and Oesterle, William (1987), ‘The Deterrent Effects of Stiffer DUI Laws: An Empirical Study’, 23 Logistics and Transportation Review, 353-371. McFarland, Henry (1987), ‘Did Railroad Deregulation Lead to Monopoly Pricing? An Application of q*’, 60 Journal of Business, 385-400. McGowan, Francis and Seabright, Paul (1989), ‘Deregulating European Airlines’, 0(9) Economic Policy: A European Forum, 283-344. McKenzie, Richard B. and Shughart, William F., II (1987), ‘Deregulation and Air Travel Safety’, 11(3-4) Regulation, 42-47. McMullen, B. Starr and Stanley, Linda R. (1988), ‘The Impact of Deregulation on the Production Structure of the Motor Carrier Industry’, 26 Economic Inquiry, 299-316. McShan, Scott and Windle, Robert J. (1989), ‘The Implications of Hub and Spoke Routing for Airline Costs and Competitiveness’, 25 Logistics and Transportation Review, 209-230. Meyer, John R. and Oster, Clinton V., Jr (eds) (1981), Airline Deregulation: The Early Experience, Boston, Auburn House. Meyer, John R., Oster, Clinton V., Jr and Strong, John S. (1987), ‘The U.S. Experience with Airline Deregulation: The Effect on Travelers: Fares and Service’, in Meyer, John R. and Oster, Clinton V., Jr (eds), Deregulation and the Future of Intercity Passengers, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 109-124. Michel, Allen and Shaked, Israel (1987), ‘Trucking Deregulation and Motor Carrier Performance: The Shareholders’ Perspective’, 22 Financial Review, 295-311. Migué, Jean-Luc, Bélanger, Gérard and Boucher, Michel (1978), Le prix du transport au Québec (The Cost of Transport in Quebec), Québec, Éditeur officiel du Quebec. Miller, James C., III (1979), ‘Airline Market Shares vs. Capacity Shares and the Possibility of Short-Run Loss Equilibria’, 1 Research in Law and Economics, 81-96.
5900
Transportation
1111
Mitchell, Mark L. and Maloney, Michael T. (1989), ‘Crisis in the Cockpit? the Role of Market Forces in Promoting Air Travel Safety’, 32 Journal of Law and Economics, 329-355. Moore, Thomas G. (1976), Trucking Regulation. Lessons from Europe, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 148 p. Moore, Thomas G. (1978), ‘The Beneficiaries of Trucking Regulation’, 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 327-343. Moore, Thomas G. (1986), ‘U.S. Airline Deregulation: Its Effects on Passengers, Capital, and Labor’, 29 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-28. Moore, Thomas G. (1988), ‘Transportation Policy’, 12(3) Regulation, 57-62. Morrison, Steven A. and Winston, Clifford (1986), The Economic Effects of Airline Deregulation, Washington, Brookings Institution, 84 p. Morrison, Steven A. and Winston, Clifford (1990), ‘The Dynamics of Airline Pricing and Competition’, 80 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 389-393. Moses, Leon N. and Savage, Ian (eds) (1989), Transportation Safety in an Age of Deregulation, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 368 p. Nelson, James C. (1987), ‘Politics and Economics in Transport Regulation and Deregulation: A Century Perspective of the ICC’s Role’, 23 Logistics and Transportation Review, 5-32. Netter, Jeffry M., Poulsen, Annette B. and Hersch, Philip L. (1988), ‘Insider Trading: The Law, the Theory, the Evidence’, 6(3) Contemporary Policy Issues, 1-13. Olson, C. Vincent and Trapani, John M. II (1981), ‘Who Has Benefited from Regulation of the Airline Industry?’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 75-93. Oum, Tae Hoon and Tretheway, Michael W. (1984), ‘Reforming Canadian Airline Regulation’, 20 Logistics and Transportation Review, 261-284. Oum, Tae Hoon and Zhang, Yimin (1991), ‘Utilisation of Quasi-Fixed Inputs and Estimation of Cost Functions: An Application to Airline Costs’, 25 Journal of Transport Economics and Policy, 121-134. Oum, Tae Hoon, Stanbury, W.T. and Tretheway, Michael W. (1990), ‘Airline Deregulation in Canada and its Economic Effects’, in Hayashi, T. (ed.), New Dimensions for Public Utilities, Osaka, Osaka University Press. Panzar, John C. (1983), ‘Regulatory Theory and the U.S. Airline Experience’, 139 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 490-505. Pastor, Santos (1982), ‘La Construcción Naval Española Veinte Años Después (The Shipbuilding Industry Twenty Years After: Dynamics and Regulation)’, in Raga, José T. (ed.), Homenaje al Profesor Lucas Beltrán, Madrid, IEF. Pastor, Santos (1982), ‘El Mercado de Transporte Marítimo en los Primeros Ochenta (The Maritime Transport in the Eighties: Problems and Policies)’, 2 Anuario de Derecho Marítimo. Pastor, Santos (1984), ‘Política Marítima Española: Valoración e Implicaciones de Futuro (The Regulation of the Shipping Industry)’, in X (ed.), El Libro Transporte Marítimo y Política Económica, Madrid, IETC-Ministerio de Transportes. Peeters, Ch., Verbeke, A. and Winkelmans, W. (1987), ‘Een Geïntegreerd Overheidsbeleid voor de Belgische Binnenvaartsector (An Integrated Governmental Policy for the Belgian Inland Shipping)’, 32 Tijdschrift voor Economie en Management, 19-37. Peltzman, Sam (1963), ‘CAB: Freedom from Competition’, New Individualist Review.
1112
Transportation
5900
Peltzman, Sam (1975), ‘Effects of CAB Regulation’, in U.S. Senate, Subcommittee on Administrative Practice and Procedures, Committee on Judiciary, Oversight of CAB Practices and Procedures. Pera, Alberto (1989), ‘Deregulation and Privatisation in an Economy Wide Context’, 0(12) OECD Economic Studies, 159-204. Peterson, Rodney (1984), ‘SYMPOSIUM: An Economic Analysis of Statutory Changes in Rail Carrier Entry and Exit’, 13 Transport Law Journal, 189 ff. Phillips, Karen Borlaug and Phillips, Laurence T. (1984), ‘Research, Politics, and the Dynamics of Policy Development: A Case Study of Motor Carrier Regulatory Reform’, 17 Policy Sciences, 367-384. Phillips, Laurence T. (1992), ‘Contractual Relationships in the Deregulated Transportation Marketplace’, 34 Journal of Law and Economics, 535-564. Plourde, André (1987), ‘On the Role and Status of Canadian Natural Gas Carriers under Deregulation’, 13(1) Journal of Energy and Development, 1-25. Ponzanelli, Giulio (1991), ‘Limitazione di Responsabilitá., Analisi Economica e Giudizio di Costituzionalit. (Limitation of Liability, Economic Analysis and Constitutional Judgement)’, I Il Foro Italiano, 643-647. Prager, Robin A. (1989), ‘Using Stock Price Data to Measure the Effects of Regulation: The Interstate Commerce Act and the Railroad Industry’, 20 Rand Journal of Economics, 280-290. Priest, George L. (1975), ‘The History of the Postal Monopoly in the United States’, 18 Journal of Law and Economics, 33-80. Pustay, Michael W. (1989), ‘Liberalization of U.S. International Aviation Policy: A Preliminary Assessment’, 29(2) Quarterly Review of Economics and Business, 15-26. Rakowski, James P. (1988), ‘Marketing Economics and the Results of Trucking Deregulation in the Less-Than-Truckload Sector’, 27 Transportation Journal, 11-22. Reiss, Peter C. and Spiller, Pablo T. (1989), ‘Competition and Entry in Small Airline Markets’, 32(S) Journal of Law and Economics, 179-202. Rose, Nancy L. (1985), ‘The Incidence of Regulatory Rents in the Motor Carrier Industry’, 16 Rand Journal of Economics, 299-318. Rose, Nancy L. (1987), ‘Labor Rent Sharing and Regulation: Evidence from the Trucking Industry’, 95 Journal of Political Economy, 1146-1178. Sacasas, Rene and Glaskowsky, Nicholas A., Jr (1990), ‘Motor Carrier Deregulation: A Decade of Legal and Economic Conflict’, 18 Transport Law Journal, 189 ff. Samuels, George E. (1990), ‘Airline Deregulation: Its Effects and the Competitive Environment’, 17 International Journal of Transport Economics, 131-146. Sarwar, Ghulam and Anderson, Dale G. (1989), ‘Railroad Rate Deregulation and Uncertainty of Farm Level Prices for Corn’, 71 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 883-891. Schipper, Katherine, Thompson, Rex and Weil, Roman L. (1987), ‘Disentangling Interrelated Effects of Regulatory Changes on Shareholders Wealth: The Case of Motor Carrier Deregulation’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 67-100. Sickles, Robin C., Good, David H. and Johnson, Richard L. (1986), ‘Allocative Distortions and the Regulatory Transition of the U.S. Airline Industry’, 33 Journal of Econometrics, 143-163. Spiller, Pablo T. (1983), ‘The Differential Impact of Airline Regulation on Individual Firms and Markets: An Empirical Analysis’, 26 Journal of Law and Economics, 655-689.
5900
Transportation
1113
Stanbury, W.T. and Tretheway, Michael W. (1986), ‘Airline Deregulation: A Bibliography’, 22 Logistics and Transportation Review, 449-489. Talley, Wayne K. and Schwarz Miller, Ann (1988), ‘The Demand for Air Services Provided by Air Passenger Cargo Carriers in a Deregulated Environment’, 15 International Journal of Transport Economics, 159-168. Taylor, D. Wayne (1989), ‘The Economic Effects of the Direct Regulation of the Taxicab Industry in Metropolitan Toronto’, 25 Logistics and Transportation Review, 169-182. Tehranian, Hassan and Bruning, Edward R. (1984), ‘Deregulation and Investor Perception of Motor Carrier Securities’, 20 Logistics and Transportation Review, 165-186. Thomas, Janet M. and Callan, Scott J. (1989), ‘Constant Returns to Scale in the Post Deregulatory Period and the Case of Specialized Motor Carriers’, 25 Logistics and Transportation Review, 271-288. Tretheway, Michael W. (1986), ‘Airline Deregulation: Introduction’,22 Logistics and Transportation Review, 293-296. Tucci, Gianrocco (1985), ‘Regulation and “Contestability” in Formulating an Air Transport Policy for the European Community’, 76 Rivista di Politica Economica, 219-239. Tullock, Gordon (1986), ‘The Case of Dutch Inland Shipping: Comment’, 6 International Review of Law and Economics, 139-140. Tye, William B. (1983), ‘The Postal Service: Economics Made Simplistic’, 3 Journal of Policy Analysis and Management, 62-73. Tye, William B. (1987), Encouraging Cooperation among Competitors: The Case of Motor Carrier Deregulation and Collective Ratemaking, New York, Greenwood Press, 202 p. Van Scyoc, Lee J. (1989), ‘Effects of Airline Deregulation on Profitability’, 25 Logistics and Transportation Review, 39-251. Vetsuypens, Michael R. and Helmuth, John A. (1988), ‘Airline Deregulation: Additional Evidence from the Capital Markets’, 27(2) Quarterly Journal of Business and Economics, 117-138. White, Evan D. (1989), ‘Economic Regulation of Oregon Intrastate Trucking: A Policy Evaluation’, 17 Transport Law Journal, 179 ff. Williams, George (1990), ‘Achieving a Competitive Environment for Europe’s Airline Industry’, National Westminster Bank Quarterly Review, 2-14. Willig, Robert D. and Baumol, William J. (1987), ‘Using Competition as a Guide’, 11(1) Regulation, 28-35. Woodbury, John R., Besen, Stanley M. and Fournier, Gary M. (1983), ‘The Determinants of Network Television Program Prices: Implicit Contracts, Regulation, and Bargaining Power’, 14 Bell Journal of Economics, 351-365. Ying, John S. (1990), ‘The Inefficiency of Regulating a Competitive Industry: Productivity Gains in Trucking Following Reform’, 72 Review of Economics and Statistics, 191-201. Ying, John S. (1990), ‘Regulatory Reform and Technical Change: New Evidence of Scale Economies in Trucking’, 56 Southern Economic Journal, 996-1009. Zimmerman, Martin B. (1979), ‘Rent and Regulation in Unit-Train Rate Determination’, 10 Bell Journal of Economics, 271-281.
5910 INTERNATIONAL TRADE Alan O. Sykes University of Chicago, School of Law © Copyright 1999 Alan O. Syles
Abstract This chapter provides a survey of the law and economics literature on international trade topics. It includes an overview of the legal system, and a general discussion of normative and positive economic approaches to the analysis of the legal rules on trade. Particular issues discussed subsequently include antidumping and subsidies rules, the escape clause for troubled industries, non-discrimination obligations in international trade, technical barriers to trade, and international dispute resolution in the trade field. JEL classification: K33 Keywords: International Trade, Dumping, Subsidies, Nontariff Barriers, Most-Favored-Nation, International Dispute Resolution
1. Introduction The instruments of international trade policy, such as border taxes (tariffs) and quantitative restrictions on the volume of imports or exports (quotas) are, in one fashion or another, laws. Economic scholars have studied the impact and wisdom of these laws for centuries, creating a branch of international economics devoted to these matters of ‘commercial policy’. It is no stretch to characterize all of the work in this field as ‘law and economics’. Were I to define the field in that fashion, however, the bibliography accompanying this chapter would by itself fill this volume. To reduce the undertaking to manageable proportions, I have restricted attention primarily to the work of economically-oriented scholars with legal backgrounds, to work with considerable legal as well as economic content, and to work that has been published in law and economics journals. I have also omitted attention to various ‘trade and’ issues, such as trade and the environment, trade and labor standards, and trade and competition policy, on the premise that they are better addressed elsewhere (see Bhagwati and Hudec, 1996). Finally, I have included a selective set of references to the mainstream international economics literature, intended to provide readers with a place to start should they desire to learn more about the basic economics of international trade. The work of many prominent figures in international economics is nevertheless 1114
5910
International Trade
1115
unrepresented or underrepresented, and to them I apologize in advance.
2. The Legal Landscape Until modern times, most nations maintained substantial tariffs or restrictive quotas on a wide array of goods. Accordingly, much of the early work in international economics focused on the wisdom of these conventional instruments of international trade policy. Scholars soon developed the economic case for free trade, which holds that (with some qualifications) nations can increase their national economic welfare through a unilateral reduction in their import restrictions. The logic of this proposition, which involves a demonstration that trade liberalization benefits consumers more than it costs producers or the government treasury, may be found in virtually any international economics textbook. The years since the end of World War II have changed the legal landscape profoundly, with equally important implications for the research agenda. From the Bretton Woods conference of 1944 emerged the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade (GATT), concluded in 1947. Although the central objective of GATT was to foster a reduction in tariffs and quotas, its drafters recognized from the outset that bare commitments to lower tariffs and quotas were but a small part of what would be necessary to an effective trade liberalizing agreement. The restrictive effects of a tariff could easily be recreated by a domestic regulatory measure that disadvantaged imported goods, by a domestic subsidy, by a state-franchised monopsonist with the sole right to import from abroad, by a cumbersome bureaucracy for import processing, or in a number of other ways. The drafters had to plug such ‘loopholes’, and also had to decide whether reductions in trade impediments could be implemented on a discriminatory basis, and whether subgroups within the GATT membership would be allowed to negotiate separate trade agreements. They had to accommodate demands by signatories for the right to address certain ‘unfair’ trade practices unilaterally. They also had to anticipate the possibility of contingencies that might make some terms of the bargain politically unpalatable, and incorporate mechanisms to permit modification of the bargain under appropriate circumstances. Finally, they had to confront the question of how to respond to breach (or alleged breach) of promise by a signatory. As a result of attention to these and other issues, the GATT emerged as a lengthy and elaborate document, with provisions governing not only tariffs and quotas but, inter alia, various domestic taxes and domestic regulatory policies, the conduct of state controlled entities, methods of customs valuation, unfair practices such as dumping and subsidization, rules governing discrimination in trade, procedures for adjusting and renegotiating the bargain, and a dispute settlement mechanism.
1116
International Trade
5910
After 1947, the GATT continued to expand its scope and coverage. In the late 1970s, additional agreements were entered on such matters as technical standards and regulations, subsidies, antidumping, and government procurement. Various regional arrangements also emerged (such as the European Union and the NAFTA) that afforded preferential trade benefits to their members pursuant to an exception to the non-discrimination obligations of GATT allowing for customs unions and free trade areas. These regional arrangements have their own legal foundation, often more complex and far reaching than that of the GATT itself (Jackson, 1989). During the most recent round of negotiations under GATT auspices (the ‘Uruguay Round’), a new institution was created to absorb the GATT and its various side agreements - the World Trade Organization (WTO). The WTO treaty elaborated many prior GATT obligations, added a new dispute resolution system with considerably greater credibility and authority, and for the first time extended the coverage of the GATT system to services industries, such as banking, securities, telecommunications and insurance. This service sector liberalization has proven even more complicated than liberalization in the goods sector due to the mix of licensing, prudential, and other regulations that are in play. The effects of international trade agreements on national regulatory policies has thus become considerably more significant, and will likely continue to grow. Current discussions in the WTO and the OECD further contemplate possible linkages between trade policy on the one hand and competition policy, environmental policy and labor market standards on the other. The WTO already extends its umbrella to the substantive rules of intellectual property law. Nations that are parties to the WTO (over 120 at this writing) or to various regional arrangements must implement their international obligations at the national level. Usually, the implementation process requires a host of domestic statutes or their equivalent, replacing or modifying preexisting domestic law in a number of areas, and creating new domestic law in a number of others. Title 19 of the United States Code, for example, a massive volume, is closely connected to and shaped by the international law of the WTO and NAFTA. For a general introduction to the scope of international and national law in the trade area, the reader may wish to consult Jackson, Davey and Sykes (1995).
3. The Framework for Law and Economics Research Although I have said little about economics to this point, the reader should already appreciate the potential scope of law and economics research in the area. Each of the topics addressed by the WTO agreement, the various regional agreements, and national laws relating thereto raises a range of normative and positive questions. In this section, I sketch a framework for thinking about and
5910
International Trade
1117
identifying these questions in general terms. The succeeding sections delve into the literature on particular topics. Normative Perspectives Much of the research in international economics has a normative cast. Early writers such as Adam Smith and David Ricardo were responding to the misguided Mercantilist instinct that national wealth was measured by the size of the gold reserve rather than the standard of living of the citizenry, urging governments to open their markets. The more modern articulation of the case for free trade grounded in the theory of comparative advantage, with various technical caveats and qualifiers, is also plainly normative in tone, resting either on Kaldor-Hicks conceptions of welfare as a basis for policy making or, in the alternative, the claim that other policy instruments can better address distributive concerns. It is also conventionally argued that trade policy is an inferior policy instrument for addressing various market failures including production externalities, labor market imperfections and the like. Better to tax the pollution output of a domestic polluter directly, for example, than to tax its imported input products - a tax on pollution will correct the externality without distorting the choice of inputs and sacrificing the least cost method of production (see Bhagwati and Srinivasan, 1983; Dixit and Norman, 1980; Kenen, 1985, and Krugman and Obstfeld, 1994). Normative discussion of international trade policy often must distinguish between national welfare and global welfare (or now regional welfare) for many purposes. For example, perhaps the best known caveat to the case for free trade - the opportunity for importing nations with the power to influence their terms of trade (that is, a degree of monopsony power) to use tariffs to extract rents from foreigners - suggests how some nations can increase their own welfare at the expense of global welfare (see Bhagwati and Srinivasan, 1983; Dixit and Norman, 1980). The modern literature on strategic trade policy, which suggests among other things how nations can increase their welfare by subsidizing or protecting certain industries with increasing returns to scale, affords yet another example of the importance of the choice between national and global objective functions (see Krugman, 1987). The same welfare economic framework can be brought to bear on the broader range of topics implicated by modern international trade law. Whether the problem concerns the discipline of national government subsidies that may distort trade, ‘dumping’ by foreign firms (explained below), the question whether nations should discriminate between trading partners in their tariff policies, the consequences of harmonizing regulations for the international marketing of prescription drugs, the procedures for certifying that imported foodstuffs are sanitary, or the wisdom of protecting declining industries to facilitate ‘orderly contraction’ or alleviate unemployment, the normative
1118
International Trade
5910
questions to be asked are much the same. The Kaldor-Hicks benchmark can be used to evaluate the available alternatives. Sometimes, but not always, global and national welfare will point in different directions. One can inquire as to what policy is optimal by the appropriate criterion in the abstract, or ask the related question whether some existing legal rule at the global, regional or national level is optimal from among the set of politically feasible choices. An alternative normative framework rests not on conventional economic measures of welfare, but on democratic legitimacy and international consensus as the underlying value. Here, the question becomes one of how national governments should faithfully implement their international obligations, or perhaps how courts and administrative agencies with discretion should exercise it to promote the international or national goals implicit in the texts of treaties and statutes. Sometimes, though not always, an interpretation of a text intended to provide it with economic coherence may be helpful in this context, much as economic scholars have helped shape the interpretation of laws such as the US Sherman Antitrust Act or sections of the Uniform Commercial Code. Positive Perspectives Although international economists have long described themselves as engaged in positive as well as normative inquiry, the distinction between the two has been muddled for much of the history of the discipline. Part of the muddle owes to the naiveté of much economic writing (particularly older writings), in which governments are ‘assumed’ to maximize national welfare. Normative analysis using the national welfare criterion then becomes positive analysis as well, with the national welfare optimum serving as a predictor of how governments will behave. That predictor has proven a poor one, however, on many fronts. Most obviously, national governments would engage in far less trade protectionism than they do in practice if the economists’ familiar measure of national welfare were the touchstone of policy making. To improve the quality of positive theory, it has been necessary for international economics to embrace the insights of public choice theory. The emergent ‘political economy’ of trade policy recognizes that different interest groups have different degrees of influence on political actors. The weakness of consumer interest groups, for example, can explain why tariffs emerge in the first instance despite their generally adverse impact on national economic welfare (see Baldwin, 1982; Dougan, 1984). Public choice has also proven successful at explaining a number of more narrow policy decisions in the trade field (see Gerber, 1976) such as the politics of partivular qutas, as well as the pattern of votes cast in elections where trade was a key issue (see Irwin, 1994). Public choice insights further help to explain why international agreements such as the GATT tend to liberalize trade despite the absence of much consumer participation - they allow producer groups comprised of exporters to
5910
International Trade
1119
reward their political representatives for securing access to foreign markets (see Baldwin, 1987). This example once again suggests the importance for analysis of the distinction between the national and global perspectives - the interest groups in play (or at least their stakes in the outcome) may change importantly as we move from an environment in which nations act noncooperatively to an environment in which nations act cooperatively. The positive analysis of international agreements also draws on another line of economic analysis - the economics of contracts. An international agreement is, after all, a contract between or among nations. It can be honored or breached, breach can be efficient or inefficient (from the perspective of the self-interested officials who enter the agreement), moral hazards and hold-up opportunities may arise, the agreement may be self enforcing or not, enforcement may rely on reputation, self help, third party coercion, and so forth. Insights from the theory of contracts about how parties design agreements to facilitate valuable adjustments of the bargain while discouraging opportunism thus have much to contribute to the understanding of international agreements generally, and international trade agreements in particular. With this background, I now turn to the literature on particular legal topics. The concluding section contains some thoughts about further research. A compact survey of many of these issues may be found in the recent volume by Trebilcock and Howse (1994). Another useful selection of writings may be found in Bhandari and Sykes (1998).
4. Antidumping Law Aside from the study of conventional tariffs and quotas, perhaps no topic in the law and economics of international trade has a longer history than the study of dumping. The term ‘dumping’ has meant different things through the years, but in modern parlance it refers to pricing behavior by an exporting firm that results in (a) an F.O.B. price to the export market that is below the F.O.B. price to the home market for the same goods; (b) an F.O.B. price to the export market that is below the F.O.B. price to some third market; or (c) an F.O.B. price to the export market that is below the fully allocated cost of production for the good in question (including an allocation of fixed costs, general selling and administrative expenses, and so on). Prior to the formation of GATT, some nations (including the United States) unilaterally condemned dumping and had statutes in place to sanction it. The GATT (now WTO) authorizes such sanctions but constrains them - an importing nation can counteract dumping with an ‘antidumping duty’ equal to the magnitude of dumping (the difference between the export price and the relevant benchmark above), but only if the dumping is causing material injury to a competing domestic industry.
1120
International Trade
5910
The early view of antidumping law in the economics profession was favorable. A distinguished University of Chicago economist, Jacob Viner, devoted an entire volume to dumping, arguing that it is harmful to the importing country. He reasoned that low prices attributable to dumping are transitory, and impose adjustment costs on the importing nation that exceed the benefits of temporarily cheaper imports (Viner, 1923). The basis for Viner’s analysis, however, was shaky. Dumping need not be transitory (as when different markets have different demand elasticities), and even when it is, nothing in Viner’s work (or since) demonstrates that temporarily cheap imports necessarily impose adjustment costs that exceed the welfare gains to the importing country from temporarily cheaper imports. Not surprisingly, therefore, scholars eventually began to question the wisdom of antidumping policy. Various possible justifications in addition to Viner’s have been considered, including the notion that dumping is somehow symptomatic of predatory pricing, and by and large rejected (see Barcelo, 1979; Ordover, Sykes and Willig, 1983; Knoll, 1987; Messerlin, 1990; Therakan, 1990; Cass, 1993). It is also clear that the administration of the antidumping laws often biases the system in favor of a finding of dumping through peculiar accounting and averaging practices (Boltuck and Litan, 1991; McGee, 1993; Dick, 1991). To be sure, an antidumping duty may by chance benefit a nation with the ability to influence its terms of trade. Or it may protect an industry with increasing returns or positive externalities, and thereby yield the sorts of benefits that are the focus of the strategic trade policy literature (see Dick, 1991). But these benefits of antidumping duties have nothing to do with the existence or nonexistence of dumping, only with the special circumstances in which protectionist measures may have utility to the importing nation for other reasons. It is thus fair to say that an academic consensus now holds antidumping law to be welfare-reducing in general. Interestingly, the national welfare effects are often worse than the global welfare effects, because the importing nation is generally harmed, ceteris paribus, when it deprives itself of cheaper imports. From the global perspective, however, if antidumping policy reduces the incidence of imperfect price discrimination, the welfare effects can be favorable (see Ordover, Sykes and Willig, 1983). Cass and Boltuck (1996) also consider various ‘fairness’ justifications for antidumping law, and for the most part reject them. Although the normative analysis of antidumping law is well developed and has probably hit diminishing returns, strikingly little has been done from the positive perspective. If antidumping policy is so foolish, why is it also so survivable, particularly in the WTO environment where nations have mutually agreed to forego economically foolish policies on a number of other fronts?
5910
International Trade
1121
5. Subsidies and Countervailing Measures Attention to the problem of subsidies in international trade, and to the legal regime that constrains them or allows nations to respond to them, also has a rich history in law and economics. Economists have long distrusted government subsidy programs, recognizing that although subsidies may in principle correct certain forms of market failure, they may also cause distortions in resource allocation. The latter concern has become increasingly prevalent with the rise of public choice. In an ideal world, governments would limit subsidies to their constructive uses and eschew unproductive uses. Suppose that this goal is doubly difficult to achieve in a noncooperative environment because governments find themselves in a race to the bottom of sorts (farmers in country A can demand subsidies to level the playing field with the subsidized farmers in country B, for example). Or suppose that subsidies are being used to protect domestic industries against foreign competition, much like tariffs. If so, international trade law might usefully incorporate a covenant to forego certain types of subsidies - indeed, such an evolving covenant has been present in the GATT system since its inception. The question of what an ideal anti-subsidy compact might look like was the focus of Schwartz and Harper (1972). In the end, however, they concluded that the problem was immense and perhaps insoluble, suggesting, among other things, that Kaldor-Hicks efficiency is not easy to identify in practice, and that is hardly clear that the Kaldor-Hicks benchmark is the proper one in any event. Related to the policies imposing multilateral constraints on subsidies are those facilitating a unilateral response to imports of subsidized goods. Subsidized competition is often labeled ‘unfair’, and the GATT system has since its inception permitted signatories to counteract the effects of subsidization at the border through the use of ‘countervailing duties’. These duties may be employed in many instances even when the foreign subsidy practice at issue is perfectly legal under international law. As in the case of antidumping duties, however, countervailing duties are only permitted when subsidized imports are causing injury to competing firms. The wisdom of unilateral countervailing measures has been questioned. Subsidized imports are cheaper than unsubsidized imports, ceteris paribus, and cheaper imports tend to enhance the welfare of the importing nation regardless of the reason for their cheapness. It is by no means clear why an importing nation should not respond to subsidized imports with, in the words of Paul Krugman, ‘a thank-you note to the embassy’. Although Barcelo (1977) viewed unilateral countervailing measures as a useful adjunct to efforts to discipline wasteful government subsidy practices, Schwartz (1978) initiates a more skeptical line of discussion. Sykes (1989) argues that under virtually any
1122
International Trade
5910
assumption about market structure or possible market imperfections, countervailing duties are an imprudent policy from the perspective of the importing country, and dubious as well from the global welfare perspective (see also Trebilcock, 1990). Another strand of literature questions the ability of existing countervailing duty law to achieve its own posited objectives (granting the possibility that those posited objectives may not be welfare enhancing). In particular, if one assumes that the goal of countervailing duty law is to counteract the effects of the subsidy on the prices charged for imported goods, it is essential for those who administer the law to identify that price effect in deciding what duty to impose. Likewise, if countervailing measures are only allowable if a subsidy is causing injury abroad, it is necessary to identify the price effect to decide whether the subsidy is indeed causing material injury. The effect of the subsidy on price will depend, in turn, and inter alia, on how the subsidy affects marginal costs for subsidized firms. Yet, existing law pays little attention to that issue (to see its importance, consider one example - farm programs that pay farmers to reduce acreage will not lower their export prices). Goetz, Granet and Schwartz (1986) made these points, which led Diamond (1989, 1990a) to suggest some specific reforms designed to make countervailing duties a more accurate device for counteracting the cross border effects of subsidies. Sykes (1990a) is critical of these proposals on grounds of administrative cost, coupled with some uncertainty as to whether they will have any welfare payoff. Cass (1990) also has a mixed reaction. As in the case of antidumping law, far less has been done with the positive side of subsidies and countervailing measures than with the normative side. The effects of duties in the presence of downstream integration have been examined (Benson et al., 1994), but the political economy of national and international rules regarding subsidies has received little attention.
6. Injury Analysis in Antidumping and Countervailing Duty Cases As noted, WTO law prohibits antidumping and countervailing duties unless the importing nation first establishes that the unfair imports in question are causing or threatening ‘material injury’ to domestic competitors. The task of determining what impact an unfair practice has on the domestic industry lends itself readily to economic analysis, and much has been written on the subject. Initial work focused on the lack of economic coherence in the analysis of the US International Trade Commission (ITC), the agency charged with administering the injury test under US law. The pertinent statute requires the ITC to determine whether dumped or subsidized imports, as the case may be, have caused or threaten to cause ‘material injury’ to domestic producers of like
5910
International Trade
1123
products. If the task of the ITC is thus to ascertain what effect the dumping or subsidization has had on domestic producers (a proposition that is not uncontroversial as a legal matter), it has often relied on information that is misleading. For example, it has tended to look for a correlation between rising imports and deterioration in the condition of domestic producers, but that correlation may be spurious. It has also emphasized price comparisons between imported and domestic goods, even though price differentials may reflect quality differentials that have nothing to do with the impact of any unfair practice. These and other criticisms have been leveled by a number of writers, most notably Knoll (1989a, 1989b). He and others have suggested that the tools of price theory be employed to construct quantitative models that would allow the ITC more accurately to measure the impact of dumping or subsidies. Proponents of this economic approach include Boltuck and Kaplan (see Therakan, 1990, as well as Rousslang, 1988; see also Morkre and Kelly, 1993). In Wood (1989), the emphasis is rather different - she argues that antidumping and countervailing duties should not be sued to protect supracompetitive rates of return to a domestic industry, and urges that lost monopoly profits not ‘count’ in the injury analysis. Other writers have wondered whether the apparent economic incoherence in the analysis of the ITC has a political economy explanation. Cass and Schwartz (1990) address the issue, and conclude that it probably does not. Sykes (1996) disagrees to an extent, offering some conjectures as to why ITC practice may serve the joint political interests of the United States and its trading partners. He further questions whether a more economic approach to injury analysis would have any welfare benefits. Finally, efforts have been made to ascertain whether injury findings reflect political factors (such as the interests of the constituencies of key Senators and Congressmen), or instead reflect judgments about the ‘merits’ of each case. Finger, Hall and Nelson (1982) hold the former view, while Anderson (1993) concludes that ITC decisions are not well explained by such political variables.
7. Safeguards Measures and the ‘Escape Clause’ Article XIX of the GATT (the ‘escape clause’) permits signatories to withdraw trade concessions temporarily when increased imports cause or threaten to cause ‘serious injury’ to a domestic competing industry. US law further provides that these ‘safeguards measures’ shall not be taken when some cause other than increased imports is a more important source of injury. Several writers have undertaken to give economic content to this inquiry. Grossman (1986) analyzes the causes of injury to the US steel industry in the early 1980s, while Pindyck and Rotemberg (1987) consider the copper industry.
1124
International Trade
5910
In these papers, the authors set forth a framework within which to think about the causal contribution of increased imports to industrial decline (no trivial task since import quantity is usually viewed as an endogenous variable by economists), as well as the causal contribution of other factors such as recession. Kelly (1988, 1989) also addresses these issues. Other writers have inquired into the wisdom of safeguards measures. Lawrence and Litan (1986) find efficiency and fairness arguments unpersuasive as a justification for protecting industries impaired by import competition, although in the end they favor the use of escape clause measures as a ‘safety valve’ against protectionist pressures that might produce an even worse outcome if left unchecked. Trebilcock, Chandler and Howse (1990) are agnostic about the possible utility of temporary protection to facilitate adjustment, although skeptical of government policies in practice. Sykes (1990c) suggests some possible reforms in the injury analysis aimed at limiting relief to plausible cases of labor market imperfections. On the positive side, Sykes (1991) offers a public choice explanation for the existence of GATT Article XIX. He suggests that declining firms will rationally expend greater resources to secure protection than growing firms, and that the escape clause may facilitate the politically ‘efficient breach’ of GATT obligations.
8. The Most-Favored Nation Obligation and Exceptions Article I of the GATT agreement is a general prohibition on discrimination in tariff policy, creating a so-called ‘most-favored nation’ obligation. Article XI creates a similar obligation relating to the use of quotas. But the GATT system also contains a number of exceptions to these obligations. The most important is Article XXIV, which permits the formation of customs unions and free trade areas (such as the European Union and NAFTA) that grant trade preferences to members. Other exceptions include the authority to use discriminatory safeguards measures under certain conditions, and the authority to grant preferences to developing countries. The normative economics of trade discrimination has been studied extensively. Other things being equal, discrimination in protectionist policies (such as the use of different tariffs for different trading partners) produces greater deadweight losses than nondiscriminatory policy. The reason is that discrimination produces ‘trade diversion’ - inefficient investment and production in higher cost countries that benefit from trade preferences. Other things may not be equal, however, because discriminatory trade liberalization may be better than none at all - in the parlance of the profession, ‘trade creation’ can dominate trade diversion (see Lipsey, 1960; Bhagwati and
5910
International Trade
1125
Srinivasan, 1983). Thus, the theoretical view of discrimination is agnostic, and it becomes a difficult empirical question whether a particular discriminatory arrangement is welfare reducing or welfare enhancing. The question is all the more difficult because the answer turns on a counterfactual - what would the world look like without the discrimination in question? The prevailing view seems to be, however, that most of the existing preferential arrangements have tended to be welfare enhancing, and that regional arrangements such as the EU and NAFTA are ‘building blocks’ rather than ‘stumbling blocks’ on the road toward a more open trading system (see Lawrence, 1996). Schwartz and Sykes (1996) examine the GATT rules on trade discrimination from a positive perspective. They argue that nondiscrimination rules tend to maximize political surplus for officials in signatory nations, other things being equal, by increasing the sum of producer surplus and government revenue (both assumed to count heavily in the political welfare functions of politicians). But exceptions exist - for example, the most-favored nation obligation may at times create a free rider problem in bargaining that makes it difficult for nations to exhaust all politically valuable deals. Schwartz and Sykes use these observations to offer an explanation for some of the exceptions to the most-favored nation obligation under GATT, including Article XXIV.
9. Technical Barriers to Trade Recent negotiations under WTO auspices have produced two agreements concerning ‘technical barriers’ to trade, which result from divergent product standards and regulations in the international economy. The agreement on sanitary and phytosanitary measures is aimed at food safety issues and related problems in the agricultural sector. The agreement on technical barriers to trade covers other product markets. These agreements contain their own commitments regarding nondiscrimination, least-restrictive means tests, covenants to rely on international standards where feasible, and many other matters. Sykes (1995) provides a survey of the economic issues involved in the technical barriers area, a review of the different legal approaches to policing technical barriers around the world, and an economic explanation for many of the legal rules that are in place. Leebron (1996) discusses in a general way the case for harmonizing national regulatory policies (see also Davidson et al., 1989).
10. Dispute Settlement, Self Help and Unilateralism International trade agreements have no central enforcement authority with the power to compel nations to adhere to them. It is also exceedingly unlikely that
1126
International Trade
5910
any nation would unilaterally go to war to vindicate its rights under these agreements. Yet, these agreements seem to hold together fairly well, and it is apparent that some mixture of reputational concerns and implicit threats of unilateral retaliation on matters of commercial policy go a long way toward making trade agreements viable. But unilateral ‘retaliation’ in the trade arena may also be opportunistic, and may be employed against nations that have done nothing wrong under international law. This concern has been expressed widely with respect to Section 301 of the 1974 US Trade Act, which permits the United States to retaliate for all manner of ‘unfair’ practices. Many prominent economists have been critical of the ‘aggressive unilateralism’ of the United States under this statute. Bhagwati (1988) is illustrative. Sykes (1990b) takes the other side of the debate, arguing that Section 301 was a potentially sensible ‘self help’ measure in the face of imperfections in the GATT dispute resolution system. Sykes (1992) argues further that Section 301 might play a constructive role in addressing trade impediments outside the coverage of GATT obligations, and that Section 301 had been fairly successful from the US point of view in opening up foreign markets without the need for any retaliatory measures in most cases. New developments in the WTO dispute resolution system moot many of the arguments in this debate, as it can no longer be argued that unilateral action is necessary to create meaningful commercial policy sanctions for breach of promise - the new Dispute Resolution Understanding ensures that WTO-authorized sanctions can be imposed on nations found to be in violation. Likewise, the number of matters still outside the explicit or implicit coverage of the WTO/GATT system has diminished greatly. Perhaps the next step in the economic literature on dispute resolution within trade agreements will be to explain the recent changes in the WTO system, including the details of procedures and sanctions, and in time to assess their efficacy.
11. A Concluding Note on the Research Agenda The expanding scope and detail of international trade law affords law and economics scholars an exceptionally broad range of research opportunities. Although the welfare economics of conventional tariffs and quotas is quite well developed, normatively inclined scholars should find much to occupy them in the treatment of nontariff issues of various sorts. Issues relating to regulatory divergence and harmonization, for example, will be central for many years in both goods and services markets. I suspect that much of the best work will be focused reasonably narrowly on particular problems, from the marketing of prescription medications to the harmonization of telecommunications standards
5910
International Trade
1127
to the opening of insurance and securities markets. Much work also remains to be done on understanding the economic consequences of regional trading arrangements, and on the question of how the WTO ought police their emergence and operation. Opportunities for normative, comparative analysis are also widespread, as the world witnesses a proliferation of sophisticated legal arrangements that must all contend with essentially similar problems. The ‘trade and’ issues that I have neglected in this chapter - trade and the environment, trade and competition policy, and so on - will also afford fruitful subjects for research as the wisdom of harmonizing policies across nations increasingly becomes a subject of topical debate. The opportunities for positive analysis are equally great, if not greater. The political economy of much of the WTO/GATT system remains unexplored, from the provisions on ‘unfair’ trade practices to the treatment of developing countries to the rules for accession, voting, renegotiation and dispute settlement to the sector specific arrangements such as the Agreement on Agriculture. Fundamental questions relating to the expansion and evolution of the GATT system, both in scope and timing, have hardly been posed, let alone answered. The same may be said about the details of regional arrangements - even the most basic questions, such as who joins a regional arrangement, when, and why, remain little touched. In short, much like other subject areas under the rubric of international law, law and economics has only begun to make a dent in the set of potential topics in the trade area. The rapid rate of change in international trade law simply adds to the possibilities for interesting new research. Mainstream economists can, of course, be expected to continue to invest considerable energy in the field, but scholars with legal training as well will retain a comparative advantage in work addressed to many of the concrete positive and normative problems raised by modern legal developments.
Bibliography on International Trade (5910) Anderson, Keith B. (1993), ‘Agency Discretion or Statutory Direction: Decision Making at the U.S. International Trade Commission’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 915-935. Anderson, Terry L. and McChesney, Fred S. (1994), ‘Raid or Trade? An Economic Model of Indian White Relations’, 37 Journal of Law and Economics, 39-74. Baldwin, Robert E. (1982), ‘The Political Economy of Protectionism’, in Bhagwati, Jagdish (ed.), Import Competition and Response, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Baldwin, Robert E. (1987), Trade Policy in a Changing World Economy, Chicago, University of Chicago. Barcelo, John J. (1977), ‘Subsidies and Countervailing Duties - Analysis and Proposal’, 9 Law and Policy in International Business, 779 ff. Barcelo, John J. (1979), ‘The Antidumping Law: Repeal it or Revise it’, in Jackson, John H. (ed.),
1128
International Trade
5910
Antidumping Law: Policy and Implementation, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan. Benson, Bruce L. and Hartigan, James C. (1983), ‘Tariff Restrictions Which Lower Price in the Restricting Country: An Analysis of Spatial Markets’, 14 Journal of International Economics, 117-133. Benson, Bruce L. and Hartigan, James C. (1984), ‘Tariffs and Quotas in a Spatial Duopoly’, 50 Southern Economic Journal, 965-978. Benson, Bruce L. and Hartigan, James C. (1987), ‘Tariffs, and Location Specific Income Redistribution’, 17 Regional Science and Urban Economics, 223-243. Benson, Bruce L., Faminow, Merle D., Marquis, Milton H. and Sauer, Douglas G. (1994), ‘Intra-National Effects of a Countervailing Duty on the U.S./Canadian Hog Market’, 16 Review of Agricultural Economics, 187-201. Bermann, George A. (1993), ‘Regulatory Cooperation with Counterpart Agencies Abroad: The FAA’s Aircraft Certification Experience’, 24 Law and Policy in International Buiness, 669-781. Bhagwati, Jagdish N. (1988), Protectionism, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Bhagwati, Jagdish N. and Hudec, Robert E. (1996), Fair Trade and Harmonization: Prerequisites to Free Trade?, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Bhagwati, Jagdish N. and Srinivasan, T.N. (1983), Lectures in International Trade, Cambridge, MIT Press. Bhandari, J.S. and Sykes, Alan O. (1998), Economic Dimensions in International Law, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Boltuck, Richard and Litan, Robert E. (1991), Down in the Dumps: Administration of Unfair Trade Laws, Washington, Brookings. Cass, Ronald A. (1990), ‘Trade Subsidy Law: Can a Foolish Inconsistency be Good Enough for Government Work?’, 21 Law and Policy in International Business, 609-661. Cass, Ronald A. (1993), ‘Price Administration and Predation Analysis in Antitrust and International Trade: A Comment’, 61 University of Cincinnati Law Review, 877 ff. Cass, Ronald A. and Boltuck, Richard D. (1996), ‘Antidumping and Countervailing Duty Law: The Mirage of Equitable International Competition’, in Bhagwati, Jagdish and Hudec, Robert E. (eds), Fair Trade and Harmonization: Prerequisites to Free Trade?, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Cass, Ronald A. and Schwartz, Warren F. (1990), ‘Coherence and Transparency in the Implementation of International Trade Laws’, in Trebilcock, Michael J. and York, Robert C. (eds), Fair Exchange: Reforming Trade Remedy Laws, Toronto, C.D. Howe Institute. Centner, Terence J. (1993), ‘The U.S.’s Organic Foods Production Act: Does the Small-Farmer Exception Breach the U.S.’s Obligations Under GATT?’, 28 Tulsa Law Journal, 715-722. Centner, Terence J. (1995), ‘Organically-Produced Food Products: Regulations from the European Union and the United States Set the Stage for Imports’, 7 Journal of International Food and Agribusiness Marketing, 41-58. Centner, Terence J. and Lathrop, K.W. (1996), ‘Differentiating Food Products: Organic Labeling Provisions Facilitate Consumer Choice’, 1 Drake Agricultural Law Review, 30-50. Cohen, Mark A. and Rubin, Paul H. (1992), ‘Politically Imposed Entry Barriers’, 18 Eastern Economic Journal, 333-344.
5910
International Trade
1129
Crocker, Keith J. and Lyon, Thomas P. (1994), ‘What do Facilitating Practices Facilitate? An Empirical Investigation of Most Favored Nation Clauses in Natural Gas Contracts’, 37 Journal of Law and Economics, 297-322. Davidson, Russell et al. (1989), ‘On the Welfare Effects of Anti-discrimination Regulations in the EC Car Market’, 7 International Journal of Industrial Organization, 205-230. Diamond, Richard (1989), ‘Economic Foundations of Countervailing Duty Law’, 29 Virginia Journal of International Law, 767 ff. Diamond, Richard (1990a), ‘A Search for Economic and Financial Principles in the Administration of United States Countervailing Duty Law’, 21 Law and Policy in International Business, 507-607. Diamond, Richard (1990b), ‘Changes in the Game: Understanding the Relationship between Section 301 and US Trade Strategies’, 8 Boston University International Law Journal, 351-361. Dick, Andrew (1991), ‘Learning by Doing and Dumping in the Semiconductor Industry’, 34 Journal of Law and Economics, 133-159. Dixit, Avanish K. and Norman, Victor D. (1980), Theory of International Trade, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Dougan, William R. (1984), ‘Tariffs and the Economic Theory of Regulation’, 6 Research in Law and Economics, 187-210. Espinosa, M.P. and Macho-Stadler, I. (1989), ‘Coordinación de Política Industrial en el Marco de la CEE (Industrial Policy Coordination in the EEC)’, 2 De Economía Pública, 61-77. Farran, Andrew (1986), ‘The Interplay of Law and Economics in International Trade Regulation’, in Snape, R.H. (ed.), Issues in World Trade Policy: GATT at the Crossroads. Papers presented at a confernce of the Centre of Policy Studies, Monash University, Australia, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 193-217. Finger, J. Michael, Hall, H. Keith and Nelson, Douglas R. (1982), ‘The Political Economy of Administered Protection’, 72 American Economic Review. Frey, Bruno S. (1988), ‘Regulations by Consensus: The Practice of International Investment Agreements: Comment’, 144 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 176-179. Garcimartin, Alférez and Francisco, Javier (1995), ‘El Régimen Normativo de las Transacciones Privadas Internacionales: una Aproximación Económica (The Regulation of International Private Transactions: an Economic Approach)’, 2 Revista Española de Derecho Internacional, 99-111. Garcimartin, Alférez and Francisco, Javier (1996), ‘El Coste de la ley Helms-Burton para las Empresas Españolas (The Costs of Helms-Burton Rule for Spanish Companies)’, Revista Derecho de los Negocios. Gerber, David J. (1976), ‘The United States Sugar Quota Program: A Study in the Direct Congressional Control of Imports’, 19 Journal of Law and Economics, 103-147. Godek, Paul E. (1985), ‘Industry Structure and Redistribution through Trade Restrictions’, 28 Journal of Law and Economics, 687-703. Goetz, Charles, Granet, Lloyd and Schwartz, Warren (1986), A Search for Economic and Financial Principles in the Administration of U.S. Countervailing Duty Law, 6 International Review of Law and Economics 17 ff. Grossman, Eugene (1986), ‘Imports as a Cause of Injury: The Case of the US Steel Industry’, 16 Journal of Industrial Economics.
1130
International Trade
5910
Haucap, Justus and Wey, Christian (1997), ‘Location Choice as a Signal of Product Quality: The Economics of “Made in Germany”’, 153 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics. Heywood, John S. (1991), ‘Imports and Domestic Wages: Is the Relationship Consistent with Expense Preference Behavior?’, 7 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 355-372. Inman, Robert P. and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1994), ‘The EMU and Fiscal Policy in the New European Community: An Issue for Economic Federalism’,14 International Review of Law and Economics, 147-161. Irwin, Douglas A. (1994), ‘The Political Economy of Free Trade: Voting in the British General Election of 1906', 37 Journal of Law and Economics, 75-108. Jackson, John H. (1989), The World Trading System, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Jackson, John H., Davey, William J. and Sykes, Alan O. (1995), Legal Problems of International Economic Relations (3rd edn), Minneapolis, West Publishing. Kalt, Joseph P. (1989), ‘Exhaustible Resource Price Policy, International Trade, and Intertemporal Welfare’, 17 Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 109-126. Kalt, Joseph P. (1991), ‘Using the Gas Industry as a Guide to Reconstituting the Electricity Industry: Comment’, 13 Research in Law and Economics, 57-61. Kelly, Kenneth (1988), ‘The Analysis of Causality in Escape Clause Cases’, Journal of Industrial Economics. Kelly, Kenneth (1989), ‘Can Imports Injure a Domestic Industry When They Decline?’, 12 Research in Law and Economics, 119-129. Kenen, Peter (1985), The International Economy, Englewood Cliffs, NJ, Prentice Hall. Knoll, Michael S. (1987), ‘United States Antidumping Law: The Case for Reconsideration’, 22 Texas International Law Journal, 265 ff. Knoll, Michael S. (1989a), ‘Legal and Economic Framework for the Analysis of Injury by the U.S. International Trade Commission’, 23 Journal of World Trade, 95-107. Knoll, Michael S. (1989b), ‘An Economic Approach to the Determination of Injury Under United States Antidumping and Countervailing Duty Law’, 22 New York University Journal of International Law and Politics, 37 ff. Kornhauser, Lewis A. and Benoit, J.-P. (1992), ‘Unsafe Havens’, 59 University of Chicago Law Review, 1421 ff. Krauss, Melvyn B. (1978), The New Protectionism. The Welfare State and International Trade, New York, New York University Press, 179 p. Krugman, Paul R. (1987), ‘Is Free Trade Passe?’, 1 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 131 ff. Krugman, Paul R. and Obstfeld, Maurice (1994), International Economics: Theory and Policy (3rd edn), Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Lawrence, Robert (1996), Regionalism, Multilateralsim and Deeper Integration, Washington, Brookings. Lawrence, Robert and Litan Robert (1986), Saving Free Trade, Washington, Brookings. Leebron, David W. (1996), ‘Lying Down with Procrustes: An Analysis of Harmonization Claims’, in Bhagwati, Jagdish and Hudec, Robert E. (eds), Fair Trade and Harmonization: Prerequisites for Free Trade?, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Lipsey, Richard (1960), ‘The Theory of Customs Unions: A General Survey’, 70 Economic Journal, 496 ff.
5910
International Trade
1131
McGee, Robert W. (1993), ‘An Economic Analysis of Protectionism in the US With Implications for International Trade in Europe’, 26 George Washington Journal of International Law and Economics, 539-573. McGee, Robert W. (1994), A Trade Policy for Free Societies: The Case Against Protectionism, Westport, Quorum Books, 197 p. Messerlin, Patrick A. (1990), ‘The Antidumping Regulations of the European Community: The Privatisation of Administered Protectection’, in Trebilcock, Michael J. and York, Robert C. (eds), Fair Exchange: Reforming Trade Remedy Laws, Toronto, C.D. Howe Institute. Mock, William B.T. (1992), ‘Game Theory Signaling and International Legal Relations’, 25 George Washington Journal of International Law and Economics, 33-66. Morkre, Morris E. and Kelly, Kenneth (1993), ‘Perspectives on the Effects of Unfair Imports of Domestic Industries’, 61 University of Cincinnati Law Review, 919 ff. Navarro, Peter (1989), ‘Creating and Destroying Comparative Advantage: The Role of Regulation in International Trade’, 13 Journal of Comparative Economics, 205-226. Niskanen, William A. (1988), ‘U.S. Trade Policy’, 12 Regulation, 34-42. Ordover, Janusz, Sykes, Alan and Willig Robert (1983), ‘International Trade Practices’, 15 New York University Journal of International Law and Politcs. Phegan, Colin (1986), ‘The Interplay of Law and Economics in International Trade Regulation: Comment’, in Snape, R.H. (ed.), Issues in World Trade Policy: GATT at the Crossroads. Papers presented at a Conference of the Centre of Policy Studies, Monash University, Australia, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 218-221. Pindyck, Robert S. and Rotemberg, Julio J. (1987), ‘Are Imports to Blame? Attribution of Injury under the 1974 Trade Act’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 101-122. Rousslang, Donald J. (1988), ‘Import Injury in U.S. Trade Law: An Economic View’, 8 International Review of Law and Economics, 117-122. Schanze, Erich (1986), Investitionsverträge im Internationalen Wirtschaftsrecht (Investment Contracts in International Economic), Frankfurt, Metzner, 305 p. Schanze, Erich (1986), ‘Untemehmensrechtliche Koordination von Staat und Wirtschaft bei internationalen Gro Projekten in Entwicklungsländern (Corporate Coordination of State and Economy Concerning Project Investment in Developing Countries)’, 6 Jahrbuch für Neue Politische Ökonomie, 269-287. Schwartz, Warren F. and Harper, Eugene W. (1972), ‘The Regulation of Subsidies Affecting International Trade’, 70 Michigan Law Review, 831 ff. Schwartz, Warren F. (1978), Zenith Radio Corp. vs. United States: Countervailing Duties and the Regulation of International Trade, 1978 Supreme Court Review 297. Schwartz, Warren F. and Sykes, Alan O. (1996), ‘Toward a Positive Theory of the Most Favored Nation Obligation and its Exceptions in the WTO/GATT System’, 16 International Review of Law and Economics, 27-52. Solomon, Lewis D. and Dicker, Howard B. (1988), ‘The Crash of 1987: A Legal and Public Policy Analysis’, 57 Fordham Law Review, 191 ff. Spier, Kathryn E. and Weinsteinn, David E. (1995), ‘Retaliatory Mechanisms for Eliminating Trade Barriers: Aggressive Unilateralism vs GATT Cooperation’, in Chang, Winston W. and Katayama, Seiichi (eds), Imperfect Competition in International Trade, Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers. Sykes, Alan O. (1989), ‘Countervailing Duty Law: An Economic Perspective’, 89 Colombia Law Review, 199-263.
1132
International Trade
5910
Sykes, Alan O. (1990a), ‘“Mandatory” Retaliation for Breach of Trade Agreements: Some Thoughts on the Strategic Design of Section 301’, 8 Boston University International Law Journal, 301-324. Sykes, Alan O. (1990b), ‘Second Best Countervailing Duty Policy: A Critique of the Entitlement Approach’, 21 Law and Policy in International Business, 699-721. Sykes, Alan O. (1990c), ‘GATT Safeguards Reform: The Injury Test’, in Trebilcock, Michael J. and York, Robert C. (eds), Fair Exchange: Reforming Trade Remedy Laws, Toronto, C.D. Howe Institute. Sykes, Alan O. (1991), ‘Protectionism as a ‘Safeguard’: A Positive Analysis of the GATT ‘Escape Clause’ with Normative Speculations’, 58 University of Chicago Law Review, 255-305. Sykes, Alan O. (1992), ‘Constructive Unilateral Threats in International Commercial Relations: The Limited Case for Section 301', 23 Law and Policy in International Business, 263-330. Sykes, Alan O. (1995), Product Standards for the Internationally Integrated Goods Markets, Washington, Brookings. Sykes, Alan O. (1996), ‘The Economics of Injury in Antidumping and Countervailing Duty Cases’, 16 International Review of Law and Economics, 5-26. Therakan, P.K.M. (1990), Policy Implications of Antidumping Measures, Amsterdam, North Holland. Thygesen, Niels (1994), ‘Why is Economic and Monetary Union an Important Objective for Europe?’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 133-145. Trebilcock, Michael J. (1990), ‘Throwing Deep: Trade Remedy Laws in a First-Best World’, in Trebilcock, Michael J. and York, Robert C. (eds), Fair Exchange: Reforming Trade Remedy Laws, Toronto, C.D. Howe Institute. Trebilcock, Michael J. and Howse, Robert (1994), The Regulation of International Trade, New York, Routledge. Trebilcock, Michael J., Chandler, Marsha and Howse, Robert (1990), Trade and Transitions, London, Routledge. Viner, Jacob (1923), Dumping: A Problem in International Trade, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Vousden, Neil (1990), The Economics of Trade Protection, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 305 p. Wils, Wouter P.J. (1993), ‘The Search for the Rule in Article 30 EEC: Much Ado About Nothing?’, 18 European Law Review, 475-492. Wils, Wouter P.J. (1994), ‘Subsidiarity and EC Environmental Policy: Taking People’s Concerns Seriously’, 6 Journal of Environmental Law, 81-91. Wood, Diane P. (1989), ‘’Unfair’ Trade Injury: A Competition Based Approach’, 41 Stanford Law Review, 1153 ff.
5920 LAND AND LIVESTOCK CONTRACTING IN AGRICULTURE: A PRINCIPAL-AGENT PERSPECTIVE Charles R. Knoeber Professor, North Carolina State University © Copyright 1999 Charles R. Knoeber
Abstract The seemingly disparate literatures on land tenancy and on the contract production of livestock actually have much in common. Here, they are examined together within a simple principal-agent framework. The core of this framework and a central issue in much writing on these agricultural contracts is the trade-off between smaller risk-bearing costs and better incentives for farmer effort, for the revelation of information and for innovation. The relative importance of risk and incentive in explaining the design and use of land tenancy and livestock production contracts remains a key topic for research. JEL classification: L14, Q12, Q15 Keywords: Land, Livestock, Contracts, Agriculture
1. Introduction Contractual arrangements in agriculture have attracted research interest along several different lines. One primary focus is land tenancy. The causes and consequences of sharecropping, land rental, and owner-operator farming inform a long, active, and widely-known stream of research (surveys include Newberry and Stiglitz, 1979; Binswanger and Rosenzweig, 1984; Otsuka and Hayami, 1989; Singh, 1989; and Otsuka, Hiroyuki and Hayami, 1992). A second important focus is more recent and less widely-known, arising out of the changing organization of livestock production in the United States (Shelden, 1996 provides an overview). Traditionally, livestock producers have bred and raised animals for sale in auction markets. Beginning with broiler chickens in the 1950s, followed by turkeys, and now spreading to swine, a new form of contract production has come to dominate (see Knoeber, 1989 and Menard, 1996 for a description of broilers; and Martin, 1994 for swine). Increasingly, ‘growers’ raise animals under contract for large ‘integrator’ firms. Under this new arrangement, an integrator firm provides young animals (chicks, poults, feeder pigs), feed, medicine and 1133
1134
Land and Livestock Contracting in Agriculture
5920
advice to contract growers. Growers provide housing, utilities, labor and management. Animals are kept by growers until maturity, but are owned by the integrator firm. At maturity, animals are collected by the integrator and transported to slaughter and processing plants. For broilers and turkeys, the breeding of chicks (poults), mixing of feed, and slaughtering and processing are all typically done by the integrator firm. For swine, integrators mix feed but only sometimes breed pigs and only rarely operate packing plants. These contracts share some features with contracts that have been used for several decades to organize the production of fruits and vegetables for processing (see Reimund, Martin and Moore, 1981; Knoeber, 1983). Reasons for the advent of contract production and the nature of its effects are important emerging research topics. The issues in land tenancy and in contract production are similar. Examining these two related research streams is the purpose of this survey. A simple principal-agent framework is used to organize the discussion, and the primary focus is choice of contract form. This approach narrows the range of issues discussed. An abstract setting in which a single principal contracts with a single agent and in which only the agent’s actions are of concern provides the background for much of the survey. Attention is paid to situations where a single principal contracts with multiple agents, but the possibility that the actions of the principal (as well as those of the agent) matter is generally ignored (Reid, 1977; Eswaran and Kotwal, 1985; Allen and Lueck, 1993; Battacharyya and Lafontaine, 1995 all examine this double moral hazard case). Collective contracts which unite farmers into cooperatives are also ignored. Finally, the effects that varying institutions (largely governmental) have on contract choice receive scant attention. This is appropriate for the discussion of livestock contracting which is largely restricted to activity in the United States, but is a defect in the discussion of land contracting which, while emphasizing the United States experience, is intended to be substantially broader.
2. Framework 2.1 Overview All contracts are formed because the parties involved expect to benefit. In the agricultural context, a focus is often the source of these benefits. One strain of literature emphasizes the stochastic nature of prices and production outcomes facing farmers and views contracts as a vehicle to shift (or share) risk. In this strain, the important benefit of contract production and marketing, as well as sharecropping or other land tenure arrangements, is the reduction in risk-bearing costs. Another strain emphasizes efficiencies in the organization of production. Here, the important benefit of contracts is
5920
Land and Livestock Contracting in Agriculture
1135
the reduction of transaction and production costs afforded by specialization and the incentives that contracts provide for effort, revelation of information, and innovation. The literature emphasizing the benefits from shifting risk presumes impediments to trading risks directly, as in insurance markets, which limit risk-shifting opportunities for participants in agriculture. Agricultural contracting offers a second-best technique to reallocate the risks of farming and processing. In this literature, the effects of contract design on behavior, except those that follow directly from changing the riskiness of producer or buyer profit functions, are often ignored. But shifting the risk of production outcomes to others also reduces the incentive to achieve better outcomes, since (part of) the gain to better outcomes inures to others. Indeed, if all risk is shifted, as when a farmer is simply paid a wage unrelated to his effort, the farmer is left with no incentive to work hard or to make good, but difficult, decisions. The reason is that the costs of such actions are borne by the farmer and all gains go to the employer. Where these incentive effects are recognized, they are treated as a cost which limits the extent to which agricultural contracts can be used to shift risk. The literature emphasizing production efficiencies takes the opposite approach. Here, agricultural contracts are often analyzed presuming risk neutrality, explicitly ignoring any risk-bearing effects that they may have. The focus is how contract design affects the incentives of farmers (and processors) and so ultimately the costs of production. Where risk is considered, it is treated as a cost of providing better incentives. For example, tying a farmer’s income more closely to production outcomes provides incentive to improve these production outcomes but also forces him to bear more risk. Here, the farmer’s aversion to risk limits the extent to which incentives can be improved. While these two strains of literature differ in emphasis, they overlap in their attention to the trade-off between the reduction in the costs of risk bearing and the provision of better incentives. This trade-off is the core of the principal-agent problem and provides a useful framework from which to view the literature on agricultural contracting. 2.2 Principal-Agent Formulation Consider a farmer (agent) acting for a landlord (principal). The farmer provides an input, effort, that contributes to output. Denote effort as a and output as X, where X(a) and X' > 0. The farmer’s income, I, depends upon the contract that he faces and in general form is written I = αX + ßa + δ, where α and ß are rewards to greater output and effort respectively. Here, the farmer’s income depends upon output, his effort, and the parameter, δ, which is a fixed payment and can be thought of as a non-contingent wage. If
1136
Land and Livestock Contracting in Agriculture
5920
both α = 0 and ß = 0, the farmer’s income is unrelated to his behavior and so he has no incentive to provide effort. To induce effort, the contract can provide either α > 0, ß > 0 or both. If α = 0 and ß > 0, the farmer is rewarded on the basis of his effort only. This is an incentive wage payment. If α > 0 and ß = 0, the farmer is rewarded on the basis of his output only. This is a cropshare or piece rate payment. If α = 1, ß = 0, and δ < 0, the farmer receives all output and has a negative fixed payment. This is a land rental contract. Why might one form of contract be preferred to others? If providing incentive to the farmer is all that matters, any level of effort can be induced using a positive α, a positive ß, or a combination of the two. None seems to have an advantage over others. Differences arise when the costs of using X or a to reward the farmer are considered. These costs take two forms. One is risk-bearing cost; the other is monitoring cost. Monitoring costs arise because it is necessary to measure. If the farmer’s reward is based on output, X must be measured. If the farmer’s reward is based on effort (input), a must be measured. In many circumstances, monitoring costs will be less when reward is based on output for two reasons. First, the physical nature of output often allows easier measurement. This will be the case where output is less subject to variation in quality and has fewer dimensions than effort. Second, it will typically be true that output must be measured for purposes of sale whether or not it is the basis for farmer reward. If so, and if no additional measurement is necessary to reward the farmer (additional measurement would be required if, for example, the crop was not of uniform quality and the farmer’s reward was a portion of the crop itself), the relevant monitoring cost is zero when output is used as the basis for farmer payment. The high cost of measuring effort also makes it likely that an imperfect measure will be used. So, measuring effort likely will be both more costly than measuring output and less precise. The degree of imprecision depends upon the cost of refining measurement. As a consequence, we can think (roughly) of the choice of how to reward a farmer as that between a precise measure of output, X and an imprecise estimator of effort, â. Since â is an estimator of a, it measures effort with error. Importantly, this introduces risk into the farmer’s reward. Using â as the basis for rewarding a farmer, then, entails two disadvantages relative to using X. Measurement costs are greater and the farmer is forced to bear the risk of errors in the measure of his effort. For this, a risk-averse farmer must be compensated. It seems that rewards based on output will provide incentive more cheaply than rewards based on effort. But, so far, the important cost of reward based on output has been ignored. Output, while increasing in effort, has a large random component. Weather, pest infestations, and many other exogenous forces have marked effects on X. Rewards based on output may be quite risky, and bearing this
5920
Land and Livestock Contracting in Agriculture
1137
risk is costly. The relative cost of rewards based on output depends upon the size of these risk-bearing costs (costs of measuring output are presumed to be zero) compared to the sum of monitoring costs and smaller risk-bearing costs associated with rewards based upon an estimator of effort, â. To see how this affects the form of contract used, consider several extreme cases. First, if the farmer is risk neutral (so, risk-bearing costs are zero) and measuring effort is costly, incentive can be provided most cheaply by rewards based on X. A land rent contract with α = 1, ß = 0, and δ < 0 seems optimal. Second, if the farmer is risk averse and monitoring costs are zero (effort can be measured without error at no cost), incentive can be provided most cheaply by rewards based on effort. An incentive wage contract with α = 0 and ß > 0 seems optimal. Third, if the farmer is risk neutral and monitoring costs are zero, a land rent contract, an incentive wage contract, and combinations of cropshare and incentive wage contracts (where 0 < α < 1 and ß > 0) all work equally well. Finally, the most interesting case is that where the farmer is risk averse (so risk costs matter) and monitoring costs are positive. Here, there is a trade-off. Effort can be maintained by increasing α and decreasing ß or the reverse. Optimality requires raising α until the additional risk-bearing costs just offset the savings in monitoring costs from the corresponding reduction in ß. Models focusing on this trade-off between incentive and risk costs include Stiglitz (1974) and Warr (1978).
3. Risk Shifting as the Motivation for Contracts 3.1 Sharecropping Drawing especially on early work by Johnson (1950), Cheung (1968, 1969) characterizes sharecropping as motivated by gains from risk shifting. Johnson notes that an exogenously imposed sharecropping contract (0 < α < 1 and ß = 0) provides too little incentive for the farmer to provide effort since he receives only a fraction (α) of the gain and incurs all of the cost, but Johnson also argues that competition works to eliminate insufficient effort. Landlord and tenant will contract not only over the share of output each receives but also over the required effort of the tenant. If effort is insufficient, the lease will not be renewed. Essentially, a is assumed to be easily observable (monitoring cost is zero), so a minimum level of a can be written into the contract. Recently, Banerji and Rashid (1996) have argued that tournaments in which a tenant farmer’s output is compared to that of other tenants provide one mechanism for the landlord to deduce the farmer’s effort. With effort observable, competition forces the farmer to provide the contractual minimum. Cheung (1968) extends Johnson’s argument by explicitly assuming that transaction costs are zero. With this assumption,
1138
Land and Livestock Contracting in Agriculture
5920
any contract (cropshare, lease, wage) provides appropriate incentive for effort. Cheung argues that sharecropping is used because it provides for risk sharing. Apland, Barnes and Justice (1984) and Petersson and Andersson (1996) adopt this framework and, ignoring any incentive effects, attempt to estimate the risk-sharing benefits from cropshare contracts for sample farms in the United States and Sweden respectively. A difficulty with Cheung’s argument, however, is that sharecropping is not universal. If sharecropping is equivalent to other contracts in incentive and superior in risk sharing, why are other contracts also used? Cheung’s (1969) answer is that transaction (monitoring and contracting) costs are not always zero. This allows a trade-off between risk sharing and incentive, a trade-off that may be unfavorable to cropshare contracts. Stiglitz (1974) and Newberry (1977) also treat risk sharing as the motivation for cropshare contracts and develop conditions under which these contracts provide efficient incentives. In addition, both authors along with Reid (1976) show that where monitoring is costless and risk enters through stochastic output, sharecropping is unnecessary to shift risk. A mixture of rental and wage contracts can duplicate the risk shifting effected by a cropshare contract. These results and a general unwillingness to accept that monitoring costs are zero, has led to substantial criticism of risk sharing as the primary motivation for sharecropping (see especially Jaynes, 1984). In an interesting twist, Reid (1973, 1976) argues that risk considerations motivate sharecropping, but through risk reduction not risk sharing. Cropshare contracts provide superior incentives to adapt to post contractual changes in the environment and so to dampen the effect of nature on output, reducing risk itself. 3.2 Livestock Contracts Even more so than cropshare contracts, livestock production contracts are viewed as motivated by risk sharing. Kliebenstein and Lawrence (1995, p. 1215) state that ‘the primary reason (that growers enter swine production contracts) is risk reduction’. Similarly, Johnson and Foster (1994) ignore any incentive effects and evaluate the desirability of swine production contracts to growers in terms of the risks that growers must bear. Knoeber and Thurman (1995), while not arguing that risk sharing necessarily motivates contracting in broilers, estimate the extent of risk shifting afforded by contract production. This is substantial. Martin (1994) makes similar estimates for swine production. But here, the extent of risk shifting is not as pronounced. Although livestock production contracts do provide considerable risk shifting, and although observers and participants claim that this is the most important motivation for such contracts, no studies have tested for a link between risk and the incidence of such contracts. A number of tests have
5920
Land and Livestock Contracting in Agriculture
1139
been conducted for cropshare contracts. If risk shifting is important, cropshare contracts should be observed where yields are most uncertain. Higgs (1973) finds weak evidence consistent with this implication for corn and cotton in the early twentieth century in the southern United States. Rao (1971) finds opposing evidence for Indian farms. More recently, Allen and Lueck (1992b, 1996), for farms, and Leffler and Rucker (1991), for timberland, find no relation between risk and the nature of contracts chosen.
4. Incentive as the Motivation for Contracts 4.1 Sharecropping Focusing on Cheung’s (1969) assertion that transactions costs (monitoring and contracting costs) are important in explaining the incidence of contracts, another stream of literature emphasizes incentives to explain sharecropping. Higgs (1974), Alston and Higgs (1982) and Alston, Datta and Nugent (1984), while not denying the potential importance of risk sharing, argue that differences in supervision costs (costs of measuring a) help explain variation in the extent of sharecropping for crops that have similar yield variability. Where it is more costly to measure a, sharecropping, or basing farmer rewards on X, becomes more likely. All three papers find evidence consistent with this prediction using historical data for the southern United States. Evidence for India is presented in Datta, O’Hara and Nugent (1986). Bell and Zusman (1976) and Stiglitz (1988) also emphasize difficulties in monitoring farmer effort as a rationale for sharecropping. Where measuring effort is expensive (so minimum a cannot be fixed by contract), a share contract, with " > 0, provides incentive but only by imposing risk on the farmer. Trading off the loss from too little incentive against that from too great risk bearing defines the optimal share contract. If capital as well as labor is allowed as an argument in the production function, and if these inputs are complementary, introducing a link to credit into a cropshare contract may be desirable. Providing subsidized credit to a sharecropper will induce greater use of capital and so greater labor productivity and hence more effort (this may not be true if tenants also work off the farm; see Subramanian, 1995). So, the common occurrence of interlinked credit and cropshare contracts may have its origin in the difficulty of providing incentives for effort (see Braverman and Stiglitz, 1982, 1986; Mitra, 1983). Murrell (1983), Eswaran and Kotwal (1985), and Chew (1991) all ignore risk costs and focus on contracting costs to explain sharecropping, but the strongest statement of the primacy of incentives (the irrelevancy of risk sharing) is in Allen and Lueck (1992b, 1993, 1995, 1996). Assuming risk neutrality, they construct a framework in which measurement and
1140
Land and Livestock Contracting in Agriculture
5920
enforcement costs dictate the form of contract chosen. They use this framework to explain both the choice between cropshare contracts and others and the choice of input and output shares when cropshare contracts are used. Using data for farms in Nebraska and South Dakota, they provide evidence that is consistent with the importance of these measurement costs and the unimportance of risk-bearing costs in explaining contract choice. 4.2 Livestock Contracts The literature on livestock contracts never ignores risk but only sometimes treats risk sharing as an end in itself. Shelden (1996) adopts a principal-agent framework to characterize contracts as providing incentive for effort by rewarding growers on the basis of output, X, but at the cost of imposing risk on growers. Knoeber (1989) also treats incentive as primary, but argues that the design of broiler production contracts can be explained partly as intended to provide this incentive while minimizing the risk borne by growers. Reducing the risk cost of providing incentive allows for higher powered incentives. An interesting feature of broiler production contracts is that growers are rewarded based upon relative performance where performance is measured largely by feed conversion, the effectiveness with which feed is used to produce meat (effort, or a, is not measured). A grower’s pay rises as his performance improves, not absolutely but relative to the performance of other growers. This scheme, which is like a tournament, shifts risks which are common to all growers (weather, feed mix, chick genetics) to the integrator company (on relative performance payments, see Lazear and Rosen, 1981 and Holmström, 1982). Common shocks, like bad weather, reduce all growers’ absolute performance but leave each grower’s payment unchanged if relative performance is unaffected. For example, a contract that rewards a grower based upon his output relative to the average of other growers, uses Xi - ' X/n to measure grower i’s performance. If bad weather affects each grower identically, each grower’s X will move in lock-step, leaving grower i’s relative performance unchanged. Where substantial variation in absolute performance is common to all growers, contracts such as those used in the broiler industry can provide incentive to growers with less risk-bearing cost than contracts rewarding absolute performance. Knoeber and Thurman (1994) test a number of hypotheses arising out of the theory of tournaments using broiler production data. In addition to incentive for effort, livestock production contracts may be designed to alleviate another incentive problem. This is the hold-up problem discussed by Klein, Crawford and Alchian (1978). When production requires investing in an asset that is specialized to a particular trading partner, any deal made prior to investing in the specialized asset may not be enforceable once the investment is made. The non-investing party has an
5920
Land and Livestock Contracting in Agriculture
1141
incentive to use his newly created bargaining power (the cost of the specialized asset cannot be recouped elsewhere) by demanding more favorable terms. Production contracts that require both parties to invest in assets specialized to the other (or an exchange of hostages as described by Williamson, 1983), as is the case where growers invest in animal houses and integrators invest in breeding facilities, feed mills, and processing plants, help to alleviate the hold-up problem. This role for livestock production contracts is emphasized by Knoeber (1989), Frank and Henderson (1992), Barry, Sonka and Lajili (1992) and Sporleader (1992).
5. Selection as a Motivation for Contracts Even with no concern for risk or farmer effort, asymmetric information may motivate the design of contracts. Where farmers differ in ability, it may be important to choose farmers to match productive circumstances. For example, for climates and crops where adaptability (decision making) is crucial, more able farmers are desired. Where rote response is sufficient, less able farmers are suitable. If only farmers know their own ability and if farmers are heterogeneous, the design of contracts may act to induce farmers to self-select into appropriate matches. Hallagan (1978) explains the simultaneous use of wage, share and rental contracts as a response to this selection problem where entrepreneurial ability is important. Where low entrepreneurial ability is sufficient, landowners will offer (low) wage contracts. Where high ability is necessary, landowners will offer (high) land rental contracts. Where intermediate ability is appropriate, share contracts will be offered. Those with the highest entrepreneurial ability will be willing to accept only the rental contract; those with the least ability will be willing to accept only the wage contract; and those with intermediate ability will be willing to accept only the cropshare contract. A similar argument, but viewing ability more generally, is developed by Newberry and Stiglitz (1979). Brown and Atkinson (1981) provide a test of this selection hypothesis by examining cropshare contracts in Indiana. They argue that where entrepreneurial ability is more important, the farmer’s share will be greater (this is closer to a rental contract), and test by examining the scope of farmer decision making across contracts with varying farmer shares. They find evidence that as the scope of decision making increases (ability becomes more important), farmer shares increase as well, consistent with the selection hypothesis. Allen (1982) argues that where it is only farmer ability that is asymmetrically known, wage and cropshare contracts are unnecessary to induce selection. If farmers have all decision-making authority, as is the case with rental contracts, they will sort themselves correctly. However, Allen
1142
Land and Livestock Contracting in Agriculture
5920
(1982, 1985) also offers two reasons why share contracts may occur for selection purposes. First, if landowners wish to maintain some decision-making authority, as would be the case if in addition to asymmetric knowledge of farmer ability there is also asymmetric knowledge about land quality (landowners alone know the quality of their holdings), sharecropping may arise. Second, if contracts must be self-enforcing (courts cannot be counted on), sharecropping may arise. Since both rental and cropshare contracts necessarily imply a loan of land to the farmer until the crop is harvested, both are subject to farmer default. Default entails absconding with the entire crop or not paying the agreed upon rent. If landowners can learn farmer abilities by observing the size of the harvest, an equilibrium may arise where farmers of low ability select wage contracts, farmers of high ability select share contracts and are later rewarded for performance (not absconding) with larger plots (and so more income). Share contracts, then, provide a self-enforcing mechanism to induce selection. There may be a similar role for selection in livestock production contracts. These contracts require growers to build expensive animal houses, with little salvage value. Growers of high ability likely will find this investment profitable; those with low ability likely will not. Knoeber (1989, p. 280) notes that broiler companies (integrators) claim that an important reason for the use of contract growers is the refusal of high-quality growers to work for wages. That is, contract production selects for high-quality growers. The likely reason for the importance of high-quality growers is that suggested by Hallagan (1978); the rapid technological change which characterizes the broiler industry requires growers of high entrepreneurial ability.
6. Innovation and Contract Form Is there a link between innovation and contract form? Bhaduri (1973) claims that sharecropping retards innovation, but the case is not clear. Since a share contract divides the gains from innovation (like the gains from farmer effort) between landlord and tenant, neither seems to have sufficient incentive to innovate. But if transaction costs do not interfere, Cheung’s (1968) argument for the efficiency of share contracting applies equally to effort and to innovation. As long as contracts can be adapted easily, extant share contracts should have little influence on the incentive to adopt new technologies. Transaction costs aside, then, there should be no relation between the form of contracts (cropshare, lease, wage) and innovation. But transaction costs may matter. Newberry (1975) argues that innovation may both increase output and make it more difficult to provide incentive to tenant farmers (require more resources devoted to measuring a in order to assure
5920
Land and Livestock Contracting in Agriculture
1143
that effort does not fall below that agreed upon or greater risk-bearing costs for the tenant if the (now, less precise) original measure of a is still used). If this is the case, innovations that would be undertaken with rental contracts may sometimes be foregone with share contracts. This transaction costs argument suggests less innovation with sharecropping. Empirical evidence, at least in developing countries, shows no relation between innovation and contract form. Parthasarathy and Prasad (1974) find no effect of share tenancy on the adoption of high yield varieties of rice in an Indian village. Ruttan (1977) summarizes research showing no persistent lag among sharecroppers in the adoption of new varieties of rice and wheat in Asia during the Green Revolution of the 1960s and 1970s. Similarly, Feder, Just and Zilberman (1985) conclude that no clear relation exists between tenancy and the adoption of agricultural innovations. These empirical findings are not surprising. If sharecropping’s effect on innovation were substantial, contracts that better facilitate innovation should replace share contracts. Interestingly, there appears to be a positive relation between the pace of technological innovation and contract production in livestock industries. Improvements in feed conversion in the United States have been most rapid and most persistent for broilers and turkeys where contract production dominates, recently rapid for hogs where contract production is increasing, and relatively slow for cattle where contract production is less significant (Knoeber, 1989). Similarly, adoption of new breeding technologies seems positively related to (contract) integration in livestock production (Johnson, 1995). This suggests that contracts may facilitate innovation. Knoeber (1989) provides an explanation for broilers. Here, decisions to adopt innovations (new genetics, and so on) are made by the integrator companies. Also, broiler contracts compensate growers based upon relative performance. These contracts serve two complementary purposes. First, they protect growers from the risk associated with innovation experiments. Innovations may raise or lower absolute performance, but have little effect on relative performance. So growers will not resist innovation. Second, these contracts automatically shift all of the gains from innovation (increases in absolute performance) to the integrator company. As a result, those making adoption decisions face the full costs and benefits of these decisions without the necessity to rewrite contracts (no additional contracting costs are incurred). The form of broiler production contracts seems particularly well adapted to an environment of rapid and persistent technological change.
1144
Land and Livestock Contracting in Agriculture
5920
7. Contracts and Performance An important issue in the land tenancy literature but not in that on livestock contracting is the relation between contract form and performance. The primary concern is that sharecroppers who receive only a portion of the gains from effort will have too little incentive and perform poorly. Bardhan and Srinivasan (1971) model this effect. To the extent that contracts are imposed exogenously (or perhaps contractual choice is constrained politically), this concern may be warranted. If sharecrop contracts are imposed where rental or owner operation is optimal, sharecroppers should perform worse than renters or owner-operators and the cross-sectional relation between sharecropping and performance should be negative. But if contracts are chosen endogenously, share contracts (like others) should be chosen where they are most effective (Lucas, 1979; Rao, 1971; Morooka and Hayami, 1989; Chew, 1993; Tunali, 1993; and especially Otsuka, Hiroyuki and Hayami, 1992, pp. 2005-2008). Here, sharecroppers should perform no better nor worse than other farmers. As a consequence, there should be no cross-sectional relation between sharecropping (or other contract form) and performance (for a statement of this argument applied to the ownership structure of corporations and firm performance, see Demsetz and Lehn, 1985; for a test, see Agrawal and Knoeber, 1996). Any empirical relation is either spurious or results from failing to control for those features of the environment that make sharecropping (or rental, or owner operation) optimal. Empirical evidence is largely consistent with optimal (unhindered) contract choice. Bell (1977) and Shaban (1987) are exceptional in offering evidence of poorer performance by sharecroppers in India. Laffont and Matoussi (1995) also find evidence of poorer performance in Tunisia but do so within an explicit framework in which exogenously imposed credit constraints on farmers induce sharecropping. Most studies find no such effect. Rao (1971), Truran and Fox (1979) and Nabi (1986) are more typical in finding no performance difference for sharecroppers. Cropshare contracts appear to exist where they are optimal.
8. Next Steps A substantial portion of the literature on sharecropping has focused on its use and its effects in developing countries. This is appropriate both because these countries are more agrarian than their western counterparts and because sharecropping seems more dominant here. But sharecropping remains important in developed countries. For some crops and some areas, sharecropping is the primary form of contracting. For example, in the
5920
Land and Livestock Contracting in Agriculture
1145
United States during the late 1980s, cropshare contracts were a large percentage of all lease contracts in the midwest where grain crops dominate (more than 50 percent in Kansas, Illinois, and Indiana; more than 40 percent in Iowa and Missouri). An important question is whether the function of sharecropping is the same in both developing and developed economies. The generally lesser use of cropshare contracts (relative to rental or wage contracts) in developed economies offers a clue. What is it about the development of markets that might lead to a decline in sharecropping? One possible answer is that with better markets also comes less risk or at least better ways to shift risk. More extensive agricultural markets reduce the effects that local conditions have on prices and so may reduce the risk associated with farming (depending upon the correlation of output among local farmers and the correlation between local output and price). But even if this is not the case, better insurance markets provide alternatives to sharecropping as ways to share risk. More developed markets reduce (or perhaps eliminate) the risk-shifting motivation for sharecropping. This may account for sharecropping’s lesser importance in developed countries. But more extensive markets and the anonymity that they allow also will affect measurement costs and so, in turn, the incentive motivation for share contracts. These changes in measurement costs, then, also may account for the lesser importance of sharecropping in developed countries (and for the variation in the importance of sharecropping across crops and regions). Both arguments are made by Otsuka, Kikuchi and Hayami (1986) to explain the lesser use of share contracts (relative to rental contracts) for drivers of jeepney (taxi cabs) in urban as opposed to rural areas of the Philippines. The ‘thicker’ urban market is less risky than rural markets making urban share contracts less desirable on risk-sharing grounds. But also tight-knit communities in rural areas (relative to the anonymity of urban areas) reduce the cost of monitoring drivers. Low effort by drivers is known more readily by owners in rural areas. So, measurement costs are relatively high in urban areas, again making share contracts less desirable. Similar arguments may explain the lesser use of cropshare contracts in more developed countries. If so, more active crop insurance markets (or more extensive government disaster payments) should coincide with lesser use of share contracts. Similarly, lesser migration (tighter knit communities) should coincide with greater use of cropshare contracts. Little role for risk considerations in contract choice in developed countries is consistent with the claim of Allen and Lueck (1996) who argue that transaction costs determine contract use in modern United States farming. Examining more carefully the nature of measurement and enforcement costs seems a fruitful approach to studying agricultural contracts. Allen and Lueck (1992a) do this to explain the length of farmland
1146
Land and Livestock Contracting in Agriculture
5920
contracts and whether their form is oral or written. In related work (Allen and Lueck, 1997), they also address a very interesting puzzle, the continued dominance of family farms in the face of growing corporatism in other sectors of the economy. Once again, measurement costs are key. Family farms eliminate the need for measurement of effort since family farmers are residual claimants. But family farms also restrict the possibilities for specialization. Where measurement of effort is difficult and specialization unimportant, family farms should dominate. Where measurement of effort is easier and gains from specialization greater, partnerships and corporations should be important. Allen and Lueck treat (Mother) nature as determining measurement and specialization costs. Where production has a larger random element, the costs of measuring effort are greater. Where seasonality is less, specialization gains are more important. This implies that family farms will be more likely where nature (weather, pests, and so on) is a more important determinant of output and for more seasonal crops. Allen and Lueck also provide some confirming evidence. That nature and seasonality are more important for agriculture than for other industries is consistent with the continued dominance of family farms. Further, the importance of corporate firms in broiler production is ascribed to the elimination of nature’s role in much of the production process. Finally, the relative importance of family farms in British Columbia and Louisiana is explained by the extent of seasonality (more seasonal crops are more likely to be grown on family farms) and the degree to which nature influences output (weakly, irrigated crops, where rainfall is less important, are less likely to be grown on family farms). Similarly, despite much opposing commentary, risk costs may not be the primary motivation for the livestock production contracts increasingly used in the United States. Focusing on measurement and enforcement costs seems a fruitful avenue. Interesting puzzles are differences in the extent of contract use and the design of contracts across varieties of livestock. In the United States, contract production dominates for broilers and turkeys, is important for eggs (although vertically integrated companies are also important and some auction markets exist), is increasingly important for hogs (but still accounts for less than 25 percent of hog production), and is unimportant for cattle. No attempt has been made to explain this pattern. Additionally, broiler contracts reward growers based on relative performance; turkey contracts sometimes do and sometimes do not; and hog contracts almost never do. Contract producers of hogs receive bonuses if they meet absolute (fixed) performance standards. Tsoulouhas and Vukina (1997) suggest a risk-related explanation for this variation in contract form. Concern with bankruptcy risk precludes the use of relative performance compensation for contract producers of swine where integrators are predominately closely-held and where price volatility is large. In contrast, the predominance of publicly
5920
Land and Livestock Contracting in Agriculture
1147
traded integrators in the broiler industry coupled with lesser price volatility allows the use of relative performance compensation for contract producers of broilers. But, there also may be a measurement cost explanation of this phenomenon. Relative performance is a less noisy measure than absolute performance whenever common shocks to performance (for example bad weather that affects all growers) are large and comparison growers are many. The reason is that relative performance differences-out the noise introduced by common shocks from a grower’s performance but also introduces the idiosyncratic variation from other growers’ performance (other growers’ performance is the benchmark). If the first effect dominates, relative performance is a less noisy measure. The noise added by the idiosyncratic variation in other growers’ performance is reduced when there are more of these other growers since the individual variations balance out (Hölmstrom, 1982). The number of other growers and their similarity, then, determine whether or not relative performance contracts are desirable (Knoeber, 1989 and Martin, 1994). Much remains to be done to explain the ongoing revolution in the contractual organization of livestock production.
Bibliography on Land and Livestock Contracting in Agriculture (5920) Agrawal, Anup and Knoeber, Charles R. (1996), ‘Firm Performance and Mechanisms To Control Agency Problems Between Managers and Shareholders’, 31 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 377-397. Allen, Douglas W. and Lueck, Dean (1992a), ‘The “Back Forty” on a Handshake: Specific Assets, Reputation, and the Structure of Farmland Contracts’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 366-376. Allen, Douglas W. and Lueck, Dean (1992b), ‘Contract Choice in Modern Agriculture: Cash Rent versus Cropshare’, 35 Journal of Law and Economics, 397-426. Allen, Douglas W. and Lueck, Dean (1993), ‘Transaction Costs and the Design of Cropshare Contracts’, 24 Rand Journal of Economics, 78-100. Allen, Douglas W. and Lueck, Dean (1995), ‘Risk Preferences and the Economics of Contracts’, 85 American Economic Review, 447-451. Allen, Douglas W. and Dean Lueck (1996), ‘Risk-Sharing and Agricultural Contracts’, North Carolina, Department of Agricultural and Resource Economics, North Carolina State University. Allen, Douglas W. and Lueck, Dean (1997), The Nature of the Farm, North Carolina, Department of Agricultural and Resource Economics, North Carolina State University. Allen, Franklin (1982), ‘On Share Contracts and Screening’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 541-547. Allen, Franklin (1985), ‘On the Fixed Nature of Sharecropping Contracts’, 95 Economic Journal, 30-48.
1148
Land and Livestock Contracting in Agriculture
5920
Alston, Lee J. and Higgs, Robert (1982), ‘Contractual Mix in Southern Agriculture since the Civil War: Facts, Hypotheses, and Tests’, 42 Journal of Economic History, 327-353. Alston, Lee J., Datta, Samar K. and Nugent, Jeffrey B. (1984), ‘Tenancy Choice in a Competitive Framework with Transactions Costs’, 92 Journal of Political Economy, 1121-1133. Anderson, Terry L. and Lueck, Dean (1992), ‘Land Tenure and Agricultural Productivity on Indian Reservations’, 35 Journal of Law and Economics, 427-454. Apland, Jeffrey, Barnes, Robert B. and Justice, Fred (1984), ‘The Farm Lease: An Analysis of Owner-Tenant and Landlord Preferences under Risk’, 66 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 376-384. Banerji, Sanjay and Rashid, Salim (1996), ‘Tournaments and Sharecropping’, 63 Economica, 343-352. Bardhan, Pranab K. and Srinivasan, T.N. (1971), ‘Cropsharing Tenancy in Agriculture: A Theoretical and Empirical Analysis’, 61 American Economic Review, 48-64. Bardhan, Pranab K. and Srinivasan, T.N. (1974), ‘Cropsharing Tenancy in Agriculture: Comment’, 64 American Economic Review, 1067-1069. Barry, Peter J., Sonka, Steven T. and Lajili, Kaouthar (1992), ‘Vertical Coordination, Financial Structure, and the Changing Theory of the Firm’, 74 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 1219-1225. Battacharyya, Sugato and Lafontaine, Francine (1995), ‘Double-Sided Moral Hazard and the Nature of Share Contracts’, 26 Rand Journal of Economics, 761-781. Bell, Clive (1977), ‘Alternative Theories of Sharecropping: Some Tests Using Evidence from Northeast India’, 13 Journal of Development Studies, 317-346. Bell, Clive and Zusman, Pinhas (1976), ‘A Bargaining Theoretic Approach to Cropsharing Contracts’, 66 American Economic Review, 578-588. Benson, Bruce L. and Faminow, Merle D. (1984), ‘Rent Seeking and Supply Management in Canada’, 32 Canadian Journal of Agricultural Economics, 548-558. Benson, Bruce L., Faminow, Merle D., Marquis, Milton H. and Sauer, Douglas G. (1994a), ‘Intra-National Effects of a Countervailing Duty on the U.S./Canadian Hog Market’, 16 Review of Agricultural Economics, 187-201. Benson, Bruce L., Faminow, Merle D., Marquis, Milton H. and Sauer, Douglas G. (1994b), ‘The Impact of Provincial Marketing Boards on Price Relations and Pricing Dynamics in the North American Slaughter Hog Market’, 26 Applied Economics, 677-688. Bhaduri, Amit (1973), ‘Agricultural Backwardness under Semifeudalism’, 83 Economic Journal, 120-137. Binswanger, Hans P. and Rosenzweig, Mark R. (1984), ‘Contractual Arrangements, Employment, and Wages in Rural Labor Markets: A Critical Review’, in Binswanger, Hans P. and Rosenzweig, Mark R. (eds), Contractual Arrangements. Employment, and Wages in Rural Labor Markets in Asia, New Haven, Yale University Press, 1-40. Braverman, Avishay and Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1982), ‘Sharecropping and the Interlinking of Agrarian Markets’, 72 American Economic Review, 695-715. Braverman, Avishay and Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1986), ‘Cost-Sharing Arrangements under Sharecropping: Moral Hazard, Incentive Flexibility, and Risk’, 68 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 642-652.
5920
Land and Livestock Contracting in Agriculture
1149
Brown, Donald J. and Atkinson, J.H. (1981), ‘Cash and Share Renting: An Empirical Test of the Link between Entrepreneurial Ability and Contractual Choice’, 12 Bell Journal of Economics, 296-299. Campbell, H.F. and Lindner, R.K. (1990), ‘The Production of Fishing Effort and the Economic Performance of Licence Limitation Programs’, 66 Land Economics, 56-66. Caputo, Michael R. and Lynch, Lori (1993), ‘A Nonparametric Efficiency Analysis of California Cotton Ginning Cooperatives’, 18 Journal of Agricultural and Resource Economics, 251-265. Centner, Terence J. (1993), ‘The U.S.’s Organic Foods Production Act: Does the Small-Farmer Exception Breach the U.S.’s Obligations Under GATT?’, 28 Tulsa Law Journal, 715-722. Cheung, Steven N.S. (1968), ‘Private Property Rights and Share Cropping’, 76 Journal of Political Economy, 1107-1122. Cheung, Steven N.S. (1969a), A Theory of Share Tenancy, Chicago, IL, University of Chicago Press, 188 p. Cheung, Steven N.S. (1969b), ‘Transaction Costs, Risk Aversion and the Choice of Contractual Arrangements’, 12 Journal of Law and Economics, 23-42. Chew, Tek-Ann (1991), ‘Share Contracts in Malaysian Rubber Smallholdings’, 67 Land Economics, 85-98. Chew, Tek-Ann (1993), ‘The Transactional Framework of Sharecropping: Further Implications’, 41 Canadian Journal of Agricultural Economics, 209-221. Coelho, Philip R.P. and McClure, James E. (1987), ‘Barriers to Entry in the Market for Stud Services: Government and “Non-Profit” Institutions in Collusion’, 25 Economic Inquiry, 659-670. Datta, Samar K., O’Hara, Donald J. and Nugent, Jeffrey B. (1986), ‘Choice of Agricultural Tenancy in the Presence of Transaction Costs’, 62 Land Economics, 145-158. Demsetz, Harold and Lehn, Kenneth (1985), ‘The Structure of Corporate Ownership: Causes and Consequences’, 93 Journal of Political Economy, 1155-1177. Eswaran, Mukesh and Kotwal, Ashok (1985), ‘A Theory of Contractual Structure in Agriculture’, 75 American Economic Review, 352-367. Feder, Gershon, Just, Richard E. and Zilberman, David (1985), ‘Adoption of Agricultural Innovations in Developing Countries: A Survey’, 33 Economic Development and Cultural Change, 255-298. Frank, Stuart D. and Henderson, Dennis R. (1992), ‘Transaction Costs as Determinants of Vertical Coordination in the U.S. Food Industries’, 74 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 941-950. Hallagan, William S. (1978a), ‘Self-Selection by Contractual Choice and the Theory of Sharecropping’, 9 Bell Journal of Economics, 344-354. Hallagan, William S. (1978b), ‘Share Contracting for California Gold’, 15 Explorations in Economic History, 196-210. Helmberger, Peter G. and Hoos, Sidney (1965), Cooperative Bargaining in Agriculture, California, University of California Division of Agricultural Sciences. Higgs, Robert (1973), ‘Race, Tenure, and Resource Allocation in Southern Agriculture’, 33 Journal of Economic History, 149-169.
1150
Land and Livestock Contracting in Agriculture
5920
Higgs, Robert (1974), ‘Patterns of Farm Rental in the Georgia Cotton Belt, 1880-1900', 34 Journal of Economic History, 468-482. Holmström, Bengt (1982), ‘Moral Hazard in Teams’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 324-340. Isé, Sabrina and Perloff, Jeffrey M. (1995), ‘Legal Status and Earnings of Agricultural Workers’, 77 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 355-386. Jaynes, Gerald Davis (1984), ‘Economic Theory and Land Tenure’, in Binswanger, Hans P. and Rosenzweig, Mark R. (eds), Contractual Arrangements, Employment, and Wages in Rural Labor Markets in Asia, New Haven, Yale University Press, 43-62. Johnson, C. Scott and Foster, Kenneth A. (1994), ‘Risk Preferences and Contracting in the U.S. Hog Industry’, 26 Journal of Agricultural and Applied Economics, 393-405. Johnson, D. Gale (1950), ‘Resource Allocation Under Share Contracts’, 58 Journal of Political Economy, 111-123. Johnson, D. Gale (1958), ‘Government and Agriculture: Is Agriculture a Special Case?’, 1 Journal of Law and Economics, 122-135. Johnson, Nancy L. (1995), The Diffusion of Livestock Breeding Technology in the U.S.: Observations on the Relationship between Technical Change and Industry Structure, Minnesota, University of Minnesota, Department of Applied Economics. Khan, Shahrukh Rafi (1988), ‘Henry George and an Alternative Islamic Land Tenure System’, 36 Economic Development and Cultural Change, 721-739. Klein, Benjamin, Crawford, Robert G. and Alchian, Armen A. (1978), ‘Vertical Integration, Appropriable Rents, and the Competitive Contracting Process’, 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 297-326. Kliebenstein, James B. and Lawrence, John D. (1995), ‘Contracting and Vertical Coordination in the United States Pork Industry’, 77 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 1213-1218. Knoeber, Charles R. (1983), ‘An Alternative Mechanism to Assure Contractual Reliability’, 12 Journal of Legal Studies, 333-343. Knoeber, Charles R. (1989), ‘A Real Game of Chicken: Contracts, Tournaments, and the Production of Broilers’, 5 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 271-292. Knoeber, Charles R. (1997), ‘Explaining State Bans on Corporate Farming’, 35 Economic Inquiry, 151-166. Knoeber, Charles R. and Baumer, David L. (1986), ‘Guaranteeing a Market and the Contracts of Bargaining Cooperatives’, 1 Journal of Agricultural Cooperation, 1-10. Knoeber, Charles R. and Thurman, Walter N. (1994), ‘Testing the Theory of Tournaments: An Empirical Analysis of Broiler Production’, 12 Journal of Labor Economics, 155-179. Knoeber, Charles R. and Thurman, Walter N. (1995), ‘Don’t Count Your Chickens...: Risk and Risk Shifting in the Broiler Industry’, 77 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 486-496. Ladd, George W. (1974), ‘A Model of a Bargaining Cooperative’, 56 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 509-519. Laffont, Jean-Jacques and Matoussi, Mohamed Salah (1995), ‘Moral Hazard, Financial Constraints and Sharecropping in El Ouja’, 62 Review of Economic Studies, 381-399. Lazear, Edward P. and Rosen, Sherwin (1981), ‘Rank-Order Tournaments as Optimum Labor Contracts’, 89 Journal of Political Economy, 841-864.
5920
Land and Livestock Contracting in Agriculture
1151
Leffler, Keith B. and Rucker, Randal R. (1991), ‘Transaction Costs and the Efficient Organization of Production: A Study of Timber Harvesting Contracts’, 99 Journal of Political Economy, 1060-1087. Lucas, Robert E.B. (1979), ‘Sharing, Monitoring, and Incentives: Marshallian Misallocation Reassessed’, 87 Journal of Political Economy, 501-521. Martin, Laura L. (1994), Pork ... The Other White Meat?, An Analysis of Vertical Coordination and Contracting in the North Carolina Pork Industry, Ph.D. Dissertation, North Carolina State University. Menard, Claude (1996), ‘On Clusters, Hybrids, and other Strange Forms: The Case of the French Poultry Industry’, 152 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 154-183. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1987), ‘The True Story of Carolene Products, 1987', Supreme Court Review, 397 ff. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1989), ‘Public Choice at the Dawn of the Special Interest State: The Story of Butter and Margarine’, 77 California Law Review, 83-131. Mitra, Pradeep K. (1983), ‘A Theory of Interlinked Rural Transactions’, 20 Journal of Public Economics, 167-191. Morooka, Yoshinori and Hayami, Yujiro (1989), ‘Contract Choice and Enforcement in an Agrarian Community: Agricultural Tenancy in Upland Java’, 26 Journal of Development Studies, 28-42. Murrell, Peter (1983), ‘The Economics of Sharing: A Transactions Costs Analysis of Contractual Choice in Farming’, 14 Bell Journal of Economics, 283-293. Nabi, Ijaz (1986), ‘Contracts, Resource Use and Productivity in Sharecropping’, 22 Journal of Development Studies, 429-442. Netz, Janet (1995), ‘The Effect of Futures Markets and Corners on Storage and Spot Price Variability’, 77 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 182-193. Netz, Janet (1996), ‘An Empirical Test of the Effect of Basis Risk on Cash Market Positions’, 16 Journal of Futures Markets, 289-312. Newberry, David M.G. (1975), ‘Tenurial Obstacles to Innovation’, 11 Journal of Development Studies, 263-277. Newberry, David M.G. (1977), ‘Risk Sharing, Sharecropping and Uncertain Labor Markets’, 44 Review of Economic Studies, 585-594. Newberry, David M.G. and Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1979), ‘Sharecropping, Risk Sharing, and the Importance of Imperfect Information’, in Roumasset, James A., Boussard, Jean-Marc and Singh, Inderjit (eds), Risk, Uncertainty, and Agricultural Development, Laguna, Philippines, Agricultural Development Council and Southeast Regional Center for Graduate Study and Research in Agriculture, 311-339. Newberry, D.M.G. (1974), ‘Cropsharing Tenancy in Agriculture: Comment’, 64 American Economic Review, 1060-1066. Otsuka, Keijiro and Hayami, Yujiro (1988), ‘Theories of Share Tenancy: A Critical Survey’, 37 Economic Development and Cultural Change, 31-68. Otsuka, Keijiro, Hiroyuki, Chuma and Hayami, Yujiro (1992), ‘Land and Labor Contracts in Agrarian Economies: Theories and Facts’, 30 Journal of Economic Literature, 1965-2018. Otsuka, Keijiro, Kikuchi, Masao and Hayami, Yujiro (1986), ‘Community and Market in Contract Choice: The Jeepney in the Philippines’, 34 Economic Development and Cultural Change, 279-298.
1152
Land and Livestock Contracting in Agriculture
5920
Parthasarathy, G. and Prasad, D.S. (1974), ‘Responses to, and Impact of, H.Y.V. Rice According to Land Size and Tenure in a Delta Village, Andhra Pradesh, India’, 12 Developing Economies, 182-198. Petersson, Johan and Andersson, Hans (1996), ‘The Benefits of Share Contracts: Some European Results’, 47 Journal of Agricultural Economics, 158-171. Porter, Philip K. and Scully, Gerald W. (1987), ‘Economic Efficiency in Cooperatives’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 489-512. Rao, C.H. Hanumantha (1971), ‘Uncertainty, Entrepreneurship, and Sharecropping in India’, 79 Journal of Political Economy, 578-595. Reid, Joseph D., Jr (1973), ‘Sharecropping as an Understandable Market Response’, 33 Journal of Economic History, 106-130. Reid, Joseph D. Jr (1976), ‘Sharecropping and Agricultural Uncertainty’, 24 Economic Development and Cultural Change, 549-576. Reid, Joseph D., Jr (1977), ‘The Theory of Share Tenancy Revisited-Again’, 25 Journal of Political Economy, 403-407. Reimund, Donn A., Martin, J. Rod and Moore, Charles V. (1981), Structural Change in Agriculture: The Experience for Broilers, Fed Cattle, and Processing Vegetables, Washington, DC, US Department of Agriculture. Rucker, Randal R. (1995), ‘Endogenous Policy Dynamics, the Visibility of Rents, and Changes in the Transferability of Production Rights: The Case of Flue-Cured Tobacco’, Montana, Department of Economics and Applied Economics, Montana State University. Rucker, Randal R. and Thurman, Walter N. (1990), ‘The Economic Effect of Supply Controls: The Simple Analytics of the U.S. Peanut Program’, 33 Journal of Law and Economics, 483-515. Rucker, Randal R., Thurman, Walter N. and Sumner, Daniel A. (1995), ‘Restricting the Market for Quota: An Analysis of Tobacco Production Rights with Corroboration from Congressional Testimony’, 103 Journal of Political Economy, 142-175. Ruttan, Vernon W. (1977), ‘The Green Revolution: Seven Generalizations’, 19 International Development Review, 16-25. Seagraves, James A. (1969), ‘Capitalized Values of Tobacco Allotments and the Return to Allotment Owners’, 51 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 320-334. Sexton, Richard J. (1986), ‘Cooperatives and the Forces Shaping Agricultural Marketing’, 68 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 1167-1172. Sexton, Richard J., Wilson, Brooks M. and Wann, Joyce J. (1989), ‘Some Tests of the Economic Theory of Cooperatives: Methodology and Applications to Cotton Ginning’, 14 Western Journal of Agricultural Economics, 56-66. Shaban, Radwan Ali (1987), ‘Testing Between Competing Models in Sharecropping’, 95 Journal of Political Economy, 893-920. Shelden, Ian M. (1996), ‘Contracting, Imperfect Information, and the Food System’, 18 Review of Agricultural Economics, 7-19. Singh, Nirvikar (1989), ‘Theories of Sharecropping’, in Pranab K. Bardhan (ed.), The Economic Theory of Agrarian Institutions, Oxford, Clarendon, 33-72. Sporleader, Thomas L. (1992), ‘Managerial Economics of Vertically Coordinated Agricultural Firms’, 74 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 1226-1231.
5920
Land and Livestock Contracting in Agriculture
1153
Squires, Dale (1987), ‘Public Regulation and the Structure of Production in Multiproduct Industries: An Application to the New England Otter Trawl Industry’, 18 Rand Journal of Economics, 232-247. Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1974), ‘Incentives and Risk Sharing in Sharecropping’, 41 Review of Economic Studies, 397-426. Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1987), ‘Sharecropping’, in Eatwell, John, Milgate, Murray and Newman, Peter (eds), The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, London, Macmillan, 20-323. Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1988), ‘Economic Organization, Information, and Development’, in Chenery, Hollis and Srinivasan, T.N. (eds), Handbook of Development Economics Volume 1, Amsterdam, North Holland, 93-159. Subramanian, Shankar (1995), ‘Wage Labor, Sharecropping and Credit Transactions’, 47 Oxford Economic Papers, 329-356. Trojan, C. (1987), ‘Landbouw (Agriculture)’, in X (ed.), 18de Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Brussel 8 en 9 mei 1987, Sociaal-economische Deregulering, Brussel, V.E.H.U.B., 475-504. Truran, James A. and Fox, Roger W. (1979), ‘Resource Productivity of Landowners and Sharecroppers in the Cariri Region of Ceara, Brazil’, 55 Land Economics, 93-107. Tsoulouhas, Theofanis and Vukina, Tomislav (1997), ‘Processor Contracts with Many Agents and Bankruptcy’, North Carolina, Department of Economics, North Carolina State University. Tunali, Insan (1993), ‘Choice of Contracts in Turkish Agriculture’, 42 Economic Development and Cultural Change, 67-87. Ulrich, Alvin, Furtan, William H. and Schmitz, Andrew (1987), ‘The Cost of a Licensing System Regulation: An Example from Canadian Prairie Agriculture’, 95 Journal of Political Economy, 160-178. Vantrese, Valerie L., Reed, Michael R. and Skees, Jerry R. (1989), ‘Mandatory Production Controls and Asset Values: A Case Study of Burley Tobacco Quotas’, 71 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 319-325. Warr, Peter G. (1978), ‘Share Contracts, Limited Information, and Production Uncertainty’, 17 Australian Economic Papers, 110-123. Wilcox, Christopher J. (1989), ‘Social Costs of Regulation of Primary Industry: An Application to Animal Welfare Regulation of the Victorian Pig Industry’, 33 Australian Journal of Agricultural Economics, 187-202. Williamson, Oliver E. (1983), ‘Credible Commitments: Using Hostages to Support Exchange’, 73 American Economic Review, 519-540.
5930 TELECOMMUNICATIONS © Copyright 1999 Boudewijn Bouckaert and Gerrit De Geest
Bibliography Collected by the Editors Baldwin, R., Cave, M. and Jones, T.H. (1987), ‘The Regulation of Independent Local Radio and Its Reform’, 7 International Review of Law and Economics, 177-191. Barnett, William P. and Carroll, Glenn R. (1993), ‘How Institutional Constraints Affected the Organization of Early U.S. Telephony’, 9 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 98-126. Baseman, K.C. and Owen, Bruce M., ‘A Framework for Economic Analysis of Electronic Media Concentration Issues’, Economists Incorporated Research Report. Baxter, William F. (1974), ‘Regulation and Diversity in Communications Media’, 64 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 392-399. Beebe, J.H. and Owen, Bruce M. (1972), Alternative Structures for Television, OTP Staff Research Paper. Reprinted in Ginsburg, D.H. (1979), Regulation of Broadcasting, Minneapolis, West Publishing. Beesley Report (1981), Liberalization of the Use of British Telecommunica, London, Her Majesty’s Stationary Office. Beesley, Michael E. and Laidlaw, Bruce (1989), The Future of Telecommunications: An Assessment of the Role of Competition in UK Policy, London, Institute of Economic Affairs, 96 p. Besen, Stanley M. and Woodbury, John R. (1983), ‘Regulation, Deregulation, and Antitrust in the Telecommunications Industry’, 28 Antitrust Bulletin, 39-68. Besen, Stanley M., Mitchell, Bridger M., Noll, Roger G., Owen, Bruce M., Park, R.E. and Rosse, J.N. (1977), ‘Economic Policy Research on Cable Television: Assessing the Cost and Benefits of Cable Deregulation,’, in MacAvoy, P.A. (ed.), Deregulation of Cable Television, Washington, American Enterprise Institute. Blankart, Charles B. and Knieps, Gunter (1989), ‘What Can We Learn from Comparative Institutional Analysis? the Case of Telecommunications’, 42 Kyklos, 579-598. Botein, Michael and Pearce, Alan (1988), ‘The Competitiveness of the U.S. Telecommunications Industry: A New York Case Study’, 6 Cardozo Arts and Entertainment Law Journal, 233-325. Brock, Gerald W. (1986), ‘The Regulatory Change in Telecommunications: The Dissolution of AT&T’, in Weiss, Leonard W. and Klass, Michael W. (ed.), Regulatory Reform: What Actually Happened, Boston, Little Brown, 210-233. Carter, Richard (1984), ‘Le Canada est-il Entraine dans la Dereglementation: le Cas des Communications (Is Canada Deregulating? The Case of Telecommunications)’, 10 Canadian Public Policy, 10-24. Coase, Ronald H. (1959), ‘The Federal Communications Commission’, 2 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-40. Coase, Ronald H. (1962), ‘The Interdepartment Radio Advisory Committee’, 5 Journal of Law and Economics, 17-47.
1154
5930
Telecommunications
1155
Coase, Ronald H. (1979), ‘Payola in Radio and Television Broadcasting’, 22 Journal of Law and Economics, 269-328. Comanor, William S. and Mitchell, Bridger M. (1972), ‘The Costs of Planning: The FCC and Cable Television’, 15 Journal of Law and Economics, 177-206. Copeland, Basil L., Jr and Severn, Alan (1985), ‘Price Theory and Telecommunications Regulation: A Dissenting View’, 3 Yale Journal on Regulation, 53-85. Crandall, Robert W. (1971), ‘The Economic Effect of Television-Network Program ‘Ownership’’, 14 Journal of Law and Economics, 385-412. Crandall, Robert W. (1988), ‘Telecommunications Policy in the Reagan Era’, 12(3) Regulation, 28-33. Crandall, Robert W. and Flamm, Kenneth (eds) (1988), Changing the Rules: Technological Change, International Competition and Regulation in Communications, Washington, Brookings Institution, 424 p. Crandall, Robert W. and Owen, Bruce M. (1984), ‘Some Economic Implications of the Divestiture of the Bell Operating Companies’, in Shooshan, D. (ed.), Disconnecting Bell, New York, Pergamon Press. Crandall, Robert W., Noll, Roger G. and Owen, Bruce M. (1983), ‘Economic Effects of the Financial Interest and Syndication Rule’, Economists Incorporated. Cude, Brenda J. (1989), ‘Consumer Response to Telecommunications Deregulation: The Equal Access Decision’, 23 Journal of Consumer Affairs, 285-300. D’Alcantara, G. (1987), ‘Telecommunicatie. Economische Aspecten (Telecommunication: Economic Aspects)’, in X (ed.), 18de Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Brussel 8 en 9 mei 1987, Sociaal-economische Deregulering, Brussel, V.E.H.U.B., 565-579. Daly, George and Mayor, Thomas H. (1980), ‘Estimating the Value of a Missing Market: the Economics of Directory Assistance’, 23 Journal of Law and Economics, 147-166. De Fontenay, Alain, Shugard, Mary H. and Sibley, David S. (eds) (1990), Telecommunications Demand Modelling: An Integrated View, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 479 p. Dnes, Anthony W. (1995), Telecommunications after Privatization, Private Sector, World Bank. Reprinted in Viewpoint: Telecommunications after Privatization, World Bank, Note 60, October 1995. Dunn, D.A. and Owen, Bruce M. (1978), ‘Policy Options in Mobile Radio Spectrum Management’, Working Paper, Stanford University. Dyk, Timothy B. (1988), ‘Full First Amendment Freedom for Broadcasters: The Industry as Elizaon the Ice and Congress as the Friendly Overseer’, 5 Yale Journal on Regulation, 299-329. Eckel, Russel (1987), ‘Industrial Relations and High Technology: The Transformation of Telecommunications through Deregulation’, in Child, John and Bate, Paul (ed.), Organization of Innovation: East-West Perspectives, Berlin, De Gruyter, 173-189. Einhorn, Michael A. (ed.) (1991), Price Caps and Incentive Regulation in Telecommunications, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 244 p. Encaoua, David and Koebel, Philippe (1987), ‘Réglementation et Déréglementation des Télécommunications: Leçons Anglo-Saxonnes et Perspectives d’Evolution en France (Regulation and Deregulation of the Telecommunication. Lessons and Evolutionary Perspectives in France)’, 38 Revue Economique, 475-520.
1156
Telecommunications
5930
Encaoua, David and Moreaux, Michel (1987), ‘L’Analyse Théorique des Problemes de Tarification et d’Allocation des Coûts dans les Télécommunications (The Theoretical Approach to Pricing and Cost Allocation for Telecommunication Services)’, 38 Revue Economique, 375-413. Faulhaber, Gerald R. (1987), Telecommunications in Turmoil: Technology and Public Policy, Cambridge, MA, Harper and Row, 186 p. Fisher, Franklin M. (1985), ‘The Financial Interest and Syndication Rules in Network Television: Regulatory Fantasy and Reality’, in Fisher, Franklin M. (ed.), Antitrust and Regulation: Essays in Memory of John, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 263-298. Fournier, Gary M. (1985), ‘Nonprice Competition and the Dissipation of Rents from Television Regulation’, 51 Southern Economic Journal, 754-765. Frankena, Mark W. and Owen, Bruce M. (1994), Electric Utility Mergers: Principles of Antitrust Analysis, New York, Praeger Publishing Company. Fuhr, Joseph P., Jr (1986), ‘Maintaining Universal Telephone Service under Deregulation’, 5 Journal of Policy Analysis and Management, 583-590. Geller, Henry (1985), ‘The Role of Future Regulation: Licensing, Spectrum Allocation, Content, Access, Common Carrier and Rates’, in Noam, Eli H. (ed.), Video Media Competition: Regulation, Economics, and Technology, Columbia Studies in Business, Government and Society, New York, Columbia University Press, 283-310. Glaister, Stephen G. (1987), ‘Regulation through Output Related Profits Tax’, 35 Journal of Industrial Economics, 281-296. Hahn, Robert W. and Kroszner, Randall S. (1990), ‘Lost in Space: U.S. International Satellite Communications Policy’, 13(2) Regulation, 57-66. Hazlett, Thomas W. (1986a), ‘Private Monopoly and the Public Interest: An Economic Analysis of the Cable Television Franchise’, 134 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1335-1409. Hazlett, Thomas W. (1986b), ‘Competition vs. Franchise Monopoly in Cable Television’, 4(2) Contemporary Policy Issues, 80-97. Hazlett, Thomas W. (1988), ‘Wiring the Constitution for Cable’, 12(1) Regulation, 30-34. Hazlett, Thomas W. (1990a), ‘Regulation and Competition in Cable Television: Reply’, 7 Yale Journal on Regulation, 141-148. Hazlett, Thomas W. (1990b), ‘Should Telephone Companies Provide Cable TV?’, 13(1) Regulation, 72-80. Hazlett, Thomas W. (1991), ‘The Demand to Regulate Franchise Monopoly: Evidence from CATV Rate Deregulation in California’, 29 Economic Inquiry, 275-296. Hazlett, Thomas W. (1995), ‘Predation in Local Cable TV Markets’, 40 Antitrust Bulletin, 609-644. Hughes, Gordon and Vines, David (eds) (1989), Deregulation and the Future of Commercial Television, Glasgow, Aberdeen University Press, 139 p. Huntley, John A.K. and Pitt, Douglas C. (1990), ‘Judicial Policymaking: The Greening of US Telecommunications’, 10 International Review of Law and Economics, 77-100. Kantzenbach, Erhard (1985), ‘Mehr Wettbewerb im Rundfunk? (More Competition in Broadcasting?)’, in Lüder, K. (ed.), Rundfunk im Umbruch, Berlin, Springer, 161-167.
5930
Telecommunications
1157
Kaserman, David L. and Mayo, John W. (1986), ‘The Ghosts of Deregulated Telecommunications: An Essay by Exorcists’, 6 Journal of Policy Analysis and Management, 84-92. Kilian, W. Picot, Arnold, Neuburger, R., Niggl, J., Scholtes, K.-L. and Seiler, W. (1994), Electronic Data Interchange (EDI), Aus ökonomischer und Juristischer Sicht, Forschungsbericht zu dem von der Volkswagen-Stiftung Geförderten Forschungsprojekt ELTRADA (Elektronische Transaktionen von Dokumenten zwischen Organisationen) (Electronic Data Interchange EDI from the Viewpoint of Economics and Law), Baden-Baden, Nomos. Knieps, Gunter (1983), ‘Is Technological Revolution a Sufficient Reason for Changing the System of Regulation? the Case of Telecommunications’, 139 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 578-597. Levin, Harvey J. (1962), ‘Federal Control of Entry in the Broadcast Industry’, 5 Journal of Law and Economics, 49-67. Levy, Brian and Spiller, Pablo T. (1994), ‘The Institutional Foundations of Regulatory Commitment: A Comparative Analysis of Telecommunications Regulation’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 201-246. Lueck, Dean (1996), ‘Ownership vs. Auctions: A Comment on Spiller and Moreton’, 39 Journal of Law and Economics. Macauley, Molly K. (1986), ‘Out of Space? Regulation and Technical Change in Communications Satellites’, 76 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 280-284. Manning, W. and Owen, Bruce M. (1976), ‘Television Rivalry and Network Power’, 24 Public Policy, 33 ff. Marshall, Robert C., Meurer, Michael J. and Richard, Jean Francois (1991), ‘The Private Attorney General Meets Public Contract Law: Procurement Oversight by Protest’, 20 Hofstra Law Review, 1-71. IRS Computer Modernization and Procurement, Hearing before the Senate Governmental Affairs Committee, June 25, 1991 and April 2, 1992 Marshall, Robert C., Meurer, Michael J. and Richard, Jean Francois (1993), ‘Incentive-Based Procurement Oversight by Protest’, in Leitzel, Jim and Tirole, J. (eds), Incentives in Procurement Contracting, Boulder, CO, Westview. Marshall, Robert C., Meurer, Michael J. and Richard, Jean Francois (1994a), ‘Curbing Agency Problems in the Procurement Process’, 25 Rand Journal of Economics, 297-318. Marshall, Robert C., Meurer, Michael J. and Richard, Jean Francois (1994b), ‘Multiple Litigants with a Public Good Remedy’, 16 Research in Law and Economics, 151-173. Melody, William H. (1989), ‘Efficiency and Social Policy in Telecommunication: Lessons from the U.S. Experience’, 23 Journal of Economic Issues, 657-688. Minasian, Jora R. (1969), ‘The Political Economy of Broadcasting in the 1920s’, 12 Journal of Law and Economics, 391-403. National Economic Research Associates (1989), Telecommunications in a Competitive Environment: Proceedings of the Third Biennial Telecommunications Conference, Marriott’s Camelback Inn, Scottsdale, Arizona, April 12-15, 1989, White Plains, N.E.R.A., 233 p. Noll, Roger G. (1987), ‘The Twisted Pair: Regulation and Competition in Telecommunications’, 11(3-4) Regulation, 15-22.
1158
Telecommunications
5930
Noo, Roger G. (1986), ‘State Regulatory Responses to Competition and Divestiture in the Telecommunications Industry’, in Grieson, Ronald E. (ed.), Antitrust and Regulation, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books, 165-200. Ohls, James C. (1970), ‘Marginal Cost Pricing, Investment Theory and CATV’, 13 Journal of Law and Economics, 439-460. Ohls, James C. (1971), ‘Marginal Cost Pricing, Investment Theory and CATV: A Reply’, 14 Journal of Law and Economics, 517-519. Olsen, Ole Jess (1989), ‘Deregulation and Reorganisation: The Case of the Danish Telecommunications’, 60 Annals of Public and Cooperative Economy, 251-258. Owen, Bruce M. (1970), ‘Public Policy and Emerging Technology in the Media’, 18 Public Policy, 539 ff. Owen, Bruce M. (1972a), Diversity and Television, OTP Staff Research Paper. Reprinted in Ginsburg, D.H., Regulation of Broadcasting, Mineapolis, West Publishing. Owen, Bruce M. (ed.) (1972b), Papers and Proceedings, Conference On Telecommunications Policy, Research Office of Telecommunications. Owen, Bruce M. (1973a), ‘The Role of Analysis in the Formation of Cable Television Policy’, in Park, R.E. (ed.), The Role of Analysis in Regulatory Decisionmaking: The Case of Cable Television, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Owen, Bruce M. (1973b), ‘Newspaper and Television Station Joint Ownership’, 18 Antitrust Bulletin, 787 ff. Owen, Bruce M. (1974), ‘Discussion Prepared for the Session on the Economics of the First Amendment, Annual Meetings of the American Economic Association, New York, December, 1973', 64 American Economic Review, 400 ff. Owen, Bruce M. (1975a), Economics and Freedom of Expression: Media Structure an the First Amendment, Cambridge, MA, Ballinger. Owen, Bruce M. (ed.) (1975b), Report of Papers and Proceedings, 1975 Conference on Telecommunications Policy Research, Aspen, Institute for Humanistic Studies Program on Communications and Society. Owen, Bruce M. (1977), ‘Regulating Diversity: The Case of Radio Formats’, 21 Journal of Broadcasting, 305 ff. Owen, Bruce M. (1978a), ‘Cable Television: The Framework of Regulation’, in X (ed.), Study on Federal Regulation, Appendix to Vol. XI, Framework for Regulation, Committee on Governmental Affairs, United States Senate, 95th Congress. Owen, Bruce M. (1978b), ‘The Place of Print in an Electronic Society’, in Robinson, G.O. (ed.), Communications for Tomorrow: Policy Perspectives for the Future, New York, Praeger Publishing Company. Owen, Bruce M. (1978c), ‘Diversity in Broadcasting: The Economic View of Programming’, 28 Journal of Communication, 43 ff. Owen, Bruce M. (1979a), ‘Structural Approaches to the Problem of TV Network Economic Dominance’, 59 Duke Law Journal, 191 ff. Owen, Bruce M. (1979b), ‘Five Propositions on the Social Effects of Television’, for the Sloan Foundation, Duke University. Owen, Bruce M. (1981), ‘The Rise and Fall of Cable Television Regulation,’, in Weiss, L. (ed.), The Regulatory Revolution, Boston, Little Brown. Owen, Bruce M. (1982), ‘Differing Media, Differing Treatment?’, in Brenner, D. and Rivers, W. (eds), Free But Regulated: Conflicting Traditions in Media Law.
5930
Telecommunications
1159
Owen, Bruce M. (1985), ‘Recent Developments in Cable Television Regulation’, 1 XXXRegulatory Reform: The ABA Section of Antitrust Law Industry Regulation Committee Newsletter. Owen, Bruce M. (1986), Horizontal Mergers: Law and Policy, ABA Section of Antitrust Law Monograph, No. 12. Owen, Bruce M. (1987), ‘Book Review of A. Brown, Commercial Media in Australia: Economics, Ownership, Technology and Regulation’, 17 Economic Analysis and Policy, 105 ff. Owen, Bruce M. (1988), ‘Book Review of P. Temin, the Fall of the Bell System’, 2 Regulation: AEI Journal on Government and Society. Owen, Bruce M. (1990), The Electronic Media, Proceedings of the 1990 Stanford Symposium on Democracy, Diversity, and News Media Ownership. Owen, Bruce M. (1996), ‘Book Reviw of G.W. Brock, Telecommunications Policy for the Information age’, Journal of Economic Literature. Owen, Bruce M. and Gottlieb, Paul D. (1986), ‘The Rise and Fall and Rise of Cable Television Regulation,’, in Weiss, Leonard W. and Klass, Michael W. (ed.), Regulatory Reform: What Actually Happened, Boston, Little Brown. Owen, Bruce M. and Greenhalgh, P.R. (1986), ‘Competitive Policy Considerations in Cable Television Franchising’, 4 Contemporary Policy Issues, 69 ff. Owen, Bruce M. and Manning, W.G., Jr (1974), Television Economics, Lexington, D.C. Heath. Owen, Bruce M. et al. (1973), Analysis of the Causes and Effects of Increases in Same-Year Rerun Programming and Related Issues in Prime Time Network Television, Office of Telecommunications Policy, Executive Office of the President. Owen, Bruce M. et al. (1993), ‘Cable Rate Regulation - A Multi-Stage Benchmark Approach’, Economists Incorporated. Owen, Bruce M. et al. (1995a), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Broadcast Television National Ownership, Local Ownership and Cross-Ownership Rules’, Economists Incorporated. Owen, Bruce M. et al. (1995b), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Prime Time Acces Rule, March 7, 1995, and A Supplementary Analysis of the Prime Time Acces Rule’, Economists Incorporated. Owen, Bruce M. and Wildman, S.S. (1992), Video Economics, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Pacey, Patricia L. (1985), ‘Cable Television in a Less Regulated Market’, 34 Journal of Industrial Economics, 81-91. Pera, Alberto (1989), ‘Deregulation and Privatisation in an Economy Wide Context’, 0(12) OECD Economic Studies, 159-204. Perrakis, Stylianos and Silva Echenique, Julio (1983), ‘The Profitability and Risk of CATV Operations in Canada’, 15 Applied Economics, 745-758. Peterman, John L. (1965), ‘The Structure of National Time Rates in the Television Broadcasting Industry’, 8 Journal of Law and Economics, 77-131. Peterman, John L. (1968), ‘The Clorox Case and the Television Rate Structures’, 11 Journal of Law and Economics, 321-422. Picard, Pierre (1988), ‘La Tarification Optimale des Télécommunications: une Présentation Synthetique (Optimal Pricing for Telecommunications: An Overview)’, 0(12) Annales d’Economie et de Statistique, 27-62.
1160
Telecommunications
5930
Richter, Wolfram F. and Weimann, Joachim (1985), ‘Ramsey Pricing the Telephone Services of the Deutsche Bundespost’, 141 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 516-524. Rowley, Charles K. (1966), The British Monopolies Commission, London, Allen and Unwin. Rubin, Paul H. and Dezhbakhsh, Hashem (1995), ‘Costs of Delay and Rent-Seeking Under the Modification of Final Judgment’, Managerial and Decision Economics, 385-400. Samuelson, Paul A. (1964), ‘Public Goods and Subscription TV: Correction of the Record’, 7 Journal of Law and Economics, 81-83. Sardinas, Joseph L., Jr (1987), ‘Regulation of International Data Communications and the Effect upon Multinational Corporations’, in Most, Kenneth S. (ed.), Advances in International Accounting, Vol. 1, Greenwood, JAI Press, 305-315. Schenk, Karl-Ernst, Schmidtchen, Dieter and Streit, Manfred E. (eds) (1997), Neue Politische Ökonomie der Integration und Öffnung von Infrastrukturnetzen Jahrbuch für Neue Politische Ökonomie 16 (Integration of and Access to Infrastructural Networks), Tübingen, Mohr. Schmandt, Jurgen, Williams, Frederick and Wilson, Robert H. (eds) (1989), Telecommunications Policy and Economic Development, New York, Greenwood Press, 299 p. Shedd, M.S., Wilman, Elizabeth A. and Burch, R. Douglas (1990), ‘An Economic Analysis of Canadian Content Regulations and a New Proposal’, 16 Canadian Public Policy, 60-72. Smiley, Albert K. (1990), ‘Regulation and Competition in Cable Television’, 7 Yale Journal on Regulation, 121-139. Snow, Marcellus S. (1986), Marketplace for Telecommunications: Regulation and Deregulation in Industrialized Democracies, New York, Longman, 304 p. Snow, Marcellus S. (1988), ‘The State as Stopgap: Social Economy and Sustainability of Monopoly in the Telecommunications Sector’, 46 Review of Social Economy, 1-23. Snow, Marcellus S. and Jussawalla, Meheroo (1986), Telecommunication Economics and International Regulatory Policy: An Annotated Bibliography, New York, Greenwood Press, 216 p. Spence, M. and Owen, Bruce M. (1977), ‘Television Programming, Monopolistic Competition and Welfare’, 91 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 103 ff. Teske, Paul E. (1991), ‘Rent-Seeking in the Deregulatory Environment: State Telecommunications’, 68 Public Choice, 235-243. Trebing, Harry M. (1986), ‘Apologetics of Deregulation in Energy and Telecommuniciations: An Institutionalist Assessment’, 20 Journal of Economic Issues, 613-632. Vietor, Richard H.K. and Davidson, Dekkers L. (1985), ‘Economics and Politics of Deregulation: The Issue of Telephone Access Charges’, 5 Journal of Policy Analysis and Management, 3-22. Voigt, Stefan (1992), ‘Das Lizenzauktionsverfahren, Ein zielkonformes Instrument zur Regulierung lokaler Kabelfernsehstationen? Eine Analyse der anglo-amerikanischen Diskussion und Praxis (The Licence Auctioning System as an Instrument to Regulate Local Cable Stations)’, 17 The European Journal of Communications, 67-90.
5930
Telecommunications
1161
Von Weizsacker, C. Christian (1984), ‘Free Entry into Telecommunications?’, 1(3) Information Economics and Policy, 197-216. Weisman, Dennis L. (1988), ‘Default Capacity Tariffs: Smoothing the Transitional Regulatory Asymmetries in the Telecommunications Market’, 5 Yale Journal on Regulation, 149-178. Wenders, John T. (1987), The Economics of Telecommunications: Theory and Policy, Cambridge, MA, Harper and Row, 284 p. Wildman, S.S. and Owen, Bruce M. (1985), ‘Program Competition in the New Video Industry’, in Noam, Eli H. (ed.), Rivalry Among the Video Transmission Media, Columbia University Press. X (1967), ‘Broadcasting, Public Policy, and the First Amendment’, 10 Journal of Law and Economics, 15-49. Zupan, Mark A. (1989), ‘Non-price Concessions and the Effect of Franchise Bidding Schemes on Cable Company Costs’, 21 Applied Economics, 305-323.
5940 PUBLIC UTILITIES Rick Geddes Assistant Professor, Department of Economics, Fordham University © Copyright 1999 Rick Geddes
Abstract In this chapter, I review the literature on public utilities. Public utilities include a wide range of industries, such as electricity, water, telecommunications, cable television, and railroads, among others. These industries share similar characteristics. I first examine utilities generally in the Introduction, focusing on issues common to them. I review alternative theories of why utilities have historically been either regulated or government-owned. In Part A, I examine the effects of regulatory reform, and the distortionary effects of utility regulation. I find that the effect of utility regulatory reform in the US has been positive. In Part B, I apply many of these general concerns to the US electric utility industry. I examine the regulatory history of this industry, the effects of structural change, the recovery of stranded costs, the natural industry structure, and issues of reliability. In Part C, I provide a brief overview of the literature on other utilities, including telephones, natural gas, and water utilities. In Part D, I summarize the literature on European utilities. JEL classification: K23, L43, L51, L9 Keywords: Utilities, Network Industries, Regulatory Reform
1. Introduction The term ‘public utility’ encompasses a wide variety of industries including, among others, airlines, telecommunications, oil, natural gas, electricity, trucking, cable television and railroads. These industries share a common ‘network’ structure, in that they have an extensive distribution system of lines, pipes, or routes requiring the use of public rights of way, often with strong physical linkages between component parts. In some cases, such as airlines, government owns a part of the infrastructure. Public utilities typically have substantial sunk costs because of the need for extensive infrastructure. Historically, utilities, where privately owned, have been rate-of-return regulated. Utilities are government-owned in some jurisdictions. In almost all cases, utilities have been granted legally enforced monopolies over their service territories. Public utilities have, in many jurisdictions, experienced regulatory reform. Reform has typically been in the form of increased competition through more 1162
5940
Public Utilities
1163
liberal entry. In some cases, the oil price shocks of the early 1970s de-stabilized the regulatory process. In others, new technologies made the old regulatory regime untenable. The paradigm for utility regulation has therefore changed dramatically. Where once regulated or government-owned monopolies dominated because of the belief that most utilities were ‘natural monopolies’, there is now a growing consensus that competition can perform a broader and more effective role. The social importance of public utilities collectively is huge, and the literature on them is correspondingly vast. I therefore focus on several salient issues. In Part A below, I survey several areas of the literature which are relevant for all utilities, including their structural similarities, the rationale for regulation, and the experience with regulatory reform. In Part B, I examine a more specific case, that of US electric utilities, and indicate how these general concerns apply in that industry. I then follow in Part C with brief discussions of telephone, natural gas, and water utilities. In Part D, I review the literature on European utilities.
A. An Overview of Utilities and Regulation In this part, I provide an overview of literature concerning regulation and utilities generally. I first discuss the structural similarities shared by utilities. I then review the literature on the various rationales for government intervention in these industries. This includes the ‘public interest’, ‘capture’, ‘economic’ and ‘contestability’ theories. In Section 4, I survey the distortionary effects of regulation, and then move on to the effects of regulatory reform. I conclude the part with a brief review of the literature on ownership form.
2. The Structural Similarities of Utilities Utilities typically create a good or service at one location, and then distribute it over a ‘network’ where it is delivered to numerous customers for end use. The use of a network structure creates special issues for utilities. The network often exhibits economies of scale and involves substantial sunk costs, so the issue of natural monopoly has played an important role in utility literature. The network may require the use of public streets or other rights of way, so government involvement is of particular concern. Since several firms often utilize the network, there are ‘network externalities’ or congestion if its use is not properly priced. The activities of utilities can be broken down into three components: production, transmission, and distribution. While the production component has, in the US, been almost exclusively privately owned, the transmission and distribution stages have been either private or government-owned. For example,
1164
Public Utilities
5940
in trucking and airlines, government-owned street, highways and airports are utilized. A useful way of describing this common structure in six utilities is illustrated in Table 1. Table 1 The Three Components of Six Utilities Industry
Production
Transmission
Distribution
Airlines
Airplanes
Air traffic control
Airports
Trucking
Trucks
Highways
Local streets, distribution centers
Telecoms Telecom terminal equipment
Long-distance cos. and local Local telecoms telecoms
Electricity Generating plants
High-voltage lines
Local power lines
Natural gas
Interstate pipelines
Local distribution companies
Trunk lines
Local sidings
Gas wells
Railroads Trains
Source: Crandall and Ellig (1997, p. 70) In some regulated utilities, the firm is fully ‘vertically integrated’ into all three activities, and a salient issue is the ‘unbundling’ of these functions under competition. Most commentators now agree that the production stage is inherently competitive in most utilities, so that different firms may perform the production and transmission/distribution functions (Crandall and Ellig, 1997). The focus is then on the proper structure for the transmission and distribution segments of the business, with particular attention paid to the question of entry by competitors, or ‘access’ to transmission and distribution infrastructure.
3. The Rationale for Regulation of Utilities As noted above, government entities have historically regulated utilities extensively. The debate in the academic literature over the rationale for this
5940
Public Utilities
1165
intervention has accordingly been considerable. The literature falls into two broad categories: positive and normative. The normative, or ‘public interest’ strand provides rationales for how and why government ought to intervene in utilities, typically pointing out ‘market failures’, or situations in which government intervention could, in theory, improve market operation. According to this approach, government enacts regulation in response to a market failure. This view was dubbed ‘normative analysis as positive theory’ (or NPT) by Joskow and Noll (1981) since it purports to explain what regulation ought to do. Natural monopoly theory has historically provided perhaps the most important public interest rationale for utility regulation. This theory holds that an industry is ‘naturally monopolistic’ if its product can be produced at least cost by a single firm. Traditionally, this was thought to be the case where a firm produces a single good and its long-run average cost curve is declining throughout the entire range of output. Therefore, to achieve productive efficiency, it is necessary to have only one firm operating in the industry (thus justifying legally protected, monopoly service territories). At the same time, this monopoly had to be regulated to prevent price gouging and to ensure it earned a ‘fair’ rate of return on its investment (Moorhouse, 1995, p. 423). Alternatively, this could be achieved through state ownership of the utility, as was more frequently the case in Europe. In this way, regulation (or ownership) would ensure both productive and allocative efficiency. There are at least four reasons why scholars, over time, became dissatisfied with the normative approach to utility regulation. Perhaps most importantly, it is at odds with empirical evidence. The incidence of regulation appears to be unrelated to the incidence of the observed characteristics of natural monopoly (Posner, 1974). Regulation occurs in many industries where the normative approach provides no rationale for it, such as potentially very competitive industries, including trucking and taxicabs. Second, since a firm’s profits are likely to be reduced if they are regulated in the public interest, the normative approach implies that firms are unlikely to favor regulation. Yet history shows that many regulated utilities actually lobbied for regulation (Viscusi, Vernon and Harrington, 1995, p. 326). Third, empirical evidence suggests that the prices of regulated firms do not behave as suggested by the normative approach. If regulation is designed to prevent monopoly gouging, then prices should decline when regulation is imposed. Stigler and Friedland (1962) examined electric utility prices from 1912 to 1937 and found that regulation had an insignificant effect on output prices. Fourth, this approach has been criticized because of its lack of a mechanism to translate market failure into regulation. That is, no model is provided of the economic behavior of regulators and interest groups which would lead to the suggested outcomes. Many bodies of research have dealt with these issues. I discuss two below: the ‘economic theory of regulation’ and ‘contestability theory’.
1166
Public Utilities
5940
The shortcomings of the normative approach led to the development of alternative theories of utility regulation. The initial attempt was provided by what came to be known as ‘capture theory’ (Jordan, 1972). Whereas regulation under the normative theory was presumed to be in the interest of consumers, under capture theory it was presumed to be in the interest of producers. This theory was able to provide answers to criticisms one, two and three, and was more consistent with available data. However, it also suffered from the fourth criticism. The capture theory did not provide any theoretical underpinnings of regulatory behavior. This led to a series of papers which attempted to provide a theoretical model and generate refutable hypotheses about the effects of regulation. This body of work became known as the ‘economic theory of regulation’ (ET). Its literature includes, among others, Coase (1959), Posner (1971, 1974), Stigler (1971) and Becker (1983). An excellent summary of this debate and its literature is provided in Priest (1993). Perhaps the most comprehensive theoretical treatment was provided in Peltzman (1976). While there are several implications of the theory, three are critical: (i) in a regulated environment, groups with low organization costs are likely to receive a disproportionate amount of economic rent; (ii) cost-based cross-subsidization is a likely outcome of the regulatory process; and (iii) in general, rents are likely to be spread among several competing groups, including politically influential consumers, rather than captured by only one constituency group, such as producers. Perhaps the most important prediction of the economic theory is that small, highly organized groups will be net winners in the regulatory process. Stigler (1971) emphasized the information and organization costs that groups face in delivering benefits to regulators. Groups that are low-cost providers of these benefits enjoy a comparative advantage in the regulatory process. The numerically smaller group will tend to face lower organization costs. Typically, the number of buyers is less than the number of sellers, so the theory predicts that regulation will benefit producers at the expense of consumers, as is frequently observed. An additional refinement of the ET in Peltzman (1976) is that regulators will allocate rents across both consumer and producer groups so as to maximize their total political support, and rents will likely fall into the hands of some consumers as well. Rent-spreading among consumers manifests itself through prices which attenuate differences in marginal cost across consumers. The ET predicts that there will be a tendency for high-cost consumers to receive a relatively low price-marginal cost ratio, which constitutes a cross-subsidy from low-cost to high-cost consumers. Indeed, a substantial empirical literature bears out many predictions of the economic theory, but inconsistencies with the data remain. Viscusi, Vernon and Harrington (1995, p. 341) provide a summary.
5940
Public Utilities
1167
A second line of research, which also questioned the natural monopoly rationale for regulation began with Demsetz (1968). He showed that there is a theoretical inconsistency in natural monopoly theory: the existence of a single producer in the market need not lead to monopolistic pricing. It is possible for competitors to bid for the right to serve the market. The threat of potential entry may discipline markets which have very few, or only one, producer actually in the market. Demsetz’s work highlighted the notion of what is now termed ‘potential competition’. This basic concept was vigorously analyzed in a series of papers developing ‘contestability’ theory. Willig (1980) first examined this notion in detail by applying it to postal markets. His inquiry led to a benchmark idealized market termed a ‘contestable’ market. As Baumol, Panzar and Willig (1988, p. xiii) state, ‘A perfectly contestable market is defined as one in which entry and exit are easy and costless, which may or may not be characterized by economies of scale or scope, but which has no entry barriers’. This notion was further developed in a series of papers, including Baumol, Bailey and Willig (1977) and Bailey and Panzar (1981). Eventually, Baumol, Panzar, and Willig (1988) published this body of work in a book entitled Contestable Markets and the Theory of Market Structure. This work called into question the original notion of natural monopoly and therefore the justification for monopoly rate-of-return style regulation of these firms. This theoretical approach encouraged a number of studies of the contestability of natural monopolies, including Coursey, Issac and Smith (1984) who used an experimental approach and concluded that (p. 111): The most significant result ... is that the behavioral predictions of the contestable market hypothesis are fundamentally correct. It is simply not true that monopoly pricing is a ‘natural’ result of a market merely because firms in the market exhibit decreasing costs and demand is sufficient to support no more than a single firm.
Moreover, serious theoretical problems with the traditional natural monopoly view arise when multi-product firms are considered. Almost all utilities produce more than one product. For example, utilities produce both peak and off-peak power, and telephone companies provide both local and long-distance phone service. In an important article, Baumol (1977) investigated the relationship between economies of scale and natural monopoly. He showed that the correct definition of natural monopoly is not that long-run average costs decline, but that the cost function is ‘sub-additive’. Briefly, subadditivity asks the question of whether it is more or less costly for two or more firms to produce the output rather than one firm. This is, therefore, a more appealing definition of natural monopoly. The cost curve is subadditive if one firm can produce a given output
1168
Public Utilities
5940
more cheaply than two or more firms. This analysis pointed out that economies of scale are a sufficient but not a necessary condition for the existence of natural monopoly. In the multi-product case, Baumol showed that economies of scale are neither necessary nor sufficient for the sub-additivity of costs. This is because of the interdependence of outputs in the multi-product case. An industry is a natural monopoly only if the firm’s cost function is subadditive over the entire range of outputs (Baumol, Panzar and Willig, 1982, p. 17). Inspired by Baumol, Panzar and Willig and other contestability literature, Gilsdorf (1995) tests for the subadditivity of vertically integrated electric utilities, and finds that there is no evidence for subadditivity in this industry. Gilsdorf thus concludes that integrated utilities are not multistage natural monopolies, thereby casting further doubt on the natural monopoly status of electric utilities. In interpreting the contestability literature, Moorhouse (1995, p. 425) concludes, ‘Thus this research suggests that competition can be substituted for government regulation and state ownership to assure good performance in, at least, the generation of electricity’. These literatures have led to a widespread change of perceptions in the need for and rationale for utility regulation. It is probable that they helped promote regulatory reform in many industries. An important question is the consequences of reform, which I discuss below.
4. The Effects of Regulatory Reform The term ‘regulatory reform’ itself has a variety of meanings. Here I focus on ‘deregulation’, using it in the sense of Stigler (1981) and Winston (1993): the withdrawal of the state’s legal powers to direct the economic conduct of non-governmental bodies. While this can occur in a variety of ways, most typically in utilities it refers to the relaxation of price, entry and/or exit controls. A wave of deregulation which began in the mid-1970s and which continues today has swept aside some of the most restrictive regulatory structures created in the US in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. Regulated industries produced 17 percent of US GNP in 1977; by 1988 this had fallen to 6.6 percent (Winston, 1993, p. 1263). Continuing deregulation of electric utilities in some states, and of some aspects of telecommunications, further reduces this proportion. In this section, I review US deregulation’s effects in six industries, including airlines, trucking, telecommunications, cable television, railroads and natural gas. Winston’s (1993) survey of the literature provides an excellent overview of the outcomes. Since most economic deregulation in the US was complete by that time (and had a chance to have its full effect) it is possible to study its impact meaningfully. Winston compiled estimates of deregulation’s
5940
Public Utilities
1169
effects across a vast literature, and presented the range of estimates in the form of billions of annual 1990 US dollars. More recently, Crandall and Ellig (1997) summarized a large body of evidence on five industries (natural gas, telecommunications, airlines, railroads and trucking), examining evidence on price, quantity and quality. Here I report Winston’s estimates for selected industries and variables, and review Crandall and Ellig’s results, where applicable. In Table 2 below, I summarize estimates from Winston (1993) on the effects of deregulation on prices and, in some cases, service. A positive number in column 3 indicates a gain for consumers due to lower prices or improved service. With the exception of the lowest estimates for railroads, US consumers uniformly benefited from deregulation. For example, airline customers gained between $4.3 billion and $6.5 billion per year (in 1990 dollars) through lower fares from deregulation of airlines. They gained approximately $8.5 billion from greater frequency of service, but lost $3 billion from increased travel restrictions. Table 2 Summary of the Assessed Effects of Regulatory Reform on Prices and Service Industry
Effect on:
Outcome ($ bill.)
Airlines
Fares Service frequency Travel restrictions
Trucking
Common carrier rates Private carrier rates
Long-Distance Telecommunications
Rates
(0.73, 1.6)
Cable TV
Price and Service
(0.37, 1.3)
(4.3, 6.5) 8.5 -3.0 7.8 6.0
Railroads Rates (-2.1, 0.43) Source: Winston (1993, pp.1274-1275). Positive values indicate consumer gains. Values are in billions of 1990 dollars. In terms of percentage declines in airline fares, Crandall and Ellig (1997, p. 34) note that ‘yields’ (the average amount of revenue received per passenger mile) are commonly used by analysts to measure fare trends, and state:
1170
Public Utilities
5940
... the average yield fell from 21.65 cents in 1977 to 13.76 cents in 1995, a 37-percent reduction. Much of this decline occurred during the first 10 years of deregulation, when the yield fell by 29 percent, from $21.65 to $15.32. Interestingly, yields fell almost immediately in response to deregulation.
Crandall and Ellig (1997) also document the fall in the price of natural gas after deregulation. Adjusting for inflation, they find that wellhead prices fell by 60 percent between 1984 and 1995. They discovered that the prices actually paid by various classes of consumers (for example, residential, commercial, electric utility) also decreased significantly. Regarding interstate telecommunications rates, they find that after the AT&T divestiture in 1984, the Consumer Price Index for interstate long distance rates decreased from approximately 60 in 1984 to about 30 today. The intrastate rates have also fallen, but somewhat less rapidly. In Table 3, I report the findings of Crandall and Ellig on percent price reductions in five utilities two, five and ten years after deregulation. For ten years, they range from a low of 27 percent to a high of 57 percent, but they were uniformly positive. Collectively, these results suggest that deregulation of utilities provide benefits for consumers. Table 3 A Summary of Price Reductions from Deregulation in the United States Industry
Percent price reduction after . . . 2 years
5 years
10 years
Natural Gas
10-38% (1984-86)
23-45% (1984-89)
27-57% (1984-94)
Long-distance telecomm.
5-16% (1984-86)
23-41% (1984-89)
40-47% (1984-94)
Airlines
13% (1977-79)
12% (1977-82)
29% (1977-97)
Trucking
N.A.
3-17% (1980-85)
28-56% (1977-87)
Railroads
4% (1980-82)
20% (1980-84)
44% (1980-90)
Source: Crandall and Ellig (1997, p. 2)
5940
Public Utilities
1171
Winston also examined the effects of regulatory reform on profits. In Table 4 below, I report the effects of US deregulation on profits. Positive numbers represent profit gains. Table 4 Summary of the Assessed Effects of Regulatory Reform on Profits Industry
Outcome ($ bill.)
Airlines
4.9
Trucking
-4.8
Long-distance Telecommunications Cable TV
Small change Increase
Railroads 3.2 Source: Winston (1993, pp. 1278-1279). Positive values indicate a profit gain. Values are in billions of 1990 dollars. Most utilities experienced a profit gain from deregulation, with airlines enjoying the largest gain of $4.9 billion annually. The trucking industry is an anomaly, since it lost $4.8 billion annually from deregulation. The political economy behind trucking deregulation remains a mystery, since the economic theory of regulation predicts that the relatively small number of highly organized trucking companies would have successfully blocked deregulation, but did not. For most industries, then, deregulation increased profits, or at least did not significantly reduce them. In Table 5 below, I present Winston’s summary of the estimates of deregulation’s effect on wages and employment. Positive numbers indicate a gain to labor. While airlines experienced a small decline in wages, deregulation there led to an increase in employment, most likely due to an increase in the frequency of flights. Trucking experienced a decline in both wages and employment, suggesting that firms and workers shared the lost monopoly rents (Rose, 1985). Railroad workers also suffered a substantial decline in wages, while employment was not affected.
1172
Public Utilities
5940
Table 5 Summary of the Assessed Effects of Regulatory Reform on Wages and Employment Industry
Effect on:
Outcome ($ bill.)
Airlines
Wages Employment
Small decline Increase 6%
Trucking
Wages Employment
(-1.1,-1.9) Decline
Long-distance telecommunications
Wages (comm.) Wages (equip.)
No change Decline
Cable TV
Wages Employment
No assessment Increase
Railroads
Wages Employment
Decline 20% No Effect
Source: Winston (1993, p. 1282). Positive values indicate a gain to labor. Values are in billions of 1990 dollars. Given that some groups benefited while others lost, it is important to consider the net effects of deregulation. In Table 6, I report findings from Winston (1993) on the overall effects of regulatory reform in the US. This table sums the effects on both consumers and producers to obtain a total or ‘net’ effect of deregulation in that industry. Positive numbers in the ‘Total’ column indicate that deregulation overall produced a welfare gain. For all six industries examined here, the net effect was clearly positive, indicating that any welfare loss by producers (for example, truckers) were outweighed by consumer gains. Net gains thus suggest improvements in economic efficiency, most of which were captured by consumers. Winston notes that, when gains are summed across industries, society gained at least $36-$46 billion annually from deregulation. Estimates of total social gains are higher if firms are assumed to adjust optimaly to deregulation.
5940
Public Utilities
1173
Table 6 Summary of the Assessed Effects of Regulatory Reform Overall Industry
Consumers
Producers
Total
Airlines
(8.8, 14.8)
4.9
(13.9, 19.7)
Trucking
15.4
-4.8
10.6
Long-distance telecommunications
(0.73, 1.6)
___
(0.73, 1.6)
Cable TV
(0.37, 1.3)
___
(0.37, 1.3)
Railroads (7.2, 9.7) 3.2 (10.4, 12.9) Source: Winston (1993, p. 1284). Positive values indicate a gain to labor. Values are in billions of 1990 dollars. These estimates suggest that deregulation of numerous utilities in the US produced substantial social gains. It is therefore probable that utility regulation created a variety of economic distortions, which I discuss below.
5. Distortionary Effects of Regulation Several branches of research relating to utilities have focused on the distortionary effects of rate-of-return regulation. Here I review two branches of this extensive literature. One branch studies the effect of rate-of-return regulation on the firm’s input mix. In a seminal article, Averch and Johnson (1962) developed a model which implied that rate-of-return regulation would cause an industry to utilize a greater than optimal amount of capital. Early studies, including those by Baumol and Klevorick (1970), and Bailey and Malone (1970) and Zajac (1970), generalized the Averch-Johnson conclusions and found that there is an incentive for overuse of the rate-regulated input and over-production of output. Studies by Courville (1974), Spann (1974) and Boyes (1976) found empirical support for the Averch-Johnson predictions. These models were often based on certainty of demand and price, and were subsequently criticized for this. A new series of papers by Perrakis (1976), Meyer (1976), Peles and Stein (1976) and Das (1980) introduced uncertainty, and concluded that the existence of the effect was dubious. Baron and Taggert (1977) found under-capitalization. The results appear to be susceptible to the type of uncertainty introduced.
1174
Public Utilities
5940
A relatively new area of inquiry involves the question of the effect of the regulatory process on the internal structure of the firm. While this research itself has several branches, a main focus is regulation’s effects on senior executive behavior. Important variables considered include CEO pay and turnover. Alternative views of regulation’s effect on CEO pay include a ‘productivity hypothesis’, in which regulation reduces the complexity of the tasks performed by managers (Peltzman, 1989). Under these circumstances, it is efficient for firms to pay CEOs less, and to hire less able CEOs. An alternative is a ‘political pressure’ hypothesis, which suggests that the regulatory process politicizes certain firm choices, including CEO pay. Joskow, Rose and Shepard (1993) for example, argue that there are political constraints on executive compensation. A body of research has established that CEOs of regulated firms are, in fact, paid significantly less than those of unregulated firms. Joskow, Rose and Shepard (1993), after controlling for firm size, firm performance and characteristics of the CEO, find that the chief executive is paid less if the firm is regulated. Carroll and Ciscel (1982) find that regulation reduces the basic annual compensation of the chief executive. They suggest that lower risk, less CEO discretion, and political constraints may all help explain the lower observed compensation. Joskow, Rose and Wolfram (1996) attempt to distinguish between these explanations by examining differing regulatory environments. They evaluate alternative environments by how ‘pro-consumer’ they are as rated by an investment bank. They find that CEOs are paid less in relatively pro-consumer environments, and conclude that a political pressure view is supported. Regarding turnover, Geddes (1997) examines the turnover of senior executives of regulated firms and finds that it is not sensitive to the financial performance of the firm. This is important since researchers examining non-regulated firms have found such a relationship. Turnover of utility executives is, however, related to changes in the price of output. Higher electricity prices increase the probability that the identity of the CEO will change. This result is consistent with estimates in Joskow, Rose and Wolfram (1996) which show that pay is inversely related to the rate of growth of electricity prices. These latter results are also consistent with a ‘political pressure’ view of CEO behavior. In addition to regulation, the effects of and correct type of ownership form for utilities has been a matter of much discussion. Below I review literature in this area.
5940
Public Utilities
1175
6. Ownership Form The debate over government versus private ownership of utilities has always been a lively one. Early economists believed that there was a strong case for government ownership, which was dependent on their ‘natural monopoly’ structure, as discussed above. As Hausman and Neufeld (1991, p. 414) state, ‘[p]rominent founding members of the American Economic Association, including Richard T. Ely, Henry C. Adams, E.W. Bemis, Edmund J. James, and E.R.A. Seligman, rejected laissez-faire public policy and advocated government ownership of a class of businesses which they designated “natural” monopolies, including municipal gas companies, water-works, and electric utilities’. While there appears to be no generally accepted formal model of the effects of ownership form on firm behavior, Boardman and Vining (1989, p. 2) state ‘the dominant positive model of the effect of ownership is the public choice, or property rights, model’. Some authors have argued on theoretical grounds that privately owned firms should exhibit greater internal efficiency in the production of goods and services than publicly owned firms. De Alessi (1974, 1980) suggested that this was due to the inability of the owners of public enterprises to effectively incorporate the benefits of additional managerial monitoring into current transfer prices of the firm: The crucial difference between private and political [publicly owned] firms is that ownership in the latter effectively is nontransferable. Since this rules out specialization in their ownership, it inhibits the capitalization of future consequences into current transfer prices and reduces owners’ incentives to monitor managerial behavior. (De Alessi 1980, pp. 27-28)
Owners of public firms thus have less incentive to monitor managers, and the cost to public managers of taking additional non-pecuniary benefits, including shirking, is lower. De Alessi argued that public managers have more job security which will be manifested in longer tenure periods. He tested this proposition in De Alessi (1974) and found that public managers did exhibit longer tenure periods. Geddes (1997), however, re-estimated the De Alessi tests with a larger data set and more control variables, and found no significant difference in tenure periods across the two ownership forms. Spann (1977) attributed expected efficiency differences to two factors. First, public firms do not have the incentive to minimize costs as do private, profit-maximizing firms. Second, private firms naturally gravitate to the optimal size while public firms are restricted by political boundaries. Alchian and Demsetz (1972) and Frech (1976) suggested that there is a greater incentive for public employees to shirk since their wealth is not as closely tied
1176
Public Utilities
5940
to the work decisions they make. Other researchers have argued in a similar vein, including, among others, Davies (1971, 1977), Moore (1970), and Crain and Zardkoohi (1978). The available evidence indicates that the relative performance of public and private enterprise is also dependent upon the structure of the industry in which they operate, as well as ownership form. For example, Boardman and Vining (1989) examine the effect of ownership form on profitability and efficiency in a number of competitive industries. They find that dummy variables for both mixed and state-owned enterprises exert significant and negative effects on profitability and other measurers of performance. For valuable surveys of this literature, see De Alessi (1980) or Boardman and Vining (1989). Numerous researchers have examined the question of the efficiency of public versus privately owned electric utilities in particular. The literature has been characterized by increasing rigor in the econometric tests of efficiency used as well as changes in the conclusions of these tests. Moore (1970) used a model with linear input and cost equations and found that private electric utilities are 5 percent more efficient than municipal utilities. Meyer (1975a) used a quadratic function to estimate costs for public and private utilities, and concluded that publicly owned utilities are more efficient. Neuberg (1977) estimated that public firms are 6-20 percent more efficient, and Pescatrice and Trapani (1980) estimated public firms to be 33 percent more efficient. Using a variety of econometric methods, more recent investigations of relative cost efficiency have indicated that the two ownership forms display few significant differences. This list includes DiLorenzo and Robinson (1982), and Fare, Grosskopf and Logan (1985). Atkinson and Halvorsen (1986) estimated relative efficiency using a translog cost function and reached a similar conclusion. As Vickers and Yarrow (1988, p. 41) state: Taken in conjunction with the research on U.S. electric utilities, we are therefore led to the conclusion that, where firms face little output market competition and are extensively regulated, there is no generally decisive evidence in favor of one type or the other type of ownership.
A unique alternative approach is taken in Hausman and Neufeld (1991). They examine the very early period in the industry’s history (1897/98) in order to examine the relative efficiency of government versus privately owned utilities prior to state rate-of-return regulation. Using a non-parametric approach, they find that in this period government-owned utilities were relatively more efficient than their privately owned counterparts. They suggest that this finding is inconsistent with the property rights view of ownership, and attribute the observed difference to a greater ‘public spirit’ associated with the operation of government-owned utilities.
5940
Public Utilities
1177
The question of ownership and efficiency is still very much alive. Most recently, Pollitt (1996) in the Oxford Economic Papers examines government and privately owned nuclear power plants in the US and UK, using data envelopment analysis. He found that, when vintage effects and poor investment decisions were taken into account, there was some evidence that privately owned nuclear plants had lower costs.
B. The US Electric Utility Industry In this section, I examine a particular utility industry in detail. I focus on the electric utility industry in the United States. Many of the issues discussed above that are common to many utilities are particularly important in the electric utility industry. I first examine the history of regulation of this industry, and some interpretations of it. I focus on electricity for four reasons. First, as measured by total assets, it is an extremely large industry. In the US, it is the largest. Second, of all the services, electricity may be the most ‘fundamental’ in that most other utilities require it for their operation. Third, it is often considered the industry with the most ‘natural monopoly’ characteristics. Finally, many of the issues in electric utilities (such as the unbundling of services and the distortionary effects of rate-of-return regulation) are similar to those in other public utilities. I examine several aspects of the industry. I first review the regulatory history of the industry. This history is particularly pertinent today, since regulatory reform is underway in many places and under consideration in others. It is also illustrative of the application of the economic theory of regulation. In Section 8, I examine the effects of the economic shocks of the early 1970s on the industry, and discuss institutional changes that occurred as a result. In Section 9, I look at legislative acts which affected the industry, including the Public Utility Regulatory Policies Act of 1978, and the Energy Policy Act of 1992. I then move on, in Section 10, to summarize the current thinking on a critical policy question resulting from deregulation: whether or not utilities should be allowed to recover the cost of investments that are ‘stranded’ through open access to the transmission grid. In Sections 11 and 12, I examine the issues of industry structure and reliability, respectively.
7. Regulatory History of the Industry The founding of the electric utility industry is generally placed at 1879, when electricity was first used to light streets and some buildings (Bradley, 1996, p. 60). In its earliest stage, neither the states nor the federal government regulated
1178
Public Utilities
5940
the industry. Since cities and towns had to grant utilities the right to use public streets, the regulation of entry was de facto controlled by municipalities. Jarrell (1982) argues that at this time there was competition between firms, as cities often granted franchises to numerous companies in the same area. Indeed, this era of contending municipal franchises is known as ‘regulation by competition’ (Bradley, 1996, p. 60). With the passage in New York and Wisconsin in 1907 of landmark statutes which granted utilities monopoly power and created strong state utility commissions, the states entered the regulatory arena. The justification for this early state regulation of the industry has spawned substantial controversy, which continues today. Economists such as John R. Commons enjoyed formulating justifications for powerful regulation (Michaels, 1996, p. 48). These early economists explained that the industry had been regulated in order to correct ‘natural monopoly-style’ market failures, as discussed above. Questioning such a view, Jarrell (1982) argued that state electricity regulation was not designed to counter natural monopoly problems, the theory of which was developed later (Bradley, 1996; Priest, 1993). Instead, he asserted that utilities sought out the state’s regulation in order to protect them from intensively competitive conditions under municipal franchising. Jarrell thus relies on the economic theory of regulation to explain the evolution of electricity regulation. To test these alternatives, Jarrell divided states into two groups: those which passed regulation in an early wave of state reforms from 1912 to 1917, and those which passed regulation later and more slowly, after 1917. The normative theory predicts that regulation will be supplied earliest in states where natural monopoly problems are the most severe; where prices and profits are the highest, and output the lowest, since these states were most in need of regulation. The economic theory predicts the opposite; since regulation was established to create economic rents by shielding firms from competition, regulation will occur first in those states where prices and profits were the lowest. Jarrell found that those states which adopted regulation early had, on average, 45 percent lower prices, 30 percent lower profits and 25 percent higher per capita output before regulation than the states which adopted regulation later. This and other evidence lead Jarrell to conclude that regulation was passed in order to shield firms from competitive conditions prevailing when municipalities were the sole regulators. Bradley (1996) also examines the origins of state regulation of electricity. He focuses on the effect of utility interests (for example, Samuel Insull) pushing for regulation and suggests that it was an act of political opportunism designed to protect utilities from competition. Bradley concludes that, because the original motivation for government intervention in the utility industry was not due to market failure, the case for the industry’s deregulation today is stronger.
5940
Public Utilities
1179
8. The Effects of Structural Change Regardless of their justification, these regulatory arrangements were relatively stable until at least the late 1960s. Joskow (1989) presents a comprehensive analysis of the changes in the industry through the 1960s, 1970s and 1980s. He documents the economic forces which led to major changes in the industry’s regulation. The same basic economic forces were operating on utilities throughout the world. Joskow’s discussion is briefly summarized here. The decades of the 1950s and 1960s were relatively uneventful for the electric utility industry. The industry benefited from technological progress and economies of scale in generation, which led to falling nominal and real prices for electricity. Utilities performed well financially and rarely filed for rate increases, but instead often voluntarily decreased their rates. The regulatory system of extensive price and entry review by state and federal agencies worked well during this period. Electric utilities were able to keep their part of the regulatory bargain by providing reliable power to their customers while regulators allowed them an adequate return on investment. Public involvement in the regulatory process was minimal and rate changes were infrequent. Several factors worked in concert in the early 1970s to change this situation. Productivity gains slowed due to the exhaustion of scale economies in electric generation, while the cost of fuel and capital increased. The OPEC oil price shocks had a substantial effect on utilities. State public utility commissions, responsible for regulating electricity rates, were slow to respond to these changing factors. Rate increases often required a full year from inception at the utility to approval by the commission (Joskow, 1989, p. 159). Also, many commissions relied on a historical test year, which reflects outdated input costs, to set future rates. This regulatory lag resulted in inflexible rates which, in the face of rising costs, caused electric utilities to become less profitable. Rate hearings became more frequent after 1973 as utilities faced rapid fuel price increases. At the same time, numerous consumer groups were organizing to resist increases in electricity rates. This ratepayer activism made it increasingly difficult for utilities to adequately adjust to unexpected fuel price changes. Additionally, demand growth slowed in response to the rate increases that had occurred. Electricity demand grew at a 7.3 percent annual rate from 1960 to 1973, but slowed to 2.5 percent a year from 1973 to 1985 (Joskow, 1989, p. 150). This hurt the financial performance of many electric utilities, as construction projects were undertaken with the expectation of continued demand increases, thus decreasing capacity utilization. Under pressure from consumer groups, regulators were loath to include these new, under-utilized plants in the rate base. Traditional cost-of-service regulatory arrangements began to erode as public utility commissions adopted new tests for inclusion of
1180
Public Utilities
5940
capital in the rate base, such as requiring the economic value of the plant to be greater than its accounting cost, called the ‘used and useful’ test (Joskow, 1989, p. 161). Under these new rules, regulatory disallowances became more common, especially for nuclear capacity after the 1979 Three Mile Island accident. Electric utility profitability declined even more. After 1975, electric utility common stock price to book ratios fell below one, and earned rates of return fell far below allowed rates (Joskow, 1989, p. 157). The difference between utility return on equity and the yield on new debt fell from 1974 onward, reaching !3.91 percentage points by 1981. The financial condition of utilities did not improve until 1985. Under these pressures, it became clear that substantial reforms of the regulatory process were necessary. Reform came in several ways. In order to deal with regulatory lag, a number of states instituted fuel adjustment mechanisms (FAMs) which allowed utilities to adjust rates without a formal rate hearing when fuel costs changed. Many states embraced these mechanisms in the mid-1970s, so that by 1979 all but five states had adopted some sort of FAM. This reform shifted the risk of fuel cost changes from the utility to the consumer. A number of economists have studied the effects of FAMs. For example, Kendrick (1975) developed a framework of automatic adjustment clauses to protect utilities from general price increases. Gollop and Karlson (1978) empirically tested the effect of FAMs by estimating translog functions. Baron and DeBondt (1979) provided a history of FAMs and analyzed their effect on incentives for efficiency. Clarke (1980) examined the effect of FAMs on input choice and showed that the effect is in the opposite directions of the rate-of-return distortion. Isaac (1982) examined their impact when input prices are uncertain. Despite the adoption of FAMs, however, utilities confronted a number of significant problems. Regulatory disallowances made utilities reluctant to plan new capacity. Environmental concerns resulted in legislation which greatly increased costs. Additional reforms, therefore, were clearly needed. These came at the federal level and dealt chiefly with the emerging wholesale power market. Two important laws were the Public Utility Regulatory Policies Act of 1978 (PURPA), and the Energy Policy Act of 1992 (EPAct).
9. Legislative Steps Toward Regulatory Reform An important result of the political and economic upheavals of the 1970s was a growing wholesale power market. Heightened opportunities for wholesale trade in electricity materialized as a result of unanticipated price differences between alternative fuels, as well as excess generating capacity (Joskow, 1989). A critical piece of legislation which encouraged the growth of the wholesale market was the Public Utility Regulatory Policies Act of 1978 (PURPA). Title
5940
Public Utilities
1181
I of PURPA directs the states to consider introducing time-of-day rates and interruptible rates, which are alternatives to traditional ratemaking methods. The more important section, Title II, requires utilities to purchase power from companies that attach generation equipment to an existing heat source (cogeneration) or companies that use renewable sources and waste fuels. Small independent generation facilities are included in this section if they meet certain guidelines laid out in the Act. These cogenerators and independent power producers are referred to as ‘qualifying facilities’. While PURPA was passed in 1978, it did not have significant effects until the mid-1980s. The FERC did not issue regulations regarding PURPA until 1980, and several key issues were not resolved until court rulings in 1983. PURPA gave little guidance as to how these transactions were to be carried out, aside from stating that utilities had to purchase excess electricity from qualifying facilities at a price that could not exceed the ‘incremental cost to the utility of alternative electric energy’. PURPA was important because it created an independent generation sector, not subject to rate-of-return regulation that provided alternative energy sources at a time when established utilities were reluctant to construct their own additional generating capacity. This law, along with economic change, provided the first real opportunity for independent firms to produce electricity without encumbering rate and entry regulations. Available evidence reveals that the resulting wholesale power market is quite competitive. Joskow (1989, p. 189) summarizes: The experience since the enactment of PURPA indicates that there exists a very elastic supply of capacity that independent producers are willing to offer at attractive prices. In addition, active markets for short- and medium-term power in excess of the current needs of integrated utilities have emerged in most areas of the country. These markets are subject to only very loose FERC regulation. As a result of extensive interconnections, coordination arrangements, and voluntary wheeling, the anecdotal evidence suggests that these markets are often very competitive.
This independent generating sector has become an important component of the industry. As Baumol and Willig (1995) note, additional units of generating capacity are now just as likely to be provided by non-utility generators (NUGs) as by utilities. During 1990-91, NUGs added more net capacity then did utilities. Furthermore, forecasts suggest that the importance of NUGs will increase in the future. Michaels (1993) notes that, in 1983, NUGs provided only 2.5 percent of total US generating capacity. By 1991, however, NUGs were constructing over half of the new capacity installed in the US and provided over 9 percent of the total. More recently, the Energy Policy Act of 1992 facilitated wholesale competition. This act gave the FERC expanded authority to order utilities to
1182
Public Utilities
5940
provide wheeling services, thus further opening the wholesale power market (Baumol, Joskow and Kahn, 1995, p. 14; Walters and Smith, 1993). Pursuant to this provision, the FERC issued an order that requires all transmission-owning public utilities to open their transmission lines to eligible wholesale customers on a non-discriminatory basis. Providing access to the transmission network will increase competitiveness at the wholesale level and make the state regulator’s job easier and their regulation more effective. However, it also creates considerable problems regarding utilities’ existing investments, as discussed below. Importantly, the Energy Policy Act did not promote retail wheeling, which would enable retail customers to purchase power directly (Baumol, Joskow and Kahn, 1995, p. 14). The Act also removed barriers to acquisitions contained in the Public Utility Holding Company Act of 1935 (PUHCA). It defined a new class of wholesale generators which are exempt from regulation under PUHCA, called ‘exempt wholesale generators’ or EWGs. It permits any person, including a registered holding company, to acquire an EWG, wherever located, or a foreign utility company (FUCO) without seeking prior approval from the Securities and Exchange Commission (which would have been required under PUHCA). Thus, owners of EWGs are exempt from PUHCA regulation. The exempt wholesale generators now constitute an important source of non-utility generation. Therefore, the unintended consequence of PURPA was to move toward increasing competition in US wholesale electricity (Moorhouse, 1995). The Energy Policy Act then substantially strengthened this trend. In these laws, states retained much discretion to restructure their energy markets. As discussed in Lenard, Geddes and Block (1996), 46 states are currently studying options for restructuring their energy markets. California instituted a plan under which all consumers were able to choose their electricity provider on January 1, 1998. Massachusetts legislators recently announced that, beginning March 1, 1998, electric utilities will have to compete for customers. A rate reduction of 15 percent is guaranteed in the bill, and power companies are allowed to recover all of their past investments in generating facilities. Many other public utility commissions or state legislatures are close to adopting specific restructuring plans. Each of these states is proposing that retail customers buy electricity directly from generators or other alternative suppliers. In such transactions, the traditional franchise utility would merely transmit and distribute power. The benefits to customers of such market arrangements are obvious: consumers will not be captive customers of a franchise utility, relying on regulators to assure that their utility does not charge excessive prices. Instead, consumers will be able to shop for power the same way they shop for long distance telephone carriers.
5940
Public Utilities
1183
Competition between generators ultimately will lead to lower prices. For example, Maloney and McCormick (1996) estimated that retail competition would, in the long term, reduce the average residential customer’s bill by 43 percent, or about $30. They also predicted large price reductions for commercial and residential customers. They estimate that the total gains to consumers are between $422.1 and $107.6 billion annually. As a result of the growing competition in the industry, there has been increasing consolidation. As McLaughlin and Mehran (1995) document, for the entire period from 1960 to 1986 there were only 9 hostile takeover attempts in the industry, and none were successful. In the five years from 1986 to 1990, there were 13 takeover attempts, with one being successful. Recently, a number of utility mergers have been announced. There has been much discussion of the importance of repealing old laws which encumber the industry in preparation for eventual complete deregulation. It is important that firms have the ability to optimally adjust to new market conditions. One focus of this research is on the Public Utilities Holding Companies Act. PUHCA was passed during the Great Depression in response to the failure of a number of utility holding companies and subsequent investor losses. The Act defines a utility holding company as ‘any company which directly or indirectly owns, controls, or holds with the power to vote, 10 per centum or more of the outstanding voting securities of a public utility’ (Section 2(a)(7)(A) of PUHCA). Numerous holding-company activities are subject to regulation under PUHCA, including the acquisition and sale of securities, the acquisition of utility assets, intercompany transactions, service, sales and construction contracts, and reports and accounts. Importantly, PUHCA places restrictions on mergers involving registered holding companies. PUHCA remains a major barrier to utility takeovers. Numerous authors have discussed economic inefficiencies associated with the Act. For example, Geddes (1996) emphasizes its effects in inhibiting the market for corporate control. Lenard, Geddes and BLock (1996) emphasize its effects on limiting experiments in deregulation on the state level, as well as its redundancy. For additional analysis in a similar vein, see Joskow (1992) and Gordon (1992).
10. The Recovery of Stranded Costs A prominent aspect of the electric utility deregulation debate involves the question of the recovery of utilities’ ‘stranded investments’. These are investments made under regulation which electric utilities, in a fully deregulated setting, would be unable to recover through prices. This question is relevant for many utilities that are facing regulatory reform.
1184
Public Utilities
5940
Electric utilities estimate that they own between $100 and $300 billion of these investments, and almost one-third of the average electric bill in California is dedicated to paying off these costs (Michaels, 1996, p. 47). In some cases the potentially stranded costs exceed the entire equity value of the firm (Baumol, Joskow and Kahn, 1995, p. 36). This issue is crucial because it affects the pace and structure of deregulation. There are several perspectives on the recovery of stranded costs. According to one view (see for example Baumol and Sidak, 1996; Sidak and Spulber, 1996) in the course of state regulation of utilities, the utility and the state formed an implicit ‘regulatory compact’. Regulators imposed a burden on utilities to serve all customers and to construct plants in expectation of demand growth. In return, the utility received a legal monopoly and a ‘fair’ rate of return. This view implies that utilities are deserving of compensation for investments that were made under the compact which, in a deregulated setting, would not receive a fair rate of return. These authors thus contend that deregulation constitutes a form of breach of contract. They also suggest that (even if one does not accept the notion of a preexisting ‘regulatory compact’) utilities deserve compensation for what amounts to a ‘deregulatory taking’. Arguing in a somewhat different vein, Baumol, Joskow and Kahn (1995) present arguments in favor of the recovery of stranded costs. They suggest that both equity and efficiency considerations work in favor of recovery. In terms of equity, they argue that utility shareholders have not been previously compensated through allowed returns for such ‘deregulatory risk’, and that regulators approved these risk-allocation arrangements. They also contend that ratepayers benefited from the previous regulatory arrangement, in that much old equipment produced substantial value for ratepayers, even while some relatively new equipment has not. On the efficiency side, they submit that without stranded cost recovery it is unlikely that the most efficient supplier of electricity will prevail, since incumbent firms will be burdened by disproportionately large historic costs, and may not be able to effectively compete even if they are the least-cost provider. In other words, in order to provide a ‘level playing field’ for utilities in a deregulated setting, it is necessary to share these historical costs on a non-discriminatory basis. Otherwise the true efficient supplier will not be revealed through the market process. On the opposite side of this debate, commentators, such as Michaels (1996), reply that there never was a regulatory compact and that utilities therefore should not receive compensation for stranded investments. They argue that, unlike typical contracts, there is no indication that a voluntary agreement was made between utilities and customers, whom the regulation was ostensibly created to serve. Indeed, Michaels (1996, p. 49) notes that the term ‘regulatory compact’ first appeared in 1983 in a legal decision. They also point out that many of these now stranded investments were made at utilities’ urging. The
5940
Public Utilities
1185
conclusion here is clear: utilities should not be compensated for losses associated with stranded investments. In an interesting third view, Niskanen (1996) suggested that the problem of stranding is only necessitated by forcing utilities to provide access to their transmission services, a policy which does not respect property rights to the grid. That is, stranding of investment is created by the legislated deregulation of electricity markets through forced ‘open access’. This has been recognized by other commentators as well. As Baumol, Joskow and Kahn (1995, p. 35) state, ‘[t]he possibility of these costs being “stranded” would obviously be greatly increased if franchised utilities were required to offer competing generators direct access to their retail customers via the utility-owned transmission and distribution systems’. Such a requirement is an element of recent legislative proposals. Consequently, these writers maintain that concerns about deregulation constituting a ‘taking’ are justified only if access to the network is forced. Niskanen (1996, p. 17) states, ‘[m]andatory wheeling, whether at the wholesale or retail level, should be recognized as a restriction, a taking, of the property rights of a utility’. Regarding stranded costs, Niskanen’s view is that property rights consist of the right to use, exclude, partition and sell property, but the property owner does not have a right to the value of his or her property. By suggesting that deregulation requires compensation because of a preexisting regulatory compact, utilities are asserting a right to the value of their property, which overextends their true property right. Both the stranded investments and the takings issues could then be solved simultaneously if government would simply divest itself from the institutional setting. By eliminating state-enforced monopolies, and by letting utilities open the grid on their own, there would be no takings and no stranding. As an intermediate solution, this would allow utilities to recover some of their costs through the market process while respecting private property rights. Regardless of the approach that is ultimately adopted, it is likely that the ‘stranded investments’ issue will be central to the utility deregulation debate. Useful summaries of these views are contained in Baumol, Sidak and Michaels (1995) and Brennan, et al. (1996). Interestingly, very similar issues of cost stranding are now arising in other industries which are in different stages of deregulation. In railroads, an important stranding issue arises when captive shippers of coal are given access to rails. A wave of mergers in this industry has brought about this concern. A similar issue arises in local phone networks between long-distance and regional carriers. Long-distance carriers are seeking access to the local carrier networks at a government-determined fee. Local phone companies respond that such access would strand much of their sunk investment. Therefore, the stranding of investment is an important issue in deregulation which cuts across numerous
1186
Public Utilities
5940
industries.
11. The Natural Industry Structure There has been considerable debate over the ‘natural’ market structure of electricity provision, and therefore the expected structure if complete competition were allowed. It has long been supposed that natural monopoly characteristics inherent in the industry, as discussed above, precluded effective competition, and that regulated, legally granted monopolies were necessary. Moorhouse (1995, p. 423) concisely summarizes this perspective: The traditional economic justification for the regulation or state ownership of electric utilities is that utilities are natural monopolies. Economies of scale and scope, and the economies associated with vertical integration mean that unit costs decline throughout the relevant range of production as output increases. Such economies preclude competition, according to the conventional view, because a single firm could supply the entire service area at lower cost than could two or more firms. Given its cost structure, an established utility could undercut its rivals and drive them from the market. Moreover, attempted entry represents a waste of resources either because of an unnecessary duplication of facilities or because such investment would not be viable in the face of undercutting. Secure from competition, the monopolist would exploit the consumer if not for regulation or state ownership.
This view implies that important variables for empirical examination include the degree of economies of scale and scope. Thus a number of studies of electric utilities involve these questions. For example, Hulbert (1969) concluded that economies of scale could be achieved in systems up to 25,000 megawatts. Alternatively, Johnston (1960) and Nerlove (1963) determined that scale economies were exhausted even for firms of relatively small size. Barzel (1964) used a input demand model which showed scale economies at the plant level. Galatin (1968) found both scale effects as well as technical change. Atkinson and Halvorsen (1976) used a profit function specification. Cowing and Smith (1978) provided a survey of the literature on estimates of production technologies. In their landmark study, Christensen and Green (1976) examined economies of scale for US electric utilities and found that in 1955 there were significant economies of scale for almost all firms, but that by 1970 these economies had been virtually exhausted, and by then almost all utilities were operating in the flat portion of their average cost curves. Importantly, given how early this paper appeared in the deregulation debate, they submit that: ‘We conclude that a small number of extremely large firms are not required for efficient production and that policies designed to promote competition in
5940
Public Utilities
1187
electric power generation cannot be faulted in terms of sacrificing economies of scale’.
12. Reliability A related branch of research focuses on the question of reliability. It deals with the ‘public good’ nature of reliability, as well as the optimal level of reliability for an electrical system. This question is particularly relevant under competition. Telson (1975) examined the question of the optimal level of reliability and found that current levels in the US were excessive. Munasinge and Gellerson (1979) developed a model for finding the optimal level of reliability. Bental and Ravid (1986) and Sanghvi (1983) discussed methods to measure the costs of outages. There is a set of articles which emphasize that price, reliability and capacity should be jointly determined. Reliability is a feature of papers by Brown and Johnson (1969), Crew and Kleindorfer (1976, 1978), Sherman and Visscher (1978) and Chao (1983). Reliability is uniform throughout an electrical system, but customers differ according to their outage costs. Some articles have examined how prices should be set for customers with differing outage costs, but who consume the same level of reliability. Such studies include Chao (1983), Chao and Wilson (1986, 1987) and Woo and Toyama (1986).
C. The Experience in Other Utilities In this part, I review literature focusing on several utilities besides electricity. I first review selected work on telephone utilities. In Section 14, I describe several studies in natural gas, and in Section 15, I review work in water utilities.
13. Telephone Utilities Numerous interesting aspects of utility regulation are illustrated by the phone industry. I first briefly describe the regulatory history of the industry, and then review several important studies. In the US, the Mann-Elkins Act of 1910 first gave the Interstate Commerce Commission (ICC) the authority to regulate the intercity telecommunications market. Through entry control by the ICC, American Telephone and Telegraph (AT&T) obtained monopoly power in long-distance telephony, and was treated as a ‘natural monopoly’ (Viscusi, Vernon and Harrington, 1995, p. 487). It was believed that the need to string open-wire line (or coaxial cable) between cities raised the fixed costs of entering the market to the point were economies of scale were realized by single-firm operation. The Communications Act of 1934 transferred the power
1188
Public Utilities
5940
to regulate price and entry into the inter-city phone market to the Federal Communications Commission (FCC), which continues to regulate telecommunications today. Thus, AT&T was a rate-regulated monopolist until the late 1950's. The impetus for regulatory reform in this industry came from new technology: microwave transmission. This technology can transmit large amounts of information via radio beams, that is, without the use of extensive networks of wire or cable. Therefore, physical connection between two points was no longer needed for communications. In the 1950s, many firms began asking the FCC for permission to build private networks (Viscusi, Vernon and Harrington, 1995, p. 488). These requests led the FCC, in 1959, to issue the ‘Above 890 Mc’ decision, in which frequencies above 890 megacycles would be shared with private users. However, other users were not allowed to sell telecommunications services, so true competition was not established. In 1963, Microwave Communications Incorporated (MCI) petitioned the FCC to allow it to enter a specific inter-city market (St. Louis-Chicago), as a competitor to AT&T. It was not until 1969 that the FCC approved the request. This decision began a process of partial deregulation of the industry by the FCC, but with extensive built-in cross-subsidies and AT&T as the dominant supplier. After seven years of antitrust litigation by the US Department of Justice, AT&T was broken up into seven holding companies, called the regional Bell operating companies. AT&T is now no longer involved in any monopoly markets. Additionally, local phone companies face competition from several sources, including cellular phones. Below, I review several specific studies of the telecommunications industry. Oum and Zhang (1995) examine the effect of competition on the productive efficiency of the US telephone industry. Their model predicts that competition will reduce allocative inefficiency in the use of inputs, as caused by rate-of-return regulation (that is, the Averch-Johnson effect, discussed above). This is in addition to the usual improvements in technical efficiency observed when competition is introduced. They examine data over the 1951-90 period, and find that competition did in fact improve the allocative efficiency of incumbent firms. There are several studies which examine the effect of ‘incentive regulation’ in telephones. Incentive regulation suggests alternative regulatory approaches, such as ‘sliding scale’ plans and ‘price cap’ regulation, as reviewed by Joskow and Schmalensee (1986). Some studies have found efficiency improvements from these methods. For example, Majumdar (1997) examined the effectiveness of incentive regulation on the productivity of US local exchange carriers. He found that there was a lagged but substantial effect on technical efficiency from a pure price-cap scheme. He also found positive effects on scale efficiency. However, Kridel, Sappington and Weisman (1996) conducted a survey of studies on the effects of incentive regulation in the telecommunications
5940
Public Utilities
1189
industry. Collectively, the studies examine productivity, investment, profit levels, new service offerings and regulatory proceedings. They find no strong evidence that incentive regulation significantly reduced the costs of providing telephone service, nor has it substantially streamlined regulatory proceedings. As suggested above, a critical policy issue is whether or not the pre-divestiture Bell System was a natural monopoly. This requires detailed tests of the subadditivity of the cost function, as mentioned in Section 2. Previous studies of this issue, such as Evans and Heckman (1983), suffered from poor data quality (as they note). However, Shin and Ying (1992) attempt to overcome these data problems by focusing on local exchange carriers (which allow more degrees of freedom than previous tests). Their global subadditivity tests demonstrate that the cost functions of these firms are definitely not subadditive. Their results suggest that permitting entry and increasing competition in the local exchange market would enhance efficiency. There have been many studies of the local telephone market, where there has been rapid regulatory change. For example, Green and Lehn (1995) suggest that recent developments in the telecommunications industry have increased the likelihood that the regional Bell operating companies (RBOCs) will face new competition in the local telephone service market. They detail major developments in these markets, including the FCC’s decision to facilitate entry and application of new technology to the local telephone market, as well as strategic decisions by AT&T, MCI and Time-Warner to enter the market. They use event-study methodology to estimate the announcement effect of several events on the equity values of the RBOCs. They find that there is a negative and significant collective effect on their values. Cramer (1994) focuses on access and cable competition in local telephone systems in the US. He provides an overview of the development and scope of local phone competition, and some predictions as to the future of local service. In particular, he believes that policies will evolve to encourage cable companies to enter the telephone business.
14. Gas Utilities In this section, I review several studies of the natural gas industry. Crandall and Ellig (1997) provide a summary of natural gas regulatory reform in the 1980s and 1990s. Barcella (1996) provides an overview of the current structure of the industry. She finds that competition is well entrenched in the production sector of the industry, and is moving downstream into the transportation sector as well. She finds that there is increased ‘unbundling’ in the industry, as gas production is being separated from the sale of pipeline transportation services and local distribution services. ‘Gas marketing’ has emerged as a new industry, which will likely be affected by upcoming electric utility deregulation, and
1190
Public Utilities
5940
transformed into a multi-fuel marketing industry. De Vany and Walls (1994) examine recent regulatory changes in the gas market. Their article describes the institutions that were developed to support exchange in gas markets, and studies the performance of these institutions. They find that spot gas prices have converged and become highly correlated. Doane and Spulber (1994) examine the spot market in natural gas. They focus on the wellhead spot price of gas from 1984 to 1991 to see if open access affected the geographic scope of the spot market. They apply three statistical tests, including spot price correlations, Granger causality, and cointegration, and find that open access integrated the regional markets into a national competitive market for gas. King and Cuc (1996) also study the degree of price convergence in the US spot gas market since deregulation. Using a Kalman Filter (time-varying parameters) approach, which allows measurement of the strength of price convergence, they find that the degree of price convergence has increased significantly since deregulation in the mid-1980s. However, they emphasize that it is not yet correct to speak of ‘one price’ in North American gas markets. In reference to Europe, Grais and Zheng (1996) examine the potential benefits of East-West gas trade within the context of a game-theoretic model. They emphasize that economic change in the former Soviet Union and Eastern Europe have heightened uncertainties in this gas trade. Their model shows how to modify the trade contract to accommodate changes in the economic environment.
15. Water Utilities Water utilities have been somewhat less frequently studied than other utilities. Nevertheless, there are many interesting contributions, several of which I review here. Many of these focus on the proper pricing for water services. For example, Zarnikau (1994) examines economically efficient water rates. He advocates the application of short-run marginal cost or spot market pricing principles to the pricing of water resources. Kim (1995) also examines the pricing of water services. The article’s focus is on current pricing systems relative to marginal cost and second-best pricing rules. He estimates a translog multi-product cost function for US water utilities, and finds that the existing price structure does not depart significantly from second-best pricing principles, but does depart from marginal cost pricing. Similarly, Renzetti (1992) examines water supply costs and demands using data from Vancouver, Canada in order to estimate the welfare gain from altering water prices. His results show that a move to seasonally differentiated pricing raises aggregate surplus by four percent, which is higher than previous estimates. Raffiee et al. (1993) examine the efficiency of public versus private water providers by calculating
5940
Public Utilities
1191
the difference between the observed cost and the optimum cost. The latter is found using the ‘Weak Axiom of Cost Minimization’ for each water utility. They find that privately owned water utilities are more efficient than public.
D. Utilities in Europe 16. Utilities in Europe In this section, I briefly review several contributions to the literature on European utilities. Since Europe is introducing competition in several utilities, this literature is rapidly growing. With regard to environmental issues, Burtraw (1993) discusses the use of international tradable sulfur dioxide emission permits in Europe, with an emphasis on electric utilities. Because tradable permits provide agents with powerful economic incentives to reduce emissions at least cost, this method of controlling for acidification has met with great success in the US. Environmental goals have been met at low cost. Burtraw argues that, because of economic unification and the liberalization of energy markets in Europe, permits have wide potential application there. However, he points to several institutional features of the European electric utility industry that may undermine the effectiveness of transferable permits. Grohnheit and Olsen (1995) discuss the consequences of introducing a competitive electricity market in the Nordic countries. They note that Britain and the Nordic countries are instituting many competitive reforms in their power sectors, and argue that opening up a competitive electricity market has the potential to create substantial efficiency gains. They focus on the use of combined heat and power for district heating, and demonstrate that it would be competitive in an open electricity market. Percebois (1994) focuses on natural gas markets in Europe. He finds that natural gas is being increasingly used in the generation of electricity, and examines the likelihood and desirability of deregulation of the industry. He argues that the prospects for its growth in Europe are promising, but only with continued government involvement. Monnier (1993) focuses on the electricity market in Europe. The first part of his article provides a survey of the economics of electricity, and an overview of the structure of the industry in Europe. The second part examines the debate over electricity restructuring in Europe, but focuses on three questions: (1) What is the future of the electric utility industry in Europe?; (2) How will competition evolve in Europe?, and (3) How will this affect government versus private ownership of utilities? Doyle and Maher (1992) also focus on electricity. They find that electricity supply is under increasing pressure to become competitive, and that the experience in the United Kingdom demonstrates the feasibility of regulatory
1192
Public Utilities
5940
reform in Europe. They examine the relationship between the generation, transmission, and distribution sectors of the industry, and find that open access to the grid is desirable if accompanied by common carriage requirements and a competitive generation sector. They also examine the pricing of transmission services under open access. Amundsen and Singh (1992) examine risk-sharing arrangements which allow consumers and producers to hedge their price-risk in European electricity markets. Specifically, they examine the feasibility of establishing futures markets in electricity in Europe, with a focus on the United Kingdom and Norway. While there is sufficient price uncertainty to justify such arrangements, they are skeptical about the competitiveness of new spot-markets.
17. Summary and Conclusions In this chapter, I have attempted to provide an overview of the utility literature. Since the term ‘utility’ has been used to refer to a broad range of industries, this literature is quite large. I discuss several issues important for utilities generally. These issues include a discussion of the original justification for utility regulation, a comparison of alternative theories of regulation, an examination of the distortionary effects of regulation, an overview of the effects of utility deregulation, and a discussion of ownership form. These issues were then applied to the specific case of the electric utility industry. This industry is of particular importance today, perhaps most importantly because it is very large and is now undergoing substantial regulatory change. It appears that reform of utility regulation has been very successful, with large net welfare gains accruing to society. While many studies focus on the US case, the results have important implications for utilities in Europe and elsewhere. Utilities face differing ownership structures across countries, but they share common structural characteristics. Thus, it is likely that utility regulatory reform will have similar beneficial effects in other institutional settings.
Acknowledgements I am grateful to William Niskanen, Juri Hwang, and two anonymous referees for helpful comments, and to Yi Luo for capable research assistance.
5940
Public Utilities
1193
Bibliography on Public Utilities (5940) Alchian, Armen L. and Demsetz, Harold (1972), ‘Production, Information Costs, and Economic Organization’, 62(5) American Economic Review, 777-95. Amundsen, Eirik S. and Singh, Balbir (1992), ‘Developing Futures Markets for Electricity in Europe’, 13(3) Energy Journal, 95-112. Armstrong, Thomas O. and Leppel, Karen (1994), ‘Are Regulated and Potentially Unregulated Combination Gas and Electric Utilities Natural Monopolies?’, 46(3) Journal of Economics and Business, 195-206. Atkinson, Scott E. and Halvorsen, Robert (1976), ‘Interfuel Substitution in Conventional Steam Electric Power Generation’, 84(5) Journal of Political Economy, 959-978. Atkinson, Scott E. and Halvorsen, Robert (1981), ‘Automatic Price Adjustment Clauses and Input Choice in Regulated Utilities’, 12 Journal of Business Administration, 185-196. Atkinson, Scott E. and Halvorsen, Robert (1986), ‘The Relative Efficiency of Public and Private Firms in a Regulated Environment: The Case of U.S. Electric Utilities’, 29(3) Journal of Public Economics, 281-294. Atkinson, Scott E. and Halvorsen, Robert (1990), ‘Tests of Allocative Efficiency in Regulated Multi-product Firms’, 12(1) Resources and Energy, 65-77. Averch H. and Johnson, L.L. (1962), ‘Behavior of the Firm Under Regulatory Constraint’, 52 American Economic Review, 1053-1069. Bailey, Elizabeth E. (1972), ‘Peak Load Pricing Under Regulatory Constraint’, 80(4) Journal of Political Economy, 662-679. Bailey, Elizabeth E. and Baumol, William J. (1984), ‘Deregulation and the Theory of Contestable Markets’, 1(2) Yale Journal on Regulation, 111-137. Bailey, Elizabeth E. and Malone, J. (1970), ‘Resource Allocation and the Regulated Firm’, 1 Bell Journal of Economics, 129-142. Bailey, Elizabeth E. and Panzar, John C. (1981), ‘The Contestability of Airline Markets during the Transition to Deregulation’, 44(1) Law and Contemporary Problems, 125-45. Baldick, Ross and Kahn, Edward (1993), ‘Network Costs and the Regulation of Wholesale Competition in Electric Power’, 5(4) Journal of Regulatory Economics, 367-384. Barcella, Mary L. (1995), ‘Natural Gas in the Twenty-First Century’, 31(4) Business Economics, 19-24. Barcella, Mary L. (1996), ‘Natural Gas in the Twenty-First Century’, 31(4) Business Economics, 1924. Baron, D.P. and De Bondt, W. (1979), ‘Fuel Adjustment Mechanisms and Economic Efficiency’, 27(3) Journal of Industrial Economics, 243-61. Baron, D.P. and Besanko, J. (1984), ‘Regulation, Asymmetric Information, and Auditing’, 15(4) Rand Journal of Economics, 447-470. Baron, D.P. and Taggert, P. (1977), ‘A Model of Regulation under Uncertainty and a Test of Regulatory Bias’, 8 Bell Journal of Economics, 151-167. Barzel, Yoram (1964), ‘The Production Function and Technical Change in the Steam Electric Industry’, 72 Journal of Political Economy, 133-150. Baumol, William J. (1977), ‘On the Proper Costs Tests for Natural Monopoly in a Multiproduct Industry’, 67(2) American Economic Review, 809 ff. Baumol, William J. and Klevorick, Alvin. K. (1970), ‘Input Choices and Rate of Return Regulation: An Overview of the Discussion’, 1 Bell Journal of Economics, 162-190.
1194
Public Utilities
5940
Baumol, William J. and Sidak, Gregory J. (1996), Transmission Pricing and Stranded Costs in the Electric Power Industry, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute. Baumol, William J. and Willig, Robert D. (1995), The Economic Case for Repeal of the Public Utility Holding Company Act of 1935, Supplement to ‘Comments of Central and South West Corporation’. Securities and Exchange Commission, Request for Comments on Modernization of the Regulation of Public Utility Holding Companies, Docket No. 57-32-94 (6 February). Baumol, William J., Bailey, Elizabeth E. and Willig, Robert D. (1977), ‘Weak Invisible Hand Theorems on the Sustainability of Multiproduct Natural Monopoly’, 67(3) American Economic Review, 350-65. Baumol, William J., Panzar, John C. and Willig, Robert D. (1982), Contestable Markets and the Theory of Industry Structure, San Diego, Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. Baumol, William J., Panzar, John C. and Willig, Robert D. (1988), Contestable Markets and the Theory of Industry Structure, Revised Edition, San Diego, Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. Baumol, William J., Joskow, Paul L. and Kahn, Alfred E. (1995), The Challenge for Federal and State Regulators: Transition from Regulation to Efficient Competition in Electric Power, Washington, DC, Edison Electric Institute. Baumol, William J., Sidak, Gregory J. and Michaels, Robert J. (1995), ‘Stranded Investment: Pay Up or Mark Down, A Point-Counterpoint’, May 15 Public Utilities Fortnightly. Becker, Gary S. (1983), ‘A Theory of Competition among Pressure Groups for Political Influence’, 98 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 371-383. Bental, B. and Ravid, S. (1986), ‘A Simple Method for Evaluating the Marginal Cost of Unsupplied Electricity’, 17 Bell Journal of Economics, 249-253. Berg, Sanford V. and Jeong, Jinook (1991), ‘An Evaluation of Incentive Regulation for Electric Utilities’, 3(1) Journal of Regulatory Economics, 45-55. Berry, Dan Michael (1994), ‘Private Ownership Form and Productive Efficiency: Electric Cooperatives versus Investor-Owned Utilities’, 6(4) Journal of Regulatory Economics, 399-420. Berry, K. (1987), ‘Rate of Return Regulation and Demand Uncertainty with a Symmetric Regulatory Constraint’, 31(2) American Economist, 8-12. Besanko, D. (1985), ‘On the Use of Revenue Requirement Regulation under Imperfect Information’, in Michael A. Crew, (ed.), Analyzing the Impact of Regulatory Change in Public Utilities, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books Boardman, Anthony E. and Vining, Aidan R. (1989), ‘Ownership and Performance in Competitive Environments: A Comparison of the Performance of Private, Mixed, and State-owned Enterprises’, 32(1) Journal of Law and Economics, 1-33. Bohi, Douglas R. and Burtraw, Dallas (1992), ‘Utility Investment Behavior and the Emission Trading Market’, 14(1-2) Resources and Energy, 129-153. Boiteux, M. (1964), ‘Peak-load Pricing’, in Marginal Cost Pricing in Practice, Englewood Cliffs, NJ, Prentice-Hall. Boyes, W. (1976), ‘An Empirical Examination of the Averch-Johnson Effect’, 14(1) Economic Inquiry, 25-35. Bradley, Robert L., Jr (1996), ‘The Origins of Political Electricity: Market Failure or Political Opportunism?’, 17(1) Energy Law Journal, 59-102. Brennan, Timothy J., Palmer, Karen L., Kopp, Raymond J., Krupnick, Alan J., Stagliano, Vito and Burtraw, Dallas (1996), A Shock to the System: Restructuring America’s Electric Industry,
5940
Public Utilities
1195
Washington, DC, Resources for the Future. Brown, G. and Johnson, M. Bruce (1969), ‘Public Utility Pricing and Output Under Risk’, 59 American Economic Review, 119-128. Burns, Philip, Jones and Weyman, Thomas G. (1996), ‘Cost Functions and Cost Efficiency in Electricity Distribution: A Stochastic Frontier Approach’, 48(1) Bulletin of Economic Research, 41-64. Burtraw, Dallas (1993), The Promise and Prospect for SO2 Emission Trading in Europe, Working Paper, Resources for the Future, Quality of the Environment Division Discussion Paper, 92-22. Burtraw, Dallas (1994), ‘Tradable Sulfur Dioxide Emission Permits and European Economic Integration’, in Toman, Michael A. (ed.), Pollution Abatement Strategies in Central and Eastern Europe, Washington, DC, Resources for the Future. Burtraw, Dallas et al. (1995), ‘Optimal “Adders” for Environmental Damage by Public Utilities’,29(3) Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, S1-S9. Carroll, Thomas M. and Ciscel, David H. (1982), ‘The Effects of Regulation on Executive Compensation’, 64(3) The Review of Economics and Statistics, 505-509. Chao, Hung-Po (1983), ‘Peak Load Pricing and Capacity Planning with Demand and Supply Uncertainty’, 14 Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, 179-180. Chao, Hung Po and Wilson, R. (1986), ‘Multilevel Demand Subscription Pricing for Electric Power’, 4 Energy Economics, 119-217. Chao, Hung Po and Wilson, Robert (1987), ‘Priority Service: Pricing, Investment, and Market Organization’, 77(5) American Economic Review, 899-916. Christensen, Laurits R. and Greene, W. (1976), ‘Economics of Scale in U.S. Electric Power Generation’, 84(4) Journalof Political Economy, 655-675. Claggett, E. Tylor, Jr, Hollas, Daniel R. and Stansell, Stanley P. (1995), ‘The Effects of Ownership Form on Profit Maximization and Cost Minimization Behavior Within Municipal and Cooperative Electrical Distribution Utilities’, 43 Quarterly Review of Economics and Finance, 533-550. Clarke, R.G. (1980), ‘The Effect of Fuel Adjustment Clauses on the Systematic Risk and Market Values of Electric Utilities’, 35(2) Journal of Finance, 347-358. Coase, Ronald H. (1959), ‘The Federal Communications Commission’, 2(1) Journal of Law and Economics. Corey, Gorden R. (1992), ‘The U.S. Electric Power Industry: Regulatory Trends and Objectives’, 14(1-2) Resources and Energy, 77-99. Costello, Kenneth W. and Hemphill, Ross C. (1990), ‘Competitive Pricing in the Electric Industry’, 12(1) Resources and Energy, 49-63. Coursey, D., Isaac, R.M. and Smith, V.L. (1984), ‘Natural Monopoly and Contested Markets: Some Experimental Results’, 27 Journal of Law and Economics, 91-113. Courville, L. (1974), ‘Regulation and Efficiency in the Electric Utility Industry’, 5(1) Bell Journal of Economics, 53-74. Cowing, T.G. (1974), ‘Technical Change and Scale Economics in an Engineering Production Function: The Case of Steam Electric Power’, 33(1) Journal of Industrial Economics, 135-152. Cowing, T.G. and Smith, V.K. (1978), ‘The Estimation of a Production Technology: A Survey of Econometric Analysis of Steam Electric Generation’, 54(2) Land Economics, 156-186. Crain, Mark W. and Zardkoohi, Asghar (1978), ‘A Test of the Property-Rights Theory of the Firm:
1196
Public Utilities
5940
Water Utilities in the United States’, 21(2) Journal of Law and Economics, 395-408. Cramer, Curtis A. (1994), ‘Local Competition for Telephone Services’, 9(3) Journal of Industrial Organization, 273-291. Crandall, Robert W. and Ellig, Jerry (1997), Economic Deregulation and Customer Choice: Lessons for the Electric Industry, Fairfax, VA, Center for Market Processes. Crew M. and Kleindorfer, P. (1976), ‘Peak Load Pricing with a Diverse Technology’, 7(1) Bell Journal of Economics, 207-231. Crew M. and Kleindorfer, P. (1978), ‘Reliability and Public Utility Pricing’, 68 American Economic Review, 31-40. Crew M. and Kleindorfer, P. (1981), ‘Regulation and Diverse Technology in the Peak Load Problem’, 48(2) Southern Economic Journal, 335-343. Cudahy, Richard D. (1992), ‘Competition and Regulation: The Swing of the Pendulum’, 14(1-2) Resources and Energy, 47-52. Das, S. (1980), ‘On the Effective Rate of Return Regulation Under Uncertainty’, 70(3) American Economic Review, 456-460. Davies, David G. (1971), ‘The Efficiency of Public versus Private Firms: The Case of Australia’s Two Airlines’, 14 Journal of Law and Economics, 149-65. Davies, David G. (1977), ‘Property Rights and Economic Efficiency: The Australian Airline Revisited’, 20 Journal of Law and Economics, 223-26. De Alessi, Louis (1974) ‘Managerial Tenure under Private and Government Ownership in the Electric Power Industry’, 82 Journal of Political Economy, 645-53. De Alessi, Louis (1980), ‘The Economics of Property Rights: A Review of the Evidence’, in Zerbe, R. (ed.), 2 Research in Law and Economics, 27-28. De Bondt, W. (1979), ‘Fuel Adjustment Mechanisms and Economic Efficiency’, 27(3) Journal of Industrial Economics, 243-261. Demsetz, Harold (1968), ‘Why Regulate Utilities?’, 11 Journal of Law and Economics, 55-65. De Vany, Arthur and Walls, W. David (1994), ‘Network Connectivity and Price Convergence: Gas Pipeline Deregulation’, in McMullen, B. Starr (ed.), Research in Transportation Economics, Volume 3. Greenwich, Conn. and London, JAI. DiLorenzo, Thomas J. and Robinson, Ralph (1982), ‘Managerial Objectives Subject to Political Market Constraints: Electric Utilities in the U.S’., 22(2) Quarterly Review of Economics and Business, 113-125. Dnes, Antony W. and Seaton, J. (1996), ‘The Regulation of Regional Electricity Companies’, 4 Utility Finance. Doane, Michael J. and Spulber, Daniel F. (1994), ‘Open Access and the Evolution of the U.S. Spot Market for Natural Gas’, 37(2) Journal of Law and Economics, 477-517. Doyle, Chris and Maher, Maria (1992), ‘Common Carriage and the Pricing of Electricity Transmission’, 13(3) Energy Journal, 63-94. Einhorn, Michael A. (1990), ‘Purchasing Power for the Grid: A Social Contract Approach’, 12(1) Resources and Energy, 33-48. Eto, Joseph et al. (1996), ‘The Total Cost and Measured Performance of Utility-Sponsored Energy Efficiency Programs’, 17(1) Energy Journal, 31-51. Evans, David S. and Heckman, James J. (1983), ‘Multiproduct Cost Function Estimates and Natural Monopoly Tests for the Bell System’, in Evans, David S., Breaking Up Bell: Essays on Industrial Organization and Regulation, New York, North Holland.
5940
Public Utilities
1197
Fare, R., Grosskopf, S. and Logan, J. (1985), ‘The Relative Performance of Publicly Owned and Privately Owned Electric Utilities’, 26(1) Journal of Public Economics, 89-106. Feigenbaum, Susan and Teeples, Ronald (1983), ‘Public Versus Private Water Delivery: A Hedonic Cost Approach’, 65(4) Review of Economics and Statistics, 672-678. Formby, John P., Mishra, Banamber and Thistle, Paul D. (1995), ‘Public Utility Regulation and Bond Ratings’, 84(1-2) Public Choice, 119-136. Fox-Penner, Peter S. (1990), ‘Regulating Independent Power Producers: Lessons of the PURPA Approach’, 12(1) Resources and Energy, 117-141. Frech, H.E. (1976), ‘The Property Rights Theory of the Firm: Empirical Results from a Natural Experiment’, 84(1) Journal of Political Economy, 143-52. Gabel, David (1994), ‘Competition in a Network Industry: The Telephone Industry, 1894-1910', 54(3) Journal of Economic History, 543-572. Galatin, M. (1968), Economics of Scale and Technological Change in Thermal Power Generation, North-Holland, Amsterdam. Geddes, R. Richard (1992), ‘A Historical Perspective on Electric Utility Regulation’, (Winter) Regulation, 75-82. Geddes, R. Richard (1994), ‘Privatization and Contracts in U.S. Electric Utilities’, in Crowley, P.T. and Geddes, R.R. (eds), Private Power in the Pacific, Pacific Economic Cooperation Council, Minerals and Energy Forum, 11-24. Geddes, R. Richard (1996), ‘Time to Repeal the Public Utility Holding Company Act’, 16(1) Cato Journal, 63-76. Geddes, R. Richard (1997), ‘Regulation, Ownership and Managerial Monitoring in the Electric Utility Industry’, 40(1) Journal of Law and Economics, 261-288. Geddes, R. Richard and Griffes, Peter H. (1990), ‘The Electric Utility Industry: New Challenges and Old Questions’, 12 Resources and Energy, 1-15. Gegax, Douglas and Nowotny, Kenneth (1993), ‘Competition and the Electric Utility Industry: An Evaluation’, 10(1) Yale Journal on Regulation, 63-87. Gilbert, Richard J. and Kahn, Edward P. (eds) (1996), International Comparisons of Electricity Regulation, Cambridge, New York and Melbourne, Cambridge University Press. Gilsdorf, Keith (1994), ‘Vertical Integration Efficiencies and Electric Utilities: A Cost Complementary Perspective’, 34(3) Quarterly Review of Economics and Finance, 261-282. Gilsdorf, Keith (1995), ‘Testing for Subaddivity of Vertically Integrated Electric Utilities’, 62(1) Southern Economic Journal, 126-138. Goldberg, Victor P. (1991), ‘The Evolution of an Independent Power Sector and Competitive Procurement of New Generating Capacity: Comment’, 13 Research in Law and Economics, 101-104. Gollop, F. and Karlson, S.H. (1978), ‘The Impact of the Fuel Adjustment Mechanism on Economic Efficiency’, 60 Review of Economics and Statistics, 574-584. Gordon, Richard L. (1990), ‘Timidity in Electric Utility Deregulation’, 12(1) Resources and Energy, 17-32. Gordon, Richard L. (1992), ‘The Public Utility Holding Company Act, The Easy Step in Electric Utility Regulatory Reform’, 15(1) Regulation, 58-67. Grais, Wafik and Zheng, Kangbin (1996), ‘Strategic Interdependence in European East-West Gas trade: A Hierarchical Stackelberg Game Approach’, 17(3) Energy Journal, 61-84. Green, Kevin C. and Lehn, Kenneth M. (1995), ‘The Effect of Enhanced Competition on the Equity
1198
Public Utilities
5940
Values of the Regional Bell Operating Companies’, 16(4) Managerial and Decision Economics, 469-477. Green, Richard C. and Newbery, David M.G. (1992), ‘Competition in the British Electricity Spot Market’, 100(5) Journal of Political Economy, 929-953. Green, Richard C. and Newbery, David M.G. (1993), ‘The Regulation of the Gas Industry: Lessons from Electricity’, 14(2) Fiscal Studies, 37-52. Grohnheit, Poul Erik and Olsen, Ole Jess (1995), ‘Electricity Liberalization and Export of Hydro Power from the Nordic Countries’, 5(2) Pacific and Asian Journal of Energy, 285-300. Harris, M. and Townsend, R.M. (1981), ‘Resource Allocation Under Asymmetric Information’, 49 Econometrica, 33-64. Hausman, William J. and Neufeld, John L. (1991), ‘Property Rights versus Public Spirit: Ownership and Efficiency of U.S. Electric Utilities Prior to Rate-of Return Regulation’, 73(3) Review of Economics and Statistics, 414-423. Hausman, William J. and Neufield, John L. (1994), ‘Public versus Private Electric Utilities in the United States: A Century of Debate over Comparative Economic Efficiency’, 64(4) Annals of Public and Cooperative Economics, 599-622. Heimann, Fritz F. (1991), ‘The Electric Policy Study’, 13 Research in Law and Economics, 1-6. Hempling, Scott (1995), ‘Electric Utility Holding Companies: The New Regulatory Challenges’, 71(3) Land Economics, 343-353. Hirshleifer, J. (1958), ‘Peak Loads and Efficient Pricing: Comment’, 72 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 451-462. Hoffman, M.C. (1994), ‘The Future of Electricity Provision’, 3 Regulation, 55-62. Hogan, W.W. (1992), ‘Contract Networks for Electric Power Transmission’, 4 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 211-242. Hollas, Daniel R. and Stansell, Stanley R. (1988), ‘An Examination of the Effect of Ownership Form on Price Efficiency: Proprietary, Cooperative and Municipal Electric Utilities’, 55(2) Southern Economic Journal, 336-350. Hollas, Daniel R. and Stansell, Stanley R. (1991), ‘Regulation, Ownership Form, and the Economic Efficiency of Rural Electric Distribution Cooperatives’, 21(2) Review of Regional Studies, 201-220. Hollas, Daniel R., Stansell, Stanley R. and Claggett, E. Tylor, Jr (1994), ‘Ownership Form and Rate Structure: An Examination of Cooperative and Municipal Electric Distribution Utilities’, 61(2) Southern Economic Journal, 519-529. Houston, Douglas A. (1983), ‘Deregulating Electric Utilities: A Market-Process Approach’, 3(3) Cato Journal, 831-853. Hulbert, G.C. (1969), ‘Power Generation in the 1970s’, in 1969 Future Power Forum: Perspective for the 70s, New York, Westinghouse. Hunt, Sally and Shuttleworth, Graham (1996), Competition and Choice in Electricity, Chichester, New York and Toronto, Wiley. Isaac, R. Mark (1982), ‘Fuel Cost Adjustment Mechanisms and the Regulated Utility Facing Uncertain Fuel Prices’, 13(1) Bell Journal of Economics, 158-169. Isaac, R. Mark (1991), ‘Price Cap Regulation: A Case Study of Some Pitfalls of Implementation’, 3(2) Journal of Regulatory Economics, 199-210. Jarrell, Gregg A. (1982), ‘The Demand for State Regulation of the Electric Utility Industry’, 21(2) Journal of Law and Economics, 269-296.
5940
Public Utilities
1199
Johnston, J.J. (1960), Statistical Cost Analysis, New York, McGraw-Hill. Jordan, Wiliam A. (1972), ‘Producer Protection, Prior Market Structure and the Effects of Government Regulation’, 15 Journal of Law and Economics, 151-176. Jorgenson, Dale W. and Wilcoxen, Peter (1992), ‘Global Change, Energy Prices, and U.S. Economic Growth’, 3(1) Structural Change and Dynamics, 135-154. Joskow, Paul L. (1987), ‘Productivity Growth and Technical Change in the Generation of Electricity’, 8(1) Energy Journal, 17-38. Joskow, Paul L. (1988), ‘Price Adjustment in Long-Term Contracts: The Case of Coal’, 31 Journal of Law and Economics, 47-83. Joskow, Paul L. (1989), ‘Regulatory Failure, Regulatory Reform, and Structural Change in the Electric Power Industry’, Brookings Papers on Economic Activity: Microeconomics, 125-208. Joskow, Paul L. (1991a), ‘Asset Specificity and the Structure of Vertical Relationships: Empirical Evidence’, in Williamson, Oliver E. and Winter, S. (eds), The Nature of the Firm, Origins, Evolution, and Development, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 117-137. Joskow, Paul L. (1991b), ‘The Evolution of an Independent Power Sector and Competitive Procurement of New Generating Capacity’, 13 Research in Law and Economics, 63-100. Joskow, Paul L. (1992), ‘Expanding Competitive Opportunities in Electricity Generation’, 15(1) Regulation, 25-37. Joskow, Paul L. and Marron, Donald B. (1992), ‘What Does a Negawatt Really Cost? Evidence from Utility Conservation Programs’, 13(4) Energy Journal, 41-74. Joskow, Paul L. and Noll, Roger G. (1981), ‘Regulation in Theory and Practice: An Overview’, in Fromm, G. (ed.), Studies in Public Regulation, Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press. Joskow, Paul L. and Rose, Nancy L. (1985), ‘The Effects of Technological Change, Experience and Environmental Regulation on the Construction of Coal-burning Generating Units’, 16(1) Rand Journal of Economics, 1-27. Joskow, Paul L. and Rose, Nancy L. (1989), ‘The Effects of Economic Regulation’, in Schmalensee, Richard and Willig, Robert D. (eds), Handbook of Industrial Organization, 2v., Amsterdam, North-Holland, 1449-1506. Joskow, Paul L. and Schmalensee, Richard (1983), Markets for Power: An Analysis of Electric Utility Deregulation, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 269 p. Joskow, Paul L. and Schmalensee, Richard (1986), ‘Incentive Regulation for Electric Utilities’, 4(1) Yale Journal on Regulation, 1-49. Joskow, Paul L., Rose, Nancy L. and Shepard, Andrea. (1993), ‘Regulatory Constraints on CEO Compensation’, Brookings Papers on Economic Activity: Microeconomics, 1-58. Joskow, Paul L., Rose, Nancy L. and Wolfram, Catherine D. (1996), ‘Political Constraints on Executive Compensation: Evidence from the Electric Utility Industry’, 27(1) Rand Journal of Economics, 165-182. Kahn, Alfred E. (1988), The Economics of Regulation: Principles and Institutions, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Kahn, Alfred E. (1991), ‘The Changing Focus of Electric Utility Regulation’, 13 Research in Law and Economics, 221-231. Kahn, Alfred E. (1992), ‘Least Cost Planning Generally and DSM in Particular’, 14(1-2) Resources and Energy, 177-185.
1200
Public Utilities
5940
Kalt, Joseph P. (1991), ‘Using the Gas Industry as a Guide to Reconstituting the Electricity Industry: Comment’, 13 Research in Law and Economics, 57-61. Kaplow, Louis (1993), ‘An Ex Ante Perspective on Deregulation, Viewed Ex Post’, 15(2) Resource and Energy Economics, 153-173. Kendrick, J.W. (1975), ‘Efficiency Incentives and Cost Factors in Public Utility Automatic Revenue Adjustment Clauses’, 6(1) Bell Journal of Economics, 299-313. Kim, Youn (1995), ‘Marginal Cost and Second-Best Pricing for Water Resources’, 10(3) Review of Industrial Organization, 323-338. King, Martin and Cuc, Milan (1996), ‘Price Convergence in North American Natural Gas Spot Markets’, 17(2) Energy Journal, 17-42. Koh, Dong-Soo, Berg, Sanford V. and Kenny, Lawrence W. (1996), ‘A Comparison of Costs in Privately Owned and Publicly Owned Electric Utilities: The Role of Scale’, 72(1) Land Economics, 56-65. Komiya, R. (1962), ‘Technical Progress and the Production Function in the United States Steam Power Industry’, 44 Review of Economics and Statistics, 156-166. Kridel, Donald J., Sappington, David E.M. and Weisman, Dennis L. (1996), ‘The Effects of Incentive Regulation in the Telecommunications Industry: A Survey’, 9(3) Journal of Regulatory Economics, 269-306. Lanen, William N. and Larcker, David F. (1992), ‘Executive Compensation Contract Adoption in the Electric Utility Industry’, 30(1) Journal of Accounting Research, 70-93. Lehman, Dale E. and Weisman, Dennis L. (1996), ‘Telephone Pools and Economic Incentives’, 10(2) Journal of Regulatory Economics, 123-146. Lenard, Thomas M., Geddes, R. Richard and Block, Michael K. (1996), The Competition Revolution and the Market for Energy: The Benefits of Repealing the Public Utility Holding Company Act of 1935, Washington, DC, The Progress and Freedom Foundation. Littlechild, Stephen C. (1992), ‘Spot Pricing of Electricity: An Appraisal of the MIT Model’, in Phillips, Fred Young and Rousseau, John James (eds), Systems and Management Science by Extremal Methods, Norwell, Mass. and Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic. Littlechild, S.C. (1996), ‘Privatization, Competition and Regulation in the Scottish Electricity Industry’, 43(1) Scottish Journal of Political Economy, 1-15. Loube, Robert (1989), ‘The Return of the Electric Utility Holding Company and the Future of the Electric Supply Industry’, 23(2) Journal of Economic Issues, 625-632. Majumdar, Sumit K. (1997), ‘Incentive Regulation and Productive Efficiency in the U.S. Telecommunications Industry’, 70(4) Journal of Business. Maloney, Michael T. and McCormick, Robert E. (1996), Consumer Choice, Consumer Value: An Analysis of Retail Competition in America’s Electricity Industry, Washington, DC, Citizens for a Sound Economy. Marino, A.M. (1978), ‘Peak Load Pricing Under Regulatory Constraint: Two Remarks’, 44(3) Southern Economic Journal, 606-615. McCabe, Kevin A., Rassenti, Stephen J. and Smith, Vernon L. (1991), ‘Experimental Research on Deregulated Markets for Natural Gas Pipeline and Electric Power Transmission Networks’, 13 Research in Law and Economics, 161-189. McLaughlin, Robyn M. and Mehran, Hamid (1995), ‘Regulation and the Market for Corporate Control: Hostile Tender Offers for Electric and Gas Utilities’, 8(2) Journal of Regulatory
5940
Public Utilities
1201
Economics, 181-204. Meyer, R. (1975a), ‘Monopoly Pricing and Capacity Choice under Uncertainty’, 63(3) American Economic Review, 326-337. Meyer, R. (1975b), ‘Publicly Owned Versus Privately Owned Utilities: A Policy Choice’, 62(4) Review of Economics and Statistics, 391-399. Meyer, R. (1976), ‘Capital Structure and Behavior of the Firm Under Uncertainty’, 42(4) Southern Economic Journal, 600-609. Michaels, Robert J. (1993), ‘Not Quite Free Wheeling: The Energy Policy Act of 1992', Winter Regulation, 19-23. Michaels, Robert J. (1996), ‘Stranded Investments, Stranded Intellectuals’, 1 Regulation, 47-51. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1993), ‘The Origins of Utility Regulation and the ‘Theories of Regulation’ Debate: Comments’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 325-329. Monnier, Lionel (1993), ‘The Structure of the Electricity Sector in the European Community’, 64(4) Annals of Public and Cooperative Economics, 531-573. Moore, Thomas Gale (1970), ‘The Effect of Regulation of Electric Utility Prices’, 36(4) Southern Economic Journal, 365-375. Moorhouse, John C. (ed.) (1986), Electric Power: Deregulation and the Public Interest, San Francisco, CA, Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy, 516 p. Moorhouse, John C. (1995), ‘Competitive Markets for Electricity Generation’, 14(3) Cato Journal, 421-441. Munasinghe, M. and Gellerson, M. (1979), ‘Econometric Criteria for Optimizing Power System Reliability’, 10 Bell Journal of Economics, 353-365. Myerson, R.B. (1982), ‘Regulating a Monopolist with Unknown Costs’, 50 Econometrica, 911-930. Nerlove, M. (1963), ‘Returns to Scale in Electric Supply’, in Christ, C.,(ed.), Measurement in Economics, Stanford, CA, Stanford University Press, 167-198. Neuberg, Leland Gerson (1977), ‘Two Issues in the Municipal Ownership of Electric Power Distribution Systems’, 8(1) Bell Journal of Economics, 303-323. Newbery, David M.G. (1994), ‘Restructuring and Privatizing Electric Utilities in Eastern Europe’, 2(3) Economics of Transition, 291-316. Nguyen, D. (1975), ‘The Problem of Peak Loads and Inventories’, 7 Bell Journal of Economics, 242-248. Niskanen, William A. (1996), ‘A Case Against Both Stranded Cost Recovery and Mandatory Access’, 16(1) Regulation, 16-17. Nix, Joan and Gabel, David (1993), ‘AT&T’s Strategic Response to Competition: Why Not Preempt Entry?’, 53(2) Journal of Economic History, 377-387. Norton, Seth W. (1985), ‘Regulation and Systematic Risk: The Case of Electric Utilities’, 28(3) Journal of Law and Economics, 671-686. Norton, Seth W. (1988), ‘Regulation, the OPEC Oil Supply Shock, and Wealth Effects for Electric Utilities’, 26(2) Economic Inquiry, 223-238. Okunade, Albert A. (1993), ‘Economies of Scale in Steam-Electric Power Generation in East-North-Central U.S’., 17(1) Journal of Economics and Finance, 149-156. Orans, Ren et al. (1994), ‘Demand -Side Management and Electric Power Exchange’, 16(3) Resource and Energy Economics, 243-254. Oum, Tae Hoon and Zhang, Yimin (1995), ‘Competition and Allocative Efficiency: The Case of the U.S. Telephone Industry’, 77(1) Review of Economics and Statistics, 82-96.
1202
Public Utilities
5940
Peles, Y.C. and Stein, J.L. (1976), ‘The Effect of Rate of Return Regulation is Highly Sensitive to the Nature of Uncertainty’, 66 American Economic Review, 278-289. Peltzman, Sam (1971), ‘Pricing in Public and Private Enterprises: Electric Utilities in the United States’, 14 Journal of Law and Economics, 109-147. Peltzman, Sam (1976), ‘Towards a More General Theory of Regulation’, 19 Journal of Law and Economics, 211-240. Peltzman, Sam (1989), ‘The Control and Performance of State-Owned Enterprises: Comment’, in MacAvoy, P.W. et al. (eds),Privatization and State-Owned Enterprises: Lessons from the United States, Great Britain and Canada, Norwell, Mass., Dordrecht and Lancaster, UK, Kluwer Academic. Peltzman, Sam (1993), ‘George Stigler’s Contribution to the Economic Analysis of Regulation’,101(5) Journal of Political Economy, 818-32. Percebois, Jacques (1994), ‘Limits of Deregulation in the Natural Gas Industry: The European Case’, 6(3) Energy Studies Review, 237-347. Perrakis, S. (1976), ‘On the Regulated Price Setting Monopoly Firm with a Random Demand Curve’, 66(3) American Economic Review, 410-416. Pescatrice, Donn R. and Trapani, John, M., III (1980), ‘The Performance and Objectives of Public and Private Utilities Operating in the United States’, 13(2) Journal of Public Economics, 259-276. Peters, Lon L. (1993), ‘Non-Profit and For-Profit Electric Utilities in the United States: Pricing and Efficiency’, 64(4) Annals of Public and Cooperative Economics, 575-604. Pierce, Richard J., Jr (1991), ‘Using the Gas Industry as a Guide to Reconstituting the Electricity Industry’, 13 Research in Law and Economics, 7-56. Pollitt, Michael G. (1995), Ownership and Performance in Electric Utilities: The International Evidence on Privatization and Efficiency, Oxford University Press for the Oxford Institute for Energy Studies, 240 p. Pollitt, Michael G. (1996), ‘Ownership and Efficiency in Nuclear Power Production’, 48(2) Oxford Economic Papers, 342-360. Posner, Richard A. (1971), ‘Taxation by Regulation’, 2 Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, 22-50. Posner, Richard A. (1974), ‘Theories of Economic Regulation’, 5 Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, 335-358. Priest, George L. (1993), ‘The Origins of Utility Regulation and the ‘Theories of Regulation’ Debate’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 289-323. Primeaux, Walter J. Jr (1985), ‘Total Deregulation of Electric Utilities: A Viable Policy Choice’, in Poole, Robert W., Jr (ed.), Unnatural Monopolies: The Case for Deregulating Public Utilities, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books,121-146. Primeaux, Walter J., Jr (1986), ‘Competition Between Electric Utilities’, in Moorhouse, John C. (ed.), Electric Power: Deregulation and the Public Interest, San Francisco, CA, Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy, 395-423. Raiffiee, Kambia et al. (1993), ‘Cost Analysis of Water Utilities: A Goodness-of-Fit Approach’, 21(3) Atlantic Economic Journal, 18-29. Renzetti, Steven (1992), ‘Evaluating the Welfare Effects of Reforming Municipal Water Prices’, 22(2) Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 147-163. Ring, Brendan J. and Grant, Read E. (1996), ‘Short Run Pricing in Competitive Electric Markets’, 29S Canadian Journal of Economics, 313-316. Riordan, M.H. (1984), ‘On Delegating Price Authority to a Regulated Firm’, 15(1) Rand Journal of
5940
Public Utilities
1203
Economics, 108-115. Robinson, H. David, Wallace N., III and Glascock, John L. (1995), ‘The Formation of Public Utility Holding Companies and their Subsequent Diversification Activity’, 7(2) Journal of Regulatory Economics, 199-214. Rose, Nancy L. (1985), ‘The Incidence of Regulatory Rents in the Motor Carrier Industry’, 16 Rand Journal of Economics, 299-318. Samuels, Warren J. and Trebing, Harry M. (1972), A Critique of Administration Regulation of Public Utilities, East Lansing, MI, Institute of Public Utilities, Michigan State University, 344 p. Sanghvi, A. (1983), ‘Household Welfare Loss Due to Electricity Supply Disruptions’, 4 Energy Journal, 33-54. Sappington, D. and Stiglitz, J.E. (1987), ‘Information and Regulation’, in Bailey, Elizabeth E. (ed.), Public Regulation: New Perspectives on Institutions and Policies, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Sherman, R. and Visscher, M. (1978), ‘Second Best Pricing with Stochastic Demand’, 68 American Economic Review, 41-53. Shin, Richard T. and Ying, John S. (1992), ‘Unnatural Monopolies in Local Telephone’, 23(2) Rand Journal of Economics, 171-183. Sidak, J. Gregory and Spulber, Daniel F. (1996), ‘Deregulatory Takings and Breach of the Regulatory Contract’, 71(4) New York University Law Review. Smith, Rodney T. (1991), ‘The Significance of the FERC’s Transmission Task Force Report in the Evolution of the Electrical Industry: Comment’, 13 Research in Law and Economics, 151-160. Smith, Vernon L. (1988), ‘Electric Power Deregulation: Background and Prospects’, 6(3) Contemporary Policy Issues, 14-24. Smith, Vernon L. (1993), ‘Can Electric Power - A “Natural Monopoly” - Be Deregulated?’, in Landsberg, Hans H. (ed.), Making National Energy Policy - John M. Olin Distinguished Lectures in Mineral Economics, 131-151. Spann, R. (1974), ‘Rate of Return Regulation and Efficiency in Production: An Empirical Test of the Averch-Johnson Thesis’, 5 Bell Journal of Economics, 38-52. Spann, Robert M. (1977), ‘The Macroeconomics of Unbalanced Growth and the Expanding Public Sector: Some Simple Tests of a Model of Government Growth’, 8(3) Journal of Public Economics, 397-404. Stalon, Charles G. (1991), ‘The Significance of the FERC’s Transmission Task Force Report in the Evolution of the Electric Industry’, 13 Research in Law and Economics, 105-149. Stalon, Charles G. (1992), ‘Restructuring the Electric Industry’, 14(1-2) Resource and Energy Economics, 55-76. Steiner, P.O. (1957), ‘Peak Load and Efficient Pricing’, 71 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 585-610. Stevenson, Rodney E. (1994), ‘Social Goals and Partial Deregulation of the Electric Utility Industry’, 28(2) Journal of Economic Issues, 403-413. Stigler, George J. (1971), ‘The Theory of Economic Regulation’, 2 Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, 3-21. Stigler, George J. (1981), ‘Regulation in Theory and Practice: An Overview, Comment’, in G. Fromm (ed.), Studies in Public Regulation, Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press, 73-77. Stigler, George J. and Friedland, Claire (1962), ‘What Can Regulators Regulate? The Case of
1204
Public Utilities
5940
Electricity’, 5 Journal of Law and Economics, 61-77. Stoft, Steven and Gilbert, Richard J. (1994), ‘A Review and Analysis of Electric Utility Conservation Incentives’, 11(1) Yale Journal on Regulation, 1-42. Taylor, Jerry (1996), ‘Electric Utility Reform: Shock Therapy or Managed Competition?’, 3 Regulation, 63-76. Teets, Walter (1992), ‘The Association between Stock Market Responses to Earnings Announcements and Regulation of Electric Utilities’, 30(2) Journal of Accounting Research, 274-285. Telson, M. (1975), ‘The Economics of Alternative Levels of Reliability for Electric Generation System’, 6(7) Bell Journal of Economics, 679-694. Tolley, George S. et al. (1992), ‘Emerging Issues in the Regulation of Electric Utilities’, 14(1-2) Resources and Energy, 3-35. Train, Kenneth E. and Mehrez, Gil (1994), ‘Optional Time-of-Use Prices for Electricity: Econometric Analysis of Surplus and Pareto Impacts’, 25(2) Rand Journal of Economics, 263-283. Troesken, Werner (1997), ‘The Sources of Public Ownership : Historical Evidence From the Gas Industry’, 13 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 1-25. Tschirhart, John (1991), ‘Entry into the Electric Power Industry’, 3 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 27-43. Tschirhart, John (1994), ‘On the Use “Adders” by Public Utility Commissions’, 15(1) Energy Journal, 121-128. Tschirhart, John (1995), ‘Monopoly Power and the Existence of Natural Monopoly in Energy Utilities’, 17(4) Resource and Energy Economics, 327-340. Tschirhart, John and Jen, F. (1979), ‘Behavior of Monopoly Offering Interruptible Services’, 10 Bell Journal of Economics, 244-258. Upadhya, Kamal P. and Mixon, Franklin G., Jr (1995), ‘Regulatory Capture and the Price of Electricity: Evidence from Time Series Estimates’, 22(1) International Journal of Social Economics, 16-23. Vickers, John and Yarrow, George (1988), Privatization: An Economic Analysis, MIT Press Series on the Regulation of Economic Activity, no.18., Cambridge, Mass., MIT Press. Vickrey, William (1992), ‘Efficient Pricing of Electric Power Service: Some Innovative Solutions’, 14(1-2) Resource and Energy Economics, 157-174. Viscusi, W. Kip, Vernon, John M. and Harrington, Joseph E., Jr (1995), Economics of Regulation and Antitrust, 2nd edn, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Wall, Richard A. and Gort, Michael (1990), ‘An Empirical Test of Feedbacks in Public Utility Regulation’, 12(1) Resources and Energy, 107-116. Walters, P.J. and Smith, D.W. (1993), ‘The Energy Policy Act of 1992 - A Watershed for Competition in the Wholesale Power Market’, 10 Yale Journal on Regulation, 447-482. Watkiss, Jeffrey D. and Smith, Douglas W. (1993), ‘The Energy Policy Act of 1992 - A Watershed for Competition in the Wholesale Power Market’, 10(2) Yale Journal on Regulation, 447-492. Waverman, L. (1975), ‘Peak Load Pricing Under Regulatory Constraint: A Proof of Efficiency’, 83(3) Journal of Political Economy, 645-654. Weiss, Leonard W. and Klass, Michael W. (eds) (1986), Regulatory Reform: What Actually Happened, Boston, Little Brown. Wenders, J. (1976), ‘Peak Load Pricing in the Electric Utility Industry’, 7 Bell Journal of Economics,
5940
Public Utilities
1205
232-241. Williamson, O.E. (1966), ‘Peak Load Pricing and Optimal Capacity under Indivisibility Constraints’, 56 American Economic Review, 810-827. Willig, Robert D. (1980), ‘What Can Markets Control?’, in Sherman, R. (ed.), Perspectives on Postal Service Issues, Washington, American Enterprise Institute Press. Winston, Clifford (1993), ‘Economic Deregulation: Days of Reckoning for Microeconomists’, 31(3) Journal of Economic Literature, 1263-1289. Wirl, Franz (1994), ‘On the Unprofitability of Utility Demand Side Conservation Programs’, 16(1) Energy Economics, 46-53. Woo, C.K. and Toyama, N. (1986), ‘Service Reliability and Optimal Interruptible Rate Option in Residential Electricity Pricing’, 4(3) Energy Journal, 123-136. Yaisawarang, Suthathip and Klein, J. Douglas (1994), ‘The Effects of Sulphur Dioxide Controls on Productivity Change in the Electric Power Industry’, 76(3) Review of Economics and Statistics, 447-460. Zajac, E. (1970), ‘A Geometric Treatment of Averch-Johnson’s Behavior of the Firm Model’, 60 American Economic Review, 117-125. Zarnikau, Jay (1994), ‘Spot Market Pricing of Water Resources and Efficient Means of Rationing Water during Scarcity’, 16(3) Resource and Energy Economics, 189-210. Zupan, Mark A. (1989a), ‘Nonprice Concessions and the Effects of Franchise Bidding Schemes on Cable Company Costs’, 21(3) Applied Economics, 305-324. Zupan, Mark A. (1989b), ‘A Test for Regulatory Lag and the Role Played by Periodic Contract Renewals in Mitigating Such Lag in Local Cable Franchise Relationships’, 1(1) Journal of Regulatory Economics, 1-20.
6000 OPTIMAL TAXATION: GENERAL © Copyright 1999 Boudewijn Bouckaert and Gerrit De Geest
Bibliography Collected by the Editors Auerbach, Alan J. and Hines, James R., Jr (1988), ‘Investment Tax Incentives and Frequent Tax Reforms’, 78 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 211-216. Backhaus, Jürgen G. (1990), ‘Die Politische Ökonomie der Schutzzolltheorie (Political Economics of the Protection Tariff Theory)’, in Schefold, Bertram (ed.), Studien zur Entwicklung der oekonomischen Theorie X, Berlin, Duncker and Humblot, 103-113. Barnett, Richard, Barrow, Michael and Smith, Peter (1991), ‘Representation Without Taxation: An Empirical Assessment of the Validity of the Accountability Argument Underlying the Reform of Local Government Finance in England’, 12(3) Fiscal Studies. Becker, Gary S. (1986), ‘The Public Interest Hypothesis Revisited: A New Test of Peltzman’s Theory of Regulation’, 49 Public Choice, 223 ff. Bell, Edward B., Bodenhorn, Diran and Taub, Allan J. (1983), ‘Taxes and Compensation for Lost Earnings’, 12 Journal of Legal Studies, 181-194. Bell, Edward B., Bodenhorn, Diran and Taub, Allan J. (1985), ‘Taxes and Compensation for Lost Earnings: Reply’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 457-458. Benson, Bruce L. (1990), ‘Interstate Tax Competition, Incentives to Collude, and Federal Influences’, 10 Cato Journal, 75-90. Benson, Bruce L. and Engen, Eric M. (1988), ‘The Market for Laws: An Economic Analysis of Legislation’, 54 Southern Economic Journal, 732-745. Benson, Bruce L. and Faminow, Merle D. (1986), ‘The Incentives to Organize and Demand Regulation: Two Ends against the Middle’, 24 Economic Inquiry, 473-484. Bizer, David S. and Judd, Kenneth L. (1989), ‘Taxation and Uncertainty’, 79 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 331-336. Bohanon, Cecil E. and Van Cott, T. Norman (1991), ‘Product Quality andTaxation: A Reconciliation’, 19 Public Finance Quarterly, 233-237. Bossons, John (1970), ‘The Value of a Comprehensive Tax Base as a Tax Reform Goal’, 13 Journal of Law and Economics, 327-363. Browning, Edgar K. and Browning, Jacquelene M. (1985), ‘Why not a True Flat Rate Tax?’, 5 Cato Journal, 629-650. Buchanan, James M. (1978), ‘Tax Reform in Constitutional Perspective’, in Skogh, Göran (ed.), Law and Economics. Report from a Symposium in Lund, Lund, Juridiska Föreningen, 103-120. Buchanan, James M., Tollison, Robert D. and Tullock, Gordon (eds) (1980), Toward a Theory of the Rent Seeking Society, College Station, Texas, A&M University Press. Bucovetsky, Sam (1991), ‘Choosing Tax Rates and Public Expenditure Levels Using Majority Rule’, 46 Journal of Public Economics, 113-131. Caanen, Ch. and Essers, P.H.J. (1990), ‘Rechtseconomie en Belastingrecht (Law and Economics and Taxation Law)’, 39(10) Ars Aequi, 677-681.
1
2
Optimal Taxation: General
6000
Carbajo, Domingo and Ruesca, Santos M. (1994), ‘La Incidencia de la Fiscalidad Sobre Bienes Inmuebles en la Movilidad de los Factores Productivos en el Mercadonico Europeo (Especial Referencia a la Movilidad del Capital) (The Effect of Real State Taxes on the Mobility of the Factors in the E.U. Market Special Regard to Capital Mobility)’, 18 Actualidad Tributaria, 475-490. Collard, David (ed) (1989), Fiscal Policy: Essays in Honour of Cedric Sandford, Aldershot, Gower, 173 p. Cooper, Graeme S. (1986), ‘Income Tax Law and Contributive Justice: Some Thoughts on Defining and Expressing a Consistent Theory of Tax Justice and Its Limitations’, 3 Australian Tax Forum, 297-332. Cooter, Robert D. (1978), ‘Optimal Tax Schedules and Rates’, 68 American Economic Review. Cooter, Robert D. and Helpman, Elhanan (1974), ‘Optimal Income Taxation for Transfer Payments Under Different Social Welfare Functions’, 88 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 656 ff. Crain, W. Mark and Oakley, Lisa K. (1995), ‘The Politics of Infrastructure’, 38 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-17. Crain, W. Mark and Tollison, Robert D. (1979), ‘The Executive Branch in the Interest-Group Theory of Government’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 555-567. Creedy, J. (1988), ‘Taxation and Compensation to Dependents of Accident Victims’, 8 International Review of Law and Economics, 85-95. Davis, Karen (1989), ‘National Health Insurance: A Proposal’, 79 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 349-352. De Clercq, Marc and Naert, Frank (1985), De Politieke Markt (The Political Market), Antwerpen, Kluwer, 163 p. De Geest, Gerrit (1990), ‘Public Choice en Rechtseconomie (Public Choice and Law and Economics)’, 39(10) Ars Aequi in Bock, Ruth de, et al. (eds), Themanummer Rechtseconomie, 666-673. Degenkamp, J.Th. and Heynen, H.M. (1980), Tolvrije Gedachten (Free Thoughts), Deventer, Kluwer, 304 p. Department of the Treasury (1984), Tax Reform for Fairness, Simplicity, and Economic Growth The Treasury Department Report to the President, 2 vols, Washington, US Treasury, 262 p. Diamond, Stephen (1983), ‘The Death and Transfiguration of Benefit Taxation: Special Assessments in Nineteenth-Century America’, 12 Journal of Legal Studies, 201-240. Dilorenzo, T.J. (1984), ‘The Domain of Rent-Seeking Behaviour: Private or Public Choice?’, 4 International Review of Law and Economics, 185-197. Dilorenzo, T.J. (1988), ‘Property Rights, Information Costs, and the Economics of Rent Seeking’, 144 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 318-322. Dye, Thomas R. (1985), ‘Impact of Federal Tax Reform on State-Local Finances’, 5 Cato Journal, 597 ff. Eden, Lorraine (1991), ‘Free Trade, Tax Reform, and Transfer Pricing’, 39(1) Canadian Tax Journal, 90-112. Ekelund, Robert B., Jr and Tollison, Robert D. (1981), Mercantilism as a Rent Seeking Society: Economic Regulation in Historical Perspective, College Station, Texas, A&M University Press, 169 p.
6000
Optimal Taxation: General
3
Fane, George (1991), ‘Piecemeal Tax Reforms, and the Compensated Radial Elasticities of Tax Bases’, 45 Journal of Public Economics, 263-270. Fazzari, Steven, Hubbard, R. Glenn and Petersen, Bruce (1988), ‘Investment, Financing Decisions, and Tax Policy’, 78 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 200-205. Fellows, Mary Louise (1990), ‘A Comprehensive Attack on Tax Deferral’, 88 Michigan Law Review, 722-813. Flowers, Marilyn R. (1987), ‘Rent Seeking and Rent Dissipation: A Critical View’, 7 Cato Journal, 431-440. Formby, John P., Keeler, James P. and Thistle, Paul D. (1988), ‘X-Efficiency, Rent-Seeking, and Social Costs’, 57 Public Choice, 115-126. Formby, John P., Keeler, James P. and Thistle, Paul D. (1991), ‘X-Efficiency, Rent-Seeking and Social Costs: Reply’, 68 Public Choice, 267-271. Frey, Donald E. (1991), ‘Optimal-Sized Tuition Tax Credits Reconsidered: Comment’, 19(3) Public Finance Quarterly, 347-354. Garcia Villarejo, Salinas, Avelino and Sánchez, Javier (1993), Manual de Hacienda Pública General y de España (Public Treasury Manual), Madrid, Tecnos. Gephardt, Richard (1985), ‘The Economics and Politics of Tax Reform’, 5 Cato Journal, 455-464. Gillette, Clayton P. and Hopkins, Thomas D. (1987), ‘Federal User Fees: A Legal and Economic Analysis’, 67 Boston University Law Review, 795-874. Gimeno Ullastres, Juan A. (1980), ‘La Incidencia del Gasto Público por Niveles de Renta: España 1990 vs. 1980 (The Effect of Public Expenditure by Levels of Income: Spain 1990 vs. 1980)’, in X (ed), I Simposio Sobre la Igualdad y Distribución de la Renta y la Riqueza, Fundación Argentaria, 63-121. Gimeno Ullastres, Juan A. (1981), ‘Reforma Fiscal y Sistema Tributario (Reforming the Tax System)’, in X (ed), Las Reformas Urgentes, Madrid, Taller Ediciones JB, 481-490. Gimeno Ullastres, Juan A. (1983), ¿A Quién Beneficia el Gasto Público? (Who Does Public Expenditure Favour?), Número Monografico de la Revista de Economía Pública e Historia Económica. Gimeno Ullastres, Juan A. (1984), ‘Los Recargos Locales sobre Impuestos Estatales (Local Overcharges on Central Taxes)’, 1114(21) La ley, 1-4. Gimeno Ullastres, Juan A. and Ruiz Huerta, Jesús (1979), ‘Descentralización Fiscal y Corresponsablidad a Través de las Grandes Figuras Tributarias (Tax Descentralization and Corresponsability)’, 3(1);2°ép Cuadernos Aragoneses de Economía, 29-40. Gimeno Ullastres, Juan A. and Ruiz Huerta, Jesús (1980), ‘Financiación Autonómica: Un Modelo Alternativo de Corresponsabilidad Fiscal (Financing the Communities: An Alternative Model for Tax Corresponsability)’, 15 Revista Valenciana de Hacienda Pública, 149-179. Gimeno Ullastres, Juan A. and Ruiz Huerta, Jesús (1981), El Nuevo Estado Fiscal Español (The New Spanish Fiscal State), Madrid, H. Blume, 315 p. Gimeno Ullastres, Juan A. and Ruiz Huerta, Jesús (1986), ‘Reforma Fiscal y Financiación del las CCAA: El Régimen Especial (Financing The Communities and Tax Reform: The Special Regime)’, in X (ed), Estado Federal/Estado Regional: La Financianción de las Comunidades Autónomas, Salamanca, Ediciones de la Diputación de Salamanca, 245-263.
4
Optimal Taxation: General
6000
Gimeno Ullastres, Juan A., Ruiz Huerta, Jesús and Olleros, Jaime (1987), Una Reforma Fiscal para España (Tax Reform in Spain), Moneda y Credito S.A. Gordon, James P.F. (1991), ‘Tax Reform and Uniformity: Explaining the Hatta Result’, 45(2) Journal of Public Economics, 161-190. Graetz, Michael J. and Wilde, Louis L. (1985), ‘The Economics of Tax Compliance: Fact and Fantasy’, 38 National Tax Journal, 355-363. Graetz, Michael J., Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, Louis L. (1986), ‘The Tax Compliance Game: Toward an Interactive Theory of Law Enforcement’, 2 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 1-32. Hansen, Susan B. (1985), ‘Tax Reform: Sound Economics or Power Politics? Comment on Dye’, 5 Cato Journal, 609-612. Hettich, Walter and Winer, Stanley L. (1988), ‘Economic and Political Foundations of Tax Structure’, 78 American Economic Review, 701-712. Hofmann, E. and Wehrt, Klaus (1992), ‘Die Reform der Kfz-Steuer - Wirtschaftspolitisch Betrachtet (Economic Analysis of the Reform of the Motor Vehicle Tax)’, 4 Zeitschrift für Verkehrswissenschaft, 263-271. Inman, Robert P. and Fitts, Michael A. (1990), ‘Political Institutions and Fiscal Policy: Evidence from the U.S. Historical Record’, 6(S) Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 79-132. Jackman, Richard (1986), ‘The Economic Effects of Tax Based Incomes Policy’, in Colander, David C. (ed), Incentive Based Incomes Policies: Advances in TIP and MAP, Cambridge, MA, Harper and Row, 95-109. Johnson, Calvin H. (1989), ‘Why Have Anti-Tax Legislation? A Response to Professor Zelenak’, 67 Texas Law Review., -625. Kalt, Joseph P. and Zupan, Mark A. (1990), ‘The Apparent Ideological Behavior of Legislators: Testing for Principal-Agent Slack in Political Institutions’, 33 Journal of Law and Economics, 103-131. Kaplow, Louis (1989), ‘Horizontal Equity: Measures in Search of a Principle’, 42 National Tax Journal, 139-154. Kaplow, Louis (1992a), ‘A Note on Horizontal Equity’, 1 Florida Tax Review, 191-196. Kaplow, Louis (1992b), ‘Government Relief for Risk Associated with Government Action’, 94 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 525-541. Kaplow, Louis (1993), ‘Should the Government’s Allocation Branch be Concerned About the Distortionary Cost of Taxation and Distributive Effects?’, Program in Law and Economics Discussion Paper, 122 ff. Kaplow, Louis (1994), ‘Taxation and Risk Taking: A General Equilibrium Perspective’, 47 National Tax Journal, 789-798. Kaplow, Louis (1995a), ‘A Note on Subsidizing Gifts’, 58 Journal of Public Economics, 469-477. Kaplow, Louis (1995b), ‘A Fundamental Objection to Tax Equity Norms: A Call for Utilitarianism’, 48 National Tax Journal, 497-514. Kaplow, Louis (1996a), ‘Tax and Non-Tax Distortions’, 57 Journal of Public Economics. Kaplow, Louis (1996b), ‘Regional Cost-of-Living Adjustments in Tax-Transfer Schemes’, 51 Tax Law Review. Kaplow, Louis (1996c), ‘Fiscal Federalism and the Deductibility of State and Local Taxes in a Federal Income Tax’, 82 Virginia Law Review.
6000
Optimal Taxation: General
5
Karp, Larry S. and Perloff, Jeffrey M. (1989), ‘Estimating Market Structure and Tax Incidence: The Japanese Television Market’, 37(3) Journal of Industrial Economics, 225-239. Katz, Avery and Mankiw, Gregory (1985), ‘How Should Fringe Benefits be Taxed?’, 38 National Tax Journal, 37-45. Kau, James B. and Rubin, Paul H. (1979), ‘Self-Interest, Ideology, and Logrolling in Congressional Voting’, 22 Journal of Law and Economics, 365-384. Kay, John A. and King, M.A. (1986), The British Tax System, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 261 p. Kerwin, Cornelis M. (1983), ‘Assessing the Effects of Consensual Processes in Regulatory Programs: Methodological and Policy Issues’, 32 American University Law Review, 401 ff. Kiesling, Herbert J. (1990), ‘Economic and Political Foundations of Tax Structure: Comment’, 80 American Economic Review. Krueger, Anne O. (1974), ‘The Political Economy of the Rent-seeking Society’, 64 American Economic Review, 291-303. Labovitz, John R. (1974), ‘The Impact of the Private Foundation Provisions of the Tax Reform Act of 1969: Early Empirical Measurements’, 3 Journal of Legal Studies, 63-105. Landry, Raymond A. (1991), ‘La Priorité Fiscale sur les Meubles et le Projet de Code Civil du Québec (Fiscal Priority on Movables and the Quebec Civil Code Bill)’, 22 Revue générale de droit, 649-658. Lehmann, Michael (1991), ‘Umwelthaftungsrecht dient der Internalisierung negativer Extemalitäten, Kommentar (Environmental Liability Law is to Internalize Negative Externalities. A Comment)’, in Ott, Claus and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (eds), Ökonomische Probleme des Zivilrechts, Berlin, Springer, 290-294. Lindsey, Lawrence (1990), The Growth Experiment: How the New Tax Policy is Transforming the U.S. Economy, New York, Basic Books, 260 p. Maddock, Rodney (1982), ‘Comment’, in Cranston, Ross and Schick, Anne (eds), Law and Economics, Canberra, Australian National University, 190-191. Marlow Michael L. and Orzechowski, William P. (1997), ‘The Separation of Spending from Taxation: Implications for Collective Choices’, 8 Constitutional Political Economy, 151-163. McCaffery, Edward J. (1990), ‘The Holy Grail of Tax Simplification’, 66 Wisconsin Law Review, 1267-1322. McChesney, Fred S. (1987), ‘Rent Extraction and Rent Creation in the Economic Theory of Regulation’, 16 Journal of Legal Studies, 101-118. McCubbins, Mathew D. (1990), ‘Note: Budget Policy-making and the Appearance of Power’, 6(S) Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 133-153. McGee, Robert W. (1993), ‘Principles of Taxation for Emerging Economies: Some Lessons from the U.S. Experience’, 12(1) Dickinson Journal of International Law, 29-93. McGee, Robert W. (1996a), ‘Tax Advice for Latvia and Other Similarly Situated Emerging Economies’, 13(2) International Tax and Business Lawyer, 223-308. McGee, Robert W. (1996b), Essays on Accounting, Taxation and Public Finance, Dumont Institute for Public Policy Research. <>
6
Optimal Taxation: General
6000
McGee, Robert W. (1996c), Taxation, Ethics and Public Policy, Dumont Institute for Public Policy Research. http:/ww.hili.com~dumontin McGee, Robert W. (1997), ‘Some Principles of Taxation for Latin America: Lessons from the USA and European Experiences’, in Gertner, David, Bocater, Paulo F. and Leal, Ricardo R.C. (eds), Regionalism and Globalization in Latin America: A Contradiction?, Rio de Janeiro, Business Association of Latin American Studies and Instituto de Administração e Gerência Pontifícia Universidade Católica do Rio de Janeiro, 266-280. Mintz, Jack M. and Whalley, John (eds) (1989), The Economic Impacts of Tax Reform, Toronto, Canadian Tax Foundation, 463 p. Musgrave, Richard A. and Musgrave, Peggy B. (1985), Public Finance in Theory and Practice, Tokyo, McGraw-Hill, 824 p. Naert, Frank (1984), ‘De Politieke Economie van Pressiegroepen (The Political Economy of Pressure Groups)’, 69 Economisch-Statistische Berichten, 56-61. Naert, Frank (1987), ‘Overheidsuitgaven en Pressiegroepen in België’, 32 Tijdschrift voor Economie en Management, 165-187. Page, William H. (1987), ‘Interest Groups, Antitrust, and State Regulation: Parker v. Brown in the Economic Theory of Legislation’, 37 Duke Law Journal, 618-668. Pauly, Mark V. (1986), ‘Taxation, Health Insurance, and Market Failure in the Medical Economy’, 24 Journal of Economic Literature, 629-675. Peacock, Alan T. and Forte, Francesco (eds) (1981), The Political Economy of Taxation, Oxford, Blackwell, 211 p. Pechman, Joseph A. (1987), Federal Tax Policy (5th edn), Washington, Brookings Institution, 430 p. Pechman, Joseph A. (1989), Tax Reform, the Rich and the Poor, Washington, Brookings Institution, 211 p. Pechman, Joseph A. (1990), ‘The Future of Income Tax’, 80 American Economic Review, 1-20. Peltzman, Sam (1980), ‘The Growth of Government’, 23 Journal of Law and Economics. Peltzman, Sam (1984), ‘Constituent Interest and Congressional Voting’, 27 Journal of Law and Economics, 181-210. Peterson, Pamela P. (1985), ‘Lingering Questions About Tax Reform: Comment on Browning and Browning’, 5 Cato Journal, 651-656. Priest, W. Curtiss (1988), Risks, Concerns, and Social Regulation: Forces that Led to Laws on Health, Safety, and the Environment, Boulder, CO, Westview Press, 204 p. Pritchard, A.C. (1991), ‘Note: Government Promises and Due Process: An Economic Analysis of the “New Property”’, 77 Virginia Law Review, 1053-1090. Provopoulos, George and Zambaras, Athanassios (1991), ‘Testing for Causality Between Government Spending and Taxation’, 68 Public Choice, 277-282. Puy Fraga, Pedro, Suárez, A. Iglésias and Ron Romero, Ron J. (1985), ‘Una Nota Sobre los Problemas que Plantea la Imposición Autonómica y la Municipal (A Note on Autonomic and Local Taxes)’, in X (ed), Actas de la X Reunión de Estudios Regionales, T. II, Asociación Española de Ciencia Regional - Junta de Castilla León, 901-909.
6000
Optimal Taxation: General
7
Ramseyer, J. Mark and Nakazato, Minoru (1989), ‘Tax Transitions and the Protection Racket: A Reply To Professors Graetz and Kaplow’, 75 Virginia Law Review, 1155 ff. Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, Louis L. (1991), ‘Equilibrium Enforcement and Compliance in the Presence of Tax Practitioners’, 7 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 163-181. Rice, Edward M. and Ulen, Thomas S. (1981), ‘Rent Seeking and Welfare Loss’, 3 Research in Law and Economics, 53-65. Rodios, Nikos D. (1986), ‘E Kampyle tou Laffer e Peri tes Phthinousas Apodoseos tes Phorologias (The Laffer Curve or On the Diminishing Return of Taxation)’, 53 Ephemeris ton Hellenon Nomikon, 216-218. Rogers, Carol Ann (1991), ‘A Simple Model of Endogenous Tax Reform’, 46 Journal of Public Economics, 91-111. Rogerson, William P. (1990), ‘Comment (on “Political Institutions and Fiscal Policy: Evidence from the U.S. Historical Record”)’, 6(S) Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 155-166. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1990), ‘Comment (on Ferejohn and Shipan’s “Congressional Influence (on Bureaucracy)”’, 6(S) Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 21-27. Ross, Thomas W. (1986), ‘Store Wars: The Chain Tax Movement’, 29 Journal of Law and Economics, 125-137. Rowley, Charles K., Tollison, Robert D. and Tullock, Gordon (eds) (1988), The Political Economy of Rent-Seeking, Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers. Ru, H.J. De (1988), Prijst de Wet Zich uit de Markt? (Does the Law Price Itself Out of the Market?), Zwolle, Tjeenk Willink. Ruiz-Huerta Carbonell, Jesús (1992), ‘Vigencia y Operatividad del Principio de la no Confiscatoriedad de los Tributos en el Ordenamiento Español (The Principle of Non Confiscation of Taxes: Enforcement in Spain)’, 64 Revista Crónica Tributaria. Ruiz-Huerta Carbonell, Jesús and Giménez, Antonio (eds) (1993), Estructura Institucional y Gestión del Gasto Público en algunos Paises de la OCDE (Institutuional Structure and Managment of Public Expenditure in Some Countries), Estudios de Hacienda Pública, Instituto de Estudios Fiscales. Russo, Enzo (1992), ‘L’Impatto Amministrativo della Riforma del Contenzioso: Spunti di Analisi Economica del Diritto (The Administrative Impact of the Reform of the Contentious Procedure: Hints of Economic Analysis of Law)’, Il Fisco, 10471-10479. Salinas, Javier (1990), Economía Política del Federalismo Fiscal España (The Political Economy of Spanish Fiscal Federalism), Madrid, Instituto de Estudios Fiscales. Schmalbeck, Richard L. and Myers, Gary (1986), ‘A Policy Analysis of Fee-Shifting Rules under the Internal Revenue Code’, 66 Duke Law Journal, 970-1002. Seidl, Christian (1980), ‘Historischer Abriß österreichischer Steuerstrukturen und Steuerreformen (A History of Austrian Tax Structures and Tax Reforms)’, in Helige, O. (ed), Dokumentation zur Steuerreformkommission, Wirtschaftsverlag Dr. Anton Orac, Wien, 219-231. Shachar, Avishai (1985), ‘The Importance of Considering Liabilities in Tax Transitions’, 98 Harvard Law Review, 1842-1868.
8
Optimal Taxation: General
6000
Shaviro, Daniel N. (1988), ‘The New Alternative Minimum Tax: Perception, Reality, and Strategy’, 66 Taxes, 91-113. Shaviro, Daniel N. (1989a), ‘Risk and Accrual: The Tax Treatment of Nonrecourse Debt’, 44 Tax Law Review, 401-457. Shaviro, Daniel N. (1989b), ‘Selective Limitations on Tax Benefits’, 56 University of Chicago Law Review, 1189-1260. Shaviro, Daniel N. (1990), ‘Beyond Public Choice and Public Interest: A Study of the Legislative Process As Illustrated by Tax Legislation in the 1980s’, 139 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1-123. Shaviro, Daniel N. (1992a), ‘An Economic and Political Look at Federalism in Taxation,’, 90 Michigan Law Review, 895-991. Shaviro, Daniel N. (1992b), ‘An Efficiency Analysis of Realization and Recognition Rules Under the Federal Income Tax’, 48 Tax Law Review, 1-68. Shaviro, Daniel N. (1993a), Federalism in Taxation: The Case for Greater Uniformity, Washington, AEI Press. Shaviro, Daniel N. (1993b), ‘Commentary: Uneasiness and Capital Gains’, 48 Tax Law Review, 393-417. Shaviro, Daniel N. (1995), ‘Risk-Based Rules and the Taxation of Capital Income’, 50 Tax Law Review, 643-724. Shaviro, Daniel N. (1997), ‘The Minimum Wage, the Earned Income Tax Credit, and Optimal Subsidy Policy’, 64 University of Chicago Law Review. Shughart, William F., II (1987), ‘Durable Tax Reform’, 7 Cato Journal, 273-281. Shughart, William F., II and Tollison, Robert D. (1986), ‘On the Growth of Government and the Political Economy of Legislation’, 9 Research in Law and Economics, 111-127. Smith, Tom and Whaley, Robert E. (1994), ‘Assessing the Costs of Regulation: The Case of Dual Trading’, 37 Journal of Law and Economics, 215-246. Spinnewyn, F. (1987), ‘Inkomensvorming en Deregulering van de Arbeidsmarkt: 4. Sociale Zekerheid (Income Formation and Deregulation of the Labour Market: Social Security)’, in X (ed.), 18de Vlaams Wetenschappelijk Economisch Congres, Brussel 8 en 9 mei 1987, Sociaal-economische Deregulering, Brussel, V.E.H.U.B., 305-320. Stake, Jeffrey E. (1995), ‘Loss Aversion and Involuntary Transfers of Title’, in Malloy, Robin P. and Braun, Christopher K. (eds), Law and Economics: New and Critical Perspectives, New York, Peter Lang, 331-360. Stein, Herbert (1966), ‘Pre-Revolutionary Fiscal Policy: The Regime of Herbert Hoover’, 9 Journal of Law and Economics, 189-223. Steuerle, C. Eugene (1986), Who Should Pay for Collecting Taxes?, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 75 p. Stout, Lynn A. (1981), ‘Note: The Case for Mandatory Separate Filing by Married Persons’, 91 Yale Law Journal, 363-382. Stout, Lynn A. (1995), ‘Are Stock Markets Costly Casinos? Disagreement, Market Failure, and Securities Regulation’, 81 Virginia Law Review, 611 ff. Tiebout, Charles M. (1956), ‘A Pure Theory of Local Government Expenditures’, 64 Journal of Political Economy, 416-424. Reprinted in Cowen, T. (ed.) (1992), Public Goods and Market Failures, Chapter 9, London: Transaction Publishers. Tillman, Georg (1989), Equity, Incentives, and Taxation, Berlin, Springer, 132 p. Tollison, Robert D. (1982), ‘Rent-Seeking: a Survey’, 35 Kyklos, 575-602.
6000
Optimal Taxation: General
9
Trebilcock, Michael J. and Engelhart, Kenneth (1981), ‘A Tax Credit for Public Interest Groups’, 3 Canadian Taxation: A Journal of Tax Policy, 29-33. Tullock, Gordon (1988), ‘The Costs of Rent-Seeking: A Metaphysical Problem’, 57 Public Choice, 15-24. Tullock, Gordon (1989), The Economics of Special Privilege and Rent Seeking, Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 104 p. Turnbull, Shann (1982), ‘Resource Tax Alternative’, 1(2) Economic Papers, The Economic Society of Australia, Sydney, 85-88. Van den Hauwe, Ludwig (1995), ‘Review of: Flair and de Boussieu, Fiscal Policy, Taxation and the Financial System in an Increasingly Integrated Europe’, 85 Public Choice, 400-405. Vanberg, Viktor J. and Buchanan, James M. (1986), ‘Organization Theory and Fiscal Economics: Society, State and Public Debt’, 2 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 215-227. Vedder, Richard (1985), ‘Federal Tax Reform: Lessons from the States’, 5 Cato Journal, 571-590. Vickrey, William (1947), Agenda for Progressive Taxation, New York, Ronald Press, 496 p. Walz, W. Rainer (1988), ‘Rechtssicherheit und Risikozuweisung bei Steuerrechtsänderungen Verbotene Rückwirkung, gebotene Übergangsregelung, richterliche Vertragsanpassung (Legal Certainty and Risk Allocation for Changes in Tax Law - Illegal Retroaction, Transitional Rules)’, Recht und Risiko, 252-286. Waters, Melissa and Moore, William J. (1990), ‘The Theory of Economic Regulation and Public Choice and the Determinants of Public Sector Bargaining Legislation’, 66 Public Choice, 161-175. Webb, V.C. (1990), ‘The Taxation Rulings System - A Helpful Child or a Potential Bully?’, 7(2) Australian Tax Forum, 217-252. Wenders, John T. (1987), ‘On Perfect Rent Dissipation’, 77 American Economic Review, 456-459. White, P.D. (1990), ‘Realization, Recognition, Reconciliation, Rationality and the Structure of the Federal Income Tax System’, 88 Michigan Law Review, 2034-2096. Wibaut, Serge (1989), Tax Reform in Disequilibrium Economies, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 113 p. Wildasin, David E. (1990), ‘R.M. Haig: Pioneer Advocate of Expenditure Taxation?’, 28 Journal of Economic Literature, 649-654. Wilson, John Douglas (1991), ‘Optimal Public Good Provision With Limited Lump-Sum Taxation’, 81 American Economic Review, 153-166. Wood, John C. (1980), ‘Alfred Marshall and the Tariff-Reform Campaign of 1903', 23 Journal of Law and Economics, 481-495. Yandle, Bruce (1989), The Political Limits of Environmental Regulation: Tracking the Unicorn, Westport, Greenwood, 180 p. Yorio, Edward (1985), ‘The President’s Tax Proposals: A Major Step in the Right Direction’, 53 Fordham Law Review, 1255 ff. Zelenak, Lawrence (1989), ‘When Good Preferences Go Bad: A Critical Analysis of the Anti-Tax Shelter Provisions of the Tax Reform Act of 1986', 67 Texas Law Review, 499 ff.
10
Optimal Taxation: General
6000
Zelinsky, Edward A. (1986), ‘Efficiency and Income Taxes: The Rehabilitation of Tax Incentives’, 64 Texas Law Review, 973-1037. Zwemmer, J.W. (1995), ‘Belastingrecht op het Grensvlak van Economie en Recht (Tax Law on the Borderline of Economics and Law)’, in X (ed), Ondernemen tussen Macht en Ordening: Opstellen op het Grensvlak van Economie en Recht, Amsterdam, Thesis Publishers, 37-45.
6010 TAXATION: MACRO ASPECTS Jef Vuchelen Vrije Universiteit Brussel © Copyright 1999 Jef Vuchelen
Abstract This chapter on macro aspects of taxation begins with a discussion of the contribution of taxation to stabilization policies. The budget constraint of the government and the expectations of economic agents about taxation are crucial elements here. The effectiveness of countercyclical policies has, however, been challenged by questions about the relevancy of the timing of taxation. We therefore cover the Barro-Ricardo equivalence theorem. Next we review the literature on taxation and inflation and the positive approaches to taxation. The discussion so far relates primarily to closed economies. The last section surveys some of the publications on the macro aspects of taxation in open economies. JEL classification: H10, H30, H70 Keywords: Taxation, Government Budget Constraint, Stabilization Policies, Ricardian Equivalence, Inflation
1. Introduction Over the past decades taxation has increased to levels not experienced before, which has stimulated theoretical and empirical research on the effects of taxation. The search for policy instruments to stimulate economic growth, led most governments to reform taxation (= lower marginal rates), especially income taxation. Notwithstanding, for most economic agents total taxes are still the main single item on the expenditure side of their accounts. Reactions to current and expected taxation are therefore among the more important economic decisions to be made. These decisions cannot be neglected by policymakers. For economists, the sheer size of taxation implies that no macroeconomic shock can be analyzed without considering the effects on the government finances. Frequently in theoretical research the tax rate is assimilated to the income tax rate. The discussion about the effects of this tax could serve as a guide for the theoretical macroeconomic effects. The interest in taxation or, more generally, in public finances, has not only been stimulated by the rise in ‘instant’ taxation but also by the tax-postponing policies pursued by many governments since the mid -1970s through the accumulation of government debt. Analyses of the long-run problems related 11
12
Taxation: Macro Aspects
6010
to large stocks of government debt were never as relevant. Data for, for example, the 15 countries of the European Union illustrate the extent of the accumulation of government debt. Total debt amounts now (1998) to about 5,270 billion ECU or 70.5 percent of GDP. This represents 153 percent of current yearly taxation. The per capita debt of every EU citizen equals nearly 14,000 ECU. Just as it does for any economic entity, a budget constraint unites all operations of the government. This constraint thus links tax policy with expenditures policy, deficits and monetary policy. Any distinction between the different policies is therefore somewhat arbitrary. Evidently some choices had to be made in this survey. We restrict this survey to issues that are directly related to the macroeconomic aspects of taxation. This implies that we will not discuss the relative merits of monetary and fiscal policy, or the link between taxation and government expenditures. We agree here with Kay (1990, p. 18): ‘The link between tax and spending is now close and symmetric. But this symmetry is rarely reflected in the theory, or the practice, of tax policy’. Furthermore, we will not consider sectorial, regional or local aspects. As a result, studies concerning, for example, the taxation of international income or commodity flows (tariffs) will not be surveyed. References related to the government debt will only be discussed when they have a direct impact on taxation. This explains, for example, the absence of studies on the world debt problem. Similarly, studies on the political determinants of the deficit or debt policies will not be surveyed; however, the political aspects of taxation will be covered. The literature on the history of taxation and the early discussion about the effects of taxation will not be surveyed. We refer to, for example, Webber and Wildavsky (1986) and Musgrave and Shoup (1959). Taxation is considered in a narrow sense so we will not cover alternatives to taxation such as regulation (see Chapter 5000). Note that because of lack of space, we could not include the literature on taxation and growth and the general equilibrium approach to taxation. We also refer the reader to other related chapters (6000 for optimal taxation, 6020 for tax evasion, 6030 property taxes, 6040 consumption taxes, 6050 income taxation, 6060 corporate taxation, 6070 inheritance taxation and 6080 international taxation). Our survey can be viewed as integrating the macroeconomic effects of taxation into the intertemporal budget constraint of the government. This constraint determines the sustainability of announced fiscal policies and therefore the perception of fiscal policy by economic agents. We start our survey with the contribution of taxation to stabilization policies (Section 2). In this discussion, the budget constraint of the government (Section 3) and the expectations of economic agents about taxation (Section 4) are crucial. The effectiveness of countercyclical policies has, however, been challenged by questions about the relevancy of the timing of taxation (Section 5). In the next section (Section 6) we review the literature on taxation and
6010
Taxation: Macro Aspects
13
inflation. Section 7 provides an overview of the positive approaches to taxation. The previous discussion relates primarily to closed economies. The last section (Section 8) surveys taxation in open economies.
2. Taxation and Stabilization Policies The macroeconomic aspects of taxation and fiscal policy have systematically been assimilated with the stabilization function. (The allocative and distribution function being the subject of more specific instruments; they are part of other surveys.) More recent research has, however, been rather critical about the traditional approach because of the formulation of anticipations and medium and longer-run implications of the models under consideration. In the Keynesian tradition (see any textbook on macroeconomics or public finance; for expositions and extensions Modigliani, 1944; Peacock and Shaw, 1976; Turnovsky, 1977, and Frenkel and Razin, 1987; for an adaptation of traditional Keynesian demand management to the stagflation situation of the 1980s, we refer to Vines, Macriejowski and Meade, 1983; see also Baily, 1978, for a discussion of the changing economic environment and its impact on stabilization policies) fiscal policy, and therefore taxation, is one of the main instruments to stabilize the economy. Stabilization policies are designed to minimize the gap between current and potential production and employment and to limit the inflation rate. This importance of fiscal policy derived from the economic situation in the 1930s and 1950s and the perceived properties of the economy (deficient aggregate demand, rigid prices and wages, an elastic money demand and an inelastic investment function). The asymmetry in its implementation (expenditures and taxes were increased but rarely reduced) resulted in a structural increase in the relative size of the government budget. This was further stimulated by the Haavelmo effect (Haavelmo, 1945) or the balanced-budget multiplier. This effect holds that no deficit penalty for higher public spending financed by an increase in taxes exists since a similar increase in taxes and government expenditures would increase income by the same amount. Later Knoester (1980, 1983) disputed this result by stressing that instead an inverted effect exists as a result of the link between taxes and wages. Furthermore, much faith was placed in the automatic stabilizing properties of expansive policies: any budget deficit would soon disappear thanks to the induced beneficial effects on economic growth (recent work is by Rodseth, 1984; Kyer, Mixon and Uri, 1988; Uri, Mixon and Kyer, 1989a, 1989b). Cameron (1978) argues that the increasing openness of countries ‘created’ a demand for stabilization policies. The mainstream approach in the 1960s was to view the economy as similar to a system that, by a clever use of impulses, could be controlled. This led to an
14
Taxation: Macro Aspects
6010
intensive search for the value of the multipliers. It explained, partly, the exploding use of large-scale econometric models (see Hickman, 1972, for the state of the debate at the beginning of the 1970s; see Sims, 1982, for an evaluation). However, also reduced form models gained some popularity. This could be explained by the success of the St. Louis model (named after the Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis). That model (Anderson and Jordan, 1968) intensified the discussion between Keynesians and the monetarists since it was shown that monetary policy and not fiscal policy affected income. In these reduced forms no attention was paid to incentives effects, so we do not survey these studies. On the empirical level, one should remember the Goldfeld and Blinder (1972) point that reduced forms could give misleading results on the efficacy of fiscal policy if this policy is designed to stabilize the economy. Intuitively, if fiscal policy manages to stabilize income, no correlation between the deficit and income will be found. In the late 1960s and early 1970s thus a lively discussion about the most appropriate policy course emerged. Buchanan and Wagner (1977) argued that the Keynesian theory destroyed the classical thesis, strengthened by consititutional rules, that budgets should balance and that deficits were immoral. Until the early 1970s, the main - if not the only - argument to denounce fiscal policy concerned crowding out; that is, that the impact of an increase in government expenditures on total demand would be offset by lower private investment or consumption expenditures. (The traditional result could thus also be defined as ‘crowding in’.) Obviously, at full employment a complete crowding out of private by public expenditures occurs so fiscal policy can only determine the division of output between the public and the private sector. When resources are not fully employed, different effects matter such as the increase in the interest rate (financial crowding out), in wealth, the composition of wealth (portfolio crowding out) and inflation (see Spencer and Yohe, 1970; Carlson and Spencer, 1975, 1980; Meyer, 1975; Buiter, 1977; Cavaco-Silva, 1977; Scarth, 1977; Turnovsky, 1977; Cohen and McMenamin, 1978; Floyd and Hynes, 1978; Friedman, 1978; Bruce and Purvis, 1979; Stevens, 1979; Taylor, 1979; Aschauer, 1985, 1988; Aschauer and Greenwood, 1985). Besides crowding-out, many other questions on the business cycle stabilization potential of fiscal policy have been raised. How is a tax reduction or a deficit financed? Is the policy credible? Is the policy sustainable? What about the foreign effects? What motivates policymakers to modify taxes? The literature on some answers to these questions will be surveyed later. We will not extend the discussion into different versions of the Keynesian and classical models like the Tobin (Tobin and Buiter, 1976; Buiter and Tobin, 1980) or Brunner-Meltzer (Brunner and Meltzer, 1976) models, since they focus on and refine monetary transmission mechanisms, or extend on the neo-
6010
Taxation: Macro Aspects
15
Keynesian or disequilibrium models. Finally, note that in recent research shocks in taxes are considered to produce business cycles fluctuations (Christiano and Eichenbaum, 1992; Braun, 1994b; McGrattan, 1994; Johnsson and Klein, 1996). This feeds the criticisms about the possibility to use taxes as a stabilization tool.
3. The Budget Constraint In the early stages of demand management policies, the ‘loose’ reasoning was that, by a judicious timing, no public finance instrument would, over the business cycle, create financing problems. This would be the result of the automatic stabilizing properties of taxation. This view was supported by the spectacular decline in the debt ratio after the Second World War. Later, however, the criticism by monetarists was supplemented by the argument that the budget constraint was neglected. By explicitly incorporating the financing aspects of government decisions two important modifications had to be made to the traditional analysis: fiscal and monetary policy became interrelated and the long-run multipliers were no longer uncertain. References to the basic articles and developments are: Ott and Ott (1965), Christ (1967, 1979), Silber (1970), Steindl (1971), Blinder and Solow (1973, 1976), Meyer (1975), Brunner and Meltzer (1976), Currie (1976), Tobin and Buiter (1976), Cavaco-Silva (1977), Smyth (1978), Cohen and De Leeuw (1980) and Mayer (1984) (surveys are to be found in Turnovsky, 1977; Artis, 1979; and Burrows, 1979). In these contributions, it is stressed that any tax reduction has to be financed implying that the budget constraint must be included in the analysis. This endogenized at least the supply of bonds, possibly money creation and therefore monetary policy. The longer-run consequences on the multipliers strengthened the macroeconomic importance of the marginal tax rate: any change in expenditures (or taxes) must be offset by an identical change in taxes (or expenditures) since no deficit and therefore no monetary or bond financing is allowed. The consequence is the irrelevancy of the method of financing the deficit; only the fiscal structure determines the long-run impact of fiscal policy. Note, however, that this attractive result disappears when interest payments are explicitly included into the budget constraint (Blinder and Solow, 1973, 1974). The size of the long-run multiplier associated with a bond-financed fiscal expansion increases, since taxes must now also finance the higher interest charges. The Blinder-Solow model was extended to include explicit stock-flows interaction of capital and bonds by Tobin and Buiter (1976). Calvo (1985) allows for price increases in a model were the money-bond ratio is important.
16
Taxation: Macro Aspects
6010
4. Rational Expectations The budgetary constraint criticism of the traditional stabilization instruments is based on the accounting argument that expenditures and revenues are linked by the budget constraint. In the 1970s, further blows on the stabilization approach were inflicted on the basis of more behavioral arguments. Indeed, the traditional approach assumes, although implicitly, that all policy changes occur unexpectedly. The rational expectation assumption, based on Muth (1961), argues that economic agents form expectations about future events. These expectations are rational in the sense that they combine all the available information and therefore do not lead to systematic forecasting errors. The implication of the rational expectations hypothesis is that policies will only be effective when they produce surprises (= forecast errors). By definition, this is not possible in the long run since rational economic agents will detect any policy rule and will therefore no longer be surprised. This is also known as the ‘irrelevance hypothesis’. This view has been applied to several policy instruments, most of the time of monetary policy; the core arguments are, however, also relevant to fiscal policy and taxation. The main contributions can be found in Fischer (1980b) and Lucas and Sargent (1981); Baily (1978) and McCallum and Whitaker (1979) apply the monetary policy results to fiscal policy. For our problem at hand it implies that any general expected tax change will already have been discounted by the economic agents in their decision process. An unexpected transitory change in taxation will leave permanent income unchanged. Only permanent unexpected changes are of interest. When government expenditures remain constant, the Ricardo equivalence theorem applies (see below) so the new tax policy will be ineffective. If government expenditures are reduced, the traditional expansive effects, depending on the tax rate change, will apply. The final effects on macroeconomic variables depend on the specification of the model. For example, what is the impact of an increased demand on inflationary expectations? One important policy implication is that fiscal consolidations should not necessarily contract demand due to the benign effects on the expectations about future taxation (see Giavazzi and Pagano, 1990, for an application to Denmark and Ireland). Note that the introduction of uncertain shocks modifies the previous picture slightly in the sense that built-in stabilizers will reduce the variability of income since they provide an automatic and immediate adjustment to current disturbances (McCallum and Whitaker, 1979). The main publications are Lucas (1972, 1973, 1975, 1976), Sargent (1973), Sargent and Wallace (1975), Barro (1976), Infante and Stein (1976), Sargent and Wallace (1976), Fischer (1977, 1979a, 1979b), Kydland and Prescott (1977, 1980), McCallum (1977, 1980), Phelps and Taylor (1977), Shiller (1978), McCallum and Whitaker (1979), Begg (1980, 1982), Buiter (1980b),
6010
Taxation: Macro Aspects
17
Taylor (1985), Lovell (1986) and Lucas (1986b). Notwithstanding the previous conclusion on the ineffectiveness of stabilization policies in a rational expectations framework, microeconomic considerations such as the incentives effects of marginal tax rates, social security payments, subsidies, and so on, on labor supply, saving behavior, investment, and so on, imply that even perfectly anticipated policy changes will have some real effects in the medium run. Furthermore, the previous analysis assumes a systematic clearing of the markets. If this assumption is relaxed and a disequilibrium framework is accepted, the standard Keynesian effects reappear even when expectations are rational (see Taylor, 1979; Begg, 1982; Neary and Stiglitz, 1983, and Buiter, 1980b).
5. The Timing of Taxation In the traditional stabilization approach, higher deficits are a crucial instrument to increase growth. However, if expenditures remain unchanged this implies, that sometime in the future taxes will have to be raised. Deficits are thus an instrument to transfer taxes intertemporally. Will citizens be aware of this and take future taxes into account in their decision process? In other words, is there a burden associated with government debt? The discussion on the burden of the government debt emerged forcefully around 1960 (most contributions are in Ferguson, 1964, and Kaounides and Wood, vol. 2, 1992; see also Buchanan, 1958; Modigliani, 1961; Bailey, 1962; Pesek and Saving, 1967, and Cavaco-Silva, 1977). The mainstream Keynesian position (also known as ‘the new orthodoxy’) was that government debt was different from private debt (repayment of principal and payment of interest is mortgaging future resources) since ‘we owe government debt to ourselves’: future generations pay interest and principal to themselves so leaving disposable income unaffected. This argument was reinforced by the proposition that the deficit cannot be a burden on future generations because their resources are unaffected; the exception being foreign debt. These views were criticized since higher deficits implied lower taxation. This allows current generations to consume more and so to crowd out investment. Future generations thus inherit less capital. The distinction between domestic and foreign debt is not relevant since, although foreign debt does not crowd out investment, the revenue from the capital will benefit foreign lenders. Posner (1987) extends this view by arguing that foreign borrowing allows higher investment. Ceteris paribus, the burden of the internally held debt will be higher than for foreign debt. In 1974, Barro rephrased the problem of the debt burden in ‘Are Government Bonds Net Wealth?’. By doing so, he could focus the attention on
18
Taxation: Macro Aspects
6010
the behavior of taxpayers. Barro showed that the real burden on current and future generations occurs when government uses resources for consumption; the financing of government expenditures (taxes or borrowing) is not relevant: they are equivalent (tax neutrality). This proposition is now known as the ‘Ricardian equivalence theorem’ (some of the papers by Ricardo are reprinted in Kaounides and Wood, vol. 1, 1992; for a discussion on the historical origins see Buchanan, 1976; O’Driscoll, 1977, and Asso and Barucci, 1988; see also Hakes and McCormick, 1996). The novel feature of Barro’s approach is that he showed that intergenerational gifts and bequests turn an overlapping-generations economy with finite-lived households into an infinite-lived households economy whose consumption would not be affected by intertemporal redistributions of lump-sum taxes. Phrased in a stabilization framework, the Ricardian equivalence theorem holds that when the government issues bonds, at the same time a liability is incurred to pay interest annually and to reimburse the par value at the date of maturity. Formulated from a wealth point of view, the net present value of the future tax liabilities equals the price of the bond. If taxpayers do capitalize future tax liabilities, the positive gross wealth effects of a bond issue will be offset by an equivalent liability leaving net wealth unchanged. Government bonds will then not be part of net private wealth. In other words, a decrease in public saving will be exactly offset by an increase in private saving, leaving total saving unchanged. Formulated from a financing point of view, the financing of government deficits is irrelevant for the real side of the economy so a substitution of debt for taxation does not affect economic development. As a result, in this ultrarational situation fiscal policy is ineffective. This can be viewed as ‘ex ante crowding out’ (David and Scadding, 1974). If the macroeconomic effects of current taxation are comparable to those of deficits, a choice between current or future taxation will have to be made by considering allocative effects (see Ihori, 1988). General discussions of the Ricardian equivalence theorem can be found in Buiter and Tobin (1979), Brennan and Buchanan (1980b), Tobin (1980), Bernheim (1987, 1989), Modigliani (1987), Perasso (1987), Leiderman and Blejer (1988), Flemming (1988), Morris (1988), Barro (1989), Thornton (1990), Seater (1993), Van Velthoven, Verbon and Van Winden (1993). Tramontana (1985) and Fields and Hart (1990) place the discussion in a traditional IS-LM framework. The Barro proposition resulted in an intense discussion and many empirical tests. Several authors, especially Keynesians, questioned his assumptions. Since taxes are in general not lump-sum taxes, tax changes involve modifications in the size and timing of marginal taxation. This affects incentives and induces intertemporal substitution effects (Buiter, 1989, and Trostel, 1993). One can also question whether taxpayers are interested or informed about taxes and the
6010
Taxation: Macro Aspects
19
government debt. This refers to the existence of fiscal illusion (Stiglitz, 1988). Similarly, is the public not assuming that government has no intention of paying off the principal (Cox, 1985)? Barro (1974) showed that the infinite life assumption is sufficient but not necessary for his proposition. A finite life assumption has the same implication if one assumes that the current generation considers the wellbeing of future generations and adjust intergenerational transfers (bequests or transfers inter vivos) to interventions of the government (for example, a tax reduction will be matched by an increase in voluntary tranfers). Expenditures on education are different since a government deficit can increase welfare: parents will be allowed to invest more in their children’s education (see Drazen, 1978). Further discussion about this issue is to be found in Blanchard (1985), Hubbard and Judd (1986), Auerbach and Kotlikoff (1987), Frenkel and Razin (1987), Poterba and Summers (1987), Weil (1987), Abel (1988), Bernheim and Bagwell (1988), Musgrave (1988), Kotlikoff, Razin and Rosenthal (1990), Lopez and Angel (1990), Abel and Bernheim (1991), Lord and Rangazas (1993) and Jaeger (1993). The assumption of perfect capital markets has been critized by several authors. Hubbard and Judd (1986) stress that consumers may face a liquidity constraint, so they prefer future taxes to be substituted for current taxes. Artis (1979) and Leiderman and Blejer (1988) argue that a higher discount rate may be applied to future tax liabilities (for example, as a result of a higher risk of default) compared to future interest payments so there is a gain in present wealth by using debt rather than taxes. In other words, since market imperfections create liquidity constraints, borrowing by the government is cheaper compared to household borrowing. Government surpluses and deficits may thus be used to reallocate consumption through time: a net positive effect of indebtness would thus occur if the government is more efficient than the private sector in carrying out the loan process between generations or if the government acts like a monopolist in the production of the liquidity services associated with debt issue (see Daniel, 1993). Webb (1981) stresses, however, differences in the ability to repay debt between households and the government. A point somewhat related to capital market imperfections is that bequests cannot be negative, which would be required if it is expected that future generations would be richer (Modigliani, 1987). Yotsuzuka (1987) stresses the importance of the exact type of capital market imperfections. The general conclusion that capital market imperfections imply debt non-neutrality is rejected. Buchanan and Wagner (1977) and Feldstein (1988) discuss the perfect certainty assumption of future tax liabilities. The complexity of the tax system would lead to an underestimation of future tax liabilities. Note that Barro (1974) argues that uncertainty would result in an overcompensation of future tax liabilities if, as could be advocated, households are risk averse (see also Chan, 1983, and Barsky, Mankiw and Zeldes, 1986). Boskin and Kotlikoff
20
Taxation: Macro Aspects
6010
(1985), Leiderman and Razin (1988), Bomberger (1990), Croushore (1990, 1992, 1996), Handa (1993) and Strawczynski (1995) study the impact of uncertainty in income and returns in an intergenerational altruistic model. Cukierman (1986) considers uncertain lifetimes. The assumption made by Barro that taxes are lump sum has been frequently critized. A modification does, however, not lead to straightforward effects since many alternatives exist (taxation of consumption, income, profit, and so on) (see Abel, 1986, and Basu, 1996). Note also that transaction costs associated with the issue of debt are neglected (Carmichael, 1982). A point that surfaced only infrequently in the recent discussion on the Ricardian equivalence, but was omnipresent in the discussion of the early 1960s is the source of the deficit. Does it matter that a deficit is the result of an increase in government investment instead of in transfer payments? Barro assumed government spending to be constant so the only issue was the financing one. Buchanan and Roback (1987) discuss the importance of the source of the deficit; Kormendi (1983) and Bohn (1992) of spending (see also Katsaitis, 1987, and Cebula and Hung, 1996b). Liviatan (1982) critizes the neglect of the inflation tax as a source of government revenue. Since additional government debt is frequently financed by money creation, this revenue could partly offset increases in interest charges linked to the issue of government debt. Government bonds will then no longer be neutral. The list of empirical verifications of the Ricardian equivalence theorem by testing for the effect of the deficit and/or government debt, however defined, on consumption, saving or interest rates is long. Therefore, we are not able to provide any further guidance. Note that any article testing for the effect of the government debt or deficit on an economic or financial variable could be listed. This is especially the case for interest rate equations estimated before the publication of the 1974 article by Barro; we only list those articles that explicitly test for the Ricardo equivalence: (some of the papers are reprinted in Kaounides and Wood, vol. 3, 1992) Kochin (1974), Yawitz and Meyer (1976), Buiter and Tobin (1979), Tanner (1979), Holcombe, Jackson and Zardkoohi (1981), Dwyer (1982), Feldstein (1982), Plosser (1982), Seater (1982), Bennett and Dilorenzo (1983), Kormendi (1983), Koskela and Viren (1983), Makin (1983), Mascaro and Meltzer (1983), Blanchard (1984), Summers (1988), Aschauer (1985), Boskin and Kotlikoff (1985), Evans (1985), King and Plosser (1985), Kormendi (1985), Modigliani, Jappelli and Pagano (1985), Seater and Mariano (1985), Tanzi (1985), Barth, Iden and Russek (1986), Evans (1986), Hoelscher (1986), Kessler, Perelman and Pestieau (1986), Kormendi and Meguire (1986), Merrick and Saunders (1986), Modigliani and Sterling (1986), Barro (1987), Carroll and Summers (1987), Modigliani (1987), Evans (1987a, 1987b), Jones (1987), Modigliani and Japelli (1987), Motley (1987), Poterba and Summers (1987), Boskin (1988), De Haan and Zelhorst (1988), Evans (1988a, 1988b), Gruen (1988), Ihori (1988), Knight and Masson (1988),
6010
Taxation: Macro Aspects
21
Leiderman and Razin (1988), Morris (1988), Nicoletti (1988), Tanzi and Blejer (1988), Viren (1988), Walsh (1988), Boothe and Reid (1989), Buiter (1989), Croushore (1989), Darrat (1989), Evans (1989), Reid (1989), Kormendi and Meguire (1990), McMillin and Koray (1990), Cadsby and Murray (1991), Evans (1991), Gruen (1991), Lee (1991), Standish and Beelders (1991), Whelan (1991), Dalamagas (1992a and 1992b), Graham (1992), Gupta (1992), Kazmi (1992), Nicoletti (1992), Beck (1993), Dalamagas (1993), Evans (1993), Jaeger (1993), Perelman and Pestieau (1993), Akai (1994), Beck (1994), Evans and Hasan (1994), Dalamagas (1994), Mukhopadhyay (1994), Graham (1995), Himarios (1995), Rose and Hakes (1995), Slate (1995), Cebula and Hung (1996a), Chakraborty and Farah (1996), Ghatak and Ghatak (1996), Leachman (1996) and Wagner (1996). Note that no standard approach exists so results are not always comparable. For a discussion of the robustness of the results, see Cardia (1997). Drawing conclusions from the empirical analysis is difficult. I am inclined to follow Seater (1993, p. 182) when he writes: ‘I think it is reasonable to conclude that Ricardian equivalence is strongly supported by the data’. This should not be interpreted absolutely but as a statement that the Ricardian equivalence theorem is an acceptable working hypothesis. The implication of the Ricardian equivalence theorem for the design of taxation policy (we refer to the chapter on optimal taxation for a more profound discussion) is that taxes should be kept as fixed as possible (‘tax smoothing’) to minimize the deadweight losses (Barro, 1979). This contradicts the countercyclical approach implied by the standard Keynesian models. In a tax smoothing framework the permanent tax rate should be set so as to finance the permanent primary government expenditures plus interest payments (see also Chari, Christiano and Kehoe, 1991, 1994). Government debt then functions as a cushion for deviations of government spending from its permanent level. We do not extend this analysis since it is part of the optimal taxation literature, covered in another survey. The Ricardian equivalence theorem does not, by definition, consider any problems related to the financing of the government debt. From a microeconomic point of view an automatic channeling of additional savings into government bonds cannot be assumed. Portfolio holders and tax payers do have alternatives for government bonds but their participation is required to defer taxes to the future. So the constraint should be imposed that bondholders evaluate the policy pursued by the government as credible. If, for example, an increase in inflation is to be feared, no bond issue will be possible (eventually issues of very short run bills are still conceivable). In the more extreme case of a possible repudiation, the demand for government debt will vanish completely. The difference between macro- and microeconomic considerations reflects that taxpayers will not only attempt to minimize their tax share but also to maximize the return on their savings so as to benefit from the postponement of
22
Taxation: Macro Aspects
6010
taxes. This is nothing but another application of the saving paradox. The credibility of fiscal policy depends on expectations by taxpayers about future policies. The determinants of credibility can therefore not be straightforwardly determined. However, some crucial factors are evident such as a combination of taxes and expenditures that respect the intertemporal budget or present value constraint, that is, the solvency condition of the government. This constraint implies that the discounted value of future primary surpluses equals the outstanding stock of government debt. Note that this does not guarantee that the rise in the debt-income ratio will be bounded. All that matters is that the real growth rate of the debt should be lower than the real rate of interest; the growth rate of income or the tax base is not directly involved (see Persson and Tabellini, 1990, and the collection of papers in Persson and Tabellini, 1994). Although not identical to the Domar approach (Domar, 1944) (in its simple version a stabilization of the debt-income ratio requires that the real after tax interest rate be smaller than the real rate of growth) it is comparable. The Domar requirement was especially very popular in the early 1980s with international organizations such as the OECD and the European Commission, withsgovernment agencies and even governments since, given the high level of the interest rates, its policy implications were relatively straightforward: reduce the primary deficit to stabilize the debt-income ratio. Articles on this subject are Chouraqui, Jones and Montador (1986), Hamilton and Flavin (1986), Bispham (1987), Spaventa (1987), Kremers (1988, 1989), Trehan and Walsh (1988, 1991), Wilcox (1989), Blanchard et al. (1990), MacDonald and Speight (1990), Corsetti (1991), Hakkio and Rush (1991), Haug (1991), Smith and Zin (1991), Buiter and Patel (1992), MacDonald (1992), Bagliani and Cherubini (1993), De Haan and Siermann (1993), Heinemann (1993), Frisch (1995) and Vanhoorebeek and Van Rompuy (1995). Violations of the intertemporal budget constraint cannot be excluded, but what are the implications? Feldstein (1982) and Masson (1985) consider uncertainty about the required policy switch in case current policies are unsustainable and Leiderman and Blejer (1988) discuss the uncertainty as to how the spending-tax plan will be adjusted to satisfy the constraint. Bohn (1991) shows that in the United States over the past centuries 50-65 percent of deficits due to tax cuts and 65-70 percent of deficits due to spending cuts have been eliminated later by spending cuts; Kremers (1989) finds that the deficit policy of the 1980s is not consistent with the pattern of the previous decades. The extreme solution to violations of the intertemporal budget constraint is, of course, a default by the government on its debt. Chari and Kehoe (1993) present a general equilibrium model of optimal taxation were this is a policy option.
6010
Taxation: Macro Aspects
23
6. Taxation and Inflation The literature on inflation is vast. We limit ourselves to two aspects that are especially relevant from a fiscal policy point of view. First, inflation as a tax. Inflation should indeed, as a process of price increases, be at least acknowledged, if not stimulated, by the government. The second question concerns the relationship between deficits and inflation. Unexpected inflation redistributes wealth between debtors and creditors. Since frequently the government is the major debtor, the budgetary consequences of inflation cannot be neglected. Inflation is thus an alternative for traditional taxation. Furthermore, tax systems are most of the time not indexed so, in general, the direct impact of inflation is a more than proportional rise in tax revenues. This is also the case for the taxation of the inflation premium included in interest rates (Darby,1975), Feldstein,1976, and Feldstein and Summers, 1978; see also Tanzi, 1984). In this approach inflation is viewed as exogenous. In the optimal inflation literature, inflation is explicitly considered as a policy instrument to generate seignorage revenues for the government. Without considering the numerous country applications, we mention Bailey (1956), Friedman (1971), Tower (1971), Barro (1972), Marty (1973), Phelps (1973), Auernheimer (1974), Cathart (1974), Kahn and Knight (1982), Barro (1983), Calvo and Peel (1983), Cox (1983), Remolona (1983), Brock (1984), Mankiw (1987), Weil (1987), Marty and Chaloupka (1988), Brock (1989), Kigel (1989), Vegh (1989), Bohanon, McClure and Van Cott (1990), Bruno and Fischer (1990), Calvo and Leiderman (1992), Calvo and Guidotti (1993), Guidotti and Vegh (1993a, 1993b), Steindl (1993), Banaian, McClure and Willett (1994), Braun (1994a), Chang (1994), Marty (1994), Mourmoras and Tijerina (1994) and Vegh (1995). The traditional assumption is that no alternative payment instruments to domestic money are available. Hercowitz and Sadka (1987) allow for currency substitution. As this limits the revenues from the inflation tax, governments will broaden financial regulations to minimize the domestic use of foreign currencies. Taxation and inflation are also, although less directly, linked by the budget constraint of the government. Note that taxation will directly affect the price level but since, in general, changes in tax rates do not occur continuously, they will not explain inflation. It is therefore more the decision not to increase taxation by incurring budget deficits that could be important for the inflation process. In general two main channels can be distinguished that link the budget deficit to inflation. A first link results from a monetization of deficits; a second, less direct link, is the consequence of crowding out. Indeed, when higher government expenditures substitute for investment, potential production declines which, when the stock of money remains constant, implies a price increase. Note that this is not the case when the deficit results from a decline in taxes since, following the previous argument, the price level will decline.
24
Taxation: Macro Aspects
6010
Modigliani (1987), however, stresses reverse causation effects running from inflation to higher interest rates and so to deficits; furthermore, restrictive monetary policy to fight inflation lowers income which leads to increased deficits. Concerning the monetization of the deficit, references mentioned above about the budget constraint are also relevant here. The link between budget deficits, whatever the origin, and inflation was forcefully formulated by Sargent and Wallace (1981) in their ‘Some Unpleasant Monetarist Arithmetic’: interest payments will, when the government debt exceeds some upper limit, have to be financed by money creation due to a shortage of savings. The ‘unpleasant arithmetic’ stresses thus that a bond-financed deficit will eventually have to be financed by money creation and therefore lead to a higher inflation rate. Darby (1984) (reply by Miller and Sargent, 1984) argues that the situation described by Sargent and Wallace is unlikely to occur since it requires that the real bond rate exceeds the real rate of growth for a considerable time (see also McCallum, 1984). King and Plosser (1985) discuss, test and reject (for the US as well as for several other developed countries) the link between seignorage revenues and different policy variables. Sargent and Wallace assume that monetary policy accomodates fiscal policy (‘fiscal dominance’); Buiter (1987) and Buti (1990) consider different policy regimes (cooperation or leadership between monetary and fiscal authorities). Drazen and Helpman (1990) stress the importance of the policies expected to be used to reduce the deficit (see also Niskanen, 1978; Blinder, 1983; Miller, 1983, and Congdon, 1987).
7. The Positive Approach to Taxation In democratic societies, tax rates are fixed by politicians and not by technicians who aim for an optimal taxation. The traditional approach holds that taxation or government expenditures are instruments that policymakers modify to realize goals such as a stabilization of the economy, a reallocation of resources or a modification in the distribution of income and wealth. This fine-tuning policy faces several problems and risks. For example, the government can misjudge both the size and timing of interventions, many conflicting objectives need to be pursued, the effects of instruments are not known with certainty, data contain errors, the theoretical structure of the model, the parameters, the value of exogenous variables, the nature of exogenous disturbances are not perfectly known, time lags are involved (recognition, decision, execution and response lag), frequent changes in policy instruments affects policy credibility, and so on. See, for example, Friedman (1960), Okun (1972), Kydland and Prescott (1977), Lucas (1980), Cooley, Leroy and Raymon (1984); and see also the recent literature on taxation as a source of business cycle fluctuations: Christiano and Eichenbaum (1992), Braun (1994b), McGrattan (1994) and
6010
Taxation: Macro Aspects
25
Johnsson and Klein (1996). The previous arguments (partly) explain the preference of several authors for policy rules. See the chapter on optimal taxation for more detail. In the public choice literature a different approach is taken. A typical formulation is Brennan and Buchannan (1980a) where a government is seen as a revenue-maximizing leviathan and taxes result out of a struggle between the government and citizens. Taxation is thus essentially viewed as an instrument to satisfy the wellbeing of the policymakers, not of the community and taxes are required to finance government expenditures. In this way taxes are more directly linked to government expenditures than in the ‘traditional’ approach. We refer to Downs (1957), Meltzer and Richard (1978), Anderson, Wallace and Warner (1986), Blackley (1986), Manage and Marlow (1986), Von Furstenberg, Green and Jeong (1986), Hibbs (1987), Ram (1988), Ahriakpor and Amirkhalkhali (1989), Mueller (1989), Blackley (1990), Holmes and Hutton (1990), Miller and Russek (1990), Cukierman and Meltzer (1991), Hoover and Sheffrin (1992) and Bella and Quinteri (1995). Consider also the collection of papers in Buchanan, Rowley and Tollison (1986). Several articles and books apply public choice arguments to a discussion of taxation or tax reform. It is impossibble to survey and list them. A pronounced view is Rose and Karran (1987). Citizens bear, however, also some responsibility: the aggregate demand for budgetary programs will be excessive since any taxpayer bases his demand on the asymmetry between his small share in the cost of the program he supports and the perceived benefits. Furthermore, they suffer from fiscal illusion (see Dollery and Worthington, 1996, for a recent survey of this literature) that is reinforced by debt finance. As a result, the perceived price of public goods is lower than the effective price resulting in a rise in the demand for these goods. On the other hand, there is little incentive to combat tax increases since the individual share is negligible. As a result the upward pressure on the supply of government programs is stronger than the incentive to hold down the budget so government expenditures tend to rise and be financed by tax increases. The literature on the ‘political business cycle’ should also be mentioned here. It concerns the creation of favorable economic conditions at election time so as to increase the re-election chances of the incumbent politicians. Obviously taxation is an instrument that could be used to generate these cycles. We refer to Alesina and Roubini (1992), Borooah and Van der Ploeg (1983), Nordhaus (1989) and Schneider and Frey (1988) for a general review of this literature. Unfortunately not much research has been performed on the use of taxes to generate a political business cycle (see, however, Tufte, 1978; Edwards and Tabellini, 1991; Grilli, Masciandaro and Tabellini, 1991, and Alesina and Rosenthal, 1995). Econometric tax functions, most of the time for separate taxes and, eventually, specified as reaction functions, have been estimated in many econometric models. More relevant here but much less numerous, are general
26
Taxation: Macro Aspects
6010
tax equations that contain political determinants. We refer, however, to Frey and Schneider (1978), Alt and Chrystal (1981), Pommerehne and Schneider (1983), Renaud and Van Winden (1987), Van Velthoven (1989) and Ohlsson and Vredin (1996).
8. Open Economies The literature on fiscal policies is too vast to cover here in a few paragraphs so we limit ourselves to some general points (we refer to Chapter 6080 for international taxation). The point of departure for the analysis of the impact of taxation-fiscal policy in open economies is the Mundell-Fleming model (see Kenen, 1995, and Marston, 1995, for surveys). The magnitude and size of the multipliers depend on different parameters such as the effect on domestic interest rates (the assumption about the country size and capital mobility is relevant here) and the exchange rate regime. For example, a fiscal expansion in a ‘large’ country will raise world interest rates and appreciate the exchange rate; in a ‘small’ country a depreciation can be expected since the trade effects will tend to dominate. In the limiting case of perfect capital mobility, fiscal policy will not affect income: any tendency for interest rates to rise will be matched by a currency appreciation leaving total demand unchanged. In other words, exports are completely crowded out. Textbook references are relevant here. Extensions by McKinnon (1973), Floyd (1980), Dixit (1985), Persson (1985) and Frenkel and Razin (1987) make use of an intertemporal approach covering aspects ranging from the impact of capital mobility and overlapping generations to different specific tax instruments. One general result is that deficits increase world interest rates and lower consumption but the effects depend on whether a country experiences a surplus or deficit. McKibbin and Sachs (1988) and Kole (1988) consider the importance of country size. In the traditional view financial crowding out will not occur in small open economies since, assuming fixed exchange rates, interest rates are given on the world market. Adjustments to imbalances between saving and investment occur through foreign borrowing by way of current account deficits. As a consequence, fiscal policies in all countries determine crowding out, also in countries with balanced budget. In a Ricardo world, this no longer holds. The previous results must, however, be modified when non-traded goods are introduced. Some models focus more explicitly on the dynamics and on the budget constraint of the government. Work by Frenkel and Razin (1987) and Knight and Masson (1988) demonstrates that, if bonds are net wealth, fiscal expansions will appreciate the exchange rate so as to finance the government deficit. Buiter (1987) takes the impact of interest rates on investment into account so deficits increase interest rates and as a result lower future domestic
6010
Taxation: Macro Aspects
27
and foreign income. For a given level of government expenditures this constrains future taxes (see also Blanchard et al., 1990; Frisch, 1995). An interesting collection of additional work on the international aspects of fiscal policy is Frenkel (1988). The survey by Dixit (1985), although limited to tax policy in open economies, should also be mentioned. Concerning the Ricardian equivalence theorem in an open economy, (see Morris, 1988, for a discussion of the Barro-Ricardo equivalence in open economies) we recall earlier comments about the burden of external versus internal debt. Note that a huge literature exists about the international coordination of fiscal policy and about fiscal policy in a monetary union. We also stress the important literature on the Maastricht convergence criteria for the European monetary union.
9. Conclusion The macroeconomic aspects of taxation have evolved considerably over the past decades.This is linked to the changing ideas about the role of the government. In a nutshell the dominating current views hold that the government should focus on longer-term goals and be very critical about short-term intervention. Due to the difficulty in modifying tax instruments, this is especially true for taxation. This also holds for the process of shifting taxes through time by piling up debt. Such policies do, however, create uncertainty as to the type of taxes and time at which they will be collected. A modern view of the goals of government intervention will therefore be much less ambitious compared to thirty or forty years ago: the actions by the government should be as predictable as possible so as to reduce uncertainty and support the development of the private sector.
Bibliography on Taxation: Macro Aspects (6010) Abel, Andrew B. (1986), ‘The Failure of Ricardian Equivalence under Progressive Wealth Taxation’, 30 Journal of Public Economics, 117-128. Abel, Andrew B. (1988), ‘An Analysis of Fiscal Policy under Operative and Inoperative Bequest Motives’, in Helpman, Elhanan, Razin, Assaf and Sadka, Efraim (eds), Economic Effects of the Government Budget, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 91-106. Abel, Andrew B. and Bernheim, B. Douglas (1991), ‘Fiscal Policy with Impure Intergenerational Altruism’, 59 Econometrica, 1687-1711. Ahmed, Shaghil (1987), ‘Government Spending, the Balance of Trade and the Terms of Trade in British History’, 20 Journal of Monetary Economics, 195-220. Ahriakpor, James C.W. and Amirkhalkhali, Saleh (1989), ‘On the Difficulty of Eliminating Deficits
28
Taxation: Macro Aspects
6010
with Higher Taxes: Some Canadian Evidence’, 56 Southern Economic Journal, 24-31. Akai, Nobuo (1994), ‘Ricardian Equivalence for Local Government Bonds: Budget Constraint Approach’, 44 Economics Letters, 191-195. Alesina, Alberto and Rosenthal, Howard (1995), Partisan Politics Divided Government, and the Economy, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Alesina, Alberto and Roubini, Nouriel (1992), ‘Political Cycles in OECD Economies’, 59 Review of Economic Studies, 663-688. Alexander, J. Davidson (1989), ‘The Political Economy of Tax Based Incomes Policy: Wealth Effects of Post Keynesian TIP’, 23 Journal of Economic Issues, 135-146. Alt, James and Chrystal, Alec (1981), ‘Politico-economic Models of British Fiscal Policy’, in Hibbs, Douglas A., Fassbender, Heino and Rivers, Douglas R. (eds), Contemporary Political Economy, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 1985-1208. Anderson, Leonell C. and Jordan, Jerry (1968), ‘Monetary and Fiscal Actions: A Test of their Relative Importance in Economic Stabilization’, 50 Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis Review, 11-24. Anderson, William, Wallace, Myles S. and Warner, John T. (1986), ‘Government Spending and Taxation: What Causes What?’, 52 Southern Economic Journal, 630-639. Andreoni, James (1989), ‘Giving with Impure Altruism: Applications to Charity and Ricardian Equivalence’, 97 Journal of Political Economy, 1447-1458. Argy, Victor (1994), International Macroeconomics: Theory and Policy, London, Routledge. Artis, Michael (1979), ‘Recent Development in the Theory of Fiscal Policy: A Survey’, in Cook, S.T. and Jackson, Peter M. (eds), Current Issues in Fiscal Policy, London, Martin Robertson, 15-43. Aschauer, David A. (1985), ‘Fiscal Policy and Aggregate Demand’, 75 American Economic Review, 117-127. Aschauer, David A. (1988), ‘The Equilibrium Approach to Fiscal Policy’, 20 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 41-62. Aschauer, David A. and Greenwood, Jeremy (1985), ‘Macroeconomic Effects of Fiscal Policy’, 23 Carnegie-Rochester Conference Series on Public Policy, 91-138. Asso, Pier F. and Barucci, Emilio (1988), ‘Ricardo on the National Debt and its Redemption, Some Notes on an Unpublished Ricardian Manuscript’, 17 Economic Notes, 5-36. Atkinson, Anthony B. and Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1980), Lectures in Public Economics, London, McGraw Hill. Auerbach, Alan J. and Kotlikoff, Laurence J. (1987), Dynamic Fiscal Policy, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Auerbach, Alan J., Gokhale, Jagadeesh and Kotlikoff, Laurence J. (1993), ‘Generational Accounts and Lifetime Tax Rates, 1900-1991', 29 Federal Reserve Bank of Cleveland Economic Review, 2-13. Auernheimer, Leonardo (1974), ‘The Honest Government Guide to the Revenue from the Creation of Money’, 82 Journal of Political Economy, 598-606. Backhaus, Jürgen G. (1989), ‘Taxation and Entrepreneurship: An Austrian Approach to Public Finance’, 16(2) Journal of Economic Studies, 5-22. Backus, David, Devreux, Michael and Purvis, Douglas (1988), ‘A Positive Theory of Fiscal Policy in Open Economies’, in Frenkel, Jacob E. (ed.), International Aspects of Fiscal Policies, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 173-196.
6010
Taxation: Macro Aspects
29
Bagliani, Angelo and Cherubini, Umberto (1993), ‘Intertemporal Budget Constraint and Public Debt Sustainability: The Case of Italy’, 25 Applied Economics, 275-283. Bagliani, Fabio C. (1994), ‘Do Anticipated Tax Changes Matter? Further Evidence from the United Kingdom’, 48 Ricerche Economiche, 87-108. Bailey, Martin J. (1956), ‘The Welfare Cost of Inflationary Finance’, 64 Journal of Political Economy, 93-110. Bailey, Martin J. (1962), National Income and the Price Level, New York, McGraw-Hill. Bailey, Martin J. (1993), ‘Note on Ricardian Equivalence’, 51 Journal of Public Economics, 437-446. Baily, Martin N. (1978), ‘Stabilization and Private Economic Behavior’, Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 11-50. Banaian, King, McClure, Harold and Willett, Thomas D. (1994), ‘The Inflation Tax is Likely to be Inefficient at any Level’, 27 Kredit und Kapital, 30-42. Bandin Tomislav (1988), ‘Politicko Jedinstvo kao Faktor Ostvarivanja Dogovorene Ekonomske i Razvojne Politike (Political Unity as a Factor of Implementation of Agreed Economic and Development Policy)’, 1 Ekonomist, 29-31. Bankman, Joseph and Griffith, Thomas (1987), ‘Social Welfare and the Rate Structure: A New Look at Progressive Taxation’, 75 California Law Review, 1905-1967. Barro, Robert J. (1972), ‘Inflationary Finance and the Welfare Cost of Inflation’, 80 Journal of Political Economy, 978-1001. Barro, Robert J. (1974), ‘Are Government Bonds Net Wealth?’, 82 Journal of Political Economy, 1095-1117. Barro, Robert J. (1976), ‘Rational Expectations and the Role of Monetary Policy’, 2 Journal of Monetary Economics, 1-33. Barro, Robert J. (1978), The Impact of Social Security on Private Savings - Evidence from U.S. Time Series, Washington, American Enterprise Institute. Barro, Robert J. (1979), ‘On the Determination of the Public Debt’, 87 Journal of Political Economy, 940-971. Barro, Robert J. (1980), ‘A Capital Market in an Equilibrium Business Cycle Model’, 48 Econometrica, 1393-1417. Barro, Robert J. (1983), ‘Inflationary Finance under Discretion and Rules’, 41 Canadian Journal of Economics, 1-16. Barro, Robert J. (1987), ‘Government Spending, Interest Rates, Prices, and Budget Deficits in the United Kingdom’, 10 Journal of Monetary Economics, 221-247. Barro, Robert J. (1989), ‘The Ricardian Approach to Budget Deficits’, 3 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 37-54. Barro, Robert J. and Gordon, David B. (1983), ‘Rules, Discretion, and Reputation in a Model of Monetary Policy’, 12 Journal of Monetary Economics, 101-121. Barry, Frank G. (1985), ‘Fiscal Policy in a Small Open Economy with Unemployment and Capital Accumulation’, 87 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 474-486. Barry, Frank G. (1987), ‘Fiscal Policy in a Small Open Economy. An Integration of the Short-run, Heckscher-Ohlin and Capital Accumulation Models’, 22 Journal of International Economics, 103-121. Barsky, Robert B., Mankiw, Gregory N. and Zeldes, Stephen P. (1986), ‘Ricardian Consumers with Keynesian Propensities’, 76 American Economic Review, 676-691. Barth, James R., Iden, George and Russek, Frank S. (1986), ‘Government Debt, Government Spending and Private Behavior: Comment’, 76 American Economic Review, 1158-1167.
30
Taxation: Macro Aspects
6010
Basu, Parantap (1996), ‘Proportional Income Tax and the Ricardian Equivalence in a Non-expected Utility Maximizing Model’, 63 Southern Economic Journal, 223-243. Baum, Donald N. (1991), ‘Economic Effects of Including Services in the Sales Tax Base: An Applied General Equilibrium Analysis’, 19(2) Public Finance Quarterly, 166-192. Beck, Stacie E. (1993), ‘The Ricardian Equivalence Proposition: Evidence from Foreign Exchange Markets’, 12 Journal of International Money and Finance, 154-169. Beck, Stacie E. (1994), ‘The Effect of Budget Deficits on Exchange Rates: Evidence from Five Industrialized Countries’, 46 Journal of Economics and Business, 397-408. Begg, David K. (1980), ‘Rational Expectations, Wage Rigidity, and Involuntary Unemployment’, 34 Oxford Economic Papers, 23-47. Begg, David K. (1982), The Rational Expectations Revolution in Macroeconomics, Oxford, Philip Allen. Bella, Mariano and Quinteri, Beniamino (1995), ‘Causality between Public Expenditure and Taxation: Evidence from the Italian Case’, 24 Economic Notes, 45-68. Bennett, James T. and Dilorenzo, Thomas J. (1983), ‘The Ricardian Equivalence Theorem: Evidence from the Off-Budget Public Sector’, 38 Public Finance, 309-316. Benson, Bruce L. (1986), ‘Do Taxes Matter? The Impact of State and Local Taxes on Economic Development’, 10 Economic Development Commentary, 13-17. Benson, Bruce L. (1990), ‘Interstate Tax Competition, Incentives to Collude, and Federal Influences’, 10 Cato Journal, 75-90. Benson, Bruce L. and Johnson, Ronald N. (1986), ‘The Lagged Impact of State and Local Taxes on Economic Activity and Political Behavior’, 24 Economic Inquiry, 389-402. Benson, Bruce L. and Johnson, Ronald N. (1986b), ‘Capital Formation and Interstate Tax Competition’, in Lee, Dwight (ed), Taxation and the Deficit Economy: Fiscal Policy and Capital Formation in the United States, Cambridge, MA, Ballinger, 407-436. Bernheim, B. Douglas (1987), ‘An Evaluation of Theory and Evidence’, in Fischer, Stanley, (ed), NBER Macroeconomics Annual, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 263-304. Bernheim, B. Douglas (1989), ‘A Neoclassical Perspective in Budget Deficits’, 3 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 55-72. Bernheim, B. Douglas and Bagwell, Kyle (1988), ‘Is Everything Neutral?’, 96 Journal of Political Economy, 308-338. Bernstein, Jeffrey I. (1986), Research and Development, Tax Incentives, Toronto, University of Toronto Press, 107 p. Biorn, E. (1989), Taxation, Technology and the User Cost of Capital, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 325 p. Bispham, John A. (1987), ‘Rising Public-sector Indebtedness: Some more Unpleasant Arithmetic’, in Boskin, Michael, Flemming, John and Gorini, Stefano (eds), Private Saving and Public Debt, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 40-71. Biwas, R., Johns, C. and Savage, D. (1985), ‘The Measurement of Fiscal Stance’, 113 National Institute Economic Review, 50-64. Blackley, Paul R. (1986), ‘Causality between Revenues and Expenditures and the Size of the Federal Budget’, 14 Public Finance Quarterly, 139-156. Blackley, Paul R. (1990), ‘A Symmetric Causality between Federal Spending and Tax Changes: Avoiding a Fiscal Loss’, 66 Public Choice, 1-13. Blanchard, Olivier Jean (1984), ‘The Lucas Critique and the Volcker Deflation’, 74 American Economic Review, 211-215. Blanchard, Olivier Jean (1985), ‘Debt, Deficits, and Finite Horizons’, 93 Journal of Political
6010
Taxation: Macro Aspects
31
Economy, 223-247. Blanchard, Olivier Jean (1993), ‘Suggestions for a New Set of Fiscal Indicators’, in Verbon, Harrie H.A. and Van Winden, Frans A.A.M. (eds), The Political Economy of Government Debt, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 307-325. Blanchard, Olivier Jean, Chouraqui, Jean Claude, Hagemann, R.P. and Satar, N. (1990), ‘The Sustainability of Fiscal Policy, New Answers to an Old Question’, 15 OECD Economic Studies. Blejer, Mario and Cheasty, A. (1991), ‘The Measurement of Fiscal Deficits: Analytical and Methodological Issues’, 24 Journal of Economic Literature, 1644-1678. Blinder, Alan S. (1983), ‘On the Monetization of Debt’, in Meyer, Laurence (ed), The Economic Consequences of Government Deficits, Boston, Kluwer-Nijhoff. Blinder, Alan S. and Goldfeld, Stephen M. (1976), ‘New Measures of Fiscal and Monetary Policy, 1958-73', 66 American Economic Review, 780-796. Blinder, Alan S. and Solow, Robert M. (1973), ‘Does Fiscal Policy Matter?’, 2 Journal of Public Economics, 319-337. Blinder, Alan S. and Solow, Robert M. (1974), ‘Analytical Foundations of Fiscal Policy’, in Blinder, Alan S., Solow, Robert M., Break, George F., Steiner, Peter O. and Netzer, Dick (eds), The Economics of Public Finance, Washington, The Brookings Institution, 3-115. Blinder, Alan S. and Solow, Robert M. (1976), ‘Does Fiscal Policy Still Matter?’, 2 Journal of Monetary Economics, 501-510. Bohanon, Cecil E. and McClure, James E. and Van Cott, T. Norman (1990), ‘Government Inflation Statistics and the Inflation Tax on Money’, 45 Public Finance, 164-166. Bohn, Henning (1991), ‘Budget Balance through Revenue or Spending Adjustments’, 27 Journal of Monetary Economics, 333-359. Bohn, Henning (1992), ‘Endogenous Government Spending and Ricardian Equivalence’, 102 Economic Journal, 588-597. Bomberger, William A. (1990), ‘The Effects of Fiscal Policies when Incomes are Uncertain: A Contradiction to Ricardian Equivalence: Comment’, 80 American Economic Review, 309-312. Boothe, Paul M. and Reid, Bradford G. (1989), ‘Asset Returns and Government Budgets in a Small Open Economy: Empirical Evidence for Canada’, 23 Journal of Monetary Economics, 65-77. Borooah, Vani and Van der Ploeg, Frederick (1983), Political Aspects of the Economy, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Boskin, Michael J. (1982), ‘Federal Government Deficits: Some Myths and Realities’, 72 American Economic Review, 196-203. Boskin, Michael J. (1988), ‘Concepts and Measures of Federal Deficits and Debt and their Impact on Economic Activity’, in Arrow, Kenneth J. and Boskin, Michael J. (eds), The Economics of Public Debt, London, Macmillan, 77-115. Boskin, Michael J. and Kotlikoff, Laurence J. (1985), ‘Public Debt and United States Saving: A New Test of the Neutrality Hypothesis’, 23 Carnegie-Rochester Conference Series on Public Policy, 55-86. Bovenberg, A. Lans (1989), ‘The Effects of Capital Income Taxation on International Competitiveness and Trade Flows’, 79 American Economic Review, 1051-1064. Braun, Anton R. (1994a), ‘How Large is the Optimal Inflation Tax?’, 34 Journal of Monetary Economics, 201-214.
32
Taxation: Macro Aspects
6010
Braun, Anton R. (1994b), ‘Tax Disturbances and Real Economic Activity in Postwar United States’, 33 Journal of Monetary Economics, 441-462. Bray, Margaret (1982), ‘Learning, Estimation, and the Stability of Rational Expectations’, 26 Journal of Economic Theory, 318-339. Brennan, Geoffrey and Buchanan, James M. (1980a), The Power to Tax, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Brennan, Geoffrey and Buchanan, James M. (1980b), ‘The Logic of the Ricardian Equivalence Theorem’, 38 Finanzarchiv, 4-16. Brock, Philip L. (1984), ‘Inflationary Finance in an Open Economy’, 14 Journal of Monetary Economics, 37-53. Brock, Philip L. (1989), ‘Reserve Requirements and the Inflation Tax’, 21 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 106-121. Brown, Cary E. (1956), ‘Fiscal Policy in the Thirties: A re-appraisal’, 46 American Economic Review, 857-579. Browning, Edgar K. (1987), ‘On the Marginal Welfare Cost of Taxation’, 77 American Economic Review, 11-23. Bruce, Neil and Purvis, Douglas (1979), ‘Deficit Finance and First Round Crowding-Out: A Correction and Further Clarification’, 14 Canadian Journal of Economics, 728-734. Brunner, Karl and Meltzer, Allan H. (1976), ‘An Aggregative Theory for a Closed Economy’, in Stein, Jerome (ed), Monetarism, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 69-103. Bruno, Michael and Fischer, Stanley (1990), ‘Seigniorage, Operating Rules and the High Inflation Trap’, 105 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 353-374. Buchanan, James M. (1958), Public Principles of Public Debt, Homewood, IL, Richard D. Irwin. Buchanan, James M. (1976), ‘Barro on the Ricardian Equivalence Theorem’, 84 Journal of Political Economy, 337-342. Buchanan, James M. and Roback, Jennifer Morse (1987), ‘The Incidence and Effects of Public Debt in the Absence of Fiscal Illusion’, 15 Public Finance Quarterly, 5-25. Buchanan, James M. and Wagner, Richard E. (1977), Democracy in Deficit, New York, Academic Press. Buchanan, James M., Rowley, Charles K. and Tollison, Robert D. (eds) (1986), Deficits, Oxford, Basil Blackwell. Buchholz, Wolfgang (1991), ‘Tax Effect in General Equilibrium Models with Uncertainty: A Generalization’, 45 Journal of Public Economics, 397-399. Buiter, William H. (1977), ‘Crowding Out and the Effectiveness of Fiscal Policy’, 7 Journal of Public Economics, 309-328. Buiter, William H. (1980a), ‘Death, Birth, Productivity Growth and Debt Neutrality’, 98 Economic Journal, 279-283. Buiter, William H. (1980b), ‘The Macroeconomics of Dr. Planglos’, 90 Economic Journal, 34-50. Buiter, William H. (1983), ‘Measurement of the Public Sector Deficit and its Implications for Policy Evaluation and Design’, 30 International Monetary Fund Staff Papers, 306-349. Buiter, William H. (1985), ‘A Guide to Public Sector Debt and Deficits’, 1 Economic Policy, 13-79. Buiter, William H. (1987), ‘A Fiscal Theory of Hyperdeflations? Some Surprising Monetarist Arithmetic’, 39 Oxford Economic Papers, 111-118.
6010
Taxation: Macro Aspects
33
Buiter, William H. (1988), ‘Macroeconomic Policy Design in an Interdependent World Economy: An Analysis of Three Contingencies’, in Frenkel, Jacob E. (ed), International Aspects of Fiscal Policies, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 121-172. Buiter, William H. (1989), ‘Debt Neutrality, Professor Vickrey and Henry George: ASingle Tax’, 29 Economics Letters, 43-47. Buiter, William H. (1990), Principles of Budgetary and Financial Policy, New York, Harvester Wheatsheaf. Buiter, William H. and Tobin, James (1979), ‘Debt Neutrality: A Brief Review of Doctrine and Evidence’, in Von Furstenberg, George M. (ed), Social Security versus Private Saving, Cambridge, MA, Ballinger, 39-63. Buiter, William H. and Tobin, James (1980), ‘Fiscal and Monetary Policies, Capital Formations, and Economic Activity’, in Von Furstenberg, George M. (ed), The Government and Capital Formation, Cambridge, MA, Ballinger, 73-151. Buiter, William H. and Patel, Urjit R. (1992), ‘Debt, Deficits and Inflation: An Application to the Public Finances of India’, 47 Journal of Public Economics, 171-205. Burrows, Paul (1979), ‘The Government Budget Constraint and the Monetarist-Keynesian Debate’, in Cook, S.T. and Jackson, Peter M. (eds), Current Issues in Fiscal Policy, London, Martin Robertson, 62-85. Buti, Marco (1990), ‘Monetary and Fiscal Rules for Public Debt Sustainability’, 44 Economic Papers, European Commission. Cadsby, Charles Bram and Murray, Frank (1991), ‘Experimental Tests of Ricardian Equivalence’, 29 Economic Inquiry, 645-664. Calvo, Guillermo A. (1978), ‘On the Time Consistency of Optimal Policy in a Monetary Economy’, 46 Econometrica, 1411-1428. Calvo, Guillermo A. (1985), ‘Macroeconomic Implications of the Government Budget’, 15 Journal of Monetary Economics, 95-112. Calvo, Guillermo A. and Guidotti, Pablo E. (1993), ‘On the Flexibility of Monetary Policy: The Case of the Optimal Inflation Tax’, 60 Review of Economic Studies, 667-687. Calvo, Guillermo A. and Leiderman, Leonardo (1992), ‘Optimal Inflation Tax under Precommitment: Theory and Evidence’, 82 American Economic Review, 179-194. Calvo, Guillermo A. and Peel, David A. (1983), ‘Growth and Inflationary Finance: Variations on a Mundellian Theme’, 91 Journal of Political Economy, 880-887. Cameron, David R. (1978), ‘The Expansion of the Public Economy: A Comparative Analysis’, 72 American Political Science Review, 1243-1261. Cardia, Emanuela (1997), ‘Replicating Ricardian Equivalence Tests with Simulated Series’, 87 American Economic Review, 65-79. Carlson, Keith M. and Spencer, Roger W. (1975), ‘Crowding Out and its Critics’, 57 Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis Review, 2-17. Carmichael, Jeffrey (1982), ‘On Barro’s Theorem of Debt Neutrality: The Irrelevance of Net Wealth’, 72 American Economic Review, 351-372. Carmichael, Jeffrey and Hawtrey, Kim (1981), ‘Social Security, Government Finance, and Savings’, 57 Economic Record, 332-343. Carroll, Chris and Summers, Lawrence H. (1987), ‘Why have Private Savings Rates in the United States and Canada Diverged?’, 20 Journal of Monetary Economics, 249-279. Cathart, Charles (1974), ‘Monetary Dynamics, Growth and the Efficiency of Inflationary Finance’, 6 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 169-190. Cavaco-Silva Anibal A. (1977), Economic Effects of Public Debt, London, Martin Robertson.
34
Taxation: Macro Aspects
6010
Cebula, Richard J. and Hung, Chao Shun (1996a), ‘Ricardian Equivalence, Budget Deficits, and Saving in the United States, 1955:1-1991:4', 3a Applied Economics Letters, 525-528. Cebula, Richard J. and Hung, Chao Shun (1996b), ‘Ricardian Equivalence, the Structural Deficit, and the Cyclical Deficit: A Note’, 49b Economia Internazionale, 19-27. Chakraborty, Atreva and Farah, Abdikarim (1996), ‘Ricardian Equivalence: Further Evidence’, 10 International Economic Journal, 19-31. Chan, Louis K.C. (1983), ‘Uncertainty and the Neutrality of Government Financing Policy’, 11 Journal of Monetary Economics, 351-372. Chang, Roberto (1994), ‘Endogenous Currency Substitution, Inflationary Finance, and Welfare’, 26 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 906-916. Chari, Varadarajan V. (1985), ‘Macroeconomic Effects of Fiscal Policy: A Comment’, 23 Carnegie-Rochester Conference Series on Public Policy, 139-141. Chari, V. and Kehoe, Patrick J. (1990), ‘International Coordination of Fiscal Policy in Limiting Economies’, 98 Journal of Political Economy, 617-636. Chari, Varadarajan V. and Kehoe, Patrick J. (1993), ‘Sustainable Plans and Debt’, 61 Journal of Economic Theory, 230-261. Chari, Varadarajan V., Christiano, Lawrence J. and Kehoe, Patrick J. (1991), ‘Optimal Fiscal and Monetary Policy: Some Recent Results’, 23 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 519-539. Chari, Varadarajan V., Christiano, Lawrence J. and Kehoe, Patrick J. (1994), ‘Optimal Fiscal Policy in a Business Cycle Model’, 102 Journal of Political Economy, 617-652. Chouraqui, Jean Claude, Jones, Brian and Montador, Robert B. (1986), ‘Public Debt in a Medium-term Perspecitve’, 7 OECD Economic Studies, 103-153. Christ, Carl A. (1967), ‘A Short-Run Aggregate-Demand Model of the Interdependence and Effects of Monetary and Fiscal Policies with Keynesian and Classical Interest Elasticities’, 57 American Economic Review, 434-443. Christ, Carl A. (1968), ‘A Simple Macroeconomic Model with a Government Budget Restraint’, 76 Journal of Political Economy, 53-67. Christ, Carl F. (1979), ‘On Fiscal and Monetary Policies and the Government Budget Restraint’, 69 American Economic Review, 526-538. Christiano, Lawrence J. and Eichenbaum, Martin (1992), ‘Current Real-Business Cycle Theories and Aggregate Labor-market Fluctuations’, 82 American Economic Review, 430-450. Cohen, Darrel and De Leeuw, Frank (1980), ‘A Note on the Government Budet Restraint’, 6 Journal of Monetary Economics, 547-560. Cohen, Darrel and McMenamin, Stuart J. (1978), ‘The Role of Financial Policy in a Financially Disaggregated Macroeconomic Model’, 10 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 322-336. Congdon, Tim G. (1987), ‘The Link between Budget Deficits and Inflation: Some Contrasts between Developed and Developing Countries’, in Boskin, Michael, Flemming, John and Gorini, Stefano (eds), Private Saving and Public Debt, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 40-71. Cooley, Thomas F., Leroy, Stephen F. and Raymon, Neil (1984), ‘Econometric Policy Evaluation: Note’, 74 American Economic Review, 467-470. Corsetti, Giancarlo (1991), ‘Testing for Solvency of the Public Sector: An Application to Italy’, 20 Economic Notes, 571-599.
6010
Taxation: Macro Aspects
35
Cox, Michael W. (1983), ‘Government Revenue from Deficit Finance’, 16 Canadian Journal of Economics, 264-274. Cox, Michael W. (1985), ‘Inflation and Permanent Government Debt’, Federal Reserve Bank of Dallas Economic Review, 13-26. Croushore, Dean D. (1989), ‘The Effect of Government Deficits on Consumption and Interest Rates: A Two Equation Approach’, 28 Quarterly Journal of Business and Economics, 85-129. Croushore, Dean D. (1990), ‘Taxation as Insurance Against Income Uncertainty’, 15 Federal Reserve Bank of Philadelphia, 29 ff. Croushore, Dean D. (1992), Ricardian Equivalence Under Income Uncertainty, Federal Reserve Bank of Philadelphia Research Working Paper, No. 6/13. Croushore, Dean D. (1996), ‘Ricardian Equivalence with Wage-Rate Uncertainty’, 28 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 279-293. Croushore, Dean D., Koot, Ronald S. and Walker, David A. (1990), ‘Economic Stability and the Government Deficit’, 12 Journal of Post Keynesian Economics, 390-403. Cukierman, Alex (1986), ‘Uncertain Lifetimes and the Ricardian Equivalence Proposition’, 45 Tel Aviv Foerder Institute for Economics, 24 ff. Cukierman, Alex and Meltzer, Allan H. (1991), ‘Theory of Progressive Income Taxation’, in Meltzer, Alan H., Cukierman, Alex and Richard, Scott F. (eds), Political Economy, New York, Oxford University Press, 76-108. Currie, David A. (1976), ‘Optimal Stabilization Policies and the Government Budget Constraint’, 43 Economica, 159-167. Dalamagas, Basil A. (1992a), ‘How Rival are the Ricardian Equivalence Proposition and the Fiscal Policy Potency View?’, 39(a) Scottish Journal of Political Economy, 457-476. Dalamagas, Basil A. (1992b), ‘Testing Ricardian Equivalence: A Reconsideration’, 24b Applied Economics, 59-68. Dalamagas, Basil A. (1993), ‘Fiscal Illusion and the Level of Indebtedness: An International Comparison’, 61 South African Journal of Economics, 45-58. Dalamagas, Basil A. (1994), ‘Testing the Debt-Illusion Hypothesis’, Revue Economique, 1079-1094. Daniel, Betty C. (1993), ‘Tax Timing and Liquidity Constraints: A Heterogenous-Agent Model’, 25 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 176-196. Darby, Michael R. (1975), ‘The Financial and Tax Effects of Monetary Policy on Interest Rates’, 13 Economic Inquiry, 266-276. Darby, Michael R. (1984), ‘Some Pleasant Monetarist Arithmetic’, 8 Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis Quarterly Review, 15-20. Darrat, Ali F. (1989), ‘Fiscal Deficits and Long-term Interest Rates: Further Evidence from Annual Data’, 56 Southern Economic Journal, 363-374. David, Paul A. and Scadding, John L. (1974), ‘Private Savings: Ultrarationality, Aggregation and Denison’s Law’, 82 Journal of Political Economy, 225-249. Davidson, Carl and Martin, Lawrence (1991), ‘Tax Incidence in a Simple General Equilibrium Model with Collusion and Entry’, 45 Journal of Public Economics, 161-190. De Haan, Jakob and Siermann, Clemens L. (1993), ‘The Intertemporal Government Budget Constraint: An Application for the Netherlands’, 48 Public Finance, 243-249. De Haan, Jakob and Zelhorst, Dick (1988), ‘The Empirical Evidence on the Ricardian Equivalence Hypothesis’, 21 Kredit und Kapital, 407-421.
36
Taxation: Macro Aspects
6010
Diamond, Peter A. and Mirlees, James A. (1977), ‘Optimal Taxation and Public Production, I: Production Efficiency, and II: Tax Rules’, 61 American Economic Review, 8-278. Dixit, Avinash K. (1985), ‘Tax Policy in Open Economics’, in Auerbach, Alan and Feldstein, Martin (eds), Handbook in Public Economics, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 313-374. Djajic, Slobodan (1987), ‘Effects of Budgetary Policies in Open Economies: The Role of Intertemporal Consumption Substitution’, 6 Journal of International Money and Finance, 373-383. Dollery, Brian E. and Worthington, Andrew C. (1996), ‘The Empirical Analysis of Fiscal Illusion’, 10 Journal of Economic Surveys, 261-298. Domar, Evsey (1944), ‘The Burden of the Debt and the National Income’, 34 American Economic Review, 798-827. Downs, Anthony (1957), An Economic Theory of Democracy, New York, Harper and Row. Drazen, Allen (1978), ‘Government Debt, Human Capital, and Bequests in a Life Cycle Model’, 86 Journal of Political Economy, 305-516. Drazen, Allen and Helpman, Elhanan (1990), ‘Inflationary Consequences of Anticipated Macroeconomic Policies’, 57 Review of Economic Studies, 147-164. Dwyer, Gerald P., Jr (1982), ‘Inflation and Government Deficits’, 20 Economic Inquiry, 315-329. Edwards, Sevastian and Tabellini, Guido (1991), ‘Explaining Fiscal Policies and Inflation in Developing Countries’, 10S Journal of International Money and Finance, 16-48. Eisner, Robert (1984), ‘Which Budget Deficit? Some Issues of Measurement and their Implications’, 14 American Economic Review, 138-143. Eisner, Robert and Pieper, Paul (1984), ‘A New View of the Federal Debt and Budget Deficits’, 74 American Economic Review, 11-29. Eisner, Robert and Pieper, Paul (1988), ‘Deficits, Monetary Policy and Real Economic Activity’, in Arrow, Kenneth J. and Boskin, Michael J. (eds), The Economics of Public Debt, London, Macmillan, 40 ff. Enders, Walter and Lee, Bong Soo (1990), ‘Current Account and Budget Deficits: Twins or Distant Cousins?’, 72 Review of Economics and Statistics, 373-381. Evans, Paul (1985), ‘Do Large Deficits Produce High Interest Rates?’, 75 American Economic Review, 68-87. Evans, Paul (1986), ‘Is the Dollar High because of Large Budget Deficits?’, 18 Journal of Monetary Economics, 227-249. Evans, Paul (1987a), ‘Interest Rates and Expected Future Budget Deficits in the United States’, 95a Journal of Political Economy, 34-58. Evans, Paul (1987b), ‘Do Budget Deficits Raise Nominal Interest Rates? Evidence from Six Countries’, 20b Journal of Monetary Economics, 281-300. Evans, Paul (1988a), ‘Are Consumers Ricardian? Evidence for the United States’, 96 Journal of Political Economy, 983-1004. Evans, Paul (1988b), ‘Are Government Bonds Net Weath? Evidence for the United States’, 26 Economic Inquiry, 551-566. Evans, Paul (1989), ‘A Test of Steady-State Government-Debt Neutrality’, 27 Economic Inquiry, 39-55. Evans, Paul (1991), ‘Is Ricardian Equivalence a Good Approximation?’, 29 Economic Inquiry, 626-644. Evans, Paul (1993), ‘Consumers are not Ricardian: Evidence from Nineteen Countries’, 31 Economic
6010
Taxation: Macro Aspects
37
Inquiry, 534-548. Evans, Paul and Hasan, Iftekhar (1994), ‘Are Consumers Ricardian? Evidence for Canada’, 34 Quarterly Review of Economics and Finance, 5-40. Feldstein, Martin (1976), ‘Inflation, Income Taxes and the Rate of Interest: A Theoretical Analysis’, 66 American Economic Review, 809-820. Feldstein, Martin (1982), ‘Government Deficits and Aggregate Demand’, 9 Journal of Monetary Economics, 1-20. Feldstein, Martin (1983), Behavioral Simulation Methods in Tax Policy Analysis, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Feldstein, Martin (1987a), ‘The Welfare Cost of Social Security’s Impact on Private Saving’, in Boskin, Michael J. (ed),Modern Developments in Public Finance, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 1-13. Feldstein, Martin (1987b), The Effects of Taxation on Capital Accumulation, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Feldstein, Martin (1988), ‘The Effects of Fiscal Policies when Incomes are Uncertain: A Contradiction to Ricardian Equivalence’, 78 American Economic Review, 14-23. Feldstein, Martin and Elmendorf, Douglas W. (1989), ‘Budget Deficits, Tax Incentives and Inflation: A Surprising Lesson from the 1983-84 Recovery’, in Summers, Lawrence H. (ed), Tax Policy and the Economy, Cambridge, National Bureau of Economic Research, 1-23. Feldstein, Martin and Summers, Lawrence (1978), ‘Inflation, Tax Rules, and the Long-Term Interest Rate’, Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 61-99. Ferguson, James M. (1964), Public Debt and Future Generations, Chapel Hill, University of North Carolina Press. Fields, T. Windsor and Hart, William R. (1990), ‘On Integrating the Ricardian Equivalence Theorem and the IS-LM Framework’, 28 Economic Inquiry, 185-193. Fischer, Stanley (1977), ‘Long-Term Contracts, Rational Expectations and the Optimal Money Supply Rule’, 85 Journal of Political Economy, 191-205. Fischer, Stanley (1979a), ‘Anticipation and the Nonneutrality of Money’, 87 Journal of Political Economy, 225-252. Fischer, Stanley (1979b), ‘Capital Accumulation on the Transition Path in a Monetary Optimising Economy’, 47 Econometrica, 1433-1440. Fischer, Stanley (1980a), ‘Dynamic Inconsistency, Cooperation and the Benevolent Dissembling Government’, 2 Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control, 93-107. Fischer, Stanley (ed) (1980b), Rational Expectations and Economic Policy, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Fischer, Stanley (1988), ‘Recent Developments in Macroeconomics’, 98 Economic Journal, 294-339. Fisher, Douglas (1988), Monetary and Fiscal Policy, London, Macmillan. Flemming, John S. (1988), ‘Debt and Taxes in War and Peace: The Closed Economy Case’, in Arrow, Kenneth J. and Boskin, Michael J. (eds), The Economics of Public Debt, London, Macmillan, 201-229. Flowers, Marilyn R. (1985), ‘Public Choice and the Flat Tax’, 5 Cato Journal, 625-628. Floyd, John E. (1980), ‘Tax Policy in the Small Open Economy: A Monetary Approach to a Keynesian Problem’, 78 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 378-397. Floyd, John E. and Hynes, Allan J. (1978), ‘Deficit Finance and First Round Crowding-Out: A Clarification’, 11 Canadian Journal of Economics, 97-105.
38
Taxation: Macro Aspects
6010
Frenkel, Jacob A. (1988), International Aspects of Fiscal Policies, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Frenkel, Jacob A. and Razin, Assaf (1985), ‘Government Spending, Debt, and International Economic Interdependence’, 95 Economic Journal, 619-636. Frenkel, Jacob A. and Razin, Assaf (1986a), ‘Fiscal Policy in the World Economy’, 94 Journal of Political Economy, 564-594. Frenkel, Jacob A. and Razin, Assaf (1986b), ‘The International Transmission and Effects of Fiscal Policies’, 76 American Economic Review, 330-335. Frenkel, Jacob A. and Razin, Assaf (1987), Fiscal Policies and the World Economy, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Frey, Bruno S. and Schneider, Friedrich (1978), ‘A Politico-Economic Model of the United Kingdom’, 88 Economic Journal, 243-253. Frey, Bruno S. and Schneider, Friedrich (1981), ‘Central Bank Behavior: A Positive Empirical Analysis’, 7 Journal of Monetary Economics, 291-315. Friedman, Benjamin M. (1978), ‘Crowding Out or Crowding In? Economic Consequences of Financing Government Deficits’, Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 593-642. Friedman, Milton (1960), A Program for Monetary Stability, New York, Fordham University Press. Friedman, Milton (1966), ‘Interest Rates and the Demand for Money’, 9 Journal of Law and Economics, 71-85. Friedman, Milton (1971), ‘Government Revenue from Inflation’, 79 Journal of Political Economy, 846-856. Frisch, Helmut (1995), ‘Government Debt and Sustainable Fiscal Policy’, 24 Economic Notes, 561-580. Galli, Giampaolo and Mascra, Rainer (1988), ‘Government Deficits and Debts. The Necessity and Cost of Adjustment: The Case of Italy’, in Eltis, Walter and Sinclair, Peter (eds), Keynes and Economic Policy, The Relevance of the General Theory after Fifty Years, London, Macmillan, 175-215. Ghatak, Anita and Ghatak, Subrata (1996), ‘Budgetary Deficits and Ricardian Equivalence: The Case of India, 1950-1986', 60 Journal of Public Economics, 267-282. Giavazzi, Francesca and Pagano, Marco (1990), ‘Can Severe Fiscal Contractions be Expenionary? Tales of two Small European Countries’, in Blanchard, Olivier J. and Fischer, Stanley (eds), NBER Macroeconomics Annual: 1990, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 75-111. Gimeno Ullastres, Juan A. (1987), ‘Las Causas del Déficit Público (Trying to Explain Public Deficit)’, 88 Hacienda Pública Espanola, 85-105. Gimeno Ullastres, Juan A. (1989), ‘Sector Público y Patrocinio (Public Sector and Sponsorship)’, in X (ed.), Cultura y Desarrollo, Madrid, Ministerio de Cultura, 116-132. Goldfeld, Stephen M. and Blinder, Alan S. (1972), ‘Some Implications of Endogenous Stabilization Policy’, Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 585-641. Graham, Fred C. (1992), ‘On the Importance of the Measurement of Consumption in Tests of Ricardian Equivalence’, 38 Economics Letters, 431-434. Graham, Fred C. (1995), ‘Government Debt, Government Spending and Private Sector Behavior: Comment’, 85 American Economic Review, 1348-1356. Graham, Fred C. and Himarios, Daniel (1996), ‘Consumption, Wealth and Finite Horizons: Tests of Ricardian Equivalence’, 34 Economic Inquiry, 527-544. Grbich, Yuri (1982), ‘Towards a More Substantial Jurisprudence to Replace Legalism: a Welfare
6010
Taxation: Macro Aspects
39
Economics Model of Decision- Making in Tax Cases’, in Cranston, Ross and Schick, Anne (eds), Law and Economics, Canberra, Australian National University, 192-205. Grilli, Vittorio, Masciandaro, Donato and Tabellini, Guido (1991), ‘Political and Monetary Institutions and Public Financial Policies in the Industrial Countries’, 11 Economic Policy, 342-392. Gruen, David W.R. (1988), Ignorance and Ricardian Equivalence (or Keynesians of the World Unite, You have Nothing to Lose but Your Bonds), Australian National University, 165. Gruen, David W.R. (1991), ‘What People Know and what Economists Think They Know: Surveys on Ricardian Equivalence’, 30 Australian Economic Papers, 1-9. Guidotti, Pablo E. and Vegh, Carlos A. (1993a), ‘Currency Substitution and the Optimal Inflation Tax’, 42 Economics Letters, 65-70. Guidotti, Pablo E. and Vegh, Carlos A. (1993b), ‘The Optimal Inflation Tax when Money Reduces Transactions Costs: A Reconsideration’, 31 Journal of Monetary Economics, 189-205. Gullason, Edward T., Kolluri, Bharat R. and Panik, Michael J. (1993), ‘Social Security and Household Wealth Accumulation: Refined Microeconometric Evidence’, 75 Review of Economics and Statistics, 548-551. Gupta, Kanhaya L. (1992), ‘Ricardian Equivalence and Crowding out in Asia’, 24 Applied Economics, 19-25. Haavelmo, T. (1945), ‘Multiplier Effects of a Balanced Budget’, 13 Econometrica, 311-318. Hakes, David R. and McCormick, Ken (1996), ‘Did Smith Address Ricardian Equivalence before Ricardo?’, 22 Eastern Economic Journal, 57-61. Hakkio, Craig, S. and Rush, Mark S. (1991), ‘Is the Budget Deficit too Large?’, 29 Economic Inquiry, 429-445. Hamilton, James T. and Flavin, Majorie (1986), ‘On the Limitations of Government Borrowing: A Framework for Empirical Testing’, 76 American Economic Review, 808-819. Handa, Jagdish (1993), ‘Consumption, Uncertainty and Ricardian Equivalence’, in Baldassarri, M., Mundell, Robert and McCallum, Bennett J. (eds), Debt, Deficit and Economic Performance, London, St. Martin’s Press, 291-318. Hansen, Bent (1969), Fiscal Policy in Seven Countries, 1955-65, Paris, OECD. Haug, Alfred A. (1990), ‘Ricardian Equivalence, Rational Expectations, and the Permanent Income Hypothesis’, 22 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 305-326. Haug, Alfred A. (1991), ‘Cointegration and Government Borrowing Constraints: Evidence for the United States’, 9 Journal of Business and Economic Statistics, 96-101. Hayford, Marc (1989), ‘Liquidity Constraints and the Ricardian Equivalence Theorem: A Note’, 21 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 380-387. Heinemann, Friedrich (1993), ‘Sustainability of National Debt in Europe’, Intereconomics, 61-68. Hercowitz, Zvi and Sadka, Efraim (1987), ‘On Optimal Currency Substitution Policy and Public Finance’, in Razin, Assaf and Sadka, Efraim (eds), Economic Policy in Theory and Practice, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 147-164. Hibbs, Douglas A. (1987), ‘Political Parties and Macroeconomic Policy’, 71 American Political Science Review, 1467-1487. Hickman, Bert G. (ed.) (1972), Econometric Models of Cyclical Behavior, New York, Columbia
40
Taxation: Macro Aspects
6010
University Press. Himarios, Daniel (1995), ‘Euler Equation Tests of Ricardian Equivalence’, 48 Economic Letters, 165-171. Hodrick, Robert J. (1988), ‘Expansionary Fiscal Policy and International Interdependence’, in Frenkel, Jacob E. (ed.), International Aspects of Fiscal Policies, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 229-272. Hoelscher, Gregory P. (1986), ‘New Evidence on Deficits and Interest Rates’, 18 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 1-17. Holcombe, Randall G., Jackson, John D. and Zardkoohi, Asghar (1981), ‘The National Debt Controversy’, 34 Kyklos, 186-202. Holmes, James M. and Hutton, Patricia (1990), ‘On the Causal Relationship between Government Expenditure and National Income’, 72 Review of Economics and Statistics, 87-95. Hoover, Kevin D. and Sheffrin, Steven M. (1992), ‘Causation, Spending, and Taxes: Sand in the Sandbox or Tax Collector for the Welfare State?’, 82 American Economic Review, 225-248. Hotelling, Harold (1938), ‘The General Welfare in Relation to Problems of Taxation and Railway and Utility Rates’, 6 Econometrica, 242-269. Hubbard, R. Glenn and Judd, Kenneth L. (1986), ‘Liquidity Constraints, Fiscal Policy and Consumption’, Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 1-50. Ihori, Toshihiro (1988), ‘Debt Burden and Intergeneration Equity’, in Arrow, Kenneth J. and Boskin, Michael J. (eds), The Economics of Public Debt, London, Macmillan, 149-200. Infante, Ettore F. and Stein, Jerome L. (1976), ‘Does Fiscal Policy Matter?’, 2 Journal of Monetary Economics, 473-500. Jaeger, Albert (1993), ‘Debt Neutrality, Finite Horizons and Private Savings Behavior’, in Verbon, Harrie H.A. and Van Winden, Frans A.A.M. (eds), The Political Economy of Government Debt, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 195-205. Johnsson, Gunnar and Klein, Paul (1996), ‘Stochastic Fiscal Policy and the Swedish Businesscycle’, 38 Journal of Monetary Economics, 245-268. Jones, Jonathan D. (1987), ‘Are Future Taxes Anticipated by Consumers? More Evidence for the U.S., 1946-1985', 16 Economic Notes, 141-144. Kahn, Mohsin S. and Knight, Malcolm D. (1982), ‘Unanticipated Monetary Growth and Inflationary Finance’, 14 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 347-364. Kaounides, Lakis and Wood, Geoffrey (eds) (1992), Debt and Deficits, Volume I, II and III, International Library of Macroeconomic and Financial History, vol. 9, Aldershot, Brookfield. Katsaitis, Odysseus (1987), ‘On the Substitutability between Private Consumer Expenditure and Government Spending in Canada’, 20 Canadian Journal of Economics, 533-543. Kay, John A. (1990), ‘Tax Policy: A Survey’, 100 Economic Journal, 18-75. Kazmi, Aqdas Ali (1992), ‘Ricardian Equivalence: Some Macro-econometric Tests for Pakistan’, 31 Pakistan Development Review, 743-755. Kenen, Peter (1995), ‘Macroeconomic Theory and Policy: How the Closed Economy was Opened’, in Jones, Ronald and Kenen, Peter (eds), Handbook of International Economics, Vol. 2 , Amsterdam, North-Holland. Kessler, Denis, Perelman, Sergio and Pestieau, Pierre (1986), ‘Public Debt, Tax and Consumption: A Test on OECD Countries’, 41 Public Finance, 43-70.
6010
Taxation: Macro Aspects
41
Kiesling, Herbert J. (1992), Taxation and Public Goods, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press. Kigel, Miguel A. (1989), ‘Budget Deficits, Stability and the Monetary Dynamics of Hyperinflation’, 21 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 148-157. Kimbrough, Kent P. (1988), ‘Optimal Tax Policy for Balance of Payments Objectives’, in Frenkel, Jacob E. (ed.), International Aspects of Fiscal Policies, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 309-348. King, Robert G. and Plosser, Charles L. (1985), ‘Money, Deficits, and Inflation’, 22 Carnegie-Rochester Conference Series on Public Policy, 147-196. Kingston, Geoffrey (1991), ‘Should Marginal Tax Rates be Equalized Through Time’, Quarterly Journal of Economics. Knight, Malcolm D. and Masson, Paul R. (1988), ‘Fiscal Policies, Net Saving, and Real Exchange Rates: The United States, the Federal Republic of Germany, and Japan’, in Frenkel, Jacob E. (ed.), International Aspects of Fiscal Policies, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 21-72. Knoester, Anthonie (1980), ‘The Haavelmo Effect Revisited’, 1 Finnish Economic Papers in Frech, H.E. (ed.), Regulating Doctors’ Fees: Competition, Benefits, and Controls under Medicare, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute, 121-125. Knoester, Anthonie (1983), ‘Stagnation and the Inverted Haavelmoo Effect, some International Evidence’, 131 De Economist, 548-584. Koch, Walter A.S. (1984), ‘Negative Einkommensteuern und Konjunkturpolitik (Negative Income Taxes and Stabilization Policy)’, 30 Konjunkturpolitik, 348-373. Kochin, Levis A. (1974), ‘Are Future Taxes Discounted by Consumers’, 6 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 385-394. Kole, Linda S. (1988), ‘Expansionary Fiscal Policy and International Interdependence’, in Frenkel, Jacob E. (ed.), International Aspects of Fiscal Policies, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 229-265. Kormendi, Roger C. (1983), ‘Government Debt, Government Spending and Private Sector Behaviour’, 75 American Economic Review, 994-1010. Kormendi, Roger C. (1985), ‘Does Deficit-financing affect Economic Growth? Cross Country Evidence’, 2 Journal of Banking and Finance, 243-255. Kormendi, Roger C. and Meguire, Philip (1986), ‘Government Debt Government Spending and Private Sector Behavior: Reply’, 76 American Economic Review, 1180-1187. Kormendi, Roger C. and Meguire, Philip (1990), ‘Government Debt, Government Spending and Private Sector Behavior: Reply and Update’, 80 American Economic Review, 604-617. Koskela, Erkki and Viren, Matti (1983), ‘National Debt Neutrality: Some International Evidence’, 36 Kyklos, 575-588. Kotlikoff, Laurence J. and Summers, Laurence T. (1981), ‘The Role of Intergenerational Transfers in Aggregate Capital Accumulation’, 89 Journal of Political Economy, 706-732. Kotlikoff, Laurence J., Razin, Assaf and Rosenthal, Robert W. (1990), ‘A Strategic Altruism Model in Which Ricardian Equivalence Does not Hold’, 100 Economic Journal, 1261-1268. Kremers, Jeroen M. (1988), ‘Long-Run Limits on the US Federal Debt’, 28 Economic Letters, 259-262. Kremers, Jeroen M. (1989), ‘Federal Indebtedness and the Conduct of Fiscal Policy’, 23 Journal of
42
Taxation: Macro Aspects
6010
Monetary Economics, 219-238. Kydland, Finn E. and Prescott, Edward C.v (1977), ‘Rules rather than discretion. The Inconsistency of Optimal Plans’, 85 Journal of Political Economy in Frech, H.E. (ed.), Regulating Doctors’ Fees: Competition, Benefits, and Controls under Medicare, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute, 473-491. Kydland, Finn E. and Prescott, Edward C.v (1980), ‘A Competitive Theory of Fluctuations and the Feasibility and Desirability of Stabilization Policies’, in Fischer, Stanley (ed.), Rational Expectations and Economic Policy, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 169-187. Kyer, Ben L., Mixon, J. Wilson, Jr and Uri, Noel D. (1988), ‘Taxes, Transfer Payments and Automatic Stabilization in the United States. Impact and Trends’, 2 Economic Notes, 50-60. Laney, Leroy O. and Willett, Thomas D. (1983), ‘Presidential Politics, Budget Deficits and Monetary Policy in the United States: 1960-1976', 40 Public Choice, 53-69. Leachman, Lori (1996), ‘New Evidence on the Ricardian Equivalence Theorem: A Multicointegration Approach’, 28 Applied Economics in Frech, H.E. (ed.), Regulating Doctors’ Fees: Competition, Benefits, and Controls under Medicare, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute, 695-704. Lee, Bong Soo (1991), ‘Government Deficits and the Term Structure of Interest Rates’, 27 Journal of Monetary Economics, 425-443. Leiderman, Leonardo and Blejer, Mario (1988), ‘Modeling and Testing Ricardian Equivalence: A Survey’, 35 International Monetary Fund Staff Papers, 1-35. Leiderman, Leonardo and Razin, Assaf (1988), ‘Testing Ricardian Neutrality with an Intertemporal Stochastic Model’, 20 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 1-21. Lipford, Jody and Dougan, William R. (1995), ‘A Public Choice Theoretic Test of Ricardian Equivalence’, 23 Public Finance Quarterly, 467-483. Liversey, David A. (1980), ‘The Uncertain Foundation of Fiscal Policy’, in Hughes, G.A. and Heal, Geoffrey M. (eds), The Public Policy and the Tax System, London, George Allen & Unwin, 194-224. Liviatan, Nissan (1982), ‘Neutrality of Government Bonds Reconsidered’, 19 Journal of Public Economics, 261-270. Lopez, Garcia and Angel, Miguel (1990), ‘On Debt Neutrality in Life-Cycle Models’, 33 Economics Letters, 233-238. Lord, William and Rangazas, Peter (1993), ‘Altruism, Deficit Policies, and the Wealth of Future Generations’, 31 Economic Inquiry, 609-639. Lovell, Michael C. (1986), ‘Tests of the Rational Expectations Hypothesis’, 76 American Economic Review, 110-114. Lucas, Robert E. (1972), ‘Expectations and the Neutrality of Money’, 4 Journal of Economic Theory, 103-124. Lucas, Robert E. (1973), ‘Some International Evidence on Output-Inflation Tradeoffs’, 63 American Economic Review, 326-334. Lucas, Robert E. (1975), ‘An Equilibrium Model of the Business Cycle’, 83 Journal of Political Economy, 1113-1144. Lucas, Robert E. (1976), ‘Econometric Policy Evaluation: A Critique’, 1 Carnegie-Rochester Conference Series on Public Policy, 19-46. Lucas, Robert E. (1980), ‘Rules, Discretion and the Role of the Economic Advisor’, in Fischer, Stanley (ed.), Rational Expectations and Economic Policy, Chicago, University of Chicago Press,
6010
Taxation: Macro Aspects
43
199-210. Lucas, Robert E. (1986a), ‘Adaptive Behavior and Economic Theory’, 59S Journal of Business, 401-426. Lucas, Robert E. (1986b), ‘Principles of Fiscal and Monetary Policy’, 17 Journal of Monetary Economics, 117-134. Lucas, Robert E. and Sargent, Thomas J. (eds) (1981), Rational Expectations and Econometric Practice, Vol 1 and Vol. 2, Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press. Lucas, Robert E. and Stokey, Nancy L. (1983), ‘Optimal Fiscal and Monetary Fiscal in an Economy without Capital’, 12 Journal of Monetary Economics, 55-93. MacDonald, Ronald (1992), ‘Some Tests of the Government’s Intertemporal Budget constraint using US Data’, 24 Applied Economics, 1287-1292. MacDonald, Ronald and Speight, Alan E.M. (1990), ‘The Intertemporal Government Budget Constraint in the UK’, 58 Manchester School of Economic and Social Studies, 329-347. Makin, John (1983), ‘Real Interest, Money Surprises, Anticipated Inflation and Fiscal Deficits’, 32 Review of Economics and Statistics, 281-299. Manage, Neela and Marlow, Michael L. (1986), ‘The Causal Relation between Federal Expenditure and Receipts’, 52 Southern Economic Journal, 617-629. Mankiw, Gregory (1987), ‘The Optimal Collection of Seigniorage: Theory and Evidence’, 20 Journal of Monetary Economics, 327-341. Mariger, Randall P. (1986), Consumption Behavior and the Effects of Government Fiscal Policies, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Marston, Richard (1995), ‘Stabilization Policies in Open Economies’, in Jones, Ronald and Kenen, Peter (eds), Handbook of International Economics, Vol. 2, Amsterdam, North-Holland. Marty, Alvin L. (1973), ‘Growth Satiety and the Tax Revenue from Money Creation’, 8 Journal of Political Economy, 1136-1152. Marty, Alvin L. (1994), ‘The Inflation Tax and the Marginal Welfare Cost in a World of Currency and Deposits’, 76 Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis Review, 67-71. Marty, Alvin L. and Chaloupka, Frank J. (1988), ‘Optimal Inflation Rates: A Generalization’, 20 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 141-144. Mascaro, Angelo and Meltzer, Allen (1983), ‘Long and Short-term Interest Rates in a Risky World’, 12 Journal of Monetary Economics, 485-518. Masson, Paul R. (1985), ‘The Sustainability of Fiscal Deficits’, 32 International Monetary Fund Staff Papers, 577-605. Mayer, Thomas (1984), ‘The Government Budget Constraint and Standard Macro-Theory’,13 Journal of Monetary Economics, 371-379. McCallum, Benneth T. (1977), ‘Price Level Stickiness and the Feasibility of Monetary Stabilization Policy with Rational Expectations’, 86 Journal of Political Economy, 627-634. McCallum, Benneth T. (1980), ‘Rational Expectations and Macroeconomic Stabilisation Policy: An Overview’, 12 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 716-746. McCallum, Benneth T. (1984), ‘Are Bond-financed Deficits Inflationary? A Ricardian Analaysis’, 92 Journal of Political Economy, 123-135. McCallum, Benneth T. and Whitaker, John K. (1979), ‘The Effectiveness of Fiscal Feedback Rules and Automatic Stabilizers under Rational Expectations’, 5 Journal of Monetary Economics, 171-186.
44
Taxation: Macro Aspects
6010
McGrattan, Ellen R. (1994), ‘The Macroeconomic Effects of Distortionary Taxation’, 33 Journal of Monetary Economics, 573-601. McKibbin, Warwick J. and Sachs, Jeffrey D. (1988), ‘Coordination of Monetary and Fiscal Policies in the Industrial Economies’, in Frenkel, Jacob E. (ed.), International Aspects of Fiscal Policies, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 73-120. McKinnon, Ronald I. (1973), ‘The Value Added Tax and the Liberalization of Foreign Trade in Developing Economics: A Comment’, 11 Journal of Economic Literature, 520-524. McMillin, Douglas W. and Koray, Faik (1990), ‘Does Government Debt Affect the Exchange Rate? An Empirical Analysis of the U.S. Canadian Exchange Rate’, 42 Journal of Economics and Business, 279-288. Meltzer, Allen and Richard, Scott H. (1978), ‘A Rational Theory of the Size of Government’, 89 Journal of Political Economy, 914-927. Merrick, John and Saunders, Allen (1986), ‘International Expected Real Interest Rates’, 18 Journal of Monetary Economics, 312-322. Meyer, Laurence H. (1975), ‘The Balance Sheet Identity, the Government Financing Constraint, and the Crowding-Out Effect’, 1 Journal of Monetary Economics, 65-78. Meyer, Laurence H. (1980), ‘Financing Constraints and the Short-Run Response to Fiscal Policy’, 62 Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis Review, 24-31. Miller, J. Preston (1983), ‘Higher Deficit Policies Lead to Higher Inflation’, 7 Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis Quarterly Review, 8-19. Miller, J. Preston and Sargent, Thomas J. (1984), ‘A Reply to Darby’, 8 Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis Quarterly Review, 21-26. Miller, Marcus H. (1985), ‘Measuring the Stance of Fiscal Policy’, 4 Oxford Review of Economic Policy, 44-57. Miller, Stephen M. and Russek, Frank S. (1990), ‘Cointegration and Error-correction Models: The Temporal Causality between Government Taxes and Spending’, 57 Southern Economic Journal, 221-229. Modigliani, Franco (1944), ‘Liquidity Preference and the Theory of Interest and Money’, 12(1) Econometrica, 45-88. Reprinted in Friedrich A. Lutz and Lloyd W. Mints (eds) (1951), Readings in Monetory Theory, Philadelphia, Balkiston, 186-239. Modigliani, Franco (1961), ‘Long-Run Implications of Alternative Fiscal Policies and the Burden of the National Debt’, 71 Economic Journal, 730-755. Modigliani, Franco (1987), ‘The Economics of Public Deficits’, in Razin, Assaf and Sadka, Efraim (eds), Economic Policy in Theory and Practice, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 3-44. Modigliani, Franco and Jappelli, Tullio (1987), ‘Fiscal Policy and Saving in Italy since 1860', in Boskin, Michael, Flemming, John and Gorini, Stefano (eds), Private Saving and Public Debt, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 126-170. Modigliani, Franco and Sterling, Arlie G. (1986), ‘Government Debt, Government Spending and Private Sector Behavior: Comment’, 76 American Economic Review, 1168 ff. Modigliani, Franco, Jappelli, Tullio and Pagano, Marco (1985), ‘Policy and Inflation on National Saving: The Italian Case’, Banca Nazionale del Lavoro Review, 91-126. Monadjemi, Mehdi and Kearney, Colm (1991), ‘The Interest Rate Neutrality of Fiscal Deficits: Testing for Ricardian Equivalence and Capital Inflow’, 10 Journal of International Money and Finance, 541-551. Morris, Dirk (1988), Government Debt in International Financial Markets, London, Pinter Publishers.
6010
Taxation: Macro Aspects
45
Motley, Brian (1987), ‘Ricardo or Keynes: Does the Government Debt Affect Consumption?’, Federal Reserve Bank of San Francisco Economic Review, 47-62. Mourmouras, Alex and Tijerina, Jose A. (1994), ‘Collection Lags and the Optimal Inflation Tax: A Reconsideration’, 41 International Monetary Fund Staff Papers, 30-54. Mueller, Dennis C. (1989), Public Choice II, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Mukhopadhyay, Arun K. (1994), ‘Are Haligonians Ricardian? A Survey of Households’ Saving Response to the Government’s Budget Deficits’, 23 Journal of Socio-Economics, 457-477. Musgrave, Richard A. (1988), ‘Public Debt and Intergeneration Equity’, in Arrow, Kenneth J. and Boskin, Michael J. (eds), The Economics of Public Debt, New York, St. Martin Press, 133-146. Musgrave, Richard A. and Shoup, Carl S. (1959), Readings in the Economics of Taxation, Homewood, IL, Richard D. Irwin. Muth, John F. (1961), ‘Rational Expectations and the Theory of Price Movements’, 29 Econometrica, 315-335. Neary, Peter and Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1983), ‘Toward a Reconstruction of Keynesian Economics: Expectations and Constrained Equilibria’, 98 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 199-228. Nicoletti, Giuseppe (1988), ‘A Cross-Country Analysis of Private Consumption, Inflation and the Debt Neutrality Hypothesis’, 11 OECD Economic Studies. Nicoletti, Giuseppe (1992), ‘Is Tax Discounting Stable over Time?’, 54 Oxford Bulletin of Economics and Statistics, 121-144. Niskanen, William A. (1978), ‘Deficits, Government Spending and Inflation: What is the Evidence?’, 8 Journal of Monetary Economics, 591-602. Nordhaus, William D. (1989), ‘Alternative Approaches to the Political Business Cycle’, 19 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 1-68. O’Driscoll, Gerald P., Jr (1977), ‘The Ricardian Nonequivalence Theorem’, 85 Journal of Political Economy, 207-210. Ohlsson, Henry and Vredin, Anders (1996), ‘Political Cycles and Cyclical Policies’, 98 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 203-218. Okun, Arthur (1972), ‘Fiscal-Monetary Activism: Some Analytical Issues’, 1 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 123-172. Ott, David J. and Ott, Attiat F. (1965), ‘Budget Balance and Equilibrium Income’, 20 Journal of Finance, 71-77. Pasula, Kit (1994), ‘Sterilization, Ricardian Equivalence and Structural and Reduced-Form Estimates of the Offset Coefficient’, 16 Journal of Macroeconomics, 683-699. Peacock, Alan and Shaw, G.K. (1976), The Economic Theory of Fiscal Policy (2nd edn), London, George Allen and Unwin. Pemberton, James (1994), ‘Ricardian Equivalence: Are the Required Assumptions Defensible?’, 46 Economics Letters, 223-227. Perasso, Giancarlo (1987), ‘The Ricardian Equivalence Theorem and the Consumption Function: A Survey of the Literature’, 34 Revista Internazionale di Scienze Economiche e Commerciali, 649-674. Perelman, Sergio and Pestieau, Pierre (1993), ‘The Determinants of the Ricardian Equivalence in the OECD’, in Verbon, Harrie H.A. and Van Winden, Frans A.A.M. (eds), The Political Economy of Government Debt, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 181-193. Persson, Torsten (1985), ‘Deficits and Intergenerational Welfare in Open Economies’, 19 Journal of
46
Taxation: Macro Aspects
6010
International Economics, 67-84. Persson, Torsten and Svensson, Lars E.O. (1984), ‘Time-consistent Fiscal Policy and Government Cash-flow’, 14 Journal of Monetary Economics, 365-374. Persson, Torsten and Svensson, Lars E.O. (1986), ‘International Borrowing and Time-consistent Fiscal Policy’, 88 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 273-295. Persson, Torsten and Tabellini, Guido (1990), Macroeconomic Policy, Credibility and Politics, New York, Harwood Academic. Persson, Torsten and Tabellini, Guido (1994), Monetary and Fiscal Policy, Volume 1: Credibility, Volume 2: Politics, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Pesek, Boris P. and Saving, Thomas R. (1967), Money, Wealth and Economic Theory, New York, Macmillan. Phelps, Edmund S. (1973), ‘Inflation in the Theory of Public Finance’, 75 Swedish Journal of Economics, 67-82. Phelps, Edmund S. and Taylor, John B. (1977), ‘The Stabilising Powers of Monetary Policy under Rational Expectations’, 85 Journal of Political Economy, 163-190. Phelps, Edmund S. and Velupillai, Kumaraswanny (1988), ‘Optimum Fiscal Policy when Monetary Policy is Bound by a Rule: Ramsey Redux’, in Arrow, Kenneth J. and Boskin, Michael J. (eds), The Economics of Public Debt, London, Macmillan, 116-130. Pissarides, Christopher A. (1986), ‘Equilibrium Effects of Tax Based Incomes Policies’, in Colander, David C. (ed.), Incentive Based Incomes Policies: Advances in TIP and MAP, Cambridge, MA, Harper and Row, 111-127. Plosser, Charles I. (1982), ‘Government Financing Decisions and Asset Returns’, 9 Journal of Monetary Economics, 325-352. Plosser, Charles I. (1987), ‘Ricardian Equivalence: An Evaluation of Theory and Evidence: Comment’, in Fischer, Stanley (ed.), NBER Macroeconomics Annual, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 309-313. Pommerehne, Werner W. and Schneider, Friedrich (1983), ‘Does Government in a Representative Democracy Follow a Majority of Voters’ Preferences? An Empirical Examination’, in Hanusch, Horst (ed.), Anatomy of Government Deficiencies, Berlin, Springer-Verlag, 61-84. Posner, Michael V. (1987), ‘Private Saving and Public Debt: A Survey of the Debate’, in Boskin, Michael, Flemming, John and Gorini, Stefano (eds), Private Saving and Public Debt, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 395-414. Poterba, James M. and Rotemberg, Julio J. (1990), ‘Inflation and Taxation with Optimizing Governments’, 12 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 1-18. Poterba, James M. and Summers, Lawrence H. (1987), ‘Finite Lifetimes and the Effects of Budget Deficits on National Saving’, 20 Journal of Monetary Economics, 369-391. Purvis, Douglas (1985), ‘Public Sector Deficits, International Capital Movements, and the Domestic Economy, the Medium-Term is the Message’, 18 Canadian Journal of Economics, 723-742. Ram, Rati (1988), ‘Additional Evidence on Causality between Revenue and Government Expenditure’, 54 Southern Economic Journal, 763-769. Razin, Assaf (1990), ‘Fiscal Policies and the Integrated World Stock Market’, 29 Journal of International Economics, 109-122. Razin, Assaf and Sadka, Efraim (1987), Economic Policy in Theory and Practice, London, Macmillan. Razin, Assaf and Svensson, Lars E.O. (1983), ‘The Current Account and Optimal Government Debt’,
6010
Taxation: Macro Aspects
47
2 Journal of International Money and Finance, 215-224. Reid, Bradford G. (1989), ‘Government Budgets and Aggregate Consumption: Cross-sectional Evidence from Canadian Provincial Data’, 11 Journal of Macroeconomics, 121-132. Remolona, Eli M. (1983), ‘A Pitfall in the Welfare Cost of Inflationary Finance’, 20 Philippine Review of Economics and Business, 205-213. Renaud, Paul S.A. and Van Winden, F.A.A.M. (1987), ‘Tax Rate and Government Expenditure’, 40 Kyklos, 349-367. Reynolds, Alan (1985), ‘Some International Comparisons of Supply-Side Tax Policy’, 5 Cato Journal, 543-569. Rodseth, Asbjorn (1979), ‘Macroeconomic Policy in a Small Open Economy’, 81 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 48-59. Rodseth, Asbjorn (1984), ‘Progressive Taxes and Automatic Stabilization in an Open Economy’, 6 Journal of Macroeconomics, 265-282. Rose, David C. and Hakes, David R. (1995), ‘Deficits and Interest Rates as Evidence of Ricardian Equivalence’, 21 Eastern Economic Journal, 57-66. Rose, Richard and Karran, Terence (1987), Taxation by Political Inertia, London, Unwin Hyman. Ruiz-Huerta Carbonell, Jesús (1994), ‘The Dimension, Effectiveness and Efficiency of Public Expenditure’, in X (ed.), National Budgeting for Economic and Monetary Union, European Institute of Public Administration, 195-199. Ruiz-Huerta Carbonell, Jesús (1995), Las Rentas de las Personas Mayores (Eldest Citizens’ Income), SECOT. Ruiz-Huerta Carbonell, Jesús and Gim‚nez, Antonio (eds) (1993), Estructura Institucional y Gestión del Gasto Público en algunos Paises de la OCDE (Institutional Structure and Managment of Public Expenditure in Some Countries), Estudios de Hacienda Pública, Instituto de Estudios Fiscales. Sargent, Thomas J. (1973), ‘Rational Expectations, the Real Rate of Interest and the Natural Rate of Unemployment’, Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 429-472. Sargent, Thomas J. (1976), ‘The Observational Equivalence of Natural and Unnatural Rate Theories of Macroeconomics’, 84 Journal of Political Economy, 631-640. Reprinted in Lucas and Sargent, 1981, 553-562. Sargent, Thomas J. and Smith, Bruce D. (1987), ‘Irrelevance of Open Market Operations in Some Economies with Government Currency Being Dominated in Rate of Return’, 77 American Economic Review, 78-92. Sargent, Thomas J. and Wallace, Neil (1975), ‘“Rational Expectations”: The Optimal Monetary Instrument and the Optimal Money Supply Rule’, 83 Journal of Political Economy, 241-254. Reprinted in Sargent and Lucas, 1981, 215-228. Sargent, Thomas J. and Wallace, Neil (1976), ‘Rational Expectations and the Theory of Economic Policy’, 2 Journal of Monetary Economics, 169-183. Sargent, Thomas J. and Wallace, Neil (1981), ‘Some Unpleasant Monetarist Arithmetic’, 5 Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis Quarterly Review, 1-17. Scarth, William M. (1977), ‘The Government Budget Constraint in an Open Economy: A Further Comment’, 77 Oxford Economic Papers, 145-151. Schneider, Friedrich and Frey, Bruno (1988), ‘Politico-economic Models of Macroeconomic Policy: A Review of the Empirical Evidence’, in Willett, Thomas (ed.),Political Business Cycles, Durban, Duke University Press, 239-275. Seater, John J. (1982), ‘Are Future Taxes Discounted’, 14 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking,
48
Taxation: Macro Aspects
6010
376-389. Seater, John J. (1993), ‘Ricardian Equivalence’, 31 Journal of Economic Literature, 142-190. Seater, John J. and Mariano, Roberto S. (1985), ‘New Tests of the Lifecycle and Tax Discounting Hypotheses’, 15 Journal of Monetary Economics, 195-215. Shaviro, Daniel N. (1997), Do Deficits Matter?, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Shaw, G.K. (1979), ‘The Measurement of Fiscal Influence’, in Cook, S.T. and Jackson, Peter M. (eds), Current Issues in Fiscal Policy, London, Martin Robertson, 44-60. Shiller, Robert J. (1978), ‘Rational Expectations and the Dynamic Structure of Macro-economic Models’, 4 Journal of Monetary Economics, 1-44. Siegfried, John J. and Smith, Paul A. (1991), ‘The Distributional Effects of A Sales Tax on Services’, 44(1) National Tax Journal, 41-54. Silber, William L. (1970), ‘Fiscal Policy in IS-LM Analysis: A Correction’, 2 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 461-472. Sims, Christopher A. (1982), ‘Policy Analysis with Econometric Models’, Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 107-152. Slate, Stephen (1995), ‘Testing Ricardian Equivalence under Uncertainty’, 85 Public Choice, 11-29. Smith, Gregor and Zin, Stanley E. (1991), ‘Persistent Deficits and the Market Value of Government Debt’, 6 Journal of Applied Econometrics, 31-44. Smyth, David J. (1978), ‘Built-in Flexibility of Taxation, the Government Budget Constraint, the Specification of the Demand for Money Function, and the Stability of an IS-LM System’, 33 Public Finance, 367-375. Soderstrom, Hans T. (1985), ‘Exchange Rate Strategies and Real Adjustment after 1970. The Experience of the Smaller European Economies’, in Peeters, Theo, Praet, Peter and Reding, Paul (eds), International Trade and Exchange Rates in the Late Eighties, Amsterdam, North Holland, 227-264. Soderstrom, Hans T. (1987), ‘Sectoral Saving and Investment Patterns in 16 OECD Countries, 1965-82', in Boskin, Michael, Flemming, John and Gorini, Stefano (eds), Private Saving and Public Debt, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 3-39. Spaventa, Luigi (1987), ‘The Growth of Public Debt: Sustainability, Fiscal Rules, and Monetary Rules’, 34 International Monetary Fund Staff Papers, 577-605. Spencer, Roger W. and Yohe, William P. (1970), ‘The Crowding out of Private Expenditures by Fiscal Actions’, 52 Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis Review, 12-24. Standish, Barry and Beelders, O. (1991), ‘Do South African Fiscal Deficits Matter?’, 15 Journal for Studies in Economics and Econometrics, 1-17. Steindl, Frank G. (1971), ‘A Simple Macroeconomic Model with a Government Budget Restraint: A Comment’, 79 Journal of Political Economy, 675-679. Steindl, Frank G. (1993), ‘Making a Dishonest Government Credible: The Inflation Tax’, 26 Kredit und Kapital, 239-245. Stevens, Neil A. (1979), ‘Government Debt Financing - Its Effects in View of Tax Discounting’, 61 Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis Review, 11-19. Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1988), ‘On the Relevance or Irrelevance of Public Financial Policy’, in Arrow, Kenneth J. and Boskin, Michael J. (eds), The Economics of Public Debt, London, Macmillan, 41-76. Stockman, Alan C. (1988), ‘Fiscal Policies and International Financial Markets’, in Frenkel, Jacob E.
6010
Taxation: Macro Aspects
49
(ed.), International Aspects of Fiscal Policies, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 196-228. Strawczynski, Michel (1995), ‘Income Uncertainty and Ricardian Equivalence’, 85 American Economic Review, 964-967. Summers, Lawrence H. (1988), ‘Tax Policy and International Competitiveness’, in Frenkel, Jacob E. (ed.), International Aspects of Fiscal Policies, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 349-386. Sumner, Michael T. (1983), ‘The Incentive Effects of Taxation’, in Millward, Robert, Parker, David, Rosenthal, Leslie, Summner, Michael and Topham, Neville (eds), Public Sector Economics, London, Longman, 6-77. Svensson, Lars E.O. (1987), ‘International Fiscal Policy Transmission’, 89 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 89-118. Svensson, Lars E.O. (1988), ‘Fiscal Policy, Sticky Goods Prices, and Resource Utilization’, in Kohn, Meir and Tsiang, Sho-Chieh (eds), Finance Constraints, Expectations, and Macroeconomics, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 185-205. Tanner, John E. (1979), ‘An Empirical Investigation of Tax Discounting’, 11 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 214-218. Tanzi, Vito (ed.) (1984), Taxation, Inflation and Interest Rates, Washington, International Monetary Fund. Tanzi, Vito (1985), ‘Fiscal Deficits and Interest Rates in the United States: An Empirical Analysis’, 32 International Monetary Fund Staff Papers, 551-576. Tanzi, Vito and Blejer, Mario (1988), ‘Public Debt and Fiscal Policy in Developing Countries’, in Arrow, Kenneth J. and Boskin, Michael J. (eds), The Economics of Public Debt, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 230-263. Taylor, John B. (1979), ‘Staggered Wage Setting in a Macro Model’, 69 American Economic Review, 108-113. Taylor, John B. (1985), ‘Rational Expectations Models in Macroeconomics’, in Honkapohja, Seppo and Arrow, Kenneth J. (eds),Frontiers of Economics, Helsinki, Y. Jahnsson Foundation, 391-425. Thornton, Daniel L. (1990), ‘Do Government Deficits Matter?’, 72 Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis Review, 25-39. Tobin, James (1980), Asset Accumulation and Economic Activity, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Tobin, James and Buiter, William H. (1976), ‘Long-run Effects of Fiscal and Monetary Policy on Aggregate Demand’, in Stein, Jerome (ed.), Monetarism, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 273-309. Tower, Edward (1971), ‘More the Welfare Cost of Inflation Finance’, 3 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 850-860. Tramontana, Antonino (1985), ‘The Wealth Effect of Public Debt: A Macroeconomic Approach’, 14 Economic Notes, 71-103. Trehan, Bharat and Walsh, Carl E. (1988), ‘Common Trends, the Government Budget Constraint, and Revenue Smoothing’, 12 Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control, 425-444. Trehan, Bharat and Walsh, Carl E. (1991), ‘Testing Intertemporal Budget Constraints: Theory and Applications to US Federal Budget and Current Account Deficits’, 23 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 206-223. Trostel, Philip A. (1993), ‘The Nonequivalence between Deficits and Distortionary Taxation’, 31 Journal of Monetary Economics, 207-227.
50
Taxation: Macro Aspects
6010
Tufte, Edward R. (1978), Political Control of the Economy, Princeton, Princeton University Press. Turnovsky, Stephen J. (1977), Macroeconomic Analysis and Stabilization Policy, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Uri, Noel D., Mixon, J. Wilson, Jr and Kyer, Ben L. (1989a), ‘An Analysis of the Automatic Stabilizers Associated with Taxes and Transfers Payments’, 3 International Review of Applied Economics, 46-56. Uri, Noel D., Mixon, J. Wilson, Jr and Kyer, Ben L. (1989b), ‘Automatic Stabilizers Reconsidered’, 44 Public Finance, 476-496. Van Der Ploeg, Frederick (1995), ‘Political Economy of Monetary and Budgetary Policy’, 36 International Economic Review, 427-439. Van Velthoven, B.C.J. (1989), The Endogenization of Government Behavior in Macroeconomic Models, Berlin, Springer. Van Velthoven, B.C.J., Verbon, H.A.A. and Van Winden, F.A.A.M. (1993), ‘The Political Economy of Government Debt: A Survey’, in Verbon, Harrie H.A. and Van Winden, Frans A.A.M. (eds), The Political Economy of Government Debt, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 3-32. Van Wijnbergen, Sweder (1988), ‘Fiscal Policy, Trade Intervention, and World Interest Rates: An Empirical Analysis’, in Frenkel, Jacob E. (ed.), International Aspects of Fiscal Policies, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 273-308. Vanhorebeek, Filip and Van Rompuy, Paul (1995), ‘Solvancy and Sustainability of Fiscal Policies in the EU’, 143 De Economist, 457-473. Vasic B. Vukasin (1986), ‘Makroekonomska Politika kao Javno Dobro (Macroeconomic Policy as a Public Good)’, 3 Ekonomist, 429-430. Vaughn, Karen I. and Wagner, Richard E. (1992), ‘Public Debt Controversies: An Essay in Reconciliation’, 45 Kyklos, 37-49. Vedder, Richard (1991), ‘Taxes, and Economic Growth’, 10 Cato Journal, 91-108. Vegh, Carlos A. (1989), ‘The Optimal Inflation Tax in the Presence of Currency Substitution’, 24 Journal of Monetary Economics, 139-146. Vegh, Carlos A. (1995), ‘Inflationary Finance and Currency Substitution in a Public Finance Framework’, 14 Journal of International Money and Finance, 679-693. Vines, David, Macriejowski, Jan and Meade, James E. (1983), Demand Management, London, George Allen and Unwin. Viren, Matti (1988), ‘Interest Rates and Budget Deficits: Cross-Country Evidence from the Period 1924-1938', 28 Economics Letters, 235-238. Von Furstenberg, George M., Green, Jeffrey R. and Jeong, Jin-Ho (1986), ‘Tax and Spend or Spend and Tax?’, 68 Review of Economics and Statistics, 179-188. Wagner, Richard E. (1996), ‘Who Ows What, and to Whom? Public Debt, Ricardian Equivalence and Governmental Form’, 9 Review of Austrian Economics, 129-142. Wallace, Neil (1981), ‘A Modigliani-Miller Theorem for Open-Market Operations’, 71 American Economic Review, 267-274. Walsh, Brendan M. (1988), ‘Ricardian Equivalence and the Irish Consumption Function: A Comment’, 20 Economic and Social Review, 49-52. Webb, David C. (1981), ‘The Net Wealth Effect of Government Bonds when Credit Markets are Imperfect’, 91 Economic Journal, 405-414. Webber, Carolyn and Wildavsky, Aaron (1986), A History of Taxation and Expenditure in the Western World, New York, Simon and Schuster.
6010
Taxation: Macro Aspects
51
Weil, Philippe (1987a), ‘Permanent Budget Deficits and Inflation’, 20 Journal of Monetary Economics, 393-410. Weil, Philippe (1987b), ‘Love the Children’s Reflections on the Barro Debt Neutrality Theorem’, 19 Journal of Monetary Economics, 377-391. Whelan, Karl (1991), ‘Ricardian Equivalence and the Irish Consumption Function: The Evidence Re-examined’, 22 Economic and Social Review, 229-238. Wilcox, David H. (1989), ‘The Sustainability of Government Deficits: Implications of the Present-value Borrowing Constraint’, 3 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 291-306. Wohar, Mark (1988), ‘How Effective is Fiscal Policy? The U.S. Experience’, 124 Weltwirtschaftliches Archiv, 458-479. Yawitz, Jess B. and Meyer, Laurence H. (1976), ‘An Empirical Investigation of the Extent of Tax Discounting’, 8 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 247-254. Yotsuzuka, Toshiki (1987), ‘Ricardian Equivalence in the Presence of Capital Market Imperfections’, 20 Journal of Monetary Economics, 411-436.
6020 TAX EVASION AND TAX COMPLIANCE Luigi Alberto Franzoni University of Bologna, Italy © Copyright 1999 Luigi Alberto Franzoni
Abstract This chapter offers an overview of the theoretical and empirical research on tax evasion, delineating the variety of factors affecting noncompliance and examining possible remedies. Particular emphasis is placed on the institutional and procedural rules governing the tax enforcement policy. JEL classification: K34 Keywords: Tax Enforcement, Compliance, Taxpayer’s Behavior, Tax Gap
1. Introduction Tax evasion is said to occur when individuals deliberately fail to comply with their tax obligations. The resulting tax revenue loss may cause serious damage to the proper functioning of the public sector, threatening its capacity to finance its basic expenses. Although tax compliance is a major concern for all governments and analytical investigation of tax evasion can be traced as far back as the work, one of the pioneers of ‘law and economics’, Cesare Beccaria (1764), the problem was long segregated from the main body of economics and left essentially to the attention of tax authorities and jurisprudence. The modern use of economic tools for the analysis of tax compliance can be credited to Allingham and Sandmo ([1972] 1991), who extended the influential work of Becker (1968) on law enforcement to taxation using modern risk theory. In the decades since, the literature on tax evasion has blossomed (as witnessed by the voluminous bibliography enclosed). Probably no aspect of tax compliance has escaped at least preliminary scrutiny. Detailed introductions to this theme are now available, as in the monographs of Cowell (1990) (theoretically oriented) and Roth, Scholtz and Witt (1989) (an interdisciplinary perspective), and the surveys of Andreoni, Erard and Feinstein (1998) (including a thorough discussion of empirical results) and Slemrod and Yitzhaki (1998) (with large sections devoted to avoidance and administration). As a complex phenomenon, tax compliance can be addressed from a variety of perspectives. Taxpayers’ stance is influenced by many factors, including their disposition towards public institutions, the perceived fairness of the taxes, 52
6020
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
53
prevailing social norms, and the chances of noncompliance being detected and punished. Without questioning the relevance of ethical and sociological motivations, the economic analysis of tax compliance has focused mainly on how evasion can be deterred through detection and sanctions. The thesis is that the taxpayer’s behavior can be fruitfully seen as the result of a rational calculus, a careful assessment of the costs and benefits of evasion. Since even in the simplest tax and enforcement systems the incentives to comply are far from obvious, this economic perspective offers precious insights that can be used to derive suitable policy measures. Yet, given the complexity of the economic set-up in which the taxpayer usually makes compliance decisions, no simple policy prescription should be expected. In fact, as we will see, to date theoretical and empirical research has managed to establish very few firm points. Nevertheless, the general picture of tax compliance is much clearer now than just a few decades ago. At least the literature has shown that evasion is a serious problem, too complex to be solved by simple policy adjustments, and that the set of instruments for controlling it is vast. This chapter provides an overview of the findings of the theoretical and the empirical literature on tax evasion. Section 2 defines tax evasion, as opposed to tax avoidance and other unlawful activities. In Section 3, Allingham and Sandmo’s basic model of tax evasion is presented and discussed, with a brief review of its numerous extensions. Section 4 surveys the empirical evidence on taxpayer compliance. Section 5 deals with optimal tax enforcement policy, and investigates some possible strategies for combating evasion. Section 6 examines additional policy issues, connected with the institutional and procedural aspects of tax enforcement. Section 7 provides some concluding observations.
2. Definition and Extent of Tax Evasion By distancing effective payments from statutory taxes, tax evasion defines a specific revenue deficiency, known as the ‘tax gap’ (in the US, for example, the federal income tax gap has been estimated at 17 percent). Let us emphasize from the outset that the tax gap is not equal to the amount of additional revenue that would be collected by stricter enforcement, for perfect enforcement would significantly affect the economic scenario (some firms would go bankrupt, taxpayers would modify their labor supply, prices and incomes would change, and so on), so the tax base would surely be altered. As a result, at least in theory, net revenue could even turn out to be smaller. Thus standard measures of tax gaps must be interpreted cautiously. They are only roughly suggestive of the likely immediate effects of marginal improvements in enforcement. Also, one should be wary of the cliché that statutory taxes represent the ideal world and tax gaps an intrinsic evil. This is not only because
54
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
6020
taxes may not be ‘just’, but also because statutory taxes themselves are usually determined by a legislature that is perfectly aware that they will only be partially enforced and therefore differ from those that would be optimal under perfect enforcement. On closer scrutiny, therefore, estimation of the tax gap merely portrays the wedge between economic reality and a purely legal construct called ‘statutory taxes’. Reality and its legal representation may differ for any number of reasons, among which, as we shall see, the willful misrepresentation of tax liabilities is just one. In economic terms, evasion problems originate in the fact that the variables that define the tax base (incomes, sales, revenues, wealth, and so on) are often not ‘observable’. That is, an external observer cannot usually see the actual magnitude of an individual’s tax base, and hence cannot know his true tax liability. Sometimes this knowledge can be obtained by means of costly audits, in which case we say that the tax base is verifiable (at a cost). In other cases, as when it is related to cash payments, the tax base cannot be verified at all. Taxpayers can take advantage of the imperfect information about their liability and elude taxation. A related concept is tax avoidance (or reduction), by which individuals reduce their own tax in a way that may be unintended by tax legislators but is permissible by law. Avoidance is typically accomplished by structuring transactions so as to minimize tax liability. In some cases, avoidance is encouraged by legislation granting favorable tax treatment to specific activities in contrast to general taxation principles. From a legal standpoint, evasion differs from avoidance in being unlawful, and hence punishable (at least in theory). As far as economic function is concerned, however, evasion and avoidance obviously have very strong similarities; sometimes, indeed, they can hardly be distinguished (see for instance Feldman and Kay, 1981; Cowell, 1990; McBarnet, 1992). This adds to the difficulty of interpreting the real implications of the tax gap. Another problem with the measurement of tax evasion relates to its proper delimitation within the broader set of the informal economy. No taxes are generally levied on transactions in the home and criminal sectors, which are usually beyond the reach of authorities and official statistics. Hence, proper determination of the boundaries of evasion is a formidable task, in that evasion is often inextricable from other illegal and unrecorded activities. What, one might ask, is the evaded tax of a hired killer? Aggregate estimates of evasion must deal with all these problems, in addition to the classic problem of lack of direct data. Various estimation methods have been devised, some based on data collected by fiscal authorities, others - less reliable - on data derived from national accounts and surveys. Their application suggests that in the Western industrialized countries evaded
6020
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
55
taxes amount to between 5 percent and 25 percent of potential tax revenue, depending on the technique adopted and the country (see monographs by Feige, 1989; Pyle, 1989, and Thomas, 1992), with higher figures (up to 30-40 percent) for less-developed countries (Tanzi and Shome, 1994). As noted, one should not attach too much importance to such estimates, which essentially tell us that statutory taxes are not the whole story. What matters is effective taxation, that is, the net tax burden on individuals. This has major implications bearing on the economic consequences of evasion: the main question is not how evasion alters the shape of statutory allocation of the fiscal burden, but how it constrains the set of policies that can be implemented. When taxes can be evaded, taxation will prove to be an imperfect tool for pursuing government aims (be they redistribution, efficiency, or whatever), which will be only partly achieved. Indeed, effective taxation may turn regressive, as the more affluent usually have better opportunities to evade (or avoid) taxes. Also, evasion may be powerfully deleterious to horizontal equity, owing to unequal distribution of opportunities to evade and of the willingness to seize them. This in turn may induce production inefficiencies, because competition would be distorted by the unequal distribution of the tax burden among firms. The adverse consequences of tax evasion are sometimes exacerbated by laws, or even constitutions, drafted as if the tax base were observable, limiting the set of corrective instruments available to the government (which cannot, for instance, set tax rates according to their presumed degree of enforceability). In order to evaluate the way in which noncompliance affects the actual tax payment of individuals, one must examine taxpayers’ compliance behavior more closely. This can be done by developing a theoretical model to predict how taxpayers’ behavior is affected by the relevant variables. The following section reviews some models and assesses their fit with observed practise.
3. The Decision to Evade Compliance with the tax law typically means: (i) true reporting of the tax base, (ii) correct computation of the liability, (iii) timely filing of the return, and (iv) timely payment of the amounts due. The bulk of tax evasion involves the first point. Most evaders either do not declare their liability at all, or declare it only in part. In the following, we concentrate on the problem faced by an individual who has to decide how much of his tax aggregate to report, or whether to report it at all. The focus is on income taxes (which account for a large part of fiscal revenue in most countries). However, the insights provided can be applied to other taxes as well.
56
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
6020
3.1 Allingham and Sandmo A useful model of taxpayers’ evasion decision is that developed by Allingham and Sandmo ([1972] 1991) and Srinivasan (1973), and revised by Yitzhaki (1974). Evasion is viewed as a portfolio allocation problem: the taxpayer must decide what portion of his income y (postulated as exogenous) to invest in the risky activity labeled ‘tax evasion’. If the taxpayer does not want to take any risk, he reports his income in full; otherwise, he reports only a fraction of it and bears the risk of being caught and fined. The problem is thus to choose the optimal tax return, when the income reported is taxed at a fixed rate t and evasion is fined at a penalty rate f proportional to the tax evaded. The probability of an audit, that is, the probability that the true income level will be discovered, is a constant denoted by a. The taxpayer decides the amount to conceal so as to maximize his expected utility from net income. If we call yNA the net income when the evader is not audited (gross income less taxes on reported income) and yA the net income when he is audited (gross income less taxes on true income less the fine), we can write the taxpayer’s expected utility as EU(e) = (1!a) u(yNA) + a u(yA) = (1!a) u[y!t(y!e)] + a u(y!ty!fte), where e denotes the amount of income concealed. This representation yields some interesting results from the standpoint of comparative statics. On the reasonable assumption that the taxpayer is risk averse, it can be shown that the amount of tax evaded, te* , varies inversely with the audit rate a and the penalty rate f, while it depends negatively on the tax rate t and positively on income y if and only if the taxpayer’s utility function displays Decreasing Absolute Risk Aversion. Further, the proportion of tax evaded, te*/y, increases with income if and only if taxpayer’s utility function displays Decreasing Relative Risk Aversion (see Cowell, 1990). Of these results, the least obvious is surely the inverse correlation between the amount of evasion and the tax rate (with DARA). This stems from the fact that both the direct gain from evasion (taxes saved) and the expected fine depend proportionally on t. Hence, an increase in the tax rate does not induce the ‘substitution’ of the risky asset for the safe one, but operates solely through the reduction in disposable income (Yitzhaki, 1974). Once the optimal amount of underreporting, e*, has been calculated, one can easily derive the ‘evasion rent’, defined as the monetary benefit accruing to the evader (more precisely, the amount of income that he would be willing to pay to switch from a virtual system of perfect enforcement to the actual, imperfect, one): Evasion rent = [1 ! a(1 + f )]te* ! RP(e*), where RP(e*) is the risk premium associated with the audit lottery. The evasion rent is therefore equal to the net return on evasion (evaded taxes less expected sanctions) less the ‘loss’ due to the riskiness associated with random auditing
6020
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
57
(note, incidentally, that if taxpayers were risk-lovers, the risk premium would effectively represent a ‘gain’). Several observations are in order. First, for evasion rent to be positive, the net return on evasion has to be positive (the evasion gamble needs to be ‘better than fair’). That is, for evasion to occur at all, it is necessary that a(1 + f ) < 1; that is, the penalty and audit rates must be sufficiently low. Second, when the net return on evasion is positive, the only reason why taxpayers may not evade their whole taxes is the fear of uncertainty (the risk premium loss). Indeed, if taxpayers were infinitely averse to risk, they would report their income in full even if the net return on evasion were positive (taxpayers are hyper-pessimists and behave as if they were to be audited for sure). Finally, the risk premium produces a differential between the rent to the taxpayer and the net revenue loss to the tax authorities. Hence, it provides a monetary measure of the ‘deadweight loss’ due to the randomness of tax enforcement (Yitzhaki, 1987). 3.2 Extensions This basic model gives an account of taxpayers’ evasion decisions in a very simple set-up: taxes and penalties are proportional, the audit rate is constant, only one form of evasion is available. In addition, the taxpayer is assumed to rely on expected utility theory and to be perfectly amoral, that is, to make compliance decisions with exclusive reference to the consequences for net income. All these assumptions are open to criticism, and models based on alternative assumptions have been developed. The following touches briefly on these contributions. One standard criticism of the Allingham and Sandmo model is grounded in the belief that compliance decisions depend on moral views. This is clearly a problematic issue, one that cannot be captured by the consequentialistic set-up of standard decision theory. Bordignon (1993) makes an interesting attempt to account for non-self-motivated decisions in tax evasion. He develops a compliance model in which taxpayers are guided by suitably defined ‘Kantian principles’, which determine the amount that each taxpayer considers fair to pay. Under this assumption, it turns out that tax evasion is generally lower than under selfish behavior, that compliance depends on the level of public expenditure, and that evasion is likely to increase with tax rates. Other authors have stressed the ‘social’ factors at the basis of the taxpayers’ decision (see Roth, Scholtz and Witt, 1989, for an excellent account of the sociological research). Economists have emphasized the ‘stigma’ attached to the violation of social norms and shown that tax evasion may have strong spillover effects. Social stigma is likely to give rise to a multiplicity of possible equilibria: when most people evade, the stigma effect is small and evasion is not in fact discouraged; when few evade, the stigma effect is great and evasion is discouraged. The transition from one equilibrium to the other takes the form of a ‘noncompliance epidemic’: if, for some reason, more people start to evade,
58
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
6020
the stigma decreases and evasion spreads to an ever larger fraction of the population (see Benjamini and Maital, 1985; Gordon, 1989, and Myles and Naylor, 1996). Alm and McCallin (1990), Landskroner, Paroush and Swary (1990), Yaniv (1990), and Wrede (1995) have extended Allingham and Sandmo with models in which taxpayers face more complex ‘portfolio’ set-ups offering other risky activities and alternative forms of evasion. Wadhawan (1992) posits that audits detect only a fraction of taxpayers’ evasion, while Das-Gupta (1994) analyses the case in which taxpayers’ income derives from a multiplicity of transactions. Scotchmer and Slemrod (1989) and Scotchmer (1989) consider the effect of randomness in tax liability assessments. Among other things, both papers conclude that uncertainty over the true liability level or outcome of the audit increases net tax revenue, either because increased uncertainty makes evasion more costly (when taxpayers are risk averse) or because it may lead taxpayers to underreport their income and be subject to a fine (whereas overreporting only yields a rebate of the overpaid tax). Several authors have tried to extend Allingham and Sandmo’s model to include the labor supply decision, so as to endogenize taxpayers’ gross income (see, among others, Andersen, 1977; Pencavel, 1979; Isachsen and Strom, 1980; Isachsen, Samuelsen and Strom, 1985, and Cowell, 1985). The problem is that as soon as the labor decision is factored in, the simple comparative statics of Allingham and Sandmo are lost. Depending on the taxpayer’s marginal disutility from labor and her risk-attitudes, all predictions become possible. This problem is usually overcome by imposing strong restrictions on the utility function. Cowell (1985) takes a different course, assuming that decisions are made in two separate stages: first, the taxpayer decides how many hours to work; then he allocates this total labor supply between legal and illegal activities (alternatively, between reported and unreported income). On this assumption, Cowell is able to show that Allingham and Sandmo’s results carry over (with some qualifications) to the extended set-up if taxpayer’s labor supply is forward rising. Perhaps more importantly, he shows that the comparative statics results are strictly dependent on the nature of the evasion choice, as it can be tied either to the amount of income to report (for the self-employed) or to the amount of time to spend in ‘off the books’ activities (for the moonlighter). The insights drawn from analysis of income tax evasion usually apply to other forms of evasion as well. Different considerations may be relevant, however, when the taxpayer is a firm subject to indirect taxation, as the evasion decision may affect output or pricing policy (tax shifting). However, Marrelli (1984) derives a separability result for the case of a monopolist: the evasion and shifting decisions are independent of one another as long as the audit probability is constant (see also Yaniv, 1995). The same result applies to oligopolistic markets when firms compete à la Cournot (Marrelli and Martina,
6020
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
59
1988). Here, the amount of evasion by each firm is shown to depend, apart from the enforcement parameters, on the degree of collusion and on market shares. Gordon (1990) offers an interesting insight on sales tax evasion. He suggests that under-the-counter cash sales may serve as a means of price discrimination: cash discounts are the best pricing strategy when the demand for cash purchases is highly elastic. The author also shows that, in order to reduce cash sales, a liability on detected cash customers could be imposed, but on the condition that this is an additional liability, and not just a transfer of a part of the supplier’s existing liability onto the consumer. As is clear from the foregoing, taxpayer noncompliance decisions may be very complex and are likely to be powerfully affected by the practical framework in which decisions are made. This thesis is strongly supported by the empirical evidence, which we now briefly review.
4. Empirical Evidence on Taxpayers’ Behavior Evidence on taxpayers’ behavior is notoriously difficult to come by. Data on the extent of evasion may be confidential (not available for external analysis) or not completely reliable (such as those derived from national accounting sources). All the same, empirical studies on the determinants of taxpayers’ compliance decisions have proliferated. The most detailed are based on the American Taxpayer Compliance Measurement Program (TCMP), conducted regularly by the IRS and based on a ‘line by line’ audit of a sample of 45,000 to 55,000 tax returns. In addition to statistical estimates, major insights on the dynamics of compliance have been obtained from questionnaires and experimentation. In his pioneering analysis, Clotfelter (1983) uses TCMP data for 1969 to investigate the determinants of underreporting, which is defined as the difference between the income reported and that assessed by IRS examiners. He finds that both the marginal tax rate and after-tax income have significant effects on individual underreporting. In contrast to Allingham and Sandmo’s prediction, he finds that elasticities with respect to marginal tax rates are positive and range from 0.5 for non-farm business to 0.8 for non-business returns. In line with Allingham and Sandmo, elasticities with respect to after-tax income are positive and range from 0.3 for non-business returns to 0.65 for farm returns. Also, wages, interest and dividends are associated with better compliance and underreporting is higher for the youngest age-groups. Witte and Woodbury (1985) also analyze data from the TCMP for 1969, but focus on the effect of enforcement parameters. They find that the percentage of underreporting is related inversely to the probability of audit (with a lagged effect), and directly to the ‘opportunities’ for tax evasion (absence of withholding and information reporting) and to income, though in a decreasing
60
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
6020
way. Dubin and Wilde (1988) criticize Witte and Woodbury’s results and highlight the potential endogeneity of audit rates. The idea is that audit rates are decided by the IRS in view of their potential yield: a decrease in noncompliance rates reduces the net return from auditing and leads the IRS to devote less effort to auditing. Using the IRS budget per return as an instrumental variable for the audit rates, they find the audit rate to be endogenous in 5 out of 7 audit classes. They also find that audits have a deterrent effect on evasion, and that noncompliance is positively related to the unemployment rate and the nonwhite fraction of the population. Feinstein (1991) uses a sophisticated estimation technique, which allows for partial detection by IRS examiners. His results confirm the great unevenness in compliance attitudes between groups of taxpayers, with ‘own business’ and ‘farm’ filers scoring the lowest compliance rates. Using TCMP data for 1982 and 1985, Feinstein more easily disentangles the effects of marginal tax rates and gross income (taxpayers with identical incomes filing in different years face different marginal tax rates). He finds that the effect of marginal tax rates on evasion is negative and highly significant, while the effect of income is essentially zero. The former finding is consistent with Allingham and Sandmo’s predictions, while the latter is not. Another finding is that greater propensity to evade is accompanied by a higher detection rate (thanks to greater IRS examination effort). Studies based on IRS data provide a picture of the compliance phenomenon in which many factors come into play: income source, socioeconomic grouping (age, sex, location), detection probability, marginal tax rate and income level. Notably, the severity of the sanction does not seem to play a significant role (partly because in the US sanctions are rarely inflicted). Estimates based on IRS data, however, are subject to several weaknesses. First, by definition, TCMP programs relate to filers only, whereas in 1976, for example, strategic non-filers accounted for an estimated 36 percent of all unreported income. In addition, it is well known that IRS examiners have only limited capacity to detect evasion, especially on income from moonlighting and cash-only businesses. Finally, strong assumptions underlie the choice of instruments and variables as exogenous regressors. Another important source of information about taxpayers’ attitudes is surveys. Much work has been done in this area, and results cannot be easily generalized (see, among others, Vogel, 1974; Spicer and Lundstedt, 1976; Lewis, 1979; Westat, 1980; Scott and Grasmick, 1981; Mason and Calvin, 1984; Yankelovich, Skelly and White, 1984; Kinsey, 1992; Sheffrin and Triest, 1992; and de Juan, Lasheras and Mayo, 1994). On the whole, though, these studies would support the deterrence hypothesis. Specifically, the following factors have been found to be significant determinants of tax compliance: (1) the perceived probability of detection; (2) the severity of informal sanctions; (3) moral beliefs about tax compliance; (4) experience with other noncompliers and
6020
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
61
past experience with IRS enforcement (both encouraging evasion), and, (5) demographic characteristics (older people seem to be more compliant) (Klepper and Nagin, 1989). These results are largely concordant with those based on TCMP data. The main additional insight they provide lies in the importance of sociological factors, which can hardly be detected by other means. Survey studies face several problems, however. First, results depend crucially on the representativeness of the sample, which is often difficult to assess. Second, respondents are reluctant to report acts of noncompliance (see, for instance, Elffers, Weigel and Hessing, 1987). Third, causal relationships are difficult to establish. The finding that respondents who perceive the highest probability of detection are most compliant, for instance, is consistent both with the standard ‘deterrence hypothesis’ and with the ‘experiential hypothesis’ whereby taxpayers initially overestimate detection probabilities and evaders later lower their estimates if they are not detected (Saltzman et al., 1982). Finally, individuals often seek to provide a consistent image of themselves, offering ad hoc rationalizations for their behavior (Elffers, Weigel and Hessing, 1987). A third, increasingly widespread empirical approach is based on ‘laboratory’ experiments (see, for instance, Baldry, 1987); Webley et al., 1991; Alm, Cronshaw and McKee, 1993; Alm, Jackson, and McKee, 1993; and Alm, Sanchez and de Juan, 1995). Individuals (often students) are asked to participate in games simulating tax compliance, where they can underreport and incur the risk of a penalty. At the end, they receive a real reward proportional to their laboratory performance. The results tend to be very sensitive to the particular design of the experiment. In general, this research suggest that audit rates may play an important role in compliance decisions (especially for those who have already been audited), and that compliance is an increasing function of income and a decreasing function of the tax rate, while it is hardly affected by the size of fines (unless the audit rate is very high). These experiments also suggest that social norms and ethical attitudes play an important part in evasion choices, that individuals often take an all-or-nothing stance, that they tend to overweight low probabilities, and that the structure of the taxes is important (Baldry, 1987). While the empirical research is far from conclusive, it does appear to support the hypothesis that expected punishment (that is, the size of sanctions discounted by the probability of incurring them) is relevant. Sociological and ethical factors surely play an important role too, although their effect is subtler and harder to measure. This suggests that standard enforcement polices based on apprehension and punishment should not be abandoned. They could be supplemented by alternative approaches, seeking to appeal to taxpayers’ moral conscience or to reinforce social cohesion. The following section treats the question of optimal design of tax enforcement policy, focusing on detection and punishment of evaders.
62
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
6020
5. Evasion and Enforcement Let us go back to the model of Allingham and Sandmo. While it provides a fairly sophisticated description of taxpayers’ evasion decisions, it leaves very little scope for enforcement policy. The latter is essentially reduced to two parameters: the penalty rate and the audit rate. The main policy prescription implicit in the model and most of its variants is that, in order to curb evasion, audits have to be stepped up and fines increased. And given that raising the audit rate is likely to require public resources while an increase in the penalty rate is not, the end result is likely to be one with Draconian but rare punishment, a rule such as ‘hang evaders with probability (close to) zero’. This is a difficult prescription to elude. But in fact it is not clear whether curbing or eliminating evasion is always a desirable goal. In general terms, the desirability of perfect enforcement is tied to the ‘goodness’ of the tax to be enforced. For instance, when perfect enforcement of income tax would result in the collapse of the taxed activity, one may well ask whether such unbearable burden represents the right policy. Even if perfect enforcement were theoretically beneficial, however, it would not be likely to be cost free, as suggested by the Draconian rule. For instance, when adjudication is not perfect and innocent individuals can be convicted, infinite sanctions may entail very high welfare costs. Also, when individuals may engage in activities to avoid conviction, the social cost of enforcement may increase with the penalty (Malik, 1990)). From a practical point of view, the major impediment to infinite fines derives from taxpayers’ limited wealth. Since convicted evaders cannot be forced to labor, they will be able to foot a penalty at most as great as their own wealth. The Draconian rule thus needs to be rephrased as follows: when strict enforcement is desirable, the optimal penalty is that which expropriates the taxpayer of all his wealth. Enforcement policies, however, can be much more sophisticated than the combination of two variables, the penalty and the audit rate. The audit probability itself, for instance, need not be the same for all taxpayers. Indeed, a simple way of making audit strategy more effective is to base it on information specific to the taxpayer, which may include any observable characteristic correlated with real tax liability, from compliance records to consumption patterns. Clearly, the relation of an individual’s reported tax liability to the average for similar taxpayers may then become the key to singling out candidates for auditing. In an important article, Reinganum and Wilde (1985) prove that by making audits conditional on the level of reported liability, the enforcer can increase net revenue. They analyze a simple cut-off rule, whereby an audit is triggered if and only if reported income is ‘too low’. They show that this rule dominates the
6020
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
63
random audit rule considered by Allingham and Sandmo, and that it is the most economical way to foster truthful reporting when taxpayers are risk neutral and taxes and fines are lump sum. Scotchmer (1987) and Sanchez and Sobel (1993) extend this result, proving that the cut-off audit rule is the optimal policy for a net revenue-maximizing enforcer when taxes and fines are proportional and taxpayers are risk-neutral. These findings prompt the following observations. First, cost-efficient enforcement requires that audits be used primarily as a deterrent rather than as a means to collect fines. Their function is to foster correct self-reporting by individuals. Indeed, under the optimal policy audits will be performed only on people who are found (ex-post) to be honest - hence no fines will ever be collected. Second, the optimal cut-off level is strictly dependent on the distribution of income among the population: effective auditing requires reliable information on taxpayers’ expected liability. Finally, optimal enforcement is likely to induce a strong regressive bias, as it provides high-income taxpayers with better chances to evade than low-income taxpayers. The idea is that high-income individuals have greater opportunities to misreport, and since it is more costly to dissuade them from evading, one should let them off the hook (on this, see also Scotchmer, 1992). This problem may be alleviated by shaping audit policy according to indexes correlated with true income (Scotchmer, 1987) and, to a lesser extent, by suitably adjusting the tax rate (Cremer, Marchand and Pestieau, 1990). These considerations indicate that simple models in the Allingham and Sandmo mold are not adequate to the problematic issues underlying the design of an effective enforcement policy. The matter becomes still more complex when one considers the interrelation between optimal enforcement and optimal taxation. Border and Sobel (1987), Mookherjee and Png (1989), Marhuenda and Ortuno-Ortin (1994), Hindriks (1994), and Chander and Wilde (1998) address the simultaneous definition of the optimal audit and tax schedules, assuming that taxpayers are subject to limited liability and risk neutral, and that the enforcer seeks to maximize net tax revenue. The main finding of this literature is that, at the optimum, effective taxation is regressive and the audit function is non-increasing in reported income. Hence, the repercussions of noncompliance for effective taxation indicated by Scotchmer (1987) and Sanchez and Sobel (1993) carry over to this more general set-up. An interesting insight (Border and Sobel, 1987) is that when sanctions are upper-bounded and taxpayers are risk neutral, it is optimal to audit taxpayers with a very small probability and to provide infinite rewards for truthful reporting. The so-called ‘principal-agent’ approach to enforcement discussed in the foregoing paragraphs constitutes one of the most general frameworks for analyzing tax evasion and its relation to public policy. The main pitfall is its extremely demanding assumptions concerning the enforcer’s ability to devise
64
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
6020
and execute the optimal policy. Indeed, one may argue that actual tax enforcers do not always possess the features that would qualify them as ‘rational’. Like other branches of the public administration, they often have conflicting or ill-defined incentives, they may be governed by ‘process’- rather than ‘outcome’-oriented rules, and they are likely to have short-sighted and perhaps multiple goals. This suggests that the enforcer may tend to act myopically and just ‘react’ to impulses from the economic system. Thus the enforcer may decide auditing policy taking the amount of evasion in the economy as given and aiming to maximize detection, disregarding deterrence. This view, based on the assumption that the tax enforcer cannot credibly precommit to any specific auditing policy, is forcefully advanced by Graetz, Reinganum and Wilde (1986) and Reinganum and Wilde (1991). Their argument is that since actual audit rates are not observed by taxpayers, the enforcer has an incentive to relax any announced auditing policy once taxpayers have reported their incomes, that is, after the policy has performed its deterrent effect. Since taxpayers will anticipate the enforcer’s ex-post deviation, they will not rely on the announced policy and will engage in greater evasion. The bottom line is that, in equilibrium, audits will be performed on likely evaders rather than on compliant (that is, deterred) taxpayers. This would appear to be a most reasonable prediction, and it tallies with actual enforcement practices. The comparative statics of the no-commitment model differ in nature from those of commitment models. With no-commitment, the evasion rate and the audit rate are determined simultaneously, whereas under commitment the audit rate determines the evasion rate. Consider, for instance, the effect of an increase in the audit cost. In the no-commitment model, evaders will evade more because they know that, ceteris paribus, the enforcer will react less harshly (due to the higher enforcement costs). The higher evasion rate, however, rises the net return from auditing and restores the enforcer’s incentive to exert effort. In equilibrium, the evasion rate will increase and the audit rate will not decrease. In the models with commitment, an increase in the audit cost means that audits become a more expensive deterrent tool. The enforcer will hence use them more parsimoniously and evasion rate will increase. In contrast to the no-commitment model, the equilibrium audit rate will decrease. The two types of model provide different insights on tax enforcement. ‘Principal-agent’ models (with commitment) are probably best used to define the constraints that tax evasion puts on the effective tax system. They neatly define the set of implementable allocations on the assumption that the enforcer performs at maximum capacity. The ‘no-commitment’ approach, with a lower profile, aims at capturing a version of tax enforcement closer to actual practice. On the whole, however, these models still provide a very ‘stylized’ view of enforcement practice. They focus on just two enforcement tools, that is, the
6020
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
65
penalty and the audit probabilities, and ignore most of the institutional features of real enforcement.
6. Procedures and Institutions It is clear by now that real compliance decisions are much more complex than those depicted by standard economic models, in that taxpayers are subject to a wide variety of sociological and ethical factors. Nor is even the effect of enforcement policy itself fully captured by standard models. Real enforcement is unquestionably more than a mere combination of penalty and audit probabilities (regardless of how sophisticated these can be made). The process that leads from the checking of tax returns to the conviction of evaders is lengthy and complex, perhaps involving various bodies (tax administration, tax courts) and procedures (interviews, cross-examinations, settlements, and so on). The shape of the prosecution process affects taxpayers’ attitudes towards compliance in two ways. First, it determines the actual probability that a sanction will be imposed on evaders and, possibly, innocent taxpayers; and second, it may affect the degree of ‘hostility’ in the taxpayer’s perception of the tax system. In a word, institutional and procedural features matter. They impose costs on taxpayers and affect the outcome of the prosecution process. We will touch briefly on some of these aspects, starting with the costs. According to a number of studies, the cost to the taxpayer of compliance with the most common taxes (income and VAT) in industrialized countries can be as high as 10-13 percent of the total tax liability (see the pioneering contribution of Sandford, 1973, as well as Sanford et al., 1981; Slemrod, 1989; Pitt and Slemrod ,1989; Sandford, Goodwin, and Hardwick, 1989; Blumenthal and Slemrod, 1992, and Sandford, 1995a). High compliance costs, which may be due to complex tax schedules and rules, not only tilt the ‘cost-benefit analysis’ towards evasion, but may also generate resentment, weakening taxpayers’ moral conscience or even prompting them to evade as a form of ‘punishment’ for the tax administration. Legislatures should accordingly avoid the vicious circle of countering evasion by increasing the complexity of tax regulations, which raises compliance costs and fosters further evasion. When the tax legislation is very complex, taxpayers usually have to turn to tax experts (CPAs or tax preparers), who have great power to influence their clients’ attitudes towards evasion, thanks to their superior knowledge of enforcement patterns. An interesting empirical study by Klepper and Nagin (1989b) on the United States suggests that tax preparers encourage compliance with regard to unequivocal items, and discourage it with regard to ambiguous ones. (Other investigations of this issue can be found in Scotchmer, 1989; Reinganum and Wilde, 1991; Erard, 1993, and Franzoni, 1998a.)
66
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
6020
Costs are also entailed in mandatory record-keeping and reporting, whose role is to increase the visibility of offenses, that is, the ‘frequency and ease with which they come to the attention of and can be proved by enforcement officials’ (Kagan, 1989). As noted in Section 3, noncompliance varies greatly with economic grouping, as tax violation by different groups has different degrees of ‘visibility’. Unsurprisingly, therefore, evasion is apparently most common among independent contractors, professionals, and farmers. Conversely, compliance is highest among payroll employees subject to withholding. In a technical sense, higher visibility makes it easier both to ‘observe’ the real situation or behavior of the taxpayer (by signaling potential violations) and to ‘verify’ it (prove it in court). Some forms of mandatory record-keeping, for example, serve a legal evidentiary function, implying a de facto shift in the burden of proof. It is the taxpayer who has to prove his compliance with the law, and bear the costs thereof. The question of the optimal amount of compliance duties to impose on taxpayers is therefore bound up with the optimal allocation of the burden of proof. Generally, the efficient allocation is that which places the onus of the proof on the party for which it is least costly (given its level of informativeness). Another important factor in the ‘visibility’ of tax law violations is the standard of proof. Indeed, the difference between the ‘observability’ and the ‘verifiability’ of the tax base is precisely defined by the type of evidence that is necessary to asses it legally (and possibly prove that the original payments were not correct). In most countries, tax authorities have the power to estimate taxpayer’s liability by discretionary means when the information supplied by the taxpayer is deemed insufficient or clearly incorrect (OECD, 1990). Clearly, under these circumstances the standard of proof can be rather lax, and the use of mere statistical evidence can be used to prove taxpayers’ obligations. Presumptive taxation is a case in which statistical estimates and proxies are used ab origine to define the tax obligation, resulting in the automatic visibility of the activities covered and imposing virtually no compliance costs on taxpayers (see Tanzi, 1991). Note that simplifications and reductions in compliance costs will ordinarily be achieved only at the expense of reduced ability to discriminate among taxpayers (for purposes of either vertical or horizontal equity). As is pointed out by Kaplow (1996), a trade-off is likely to arise between containing compliance costs and accuracy in liability assessment. On the procedural side, another important consideration is the possibility of resolving disputes through amicable settlements between taxpayers and the administration. In most countries, taxpayers can make a ‘deal’ with inspectors and obtain substantial penalty discounts in exchange for collaboration (OECD, 1990). When deals are left to the discretion of the revenue service, enforcement is likely to be adversely affected. Discretionary deals not only reduce the administration’s ability to precommit itself to any specific enforcement policy
6020
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
67
but may also foster opportunism, tempting the administration to increase its inefficiencies (for example, lengthy and invasive prosecution procedures) so as to increase its ‘take’ at the settlement stage (Franzoni, 1995). Tax amnesties, though sharing some of these problems, may prove desirable, as they offer taxpayers social insurance against unexpected shocks, allowing them to complete their payments after uncertainty (about their income or their true preferences) has been resolved (Andreoni, 1991; Malik and Schwab, 1991). A fundamental problem in considering the optimal institutional design of tax enforcement relates to incentives for enforcers. More fundamentally, the question is whether enforcement should be the job of public or private agents. First raised in general terms by Becker and Stigler (1974), the issue has been examined in the specific context of tax evasion by several authors. While in most countries taxes are collected by a public agency, in a few cases (as with import duties in Indonesia) collection is delegated to private contractors. Melumad and Mookherjee (1989) show that delegation of tax enforcement to a private party may be viable (that is, it can replicate the full-commitment solution) if it is backed by an incentive scheme based on publicly observable aggregate variables (audit expenditure, taxes filed and fines collected). This scheme rewards the agent for collecting fines, or, when no fine is collected, for meeting the target audit budget. Toma and Toma (1992) observe that different institutional arrangements may entail different agency costs so that depending on their incidence either public or private enforcement may be desirable. A key agency cost is that associated with the danger of corruption. Since the personal aim of enforcement officers may not correspond to institutional purposes, there is scope for collusion with taxpayers. This seriously complicates the analysis, as a third constraint (no collusion) must now be taken into account. For while it may be contended that combating corruption can help control tax evasion, it may well be that anti-evasion measures as such ultimately just increase the scope and the extent of corruption (see Chu, 1990a; Chander and Wilde, 1992a; Besley and McLaren, 1993; Mookherjee and Png, 1995; Flatters and McLoad, 1995; Hindriks, Keen and Muthoo, 1996). This confirms that the institutional features of the enforcement system represent a point of fundamental importance. These features define the incentive structure governing the conduct of enforcers and crucially affect the actual functioning of all enforcement tools.
7. Conclusions The foregoing offers an analytical framework for treating some salient aspects of tax noncompliance, suggesting causes and possible remedies. As must be clear by now, tax evasion is a complex phenomenon that cannot be eradicated by marginal changes in enforcement practice. Social and moral attitudes, which
68
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
6020
play a very important role, are very slow to change and are often beyond the reach of public policy. Standard enforcement therefore remains crucial. The empirical evidence suggests that a stricter enforcement regime is likely to induce greater compliance; the key variable here is the probability of detection. To date, most studies in this field have focused on two enforcement tools: penalty rates and auditing probabilities. Much work remains to be done to ascertain the impact on compliance of less striking but nonetheless important procedural and institutional factors. Actually, closer examination of institutional reality suggests that the audit rate may not be the relevant variable. What really matters is the probability that an investigation will eventually result in conviction and sanction for the wrongdoer. Here a host of additional factors come into play: whether evasion leaves detectable traces, the specific ability and expertise of the auditors, the set of investigative tools at their disposal (for example, the degree of banking secrecy), the possibility of inducing taxpayer collaboration, the feasibility of out-of-court settlements, the standard of proof, the definition of ‘fault’, the clarity of the tax law, the number of levels of appeal, and so on. Research into the impact that these procedural aspects have on taxpayer compliance is still in its infancy. Better integration of the research on tax evasion with the ‘law and economics’ analysis of legal rules is definitely desirable. As theoretical analysis proceeds, additional empirical work will be needed together with more extensive study of comparative tax enforcement law and procedure.
Bibliography on Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance (6020) Aaron, Henry J. and Munnell, Alicia H. (1992), ‘Reassessing the Role for Wealth Transfer Taxes’, 45(3) National Tax Journal, 119-143. Agapitos, George and Mavraganis, George (1995), ‘Tax Evasion: The Case of Greece: Greece’, 49 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 569-576. Al Zakari, Ibrahim A. (1994), Corporate Tax Compliance: A Case Study of Saudi Arabia, University of New Mexico, Ph.D. Alexeev, Michael V., Gaddy, Clifford and Leitzel, Jim (1995), ‘Economic Crime and Russian Reform’, 151 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 677-692. Alford, Robert R. and Feige, Edgar L. (1989), ‘Information Distortions in Social Systems: The Underground Economy and Other Observer-Subject-Policymaker Feedbacks’, in Feige, Edgar L. (ed.), The Underground Economies: Tax Evasion and Information Distortion, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 57-79. Allingham, Michael G. and Sandmo, Agnar ([1972] 1991), ‘Income Tax Evasion: A Theoretical Analysis’, in Atkinson, A.B. (ed.), Modern Public Finance. Volume 1, Aldershot, Edward Elgar, 50-65. Alm, James (1988), ‘Compliance Costs and the Tax Avoidance-Tax Evasion Decision’, 16 Public Finance Quarterly, 31-66.
6020
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
69
Alm, James (1991), ‘A Perspective on the Experimental Analysis of Taxpayer Reporting’, 66(3) Accounting Review, 577-593. Alm, James and Beck, William (1991), ‘Wiping the Slate Clean: Individual Response to State Tax Amnesties’, 57 Southern Economic Journal, 1043-1053. Alm, James and Beck, William (1993), ‘Tax Amnesties and Compliance in the Long Run: A Time Series Analysis’, 46 National Tax Journal, 53-60. Alm, James and McCallin, Nancy J. (1990), ‘Tax Avoidance and Tax Evasion as a Joint Portfolio Choice’, 45 Public Finance, 193-200. Alm, James, Bahl, Roy and Murray, Matthew N. (1990), ‘Tax Structure and Tax Compliance’, 72 Review of Economics and Statistics, 603-613. Alm, James, Bahl, Roy and Murray, Matthew N. (1991a), ‘Income Tax Evasion’, in Bahl, Roy (ed.), The Jamaican Tax Reform, Cambridge, MA, Lincoln Institute of Land Policy, 181-214. Alm, James, Bahl, Roy and Murray, Matthew N. (1991b), ‘Tax Base Erosion in Developing Countries’, 39 Economic Development and Cultural Change, 849-872. Alm, James, Bahl, Roy and Murray, Matthew N. (1993), ‘Audit Selection and Income Tax Underreporting in the Tax Compliance Game’, 42(1) Journal of Development Economics, 1-33. Alm, James, Cronshaw, Mark B. and McKee, Michael (1993), ‘Tax Compliance with Endogenous Audit Selection Rules’, 46 Kyklos, 27-45. Alm, James, Jackson, Betty R. and McKee, Michael (1992a), ‘Institutional Uncertainty and Taxpayer Compliance’, 82 American Economic Review, 1018-1026. Alm, James, Jackson, Betty R. and McKee, Michael (1992b), ‘Deterrence and Beyond: Toward a Kinder, Gentler IRS’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 311-329. Alm, James, Jackson, Betty R. and McKee, Michael (1992c), ‘Estimating the Determinants of Taxpayer Compliance with Experimental Data’, 45 National Tax Journal, 107-114. Alm, James, Jackson, Betty R. and McKee, Michael (1993), ‘Fiscal Exchange, Collective Decision Institutions, and Tax Compliance’, 22 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 285-303. Alm, James, McClelland, Gary H. and Schulze, William D. (1992), ‘Why Do People Pay Taxes?’, 48 Journal of Public Economics, 21-38. Alm, James, Sanchez, Isabel and de Juan, Ana (1995), ‘Economic and Noneconomic Factors in Tax Compliance’, 48 Kyklos, 3-18. Altshuler, Rosanne and Fulghieri, Paolo (1992), Dynamic Effects of Foreign Tax Credits on Multinational Corporations, Columbia University Department of Economics Discussion Paper, No. 611. Altshuler, Rosanne and Newlon, T. Scott (1991), The Effects of U.S. Tax Policy on the Income Repatriation Patterns of U.S. Multinational Corporations, National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper, No. 3925. Andersen, Per (1977), ‘Tax Evasion and Labor Supply’, 79 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 375-383. Andjelkovic Mileva (1995), ‘Koncept Zloupotrebe Prava u Poreskoj Materiji (Concept of Abuse of Law in Fiscal Matters)’, 5-6 Finansije, 269-277. Andreoni, James (1991), ‘The Desirability of a Permanent Tax Amnesty’, 45 Journal of Public Economics, 143-160.
70
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
6020
Andreoni, James (1992), ‘IRS as Loan Shark: Tax Compliance with Borrowing Constraints’, 49(3) Journal of Public Economics, 35-46. Andreoni, James, Erard, Brian and Feinstein, Jonathan S. (1996), Tax Compliance, University of Wisconsin Working Paper, No. 9610. Andreoni, James, Erard, Brian and Feinstein, Jonathan S. (1998), ‘Tax Compliance’, Journal of Economic Literature, forthcoming. Antonides, Gerrit and Robben, Henry S.J. (1995), ‘True Positives and False Alarms in the Detection of Tax Evasion’, 16 Journal of Economic Psychology, 617-640. Asorey, Ruben O. (1991), ‘Transfer Pricing and the New Criminal Tax Law: Argentina’, 45 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 74-75. Baldry, Jonathan C. (1987), ‘Income Tax Evasion and the Tax Schedule: Some Experimental Results’, 42 Public Finance, 357-383. Baldry, Jonathan C. (1994), ‘Economic Analysis and Taxpayer Compliance: Time for a New Agenda’, 11 Australian Tax Forum, 45-62. Banerji, Arup (1991), Tax Evasion Enforcement and Intertemporal Choice, University of Pennsylvania, Ph.D. Bardsley, Peter (1994), ‘Tax Compliance Research: An Economic Perspective on the Research Agenda’, 11 Australian Tax Forum, 271-290. Barthelemy, Philippe (1989), ‘The Underground Economy in France’, in Feige, Edgar L. (ed.), The Underground Economies: Tax Evasion and Information Distortion, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 281-294. Batina, Raymond G. (1992), ‘Time-Consistent Income Taxation’, 32 Quarterly Review of Economics and Finance, 68-81. Bayar, Ali and Frank, Max (1987), ‘The Erosion of the Different Tax Bases’, 42 Public Finance, 341-356. Bazzoni, Stefania and Mori, Antonella (1994), ‘Politiche Fiscali e Crescita Endogena in un’Economia con un Settore Informale (Fiscal Policy and Endogenous Growth in an Economy with an Informal Sector)’, 53 Giornale degli Economisti e Annali di Economia, 219-234. Beams, Mark K. (1992), ‘Obtaining Relief through Competent Authority Procedures and Treaty Exchange of Tax Information: The U.S. Approach’, 46 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 119-122. Beaumont, Marion S. (1991), ‘Proposition 13 Winners and Losers: Were First-Time Home Buyers Affected Adversely?’, in Stocker, Frederick D. (ed.), Proposition 13: A Ten Year Retrospective, Cambridge, MA, Lincoln Institute of Land Policy, 135-173. Becker, G. (1968), ‘Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach’, 76 Journal of Political Economy, 169-217. Becker, G. and Stigler, G. (1974), ‘Law Enforcement, Malfeasance, and Compensation of Enforcers, 3 Journal of Legal Studies, 1 ff. Becker, Winfried, Buchner, Heinz Jurgen and Sleeking, Simon (1987), ‘The Impact of Public Transfer Expenditures on Tax Evasion: An Experimental Approach’, 34 Journal of Public Economics, 243-252. Benjamini, Yael and Maital, Shlomo (1985), ‘Optimal Tax Evasion and Optimal Tax Evasion Policy: Behavioral Aspects’, in Gaertner, Wulf and Wenig, Alois (eds), The Economics of the Shadow Economy: Proceedings of the International Conference on the Economics of the Shadow Economy Held at the University of Bielefeld, West Germany, October 10-14, 1983, Berlin, Springer, 245-264.
6020
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
71
Beron, Kurt, Tauchen, Helen V. and Witte, Ann Dryden (1988), A Structural Equation Model for Tax Compliance and Auditing, National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper, No. 2556. Beron, Kurt, Tauchen, Helen V. and Witte, Ann Dryden (1992), ‘The Effect of Audits and Socioeconomic Variables on Compliance’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 67-89. Besley, Timothy and McLaren, John (1993), ‘Taxes and Bribery: The Role of Wage Incentives’, 103 Economic Journal, 119-141. Besley, Timothy, Preston, Ian and Ridge, Michael (1993), Fiscal Anarchy in the U.K. Modelling Poll Tax Noncompliance, National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper, No. 4498. Besley, T., Preston, Ian and Ridge, Michael (1994), Fiscal Anarchy in the UK, University College London Discussion Paper, No. 94-01. Bird, Richard M. (1992), ‘Does Deterrence Deter? Measuring the Effect of Deterrence on Tax Compliance in Field Studies and Experimental Studies: Commentary’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 306-310. Bird, Richard M. and Miller, Barbara (1991), ‘The Incidence of Indirect Taxes on Low-Income Households in Jamaica’, in Bahl, Roy (ed.), The Jamaican Tax Reform, Cambridge, MA, Lincoln Institute of Land Policy, 793-811. Blumenthal, Marsha and Slemrod, Joel B. (1992), ‘The Compliance Cost of the U.S. Individual Income Tax System: A Second Look After Tax Reform’, 45 National Tax Journal, 185-202. Blumenthal, Marsha and Slemrod, Joel B. (1995), ‘The Compliance Cost of Taxing Foreign-Source Income: Its Magnitude, Determinants, and Policy Implications’, 2 International Tax and Public Finance, 37-53. Boadway, Robin W. and Keen, Michael (1993), ‘Evasion and Time Consistency in the Taxation of Capital Income’, Queen’s Institute for Economic Research Discussion Paper. Boadway, Robin, Marchand, Maurice and Pestieau, Pierre (1992), ‘Towards a Theory of the Direct-Indirect Tax Mix’, Queen’s Institute for Economic Research Discussion Paper. Bogetic, Zeljko and llman, Arye L. (eds) (1995), Financing Government in the Transition: Bulgaria: The Political Economy of Tax Policies, Tax Bases, and Tax Hvasion, Regional and Sectoral Studies. Washington, DC, World Bank, 254 p. Boidman, Nathan (1983), ‘Tax Evasion: The Present State of Non-Compliance’, 37(9-10) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 451-479. Bolderson, Sarah and Huiskes, Theodoor (1994), ‘Central and Eastern Europe: Meeting Tax Obligations in Central and Eastern Europe’, 48 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 648-654. Boone, Catherine (1994), ‘Trade, Taxes, and Tribute: Market Liberalizations and the New Importers in West Africa’, 22 World Development, 453-467. Border, K. and Sobel, J. (1987), ‘Samurai Accountant: A Theory of Auditing and Plunder’, 54(4) Review of Economic Studies, 525-540. Bordignon, Massimo (1993), ‘A Fairness Approach to Income Tax Evasion’, 52(3) Journal of Public Economics, 345-362.
72
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
6020
Bowles, Roger A. and Jones, Philip (1993), ‘Nonpayment of Poll Tax: An Exploratory Analysis of Tax Resistance’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 445-455. Brenner, Reuven and Brenner, Gabrielle A. (1990), Gambling and Speculation, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Reprinted in French edition by Presses Universitaires de France, 1993. Broesterhuizen, G.A.A.M. (1989), ‘The Unrecorded Economy and the National Income Accounts in the Netherlands: A Sensitivity Analysis’, in Feige, Edgar L. (ed.), The Underground Economies: Tax Evasion and Information Distortion, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 159-174. Brown, C.V. et al. (1984), ‘Tax Evasion and Avoidance on Earned Income: Some Survey Evidence’, 5(3) Fiscal Studies, 1-22. Burgess, Robin and Stern, Nicholas (1992), Taxation and Development, London School of Economics Suntory Toyota International Centre for Economics and Related Disciplines Working Paper, No. DEP 42. Burgess, Robin and Stern, Nicholas (1993), A VAT in India, Problems and Options, London School of Economics Suntory Toyota International Centre for Economics and Related Disciplines Working Paper, No. EF/4. Burgess, Robin, Howes, Stephen and Stern, Nicholas (1993), The Reform of Indirect Taxes in India, London School of Economics Suntory Toyota International Centre for Economics and Related Disciplines Working Paper, No. EF/7. Carroll, John S. (1992), ‘How Taxpayers Think about Their Taxes: Frames and Values’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 43-63. Cassone, Alberto and Marchese, Carla (1995), ‘Tax Amnesties as Special Sales Offers: the Italian Experience’, 50 Public Finance/Finances Publiques, 51-66. Chadha, V. and Singh, Gurjeet (1988), ‘An Analysis of Tax Evasion in Punjab’, in Raikhy, P.S. and Gill, Sucha Singh (eds), Resource Mobilisation and Economic Development: A Regional Perspective, Amritsar, India, Guru Nanak Dev University, Punjab School of Economics, 140-151. Chander, Parkash and Wilde, Louis (1992), ‘Corruption in Tax Administration’, 49 Journal of Public Economics, 333-349. Chander, P. and Wilde, Louis (1998), ‘A General Characterization of Optimal Income Tax Enforcement’, 65 Review of Economic Studies, 165-183. Chelvathurai, S.I. (1990), ‘Tax Avoidance, Tax Evasion and the Underground Economy - The CATA Experience: International’, 44 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 594-599. Christiansen, Vidar (1980), ‘Two Comments on Tax Evasion’, 13 Empirical Economics, 389-393. Chu, C.Y. Cyrus (1990a), ‘A Model of Income Tax Evasion with Venal Tax Officials: The Case of Taiwan’, 45(3) Public Finance, 392-408. Chu, C.Y. Cyrus (1990b), ‘Plea Bargaining with the IRS’, 41(3) Journal of Public Economics, 1319-1333. Chu, C.Y. Cyrus (1992), ‘Analyzing Income Tax Evasion Using Amnesty Data with Self-Selection Correction: The Case of the Michigan Tax Amnesty Program: Commentary’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 190-192.
6020
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
73
Clotfelter, Charles T. (1983), ‘Tax Evasion and Tax Rates: An Analysis of Individual Returns’, 65 Review of Economics and Statistics, 363-373. Cnossen, Sijbren (1991), ‘The Future Development of the Sales Tax in Jamaica’, in Bahl, Roy (ed.), The Jamaican Tax Reform, Cambridge, MA, Lincoln Institute of Land Policy, 519-535. Coffey, Sergia (1995), Tax Evasion and the Development of a Financial Sector in LDCs, New York University, Ph.D. Coleman, Cynthia and Freeman, Lynne (1994), ‘The Development of Strategic Marketing Options Directed at Improving Compliance Levels in Small Business’,11 Australian Tax Forum, 347-367. Collins, Julie H. (1992), ‘Deterrence and Beyond: Toward a Kinder, Gentler IRS: Commentary’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 330-332. Collins, Julie H. and Plumlee, R. David (1991), ‘The Taxpayer’s Labor and Reporting Decision: The Effect of Audit Schemes’, 66 Accounting Review, 559-576. Collins, Julie H., Murphy, Daniel P. and Plumlee, R. David (1992), ‘The Taxpayer’s Dilemma: How Hard to Work and What to Report?’, in Stern, Jerrold J. (ed.), Advances in Taxation. Volume 4, Greenwich, CT, JAI Press, 31-53. Commerce Clearing House Tax Law (eds) (1989), Understanding IRS Communications, Chicago, Commerce Clearing House, 120 p. Contini, Bruno (1989), ‘The Irregular Economy of Italy: A Survey of Contributions’, in Feige, Edgar L. (ed.), The Underground Economies: Tax Evasion and Information Distortion, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 237-250. Cowell, Frank A. (1985a), ‘Public Policy and Tax Evasion: Some Problems’, in Gaertner, Wulf and Wenig, Alois (eds), The Economics of the Shadow Economy: Proceedings of th International Conference on the Economics of the Shadow Economy Held at the University of Bielefeld, West Germany, October 10-14, 1983, Berlin, Springer, 273-284. Cowell, Frank A. (1985b), ‘The Economic Analysis of Tax Evasion’, 37 Bulletin of Economic Research, 163-193. Cowell, Frank A. (1985c), ‘Tax Evasion with Labour Income’, 26 Journal of Public Economics, 19-34. Cowell, Frank A. (1987), ‘The Economic Analysis of Tax Evasion’, in Hey, John D. and Lambert, Peter J. (eds), Surveys in the Economics of Uncertainty, Oxford, Blackwell, 173-203. Cowell, Frank A. (1990a), Cheating the Government: The Economics of Evasion, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 267 p. Cowell, F.A. (1990b), ‘Tax Sheltering and the Cost of Evasion’, 42 Oxford Economic Papers, 231-243. Cowell, Frank A. (1991), ‘Tax Sheltering and the Cost of Evasion’, in Sinclair, Peter J. N. and Slater, Martin D.E. (eds), Taxation, Private Information and Capital. Oxford Economic Papers, Special Issue 1990, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 231-243. Cowell, F.A. (1992), ‘Tax Evasion and Inequity’, 13 Journal of Economic Psychology, 521-543. Cowell, Frank A. and Gordon, James P.F. (1988), ‘Unwillingness to Pay: Tax Evasion and Public Good Provision’, 36 Journal of Public Economics, 305-321.
74
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
6020
Crane, Steven E. and Nourzad, Farrokh (1985), ‘Time Value of Money and Income Tax Evasion under Risk-averse Behavior: Theoretical Analysis and Empirical Evidence’, 40 Public Finance, 481-494. Crane, Steven E. and Nourzad, Farrokh (1986a), ‘Inflation and Tax Evasion: An Empirical Analysis’, 68 Review of Economics and Statistics, 217-223. Crane, Steven E. and Nourzad, Farrokh (1986b), ‘Federal Income Tax Evasion’, in Lindholm, Richard W. (ed.), Examination of Basic Weaknesses of Income as the Major Federal Tax Base, New York, Greenwood Press, 140-162. Crane, Steven E. and Nourzad, Farrokh (1987), ‘On the Treatment of Income Tax Rates in Empirical Analysis of Tax Evasion’, 40 Kyklos, 338-348. Crane, Steven E. and Nourzad, Farrokh (1990), ‘Tax Rates and Tax Evasion: Evidence from California Amnesty Data’, 43 National Tax Journal, 189-199. Crane, Steven E. and Nourzad, Farrokh (1992), ‘Analyzing Income Tax Evasion Using Amnesty Data with Self-Selection Correction: The Case of the Michigan Tax Amnesty Program’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 167-189. Crane, Steven E. and Nourzad, Farrokh (1994), ‘An Empirical Analysis of Factors that Distinguish those who Evade on their Tax Return from those who Choose Not to File a Return’, 49(Suppl) Public Finance, 106-116. Creedy, John (1994), Taxation, Poverty and Income Distribution, Aldershot, Edward Elgar, 255 p. Creedy, John and McDonald, Ian M. (1990), ‘A Tax Package to Reduce the Marginal Rate of Income Tax and the Wage Demands of Trade Unions’, 66 Economic Record, 195-202. Cremer, H., Marchand, M. and Pestieau, P. (1990), ‘Evading, Auditing and Taxing: The Equity-Compliance Tradeoff’, 43 Journal of Public Economics, 67-92. Cremer, Helmuth and Gahvari, Firouz (1992), ‘Tax Evasion and the Structure of Indirect Taxes and Audit Probabilities’, 47(Suppl) Public Finance, 351-365. Cremer, Helmuth and Gahvari, Firouz (1993), ‘Tax Evasion and Optimal Commodity Taxation’, 50(2) Journal of Public Economics, 261-275. Cremer, Helmuth and Gahvari, Firouz (1994), ‘Tax Evasion, Concealment and the Optimal Linear Income Tax’, 96 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 219-239. Cronshaw, Mark B. and Alm, James (1995), ‘Tax Compliance with Two-Sided Uncertainty’, 23 Public Finance Quarterly, 139-166. Cunningham, William T. (1989), ‘Withholding Taxes: Portugal’, 43 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 223-224. Cunningham, William T. (1994), ‘Portugal: Recent Developments’, 48 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 185-190. Danesh, Abol Hassan (1991), The Informal Economy: Underground Economy, Moonlighting, Subcontracting, Household Economy,Uunorganized Sector, Barter, Ghetto Economy, Second Economy: A Research Guide, New York, Garland Inc., 420 p. Das Gupta, Arindam (1994), ‘A Theory of Hard-to-Tax Groups’, 49(Suppl) Public Finance, 28-39. Das Gupta, Arindam, Lahiri, Radhika and Mookherjee, Dilip (1995), ‘Income Tax Compliance in India: An Empirical Analysis’, 23 World Development, 2051-2064.
6020
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
75
Dassesse, Marc (1994), ‘Introduction of the “Economic Reality” Test in Belgian Tax Law: Years of Uncertainty Ahead?’, 48 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 127-129. de Jantscher, Milka Casanegra, Silvani, Carlos and Holland, Graham (1991), ‘The Audit of VAT’, in Tait, Alan A. (ed.), Value Added Tax: Administrative and Policy Issues. Occasional Paper, no. 88, Washington, International Monetary Fund, 67-88. de Juan, Ana, Lasheras, Miguel A. and Mayo, Rafaela (1994), ‘Voluntary Tax Compliant Behavior of Spanish Income Tax Payers’, 49(Suppl) Public Finance, 90-105. Dermine, J. (1994), EC Banking Regulation, Centralization or National Autonomy, INSEAD Working Papers, No. 94/13/FIN/EPS. Drummond, Don et al. (1994), ‘The Underground Economy: Moving the Myth Closer to Reality’, 2 Canadian Business Economics, 3-17. Dubin, Jeffrey A. (1992), ‘Can Brute Deterrence Backfire? Perceptions and Attitudes in Taxpayer Compliance: Commentary’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 219-222. Dubin, Jeffrey A. and Wilde, Louis L. (1988), ‘An Empirical Analysis of Federal Income Tax Auditing and Compliance’, 41 National Tax Journal, 61-74. Dubin, Jeffrey A., Graetz, Michael J. and Wilde, Louis L. (1987), ‘Are We a Nation of Tax Cheaters? New Econometric Evidence on Tax Compliance’, 77 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 240-245. Dubin, Jeffrey A., Graetz, Michael J. and Wilde, Louis L. (1989), ‘The Effect of Audit Rates on Federal Income Tax Filings and Collections, 1977-1986', Caltech Social Science Working Paper. Dubin, Jeffrey A., Graetz, Michael J. and Wilde, Louis L. (1992), ‘State Income Tax Amnesties: Causes’, 107 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 1057-1070. Elffers, Henk and Hessing, Dick J. (1988), ‘A Linear Structural Model for Tax Evasion Measurements’, in Maital, Shlomo (ed.), Applied Behavioural Economics Volume 2, New York, New York University Press, 562-567. Elffers, H., Robben, H.S.J. and Hessing, D.J. (1991), ‘Under-reporting Income: Who is the Best Judge - Tax-payer or Tax Inspector?’, 154 Journal of Royal Statistical Society, Series A, 125-127. Elffers, Henk, Robben, Henry S.J. and Hessing, Dick J. (1992), ‘On Measuring Tax Evasion’, 13 Journal of Economic Psychology, 545-567. Ellfers, H., Weigel, R. and Hessing, D. (1987), ‘The Consequences of Different Strategies for Measuring Tax Evasion Behavior’, 8 Journal of Economic Psychology, 311-337. Erard, Brian (1990), Tax Practitioners and Tax Compliance: A Microeconometric Analysis of the Decision to Engage a Tax Preparer and Its Consequences, University of Michigan, Ph.D. Erard, Brian (1992), ‘The Influence of Tax Audits on Reporting Behavior’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 95-114. Erard, Brian (1993), ‘Taxation with Representation: An Analysis of the Role of Tax Practitioners in Tax Compliance’, 52(2) Journal of Public Economics, 163-197. Erard, Brian and Feinstein, Jonathan S. (1994a), ‘The Role of Moral Sentiments and Audit Perceptions in Tax Compliance’, 49(Suppl) Public Finance, 70-89. Erard, Brian and Feinstein, Jonathan S. (1994b), ‘Honesty and Evasion in the Tax Compliance Game’, 25 Rand Journal of Economics, 1-19.
76
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
6020
Erbas, S. Nuri (1993), Presumptive Taxation: Revenue and Automatic Stabilizer Aspects, International Monetary Fund Working Paper, No. WP/93/69. Falkinger, Josef (1988), ‘Tax Evasion and Equity: A Theoretical Analysis’, 43 Public Finance, 388-395. Falkinger, Josef (1991), ‘On Optimal Public Good Provision with Tax Evasion’, 45 Journal of Public Economics, 127-133. Falkinger, Josef (1995), ‘Tax Evasion, Consumption of Public Goods and Fairness’, 16 Journal of Economic Psychology, 63-72. Falkinger, Josef and Walther, Herbert (1991a), ‘Separating Small and Big Fish: The Case of Income Tax Evasion’, 54 Journal of Economics (Zeitschrift für Nationalökonomie), 55-67. Falkinger, Josef and Walther, Herbert (1991b), ‘Rewards versus Penalties: On a New Policy Against Tax Evasion’, 19 Public Finance Quarterly, 67-79. Feige, Edgar L. (1986), ‘A Re-examination of the “Underground Economy’ in the United States: A Comment’, 33 International Monetary Fund Staff Papers, 768-781. Feige, Edgar L. (1989a), ‘The Meaning and Measurement of the Underground Economy’, in Feige, Edgar L. (ed.), The Underground Economies: Tax Evasion and Information Distortion, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 13-56. Feige, Edgar L. (1989b), ‘The Underground Economies: Tax Evasion and Information Distortion: Introduction’, in Feige, Edgar L. (ed.), The Underground Economies: Tax Evasion and Information Distortion, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1-9. Feige, Edgar L. (1989c), The Underground Economies: Tax Evasion and Information Distortion, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 378 p. Feinstein, Jonathan S. (1991), ‘An Econometric Analysis of Income Tax Evasion and its Detection’, 22 Rand Journal of Economics, 14-35. Feinstein, Jonathan S. (1992), ‘The Effect of Audits and Socioeconomic Variables on Compliance: Commentary’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 90-94. Feldbrugge, F.J.M. (1989), ‘The Soviet Second Economy in a Political and Legal Perspective’, in Feige, Edgar L. (ed.), The Underground Economies: Tax Evasion and Information Distortion, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 297-338. Feldman, J. and Kay, John A. (1981), ‘Tax Avoidance’, in Burrows, Paul and Veljanovski, Cento G. (eds), The Economic Approach to Law, London, Butterworths, 320-333. Filosa, Vincenzo (1979), ‘Evasione Fiscale: Sanzioni Anche per il governante e il Legislatore (Tax Evasion: Sanctions Also for the Government and the Legislature)’, 26 Rivista Internazionale di Scienze Economiche e Commerciali, 705-713. Fishburn, Geoffrey (1981), ‘Tax Evasion and Inflation’, 20(37) Australian Economic Papers, 325-332. Fisher, Vickie L. (1985), ‘Recent Innovations in State Tax Compliance Programs’, 38 National Tax Journal, 565-571. Fishlow, Albert and Friedman, Jorge (1994), ‘Tax Evasion, Inflation and Stabilization’, 43 Journal of Development Economics, 105-123. Flatters, Frank and MacLeod, W. Bentley (1995), ‘Administrative Corruption and Taxation’, 2 International Tax and Public Finance. Fluet, Claude (1987), ‘Fraude Fiscale et Offre de Travail au Noir (Tax Evasion and the Supply of Unofficial Labour)’, 63 L’Actualité Economique, 225-242.
6020
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
77
Fortin, Bernard and Lacroix, Guy (1994), ‘Labour Supply, Tax Evasion and the Marginal Cost of Public Funds: An Empirical Investigation’, 55 Journal of Public Economics, 407-431. Fortin, Bernard, Garneau, Gaétan, Lacroix, Guy, Lemieux, Thomas and Montmarquette, Claude (1996), L’Économie Souterraine au Québec - Mythes et Réalités (The Underground Economy in Quebec - Myths and Realities), Sainte-Foy, Presses de l’Université Laval. Fossati, Amedeo, Cavalletti, Barbara and Pench, Alberto (1992), ‘From Personal to Indirect Taxation: A General Equilibrium Approach’, in Galeotti, G. and Marrelli, M. (eds), Design and Reform of Taxation Policy. Financial and Monetary Policy Studies, vol. 25, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 95-112. Frank, Max (1976), ‘Fraude des Revenus Soumis a l’Impot des Personnes Physiques et Perte d’Impot qui en Resulte pour le Tresor-Etude Methodologique. (Income Tax Evasion and Resulting Revenue Losses for the Treasury-Methodological Study. With English summary)’,31 Public Finance, 1-30. Frank, Max and Dekeyser Meulders, Daniele (1977), ‘A Tax Discrepancy Coefficient Resulting from Tax Evasion or Tax Expenditures’, 8 Journal of Public Economics, 67-78. Franzoni, Luigi Alberto (1994), ‘Costly Prosecution, Tax Evasion and Amnesties’, 23 Economic Notes, 248-265. Franzoni, Luigi Alberto (1995), On the Economics of Tax Amnesties (D.Phil. thesis), Nuffield College, Oxford. Franzoni, Luigi Alberto (1998a), ‘Punishment and Grace: on the Economics of Tax Amnesties’, Public Finance; forthcoming. Franzoni, Luigi Alberto (1998b), ‘Independent auditors as fiscal gatekeepers’, International Review of Law and Economics, forthcoming Frey, Bruno (1989), ‘How Large (or Small) Should the Underground Economy Be?’, in Feige, Edgar L. (ed.), The Underground Economies: Tax Evasion and Information Distortion, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 111-126. Friedland, Nehemiah, Maital, Shlomo and Rutenberg, Aryeh (1978), ‘A Simulation Study of Income Tax Evasion’, 10 Journal of Public Economics, 107-116. Friedman, Jorge Ricardo (1993), Essays in Tax Evasion, University of California, Berkeley, Ph.D. 1993. Fullerton, Don and Karayannis, Marios (1993), Tax Evasion and the Allocation of Capital, National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper, No. 4581. Fullerton, Don and Karayannis, Marios (1994), ‘Tax Evasion and the Allocation of Capital’, 55 Journal of Public Economics, 257-278. Gabor, Istvan R. (1989), ‘Second Economy and Socialism: The Hungarian Experience’, in Feige, Edgar L. (ed.), The Underground Economies: Tax Evasion and Information Distortion, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 339-360. Gangemi, Avv. Bruno (1993), ‘Tax Avoidance: The Italian Experience’, 47 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 522-528. Geeroms, Hans J.A. and Wilmots, Hendrik (1985), ‘An Empirical Model of Tax Evasion and Tax Avoidance’, 40 Public Finance, 190-209. Gentry, William M. (1994), ‘Review of: Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement’, 32 Journal of Economic Literature, 1248-1249.
78
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
6020
Giovannini, Alberto (1987a), Capital Controls and Public Finance: The Experience in Italy, Columbia First Boston Series in Money, Economics and Finance Working Paper, FB-87-19. Giovannini, Alberto (1987b), International Capital Mobility and Tax Evasion, National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper, No. 2460. Gordon, James P.F. (1989), ‘Individual Morality and Reputation Costs as Deterrents to Tax Evasion’, 33 European Economic Review, 797-805. Gordon, James P.F. (1990), ‘Evading Taxes by Selling for Cash’, 42 Oxford Economic Papers, 244-255. Gordon, James P.F. (1991), ‘Evading Taxes by Selling for Cash’, in Sinclair, Peter J.N. and Slater, Martin D.E. (eds), Taxation, Private Information and Capital. Oxford Economic Papers, Special Issue 1990, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 244-255. Gordon, Richard K., Jr (1988), ‘Income Tax Compliance and Sanctions in Developing Countries: An Outline of Issues’, 42(1) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 3-12. Gottlieb, Daniel (1985), ‘Tax Evasion and the Prisoner’s Dilemma’, 10(1) Mathematical Social Sciences, 81-89. Graetz, Michael J. and Wilde, Louis L. (1985), ‘The Economics of Tax Compliance: Fact and Fantasy’, 38 National Tax Journal, 335-363. Graetz, Michael J. and Wilde, Louis L. (1993), ‘The Decision by Strategic Nonfilers to Participate in Income Tax Amnesties’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 271-283. Graetz, Michael J., Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, Louis L. (1984), ‘A Model of Tax Compliance with Budget-Constrained Auditors’, Caltech Social Science Working Paper. Graetz, Michael J., Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, Louis L. (1986), ‘The Tax Compliance Game: Toward an Interactive Theory of Law Enforcement’, 2 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 1-32. Graetz, Michael J., Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, Louis L. (1989), ‘Expert Opinions and Taxpayer Compliance: A Strategic Analysis’, Caltech Social Science Working Paper. Green, Susan (1992), Schedule D Non-Compliance: Would an Amnesty Help?, University of Bristol Discussion Paper, No. 92/334. Greenberg, Joseph (1984), ‘Avoiding Tax Avoidance: A (Repeated) Game Theoretic Approach’, 32(1) Journal of Economic Theory, 1-13. Greenfield, Harry I. (1993), Invisible, Outlawed, and Untaxed: America’s Underground Economy, Westport, Praeger, 137 p. Greenspan, Edward L. (1988), Tax Evasion is a Crime!, Canadian Tax Foundation. Income Tax Enforcement, Compliance, and Administration: Corporate Management Tax Conference, Toronto, Author. Groenland, Edward A.G. (1992), ‘Developing a Dynamic Research Strategy for the Economic Psychological Study of Taxation’, 13 Journal of Economic Psychology, 589-596. Gros, Daniel (1990), ‘Tax Evasion and Offshore Centres’, in Siebert, Horst (ed.), Reforming Capital Income Taxation. Symposien und Konferenzbande Series, Tübingen, Mohr, 113-127. Hagemann, Robert P. (1990), ‘Tax Evasion and Offshore Centres: Comment’, in Siebert, Horst (ed.), Reforming capital income taxation. Symposien und Konferenzbande series, Tübingen, Mohr, 128-131.
6020
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
79
Hansson, Ingemar (1985), ‘Tax Evasion and Government Policy’, in Gaertner, Wulf and Wenig, Alois (eds), The Economics of the Shadow Economy: Proceedings of th International Conference on the Economics of the Shadow Economy Held at the University of Bielefeld, West Germany, October 10-14, 1983, Berlin, Springer, 285-300. Hansson, Ingemar (1989), ‘The Underground Economy in Sweden’, in Feige, Edgar L. (ed.), The Underground Economies: Tax Evasion and Information Distortion, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 219-236. Harris, David et al. (1991), Income Shifting in U.S. Multinational Corporations, National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper, No. 3924. Harriss, C. Lowell (1994), ‘An Address on Land Taxation as an Evasion-Proof Revenue Source’, 53 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 97-98. Hasseldine, D. John and Bebbington, K. Jan (1991), ‘Blending Economic Deterrence and Fiscal Psychology Models in the Design of Responses to Tax Evasion: The New Zealand Experience’, 12 Journal of Economic Psychology, 299-324. Hasseldine, D. John and Kaplan, Steven E. (1992), ‘The Effect of Different Sanction Communications on Hypothetical Taxpayer Compliance: Policy Implications from New Zealand’, 47 Public Finance, 45-60. Hepburn, Glen (1992), ‘Estimates of Cash-Based Income Tax Evasion in Australia’, 0(2) Australian Economic Review, 54-62. Herschel, Federico J. (1978), ‘Tax Evasion and Its Measurement in Developing Countries’, 33 Public Finance, 232-268. Hessing, Dick J. et al. (1988), ‘Tax Evasion Research: Measurement Strategies and Theoretical Models’, in van Raaij, W. Fred, van Veldhoven, Gery M., Warneryd, Karl Erik (eds), Handbook of Economic Psychology, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 517-537. Hessing, Dick J. et al. (1992), ‘Does Deterrence Deter? Measuring the Effect of Deterrence on Tax Compliance in Field Studies and Experimental Studies’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 291-305. Hessing, Dick J., Elffers, Henk and Weigel, Russell H. (1988), ‘Research in Tax Resistance: An Integrative Theoretical Scheme for Tax Evasion Behavior’, in Maital, Shlomo (ed.), Applied Behavioural Economics Volume 2, New York, New York University Press, 568-576. Hey, John D. and Lambert, Peter J. (eds) (1987), Surveys in the Economics of Uncertainty, Oxford, Blackwell, 232 p. Hindriks, J. (1994), On the Equity-Compliance Tradeoff, mimeo, University of Namur. Hindriks, J., Keen, M. and Muthoo, A. (1996), Corruption, Extortion and Evasion, mimeo, University of Essex. Hines, James R., Jr (1990), The Flight Paths of Migratory Corporations, John M. Olin Program for the Study of Economic Organization and Public Policy, No. 65. Hite, Peggy A. (1990), ‘An Experimental Investigation of the Effects of Tax Shelters on Taxpayer Noncompliance’, 45 Public Finance, 90-108. Holland, Daniel M. (1984), ‘Measuring and Combatting Income Tax Evasion’, in Hanusch, Horst (ed.), Public Finance and the Quest for Efficiency: Proceedings of the 38th Congress of the International Institute of Public Finance, Copenhagen, Detroit, Wayne State University Press, 329-348.
80
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
6020
Holland, Daniel M. (1991), ‘Property Taxes: Section Postscript’, in Bahl, Roy (ed.), The Jamaican Tax Reform, Cambridge, MA, Lincoln Institute of Land Policy, 673-676. Hunter, William C. (1992), ‘Cheating the Government: The Economics of Evasion: Review Essay’, 77 Federal Reserve Bank of Atlanta Economic Review, 35-41. Hunter, William J. and Nelson, Michael A. (1995), ‘Tax Enforcement: A Public Choice Perspective’, 82 Public Choice, 53-67. Inhaber, Herbert and Carroll, Sidney (1992), How Rich is too Rich? Income and Wealth in America, Westport, Praeger, 252 p. International Fiscal Association (ed.) (1989), Administrative and Compliance Costs of Taxation, Deventer, Kluwer, 650 p. Isachsen, Arne Jon and Ström, Steinar (1980), ‘The Hidden Economy: The Labor Market and Tax Evasion’, 82 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 304-311. Isachsen, Arne Jon and Ström, Steinar (1981), Skattefritt. Svart Sektor i Vekst (Taxfree. The Growth of the Black Sector), Oslo, Universitetsforlaget. Isachsen, Arne Jon and Strom, Steinar (1989), ‘The Hidden Economy in Norway with Special Emphasis on the Hidden Labor Market’, in Feige, Edgar L. (ed.), The Underground Economies: Tax Evasion and Information Distortion, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 251-265. Isachsen, Arne Jon, Samuelson, S.S. and Strom, Steinar (1985), ‘The Behavior of Tax Evaders’, in Gaertner, Wulf and Wenig, Alois (eds), The Economics of the Shadow Economy: Proceedings of the International Conference on the Economics of the Shadow Economy Held at the University of Bielefeld, West Germany, October 10-14, 1983, Berlin, Springer. Ishi, Hiromitsu (1984), ‘International Tax Evasion and Avoidance in Japan’, 25(1) Hitotsubashi Journal of Economics, 276-294. Jain, Anil Kumar (1972), ‘The Problem of Income Tax Evasion in India’, 26(7) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 276-294. Jensen, Richard, Toma, Eugenia Froedge and Toma, Mark (1994), ‘Privatization of Tax Collection and the Time-Consistency Problem’, 49 Public Finance, 57-71. Jepsen, Gunnar Thorlund (1991a), Wage Contracts and Design of Tax Enforcement Policy in the Shadow Economy, Aarhus Institute of Economics Memo, No. 1991-21. Jepsen, Gunnar Thorlund (1991b), How to Close ‘The Gap’? Wage Contracts and Design of Tax Enforcement Policy in the Shadow Economy, Aarhus Institute of Economics Memo, No. 1991-14. Jepsen, Gunner Thorlund (1992), Measuring the Tax Evaders’ Aversion Against Evading: An Introduction to an Empirical Research, Aarhus Institute of Economics Memo, No. 1991-7. Jepsen, Gunnar Thorlund (1994), Is There Aversion Against Moonlighting?, Aarhus Institute of Economics Memo, No. 1991-19. Jonathan, R. Kesselman (1988), Income Tax Evasion in General Equilibrium, University of British Columbia Department of Economics Discussion Paper, No. 88-03. Jou, Jyh Bang (1992), Income Tax Evasion: Theory and Empirical Evidence from the U.S. State-Level Data, Tax Year 1976-1989, University of Chicago, Ph.D. 1992. Jung, Young Heon (1992), Contributions to the Economic Theory of Tax Evasion, University of Georgia, Ph.D. 1992. Jung, Young H., Snow, Arthur and Trandel, Gregory A. (1994), ‘Tax Evasion and the Size of the Underground Economy’, 54(3) Journal of Public Economics, 391-402.
6020
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
81
Kagan, Robert A. (1989), ‘On the Visibility of Income Tax Violations’, in Roth, Jeffrey A. and Scholz, John T. (eds), Taxpayer Compliance, Philadelphia, University of Pennsylvania Press. Kamdar, Nipoli (1993), Essays on Tax Compliance, Syracuse University, Ph.D. Kamdar, Nipoli (1995), ‘Information Reporting and Tax Compliance: An Investigation Using Individual TCMP Data’, 23 Atlantic Economic Journal, 278-292. Kaplan, Richard L. (1989), ‘Perspectives on International Tax Compliance and Enforcement: Transfer Pricing in the United States’, 6 Australian Tax Forum, 423-454. Kaplan, Steven E. and Reckers, Philip M.J. (1985), ‘A Study of Tax Evasion Judgments’, 38 National Tax Journal, 97-102. Kaplow, Louis (1989), The Optimal Probability and Magnitude of Fines for Acts that are Definitely Undesirable, National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper, No. 3008. Kaplow, Louis (1990), ‘Optimal Taxation with Costly Enforcement and Evasion’, 43 Journal of Public Economics, 221-236. Kaplow, Louis (1995), ‘A Model of the Optimal Complexity of Legal Rules’, 11 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 150-163. Kaplow, Louis (1996), ‘How Tax Complexity and Enforcement Affect the Equity and Efficiency of the Income Tax’, 49 National Tax Journal, 135-150. Karayannis, Marios (1991), Tax Evasion, Portfolio Choice, and the Allocation of Capital in the U.S. Economy, University of Virginia, Ph.D. Karoly, Lynn A. (1994), ‘Review of: How Rich is too Rich? Income and Wealth in America’, 32 Journal of Economic Literature, 130-131. Kazemier, Brugt and van Eck, Rob (1992), ‘Survey Investigations of the Hidden Economy: Some Methodological Results’, 13 Journal of Economic Psychology, 569-587. Kelsey, David and Schepanski, Al (1988), Testing for Regret and Disappointment in Tax Compliance Decisions, University of Cambridge Economic Theory Discussion Paper, No. 124. Kemp, Robert, Reckers, Philip M.J. and Arrington, C. Edward (1986), ‘U.S. Tax Reform: Tax Evasion Concerns’, 21 Business Economics, 55-57. Kesselman, Jonathan R. (1986), Evasion of Taxes in General Equilibrium, University of British Columbia Department of Economics Discussion Paper, No. 86-45. Kesselman, Jonathan R. (1989), ‘Income Tax Evasion: An Intersectoral Analysis’, 38 Journal of Public Economics, 137-182. Kesselman, Jonathan R. (1993a), Compliance, Enforcement, and Administrative Factors in Improving Tax Fairness, University of British Columbia Department of Economics Discussion Paper, No. 93-45. Kesselman, Jonathan R. (1993b), ‘Evasion Effects of Changing the Tax Mix’, 69 Economic Record, 131-148. Kim, Chungkweon (1994), The Effects of Public Transfers and Tax Rate Changes on Reported Income: Experimental Evidence, University of Pittsburgh, Ph.D. Kinsey, Karyl A. (1992), ‘Deterrence and Alienation Effects of IRS Enforcement: An Analysis of Survey Data’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 259-285. Klepper, Stephen and Nagin, Daniel (1989a), ‘The Criminal Deterrence Literature: Implications for Research on Taxpayer Compliance’, in Roth, Jeffrey A. and Scholz, John T. (eds), Taxpayer Compliance, Philadelphia, University of Pennsylvania Press.
82
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
6020
Klepper, Steven and Nagin, Daniel (1989b), ‘The Role of Tax Preparers in Tax Compliance’, 22 Policy Sciences, 167-194. Klepper, Steven, Mazur, Mark and Nagin, Daniel S. (1991), ‘Expert Intermediaries and Legal Compliance: The Case of Tax Preparers’, 34 Journal of Law and Economics, 205-229. Klepper, Steven, Nagin, Daniel and Spurr, Stephen (1991), ‘Tax Rates, Tax Compliance, and the Reporting of Long-Term Capital Gains’, 46 Public Finance, 236-251. Klovland, Jan Tore (1984), ‘Tax Evasion and the Demand for Currency in Norway and Sweden. Is There a Hidden Relationship?’, 86 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 423-439. Kolm, Serge Christophe (1973), ‘A Note on Optimum Tax Evasion’, 2 Journal of Public Economics, 265-270. Kong, Randolph (1988), ‘Cooperative Approaches among Tax Administrations to Prevent and Counteract International Tax Evasion and Avoidance: Trinidad and Tabago’, 42 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 526-530. Koskela, Erkki (1983), ‘On the Shape of Tax Schedule, the Probability of Detection, and the Penalty Schemes as Deterrents to Tax Evasion’, 38 Public Finance, 70-80. Koskela, Erkki (1983), ‘A Note on Progression, Penalty Schemes and Tax Evasion’, 22 Journal of Public Economics, 127-133. Kreutzer, David and Lee, Dwight R. (1988), ‘Tax Evasion and Monopoly Output Decisions: A Reply’, 41 National Tax Journal, 583-584. Krupsky, Kenneth J. (1992), ‘IRS Access to Foreign Transfer Pricing Information: United States’, 46 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 113-118. Kuboniwa, Masaaki (1995), ‘From Upward to Downward Bias of the Russian Output Statistics. (In Japanese, with English summary)’, 46 Economic Review (Keizai Kenkyu), 289-302. Laban, Raul and Sturzenegger, Federico (1992), ‘La Economia Politica de los Programas de Estabilizacion (The Political Economy of Stabilization Programs. With English summary)’, 0(36) Coleccion Estudios CIEPLAN, 41-66. Lai, Ching Chong (1991), ‘The Effect of Tax Evasion on Tax Collections: The Implication of the Cebula Model’, 38 Rivista Internazionale di Scienze Economiche e Commerciali, 639-647. Lai, Ching Chong and Chang, Wen Ya (1988), ‘Tax Evasion and Tax Collections: An Aggregate Demand-Aggregate Supply Analysis’, 43 Public Finance, 138-146. Landsberger, Michael and Meilijson, Isaac (1982), ‘Incentive Generating State Dependent Penalty System: The Case of Income Tax Evasion’, 19 Journal of Public Economics, 333-352. Landskroner, Yoram, Muller, Eitan and Swary, Itzhak (1991), ‘Tax Evasion and Financial Equilibrium’, 43 Journal of Economics and Business, 25-35. Landskroner, Yoram, Paroush, J. and Swary, Itzhak (1990), ‘Tax Evasion and Portfolio Decisions’, 45 Public Finance, 409-422. Langfeldt, Enno (1989), ‘The Underground Economy in the Federal Republic of Germany: A Preliminary Assessment’, in Feige, Edgar L. (ed.), The Underground Economies: Tax Evasion and Information Distortion, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 197-217. Lazos, Vaios (1996), ‘E Kambyle Adiaforias enos Eglematos (The Indifference Curve of a Crime)’, 6 Aissymnetes. Lemieux, Thomas, Fortin, Bernard and Frechette, Pierre (1994), ‘The Effect of Taxes on Labor Supply in the Underground Economy’, 84 American Economic Review, 231-254.
6020
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
83
Lempert, Richard (1992), ‘Reciprocity and Fairness: Positive Incentives for Tax Compliance: Commentary’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 251-257. Leonard, Herman B. and Zeckhauser, Richard J. (1986), Amnesty, Enforcement and Tax Policy, National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper, No. 2096. Lewis, A. (1979), ‘An Empirical Assessment of Tax Mentality’, 43 Public Finance/Finances Publiques, 245-257. Lindholm, Richard W. (1986), Examination of Basic Weaknesses of Income as the Major Federal Tax Base, New York, Greenwood Press, 320 p. Long, Susan B. (1992), ‘The Influence of Tax Audits on Reporting Behavior: Commentary’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 115-123. Lovely, Mary E. (1994), ‘Crossing the Border: Does Commodity Tax Evasion Reduce Welfare and Can Enforcement Improve It?’, 27 Canadian Journal of Economics, 157-174. Lugaresi, Sergio and Di Nicola, Fernando (1991), Tax Policy and Income Redistribution in Italy, London School of Economics Suntory Toyota International Centre for Economics and Related Disciplines Working Paper, No. TIDI/152. Lyttkens, Carl Hampus (1992), ‘Effects of the Taxation of Wealth in Athens in the Fourth Century B.C.’, 40 Scandinavian Economic History Review, 3-20. Macho-Stadler, I. and Pérez-Castrillo, J. David (1994), Random Audits in Tax Evasion Models, W.P. UAB-IAE, No. 287.94. Macho-Stadler, I. and Pérez-Castrillo, J. David (1996), ‘Optimal Tax Auditing when Some Individuals Need Not File’, Economic Design, forthcoming. Macho-Stadler, I. and Pérez-Castrillo, J. David (1997), ‘Optimal Auditing Policy with Heterogeneous Incomes Sources’, 38 International Economic Review. Macho-Stadler, I., Olivella-Cunill, P. and Pérez-Castillo, J. David (1993),Tax Amnesties in a Dynamic Model of Tax Evasion, W.P. UAB-IAE, No. 247.94. MacKie Mason, Jeffrey K. (1992), ‘The Corporate Tax Gap: Evidence on Tax Compliance by Small Corporations: Commentary’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 162-166. Madeo, Silvia A. (1992), ‘How Taxpayers Think about Their Taxes: Frames and Values: Commentary’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 64-66. Madeo, Silvia A., Schepanski, Albert and Uecker, Wilfred C. (1987), ‘Modeling Judgments of Taxpayer Compliance’, 62 Accounting Review, 323-342. Maital, Shlomo (1988), Applied Behavioural Economics. 2 vols, New York, New York University Press, 831 p. Malik, Arun S. (1990), ‘Avoidance, Screening and Optimum Enforcement’, 21 Rand Journal of Economics, 341-353. Malik, Arun S., and Schwab, R. (1991), ‘The Economics of Tax Amnesties’, 46 Journal of Public Economics, 29-49. Mann, Arthur J. and Smith, Robert (1988), ‘Tax Attitudes and Tax Evasion in Puerto Rico: A Survey of Upper Income Professionals’, 13 Journal of Economic Development, 121-141. Marhuenda, F. and Ortuno-Ortin, I. (1994), Honesty versus Progressiveness in Income Tax Enforcement Problems, University of Alicante WP, No. 94-06.
84
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
6020
Marrelli, Massimo (1984), ‘On Indirect Tax Evasion’, 25 Journal of Public Economics, 181-196. Marrelli, M. (1987), ‘The Economic Analysis of Tax Evasion: Empirical Aspects’, in Hey, John D. and Lambert, Peter J. (eds), Surveys in the Economics of Uncertainty, Oxford, Blackwell, 204-228. Marrelli, Massimo and Martina, Riccardo (1988), ‘Tax Evasion and Strategic Behaviour of the Firms’, 37 Journal of Public Economics, 55-69. Martinez Vazquez, Jorge, Harwood, Gordon B. and Larkins, Ernest R. (1992), ‘Withholding Position and Income Tax Compliance: Some Experimental Evidence’, 20 Public Finance Quarterly, 152-174. Mason, Robert and Calvin, Lyle D. (1984), ‘Public Confidence and Admitted Tax Evasion’, 37 National Tax Journal, 489-496. McBarnet, Doreen (1992), ‘The Construction of Compliance and the Challenge for Control: The Limits of Noncompliance Research’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 333-345. McCaleb, Thomas S. (1976), ‘Tax Evasion and the Differential Taxation of Labor and Capital Income’, 31 Public Finance, 287-294. McCracken, Gerald H. (1988), Preventing Tax Evasion through Enforcement: The Government Perspective, Canadian Tax Foundation. Income Tax Enforcement, Compliance, and Administration: Corporate Management Tax Conference. McGee, Robert W. (1994), ‘Is Tax Evasion Unethical?’, 42(2) University of Kansas Law Review, 411-435. McGee, Robert W. (1996a), Taxation, Ethics and Public Policy, Dumont Institute for Public Policy Research. <> McGee, Robert W. (1996b), Essays on Accounting,Taxation and Public Finance, Dumont Institute for Public Policy Research. McGee, Robert W. and Feige, Edgar L. (1989), ‘Policy Illusion, Macroeconomic Instability, and the Unrecorded Economy’, in Feige, Edgar L. (ed.), The Underground Economies: Tax Evasion and Information Distortion, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 81-109. Mehta, Shekhar (1990), Evasion of State Taxes in India, New Delhi, Criterion. Melumad, Nahum D. and Mookherjee, D. (1989), ‘Delegation as Commitment: The Case of Income Tax Audits’, 104(2) Rand Journal of Economics, 399-415. Mintz, Jack M. and Seade, Jesus (1991), ‘Cash Flow or Income? The Choice of Base for Company Taxation’, 6 World Bank Research Observer, 177-190. Mirus, Rolf and Smith, Roger S. (1989), ‘Canada’s Underground Economy’, in Feige, Edgar L. (ed.), The Underground Economies: Tax Evasion and Information Distortion, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 267-280. Mookherjee, D. and Png, Ivan Paak-Liang (1989), ‘Optimal Auditing, Insurance and Redistribution’, 20(2) Quarterly Journal of Economics, 139-163. Mork, Knut Anton (1975), ‘Income Tax Evasion: Some Empirical Evidence’, 30 Public Finance, 70-76. Moser, Donald V., Evans, John H., III and Kim, Chung K. (1995), ‘The Effects of Horizontal and Exchange Inequity on Tax Reporting Decisions’, 70 Accounting Review, 619-634. Mtatifikolo, Fidelis P. (1990), ‘An Economic Analysis of Tanzania’s Tax Performance Experiences since the 1973 Tax Act’, 6 Eastern Africa Economic Review, 55-67.
6020
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
85
Mullin, Ronald David (1993), Enhancing Taxpayer Compliance: Experimental Evidence on Alternative Policies, University of Virginia, Ph.D. Murray, Matthew N. (1986), A Theoretical and Empirical Analysis of Tax Evasion and Tax Avoidance, Syracuse University, Ph.D. Murray, Matthew N. (1995), ‘Sales Tax Compliance and Audit Selection’, 48 National Tax Journal, 515-530. Myles, G. and Naylor, R. (1996), ‘A Model of Tax Evasion with Group Conformity and Social Customs’, 12 European Journal of Political Economy, 49-66. Nagin, Daniel (1992), ‘The Construction of Compliance and the Challenge for Control: The Limits of Noncompliance Research: Commentary’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 346-348. Nayak, P.B. (1978), ‘Optimal Income Tax Evasion and Regressive Taxes’, 33 Public Finance, 358-366. Nguyen, Trien T. (1989), ‘The Parallel Market of Illegal Aliens: A Computational Approach’, 17 World Development, 1965-1978. Nitzan, Shmuel and Tzur, Joseph (1987), Taxpayers, Auditors and the Government - an Extended Tax Evasion Game, Universitat Bonn Sonderforschungsbereich 303 Discussion Paper, No. A-105. O’Higgins, Michael (1989), ‘Assessing the Underground Economy in the United Kingdom’, in Feige, Edgar L. (ed.), The Underground Economies: Tax Evasion and Information Distortion, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 175-195. OECD (1990), Taxpayers’ Rights and Obligations, Paris, OECD. OKeeffe, Mary (1986), Audit Strategies with Heterogeneous Agents: Is Efficient Deterrence Compatible with Efficient Detection?, Harvard Kennedy School of Government Discussion Paper, No. 145D. Olivella, P. (1992a), ‘Un Estudio de la Evasion Fiscal desde la Perspectiva de las Relaciones Principal-Agente (A Principal-Agent Approach of Tax Evasion)’, 9(2) Revista Española de Economía. Olivella, P. (1992b), Las Amnistias Fiscales: Descripcion y Analisis Economico (Economic analysis of Tax Amnesties), Universitat Autonoma de Barcelona. Olivella, P. (1996), Tax Amnesties and Tax Evasion Inertia, Universitat Autonoma de Barcelona. Panagariya, Arvind and Narayana, A.V.L. (1988), ‘Excise Tax Evasion: A Welfare cum Crime Theoretic Analysis’, 43 Public Finance, 248-260. Panagariya, Arvind and Narayana, A.V.L. (1989), ‘Excise Tax Evasion: Reply’, 44 Public Finance, 510-512. Pandit, V. and Sundaram, K. (1977), ‘Aggregate Demand under Conditions of Tax Evasion’, 32 Public Finance, 333-342. Parikh, Parimal M. (1986), ‘India: Is Tax Avoidance Merging into Tax Evasion? A Change in the Judiciaries’ Approach to Tax Avoidance’,40(1) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 11-14. Pasha, Hafiz A. (1993), ‘Tax Audit Schemes in Pakistan and the Level of Income Declaration’, 38 Singapore Economic Review, 167-184. Pastor, Santos (1995), ‘Qué Hacer en los Conflictos Fiscales? Un Análisis Económico de las Propuestas de Actas de Conformidad (The Resolution of Tax Disputes)’, Hacienda Pública Española, 225-244.
86
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
6020
Peacock, Alan and Shaw, G.K. (1982), ‘Tax Evasion and Tax Revenue Loss’, 37 Public Finance, 269-278. Pencavel, John H. (1979), ‘A Note on Income Tax Evasion, Labor Supply, and Nonlinear Tax Schedules’, 12 Journal of Public Economics, 115-124. Persson, Mats and Wissen, Pehr (1984), ‘Redistributional Aspects of Tax Evasion’, 86 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 131-149. Persson, Mats and Wissen, Pehr (1985), ‘Redistributional Aspects of Tax Evasion’, in Forsund, Finn R. and Honkapohja, Seppo (eds), Limits and Problems of Taxation, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 33-51. Pestieau, Pierre and Possen, Uri M. (1991), ‘Tax Evasion and Occupational Choice’, 45 Journal of Public Economics, 107-125. Pestieau, Pierre, Possen, Uri M. and Slutsky, Steve (1994a), ‘Optimal Differential Taxes and Penalties’, 49(Suppl) Public Finance, 15-27. Pestieau, Pierre, Possen, Uri M. and Slutsky, Steven M. (1994b), The Penalty for Tax Evasion When Taxes are Set Optimally, Universite Catholique de Louvain CORE Discussion Paper, No. 9416. Peters, B. Guy (1991), The Politics of Taxation: A Comparative Perspective, Oxford, Blackwell, 338 p. Pitt, Mark M. and Slemrod, Joel (1989), ‘The Compliance Cost of Itemizing Deductions: Evidence from Individual Tax Returns’, 79 American Economic Review, 1224-1232. Plumley, Alan H. (1992), ‘Deterrence and Alienation Effects of IRS Enforcement: An Analysis of Survey Data: Commentary’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 286-290. Png, Ivan Paak-Liang (1987), ‘Litigation, Liability, and Incentives for Care’, 34 Journal of Public Economics, 61-85. Pommerehne, Werner W. (1983), ‘Steuerhinterziehung und Schwarzarbeit als Grenzen der Staatstatigkeit (Tax Evasion and Underground Activities as Limits of Government’s Growth)’, 119 Schweizerische Zeitschrift für Volkswirtschaft und Statistik, 261-284. Pommerehne, Werner W. and Zweifel, Peter (1991), ‘Success of a Tax Amnesty: At the Polls, for the FISC?’, 72 Public Choice, 131-165. Pommerehne, Werner W., Hart, Albert and Frey, Bruno S. (1994), ‘Tax Morale, Tax Evasion and the Choice of Policy Instruments in Different Political Systems’, 49(Suppl) Public Finance, 52-69. Pope, Jeff (1994), ‘Compliance Costs of Taxation: Policy Implications’, 11 Australian Tax Forum, 85-121. Pope, Jeff and Fayle, Richard (1991), ‘The Compliance Costs of Public Companies’ Income Taxation in Australia 1986/87: Empirical Results’, 8 Australian Tax Forum, 485-538. Porcano, Thomas M. (1988), ‘Correlates of Tax Evasion’, 9 Journal of Economic Psychology, 47-67. Porter, Richard D. and Bayer, Amanda S. (1989), ‘Monetary Perspective on Underground Economic Activity in the United States’, in Feige, Edgar L. (ed.), The Underground Economies: Tax Evasion and Information Distortion, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 129-157. Poterba, James M. (1987), ‘Tax Evasion and Capital Gains Taxation’,77 American Economic Review, 234-239. Prebble, Mark (1990), ‘Tax Compliance and the Use of Tax Information’, 7 Australian Tax Forum, 207-216.
6020
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
87
Pyle, David J. (1989), Tax Evasion and the Black Economy, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 212 p. Pyle, D.J. (1991), ‘The Economics of Taxpayer Compliance’, 5 Journal of Economic Surveys, 163-198. Pyle, D.J. (1992), ‘The Economics of Taxpayer Compliance’, in Jackson, Peter M. (ed.), Current Issues in Public Sector Economics, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 58-93. Raikhy, P.S. and Gill, Sucha Singh (1988), Resource Mobilisation and Economic Development: A Regional Perspective, Amritsar, India, Guru Nanak Dev University, Punjab School of Economics, 227 p. Rao, J. Mohan (1987), ‘Class Relations in an “Asiatic” Regime’, 11 Cambridge Journal of Economics, 229-250. Reckers, Philip M.J., Sanders, Debra L. and Roark, Stephen J. (1994), ‘The Influence of Ethical Attitudes on Taxpayer Compliance’, 47 National Tax Journal, 825-836. Reinganum, Jennifer F. (1984), Sequential Equilibrium Detection and Reporting Policies in a Model of Tax Evasion, Caltech Social Science Working Paper, No. 525. Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, Louis L. (1985), ‘Income Tax Compliance in a Principal-Agent Framework’, 26 Journal of Public Economics, 1-18. Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, Louis L. (1986), ‘Equilibrium Verification and Reporting Policies in a Model of Tax Compliance’, International Economic Review, 739-760. Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, Louis L. (1991), ‘Equilibrium Enforcement and Compliance in the Presence of Tax Practitioners’, 7 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 163-181. Rice, Eric M. (1990), Skirting the Law: Essays on Corporate Tax Evasion and Avoidance, Harvard University, Ph.D. Rice, Eric M. (1992), ‘The Corporate Tax Gap: Evidence on Tax Compliance by Small Corporations’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 125-161. Richupan, Somchai (1984), ‘Measuring Tax Evasion’, 21(4) Finance and Development, 38-40. Rickard, J.A., Russell, A.M. and Howroyd, T.D. (1982), ‘A Tax Evasion Model with Allowance for Retroactive Penalties’, 58 Economic Record, 379-385. Ricketts, Martin (1984), ‘On the Simple Macroeconomics of Tax Evasion: An Elaboration of the Peacock-Shaw Approach’, 39 Public Finance, 420-424. Robben, Henry S.J. et al. (1989), ‘A Cross-National Comparison of Attitudes, Personality, Behaviour, and Social Comparison in Tax Evasion Experiments’, in Grunert, Klaus-G. and Olander, Folke (eds), Understanding Economic Behaviour. Theory and Decision Library Series A: Philosophy and Methodology of the Social Sciences, vol. 11, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 121-134. Robben, Henry S.J. et al. (1990a), ‘Decision Frame and Opportunity as Determinants of Tax Cheating: An International Experimental Study’, 11 Journal of Economic Psychology, 341-364. Robben, Henry S.J. et. al. (1990b), ‘Decision Frames, Opportunity and Tax Evasion: An Experimental Approach’, 14 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 353-361. Roberts, Michael L. and Englebrecht, Ted D. (1992), ‘Potential Application of Civil Tax Penalties for Undervaluation of Assets: Evidence and Policy Analysis’, in Stern, Jerrold J. (ed.), Advances in Taxation. Volume 4, Greenwich, CT, JAI Press, 211-223.
88
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
6020
Roth, J., Scholtz, J. and Witt A. (1989), Taxpayer Compliance: An Agenda for Research. Vol. 1, Philadelphia, University of Pennsylvania Press. Roubini, Nouriel and Sala i Martin, Xavier (1995), ‘A Growth Model of Inflation, Tax Evasion, and Financial Repression’, 35 Journal of Monetary Economics, 275-301. Ruesca, Santos M. (1982), ‘La Economía Irregular en el Mercado de Trabajo (Irregular Economy in the Labour Market)’, 587 Información Comercial Española, 91-102. Ruesca, Santos M. (1986), ‘Economía Oculta: de la Definición y los Métodos de Estimación (Underground Economy: Definition and Estimation Methods)’, in X (ed.),Problemas Estadísiticos de la Economía Sumergida, Madrid, Instituto Nacional de Estadística, 25-48. Ruesca, Santos M. (1987), ‘La Economía Sumergida en España (Underground Economy in Spain)’, Revista del Instituto de Estudios Económicos. Russell, A.M. and Rickard, J.A. (1987), ‘A Model of Tax Evasion Incorporating Income Variation and Retroactive Penalities’, 26 Australian Economic Papers, 254-264. Saltzman, L., Paternoster, R., Waldo, G. and Chiricos, T. (1982), ‘Deterrent and Experiental Effects: the Problem of Causal Order in Percepual Deterrence Research’, 19 Journal of Research on Crime and Delinquency, 172-189. Samuelson, Paul A. (1954), ‘The Pure Theory of Public Expenditure’, 36 Review of Economic Statistics, 387-389. Sanchez, Isabel (1990), ‘Evasión Fiscal, Regulación y Mecanismos Óptimos de Inspección (Tax Evasion, Regulation, and Optimal Auditing Mechanisms)’, 2 Cuadernos Económicos de ICE, 45 ff. Sanchez, Isabel (1993), ‘Hierarchical Design and Enforcement of Income Tax Policies’, 50 Journal of Public Economics, 345-369. Sanchez, Isabel (1994), Determinantes Individuales de la Evasión Fiscal: un Enfoque Experimental (Individual Determinants of Tax Evasion: an Experimental Approach), Monografía, Instituto de Estudios Fiscales. Sanchez, Isabel (1995a), ‘Unraveling the Puzzle of Tax Compliance Using Experimental Methods’, 48 Kyklos, 3-18. Sanchez, Isabel (1995b), ‘Experimental Analysis of Individuals’ Tax Compliance Rate’, in de Juan, A. (ed.), Frontiers in Economic Psychology, Proceedings of the IAREP Conference, Agosto. Sanchez, Isabel and Sobel, Joel (1993), ‘Hierarchical Design and Enforcement of Income Tax Policies’, 50(3) Journal of Public Economics, 345-369. Sandford, Cedric T. (1973), Hidden Costs of Taxation, Institute for Fiscal Studies, London. Sandford, Cedric T. (1994), ‘International Comparisons of Administrative and Compliance Costs of Taxation’, 11 Australian Tax Forum, 291-309. Sandford, Cedric T. (ed.) (1995a), Tax Compliance Costs: Measurement and Policy, Bath, Fiscal Publications, 413 p. Sandford, Cedric T. (1995b), More Key Issues in Tax Reform, Bath, Fiscal Publications, 214 p. Sandford, C., Goodwin, M., Hardwick, P. and Butterworth, M. (1981), Costs and Benefits of VAT, London, Heinemann Educational Books. Sandford, C., Goodwin, M. and Hardwick, P. (1989), Administrative and Compliance Costs of Taxation, Bath, Fiscal Publications. Sandmo, Agnar (1981), ‘Income Tax Evasion, Labour Supply, and the Equity-Efficiency Tradeoff’, 16 Journal of Public Economics, 265-288.
6020
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
89
Sansing, Richard C. (1993), ‘Information Acquisition in a Tax Compliance Game’, 68 Accounting Review, 874-884. Sawyer, Adrian J. (1994), ‘New Zealand: Raising the Threshold for Taxpayer Compliance: A New Era of Compliance Standards and Penalties’, 48 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 655-664. Sawyer, Adrian J. (1995), ‘Taxpayer Compliance Standards and Penalties: Version II Signifies Progress: New Zealand’, 49 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 510-521. Sawyer, Adrian J. (1996), ‘Taxpayer Compliance, Penalties and Disputes Resolution Bill: An Update: New Zealand’, 50 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 72-78. Schenk, Karl-Ernst (1983), ‘Second Economy und Wirtschaftsordnung - Ein sSstemübergreifender, Transaktionsökonomischer Erklärungsansatz (Second Economy and Economic Constitution. An Explanation Approach Encompassing Different Systems on the Basis of Transaction Economics mit A. Wass von Czege)’, in Hedtkamp, G. (ed.), Beiträge zum Problem der Schattenwirtschaft, Schriften des Vereins für Socialpolitik N.F., Bd. 132, Berlin, 33-51. Schjelderup, Guttorm (1993), ‘Optimal Taxation, Capital Mobility and Tax Evasion’, 95 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 377-386. Schmidtchen, Dieter (1994), ‘Vom nichtmarginalen Charakter der Steuermoral (On the Non-marginal Character of Tax Morals)’, in Smekal, Chr. And Theurl, E. (eds), Stand und Entwicklung der Finanzpsychologie, Baden-Baden, 185-211. Schulze, Gunther G. (1994), ‘Misinvoicing Imports: The Interdependence of Tax and Tariff Evasion’, 22 Public Finance Quarterly, 335-365. Schweizer, Urs (1984), ‘Welfare Analysis of Excise Tax Evasion’, 140 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 247-258. Scotchmer, Suzanne (1987), ‘Audit Classes and Tax Enforcment Policy’, 77 American Economic Review, 229-233. Scotchmer, Suzanne (1989), ‘Who Profits fromTaxpayer Confusion?’,29(1) Economic Letters, 49-55. Scotchmer, Suzanne (1992), ‘The Regressive Bias in Tax Enforcement’, 47(Suppl) Public Finance, 366-371. Scotchmer, Suzanne and Slemrod, Joel (1989), ‘Randomness in Tax Enforcement’, 38 Journal of Public Economics, 17-32. Scott, W. and Grasmick, H. (1981), ‘Deterrence and Income Tax Cheating: Testing Interaction Hypotheses in Utilitarian Theories’, 17 Journal of Applied Behavioral Science, 395-408. Sen, Tapas Kumar (1990), ‘Sales Tax Evasion in India: Some Issues’, 44 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 605-608. Sengupta, Partha (1991), Essays on the Theory of Tax Evasion, Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University, Ph.D. Shea, Jia Dong and Wu, Jy Wen (1994), ‘Tax Evasion, Anti-monitoring Activities and the Impacts of Government Policies (in Chinese, with English summary)’, 22(1) Academia Economic Papers, 81-100. Sheffrin, Steven M. and Triest, Robert K. (1992), ‘Can Brute Deterrence Backfire? Perceptions and Attitudes in Taxpayer Compliance’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 193-218.
90
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
6020
Siebert, Horst (ed.) (1990), Reforming Capital Income Taxation, Tübingen, Mohr, 298 p. Silvani, Carlos and Vehorn, Charles L. (1991), ‘Invoices, Books of Account, and Tax Return Forms for VAT’, in Tait, Alan A. (ed.), Value Added Tax: Administrative and Policy Issues. Occasional Paper, no. 88, Washington, International Monetary Fund, 40-48. Simon, V.O. and Rao, D.N. (1993), ‘Estimation of Leakages in Sales Tax Revenue of Delhi’, 25(2) Margin, 178-215. Skinner, Jonathan and Slemrod, Joel (1985), ‘An Economic Perspective on Tax Evasion’, 38 National Tax Journal, 345-353. Slemrod, Joel (1985), The Return to Tax Simplification: An Econometric Analysis, National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper, No. 1756. Slemrod, Joel (1989a), ‘Are Estimated Tax Elasticities Really Just Tax Evasion Elasticities? The Case of Charitable Contributions’, 71 Review of Economics and Statistics, 517-522. Slemrod, Joel (1989b), Optimal Taxation and Optimal Tax Systems, National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper, No. 3038. Slemrod, Joel (1992a), ‘Why People Pay Taxes: Introduction’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 1-8. Slemrod, Joel (1992b), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 361 p. Slemrod, Joel and Yitzhaki, Shlomo (1998), ‘Tax Avoidance, Evasion and Administration’, in Auerbach, Alan and Feldstein, Martin (eds), Handbook in Public Economics, North-Holland, Amsterdam. Slemrod, Joel B. (1985b), ‘An Empirical Test for Tax Evasion’, 67 Review of Economics and Statistics, 232-238. Slemrod, Joel B. (1989c), ‘Complexity, Compliance Costs, and Tax Evasion’, in Roth, Jeffrey A. and Scholz, John T. (eds), Taxpayer Compliance, Philadelphia, University of Pennsylvania Press. Smith, Andrew M.C. (1991), ‘The Implications of the Commissioner’s Statement on Section 99: New Zealand’, 45 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 60-66. Smith, Kent W. (1992), ‘Reciprocity and Fairness: Positive Incentives for Tax Compliance’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 223-250. Smith, Rodney T. (1976), ‘The Legal and Illegal Markets for Taxed Goods: Pure Theory and Application to State Governement Taxation of Distilled Spirits’, 19 Journal of Law and Economics, 393-429. Snavely, Keith (1990), ‘Governmental Policies to Reduce Tax Evasion: Coerced Behavior versus Services and Values Development’, 23 Policy Sciences, 57-72. Soldatos, Gerasimos T. (1994), ‘An Analysis of the Conflict between Underground Economy and Tax Evasion’, 213 Jahrbuch für Nationalökonomie und Statistik, 292-304. Sommerhalder, Ruud A. and Elffers, Henk (1994), ‘Compliance Effects of Some European Tax Reforms’, 11 Australian Tax Forum, 185-202. Son, Gwang Lag (1991), A Model of Tax Compliance with Endogenous Probability of Audit, University of Washington, Ph.D. Spicer, Michael W. (1986), ‘Civilization at a Discount: The Problem of Tax Evasion’, 39 National Tax Journal, 13-20. Spicer, Michael W. (1987), ‘The Effect of Tax Evasion on Tax Rates under Leviathan’, 40 National Tax Journal, 625-628.
6020
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
91
Spicer, Michael W. (1990), ‘On the Desirability of Tax Evasion: Conventional versus Constitutional Economic Perspectives’, 45 Public Finance, 119-127. Spicer, Michael W. and Becker, Lee A. (1980), ‘Fiscal Inequity and Tax Evasion: An Experimental Approach’, 33(2) National Tax Journal, 171-175. Spicer, Michael W. and Hero, Rodney E. (1985), ‘Tax Evasion and Heuristics: A Research Note’, 26 Journal of Public Economics, 263-267. Spicer, M.W. and Lundstedt, S.B. (1976), ‘Understanding Tax Evasion’, 31 Public Finance, 295-305. Spiro, Peter S. (1994), ‘The Underground Economy: Toward a More Balanced View of Alternative Methodologies’, 2 Canadian Business Economics, 18-21. Sproule, Robert A. (1985), ‘Tax Evasion and Labor Supply under Imperfect Information about Individual Parameters of the Tax System’, 40 Public Finance, 441-456. Sproule, Robert, Komus, David and Tsang, Eric (1980), ‘Optimal Tax Evasion: Risk-neutral Behaviour under a Negative Income Tax’, 35 Public Finance, 309-317. Srinivasan, T.N. (1973), ‘Tax Evasion: A Model’, 2 Journal of Public Economics, 339-346. Steenbergen, Marco R., McGraw, Kathleen M. and Scholz, John T. (1992), ‘Taxpayer Adaptation to the 1986 Tax Reform Act: Do New Tax Laws Affect the Way Taxpayers Think about Taxes?’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 9-37. Stella, Peter (1991), ‘An Economic Analysis of Tax Amnesties’, 46 Journal of Public Economics, 383-400. Stella, Peter (1993), ‘Tax Farming: A Radical Solution for Developing Country Tax Problems?’, International Monetary Fund Staff Papers, 217 ff. Stern, Jerrold J. (1993), Advances in Taxation. Volume 5. A Research Annual, Greenwood, JAI Press, 272 p. Steuerle, C. Eugene (1992), ‘Taxpayer Adaptation to the 1986 Tax Reform Act: Do New Tax Laws Affect the Way Taxpayers Think about Taxes? Commentary’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 38-41. Stroope, John C. (1988), An Empirical Analysis of the Impact of ERTA and TEFRA on Tax Compliance, Pennsylvania Economic Association. Proceedings of the Third Annual Meeting, May 27 and 28, 1988. University Park: Pennsylvania State University. Stroope, John C. (1991), ‘Changing Perceptions of Taxation and the Impact of Recent Tax Legislation on Tax Compliance and Budget Deficits’, in Long, Stanley G. (ed.), Pennsylvania Economic Association: Proceedings of the Sixth Annual Meeting, May 23-25, 1991, Johnstown, University of Pittsburgh, 178-186. Tanzi, V. (1991), Public Finance in Developing Countries, Aldershot, Edward Elgar. Tanzi, Vito and Shome, Parthasarathi (1994), ‘International: A Primer on Tax Evasion’, 48 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 328-337. Tauchen, Helen V., Witte, Ann Dryden and Beron, Kurt J. (1989), Tax Compliance: An Investigation Using Individual TCMP Data, National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper, No. 3078. Thalmann, Philippe (1992), ‘Factor Taxes and Evasion in General Equilibrium’, 22 Regional Science and Urban Economics, 259-283. Thomas, J. (1992), Informal Economic Activity, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press. Thurman, Quint C. (1991), ‘Taxpayer Noncompliance and General Prevention: An Expansion of the Deterrence Model’, 46 Public Finance, 289-298.
92
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
6020
Tillmann, Georg (1992), Tax Evasion in an Open Economy, Universitat Bonn Sonderforschungsbereich 303 Discussion Paper, No. A-377. Toma, Eugenia Froedge and Toma, Mark (1992), ‘Tax Collection with Agency Costs: Private Contracting or Government Bureaucrats?’, 59 Economica, 107-120. Tomasic, Roman and Pentony, Brendan (1991), ‘Tax Compliance and the Rule of Law: From Legalism to Administrative Procedure?’, 8 Australian Tax Forum, 85-116. Tower, Edward (1989), ‘Excise Tax Evasion: Comment’, 44 Public Finance, 506-509. Trandel, Gregory (1992), Essays on Commodity Taxation: Evasion, Tax Competition, and the Form of the Tax, Princeton University, Ph.D. Trandel, Gregory A. (1992), ‘Evading the Use Tax on Cross-Border Sales: Pricing and Welfare Effects’, 49 Journal of Public Economics, 313-331. Troup, Edward (1992), ‘Unacceptable Discretion: Countering Tax Avoidance and Preserving the Rights of the Individual’, 13(4) Fiscal Studies, 128-138. Udell, Michael A. (1995), Essays in Applied Economics: New Techniques in Aggregate Data Analysis, California Institute of Technology, Ph.D. Urbiztondo, Santiago (1993), ‘Un Sistema de Incentivos para Mejorar la Recaudacion Impositiva (An Incentive System to Improve the Impositive Collecting. With English Summary)’, 39 Economica (National University of La Plata), 141-162. Usher, Dan (1986), ‘Tax Evasion and the Marginal Cost of Public Funds’, 24 Economic Inquiry, 563-586. Van Raaij, W. Fred, van Veldhoven, Gery M. and Warneryd, Karl Erik (1988), Handbook of Economic Psychology, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 683 p. Viren, Matti (1992), ‘Financial Innovations and Currency Demand: Some New Evidence’, 17 Empirical Economics, 451-461. Virmani, Arvind (1989), ‘Indirect Tax Evasion and Production Efficiency’, 39 Journal of Public Economics, 223-237. Vogel, Kenneth R. (1974), ‘Taxation and Public Opinion in Sweden: An Interpretation of Recent Survey Data’, 27(4) National Tax Journal, 499-513. von Zameck, Walburga (1989), ‘Tax Evasion and Tax Revenue Loss: Another Elaboration of the Peacock-Shaw Approach’, 44 Public Finance, 308-315. Wadhawan, Satish C. (1992), ‘Evasion, Partial Detection and Optimal Tax Policy’, 47(Suppl) Public Finance, 372-383. Wahlund, Richard (1992), ‘Tax Changes and Economic Behavior: The Case of Tax Evasion’, 13 Journal of Economic Psychology, 657-677. Wallschutzky, Ian (1991), ‘Reforming a Tax System to Reduce Opportunities for Tax Evasion: Australia’, 45 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 165-175. Wallschutzky, Ian G. and Gibson, Brian (1993), ‘Small Business Cost of Tax Compliance’, 10 Australian Tax Forum, 511-543. Wang, Leonard F.S. (1990), ‘Tax Evasion and Monopoly Output Decisions with Endogenous Probability of Detection’, 18 Public Finance Quarterly, 480-487. Wang, Leonard F.S. and Conant, John L. (1988), ‘Corporate Tax Evasion and Output Decisions of the Uncertain Monopolist’, 41 National Tax Journal, 579-581. Wang, Xuejun (1995), ‘Equilibrium Models of Asset Pricing with Progressive Taxation and Tax Evasion’, 2 Applied Economics Letters, 440-443. Watson, Harry (1985), ‘Tax Evasion and Labor Markets’, 27 Journal of Public Economics, 231-246.
6020
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
93
Waud, Roger N. (1985), ‘Tax Aversion, Deficits and the Tax Rate - Tax Revenue Relationship’, National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper. Waud, Roger N. (1988), ‘Tax Aversion, Optimal Tax Rates, and Indexation’, 43 Public Finance, 310-325. Webley, Paul, Cowell, Frank A., Long, Susan B. and Swingen, Judyth A. (1991), Tax Evasion: An Experimental Approach. European Monographs in Social Psychology, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Webley, Paul, Robben, Henry and Morris, Ira (1988), ‘Social Comparison and Tax Evasion in a Shop Simulation’, in Maital, Shlomo (ed.), Applied Behavioural Economics Volume 2, New York, New York University Press, 553-561. Weck-Hannemann, Hannelore and Pommerehne, Werner W. (1989), ‘Einkommenssteuerhinterziehung in der Schweiz. Eine empirische Analyse (An Empirical Analysis of Income Tax Evasion in Switzerland)’, 125(4) Schweizerische Zeitschrift für Volkswirtschaft und Statistik, 515-556. Westat, Inc. (1980), Individual Income Tax Compliance Factors Study: Qualitative Research Results, Prepared for the Internal Revenue Service, Rockville, MD. White, Michelle J. (1990), Why are Taxes So Complex and Who Benefits?, University of Michigan Center for Research on Economic and Social Theory Working Paper, No. 90-7. Wickerson, John (1994), ‘Measuring Taxpayer Compliance: Issues and Challenges Facing Tax Administrations’, 11 Australian Tax Forum, 1-44. Wiegand, Bruce (1993), ‘Petty Smuggling as “Social Justice”: Research Findings from the Belize-Mexico Border’, 42 Social and Economic Studies, 171-193. Wirth, Andrew (1994), ‘Changing Taxpayer Compliance: The Impact of Business Auditors as Service Providers’, 11 Australian Tax Forum, 63-84. Witte, Ann Dryden and Woodbury, Diane F. (1985), ‘The Effect of Tax Laws and Tax Administration on Tax Compliance: The Case of the U.S. Individual Income Tax’, 38 National Tax Journal, 1-13. Wolf, Holger, C. (1993), Anti-Tax Revolutions and Symbolic Prosecutions, National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper, No. 4337. Wrede, Matthias (1995), ‘Tax Evasion and Risk Taking: Is Tax Evasion Desirable?’, 50(2) Public Finance, 303-316. Wrede, Matthias (1995), ‘Tax Evasion and Growth’, 8(2) Finnish Economic Papers, 82-90. Yamada, Masatoshi (1990), ‘An Analysis of Optimal Taxation with Tax Evasion’, 45 Public Finance, 470-490. Yaniv, Gideon (1986), ‘Fraudulent Collection of Unemployment Benefits: A Theoretical Analysis with Reference to Income Tax Evasion’, 30 Journal of Public Economics, 369-383. Yaniv, Gideon (1988), ‘Withholding and Non-withheld Tax Evasion’, 35 Journal of Public Economics, 183-204. Yaniv, Gideon (1990a), ‘On the Interpretation of the Income Effect in Tax Evasion Models’, 45 Public Finance, 235-239. Yaniv, Gideon (1990b), ‘Tax Evasion under Differential Taxation: The Economics of Income Source Misreporting’, 43 Journal of Public Economics, 327-337. Yaniv, Gideon (1994), ‘Tax Evasion and the Income Tax Rate: A Theoretical Reexamination’, 49 Public Finance, 107-112.
94
Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance
6020
Yaniv, Gideon (1995), ‘A Note on the Tax-Evading Firm’, 48 National Tax Journal, 113-120. Yankelovich, Skelly and White, Inc. (1984), ‘Taxpayer Attitudes Study: Final Report. Public opinion survey prepared for the Public Affairs Division’, Internal Revenue Service, New York. Yitzhaki, Shlomo (1974), ‘A Note on Income Tax Evasion: A Theoretical Analysis’, 3 Journal of Public Economics, 201-202. Yitzhaki, Shlomo (1987), ‘On the Excess Burden of Tax Evasion’, 15 Public Finance Quarterly, 123-137. Yitzhaki, Shlomo and Vakneen, Yitzhak (1989), ‘On the Shadow Price of a Tax Inspector’, 44 Public Finance, 492-505. Zheng, Kangbin (1992), Four Essays on Linear Tax Evasion Games, Georgetown University, Ph.D.
Other References Beccaria, Cesare (1764), ‘An Attempt at an Analysis of Smuggling (Tentativo Analitico sui Contrabbandi)’, Il Caffè, Brescia, Italy, 118-199, in Baumol, William J. and Goldfeld, S. (eds), Precursors in Mathematical Economics: An Anthology, London, London School of Economics and Political Science. Border, K. and Sobel, J. (1987), ‘Samurai Accountant: A Theory of Auditing and Plunder’, 54(4) Review of Economic Studies, 525-540. Elfers, H., Weigel, R. and Hessing, D. (1987), ‘The Consequences of Different Strategies Measuring Tax Evasion Behavior’, 8 Journal of Economic Psychology, 311-337. Mookherjee, D. and Png, I. (1995), ‘Corruptible Law Enforcers: How Should they be Compensated?’, 105(428) Economic Journal, 145-159. Roth, J. and Scholtz, J. (eds) (1989), Taxpayer Compliance, Vol. 2: Social Science Perspectives, University of Pennsylvania Press, Philadelphia. Saltzman, L., Paternoster, R., Waldo, G. and Chiricos, T. (1982), ‘Deterrent and Experiental Effects: The Problem of Causal Order in Perceptual Deterrence Research’, 19 Journal of Research on Crime and Delinquency, 172-189. Scotchmer, Suzanne (1987), ‘Audit Classes and Tax Enforcement Policy’, 77(2) American Economic Review, 229-233. Scotchmer, Suzanne (1989), ‘The Effect of Tax Advisors on Tax Compliance’ in Roth, J. and Scholtz, J. (eds), Taxpayer Compliance, Vol. 2, University of Pennsylvania Press, Philadelphia. Slemrod, Joel and Yitzhaki, Shlomo (1987), ‘The Optimal Size of a Tax Collection Agency’, 89(2) Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 183-192. Thomas, J. (1992), Informal Economic Activity, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press.
6030 PROPERTY TAXES David L. Cameron Professor of Law, Willamette University, College of Law © Copyright 1999 David L. Cameron
Abstract The consideration of property taxation has long been a part of the development of economic analysis beginning with the French Physciocrats, through Ricardo, and then George. As a result, the economic literature concerning property taxation is vast. This chapter surveys an important slice of that literature which considers the incidence of property taxes. Over the past thirty years, three theories have been proposed to describe the economic effect of property taxes. The ‘Traditional View’ suggests that, because of the fixed supply of land, taxes on land will be borne by the owners or renters of land. The ‘New View,’ however, concludes that a tax on land is largely equivalent to a general tax on all capital. Finally, the ‘Benefit View’ suggests that property taxes are appropriately viewed, not as a tax, but as an efficient user charge for local public services. Empirical study to date has not determined whether the new view or the benefit view is the more appropriate model of property taxation. JEL classification: H2, H22, K3, K34 Keywords: Property Taxation, Economic Rent, User Fee, Fiscal Zoning
1. Introduction Property taxes are typically defined to encompass those taxes levied on both real and personal property that are dependent on the value of the property itself. Generally, a property tax is administered through the use of a uniform tax rate imposed on the assessed value of the property subject to tax. Within a given jurisdiction, the tax rates frequently vary depending on the type or class of property being taxed. More importantly perhaps for comparative purposes, property tax systems vary significantly across jurisdictions with respect to the types of property that comprise the tax base as well as the exclusions for specific types of property, the assessment techniques used to determine the value of the property subject to the tax, and the tax rates applicable to the various classes of property. Within the United States, the property tax is the principal source of revenue for county and municipal governments. The economic literature that considers the law of property taxation is extremely broad in scope. Economists have developed various theories 95
96
Property Taxes
6030
concerning the incidence of property taxes and have conducted empirical studies to test those theories. The study of property taxation is closely tied to the study of the provision of public goods as any general equilibrium analysis of property taxation must consider the public benefits provided through a system of property taxation. The following discussion will consider the three principal models of the incidence of property taxes, and in particular the taxation of land, that form the basis for the examination of property taxes from an economic perspective. These economic models of property taxation have also served as the basis for public policy proposals under which differential property tax rates or assessment procedures could be used to protect agricultural lands or encourage development in urban areas. Economists have also examined the administration of property tax systems, including the proper assessment procedures for the valuation of property for tax purposes.
A. Conceptual History of the Property Tax 2. Survey As described by Winfrey (1973), as well as Buchanan and Flowers (1975), property taxes were one of the earliest forms of taxation to be considered from an economic perspective. Beginning with the French Physiocrats of the mid-eighteenth century, including Francois Quesnay their leader, early economists concluded that property, and more specifically land, was the only logical base for taxation. The Physiocrats viewed agricultural land as the only ‘productive’ sector of the economy, producing a surplus over the real costs of production. All other sectors of the economy simply provided services or transformed goods from one form to another. The English classical economist David Ricardo also maintained that land was the appropriate factor of production to be taxed. According to Ricardo, increases in population increased the demand for agricultural goods, thus causing more marginal lands to be brought into use. Because greater labor was necessary to make these more marginal lands productive, Ricardo reasoned that these greater costs would be reflected in higher prices for agricultural goods. These higher prices, in turn, increased the return to the owners of the more productive land who did not confront the greater costs of production applicable to the more marginal lands. According to Ricardo, this increased return or ‘rent’ represented ‘the original and indestructible powers of the soil’. Ricardo maintained that this ‘surplus’ should be taxed as it did not represent a real cost of production. The views of the Physciocrats and Ricardo served as the basis for the single tax movement which gained strong support in the United States at the end of the nineteenth century under Henry George. George (1879) maintained that the
6030
Property Taxes
97
return on land represented an economic rent that could be taxed away without distorting the allocation of resources that would otherwise result in the absence of the tax. In today’s terminology, an economic rent is defined as the return to any factor of production in excess of that which the factor could receive in its next best employment. Thus, the taxing of only the economic rent attributable to any particular factor will not result in the transfer of that factor from its current use to an alternative use. In addition, the Georgists maintained that any increase in the value of land resulting from growth in the economy was viewed as a surplus created by society that could rightfully be taxed. As stated by George: Taxes levied upon the value of land cannot check production in the slightest degree, until they exceed rent, or the value of land taken annually, for unlike taxes upon commodities, or exchange, or capital, or any of the tools or processes of production, they do not bear upon production. The value of land does not express the reward of production, as does the value of crops, of cattle, of buildings, or of any of the things which are styled personal property or improvements. It expresses the exchange value of a monopoly. It is not in any case the creation of the individual who owns the land; it is created by the growth of the community. Hence the community can take it all without in any way lessening the incentive to improvement or in the slightest degree lessening the production of wealth. Taxes may be imposed upon the value of land until all rent is taken by the State, without reducing the wages of labor or the reward of capital one iota; without increasing the price of a single commodity, or making production in any way more difficult. (George, 1879, p. 413)
George’s claim that a tax on the value of land is nondistortionary has been supported by modern commentators such as Wildasin (1982), Vickrey (1970), and Tideman (1982) provided the tax is imposed on pure land rentals, defined as the value of the land independent of anything that might be done with the land, and not, as Bentick (1982) and Mills (1981) point out, on the current market value of land which reflects present and future uses of the land. Unfortunately, the Physciocrats, Ricardo, and George all failed to recognize that rents may be attributable to all factors of production. Under a marginal analysis, each factor of production - labor and capital, as well as land - will receive the value of its marginal product in a competitive economy. Land alone cannot be viewed as receiving the residual value of all production. As noted by Fischel (1985, pp. 16-17), ‘the only economic difference between land and the other factors of production is that [land] is fixed in supply by virtue of its immobility’. As discussed below, this characteristic - the fixed supply of land as a result of its immobility - remains important in understanding the economic effects of property taxation.
98
Property Taxes
6030
In the United States, the use of property taxation is largely limited to state and local jurisdictions. In addition, revenues collected through the imposition of property taxes on personal property has declined in relation to the imposition of property taxes on real property (Netzer, 1966). Although George’s single tax movement was never fully implemented, principally because of administrative difficulties (Holland, 1970), it remains visible in those property tax regimes under which land is more heavily taxed than other forms of property (Oates and Schwab, 1997).
B. The Modern Theoretical Framework 3. Overview Economists have developed three principal theories under which the incidence of property taxation has been considered. Importantly, each theory distinguishes between taxes on land and taxes on capital. The observation that a property tax may have a differential effect on land as opposed to other forms of capital results from the difference in elasticity of the supply of each item. Based on the assumption that the supply of land subject to taxation in a given jurisdiction is fixed, the ‘Traditional View’ suggests that taxes on land will be borne by the users of land, that is, the owners or renters of the land (Netzer, 1966). The ‘New View,’ however, concludes that a local tax on land can be broken into two components, a ‘profits tax’ and an ‘excise tax’ (Mieszkowski, 1972b; Aaron 1975). Because the profits tax component is equivalent to a general tax on all capital, that portion of any property tax will fall on the owners of all capital. Finally, the ‘Benefit View’ suggests that property taxes are appropriately viewed as a user charge for local public services (Hamilton, 1975b, 1976b; Fischel, 1985, 1992). Because consumers of public services are mobile, the benefits view suggests that a property tax is in many situations is an efficient financing mechanism for public services.
4. The Traditional View The traditional view of property taxes was originally articulated by Simon (1943) and Netzer (1966). The traditional view adopts a partial-equilibrium approach under which property taxes are considered as separate payments for capital and land. The supply of capital is considered to be perfectly elastic, and the supply of land is considered to be perfectly inelastic. As shown in Figure 1, the return to owners of capital is at a nationally determined rental rate for capital (Rn). If a jurisdiction enacts an ad valorem property tax (t) on capital,
6030
Property Taxes
99
the price of capital will rise to Rn (1 + t) in order to maintain an after-tax return on capital of Rn and the amount of capital in the jurisdiction will fall from C0 to C1. This effect can be modeled as a decline in the demand for capital from D to D'. This effect will also occur if the jurisdiction enacts an increase in the rate of an existing property tax.
If the ad valorem property tax is also imposed on the jurisdiction’s perfectly inelastic supply of land, the result is the perfect capitalization of the tax in the return of the land. As shown in Figure 2, the return on the land will fall from Rn to Rn (1- t). Nevertheless, because the supply of land in the jurisdiction is fixed, the tax has no effect on the quantity of land but results only in a reduction in the price of land.
100
Property Taxes
6030
The traditional view has been employed to conclude that the imposition of a property tax on residential land is regressive in nature. This conclusion is based on the assumption that the proportion of income spent on housing falls as income rises. Based on the traditional view, Netzer (1966), however, concluded that, in the aggregate, the property tax was more nearly proportional than regressive. Nevertheless, with respect to housing, Netzer recognized that the property tax was regressive based on empirical studies available at that time. Netzer (1973) later cautioned that studies concluding that the property tax was regressive in nature were biased because they typically adopted current income rather than normal or permanent income. He hypothesized that the regressive aspects of the property tax would be diminished if the studies, like consumers themselves when making housing decisions, considered income prospects over periods longer than a single year.
5. The New View The new view of property taxation was originally developed by Thomson (1965), Mieszkowski (1972b) and Aaron (1975) and reformulated byMieszkowski and Zodrow (1986). The new view adopts a general equilibrium analysis for all jurisdictions in a country, and assumes that both the capital in the country and the land in any one jurisdiction are fixed.
6030
Property Taxes
101
As described by Wassmer (1993), the analysis underlying the new view is often simplified by assuming that only three types of jurisdictions exist which differ in the demand for local services - low, medium, and high. In the short run, property, which is made up of capital as well as land, is considered fixed in each jurisdiction at P0. Prior to the introduction of the tax, the return on capital is at a nationally determined rate, Rn. Following the introduction of the tax, the return on capital declines by the amount of the tax in the same manner as that described under the traditional view for land alone. The decline will be greatest in the jurisdiction for which the demand for services is highest as greater revenues are necessary to provide the services demanded. As shown in Figure 3, the return declines to Rh1 in the high demand jurisdiction, Rm1 in the medium demand jurisdiction, and Rl1 in the low demand jurisdiction. The decline in the return on property in the medium-demand type jurisdiction from Rn to Rm1 has been referred to as the ‘profits tax’ effect, a decline in the market value of property across all jurisdictions by the average rate of taxation. (Zodrow and Mieszkowski, 1989). The profits tax effect is exacerbated in the high-demand type jurisdiction by a negative ‘excise tax’ effect equal to the difference between Rh1 and Rm1 resulting from a higher tax rate in the high-demand type jurisdiction as compared to the medium-demand type. The profits tax effect is partially offset, however, in the low-demand type jurisdiction by a positive excise tax effect equal to the difference between R11 and Rm1 resulting from a lower tax rate in the low-demand type jurisdiction as compared to the medium-demand type jurisdiction. Because the relative return on property among the three types of jurisdictions differ and because capital is assumed to be perfectly mobile in the long run, capital will exit the high-demand type jurisdiction where the return on property is the lowest, decreasing the supply of property in that jurisdiction from P0 to P1. This capital will enter the low-demand type jurisdiction where the return on property is the highest, increasing the supply of property in that jurisdiction from P0 to P1. The decrease in the supply of property in the high-demand type jurisdiction will increase the return on property from Rh1 to Rh2. The increase in the supply of property in the low-demand type jurisdiction will decrease the return on property from Rl1 to Rl2. Equilibrium will be achieved when the after-tax return on property is equalized across all three types of jurisdictions at Rh2, Rm1, and Rl2. Importantly, however, the excise tax effects of the property tax, as described above, will result in distortionary effects in the high- and low-demand type jurisdictions.
102
Property Taxes
6030
Figure 3
As shown in Figure 3, the rental rates paid for property in the three types of jurisdictions differ. The rental rate in the high-demand type jurisdiction, Rh3, exceeds the rental rate in the medium-demand type jurisdiction, Rn, which, in turn, exceeds the rental rate in the low-demand type jurisdiction, Rl3. To the extent that the higher rental rates in high-demand type jurisdictions are not offset by increased utility from higher service levels, individuals may move from high-demand type jurisdictions to medium- or low-demand type jurisdictions. Conversely, to the extent that higher rental rates are offset by increased utility from higher service levels, individuals may move from low-demand type jurisdictions to medium- or high-demand type jurisdictions. Such a movement would cause rental rates across all three types of jurisdictions to converge but, unless individuals are assumed to be perfectly mobile, rent differentials will persist. Unlike the traditional view, the incidence of the property tax under the new view is generally seen as progressive. This is because the property tax results principally in a decline in the return on capital by the ‘average’ rate of taxation in the nation. Because capital is disproportionately held by those with higher incomes, Mieszkowski and Zodrow (1989) conclude that the profits tax portion of any property tax under the new view is ‘highly progressive’.
6. The Benefit View The benefit view, which extends the analysis of the new view, includes within its analysis the benefits conferred on property owners through property taxes. As developed by Hamilton (1975b, 1976b), the benefit view adopts the assumptions underlying the new view but also assumes the perfect mobility of
6030
Property Taxes
103
individual consumers and the ability of jurisdictions to engage in fiscal zoning. If the provision of public services is viewed as a public good, the new view suggests that incentives exist to utilize land in a high-demand type jurisdiction in such a manner that the benefit of public services exceeds the burden of the property tax. The benefit view assumes that jurisdictions will engage in fiscal zoning under which the value of the housing units permitted within the jurisdiction will be restricted to some minimum value, typically through the use of the jurisdiction’s zoning authority or through some other power to control land uses and intensities. At this minimum value, the revenues generated through the property tax will exactly offset the value of the public services obtained. The benefit view, thus, follows a Tiebout (1956) model under which the property tax becomes a head tax or nondistortionary user charge for public services. Assuming a sufficiently large number of jurisdictions within a larger metropolitan region offering a diversity of public services and assuming further the mobility of consumers for those services, the property tax represents an efficient means of financing the provision of public services. Importantly, the benefit view does not require that any particular jurisdiction be homogenous with respect to residential values. Hamilton (1976b) demonstrated that, in heterogenous communities, differentials between benefits received through public services and taxes paid will be capitalized into the price of the property. Fischel (1975) and White (1975a) have extended the benefit view to the taxation of commercial and industrial property. Viewing the property tax as a head tax or a user charge for the provision of public services under the benefit view, the concerns involving the progressivity or regressivity of the property tax under the traditional and new views do not arise based on the relationship between the property tax and the provision of public goods and services and the assumption of consumer mobility.
7. Evidence Concerning the Validity of the Alternative Theories Commentary and empirical studies concerning the validity of the traditional, new, and benefit views have reached no definitive results. For example, Netzer (1973), a proponent of the traditional view, suggests that the lack of uniformity of the property tax, at least on a national level in the United States, means that it is not even ‘sensible’ to speak of a partial tax on capital (such as a property tax in only one jurisdiction) in terms of a tax that lowers the average rate of return on all capital as proposed under the new view. This observation is disputed by Mieszkowski and Zodrow (1989) who suggest that the work of Lin (1986) concludes otherwise. The proponents of the new view have suggested, in turn, that little evidence exists to support the view that jurisdictions engage in perfect fiscal zoning or that any benefit or burden differentials are perfectly capitalized into the value
104
Property Taxes
6030
of property as required by the benefit view. Nevertheless, Fischel (1985, 1992) suggests that the multi-dimensional land use restrictions available to communities under typical zoning enabling acts can be effective mechanisms to engage in fiscal zoning. In addition, Fischel (1992) maintains that the widespread use of exactions or impact fees may directly substitute for expenditures otherwise financed by property taxes. The existence and relative importance of exactions and impact fees are typically overlooked in studies of the property tax itself. Fischel (1989) also maintains that the benefit view is supported by voter hostility towards property taxation when the level of benefits typically paid for through the imposition of property taxes, such as expenditures for education, are no longer related to the property taxes paid. Fischel suggests that the overwhelming voter support for property tax reduction in California in 1978 under Proposition 13 was the result of the California Supreme Court’s 1976 decision in Serrano v. Priest (135 Cal. Rptr. 345) requiring stringent equality in spending per pupil across California school districts. Empirical studies of various types have not succeeded in fully determining whether the new view or the benefit view provides the more valid description of the property tax. As summarized by Mieszkowski and Zodrow (1989), the majority of empirical studies have focused on the extent to which property taxes and local government expenditures are capitalized into property values. These studies by Oates (1969), Edel and Sclar (1974), and Hamilton (1976b, 1983) as well as others indicate that property taxes and government expenditures are capitalized into property values. This observation does not confirm the benefit view, however, because the new view also implies some capitalization. The existence of capitalization of benefits, such as school quality, further supports the benefits view (Gurwitz, 1980; Hoxby, 1997). Responding to the suggestion of Mieszkowski and Zodrow (1989, p. 1131), Wassmer (1993), Carroll and Yinger (1994) and Man (1995) conducted studies considering changes in the aggregate value of the property tax base and intermetropolitan rent differentials. The results of these studies support the new view’s conception of the property tax as, at least in part, a distortionary tax on capital. Wildasin (1986a) has suggested that neither the new view nor the benefit view may be entirely correct, however, and that, because of imperfect fiscal zoning and imperfect capitalization, the property tax may best be considered as a combination of a capital tax and user charge. Despite the fact that the benefit view has not been entirely validated based on empirical study, it has focused inquiry on the question whether property taxation can be properly analyzed in isolation from the public goods and services that it finances. This aspect of the benefits view, in turn, has spurred more recent research into the political behavior of local governments, particularly in the area of tax competition as governments compete for capital through adjustments in property tax rates (Coates, 1993; Edwards and Keen, 1996; Nechyba, 1997).
6030
Property Taxes
105
Bibliography on Property Taxes (6030) Aaron, Henry J. (1969), ‘Some Observations on Property Tax Valuation and the Significance of Full Value Assessment’, in Lynn, A.D., Jr (ed.), The Property Tax and Its Administration, Madison, University of Wisconsin. Aaron, Henry J. (1973), ‘What Do Circuit-Breaker Laws Accomplish?’, in Peterson, George E. (ed.), Property Tax Reform, Washington, DC, Urban Institute Press. Aaron, Henry J. (1974), ‘A New View of Property Tax Incidence’, 64 American Economic Review, 212-221. Aaron, Henry J. (1975), Who Pays the Property Tax? A New View, Washington, Brookings Institution. Agapos, A.M. and Dunlap, Paul R. (1973), ‘Elimination of Urban Blight Through Inverse Proportional Ad Valorem Property Taxation’, 32 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 143-152. Almy, Richard R. (1977), ‘The Impact of Assessment Practices Upon Assessment Performance’, in Analyzing Assessment Equity: Techniques for Measuring and Improving the Quality of Property Tax Administration, Chicago, Illinois, International Association of Assessment Officers. Anderson, John E. (1986), ‘Property Taxes and the Timing of Land Development’, 16 Regional Science and Urban Economics, 483-492. Anderson, John E. and Bunch, Howard C. (1989), ‘Agricultural Property Tax Relief: Tax Credits, Tax Rates, and Land Values’, 65 Land Economics, 13-22. Andrews, R.B. and Dasso, Jerome J. (1961), ‘The Influence of Annexation on Property Tax Burdens’, 14 National Tax Journal, 88-97. Arnott, Richard J. and MacKinnon, James G. (1977), ‘The Effects of the Property Tax: A General Equilibrium Simulation’, 4 Journal of Urban Economics, 389-407. Arnott, Richard J. and Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1979), ‘Aggregate Land Rents, Expenditure on Public Goods, and Optimal City Size’, 93 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 471-500. Aronson, J. Richard (1966), ‘Intangible Taxes - A Wisely Neglected Revenue Source for States’, 19 National Tax Journal, 184-186. Ashworth, John and Gemmell, Norman (1996), ‘Local Governments’ Monopoly Power and Local Tax Reform: Theory and Evidence from the U.K.’, 89 Public Choice, 393-417. Auerbach, Alan J. (1981), ‘Taxation of Wealth’, in Eatwell, John, Milgate, Murray and Newman, Peter (eds), The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, New York, Stockton Press. Aull, G.H. (1959), ‘The Situation and Outlook for Property Taxation in the South’, 12 National Tax Journal, 86-92. Back, Kenneth (1970), ‘Land Value Taxation in Light of Current Assessment Theory and Practice’, in Beck, Athur P. (ed.), The Assessment of Land Value - A Symposium, Committee on Taxation, Resources and Economic Development, Madison, University of Wisconsin. Bahl, Roy (ed.) (1979), The Taxation of Urban Property in Less Developed Countries, Madison, University of Wisconsin. Bahl, Roy (ed.) (1991), The Jamaican Tax Reform, Cambridge, MA, Lincoln Institute of Land Policy. Bahl, Roy and Linn, Johannes F. (1992), Urban Public Finance in Developing Countries, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Bahl, Roy, Sjoquist, David Lawrence and Williams, W. Loren (1990), School Finance Reform and Impact on Property Taxes, Proceedings of the Eighty-Third Annual Conference on Taxation, National Tax Association-Tax Institute of America.
106
Property Taxes
6030
Barkume, Anthony (1976), ‘Criteria for Voting Judgments on a Property Tax Initiative: An Analysis of the Watson Amendment’, 29 National Tax Journal, 448-460. Barnes, Ralph and Raymond, George (1955), ‘The Fiscal Approach to Land Use Planning’, 21 Journal of the American Institute of Planners, 2-3. Barr, James L. and Davis, Otto A. (1966), ‘An Elementary Political and Economic Theory of the Expenditures of Local Governments’, 33 Southern Economic Journal, 149-165. Bartik, Timothy J. (1991), ‘The Effects of Property Taxes and Other Local Public Policies on the Intrametropolitan Pattern of Business Location’, in Herzog, Henry W., Jr and Schlottmann, Alan M. (eds), Industry Location and Public Policy, Knoxville, Tennessee, University of Tennessee Press. Bates, Laurie J. and Santerre, Rexford E. (1993), ‘Property Tax Collector Performance and Pay’, 46 National Tax Journal, 23-31. Beck, John H. (1983), ‘Tax Competition, Uniform Assessment, and the Benefit Principle’, 13 Journal of Urban Economics, 127-146. Beck, John H. (1993), ‘Tax Abatements and Tax Rates in a System of Overlapping Revenue-Maximizing Governments’, 23 Regional Science and Urban Economics, 645-665. Beck, Morris (1963), Property Taxation and Urban Land Use in Northeastern New Jersey, Washington, DC, Urban Land Institute. Beck, Morris (1965), ‘Determinants of the Property Tax Level: A Case Study of Northeastern New Jersey’, 18 National Tax Journal, 74-77. Becker, Arthur P. (ed.) (1969), Land and Building Taxes: Their Effect on Economic Development - A Symposium, Committee on Taxation, Resources, and Economic Development, Madison, University of Wisconsin. Becker, Arthur P. (ed.) (1970), The Assessment of Land Value - A Symposium, Committee on Taxation, Resources, and Economic Development, Madison, University of Wisconsin. Behrens, John O. (1980), ‘Property Taxes and Property Values: What’s New About Base, Burden, and Other Mysteries’, in Tron, Esther O. (ed.), Public School Finance Programs, Washington, DC, U.S. Government Printing Office. Bell, Earl J. (1984), ‘Administrative Inequity and Property Assessment: The Case for the Traditional Approach’, 3 Property Tax Journal, 123-131. Bendick, Marc, Jr (1974), ‘Designing Circuit-Breaker Property Tax Relief’, 27 National Tax Journal, 19-28. Bennion, Fred W. (1958), ‘Veteran Tax Exemption in Wyoming’, 11 National Tax Journal, 377-378. Benson, G.C.S., Benson, Sumner, McClelland, Harold and Thomson, Procter (1965), The American Property Tax: Its History, Administration and Economic Impact, Claremont, California, Claremont College Print Service. Bentick, Brian L. (1972), ‘Improving the Allocation of Land Between Speculators and Users: Taxation and Paper Land’, 48 Economic Record, 18-41. Bentick, Brian L. (1974), ‘The Allocation of Land Between Speculators and Users under a Land Ownership Tax: Reply’, 50 Economic Record, 451-452. Bentick, Brian L. (1979a), ‘The Impact of Taxation and Valuation Practices on the Timing and Efficiency of Land Use’, 87 Journal of Political Economy, 859-868. Bentick, Brian L. (1979b), ‘The Capitalization of the Property Tax and Idle Land’, 55 Land Economics, 545-548. Bentick, Brian L. (1980a), ‘Property and Income Taxation in Rural Industries with Different Rotation Periods’, 33 National Tax Journal, 219-225.
6030
Property Taxes
107
Bentick, Brian L. (1980b), ‘Capitalized Property Taxes and the Viability of Rural Enterprise Subject to Urban Pressure’, 56 Land Economics, 451-456. Bentick, Brian L. (1982), ‘A Tax on Land Value May Not be Neutral’, 35 National Tax Journal, 113 ff. Bentick, Brian L. (1996), ‘The Differential Incidence of an Urban Land Tax Depends on the Travel Intensities of Substitutes for Land’, 33 Urban Studies, 1729-1732. Bentick, Brian L. and Pogue, Thomas F. (1988), ‘The Impact on Development Timing of Property and Profit Taxation’, 64 Land Economics, 317-324. Berglas, Eitan (1982), ‘User Charges, Local Public Services, and Taxation of Land Rents’, 32 Public Finance, 178-188. Bevins, Robert J. (1975), ‘Real Property Taxes and Farm Real Estate Values: Incidence and Implications: Comment’, 57 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 725 ff. Billings, R. Bruce and Folsom, Roger Nils (1980), ‘Voter Perception of Property Tax Incidence as Revealed by School Expenditure Decisions’, 33 National Tax Journal, 459-471. Birch, John W., Sunderman, Mark A. and Hamilton, Thomas W. (1990), ‘Adjusting for Vertical Inequity in Property Assessment’, 3 Property Tax Journal, 197-211. Bird, Frederick L. (1960), The General Property Tax: Findings of the 1957 Census of Governments, Chicago, Illinois, Public Administration Service. Bird, Richard M. (1960), ‘A National Tax on the Unimproved Value of Land: The Australian Experience 1910-52', 13 National Tax Journal, 386-392. Bird, Richard M. (1976), ‘The Incidence of the Property Tax: Old Wine in New Bottles’, 4 Canadian Public Policy, 323-334. Bird, Richard M. (1993), ‘Threading the Fiscal Labyrinth: Some Issues in Fiscal Decentralization’, 46 National Tax Journal, 207-227. Black, David E. (1972), ‘The Nature and Extent of Effective Property Tax Rate Variation Within the City of Boston’, 25 National Tax Journal, 203-210. Black, David E. (1974), ‘The Incidence of Differential Property Taxes on Urban Housing: Some Further Evidence’, 27 National Tax Journal, 367-369. Black, David E. (1977), ‘Property Tax Incidence: The Excise-Tax Effect and Assessment Practices’, 30 National Tax Journal, 429-434. Blackburn, John O. (1965), ‘Intangibles Taxes: A Neglected Revenue Source for States’, 18 National Tax Journal, 214-218. Blank, David M. (1954), ‘The Role of the Real Property Tax in Municipal Finance’, 7 National Tax Journal, 319-326. Bloom, Howard S. (1979), ‘Public Choice and Private Interest: Explaining the Vote for Property Tax Classification in Massachusetts’, 32 National Tax Journal, 527-534. Bloom, Howard S. and Ladd, Helen F. (1982), ‘Property Tax Revaluation and Tax Levy Growth’, 11 Journal of Urban Economics, 73-84. Boadway, Robin W. (1982), ‘On the Method of Taxation and the Provision of Local Public Goods: Comment’, 72 American Economic Review, 846-851. Bogart, William T. and Bradford, David F. (1989), ‘Incidence and Allocation Effects of the Property Tax and a Proposal for Reform’, 45 Tax Notes, 223-234. Borgia, Daniel (1994), ‘How a Land Value Tax System Promotes Economic Development’, 9 Real Estate Finance Journal, 89 ff. Borland, Melvin and Lile, Stephen (1980), ‘The Property Tax Rate and Assessment Uniformity’, 33 National Tax Journal, 99-102. Boskin, Michael J. (1973), ‘Local Government Tax and Product Competition and the Optimal Provision of Public Goods’, 81 Journal of Political Economy, 203-210.
108
Property Taxes
6030
Botha, D. (1971), ‘Towards a New Variant of Property Taxation’, 39 South African Journal of Economics, 1-12. Bourassa, Steven C. (1987), ‘Land Value Taxation and New Housing Development in Pittsburgh’, 18 Growth and Change, 44-55. Bourassa, Steven C. (1990), ‘Land Value Taxation and Housing Development: Effects on the Property Tax Reform in Three Types of Cities’, 49 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 101-111. Bourassa, Steven C. (1992), ‘Economic Effects of Taxes on Land: A Review’, 51 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 109-113. Bowman, John H. (ed.) (1995), Taxation of Business Property: Is Uniformity Still a Valid Norm?, Westport, Connecticut, Greenwood, Praeger Publishing Company. Bowman, John H. and Mikesell, John (1978), ‘Uniform Assessment of Property: Returns From Institutional Remedies’, 31 National Tax Journal, 137-152. Bowman, John H., Hoffer, George E. and Pratt, Michael D. (1990), ‘Current Patterns and Trends in State and Local Intangible Taxation’, 43 National Tax Journal, 439-450. Bradbury, Katherine, Ladd, Helen F., Perrault, Michael, Reschovsky, Andrew and Yinger, John (1984), ‘State Aid to Offset Fiscal Disparities Across Communities’, 37 National Tax Journal, 151-170. Bradbury, Katherine and Ladd, Helen F. (1987), ‘City Property Taxes: The Effects of Economic Change and Competitive Pressures’, 1989 New England Economic Review, 22-36. Bradford, David F., Malt, R.A. and Oates, Wallace E. (1969), ‘The Rising Cost of Local Public Services: Some Evidence and Reflections’, 22 National Tax Journal, 185-202. Bradley, James F. (1988), ‘Property Tax Proposals for the Republic of Ireland’, British Tax Review, 446-461. Brainin, David and Germanis, John J. (1967), ‘Comments on “Distribution of Property, Retail Sales and Personal Income Tax Burdens in California: An Empirical Analysis of Inequity in Taxation” by Gerhard N. Rostvold’, 20 National Tax Journal, 106-111. Brazer, Harvey E. (1961),’The Value of Industrial Property as a Subject of Taxation’, 55 Canadian Public Administration, 137-147. Brazer, Harvey E. (ed.) (1967), Essays in State and Local Finance, Ann Arbor, Michigan, University of Michigan, Institute of Public Administration. Break, George F. (1974), ‘The Incidence and Economic Effects of Taxation’, in The Economics of Public Finance, Washington, DC, Brookings Institution. Bridges, Benjamin (1964a), ‘The Elasticity of the Property Tax Base: Some Cross Section Estimates’, 40 Land Economics, 449-451. Bridges, Benjamin (1964b), ‘Income Elasticity of the Property Tax Base’, 17 National Tax Journal, 253-264. Brown, Harry Gunnison (1924), The Economics of Taxation, New York, NY, Henry Holt and Company. Brown, Harry Gunnison (1955), Land Taxation Around the World, New York, NY, Robert Schalkenbach Foundation. Brown, J. Bruce (1968), ‘The Incidence of Property Taxes Under Three Alternative Systems in Urban Areas in New Zealand’, 21 National Tax Journal, 237-252. Brueckner, Jan K. (1979), ‘Property Values, Local Public Expenditure, and Economic Efficiency’, 11 Journal of Public Economics, 223-245. Brueckner, Jan K. (1981a), ‘Zoning and Property Taxation in a System of Local Governments: Further Analysis’, 18 Urban Studies, 113-120. Brueckner, Jan K. (1981b), ‘Labor Mobility and the Incidence of the Residential Property Tax’, 10 Journal of Urban Economics, 173-182.
6030
Property Taxes
109
Brueckner, Jan K. (1982), ‘A Test for Allocative Efficiency in the Local Public Sector’, 19 Journal of Public Economics, 311-331. Brueckner, Jan K. (1986), ‘A Modern Analysis of the Effects of Site Value Taxation’, 39 National Tax Journal, 49-58. Buchanan, James M. and Flowers, Marilyn R. (1975), The Public Finances: An Introductory Textbook, 4th edn, Homewood , IL, Richard D. Irwin. Buchanan, James M. and Weber, Bruce A. (1982), ‘Growth in Residential Property Taxes: A Model for Estimating Direct and Indirect Population Impacts’, 58 Land Economics, 324-337. Buehler, Alfred G. (1939), Property Taxes, Tax Policy League, Inc. Buehler, Alfred G. (1950), ‘The Capitalization of Taxes’, 3 National Tax Journal, 283-297. Buehler, Alfred G., St. George, John F., Long, Henry F., Bird, Frederick L., Pond, Chester B. and Soule, Raymond L. (1948), ‘Improving the Property Tax: New England Tax Conference’, 1 National Tax Journal, 369-372. Calvo, Guillermo A., Kotlikoff, Laurence J. and Rodriquez, Carlos Alfredo (1979), ‘The Incidence of a Tax on Pure Rent: A New (?) Reason for an Old Answer’, 87 Journal of Political Economy, 869-874. Carlton, Dennis W. (1981), ‘The Spacial Effects of a Tax on Housing and Land’, 11 Regional Science and Urban Economics, 509-527. Carman, Hoy F. and Polson, Jim G. (1971), ‘Tax Shifts as a Result of Differential Assessment of Farmland: California, 1968-69', 24 National Tax Journal, 449-457. Carroll, Robert J. and Yinger, John (1994), ‘Is the Property Tax a Benefit Tax? The Case of Rental Housing’, 47 National Tax Journal, 295-316. Case, Karl E. (1978), Property Taxation: The Need for Reform, Cambridge, MA, Ballinger. Case, Karl E. and Grant, James H. (1991), ‘Property Tax Incidence in a Multijurisdictional Neoclassical Model’, 19 Public Finance Quarterly, 379-392. Cebula, Richard J. (1982), ‘Property Taxation and Prices: An Exploratory Note’, 17 Review of Business and Economic Research, 85-87. Chang, Cyril F. and Tuckman, Howard P. (1990), ‘Do Higher Property Tax Rates Increase the Market Share of Nonprofit Hospitals?’, 43 National Tax Journal, 175-187. Cheng, Pao Lun (1970), ‘The Common Level of Assessment in Property Taxation’, 23 National Tax Journal, 50-65. Cheng, Pao Lun (1974), ‘Property Taxation, Assessment Performance and Its Measurement’,29 Public Finance Quarterly, 268-284. Cheng, Pao Lun and Edwards, Alfred L. (1959), ‘Compensatory Property Taxation: An Alternative’, 12 National Tax Journal, 270-275. Cheng, Yung-Ping (1965), ‘Present Status and Fiscal Significance of Property Tax Exemptions for the Aged’, 18 National Tax Journal, 162-174. Ching, C.T.K. and Frick, G.E. (1970), ‘Effect of Use Value Assessment on Property Tax Rates’, 52 American Journal of Agricultural Research, 603-606. Chinloy, Peter T. (1978), ‘Effective Property Taxes and Tax Capitalization’, 11 Canadian Journal of Economics, 740-750. Church, Albert M. (1974), ‘Capitalization of the Effective Property Tax Rate on Single Family Residences’, 27 National Tax Journal, 113-122. Church, Albert M. (1981), ‘The Effects of Local Government Expenditures and Property Taxes on Investment’, 9 American Real Estate and Urban Economics Association Journal, 165-180. Clapp, John M. (1990), ‘A New Test for Equitable Real Estate Tax Assessment’, 3 Journal of Real Estate Finance and Economics, 233-249. Clatanoff, Robert M. (1986), Patterns of Property Tax Administration in the U.S., Research and
110
Property Taxes
6030
Information Series, No. 5, Chicago, Illinois, International Association of Assessment Officers. Coates, Dennis (1993), ‘Property Tax Competition in a Repeated Game’, 23 Regional Science and Urban Economics, 111-119. Coen, Robert M. and Powell, Brian J. (1972), ‘Theory and Measurement of the Incidence of Differential Property Taxes on Rental Housing’, 25 National Tax Journal, 211-216. Colberg, Marshall R. (1955), ‘Utility Profits: A Substitute for Property Taxes’, 8 National Tax Journal, 382-387. Coughlin, Robert E. and Isard, Walter (1957), Municipal Costs and Revenues Resulting from Community Growth, Wellesley, Massachusetts, Chandler-Davis Publishing Company. Coughlin, Robert E., Berry, David and Plaut, Thomas (1979), ‘Differential Assessment of Real Property as an Incentive to Open Space Preservation and Farmland Retention’, 31 National Tax Journal, 165-179. Courant, Paul N. (1977), ‘A General Equilibrium Model of Heterogenous Local Property Taxes’, 8 Journal of Public Economics, 313-327. Courant, Paul N., Gramlich, Edward M. and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1979), ‘Tax Limitation and the Demand for Public Services in Michigan’, 32 National Tax Journal, 147-157. Cowing, T.G. (1974), ‘Real Property Taxes, Local Government Services and Residential Property Values: Comment’, 41 Southern Economic Journal, 325-329. Daicoff, Darwin W. (1967), ‘Capitalization of the Property Tax’, in Brazer, Harvey E. (ed.), Essays in State and Local Finance, Ann Arbor, Michigan, University of Michigan, Institute of Public Administration. Davenport, Herbert Joseph (1917), ‘Theoretical Issues in the Single Tax’, 7 American Economic Review, 1-30. David, E.L. and Skurski, Roger B. (1966), ‘Property Tax Assessment and Absentee Owners’, 19 National Tax Journal, 421-426. Davies, Edgar J. (1948), ‘The Louisana Property Tax Relief Fund: A Source of Financial Assistance for Local Governments’, 1 National Tax Journal, 270-272. Davis, Otto and Wertz, Kenneth (1969), ‘The Consistency of the Assessment of Property: Some Empirical Results and Managerial Suggestions’, 1 Applied Economics, 151-157. Davisson, Malcolm M. and Schmelzle, William K. (1950), ‘Equalization of Property Tax Assessments in California’, 3 National Tax Journal, 221-232. De Tray, Dennis and Fernandez, Judith (1986), ‘Distributional Impacts of the Property Tax Revolt’, 39 National Tax Journal, 435-450. Deaton, Brady J. and Mundy, S. Darrell (1975), ‘Real Property Taxation and Farm Real Estate Values: Incidence and Implications: Comment’, 57 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 125-126. Delipalla, Sophia and Keen, Michael (1992), ‘The Comparison Between ad Valorem and Specific Taxation Under Imperfect Competition’, 49 Journal of Public Economics, 351-367. DeSalvo, Joseph S. (1971), ‘Effects of the Property Tax on Operating and Investment Decisions of Rental Property Owners’, 24 National Tax Journal, 45-50. DeSalvo, Joseph S. (1973), ‘Effects of the Property Tax on Operating and Investment Decisions of Rental Property Owners: Reply’, 26 National Tax Journal, 129-131. Diamond, Stephen (1983), ‘The Death and Transfiguration of Benefit Taxation: Special Assessments in Nineteenth-Century America’, 12 Journal of Legal Studies, 201-240. Dimasi, Joseph A. (1986), ‘Property Tax Classification and Welfare in Urban Areas: A General Equilibrium Computational Approach’, 23 Journal of Urban Economics, 131-149. Dimasi, Joseph A. (1987), ‘The Effects of Site Value Taxation in an Urban Area: A General
6030
Property Taxes
111
Equilibrium Computational Approach’, 40 National Tax Journal, 577-590. DiPasquale, Denise and Wheaton, William C. (1996), Urban Economics and Real Estate Markets, Englewood Cliffs, NJ, Simon and Schuster, Prentice Hall. Do, A. Quang and Sirmans, C.F. (1994), ‘Residential Property Tax Capitalization: Discount Rate Evidence from California’, 47 National Tax Journal, 341-348. Dornfest, Alan S. (1993), ‘Assessment Ratio Study Issues: 1992 Survey Results’, 12 Property Tax Journal, 3 ff. Douglas, Richard W., Jr (1980), ‘Site Value Taxation and the Timing of Land Development’, 39 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 289-294. Dowding, Keith, John, Peter and Biggs, Stephen (1994), ‘Tiebout: A Survey of the Empirical Literature’, 31 Urban Studies Abstracts, 767-797. Due, John F. (1961), ‘Studies of State-Local Tax Differences on Location of Industry’, 14 National Tax Journal, 163-173. Due, John F. (1963), Government Finance, An Economic Analysis, Homewood, IL, Richard D. Irwin. Dushansky, Richard, Ingber, Melvin and Karatjas, Nicholas (1981), ‘The Impact of Property Taxation on Housing Values and Rents’, 10 Journal of Urban Economics, 240-255. Eaton, Jonathan (1988), ‘Foreign-Owned Land’, 78 American Economic Review, 76-88. Ebel, Robert D. and Ortbal, James (1989), ‘Direct Residential Property Tax Relief’, 15 Intergovernmental Perspective, 9-14. Eckart, Wolfgang (1983), ‘The Neutrality of Land Taxation in an Uncertain World’, 36 National Tax Journal, 237-241. Eckert, Joseph K. (ed.) (1990), Property Tax Appraisal and Assessment Administration, Chicago, Illinois, International Association of Assessing Officers. Edel, Matthew and Sclar, Elliot (1974), ‘Taxes, Spending, and Property Values: Supply Adjustment in a Tiebout-Oates Model’, 82 Journal of Political Economy, 941-954. Edwards, J. and Keen, Michael (1996), ‘Tax Competition and Leviathan’, 40 European Economic Review, 113-134. Ellis, Larry V., Combs, J. Paul and Weber, William (1983), ‘Administrative Inequity in the Property Tax: Further Evidence’, 11 Public Finance Quarterly, 491-506. Engle, Robert F. (1975), ‘De Facto Discrimination in Residential Assessments: Boston’, 28 National Tax Journal, 445-451. Epple, Dennis, Filimon, Radu and Romer, Thomas (1993), ‘Existence of Voting and Housing Equilibrium in a System of Communities With Property Taxes’, 23 Regional Science and Urban Economics, 585-610. Erickson, Robert A. and Wollover, David R. (1987), ‘Local Tax Burdens and the Supply of Business Sites in Suburban Municipalities’, 27 Journal of Regional Science, 25-37. Feldman, Edward S. (1949), ‘Exemption of House Furnishings from Property Taxation’, 2 National Tax Journal, 334-342. Feldstein, Martin S. (1977), ‘The Surprising Incidence of a Tax on a Pure Rent: A New Answer to an Old Question’, 85 Journal of Political Economy, 349-360. Fischel, William A. (1975), ‘Fiscal and Environmental Considerations in the Location of Firms in Suburban Communities’, in Mills, Edwin S. and Oates, Wallace E. (eds), Fiscal Zoning and Land Use Controls, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Fischel, William A. (1976), ‘An Evaluation of Proposals for Metropolitan Sharing of Commercial and Industrial Property Tax Base’, 3 Journal of Urban Economics, 253-263. Fischel, William A. (1980), ‘Zoning and Land Use Reform: A Property Rights Perspective’, 1 Virginia Journal of Natural Resources Law, 69-93. Fischel, William A. (1981), ‘Is Local Government Structure in Large Urbanized Areas Monopolistic
112
Property Taxes
6030
or Competitive?’, 34 National Tax Journal, 95-104. Fischel, William A. (1985), The Economics of Zoning Laws: A Property Rights Approach to American Land Use Controls, Baltimore, MD, John Hopkins University Press. Fischel, William A. (1989), ‘Did Serrano Cause Proposition 13?’, 42 National Tax Journal, 465-474. Fischel, William A. (1992), ‘Property Taxation and the Tiebout Model: Evidence for the Benefit View from Zoning and Voting’, 30 Journal of Economic Literature, 163-169. Fischel, William A. (1995), ‘Review of: “Property Taxes and Tax Revolts: The Legacy of Proposition 13"’, 33 Journal of Economic Literature, 239-240. Fischel, William A. (1996), ‘How Serrano Caused Proposition 13', 12 Journal of Law and Politics, 407-434. Fischel, William A. and Campbell, Colin D. (1996), ‘Preferences for School Finance Systems: Voters versus Judges’, 49 National Tax Journal, 1-15. Fisher, Glen W. (1987), ‘The Evolution of the General Property Tax in the Nineteenth Century: The Search for Equality’, 6 Property Tax Journal, 99-117. Fisher, Peter S. (1980), ‘Adjustments for Household Size in Property Tax Circuit-Breaker Programs’, 33 National Tax Journal, 161-170. Flaherty, Shelia M. (1992), ‘Property Tax Limitations: Do We Need a New Approach for the 1990s?’, 45 Tax Lawyer, 827-843. Follain, James R. and Miyake, Tamar Emi (1986), ‘Land Versus Capital Taxation: A General Equilibrium Analysis’, 39 National Tax Journal, 451-470. Frech, H. Edward III, Deacon, Rovert, Decanio, Stephen J. and Johnson, Bruce M. (1990), Taxing Energy: Oil Severence Taxation and the Economy, New York, Holmes and Meyer. Fuerst, J.S. and Ditton, Andrew (1975), ‘Reducing Property Taxes: An Evaluation of a Collective Action’, 51 Land Economics, 94-97. Fullerton, Don and Gordon, Roger H. (1983), ‘A Reexamination of Tax Distortions in General Equilibrium Models’, in Feldstein, Martin S. (ed.), Behavioral Simulation Methods in Tax Policy Analysis, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Fullerton, Don and Henderson, Yolanda K. (1984), ‘Incentive Effects of Taxes on Income from Capital: Alternative Policies in the 1980s’, in Hulten, Charles R. and Sawhill, Isabel V. (eds), The Legacy of Reaganomics: Prospects for Long-Term Growth, Washington, Urban Institute Press. Funk, Gerald M. and Kryscio, Richard J. (1978), ‘Equity and the Property Tax: Comments on Two Seemingly Unrelated Conceptual Frameworks’, 31 National Tax Journal, 411-413. Gaffney, Mason (1972), The Property Tax is a Progressive Tax, Proceedings of the Sixty-Fourth Annual Conference on Taxation, Columbus, Ohio, National Tax Association, 1972. Gaffney, Mason (1972), ‘What is Property Tax Reform?’, 31 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 139-152. Gaffney, Mason (1973), ‘An Agenda for Strengthening the Property Tax’, in Peterson, George E. (ed.), Property Tax Reform, Washington, Urban Institute Press. Garwood, John D. (1952), ‘Taxes and Industrial Location’, 5 National Tax Journal, 365-369. Garwood, John D. (1956), ‘Kansas Citizens Examine Their Property Taxes’, 9 National Tax Journal, 258-267. George, Henry (1879), Progress and Poverty, New York, NY, Robert Schalkenbach Foundation. George, Henry (1883), Social Problems, New York, NY, Robert Schalkenbach Foundation.
6030
Property Taxes
113
George, Henry (1885), Land and Taxation, Our Land and Land Policy, Speeches, Lectures, and Miscellaneous Writings, New York, NY, National Single Tax League. Geraci, Vincent J. (1977), ‘Measuring the Benefits from Property Tax Assessment Reform’, 30 National Tax Journal, 195-205. Geraci, Vincent J. and Plourde, James L. (1976), ‘The Determinants of Uniform Property Tax Assessment’, 11 Assessors Journal, 235-251. Ghaus, Aisha, F.A. and Pasha, Hafiz A. (1996), ‘Excess Burden of the Property Tax: The Open Jurisdiction Case’, 24 Public Finance Quarterly, 120-128. Gibb, Kenneth (1992), ‘The Council Tax: The Distributional Implications of Returning to a Tax on Property’, 39 Scottish Journal of Political Economy, 302-317. Glaeser, E.L. (1996), ‘The Incentive Effects of Property Taxes on Local Government’, 89 Public Choice, 93-111. Gold, Steven D. (1976), ‘A Note on Designing Property Tax Circuit-Breakers’, 29 National Tax Journal, 477-481. Gold, Steven D. (1979), Property Tax Relief, Lexington, MA, Heath. Gold, Steven D. (1981), ‘Homeowner Property Taxes, Inflation and Property Tax Relief’, 34 National Tax Journal, 167-184. Goodman, Allen C. (1978), ‘Hedonic Prices, Price Indices, and Housing Markets’, 5 Journal of Urban Economics, 471-484. Goodman, Allen C. (1983), ‘Capitalization of Property Tax Differentials Within and Among Municipalities’, 59 Land Economics, 211-219. Goodman, Allen C. (1988), ‘An Econometric Model of Housing Price, Permanent Income, Tenure Choice, and Housing Demand’, 23 Journal of Urban Economics, 327-353. Gouldemans, Robert (1974), Use-Value Farmland Assessments: Theory, Practice, Impacts, Chicago, Illinois, International Association of Assessing Officers. Grieson, Ronald E. (1973), ‘Effects of the Property Tax on Operating and Investment Decisions of Rental Property Owners: A Note’, 26 National Tax Journal, 127-128. Grieson, Ronald E. (1974), ‘The Economics of Property Taxes and Land Values: The Elasticity of Supply of Structures’, 1 Journal of Urban Economics, 367-381. Grieson, Ronald E. (1975), ‘The Incidence of Profits Taxes in a Neoclassical Growth Model’, 4 Journal of Public Economics, 75-85. Gronouski, John A. (1957), ‘State Supervision of Property Tax Administration’, 10 National Tax Journal, 158-170. Groves, Harold M. (1967), ‘Property Taxation of Intangibles’, in Lindholm, Richard W. (ed.),Property Taxation USA, Madison, Wisconsin, University of Wisconsin Press. Groves, Harold M. and Kahn, C. Harry (1952), ‘The Stability of State and Local Tax Yields’, 42 American Economic Review, 87-102. Groves, Harold M. and Riew, John (1963), ‘The Impact of Industry on Local Taxes - A Simple Model’, 16 National Tax Journal, 137-146. Gurwitz, Aaron S. (1980), ‘The Capitalization of School Finance Reform’, 5 Journal of Education Finance, 297-319. Gustely, Richard D. (1976), ‘Local Taxes, Expenditures and Urban Housing: A Reassessment of the Evidence’, 42 Southern Economic Journal, 659-665. Gyourko, Joseph and Tracy, Joseph (1989), ‘On the Political Economics of Land Value Capitalization and Local Public Sector Rent Seeking in a Tiebout Model’, 26 Journal of Urban Economics, 152-173. Hady, Thomas F. (1962), ‘The Incidence of the Personal Property Tax’, 15 National Tax Journal, 368-384. Hady, Thomas F. (1970), ‘Differential Assessment of Farmland on the Rural-Urban Fringe’, 52 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 25-32.
114
Property Taxes
6030
Haig, Robert Murray (1914), A History of the General Property Tax in Illinois, Illinois, Urbana, Illinois, University of Illinois Studies in the Social Sciences. Hall, James K. (1956a), ‘Sales-Assessment Ratio Survey in Washington’, 9 National Tax Journal, 177-192. Hall, James K. (1956b), ‘Assessment Equalization in Washington’, 9 National Tax Journal, 302-325. Hamilton, Bob and Whalley, John (1985), ‘Tax Treatment of Housing in a Dynamic Sequenced General Equilibrium Model’, 27 Journal of Public Economics, 157-175. Hamilton, Bruce W. (1975a), ‘Property Taxes and the Tiebout Hypothesis: Some Empirical Evidence’, in Mills, Edwin S. and Oates, Wallace E. (eds), Fiscal Zoning and Land Use Controls, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books, 13-29. Hamilton, Bruce W. (1975b), ‘Zoning and Property Taxation in a System of Local Governments’, 12 Urban Studies, 205-211. Hamilton, Bruce W. (1976a), ‘The Effects of Property Taxes and Local Public Spending on Property Values: A Theoretical Comment’, 84 Journal of Political Economy, 647-650. Hamilton, Bruce W. (1976b), ‘Capitalization of Intrajurisdictional Differences in Local Tax Prices’, 66 American Economic Review, 743-753. Hamilton, Bruce W. (1977), ‘Local Government, the Property Tax, and the Quality of Life: Some Findings on Progressivity’, in Wingo, Lowdon and Evans, Alan (eds), Public Economics and the Quality of Life, Baltimore, MD, John Hopkins Press for Resources for the Future. Hamilton, Bruce W. (1979), ‘Capitalization and the Regressivity of the Property Tax: Empirical Evidence’, 32 National Tax Journal, 169-180. Hamilton, Bruce W. (1983), ‘A Review: Is the Property Tax a Benefit Tax?’, in Zodrow, George R. (ed.), Local Provision of Public Services: The Tiebout Model After Twenty-Five Years, New York, Academic Press. Hansen, David E. and Schwartz, Seymour I. (1975), ‘Landowner Behavior at the Rural-Urban Fringe in Response to Preferential Taxation’, 51 Land Economics, 341-354. Hansmann, Henry B. (1991), ‘Condominium and Co-operative Housing: Transactional Efficiency, Tax Subsidies, and Tenure Choice’, 20 Journal of Legal Studies, 25-71. Harmon, O.R. (1989), ‘A New View of the Incidence of the Property Tax: The Case of New Jersey’, 17 Public Finance Quarterly, 323-348. Harriss, C. Lowell (1952), ‘The British Revaluation of Real Estate for Local Taxation’, 5 National Tax Journal, 239-244. Harriss, C. Lowell (1968), ‘Economic Evaluation of Real Property Taxation’, in Connery, Robert H. (ed.), Municipal Income Taxes, Academy of Political Science Proceedings, New York, Columbia University Press. Harriss, C. Lowell (1974), ‘Property Taxation: What’s Good and What’s Bad About It’, 33 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 89-102. Harriss, C. Lowell (ed.) (1983), The Property Tax and Local Finance, New York, NY, Academy of Political Science. Haurin, Donald (1980), ‘The Effect of Property Taxes on Urban Areas’, 7 Journal of Urban Economics, 384-396. Haurin, Donald (1981), ‘Property Taxation and the Structure of Urban Areas’, in Henderson, J. Vernon (ed.), Research in Urban Economics, Vol. 1, Greenwood, JAI Press. Heilbrun, James (1966), Real Estate Taxes and Urban Housing, New York, Columbia University Press. Heinburg, John D. and Oates, Wallace E. (1970), ‘The Incidence of Differential Property Taxes on
6030
Property Taxes
115
Urban Housing: A Comment and Some Further Evidence’, 23 National Tax Journal, 92-98. Heinburg, John D. and Oates, Wallace E. (1972), ‘The Incidence of Differential Property Taxes on Rental Housing: An Addendum’, 25 National Tax Journal, 221-222. Hellerstein, Jerome R. (1959), ‘Judicial Review of Property Tax Assessments’, 14 Tax Law Review, 327-352. Hellman, Daryl A. and Sifniotis, Costas (1977), ‘Distributional Considerations of Property Tax Exemption: An Analytical Framework’, 5 Public Finance Quarterly, 127-136. Henderson, J. Vernon (1985), ‘Property Tax Incidence Within a Public Sector’, 93 Journal of Political Economy, 649-665. Henderson, J. Vernon (1994), ‘Community Choice of Revenue Instruments’, 24 Regional Science and Urban Economics, 159-183. Henderson, J. Vernon (1995), ‘Will Homeowners Impose Property Taxes?’, 25 Regional Science and Urban Economics, 153-181. Henry, Edward L. (1951), ‘The Farmer’s Tax Burden’, 4 National Tax Journal, 341-350. Hickelman, Jac C. and Wallis, J. (1997), ‘Railroads and Property Taxes’, 34 Explorations in Economic History, 77-99. Hobson, Paul A. R. (1986), ‘The Incidence of Heterogeneous Residential Property Taxes’, 29 Journal of Public Economics, 363-373. Hochman, Oded (1981), ‘Land Rents, Optimal Taxation and Local Fiscal Independence in an Economy with Local Public Goods’, 15 Journal of Public Economics, 59-85. Hoff, Karla (1991), ‘Land Taxes, Output Taxes, and Sharecropping: Was Henry George Right?’, 5 World Bank Economic Review, 93-111. Holland, Daniel M. (ed.) (1970), The Assessment of Land Value, Madison, University of Wisconsin. Holtz-Eakin, Douglas (1986), ‘Unobserved Tastes and the Determination of Municipal Services’, 39 National Tax Journal, 527-532. Holtz-Eakin, Douglas and Rosen, Harvey S. (1989), ‘The ‘Rationality of Municipality Capital Spending: Evidence from New Jersey’, 19 Regional Science and Urban Economics, 517-536. Howards, Irving (1963), ‘Property Tax Rate Limits in Illinois and Their Effect Upon Local Government’, 16 National Tax Journal, 285-293. Hoxby, Coroline Minter (1997), ‘Are Efficiency and Equity in School Finance Substitutes or Complements?’, 10 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 51-72. Hoyt, William H. (1990), ‘Local Government Inefficiency and the Tiebout Hypothesis: Does Competition Among Municipalities Limit Local Government Inefficiencies?’, 57 Southern Economic Journal, 481-496. Hoyt, William H. (1991), ‘Competitive Jurisdictions, Congestion, and the Henry George Theorem: When Should Property be Taxed Instead of Land?’, 21 Regional Science and Urban Economics, 351-370. Hoyt, William H. (1991), ‘Property Taxation, Nash Equilibrium, and Market Power’, 30 Journal of Urban Economics, 123-131. Hyman, David N. and Pasour, Ernest C., Jr (1973a), ‘Real Property Taxes, Local Public Services and Residential Property Values’, 39 Southern Economic Journal, 601-611. Hyman, David N. and Pasour, Ernest C., Jr (1973b), ‘Property Tax Differentials and Residential Rents in North Carolina’, 26 National Tax Journal, 303-307. Hyman, David N. and Pasour, Ernest C., Jr (1974), ‘Real Property Taxes, Local Public Services and Residential Property Values: A Reply’, 41 Southern Economic Journal, 329-331. Ihlanfeldt, Keith (1979), ‘The Incidence of the Property Tax on Homeowners: Evidence from the Panel Study of Income Dynamics’, 32 National Tax Journal, 535-541.
116
Property Taxes
6030
Ihlanfeldt, Keith (1982), ‘Property Tax Incidence on Owner-Occupied Housing: Evidence from the Annual Housing Survey’, 35 National Tax Journal, 89-97. Ihlanfeldt, Keith (1984), ‘Property Taxation and the Demand for Housing: An Econometric Analysis’, 16 Journal of Urban Economics, 208-224. Ihlanfeldt, Keith and Boehm, Thomas P. (1983), ‘Property Taxation and the Demand for Home Ownership’, 11 Public Finance Quarterly, 47-66. Ihlanfeldt, Keith and Jackson, John D. (1982), ‘Systematic Assessment Error and Intrajurisdictional Property Tax Capitalization’, 49 Southern Economic Journal, 417-427. Ihori, Toshihiro (1990), ‘Economic Effects of Land Taxes in an Inflationary Economy’, 42 Journal of Public Economics, 195-211. Inman, Robert P. (1979), ‘The Fiscal Performance of Local Governments: An Interpretative Review’, in Mieszkowski, Peter and Straszheim, Mahlon (eds), Current Issues in Urban Economics, Baltimore, MD, John Hopkins University Press. International Association of Assessing Officers (1992), Assessment Administrative Practices in the U.S. and Canada, Chicago, Illinois. Islam, Mohammed N. (1989), ‘Tiebout Hypothesis and Migration Impact of Local Fiscal Policies’, 44 Public Finance, 406-418. Islam, Mohammed N. and Sahni, Balbir S. (1987), ‘Property Taxation and Regional Public Services in Canada: A Causality Analysis’, 58 Annals of Public and Cooperative Economy, 275-286. Jaffee, Bruce L. (1978), ‘State Taxation of Intangibles: The Problem of Evasion’, 6 Public Finance Quarterly, 485-502. James, F.J. (1975), Assessment Procedures, Community Characteristics and the Accuracy of Property Tax Assessments, Washington, Urban Institute Press. Jensen, Jens P. (1931), Property Taxation in the United States, Chicago, Illinois, University of Chicago Press. Johnson, David B. (1993), ‘A Review of Taxation of Property: Local Government Rates in Victoria’, 61 Review of Marketing and Agricultural Economics, 455-477. Johnson, Dudley W. (1958), ‘A Note on Local Administration of the Property Tax : A Case Study of Bethlehem, Pennsylvania’, 11 National Tax Journal, 265-271. Kanemoto, Yoshitsugu (1985), ‘Housing as an Asset and the Effects of Property Taxation on the Residential Development Process’, 17 Journal of Urban Economics, 145-166. King, A. Thomas (1973), Property Taxes, Amenities, and Residential Land Values, Cambridge, MA, Ballinger. King, A. Thomas (1977), ‘Estimating Property Tax Capitalization: A Critical Comment’, 85 Journal of Political Economy, 425-431. Kish-Goodling, Donna M. (1995), Property Taxes and Local Economic Development, New York, Garland Inc. Kitchen, Harry M. (1987), ‘Property Taxation as a Tax on Wealth: Some New Evidence’, 35 Canadian Tax Journal, 953-963. Kitchen, Harry M. (1992), Property Taxation in Canada, Canadian Tax Paper No. 92, Toronto, Canada, Canadian Tax Foundation. Klemperer, W. David (1974), ‘Forests and the Property Tax - A Re-Examination’, 27 National Tax Journal, 645-651. Klemperer, W. David (1977), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Case Against ad Valorem Property Taxation in Forestry - A Comment’, 30 National Tax Journal, 469 ff. Knapp, John L. (1974), Virginia Issues: The Real Property Tax, Charlottesville, VA, University Press of Virginia. Kochin, Lewis A. and Parks, Richard W. (1982), ‘Vertical Equity in Real Estate Assessment: A Fair
6030
Property Taxes
117
Appraisal’, 20 Economic Inquiry, 511-531. Kochin, Lewis A. and Parks, Richard W. (1984), ‘Testing for Assessment Uniformity: A Reappraisal’, 3 Property Tax Journal, 27-53. Kotlikoff, Laurence J. and Summers, Lawrence H. (1987), ‘Tax Incidence’, in Auerbach, Alan and Feldstein, Martin (eds), Handbook in Public Economics, North-Holland, Amsterdam. Krelove, R. (1992), ‘Do Local Governments Use Their Tax Bases Efficiently’, 31 Journal of Urban Economics, 285-300. Krelove, R. (1993), ‘The Persistence and Inefficiency of Property Tax Finance of Local Public Expenditures’, 51 Journal of Public Economics, 415-435. Kurnow, Ernest (1963), ‘On the Elasticity of the Real Property Tax’, 18 Journal of Finance, 36-38. Ladd, Helen F. (1973), ‘The Role of the Property Tax: A Reassessment’, in Musgrave, Richard A. (ed.), Broad Based Taxes, New and Old, Baltimore, MD, John Hopkins University Press. Ladd, Helen F. (1975), ‘Local Education Expenditures, Fiscal Capacity, and the Composition of the Property Tax Base’, 28 National Tax Journal, 145-158. Ladd, Helen F. (1976a), ‘State Wide Taxation of Commercial and Industrial Property for Education’, 29 National Tax Journal, 143-153. Ladd, Helen F. (1976b), ‘Municipal Expenditures and the Composition of the Property Tax Base’, in Lynn, Arthur D., Jr (ed.), Property Taxation, Land Use, and Public Policy, Washington, Brookings Institution. Ladd, Helen F. (1992), ‘Population Growth, Density and the Cost of Providing Public Services’, 29 Urban Studies, 273-295. Ladd, Helen F. and Bradbury, Katherine (1988), ‘City Taxes and Property Tax Bases’, 41 National Tax Journal, 503-524. Lea, Michael J. (1982), ‘Local Tax and Expenditure Capitalization: Integrating Evidence from the Market and Political Process’, 10 Public Finance Quarterly, 95-117. Lee, Eugene C. (1953), ‘State Equalization of Local Assessments’, 6 National Tax Journal, 177-187. Lent, George E. (1966), Taxation of Unimproved Land Value, Washington, International Monetary Fund. Lent, George E. (1982), ‘Property Taxes in the Carribean Community’, 36 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 439-444. Leonard, Lawrence A. (1958), ‘Property Taxation in Kansas, An Historical Analysis’, 11 National Tax Journal, 230-240. Leong, Y.S. and Kamins, Robert M. (1961), ‘Property Taxation in the 50th State’, 14 National Tax Journal, 59-69. Leroy, Stephen F. (1976), ‘Urban Land Rent and the Incidence of Property Taxes’, 3 Journal of Urban Economics, 167-179. Lewis, Chris W. and McNutt, Paul J. (1979), ‘The Incidence of Property Taxes on Single Family Housing’, 7 American Real Estate and Urban Economics Association Journal, 344-361. Lin, Chuan (1986), ‘A General Equilibrium Analysis of Property Tax Incidence’, 29 Journal of Public Economics, 113-132. Lin, Chuan (1994), ‘Property Taxation as a National Policy Tool in Taiwan’, in Musgrave, Richard A., Chang, Ching-huei and Riew, John (eds), Taxation and Economic Development Among Pacific Asian Countries, Boulder, CO, Westview Press. Lindauer, John H. and Singh, Sarjit (1966), ‘Effects of the Punjab Land Tax’, 19 National Tax Journal, 427-433.
118
Property Taxes
6030
Lindholm, Richard W. (ed.) (1967), Property Taxation USA - A Symposium, Committee on Taxation, Resources, and Economic Development, Madison, Wisconsin, University of Wisconsin Press. Linn, Johannes F. (1980), ‘Property Taxation in Bogota, Columbia: An Analysis of Poor Revenue Performance’, 8 Public Finance Quarterly, 457-476. Lockner, Allyn O. and Kim, Han J. (1973), ‘Circuit-Breakers on Farm-Property-Tax Overload: A Case Study’, 26 National Tax Journal, 233-240. Lowenstein, Louis K. (1963), ‘The Impact of New Industry on the Fiscal Revenues and Expenditures of Suburban Communities’, 16 National Tax Journal, 113-136. Lynn, Arthur D. (1967), ‘Trends in Taxation of Personal Property’, in Buehler, Alfred G. (ed.), The Property Tax: Problems and Potentials, Princeton, NJ, Tax Institute of America. Lynn, Arthur D. (ed.) (1976), Property Taxation, Land Use and Public Policy, Madison, Wisconsin, University of Wisconsin Press. Mair, Douglas (1991), ‘The Incidence of the Property Tax: A Survey’, 13 British Review of Economic Issues, 1-27. Mair, Douglas and Damania, Richard (1988), ‘The Richardian Tradition and Local Property Taxation’, 12 Cambridge Journal of Economics, 435-449. Mair, Douglas and Laramie, Anthony J. (1992), ‘The Incidence of Business Rates on Manufacturing Industry in Scotland and the Rest of the UK’, 39 Scottish Journal of Political Economy, 76-94. Man, Joyce Y. (1995), ‘The Incidence of Differential Commercial Property Taxes: Empirical Evidence’, 48 National Tax Journal, 479-496. Manning, Glenn H. and Thompson, Emmett F. (1969), ‘Forest Property Taxation: Another Look’, 47 Journal of Forestry, 556-559. Manning, Raymond E. (1949), ‘Burden of State and Local Taxes in 18 Large Cities’, 2 National Tax Journal, 173-178. Margolis, Julius (1956a), ‘The Variation of Property Tax Rates Within a Metropolitan Region’, 9 National Tax Journal, 326-330. Margolis, Julius (1956b), ‘On Municipal Land Policy For Fiscal Gains’, 9 National Tax Journal, 247-257. Marshall, Alfred (1890), Principles of Economics, London, Macmillan. Martinez Vazquez, Jorge and Ihlanfeldt, Keith (1987), ‘Why Property Tax Capitalization Rates Differ: A Critical Analysis’, in Quigley, J.M. and Smolensky, E. (eds), Modern Public Finance, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. May, Peter J. (1982), ‘Local Tax Burdens, Benefit Levels and Fiscal Illusion’, 35 National Tax Journal, 465-475. McCluskey, William J. (ed.) (1991), Comparative Property Tax Systems, Aldershot, Ashgate, Avebury. McDonald, John F. (1993), ‘Incidence of the Property Tax on Commercial Real Estate: The Case of Downtown Chicago’, 46 National Tax Journal, 109-120. McDougall, Gerald S. (1976), ‘Local Public Goods and Residential Property Values: Some Insights and Extensions’, 29 National Tax Journal, 436-447. McEachern, William A. (1981), ‘Tax Exempt Property, Tax Capitalization, and the Cumulative-Urban-Decay Hypothesis’, 34 National Tax Journal, 185-192. McGuire, Therese J. (1985), ‘Are Local Property Taxes Important in the Intrametropolitan Location Decisions of Firms? An Empirical Analysis of the Minneapolis-St. Paul Metropolitan Area’, 18 Journal of Urban Economics, 226-234. McGuire, Therese J. (1987), ‘The Effect of New Firm Locations on Local Property Taxes’, 22 Journal of Urban Economics, 223-229.
6030
Property Taxes
119
McLure, Charles E., Jr (1967), ‘The Interstate Exporting of State and Local Taxes: Estimates for 1962', 20 National Tax Journal, 49-77. McLure, Charles E., Jr (1977), ‘The “New View” of the Property Tax - A Caveat’, 30 National Tax Journal, 69-75. McLure, Charles E., Jr (1979), ‘The Relevance of the “New View” of the Incidence of the Property Tax in Developing Countries’, in Bahl, Roy (ed.), The Taxation of Urban Property in Less Developed Countries, Madison, University of Wisconsin. McLure, Charles E., Jr (1981), ‘Market Dominance and the Exporting of State Taxes’, 34 National Tax Journal, 483-485. McLure, Charles E., Jr and Thirsk, Wayne R. (1975), ‘A Simplified Exposition of the Harberger Model, I: Tax Incidence’, 28 National Tax Journal, 24-25. McMillan, Melville and Carlson, Richard (1977), ‘The Effect of Property Taxes and Local Public Services Upon Residential Property Values in Small Wisconsin Cities’, 59 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 81-87. Meng, Ronald (1986), ‘Horizontal Equity and Property Taxation in Canada’, 39 National Tax Journal, 221-228. Meng, Ronald and Gillespie, W. Irwin (1986), ‘The Regressivity of Property Tax in Canada: Another Look’, 34 Canadian Tax Journal, 1417-1430. Metha, Shekhar and Giertz, J. Fred (1996), ‘Measuring the Performance of the Property Tax Assessment Process’, 49 National Tax Journal, 73-85. Meyer, Charles W. (1965), ‘Geographic Inequalities in Property Taxes in Iowa, 1962', 18 National Tax Journal, 388-397. Mieszkowski, Peter (1969), ‘Tax Incidence Theory: The Effects of Taxes on the Distribution of Income’, 7 Journal of Economic Literature, 1103-1124. Mieszkowski, Peter (1972a), ‘On the Theory of Tax Incidence’, 75 Journal of Political Economy, 250-262. Mieszkowski, Peter (1972b), ‘The Property Tax: An Excise or Profits Tax’, 1 Journal of Public Economics, 73-96. Mieszkowski, Peter and Straszheim, Mahlon (eds) (1979), Current Issues in Urban Economics, Baltimore, MD, John Hopkins University Press. Mieszkowski, Peter and Zodrow, George R. (1983), ‘The Incidence of the Property Tax: The Benefit View Versus the New View’, in Zodrow, George R. (ed.), Local Provision of Public Services: The Tiebout Model After Twenty-Five Years, New York, Academic Press. Mieszkowski, Peter and Zodrow, George R. (1989), ‘Taxation and the Tiebout Model: The Differential Effects of Head Taxes, Taxes in Land Rents, and Property Taxes’, 27 Journal of Economic Literature, 1098-1146. Mikesell, John (1992), ‘Patterns of Exclusion of Personal Property from the American Property Tax Systems’, 20 Public Finance Quarterly, 528-542. Mills, David E. (1981), ‘The Non-Neutrality of Land Value Taxation’, 34 National Tax Journal, 125-130. Mills, David E. (1982), ‘Reply to Tideman’, 35 National Tax Journal, 115 ff. Mills, Edwin S. and Oates, Wallace E. (eds) (1975), Fiscal Zoning and Land Use Controls: The Economic Issues, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Miner, Ralph E. (1974), ‘Property Taxes, Services, and Calculating Voters’, 2 Public Finance Quarterly, 139-154. Mitchell, George (1948), ‘Using Sales Data to Measure the Quality of Property Tax Administration’, 1 National Tax Journal, 330-340. Moomau, Pamela H. and Morton, Rebecca B. (1992), ‘Revealed Preferences for Property Taxes: An Empirical Study of Tax Incidence’, 74 Review of Economics and Statistics, 176-179.
120
Property Taxes
6030
Moss, William G. (1977), ‘Large Lot Zoning, Property Taxes, and Metropolitan Area’, 4 Journal of Urban Economics, 408-427. Mullen, John K. (1990), ‘Property Tax Exemptions and Local Fiscal Stress’, 43 National Tax Journal, 467-479. Murphy, Louis S. (1915), ‘The Single Tax in Relation to Forestry’, 18 The Public, 217-223. Murphy, Louis S. (1925), ‘The General Property Tax and Forest Property’, 23 Journal of Forestry, 762-780. Murray, William G. (1952), ‘Improvement in Real Estate Taxation Through Assessment-Sales Studies’, 5 National Tax Journal, 86-92. Murray, William G. and Bivens, Gordon E. (1952), ‘Clinics, Bench Marks, and Improved Assessments’, 5 National Tax Journal, 370-375. Musgrave, Richard A. (1974), ‘Is a Property Tax On Housing Regressive?’, 64 American Economic Review, Papers and Proceedings, 222-229. Musgrave, Richard A. (ed.) (1973), Broad Based Taxes, New and Old, Baltimore, MD, John Hopkins University Press. Musgrave, Richard A. and Musgrave, Peggy B. (1989), Public Finance in Theory and Practice, 5th ed, New York, McGraw-Hill. Musgrave, Richard A., Chang, Ching-huei and Riew, John (eds) (1994), Taxation and Economic Development Among Pacific Asian Countries, Boulder, CO, Westview Press. Myers, Eugene A. and Stout, Randall S. (1950), ‘Recent Trends in Property Tax Equalization’, 3 National Tax Journal, 179-186. Nechyba, Thomas J. (1997), ‘Local Property and State Income Taxes: The Role of Interjurisdictional Competition and Collusion’, 105 Journal of Political Economy, 351-384. Netzer, Dick (1964), ‘Income Elasticity of the Property Tax: A Post-Mortem Note’, 17 National Tax Journal, 205-207. Netzer, Dick (1966), Economics of the Property Tax, Washington, DC, Brookings Institution. Netzer, Dick (1973), ‘The Incidence of the Property Tax Revisited’, 26 National Tax Journal, 515-535. Netzer, Dick (1984), ‘On Modernizing Local Public Finance: Why Aren’t Property Taxes in Urban Areas Being Reformed into Land Value Taxes?’, 43 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 497-501. Netzer, Dick (1993), ‘Property Taxes: Their Past, Present, and Future in Government Finance’, in Swartz, Thomas R. and Bonello, Frank J. (eds), Urban Finance Under Siege, Armonk, NY, Sharpe. Neufeld, Ernest (1965), ‘Is Tax Exempt Property a Municipal Asset?’, 18 National Tax Journal, 414-419. Newcomer, Mabel (1953a), ‘The Decline in the General Property Tax’, 6 National Tax Journal, 38-51. Newcomer, Mabel (1953b), ‘The Growth of Property Tax Exemptions’, 6 National Tax Journal, 116-128. Noguchi, Yukio (1982), ‘On the Neutrality of the Property Tax’, 58 Land Economics, 383-385. Noiset, Luc (1995), ‘Pigou, Property Taxation, and the Underprovision of Local Public Goods: Comment’, 38 Journal of Urban Economics, 312-316. Noonan, Albert W. (1947), ‘Improvements in Personal Property Taxation’, in Groves, Harold M. (ed.), Viewpoints on Public Finance: A Book of Readings, New York, NY, Henry Holt and Company. Note (1962), ‘Inequality in Property Tax Assessment: New Cures for an Old Ill’, 75 Harvard Law
6030
Property Taxes
121
Review, 1374-1395. O’Sullivan, Arthur M., Sexton, Terri A. and Sheffrin, Steven M. (1994), ‘Differential Burdens from the Assessment of Proposition 13', 47 National Tax Journal, 721-729. O’Sullivan, Arthur M., Sexton, Terri A. and Sheffrin, Steven M. (1995), Property Taxes and Tax Revolts: The Legacy of Proposition 13, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Oakland, W.H. (1978), ‘Local Taxes and Intra-Urban Industrial Location: A Survey’, in Break, George (ed.), Metropolitan Financing and Growth Management Policies, Madison, University of Wisconsin. Oates, Wallace E. (1969), ‘The Effects of Property Taxes and Local Public Spending on Property Values: An Empirical Study of Tax Capitalization and the Tiebout Hypothesis’, 77 Journal of Political Economy, 957-971. Oates, Wallace E. (1973), ‘The Effects of Property Taxes and Local Public Spending on Property Values: A Reply and Yet Further Results’, 81 Journal of Political Economy, 994-1003. Oates, Wallace E. (1987), ‘Property Taxation’, in Eatwell, John, Milgate, Murray and Newman, Peter (eds), The New Palgrave, a Dictionary of Economics, New York, The Stockton Press. Oates, Wallace E. and Schwab, Robert M. (1988), ‘Economic Competition Among Jurisdictions: Efficiency Enhancing or Distortion Inducing?’, 35 Journal of Public Economics, 333-354. Oates, Wallace E. and Schwab, Robert M. (1997), ‘The Impact of Urban Land Taxation: The Pittsburgh Experience’, 50 National Tax Journal, 1-21. Oberhauser, Alois (1975), ‘Death Duties and Property Taxation as a Means of More Even Distribution of the Stock of Wealth’, 13 German Economic Review, 1-15. Oldman, Oliver and Aaron, Henry J. (1965), ‘Assessment Sales Ratios Under the Boston Property Tax’, 18 National Tax Journal, 36-49. Ordeshook, Peter C. (1979), ‘Property Tax Consciousness’, 34 Public Choice, 285-295. Orr, Larry L. (1968), ‘The Incidence of Differential Property Taxes on Urban Housing’, 21 National Tax Journal, 253-262. Orr, Larry L. (1970), ‘The Incidence of Differential Property Taxes on Urban Housing: A Response’, 23 National Tax Journal, 99-101. Orr, Larry L. (1972), ‘The Incidence of Differential Property Taxes on Urban Housing: Reply’, 25 National Tax Journal, 217-220. Owen, Michael S. and Thirsk, Wayne R. (1974), ‘Land Taxes and Idle Land: A Case Study of Houston’, 50 Land Economics, 251-260. Paglin, Morton and Fogarty, Michael (1972), ‘Equity and the Property Tax: A New Conceptual Focus’, 25 National Tax Journal, 557-565. Paglin, Morton and Fogarty, Michael (1973), ‘Equity and the Property Tax: A Reply’, 26 National Tax Journal, 651-652. Parai, Amar K. and Beck, John H. (1989), ‘The Incidence of Classified Property Taxes in a Three-Sector Model with an Imperfectly Mobile Population’, 25 Journal of Urban Economics, 77-92. Parks, Peter J. and Quimio, Wilma-Rose H. (1996), ‘Preserving Agricultural Land with Farmland Assessments: New Jersey as a Case Study’, 25 Agricultural and Resource Economics Review, 22-27. Pasour, Ernest C., Jr (1973), ‘Real Property Taxes and Farm Real Estate Values: Incidence and Implications’, 55 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 549-556. Pasour, Ernest C., Jr (1975), ‘The Capitalization of Real Property Taxes Levied on Farm Real Estate’, 57 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 539-548. Pasour, Ernest C., Jr (1980), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Case Against ad Valorem Property
122
Property Taxes
6030
Taxation in Forestry: Reply’, 33 National Tax Journal, 119 ff. Pasour, Ernest C., Jr and Holley, D.L. (1976), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Case Against ad Valorem Property Taxation in Forestry’, 29 National Tax Journal, 155-164. Paul, Diane B. (1975), The Politics of the Property Tax, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Pauly, Mark V. (1976), ‘A Model of Local Government Expenditure and Tax Capitalization’, 6 Journal of Public Economics, 231-242. Pechman, Joseph A. (1985), Who Paid the Taxes? 1966-85, Washington, Brookings Institution. Pechman, Joseph A. and Okner, Benjamin A. (1974), Who Bears the Tax Burden?, Washington, Brookings Institution. Penniman, Clara (1956), ‘The Role of Property Tax in Wisconsin Since 1929', 9 National Tax Journal, 331-338. Penniman, Clara (1961), ‘Property Tax Equalization in Wisconsin’, 14 National Tax Journal, 182-189. Perry, David B. (1996), ‘Property Taxes in Canada’, 44 Canadian Tax Journal, 1243-1250. Peterson, George E. (1972), The Regressivity of the Residential Property Tax, Urban Institute Working Paper, 1972. Peterson, George E. (1973), ‘The Issues of Property Tax Reform’, in Peterson, George E. (ed.), Property Tax Reform, Washington, Urban Institute Press. Peterson, George E., Solomon, Arthur, Madjid, Hadid and Apgar, William C. (1973), Property Taxes, Housing and the Cities, Lexington, MA, Heath. Pfister, Richard L. (1976), ‘A Re-evaluation of the Justification for Property Tax Exemption’, 4 Public Finance Quarterly, 431-452. Phares, Donald (1980), Who Pays State and Local Taxes?, Cambridge, Massachusetts, Oelgeschlager, Gunn and Hain. Pillai, Vel (1987), ‘Property Taxation in Thailand: An Uncommon Combination of a Land Tax and a Rental Tax’, 32 Singapore Economic Review, 43-55. Pines, David (1991), ‘Tiebout Without Politics’, 21 Regional Science and Urban Economics, 469-489. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1978), ‘The Long-Run Effects of a Residential Property Tax and Local Public Services’, 5 Journal of Urban Economics, 241-262. Pollakowski, Henry O. (1973), ‘The Effects of Property Taxes and Local Public Spending on Property Values: A Comment and Further Results’, 81 Journal of Political Economy, 994-1003. Preston, Anne and Ichniowski, Casey (1991), ‘A National Perspective on the Nature and Effects of the Local Property Tax Revolt, 1976-1986', 44 National Tax Journal, 123-145. Property Tax Committee of The National Tax Association (1973), ‘The Erosion of the Ad Valorem Real Estate Tax Base’, 60 Tax Policy, 1-94. Prud’Homme, Remy and Navarre, Francoise (1992), ‘Property Taxation in France’, in King, David (ed.), Local Government Economics in Theory and Practice, London, Routledge. Quigley, John M. and Schmenner, Roger W. (1975), ‘Property Tax Exemption and Public Policy’, 23 Public Policy, 259-278. Raimondo, Henry J. (1980), ‘Compensation for Tax Exempt Property in Theory and Practice’, 70 Land Economics, 410-414. Reeves, H. Clyde (1973), ‘System Value Determinations in the Assessment of Railroads for Property Taxation’, 26 National Tax Journal, 133-135. Reeves, H. Clyde and Pardue, Lea (1948), ‘Some Reasons why Property is Poorly Assessed for
6030
Property Taxes
123
Taxation’, 1 National Tax Journal, 366-368. Reeves, H. Clyde and Spaulding, Henry A. (1950), ‘Assessment of Coal Producing Properties in Kentucky’, 3 National Tax Journal, 173-178. Reinhard, Raymond M. (1981), ‘Estimating Property Tax Capitalization: A Further Comment’, 89 Journal of Political Economy, 1251-1260. Reinmuth, James E. (1975), ‘Innovative Techniques for Measuring Assessment Performance’, 8 International Property Assessment Administration, 175-185. Renshaw, Edward F. (1958), ‘Scientific Appraisal’, 11 National Tax Journal, 314-322. Richardson, David H. and Thalheimer, Richard (1981), ‘Measuring the Extent of Property Tax Capitalization for Single Family Residences’, 48 Southern Economic Journal, 671-689. Richman, Raymond L. (1967), ‘The Incidence of Urban Real Estate Taxes Under Conditions of Static and Dynamic Equilibrium’, 43 Land Economics, 172-180. Ricks, R. Bruce (1967), ‘Possessory Interests in Publicly Owned Property: Improperly Assessed’, 20 National Tax Journal, 347-351. Riew, John (1983), ‘Property Taxation and Economic Development: With Focus on Korea’, 8 Journal of Economic Development, 7-24. Robertson, Jack E. (1962), ‘Comparative Tax Burdens for a Midwestern City’, 15 National Tax Journal, 308-313. Romans, J.T. (1970), ‘On the Measurement of Assessment Error’, 23 National Tax Journal, 89-91. Rosen, Harvey S. and Fullerton, David J. (1977), ‘A Note on Local Tax Rates, Public Benefit Levels, and Property Values’, 85 Journal of Political Economy, 433-440. Rosett, Richard N. (1970), ‘Inequity in the Real Property Tax of New York State and the Aggravating Effects of Litigation’, 23 National Tax Journal, 66-73. Ross, Myron H. (1971), ‘The Property Tax Assessment Review Process: A Cause for Regressive Property Taxation?’, 24 National Tax Journal, 37-43. Rostvold, Gerhard N. (1963), ‘Property Tax Payments in Relation to Household Income: A Case Study of Los Angeles County’, 16 National Tax Journal, 197-199. Rostvold, Gerhard N. (1966), ‘Distribution of Property, Retail Sales, and Personal Income Tax Burdens in California: An Empirical Analysis of Inequity in Taxation’, 19 National Tax Journal, 38-47. Rostvold, Gerhard N. (1967), ‘Reply’, 20 National Tax Journal, 112-113. Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1979), ‘Judicial Approaches to Local Public Sector Equity: An Economic Analysis’, in Mieszkowski, Peter and Straszheim, Mahlon (eds), Current Issues in Urban Economics, Baltimore, MD, John Hopkins University Press. Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1987), ‘The Economics of the Local Public Sector’, in Auerbach, Alan and Feldstein, Martin (eds), Handbook in Public Economics, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 571-645. Sabella, Edward M. (1973), ‘Equity and the Property Tax: A Comment and an Alternative Conceptual Framework’, 26 National Tax Journal, 645-650. Sanders, Joe C. (1967), ‘A Defense of Personal Property Taxation’, in Buehler, Alfred G. (ed.), The Property Tax: Problems and Potentials, Princeton, NJ, Tax Institute of America. Sazama, Gerald W. (1965), ‘Equalization of Property Taxes for the Nation’s Largest Central Cities’, 18 National Tax Journal, 151-161. Sazama, Gerald W. (1970), ‘Land Taxes - Prerequisites and Obstacles: Boliva’, 23 National Tax Journal, 315-323. Schaaf, A.H. (1969), ‘Effects of Property Taxation on Slums and Renewal: A Study of Land-Improvement Assessment Ratios’, 45 Land Economics, 111-117.
124
Property Taxes
6030
Schmidt, E.B. (1952), ‘Categorical Inequalities in Assessment in Nebraska, 1930-1950', 5 National Tax Journal, 130-144. Schmitt, Robert C. (1951), ‘Fringe Growth and Tax Rates’, 4 National Tax Journal, 370-371. Schmitt, Robert C. (1952), ‘Annexation and Tax Rates’, 5 National Tax Journal, 176-178. Schoettle, Ferdinand P. (1972), ‘Judicial Requirements for School Finance and Property Tax Redesign: The Rapidly Evolving Case Law’, 25 National Tax Journal, 455-472. Schoettle, Ferdinand P. (1985), ‘A Three-Sector Model for Real Property Taxation’, 27 Journal of Public Economics, 355-370. Schroeder, Larry D. (1975), The Property Tax and Alternative Local Taxes: An Economic Analysis, New York, Praeger. Sears, G. Alden (1964), ‘Incidence of Profiles of a Real Estate Tax and Earned Income Tax: A Study in the Formal, Differential Incidence of Selected Local Taxes’, 17 National Tax Journal, 340-356. Seligman, Edwin R. (1925), Essays in Taxation, New York, Macmillan. Seligman, Edwin R. (1927), The Shifting and Incidence of Taxes, 5th edn, New York, Columbia University Press. Sexton, Terri A. (1987), ‘Forecasting Property Taxes: A Comparison and Evaluation of Methods’, 40 National Tax Journal, 47-59. Sexton, Terri A. and Sexton, Richard J. (1986), ‘Re-Evaluating the Income Elasticity of the Property Tax Base’, 62 Land Economics, 182-191. Shah, A. (1992), ‘Empirical Test for Allocative Efficiency in the Local Public Sector’, 20 Public Finance Quarterly, 359-377. Shannon, Francis John (1950), ‘Assessment Improvement Program in Kentucky’, 3 National Tax Journal, 233-241. Shannon, John (1971), ‘Federal Assistance in Modernizing State Sales and Local Property Taxes’, 24 National Tax Journal, 379-388. Shannon, John (1973), ‘The Property Tax: Reform or Relief?’, in Peterson, George E. (ed.), Property Tax Reform, Washington, Urban Institute Press. Shapiro, Harvey (1965), ‘Assessment and Taxation of Tangible Personal Property on Farms’, 18 National Tax Journal, 25-35. Shoup, Carl S. (1940), ‘Capitalization and Shifting of the Property Tax’, in Woodworth, L.D. (ed.), Property Taxes, New York, Tax Policy League Symposium, Inc. Shoup, Carl S. (1969), Public Finance, Chicago, Aldine-Atherton. Simon, Herbert A. (1943), ‘The Incidence of a Tax on Urban Real Property’, 57 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 398-421. Sinha, K.K. (1978), ‘Theory of Property Taxation: Some Issues’, 26 Indian Economic Journal, 8-17. Sirmans, G. Stacy and Sirmans, C.F. (1991), ‘Rents, Selling Prices and Financing Premiums’, 28 Urban Studies, 267-276. Sirmans, G. Stacy, Diskin, Barry A. and Friday, H. Swint (1995), ‘Vertical Inequity in the Taxation of Real Property’, 48 National Tax Journal, 71-84. Sjoquist, David Lawrence (1981), ‘A Median Voter Analysis of Variations in the Use of Property Taxes Among Local Governments’, 36 Public Choice, 273-285. Skinner, Jonathan (1991), ‘If Agricultural Land Taxation is so Efficient, Why is it so Rarely Used?’, 5 World Bank Economic Review, 113-133. Skouras, Athanassios (1973), ‘On the Analysis of Property Tax Effects on Operating and Investment Decisions of Rental Property Owners’, 26 National Tax Journal, 123-125. Skouras, Athanassios (1974), ‘The Allocation of Land Between Speculators and Users under a Land Ownership Tax: A Comment’, 50 Economic Record, 449-450.
6030
Property Taxes
125
Slinn, R.J. (1968), ‘Taxes on Private Forests in Australia’, 32 Australian Forestry, 163-170. Smith, Lawrence B. (1976), ‘The Ontario Land Speculation Tax: An Analysis of an Unearned Increment Land Tax’, 52 Land Economics, 1-12. Smith, R. Stafford (1970), ‘Property Tax Capitalization in San Francisco’, 23 National Tax Journal, 177-193. Smith, Roger S. (1990), ‘Why the Canadian Property Tax(payer) is not Revolting’, 38 Canadian Tax Journal, 298-327. Smith, Theodore R. (1970), ‘Land Value vs. Real Property Taxation: A Case Study Comparison’, 46 Land Economics, 305-313. Sonstelie, Jon C. (1979), ‘The Incidence of a Classified Property Tax’, 12 Journal of Public Economics, 75-85. Spears, McGehee H. (1958), ‘Veterans’ Property Tax Exemptions’, 11 National Tax Journal, 129-137. Starrett, David A. (1980), ‘On the Method of Taxation and the Provision of Local Public Goods’, 70 American Economic Review, 380-392. Starrett, David A. (1981), ‘Land Value Capitalization in Local Public Finance’, 89 Journal of Political Economy, 306-327. Starrett, David A. (1982), ‘On the Method of Taxation and the Provision of Local Public Goods: A Reply’, 72 American Economic Review, 852-853. Steen, Robert C. (1987), ‘Effect of the Property Tax in Urban Areas’, 21 Journal of Urban Economics, 146-165. Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1983), ‘The Theory of Local Public Goods Twenty-Five Years after Tiebout: A Perspective’, in Zodrow, George R. (ed.), Local Provision of Public Services: The Tiebout Model After Twenty-Five Years, New York, Academic Press. Stober, William J. and Falk, Laurence H. (1967), ‘Property Tax Exemption: An Efficient Subsidy to Industry’, 20 National Tax Journal, 386-394. Sullivan, Arthur M. (1984), ‘The General Equilibrium Effects of the Industrial Property Tax: Incidence and Excess Burden’, 14 Regional Science and Urban Economics, 547-563. Sullivan, Arthur M. (1985), ‘The General Equilibrium Effects of the Residential Property Tax: Incidence and Excess Burden’, 18 Journal of Urban Economics, 235-250. Sullivan, Arthur M. (1987), ‘The Spatial Effects of a General Capital Tax’, 17 Regional Science and Urban Economics, 209-222. Sunderman, Mark A., Birch, John W., Cannaday, Roger A. and Hamilton, Thomas W. (1990), ‘Testing for Vertical Inequity in Property Tax Systems’, 5 Journal of Real Estate Research, 319-334. Thather, George W. (1951), ‘Taxation of Intangible Personal Property in Ohio’, 4 National Tax Journal, 351-360. Thirsk, Wayne R. (1979), ‘The Capitalization of the Property Tax and Idle Land: Reply’, 55 Land Economics, 549-552. Thomassen, Henry (1978), ‘Circuit Breaking and Life-Cycle Lock-In’, 31 National Tax Journal, 59-65. Thompson, James H. (1951), ‘Effects of Property Tax Limitations in West Virginia’, 4 National Tax Journal, 129-138. Thomson, Procter (1965), ‘The Property Tax and the Rate of Interest’, in Benson, George C.S., Benson, Sumner, McClelland, Harold and Thomson, Procter (eds), The American Property Tax, Claremont, California, Lincoln School of Public Finance. Tideman, T. Nicolaus (1982), ‘A Tax on Land Value is Neutral’, 35 National Tax Journal, 109-111. Tiebout, Charles M. (1956), ‘A Pure Theory of Local Expenditures’, 64 Journal of Political Economy, 416-424.
126
Property Taxes
6030
Topham, Neville (1982), ‘A Note on Zoning and Property Taxation in a System of Local Governments’, 19 Urban Studies, 197-199. Topham, Neville and Ward, Robert (1992), ‘Property Prices, Tax and Expenditure Levels and Local Fiscal Performance’, 24 Applied Economics, 1225-1232. Townsend, Roswell G. (1951), ‘Inequalities of Residential Property Taxation in Metropolitan Boston’, 4 National Tax Journal, 361-369. Trestrail, Richard W. (1969), ‘Forests and the Property Tax - Unsound Accepted Theory’, 22 National Tax Journal, 347-356. Trestrail, Richard W. (1980), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Case Against Ad Valorem Property Taxation in Forestry: Comment’, 33 National Tax Journal, 117-118. Turnbull, Geoffrey K. (1987), ‘Land Taxes, Income Taxes, and Land Use’, 40 National Tax Journal, 265-269. Vedder, Richard (1990), ‘Tiebout, Taxes, and Economic Growth’, 10 Cato Journal, 91-108. Vickery, William (1970), ‘Defining Land Value for Tax Purposes’, in Holland, Daniel M. (ed.), The Assessment of Land Value - A Symposium, Madison, Wisconsin, University of Wisconsin Press. Vickery, William (1977), ‘The City as a Firm’, in Feldstein and Inman (eds), The Economics of Public Services, London, Macmillan. Vitaliano, Donald F. and Hill, Constance (1994), ‘Agricultural Districts and Farmland Prices’, 8 Journal of Real Estate Finance and Economics, 213-223. Vuuren, Willem (1970), ‘An Evaluation of Ontario’s Farm Assessment Proposals for Property Taxation’, 18 Canadian Journal of Agricultural Economics, 87-94. Vuuren, Willem and Cumming, John R. (1978), ‘The Impact of Housing Development in Rural Areas on Farm Property Taxes’, 26 Canadian Journal of Agricultural Economics, 31-37. Wald, Haskell P. (1959), The Taxation of Agricultural Land in Underdeveloped Economies, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Wales, T.J. and Wiens, E.G. (1974), ‘Capitalization of Residential Property Taxes: An Empirical Study’, 56 Review of Economics and Statistics, 329-333. Wassmer, Robert W. (1990), ‘Local Fiscal Variables and Intrametropolitan Firm Location: Regression Evidence from U.S. and Research Suggestions’, 8 Environment and Planning, 283-296. Wassmer, Robert W. (1993), ‘Property Taxation, Property Base, and Property Value: An Empirical Test of the “New View”’, 46 National Tax Journal, 135-159. Waters, Edward C., Holland, David W. and Weber, Bruce A. (1977), ‘Economic Impacts of Property Tax Limitation: A Computable General Equilibrium Analysis of Oregon’s Measure 5', 73 Land Economics, 72-89. Weil, Rolf A. (1953), ‘Property Tax Equalization in Illinois’, 6 National Tax Journal, 157-167. Weinberg, Daniel H., Friedman, Joseph and Mayo, Stephen K. (1981), ‘Intra-Urban Residential Mobility: The Role of Transactions Costs, Market Imperfections, and Household Disequilibrium’, 9 Journal of Urban Economics, 332-348. Weir, Michael and Peters, Lillian E. (1986), ‘Development, Equity, and the Graded Tax in the City of Pittsburgh’, 5 Property Tax Journal, 71-84. Welch, Ronald B. (1957), ‘Intercounty Equalization in California, Part 1: The Mechanics’, 10 National Tax Journal, 57-66. Welch, Ronald B. (1957), ‘Intercounty Equalization in California, Part 2: Action and Reaction’, 10 National Tax Journal, 148-157. Welch, Ronald B. (1964), ‘Some Observations on Assessment Ratio Measurement’, 17 National Tax Journal, 13-21.
6030
Property Taxes
127
Welch, Ronald B. (1974), ‘Disclosure of Property Tax Information’, 27 National Tax Journal, 409-411. Welch, Ronald B. (1976), ‘Property Tax Developments: Modernization, Classification, Site Value Taxation’, 29 National Tax Journal, 323-327. Wheaton, William C. (1975), ‘Consumer Mobility and Commodity Tax Bases: The Financing of Local Public Goods’, 4 Journal of Public Economics, 377-384. Wheaton, William C. (1984), ‘The Incidence of Inter-Jurisdictional Differences in Commercial Property Taxes’, 37 National Tax Journal, 515-527. White, Michelle J. (1975a), ‘Firm Location in a Zoned Metropolitan Area’, in Mills, Edwin S. and Oates, Wallace E. (eds), Fiscal Zoning and Land Use Controls, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books, 175-201. White, Michelle J. (1975b), ‘Fiscal Zoning in Fragmented Metropolitan Arreas’, in Mills, Edwin S. and Oates, Wallace E. (eds), Fiscal Zoning and Land Use Controls, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books, 31-100. White, Michelle J. (1979), ‘Suburban Growth Controls: Liability Rules and Pigouvian Taxes’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 207-230. White, Michelle J. (1986a), ‘Property Taxes and Urban Housing Abandonment’, 20 Journal of Urban Economics, 312-330. White, Michelle J. (1986b), ‘Property Taxes and Firm Location: Evidence from Proposition 13', in Rosen, Harvey S. (ed.), Studies in State and Local Public Finance, Chicago, Illinois, University of Chicago Press. Wicks, John H., Little, Robert A. and Beck, Ralph A. (1968), ‘A Note on Capitalization of Property Tax Changes’, 21 National Tax Journal, 263-265. Wildasin, David E. (1982), ‘More on the Neutrality of Land Taxation’, 35 National Tax Journal, 105-108. Wildasin, David E. (1986a), ‘Theoretical Analyzes of Local Public Economics’, in Mills, Edwin S. (ed.), Handbook of Urban Economics, Amsterdam, Elsevier/North Holland, 1131-1178. Wildasin, David E. (1986b), Urban Public Economics, New York, Harwood. Wildasin, David E. (1989), ‘Interjurisdictional Capital Mobility: Fiscal Externalities and a Corrective Subsidy’, 25 Journal of Urban Economics, 193-212. Williams, Alan (1966), ‘The Optimal Provision of Public Goods in a System of Local Governments’, 74 Journal of Political Economy, 18-33. Williams, Ellis T. (1961), ‘Trends in Forest Taxation’, 14 National Tax Journal, 113-144. Williams, Ellis T. (1974), ‘Site Value Taxation - How Does it Relate to Forest Land?’, 27 National Tax Journal, 29-44. Wilson, John D. (1984), ‘The Excise Tax Effects of the Property Tax’, 24 Journal of Public Economics, 309-329. Wilson, John D. (1985), ‘Optimal Property Taxation in the Presence of Interregional Capital Mobility’, 18 Journal of Urban Economics, 73-89. Wilson, John D. (1986), ‘A Theory of Interregional Tax Competition’, 19 Journal of Urban Economics, 296-315. Wilson, John D. (1987), ‘Trade, Capital Mobility, and Tax Competition’, 95 Journal of Political Economy, 835-856. Wilson, John D. (1997), ‘Property Taxation, Congestion, and Local Public Goods’, 64 Journal of Public Economics, 207-217. Windsor, Duane (1979), Fiscal Zoning in Suburban Communities, Lexington , MA, Lexington Books. Winfrey, John C. (1973), Public Finance: Public Choices and the Public Economy, New York, NY, Harper & Row Publishers.
128
Property Taxes
6030
Woodard, F.O. and Brady, Ronald W. (1965), ‘Inductive Evidence on Tax Capitalization’, 18 National Tax Journal, 193-201. Woodruff, A.M. (1967), ‘Land Value Taxation - A 1966 Evaluation’, in Buehler, Alfred G. (ed.), The Property Tax Problems and Potentials, Princeton, NJ, Tax Institute of America. Wunderlich, Gene (1997), ‘Land Taxes in Agriculture: Preferential Rate and Assessment Effects’, 56 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 215-228. Wunderlich, Gene (ed.) (1993), Land Ownership and Taxation in American Agriculture, Boulder, CO, Westview Press. Yang, Chin Wei, Means, Dwight B., Jr and Moody, George E. (1993), ‘Tax Rates and Total Tax Revenues from Local Property Taxes’, 21 Public Finance Quarterly, 355-377. Yinger, John (1982), ‘Capitalization and the Theory of Local Public Finance’, 90 Journal of Political Economy, 917-943. Yinger, John (1985), ‘Inefficiency and the Median Voter: Property Taxes, Capitalization, Heterogeneity, and the Theory of Second Best’, in Quigley, John M. (ed.), Perspectives on Local Public Finance and Public Policy, Greenwood, JAI Press. Yinger, John, Bloom, Howard S., Borsch-Supan, Axel and Ladd, Helen F. (1988), Property Taxes and Housing Values: The Theory and Estimation of Intrajurisdictional Property Tax Capitalization, Studies in Urban Economics Series, San Diego, Harcourt, Brace, Jovanovich, Academic Press. Zimmer, Basil G. (1958), ‘Differential Property Taxation in a Metropolitan Area’, 11 National Tax Journal, 280-286. Zodrow, George R. (1983a), ‘The Tiebout Model After Twenty-Five Years: An Overview’, in Zodrow, George R. (ed.), Local Provision of Public Services: The Tiebout Model After Twenty-Five Years, New York, Academic Press. Zodrow, George R. (ed.) (1983b), Local Provision of Public Services: The Tiebout Model After Twenty-Five Years, New York, Academic Press. Zodrow, George R. (1984), ‘The Incidence of Metropolitan Property Tax Base Sharing and Rate Equalization’, 15 Journal of Urban Economics, 210-229. Zodrow, George R. (1986), ‘Pigou, Tiebout, Property Taxation and the Underprovision of Local Public Goods’, 19 Journal of Urban Economics, 356-370. Zodrow, George R. and Mieszkowski, Peter (1983), ‘The Incidence of the Property Tax: The Benefit View versus the New View’, in Zodrow, George R. (ed.), Local Provision of Public Services: The Tiebout Model After Twenty-Five Years, New York, Academic Press. Zodrow, George R. and Mieszkowski, Peter (1986), ‘The New View of Property Taxation: A Reformulation’, 16 Regional Science and Urban Economics, 309-327.
6040 CONSUMPTION TAX, VALUE ADDED TAX, EXCISE TAX AND SALES TAX © Copyright 1999 Boudewijn Bouckaert and Gerrit De Geest
Bibliography Collected by the Editors Aguirre, Carlos A. and Shome, Parthasarathi (1988), ‘The Mexican Value Added Tax (VAT): Methodology for Calculating the Base’, 41(4) National Tax Journal, 543-554. Ashenfelter, Orley and Sullivan, Daniel (1987), ‘Nonparametric Tests of Market Structure: An Application to the Cigarette Industry’, 35(4) Journal of Industrial Economics, 483-498. Barham, Vicky, Poddar, S.N. and Whalley, John (1987), ‘The Tax Treatment of Insurance under a Consumption Type, Destination Basis VAT’, 40(2) National Tax Journal, 171-182. Barker, Phyllis A. (1972), ‘Projected Compliance Costs Associated with the Value Added Tax as Proposed’, 47 Indiana Business Review, 22-27. Barlow, Robin and Snyder, Wayne (1994), ‘The Tax That Failed: The VAT in Niger’, 14(3) Public Budgeting and Finance, 77-89. Barman, Kiran and Bisonoi, Usha (1983), ‘Value Added Tax as an Alternative to Corporation Tax’, 28(4) Economic Affairs, 860-865. Barnett, Paul G., Keeler, Theodore E. and Hu, Teh Wei (1995), ‘Oligopoly Structure and the Incidence of Cigarette Excise Taxes’, 57(3) Journal of Public Economics, 457-470. Barthold, Thomas A. (1994), ‘Issues in the Design of Environmental Excise Taxes’, 8(1) Journal of Economic Perspectives, 133-151. Bates, Christopher (1993), ‘Value Added Tax and Holding Companies: A Major Change of Policy or a Small Problem of Translation?’, 14(2) Fiscal Studies, 117-127. Becker, Gary S., Grossman, Michael and Murphy, Kevin M. (1994), ‘An Empirical Analysis of Cigarette Addiction’, 84(3) American Economic Review, 396-418. Bell, Michael E., Dearborn, Philip M. and Hunter, Roland (1993), ‘Financing the Post Apartheid City in South Africa’, 30(3) Urban Studies, 581-591. Berglas, Eitan (1971), ‘The Effect of the Public Sector on the Base of the Value Added Tax’, 24(4) National Tax Journal, 459-464. Bergstrom, Theodore C. (1982), ‘On Capturing Oil Rents with a National Excise Tax’, 72(1) American Economic Review, 194-201. Besley, Timothy and Suzumura, Kotaro (1992), ‘Taxation and Welfare in an Oligopoly with Strategic Commitment’, 33(2) International Economic Review, 413-431. Bhatia, Kul B. (1982), ‘Value Added Tax and the Theory of Tax Incidence’, 19(2) Journal of Public Economics, 203-223. Black, David E. (1977), ‘Property Tax Incidence: The Excise Tax Effect and Assessment Practices’, 30(4) National Tax Journal, 429-434.
129
130
Consumption Tax
6040
Blazic, Helena (1993), ‘Adaptacija Oporezivanja Potrosnje u Hrvatskoj (With English summary) (Adaptation of Consumption Taxation in Croatia)’, 11(0) Zbornik Radova Ekonomskog Fakulteta Rijeka, 3-22. Brannon, Gerald M. (1973), ‘Death Taxes in a Structure of Progessive Taxes’, 26 National Tax Journal, 451-457. Brannon, Gerald M. (1984), ‘The Value Added Tax is a Good Utility Infielder’, 37(3) National Tax Journal, 303-312. Brashares, Edith, Speyrer, Janet Furman and Carlson, George N. (1988), ‘Distributional Aspects of a Federal Value Added Tax’, 41(2) National Tax Journal, 155-174. Burgess, Robin, Howes, Stephen and Stern, Nicholas (1995), ‘Value Added Tax Options for India’, 2(1) International Tax and Public Finance, 109-141. Carlson, George N. and Patrick, Melanie K. (1989), ‘Addressing the Regressivity of a Value Added Tax’, 42(3) National Tax Journal, 339-351. Caspersen, Erik and Metcalf, Gilbert E. (1994), ‘Is a Value Added Tax Regressive? Annual versus Lifetime Incidence Measures’, 47(4) National Tax Journal, 731-746. Chiles, Ted W., Jr and Sollars, David L. (1993), ‘Estimating Cigarette Tax Revenue’, 17(3) Journal of Economics and Finance, 1-15. Chowdhury, Osman H. (1989), ‘Equity and Efficiency Tradeoff in Bangladesh Tax Policy Reform: A Computable General Equilibrium Model’, 26(2) Philippine Review of Economics and Business, 262-286. Chowdhury, Osman Haider (1991), ‘Revenue Neutral Value Added Tax (VAT) in Bangladesh: Some General Equilibrium Illustrations’, 19(4) Bangladesh Development Studies, 49-63. Clotfelter, Charles T. and Cook, Philip J. (1987), ‘Implicit Taxation in Lottery Finance’, 40(4) National Tax Journal, 533-546. Cnossen, Sijbren (1981), ‘Dutch Experience with the Value Added Tax’, 39(2) Finanzarchiv, 223-254. Cnossen, Sijbren (1982), ‘What Rate Structure for a Value Added Tax?’, 35(2) National Tax Journal, 205-214. Cnossen, Sijbren (1989), ‘The Value Added Tax: Key to a Better Tax Mix’, 6(3) Australian Tax Forum, 265-281. Cnossen, Sijbren (1992), ‘Key Questions in Considering a Value Added Tax for Central and Eastern European Countries’, 39(2) International Monetary Fund Staff Papers, 211-255. Cosciani, Cesare (1970), ‘Sulle Probabili Conseguenze dell’Introduzione dell’I. V. A. in Italia. (With English summary) (On the Probable Consequences of the Introduction of the Added Value Tax in Italy)’, 26(8) Bancaria, 909-916. Dahl, Henrik and Mitra, Pradeep (1991), ‘Applying Tax Policy Models in Country Eocnomic Work: Bangladesh, China, and India’, 5(3) World Bank Economic Review, 553-572. Davie, Bruce F. (1994), ‘Tax Expenditures in the Federal Excise Tax System’, 47(1) National Tax Journal, 39-62. Devers, M. (1969), ‘De B.T.W. Aangifte en de Factuur (The Value Added Tax Declaration and the Invoice with English summary)’, 23(3) Economisch en Sociaal Tijdschrift, 287-303.
6040
Consumption Tax
131
Dewatripont, C. et al. (1991), ‘The Effects on Unemployment of Reducing Social Security Contributions: A General Equilibrium Analysis for Belgium’, 139(2) De Economist, 272-290. Dosser, Douglas and Hitiris, Theodore (1972), ‘Trade Effects of Tax Harmonisation: Harmonisation of Value Added Tax in E.E.C. A Reply’, 40(2) Manchester School of Economic and Social Studies, 189-191. Dosser, Douglas, Han, S.S. and Hitiris, Theodore (1969), ‘Trade Effects of Tax Harmonisation: Harmonisation of the Value added Tax in E.E.C.’, 37(4) Manchester School of Economic and Social Studies, 337-346. Due, John F. (1974), ‘The Value Added Tax Sense and Nonsense’, 13(4) Nebraska Journal of Economics and Business, 54-65. Due, John F. (1990), ‘Some Unresolved Issues in Design and Implementation of Value Added Taxes’, 43(4) National Tax Journal, 383-394. Due, John F. and Greaney, Francis (1991), ‘The Development of a Value Added Tax: Trinidad and Tobago’, 45(6) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 260-268. Dye, Richard F. and McGuire, Therese J. (1991), ‘Growth and Variability of State Individual Income and General Sales Taxes’, 44(1) National Tax Journal, 55-66. Edwards, Franklin R. (1993), ‘Taxing Transactions in Futures Markets: Objectives and Effects’, 7(1) Journal of Financial Services Research, 75-91. Engineer, Merwan (1989), ‘Taxes, Public Goods, and the Ruling Class: An Exploration of the Territory between Brennan and Buchanan’s Leviathan and Conventional Public Finance’, 44(1) Public Finance, 19-30. Epley, Donald R. (1978), ‘A Note on the Substitution of a Value Added Tax for the Corporate Income Tax, and Its Impact upon Stabilization’, 17(1) Nebraska Journal of Economics and Business, 47-56. Fourie, F.C.V.N. and Owen, A. (1993), ‘Value Added Tax and Regressivity in South Africa’, 61(4) South African Journal of Economics, 281-300. Frech, H. Edward III, Deacon, Rovert, Decanio, Stephen J. and Johnson, Bruce M. (1990), Taxing Energy: Oil Severence Taxation and the Economy, New York, Holmes and Meyer. Frenkel, Jacob A. (1988), ‘Budget Deficits under Alternative Tax Systems: International Effects’, 35(2) International Monetary Fund Staff Papers, 297-315. Frenkel, Jacob A., Razin, Assaf and Symansky, Steven (1991), ‘International VAT Haromonization: Macroeconomic Effects’, 38(4) International Monetary Fund Staff Papers, 789-827. Gantner, Manfred (1993), ‘Anmerkungen zur Universitätsreform aus Finanzwissenschaflticher Sicht (Notes on Reforming Universities from a Public Finance Perspective)’, in Strasser, R. (ed.), Beiträge zum Universitätsrecht, Vienna, 119-139. Gantner, Manfred (1995), ‘Energieabgaben als Ländersteuern? Wirkungsanalyse und Fnanzverfassungsrechtliche Überlegungen am Beispiel des Feldversuch Vorarlbergs (Duties on Energy as Provincial Taxes?)’, 21 Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft, 47-76. Garton, Steven D. (1974), ‘The Value Added Tax’, 55(8) Management Accounting, 16-18. Gelauff, G.M.M. et al. (1991), ‘Towards an Analysis of Tax Effects on Labour Market and Allocation: A Micro/Macro Approach’, 139(2) De Economist, 243-271.
132
Consumption Tax
6040
Georgakopoulos, Theodore A. (1972), ‘Trade Effects of Tax Harmonisation: Harmonisation of the Value Added Tax in E.E.C. A Comment and a Suggested Methodology’, 40(2) Manchester School of Economic and Social Studies, 177-188. Georgakopoulos, Theodore A. (1975), ‘Stabilisation Aspects of Tax Substitution: The Value Added Tax in the UK’, 30(3) Public Finance, 333-346. Georgakopoulos, Theodore A. (1991), ‘Some Economic Effects of Value Added Tax Substitution in Greece: A First Ex post Assessment’, 13(1) Greek Economic Review, 117-134. Gimeno Ullastres, Juan A., ‘Los Beneficios de los Gastos Indivisibles (Benefits of Indivisible Expenses)’, 133 Hacienda Pública Española, 115-130. Gimeno Ullastres, Juan A. (1980), Imposición Sobre el Consumo y Distribución Personal de Rentas (Consumption Taxes and Personal Distribution of Income), Madrid, Instituto de Estudios Fiscales, 341 p. Gimeno Ullastres, Juan A. (1985), ‘La Incidencia del I.V.A. sobre los Consumidores (How V.A.T. Affects Consumers)’, 4 Estudio Sobre le Consumo, 37-55. Gimeno Ullastres, Juan A. (1994), La Fiscalidad del Tabaco en la CEE (Taxing Tobacco in the E.C.), Madrid, Editorial Cívitas, 127 p. Goffin, R. (1970), ‘An Account of T.V.A. in Belgium (Value Added Tax V.A.T.)’, 24(789) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 299-347. Goode, Richard (1993), ‘Tax Advice to Developing Countries: An Historical Survey’, 21(1) World Development, 37-53. Gottfried, Peter and Wiegard, Wolfgang (1991), ‘Exemption versus Zero Rating: A Hidden Problem of VAT’, 46(3) Journal of Public Economics, 307-328. Guerard, Michele (1973), ‘The Brazilian State Value Added Tax’, 20(1) International Monetary Fund Staff Papers, 118-169. Hafer, R.W. and Trebing, Michael E. (1980), ‘The Value Added Tax A Review of the Issues’, 62(1) Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis Review, 3-10. Hamilton, Bob and Kuo, Chun-Yan (1991), ‘Reforming the Canadian Sales Tax System: A Regional General Equilibrium Analysis’, 39(1) Canadian Tax Journal, 113 ff. Hilzenbecher, Manfred (1990), ‘Horizontale und vertikale Verteilungswirkungen einer Mehrwertsteuererhohung (With English summary) (Horizontal and Vertical Distribution Effects of an Increase of the Value Added Tax)’, 36(23) Konjunkturpolitik, 63-79. Holcombe, Randall G. (1990), ‘The Value Added Tax and the Sales Tax’, 37(9) Rivista Internazionale di Scienze Economiche e Commerciali, 799-815. Homma, Masaaki, Atoda, Naosumi and Hashimoto, Kyoji (1989), ‘Welfare Analysis of the 1988 Tax Reform in Japan’, 40(4) Economic Studies Quarterly, 336-348. Hong, Lee Fook (1995), ‘People’s Republic of China: Value Added Tax, Consumption Tax and Business Tax’, 49(1) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 23-26. Hossain, Shahabuddin M. (1995), ‘The Equity Impact of the Value Added Tax in Bangladesh’, 42(2) International Monetary Fund Staff Papers, 411-430. Hu, Sheng Cheng (1983), ‘Value Added Tax as a Source of Social Security Financing’, 11(2) Public Finance Quarterly, 154-180. Hunter, William J. and Nelson, Michael A. (1990), ‘Excise Taxation and the Theory of Tax Exploitation’, 45(2) Public Finance, 268-282.
6040
Consumption Tax
133
Ichioka, Osamu (1988), ‘The Value Added Tax in Japan: A Numerical General Equilibrium Evaluation’, 2(1) Journal of the Japanese and International Economy, 11-41. Ingberg, Mikael (1990), ‘Steg mot Mervardesomsattningsskatt (With English summary) (Steps toward a Value Added Tax)’, 43(4) Ekonomiska Samfundets Tidskrift, 251-252. Jap, Kim Siong (1986), ‘Taiwan: An Outline of the Proposed Value Added Tax System’, 40(1) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 18-19. Jhun, U. Jin (1976), ‘Value Added Tax and Balance of Trade’, 1(1) Journal of Economic Development, 139-147. Johnson, Darwin G. (1980), ‘The Inflation Elasticity of a Specific Excise Tax’, 33(1) National Tax Journal, 107-110. Johnson, Peter and Parker, Simon (1994), ‘The Interrelationships between Births and Deaths’, 6(4) Small Business Economics, 283-290. Kaiser, Helmut and Spahn, P. Bernd (1989), ‘On the Efficiency and Distributive Justice of Consumption Taxes: A Study on VAT in West Germany’, 49(2) Journal of Economics (Zeitschrift für Nationalökonomie), 199-218. Kaplow, Louis (1988), ‘Savings Incentives in a Hybrid Income Tax: Comment’, in Aaron, Henry J., Galper, Harveu and Pechman, Joseph A. (eds), Uneasy Compromise: Problems of a Hybrid Income-Consumption Tax, Washington, Brookings Institution. Kaplow, Louis (1994), ‘Human Capital under An Ideal Income Tax’, 80 Virginia Law Review, 1477-1514. Kaplow, Louis (1995), ‘Recovery of Pre-Enactment Basis Under a Consumption Tax: The USA Tax System’, 68 Tax Notes, 1109-1118. Kaplow, Louis (1996), ‘On the Divergence Between ‘Ideal’ and Conventional Income Tax Treatment of Human Capital’, American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings. Kaplow, Louis and Warren, Alvin (1986), ‘An Income Tax by Any Other Name - A Reply to Professor Strnad’, 38 Stanford Law Review, 339-421. Kaplow, Louis and Warren, Alvin (1987), ‘Professor Strnad’s Rejoinder: Simply Semantics’, 39 Stanford Law Review, 419-425. Kay, John A. and Keen, Michael (1991), ‘Product Quality Under Specific and Ad Valorem Taxation’, 19 Public Finance Quarterly, 238-247. Kehoe, Timothy J. et al. (1989), ‘Un Analisis de Equilibrio General de la Reforma Fiscal de 1986 en Espana (A General Equilibrium Analysis of the Spanish Fiscal Reform of 1986) (with English Summary)’, 13(3) Investigaciones Económicas, 337-385. Krauss, Melvyn B. and Bird, Richard M. (1971), ‘The Value Added Tax: Critique of a Review’, 9 Journal of Economic Literature, 1167-1173. Kudrle, Robert Thomas (1984), ‘Excise Tax Incidence in Limit Price Oligopoly’, 39(3) Public Finance, 321-346. Lakdawala, D.T. (1976), ‘Value Added Tax’, 24(2) Indian Economic Journal, 183-207. Lent, George E. (1974), ‘Value Added Tax in Developing Countries’, 11(4) Finance and Development, 35-37. Lent, George E., Casanegra, Milka and Guerard, Michele (1973), ‘The Value Added Tax in Developing Countries’, 20(2) International Monetary Fund Staff Papers, 318-378. Li, Jinyan (1988), ‘Value Added Tax: People’s Republic of China’, 42(1) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 17-22.
134
Consumption Tax
6040
Lindholm, Richard W. (1970), ‘The Value Added Tax: A Short Review of the Literature’, 8 Journal of Economic Literature, 1178-1189. Lindholm, Richard W. (1971), ‘The Value Added Tax: Rejoinder to a Critique’, 9 Journal of Economic Literature, 1173-1179. Lott, William F. and Miller, Stephen M. (1974), ‘Excise Tax Revenue Maximization’, 40(4) Southern Economic Journal, 657-664. Lyons, Susan M. (1992), ‘The Taxation of Companies and Individuals in Mexico’, 46(9) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 436-443. Maital, Shlomo and Krevinsky, Shlomo (1970), ‘Shifting Parameters and the Value Added Tax: A Note’, 23(2) National Tax Journal, 221-222. Mann, Arthur J. (1990), ‘Bolivia: Tax Reform 1986-1989’, 44(1) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 32-36. Massone, Pedro F. (1979), ‘Recent Developments in Latin America: The Mexican Value Added Tax’, 33(12) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 539-549. Matthiasson, Bjorn (1970), ‘The Value Added Tax’, 7(1) Finance and Development, 40-46. McClure, Charles E., Jr (1980), ‘Tax Restructuring Act of 1979: Time for an American Value Added Tax?’, 28(3) Public Policy, 301-322. McGee, Robert W. (1984a), Software Taxation, National Association of Accountants, 305 p. McGee, Robert W. (1984b), ‘Loophole of the Month’, CPA Digest, 4 ff. McGee, Robert W. (1984c), ‘Software Taxation: A New NAA Research Study’, 66 Management Accounting, 7071-7077. McGee, Robert W. (1985a), Accounting for Software, Homewood, IL, Dow Jones-Irwin, 168 p. McGee, Robert W. (1985b), ‘Sales, Use and Property Taxation of Computer Software’, 8 Hamline Law Review, 307-342. Reprinted in Accounting and Tax Aspects of Computer Software Manufacturing, New York, Praeger Publishing Company, 1987. McGee, Robert W. (1985c), ‘Financial and Tax Accounting for Computer Software’, 7 Western New England Law Review, 651-704. Reprinted in Accounting for Data Processing Department Costs, New York, Greenwood Press, 1988. McGee, Robert W. (1987), Accounting and Tax Aspects of Computer Software Manufacturing, New York, Praeger Publishing Company, 162 p. McGee, Robert W. (1996a), Taxation, Ethics and Public Policy, Dumont Institute for Public Policy Research. http:/ww.hili.com~dumontin McGee, Robert W. (1996b), Essays on Accounting. Taxation and Public Finance, Dumont Institute for Public Policy Research. http:/ww.hili.com~dumontin McGibany, James M. (1991), ‘The Effect of Property Tax Rate Differentials on Single Family Housing Starts in Wisconsin, 1978-1989’, 31(3) Journal of Regional Science, 347-359. McKinnon, Ronald I. (1973), ‘The Value Added Tax and the Liberalization of Foreign Trade in Developing Economies: A Comment’, 11 Journal of Economic Literature, 520-524. McLure, Charles E., Jr (1991), ‘Tax Policy for Bulgaria’, 45(5) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 235-247. Merriman, David (1994), ‘Do Cigarette Excise Tax Rates Maximize Revenue?’, 32(3) Economic Inquiry, 419-428.
6040
Consumption Tax
135
Meyer, Carrie and Due, John F. (1988), ‘Value Added Tax: Dominican Republic’, 42(1) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 13-16. Militzer, Ken and Ontscherenki, Ilona (1990), ‘The Value Added Tax: Its Impact on Saving’, 25(2) Business Economics, 32-37. Modesto, Leonor, Vasco, Alexandra and Bernardes, Luis (1992), ‘Macroeconomic Effects of an Energy Tax in Portugal: Simulation Results for 1991-2000’, 16(1) Economia (Portuguese Catholic University), 33-45. Morrison, Clarence C. (1995), ‘Comparing the Welfare Effects of Income and Excise Taxes in the Presence of the Other Taxation Paradox’, 23(3) Atlantic Economic Journal, 189-202. Musgrave, Richard A. (1972), ‘Problems of the Value Added Tax’, 25(3) National Tax Journal, 425-430. Nakamura, Kazuo (1979), ‘On the Actual State of Value Added Tax in England (In Japanese)’, 139(5) Kokumin Keizai Zasshi, 42-57. Nakamura, Kazuo (1980), ‘Value Added Tax in Retail Stage (In Japanese)’, 141(5) Kokumin Keizai Zasshi, 17-31. Nakamura, Kazuo (1982), ‘Pros and Cons of Value Added Tax in the United Kingdom (In Japanese)’, 145(4) Kokumin Keizai Zasshi, 47-60. O’Higgins, T.J. (1971), ‘Proposals for a Value Added Tax in Ireland’, 25(7) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 243-247. Panagariya, Arvind and Narayana, A.V.L. (1988), ‘Excise Tax Evasion: A Welfare cum Crime Theoretic Analysis’, 43 Public Finance, 248-260. Panagariya, Arvind and Narayana, A.V.L. (1989), ‘Excise Tax Evasion: Reply’, 44 Public Finance, 510-512. Parr, Michael and Day, John (1977), ‘Value Added Tax in the United Kingdom’, National Westminster Bank Quarterly Review, 7-18. Patel, Himat (1978), ‘Scope for Value Added Tax in India’, 14(2) Artha Vikas, 70-84. Peeters, Frans (1969), ‘De B.T.W. in de Onderneming (The Value Added Tax and the Enterprise. With English summary)’, 23(4) Economisch en Sociaal Tijdschrift, 391-403. Perraudin, W.R.M. and Pujol, T. (1991), ‘European Fiscal Harmonization and the French Economy’, 38(2) International Monetary Fund Staff Papers, 399-440. Perry, John (1990), ‘Business Registers the Search for Quality’, 7(1) Statistical Journal, 55-61. Peters, Douglas D. (1991), ‘International Perspective: Canada: Recession and Recovery’, 26(2) Business Economics, 51-55. Petersen, Mitchell A. (1992), ‘Pension Reversions and Worker Stockholder Wealth Transfers’, 107(3) Quarterly Journal of Economics, 1033-1056. Poterba, James (1989), ‘Lifetime Incidence and the Distributional Burden of Excise Taxes’, 79 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 325-330. Ribich, Thomas I. (1973), ‘Soft Sell for Soft Drinks: An Excise Tax Problem’, 26(1) National Tax Journal, 115-117. Rienstra, J.G. (1992), ‘United States: German Treaty Exemption for Foreign Insurance Premiums’, 46(11) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 545-550. Ruebling, Charlotte E. (1973), ‘A Value Added Tax and Factors Affecting Its Economic Impact’, 55(9) Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis Review, 15-19. Ruggeri, G.C. and Bluck, K. (1990), ‘On the Incidence of the Manufacturers’ Sales Tax and the Goods and Services Tax’, 16(4) Canadian Public Policy, 359-373.
136
Consumption Tax
6040
Saba, Richard P. et al. (1995), ‘The Demand for Cigarette Smuggling’, 33(2) Economic Inquiry, 189-202. Saffer, Henry and Grossman, Michael (1987), ‘Beer Taxes, the Legal Drinking Age, and Youth Motor Vehicle Fatalities’, 16 Journal of Legal Studies, 351-374. Salter, Sarah W. (1982), ‘Value Added: Economic Concepts in Tax Policy Analysis’, in Cranston, Ross and Schick, Anne (eds), Law and Economics, Canberra, Australian National University, 175-189. Sapona, Ingrid (1990), ‘Goods and Services Tax: Canada’, 44(10) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 489-498. Schlecht, Otto (1987), ‘Die Vollendung des Europaischen Binnenmarktes Ziele, Voraussetzungen und Chancen (With English summary) (The Completion of the European Internal Market Goals, Prerequisites, and Opportunities)’, 33(6) Konjunkturpolitik, 303-310. Schweizer, Urs (1984), ‘Welfare Analysis of Excise Tax Evasion’, 140 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 247-258. Sgontz, Larry G. (1992), ‘An Excise Tax that Reduces Price’, 45(1) National Tax Journal, 115-117. Shapiro, Perry and Petchey, Jeffrey D. (1994), ‘“Shall Become Exclusive”: An Economic Analysis of Section 90’, 70(209) Economic Record, 171-182. Shoup, Carl S. (1969), ‘Experience with the Value Added Tax in Denmark, and Prospects in Sweden’, 28(2) Finanzarchiv, 236-252. Shoup, Carl S. (1988), ‘The Value Added Tax and Developing Countries’, 3(2) World Bank Research Observer, 139-156. Shughart, William F., II, Tollison, Robert D. and Higgins, Richard S. (1987), ‘Rational Self Taxation: Complementary Inputs and Excise Taxation’, 20(3) Canadian Journal of Economics, 527-532. Siong, Jap Kim (1986), ‘Taiwan: The Value Added Tax Law in Force’, 40(7) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 315-318. Slovin, Myron B., Sushka, Marie E. and Bendeck, Yvette M. (1990), ‘The Market Valuation Effects of Reserve Regulation’, 25(1) Journal of Monetary Economics, 3-19. Smith, Dan Throop (1970), ‘Value Added Tax: The Case For’, 48(6) Harvard Business Review, 77-85. Spindler, Z.A. (1972), ‘A Predicition of the Effects of an Excise Tax Change on the Automobile Market: A Note’, 24(2) Economic and Business Bulletin, 66-68. Steedman, Ian (1986), ‘Produced Inputs and Tax Incidence Theory’, 41(3) Public Finance, 331-349. Stephenson, Peter (1970), ‘Problems and Political Implications for the United Kingdom of Introducing the EEC Value Added Tax’, 8(4) Journal of Common Market Studies, 305-324. Stout, Lynn A. (1995), ‘Are Stock Markets Costly Casinos? Disagreement, Market Failure, and Securities Regulation’, 81 Virginia Law Review, 611 ff. Sumner, Daniel A. and Wohlgenant, Michael K. (1985), ‘Effects of an Increase in the Federal Excise Tax on Cigarettes’, 67(2) American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 235-242. Surrey, Stanley S. (1970), ‘Value Added Tax: The Case Against’, 48(6) Harvard Business Review, 86-94.
6040
Consumption Tax
137
Tait, Alan A. (1981), ‘Is the Introduction of a Value Added Tax Inflationary?’, 18(2) Finance and Development, 38-42. Tait, Alan A. (1989), ‘Misconceptions about the Value Added Tax’, 26(1) Finance and Development, 25-27. Tamaoka, Masayuki (1994), ‘The Regressivity of a Value Added Tax: Tax Credit Method and Subtraction Method. A Japanese Case’, 15(2) Fiscal Studies, 57-73. Théret, Bruno (1981), ‘Un Point de Vue Macroeconomique sur le Traitement de la Taxe sur la Valeur ajoutee dans le Systeme Elargi de Comptabilite Nationale Francaise (A Macroeconomic View on the Treatment of the Value Added Tax in the Extended French National Accounting System)’, 36(1) Public Finance, 108-124. Thirsk, Wayne R. (1987), ‘The Value Added Tax in Canada: Saviour or Siren Song?’, 13(3) Canadian Public Policy, 259-283. Thiry, Beranrd (1988), ‘Distributive Effects of the Reform of Value Added Tax: The Case of Belgium’, 59(3) Annals of Public and Cooperative Economy, 341-368. Thomson, Trevor (1974), ‘The Value Added Tax and the Cost of Change’, 42(1) South African Journal of Economics, 56-64. Tower, Edward (1989), ‘Excise Tax Evasion: Comment’, 44 Public Finance, 506-509. Van Rensburg, B.P.J. (1990), ‘Belasting op Toegevoegde Waarde: Pas dit Suid Afrika? (With English summary) (Value Added Tax: Can it be Applied to South Africa?)’, 58(1) South African Journal of Economics, 21-42. Vandenhouten, F. (1969), ‘De Invoering van de B.T.W. in de Ondernemingen (The Value Added Tax in the Administration of the Firms with English summary)’, 23(2) Economisch en Sociaal Tijdschrift, 159-171. Vartholomeos, John (1974), ‘Price and Trade Effects of the Substitution of a Value Added Tax for the Corporate Income Tax: The British Case’, 32(3) Finanzarchiv, 469-480. Wajsman, Nathan (1992), ‘Indirect Tax Harmonization in Denmark’, 128(4) Weltwirtschaftliches Archiv - Review of World Economics, 727-741. Waldauer, Charles (1981), ‘Comment (on ‘The Variable Rate Value Added Tax as an Anti Inflation Fiscal Stabilizer’)’, 34(1) National Tax Journal, 131-132. Walker, John F. (1974), ‘Do Economists Ever Agree? The Case of the Teaching of Excise Tax: Shifting and Incidence’, 27(2) National Tax Journal, 351-355. Wetzler, James W. (1979), ‘The Role of a Value Added Tax in Financing Social Security’, 32(3) National Tax Journal, 334-345. White, Daniel L. (1980), ‘The Variable Rate Value Added Tax as an Anti Inflation Fiscal Stabilizer’, 33(2) National Tax Journal, 227-232. White, Daniel L. (1981), ‘The Variable Rate Value Added Tax as an Anti Inflation Fiscal Stabilizer: A Response’, 34(1) National Tax Journal, 133 ff. Wilson, John Douglas (1984), ‘The Excise Tax Effects of the Property Tax’, 24(3) Journal of Public Economics, 309-329. Wilson, John Douglas (1989), ‘On the Optimal Tax Base for Commodity Taxation’, 79 American Economic Review, 1196-1206. Wright, L. Hart (1983), ‘Personal, Living or Family Matters and the Value Added Tax’, 82(3) Michigan Law Review, 419-430. Yeh, Chiou Nan (1979), ‘The Incidence of the Value added Tax in a Neoclassical Growth Model’, 34(2) Public Finance, 277-292. Young, Claire F.L. (1991), ‘Introduction of a Goods and Services Tax: The Canadian Experience’, 8(3) Australian Tax Forum, 259-280.
138
Consumption Tax
6040
Zuckerman, Ben Ami (1972), ‘Proposals for a Value Added Tax in Israel’, 26(6) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 241-243.
6050 PERSONAL INCOME TAXATION Yoshihiro Masui Associate Professor Graduate School of Law and Politics, The University of Tokyo
Minoru Nakazato Professor Graduate School of Law and Politics, The University of Tokyo © Copyright 1999 Minoru Nakazato and Yoshihiro Masui
Abstract This survey traces the literature on the three fundamental components of personal income taxation: base, unit and rates. It first discusses the debates between income tax base and consumption tax base in a chronological order, starting from Simons, and continuing up until the law and economics literature in the 1990s. The chapter then reviews recent law review articles on tax units. Finally, it examines discussions on progressive rate structures. This article finds a distinct shift in appproach, due to the emergence of optimal tax theory. JEL classification: K34 Keywords: Taxation, Income, Consumption, Tax Base, Tax Unit, Tax Rates
1. Introduction Taxation is an ‘old’ area of law and economics studies. It has been studied by economists as an important area of public finance as well as by lawyers as an integral branch of law governing private property. Thus, personal income taxation, especially after its emergence as a major revenue raiser in industrially developed countries, could be called one of the oldest research subjects in law and economics. Indeed, the modern concept of comprehensive income can be traced back to Schantz (1896) who, based on the ability-to-pay (Leistungsfaehigkeit) tradition of tax theory, argued against his predecessors by defining income broadly as the increase of net assets during a given period. It is well known that his conception was well received on the other side of the Atlantic. It was refined by Haig (1921) and Simons (1938). Particularly the latter laid down a conceptual foundation of personal income taxation in the US, refuting the Fisherian concept of income as consumption.
139
140
Personal Income Taxation
6050
On the other hand, lawyers’ inquiries into issues of personal income taxation have differed from country to country. It is by no means the US that has produced the richest volume of academic work on the law and economics concerning taxation. In Germany, legal scholars traditionally have been remote from law and economics studies. Although Germany is the mother country of Adolf Wagner and Georg Schantz, capital gains from personal property have been excluded from the taxable income of individuals, which is a significant deviation from the comprehensive income principle. The UK has traditionally adhered to a schedular system of personal income taxation, rather than comprehensive conception of income; tax lawyers are trained in an environment where they tend to view income tax as a set of various levies on transactions, rather than a personal tax on a single base. In Japan, lawyers began a systematic research on income taxation after the 1949 Shoup Recommendation (for a synthesis, see Kaneko, 1995), and their interest has been recently bolstered by developments in law and economics studies in general.
2. The Scope and Structure of this Survey Given the long history of tax research and the variety of studies taking place in different regions, it is impossible to introduce all the major works on the subject; by its very nature, the quest for creating an academic inventory has to be partial. Instead of being exhaustive, this chapter shall trace those articles, mainly written in English, which aroused salient debates on the three fundamental components of personal income taxation: base, unit and rates. Accordingly, the chapter proceeds as follows. Part A will trace the major debates between income tax base and consumption tax base in chronological order, starting from Simons (1938), and continuing up until the law and economics literature in the 1990s. Part B will review recent law review articles on tax units. Part C will examine the literature on progressive tax rate structures. Part D will conclude briefly. The line taken here is basically within the ET (equitable taxation) paradigm (Musgrave, 1976) in the sense that personal income tax versus consumption tax is contrasted as measures of equitable taxation. However, it is necessary also to introduce the OT (optimal taxation) perspective, since recent articles increasingly employ the OT analysis. For a convenient anthology of these articles, see White (1995), Baker and Elliot (1990), and McIntyre, Sander and Westfall (1983). The impact of OT perspective is discussed in Cooper (1994).
6050
Personal Income Taxation
141
A. Base 3. Origins In the late nineteenth century, researchers started to discuss the concept of income as a basis for personal taxation. The various concepts of income of the time were reviewed by Wueller (1938a, 1938b, 1939) as belonging either to an ‘accrual type’, which focuses upon inflow, or to a ‘disposition type’, which focuses upon expenditure or disposition. The latter type of definition was put forward by Irving Fisher, and represents an alternative stream within following discussion. It was advocated most notably by Kaldor (1958), who elaborated an expenditure tax design. However, expenditure tax was considered unpractical until recently. The ‘accrual type’ income concept has many varieties. Without going into preceding constructions, let us start directly from Henry Simons whose formulation dominates the following debates. For readers interested in a historical review of the scholarly works of this period, McCombs (1990) gives a good summary of discussions by Haig, Hewett, Simons and Vickrey. For analyses of Simons’ value judgement, see Hettich (1979), Kiesling (1981) and Long (1990).
4. The Impact of Henry Simons Simons (1938) measured personal income as ‘the algebraic sum of (1) the market value of rights exercised in consumption, and (2) the change in the value of the store of property rights between the beginning and end of the period in question’. The essential feature of this formulation is that it defines income as gain to someone during a specified time period. The definition is comprehensive in the sense it does not make any distinction according to source or recurrence; it includes income in kind, gratuitous receipts such as gifts or bequests, and capital gains. Simons saw the comprehensive income as an appropriate tax base for persons, since, by this construction, taxes may be distributed to persons in an equitable manner, especially using a graduated rate structure. Simons’ book covered most of the basic issues in personal income taxation, and his initial definition is modified in order to account for the implementation needs in the real world. Although never fully implemented in any country, Simons’ concept of income became an analytical framework commonly used by researchers especially in the Anglo-Saxon tradition. This was especially true in the US after the Second World War, where numerous casebooks of Federal Income Taxation were compiled with an emphasis on the concept of income as it appeared in legal rules and court cases. Surrey (1973) was one of the most prominent
142
Personal Income Taxation
6050
proponents of comprehensive income taxation, arguing that the concessions to deviate from the normal income tax structure constitutes another form of subsidy - the so-called ‘tax expenditure’. Based on this idea, the tax expenditure budget was introduced in 1974. Surrey and McDaniel (1985) traced the development since 1973 of the tax expenditure concept, considering its impact on budget policy, on tax policy and administration, and on government decisions between using tax expenditure or direct spending to implement subsidy programs. It is noteworthy that the idea of comprehensive income taxation as developed elsewhere, too. In Japan, Kaneko (1966-75) carefully traced the various concepts of income by public finance economists and, based on his detailed comparative survey on the legal systems in various countries, applied the comprehensive concept to the Japanese positive tax law on the issues of realization, imputed income, and illegal income.
5. Comprehensive Tax Base Debate During the same period when proponents of comprehensive income taxation were making efforts to streamline the tax system, growing dissent was emerging, and culminated in the so-called comprehensive tax debate of the late 1960s. The debate was started by Bittker (1967), who argued that a neutral, scientific measure of taxable income is a mirage (for his earlier examination of personal expenditures, see Bittker, 1973). Bittker argues that the concept of Haig-Simons economic income yields no help in many of the contentious areas of income definition. Based on this observation, he concludes that there is no touchstone for tax reform: proposals must be considered provision by provision and policy by policy, on their own particular merits. Bittker’s penetrating criticism invited rejoinders from the proponents of comprehensive income tax such as Musgrave (1967), Pechman (1967) and Galvin (1968). The debate made clear that in many senses the existing income tax base inevitably departed from a pure concept of comprehensive income and that the concept itself has vague outer boundaries. However, Bittker was not formulating a systematic alternative, which may be a reflection of his agnosticism towards the foundations of tax policy. This explains why Surrey, despite Bittker’s criticism, was able to institutionalize a tax expenditure budget after the debate.
6050
Personal Income Taxation
143
6. Andrews’ Breakthrough It did not take long for an alternative construction to come to emerge in discussion. Two works by William Andrews changed the landscape of the debate. While agreeing that it is useful to evaluate departures from an ideal income tax as tax expenditures, Andrews (1972) maintained that the ideal for this purpose must be carefully stated and worked out to embody the intrinsic objectives of the tax. Starting from the Simons’ formulation, Andrews argued that an ideal income tax is one in which tax burdens are apportioned to a taxpayer’s aggregate personal consumption and accumulation. Focusing on the consumption component of the tax base, he contended that there are persuasive reasons why the concept of personal consumption for tax purposes should be elaborated in a way that excludes medical services and whatever satisfactions one obtains from making charitable contributions. One is struck by Andrews’ careful reading of the Simons’ formulation, distinguishing the consumption and the accumulation components of the personal income tax base. By showing that an exclusion of the accumulation component from the income tax base delivers a graduated personal consumption tax, Andrews paved the way for a renewed discussion of tax on personal consumption. Andrews (1974) extended this analysis further. He asserted that the worst inequities, distortions and complexities in the present tax, and the most intractable difficulties in approaching the accretion ideal, have essentially to do with the accumulation component of accretion. He therefore urged that consideration be given to an alternative ideal in which personal taxable income would be computed on a simple cash flow basis to reflect only personal consumption, with accumulation in the form of business and investment assets being comprehensively eliminated. He showed how pursuit of this would produce a substantial net simplification of the tax as well as a fairer and more efficient distribution of tax burdens. Unlike Bittker, who tended to take a piecemeal approach, Andrews was able to build on a conceptual framework based on the economics of time value of money, an essential analytical tool for the accumulation component of the income tax base. Andrews’ work was a breakthrough: while the earlier version of the consumption tax scheme required computation of borrowing, dissaving and imputed income from assets, his prepayment system simply exempts the yield from capital, arriving at the consumption component by deducting the accumulation portion from the tax base. Moreover, Andrews successfully showed that the existing personal income tax is a hybrid of the consumption and accretion models in relation to accumulation, and his diagnosis became accepted by tax theorists and policymakers alike, regardless of their positions for or against his specific proposals for reform.
144
Personal Income Taxation
6050
7. Income or Consumption? Recognizing that the existing personal income tax is a hybrid, opinions diverged whether to pursue a comprehensive income tax ideal or a consumption tax ideal. In the debates that followed, several factors were posited and examined, such as fairness, efficiency and administrative feasibility. On the fairness issue, Warren (1975) suggested that the neutrality of the consumption-type tax is obtained at the cost of allowing income from wealth to escape taxation. Finding the consumption-based tax to be analogous to a tax on wages alone, Warren rejects it as an insufficient compromise in regard to the various legitimate objectives of a basic tax system. To this, Andrews (1975) replied that Warren’s observations do not refute the conclusion that a consumption-type tax would be fairer, pointing out important differences between a wage tax and a consumption-type personal income tax. To Andrews, an income tax, even a true accretion-type tax, was a deficient device for attacking disparities in wealth. Five years later, Warren (1980) further evaluated the arguments that have been advanced in favor of the consumption criterion being superior to the income criterion. He concluded that while either tax can be justified as a means of implementing a plausible principle of distributional equity, the case for superior fairness of the consumption tax is not persuasive on its own terms. Fried (1992), provisionally setting aside the Hobbesian foundational argument that asserts wealth ought not to be regarded as appropriated for private purposes until withdrawn for personal use from the common pool, focused on the unfairness argument of taxing returns to capital per se. She distinguished three theories implicit in the arguments for exempting the return to capital: (1) returns to capital should be exempted as a means of perfecting the income tax; (2) they should be exempted as a means of implementing an endowments tax; and (3) they should be exempted to preserve the relative pre-tax welfare of savers and spenders. Her conclusion was that none presents a persuasive case for the greater fairness of a consumption tax. On efficiency, economists are almost unanimous in holding that an income tax base discriminates against savings and favors current consumption, whereas a consumption tax base is more neutral as regards the saving decision of individuals. On administrative feasibility, Graetz (1979) applied his general analysis of legal transitions to the issue of substituting a progressive consumption tax for income tax, and suggests that the obstacles to implementing a progressive personal tax on consumption would be substantial, but not prohibitive. Given practical difficulties, however, he warned that proponents of an expenditure tax should be required to demonstrate that its claimed advantages in terms of equity and economic efficiency are real and cannot be achieved in a simpler fashion. He asserted that unless and until this burden of proof is met, replacing the income tax with a progressive personal tax
6050
Personal Income Taxation
145
on consumption should remain low on the list of political priorities, and that the principal utility of expenditure tax analysis should continue to lie in illuminating issues of income taxation and increasing the understanding of tax policy. Shachar (1984) examined the issue of transition, proposing that changes in the tax treatment of both assets and liabilities must be considered on a case-by-case basis in order to determine which type of transition rule would place the tax burden on the superior risk bearer. He pointed out that transition rules are necessary to avoid windfalls and double taxation. Serious debates in academic and policy circles followed between income tax proponents and consumption tax proponents (Pechman, 1977; Gulper and Pechman, 1980; Aaron, 1988; and Marshall and Wells, 1993). Some tried to pave the way to an income tax model (Gunn, 1979; Shakow, 1986; Fellows, 1990), while others urged the move to a consumption tax model (Institute for Fiscal Studies, 1978; Bradford et al. 1984; and Bradford, 1986). Nakazato (1991a) supported the consumption tax base from a lifetime perspective, arguing that Simons’ income artificially limits the time range of base measurement, that the traditional equity justification of Simons’ income lacks grounds, and that the consumption tax base is neutral in the time preferences of individuals.
8. Extension In the meantime, the relevance of a comparison between income and consumption tax bases was questioned by Strnad (1985). Strnad argued that in a non-general-equilibrium setting where the effect of taxes on pre-tax prices is not included in the analysis, the cash-flow income tax and not the traditional income tax implements the Haig-Simons ideal; thus, the generally accepted income tax analyses of activities as disparate as corporations investing in machines, individuals contributing to pension funds, and businesses financing their operations by debt have no theoretical basis. Strnad’s sensational reappraisal was rejected by Kaplow and Warren (1986), who demonstrated that Strnad’s conclusion that a cash flow tax properly implements a tax on ‘income’ is a correct, but tautological, derivation from the starting point of Strnad income, which is not the same as Haig-Simons income. Popkin (1986) agreed with Kaplow and Warren in that Strnad’s conclusion rests on a definition of the Haig-Simons ideal that already contains a bias in favor of the consumption tax. Further he added that the Strnad version of the Haig-Simons definition is defective on basic fairness grounds because it adopts a mistaken view of when a taxpayer has fairly discharged a tax obligation to the government. Strnad (1986) and Strnad (1987) are replies to Popkin and to Kaplow and Warren respectively. Strnad (1990) dealt with the question of ‘periodicity’ - how often changes in value should be assessed and taxed - in the context of implementing
146
Personal Income Taxation
6050
accrual taxation. Despite heated debates and strong criticism, the robustness of income tax idea proved itself in the real world. The US Department of the Treasury (1984) opted for an expansion of the income tax base with a less graduated rate structure, which became a basis for the 1986 Reagan Tax Reform. In the late 1980s, similar tax reforms with base-broadening and rate-flattening followed in other countries, although no country ever switched completely to a consumption tax structure. The income tax system remains a hybrid. It has not been perfected as a pure accretion model, nor has it undergone a complete change to a consumption tax model. From his perspective as a political scientist, Witte (1985) attacks Simons’ position as ultimately resting on an unclear set of value premises, but still defends a comprehensive income tax on pragmatic grounds such as revenue capacity, administrative efficiency, certainty, simplicity and legitimacy, rather than by traditional value criteria such as fairness and efficiency. While casting a doubt on the future of income taxation, Isenberg (1990) rejects the adoption of a personal tax on consumption, and opts for a value added tax which is essentially a tax on firms. Noting the near consensus among economists that long-term growth would be less hampered by additional taxes if they fell on consumption rather than on income, Graetz (1992), nonetheless, cautions against a broad-based tax on consumption, instead advocates a tax on energy consumption.
9. Enter Optimal Taxation For traditional income tax idealists the hybrid system may seem like a stalemate, but for newer generations the hybrid tax is already a given. Discussions in 1990s tend to focus on the policy evaluation of specific rules and provisions within the hybrid tax framework, but made little direct normative assessment over the appropriateness of either tax base. Underlying this newer work is the emergence of the optimal tax framework and the elaboration of finance theory. McCaffery (1992) argues that one should accept the fact of a hybrid income-consumption tax and begin to examine how best to structure it. Dividing savings into three categories (life cycle, precautionary, and bequest savings), McCaffery contends that because of the different values one places on the different types of savings, some form of a hybrid may in fact be ideal and not merely a practical necessity. Although more empirical work and normative exploration is necessary, his work exemplifies a new trend of discussion on an old issue. Knoll (1994) seeks to direct scholarly attention towards large-scale redesign of the hybrid, away from both marginal improvements in the existing hybrid and the debate over whether there should be an income tax or a consumption tax. He describes and evaluates three hybrid taxes. A blended hybrid, which would reduce the tax rate on investment income, is rejected
6050
Personal Income Taxation
147
because of the impossibility of allocating returns between capital and effort and among various investments. A simple hybrid, which would supplement economic depreciation with an immediate write-off of a given fraction of the investment, and a COCA (Cost of Capital Allowance) system, which would supplement economic depreciation by providing a deduction based on the undepreciated portion of a taxpayer’s assets, are held to serve as models for comprehensive reform. Significance of risk rather than deferral is articulated by Bankman and Griffith (1992). By reviewing historical data, they reveal that substantially all of the real return realized on investments during the past 60 years has been attributable to investment risk, and contend that thus it is appropriate to center the income versus consumption tax debate on the way in which the two tax bases treat risky investments, rather than the way the two tax bases treat interest (interest being defined as the inflation-adjusted return on riskless assets). According to their analysis, taxation of risk premia is much less troublesome than taxation of interest, because many taxpayers will be able to offset the effects of taxation of risk premia by increasing the proportion of risky assets in their portfolios, and because such taxpayers will not be disadvantaged by an income tax. On the other hand, Bankman and Griffith conclude that taxation of risk premia without full loss offsets will disfavor investors in risky assets and raise efficiency concerns. While previous analyses have focused on the time value of money aspect, Bankman and Griffith have highlighted the way in which risk matters. The conceptual weakness, even as an analytical tool, of the Haig-Simons definition of income as a first-best tax principle is revealed by Shaviro (1989b). Shaviro defines as selective limitation of tax benefits those provisions in the Revenue Code that, in response to preferences and resultant income undermeasurement, make certain tax benefits conditional on the character or amount of other items on the taxpayer’s return. He argues that such selective limitations cannot be analyzed solely through the consideration of first-best tax principles, notably the Haig-Simons definition of income, and that the question gives rise to second-best issues that have a discernible theoretical structure with identifiable tradeoffs but are indeterminate in the absence of empirical information. Shaviro (1990) shows the similar indeterminacy of the Haig-Simons definition of income in the measurement of taxable consumption. Shaviro (1992) makes an efficiency analysis of the hybrid tax system and argues that the main advantage of realization and recognition rules, as compared with no tax at all even upon realization, is that they may tend to equalize the ex ante expected taxes from alternative activities or investments. Appeal to definitions, which has been the basic communication code of the income versus consumption tax debate, is set aside by Kaplow (1991), who views that debates about definitions cannot give meaningful guidance to policy unless informed by the objectives underlying the definitions. Kaplow prefers evaluating directly the effects of possible tax rules on individuals’ well-being. He reconsiders the justification for casualty loss and medical expense
148
Personal Income Taxation
6050
deductions, taking into account the availability of private insurance. He argues that when individuals can insure, the second level of insurance implicit in the casualty loss and medical expense deductions has undesirable effects on consumption choices and insurance decisions: individuals may be more exposed to losses because of tax deductions commonly believed to mitigate them. He concludes that, given the option, individuals would prefer a regime that eliminated the deductions and offered correspondingly lower tax rates. His later work (Kaplow, 1994) is another example of his contribution by the use of direct explorations. Here he shows the arithmetic interchangeability between standard deduction and floors. Zolt (1996) examines the case for uniform taxation on efficiency and equity grounds. He concludes that neither economic theory or equity considerations require uniform treatment. He contends that even if we could devise rules that taxed ‘appropriately’ such items as unrealized gains, imputed income, or government services, we may still be able to achieve efficiency and equity gains using tax treatment that varies by type of income or type of taxpayer. He carefully adds, however, that the desirability of the use of nonuniform taxes likely varies among countries and over time.
10. Paradigm Shift Recent law and economics contributions to the debate thus reflect the mainstream intellectual trends in public sector economics which have leaned away from the traditional ET paradigm and towards the OT framework. It is an interesting question if and how this academic work will have an impact on real-world policymaking.
B. Unit 11. The Choice: Individual, Marital, or Family In order to measure income during a specified period, it is necessary to identify whose income is in question. Simons (1938) seems to have advanced his theory on the assumption that natural persons should be taxed as isolated individuals. His approach is a logical consequence of methodological individualism. Others may view persons as social beings whose family ties affect their taxpaying capacity. Underlying this view is the rejection of naked individualism in favor of a conception of ‘self’ which is encumbered with communal conditions. Personal tax units may be designed as based on either of the following: individual, marital, or family. Which system to adopt has been long discussed
6050
Personal Income Taxation
149
in many countries, producing numerous legislative movements. For a comparative survey, see Pechman and Engelhardt (1990), and Kaneko (1996b). Among OECD countries, the design of tax units differs from country to country: some adopt an individual unit system (Australia, Canada, Denmark, Italy, Japan, the UK, and Sweden), some employ a marital unit system (Belgium, Germany and Spain), and others have a family unit system (France and Luxembourg). The US provides multiple tax rates for (1) single individuals, (2) married individuals filing joint tax returns and surviving spouses, (3) married persons electing separate tax returns and (4) heads of households. In addition to the diversity of treatments among different countries, systems in each country often have undergone numerous changes. The discussion of tax unit has multiple facets because it is a reflection of how one views a family, a very controversial institution in our swiftly changing societies. The difficulty of finding common ground is aggravated by the fact that the treatment of a family under personal income taxation is related to all three of the fundamental elements of taxation: base, unit and rates. For example, within an individual unit system, personal deductions could be introduced to make adjustments according to the family status of an individual. Moreover, many legal issues concerning family taxation are inherent to progressive rate structure.
12. Early Discussion Although recognizing the aforementioned difficulty, Oldman and Temple (1960) tried to illuminate the guiding policies for the design of tax units. With a detailed description of the systems then in operation in the Philippines, UK, Sweden, Canada, US and the Netherlands, Oldman and Temple supported the marital unit system as a more reasonable choice than the individual unit system in light of economic realities and administrative feasibility. In so doing they suggested the following: (1) a married couple with only one spouse having an income should pay a greater total tax than a married couple with both spouses working, assuming both couples have the same total income (imputed income from household services); (2) the dual-income couple should pay a greater total tax on its two incomes than would be paid by two single persons with corresponding incomes (economic advantages of joint living); (3) one single person should pay the same or a greater tax than the married couple with one income (the advantages of joint living are never so great that two can live more cheaply than one). Bittker (1975) questioned the validity of these guiding policies. He demonstrated that it is impossible to have (a) progression, (b) equal taxes on equal-income married couples, and (c) a marriage-neutral tax burden. In discussing the relative tax burdens of married couples and other taxpayers, he
150
Personal Income Taxation
6050
examined whether the assumptions of commentators, such as marital burden of supporting a spouse, economies of scale, and unpaid household services, would hold in reality. He concluded that theoreticians, regardless of their backgrounds, be it economics, anthropology or sociology, cannot ‘solve’ the problem of taxing family income; they can only identify the issues, point out conflicts among objectives, propose alternative approaches, and predict the outcome of picking one route rather than another. Having performed these functions, the expert must give way to the citizen, whose judgments can rest on nothing more precise or permanent than collective social preferences. Bittker thus exposed the fundamental dilemma between neutrality among couples and neutrality on marital decisions under a progressive income tax. No commentators since have been able to escape this dilemma. In the face of controversy surrounding the treatment of the family in federal income tax, McIntyre and Oldman (1977) developed a normative model for the taxation of the family based on the ideal of a comprehensive tax base. From this ideal, they suggested a program for reform in which tax burdens would be distributed in accordance with practical estimates of the monetary income enjoyed by individual taxpayers.
13. Divergent Family Models, and a Look at Behavioral Response Although the debate in the 1970s seemed to have led to a fairly widespread consensus that the married couple is an appropriate tax unit, in the 1980s more emphasis was given to the aspect of marriage penalty, rather than the aspect of non-neutrality among couples. Gann (1980) argues that a marriage-neutral income tax system under which all individuals file separate returns under a single rate structure is the most defensible position in the long run. Gann (1983) criticizes the earned income deduction provisions introduced in the US by the 1981 Act, urging that the earned income deduction cannot be supported on an equity criterion of marriage neutrality, although noting that it produces some efficiency gains. Kornhauser (1993) examines the premise that married couples share or pool their incomes. She surveys the changing concept and reality of the ‘family’ and examines several empirical studies that address the issue of the allocation of financial resources between members of a couple living together. Her findings are: not all couples pool assets; that pooling is not confined to married couples, and separation of assets is not confined to non-married couples; that financial arrangements sometimes change during the course of the relationship; and that even among those couples who claim they pool, the non-earner spouse often does not have equal access to assets. Based on this evidence, she argues that the joint filing system is unfair, because it is both under-inclusive (barring some
6050
Personal Income Taxation
151
unmarried poolers from its benefits) and over-inclusive (bestowing its benefits on non-pooling married couples). McCaffery (1993) explores how the tax laws provide behavioral incentives that affect three types of decisions: whether to marry, whether to form a oneor a two-earner household, and whether to work full or part time. He finds that tax laws contribute to the marginalization of women in the workplace, and that they impede a more creative formulation of alternative models of work and family. Pointing out strong class dimensions in the actual patterns of effects, he urges to take steps to put one- and two-earner families on an equal footing. He thus argues a case for altering the basic rate structure to provide significantly lower, even negative, rates for secondary earners, financed by higher rates on primary earners. McCaffery’s approach was to focus on behavioral incentives, where traditional tax policy analysis looked at distributive burdens. McCaffery (1997) is a synthesis of his research based on this approach. Struggling with the dilemma posed by Bittker, Zelenak (1994b) argues that American society at the end of the twentieth century would be better served by separate returns, predicting that the joint return system will eventually disappear, the only question being when. Nakazato (1995) applies Gary Becker’s theory of productive consumption to the treatment of households under the comprehensive income tax model, examining income transfer, imputed income and leisure within a family. He concludes that tax units and income deductions do not provide a satisfactory solution, and that full implementation of a comprehensive income base under an individual unit system would approximately achieve tax neutrality towards the organization of a household. The design of tax units and of various deductions and credits within a household has another dimension: its role as an instrument of welfare and family policies. Alstott (1995) examines the role of tax system in welfare programs, arguing that the case for the EITC (earned income tax credit) has been oversimplified in two significant ways. First, the conventional policy debate over the EITC’s behavioral incentives has been framed too narrowly. Second, the EITC, as a tax-based income-transfer program, faces inherent institutional constraints not present in traditional welfare programs. These include problems of inaccuracy, unresponsiveness and noncompliance that are inherent in tax-based administration.
14. Expansion of Arena In sum, recent studies embody analyses of people’s behavioral responses to the structure of tax units, as well as wider examinations of family taxation in interaction with social and welfare policies.
152
Personal Income Taxation
6050
C. Rates 15. The Conundrum Concerning Progression The most significant issue on the tax rates of personal income tax is progression. The progressive tax rate structure is one component of the progressive tax mechanism, and the overall progression of the tax is dependent on all three elements of personal income taxation: base, unit and rates. Simons (1938) recognized this, arguing against the theory of declining utility and examining the case for redistribution of income and wealth in its own terms. The support for redistribution and for progressive taxation as a means to more economic equality was strong among New Dealers. One example is Vickrey (1947), who proposed an agenda for progressive taxation: he devoted a chapter on the graduation of taxes, examining the methods of graduation, the choice of graduation curves, the use of mathematical formulas, and the size of tax brackets. Throughout the decades after the Second World War, the patterns of Federal Income Tax legislation in the US were consistently progressive.
16. The Uneasy Case It is ironic that Blum and Kalven (1953), the most widely acknowledged academic work on the issue of progression, claimed that the case for progressive taxation is uneasy. They traced various affirmative arguments for progressive tax on all incomes over a minimum subsistence exemption, looking at: (1) maintaining economic stability and a high level of business activity; (2) taxes levied in accordance with the benefits received; (3) the declining utility of money (sacrifice theory); and (4) mitigating economic inequality. They also examined the implications of exemptions on the case for progression, and considered whether any of the preceding analysis of the merits of progression would be affected by considerations regarding how the government spends the tax money that it collects. They concluded that the case for progression turns out to be stubborn but uneasy. Galvin and Bittker (1969) made several points in support of a progressive federal income tax rate structure. They note that (1) if the case for progression is ‘uneasy’, so too is the case for a proportional rate schedule; (2) progression in federal income tax serves to counterbalance the regressive tendencies in other federal, state and local taxes; (3) progression is an inevitable consequence of allowing personal exemption in computing income tax liability; (4) economic security increases more than proportionately as one moves up the income scale; (5) benefits of government expenditures increase progressively with income and wealth; and (6) progressive tax rates
6050
Personal Income Taxation
153
serve as a measure to reduce economic inequality, fitting comfortably within the forms of democratic capitalism.
17. Flat Tax and the Optimal Taxation Framework It was not until the 1980s that the progressive rate structure was overhauled. Various proposals were made to make the personal income tax rates flat in the US Congress. The 1986 Tax Reform reduced the number of brackets and the top marginal income tax rate significantly. Subsequently, rate cutting, coupled with base broadening measures, became a worldwide trend in tax reform in other countries. Graetz (1983) addresses the problem of the transition to a flat-rate tax, arguing that the minimum tax amendments of the 1982 Act in the Internal Revenue Code constitute a transitional mechanism that can be regarded as a first step to phasing in a broad-based tax. Hall and Rabushka (1995) propose a flat-tax plan under which all income would be taxed once at a uniform rate of 19 percent, based on the consumption tax principle. O’Kelley (1985) describes how adopting a flat rate comprehensive income tax that uses personal exemption could result in tax burdens substantially more progressive than under the then current system, arguing for a personal exemption equal in amount to the minimum wage, and for integrating the income tax and the social security systems. Bankman and Griffith (1987) re-examine the traditional economic arguments against progressive taxation from the perspective of distributive justice. They critically analyze both the labor-related efficiency costs of progressive taxation, and the traditional arguments that progressivity imposes significant administrative costs, promotes misallocation of capital, and increases tax evasion. They go on to describe an optimal tax model for calculating the most desirable tax rate, balancing the costs of progressivity against possible gains from redistribution. Their model suggests that under most welfare theories, the optimal tax rate should be progressive, but not confiscatory, and that a progressive tax is best implemented not in the form of graduated or rising marginal rates, but rather through a combination of cash grants and constant or even declining marginal rates.
D. Conclusion 18. From Definition to Numbers This chapter briefly reviewed the existing literature on personal income taxation. Overall, the survey shows a shift in approach, which broadly involved a change ‘from definition to numbers’. Traditionally, the main interests of
154
Personal Income Taxation
6050
researchers were how to define the concept of income, how to structure an appropriate tax unit based on taxpaying capacity, and how to design the rate according to some intuitive notion of vertical equity. More recently, with the emergence of optimal taxation theory, discussions are beginning to focus on the implications of social welfare functions, and on the market responses to particular tax rules. Looking at the names of authors cited, one may note that this intellectual shift is due to the advent of new generation of law and economics scholars armed with analytical devices which connect policy discussions directly to normative criteria such as equity and efficiency. Personal income taxation has strong connections with other elements of human behavior, including the formation of human capital, the choice between labor and leisure, the investment decision, the compliance and evasion of legal rules, and the geographical location of resources. Hereby, personal income taxation is but one aspect of a larger inquiry into the connection between law and human behavior. As such, interested readers should consult other chapters in this volume relating to the family, finance, labor, social security and administration.
Bibliography on Personal Income Taxation (6050) Aaron, Henry J., Galper, Harveu and Pechman, Joseph A. (eds) (1988), Uneasy Compromise: Problems of a Hybrid Income-Consumption Tax, Washington, Brookings Institution, 441 p. Alchin, Terry (1985), ‘Prota: A New Measure of the Progressivity of Personal Income Taxation’, 24(44) Australian Economic Papers, 185-200. Allen, Tuovi (1985), ‘Vahennykset Tuloverotuksessa Tulonsiirtopolitiikan Jatke? (With English summary) (Deductions in Personal Income Taxation Substitutes for Government Transfer Programmes?)’, 81(1) Kansantaloudellinen Aikakauskirja, 65-72. Alstott, Anne L. (1995), ‘The Earned Income Tax Credit and the Limitation of Tax-Based Welfare Reform’, 108 Harvard Law Review, 533-592. Anderson, Gary M. and Tollison, Robert D. (1993), ‘Political Influence and the Ratification of the Income Tax Amendment’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 259-270. Andrews, William D. (1972), ‘Personal Deductions in an Ideal Income Tax’, 86 Harvard Law Review, 309-385. Andrews, William D. (1974), ‘A Consumption-Type or Cash-Flow Personal Income Tax’, 87 Harvard Law Review, 1113-1188. Andrews, William D. (1975), ‘Fairness and the Choice Between a Consumption-Type and an Accretion-Type Income Tax: A Reply to Professor Warren’, 88 Harvard Law Review, 947-958. Arnold, Brian J. (1983), Timing and Income Taxation: The Principles of Income Measurement for Tax Purposes, Canadian Tax Paper, 71. Baker, Samuel H. and Elliott, Catherine S. (1990), Readings in Public Sector Economics, Lexington, D.C. Heath, 603 p.
6050
Personal Income Taxation
155
Bankman, Joseph and Griffith, Thomas (1987), ‘Social Welfare and the Rate Structure: A New Look at Progressive Taxation’, 75 California Law Review, 1905-1967. Bankman, Joseph and Griffith, Thomas (1992), ‘Is the Debate Between an Income Tax and a Consumption Tax a Debate About Risk? Does it Matter?’, 47 Tax Law Review, 377-406. Batina, Raymond G. (1991), ‘Equity, and the Time Consistent Taxation of Income’, 93(3) Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 407-419. Bhargava, P.K. and Jain, A.K. (1982), ‘Personal Income Taxation and Equity in India’,36(12) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 535-538. Bittker, Boris I. (1967), ‘A Comprehensive Tax Base as a Goal of Income Tax Reform’, 80 Harvard Law Review, 925-985. Bittker, Boris I. (1968), ‘Comprehensive Income Taxation: A Response’, 81 Harvard Law Review, 1032-1043. Bittker, Boris I. (1973), ‘Income Tax Deductions, Credits, and Subsidies for Personal Expenditures’, 16 Journal of Law and Economics, 193-213. Bittker, Boris I. (1975), ‘Federal Income Taxtion and the Family’, 27 Stanford Law Review, 1389-1463. Blum, Walter J. and Kalven, Harry, Jr (1953), The Uneasy Case for Progressive Taxation, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Blum, Walter J. and Kalven, Harry, Jr (1982), ‘Revisiting the Uneasy Case for Progressive Taxation’, 60 Taxes, 16 ff. Bradford, David F. (1986), Untangling the Income Tax, A Committee for Economic Development Publication, Harvard University Press, 386 p. Bradford, David F. and the U.S. Treasury Tax Policy Staff (1984), Blueprints for Basic Tax Reform (second edition), Arlington, Tax Analysts, 194 p. Chen, Charng Yi (1990), ‘Risk-Preferences and Tax-Induced Dividend Clienteles: Evidence from the Insurance Industry’, 57 Journal of Risk and Insurance, 199-219. Chirinko, Robert S. (1981), ‘A Further Comment on ‘Would Tax Shifting Undermine the Tax Based Incomes Policy?’’, 15 Journal of Economic Issues, 177-181. Cooper, Graeme S. (1994), ‘An Optimal or Comprehensive Income Tax?’, 22 Federal Law Review, 414-447. Coven, G.E. (1981), ‘Decline and Fall of Taxable Income’, 79 Michigan Law Review, 1525-1572. Davies, John H. (1984), ‘Income-Plus-Wealth: In Search of a Better Tax Base’, 15 Rutgers Law Journal, 849-896. Fellows, Mary Louise (1990), ‘A Comprehensive Attack on Tax Deferral’, 88 Michigan Law Review, 722-813. Fortin, Bernard (1988), ‘Should the Current Tax-Transfer System be Replaced by a Flat-Rate Income Tax?’, 26 Osgoode Hall Law Journal, 423-431. Fried, Barbara H. (1992), ‘Fairness and the Consumption Tax’, 44 Stanford Law Review, 961-1017. Galvin, Charles (1968), ‘More on Boris Bittker and the Comprehensive Tax Base: The Practicalities of Tax Reform and ABA’s CSTR’, 81 Harvard Law Review, 1016-1031. Galvin, Charles and Bittker, Boris I. (1969), The Income Tax: How Progressive Should It Be?: Rational Debate Seminars, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 183 p.
156
Personal Income Taxation
6050
Gann, P.B. (1980), ‘Abandoning Marital Status as a Factor in Allocating Income Tax Burdens’, 59 Texas Law Review. Gann, P.B. (1983), ‘The Earned Income Deduction: Congress’s 1981 Response to the “Marriage Penalty” Tax’, 68 Cornell Law Review, 468-487. Gavrielidou, Alexandra A. (1990), ‘Enallaktikes Protaseis sto Phoro Eisodematos (Alternative Proposals to the Income Tax)’, 38 Nomiko Vema, 382-400. Gergen, Mark P. (1988), ‘The Case for a Charitable Contributions Deduction’, 74 Virginia Law Review, 1393-1450. Gimeno Ullastres, Juan A. (1980), Imposición Sobre el Consumo y Ddistribución Personal de Rentas (Consumption Taxes and Personal Distribution of Income), Madrid, Instituto de Estudios Fiscales, 341 p. Gimeno Ullastres, Juan A. (1984), ‘Los Presupuestos Familiares (Family Budgets)’, 1 Estudios Sobre el Consumo, 39-45. Graetz, Michael J. (1975), ‘Assessing the Distributional Effects of Income Tax Revision: Some Lessons from Incidence Analysis’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 351-368. Graetz, Michael J. (1979), ‘Implementing a Progressive Consumption Tax’, 92 Harvard Law Review, 1575-1661. Graetz, Michael J. (1983), ‘The 1982 Minimum Tax Amendments as a First Step in the Transition to a “Flat-Tax”’, 56 Southern California Law Review, 527-571. Graetz, Michael J. (1992), ‘Revisiting the Income Tax versus Consumption Tax Debate’, 7 Tax Notes, 1437-1442. Graetz, Michael J. and McDowell, Barbara (1984), ‘Tax Reform 1985: The Quest for a Fairer, More Efficient and Simpler Income Tax’, 3 Yale Law and Policy Review, 5-40. Griffith, Thomas (1989), ‘Theories of Personal Deductions in the Income Tax’, 40 Hastings Law Journal, 343-395. Griffith, Thomas (1994), ‘Efficient Taxation of Mixed Personal and Business Expenses’,41 UCLA Law Review, 1769-1789. Gunn, Alan (1979), ‘The Case for an Income Tax’, 46 University of Chicago Law Review, 370-400. Haig, Robert Murray (1921), The Federal Income Tax. Hall, Robert E. and Rabushka, Alvin (1995), The Flat Tax, 2nd edn, Stanford, Stanford University Press, 152 p. Halperin, Daniel I. (1986), ‘Interest in Disguise: Taxing the ‘Time Value of Money’’, 95 Yale Law Journal, 508-552. Hansmann, Henry B. (1989), ‘Unfair Competition and the Unrelated Business Income Tax’, 75 Virginia Law Review, 605-635. Hatakeyama, Takemichi (1990), ‘Flat Zeiritsu Ronso (Flat Tax Rates Debate)’,964 Juristen, 115-119. Head, John G. and Krever, Richard (1990), Flattening the Tax Rate Scale: Alternative Scenarios and Methodologies, Longman Professional, 410 p. Head, John G. and Krever, Richard (1996), Tax Units and the Tax Rate Scale, Australian Tax Research Foundation, 213 p. Heimler, Alberto and Milana, Carlo (1992), ‘Riforma del Salario, Finanziamento del Servizio Sanitario Nazionale e Crescita Economica (With English summary) (Wage Reform, Functioning of the National Health Service and Economic Growth)’, 26(1) Economia e Lavoro, 67-78.
6050
Personal Income Taxation
157
Hellmuth, William F. and Oldman, Oliver (1973), Tax Policy and Tax Reform: 1961-1969, Selected Speeches and Testimony of Stanley S. Surrey, CCH, 780 p. Hettich, Walter (1979), ‘Henry Simons on Taxation and the Economic System’, 32 National Tax Journal, 1-9. Holland, D.M. (1971), ‘An Evaluation of Tax Incentives for on- the-Job Training of the Disadvantaged’, 2 Bell Journal of Economics, 293-327. Hulten, Charles R. and Schwab, Robert M. (1991), ‘A Haig-Simons-Tiebout Comprehensive Income Tax’, 44(1) National Tax Journal, 67-78. Institute for Fiscal Studies (1978), The Structure and Reform of Direct Taxes: Report of a Committee Chaired by Professor J.E. Meade, London, George Allen and Unwin Ltd., 533 p. Isenberg, Joseph (1990), ‘The End of Income Taxation’, 45 Tax Law Review, 283-361. Jepsen, Gunnar Thorlund (1980), ‘Horisontal Lighed og den Personlige Indkomstskat (Horizontal Equity in Personal Income Taxation. With English summary)’, 118(1) Nationalokonomisk Tidsskrift, 37-50. Johnson, Calvin H. (1989), ‘Soft Money Investing Under the Income Tax’, 1989 University of Illinois Law Review, 1019-1093. Johnson, Manuel H. (1985), ‘President Reagan’s Modified Flat Tax: Analysis and Comparison’, 5 Cato Journal, 499-520. Jones, A.M. and Posnett, J.W. (1991), ‘The Impact of Tax Deductibility on Charitable Giving by Covenant in the U.K.’, 101 Economic Journal, 1117-1129. Joseph, Richard, J. (1996), ‘Why Progressive Taxation?’, 15 Tax Notes, 313-318. Kaldor, N. (1958), An Expenditure Tax, London, George Allen and Unwin Ltd., 249 p. Kale, Jayant R. and Noe, Thomas H. (1990), ‘Corporate Hedging under Personal and Corporate Taxation’, 11(3) Managerial and Decision Economics, 199-205. Kaneko, Hiroshi (1966-75), ‘Sozeiho Ni Okeru Shotoku Gainen No Kosei (1) (3) (Construction of the Concept of Income in Tax Law)’, 92 Hogaku Kyokai Zasshi, 1081-1143. Kaneko, Hiroshi (1995), Shotoku Gainen No Kenkyu (Studies on the Concept of Income), Tokyo, Yuhikaku, 444 p. Kaneko, Hiroshi (1996a), Shotoku Kazei No Ho to Seisaku (Law and Policy in Income Taxation), Tokyo, Yuhikaku, 481 p. Kaneko, Hiroshi (1996b), Kazei Tanni Oyobi Joto Shotoku No Kenkyu (Studies on the Tax Unit and Capital Gains), Tokyo,Yuhikaku, 364 p. Kaplow, Louis (1986), ‘An Economic Analysis of Legal Transitions’, 99 Harvard Law Review, 509-617. Kaplow, Louis (1987), Optimal Transition Policy: Replacing Horizontal Equity with an Ex Ante Incentives Perspective, Dissertation accepted by Harvard University Department of Economics. Kaplow, Louis (1988), ‘Savings Incentives in a Hybrid Income Tax: Comment’, in Aaron, Henry J., Galper, Harveu and Pechman, Joseph A. (eds), Uneasy Compromise: Problems of a Hybrid Income-Consumption Tax, Washington, Brookings Institution. Kaplow, Louis (1989), ‘Horizontal Equity: Measures in Search of a Principle’, 42 National Tax Journal, 139-154. Kaplow, Louis (1991), ‘The Income Tax as Insurance: The Casualty Loss and Medical Expense Deductions and the Exclusion of Medical Insurance Premiums’, 79 California Law Review, 1485-1510.
158
Personal Income Taxation
6050
Kaplow, Louis (1992a), ‘Government Relief for Risk Associated with Government Action’, 94 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 525-541. Kaplow, Louis (1992b), ‘Income Tax Deductions for Losses as Insurance’, 82 American Economic Review, 1013-1017. Kaplow, Louis (1993), ‘Should the Government’s Allocation Branch be Concerned About the Distortionary Cost of Taxation and Distributive Effects?’, Program in Law and Economics Discussion Paper, 122 ff. Kaplow, Louis (1994a), ‘Human Capital under An Ideal Income Tax’, 80 Virginia Law Review, 1477-1514. Kaplow, Louis (1994b), Accuracy, Complexity, and the Income Tax, National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper, No. 4631. Also Harvard Program in Law and Economics Discussion Paper. Kaplow, Louis (1994c), ‘The Standard Deduction and Floors in the Income Tax’, 50 Tax Law Review, 1-31. Kaplow, Louis (1994d), ‘A Note on Taxation as Social Insurance for Uncertain Labor Income’, 49 Public Finance, 244-256. Kaplow, Louis (1994e), ‘Taxation and Risk Taking: A General Equilibrium Perspective’, 47 National Tax Journal, 789-798. Kaplow, Louis (1995a), ‘A Fundamental Objection to Tax Equity Norms: A Call for Utilitarianism’, 48 National Tax Journal, 497-514. Kaplow, Louis (1995b), ‘A Note on Subsidizing Gifts’, 58 Journal of Public Economics, 469-477. Kaplow, Louis (1996a), ‘Tax Treatment of Families’, Encyclopedia of Taxation and Tax Policy, Maryland, University Press of America. Kaplow, Louis (1996b), ‘Fiscal Federalism and the Deductibility of State and Local Taxes in a Federal Income Tax’, Virginia Law Review. Kaplow, Louis (1996c), ‘Regional Cost-of-Living Adjustments in Tax-Transfer Schemes’, Tax Law Review. Kaplow, Louis (1996d), ‘How Tax Complexity and Enforcement Affect the Equity and Efficiency of the Income Tax’, 49 National Tax Journal, 135-150. Kaplow, Louis (1996e), ‘Tax and Non-Tax Distortions’, 24 Journal of Public Economics. Kaplow, Louis (1996f), ‘On the Divergence Between ‘Ideal’ and Conventional Income Tax Treatment of Human Capital’, 86 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings. Kaplow, Louis (1996g), ‘Optimal Distribution and the Family’, Scandinavian Journal of Economics. Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (1994), ‘Why the Legal System is Less Efficient than the Income Tax in Redistributing Income’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 667-681. Kaplow, Louis and Warren, Alvin (1986), ‘An Income Tax by Any Other Name - A Reply to Professor Strnad’, 38 Stanford Law Review, 339-421. Kaplow, Louis and Warren, Alvin (1987), ‘Professor Strnad’s Rejoinder: Simply Semantics’, 39 Stanford Law Review, 419-425. Katz, Avery and Mankiw N. Gregory (1985), ‘How Should Fringe Benefits be Taxed?’, 38 National Tax Journal, 37-45. Kelman (1983), ‘Time Preference and Tax Equity’, 35 Stanford Law Review, 649-680. Kiesling, Herbert J. (1981), ‘Henry Simons, Equality, and the Personal Income Tax’, 34 National Tax Journal, 257-259.
6050
Personal Income Taxation
159
Klein, William A. (1977), ‘Timing in Personal Taxation’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 461-481. Knoll, Michael S. (1994), ‘Designing a Hybrid Income-Consumption Tax’, 41 UCLA Law Review, 1791-1860. Koren, Stephan (1989), ‘Ausgewahlte Steuerreformen im Vergleich. (On the Recent Tax Reforms in Five Industrial Countries) (With English summary)’, 35(5) Konjunkturpolitik, 251-275. Kornhauser, Marjorie E. (1987), ‘The Rhetoric of the Anti- Progressive Income Tax Movement: A Typical Male Reaction’, 86 Michigan Law Review, 465-523. Kornhauser, Marjorie E. (1993), ‘Love, Money and the IRS: Family, Income-Sharing, and the Joint Income Tax Return’, 45 Hastings Law Journal, 63-111. Krever, Richard (1984), ‘Structural Issues in the Taxation of Capital Gains’, 1 Australian Tax Forum, 164-184. Lindholm, Richard W. (ed.) (1986), Examination of Basic Weaknesses of Income as the Major Federal Tax Base, New York, Greenwood Press, 320 p. London, Jack R. (1988), ‘The Impact of Changing Perspectives of Social Equity on Tax Policy: The Marital Tax Unit’, 26 Osgood Hall Law Journal, 287-312. Long, J.B., Jr (1990), ‘In Defense of Henry Simons’ Standing as a Classical Liberal’, 9 Cato Journal, 601-618. Marshall, Marion B. and Wells, Robert J. (1993), ‘Prior Coverage of Consumption Tax Issues’, 15 Tax Notes, 951-955. Martinello, F. and West, E.G. (1991), ‘Education Budget Reductions Via Tax Credits: Some Further Considerations’, 19 Public Finance Quarterly, 355-368. Matthiessen, Lars (1975), ‘Recent Trends in Personal Income Taxation in Sweden’, 33(2) Finanzarchiv, 272-304. McCaffery, Edward J. (1992), ‘Tax Policy Under a Hybrid Income-Consumption Tax’, 70 Texas Law Review, 1145-1218. McCaffery, Edward J. (1993), ‘Taxation and the Family: A Fresh Look at Behavioral Gender Biases in the Code’, 40 UCLA Law Review, 983-1060. McCaffery, Edward J. (1997), Taxing Women, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 310 p. McCaleb, Thomas S. (1985), ‘Public Choice Perspectives on the Flat Tax Follies’, 5 Cato Journal, 613-624. McClelland, Alison and Krever, Rick (1993), ‘Social Security, Taxation Law, and Redistribution: Directions for Reform’, 31 Osgood Hall Law Journal, 63-135. McCombs, J.B. (1990), ‘An Historical Review and Analysis of Early United States Tax Policy Scholarship: Definition of Income and Progressive Rates’, 64 St. John’s Law Review, 471-525. McGee, Robert W. (1975a), ‘Investment Credit for Progress Expenditures Using Phase-In Rule’, Taxation for Accountants, 250-251. McGee, Robert W. (1975b), ‘T.D. 7352: New Rules on Application of Sick Pay Exclusion to Disability Pension Payments’, Taxes, 436-441. McGee, Robert W. (1976), ‘The New Imputed Interest Rules: How They Work’, The Practical Accountant, 63-67. McGee, Robert W. (1984a), The History of the Income Tax in the United States, Occasional Paper, Deakin University, Australia, No. 69.
160
Personal Income Taxation
6050
McGee, Robert W. (1984b), Software Taxation, National Association of Accountants, 305 p. McGee, Robert W. (1985a), ‘Computer Software and the Investment Tax Credit’, 5 Computer Law Journal, 347-362. Reprinted in Accounting and Tax Aspects of Computer Software Manufacturing, Praeger Publishing Company, 1987. Reprinted in The Monthly Digest of Tax Articles, 1985, 6-21. McGee, Robert W. (1985b), Tax Planning in Divorce Settlements, Prentice Hall, 64 p. McGee, Robert W. (1985c), ‘The 1985 Tax Simplification Act’, 1 Business Planning, 14-17. McGee, Robert W. (1985d), ‘Keeping Track of Fringe Benefits ... When To Tax and When Not To Tax’, 1 Controllers Quarterly, 24-27. McGee, Robert W. (1986a), Capital Gains and Losses, Alternative Minimum Tax, Accounting Provisions, Prentice-Hall’s Explanation of the Tax Reform Act of 1986, New Jersey, Prentice Hall, 500 p. McGee, Robert W. (1986b), How Tax Reform Would Affect Profit-Sharing, New Jersey, Prentice Hall, 23 p. McGee, Robert W. (1986c), Tax-Wise Executive Comensation Strategies, New Jersey, Prentice Hall, 44 p. McGee, Robert W. (1986d), International Revenue Service Special Enrollment Examination Questions and Answers, New Jersey, Prentice Hall, 59 p. McGee, Robert W. (1996a), Taxation, Ethics and Public Policy, Dumont Institute for Public Policy Research. <> McGee, Robert W. (1996b), Essays on Accounting,Taxation and Public Finance, Dumont Institute for Public Policy Research. <> McIntyre, M.J. and Oldman, Oliver (1977), ‘Taxation of the Family in a Comprehensive and Simplified Income Tax’, 90 Harvard Law Review, 1573-1630. McIntyre, M.J., Sander, Frank E.A. and Westfall, David (1983), Readings in Federal Taxation, 2nd edn, New York, Foundation, 625 p. Meyer, Peter B. (1976), ‘The Acceptance over Time of Personal Income Taxation: Voluntary Compliance in the Philippines’, 1965, 15(4) Philippine Economic Journal, 604-613. Mookherjee, Dilip and Png, Yvan P.L. (1990), ‘Enforcement Costs and the Optimal Progressivity of Income Taxes’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 411-431. Musgrave, Richard A. (1967), ‘In Defense of an Income Concept’, 81 Harvard Law Review, 44-62. Musgrave, Richard A. (1976), ‘ET, OT, and SBT’, 6 Journal of Public Economics, 3-16. Nadeau, Serge (1988), ‘A Model to Measure the Effects of Taxes on the Real and Financial Decisions of the Firm’, 41(4) National Tax Journal, 467-481. Nakazato, Minoru (1991a), ‘Shotoku Gainen To Jikan (Income Concept and Timing)’, in Kaneko, Hiroshi (ed.), Shotoku Kazei No Kenkyu (Studies on Income Taxation), Tokyo, Yuhikaku, 129-163. Nakazato, Minoru (1991b), ‘Shotoku No Kosei Yoso Toshiteno Shohi (Consumption as a component of income)’, in Kaneko, Hiroshi (ed.), Shotoku Kazei No Kenkyu (Studies on Income Taxation), Tokyo, Yuhikaku, 35-71. Nakazato, Minoru (1995), ‘Katei To Sozei Seido (Family and Tax System)’, 1059 Jurist, 31-36.
6050
Personal Income Taxation
161
O’Kelley, C.R. (1981), ‘Rawls, Justice, and The Income Tax’, 16 Georgia Law Review, 1-32. O’Kelley, C.R. (1985), ‘Tax Policy for Post-Liberal Society: A Flat-Tax-Inspired Redefinition of the Purpose and Ideal Structure of a Progresive Income Tax’, 58 Southern California Law Review, 727-776. Oldman, Oliver and Temple, Ralph (1960), ‘Comparative Analysis of the Taxation of Married Persons’, 12 Stanford Law Review, 585-605. Paci, Pierella (1988), ‘Tax Based Incomes Policies: Will They Work? Have They Worked?’, 9(2) Fiscal Studies, 81-94. Parsons, Ross W. (1986), ‘Income Taxation An Institution in Decay?’, 3 Australian Tax Forum, 233-266. Pechman, Joseph A. (1967), ‘Comprehensive Income Taxation: A Comment’, 81 Harvard Law Review, 63-67. Pechman, Joseph A. (1977),Comprehensive Income Taxation, Washington, Brookings Institution, 311 p. Pechman, Joseph A. (1980),What Should Be Taxed: Income or Expenditure?, Washington, Brookings Institution, 311 p. Pechman, Joseph A. and Engelhardt, Gray V. (1990), ‘The Income Tax Treatment of the Family’, 43 National Tax Journal, 1-22. Peterson, Wallace C. (1991), Transfer Spending, Taxes, and the American Welfare, Dordrecht, Kluwer, 192 p. Pope, Jeff (1989), ‘The Compliance Costs of Personal Income Taxation: A Review of the Issues’, 6(2) Australian Tax Forum, 125-142. Pope, Jeff and Fayle, Richard (1990), ‘The Compliance Costs of Personal Income Taxation in Australia 1986/87: Empirical Results’, 7(1) Australian Tax Forum, 85-126. Popkin, William D. (1986), ‘Tax Ideals in the Real World: A Comment on Professor Strnad’s Approach to Tax Fairness’, 62 Indiana Law Journal, 63-72. Rea, Samuel A., Jr (1984), ‘Taxes, Transfers and the Family’, 34 University of Toronto Law Journal, 314-340. Roin, Julie, A. (1988), ‘United they Stand, Divided They Fall: Public Choice Theory and the Tax Code’, 74 Cornell Law Review, 62-134. Ruiz-Huerta Carbonell, Jesús (1995), Las Rentas de las Personas Mayores (Eldest Citizens’ Income), SECOT. Ruiz-Huerta Carbonell, Jesús, Alvarez, Jesús, Ayala, Luis, Iriondo, Iñaki, Martinez, Rosa and Palacios, Juan Ignacio (1995), La Distribución Funcional y Personal de la Renta en España (Functional and Personal Distribution of Income in Spain), Premio de Investagión 1995 del Consejo Económico y Social. Rupley, Lawrence A. (1978), ‘Personal Income-based Taxation in the Northern States of Nigeria and the Effect of Uniform Income Taxation’, 32(89) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 401-410. Russell, R. Robert (1986), ‘Tax Based Incomes Policies: Some Skeptical Remarks’, in Colander, David C. (ed.), IncentiveBased Incomes Policies: Advances in TIP and MAP, Cambridge, MA, Harper and Row, 159-175. Salzyn, Vladimir (1988), ‘Desigining an Optimal Personal Income Tax Rate Structure: Goals and Criteria’, 26 Osgoode Hall Law Journal, 577-602.
162
Personal Income Taxation
6050
Sanchez, Isabel (1990), ‘Evasión Fiscal, Regulación y Mecanismos Óptimos de Inspección (Tax Evasion, Regulation, and Optimal Auditing Mechanisms)’, 2 Cuadernos Económicos de ICE, 45 ff. Sanchez, Isabel (1993), ‘Hierarchical Design and Enforcement of Income Tax Policies’, 50 Journal of Public Economics, 345-369. Schantz, Georg (1896), ‘Der Einkommensbefriff und die Einkommensteuergesetze’, 13 Finanzarchiv, 1-87. Schmalbeck, Richard L. (1984), ‘Income Averaging After Twenty Years: A Failed Experiment in Horizontal Equity’, 64 Duke Law Journal, 509-580. Schwartz, Eli and Aronson, J. Richard (1972), ‘How to Integrate Corporate and Personal Income Taxation’, 27(5) Journal of Finance, 1073-1080. Seidl, Christian (1979a), ‘Reform der Steuern auf Einkommen und Ertrag, Novellierung des herrschenden Steuersystems oder Systemänderung durch eine modifizierte analytische Einkommensteuer? (Reforming the Income Tax, Improving the Traditional Tax or Tax Reform by a Schedule Income Tax?)’, 6(4) Freie Argumente, Freiheitliche Zeitschrift für Politik, 1-56. Seidl, Christian (1979b), ‘Das Konzept einer Modifizierten Analytischen Einkommensteuer als Alternative zum Herrschenden System Direkter Steuern (A Schedule Income Tax as an Alternative to the Traditional System of Direct Taxation)’, 26(5) Wirtschaftspolitische Blätter, 49-62. Seidl, Christian (1980), ‘Ein Analytisches Einkommensteuerkonzept mit Flankierenden Steuern (A Schedule Income Tax with Matching Other Taxes)’, in Helige, O. (ed.), Dokumentation zur Steuerreformkommission, Wirtschaftsverlag Dr. Anton Orac, Wien, 128-155. Sewell, David (1988), ‘Towards Longer Time Horizons in Personal Taxation’, 26 Osgoode Hall Law Journal, 235-258. Shachar, Avishai (1984), ‘From Income to Consumption Tax: Criteria for Rules of Transition’, 97 Harvard Law Review, 1581-1609. Shakow, David J. (1986), ‘Taxation Without Realization: A Proposal for Accrual Taxation’, 134 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1111-1205. Shaviro, Daniel N. (1988), ‘The New Alternative Minimum Tax: Perception, Reality, and Strategy’, 66 Taxes, 91-113. Shaviro, Daniel N. (1989a), ‘Risk and Accrual: The Tax Treatment of Nonrecourse Debt’, 44 Tax Law Review, 401-457. Shaviro, Daniel N. (1989b), ‘Selective Limitations on Tax Benefits’, 56 University of Chicago Law Review, 1189-1260. Shaviro, Daniel N. (1990), ‘The Man Who Lost Too Much: Zarin v. Commissioner and the Measurement of Taxable Consumption’, 45 Tax Law Review, 215-258. Shaviro, Daniel N. (1992), ‘An Efficiency Analysis of Realization and Recognition Rules Under the Federal Income Tax’, 48 Tax Law Review, 1-68. Shaviro, Daniel N. (1993), ‘Commentary: Uneasiness and Capital Gains’, 48 Tax Law Review, 393-417. Shaviro, Daniel N. (1995), ‘Risk-Based Rules and the Taxation of Capital Income’, 50 Tax Law Review, 643-724. Simons, Henry C. (1938), Personal Income Taxation: The Definition of Income as a Problem of Fiscal Policy, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 283 p.
6050
Personal Income Taxation
163
Sommerhalder, Ruud A. (1996), Comparing Individual Income Tax Reforms: a Dutch Perspective, IBFD, 471 p. Steven, Paul B. (1984), ‘Federal Income Taxation and Human Capital’, 70 Virginia Law Review, 1357-1427. Stout, Lynn A. (1981), ‘Note: The Case for Mandatory Separate Filing by Married Persons’, 91 Yale Law Journal, 363-382. Strnad, Jeff (1985), ‘Taxation of Income from Capital: A Theoretical Reappraisal’, 37 Stanford Law Review, 1023-1107. Strnad, Jeff (1986), ‘Tax Timing and the Haig-Simons Ideal: A Rejoinder to Professor Popkin’, 62 Indiana Law Journal, 73-94. Strnad, Jeff (1987), ‘The Bankruptcy of Conventional Tax Timing Wisdom is Deeper Than Semantics: A Rejoinder to Professors Kaplow and Warren’, 39 Stanford Law Review, 389-417. Strnad, Jeff (1990), ‘Periodicity and Accretion Taxation: Norms and Implementation’, 99 Yale Law Journal, 1877-1911. Surrey, Stanley S. (1973), Pathways to Tax Reform: The Concept of Tax Expenditures, Harvard University Press, 418 p. Surrey, Stanley S. and McDaniel, P.R. (1985), Tax Expenditures, Harvard University Press, 303 p. US Department of the Treasury (1984), Tax Reform for Fairness, Simplicity, and Economic Growth, The Treasury Department Report to the President, US Department of the Treasury, 262 p. Veall, Michael R. (1987), ‘A Note on the Expenditure Tax and Progressivity’, 40 National Tax Journal, 261-263. Vickrey, William (1947), Agenda for Progressive Taxation, New York, Ronald Press, 496 p. Warren, Alvin (1975), ‘Fairness and a Consumption-Type or Cash Flow Personal Income Tax’, 88 Harvard Law Review, 931-946. Warren, Alvin (1980), ‘Would a Consumption Tax be Fairer than an Income Tax?’, 89 Yale Law Journal, 1081-1124. Weck-Hannemann, Hannelore (1996), ‘Frauenerwerbstätigkeit und Familienbesteuerung (Female Employment and Family Taxation)’, in Thöni, Erich and Winner, Hannes (eds), Die Familie im Sozialstaat. Familienbesteuerung aus ökonomischer und juristischer Sicht Veröffentlichungen der Universität Innsbruck 216, Innsbruck, 191-207. Weiss, Deborah (1993), ‘Can Capital Tax Be Fair? Stimulating Savings Through Differentiated Tax Rates’, 78 Cornell Law Review, 206-251. White, P.D. (1995), Tax Law I., II., Dartmouth, Aldershot, 1008 p. Witte, John F. (1985), The Politics and Development of the Federal Income Tax, Madison, University of Wisconsin, 438 p. Wittmann, Rolf (1992), Das Markteinkommen: einfachgesetzlicher Struckturbegriff und verfassungsdirigierter Anknuepfungsgegenstand der Einkommensteuer?, Augsburg, Verlag Rudolf Wittmann, 132 p. Wueller, Paul H. (1938a), ‘Concepts of Taxable Income I: The German Contribution’, 53 Political Science Quarterly, 83-110. Wueller, Paul H. (1938b), ‘Concepts of Taxable Income II: The American Contribution’, 53 Political Science Quarterly, 557-583.
164
Personal Income Taxation
6050
Wueller, Paul H. (1939), ‘Concepts of Taxable Income III: The Italian Contribution’, 54 Political Science Quarterly, 555-576. Yohe, Gary W. (1985), ‘Improving Tax-based Incomes Policies: The Lessons of the Environmental Literature’, 13 Public Finance Quarterly, 183-205. Yorio, Edward (1982), ‘Federal Income Tax Rulemaking: An Economic Approach’, 51 Fordham Law Review, 1 ff. Zelenak, Lawrence (1994a), ‘Children and the Income Tax’, 49 Tax Law Review, 349-418. Zelenak, Lawrence (1994b), ‘Marriage and the Income Tax’, 67 Southern California Law Review, 339-405. Zelenak, Lawrence (1995), ‘Flat Tax vs. VAT: Progressivity and Family Alloances’, 27 Tax Notes, 1129-1134. Zelinsky, Edward P. (1986), ‘Efficiency and Income Taxes: The Rehabilitation of Tax Incentives’, 64 Texas Law Review, 973-1037. Zolt, Eric M. (1996), ‘The Uneasy Case for Uniform Taxation’, 16 Virginia Tax Review, 39-109.
6060 CORPORATE TAXATION Charlotte Crane Northwestern University School of Law © Copyright 1999 Charlotte Crane
Abstract Much of the traditional economic literature has until relatively recently ignored almost all of the details of the coverage of the tax and the legal institutions within which the tax has developed. As a result, most of the rules used in establishing corporate tax liabilities are the outgrowth of legal formalisms. Although many discussions of reforms of tax rules use as their starting point some rudimentary assumptions about incentives and effects, few of these discussions consider less obvious incentives and interactions or attempt to verify their analysis empirically. This chapter will therefore focus primarily on those treatments that go beyond these typical rudimentary assumptions. The bibliography deals only with those works that go well beyond descriptive treatments and practical expositions of the legal rules in question. JEL classification: K22, K34 Keywords: Corporate Income Tax, Tax Burden and Incidence, Corporate Financial Structure
1. Introduction and Note on Scope Corporations, measures of corporate profits, and taxes imposed thereon are uniquely legal institutions. They have no physical reality; they are entirely the product of legal and accounting rules. But because of the importance of corporate activity in modern economies, scholars in economics and finance who have no other interest in law or legal institutions have long had an interest in analyzing the effects of corporate taxes. To the extent that this work uses economic analysis to understand and predict the behavior of firms as well as the development of legal rules, this body of literature must be considered in any review of the treatment of the corporate tax as ‘law and economics’. References to works in a wide variety of methodologies are therefore included in this bibliographic review. Much of this traditional economic literature has until relatively recently ignored almost all of the details of the coverage of the tax and the legal institutions within which the tax has developed. At least in the United 165
166
Corporate Taxation
6060
States, these details have evolved through a continuing dialog between the legislature (which until relatively recently formally prescribed only the most skeletal of rules) and the courts (which have felt free to allow the approaches of the common law to contribute to the development of the legal rules), as prompted by the Internal Revenue Service. As a result, most of the rules used in establishing corporate tax liabilities (for instance, those according to which entities are classified as subject to the tax, those according to which debt is distinguished from equity, those according to which share redemptions are distinguished from dividends, and those according to which corporate reorganizations are classified as taxable or nontaxability) are the outgrowth of legal formalisms, particularly the idea that a corporation can be an entity entirely separate from its participants. These formalisms developed without any conscious attention to their economic effect. There are therefore only a few justifications and analyses of the substantive rules of corporate taxation of the sort those well-read in other areas of law and economics might find familiar. Indeed, a leading monograph analyzing the corporate law through the lens of law and economics makes only scant reference to the possibility that taxes have an influence on the legal relationships between corporations and their shareholders (Easterbrook and Fischel, 1991). Furthermore, the evolution of most of these details has historically been, and continues to be, dominated by manipulation of these formal constructs by institutions for which there is only rudimentary understanding of their nature as ‘economic’ actors. Although many discussions of reforms of tax rules use as their starting point some rudimentary assumptions about incentives and effects (most commonly, that taxpayers will attempt to minimize tax burdens at least to the extent that the avoided burden exceeds the cost of avoidance and that differential treatment of economically similar transactions will produce inefficient distortions), few of these discussions consider less obvious incentives and interactions or attempt to verify their analysis empirically. (Roin, 1988; Kanda and Levmore, 1991, and Arlen and Weiss, 1995, are notable exceptions). This review will therefore focus primarily on those treatments that go beyond these typical rudimentary assumptions. Thus only a small portion of the literature considered here can be solidly classified as ‘law and economics’, rather than traditional economic analysis of the effect of tax laws on legal institutions. This chapter focuses on the effects of taxes that are encountered only by incorporated entities, and does not consider the effects of taxes that are imposed regardless of the legal form in which capital is held. Thus it does not generally consider the effect of taxes on overall capital formation beyond basic questions of corporate financial structure. However, many of the works cited herein, particularly earlier works, may have (in many cases knowingly, but in other cases unwittingly) assumed a substantial congruence between
6060
Corporate Taxation
167
the ‘business’ and ‘corporate’ sectors, and there is, therefore, a substantial overlap with that literature. For survey treatments of capital and business taxes generally, see Gravelle (1994) and Halpern and Mintz (1992, with emphasis on Canada). This bibliography deals only with those works that go well beyond descriptive treatments and practical expositions of the legal rules in question. The reader is cautioned, however, that, perhaps more than other areas of the law, the rules outlining the base of the corporate income tax are complex, and that assumptions about the impact of potential tax liabilities can rarely be made without a relatively sophisticated understanding of them. Comprehensive introductions to the overall income tax systems of various jurisdictions and an introductory bibliography can be found in Ault (1997); additional descriptions of the corporate tax systems in specific jurisdictions can be found in Brooks (1997) (Canada); Pender (1997) (Australia); Muten (1997) (Scandinavia); Teixeira (1997) (Portugal, Great Britain, Holland). More detailed surveys of tax-base defining rules and rates can be found in the looseleaf services of the International Bureau of Fiscal Documentation, as well as in various pamphlet series of the larger accounting firms, including Coopers and Lybrand, Klynveld Peat Marwick Goerdeler, Price Waterhouse, and Deloitte Touche Tohmatsu International. Useful short summaries of various topics include Auerbach (1990) (the predominant features of the classical double tax), Shoven and Waldfogel (1990) (the treatment of debt and equity), Scholes and Wolfson (1991) (the general pattern of rules for mergers and acquisitions) and the international scheme generally. Wiseman (1974), Harberger (1983) and Goode (1951) should give the reader good perspective on the early contributions of traditional economists. A useful survey of the issues raised by the presence of taxes in the traditional corporate finance literature is provided by Gordon and Malkiel (1981). Other more recent surveys of slightly different scope include that by Head (1997), Mintz (1995) (including tables showing the prominent features of the tax schemes used in various jurisdictions and providing more general background on taxes, costs of capital and risky investments), and Cnossen (1997), focusing on the OECD jurisdictions.
2. Overview of the Tax Under the ‘classical’ scheme for taxation of corporate income, corporations are recognized as separate taxable entities, legitimately subject to tax upon their income. Distributions of earnings to shareholders are also taxed as income to shareholders, as if they represented entirely new values available to be taxed. Such schemes essentially tax the earnings on corporate equity
168
Corporate Taxation
6060
investments twice, once at the corporate level as earned and later upon the distribution of the earnings to the shareholders. Bittker and Eustice (1994) provide a comprehensive summary of the complex US tax rules controlling corporate/shareholder relations. Clark (1977) provides useful insights into legal concepts behind the classification of various corporate/shareholder transactions in the classical scheme. Stephan (1990) provides a slightly more intricate update of US taxation of corporate/shareholder relations, taking into account both the many legislative changes occurring in the 1980s and more recent theoretical analysis of corporate/shareholder relations. Not all business activity is subject, even nominally, to the corporate tax. Much business activity is undertaken by entities, including charities (Hansmann, 1981; Rose-Ackerman, 1982) and local governments, that may be entirely exempt from income taxation. Even in the for-profit sector, there is much business activity that is not subject to corporate tax. In the classical system, the corporate tax only attaches to those entities that are in fact incorporated, or are deemed to be operating as if they were in fact incorporated. It does not attach to joint ventures and partnerships. In the US, the legal nature of business entities is a matter of state, not federal law, while the reach of the federal income tax on corporations has been a matter of federal law. As a consequence, in the US, an entity could be subject to the corporate income tax regardless of its formal legal classification as a partnership or trust. As an historical matter, entities that enjoy limited liability, free transferability of interests, centralized management, and continuity of life traditionally were subject to corporate tax even if unincorporated. In the US, this line proved very difficult to police. See Klein (1972), Lee (1988) and Hobbes (1995) for a review of this history. Recent regulatory changes in the US have made avoidance of the classical double tax scheme elective for all but publicly traded entities. Even a publicly traded entity can also avoid the classic double tax if its activities and capital requirements can fit certain rigid structures, generally designed for entities serving as financial intermediaries, see, for example, Gergen (1997) and Clark (1975). For an overview of current thinking about the scope of the corporate tax base in the US, see Yin (1997) and Klein and Zolt (1995). In other jurisdictions, the formal legal status of the business entity is likely to determine whether the entity is subject to the income tax (Thomas, 1997). Under the traditional income tax, an increase in the value of corporate stock is not taxed to shareholders until it is ‘realized’, generally, reduced to cash in the hands of the shareholders. There are recurring proposals to alter this rule, especially with respect to publicly held debt and equity (Slawson, 1967; Davies, 1975; Dodge, 1995). Under the classical scheme, dividends distributed to shareholders are taxed without offset for shareholder
6060
Corporate Taxation
169
investment or credit for corporate taxes paid. Increased share value, however, can be realized by shareholders by selling shares to third parties. This value can be both realized by the shareholder and removed from the corporate solution if it is the corporation, not a third party, who purchases the shares. In the US scheme, the rules applicable to such tactics sometimes leave the consequences of such transactions uncertain. Kingson (1976) and Jassy (1974) explore these rules in detail; Chirelstein (1969) explores the effects of such transactions on the remaining shareholders. Shareholders can ordinarily enjoy the benefits of increased share value without such values leaving corporation solution merely by selling shares. When such a sale is for cash or other relatively liquid consideration, the shareholder will ordinarily be taxed. However, increased share value can often be enjoyed without any taxation at the shareholder level as a result of tax-free mergers with corporations the stock of which represents more diversified holdings or is more easily pledged, through sophisticated futures and other hedging transactions. Such tactics can result in permanent escape from income tax on increases in share value when stock need not be liquidated until after the shareholder’s death because, upon death, the shareholder’s basis (that is, deemed after tax investment) is increased to fair market value. Some investors, especially offshore investors, will effectively be subject to income tax upon dividend payments but not on stock sales. Finally, tax exempt shareholders, including pension plans, will be taxed neither on dividend receipt or sale, although their beneficiaries will be subject to tax upon the ultimate payout. Most classical schemes are designed to avoid full taxation of earnings at more than one corporate level, limiting the tax burden to a ‘double tax’. In the United States’ income tax this is achieved by allowing a deduction for dividends received, which may vary with the extent of payee ownership in the payor corporation, and through the elimination of the ordinary consequences of asset transfers among very closely related corporations. This feature of the classical scheme, considered together with the number of shareholders that are explicitly exempt from taxation (including pension plans) and effectively exempt (including foreign shareholders), reduces the extent to which the classical scheme in fact results in double taxation of corporate enterprise.
3. Other Taxes Attaching to the Corporate Form Corporate income taxes can be combined with various other adjunct taxes designed to offset various undesirable effects of the classical income tax or some particular implementation feature of it. Such devices include the undistributed earnings (or accumulated earnings) tax (designed to offset the
170
Corporate Taxation
6060
incentive to retain earnings in corporations rather than distribute them and subject them to the shareholder level tax), excess profits taxes (designed to capture the excessive return thought to be available during war time) and minimum taxes (designed to counteract perceived flaws in the ordinary rules defining the tax base). Lyon (1997) examines the inefficiencies introduced by one such tax in the US, the alternative minimum tax, the aim of which was to reduce the claimed overuse of certain incentive provisions in the US corporate income tax. Other taxes may be specifically imposed only on corporations, including franchise and capital taxes, property taxes at special rates, net worth and gross asset taxes can be imposed with or without regard for their relation to the corporate income tax. Taxes generally imposed on property, value-added, imports, sales and sales are almost never coordinated with corporate income taxes, although such payments are ordinarily allowed as business expenses in the computation of corporate income. The problems inherent in defining corporate income have led to recent proposals alternative measures. Knoll (1996), following Bankman (1995) sets out the conditions under which a corporate tax, imposed directly on the corporation, for increases in its total market value would replicate the current, accounting based tax. The possibility that even a perfectly defined income tax creates disincentives for investment has fueled additional proposals for substantial changes in the definition of the tax base that includes corporate income. Zodrow (1997), King (1987) and Auerbach (1990) build on earlier work to propose a corporate cash flow tax that would sever a corporate tax from its routes in profit accounting and eliminate any tax-driven biases regarding corporate structure and investment; the base of such a tax could be approximated to all current distributions to shareholders (both of dividends and share repurchases) by reducing corporate receipts for all new investment.
4. The Origins of the Corporate Income Tax The earliest attempts to impose taxes upon corporations, rather than upon any particular corporate activity or holding, appear to have origins in efforts to include individual wealth represented by corporate interests in property tax bases. Taxation of the corporation itself could serve as a surrogate for taxation of the wealth of the shareholder, and would be preferred by those jurisdictions which could claim that the corporation was entirely within its taxing jurisdiction, even if its shareholders were not. Initial efforts focused on the par value of the stock, or its paid in capital, but as it became clear that these legal and accounting concepts had no economic meaning, jurisdictions either switched to, or added, corporate income as the measure of the tax.
6060
Corporate Taxation
171
Further support for the tax derived from the notion that doing business as a corporation was a privilege for which charging a fee or franchise tax was appropriate. (These franchise taxes are thought to have played an important part in the competition among states for the most attractive law governing corporate shareholder relations, see Cary, 1974, pp. 668-669.) With the possible exception of the privilege of limited liability (which is now frequently available without subjection to the classical tax regime), this justification now has limited appeal. A good survey of the historical attitudes in the US can be found in Goode (1951, pp. 24-43). The introduction of the modern corporate income tax at the federal level in the US has alternatively been explained as an early effort to respond to the popular pressure to regulate corporate activity without infringing upon the state’s prerogatives in corporate law (Kornhauser, 1990). The details of its later development has been described (by a political scientist reaching conclusions that except in their general optimism, resemble a public choice approach) as a reflection of a coalition between elected government and the business community to promote economic growth (Martin, 1991).
5. Modern Justifications for the Corporate Income Tax Some early writers simply assumed that the corporation, as a separate legal entity, was appropriately subject to tax. Corporate income taxes remain politically popular, especially among those who view corporations as sources of wealth entirely independent of shareholders, employees or customers. But most modern justifications for the tax are even less unsatisfying than those relied upon historically. Some justify the tax as necessary to secure the goals of other tax regimes. When corporate income tax is part of a larger scheme of income taxation, particularly a scheme with substantial redistributive goals implemented through progressive rates, the corporate tax can be viewed as an expedient buttress to the income tax. Without a corporate tax, the personal income tax would be substantially undermined by entrepreneurs who could shift the return on their efforts into untaxed corporate profits. (Gordon and Mackie Mason, 1995, explore this rationale as an explanation for the presence of corporate income taxes even in small capital importing jurisidictions.) Even if taxation of return to effort were not at issue, corporate earnings would be retained, providing economic benefit to shareholders, outside of the reach of the income tax. Under this justification, the corporate tax serves as a withholding tax to insure at least minimum correspondence with the nominal personal income tax scheme. This rationale, however, can only justify the imposition of the tax upon the income when realized by the corporation, not the failure to avoid taxing the remaining value again upon its distribution to shareholders (Gabinet and
172
Corporate Taxation
6060
Coffey, 1977). Alternatively, the corporate income tax would be fully justified, however, as a means of buttressing the personal income tax in cases in which jurisdiction is lacking to tax shareholders (Musgrave, 1987). Under this justification, however, some credit for corporate taxes paid should be allowed at least to domestic taxpayers. Some claims have been made that the corporate tax under the classical scheme can be justified because of certain other economic characteristics of corporations. (Caution must be used in relying upon such justifications, since there is unlikely to be an identity between the entities attracting the tax and these characteristics. Only relatively recently have the rules for determining which entities will attract the tax actually reflected any of these justifications.) Early writers relied upon the benefits of limited liability to justify the imposition of tax. Goode (1951), Break (1969) and Rudnick (1989) all suggest that liquidity, resulting both from marketability and from the limited liability ordinarily afforded to shareholders, justifies attracting an entity level tax. Kose, Senbet and Sundaram (1994) outline the contours of a tax that would more precisely internalize the costs of limited liability. Stiglitz (1973, 1976) posits that the corporate tax should be viewed as only a tax on pure profits and entrepreneurship, a tax which allows the government a partial return on an implicit partnership with the owners of equity. This view relies heavily on the notion that all ordinary returns to capital can be paid out as returns to debt finance which returns are not subject to tax because they are deducted from corporate income, but does not attempt to reconcile the actual contours of the tax with this description given the fact that corporations frequently do not appear to be so fully leveraged. Head (1997) provides an in-depth examination of these various explanations of the corporate tax in light of the current finance literature. Even if the corporate tax can only be explained as an historical accident, its persistence in the face of its apparent inefficiencies remains an enigma. One possible explanation is that corporate managers have little incentive to lobby to eliminate the corporate tax, or to otherwise integrate the personal and corporate taxes, when they can enjoy a higher payoff from lobbying to alter the corporate tax base in ways that benefit them as managers even if integration or elimination would benefit shareholders more (Arlen and Weiss 1995). Still others have suggested that the corporate tax can serve to avoid the agency costs that would be incurred if other means were used to resolve the conflicts over timing of income among stakeholders facing different tax consequences upon corporate asset sales and distributions (Kanda and Levmore, 1991; Snoe, 1993).
6060
Corporate Taxation
173
Cooper (1994) considers the possibility that corporate managers consider tax compliance as a financing and investment decision, and the implications of this view for tax administrators.
6. The Definition of the Corporate Tax Base Perhaps because there can be no economically sound justification for the corporate income tax under the classical scheme, there has been little serious effort to develop an economically sound measure of the corporate income tax base (Levmore, 1988). (This is in stark contrast with the individual income tax base, for which the combined articulations of Georg Schanz, Robert M. Haig and Henry C. Simons (Simons, 1938) provides the most common measure.) There is a general consensus, for instance, that the current standards for base-defining are far from that which would justify the corporate tax as merely a tax on economic rents under the Stiglitz view (Bond and Devereux, 1995). The few preliminary attempts have merely deduced from the existing accounting rules defining the corporate base that their overall purpose seems to be the taxation of all income, above and beyond the contributions made by the shareholders, that the corporation can be expected to make available to shareholders in the future (Bryan, 1984; Crane, 1988). Levmore (1987) suggests that at least some of the rules used to define the corporate tax base and which govern corporate shareholder relations serve to constrain managers in an efficient way. Repetti (1997) explores some more closely tailored efforts in the US to manipulate the incentives of corporate managers through particular base-defining provisions. The corporate tax base is frequently defined so as to identify a base only roughly equivalent to profit for other purposes. Accounting for tax purposes may deviate substantially from accounting for financial, rate-making or internal purposes. Some such disparities are introduced to overcome the bias of financial accounting against overstating earnings. Cummins, Harris and Hassett (1995) offer some preliminary analysis of the relative effects of such ‘one-book’ and ‘two-book’ regimes, as well as survey information on various tax schemes in place. Other disparities between book and tax income are deliberate preferences, introduced to provide incentives for investment, sometimes available only for investment by entities subject to the corporate tax. Auerbach (1982) and Hulten and Robertson (1982) examine the accelerated depreciation scheme in place for a brief time in the US in the early 1980s, which under many plausible conditions, and in connection with mechanisms for transferring tax losses that temporarily moved the US system closer to full loss offsets (see Gravelle, 1982), effectively eliminated the corporate tax. Interest generally is deductible, producing a potential bias
174
Corporate Taxation
6060
against equity and in favor of debt financing (see Warren, 1974, and below). Although preferential treatment may be available for capital gains, the corporate tax base frequently includes extraordinary gains as well as income from operations. Corporate income is ordinarily computed on an annual basis, with only clumsy mechanisms for carrying back and forward losses to smooth out income. Among the shortcomings in such mechanisms are nonrefundability and an unwillingness to allow the loss incurred with respect to one corporate investment to be available to shelter the gain from a previously unrelated investment, or to allow adjustments for the timing of payment and refund. Many systems provide for carrybacks and carryforwards of losses, but few provide for full loss offsets. Failure to provide such offsets may affect the type of risks undertaken and may provide an advantage for diversified over undiversified firms (Romano and Campisano, 1981). Those firms with loss carryforwards ordinarily face a lower than statutory rate on earnings from new investments (since carryforwards effectively postpone tax payments), while those with carrybacks face the statutory rate (since carrybacks produce current refunds). Auerbach and Poterba (1987b) find that the presence of such carryforwards can have significant effects on investment incentives. Although corporate income is taxed both to the corporation and when realized by shareholders, most classical tax schemes include some mechanism whereby additional levels of corporate tax are avoided. Dividends from wholly-owned subsidiaries are frequently eliminated entirely in the measure of corporate income; dividends on portfolio stock maybe partially eliminated; certain other transactions among related, and sometimes even among unrelated, corporations may be given special tax accounting treatments (see generally Mundstock, 1988). As noted above, interest paid on debt is generally deductible, while returns paid on equity are not. Despite the apparently enormous consequences, distinction between debt and equity is not easily maintained, Plumb (1971) contains a thorough examination of the case law attempting to establish the distinction; Bulow, Summers and Summers (1990) examine more recent devices used to obtain debt tax treatment for equity investment. Scholes and Wolfson (1990) explore the extent to which this distinction can be exploited to avoid the double tax completely; and ultimately conclude that, as long as competitive investment is available, full self-help integration is not possible.
6060
Corporate Taxation
175
7. Measures of Corporate Tax Burden and Incidence. Establishing Effective Corporate Tax Rates Despite the obvious significance of the question, very little conclusive analysis or reliable data is available regarding the actual burden of the corporate tax. Frequently, information about the tax liabilities of particular firms is simply not available. It is generally accepted that effective corporate tax rates are likely to differ from statutory rates in at least three important ways, even if tax payments can be matched with reliable information about income for tax purposes. First, if the permanent preferences that are available for certain types of corporate income (as are commonly offered for corporate dividends paid on stock held by corporations) have been capitalized, an implicit tax will reduce corporate tax payments without increasing corporate after-tax income. Second, some express preferences reduce current corporate tax liabilities but increase future tax liabilities, resulting in deferred taxes. Third, tax accounting rules (such as the limitation on corporate capital losses) will frequently result in additional timing disparities that make comparisons of tax payments with corporate income in any one year difficult. Perhaps the most controversial efforts to estimate the effective corporate tax rate in the US have been prepared with the popular press in mind. McIntyre and Folen (1984), McIntyre and Wilhelm (1986), Marovelli and Moser (1990) provide calculations of effective corporate tax rates in the United States based on publicly available data; such analysis frequently is limited by the fact that it can compare only current taxes with current financial income, with no accounting for implicit taxes or even for deferred taxes. Dworin (1985) demonstrates how difficult reliance on such data can be. A somewhat more sophisticated analysis is offered by Shevlin (1990). Collins and Shackelford (1990) attempt to use data available from financial statements to establish average effective tax rates in various jurisdictions. Auerbach and Poterba (1987a) provide some more meaningful measures of corporate tax payments in the United States from the mid-1950s to the mid1980s. Mintz (Canada, 1985) and Mayer (United Kingdom, 1986) analyze the effect of loss carryovers on tax rates. It must be noted that effective tax rates on capital are difficult to determine without taking into account personal taxes as well as corporate taxes and the interplay between personal taxes, corporate taxes, the form of business organization and the form of financing, for example, King and Fullerton (1984). But in the presence of an open international market these relationships may not hold.
176
Corporate Taxation
6060
8. Incidence of Corporate Tax Although the primary legal incidence of the corporate income tax is on the corporation itself, the economic incidence is uncertain. If corporate investment must take the form of equity, and if current earnings must be distributed, the classical system will create a bias against investments in corporations, but the prevalence of those conditions is uncertain. Furthermore, the use of the corporate form to allow maximum use of preferences for capital gains and basis step-up at death for share appreciation when earnings can be retained, the availability of preferences only for investment in corporate form, and the use of debt as a means of distribution for those returns that cannot be retained all mitigate the bias against investment in corporate form. Nevertheless, it is generally assumed that the classical corporate tax system raises the corporate cost of capital and therefore increases the share of capital allocated to the noncorporate sector. Under such a view, the burden of the corporate tax might well be ultimately borne equally by corporate and noncorporate capital owners, but the distorting effects on the allocation of capital between corporate and noncorporate are great (Harberger, 1962, 1966; Shoven and Whalley, 1972; Shoven, 1976; Ballard et al., 1985; Gravelle and Kotlikoff, 1989; but Harberger, 1983). McLure (1981) provides a perspective on this literature and applies its insights to questions regarding the determination of sub-national tax incidence. Rogers (1996) provides a useful summary of the research and issues. Empirical work regarding the incidence of the corporate income tax has been, and is likely to remain, inconclusive. In one early and interesting effort, Krzyzaniak and Musgrave (1963) contended that corporations are in fact able to more than fully recoup additional taxes, but were quickly criticized by many, including Cragg, Harberger and Miezkowski (1967) and Slitor (1966). Fullerton and Lim Rogers (1993) report that because very little corporate tax is actually paid, its effect in the United States is primarily through relative price changes, and that because those who are relatively poorer spend more of their incomes on goods produced in the corporate sector, and thus bear a relatively higher burden.
9. Corporate Tax and the Choice of Business Form Very few of the jurisdictions committed to a classical corporate tax attempt to impose taxes on aggregations of business capital or business activity that would remove the tax disincentive to use the corporate form. (However, one such proposal was included in US Treasury, 1992.) Hence there is likely to
6060
Corporate Taxation
177
be a bias against incorporation where non-tax considerations allow the activity to be conducted and the required aggregation of capital without incorporation. The bias against suggested by the classical double tax scheme will not be present, however, if the corporate tax rate is substantially lower than the individual tax rate, whether because of difference in statutory rates, or because of special provisions (including deductions for deferred compensation and cost recovery) available only to corporate taxpayers. Such conditions were likely to be present in the US prior to the mid-1980s. Auerbach (1997) summarizes the changes in US law introduced in 1986. The bias against moving capital into corporate form seems likely to have increased given the increasing availability of limited liability, in the US at least, without submission to a corporate level tax. For summaries of the changes in US legal rules that have led to complete avoidance of corporate level tax for new business investment in the absence of public trading, see Burke (1995). The overall impact of the incentives against moving capital into corporate form remains undecided. Mackie-Mason and Gordon (1997) and Gordon and Mackie-Mason (1994) report that changes in organizational form are sensitive to changes in tax rates. Gordon and Slemrod (1998) concur, demonstrating that much of the apparent rise in personal incomes in the US after 1986 resulting from shifts in business activity away from the corporate form, implying a strong response. Finally, even if the double tax aspects of the corporate tax do not entirely discourage incorporation, they are likely to affect the ways in which capital is provided to corporations, since returns provided as wages, interest, rents, and royalties will be deducted from the corporate tax base while returns on equity contributions will not.
10. The Corporate Tax and Corporate Financial Structure Under the classic corporate tax, dividends are not deducted from corporate income as paid, but in general interest is deducted as it accrues. It is generally accepted that the resulting removal from the corporate tax base of returns to debt is likely to create a strong incentive toward financing with debt. Indeed, if all corporate earnings are paid out as return on debt financing rather than return on equity, the disincentive resulting from presence of the corporate tax to use the corporate form can be eliminated. There is a general consensus, however, that there is not as much corporate debt as would be expected if taxes were the only consideration. Good general summaries of the issues and current research in the US can be found in Scholes and Wolfson (1992) and Auerbach (1990).
178
Corporate Taxation
6060
The fact that the classical corporate tax provides an incentive to finance through debt does not, however, suggest that only debt be issued, despite Modigliani and Miller’s early suggestion (1963) that the optimal source of all capital should be debt in the presence of such a preference. Miller (1977) observed that at some point, the price that must be offered to attract debt financing will offset the tax advantage of debt, at least if there is any preference for returns on equity. Furthermore, other aspects of tax accounting and tax preferences will make some firms less able to take advantage of the tax incentive afforded by debt, and may result in lower levels of debt (DeAngelo and Masulis, 1980). Although it is hard to explain changes in the amount of corporate leverage without understand more about the phenomenon generally, several empirical studies suggest that corporate debt levels do indeed respond to relative tax rates on corporate income. Auerbach (1985) (finding relation between debt levels and low effective rates resulting from carryforwards, but not composition of asset cost recovery), Bartholdy, Fisher and Mintz (1985) (a one-point increase in Canadian corporate tax results in 3/4 point increase in corporate debt/equity ratio), Mackie-Mason (1990), Graham (1996) and others have attempted to estimate the sensitivity of this relationship (Rangazas and Abdullah, 1987). Gentry (1994) shows an increase in debt by firms who can pass-through tax losses to investors. Schulman et al. (1996) report that imputation integration in New Zealand and Canada reduced debt/equity ratios. Others, however, have failed to find tax effects on levels of corporate borrowing (Ang and Peterson, 1986; Bradley, Jarrel and Kim, 1984). Taggert (1985) concludes that although tax factors have played a role in the increased debt levels of corporations in the United States, they do not provide a complete explanation; Gordon and Mackie-Mason (1990) similarly find less response to taxes than predicted. Even less certain is whether this possible distortion in favor of debt financing should be considered inefficient. The discipline that debt brings to managers is likely to reduce agency costs, but the losses occurring as a result of the incentive to choose less risky and shorter termed investments which are not wealth-maximizing may outweigh them. Full consideration of equity/debt and corporate financial structure beyond the scope of this article; more general surveys of optimal capital structure can be found in Barclay, Smith and Watts (1995), Myers (1993), Harris and Raviv (1991), Taggert (1985), Auerbach (1985) and Jensen and Meckling (1976).
6060
Corporate Taxation
179
11. The Corporate Tax and the Incentive to Distribute Corporate Earnings Under the classic corporate tax, individual shareholders that receive dividends are taxed on the full amount of those dividends, usually without preference and without offset for their investment in their shares. Shareholders who realize their returns through the sale of shares, on the other hand, frequently enjoy a capital gains preference, and can offset proceeds with investment basis on all sales of shares. They may be able to avoid tax entirely through the rules avoiding income tax on gains remaining unrealized at death. (Although this fact is almost entirely overlooked in the analytical literature mentioned below, there are significant exceptions to this general pattern of tax burden on dividend payments in the US. First, payments denominated ‘dividends’ will be subject to only capital gains taxation if there are no corporate earnings for tax purposes (‘earnings and profits’), even though ordinarily there must be earnings for corporate law purposes in order for dividends to be paid. Such ‘return of capital’ dividends are highly likely when cost recovery allowances for tax purposes exceed similar allowances for corporate law purposes, and when corporations are successful in engaging in restructuring transactions which reduce earnings for tax purposes. Second, only individual shareholders are in fact subject to the double tax: corporate shareholders are allowed to eliminate a substantial portion of dividends paid by domestic corporations, and tax-exempt entities, including pension plans, pay no tax at on dividend receipts at all.) This disparity between the tax treatment of shareholders who receive dividends and shareholders who participate in sale transactions led to an early debate about whether the regular payment of dividends lowered share prices and required higher dividend rates, for example, Litzenberger and Ramaswamy (1979, 1982), Bradford and Gordon (1980), Miller and Scholes (1982), Morgan (1982), Poterba and Summers (1984), Wu and Hsu (1996). This disincentive would not, however, affect dividend behavior if the share price of corporate stock is set by investors for whom the tax impact of dividends and capital gains are the same (Miller and Scholes, 1978). Miller (1986) reviews this literature. Similarly, it is frequently supposed that the classic corporate tax provides a imposes a cost on the distribution of earnings, and that an increase in the tax cost of dividend distributions should result in a lower level of dividend payouts. Some empirical studies support this view: Brittain (1966) (analyzing US dividend behavior from 1920 to 1960); Feldstein (1970) (British firms from 1953 through 1964); King (1971, 1972) (British firms from 1949 through 1967), but Feldstein (1972); Poterba and Summers (1985); Poterba (1987) (US firms through 1986). On the other hand, there should be no incentive to avoid distribution of corporate earnings simply to avoid the shareholder level tax on the
180
Corporate Taxation
6060
distribution, if those earnings must eventually be distributed and must be subject to the same tax in the future. (Under this view, the tax cost of a distribution must decrease the overall return to the shareholder, whether it does so on an immediate distribution that reduces the net-after-tax amount received by the shareholder now, or whether, if the earnings are retained, reinvested, and distributed in the future, it reduces the net-after-tax amount received by the shareholder on that future distribution (Auerbach, 1990). Thus, there should be no effect on the marginal investment decisions of firms as a result of the double tax resulting from the taxation of dividends. Although the tax treatment of dividends should create a disincentive to new contributions to firms through new share issues and should generally reduce the amount by which such new share issues increase the value of the firm, this tax treatment would not change the firm’s dividend behavior, which would be governed by nontax considerations. In the absence of any significant nontax benefits to distributions, the firm would pay dividends only when no profitable investment could be made. A permanent change in the tax on dividends would not affect distributions, but would operate only as a charge on retained earnings and on new equity contributions. Under this view (sometimes still referred to as the ‘new’ view), equity is ‘trapped’ in corporate form, and the inevitable tax on payout is capitalized into share price. Early contributions supporting this view include King (1974, 1977), Auerbach (1979, 1983b), Bradford (1981). In fact, however, the future tax on distributions can be avoided in several ways: (1) if no current distribution of corporate funds is ever made and the shareholder’s return is received through the sale of stock (especially when this return is, as is frequently the case, entitled to a special capital gains rate or to the benefit of forgiveness at death through stepped up basis) and (2) distributions are made from the corporation in the form of share redemptions (not permitted in all jurisdictions) and distributions made in connection with acquisitions, both of which may also be subject to more favorable tax treatment. If corporate earnings can be transformed without significant cost to borrowings (for instance through redemptions of stock held by exempt shareholders) there may in fact be little or no disincentive for current distribution of corporate earnings through such non-dividend techniques. Shoven (1987) reviews the tax consequences and provides estimates of such behaviors by firms in the 1970s and 1980s. Bagwell and Shoven (1989) provide a useful summary of the various incentives faced by corporate managers and conclude that the increased use of non-dividend techniques for distributions to shareholders may be attributable to the simple phenomena of an increased awareness and understanding of the ‘technology’ of implementing such devices under relatively complicated tax rules.
6060
Corporate Taxation
181
The debate about the limitations inherent in the assumptions necessary to the ‘new view’ and the implications of the new view remains unresolved. Most agree that for the traditional view to hold, there must be some countervailing benefit to the corporation or its managers upon the distribution of dividends, but there is little agreement as to whether those benefits include signaling or merely provide a mechanism for disciplining corporate management. If there is such a benefit, it may be exceeded by an increased tax cost of dividend distributions and, therefore, increased tax burdens on dividends would decrease dividend payouts. Most also agree that one strong implication of the new view is that the net value of the firm’s shares must be less than the total value of the firm’s assets. Such a discount to share value would be present unless there were some inherent advantage to investments conducted through the corporate form, but the identification of this advantage has been elusive (and will likely remain elusive as the tax law, at least in the US, continues to shift). This appears to have led some to conclude that the new view can hold only if share repurchases are prohibited, since if they were not, firms would simply repurchase shares until the discount was eliminated. Sinn (1991c) argues that the traditional view implies that corporations do not minimize their cost of capital, and further that the new view is plausible even when share repurchases can be made, so long as limits on such devices are present. Zodrow (1997, 1991), Poterba and Summers (1985) and Sorensen (1995) also elaborate upon the implications of the ‘traditional’ and ‘new’ views. Zodrow (1997) and Gerardi, Graetz and Rosen (1990) both conclude, after reviewing the empirical literature, that it primarily supports the traditional view. Perhaps the most significant practical implication of the new view is that to the extent that the new view is correct, the burden of the double tax on corporate dividends is capitalized in the market value of its shares. Any lessening of the burden of double taxation through any form of integration would therefore create a windfall for shareholders of firms with retained earnings. The likelihood that the new view is correct at least to this extent explains at least part of the reluctance in the US to move toward full integration (Hubbard, 1993; Halperin, 1992, considering the conclusions reached in American Law Institute, 1979, 1989).
12. Jurisdiction over the Corporate Tax Base and Sufficiency of Nexus to Tax Corporate economic activity frequently ignores the political boundaries by which jurisdiction to tax is ordinarily assigned. Rarely are there constitutional barriers to the assertion by each polity with which the activity
182
Corporate Taxation
6060
has some minimal nexus asserting the power to tax such economic activity and to define the base according to which that tax will be assessed. Nevertheless, most polities acknowledge a need to avoid overtly duplicative taxes, especially when the chosen base is income. A good survey of the issues and patterns of solutions can be found in Easson (1997). There are two principal approaches that can be used to assign taxing power among competing taxing polities. Under an assignment or sourcing method, each polity adopts rules according to which a corporation’s income is categorized as most closely related to one taxing jurisdiction. If more than one jurisdiction asserts the power to tax this income, a credit can be given (generally by the home polity) for the taxes paid elsewhere (generally the foreign site of the economic activity). McIntyre (1994) provides an overview of this approach as applied by the United States; Green (1993) Ault and Bradford (1990) and Hufbauer (1992) highlight the issues inherent in its use. Under the apportionment method, a corporation’s income can be apportioned to each taxing jurisdiction according to a formula that takes into account the location of the business activity (frequently sales, payroll and property). Even if two jurisdictions adopt the same approach to avoiding duplicative taxes, there is rarely any device for ensuring that the implementation of the approaches are consistent. Avi-Yonah (1995) explores agency-theory-based rationales for the approaches taken for operational and passive income. Each state in the United States, for instance, is free to define its own apportionment formula so long as that apportionment formula, if adopted by every state, would avoid duplicative taxes (McLure, 1986; Gordon and Wilson, 1986; Hreha and Silhan, 1986). Each of these approaches must include variants to take into account the fact that frequently corporate activity that encompasses more than one jurisdiction will be undertaken by more than one formal corporate entity. Generally, jurisdictions (including the United States) that rely on an assignment approach will require that transfer prices among entities be at ‘arm’s length’ prices so as to avoid jurisdictional distortions (see generally Avi-Yonah, 1995). Jurisdictions that use an apportionment method are likely to require that all related corporations ‘combine’ their income, so that apportionment will take into account all related entities. Each approach must also consider how to treat transfers of dividends to related corporations that are not wholly or exclusively subject to their taxing power. Under the assignment method as implemented by the United States, income of foreign subsidiaries will ordinarily not be subject to United States’ tax as earned, but will be subject to United States’ tax as it is repatriated as dividends, and a credit for foreign taxes paid will be available upon repatriation. Under a fully combined apportionment method, dividends paid to related corporations should be ignored.
6060
Corporate Taxation
183
Finally, it is highly likely that any one taxing scheme will, at least in some of its details, include features from both approaches. For instance, despite the fact that the United States in general uses sourcing with arm’s length pricing to establish the taxable income of multinational groups, since 1986 interest expense must be apportioned according to asset holdings. (For an analysis of this change, see Froot and Hines, 1995; Altshuler and Mintz, 1995.) There is at least some evidence that sourcing systems impose significantly greater compliance costs than apportionment systems (Blumenthal and Slemrod, 1996).
13. Effect of Corporate Taxes on Investment in Multinational Economies Although it might not be obvious to the modern observer, the pattern of taxation for multinational businesses was the product of more systematic thinking than many other areas of US federal taxation. Graetz and O’Hear (1997) recount the role of early economists in this history. Picciotto (1992) provides an exhaustive review and analysis of the current patterns. A good summary of the relevant rules and a straightforward review of the most prominent empirical research can be found in Hines (1997). (In this review, Hines concludes that real responses to taxes are as one would expect: there tends to be more direct investment where corporate tax burdens are anticipated to be lower.) Gordon and Mackie-Mason (1995) offers interesting speculation about the incentives leading to the prevailing patterns of international tax, and conclude that significant parts of the current pattern reflect the need to preserve the personal income tax on the return to entrepreneurial labor. Some jurisdictions, including the US, claim the right to tax all income, domestic and foreign, of their resident taxpayers, including corporations. However, in keeping with the classical corporate income tax, the income of separately incorporated foreign entities conducting active businesses is ordinarily not subject to US tax until it is repatriated through dividends. Hartman (1985) theorized that if such repatriation taxes are unavoidable, their existence should not affect the decision whether to repatriate or reinvest in the source jurisdiction, essentially applying a ‘trapped equity’ analysis to the repatriation decision. Hines (1994) and Leechor and Mintz (1993) point out that variations in income-defining rules can be sufficient to alter this result. Empirical studies (Goodspeed and Frisch, 1989; Hines and Hubbard, 1990; Altshuler, Newlon and Randolph, 1995) suggest that repatriation taxes do in fact vary sufficiently to provide other incentives. Hines (1997) suggests that the tax costs of repatriation may encourage undercapitalization of foreign subsidiaries so that profitable opportunities
184
Corporate Taxation
6060
remain for the reinvestment of retained earnings, and notes that this incentive may make attempts to measure the influence of foreign tax rates on foreign direct investment. Roin (1988) develops a public choice analysis of the exceptions to the limitations on deferral for relatively passive foreign acitivities. In the US, a credit against domestic taxes is allowed for foreign taxes paid. It has sometimes been assumed that the foreign tax crediting device used by the US results in a lower national return on foreign direct investment by US corporations than the national return on displaced domestic investment (for example, Dutton, 1982). Recent analysis suggests that the loss due to taxes yielded to the foreign jurisdiction may be offset by the overall greater return resulting from lower costs of foreign capital (Feldstein, 1995). At the multinational level, all of the possibility of tax effects on choice of form and financial structure found domestically are present, with additional possibilities resulting from the variety of rates, the special treatments afforded by treaty, and the arbitrary and inconsistent nature of the rules used by the various jurisdictions for allocating items affecting measures of income. Predictably, multinationals structure their transactions in ways that, for instance, yield accounting profits in low tax jurisdictions and place the tax shields afforded by debt finance. Hines (1997) reviews the empirical studies evidencing this behavior. Among the most difficult, and yet most fundamental, problems in analyzing the effect of national corporate income taxes on corporate behavior and general business investment is a determination of the effective tax rates in the various jurisdictions to be studied. The problem is complicated by the fact that stated nominal tax rates and published legal rules are unlikely to provide complete information about the tax burdens actually felt by corporations. The most ambitious empirical study, and an enormous amount of data regarding rates and bases can be found in OECD (1991). Attempts to further analyze and update such data include Jun (1995).
14. The Corporate Tax and Corporate Mergers and Acquisitions Any corporate income tax scheme, whether classic or integrated, must set out criteria for determining when transactions relating to corporate assets and to corporate stock interests will be treated as events that will trigger corporate income tax. (Such events frequently will trigger all unrealized gain on assets and will trigger reconciliation of various suspended accounting preferences.) The US scheme has evolved largely through judicial interpretation with only limited statutory modification. Very little
6060
Corporate Taxation
185
attention has been given to the distortions created by the resulting framework, perhaps because the framework, although arcane, provides sufficient flexibility. Under the US scheme for taxing restructuring transactions, shareholder realization is frequently tied to corporate realization, and flexibility in accommodating all shareholder interests may be difficult. Ginsburg and Levin (1996 and updated regularly) provide an intricate account of the current US rules. Some changes in control will be treated as merely continuing the tax existence of a corporation, and thus will not result in the triggering of gains on assets, the loss of grandfathered accounting methods, or the discontinuance of carryover tax losses. Other changes in control may be treated as discontinuous, and will trigger gains, force new accounting methods and cut off unused losses. Under certain circumstances prior to 1986, however, such a change in control that is treated as discontinuous could have produced a highly desirable result for US corporations, since it allowed a step-up in tax-basis of assets held at the corporate level without the payment of corporate level tax. These rules must establish highly arbitrary distinctions upon which rest frequently enormous stakes. For instance, sales of stock among shareholders will not ordinarily trigger gain on corporate assets, since the formal identity of the owner of the assets has not changed, but transfers of assets to different corporate entities will trigger gain on those assets unless there is substantial overlap between the owners of the new entity and the owners of the old. Therefore when an existing corporation is acquired, there can be enormous tax differences depending upon whether the transaction is viewed as a transfer of assets or of stock. To complicate things further, corporate tax regimes frequently will include special rules designed to mitigate the arbitrariness of such distinctions, but that make it still harder for observers to ascertain the effect of any particular set of rules. (For instance, until 1986, the United States allowed certain purchases of corporate stock to be treated as purchases of stock for the purpose of taxing shareholders, but as purchases assets for the purpose of the corporate level tax. This special rule was available only if the purchaser was a domestic corporation that acquired at least 80 percent of the stock of the target.) These arbitrary distinctions clearly have an enormous influence on the form that changes in corporate control take. It is less clear, however, whether they have any effect upon the frequency or price at which changes in corporate control occur. In the older literature it was generally assumed that at least some some changes in corporate control occurred in which the only motivation was tax-related (see Feld, 1982; Hellerstein, 1959; Butters, Lintner and Cary, 1951). More recent literature suggests that at least in the aggregate, the presence of tax gains are not as certain to have increased acquisition activity.
186
Corporate Taxation
6060
Auerbach and Reishus (1988a) provides a useful summary of the various incentives in US law. Gilson, Scholes and Wolfson (1988) review the overall interaction of the pre-1986 United States tax rules most frequently thought to produce tax gains from acquisitions, and conclude that many such gains could be accomplished in other ways. Their conclusions seem too dependent on the availability of other means of accomplishing the tax gains, which although plausible for some tax gains when viewed separately, seem less likely to be available in conjunction with other tax gains and with other goals. Another study by Auerbach and Reishus (1988b) however, concluded that in a least a fifth of the mergers studied, occurring between 1968 and 1983, the merger allowed a corporation to free itself from constraints on the use of tax benefits but did not find useful measures either of increased cost recovery or increase debt shields. One survey of transactions concluded that the primary gains from management buyouts were tax gains (Lowenstein, 1985). Jensen, Kaplan and Stiglin (1989) argue that certain acquisition activities actually increase tax revenues, although Bulow, Summers and Summers (1990) demonstrate that an increase in revenue is not necessarily inconsistent with a tax incentive derived subsidy. Some of the earlier writing regarding tax-motivations for corporate acquisition activity assumed that such activity would be socially undesirable. Several recent writers have challenged this assumption in passing, and offered several possible scenarios in which tax-motivated acquisition activity could produce social gains. Tax gains from various acquisition activities could, for instance, increase the premium for successful searches for operating efficiencies through acquisition activity (Gilson, Scholes and Wolfson, 1988); or restore incentives for investment by restoring tax incentives for investment that are weak in the absence of positive corporate tax liabilities (Auerbach and Reishus, 1988). Changes in the US law in 1984 (eliminating the possibility of stepping up depreciation deductions without a corporate level tax), and in 1986 (generally eliminating the exemption from capital gains taxation for distributed assets imposing additional limits on the use of carryover losses after a merger transaction), have substantially decreased the likely to be obtained through merger activity. The changes appear to have lessened interest in the study of tax motivations for merger activity, despite the possibility that data reflecting the change in tax regimes may be more useful than that studied previously. An analysis of these changes, and some discussion of their impact appear in Scholes and Wolfson (1991). Hayn (1989) provides an interesting study of the effect of the value of tax attributes on merger activity for which a IRS ruling was requested.
6060
Corporate Taxation
187
15. Integration of Corporate and Individual Level Income Taxes Under ‘integrated’ schemes, various devices are used to attempt to eliminate or minimize this double tax effect. Among the simplest of such devices is a ‘passthrough’ of corporate income to the shareholders even in the absence of a distribution of earnings, producing a liability at the shareholder level even if the corporation retains the funds generating the liability. Later distributions of corporate earnings are not subject to tax. (Although the classic scheme prevails for capital transferred to corporations before 1986, an increasing number of US enterprises can enjoy both passthrough integration and the limited liability associated with incorporation by using either the special rules available under subchapter S of the Internal Revenue Code (at the cost of a being restricted to a very limited number of shareholders and corporate structure), or by using the newly emerging limited liability company (at a cost of uncertainty regarding both the tax consequences and the default rules governing stakeholder relations).) Yin (1992) and Warren (1981) provide an exhaustive summaries of the available choices for implementing integration from the starting point of the classical system in the US. Integration can also be accomplished by allowing dividends to be paid without tax consequence to shareholders. Other more complicated integration devices include a corporate level tax, with a credit for such tax to be claimed by the shareholder upon the ultimate distribution of the earnings and after the amount of tax actually paid is imputed as part of the distribution (Australia, New Zealand, Canada, France, the United Kingdom and Germany all have used some form of imputation credit to accomplish varying degrees of integration), a split rate tax (under which distributed earnings are taxes at a lower rate than undistributed earnings, used by Japan and Germany), or a credit to the paying corporation upon the distribution of dividends. To the extent that the anticipated burdens of the classical double tax have been capitalized in existing capital, the considerations involved in moving from a classical scheme to an integrated scheme differ from those that would be considered prior to the imposition of any tax because a transition device would be necessary to avoid a windfall to existing corporate holdings. It is not clear, however, that such windfalls would be present, as suggested by the lack of price response to the announcement of integration in the United Kingdom in 1970 revealed by Poterba and Summers (1985). Auerbach (1990), McLure (1979), Sunley (1992), Cnossen (1993) and US Department of the Treasury (1992) provide in-depth discussions of the circumstances under which various approaches to integration might be desirable. International considerations make integration issues even more difficult, especially since there is no consensus about whether the jursidiction to tax should lie primarily with the jurisdiction in which business activity is
188
Corporate Taxation
6060
conducted or the jurisdiction whose resident is supplying capital through share or debt ownership. Uncertainty about tax effects in open and closed economies makes evaluations of integration proposals especially difficult (Boadway and Bruce, 1992; Devereux and Freeman, 1995). Under the more common approaches to the integration, relief form double taxation is appropriate only for resident shareholders (Ault, 1992; Doernberg, 1992).
Bibliography on Corporate Taxation (6060) Abbott, Ashok Bjardway (ed.) (1987), The Valuation Effects of Tax Legislation in Corporate Sell Offs, Ph.D. Thesis, Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University. Aivazian, Varouz A. and Turnbull, Stuart M. (1988), 'Taxation and Capital Structure: A Selected Review', in Coffee, John, Lowenstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (eds), Knights, Raiders and Targets: The Impact of the Hostile Takeover, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 230-277. Allen, Franklin (1989), ‘The Changing Nature of Debt and Equity: a Financial Perspective’ (Discussion), in Hart Oliver D. and Merton Robert C., Are the Distinctions Between Debt and Equity Disappearing? Allerdings, Jeffrey Paul (ed.) (1992), The Effects of the Corporate Alternative Minimum Tax on Corporate Tax Liability, MS Thesis, San Francisco, State University. Allsop, Peter (1991), 'Taxation Aspects of Corporate Finance', in Coffee, John, Lowenstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (eds), Knights, Raiders and Targets: The Impact of the Hostile Takeover, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 443-466. Alstott, Anne L. and Mackie, James B. (1992), 'Approaches to Corporate Integration: The Treasury Department Report’ Ph.D. Dissertation, 45 National Tax Journal, 209-223. Altshuler, Rosanne T. and Auerbach, Alan J. (1990), 'The Importance of Tax Law Asymmetries: An Empirical Investigation', 105 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 61-86. Altshuler, Rosanne T. and Mintz, Jack M. (1995), 'United States Interest-Allocation Rules: Effects and Policy', in Giovannini, A., Hubbard, R.G. and Slemrod, J. (eds), Studies in International Taxation, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Altshuler, Rosanne T. and Newlon, T. Scott (1993), 'The Effects of U.S. Tax Policy on the Income Repatriation Patterns of U.S. Multinational Corporations', in Giovannini, A., Hubbard, R.G. and Slemrod, J. (eds), Studies in International Taxation, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 77-115. Altshuler, Rosanne T., Newlon, T. Scott and Randolph, William C. (1995), 'Do Repatriation Taxes Matter? Evidence from the Tax Returns of U.S. Multinationals', in Feldstein, M. (ed.), The Effects of Taxation on Capital Accumulation, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 253-276. Alworth, J.S. (ed.) (1988), ‘Investment and Taxation Decisions of Multinationals', in Coffee, John, Lowenstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (eds), Knights, Raiders and Targets: The Impact of the Hostile Takeover, Oxford, Oxford University Press.
6060
Corporate Taxation
189
Alworth, J.S. (ed.) (1988), The Finance, Investment and Taxation Decisions of Multinationals. American Bar Association (ed.) (1988), A Report of the Invitational Conference on Subchapter C. American Institute of Certified Public Accountants (ed.) (1993), Integration of the Corporate and Shareholder Tax Systems, New York. American Law Institute (1991), 'Federal Income Tax Project, Integration of the Individual and Corporate Income Taxes', 2 Reporter's Memorandum. American Law Institute (ed.) (1979), Federal Tax Project, Tentative Draft No. 2, Subchapter C Corporate Distributions, Philadelphia, The American Law Institute. American Law Institute (ed.) (1982), Federal Income Tax Project, Subchapter C: Proposals on Corporate Acquisitions and Dispositions and Reporter's Study on Corporate Distributions, Philadelphia, The American Law Institute. American Law Institute (ed.) (1989), Federal Income Tax Project, Subchapter C, Reporter's Study Draft (Supplemental Study), Philadelphia, The American Law Institute. American Law Institute (ed.) (1990), Federal Income Tax Project, Integration of the Individual and Corporate Income Taxes, Reporter's Memorandum No. 1, Philadelphia, The American Law Institute. American Law Institute (ed.) (1991), Federal Income Tax Project Integration of the Individual and Corporate Income Taxes, Reporter's Memorandum No. 3, Philadelphia, The American Law Institute. American Law Institute (ed.) (1992), Federal Income Tax Project, Integration of the Individual and Corporate Income Taxes, Reporter's Study of Corporate Tax Integration, Philadelphia, The American Law Institute. Amihud, Yakov and Murgia, Maurizio (1997), 'Dividends, Taxes, and Signaling: Evidence from Germany', 52 Journal of Finance, 397-408. Anderson, F.J., Beaudreau, B.C. and Bonsor, N.C. (1983), 'Effective Corporate Tax Rates, Inflation, and Contestability', 16(4) Canadian Journal of Economics, 686-703. Andersson, Edward (1983), 'Corporate Tax Laws as Instruments of Economic Policy: Some Finnish Experiences', 37(1) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 35-39. Andersson, Krister (1991), 'Taxation and the Cost of Capital in Hungary and Poland: A Comparison with Selected European Countries', 38(2) International Monetary Fund Staff Papers, 327-355. Andrews, William D. (1956), 'Out of Earnings and Profits: Some Reflections on the Taxation of Dividends', 69 Harvard Law Review, 1403 ff. Andrews, William D. (1984), 'Tax Neutrality between Equity and Debt Capital', 30 Wayne Law Review, 1057-1071. Andrews, William D. (1995), The Unintegrated Economics of Corporate Tax Integration,. Ang, James S. and Peterson, David, 'Optimal Debt Versus Debt Capacity: A Disequilibrium Model of Corporate Behavior', in Coffee, John, Lowenstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (eds), Knights,Raiders and Targets: The Impact of the Hostile Takeover, Oxford, Oxford University Press.
190
Corporate Taxation
6060
Appelbaum, Elie and Katz, Eliakim (1996), 'Corporate Taxation, Incumbency Advantage and Entry', 40 European Economic Review, 1817-1828. Arbor, Ann (1992), 'Tax Compliance and Enforcement', in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), Why People Pay Taxes: Tax Compliance and Enforcement, University of Michigan Press, 125-661. Aretz, Adward (1991), 'Taxation and Incorporation: An Economic Analysis of Post-1992 Business Incorporations', in Weigel, Wolfgang (ed.), Economic Analysis of Law - A Collection of Applications, Vienna, Österreichischer Wirtschaftsverlag, 122-132. Arlen, Jennifer H. and Weiss, Deborah M. (1995), 'A Political Theory of Corporate Taxation', 105 Yale Law Journal, 325 ff. Arnold, Brian J. (1994), 'Canadian Finance Minister Announces Release of Tax Expenditures Account: Corporate Tax Expenditures Detailed', 8 Tax Notes International, 841 ff. Auerbach, Alan J. (1979a), 'Wealth Maximization and the Cost of Capital', 93 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 443-446. Auerbach, Alan J. (1979b), 'Share Valuation and Corporate Equity Policy', 11 Journal of Public Economics, 291-305. Auerbach, Alan J. (1981a), 'Inflation and the Tax Treatment of Firm Behavior', American Economic Review, 419-423. Auerbach, Alan J. (1981b), Tax Integration and the New View of the Corporate Tax: a 1980 Perspective. Auerbach, Alan J. (1982a), 'The New Economics of Accelerated Depreciation', 23 Boston College Law Review, 1327-1355. Auerbach, Alan J. (1982b), 'Whither the Corporate Tax? Reform after ACRS', 35(3) National Tax Journal, 275-286. Auerbach, Alan J. (1983a), ‘Stockholder Tax Rates and Firm Attributes’, 21 Journal of Public Economics, 107 ff. Auerbach, Alan J. (1983b), ‘Taxation, Corporate Financial Policy, and the Cost of Capital’, 21 Journal of Economic Literature, 905-940. Auerbach, Alan J. (1983c), ‘Corporate Taxation in the United States’, 2 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 451-505. Auerbach, Alan J. (1984), ‘Taxes, Firm Financial Policy and the Cost of Capital: An Empirical Analysis’, 23 Journal of Public Economics, 27-57. Auerbach, Alan J. (1985), Real Determinants of Corporate Leverage, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Auerbach, Alan J. (1986), ‘The Dynamic Effects of Tax Law Asymmetries’, 53 Review of Economic Studies, 205-226. Auerbach, Alan J. (1987), ‘The Tax Reform Act of 1986 and the Cost of Capital’, 1 Economic Perspectives, 73-86. Auerbach, Alan J. (1989), ‘Implications for Public Policy: Tax Policy and Corporate Borrowing’, Proceedings of a conference held at Melvin Village, New Hampshire in Kopcke, Richard and Rosengren, Eric (eds), Are the Distinctions between Debt and Equity disappearing ?, Federal Reserve Bank of Boston. Auerbach, Alan J. (1998), ‘Should Interest Deductions be Limited?’, in Aaron, Henry J., Galper, Harveu and Pechman, Joseph A. (eds), Uneasy Compromise: Problems of a Hybrid Income-Consumption Tax, Washington, Brookings Institution.
6060
Corporate Taxation
191
Auerbach, Alan J. and King, Mervyn (1983), ‘Taxation, Portfolio Choice and Debt Equity Rations: a General Equilibrium Model’, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 587-609. Auerbach, Alan J. and Poterba, James M. (1987a), ‘Why Have Corporate Revenues Declined?’, in Coffee, John, Lowenstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (eds), Knights, Raiders and Targets: The Impact of the Hostile Takeover, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 3-29. Auerbach, Alan J. and Poterba, James M. (1987b), ‘Tax Loss Carryforwards and Corporate Tax Incentives’, in Feldstein, M. (ed.), The Effects of Taxation on Capital Accumulation, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Auerbach, Alan J. and Reishus, David (1988), ‘The Impact of Taxation on Mergers and Acquisitions’, 69 in Coffee, John, Lowenstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (eds), Knights,Raiders and Targets: The Impact of the Hostile Takeover, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 81 ff. Auerbach, Alan J. and Reishus, David (1988), ‘The Effects of Taxation on the Merger Decision’, in Coffee, John, Lowenstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (eds), Knights,Raiders and Targets: The Impact of the Hostile Takeover, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Auerbach, Alan J. and Reishus, David (1988), ‘Taxes and the Merger Decision’, in Coffee, John, Lowenstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (eds), Knights,Raiders and Targets: The Impact of the Hostile Takeover, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Auerbach, Alan J. and Hassett, Kevin A. (1992), ‘Tax Policy and Business Fixed Investment in the United States’, 47 Journal of Public Economics, 141-170. Auerbach, Alan J., Hassett, Kevin A. and Sodersten, Jan (1995), ‘Taxation and Corporate Investment: The Impact of the 1991 Swedish Tax Reform’, 2 Swedish Economic Policy Review, 361-383. Auerbach, Alan J. and Slemrod, Joel (1997), ‘ The Economic Effects of the Tax Reform Act of 1986', 35 Journal of Economic Literature, 589-632. Ault, Hugh J. (1978), ‘International Issues in Corporate Tax Integration’, 10 Law and Policy in International Business, 461 ff. Ault, Hugh J. (1980), ‘Exploration of Income Tax Treaty Policy Issues in the United States: Interaction of the U. S. Tax System and U.S. Tax Treaty Rules with Foreign Integrated Corporate Shareholder Tax Systems’, 34(23) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 62-64. Ault, Hugh J. (1992), ‘Corporate Integration, Tax Treaties and the Division of the International Tax Base: Principles and Practices, with commentary by Kees Van Raad’, 47 Tax Law Review, 565 ff. Ault, Hugh J. (ed.) (1997), Comparative Income Taxation: A Structural Analysis, Kluwer Law International. Ault, Hugh J. and Bradford, David F. (1990), ‘Taxing International Income: An Analysis of the U.S. System and its Economic Premises’, in Razin and Slemrod (eds), Taxation in the Global Economy, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 11 ff. Avi-Yonah, R. S. and Reuven, S. (1990), ‘The Treatment of Corporate Preference Items under an Integrated Tax System: a Comparative Analysis’, 44 Tax Lawyer, 195 ff. Avi-Yonah, R. S. and Reuven, S. (1995), ‘The Rise and Fall of Arms’ Length: A Study in the Evolution of U.S. International Taxation’, 15 Va. Tax Review, 89 ff.
192
Corporate Taxation
6060
Ayers, Benjamin, Robinson, John R. and Cloyd, Bryan C. (1996), ‘Organizational Form and Taxes: An Empirical Analysis of Small Businesses’,Journal of the American Taxation Association, 49-67. Bacon, Frank W., Shin, Tai S. and Murphy, Neil B. (1994), ‘Factors Motivating Mergers: The Case of Rural Electric Cooperatives’, 46(2) Journal of Economics and Business, 129-134. Bagwell, Laurie Simon and Shoven, John B. (1989), ‘Cash Distributions to Shareholders’, 3 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 129-140. Ballard, Billy L. (ed.), Corporate Tax Rates and the Purchasing Power Parity Doctrine: Thesis (M.S.), University of North Texas. Ballard, Charles L., Fullerton, Don, Shoven, John B. and Walley, A. (eds) (1985), A General Equilibrium Model for Tax Policy Evaluation, Chicago. Ballentine, J. Gregory (1980), ‘Sales Maximization and Corporate Tax Shifting’, 47(2) Southern Economic Journal, 498-501. Ballentine, J. Gregory (1986), Effective Corporate Tax Rates: Their Level and Dispersion Across Industries. Bamberg, Gunter and Roder, Klaus (1994), ‘Arbitrage institutioneller Anleger am DAX Futures Markt unter Berucksichtigung von Korperschaftsteuern und Dividenden. (With English summary)’, 64(12) Zeitschrift für Betriebswirtschaft, 1533-1566. Bankman, Joseph (1995), ‘A Market-Value Based Corporate Income Tax’, 68 Tax Notes, 1347 ff. Barclay, Michael J., Smith, C.W. and Watts, Ross L. (1995), ‘The Determinants of Corporate Leverage and Dividends Policies’, 7 Journal of Applied Corporate Finance, 4-19. Barnes, Tom and Burnie, David A. (1987), ‘The Estimation of Corporate Bond Yield Curves as a Function of Term to Maturity and Coupon’, 26(4) Quarterly Journal of Business and Economics, 50-64. Bartholdy, J., Fisher, G. and Mintz, Jack M. (1985), Some Theory of Taxation and Financial Policy with Application to Canadian Corporate Data, Econometric Society Fifth World Congress, Cambridge. Battacharya, Sugato (1980), ‘Imperfect Information, Dividend Policy and the “Bird in the Hand Fallacy”’, 10 Bell Journal of Economics, 259-270. Batten, Dallas S. and Ott, Mack (1985), ‘The President’s Proposed Corporate Tax Reforms: A Move toward Tax Neutrality’, 67(7) Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis Review, 5-17. Benge, Matt (1997a), The Australian Full Imputation Reform in Company Tax Systems,. Benge, Matt (1997b), ‘Taxes, Corporate Financial Policy and Investment Decisions in Australia’, 73 Economic Record, 1-15. Benge, Matt and Robinson, Tim (eds) (1986), How to Integrate Company and Shareholder Taxation: Why Full Imputation is the Best Answer, Wellington University Press for the Institute of Policy Studies. Bernard, Jean Thomas and Weiner, Robert J. (eds) (1990), ‘Multinational Corporations, Transfer Prices, and Taxes: Evidence from the U.S. Petroleum Industry’, in Razin and Slemrod (eds), Taxation in the Global Economy, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Bernard, Victor L. and Hayn, Carla (1986), ‘Inflation and the Distribution of the Corporate Income Tax Burden’, 39 National Tax Journal, 171-187.
6060
Corporate Taxation
193
Bernheim, B. Douglas (1991), ‘Tax Policy and The Dividend Puzzle’, 22 Rand Journal of Economics, 455-476. Bernheim, B. Douglas and Shoven, John B. (1987), ‘Taxation and the Cost of Capital: An International Comparison’, 61, 74-75. Bernheim, B. Douglas and Wantz, Adam (1995), ‘A Tax-Based Test of the Dividend Signalling Hypothesis’, 85 American Economic Review, 532-551. Bernstein, Jeffrey I. and Nadiri, M., Corporate Taxes and Incentives and the Structure of Production: a Selected Survey, Kingston, Ontario. Bernstein, Jeffrey I. and Shah, Anwar (1993), Corporate Tax Structure and Production, World Bank Policy Research Dept., 1196. Berry, Richard J. (ed.) (1978), Short-run Shifting and Incidence of the Corporate Income Tax for U.S. Manufacturing. Bird, Richard M. (ed.) (1980), Taxing Corporations, Montreal, Institute for Research on Public Policy. Bird, Richard M. (1987), ‘Corporate-Personal Tax Integration’, in Cnossen, S. (ed.), Tax Coordination In The European Community, London: Kluwer Law And Taxation, 227 ff. Bird, Richard M. (1996), Why Tax Corporations?, Ottawa, Technical Committee on Business Taxation., 96-2. Bittker, Boris I. and Rahdert (1976), ‘The Exemption of Nonprofit Organizations from Federal Income Taxation’, 85 Yale Law Journal, 299 ff. Bittker, Boris I., Eustice, James S. and Cummings, Jasper L., Jr (1994), Federal Income Taxation of Corporations and Shareholders. Blair, Margaret, M. and Litan Robert (1990), ‘Corporate Leverage and Leveraged Buyouts in the Eighties: Taxes, Debt, and Corporate Restructuring’, in Coffee, John, Lowenstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (eds), Knights, Raiders and Targets: The Impact of the Hostile Takeover, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Blais, Andre and Vaillancourt, Francois (1986), The Political Economy of Taxation: the Corporate Income Tax and the Canadian Manufacturing Industry, Dept. De Science Economique, Universite de Montreal, 8610. Blum, Walter J. (1975), ‘The Earnings and Profits Limitation on Dividend Income: A Reappraisal’, 53 Taxes, 68 ff. Blumenthal, Marsha and Slemrod, Joel (1994), The Compliance Costs of the US Corporate Income Tax for Large Corporations,. Blumenthal, Marsha and Slemrod, Joel (1995), ‘The Compliance Cost of Taxing Foreign-Source Income: Its Magnitude, Determinants and Policy Implications’, International Tax and Public Finance in Coffee, John, Lowenstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (eds), Knights,Raiders and Targets: The Impact of the Hostile Takeover, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Slemrod J. (ed.), The taxation of multinational corporations (1996) Boadway, Robin W. (1988), ‘The Theory and Measurement of Effective Tax Rates’, in Coffee, John, Lowenstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (eds), Knights,Raiders and Targets: The Impact of the Hostile Takeover, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 60-98. Boadway, Robin W. (1989), ‘Corporate Tax Harmonisation: Lessons from Canada in Gammie, Malcolm, Robinson, Bill, and Fitchew, Geoffrey, Beyond 1992: a European Tax System’, in
194
Corporate Taxation
6060
Coffee, John, Lowenstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (eds), Knights,Raiders and Targets: The Impact of the Hostile Takeover, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Boadway, Robin W. and Bruce, Neil (1984), ‘A General Proposition on the Design of a Neutral Business Tax’, 24 Journal of Public Economics, 231-239. Boadway, Robin W. and Bruce, Neil (1992a), ‘Problems with Integrating Corporate and Personal Income Taxes in an Open Economy’, 24 Journal of Public Economics, 231-239. Boadway, Robin W. and Bruce, Neil (1992b), ‘Problems with Integrating Corporate and Personal Income Taxes in an Open Economy’, 48(1) Journal of Public Economics, 39-66. Boadway, Robin W. and Treddenick, John M. (1975a), The Effects of the U.S. Corporate Tax on Resource Allocation and Welfare Institute for Economic Research, Queen’s University Institute for Economic Research Discussino Paper, 165. Boadway, Robin W. and Treddenick, John M. (1975b), ‘The Effect of Corporate Tax Changes by Industry on Employment in Canada: A Short Run Analysis’, 30(1) Public Finance, 46-60. Boadway, Robin, Bruce, Neil and Mintz, Jack M. (1982), ‘Corporate Taxation in Canada: Toward an Efficient System’, in Coffee, John, Lowenstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (eds), Knights, Raiders and Targets: The Impact of the Hostile Takeover, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Boadway, Robin, Bruce, Neil and Mintz, Jack M. (1984), ‘Taxation, Inflation, and the Effective Marginal Tax Rate in Canada’, 17 Canadian Journal of Economics, 62-79. Boadway, Robin, Bruce, Neil and Mintz, Jack M. (1992), ‘Corporate Taxation and the Holding of Inventories’, 25 Canadian Journal of Economics, 278-293. Bodie, Zvi (1989), ‘The Lender’s View of Debt and Equity: the Case of Pension Funds’, Proceedings of a conference held at Melvin Village, New Hampshire. Bolderson, Sarah and Huiskes, Theodoor (1994), ‘Central and Eastern Europe: Meeting Tax Obligations in Central and Eastern Europe’, 48 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 648-654. Bond, S. and Devereux, Michael P. (1995), ‘On the Design of a Neutral Business Tax under Uncertainty’, 58 Journal of Public Economics, 57-71. Bonner, Sarah E., Davis, Jon S. and Jackson, Betty R. (1992), ‘Expertise in Corporate Tax Planning: The Issue Identification Stage’, 30(0) Journal of Accounting Research, 1-28. Boshoff, Vanessa (1993), ‘Corporate Tax Rates and Inter-country Comparisons’, 61(4) South African Journal of Economics, 301-316. Bovenberg, A. Lans (1993), ‘Investment Promoting Policies in Open Economies: The Importance of Intergenerational and International Distributional Effects’, 51(1) Journal of Public Economics, 3-54. Bovenberg, A. Lans and Goulder, Lawrence H. (1993), ‘Promoting Investment under International Capital Mobility: An Intertemporal General Equilibrium Analysis’, 95(2) Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 133-156. Boyle, Glenn W. (1996), ‘Corporate Investment and Dividend Tax Imputation’, 31 Financial Review, 209-226. Boynton, Charles E., Dobbins, Paul S. and Plesko, George A. (1992), ‘Earnings Management and the Corporate Alternative Minimum Tax in Conference on Accounting Research’, Studies on Accounting and Taxation.
6060
Corporate Taxation
195
Bracewell-Milnes, J. Barry (1995), ‘Summary of Proceedings in International Fiscal Association. International Taxation of Dividends Reconsidered in Light of Corporate Tax Integration’, Proceedings of a seminar organised jointly with the EOCD in Toronto in 1994 during the 48th Congress of the International Fiscal Association. Bradford, David F. (1981), ‘The Incidence and Allocation Effects of a Tax on Corporate Distributions’, 15 Journal of Public Economics, 1-22. Bradford, David F. and Fullerton, David J. (1982), ‘Pitfalls in the Construction and Use of Effective Tax Rates’, in Hulten, Charles R (ed.), Depreciation, Inflation, and the Taxation of Income from Capital., Washington, Urban Insitute, 251-279. Bradford, David F. and Gordon, Roger H. (1980), ‘Taxation and the Stock Market Valuation of Capital Gains and Dividends’, 14 Journal of Public Economics, 109-136. Bradley, Cassie Francis (ed.) (1994), An Empirical Investigation of Factors Affecting Corporate Tax Compliance Behavior: Ph.D. Thesis, University of Alabama, Culverhouse School of Accountancy. Bradley, Michael, Jarrell, Gregg A. and Kim, E. Han (1984), ‘On the Existence of an Optimal Capital Structure: Theory and Evidence’, 39 The Journal of Finance, 857 ff. Bravenec, Lorence L. (1989), ‘A Nontraditional Approach to Corporate Integration’, Tax Notes, 1381 ff. Break, George F. (1969), ‘Integrating Corporate and Personal Income Taxes: The Carter Commission Proposals’, 34 Law and Contemporary Problems, 726-735. Break, George F. (1969), ‘Integration of the Corporate and Personal Income Taxes’, 22 National Tax Journal, 39-56. Break, George F. (1978), ‘Corporate Tax Integration: Radical Revisions or Common Sense?’, in Boskin, Michael J. (ed.), Federal Tax Reform Myths and Realities, San Francisco, Institute for Contemporary Studies Press. Break, George F. (1991), ‘Corporate Income Taxation in Jamaica: A Framework for Policy Formation’, in Bahl, Roy (ed.), The Jamaican Tax Reform, Cambridge, MA, Lincoln Institute of Land Policy, 251-263. Break, George F. and Pechman, Joseph A. (1975), ‘Relationship Between the Corporation and Individual Income Taxes’, 28 National Tax Journal, 341 ff. Brennan, Michael J. (1970), ‘Taxes, Market Valuation and Corporate Financial Policy’, 23 National Tax Journal, 417-427. Brittain, John A. (1964), ‘The Tax Structure and Corporate Dividend Policy’, 54 American Economic Review, 272 ff. Reprinted by Brookings Institution, Washington, DC Studies of Government Finance reprint no. 78. Brittain, John A. (ed.) (1966), Corporate Dividend Policy, Washington, Brookings Institution. Brody, Evelyn (1995), ‘Agents Without Principals: the Economic Convergence of the Nonprofit and For-Profit Organizational Forms’, 40 New York Law School Law Review, 457 ff. Brooke, Peter (1989), ‘The Government’s Approach to the Community: Some Myths Dispelled’, in Gammie, Malcolm, Robinson, Bill and Fitchew Geoffrey, Beyond 1992: A European Tax System: Proceedings of the Fourth Institute for Fiscal Studies Residential Conference, Oxford. Brooks, Janet (1990), ‘Tax Reform: A Response to Economic and Social Changes: Korea’, 44(6) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 271-272.
196
Corporate Taxation
6060
Brooks, Neil (1997), ‘Canadian Corporate Tax: Logic, Policies and Politics’, in Head, G. And Krever, Richard (eds), Company Tax Systems, Australian Research Foundation, 115-158. Brown, E. (1973), Cary Recent Studies of the Incidence of the Corporate Income Tax, Massachusetts Institute of Technology Dept. of Economics Working paper No. 116. Brown, Fred B. (1993), ‘Federal Income Taxation of U.S. Branches of Foreign Corporations: Separate Entity or Separate Rules?’, 49 Tax Law Review, 195-196. Brumbaugh, David L. and Gravelle, Jane G. (ed.) (1984), The Corporate Income Tax and the U.S. Economy, Washington DC, Congressional Research Service, Library of Congress. Bryan (1984), ‘Cancellation of Indebtedness by Issuing Stock in Exchange, Challenging the Congressional Solution to Debt-Equity Swaps’, 63 Texas Law Review, 89-130. Bryan (1987), ‘Leveraged Buyouts and Tax Policy’, 65 North Carolina Law Review, 1039 ff. Buck, Ingerlise (1990), ‘Budgetdepartementets Behandling af Erhvervsbeskatningen (with English summary) (A Critical Evaluation of the Assumptions on Corporate Tax in the Macroeconomic Model Used by the Danish Ministry of Finance)’, 128(1) Nationalokonomisk Tidsskrift, 30-39. Bulow, Jeremy I. and Summers, Lawrence H. (1984), ‘The Taxation of Risky Assets’, 92 Journal of Political Economy, 20-39. Bulow, Jeremy I., Summers, Lawrence H. and Summers, Victoria P. (1990), ‘Distinguishing Debt from Equity in the Junk Bond Era’, in Shoven, John B. and Waldfogel, Joel (eds), In Debt, Taxes, and Corporate Restructuring, Washington, Brookings Institution. Burke, Karen C. (1995), ‘The Uncertain Future of Limited Liability Companies’, 12 American Jounal of Tax Policy, 14 ff. Burns, Arthur Edward (1970), ‘The Tax Court and Profit Renegotiation’, 13 Journal of Law and Economics, 307-326. Butters, J. Keith, Lintner, John V. and Cary, William L. (1951), Effects of Taxation on Corporate Mergers. Canellos, Peter C. (1985), ‘The Over-Leveraged Acquisition’, 39 Tax Lawyer, 91 ff. Canellos, Peter C. (1987), ‘Corporate Tax Integration: by Design or by Default’, Tax Notes, 999 ff. Canellos, Peter C. (1988), ‘Corporate Tax Integration: by Design or by Default?’, in Yin, George K. and Mundstock, George (eds), Corporate Tax Reform: A Report of the Invitational Conference on Subchapter C 129. Canellos, Peter C. and Yin, George K. (eds) (1987), Corporate Tax Reform: A Report of the American Bar and New York State Bar Associations Invitational Conference on Subchapter C. Caplin, Mortimer M. (1961), ‘Income Tax Pressures on the Form of Business Organization: Is it Time for a “Doing Business” Tax?’, 47 Va. Law Review, 249 ff. Carrera, Carmen (1991), ‘On the Consequences of Legal Constraints and Taxation for Corporate Choice’, 24 Canadian Journal of Economics, 471-485. Carter, Mary Ellen and Manzon, Gil B., Jr (1995), ‘Evidence on the Role of Taxes on Financing Choice: Consideration of Mandatorily Redeemable Preferred Stock’, 18 Journal of Financial Research, 103-114.
6060
Corporate Taxation
197
Cary, William L. (1974), ‘Federalism and Corporate Law: Reflections Upon Delaware’, 83 Yale Law Journal, 663 ff. Centre for European Policy Studies (ed.) (1992), Corporate Tax Harmonisation in the European Community. Chen, Charng Yi and Ponarul, Richard (1991), ‘Tax Sheltering Behavior of Property Liability Insurers: Some Additional Evidence’, 58(4) Journal of Risk and Insurance, 722-728. Cheung, Joseph K. (1987), ‘Depreciation, Debt, and Equilibrium Tax Rates: A Reconsideration’, 27(1) Quarterly Review of Economics and Business, 6-15. Chiang, Raymond C. and Narayanan, M.P. (1991), ‘Bond Refunding in Efficient Markets: A Dynamic Analysis with Tax Effects’, 14(4) Journal of Financial Research, 287-302. Chirelstein, Marvin A. (1969), ‘Optional Redemptions and Optional Dividends: Taxing the Repurchase of Common Shares’, 78 Yale Law Journal, 739 ff. Chirinko, Robert S. (1986), ‘Business Investment and Tax Policy: a Perspective on Existing Models and Empirical Results’, 39 National Tax Journal, 137 ff. Chirinko, Robert S. (1987), ‘The Ineffectiveness of Effective Tax Rates on Business Investment: a Critique of Feldstein’s Fisher-Schultz Lecture’, 32 Journal of Public Economics, 369 ff. Chirinko, Robert S. (ed.), Business Fixed Investment Spending: A Critical Survey of Modeling Strategies, Empirical Results, and Policy Implications, University of Munich, Centre for Economic Studies, 27. Chorvat, Terrence R. (1998), ‘Taxing International Corporate Income Efficiently’, Tax Law Review. Chown, John (1989), ‘Tax Harmonisation in Europe’, in Gammie, Malcolm, Robinson, Bill and Fitchew Geoffrey, Beyond 1992: A European Tax System: Proceedings of the Fourth Institute for Fiscal Studies Residential Conference, Oxford. Christie, William G. and Nanda, Vikram (1994), ‘Free Cash Flow, Shareholder Value, and the Undistributed Profits Tax of 1936 and 1937’, 49 Journal of Finance, 1727-1754. Citizens for Tax Justice (1985), ‘Corporate Taxpayers and Corporate Freeloaders: Four Years of Continuing, Legalized Tax Avoidance by America’s Largest Corporation, 1981-84', Tax Notes, 947-971. Clark (1975), ‘The Federal Income Taxation of Financial Intermediaries’, 84 Yale Law Journal, 1603 ff. Clark, Robert C. (1977), ‘The Morphogenesis of Subchapter C: An Essay in Statutory Evolution and Reform’, 87 Yale Law Journal, 90 ff. Clotfelter, Charles T. (1989), ‘Tax-Induced Distortions in the Voluntary Sector: in What is Charity? Implications for Law and Policy’, 39 Case Western Reserve Law Review, 663 ff. Clowery, Grant M., Outslay, Edmund and Wheeler, James, E. (1986), ‘The Debate on Computing Corporate Effective Tax Rates - an Accounting View’, Tax Notes. Cloyd, Bryan C., Limberg, Stephen T. and Robinson, John R. (1997), ‘The Impact of Federal Taxes on the Use of Debt by Closely-Held Corporations’, National Tax Journal, 261-277. Cnossen, Sijbren (1989), ‘How Much Tax Harmonisation in the European Community?’, in Gammie, Malcolm, Robinson, Bill and Fitchew, Geoffrey, Beyond 1992: A European Tax
198
Corporate Taxation
6060
System: Proceedings of the Fourth Institute for Fiscal Studies Residential Conference, Oxford. Cnossen, Sijbren (1993), ‘What Kind of Corporation Tax?’, 47 International Bureau of Fiscal Documentation, 3-16. Cnossen, Sijbren (1993), ‘Must the Corporation Tax be Harmonised?’, in Knoester, Anthonie (ed.), Taxation in the United States and Europe: Theory and Practice: Proceedings of a Conference Held by the Confederation of European Economic Associations at Amsterdam, the Netherlands, 1991, 165-201. Confederation of European Economic Associations Conference Volumes 1993. Cnossen, Sijbren (1996), ‘Company Taxes in the European Union: Criteria and Options for Reform’, 17 Fiscal Studies, 67-97. Cnossen, Sijbren (1997a), ‘Reform and Harmonization of Company Tax Systems in the European Union’, in , Tax Conversations: A Guide to the Key Issues in the Tax Reform Debate: Essays in Honour of John G. Head, Kluwer, 365-413. Cnossen, Sijbren (1997b), ‘The Role of the Corporation Tax in OECD Member Countries’, in Head, G. And Krever, Richard (eds), Company Tax Systems, Australian Research Foundation, 49-84. Coates, Dennis (1991), ‘Endogenous Capital Utilization and Taxation of Corporate Capital’, 44 National Tax Journal, 79-91. Cohen, Edwin S. (1975), ‘Possible Solutions to Practical Problems in Integration of the Corporate and Shareholder Income Tax’, 28 National Tax Journal, 359-367. Cohen, Edwin S., Warren, Alvin C. and Andrews, William D. (1985), ‘The Meaning of Changes Within the Framework of Subchapter C and the Impact on Proposals for Integration of the Corporate and Individual Income Tax’, 22 San Diego Law Review, 317 ff. Collins, Julie H. and Shackelford, Douglas A. (1990), ‘Corporate Domicile and Average Effective Tax Rates: The Cases of Canada, Japan, the United Kingdom, and the United States’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), The Taxation of Multinational Corporations. Collins, Julie H. and Shackelford, Douglas A. (1992a), ‘Foreign Tax Credit Limitations and Preferred Stock Issuances’, 30 Journal of Accounting Research, 103-124. Collins, Julie H. and Shackelford, Douglas A. (eds) (1992b), Foreign Tax Credit Limitations and Preferred Stock Issuances in Conference on Accounting Research, Studies on Accounting and Taxation, Chicago, University of Chicago. Collins, Julie H., Kelmsley, D. and Shackelford, Douglas A. (1995), ‘Tax Reform and Foreign Acquisitions: A Microanalysis’, 48 National Tax Journal, 1-21. Colm, Gerhard (1940), ‘Conflicting Theories of Corporate Income Taxation’, 7 Law and Contemporary Problems, 282 ff. Commission on Corporations (1977), ‘Report on the Integration of Corporate and Individual Income Taxes’, 31 Tax Lawyer, 37 ff. Commission of European Communities (ed.) (1992), Report of the Committee of Independent Experts on Company Taxation, Brussels. Cooley, Thomas F. and Salyer, Kevin D. (1987), ‘The Effects of Inflation Induced Tax Increases on Stock and Housing Prices’, 89(4) Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 421-434. Cooper, Graeme S. (1994), ‘Analyzing Corporate Tax Evasion’, 50 Tax Law Review, 33 ff.
6060
Corporate Taxation
199
Cooper, Graeme S. (1996), ‘The Return to Corporate Tax Evasion in the Presence of an Income Tax on Shareholders: The Return to Corporate Tax Evasion in the Presence of an Income Tax on Shareholders’, 12 Akron Tax Journal, 1 ff. Cooper, Graeme S. (1997), ‘The Effect of an Income Tax on Corporate Tax Compliance’, in Head, G. And Krever, Richard (eds), Company Tax Systems, Australian Research Foundation, 341-378. Cooper, Graeme S. and Gordon, Richard K., Jr (1988), ‘Taxation of Legal Persons and Their Owners’, in Coffee, John, Lowenstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (eds), Knights, Raiders and Targets: The Impact of the Hostile Takeover, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Cordes, Joseph J. and Sheffrin, Steven M. (1983), ‘Estimating the Tax Advantage of Corporate Debt’, 38 Journal of Finance, 95-105. Cosciani, Cesare (1959), The Effects of Differential Tax Treatment of Corporate and Non-corporate Enterprises, European Productivity Agency of the Organisation for European Economic Cooperation Project, 314. Couzin, Robert (1992), ‘Taxation and Its Impact on Market Structure: Comment’, in Bird, R.M. and Mintz, J.M. (eds), Taxation to 2000 and Beyond. Canadian Tax Paper, Toronto: Canadian Tax Foundation, 257-262. Coyne, Christopher, Fabozzi, Frank J. and Yaari, M.E. (1992), ‘How Taxes Transform Corporate Acquisitions into Asset Arbitrage’, in Coffee, John, Lowenstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (eds), Knights, Raiders and Targets: The Impact of the Hostile Takeover, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 173-203. Cragg, John C., Harberger, Arnold, C. and Mieszkowski, Peter M. (1967), ‘Empirical Evidence on the Incidence of the Corporation Income Tax’, Journal of Political Economy, 811-822. Reprinted in Harberger, Arnold C. (ed.) Taxation and Welfare, 1974, 135-162 Craig, Caroline Kern (ed.) (1987), The Shifting of Corporate Capital Acquisition Tax Subsidies an Empirical Analysis, Ph.D. Thesis, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign. Craig, Caroline Kern and Todd, Heidi l. (1993), ‘An Overview of Corporate Tax Issues Involving the European Communit’, 175 Journal of Accountancy, 29 ff. Crane, Charlotte (1988), ‘Toward a Theory of the Corporate Tax Base: The Effect of a Corporate Distribution of Encumbered Property to Shareholders’, 44 Tax Law Review, 13 ff. Crockett, Ulysses S. (ed.) (1973), Tax Exemption for Corporate Mergers and Consolidations: a Legislative History of Congressional Policy, LL.M. Thesis, Columbia University Press. Cross, Mark L., Davidson, Wallace N. II and Thornton, John H. (1988), ‘Taxes, Stock Returns and Captive Insurance Subsidiaries’, 55 Journal of Risk and Insurance, 331-338. Cummings, Jasper L., Jr (1992), ‘The Silent Policies of Conservation and Cloning of Tax Basis and Their Corporate Applications’, 48 Tax Law Review, 126-131. Cummins, Jason G., Harris, Trevor S. and Hassett, Kevin A. (1995), ‘Accounting Standards, Information Flow, and Firm Investment Behavior’, in Feldstein, M., Hines, J.R., Jr, Hubbard, R.G. (eds), The Effects of Taxation on Multinational Corporations, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 181-224.
200
Corporate Taxation
6060
Cutler, David M. (1988), ‘Tax Reform and the Stock Market: An Asset Price Approach’, 78 American Economic Review, 1107-1117. Daly, Kevin and Hart, Neil (1994), ‘Mark-up Pricing and the Forward Shifting of the Corporate Income Tax’, 0 Australian Economic Review, 45-54. Daly, Michael and Jung, Jack (1987), ‘The Taxation of Corporate Investment Income in Canada: An Analysis of Marginal Effective Tax Rates’, 20 Canadian Journal of Economics, 555-587. Daly, Michael and Weiner, Joann (1993), ‘Corporate Tax Harmonization and Competition in Federal Countries: Some Lessons for the European Community?’, 46(4) National Tax Journal, 441-461. Dammon, Robert M. and Senbet, Lemma W. (1988), ‘The Effect of Taxes and Depreciation on Corporate Investment and Financial Leverage’, 43(2) Journal of Finance, 357-373. Damus, Sylvester, Hobson, Paul A.R. and Thirsk, Wayne R. (1991), ‘Foreign Tax Credits, the Supply of Foreign Capital, and Tax Exporting: A Numerical General Equilibrium Model of Corporate Tax Reform in Canada’, 45(1) Journal of Public Economics, 29-46. Darrow, Jill E. (1994), ‘Limited Liability Companies and S Corporations: Deciding Which is Optimal and Whether to Convert to LLC Status’, 48 Tax Lawyer, 1 ff. Davies, John H. (1975), ‘Public Stock, Private Stock: A Model for the Corporate Income Tax’, 124 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 299 ff. de la Fuente, Angel and Gardner, Edward (eds) (1990), Corporate Income Tax Harmonization and Capital Allocation in the European Community, International Monetary Fund. Deangelo, Harry (1991), ‘Payout Policy and Tax Deferral’, 46(1) Journal of Finance, 357-368. Deangelo, Harry and Masulis, Ronald W. (1980), ‘Optimal Capital Structures under Corporate and Personal Taxation’, 8 Journal of Financial Economics, 3-30. Desai, Mihir A. and Hines, James R., Jr (eds) (1996), “Basket” Cases : International Joint Ventures after the Tax Reform Act of 1986, National Bureau of Economic Research, 5755. Devereux, Michael P. (1989), ‘Tax Asymmetries: The Cost of Captial and Investment’, 99 Economic Journal, 103-112. Devereux, Michael P. and Freeman, Harold (1991), ‘A General Neutral Profits Tax’, 12(3) Fiscal Studies, 2 ff. Devereux, Michael P. and Freeman, Harold (1995), ‘The Impact of Tax on Foreign Dirrect Investment: Empirical Evidence and the Implications for Tax Integration Schemes’, 2 International Tax and Public Finance, 85-106. Devereux, Michael P. and Freeman, Harold (1996), ‘The Impact of Tax on Foreign Direct Investment: Empirical Evidence and the Implications for Tax Integration Schemes’, in Slemrod, Joel (ed.), The Taxation of Multinational Corporations. International Tax and Public Finance, 1995 Devereux, Michael P. and Pearson, Mark (1990), ‘Harmonising CorporateYaxes in Europe’, 11 Fiscal Studies, 21-35. Devereux, Michael P. and Pearson, Mark (1992), ‘The Interactions of Corporate Tax between the EC, Japan and the United States: International’, 46(8) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 367-383.
6060
Corporate Taxation
201
Devereux, Michael P. and Pearson, Mark (1994), ‘Production Efficiency and Corporate Tax Harmonization’, European Economic Review. Devereux, Michael P. and Pearson, Mark (eds), Corporate Tax Harmonisation and Economic Efficiency,. Devereux, Michael P., Keen, Michael and Schiantarelli, F. (1994), ‘Corporation Tax Asymmetries and Investment: Evidence from UK Panel Data’, 53 Journal of Public Economics, 3950-3418. Diamond, Peter and Mirrlees, J.A. (1971), ‘Optimal Taxation and Public Production, I: Production Efficiency, and II: Tax Rules’, 61 American Economic Review, 261-278. Dodge, Joseph A. (1995), ‘A Combined Mark-to-Market and Pass-Through Corporate-Shareholder Integration Proposal’, 50 Tax Law Review, 265 ff. Doernberg, Richard L. (1992), ‘International Aspects of Individual and Corporate Tax Integration’, 4 Tax Notes International, 506 ff. Doernberg, Richard L. (1995), Amending the OECD Model Treaty and Commentary in Response to Corporate Tax Integration, Proceedings of a Seminar Organised Jointly with the OECD in Toronto in 1994 During the 48th Congress of the International Fiscal Association. Doernberg, Richard L. and McChesney Fred S. (1987), ‘On the Accelerating Rate and Decreasing Durability of Tax Reform’, 71 Minnesota Law Review, 913 ff. Douglas, Richard W., Jr (ed.) (1987), Consultative Document on Full Imputation, Wellington, New Zealand Ministry of Finance. Douvier, Pierre Jean (1993), ‘Major Measures Concerning International Taxation: The Finance Act 1993 and Transfer of Assets Abroad’, 47(4) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 214-219. Downs, Thomas, W. (1992), ‘Q and the Tax Bias Theory: The Role of Depreciation Tax Shields’, 47 Journal of Public Economics, 59-84. Downs, Thomas, W. (1993), ‘Corporate Leverage and Nondebt Tax Shields: Evidence on Crowding-Out’, 28 Financial Review, 549-583. Downs, Thomas, W. and Demirgures, Cuneyt (1992), ‘The Asset Price Theory of Shareholder Revaluations: Tests with the Tax Reforms of the 1980s’, 27 Financial Review, 151-184. Downs, Thomas and Hendershott, Patric H. (1987), ‘Tax Policy and Stock Prices’, 40(2) National Tax Journal, 183-190. Downs, Thomas, W. and Shriver, Keith A. (1992), ‘The Analytical Derivation and Empirical Test of a Tax-Adjusted Fundamental Value Model’, 30 Journal of Accounting Research, 77-98. Downs, Thomas, W. and Tehranian, Hassan (1988), ‘Predicting Stock Price Responses to Tax Policy Changes’, 78 American Economic Review, 1118-1130. Driessen, Patrick A. (1991), ‘Net Imports and the U.S. Corporate Tax Base’, 44(3) National Tax Journal, 315-324. Duggal, V.G. and Adams, F.G. (1987), ‘Corporate Tax Reform and Business Investment: Empirical Estimates for Structures and Equipment’, 12(3) Empirical Economics, 187-195. Dusansky, Richard (ed.), Corporate Income Tax Shifting in the U.S.: A Simultaneous Equations Approach Stony Brook, Economic Research Bureau, State University of New York, 31.
202
Corporate Taxation
6060
Dutton, John (1982), ‘The Optimal Taxation of International Investment Income: A Comment’, 97 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 373-380. Dworin, Lowell (1985), ‘On Estimating Corporate Tax Liabilities from Financial Statements’, 9 Tax Notes, 947-971. Dworin, Lowell (1987), Impact of the Corporate Alternative Minimum Tax: A Monte Carlo Simulation. Easson, Alex J. (1997), Company Tax Reform and the Inter-nation Allocation of Tax Jurisdiction, Australian Research Foundation. Easterbrook, Frank H. (1984), ‘Two Agency-cost Explanations of Dividends’, 74 American Economic Review, 650 ff. Easterbrook, Frank H. and Fischel, Daniel R. (1991), The Economic Structure of Corporate Law, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Ebrill, Liam, P. and Hartman, David, G. (1982), ‘On the Incidence and Excess Burden of the Corporation Income Tax’, 37 Public Finance, 48 ff. Ebrill, Liam, P. and Hartman, David, G. (1983), ‘The Corporate Income Tax, Entrepreneurship, and the Noncorporate Sector’, 11 Public Finance Quarterly, 419-436. Eckhard, Janeba (1995), ‘Corporate Income Tax Competition, Double Taxation Treaties, and Foreign Direct Investment’, 56 Journal of Public Economics, 311-325. Eden, Lorraine (ed.) (1998), Taxing Multinationals: Transfer Pricing and Corporate Income Taxation in North America, Toronto, University of Toronto Press. Egger, John, B. (1985), ‘Citizens for Tax Justice’s Latest Misrepresentation of Corporate Tax Burdens’, Tax Notes, 947-971. Eisner, Robert (1969), ‘Tax Policy and Investment Behavior: Comment’, 59 American Economic Review, 379 ff. Eisner, Robert and Nadiri, M. (1968), ‘Investment Behavior and Neoclassical Theory’, 50 Review of Economics and Statistics, 369 ff. Elitzur, R. Ramy and Mintz, Jack M. (1994), ‘Transfer Pricing Rules and Corporate Tax Competition. Dept. of Economics and Institute for Policy Analysis’, in Coffee, John, Lowenstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (eds), Knights, Raiders and Targets: The Impact of the Hostile Takeover, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 829-4909. Elitzur, R. Ramy and Mintz, Jack M. (1996), ‘Transfer Pricing Rules and Corporate Tax Competition’, 60 Journal of Public Economics, 401-422. Elitzur, R. Ramy and Mintz, Jack M. (1997), ‘Corrigendum to Transfer Pricing Rules and Corporate Tax Competition’, 64 Journal of Public Economics, 287 ff. Elston, Julie Ann (1992), ‘Tax Reform and Corporate Investment: Theory and Evidence of a Q Theoretic Approach’, in Coffee, John, Lowenstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (eds), Knights, Raiders and Targets: The Impact of the Hostile Takeover, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Elton, Edwin, J. and Gruber, Martin (1970), ‘Marginal Stockholder Tax Rates and the Clientele Effect’, 52 Review of Economics and Statistics, 68-74. Esam, Richard, T. (1979), ‘International and Comparative Aspects of Corporate/Shareholder Integration: A View from the United Kingdom’, 33 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 312-316. Esenwein, Gregg, A. and Gravelle, Jane G. (1982), A Comparative Analysis of the Accelerated Cost Recovery System and a Repeal of the Corporate Income Tax, Washington, DC, Fund for Public Policy Research.
6060
Corporate Taxation
203
Evans, Thomas L. (1991), ‘The Taxation of Multi-Period Projects: An Analysis of Competing Models’, 69(5) Texas Law Review, 1109 ff. Faber, Peter (1985), ‘Taxation of Corporations and Shareholders: Premises of the present System’, 22 San Diego Law Review, 5 ff. Fabozzi, Frank J. and Fonfeder, Robert (1981), ‘Corporate Tax Rates in an Inflationary Environment: 1976 and 1977', 16(1) Business Economics, 55-58. Fama, Eugene F. and French, Kenneth R. (1998), ‘Taxes, Financing Decisions, and Firm Value’, Journal of Finance. Fantozzi, Augusto (1993), ‘Italy Welcomes Further EC Harmonization’, 47(9) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 474-479. Fazzari, Steven, Hubbard, R. Glenn and Petersen, Bruce (1988), ‘Financing Constraints and Corporate Investment’, 1 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 141 ff. Feld, Alan (ed.) (1982), Tax Policy and Corporate Concentration, Lexington Books. Feldstein, Martin S. (1970a), Testimony on Tax Policy Aspects of Mergers and Acquisitions, House of Representatives, Committee on Ways and Means, No.101-10. Feldstein, Martin, S. (1970b), ‘Corporate Taxation and Dividend Behavior’, 37 Review of Economic Studies, 57-72. Feldstein, Martin S. (1972), ‘Corporate Taxation and Dividend Behavior: a Reply and Extension’, 39 Review of Economic Studies, 235 ff. Feldstein, Martin S. (1987), Imputing Corporate Tax Liabilities to Individual Taxpayer, Cambridge: National Bureau of Eocnomic Research, 2349. Feldstein, Martin S. (1988), ‘Imputing Corporate Tax Liabilities to Individual Taxpayers’, 41(1) National Tax Journal, 37-59. Feldstein, Martin S. (1989), ‘Tax Policy for the 1990s: Personal Saving, Business Investment, and Corporate Debt’, 79 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 108-112. Feldstein, Martin S. (1995), ‘The Effects of Tax Based Saving Incentives on Government Revenue and National Saving’, 110(2) Quarterly Journal of Economics, 475-494. Feldstein, Martin S. and Frisch, Daniel, J. (1977a), ‘Corporate Tax Integration: the Estimated Effects on Capital Accumulation and Tax Distribution of Two Integration Proposals’, 30 National Tax Journal, 37 ff. Feldstein, Martin S. and Frisch, Daniel, J. (1977b), ‘Corporate Tax Integration: The Estimated Effects on Capital Accumulation and Tax Distribution of Two Integration Proposals’, 30(1) National Tax Journal, 37-52. Feldstein, Martin, S. and Frisch, Daniel, J. (1977c), ‘Corporate Tax Integration: A Quantitative Comparison of Alternatives Tax Foundation’, 28 Government Finance Brief. Feldstein, Martin, S. and Slemrod, Joel (1980), ‘Personal Taxation, Portfolio Choice, and the Effect of the Corporate Income Tax’, 21 Journal of Political Economy, 854-866. Feltenstein, Andrew and Shah, Anwar (1995), ‘General Equilibrium Effects of Investment Incentives in Mexico’, 46(2) Journal of Development Economics, 253-269. Feldstein, Martin S, Hines, James R., Jr and Hubbard, R. Glenn (eds) (1995), Taxing Multinational Corporations. Feltham, Glenn, D. and Paquette, Suzanne, M. (1996), To Pay or to Delay: an Economic Analysis of the Decision to Delay, and the Incidence of Delaying, the Payment of Corporate Income Tax.
204
Corporate Taxation
6060
Fisher (1985), ‘Corporate Tax Incentives: The American Version of Industrial Policy’, 19 Journal of Economic Issues, 9-12. Fisher, Peter S. (1985), ‘Corporate Tax Incentives: The American Version of Industrial Policy’, 19 Journal of Economic Issues, 1-19. Fitchew, Geoffrey (1989), The Single European Market and Tax Harmonisation. Flak, Henry (1965), A Study of the Methods of Shifting the Corporate Income Tax, Houston University. Flemming (1976), ‘A Reappraisal of the Corporation Income Tax’, 6 Journal of Public Economics, 163 ff. Fletcher, Douglas, R. (1994), ‘The International Argument for Corporate Tax Integration’, 11 American Jounal of Tax Policy, 156 ff. Frech, H. Edward III, Deacon, Rovert, Decanio, Stephen J. and Johnson, Bruce M. (1990), Taxing Energy: Oil Severence Taxation and the Economy, New York, Holmes and Meyer. Freeman, Louis, S. (1996), Tax Strategies for Corporate Acquisitions, Dispositions, Spin-offs, Joint Ventures, Financings, Reorganizations and Restructurings. Frisch, Daniel, J. (1990), ‘The Economics of International Tax Policy: Some Old and New Approaches’, 47 Tax Notes in Coffee, John, Lowenstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (eds), Knights, Raiders and Targets: The Impact of the Hostile Takeover, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 581 ff. From, Gary (ed.) (1971), Tax Incentives and Capital Spending. Froot, Kenneth A. and Hines, James R., Jr (1995), ‘Interest Allocation Rules, Financing Patterns, and the Operations of U.S. Multinationals’, in Feldstein, M., Hines, J.R., Jr and Hubbard, R.G. (eds), The Effects of Taxation on Multinational Corporations, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Frost, James Lyon (ed.) (1980), Corporate Tax and Wealth Redistribution Effects in Mergers and Acquisitions, MS Thesis, MIT, Alfred P. Sloan School of Management. Fujisaki, Tetsuya (ed.) (1987), Effect of 1986 Tax Reform on Corporate Mergers: MS Thesis, Massachusetts, Institute of Technology, Sloan School of Management. Fullerton, Don (1981), ‘Corporate Tax Integration in the United States: A General Equilibrium Approach’, 71 American Economic Review, 677-691. Fullerton, Don (1984), ‘Which Effective Tax Rate?’, 37 National Tax Journal, 23-41. Fullerton, Don (1987), ‘The Indexation of Interest, Depreciation, and Capital Gains and Tax Reform in the United States’, 32(1) Journal of Public Economics, 25-51. Fullerton, Don and Hamdan, Lawrence A. (1983), ‘The Aborted Phase in of Marginal Effective Corporate Tax Rates’, 11(4) Public Finance Quarterly, 437-464. Fullerton, Don and Rogers, Diane, Lim (eds) (1993), Rogers, Diane, Lim, Washington, DC, Brookings Institution. Fullerton, Don et al. (1981), ‘Corporate Tax Integration in the United States: A General Equilibrium Approach’, 71(4) American Economic Review, 677-691. Fullerton, Don, Gillete, Robert and Mackie, James B. (eds) (1987), Investment Incentives Under the Tax Reform Act of 1986. Funke, Michael and Hubbard, R. Glenn (1992), ‘Corporate Financial Policy, Taxation, and Macroeconomic Risk’, US Treasury. Funke, Michael and Willenbockel, Dirk (1996), ‘Das Jahressteuergesetz 1996 und die private Investitionstatigkeit’, 42 Ifo-Studien, 221-233.
6060
Corporate Taxation
205
Gabinet, Leon and Coffey, Ronald, J. (1977), ‘The Implications of the Economic Concept of Income for Corporation-Shareholder Income Tax Systems’, 27 Case Western Reserve Law Review, 895 ff. Gaffrey, Dennis, J. and Wheeler, James, E. (1977), ‘The Double Taxation of Corporate Source Income: Reality or Illusion?’, 8 Tax Advisor, 523 ff. Gammie, Malcolm (1991), ‘Corporate Tax Harmonization: an “ACE” Proposal’, 545 12 IBFD European Taxation. Gammie, Malcolm (1992), ‘The Harmonisation of Corporate Income Taxes in Europe: The Ruding Committee Report’, 13 Fiscal Studies, 108-121. Gammie, Malcolm (1997), ‘The Future of UK Corporation Tax’, in Head, G. and Krever, Richard (eds), Company Tax Systems, Australian Research Foundation, 207-270. Gammie, Malcolm and Robinson, Bill (1989), ‘Introduction: The Impact of the Single Market on EC Tax Systems’, in Coffee, John, Lowenstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (eds), Knights, Raiders and Targets: The Impact of the Hostile Takeover, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Gann, Pamela, B. (1985), ‘Neutral Taxation of Capital Income: An Achievable Goal?’, 48 Law and Contemporary Problems, 77 ff. Gendron, Pierre-Pascal (1996), ‘Corporate Tax Analysis in a Dominant Firm Model with Sunk Capital Investment’, 29 Canadian Journal of Economics, 298-302. Gentry, William M. (1994), ‘Taxes, Financial Decisions and Organization Form: Evidence from Publicly Traded Partnerships’, 53 Journal of Public Economics, 223-244. Gentry, William M. and Hubbard, R. Glenn (1997), ‘Fundamental Tax Reform and Corporate Financial Policy’, National Tax Association Proceedings. Gerardi, Geraldine, Greatz, Michael, J. and Rosen, Harvey S., ‘Corporate Integration Puzzles, US Dept of the Treasury’, 3 National Tax Journal, 307-314. Gergen, Mark P. (1997), ‘Subchapter K and Passive Financial Intermediation’, 51 Law Review, 37 ff. Gertler, Mark and Hubbard, R. Glenn (1990), ‘Taxation, Corporate Capital Structure, and Financial Distress’, Tax Policy and the Economy 4 in Coffee, John, Lowenstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (eds), Knights, Raiders and Targets: The Impact of the Hostile Takeover, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Gilson, Ronald J. (1991), ‘Unlimited Liability and Law Firm Organization: Tax Factors and the Direction of Causation’, 99 Journal of Political Economy, 420-425. Gilson, Ronald J. and Black, Bernard, S. (1995), The Law and Finance of Corporate Acquisitions. Gilson, Ronald J., Scholes, Myron S. and Wolfson, Mark, Alan, ‘Taxation and the Dynamics of Corporate Control: the Uncertain Case for Tax Motivated Acquisitions’, in Coffee, John, Lowenstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (eds), Knights, Raiders and Targets: The Impact of the Hostile Takeover, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Gilson, Stuart C., ‘Transactions Costs and Capital Structure Choice: Evidence from Financially Dostressed Firms’, Journal of Finance. Ginsburg, Martin, D. (1992), ‘Maintaining Subchapter S in an Integrated Tax World’, 47 Tax Law Review, 665-680. Ginsburg, Martin, D. and Mergers, Jack, Levin (eds) (1996), Acquisitions and Buyouts, Little, Brown and Company.
206
Corporate Taxation
6060
Givoly, Dan, Hayn, Carla, Ofer, Aharon, D. and Sarig, Oded (1992), ‘Taxes and Capital Structure: Evidence From Firms’ Response to The Tax Reform Act of 1986', 5 Review of Financial Studies, 331-355. Goldberg, Daniel, S. (1995), ‘The Tax Treatment of Limited Liability Companies: Law in Search of Policy’, 50 Business Lawyer. Goode, Richard (1946), ‘Postwar Corporate Tax Structure’, U.S. Treasury. Goode, Richard (1951), The Corporation Income Tax. Goode, Richard (1966), ‘Rates of Return, Income Shares, and Corporate Tax Incidence’, in Krzyzaniak, M. (ed.), Effects of Corporation Income Tax, Papers Presented at the Symposium on Business Taxation. Goode, Richard (1989), ‘Forward Shifting of the Corporate Tax in the Presence of Competing Imports: A Reply’, 44(2) Public Finance, 327-328. Goodman, Leonard and Miranti, Paul, J., Jr, A Bridge between Knowledge and Action: E. R. A.. Goodspeed, Timothy J. and Frisch, Daniel, J. (eds), ‘US Tax Policy and the Overseas Activities of US Multinational Corporations: A Quantitative Assessment’. Goolsbee, Austan, ‘Taxes, Organizational Form and the Deadweight Loss of the Corporate Income Tax’, Journal of Public Economics. Gordon, R.J. (1967), ‘The Incidence of the Corporation Tax in U.S. Manufacturing’, 57 American Economic Review, 731-758. Gordon, Robert J. (1970), ‘Specification Bias and Corporate Tax Incidence’, 23(4) National Tax Journal, 373-378. Gordon, Roger H., ‘Taxation of Corporate Capital Income: Tax Revenues Versus Tax Distortions’, 53 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 223-244. Gordon, Roger H., ‘Taxation of Investment and Savings in a World Economy’, 76 American Economic Review, 1086-1102. Gordon, Roger H. (ed.) (1981), ‘Uncertainty and the Analysis of Corporate Tax Distortions’, Proceedings of the 74th Annual Conference. Gordon, Roger H. (1984), ‘Inflation, Taxation and Corporate Behavior’, 99 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 313 ff. Gordon, Roger H. and Bradford, David F. (1980), ‘Taxes and Capital Structure: Evidence From Firms’ Response to The Tax Reform Act of 1986’, 14 Journal of Public Economics, 109-136. Gordon, Roger H. and Jun, Joosung (1993), ‘Taxes and the Form of Ownership of Foreign Corporate Equity’, in Giovannini, A., Hubbard, R.G. and Slemrod, J. (eds), Studies in International Taxation, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 13-44. Gordon, Roger H. and Levinsohn, James (1990), ‘The Linkage Between Domestic Taxes and Border Taxes’, in Razin and Slemrod (eds), Taxation in the Global Economy, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Gordon, Roger H. and MacKie Mason, Jeffrey K. (1990), ‘Effects of the Tax Reform Act of 1986 on Corporate Financial Policy and Organizational Form’, in Slemrod, J. (ed.), Do Taxes Matter?, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 91-131. Gordon, Roger H. and MacKie Mason, Jeffrey K. (1994), ‘Tax Distortions to the Choice of Organization Form’, 55 Journal of Public Economics, 279-306. Gordon, Roger H. and MacKie Mason, Jeffrey K. (1995), ‘Why is There Corporate Taxation in a Small Open Economy? The Role of Transfer Pricing and Income Shifting’, in Feldstein, M.,
6060
Corporate Taxation
207
Hines, J.R., Jr and Hubbard, R.G. (eds), , The Effects of Taxation on Multinational Corporations, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 67-94. Gordon, Roger H. and Malkiel, Burton, G., ‘Corporation Finance’, in Aaron, Henry and Pechman, Joseph (eds), How Taxes Affect Economic Behavior, Washington, DC, Brookings Institution.. Gordon, Roger H. and Slemrod, Joel (1998), Are ‘Real’ Responses to Taxes Simply Income Shifting between Corporate and Personal Tax Bases?, Office of Tax Research, University of Michigan Business School, 98-9. Gordon, Roger H. and Wilson, John D. (1986), ‘An Examination of Multijurisdictional Corporate Income Taxation Under Formula Apportionment’, Econometrica, 1357-1373. Gordon, Roger H. and Wilson, John Douglas (1989), ‘Measuring the Efficiency Cost of Taxing Risky Capital Income’, 79 American Economic Review, 427-439. Goudie, A.W. (1984), ‘Tax Exhaustion: Estimates from a Disaggregate Model of Corporate Tax Liabilities’, 16(2) Applied Economics, 205-224. Goulder, Lawrence H. and Summers, Lawrence H. (1989), ‘Tax Policy, Asset Prices, and Growth: A General Equilibrium Analysis’, 38(3) Journal of Public Economics, 265-296. Gourevitch, Harry, G. (1977), ‘Corporate Tax Integration: The European Experience’, 31 Tax Lawyer, 65 ff. Gourevitch, Harry, G. (1978), ‘Corporate Tax Integration: The European Experience’, 31 Tax Lawyer, 65 ff. Gradus, Raymond and de Zeeuw, Aart (1989), Corporate Tax Rate Policy and Public and Private Employment, Discussion paper, Center for Economic Research, Tilburg University. Graetz, Michael J. (1989), ‘The Tax Aspects of Leveraged Buyouts and Other Corporate Financial Restructuring Transactions’, 42 Tax Notes, 721 ff. Graetz, Michael J. and O’Hear, Michael, M. (1997), ‘The”Original Intent” of U.S. International Taxation’, 46 Duke Law Journal, 1021 ff. Graham, John, R. (1996a), ‘Debt and the Marginal Tax Rate’, Journal of Financial Economics. Graham, John, R. (1996b), ‘Proxies for the Corporate Marginal Tax Rate’, 42 Journal of Financial Economics, 187-221. Gravelle, Jane G. (1979), ‘Differential Taxation of Capital Income: Another Look at the 1986 Tax Reform Act’, 42 National Tax Journal, 441-463. Gravelle, Jane G. (1981), ‘The Social Cost of Non-Neutral Taxation: Estimates from Nonresidential Capital’, in Hulten, Charles R (ed.), Depreciation, Inflation, and the Taxation of Income from Capital, Washington, Urban Institute. Gravelle, Jane G. (1982), Safe Harbor Leasing under the Economic Recovery Tax Act of 1981 and Investment Efficiency. Gravelle, Jane G. (1995), ‘The Corporate Income Tax: Economic Issues and Policy Options’, 48 National Tax Journal, 267-277. Gravelle, Jane G. (ed.) (1991), Corporate Tax Integration: Issues and Options, Washington, DC, Congressional Research Service, Library of Congress. Gravelle, Jane G. (ed.) (1994), The Economic Effects of Taxing Capital Income, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.
208
Corporate Taxation
6060
Gravelle, Jane G. and Esenwein, Gregg, A. (1983), ‘The Measurement and Interpretation of Effective Corporate Tax Rates: A Comment’, Tax Notes, 867-872. Gravelle, Jane G. and Kotlikoff, Laurence J. (1988), ‘Does the Harberger Model Greatly Understate the Excess Burden of the Corporate Tax?: Another Model Says Yes’. Gravelle, Jane G. and Kotlikoff, Laurence J. (1989), ‘The Incidence and Efficiency Costs of Corporate Taxation when Corporate and Noncorporate Firms Produce the Same Good’, 97 Journal of Political Economy, 749-780. Gravelle, Jane G. and Kotlikoff, Laurence J. (1993), ‘Corporate Tax Incidence and Inefficiency when Corporate and Noncorporate Goods Are Close Substitutes’, 31(4) Economic Inquiry, 501-516. Gravelle, Jane G. and Kotlikoff, Laurence J. (1995), ‘Corporate Taxation and the Efficiency Gains of the 1986 Tax Reform Act’, 6 Economic Theory, 51-81. Green, Richard C. and Talmor, Eli (1985), ‘The Structure and Incentive Effects of Corporate Tax Liabilities’, 40(4) Journal of Finance, 1095-1114. Green, Robert, A. (1993), ‘The Future of Source-Based Taxation of the Income of Multinational Enterprises’, 79 Cornell Law Review, 67-70. Grier, Paul and Strebel, Paul (1980), ‘The Empirical Relationship between Taxation and Capital Structure’, 15 Financial Review, 45-57. Griffith, Thomas, D. (1983), ‘Integration of the Corporate and Personal Income Taxes and the ALI Proposal’, 23 Santa Clara Law Review, 715 ff. Gropp, Reint, E. (ed.) (1994), Corporate Taxation and Capital Structure Choice in the U.S. and Germany, Wisconsin University. Gropp, Reint, E. (1995), ‘Corporate Taxation and Capital Structure Choice in Germany: A General Equilibrium Model’, 52 Finanzarchiv, 196-121. Grubert, Harry and Mutti, John H. (eds) (1987), ‘The Impact of the Tax Reform Act of 1986 on Trade and Capital Flows’. Grubert, Harry and Mutti, John H. (1991), ‘Taxes, Tariffs and Transfer Pricing in Multinational Corporate Decision Making’, 73 Review of Economics and Statistics, 285-293. Grubert, Harry and Mutti, John H. (1994), ‘International Aspects of Corporate Tax Integration: The Contrasting Role of Debt and Equity Flows’, 47(1) National Tax Journal, 111-133. Grubert, Harry, Goodspeed, Timothy J. and Swenson, Deborah (1991), Explaining the Low Taxable Income of Foreign-controlled Companies in the United States. Guenther, David, A. (1992), ‘Taxes and Organizational Form: A Comparison of Corporations and Master Limited Partnerships, UCT’, 67 Accounting Review, 17-45. Gulley, O. David and Santerre, Rexford E. (1993), ‘The Effect of Tax Exemption on the Market Share of Nonprofit Hospitals’, 46(4) National Tax Journal, 477-486. Hadjina, Branko and Sever, Ivo (1995), ‘Ucinci Upravljanja Porezom Poduzeca s Posebnim Osvrtom na Mala i Srednja Poduzeca. (Effects of Company Taxation — With Special Regard to SMEs. With English summary.)’, 13 Zbornik Radova Ekonomskog Fakulteta Rijeka, 479-496. Hall, Mark A. and Columbo, John D. (1991), ‘The Charitable Status of Nonprofit Hospitals: Toward a Donative Theory of Tax Exemption’, 66 Washington Law Review, 307-411. Hall, Robert E. (1991), ‘Dividends, Capital Gains, and the Corporate Veil: Evidence from Britain, Canada, and the United States: Comment’, in Bernheim, B. Douglas and Shoven, John B. (eds), National Saving and Economic Performance, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 71-73.
6060
Corporate Taxation
209
Halpem, Paul and Mintz, Jack M. (1992), ‘Taxation and Its Impact on Market Structure’, in Bird, R.M. and Mintz, J.M. (eds), Taxation to 2000 and Beyond. Canadian Tax Paper, Toronto, Canadian Tax Foundation, 214-256. Halperin, Daniel I. (1992), ‘Commentary, Will Integration Increase Efficiency? The Old and New View of Dividend Policy’, 47 Tax Law Review, 645 ff. Hamill, Susan, Pace (1995), ‘The Taxation of Domestic Limited Liability Companies And Limited Partnerships: a Case For Eliminating The Partnership Classification Regulations’, 73 Washington United Law Quaterly, 565 ff. Hamill, Susan, Pace (1996), ‘The Limited Liability Company: A Catalyst Exposing the Corporate Integration Question’, 95 Michigan Law Review, 393 ff. Hamilton, Bob, Shah, Anwar and Whalley, John (eds) (1986), A Dynamic General Equilibrium Model for Corporate Tax Policy Evaluation in Canada, Canada, Dept. of Finance. Hammer, Richard, M. (1975), ‘The Taxation of Income from Corporate Shareholders: Review of Present Systems in Canada, France, Germany, Japan and the UK’, 28 National Tax Journal, 315 ff. Hammer, Richard, M. (1979), ‘Corporate/Shareholder Tax Integration’, 33 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 290-292. Han, Kim E., ‘Optimal Capital Structure in Miller’s Equilibrium’, in Bhattacharya, S. and Constandtinides, G.M. (eds), Financial Markets and Incomplete Information. Han, Kim E. (1978), ‘A Mean-variance Theory of Optimal Captial Structure and Corporate Debt Capacity’, 33 Journal of Finance, 45-63. Haney, James, R. (1977), ‘Integration of the Corporate and Individual Income Taxes’, 3 National Tax Journal, 345-358. Haney, James, R. (1979), ‘Integration of Corporate and Individual Income Taxes’, 33 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 298-305. Hanka, Gordon, The External Effects of Debt: A Back to Basics Evaluation of the Tax Incentive for Leverage. Hansmann, Henry (1981), ‘The Rationale for Exempting Nonprofit Organizations from Corporate Income Taxation’, 91 Yale Law Journal, 54 ff. Harberger, Arnold, C. (1962), ‘The Incidence of the Corporation Income Tax’, 70 Journal of Political Economy, 215-240. Reprinted in Harberger, Arnold C. (1974), Taxation and Welfare, 135-62. Harberger, Arnold, C. (1966), ‘Efficiency Effects of Taxes on Income from Capital’, in Krzyzaniak, Marian (ed.), Effects of the Corporation Tax, Detroit, Wayne State University Press. Reprinted in Harberg, Arnold C; (ed.) (1974), Taxation and Welfare 162-184. Harberger, Arnold, C. (1980), ‘Vignettes on the World Capital Market’, 70 American Economic Review, 331 ff. Harberger, Arnold, C. (1983), ‘The State of the Corporate Income Tax: Who Pays? Should it be Repealed?’, in Walker, Charles E. and Bloomfield, Mark A. (eds), New Directions in Federal Tax Policy for the 1980's, Cambridge, Ballinger Publishing Company.
210
Corporate Taxation
6060
Harberger, Arnold, C. (ed.) (1959), The Corporation Income Tax: An Empirical Appraisal, U.S. Congress House, Committee on Ways and Means, Tax Revision Compendium. Hardman, Ann Louise (1992), ‘Corporate Tax Reform: The Key to International Competitiveness’, 25 Vanderbilt Journal of Transnational Law, 509 ff. Harris, David, G., ‘The Impact of US Law Revision on Multinational Corporation Decision Making’, 31 Journal of Accounting Research, 111-140. Harris, David, Morck, Randall, Slemrod, Joel and Yeung, Bernard (1993), ‘Incoming Shifting in U.S. Multinational Corporations’, 277-302. Harris, M. and Raviv, Artur (1991), ‘The Theory of Optinal Capital Structure’, 48 Journal of Finance, 297-356. Harris, Peter, A. (1994), ‘Passing Corporate Foreign Tax Credits to Shareholders: Lessons from the UK’s FID Scheme, Supreme Court of Queensland and of England & Wales’, 11 Australian Tax Forum, 229-246. Harris, Peter, A. (ed.) (1996), Corporate/Shareholder Income Taxation and Allocating Taxinng Rights Between Countries: A Comparison of Imputation Systems, Amsterdam, IBFD. Harris, Richard A., Franks, Julian and Mayer, Colin (1987), Means of Payment in Takeovers: The Results for the U.K. and U.S., National Bureau of Economic Research, Inc., 2456. Hart, Kenneth, D. (ed.) (1987), ‘Research and Development Impacts of Corporate Income Tax Reform: A Manuscript Report’. Hartman, David, G. (1985), ‘Tax Policy and Foreign Direct Investment’, 26 Journal of Public Economics, 107-121. Haskins, Matthew, P. (1995), ‘The Theory and Politics of Tax Integration’, 67 Tax Notes, 401 ff. Hayn, Carla (1989), ‘Tax Attributes as Determinants of Shareholder Gains in Corporate Acquisitions’, 23 Journal of Financial Economics, 121 ff. Head, John G. (1997), ‘Company Tax Structure and Company Tax Incidence’, 4 International Tax and Public Finance, 61-100. "Company Tax Systems: From Theory to Policy" in Head, John G. and Krever, Richard (eds), Company Tax Systems, Australian Research Foundation, Conference Series No. 18 (1997) Head, John G. and Krever, Richard (eds) (1997), Company Tax Systems, Australian Research Foundation, 18. Heaton, Hal (1986), ‘The Relative Yields on Taxable and Tax Exempt Debt’, 18(4) Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 482-494. Heaton, Hal (1987), ‘On the Bias of the Corporate Tax against High Risk Projects’, 22(3) Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 365-371. Hein, Scott E., Koch, Timothy W. and MacDonald, S. Scott (1995), ‘The Changing Role of Commercial Banks in the Municipal Securities Market’, 27(3) Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 894-906. Hellerstein, Jerome R. (1957), ‘Mergers, Taxes and Realism’, 71 Harvard Law Review. Hellerstein, Jerome R. (1959), ‘Judicial Review of Property Tax Assessments’, 14 Tax Law Review, 327-352. Hellerstein, Walter (1980), ‘State Income Taxation of Multijurisdictional Corporations: Reflections on Mobil, Exxon, and H.R.’, 113 Michigan Law Review, 160 ff.
6060
Corporate Taxation
211
Hendershott, Patric H. (1991), ‘The Long-Run Impact on Federal Tax Revenues and Capital Allocation of a Cut in the Capital Gains Tax Rate’, 19(1) Public Finance Quarterly, 3-21. Hendershott, Patric H., Toder, H. and Won Yunhi (1991), ‘Effects of Capital Gains Taxes on Revenue and Economic Efficiency’, 44(1) National Tax Journal, 21-40. Hershberg, Susan (1979), ‘Consolidated Returns: A Tax Policy Perspective’, 27 Canadian Tax Journal, 552 ff. Hicks, Samuel, Alton, The Effect of Corporate Tax Incentives on the Horizontal Equity. Higgins, Mark, Marthew (ed.) (1989), An Empirical Analysis of the Relationship Between Corporate Effective Tax Rates and Book Effective Tax Rates with an Analysis of the Financial Characteristics That Influence Corporate Effective Tax Rates. Higson, C. and Eliot, J. (1994), ‘The Incentive to Locate a Multinational Firm: The Effect of Tax Reforms in the United Kingdom’, 1 International Tax and Public Finance, 81-97. Hines, James R., Jr (1994), ‘Credit and Deferral as International Investment Incentives’, 2 Journal of Public Economics, 323-347. Hines, James R., Jr (1996), ‘Altered States: Taxes and the Location of Foreign Direct Investment in America’, 86 American Economic Review, 1076-1094. Hines, James R., Jr (1997), ‘Tax Policy and the Activities of Multinational Corporations’, in Auerbach, Alan (ed.), Fiscal Policy, MIT Press. Hines, James R., Jr and Hubbard, R. Glenn (1990), ‘Coming Home to America: Dividend Repatriations by U.S. Multinationals’, in Razin and Slemrod (eds), Taxation in the Global Economy, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 161-207. Hobbes, Patrick, E. (1995), ‘Entity Classification: The One Hundred-year Debate’, 44 Catholic University Law Review, 437 ff. Hodder, James E. and Senbet, Lemma W. (1990), ‘International Capital Structure Equilibrium’, 45(5) Journal of Finance, 1495-1516. Holland, Daniel, M. (1975), ‘Some Observations on Full Integration’, 28 National Tax Journal, 353 ff. Hong, Lee Fook (1989), ‘1989 Budget: Pro business or Pro family? Singapore’, 43(6) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 283-285. Hong, Lee Fook (1990), ‘1900: Celebration Budget for a Maturing Nation: Singapore’, 44(6) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 273-276. Hong, Lee Fook (1991), ‘Singapore’s 1991 Budget: A Successful Nation’s Budget’, 45(5) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 211-213. Hong, Lee Fook (1992), ‘1992 Budget: A Carry on Budget with a Few Surprises: Singapore’, 46(5) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 254-256. Horst, Thomas, ‘A Note on Optimal Raxation of International Investment Income Quarterly’, 94 Journal of Economics, 793-799. Horst, Thomas (1982), ‘Some Issues in the Calculation and Uses of Effective Corporate Income Tax Rates’, Tax Notes, 347-351. Howitt, Peter and Sinn, Hans-Werner (1989), ‘Gradual Reforms of Capital Income Taxation’, 79 American Economic Review, 106-124. Hreha, Karen, S. and Silhan, Peter, A. (1986), ‘An Empirical Analysis of Unitary Apportionment’, Journal of the American Taxation Association, 7-18.
212
Corporate Taxation
6060
Hubbard, Jeff and Michaely, Roni (1997), ‘Do Investors Ignore Dividend Taxation? A Reexamination of the Citizens Utilities Case’, 32 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 117-135. Hubbard, R. Glenn (1990), Asymmetric Information, Corporate Finance and Investment, Chicago. Hubbard, R. Glenn (1993), ‘Corporate Tax Integration: A View from the Treasury Department’, 7(1) Journal of Economic Perspectives, 115-132. Hubbard, R. Glenn and Reiss, Peter C. (1989), ‘Corporate Payouts and the Tax Price of Corporate Retentions: Evidence from the Undistributed Profits Tax of 1936-1938'. Huber, Bernd (1994), ‘Dividend Taxes and Investment’, 51 Finanzarchiv, 457-471. Hufbauer, Gary, C. (ed.) (1992), U.S. Taxation of International Income. Huizinga, Harry (1992), ‘The Tax Treatment of R&D; Expenditures of Multinational Enterprises’, 47(3) Journal of Public Economics, 343-359. Hulten, Charles R. and Robertson, James, W. (1982), Corporate Tax Policy and Economic Growth: An Analysis of the 1981 and 1982 Tax Acts, Washington, DC, Urban Institute. Institute For Fiscal Studies (1991), Equity for Companies: A Corporation Tax for the 1990s, Fourth Report of the IFS Capital Taxes Group, 26. International Fiscal Association (1987), ‘The Fiscal Residence of Companies: La Residence Fiscale Des Societes: Die Steuerliche Ansassigkeit von Kapitalgesellschaften: La Residencia Fiscal De Las Sociedades’, in Cahiers de Droit Fiscal International. International Fiscal Association (1987), Tax Problems of the Liquidation of Corporations: Regime de liquidation des societes: Steuerliche Probleme der Liquidation von Korperschaften: Problemas fiscales de la liquidacion de sociedades. International Fiscal Association (1992), ‘Tax Consequences of International Acquisitions and Business Combinations - Consequences fiscales des acquisitions et regroupements internationaux d’entreprises’, in Cahiers de Droit Fiscal International. International Fiscal Association (1992), ‘Transfer Pricing in the Absence of Comparable Market Prices - Determination des prix de transfert en l’absence de prix de marche camparables’, in Cahiers de Droit Fiscal International. International Fiscal Association (1993), ‘Corporate Tax on Distributions (Equalization Tax)’, Proceedings of the 47th Congress of the International Fiscal Association. International Fiscal Association (ed.) (1993), ‘Interpretation of Double Taxation Conventions’, 78a in Cahiers de Droit Fiscal International. Iqbal, Mahmood (1994), ‘A Corporate Tax Comparison for Canada, the United States and Mexico’, 3(1) Canadian Business Economics, 54-64. Isaac, John (1989), ‘Corporate Tax Harmonisation’, in Gammie, Malcolm, Robinson, Bill and Fitchew Geoffrey, Beyond 1992: A European Tax System: Proceedings of the Fourth Institute for Fiscal Studies Residential Conference, Oxford. Isaac, John (1997), ‘A Comment on the Viability of the Allowance for Corporate Equity’, 18 Fiscal Studies, 303-318. Isard, Peter (1990), ‘Corporate Tax Harmonization and European Monetary Integration’, 43(1) Kyklos, 3-24. Isenbergh, Joseph (1988), ‘Perspectives on the Deferral of United States Taxation of the Earnings of Foreign Corporations’, Taxes, 1062 ff.
6060
Corporate Taxation
213
Iwamoto, Yasushi (1992), ‘Effective Tax Rates and Tobin’s q’, 48 Journal of Public Economics, 225-237. Jaffe, Jeffrey F. (1978a), ‘Corporate Taxes, Inflation, the Rate of Interest, and the Return to Equity’, 13 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 55-64. Jaffe, Jeffrey F. (1978b), ‘A Note on Taxation and Investment’, 33 Journal of Finance, 1439-1445. Jaffe, Jeffrey F. (1991), ‘Taxes and the Capital Structure of Partnerships, REIT’s, and Related Entities’, 46 Journal of Finance, 401-407. Jaffe, Jeffrey F. and Westerfield, Randolph (1984), ‘Leverage and the Value of a Firm under a Progressive Income Tax: A Correction and Extension’, 8 Journal of Banking and Finance, 491-494. Janeba, Eckhard (1995), ‘Corporate Income Tax Competition, Double Taxation Treaties, and Foreign Direct Investment’, 56(2) Journal of Public Economics, 311-325. Janeba, Eckhard (ed.), Corporate Income Tax Competition, Double Taxation Treaties, and Foreign Direct Investment, Department of Economics, University of Bonn, A-36.1. Jassy, B. (1974), ‘Treatment of Bootstrap Stock Acquisitions: The Redemption Route vs. Dividend Route’, 87 Harvard Law Review, 1459 ff. Jeffcote, Bernard (ed.) (1993), The Developing European Corporate Tax System. Jensen, Michael C. (1986), ‘Agency Costs of Free Cash Flow, Corporate Finance, and Takeovers’, 32 American Economic Review, 323 ff. Jensen, Michael C. (1988), ‘The Takeover Controversy: Analysis and Evidence’, in Coffee, John, Lowenstein, Louis and Rose-Ackerman, Susan (eds), Knights, Raiders and Targets: The Impact of the Hostile Takeover, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Jensen, Michael C. and Meckling, W. (1976), ‘Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behavior, Agency Costs and Ownership Structures’, 3 Journal of Financial Economics, 305-360. Jensen, Michael C., Kaplan, Steven, N. and Stiglin, Laura (1989), ‘The Effects of LBOs on Tax Revenues of the U.S. Treasury’, 42 Tax Notes, 727 ff. Jensen, Ronald, H. (1991), ‘Of Form and Substance: Tax Free Incorporations and Other Transactions Under Section 351’, 11 Virginia Tax Review, 349 ff. Jones, David D. (1979), ‘Corporations, Double Taxation and the Theory of Integration’, 27 Canadian Tax Journal, 405 ff. Jones, Robert (1991), ‘The Effective Taxation of Australian Corporate Source Income’, in Hamilton, Clive (ed.), The Economic Dynamics of Australian Industry, Sydney, Allen and Unwin, distributed by Paull, Concord, Mass., 196-215. Jones, Shirley, A. (1994), ‘The Evolution of the Corporate Minimum Tax’, 20 Journal of Corporate Taxation, 351 ff. Jun, Joosung (1995), The Impact of International Tax Rules on the Cost of Capital. Kalambokidis, Laura (ed.) (1992), What Is Being Taxed?: A Test for the Existence of Excess Profit in the Corporate Income Tax Base, University of Michigan. Kale, Jayant R. and Noe, Thomas H. (1990), ‘Corporate Hedging under Personal and Corporate Taxation’, 11(3) Managerial and Decision Economics, 199-205. Kale, Jayant R. and Noe, Thomas H. (1992), ‘Taxes, Financial Distress, and Corporate Capital Structure’, 32(1) Quarterly Review of Economics and Finance, 71-83.
214
Corporate Taxation
6060
Kale, Jayant R., Noe, Thomas H. and Ramirez, Gabriel G. (1991), ‘The Effect of Business Risk on Corporate Capital Structure: Theory and Evidence’, 46(5) Journal of Finance, 1693-1715. Kanda, Hideki and Levmore, Saul (1991), ‘Taxes, Agency Costs, and the Price of Incorporation’, 77 Virginia Law Review, 211-256. Kanniainen, Vesa and Sodersten, Jan (1994), ‘Costs of Monitoring and Corporate Taxation’, 55 Journal of Public Economics, 307-321. Kanniainen, Vesa and Sodersten, Jan (1995), ‘The Importance of Reporting Conventions for the Theory of Corporate Taxation’, 57 Journal of Public Economics, 417-430. Kaplan, Steven E. (1989), ‘Management Buyouts: Evidence on Taxes as a Source of Value’, 44 Journal of Finance, 611-632. Karier, Thomas (1991), ‘A Proposal to Restore the Corporate Profit Tax’, 49(2) Review of Social Economy, 141-167. Kassanen, Eero (1992), Sensitivity of Dividend Decisions to Corporate Tax Reform: Empirical Test with Aggregate Data of Finnish Firms, Felsingin Kauppakorkoulu, 1235-5674. Keen, Michael (1993), ‘Corporation Tax, Foreign Direct Investment and the Single Market in European Integration’, in Winters, L., Venables, Alan and Anthony J (eds), Trade and Industry, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 165-198. Keen, Michael and Shiantarelli, Fabio (eds) (1991), ‘Corporation Tax Asymmetries and Optimal Financial Policy’, 43 Oxford Economic Papers, 280-291. Keller, Robert R. (1985), ‘The Tax Effects of a Shareholder’s Post-Incorporation Sale of Stock: A Reappraisal’, 2 Tax Law Journal, 107-111. Kiefer, Donald W. (1973), ‘The 1973 Tax Package: Corporate Tax Restructuring’, 48 Indiana Business Review, 1-2. Kiefer, Donald W. (1990), ‘Lock-In Effect Within a Simple Model of Corporate Stock Trading’, 53 National Tax Journal. Kimbrough, Kent P. (1984), ‘The Corporation Income Tax in the Open Economy’, 25 International Economic Review, 391-407. King, Mervyn A. (1971), ‘Corporate Taxation and Dividend Behavior: A Comment’, Review of Economic Studies, 377 ff. King, Mervyn A. (1972), ‘Corporate Taxation and Dividend Behavior: a Further Comment’, 39 Review of Economic Studies, 231 ff. King, Mervyn A. (1974a), ‘Dividend Behavior and the Theory of the Firm’, 41 Economica, 25-34. King, Mervyn A. (1974b), ‘Taxation and the Cost of Capital’, 41 Review of Economic Studies, 21-35. King, Mervyn A. (1975), ‘Taxation, Corporate Financial Policy, and the Cost of Capital: A Comment’, 4 Journal of Public Economics, 271 ff. King, Mervyn A. (ed.) (1977), Public Policy and the Corporation, London, Chapman and Hall. King, Mervyn A. (1987), ‘The Cash Flow Corporate Income Tax’, in Feldstein, M. (ed.), The Effects of Taxation on Capital Accumulation, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. King, Mervyn A. and Fullerton, David J. (eds) (1984), The Taxation of Income from Capital: A Comparative Study of the US, UK, Sweden, and West Germany, Chicago.
6060
Corporate Taxation
215
Kingson, Charles I. (1976), ‘The Deep Structure of Taxation: Dividend Distributions’, 85 Yale Law Journal, 861 ff. Kingson, Charles I. (1991), ‘The Foreign Tax Credit and its Critics’, 9 American Jounal of Tax Policy, 1 ff. Klassen, Kenneth, Lang, Mark and Wolfson, Alan (1993), ‘Geographic Income Shifting by Multinational Corporations in Response to Tax Rate Changes’, Journal of Accounting Research, 141-173. Klein (1972), ‘Income Taxation and Legal Entities’, 20 UCLA Law Review, 13 ff. Klein, William A. (1965), ‘The Incidence of the Corporation Income Tax: A Lawyer’s View of a Problem in Economics’, Wisconsin Law Review, 576 ff. Klein, William A. and Zolt, Eric M. (1995), ‘Business Form, Limited Liability, and Tax Regimes: Lurching Toward a Coherent Outcome’, 66 UCLA Law Review, 1001-1041. Knauer, Nancy J. (1994), ‘The Paradox of Corporate Giving: Tax Expenditures, the Nature of the Corporation, and the Social Construction of Charity’, 44 DePaul Law Review, 1 ff. Knoll, Michael S. (1993), ‘Taxing Prometheus: How the Corporate Interest Deduction Discourages Innovation and Risk-taking’, 38 Villanova Law Review, 1461 ff. Knoll, Michael S. (1996), ‘An Accretion Corporate Income Tax’, 49 Stanford Law Review, 1 ff. Konrad, Kai A. (1991), ‘The Decision to Go Public, Accrued Capital Gains and Taxation’, 37 Economics Letters, 439-445. Kopcke, Richard W. and Rosengren, Eric S. (1989), ‘Are the Distinctions Between Debt and Equity Disappearing?: An Overview’. Kopcke, Richard W. and Rosengren, Eric S. (eds) (1989), ‘Regulation of debt and equity’, Proceedings of a conference held at Melvin Village, New Hampshire. Kornhauser, Marjorie E. (1990), ‘Corporate Regulation and the Origins of the Corporate Income Tax’, 66 Industrial Law Journal, 53 ff. Kose John and Senbet, Lemma W. (1989), Limited Liability, Tax Deductibility of Corporate Debt, and Public Policy, Salomon Brothers Center for the Study of Financial Institutions, 544. Kose, John (1987), ‘Risk-Shifting Incentives and Signaling Through Corporate Capital Structure’, 42 Journal of Finance, 623 ff. Kose, John and Williams, Joseph (1985), ‘Dividends, Dilution and Taxes: A Signalling Equilibrium’, 40 Journal of Finance, 1053-1070. Kose, John, Teresa, A. and Ronen, Joshua (1996), ‘Corporate Taxes, Choice among Accounting Alternatives, and Information Content of Earnings’, 11 Journal of Accounting, Auditing and Finance, 163-183. Kose, John, Senbet, Lemma W. and Sundaram, Anant (1994), ‘Corporate Limited Liability and the Design of Corporate Taxation’. Krause-Junk, Gerold (1988), ‘Uberlegungen zu einem Kunftigen Europaischen Korperschaftsteuersystem’, 34 Konjunkturpolitik, 268-290. Krueger, LaVern Eldon (ed.) (1974), The Value Added Tax Compared to the Corporate Income Tax: Effects on Capital Formation, Colorado, Coen Lecture, University Of Colorado Law School.. Krzyzaniak, Marian (ed.) (1966), Effects of the Corporation Income Tax, Wayne State University.
216
Corporate Taxation
6060
Krzyzaniak, Marian and Musgrave, Richard A. (eds) (1963), The Shifting of the Corporation Income Tax, Baltimore, MD, John Hopkins University Press. Kurtz, Jerome (1992), ‘The Limited Liability Company and the Future of Business Taxation: A Comment on Professor Berger’s Plan’, 47 Tax Law Review, 815 ff. Kwall, Jeffrey L. (1990), ‘The Uncertain Case Against the Double Taxation of Corporate Income’, 68 Law Review, 613 ff. Kwall, Jeffrey L. (1997), ‘Taxing Private Enterprise in the New Millenium’, 51 Tax Lawyer, 229 ff. Kweit, Catherine and Rubin, Marilyn M. (1982), ‘Impact of the Economic Recovery Tax Act on State and Local Revenues: A Case Study of New York City Corporate Tax Revenues’, 35(3) National Tax Journal, 295-306. Lakonishok, Josef and Baruch, Lev (1987), ‘Stock Splits and Stock Dividends: Why, Who, and When’, 42 Journal of Finance, 913 ff. Lall, Vinay D. (1983), Fiscal Incentives and Corporate Tax Saving, New Dehli, National Institute of Public Finance and Policy. Lall, Vinay D. (ed.) (1984), Economic Effects of the Corporate Profits Tax, New Dehli, National Institute of Public Finance and Policy. Lamoureux, Christopher G. and Poon, Percy (1987), ‘The Market Reaction to Stock Splits’, 42 Journal of Finance, 1347 ff. Lander, Joel Martin (1989), Optimal Taxation Policies Which Affect Capital Structure, Law and Economics Workshop, UCLA Economics Dept.. Lander, Joel Martin (ed.) (1990), Essays on the Corporate Tax Policy Effects on Investments and Financing Choices, UCLA. Langbein, Stanley I. (1986), ‘The Unitary Method and the Myth of Arm’s Length’, 30 Tax Notes, 625 ff. Lapidoth, Arye (1990), ‘The 1990 Israeli Tax Reform: Israel’, 44(12) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 609-610. Laramie, Anthony J., The Incidence of the Corporate Profits Tax Revisited: A Post Keynesian Approach, Bard College, Jerome Levy Economics Institute, 109. Laumas, G.S. (1971), ‘The Effectiveness of Corporate Tax Increases as an Anti inflationary Policy’, 30(4) American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 397-402. Leauby, Bruce Alan (ed.) (1990), Determinants of Corporate Tax Avoidance Strategy: an Empirical Analysis, Drexel University. LeClere, Marc J. (1993), ‘Commonality among Alternative Measures of Corporate Effective Tax Rates’, in Stern, Jerrold J. (ed.), Advances in Taxation. Volume 4, Greenwich, CT, JAI Press, 175-195. Lee, Dwight R. (ed.) (1986), Taxation and the Deficit Economy: Fiscal Policy and Capital Formation in the United States, - San Francisco, Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy, 554 p. Lee, John W. (1988), ‘Entity Classification and Integration: Publicly Traded Partnerships, Personal Service Corporations, and the Tax Legislative Process’, 8 Virginia. Tax Review, 57 ff. Leechor, Chad and Mintz, Jack M. (1993), ‘On the Taxation of Multinational Corporate Investment When the Deferral Method is Used by the Capital Exporting Country’, 51(1) Journal of Public Economics, 75-96. Lehn, Kenneth and Poulsen, Annette B. (1987), Sources of Value in Leveraged Buyouts.
6060
Corporate Taxation
217
Lenhardt, Ingrid Lynn (1996), ‘Limited Liability Companies: The Corporate and Tax Advantages of a Limited Liability Company: A German Perspective’, 64 University of Cincinatti Law Review, 551 ff. Lent, George E. (1948), The Impact of the Undistributed Porfits Tax, Columbia University Press, 1936-1937. Levinsohn, James and Slemrod, Joel (1993), ‘Taxes, Tariffs, and the Global Corporation’, 97 Journal of Public Economics, 116 ff. Levis, Mario (1986), ‘The 1984 Budget: The Impact on Corporate Tax Payments’, 0(0) National Westminster Bank Quarterly Review, 28-42. Levmore, Saul (1982), ‘Identifying Section 306 Stock: The Sleeping Beauty of Revenue Ruling 66-332', 2 Virginia Tax Review, 59-78. Levmore, Saul (1987), ‘The Positive Role of Tax Law in Corporate and Capital Markets’, 12 Journal of Corporation Law, 483-502. Levmore, Saul (1988), ‘Recharacterizations and the Nature of Theory in Corporate Tax Law’, 136 University of Pennsylvania Journal Law Review, 1019-1065. Levmore, Saul (1992), ‘Partnerships, Limited Liability Companies, and Taxes: A Comment on the Survival of Organizational Forms’, 70 Washington University Law Quarterly (Symposium Comment), 489-495. Lewellen, Wilbur G. and Mauer, David C. (1988), Tax Options and Corporate Capital Structures, Graduate School of Business, University of Wisconsin-Madison Wisconsin, 1-88-4. Lintner, John V. (1956), ‘The Distribution of Incomes of Corporations among Dividends, Retained Earnings, and Taxes’, 46 American Economic Review, 97-113. Litzenberger, Robert H. and Ramaswamy, K. (1979), ‘The Effect of Personal Taxes and Dividends on Capital Asset Prices: Theory and Empirical Evidence’, 7 Journal of Financial Economics, 163-195. Litzenberger, Robert H. and Ramaswamy, K. (1982), ‘The Effects of Dividends on Common Stock Prices: Tax Effects or Information Effects’, 37 Journal of Finance, 429-443. Litzenberger, Robert H. and Van Horne, James C. (1978), ‘Elimination of the Double Taxation of Dividends and Corporate Financial Policy’, 33 Journal of Finance, 737 ff. Livingston, John (1993), ‘Corporate Tax Integration in the United States: A Review of the Treasury’s Integration Study’, 58 Modern Law Review, 717 ff. Long, Michael S. and Malitz, Ileen B. (1985), ‘Investment Patterns and Financial Leverage’, in Friedman, Benjamin (ed.), Financing Corporate Capital Formation, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Lowenstein, Louis K. (1985), ‘Management Buyouts’, 85 Columbia Law Review, 730 ff. Ludwig, Matthias (ed.) (1993), A Proposal for a Reform of the U.S. Corporate Income Tax System on the Basis of the Experiences with the Tax System of the Federal Republic of Germany, American Graduate School of International Management. Luscombe, Mark A. (1995), ‘The Transformation of Entity Classification’, 73 Taxes, 562 ff. Lustig, Eric A. (1988), ‘The Emerging Role of the Federal Tax Law in Regulating Hostile Corporate Takeover Defenses: The New Section 5881 Excise Tax on Greenmail’, 40 University of Florida Law Review, 825-827.
218
Corporate Taxation
6060
Lynch, Howell Jackson, Jr (ed.) (1991), Effective Corporate Income Tax Rates and Their Relationship to Corporate Attributes: A Multidefinitional, Multiperiod View, Texas, A&M University. Lyon, Andrew B.R. (ed.) (1986), How Do Stock Prices Change When Corporate Tax Laws Change?: An Empirical Analysis of the Effect of Tax Laws on the Value of the Firm, Princeton University. Lyon, Andrew B.R. (1990), ‘Investment Incentives under the Alternative Minimum Tax’, 43 National Tax Journal, 451-465. Lyon, Andrew B.R. (1992), ‘Tax Neutrality under Parallel Tax Systems’, 20 Public Finance Quarterly, 338-358. Lyon, Andrew B.R. (ed.) (1997), Cracking the Code: Making Sense of the Corporate Alternative Minimum Tax, Washington, DC, Brookings Institution. Lyon, Andrew B.R. and Silverstein, Gerald (1995), ‘The Alternative Minimum Tax and the Behavior of Multinational Corporations’, in Feldstein, M., Hines, J.R.Jr and Hubbard, R.G. (eds), The Effects of Taxation on Multinational Corporations, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 153-177. MacKie Mason, Jeffrey K. (1990), ‘Do Taxes Affect Corporate Financing Decisions?’, 45 Journal of Finance, 1471 ff. MacKie Mason, Jeffrey K. and Gordon, Roger H. (1997), ‘How Much Do Taxes Discourage Incorporation?’, 52 Journal of Finance, 2 ff. Majd, Saman and Myers, Stewart C. (1987), ‘Tax Asymmetries and Corporate Tax Reform’, in Feldstein, M. (ed.), The Effects of Taxation on Capital Accumulation, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Maksimovic, Vojislav and Zechner, Josef (1991), ‘Debt, Agency Costs, and Industry Equilibrium’, 46(5) Journal of Finance, 1619-1643. Malcomson, James M. (1981), ‘Corporate Tax Policy and the Service Life of Capital Equipment’, 48(2) Review of Economic Studies, 311-316. Mansfield, Edwin (1986), ‘The R&D; Tax Credit and Other Technology Policy Issues’, 76 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 191-197. Mansoorian, Arman (1995), ‘Budget Deficits, Corporate Income Taxes, and the Current Account’, 27 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 378-388. Marovelli, Forrest D. and Moser, Beth (eds) (1990), Effective Corporate Tax Rates: 1980-84, Tax Analysts. Marsh, Paul (1982), ‘The Choice Between Equity and Debt: An Empirical Study’, 37 Journal of Finance, 121 ff. Martin, Cathie Jo (1989), ‘Business Influence and State Power: The Case of U.S. Corporate Tax Policy’, 17 Politics and Society. Martin, Cathie Jo (1993), ‘Growth Strategies and Corporate Taxation: Politics as Cause and Effect’, in Post, James E. (ed.), Research in Corporate Social Performance and Policy. A Research Annual, Greenwich, Conn. And London, JAI Press, 57-76. Martin, Cathie Jo (ed.) (1991), Shifting the Burden: the Struggle over Growth and Corporate Taxation. American Politics and Political Economy Series Chicago and London, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Masulis, Ronald W. and Trueman, B. (1988), ‘Corporate Investment and Dividend Decsions under Differential Personal Taxation’, 23 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 369-385.
6060
Corporate Taxation
219
Maule, James Edward (1982), ‘The Effect of Federal Income Tax Integration on State Tax Systems’, Tax Notes, 99 ff. Mavraganis, George (1993), ‘Corporate Income Tax Harmonization in the Nineties: European Community’, 47(4) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 220-225. Mayer, Colin (1986), ‘Corporation Tax, Finance and the Cost of Capital’, 153 Review of Economic Studies, 93 ff. McClure, Charles E., Jr (1975), ‘The Case for Integrating the Income Taxes’, 28 National Tax Journal, 257-258. McCutcheon, Maeve (1995), ‘The Tax Incentives Applying to US Corporate Investment in Ireland’, 26(2) Economic and Social Review, 149-171. McFetridge, Donald G. (1992), ‘Taxation and Its Impact on Market Structure: Comment’, in Bird, R.M. and Mintz, J.M. (eds), Taxation to 2000 and Beyond. Canadian Tax Paper, Toronto, Canadian Tax Foundation, 263-268. McGee, Robert W. (1975), ‘Investment Credit for Progress Expenditures Using Phase-In Rule’, Taxation for Accountants, 250-251. McGee, Robert W. (1976a), ‘Tax Impact of Debt v. Equity Financing’, Taxes, 110-116. McGee, Robert W. (1976b), ‘How to Handle Corporate Obligations that Are Issued at a Discount or Premium’, Monthly Digest of Tax Articles, 64-69. McGee, Robert W. (1976c), ‘The New Imputed Interest Rules: How They Work’, The Practical Accountant, 63-67. McGee, Robert W. (1976d), ‘How to Handle Corporate Obligations That Are Issued at a Discount or Premium’, Taxation for Accountants, 48-50. Reprinted inThe Monthly Digest of Tax Articles, 1976, 64-69. McGee, Robert W. (1977), ‘Planning a Tax-Free Corporate Reorganization: Selecting the One Best Suite to a Client’s Needs’, Taxation for Lawyers, 36-41. McGee, Robert W. (1983), ‘Deferred Taxation’, Bibliography, National Association of Accountants. McGee, Robert W. (1984a), The History of the Income Tax in the United States, Occasional Paper, Deakin University, Australia, No. 69. McGee, Robert W. (1984b), ‘Loophole of the Month’, CPA Digest, 4 ff. McGee, Robert W. (1984c), ‘Software Taxation: A New NAA Research Study’, Management Accounting, 7071-7077. McGee, Robert W. (1984d), ‘The Growth of the Deferred Tax Account’, Management Accounting, 18 ff. McGee, Robert W. (1985a), A Summary of Deferred Income Tax Studies Conducted in the United States and Canada, Occasional Paper, Deakin University, Australia, No. 74. McGee, Robert W. (1985b), Accounting for Software, Dow Jones Irwin, 168 p. McGee, Robert W. (1985c), ‘Developing Computer Technology With the Research Credit’, The Practical Lawyer, 13-24. McGee, Robert W. (1985d), ‘The 1985 Tax Simplification Act’, 1 Business Planning, 14-17. McGee, Robert W. (1985e), ‘Keeping Track of Fringe Benefits ... When To Tax and When Not To Tax’, 1 Controllers Quarterly, 24-27. McGee, Robert W. (1985f), ‘New IRS Regs on Company Cars Raise Taxes ... And Tempers’, 1 Controllers Quarterly, 25-27.
220
Corporate Taxation
6060
McGee, Robert W. (1985g), ‘Computer Software and the Investment Tax Credit’, 5 Computer Law Journal, 347-362. Reprinted in Accounting and Tax Aspects of Computer Software Manufacturing, Praeger Publishing Company, 1987. Reprinted in The Monthly Digest of Tax Articles, 1985, 6-21. McGee, Robert W. (1985h), ‘Computer Software and the Research Credit’, 5 Computer Law Journal, 363-378. Reprinted in The Monthly Digest of Tax Articles, 1985, 6-21; Accounting and Tax Aspects of Computer Software Manufacturing, Praeger Publishing Company, 1987. McGee, Robert W. (1985i), ‘Financial and Tax Accounting for Computer Software’, 7 Western New England Law Review, 651-704. Reprinted in Accounting for Data Processing Department Costs, Greenwood Press, 1988. McGee, Robert W. (1985j), A Guide To VEBAs and Funded Welfare Benefite Plans, New Jersey, Prentice Hall, 32 p. McGee, Robert W. (1985k), Employee Stock Ownership Plans: A guide te ESOPs Under The Latest Rules, New Jersey, Prentice Hall, 44 p. McGee, Robert W. (1986a), Capital Gains and Losses, Alternative Minimum Tax, Accounting Provisions, Prentice-Hall’s Explanation of the Tax Reform Act of 1986, New Jersey, Prentice Hall, 500 p. McGee, Robert W. (1986b), How Tax Reform Would Affect Profit-Sharing, New Jersey, Prentice Hall, 23 p. McGee, Robert W. (1986c), The Corporate Alternative Minimum Tax, National Association of Accountants. McGee, Robert W. (1986d), Tax-Wise Executive Comensation Strategies, New Jersey, Prentice Hall, 44 p. McGee, Robert W. (1986e), International Revenue Service Special Enrollment Examination Questions and Answers, New Jersey, Prentice Hall, 59 p. McGee, Robert W. (1986f), How the New Tax Law Affects Business, - National Association of Accountants. McGee, Robert W. (1987), Accounting and Tax Aspects of Computer Software Manufacturing, Praeger Publishing Company, 162 p. McGee, Robert W. (1996a), Essays on Accounting, Taxation and Public Finance, Dumont Institute for Public Policy Research. http:/ww.hili.com~dumontin McGee, Robert W. (1996b), Taxation, Ethics and Public Policy, Dumont Institute for Public Policy Research. http:/ww.hili.com~dumontin McIntyre, Michael J. (1986), ‘Toward a Fairer and Less Complicated Foreign Tax Credit System’, Tax Notes, 1269 ff. McIntyre, Michael J. (1989), The International Income Tax Rules of the United States. 1995 McIntyre, Michael J. (1996), ‘Separate Basket Limitations in Theory and in Practice’, Tax Notes. McIntyre, Robert S. and Folen, Robert (1984), Corporate Income Taxes in the Reagan Years, Washington DC, Ciitizens for Tax Justice. McIntyre, Robert S. and Wilhelm, David (eds) (1986), ‘Money for Nothing: The Failure of Corporate Tax Incentives 1981-84’. McKenzie, Kenneth J. (1994), ‘The Implications of Risk and Irreversibility for the Measurement of Marginal Effective Tax Rates on Capital’, 27(3) Canadian Journal of Economics, 604-619.
6060
Corporate Taxation
221
McKenzie, Kenneth J. and Mintz, Jack M. (1992), ‘Tax Effects on the Cost of Capital’, in Shoven, John B. and Whalley, John (eds), Canada-U.S. Tax Comparisons. A National Bureau of Economic Research Project Report, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 189-216. McLure, Charles E., Jr (1975a), ‘The Case for Integrating the Income Taxes’, 28 National Tax Journal, 255 ff. McLure, Charles E., Jr (1975b), ‘Integration of the Personal and Corporate Income Taxes: The Missing Element in Recent Tax Reform Proposals’, 88 Harvard Law Review, 532 ff. McLure, Charles E., Jr (1976), ‘Integration of the Income Taxes: Why and How’, 2 Journal of Corporate Taxation, 458 ff. McLure, Charles E., Jr (1977), ‘Integrating the Income Taxes: How to Do it Right’, Tax Notes, 3 ff. McLure, Charles E., Jr (1978), ‘A Status Report on Tax Integration in the United States’, 31 National Tax Journal, 313 ff. McLure, Charles E., Jr (1980), ‘International Aspects of Dividend Relief’, 7 Journal of Corporate Taxation, 137 ff. McLure, Charles E., Jr (1980), ‘The State Corporate Income Tax: Lambs in Wolves’ Clothing’, in Aaron, Henry, J. And Boskins, Michael J. (eds), The Economics of Taxation, Washington, Brookings Institution, 345 ff. McLure, Charles E., Jr (1981), ‘The Elusive Incidence of the Corporate Income Tax: The State Case’, 9 Public Finance Quarterly, 4 ff. McLure, Charles E., Jr (1984), ‘Corporate Income Tax: Restoration, Integration, or Elimination?’, in Moore, J. (ed.), To Promote Prosperity: U.S. Domestic Policy in the Mid-1980s, 303-318. McLure, Charles E., Jr (1989), ‘European Integration and Taxation of Corporate Income at Source: Lessons from the U.S.’, in Gammie, Malcolm, Robinson, Bill and Fitchew Geoffrey., Beyond 1992: A European Tax System: Proceedings of the Fourth Institute for Fiscal Studies Residential Conference, Oxford. McLure, Charles E., Jr (ed.) (1979), Must Corporate Income be Taxed Twice?, Washington, Brookings Institution. McLure, Charles E., Jr (ed.) (1984), The State Corporation Income Tax : Issues in Worldwide Unitary Combination, Stanford, Hoover Institute Press, Stanford University. McLure, Charles E., Jr (ed.) (1986), ‘Economic Perspectives on State Taxation of Multijurisdictional Corporations’. McLure, Charles E., Jr and Mieszkowski, Peter (1983), ‘Tax Exporting and the Commerce Clause’, in McLure, Charles, E., Jr and Mieszkowski, Peter (eds), Fiscal Federalism and the Taxation of Natural Resources, 169 ff. McLure, Charles E., Jr and Surrey, Stanley S. (1977), ‘Integration of Income Taxes - Issues for Debate’, 55 Harvard Business Review, 169 ff. McLure, Charles E., Jr, Mutti, Jack, Thuronyi, Victor and Zodrow, George R. (eds) (1990), The Taxation of Income From Business and Capital in Colombia, Chapel Hill, Duke University. McNulty, John K. (1983), ‘Integrating the Corporate Income Tax?’, 31 American Journal of Comparative Law, 661-666.
222
Corporate Taxation
6060
McNulty, John K. (1990), ‘Reform of the Individual Income Tax by Integration of the Corporate Income Tax’, 46 Tax Notes, 1445 ff. McNulty, John K. (1992), ‘Commentary, Preserving the Virtues of Subchapter S in an Integrated World’, 47 Tax Law Review, 681 ff. McNulty, John K. (1994), ‘Corporate Income Tax Reform in the United States: Proposals for Integration of the Corporate and Individual Income Taxes, and International Aspects’, 12 International Tax & Business Lawyer, 161 ff. Meade, James E. (ed.) (1978), The Taxation of Corporate Reorganizations: How Are We Doing So Far?, London, Allen and Unwin. Meier, Donald L. (1991), ‘Europe in 1992: A U.S. Tax Perspective, Sara Lee Corporation’, 45 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 328-331. Merski, Paul G. (ed.) (1990), The Corporate Tax Burden, Washington, DC, Brookings Institution. Michaely, Roni (1991), ‘Ex-dividend Day Stock Price Behavior: The Case of the 1986 Tax Reform Act’, 46 Journal of Finance, 845-859. Michaely, Roni and Murgia, Maurizio (1995), ‘The Effect of Tax Heterogeneity on Prices and Volume around the Ex-dividend Day: Evidence from the Milan Stock Exchange’, 8 Review of Financial Studies, 369-399. Michaely, Roni and Murgia, Maurizio (1997), ‘Fiscalita e Mercato Azionario: Come Interpretare lo Stacco dei Dividendi dei Titoli Italiani? (Dividends and Taxes in the Italian Stock Market. Evidence from the Ex-Dividend Day Behavior)’, 13 Politica Economica, 117-152. Mieszkowski, Peter M., ‘Integration of the Corporate and Personal Income Taxes: The Bogus Issue of Shifting’, 31 Finanzarchiv, 286-297. Mieszkowski, Peter M. (1969), ‘Tax Incidence Theory: the Effects of Taxes on the Distribution of Income’, 7 Journal of Economic Literature, 1103 ff. Mieszkowski, Peter M. and Zodrow, George R. (1985), ‘The Incidence of a Partial State Corporate Income Tax’, 38 National Tax Journal, 4 ff. Miller, Merton H. (1977), ‘Debt and Taxes’, 32 Journal of Finance, 261-275. Miller, Merton H. (1982), The Corporation Income Tax and Corporate Financial Policies, New Jersey, Prentice Hall. Miller, Merton H. (1986), ‘Behavioral Rationality in Finance: The Case of Dividends’, 59 Journal of Business, 451-468. Miller, Merton H. (1988), ‘The Modigliani-Miller Propositions After Thirty Years’, 2 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 99-120. Miller, Merton H. and Modigliani, Franco (1961), ‘Dividend Policy, Growth and the Valuation of Shares’, 34 Journal of Business, 41 ff. Miller, Merton H. and Rock, Kevin (1985), ‘Dividend Policy Under Asymmetric Information’, 40 Journal of Finance, 103 ff. Miller, Merton H. and Scholes, Myron S. (1979), ‘Dividends and Taxes’, 6 Journal of Financial Economics, 1118-1141. Miller, Merton H. and Scholes, Myron S. (1982), ‘Dividends and Taxes: Some Empirical Evidence’, 90 Journal of Political Economy, 1118-1141. Minarik, Joseph J. (1984), ‘The Effects of Taxation on the Selling of Corporate Stock and the Realization of Capital Gains: Comment’, 99 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 93 ff.
6060
Corporate Taxation
223
Mintz, Jack M. (1976), ‘Is there a Future for Capital Income Taxation?’, 24 Canadian Tax Journal, 1469-1503. Mintz, Jack M. (1987a), Alternative Views of the Corporate Tax: A Reassessment of the Carter Report Twenty Years Later, Department of Economics, Queen’s University, Queen’s Institute for Economic Research, 56. Mintz, Jack M. (1987b), An Empirical Estimate of Corporate Tax Refundability and Effective Tax Rates, Department of Economics, Carleton University, Carleton Industrial Organization Research Unit, 87-02. Mintz, Jack M. (1988), ‘An Empirical Estimate of Corporate Tax Refundability and Effective Tax Rates’, 103(1) Quarterly Journal of Economics, 225-231. Mintz, Jack M. (1990), ‘Corporate Tax Holidays and Investment’, 4(1) World Bank Economic Review, 81-102. Mintz, Jack M. (1991), ‘Economic Implications of Non-Refundability of Tax Losses’, in X (ed.), 4 Policy Options for the Treatment of Tax Losses, Toronto, Clarkson Gordon Foundation, 1-43. Mintz, Jack M. (1995), ‘The Corporation Tax: A Survey’, 16 Fiscal Studies, 23-68. Mintz, Jack M. and Tsiopoulos, Thomas (1992), ‘Contrasting Corporate Tax Policies: Canada and Taiwan’, 40 Canadian Tax Journal, 902 ff. Mintz, Jack M. and Tsiopoulos, Thomas (1994), ‘The Effectiveness of Corporate Tax Incentives for Foreign Investment in the Presence of Tax Crediting’, 55(2) Journal of Public Economics, 233-255. Moden, Karl, Markus (ed.) (1993), ‘Tax Incentives of Corporate Mergers and Foreign Direct Investments’, Ph.D. Thesis. Moden, Karl, Markus (ed.) (1993), Tax Incentives of Corporate Mergers and Foreign Direct Investments, Ph.D. Dissertation, University of Pennsylvania. Modigliani, Franco (1982), ‘Debt, Dividend Policy, Taxes, Inflation, and Market Valuation’, 37 Journal of Finance, 255-273. Modigliani, Franco and Miller, Merton H. (1961), ‘Dividend Policy, Growth, and the Valuation of Shares’, 34 Journal of Business, 411 ff. Modigliani, Franco and Miller, Merton H. (1963), ‘Corporate Income Taxes and the Cost of Capital: A Correction’, 53 American Economic Review, 433 ff. Morgan, Eleanor J. (1987), ‘The UK Corporate Tax Reform and Business Investment Decisions’, 8(2) Managerial and Decision Economics, 149-159. Morgan, I.G. (1982), ‘Dividends and Capital Asset Prices’, 37 Journal of Finance, 1071 ff. Mundstock, G. (1988), ‘Taxation of Intercorporate Dividends Under an Unintegrated Regime’, 44 Tax Law Review, 1 ff. Musgrave, Peggy B. (1974), ‘International Tax Base Division and the Multinational Corporation’, 27 Journal of Public Finance, 394 ff. Musgrave, Peggy B. (1987), ‘Interjurisdictional Coordination of Capital Income’, in Cnossen, S. (ed.), Tax Coordination In The European Community, London, Kluwer Law and Taxation. Mutén, Leif (1997), ‘Dual Income Tax: The Scandinavian Experience’, in Head, G. and Krever, Richard (eds), Company Tax Systems, Australian Research Foundation, 271-285. Mutti, John H. (1981), ‘Tax Incentives and Repatriation Decisions of US Multimational Coporations’, 34 National Tax Journal, 241-248.
224
Corporate Taxation
6060
Mutti, John H. and Grubert, Harry (eds) (1984), Corporate and Personal Taxation of Capital Income in an Open Economy, Washington, DC, Office of Tax Analysis, U.S. Treasury Dept.. Mutti, John H. and Grubert, Harry (1985), ‘The Taxation of Capital Income in an Open Economy: The Importance of Resident-Nonresident Tax Treatment’, 27 Journal of Public Economics, 291-309. Myers, Stewart C. (1984), ‘The Capital Structure Puzzle’, 39 Journal of Finance, 575-592. Myers, Stewart C. (1993), ‘Still Searching for Optimal Capital Structure’, 6 Journal of Applied Corporate Finance, 4-14. Nadean, Serge and Strauss, Robert P. (1991), ‘Tax Policies and the Real and Financial Decisions of the Firm: The Effects of the Tax Reform Act of 1986', 19 Public Finance Quarterly, 251-292. Nadeau, Serge J. (1988), ‘A Model to Measure the Effects of Taxes on the Real and Financial Decisions of the Firm’, 41 National Tax Journal, 467-481. Nadeau, Serge J. and Strauss, Robert P. (1993), ‘Taxation, Equity, and Growth: Exploring the Trade-off Between Shareholder Dividend Tax Relief and Higher Corporate Income Taxes’, 6 National Tax Journal, 161-172. Nadeau, Serge J. and Strauss, Robert P. (1993), ‘Taxation, Equity, and Growth: Exploring the Trade-Off Between Shareholder Dividend Tax Relief and Higher Corporate Income Taxes, U Victoria; Carnegie Mellon U’, 46 National Tax Journal, 161-175. Nadeau, Serge J. and Strauss, Robert P. (1997), ‘Observations on US Corporate Tax Policy and the 1992 US Treasury Report on Integration’, in Head, G. and Krever, Richard (eds), Company Tax Systems, Australian Research Foundation, 85-114. Narayanan, Suresh (1989), ‘Forward Shifting of the Corporate Tax in the Presence of Competing Imports: A Note’, 44(2) Public Finance, 320-326. Neville, Norman (1985), ‘The Economics of Tax Ploision and Corporate Tax Integration’, 2 Australian Tax Forum, 71-77. Newberry, Kaye J. (ed.) (1994), Foreign Tax Credit Limitations and Public Issuances by U.S. Multinationals: New Evidence of Tax Clienteles, Thesis, Arizona State University. Normadin, Charles P. (1989), ‘A Legal Perspective (Discussion)’, in Peters, Richard T. and Scott, Robert E. (eds), Are the Distinctions Between Debt and Equity Disappearing? Proceedings of a conference held at Melvin Village, New Hampshire Federal Reserve Bank of Boston. Norr, M. (1982), The Taxation of Corporations and Shareholders. Norregaard, John and Owens, Jeffrey (1992), ‘Taxing Profits in a Global Economy: International’, 46(5) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 223-228. Note (1995), ‘Losing Control: Toward a New Understanding of the Taxation of Post-Incorporation Stock Sales’, 108 Harvard Law Review, 1661 ff. Ofer, Aharon, R. and Siegel, Daniel R. (1987), ‘Corporate Financial Policy, Information, and Market Expectations: an Empirical Investigation of Dividends’, 42 Journal of Finance, 889 ff. Officer, Robert R. (1990), The Australian Imputation System for Company Tax and Its Likely Effect on Shareholders, Financing and Investment Australian Tax Forum. Officer, Robert R. (1994), ‘The Cost of Capital of a Company under an Imputation Tax System’, 1-17.
6060
Corporate Taxation
225
Olin, John M. (ed.) (1990), ‘Taxation and the Cost of Capital: The ‘Old’ View, the ‘New’ View, and Another View. Omer, Thomas C. and Ziebart, David A. (1993), ‘The Effect of the Alternative Minimum Tax on Corporate Tax Burdens’, 33(2) Quarterly Review of Economics and Finance, 123-139. Omer, Thomas C., Molloy, Karen H. and Ziebart, David A. (1991), ‘Measurement of Corporate Tax Rates Using Financial Statement Information’, Journal of the American Taxation Association, 57-72. Ono, Yoshiyasu and Shibata, Akihisa (1992), ‘Spill Over Effects of Supply Side Changes in a Two Country Economy with Capital Accumulation’, 33(12) Journal of International Economics, 127-146. Osterberg, William P. (1989), ‘Tobin’s q, Investment, and the Endogenous Adjustment of Financial Structure’, 40(3) Journal of Public Economics, 293-318. Parai, Amar K. (1988), ‘The Incidence of Corporate Income Tax under Variable Returns to Scale’, 43(3) Public Finance, 414-424. Parai, Amar K. (1991), ‘The Incidence of Corporate Income Tax under Variable Returns to Scale: Reply’, 46 Public Finance, 337-338. Parai, Amar K. and Choudhary, Munir A.S. (1992), ‘Imperfect Labor Mobility and Corporate Tax Incidence’, 6(3) International Economic Journal, 75-82. Pastor, Santos (1991), ‘Comment (on Aretz, Taxation and Incorporation)’, in Weigel, Wolfgang (ed.), Economic Analysis of Law - A Collection of Applications, Vienna, Österreichischer Wirtschaftsverlag, 133-134. Pearson, Mark (1989), ‘Corporate Tax Harmonisation in the European Community’, in Gammie, Malcolm, Robinson, Bill and Fitchew Geoffrey, Beyond 1992: A European Tax System: Proceedings of the Fourth Institute for Fiscal Studies Residential Conference, Oxford. Pedersen, Bente Moll (1994), ‘Denmark: Joint Taxation: A Unique Way of Reducing Corporate Tax’, 48(11) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 574-578. Peel, Fred W. (1985), ‘A Proposal for Eliminating Double Taxation of Corporate Dividends’, 39 Tax Law Journal, 29 ff. Pender, Howard (1997), ‘Company Tax in Australia’, in Head, G. and Krever, Richard (eds), Company Tax Systems, Australian Research Foundation, 195-206. Pereira, Alfredo M. (ed.) (1989), Corporate Tax Integration in the United States: A Dynamic General Equilibium Analysis, San Diego, of California. Pereira, Alfredo M. (1993), ‘A Dynamic General Equilibrium Analysis of Corporate Tax Integration’, 15(1) Journal of Policy Modeling, 63-89. Peroni, Robert J. (1997), ‘Back to the Future: A Path to Progressive Reform of the U.S. International Income Tax Rules’, 51 University of Miami Law Review, 975 ff. Petersen, Dorothy Ann (ed.) (1993), D Average Tax Rates Matter for Corporate Investment?, Northwestern University Press. Peterson, George E. (1985), ‘Direct Evidence on the Marginal Rate of Taxation on Dividend Income’, 14 Journal of Financial Economics, 272-280. Petit, R.R. (1977), ‘Taxes, Transaction Costs and the Clientele Effects of Dividends’, Journal of Financial Economics, 419-436. Piccioti, Sol (ed.) (1992), International Business Taxation: A Study in the Internationalization of Business Regulation .
226
Corporate Taxation
6060
Plasmans, J. and Vanneste, J. (1991), ‘The Incidence of Corporate Taxation in Belgium on Employment and Investment’, 0 Cahiers Economiques de Bruxelles, 3-25. Platt, Joseph S. (1947), ‘Integration and Correlation - The Treasury Proposal’, 3 Tax Law Review, 59 ff. Plesko, George A. (1994), ‘Corporate Taxation and the Financial Characteristics of Firms’, 22 Public Finance Quarterly, 311 ff. Plumb, W.T. (1971), ‘The Federal Income Tax Significance of Corporate Debt: A Critical Analysis and A Proposal’, 26 Tax Law Review, 359 ff. Polito, Anthony P. (1989), ‘Note, A Proposal for an Integrated Income Tax’, 12 Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy, 1009 ff. Pomp, Richard D. (1993), ‘The Disclosure of State Corporate Income Tax Data: Turning the Clock Back t the Future’, 22 Capital University Law Review, 373 ff. Porteba, James M. (1987), ‘How Burdensome ae Capital Gains Taxes?: Evidence from the United States’, 33 Journal of Public Economics, 157 ff. Porteba, James M. (1987), ‘Tax Policy and Corporate Saving’, 2 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 455-515. Porteba, James M. (1991), ‘Dividends, Capital Gains, and the Corporate Veil: Evidence from Britain, Canada, and the United States’, in Bernheim, B. Douglas and Shoven, John B. (eds) National Saving and Economic Performance, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 49-71. Porteba, James M. (1992), ‘Why Didn’t the Tax Reform Act of 1986 Raise Corporate Taxes?’, in X (ed.), Tax Policy and the Economy, Cambridge and London, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass. National Bureau of Economic Research, 43-58. Porteba, James M. and Summers, Lauwrence H. (1983), ‘Dividends, Taxes, Corporate Investment, and “Q”’, 22 Journal of Public Economics, 135-167. Porteba, James M. and Summers, Lauwrence H. (1984), ‘New Evidence that Taxes Affect the Valuation of Dividends’, 39 Journal of Finance, 1397-1415. Porteba, James M. and Summers, Lauwrence H. (1985), ‘The Economic Effects of Dividend Taxes’, in Altman Edward and Subrahmanyam Marti (eds), Recent Advances in Corporate Finance, Homewood: Richard D. Irwin, 227-284. Posin, Daniel Q. (1985), ‘Taxing Corporate Reorganizations: Purging Penelope’s Web’, 133 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1381-1382. Pozdena, Randall Johnston (1987), ‘Tax Policy and Corporate Capital Structure’, 4 Economic Review. Quirmbach, Herman C., Swenson, Charles W. and Vines, Cynthia Carol (1996), ‘An Experimental Examination of General Equilibrium Tax Incidence’, 61 Journal of Public Economics, 337-358. Rajagopal, Dagmar (ed.) (1987), The Corporate Income Tax and the User Cost of Capital a New Method to Test for Short-run Forward Shifting of the Tax, Ph.D. Thesis, Toronto, University of Toronto Faculty of Law. Rands, William J. (1995), ‘Passthrough Entities and Their Unprincipled Differences Under Federal Tax Law’, 49 SMU Law Review, 15 ff. Rangazas, Peter and Dewan, Abdullah (1987), ‘Taxes and the Corporate Sector Debt Ratio: Some Time Series Evidence’, 69 Review of Economics and Statistics, 357 ff. Rapanos Vassilis T. (1991), ‘The Incidence of Corporate Income Tax under Variable Returns to Scale: Comment’, 46 Public Finance, 335-336.
6060
Corporate Taxation
227
Razin, Assaf and Sadka, Efraim (1990), ‘Integration of International Capital Markets: The Size of Government and Tax Coordination’, in Razin and Slemrod, Joel (eds), Taxation in the Global Economy, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Reamonn, Sean (ed.) (1970), The Philosophy of the Corporate Tax, Dublin. Reaume, David M. (1976), ‘Short Run Corporate Tax Shifting by Profit Maximizing Oligopolists’, 4(1) Public Finance Quarterly, 33-44. Repetti, James R. (1990), ‘Long-Term Capital Gains, the Long-Term Investment Perspective, and Corporate Productivity’, 49 Tax Notes, 85 ff. Repetti, James R. (1992), ‘Corporate Governance and Stockholder Abdication: Missing Factors in Tax Policy Analysis’, 67 Notre Dame Law Review, 983-984. Repetti, James R. (1997), ‘Accounting and Taxation: the Misuse of Tax Incentives to Align Management-Shareholder Interests’, 19 Cardozo Law Review, 697 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. (1988), ‘An Applied Theory of Limited Partnership’, 37 Emory Law Journal, 852-854. Ribstein, Larry E. (1992), ‘The Deregulation of Limited Liability and the Death of Partnership’, 70 Washington United Law Quarterly, 471 ff. Rice, Eric M. (ed.) (1990), Eric M. Skirting the Law: Essays on Corporate Tax Evasion and Avoidance, Ph.D. Thesis, Harvard University Press. Ritter, Wolfgang (1989), ‘Harmonisation of Taxes as a Prerequisite for a Single European Market’, in Gammie, Malcolm, Robinson, Bill and Fitchew, Geoffrey, Beyond 1992: A European Tax System: Proceedings of the Fourth Institute for Fiscal Studies Residential Conference, Oxford. Robichek, Alexander and Myers, Eugene A. (1966), ‘Stewart Problems in the Theory of Optimal Capital Structure’, 1 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 1-35. Rocap and Waimon (1989), ‘Passthrough Rules for Financial Intermediairies: Different Routes to a Single Tax’, 67 Taxes, 1025 ff. Rodios, Nikos D. (1986), ‘E Kampyle tou Laffer e Peri tes Phthinousas Apodoseos tes Phorologias (The Laffer Curve or On the Diminishing Return of Taxation)’, 53 Ephemeris ton Hellenon Nomikon, 216-218. Rogers, Diane, Lim (ed.) (1996), ‘The Incidence of the Corporate Income Tax’, Congressional Office Paper. Roin, Julie, A. (1988), ‘United They Stand, Divided They Fall: Public Choice Theory and the Tax Code’, 74 Cornell Law Review, 62 ff. Roin, Julie, A. (1995), ‘Rethinking Tax Treaties in a Strategic World with Disparate Tax Systems’, 81 Virginia. Law Review, 1753 ff. Ronen, Joshua and Aharoni, A. (1989), ‘The Choice among Accounting Alternatives and Management Compensation: Effects of Corporate Tax’, 64(1) Accounting Review, 69-86. Rooijen, Martin J. (1977), ‘Interrelationship of Corporate Tax and Income Tax of Shareholders’, 31 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 64-68. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1982), ‘Unfair Competition and Corporate Income Taxation’, 34 Stanford Law Review, 1017-1039. Reprinted In Rose Ackerman (ed.), The Economics of Nonprofit Institutions, pp. 394 414. Rousslang, Donald J. (1987), ‘The Effects of Recent Corporate Tax Changes on U.S. International Trade’, 40(4) National Tax Journal, 603-615. Rozycki, John J. (1997), ‘A Tax Motivation for Smoothing Dividends’, 37 Quarterly Review of Economics and Finance, 563-578.
228
Corporate Taxation
6060
Rudnick, Rebecca S. (1988), ‘Who Should Pay the Corporate Tax in a Flat Tax World?’, 39 Case Western Reserve Law Review, 965 ff. Rudnick, Rebecca S. (1989), ‘Corporate Tax Integration: Liquidity of Investment’, 42 Tax Notes, 1107 ff. Sadowitz, March (ed.) (1992), Corporate Tax Policy: a Factor in Environmental Decision Making, Thesis, Albany, State University of New York Press. Sahni, Balbir Singh and Mathew, T. (eds) (1976), The Shifting and Incidence of the Corporation Income Tax, Rotterdam University Press. Salinger, Michael A. and Summers, Lawrence H. (eds) (1981), Tax Reform and Corporate Investment: a Micro-econometric Simulation, National Bureau of Economic Research, 757. Sandberg, Milton (1938), ‘The Income Tax Subsidy to “Reorganizations”’, 38 Columbia Law Review, 98 ff. Sanden, B. Kenneth (1975), ‘The Taxation of Income from Corporate Shareholding: Introductory Remarks’, 28 National Tax Journal, 255 ff. Sansing, Richard C. (1993), ‘Information Acquisition in a Tax Compliance Game’, Accounting Review, 874-884. Sarma, J.V.M. (1990), ‘1990-91 Budget and the New Corporate Tax Proposals: An Evaluation: India’, 44(7) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 347-349. Sasseville, Jacques (ed.) (1995), ‘Article 10 of the OECD Model Tax Convention and the Different Approaches to Integration in International Fiscal Association. International taxation of dividends reconsidered in light of corporate tax integration’, Proceedings of a seminar organised jointly with the EOCD in Toronto in 1994 during the 48th Congress of the International Fiscal Association. Sato, Mitsuo and Bird, Richard M. (1975), ‘International Aspects of the Taxation of Corporations and Shareholders’, 22 International Monetary Fund Staff Papers, 384-455. Scarborough, Robert H. (1993), ‘Risk, Diversification and the Design of Loss Limitations Under a Realization-Based Income Tax’, 48 Tax Law Review, 677 ff. Schadewald, Michael S. (1992), ‘Discussion of Expertise in Corporate Tax Planning: The Issue Identification Phase’, 30(0) Journal of Accounting Research, 29-36. Schaffer, Daniel C. (1979), ‘The Income Tax on Intercorporate Dividends’, 33 Tax Lawyer, 161 ff. Schenk, Deborah H. (1992), ‘Complete Integration in a Partial Integration World’, 47 Tax Law Review, 697 ff. Schipper, Katherine and Smith, Abbie (1988), Corporate Income Tax Effects of Management Buyouts. Schler, Michael L. (1992), ‘Taxing Corporate Income Once (or Hopefully Not at All): A Practitioner’s Comparison of the Treasury and ALI Integration Models’, 47 Tax Law Review, 509 ff. Scholes, Myron S. and Wolfson, Mark, Alan (1980), ‘Employee Stock Ownership Plans and Corporate Restructuring: Myths and Realities’, in Samets, Arnold W. and Bicksler, James L. (eds), The Battle for Corporate Control: Shareholder Rights, Stakeholder Interest, and Managerial Responsibilities. Scholes, Myron S. and Wolfson, Mark, Alan (1990), ‘The Effects of Change in Tax Laws on Corporate Reorganization Activity’, 63 Journal of Business, 141-164.
6060
Corporate Taxation
229
Scholes, Myron S. and Wolfson, Mark Alan (1990), ‘The Effects of Changes in Tax Laws on Corporate Reorganization Activity’, 63(S) Journal of Business, 141-164. Scholes, Myron S. and Wolfson, Mark, Alan (1991), ‘The Role of Tax Rules in the Recent Restructuring of U.S. Corporations, in D. Bradford’, 5 Tax Policy and the Economy, 1-25. Scholes, Myron S. and Wolfson, Mark, Alan (eds) (1992), Taxes and Business Strategy: A Planning Approach, Englewood Cliffs, NJ, Prentice-Hall. Scholes, Myron S., Wilson, Peter G. and Wolfson, Mark Alan (1992), ‘Firms’ Responses to Anticipated Reductions in Tax Rates’, 30 Journal of Accounting Research, 161-185. Scholz, John Karl (1988), The Effect of the Relative Tax Treatment of Dividends and Capital Gains on Corporate Valuation and Behavior, Ph.D. Dissertation, Stanford University. Schulman, Graig T., Thomas, Deborah W., Sellers, Keith F. and Kennedy, Duane (1996), ‘Effects of Tax Integration and Capital Gains Tax on Corporate Leverage’, 49 National Tax Journal, 31-54. Schultz, Michael L. (1990), ‘Section 382 and the Pursuit of Neutrality in the Treatment of Net Operating Loss Carryovers’, 39 University of Kansas Law Review, 84 ff. Schwidetzky, Walter D. (1995), ‘A Comparison of Partnership Income Taxation in the United States and Germany: A Study in Differences’, 10 American University Journal of International Law and Policy, 1331 ff. Seidl, Christian (1989), ‘Betriebssteuer und Neutralität (On the Neutrality of a Business Tax)’, 66/4 Steuer und Wirtschaft, 350-357. Sellers, Keith F., Thomas, Deborah W. and Schulman, Craig T. (eds) (1994), Effects of Tax Policy on Corporate Financing Decisions: Integration of the Corporate and Personal Income Tax, Washington, DC, Tax Foundation and Ernst & Young. Senate Finance Committee Staff (ed.) (1983), The Reform and Simplification of the Income Taxation of Corporations, Washington, DC, United States G.P.O.. Preliminary Report of the Staff of the Senate Finance Committee, ‘Corporate Tax Study’, issued September 27, 1983, by Commerce Clearing House, Chicago no. 45 (Oct. 6, 1983) Shaikh, Abdul Quader J. (1971), The Corporate Income Tax and the Growth of the Corporate Sector: a Case Study of India, Ph.D. Thesis, University of Massachusetts. Shakow, David J. (1990), ‘Wither, C!’, 45 Tax Law Review, 177 ff. Shapiro, Robert J. (1997), ‘Building a Conceptual Baseline for Corporate Tax Reform’, 50 National Tax Journal, 507-517. Sharpe, Donald (1996), ‘Unfair Business Competition and the Tax on Income Destined for Charity: Forty Six Years Later’, 3 Florida Tax and Law Review, 367 ff. Shaviro, Daniel N. (1992), ‘An Efficiency Analysis of Realization and Recognition Rules Under the Federal Income Tax’, 48 Tax Law Review, 53 ff. Shaviro, Daniel N. (1995), ‘Risk-Based Rules and the Taxation of Capital Income’, 50 Tax Law Review, 643-724. Shay, Steven E. (1996), ‘Revisiting U.S. Anti-Deferral Rules’, 74 Taxes, 1042 ff. Sheffrin, Steven M. (1982), ‘What Have We Done to the Corporate Tax System?’, 25(2) Challenge, 46-52. Shefrin, Hersch M. and Statman, Meir (1984), ‘Explaining Investor Preference for Cash Dividends’, 13 Journal of Financial Economics, 253 ff.
230
Corporate Taxation
6060
Sheppard, Lee A. (1985), ‘Corporate Tax Integration, the Proper Way to Eliminate the Corporate Tax’, 27 Tax Notes, 637 ff. Shevlin, Terry (1990), ‘Estimating Corporate Marginal Tax Rates’, Journal of the American Taxation Association. Shim, Ki-Ryon (1976), The Shifting of the Corporation Income Tax in Japanese Manufacturing, Ph.D. Thesis, University of Cincinnati. Shnaider, Eliahu (1987), ‘ The Use of Fuzzy Set Theory for Forecasting Corporate Tax Revenu’, M.S. Thesis. Shome, Parthasarathi (1982), ‘Corporate Tax Shifting: Empirical Evidence from ASEAN’, 4 Papers in Asian Studies. Shome, Parthasarathi (1985), ‘Is the Corporate Tax Shifted? Empirical Evidence from ASEAN’, 13(1) Public Finance Quarterly, 21-46. Shoven, John B. (1976), ‘The Incidence and Efficiency Effects of Taxes on Income from Capital’, 84 Journal of Political Economy, 1261 ff. Shoven, John B. (1986), New Developments in Corporate Finance and Tax Avoidance: Some Evidence, National Bureau of Economic Research, 2091. Shoven, John B. (1987), ‘The Tax Consequences of Share Repurchases and Other Non-Dividend Cash Payments to Equity Owners’, in Summers, Lawrence H. (ed.), Tax Policy and the Economy, Cambridge, MIT Press, 29-54. Shoven, John B. (ed.), ‘Using the Corporate Cash Flow Tax to Integrate Corporate and Personal Taxes’, Proceedings of the 83rd Annual Conference of the National Tax Association, 19-26. Shoven, John B. (ed.) (1990), The Japanese Tax Reform and the Effective Rate of Tax on Japanese Corporate Investments, Stanford University, Center for Economic Policy Research, 147. Shoven, John B. and Waldfogel, Joel (eds) (1990), ‘Introduction and Summary’, in Shoven, John B. and Waldfogel, Joel (eds), In Debt, Taxes, and Corporate Restructuring, Washington, Brookings Institution, 1-19. Shoven, John B. and Whalley, John (1972), ‘A General Equilibrium Calculation of the Effects of Differential Taxation of Income from Capital in the U.S.’, 1 Journal of Public Economics, 281 ff. Shoven, John B. and Whalley, John (eds) (1992), Canada-U.S. Tax Comparisons, A National Bureau of Economic Research Project Report, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Shuldiner, Reed H. (1992), ‘Corporate Integration: Do the Uncertainties Outweigh the Benefits?’, 47 Tax Law Review, 653 ff. Shum, Pauline M. (1996), ‘Taxes and Corporate Debt Policy in Canada: An Empirical Investigation’, 29 Canadian Journal of Economics, 556-572. Siegel, Stanley (1995), ‘The Effects of Tax Laws on the Choice of Organizational Form and Structure: A Comparison of Integrated and Nonintegrated Tax Systems’, 29 International Lawyer, 1-6. Siegfried, John J. (1972), The Relationship Between Economic Structure and the Effect of Political Influence: Empirical Evidence from The Federal Corporation Income Tax Program, Ph.D. Dissertation, Madison, Wisconsin University. Siegfried, John J. (1974), ‘Effective Average U.S. Corporation Income Tax Rates’, 27 National Tax Journal, 245-259.
6060
Corporate Taxation
231
Siegfried, John J. and Weiss, Leonard W. (1974), ‘Advertising, Profits, and Corporate Taxes Revisited Review of Economics and Statistics’, 56 National Tax Journal, 195-200. Simeone, Gary John (1994), U.S. Corporate Tax Integration - Analysis of the Alternatives, M.S. Thesis, San Francisco, State University. Simmons, Daniel L. (1983), ‘Net Operating Losses and Section 382: Searching for a Limitation on Loss Carryovers’, 63 Tulane Law Review, 1045 ff. Simon, Herbert A. (1972), ‘Antitrust and the “Size” Problem: The “Graduated” Corporate Income Tax as an Anti-Bigness Device’, 6 Antitrust Law and Economics Review, 53 ff. Simons, Henry C. (1938), Personal Income Taxation. Sinn, Hans-Werner (1990), Taxation and the Birth of Foreign Subsidiaries, National Bureau of Economics, 3519. Sinn, Hans-Werner (1991a), ‘The Vanishing Harberger Triangle’, 45 Journal of Public Economics, 271-300. Sinn, Hans-Werner (1991b), ‘Taxation and the Cost of Capital: The Old View, the “New” View and Another View’, 5 Tax Policy and the Economy, 25-54. Sinn, Hans-Werner (1991c), ‘Share Repurchases, the “New” View, and the Cost of Capital’, 36 Economic Letters, 187-190. Sinn, Hans-Werner (1993), ‘Taxation and the Birth of Foreign Subsidiaries’, in Herberg, H. and Long, N.V. (eds), Trade Welfare, and Economic Policies: Essays in Honor of Murray C Kemp, Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 325-352. Slawson (1967), ‘Taxing as Ordinary Income the Appreciation of Publicly Held Stock’, 76 Yale Law Journal, 623 ff. Slemrod, Joel (1990), ‘The Impact of the Tax Reform Act of 1986 on Foreign Direct Investment To and From the United States’, in Slemrod, J. (ed.), Do Taxes Matter?, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Slemrod, Joel (1990), ‘Tax Effects on Foreign Direct Investment in the United States: Evidence from a Cross-Country Comparison’, in Razin and Slemrod (eds), Taxation in the Global Economy, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Slitor, Richard E. (1963), ‘The Enigma of Corporate Tax Incidence’, 18 Public Finance. Slitor, Richard E. (1966), ‘Corporate Tax Incidence: Economic Adjustments to Differentials Under a Two-Tied Tax Structure’, in Krzyzaniak, M. (ed.), Effects of Corporation Income Tax, Papers Presented at the Symposium on Business Taxation, 136-206. Sloan, Frank A. Et al. (1988), ‘Cost of Capital to the Hospital Secto’, 7(1) Journal of Health Economics, 25-45. Smirlock, Michael Randolph and Beatty, Saman Majd (eds) (1986), Taxes and Mergers: A Survey, Salomon Brothers Center for the Study of Financial Institutions, New York, University Graduate School of Business Administration. Smith, Abbie (1990), ‘The Effects of Leveraged Buyouts’, 25(2) Business Economics, 19-25. Smith, Andrew M.C. (1991), ‘Corporate and International Tax Reforms in 1991 Budget: New Zealand’, 45(11) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 530-537. Smith, Andrew M.C. (1993), ‘Comprehensive Dividend Imputation, Neutrality and Double Taxation of Corporate Profits: New Zealand’, 47 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 568-580.
232
Corporate Taxation
6060
Smith, Andrew M.C. (1994), ‘Dividend Imputation and International Equity Investment: Unilateral Extension of Imputation to Non-Resident Investors’, 11 Australian Tax Forum, 247-269. Smith, Dan Throop (1977), ‘Relief From Double Taxation of Dividend Income’, 55 Harvard Business Review, 87 ff. Smith, David Duane (ed.) (1979), The Relationship Between Market Structure and the Effective Corporate Income Tax Rate, Ph.D. Thesis, University of Michigan. Smith, Peter Jefferson (1989), ‘Proposals to Date, and Aims for 1992’, in Gammie, Malcolm, Robinson, Bill and Fitchew Geoffrey, Beyond 1992: A European Tax System: Proceedings of the Fourth Institute for Fiscal Studies Residential Conference, Oxford. Snoe, Joseph A. (1993), ‘The Entity Tax and Corporate Integration: An Agency Cost Analysis and A Call for a Deferred Distributions Tax’, University of Miami Law Review. Snow, Sandra L. (ed.) (1976), A Comparative Model of Corporate Income Tax Shifting Utilizing Cross Sectional Data, Ph.D. Thesis, University of Missouri, Columbia. Sommerfeld, Ray M. and Jones, Sally M. (ed.) (1991), Federal Taxes and Management Decisions, Homewood, IL, Richard D. Irwin. Sommerfeld, Ray M. and Jones, Sally M. (1995), Federal Taxes and Management Decisions, Chicago, Ill., Richard D. Irwin, Inc.. Sorensen, Peter Birch (1994), ‘Some Old and New Issues in the Theory of Corporate Income Taxation’, 51 Finanzarchiv, 425-456. Sorensen, Peter Birch (1995a), ‘Changing Views of the Corporate Income Tax’, 48 National Tax Journal, 279-294. Sorensen, Peter Birch (1995b), ‘Comment on Alan J. Auerbach, Kevin Hassett and Jan Sodersten: Taxation and Corporate Investment: The Impact of the 1991 Swedish Tax Reform’, 2 Swedish Economic Policy Review, 385-390. Spooner, Gillian M. (1986), ‘Effective Tax Rates from Financial Statements’, 39 National Tax Journal, 293-306. Spooner, Gillian M. and Sunley, Emil M. (eds) (1988), ‘The Corporate Tax Burden in the United States’. Stapleton, R.C. (1972), ‘Taxes, the Cost of Capital and the Theory of Investment’, 82 The Economic Journal, 1273-1292. Steenekamp, T.J. (1996), ‘Some Aspects of Corporate Taxation in South Africa: The Katz Commission’, 64 South African Journal of Economics, 1-19. Stephan, Paul B. III (1990), ‘Disaggregation and Subchapter C: Rethinking Corporate Tax Reform’, 76 Virginia Law Review, 655-711. Steuerle, C. Eugene (1989), ‘A Simplified Integrated Tax’, 44 Tax Notes, 335 ff. Stewart, J.C. (1989), ‘Transfer Pricing: Some Empirical Evidence from Ireland’, 16(3) Journal of Economic Studies, 40-56. Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1973), ‘Taxation, Corporate Financial Policy, and the Cost of Capital’, 2 Journal of Public Economics, 1-33. Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1976), ‘The Corporation Tax’, 5 Journal of Public Economics, 303 ff. Strecker, (1965), ‘When Will the Corporate Form Save Taxes’, 18 Vanderbilt Law Review, 1695 ff.
6060
Corporate Taxation
233
Sugin, Linda (1997), ‘Theories of the Corporation and the Tax Treatment of Corporate Philanthropy’, 41 New York Law School Law Review, 835 ff. Summers, Lawrence H. (1980), Tax Policy and Corporate Investment, National Bureau of Economic Research, 605. Summers, Lawrence H. (1981), ‘Taxation and Corporate Investment: A Q-Theory Approach’, 1 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 105 ff. Sunley, Emil M. (1992), ‘Corporate Integration: An Economic Perspective’, 47 Tax Law Review, 621 ff. Surrey, Stanley S. (1975), ‘Reflections on “Integration” of Corporation and Individual Income Taxes’, 28 National Tax Journal, 335-340. Suwanmala, Charas (1989), ‘Crisis and Response: Treasury Cash Balance Crisis in Thailand 19801982’, 9(3) Public Budgeting and Finance, 27-36. Swaine, David (1989), ‘The Longer-term Implications for European Tax Systems’, in Gammie, Malcolm, Robinson, Bill and Fitchew Geoffrey, Beyond 1992: A European Tax System: Proceedings of the Fourth Institute for Fiscal Studies Residential Conference, Oxford. Swan, Peter L. (1984), ‘Capital Gains, Cash Flow Taxes, and Corporate Tax Reform’, 1(3) Australian Tax Forum, 292-311. Swayze, James P. (ed.) (1992), The Effect of Corporate Income Tax Integration on the Demand for Risky Stock, Ph.D. Thesis, University of Houston, College of Business Administration. Swenson, Deborah (1993), ‘Explaining the Low Taxable Income of Foreign-Controlled Companies in the United States’, in Giovannini, A., Hubbard, R.G. and Slemrod, J. (eds), Studies in International Taxation, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Taggert, Robert A. (1980), ‘Taxes and Corporate Capital Structure in an Incomplete Market’, 35 Journal of Finance, 645-659. Taggert, Robert A. (1985), ‘Secular Patterns in the Financing of U.S. Corporations’, in Friedman, Benjamin (ed.), Corporate Capital Structures in the United States: An Introduction and Overview, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Tajika, Eiji and Yui, Yuji (1988), ‘Cost of Capital and Effective Corporate Tax Rate the Case of Post War Japan (In Japanese)’, 39(2) Economic Review (Keizai Kenkyu), 118-128. Takirambudde, Peter Nanyenya (1994), ‘Botswana: Double Corporate Tax: Untangling the Undergrowth of Company and Shareholder Tax Rules’, 48(2) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 82-88. Tax Executives Institute (ed.) (1993), The Structure and Size of the Corporate Tax Department: An Empirical Analysis, Washington. Taylor, Scott A. (1990), ‘Corporate Integration in the Federal Income Tax: Lessons From the Past and A Proposal for the Future’, 10 Virginia Tax Review, 237 ff. Taylor, Willard B. (1977), ‘Report on the Integration of Corporate and Individual Income Taxes’, 31 Tax Lawyer, 37 ff. Teixeira, Gloria (ed.) (1997), Taxing Corporate Profits in the EU: A Comparison of the Portuguese, British and Dutch Systems, London, Kluwer Law International. Terborgh, George Willard (ed.) (1959), ‘Effect of the Corporate Income Tax on Investment. Machinery and Allied Products Institute’, 37. Tetreault, David T. and Lindsay, Robert F. (1995), ‘The Taxation of Corporate Reorganizations: How are we Doing so Far?’, 43 Canadian Tax Journal, 1441-1464.
234
Corporate Taxation
6060
The Valabh Committee (ed.) (1988), International Tax Reform: Full Imputation, an Independent Report to the New Zealand Government, Wellington. The Valabh Committee (ed.) (1991), The Taxation of Distributions from Companies, an Independent Report to the New Zealand Government, Wellington. Thomas, Ann F. (1997), ‘Square Wheels: U.S. Passthrough Taxation of Privately Held Enterprises in a Comparative Law Context’, 17 New York Law School Journal of International and Comp. Law, 429-471. Thompson, Samuel C., Jr (1975), ‘Tax Policy Implications of Contributions of Appreciated and Depreciated Property to Partnerships, Subchapter C Corporations and Subchapter S Corporations in Exchange for Ownership Interests’, 31 Tax Law Review, 51 ff. Thompson, Samuel C. Jr (ed.) (1993), Reform of the Taxation of Mergers, Acquisitions, and LBOs, Durham, NC, Carolina Academic Press. Thuronyi, Victor (1983), ‘The Taxation of Corporate Income - A Proposal for Reform’, 2 American Journal of Tax Policy, 109 ff. Tillinghast, David R. (1990), ‘International Tax Simplification’, 8 American Jounal of Tax Policy, 204-205. Treubert, Patrice and Pavelko, Amy (1991), Internal Revenue Service, ‘The Alternative Minimum Tax: An Analysis of Its Effect on Corporations in 1987'. Trezevant, Robert (1981), ‘How did Firms Adjust their Tax-Deductible Activities in Response to the Economic Recovery Tax Act of 1981?’, 67 National Tax Journal, 253-271. Trezevant, Robert (1992), ‘Debt Financing and Tax Status: Test of the Substitution Effect and the Tax Exhaustion Hypothesis Using Firm’s Responses to the Economic Recovery Act of 1981’, 47 The Journal of Finance, 1557-1568. U.S. Department of the Treasury (1992), ‘A Recommendation for Integration of the Individual and Corporate Tax Systems’, 14 Daily Tax Rep. (BNA), 7 ff. U.S. Department of the Treasury (1992), Report on Integration of the Individual and Corporate Tax Systems: Taxing Business Income Once. United States General Accounting Office (ed.), Tax Policy Implications of Replacing the Corporate Income Tax with a Consumption Tax. Unni, Sanjay (1994), ‘An Intertemporal Analysis of Optimal Capital Structure under Corporate and Personal Taxation’, Ph.D. Dissertation. Van Den Dempel, A. (1970), Corporation Tax and Individual Income Tax in the European Communities. Van Raad, Kees (1995), ‘In a World where Classical and Integration Systems Co-exist, Article 10 OECD Model should not Disregard the Underlying Corporation Income Tax in International Fiscal Association’, Proceedings of a seminar organised jointly with the EOCD in Toronto in 1994 during the 48th Congress of the International Fiscal Association. Van Rooijen, Martin J. (1977), ‘Interrelationship of Corporate Tax and Income Tax of Shareholders’, 31(2) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 64-68. Vanistendael, Frans and Gammie, Malcolm (ed.) (1992), The Ruding Committee Report on European Corporate Tax Harmonisation, Conference held by the Institute for Fiscal Studies.
6060
Corporate Taxation
235
Vanthienen, Lambert and Vermaelen, Theo (1987), ‘The Effect of Personal Taxes on Common Stock Prices: The Case of a Belgian Tax Reform’, 11 Journal of Banking and Finance, 243 ff. Vasquez, Nilda D. (ed.) (1981), The Corporate Income Tax: its Distributive Implications on Individual Shareholders, University of the Philippines, School of Economics, 8102. Vazquez Vega, Pablo (1996), ‘¿Discriminación positiva? La reforma del impuesto de sociedades en el Pais Vasco (Positive Discrimination? Corporate Tax Reform in Euskadi)’, Revista de la Camara de Comercio, Industria y Navegación. Vickrey, William, ‘The Corporate Income Tax and How to Get Rid of It’, in Eden, Lorraine (ed.). Village, George Paul (ed.) (1989), The Effect of Safe Harbor Leasing on Investment and Capital Allocation, Ph.D. Thesis, Notre Dame Press. Vines, Cynthia Carol (ed.) (1991), The Effects of Regulation on Corporate Tax Shifting : an Analysis of the Property and Casualty Insurance Industry, Ph.D. Thesis, University of Southern Carolina. Virolainen, Kimmo (1991), ‘Corporate Tax Exhaustion and Financial Policy: Evidence on Finnish Data’, 4(2) Finnish Economic Papers, 130-141. Vogel, Klaus (1990), World-wide vs. Source Taxation of Income - A Review and Reevaluation of Arguments. Vogel, Klaus (1995), ‘Introductory Notes in International Fiscal Association. International Taxation of Dividends Reconsidered in Light of Corporate Tax Integration’, Proceedings of a seminar organised jointly with the EOCD in Toronto in 1994 during the 48th Congress of the International Fiscal Association. Von Martens, Christel (1992), ‘Beskattning av Kapitalinkomster och av Foretagsinkomst ur Kommunal Synvinkel (with English summary) (The Effect of the New Capital and Corporate Tax Reform on Local Government Finances)’, 45(3) Ekonomiska Samfundets Tidskrift, 131-137. von Zur Muehlen, Peter (ed.), Some Partial Equilibrium Effects of Tax Reform on Corporate Policy, Federal Reserve Board, Washington, Division of Research and Statistics Special Studies, 97. Waggoner, Michael J. (1977), ‘Eliminating the Capital Gains Preference. Part II: The Problem of Corporate Taxation’, 19 University of Colorado Law Review, 18 ff. Wang, Leonard F.S. (1993), ‘Sector Specific Unemployment and Corporate Income Tax Incidence: A Geometric Exposition’, 37(1) American Economist, 64-67. Wang, Leonard F.S. and Conant, John L. (1988), ‘Corporate Tax Evasion and Output Decisions of the Uncertain Monopolist’, 41 National Tax Journal, 579-581. Wang, Shiing-wu (1991), ‘The Relation between Firm Size and Effective Tax Rates: A Test of Firms’ Political Success’, 66 Accounting Review, 158-169. Wang, Shiing-wu (1994), ‘The Relationship between Financial Reporting Practices and the 1986 Alternative Minimum Tax’, 69 Accounting Review, 495-506. Warda, Jacek P. and Zollo, Trancredi (eds) (1987), The Competitiveness of Canada’s Corporate Tax Structure, Ottawa, Canada Conference Board. Warren (1981), ‘The Relationship Between the Corporate and Individual Federal Income Taxes After the Economic Recovery Tax Act of 1981’, 27 Proc. National Tax Ass’n.
236
Corporate Taxation
6060
Warren (1989), ‘Recent Corporate Restructuring and the Corporate Tax System’, 42 Tax Notes, 715 ff. Warren, Alvin C. (1975), ‘Fairness and A Consumption-Type or Cash Flow Personal Income Tax’, 88 Harvard Law Review, 931 ff. Warren, Alvin C. (1994), ‘Alternatives for International Corporate Tax Reform’, 49 Tax Law Review, 601 ff. Warren, Alvin C. Jr (1974), ‘The Corporate Interest Deduction: A Policy Evaluation’, 83 Yale Law Journal, 1585 ff. Warren, Alvin C. Jr (1981), ‘The Relation and Integration of Individual and Corporate Income Taxes’, 94 Harvard Law Review, 719 ff. Warren, Alvin C. Jr (1985), ‘Corporate Integration Proposals and ACRS’, 22 San Diego Law Review, 325 ff. Warren, Alvin C. Jr (1987), ‘Taxing Corporate Income in the U.S. Twenty Years After The Carter Commission: Integration or Disintegration?’, 4 Australian Tax Forum, 465-489. Weisfelder, Christine J. (ed.) (1991), Linkages Between Tax Systems: An Analysis of the Corporate Tax Consequences of Transferring Royalties, Interest, and Dividends between Germany, Japan and the United States, Ph.D. Thesis, University of Michigan. Weiss, Randall D. (1979), ‘Effective Corporation Income Tax Rates’, 32 National Tax Journal. Werner, Ingrid M. (1994), ‘Capital Income Taxation and International Portfolio Choice’, 53 Journal of Public Economics, 205-222. Wetzler, James W. (1993), ‘Federal Tax Policy and the States: Corporate Integration’, 46 National Tax Journal, 393-397. Whalley, John (1984), ‘Regression or Progression: the Taxing Question of Incidence’, 17 Canadian Journal of Economics, 654-682. Wheeler, J. (1988), ‘An Academic Look at Transfer Pricing in a Global Economy’, Tax Notes, 87-96. Wickham, Dale W. and Kerester, Charles J. (1992), ‘New Directions Needed for Solution of the International Transfer Pricing Puzzle: Internationally Agreed Rules or Tax Warfare?’, 56 Tax Notes, 339 ff. Wilkie, Patrick J. and Limberg, Stephen T. (1993), ‘Measuring Explicit Tax (Dis)Advantage for Corporate Taxpayers: An Alternative to Average Effective Tax Rates’, Journal of the American Taxation Association, 46-71. Wilkie, Patrick J., Young, James C. and Nutter, Sarah E., Corporate Business Activity Before and After the Tax Reform Act of 1986. Willard, Kristen L. (1994), ‘Do Taxes Level the Playing Field? How U.S. Tax Policy Affects the Investment Decisions of Foreign Affiliates in the United States’, 29(4) Columbia Journal of World Business, 20-28. Williams, David (1995), ‘An Optimum Form of Article 10 of the OECD Model in International Fiscal Association. International Taxation of Dividends Reconsidered in Light of Corporate Tax Integration’, Proceedings of a seminar organised jointly with the EOCD in Toronto in 1994 during the 48th Congress of the International Fiscal Association.
6060
Corporate Taxation
237
Wilson, G. Peter (1993), ‘The Role of Taxes in Location and Sourcing Decisions’, in Giovannini, A., Hubbard, R.G. and Slemrod, J. (eds), Studies in International Taxation, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Winsen, Joseph K. (1992), ‘The Interaction Between Fringe Benefits Tax, Salary and Franked Dividends’, Sept Australian Tax Review, 149-154. Wiseman, Jack (1974), Theoretical and Empirical Aspects of Corporate Taxation. Wolfman, Bernard (1979), ‘Integration of the Corporate and Individual Income Taxes in the United States’, 33 Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 305-309. Wolfson, Mark, Alan, ‘The Effects of Ownership and Control on Taxes and Financial Reporting Policy’, 22 Economic Notes, 318-322. Woodside, Kenneth (1982), ‘The Symbolic Politics of the Corporate Income Taxation: Canada and Britain, 1945-1980’, in Stone, Alan and Harpham Edward (eds), The Political Economy of Public Policy, Sage, Beverly Hills. Woodworth, Jay N. (1990), ‘Different Economic Systems: Vast New Opportunities for Business Economists: NABE Presidential Address’, 25(1) Business Economics, 10-17. Wozny, James (1991), ‘The Taxation of Corporate Source Income in Jamaica’, in Bahl, Roy (ed.), The Jamaican Tax Reform, Cambridge, MA, Lincoln Institute of Land Policy, 265-323. Wu, Chunchi (1996), ‘Taxes and Dividend Policy’, 5 International Review of Economics and Finance, 291-305. Wu, Chunchi and Hsu, Junming (1996), ‘The Impact of the 1986 Tax Reform on Ex-Dividend Day Volume and Price Behavior’, 49 National Tax Journal, 177 ff. Yin, George K. (1990), ‘A Different Approach to the Taxation of Corporate Distributions: Theory and Implementation of a Uniform Corporate-Level Distributions Tax’, 78 Georgetown Law Journal, 1837 ff. Yin, George K. (1992a), ‘Achieving Corporate Integration Through Double Taxation’, 56 Tax Notes, 1365-1368. Yin, George K. (1992b), ‘Corporate Tax Integration and the Search for the Pragmatic Ideal’, 47 Tax Law Review, 449-468. Yin, George K. (1997), ‘The Taxation of Private Business Enterprises: Some Policy Questions Stimulated by the "Check-the-Box" Regulations’, 51 SMU Law Review, 125 ff. York, Harold L. (1993), ‘An Applied General Equilibrium Model of International Tax Competition among the Group of Seven Countries’, 15(56) Journal of Policy Modeling, 653-672. Young, K. H., ‘The Effects of Taxes and Rates of Return on Foreign Direct Investment in the U.S’, 41 National Tax Journal, 109-121. Zarin Nejadan, Milad (1992), ‘Fiscalite, q de Tobin et Investissement Prive en Suisse’, 58(2) Recherches Economiques de Louvain, 213-235. Zelenak, Lawrence (1984), ‘Serving Two Masters: Commercial Hues and Tax Exempt Organizations’, 8 U.P.S. Law Review, 1 ff. Zelinsky, Edward A. (1990), ‘Greenmail, Golden Parachutes and the Internal Revenue Code: A Tax Policy Critique of Sections 280G, 4999 and 5881’, 35 Villanova Law Review, 131 ff. Zelinsky, Edward A. (1993), ‘The Tax Policy Case for Denying Deductibility To Excessive Executive Compensation: Disguised Dividends, Reasonable Compensation, and the Protection of the Corporate Income Tax Base’, 58 Tax Notes, 1123 ff.
238
Corporate Taxation
6060
Zodrow, George R. (1991), ‘On the “Traditional” and “New” Views of Dividend Taxation’, 44 National Tax Journal, 497-509. Zodrow, George R. (1997), ‘A Corporate Cash Flow Tax as an Income Tax Integration Mechanism’, in Head, G. and Krever, Richard (eds), Company Tax Systems, Australian Research Foundation, 321-340. Zolt, Eric M. (1988), ‘Corporate Taxation After The Tax Reform Act of 1986: A State of Disequilibrium’, 66 North Carolina Law Review, 839 ff.
6070 INHERITANCE AND GIFT TAXATION Paul B. Stephan Percy Brown, Jr. Professor and Barron F. Blak Research Professor, University of Virginia School of Law © Copyright 1999 Paul B. Stephan
Abstract This chapter reviews the economic literature on inheritance and gift taxation. It discusses, among other things, the arguments for subsidizing transfers, the advantages of and problems with accessions taxation, the relationship of transfer taxes to income tax, proposals for unification of tax rates, proposals for base integration, special rules for transfers within family units, problems with interspousal transfers, and the implementation of generation-skippingtransfer taxes. JEL categories: K34 Keywords: Life-Cycle Assets, Transferor Tax, Accessions Tax, Interspousal Transfers, Generational Issues
1. Introduction Although death duties and comparable excises have existed since ancient times, long outstripping income taxation in length of history, no modern industrial or postindustrial state relies on estate, inheritance, or gifts taxes (‘transfer taxes’) for a significant portion of its revenues. As a result, transfer taxation plays almost no role in fiscal policy. Moreover, in most countries transfer taxes affect a small proportion of the population. In the United States, for example, less than 1 percent of all decedents who have died since the 1981 rate cuts went into effect have had to file estate tax returns, much less pay any tax. But for the few persons affected by transfer taxation, either as a potential transferor or transferee, the levy can be huge. For the wealthiest persons in the United States, a bequest to grandchild might be taxed at a 78.25 percent marginal rate.
2. Historical Pattern Perhaps for these reasons, the law and economics literature has not focused on transfer taxation to the extent it has on other tax issues. Rather, one may detect a pattern where, every generation or so, there takes place broad normative 239
240
Inheritance and Gift Taxation
6070
discussions of transfer tax design. The discussion plays itself out, usually without much consequence for the actual tax rules. The topic disappears from view, to return some years later. When less radical changes do transpire, the ensuing commentary reflects the broad-based literature but does not necessarily build upon it. Thus in the 1960s Meade (1964), Shoup (1966), Tait (1967), Jantscher (1969), and Andrews (1973), among others, either initiated or responded to proposals for systemic and expansionary transformation of transfer taxation. These proposals in turn drew on ideas propounded in Simons (1938) and Vickrey (1947). Two decades after this flurry of interest in increasing the effectiveness of transfer taxation, Bracewell-Milnes (1989) presented diametrically opposed, but at least as radical, proposals to abolish taxes on gifts and bequests. These works and the scholarly traditions to which they have contributed have framed a number of policy issues, some fundamental and others more technical, but have not provided definitive answers to any of the questions raised.
3. Role in Redistribution of Wealth Most transfer tax systems, and particular that of the United States, target the rich, either largely or exclusively. Much of the debate about these taxes therefore turn on assumptions about the existing distribution of wealth and the feasibility of effecting a redistribution. Both sides of this debate accept for purposes of argument the legitimacy of wealth redistribution as a social goal. Proponents of transfer taxation argue that ownership of assets is concentrated among a small portion of the population, that this concentration of wealth does not represent only differences in lifetime consumption, and that transfer taxation represents an effective way of redressing the misdistribution of economic power. These points are forcefully put in Vickrey (1947), Meade (1964), Shoup (1966), Tait (1967), Jantscher (1969), Kurtz and Surrey (1970), Brannon (1973), Graetz (1983) and Pechman (1987). Critics argue that measures of the concentration of wealth are underinclusive and therefore exaggerate the exent of concentration, that a large portion of wealth represents provisions against future consumption, and that the causes of inequality in society either are not related to family property holdings or cannot be remedied by a tax on gratuitous transfers of property. Variations of these points can be found in Collie (1973), Covey (1973), McCaffery (1994), Wagner (1977) and Bracewell-Milnes (1989).
6070
Inheritance and Gift Taxation
241
4. Life-Cycle Assets versus Capital Assets One important emprical question that underlies the debate over the efficacy of transfer taxation as a means of redistributing wealth is the proportion of wealth that is transferred gratuitously. The literature has developed a distinction between life-cycle assets, which represent household savings intended to finance future consumption, and capital assets, which households accumulate with the purpose of transferring to future generations. If most wealth is acquired for future consumption, a tax that applies only to transfers will not reach it. People would die holding assets only because of unanticipated mortality, and transfer taxes would serve only to punish the unlucky. If, on the other hand, a large portion of wealth constitutes capital assets, a tax on gratuitous transfers would have a significant impact on its ownership and could contribute to its redistribution.
5. Relative Mix of Life-Cycle and Capital Assets A sharp disagreement exists among researchers who have tried to estimate the relative mix of life-cycle and capital assets. Modigliani (1988) estimates that 80 percent of US wealth constitutes life-cycle assets, while Summers (1981) and Kotlikoff (1988) argue that more than half of all wealth represents capital assets. The gap reflects a dispute over how to characterize particular types of transfers, in particular income from inherited property and support of children over the age of majority but still in school. Underlying these disagreements are deep problems. In a post-industrial society, one might argue, the education purchased by affluent parents may prove to have greater income-generating capacity than financial property such as stock and bonds. This claim would support the characterization of tuition payments and similar support to students as the creation of a capital asset. But, at least in the United States, a substantial portion of the cost of education is financed by alumni, who make deferred payments in the form of nominally charitable contributions once their investment reaches its peak income-producing potential. If parental funding is incidental to education’s wealth-creating potential, then one instead might characterize education-related payments as a form of intrahousehold consumption.
242
Inheritance and Gift Taxation
6070
6. Research on Distribution of Wealth Aaron and Munnell (1992) provide a relatively recent review of the research on the distribution of wealth and the relative distribution of assets used for consumption and other purposes. W1 consists of tangible assets, equities and bonds, and the cash surrender value of trust funds and pension plans. W2 adjusts W1 to take into account the full value of trust funds and pension plans. W 3 adds the discounted present value of future social insurance receipts. The authors further attempt to estimate the distribution of life-cycle wealth and capital wealth by splitting the difference between the Modigliani and SummersKotlikoff approaches. If one looks only at W1, the data suggest that in the United States the proportion of capital wealth to life-cycle wealth has grown significantly between 1930 and 1990, which in turn implies an increase in the power of assets holders to wield dynastic power. If one instead includes W3, the data indicate that the proportion of capital wealth to total wealth has remained fairly steady. In other words, the rich are getting richer, but only at the same rate as everyone else. Other survey data suggest that the amount of W1 held by the wealthiest 1 percent of the population increased substantially during the 1980s, after the 1981 transfer tax rate cut went into effect, but these surveys do not measure W3 after 1983. Studies of Great Britain and Sweden show a marked decline in the concentration of ownership of W1 between 1940 and 1980.
7. Unconventional Forms of Property Part of the debate over the efficacy of transfer taxation as a means of redressing wealth inequality turns on the capacity of such taxes to reach not just traditional forms of property, but other kinds of rights, powers, and expectations that might seem analogous to property simpliciter. One much-discussed problem is the so-called ‘estate freeze’, which allows an owner to retain some degree of control over an asset while transferring the formal right to enjoy all further appreciation in the asset’s value. A simple example would be a restructuring of a family business in which the sole owner of a company transfers a new class of common stock to children while retaining preferred stock equal in value to the firm’s current worth. US lawmakers have taken several stabs at limiting the freedom of owners to achieve these results, notably in the Revenue Act of 1987 and the Budget Act of 1990 (which substituted a new scheme for the one created only three years previously). Most observers, however, believe that the capacity of families to accommodate their business transactions to the forms required by the tax law outstrips the ability of the legislature to attack the problem. As a result, the transfer tax seems largely an excise extracted from the inattentive or improvident wealthy. Shoup (1966) asks the question of why
6070
Inheritance and Gift Taxation
243
wealthy persons ever find themselves in the position of paying the federal estate tax, given the many means available for avoiding it. At the same time he recounts substantial anectdotal evidence indicating that some extremely rich people do fall prey to this levy.
8. Contribution of US Tax to Progressivity Reforms proposed in 1969 and to some extent adopted in 1976 broadened the scope of US transfer taxation but did not significantly change the rate schedule as such. In 1981 the United States both lowered the maximum tax rates applicable to gifts and estates and increased the amounts that could be transferred exempt from tax. In real dollar terms, the enlarged exemptions were still smaller than those in effect in 1932, when the federal taxes were made permanent. Nonetheless, a number of commentators contend that the 1981 changes represented a significant departure from the previous policy of promoting the redistribution of wealth. Graetz (1983) argues that the pre-1981 federal transfer taxes, although insignificant in terms of absolute amount of government revenues, were responsible for about a third of the total amount of progressivity in federal taxation. He defines progressivity as the increment in taxes collected from persons with greater than average wealth over the amount they would pay if average tax rates applied at all levels of income. He deplores the move away from redistribution implied by the 1981 changes. However, he does not consider the claim that such progressivity as the pre-1981 taxes achieved represented levies against unusually improvident or poorly advised persons, rather than a systematic effort to redistribute wealth.
9. Welfare Analysis of Voluntary Wealth Transmission The intuition that a gratuitous transfer represents a form of valuable consumption for the transferor while benefiting the transferee by increasing either capital or the capacity to consume appears in Simons (1938). The transferor has revealed a preference for the transferee’s welfare, which the transferor values at least as much as possession of the property transferred. The transferee is enriched by the value of the property, defined as the amount for which the property could be exchanged. A formal statement of the claim can be found in Becker (1974). The implications of this insight for tax policy took longer to work out. For Simons, it was enough to show that gratuitous transfers were economically indistinguishable from other transactions normally subjected to income taxation. Following a principle of strict nondiscrimination among categories of income, he therefore would have included the transfers in the
244
Inheritance and Gift Taxation
6070
transferee’s income tax base while continuing the existing rule of not allowing transferors a deduction. A Canadian government study proposed exactly this step in 1966 (Jantscher, 1969), and a study commissioned by the US Treasury explored the implications of such a system in 1976. Other scholars, notably Dodge (1978), also have advocated including gratuitous transfers in the income tax base.
10. Arguments for Subsidizing Transfers More recently, scholars have seized on the welfare implications of Simons’ insight to argue against transfer taxation. Bracewell-Milnes (1989) puts the argument in nontechnical terms by coining the term ‘owner’s surplus’ to connote the value owners attach to their assets in excess of the discounted present value of the asset’s anticipated income stream. He claims that gratuitous transfers, whether charitable or intrafamilial, increase welfare by bestowing owner’s surplus on transferees while providing transferors with value equal to the discounted present value of the anticipated income from the asset. Kaplow (1995) states the argument in formal terms and with great rigor. They both conclude that, to the extent welfare maximization is a legitimate social end, society ought to subsidize gratuitous transfers rather than tax them. Kaplow notes that a number of rules found in US law - income tax deductibility of charitable transfers, the treatment of gratuitous transfers as a nonrealization event to the transferor and as excluded from the transferee’s income tax base, and the basis increase for assets received from a decedent - might be characterized as a kind of subsidy for giving.
11. Arguments for Subsidizing Earlier Transfers A variation on this argument looks at evidence suggesting that younger owners may tend to prefer riskier investments than do older persons. To the extent this claim is true, it would imply that, ceteris paribus, younger owners might underwrite a greater amount of technological innovation and therefore increase social welfare. The data presented by Menchick and David (1983) is suggestive but not conclusive. Stephan (1986) uses this hypothesis to support an argument for tax rules that subsidize lifetime gifts relative to deathtime bequests. He notes that US law generally encourages gifts: the effective gift tax rates are substantially less because the tax is not included in the base, as it is with respect to estates. US income tax rules do disfavor gifts to the extent that gifts are not eligible for the basis step up to fair market value that applies to bequests, but in many cases this distinction is inconsequential because of the upward basis
6070
Inheritance and Gift Taxation
245
adjustment available to gifts subject to the gift tax.
12. Rate Differential Depending on Whether First- or Later-Generation Wealth Economists have made a somewhat different distinction between wealth in the possession of the person who accummulated it and inherited wealth. Rignano (1924) was the first to argue that either an estate or inheritance tax should base the rate of taxation on the age of the wealth. He would have imposed low rates on wealth being transferred by the person who created it and progressively higher rates on those who acquire wealth by inheritance and then seek to pass it on to later generations. He argued that such a system could achieve significant socialization of wealth without destroying the incentive to save and take risks. Kiesling (1992) returned to this proposal and defended it against criticisms based on its difficulty of administration. He proposed operating with a presumption that all wealth passing at death had been ‘aged’ and then placing the burden on the decedent or his beneficiaries to present evidence justifying lower rates. The US generation-skipping-transfer tax, discussed below in Sections 34-35, offers an alternative approach to an analogous problem.
13. Transferor Tax versus Accessions Tax Were all transfers taxed at a uniform rate, it would make no difference whether the levy fell on transferors or transferees. For most purposes the administration of these taxes is indistinguishable, especially if one party has secondary liability for the other’s tax obligation. But as soon as one introduces exempt amounts and a progressive rate structure, the identification of the taxpayer becomes significant. Estate and gift taxes calculate the amount owed by reference to the size of the decedent’s holdings. Inheritance and other accessions taxes look instead at what the transferee receives. The United States and the United Kingdom tax transferors, although their systems differ substantially. Most Continental European countries have accessions taxes instead.
246
Inheritance and Gift Taxation
6070
14. Advantages of Accessions Taxation Advocates of accessions taxes contend that this system has two main advantages over the estate tax (see Andrews, 1973, and Aaron and Munnell, 1992). First, to the extent gratuitious transfers involve life-cycle assets and therefore increase the transferee’s consumption, the tax should fall on the person engaged in the higher level of consumption. Second, to the extent that the tax is intended to encourage the redistribution of capital assets through dispersion of ownership, it should impose a lower burden on bequests to multiple beneficiaries. An estate tax, which does not take into account how a decedent spreads the estate among noncharitable beneficiaries, cannot do this.
15. Income Taxation of Transfers as an Alternative Accessions Tax A variation on the imposition of accessions taxes would be the inclusion of bequests and gifts in the income tax base, as advocated by Simons (1938) and Dodge (1978). The 1966 Canadian proposal contains the most detailed analysis of what this approach would entail. One important collateral consequence of including accessions in income would be the greater likelihood of high taxes during years in which a taxpayer received an extraordinary accession, such as a once-in-a-lifetime bequest. The Canadian proposal would have introduced a form of income-averaging to alleviate this problem.
16. Problems with Accessions Taxes A complication associated with accessions taxes is the opportunity trusts present for separating the transferor’s relinquishment of ownership from the transferee’s accession to wealth. The creation of the trust may give beneficiaries an expectation sufficient to alter their behavior but not create property interests substantial enough to sustain immediate taxation (compare Dickens, 1861). The problem does not exist in the case of trusts where all interests are fixed (for example, to A for life, remainder to B), because an inheritance tax can be levied on the discounted present value of a vested future interest. But it is easy enough to design trusts where vesting is delayed (for example, to W for life, then income divided equally among those of my children alive at the time of W’s death, then the corpus distributed equally to my issue per stirpes; only W’s interest would be vested). Nor is there a problem even in such cases, if the trust corpus grows at the rate that the designated discount rate assumes. The increased tax paid on distribution attributable to appreciation of the trust property would offset the benefit of deferral. But discount rates are only guesses
6070
Inheritance and Gift Taxation
247
as to future value, and become less useful to the extent that trust corpus does not comprise assets for which reliable and thick markets exist. Income taxation of the trust may substitute in part, but is not equivalent to an immediate levy at the inheritance tax rate on the discounted present value of the future distribution.
17. Withholding on Trusts under Accessions Taxation An alternative approach would be to impose a withholding tax on complex trusts that could be credited against accessions taxes due on distribution of trust property (see Andrews, 1973). To be a complete substitute for the ultimate inheritance tax payable, however, the credits attributable to withholding would have to be refundable and interest would have to be paid, by the taxpayer or the government as the case may be, on any difference between the amount withheld and the amount of tax payable at the time of distribution. Such refinements would add to the administrative burden of the tax and to that extent make it somewhat less attractive.
18. Relationship of Transfer Taxes to Income Tax Transfer taxes, and in particular taxes levied on transferors, are sometimes defended on the grounds that the property subject to these levies benefits from unavoidable but undesirable gaps in the income tax. Gutman (1981) argues that the US estate and gift taxes compensate for the income tax deferral implicit in the rule treating gifts as nonrealization events, and for the foregone income tax produced by the basis increase enjoyed by holders of propertry received from a decedent. More generally, capital assets tend to benefit from the realization principle, which defers taxation of capital gain until the holder sells or exchanges the asset. Imposition of a substitute tax on persons who benefit from these gaps brings the income tax closer to the ideal of nondiscrimination among types of income.
19. Difficulties with Nondiscrimination Principle Appeals to the nondiscrimination principle have a certain intuitive attraction but often obscure difficult issues. Recalling the concept of W3, for example, one might note that most income taxes do not include social insurance in their base. Yet transfer taxes for the most part reach very few people who benefit from this exclusion. The point is illustrative: all income taxes in practice contain many
248
Inheritance and Gift Taxation
6070
violations of a strict nondiscrimination principle, and the nondiscrimination norm standing alone does not suggest a weighting strategy that can indicate which violations should be seen as more serious than others.
20. Choice of Nondiscrimination Principles Moreover, as Andrews (1974) was among the first to note, to the extent existing law indicates adherence to any nondiscrimination principle, it suggests a commitment to neutrality among types of consumption, with a surtax on the kinds of capital held by the most wealthy. The US (so-called) income tax, like those of many countries, excludes from the base imputed rents from owneroccupied housing and most employer contributions to retirement savings. The exclusion of imputed rents in turn can be seen as equivalent to allowing an immediate deduction for the cost of acquiring an asset, as a consumption tax would require. And for the nonwealthy, housing and pension plans are the most significant forms of savings. In other words, when considered from the perspective of neutrality among types of consumption, these systems discriminate against financial assets such as stock and bonds, the ownership of which (disregarding tax-favored retirement savings) is heavily concentrated among the wealthiest persons. Taking this point to its logical conclusion, one might argue that the structure of the income tax implies an argument against any further taxation of wealth transfers.
21. Unification of Transfer Taxes Some countries tax gifts separately from deathtime transfers, others treat gifts as deathtime transfers if the donation precedes death by less than a specified period, and a few attempt to treat gifts and deathtime transfers as functionally equivalent. Aaron and Munnell (1992) and Andrews (1973) advocate development of an accessions tax that would include gifts and bequests in an integrated base, with the tax rate increasing with the amount of the transferee’s lifetime receipts. Shoup (1966), Kurtz and Surrey (1970), Brannon (1973) and Sims (1984) instead call for an integrated progressive transfer tax that would determine its rate by reference to the sum of the transferor’s lifetime and deathtime transfers.
6070
Inheritance and Gift Taxation
249
22. Unification and US Practice Before 1976 US law subjected lifetime and deathtime transfers to completely different levies. Gifts made in ‘contemplation of death’, a gloriously openended standard, were subjected to both taxes, but the gift tax paid on these transfers was both credited against the estate tax and excluded from the estate tax base. Since 1976, the US has had a partially integrated system. The rate of tax on estates depends on the decedent’s lifetime taxable transfers, and all transfers have a single ‘unified credit’ to offset gift and estate taxes. But gifts occurring more than three years before death (whether made in contemplation of death or not) enjoy a distinct benefit. First, a per-person exemption of $10,000 a year exists for gifts. The gift tax base does not include the amount of tax. By contrast, the estate tax base is tax inclusive. To illustrate, a US transferor in the highest rate bracket would part with $ 1,550,000 to effect a gift of $1,000,000 (disregarding the $10,000 exemption). A decedent in the highest bracket (because of lifetime gifts) would have to have a taxable estate of $2,222,222 to make an after-tax bequest of $1,000,000. Stated differently, the top gift tax rate, translated into tax-inclusive terms, is slightly in excess of 36 percent, while the equivalent estate tax rate is 55 percent.
23. Proposals for Unification of Tax Rates In 1984 the US Treasury proposed a more complete integration of the gift and estate taxes (Department of the Treasury, 1984). This would have been accomplished by increasing the tax rate on gifts. This proposal was not incorporated into the major tax changes enacted in 1986. Stephan (1986) subsequently criticized it for its failure to take account of differences in both the income tax treatment and welfare implications of gifts and bequests.
24. Issue of Base Integration A different kind of integration occurs when the same transaction comes under both taxes. A simple example would involve a trust in which the transferor retains income for life, remainder to the beneficiary. The creation of the vested remainder constitutes a completed gift and is subject to tax. This transaction, however, seems functionally indistinguishable from retention of full ownership until death, at least for those persons with no need to invade capital. As a result, US law for many years also has included the full value of the trust corpus in the decedent’s taxable estate. The decedent is given a credit against the estate tax for the gift tax payable on the remainder.
250
Inheritance and Gift Taxation
6070
25. Historical Dimensions of Problem The actual rules for determining which lifetime transfers are includible in the estate tax base are complex and inconsistent. During the early years of the US estate tax, the Supreme Court expressed its hostility to this levy by imposing narrow constructions on the statutory language. These decisions in turn provoked the Congress to overrule the Court through new legislation. In the period after World War II, a more liberal Court both repudiated some of its earlier decisions and imposed expansive constructions on the new legislation, provoking a by-then more conservative Congress to enact further legislation. The resulting hodge podge produces rents for professors and specialists but otherwise serves no apparent good.
26. Proposals for Base Integration Various suggestions have been made for cutting this Gordian knot. The Department of the Treasury (1984) would subject all transfers to either a gift or an estate tax but not both. It would have included transactions where the transferor retained some form of present enjoyment in the estate tax base. In all other cases, it would have imposed a gift tax on the value of the transferred property. Isenbergh (1984) and Sims (1984) offer schemes that differed in detail but in general followed the Treasury’s ‘easy to complete’ preference for earlier gift taxation. Stephan (1986) instead favors ‘hard to complete’ rules that would classify more transactions as deathtime. His rule would regard any transfer where the determination of the interest depends on the transfer’s life as testamentary. Thus in the case of a trust with income to accumulate, then the corpus to B at the transferor’s death, only the estate tax would apply.
27. Special Rules for Transfers within Family Units Most transfer tax systems, whether levied on transferors or transferees, contain special exemptions or reduced rates where the transfers involve specific family relationships. Transfers between spouses present particular problems, because the underlying law of ownership may depend on marital status. In the United States, for example, an asset acquired by a married couple living in a community property state often will become the common property of the couple, regardless of who furnished the consideration for the acquisition. In 1948 the United States sought to create a uniform national tax rule by allowing a 50 percent deduction for gifts to a spouse and a deduction up to half the size of the taxable estate for deathtime transfers. The 1981 amendments exclude most
6070
Inheritance and Gift Taxation
251
interspousal transfers from both taxes.
28. Implications of Complete Exclusion for Interspousal Transfers A rule of complete exclusion creates a hypothetical possibility for indefinite avoidance of the transfer taxes in cases where remarriage occurs successively. As a practical matter, however, the progressive nature of the transfer taxes still creates an incentive for most spouses to split their estates between the survivor and other noncharitable beneficiaries. All other things being equal, under a progressive rate structure a tax equal to twice the tax on half of a large sum is less than the tax on that sum. In other words, spouses still will benefit if their property is distributed in such a way that at least one is treated for estate tax purposes as having an estate that does not fall into the top taxable bracket.
29. Problems with Interspousal Transfers Transfers to spouses in trust continue to present problems. In the simplest case, namely a transfer to a spouse for life, remainder to the children, permitting a deduction for the spouse’s interest may present tax avoidance opportunities. If standard actuarial tables overestimated the spouse’s actual life expectancy or if the applicable discount rate underestimates the appreciation of the corpus, a present tax on the remainder interest will not be economically equivalent to a deferred tax on the full value of the property. US law instead denies a deduction for the spouse’s interest in most cases where that interest terminates and, upon that event, others acquire an interest in the property. The rules implementing this policy, which contain many exceptions, are exceedingly complex and have occasioned much litigation.
30. Nonspousal Intrafamilial Transfers Interspousal transfers aside, US gift and estate taxation generally attaches little significance to consanguinity. Most inheritance taxes, however, do increase the rate of tax with the degree of separation between transferor and transferee. As Tait (1967) observes, to the extent these taxes are designed to break up economic dynasties, this characteristic seems perverse. Bequests to children suffer lower taxes than bequests to strangers. Nor, in Tait’s view, do there exist other reasons for treating transfers among close family members more favorably than others. He dismisses one common claim - that inheritances from distant relatives come as windfalls and therefore are more easily surrendered to the tax
252
Inheritance and Gift Taxation
6070
authorities - as dependent on what he considers the dubious assumption that expectancy is correlated with closeness of relationship.
31. Defenses of Consanguinity Preferences In response to Tait, Richter (1987) argues that consanguinity rate reductions make sense if one regards inheritance taxation not as a mechanism to redistribute wealth, but rather as a form of social insurance. Drawing on Friedman (1957), Richter distinguishes between ‘permanent’ and ‘transitory’ inheritances. The former are reliable, in the sense that the potential beneficiary reasonably may make plans based on the expectation of receiving them. The latter become reliable only if the beneficiary can insure against nonreceipt. The market does not supply inheritance insurance as such, but a tax on transitory inheritances, to the extent that the tax receipts are converted by the state into commonly shared benefits, serves the same function. To conclude the argument, Richter maintains that consanguinity is a good proxy for the relative mix of permanent and transitory components in any given inheritance.
32. Consanguinity Preferences and Redistribution Cremer and Pestieau (1988) extend Richter’s argument to defend the consanguinity perference on grounds of promoting redistribution. Their model assumes variablity in the number of children, including the existence of childless transferors. They show that under certain plausible assumptions about inheritance patterns, wealth transferred to lineal descendents result in dispersion of property among children and grandchildren. Transfers to collateral relatives, however, may result in concentration of multiple couples’ assets in the hands of a single niece or nephew. A rate preference for lineal over collateral transfers thus may reflect a desire to disperse the ownership of property.
33. Generational Issues Although US estate taxation does not take consanguinity into account, the system does adjust the tax rates to take into account wealth transfers that skip over one or more generations. The argument for this surtax on generationskipping transfers is that the transfer taxes should function as a once-ageneration levy on financial capital. Moderately wealthy people transfer capital to children, with the assumption that the children will consume the income thrown off by the assets and then transfer them to grandchildren. Persons so
6070
Inheritance and Gift Taxation
253
wealthy that they can provide for their children and still have capital left over to transfer to grandchildren should be taxed as if their capital first passed through their childrens’ hands, whether or not the children directly benefited from the property. An exception to this policy exists for orphaned grandchildren, who are treated as if they were the transferor’s children.
34. Implementation of the Generation-Skipping Transfer Tax The United States first enacted a generation-skipping transfer (GST) tax in 1976 but deferred its implementation for several years. In 1986 Congress created a significantly different tax in place of the earlier one. The current levy imposes a flat rate of 55 percent on generation-skipping transfers in excess of $1,000,000 per transferor. The statute assigns persons to generations based on lineal relationship to the transferor; nonrelative transferees are assigned to a generation on the basis of difference in age with the transferor. The tax is calculated by reference to the amount received by the transferee, which means that any estate or gift tax generated by the transfer will not be included in the tax base. The amount of GST tax is, however, treated as a taxable gift. The GST tax on direct transfers is not included in the GST tax base, but the tax on generation-skipping transfers from trusts, either of income or corpus, is.
35. Technical Issues in Generation-Skipping Transfer Taxation The GST tax treats direct transfers to grandchildren more favorably than it does trust transactions that encumber financial capital and delay ultimate power to dispose of the property. Stephan (1986) observes that this difference parallels the lower rates imposed on gifts as opposed to deathtime transfers, and may reflect a similar policy of encouraging wealthy people to transfer control over financial capital to younger persons sooner rather than later.
254
Inheritance and Gift Taxation
6070
Bibliography on Inheritance and Gift Taxation (6070) Aaron, Henry J. and Munnell, Alicia H. (1992), ‘Reassessing the Role for Wealth Transfer Taxes’, 45 National Tax Journal, 119-143. Andrews, William D. (1973), ‘What’s Fair About Death Taxes?’, 26 National Tax Journal, 465-469. Blum, Robert (1973), ‘Estate and Gift Taxation Moderator’s Remarks’, 26 National Tax Journal, 439-440. Bracewell-Milnes, Barry (1989), The Wealth of Giving: Every One in his Inheritance, London, Institute of Economic Affairs, 112 p. Brannon, Gerald M. (1973), ‘Death Taxes in a Structure of Progessive Taxes’, 26 National Tax Journal, 451-457. Collie, Martin K. (1973), ‘Estate and Gift Tax Revision’, 26 National Tax Journal, 441-449. Covey, Richard B. (1973), ‘Estate and Gift Taxation’, 26 National Tax Journal, 459-463. Cremer, Helmuth and Pestieau, Pierre (1988), ‘A Case for Differential Inheritance Taxation’, 0(9) Annales d’Economie et de Statistique, 167-182. Dodge, Joseph M. (1978), ‘Beyond Estate and Gift Tax Reform: Including Gifts and Bequests in Income’, 91 Harvard Law Review, 1177-1211. Graetz, Michael J. (1983), ‘To Praise the Estate Tax, Not to Bury It’, 93 Yale Law Journal, 259-286. Gutman, Harry L. (1981), ‘Reforming Federal Wealth Transfer Taxes after ERTA’, 69 Virginia Law Review, 1183-1272. Isenbergh, Joseph (1984), ‘Simplifying Retained Life Interests, Revocable Transfers, and the Marital Deduction’, 51 University of Chicago Law Review, 1-33. Jantscher, Gerald R. (1969), ‘Death and Gift Taxation in the United States after the Report of the Royal Commission’, 22(1) National Tax Journal, 121-138. Kaplow, Louis (1995), ‘A Note on Subsidizing Gifts’, 58 Journal of Public Economics, 469-477. Kiesling, Herbert J. (1992), Taxation and Public Goods - A Welfare-Economic Critique of Tax Policy Analysis, Ann Arbor, MI, University of Michigan Press, 362 p. Kotlikoff, Laurence J. (1988), ‘Intergenerational Transfers and Savings’, 2 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 41-58. Kurtz, Jerome and Surrey, Stanley S. (1970), ‘Reform of Death and Gift Taxes: The 1969 Treasury Proposals, the Criticisms, and a Rebuttal’, 70 Columbia Law Review, 1365-1401. McCaffery, Edward J. (1994), ‘The Uneasy Case for Wealth Transfer Taxation’, 104 Yale Law Journal, 283-365. Menchik, Paul and David, Martin (1983), ‘Income Distribution, Lifetime Savings, and Bequests’, 73 American Economic Review, 672-690. Modigliani, Franco (1988), ‘The Role of Intergenerational Transfers and Life Cycle Saving in the Accumulation of Wealth’, 2 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 15-40. Richter, Wolfram F. (1987), ‘Taxation as Insurance and the Case of Rate Differentiation According to Consanguinity under Inheritance Taxation’, 33 Journal of Public Economics, 363-376. Rignano, Eugenio (1924), The Social Significance of the Inheritance Tax, New York, Knopf, 128 p.
6070
Inheritance and Gift Taxation
255
Shoup, Carl S. (1966), Federal Estate and Gift Taxes, Washington, Brookings Institution, 253 p. Sims, Theodore S. (1984), ‘Timing Under a Unified Wealth Transfer Tax’, 51 University of Chicago Law Review, 34-90. Stephan, Paul B. (1986), ‘A Comment on Transfer Tax Reform’, 72 Virginia Law Review, 1471-1496. Summers, Lawrence H. (1981), ‘Capital Taxation and Capital Accumulation in a Life Cycle Growth Model’, 71(4) American Economic Review, 533-544. Tait, Alan A. (1967), The Taxation of Personal Wealth, Urbana, University of Illinois Press, 283 p. Wagner, Richard E. (1977), Inheritance and the State-Tax Principles for a Free and Prosperous Commonwealth, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 95 p.
Other References Andrews, William D. (1974), ‘A Consumption-Type or Cash-Flow Personal Income Tax’, 87 Harvard Law Review, 1113-1188. Becker, Gary S. (1974), ‘A Theory of Social Interactions’, 82 Journal of Political Economy; 10631091. Department of the Treasury (1984), Tax Reform for Fairness, Simplicity, and Economic Growth - The Treasury Department Report to the President, 2 vols, Washington, US Treasury, 262 and 408 p. Dickens, Charles (1861), Great Expectations, London, Chapman and Hall, 225 p. Friedman, Milton (1957), A Theory of the Consumption Function, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 243 p. Meade, James E. (1964), Efficiency, Equality, and the Ownership of Property, London, Allen and Unwin, 92 p. Pechman, Joseph A. (1987), Federal Tax Policy (5th edn), Washington, Brookings Institution, 430 p. Simons, Henry C. (1938), Personal Income Taxation: The Definition of Income as a Problem of Fiscal Policy, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 238 p. Vickrey, William (1947), Agenda for Progressive Taxation, New York, Ronald Press, 496 p.
6080 INTERNATIONAL TAXATION Timothy J. Goodspeed Hunter College and CUNY Graduate Center
Ann Dryden Witte Florida International University, Wellesley College and NBER © Copyright 1999 Timothy J. Goodspeed and Ann Dryden Witte
Abstract We consider various systems for taxing international income (source vs. residency systems) and international transactions (origin vs. destination systems) and the empirical literature that has addressed issues related to such systems. The optimal taxation literature finds a conflict between static and dynamic efficiency considerations but fails to consider such important aspects of taxation as the benefits arising from public goods and services, compliance costs and administrative costs. Empirical work finds that the level of taxation significantly affects the location of investment and the way in which investment is financed. However, estimates of the magnitude of these effects of taxation are varied. Non-tax considerations (for example, political and economic stability) often dominate tax considerations in firm decision making. Firms use intra-company prices (for example, transfer prices) to reduce the total amount of taxes paid, but the magnitude of this type of evasion does not appear to be large. Countries often use their tax systems to encourage exports and to attract investment. Many tax treaties between developed and developing countries have tax sparing provisions that allow firms to credit unpaid taxes due to ‘tax holidays’. We suggest that future research on international taxation consider second-best worlds, incorporate administrative considerations and consider the effect of regulatory as well as tax regimes. This research could also usefully incorporate equity considerations and such non-tax aspects of international decision making as the availability of skilled labor, infrastructure and legal and regulatory environments. JEL classification: F2, F3, H2, K3, M4, O0 Keywords: International Taxation, Transfer Pricing, Foreign Investment, Tax Treaties, Capital Taxation
256
6080
International Taxation
257
1. Systems of International Taxation International taxation generally refers to the tax treatment of cross-national transactions. Since each nation has its own tax rules and the rules of one nation are rarely perfectly meshed with those of another, it is possible that income will be taxed more than once (sometimes referred to as double taxation) or that it will go untaxed by any jurisdiction. To prevent this, countries employ different methods. In principal, two methods of taxation have been distinguished for direct taxes such as personal and corporate income taxes: the territorial (or source) system of taxation and the worldwide (or residence) system. Under a pure source system, all income earned in a country is taxed by that country regardless of whether the earner is deemed to be foreign. A pure residence system taxes income regardless of where it was earned as long as the earner is deemed to be a resident of the country. An analogy to the familiar distinction between gross domestic product (GDP) and gross national product (GNP) may be helpful. GDP includes all income produced domestically, whether by domestic or foreign nationals, and is analogous to income taxed under the source method. GNP includes all income produced by nationals, whether at home or abroad, and is analogous to income taxed under the residence method. As long as those receiving income are classified by all countries in the same mutually exclusive way as residents or nonresidents, and all countries use the same method of taxation, there is no problem of double taxation. (However, there are efficiency issues, which we address in the next section.) Double taxation problems arise because countries have different residency rules and tax systems. For example, some countries use a territorial system when defining income while others use a residence basis for determining what income is taxable. Further, no country uses the pure form of either of these systems. All countries claim the right to tax all income generated within that country’s border; that is, all countries begin with a source basis for taxation. This is reasonable in terms of both tax administration and tax compliance. It is always easier to assess and collect taxes on income earned in the taxing jurisdiction. Source taxation also accords with the widely accepted principle of taxing individuals who receive benefits from public expenditures (the benefit principle of taxation). For the most part, the government of the country in which that taxpayer is physically present provides the public goods and services consumed by a taxpayer. Both efficiency and common concepts of fairness dictate that those who benefit from government should help to pay for it. However, most nations try to tax at least some of the foreign income of their residents. These attempts to tax the foreign income of residents result in a mixed source and residence basis for taxation. For instance, the US Government claims the right to tax all income earned in the US, a source system of taxation. However, it also claims the right to tax some of the income
258
International Taxation
6080
that its permanent residents and citizens earn abroad, a residence basis of taxation. Countries that tax such foreign-source income normally provide a credit for foreign taxes paid (up to a limit discussed below). Other countries such as France come closer to a true source/territorial basis for taxation. These countries generally exclude the foreign income of their residents from domestic taxation. Regardless of which method of direct taxation is used, the tax code must provide a set of rules determining residency. For individuals, residency is usually determined by a test based on the number of days an individual is present in a country. Unlike other countries, US citizenship also triggers the definition of a resident for US tax purposes. For corporations, this may be triggered by incorporation (as in the US) or by the place of management and control. The UK relied exclusively on the place of management and control until 1988. Since 1988, UK residency for a corporation may be triggered either by incorporation, or by the place of management and control. A second question in countries that tax foreign source income is the timing of such taxation. For a business, the way in which foreign operations are set up can influence when taxes are paid. For instance, a US corporation can set up an overseas operation as a branch, which is not separately incorporated. The income (or loss) of a foreign branch is combined with domestic income and taxed currently. The companies that tend to set up foreign operations as branches are concentrated in the banking and petroleum industries (Goodspeed and Frisch, 1989). Alternatively, the foreign operation can be set up as a controlled foreign corporation (CFC). CFCs are incorporated in the foreign country, but a controlling share of their stock (over 50 percent for the US) is owned by domestic shareholders. Except for certain types of income (described below), the income of a CFC is only subject to domestic taxation when it is repatriated. Since a CFC can delay subjecting its income to tax by not repatriating income, this feature of international tax law is commonly referred to as ‘deferral’. Many countries (for example, the US, Germany and Japan) allow deferral on undistributed income. These countries also generally have ‘anti-deferral’ regimes that restrict the types of income on which taxation may be deferred until repatriation. The US anti-deferral regime began with the addition of Subpart F to the US Internal Revenue Code by the US Revenue Act of 1962. Subpart F provides for current taxation of certain types of unrepatriated income of US CFCs. Unrepatriated income subject to Subpart F is treated as if it had been repatriated as a dividend. The income subject to Subpart F provisions has been broadened over the years and the US has enacted other anti-deferral rules. However, deferral remains important. The US Treasury estimates that deferral cost $2 billion in lost tax revenue in 1997 (OMB, 1996). See Ault (1997) or Gramwell, Merrill and Dubert (1996) for a detailed discussion of anti-deferral regimes in a number of countries.
6080
International Taxation
259
Residents of countries that tax on a worldwide basis will have their foreign source income taxed twice, first in the foreign country where the income is earned and next in the home country. Most countries that attempt to tax the worldwide income of their residents allow a credit or deduction for taxes paid to foreign countries. To avoid giving refunds for high foreign taxes, the credit is limited to the tax that would have been paid had the income been earned in the home country (usually given both the home country tax rate and the home country definition of the tax base). This creates two types of resident taxpayers; those that receive full credit for foreign taxes paid and those that do not. Taxpayers who are not able to credit all taxes paid abroad against taxes in their home country are said to be in an ‘excess credit’ position. Taxpayers who do receive full credit are said to be in a ‘deficit of credit’ or ‘excess limitation’ position. Two methods are used to determine the foreign tax credit. One method treats income in each foreign country separately in determining the credit. The second method determines the credit on a worldwide basis. Income and taxes from all countries are added to determine whether the limitation applies; thus, the taxpayer will be in excess credit if its (weighted) average foreign tax rate is greater than the home country tax rate. Consequently, a taxpayer may be able to reduce its home country tax liability because of the averaging of high and low taxed income. Consider, for instance, a multinational with a large proportion of income coming from investments in high-tax countries and a small proportion of income coming from investments in low-tax foreign countries. The multinational will not obtain full credit for foreign taxes paid; that is, it will be in an excess credit position. This firm would then have an incentive (absent under a per-country limitation) to try to shift income from high-tax to low-tax foreign countries so that the average foreign tax rate falls below the home country rate. The multinational will thereby obtain credit for all foreign taxes paid. (The shifting of income may not require actually shifting production facilities; it could be accomplished through paper transactions - see the later section on transfer pricing.) To combat this tendency of the worldwide credit system, some countries force multinational companies to make separate credit calculations for particularly high- or low-tax categories called ‘baskets’ of income. The US basket classification system is particularly complex. Prior to the US Tax Reform Act of 1986 (TRA86), there were five baskets. TRA86 substantially increased the number of baskets by expanding the Internal Revenue Code Section 904(b) interest income basket to include all passive income and adding four new baskets: (1) high withholding tax on interest (defined as 5 percent or more), (2) financial services income, (3) shipping income, and (4) dividends from each uncontrolled foreign corporation. This last basket potentially created a large number of new baskets since the credit on dividends from each
260
International Taxation
6080
uncontrolled foreign corporation had to be computed separately. The basket system is designed to prevent US taxpayers from combining high-taxed and low-taxed foreign income in order to receive a credit for taxes paid in excess of the US rate on one portion of income. To some extent, countries can be classified on the basis of whether their foreign tax credit systems are per-country or worldwide. The US, Japan and Iceland provide credits on a worldwide basis; Canada, Germany, Greece, Ireland, Italy, the Netherlands, New Zealand, Norway, Portugal, Spain, Turkey, and the United Kingdom use a per country limit in determining the foreign tax credit. However, as Ault (1997) notes, this division is somewhat misleading. In the UK, for instance, the per-country credit limitation can be avoided by routing income through a nonresident holding company. The income going through this ‘mixer’ company is considered all from one source, and hence averaged and the per-country limitation avoided. (There are no ‘pass-thru’ rules in the UK as there are in the US.) Ault suggests that the use of such companies is common. In principal, the resident system taxes individuals on their worldwide income. However, since most countries determine resident status by a test based on the number of days one is in a country, most expatriates are not residents of their home country for tax purposes. The US is an exception. Since US citizens are considered US residents, US expatriates are required to file US tax returns as well as tax returns for the country in which they reside. However, if a US citizen is not in the United States for 11 out of 12 consecutive months, the individual can exempt $70,000 of income earned abroad from US personal income taxation. Self-employed US citizens working abroad will still owe the 15 percent US payroll tax for Social Security, but this is often overridden by treaty if the US citizen pays the foreign social security tax, and the foreign social security tax otherwise qualifies for the foreign tax credit. Lower-level governments that form a federation sometimes use a somewhat different arrangement for apportioning the tax base of firms with operations in a number of different taxing jurisdictions. The approach used is called formula apportionment. The US states that belong to the Multi-State Tax Compact, Canadian provinces, and Swiss cantons use formula apportionment to tax corporations (Daly and Weiner, 1993). Formula apportionment can be considered a source-based approach to taxation. The formula used under a formula apportionment system divides the entire tax base of the corporation (for example, the worldwide base) among a participating set of taxing authorities. Each authority taxes only that portion of the tax base attributed to it. If all regions use the same formula and the same definition of profits, the portions are mutually exclusive and exhaustive, and the ‘worldwide’ base is taxed only once. Formula apportionment begins by selecting a set of indicators (for example, sales, property value, and wage payments of a corporation in the case of US states) to reflect the level of economic activity of a taxable economic
6080
International Taxation
261
entity in a tax jurisdiction. It then weights these indicators to form an index of economic activity in a jurisdiction. The jurisdictions split the taxable base on the basis of this index. In practice, one problem that this method encounters in the US is that states use different weights in determining the index so that the base ends up being taxed more than once. The economic effects of formula apportionment have been explored by McLure (1980, 1981), and have even been discussed in the context of the European Union (Daly and Weiner, 1993). On a broader international basis, formula apportionment is rarely used because of difficulty agreeing to the ‘formula’ and enforcing its use. A second set of taxes on foreign income, both for wage and capital income, are termed ‘withholding taxes’. These taxes are applied at source, usually on gross income. For instance, interest income received by a British citizen holding money in an Italian bank would have taxes withheld prior to remittance to the British citizen. The same holds for wage income: a US citizen working in Spain for a few months is subject to a 15 percent withholding tax. The income is also subject to US tax, although the individual can get credit for the 15 percent Spanish withholding tax. The reason for withholding tax on the income of nonresidents is principally for compliance purposes.Without withholding, individuals may fail to report such income in both home and source country. Bilateral treaties generally reduce withholding taxes on dividends and interest. In addition, the US has unilaterally eliminated its withholding tax on interest income (both for individuals and corporations). For a summary of reductions see Gramwell, Merrill and Dubert, 1996. Countries may also enter into information exchange agreements and other cooperative arrangements. Since tax treaties are bilateral and only cover selective countries, withholding tax rates can vary widely. This creates incentives to funnel income through third countries that have a low withholding tax rate. (See Giovannini, 1989, for an example.) As described in Hufbauer, Elliott, and Maldonado (1988), tax treaties grew out of recommendations by the League of Nations in 1927 as a way to reduce double and zero taxation, and to reduce withholding taxes. They also serve the purpose of stimulating international investment and structuring cooperation among different national taxing authorities. ‘Model’ tax treaties were developed by the OECD in 1963 and the UN in 1979. The OECD issued its most recent model treaty in 1994. These model treaties are meant to serve as general guidelines. The US has from time to time issued its own model treaty. The most recent US model was issued in 1996. Countries do not have tax treaties with all other countries. For example, France has treaties with approximately 90 countries while the US has treaties with approximately 50 countries (see Gramwell, Merill and Dubert, 1996 for a summary). Indirect taxes, such as sales and value-added taxes, also suffer from problems of double taxation. As with direct tax systems, international indirect tax systems can in principal be of two types: a destination system or an origin
262
International Taxation
6080
system. The destination system taxes goods where they are consumed and is analogous to resident taxation; the origin system taxes goods where they are produced and is analogous to source taxation. International trade agreements have set rules for indirect taxation so that taxes cannot be used to favor domestically produced goods. Under the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade (GATT) indirect taxes can be imposed on import and rebated on export. This is consistent with the destination system of indirect taxation.
2. Theory: Equilibrium, Efficiency and Tax Competition Having outlined various systems of taxation, we turn to the nature of the equilibrium under various forms of taxation and the relative efficiency of different systems. While the residence and source principles of taxation apply to labor as well as capital taxation, most of the literature discussing these concepts relates to capital taxation, and our discussion will therefore proceed in terms of capital taxation. The standard view is that pure residence taxation promotes efficiency in investment decisions while pure source taxation promotes efficiency in savings decisions. To understand why, we must first consider the nature of the equilibrium under source and residence taxation. Recent discussions of equilibrium in international taxation can be found in Keen (1992); we follow the notation of Keen. Consider two countries, A and B. Each country can be characterized by a representative investor who can earn a pre-tax return rk in country k. Each investor faces two possibly different tax rates, one on domestic income and one on foreign income. Denoting the foreign income tax rate with an asterisk, this means that there are potentially four different tax rates: TA, TB, TA* , T*B . Tk is the tax rate of an investor from k investing in k, while T*k'‘ is the tax rate of an investor from k investing abroad. An equilibrium is characterized by a lack of arbitrage possibilities for each investor. Hence, for the investor from A, equilibrium requires equality of after tax returns in each country: rA (1 ! TA) = rB (1 ! TA*). Similarly for the investor from B, rA (1 ! T*B) = rB (1 ! TB). Dividing the arbitrage condition for the investor from A by that for the investor from B yields (1 ! TA)/(1 ! T*B) = (1 ! TA*)/(1 ! TB). Since we have four possible variables for only one equilibrium condition, existence of a unique equilibrium is far from guaranteed. Despite these possible problems in the existence of an equilibrium, both pure source taxation by both countries (TA = T*B and TB = TA*) or pure residence taxation by both countries (TA = TA* and TB = T*B) present no existence problems. We now consider the implications of an equilibrium under pure source and pure residence taxation. Consider first the case of pure source taxation with differential tax rates so that TA … TA* (and similarly for B). Given the equilibrium condition for the investor from A, differential tax rates imply that
6080
International Taxation
263
rA … rB. That is, the before-tax return in A is not equal to that in B. Since factors are paid their marginal product, this implies that the marginal product of capital in A is not equal to that in B. If TA > TA*, then rA < rB, and we could therefore reallocate capital from A to B and increase total production. Another way to think of this is that differential tax rates have set up a fiscal incentive to locate capital in the low-tax country so that too much capital will flow to the low-tax country. Source taxation therefore is said to distort the location of capital and investment decisions. In its pure form, the residence approach leads to production efficiency. To see this, note that the definition of residence taxation (TA = TA*) implies from the equilibrium condition that rA = rB. There is no tax-induced incentive for capital to locate in one country over another with residence-based taxation. While residence based taxation therefore eliminates the incentive for capital to move from high-to low-tax jurisdictions, it may induce the owners of factors to change their residence. (The effect of such migration incentives are apparent in the decision of high income individuals to locate across the border in Greenwich, Connecticut rather than New York (avoiding taxes on capital income) or the migration of high income individuals from high tax countries such as Sweden.) Moreover, since TA … T*B, the after-tax return of an investor from A will differ from the after-tax return of an investor from B. Since saving depends on the after-tax return, a given level of world savings will be misallocated between investors from A and B. If TA > TB*, investors from A realize a lower after-tax return and will save too little, while investors from B will save too much. Since the value of an extra dollar of savings is greater for investors from A than for investors from B, we could increase welfare by transferring some of the future consumption generated from the savings of investors from B to investors from A. In contrast, source taxation leads to an efficient allocation of savings since investors from A and B face the same after-tax return. To summarize, source taxation leads capital to locate inefficiently (production inefficiency) but leads to intertemporal exchange efficiency. Resident taxation leads to efficiency in capital location but violates intertemporal exchange efficiency. In a first-best world (that is, when we can raise revenue without distortions), both efficiency conditions are required. These two efficiency concepts have often been captured in the literature by the terms ‘capital export neutrality’ and ‘capital import neutrality’. Capital export neutrality is associated with pure residence taxation: facing the same tax consequences at home or abroad, capital is neutral as to its location. (As mentioned above, it is not neutral as to its choice of residence.) Capital import neutrality is associated with pure source taxation: capital from abroad is taxed the same as domestic capital, so there is no tax discrimination for or against foreign capital. Horst (1980) and Dutton (1982) suggest that the optimal tax on foreign income will balance these two efficiency concerns; the proper balance, they
264
International Taxation
6080
suggest, depends on the elasticities of capital demand and supply. For instance, Horst shows that if the elasticity of supply of capital is zero and the combined tax on international income is equal to the tax on domestic income in the capital exporting country, the optimal tax on foreign source income results in capital export neutrality. Intuitively, there is no saving distortion for this case. To ensure an efficient allocation of capital, the capital exporting country should tax the worldwide income of its residents and provide an unlimited credit for taxes paid abroad. Horst also shows that when the elasticity of demand for capital is zero and the combined tax on international income is equal to the tax on domestic income in the capital-importing country, the optimal tax on foreign source income results in capital import neutrality. To ensure an efficient allocation of capital, the capital-exporting country should exempt foreign source income from tax. It is sometimes argued that capital export neutrality is more important, possibly because savings elasticities are often thought to be low and the elasticity of the demand for capital relatively high. Gordon (1986) points out an interesting parallel to the ‘production efficiency lemma’ of Diamond and Mirrlees (1971) that also supports capital export neutrality. Diamond and Mirrlees showed (under some rather stringent assumptions) that the optimal commodity tax system will lead to productive efficiency; that is, no input taxes should be used if commodity tax rates are set optimally. Gordon shows that it will be optimal for a small open economy to set its tax rate on capital equal to zero. As Gordon explains, since capital supply is perfectly elastic for the small open economy, a tax on capital will be borne by labor and hence will create the same labor market distortion as a direct tax on labor; in addition, however, the tax on capital will reduce capital investment in the small open economy, and will therefore be dominated by a direct tax on labor. The implication is that capital export neutrality will be part of the optimal tax system for small open economies. We suggest below some possible new directions for the literature on the optimal tax on foreign source income. First, given the reality that for administrative reasons all countries start from source taxation, it may be worthwhile for the theoretical literature to incorporate this important institutional detail that turns the problem into one of second-best. An interesting question to analyze is whether it is better to augment the initial source taxation by further source taxation (excluding foreign-source income from tax), by residence-based taxation (using a credit system to avoid double taxation), or perhaps by some combination of the two. Perhaps the difficulties in establishing an equilibrium has precluded this sort of discussion in the past, and this is a formidable problem to overcome; still, one might be able to use the approach of Slemrod (1988), for instance, to model an equilibrium and gain some insight into the efficiency consequences of current practices. Second, the optimal tax should incorporate administrative issues (for example,
6080
International Taxation
265
administrative costs, enforceability) as well as more traditional efficiency issues. (See Slemrod, 1990a, for an excellent and very readable discussion of optimal taxation that also incorporates administrative concerns.) Third, since no country has an unlimited foreign tax credit, the limitation is another institutional constraint that should be incorporated in the theoretical problem. Fourth, the literature tends to ignore benefits provided by the government that tax payments support; presumably owners of capital would willingly pay for government expenditures that enhance capital investments (for example, infrastructure investment). Fifth, externalities generated by capital location decisions have not been dealt with, and would presumably alter optimal taxation rules. As a normative concept, economic efficiency naturally refers to the maximization of world welfare. Positive issues of why tax systems develop in certain ways presents another set of issues. One of the first issues of a positive nature to be raised concerns the sort of tax system that maximizes national welfare. Musgrave (1969) (also clearly discussed in Caves, 1982) raises the point that a capital exporting country (that is large enough to alter the return on capital) will maximize national income by using a deduction system rather than a tax-credit system. This conclusion has a number of qualifications discussed in Hartman (1980), but still raises the question of why a large capital exporting country like the US relies on a tax-credit system. While international taxation naturally involves more than one country, analysis until recently has considered the situation of a single country under the assumption that other countries’ tax systems do not matter. Several recent papers, however, use game theoretic frameworks to analyze strategic decisions between countries that use a corporate income tax. One of the first is Feldstein and Hartman (1979), who find that if one takes into account the reaction of the (small) capital importer, the optimal tax from the large capital exporter’s perspective is even higher than otherwise, which seems to add to the puzzle of why the US has a tax-credit system. A more recent paper Bond and Samuelson (1989), finds that the only Nash equilibrium for two countries under a tax credit system is zero tax rates on capital. This is also found by Razin and Sadka (1991c). Bond and Samuelson find that a deduction system yields positive tax rates on capital, again adding to the puzzle of why we do not typically observe the deduction system in practice. In an interesting variation on strategic behavior, Gordon (1992) finds that if one country (for example, the US) acts as a Stackelberg leader, and countries use tax crediting systems, positive tax rates on capital income emerges as the equilibrium solution. Strategic considerations have also been a recent focus of international commodity taxation. In an early study, Mintz and Tulkens (1986) analyze the inefficiencies liable to arise from duopolistic competition in commodity taxes. One problem with these early studies is that no equilibrium in pure strategies exists because of discontinuities in reaction functions. More recently, Kanbur
266
International Taxation
6080
and Keen (1993) use a simpler model, in which an equilibrium exists, to examine the merits of cooperative tax agreements versus tax competition. They find that two countries with different tax rates may be worse off if both countries are forced to set an average tax rate, while both may be better off if a minimum tax rate is imposed. The literature on tax competition and international taxation is closely related to the fiscal federalism and local public finance literatures, a point made by Gordon (1990) and Goodspeed (forthcoming). A seminal treatise on fiscal federalism and local public finance is Oates (1972). Since there are several surveys for the reader (Wildasin, 1986; Zodrow and Mieszkowski, 1986; Rubinfeld, 1987; Oates, 1994) and since the focus of this entry is international taxation, we do not undertake an exhaustive survey. Rather, we briefly point out some similarities and differences, and suggest some ways that research on international taxation can benefit from the local public finance/fiscal federalism perspective. The key similarity of the literatures on international taxation and local public finance/fiscal federalism is that both study the taxation of mobile factors of production. The heart of the fiscal federalism/local public finance literature begins with the Tiebout (1956) model, which postulates many communities offering different tax-expenditure packages. The basic message from the Tiebout literature is that, given the proper type of financing (that is, given that consumers of publicly provided goods face ‘prices’ that reflect marginal social cost), individuals and firms will sort themselves among communities in an efficient manner. Tax bills (or effective tax rates) may differ across communities, but this will simply reflect differing demands for public services. An efficient locational equilibrium in the Tiebout model is therefore characterized by tax rates that differ across regions. This may at first seem in stark contrast to the international tax literature, but the similarity is evident upon further reflection. Two differences are particularly noteworthy. First, the Tiebout model considers both the expenditure and tax sides of a government’s budget. In contrast, the international taxation literature ignores the expenditure side, or, equivalently, assumes that the taxed factor gains no benefit from public goods and services that are provided by tax revenues. Secondly, a crucial aspect of locational efficiency in the Tiebout model is the method of taxation. Efficiency requires taxes that reflect the marginal social cost of a resident. However, as suggested by Oates (1972) and others, taxes such as income or property taxes may create externalities so that tax-prices diverge from social marginal cost. If externalities are present, incentives for inefficient location decisions are created. In addition to these problems, taxation in an open economy can result in several other sorts of externalities (for example, benefit spillovers); Gordon (1983) provides an elegant and concise derivation of the many types of externalities that may arise from local (as opposed to national) taxation.
6080
International Taxation
267
The local public finance literature has focused on cases in which efficiency is achieved in small open economies. Some, such as Hamilton (1976), argue that zoning laws in the US effectively convert the property tax (the major source of locally raised revenue in the US) into a benefit tax. If this is the case, and there are enough jurisdictions to satisfy different preferences both for housing and public goods, the taxation of mobile individuals will lead them to choose their place of residence efficiently. Moreover, a modification of Hamilton’s argument made by Fischel (1975) suggests that local property taxes on businesses may represent payment for disamenities suffered by residents from business location. Incidentally, the zoning argument is quite general. If one could zone on the basis of income, income taxes could also be converted to benefit taxes, at least for jurisdictions within a country. Such zoning is generally rejected on the grounds of equity and social stability. However, many immigration laws suggest that countries are well aware of the benefits of wealthy immigrants and the costs of poor ones. As international taxes may not represent benefit taxes, they may lead to location distortions. However, one of the first studies to measure the efficiency loss that results from income taxes in a general equilibrium model of an open economy (Goodspeed, 1989), finds relatively small differences in the way individuals allocate themselves under a head tax and under an income tax. Consequently, he finds a small welfare loss resulting from income taxation of mobile individuals. This suggests that the magnitude of the welfare loss from income taxes in an open economy may not be very large. The international tax literature tends to ignore the link between taxes and benefits that is the focus of the Tiebout model. Moreover, Wilson (1993) suggests that such benefits may be as important as taxes in multinational planning decisions. As Hubbard (1993) notes in his comment on Wilson’s paper, ‘part of the apparent insensitivity to tax considerations could reflect the link between taxes paid and the provision of important infrastructure (for example, in education and transportation support)’. This would be an important area to develop in further studies of international taxation. The fiscal federalism literature on tax competition has revolved around the type of financing that is used for public services. One of the first modern formulations of tax competition in local public finance is Zodrow and Miezskowski (1986), who show that if communities rely exclusively on taxes on mobile capital, an externality is created by the tax system, and competition leads to an underprovision of public goods. Closer to results obtained in the international tax literature is the finding of Oates and Schwab (1988) that if both benefit taxes and non-benefit taxes on capital are available, efficiency will result if governments choose a zero non-benefit tax on capital and finance entirely from benefit taxes. Goodspeed (1995) shows that political considerations are important for this result to hold. He shows that an
268
International Taxation
6080
asymmetric income distribution may lead to a median voter who chooses to finance via non-benefit taxes despite the inefficiency that results from the mobility of the taxed entity. This work suggests that political considerations could also be used to explain equilibrium outcomes of international tax systems.
3. International Taxation and Corporate Behavior A key question in the study of any tax is the extent to which the tax distorts behavior and thereby creates economic inefficiencies and alters the revenue potential of the tax. Broadly speaking, one can think of the effects of taxation on the multinational firm as affecting (i) the location of investment, (ii) the method of financing an investment, and (iii) intra-multinational transfer pricing decisions. We begin by discussing two opposing theoretical hypotheses about the effects of the tax system on multinational decisions concerning the location of investment and the method of finance. We then discuss the empirical literature on the effect of taxation on the location of investment, followed by a discussion of the empirical literature on financing decisions. Hines (1996b) provides a thorough review of the empirical literature on the effect of taxation on foreign investment and financial decisions, which we have relied upon. Finally, we discuss tax-related issues concerning transfer pricing and review the empirical literature on the prevalence of tax avoidance by judicious use of transfer prices. We have relied on Goodspeed’s (1997) review of the empirical transfer pricing literature. For a comprehensive treatment of transfer pricing issues see Lowell, Burge and Briger (1994). A starting point for understanding the empirical literature on investment and financial decisions are the theoretical works of Horst (1977) and Hartman (1985). Somewhat surprisingly, these two works come to different conclusions about the incentive effects of a foreign tax credit system. The traditional view, laid out by Horst (1977), is that incentives are different for excess credit and deficit of credit firms. The excess credit firm faces the tax rate of the country in which it invests on the margin; the deficit of credit firm faces the tax rate of the home country no matter where it invests. One way to interpret this in terms of our previous discussion of source versus resident taxation is that once a firm has hit the limit of creditable taxes (as is the case for an excess credit firm), the marginal return on an investment faces a source tax system, and the firm should compare the home and foreign after-tax returns when deciding where to invest. If a firm has not yet hit the limit of creditable taxes (the case of a deficit of credit firm), the marginal return on an investment faces a resident tax system and hence faces the tax rate of the home country no matter where the investment takes place.
6080
International Taxation
269
In contrast, Hartman argues that deferral combined with the fact that mature firms finance investment from retained earnings that are already abroad implies that the foreign tax credit position of the multinational is irrelevant for investment decisions. Both deferral and an investment financed from retained earnings that are already abroad are necessary for Hartman’s result. These two conditions essentially convert the tax-credit system of the home country into a source-based system; hence, the firm should compare the home and foreign after-tax returns when deciding where to invest, and the tax-credit position of the multinational is irrelevant. The Hartman result is often explained by reference to an analogy relating to the debate on the effect of dividend taxes in a closed economy setting. The ‘old view’ of dividend taxes assumes that dividends have some intrinsic value as either a signal (Bhattacharya, 1979) or as a control on managers (Jensen and Meckling, 1976). Hence, there will be an optimal dividend payout rate that balances the intrinsic benefit of dividends and their tax cost. But this implies that dividend taxes matter: a higher tax on dividends leads to a lower optimal dividend payout rate. The ‘new view’ of dividend taxes (King, 1974; Bradford, 1981; Auerbach, 1983) disputes this and suggests that dividend taxes are irrelevant. In the new view, dividends are ultimately the only way that the returns to equity-financed investment can be distributed to shareholders. Hence, according to the new view, dividend taxes are lump-sum taxes that cannot be avoided; consequently, they have no effect on the dividend payout rate. (See, for instance, Zodrow, 1991, for a nice summary and further discussion of these views.) The Hartman scenario is similar to the new view of dividend taxation. In Hartman’s case, deferral does not help firms that invest funds that are already abroad and must eventually be repatriated; the return on those funds must eventually absorb the home country tax. Hence, the investment rule for excess-credit and deficit of credit firms is the same: invest abroad if the after-foreign-tax return is higher than the after-domestic-tax return. While the Hartman result depends on an unchanging home tax rate (Altshuler and Fulghieri, 1994; Keen, 1990) among other things, it has become a focal point in many studies. Nevertheless, the difference between the traditional and Hartman views may not be of much consequence in terms of economic efficiency. As detailed in Goodspeed and Frisch (1989), there is little difference between the traditional and Hartman views in terms of the amount of US earnings abroad that face the foreign tax rate on the margin. While the Hartman view is that 100 percent of earnings abroad (of mature firms that finance from retained earnings) face the foreign tax rate, data from 1984 indicate that in that year the traditional view implied that 82 percent of foreign earnings faced the foreign tax rate on the margin. Under either view, therefore, most foreign earnings faced the foreign tax rate on the margin, as would be the case for a source-based tax system.
270
International Taxation
6080
Most studies of the effect of international taxation on investment location have concentrated on the United States, examining both US investment abroad and foreign investment in the US These studies have used time-series data, cross-sectional data, and a pooled approach that combines cross-sectional and time-series data. We first examine the time-series studies, then the cross-sectional studies, and finally the studies that pool cross sectional and time series data. Time series studies typically use aggregate annual data on direct investment collected by the Bureau of Economic Analysis (BEA), US Department of Commerce Department. Early time-series studies are based on the seminal work of Hartman (1981, 1984), and include Boskin and Gale (1987), Newlon (1987), and Young (1988). These early studies ignore the tax credit position of the parent, and so implicitly assume that the Hartman (1985) model is correct. More recent time-series studies have used somewhat more disaggregated BEA data. Swenson (1994) disaggregates the BEA data by using 18 industries, and tries to gain insight into the reactions to the Tax Reform Act of 1986. Slemrod (1990b), in the first study to actually attempt to test some implications of Hartman’s (1985) model for investment decisions, is able to use information on the tax systems (exemption versus foreign tax-credit) of seven countries that invest in the US. He does not, however, find much evidence that allows him to differentiate between the Hartman and traditional views for foreign firms investing in the US. Cross-sectional studies have also been able to tap into the BEA data by using country information; for instance, Hines and Rice (1994) use data from 1982 for 73 countries while Grubert and Mutti (1991) use the 1982 data for 33 countries. Hines (1996c) is able to generate enough data points for a meaningful regression using a cross-section of 1987 BEA data for 7 countries by exploiting differences in US state taxes. In contrast to Slemrod’s (1990b) study, Hines (1996c), does find evidence of differences in the choice of highor low-tax US states by foreign firms depending on whether the firm comes from an exemption or a foreign tax credit country, which contradicts the Hartman view (if the investment coming from foreign tax credit countries is financed by retained earnings already in the US). Data from tax returns have also been used in cross-sectional studies, either aggregated from the Statistics of Income (SOI) such as in Frisch and Hartman (1983), or at the firm level as in Grubert and Slemrod (1994). Several studies that use pooled time-series and cross-sectional data have used Compustat as a data source. Studies using pooled data include Harris (1993), Auerbach and Hassett (1993) and Cummins and Hubbard (1995). Other pooled data sources are Labor Department Surveys, utilized by Bond (1981), and Commerce Department Surveys, utilized by Ondrich and Wasylenko (1993). The time-series estimates that use BEA data tend to find an elasticity
6080
International Taxation
271
of investment with respect to the after-tax return in the vicinity of 1. This is true even through the most recent study of Swenson (1994), who investigates the effect of the Tax Reform Act of 1986. Cross-sectional results are more varied. Hines and Rice (1994) find an elasticity of the demand for capital with respect to the tax rate of about -3 while Grubert and Mutti (1991) find an elasticity of only -0.11. Cummins and Hubbard (1995), using an unbalanced panel of foreign subsidiaries of US firms, find an elasticity of investment with respect to the after-tax cost of capital of between -1 and -2. Hines (1996c) finds a large impact of taxes on FDI coming from tax-credit as opposed to exemption countries. While his elasticity is not quite comparable to those mentioned, his finding that a 1 percent reduction in tax results in a 9-11 percent increase in the share of investment coming from tax-credit countries suggests a large tax impact. The overall conclusion of this literature is that taxes play a statistically significant role in determining the location of foreign direct investment, but the magnitude of the impact of taxes remains uncertain. While time-series studies seem to produce similar elasticities of about 1, the rather large range of elasticity estimates that result from cross-sectional estimates indicates some uncertainty about the magnitude of the effect that taxes have on foreign investment. Additional panel studies that control for unobserved heterogeneity across firms, such as that of Cummins and Hubbard, may provide additional confidence concerning the range of estimates. One possible reason for the large effect found by Hines is that, by studying investment in a single country and using state dummies, he has effectively controlled for some unobserved heterogeneity that cross-country regressions lack. One aspect that a firm needs to consider as it evaluates an investment project is how that project will be financed. In general, a project can be financed from debt or equity; the way in which a multinational finances a project will have different tax consequences. For instance, as discussed earlier, those profits of a CFC of a US multinational (or the CFC equivalent of a non-US multinational) that are financed by equity (and not subject to Subpart F in the US or equivalent rules in other countries) are not taxable by the home country until repatriated as dividends. If the CFC is instead financed by debt issued by the parent, the interest paid by the CFC is taxable foreign source income for the parent. The interest payments are (usually) deductible in the country in which the CFC is located. As mentioned previously, withholding taxes (often reduced by treaty) are also usually owed to the host country for interest (as well as dividend and royalty) payments. If interest paid by a CFC is deductible and interest received by the parent is taxable foreign source income, a multinational that has a CFC located in a high-tax (including withholding taxes) country would do better to finance the CFC’s investment by debt since it will save money by deducting the interest in the high-tax country and paying tax at home. Countries tend to restrict the use
272
International Taxation
6080
of debt to some extent by using ‘thin-capitalization’ rules that specify certain limits in terms of a debt-to-asset ratio. The financing decision of the multinational is a bit more complex for the case of a subsidiary located in a low-tax country because of the Hartman (1985) argument. Traditionally, the argument is that an excess credit multinational might prefer to finance an investment project by equity since it could use deferral to avoid paying the high home country tax for a while. As explained above, however, the implication of Hartman (1985) is that deferral has no value because the present value of the deferred dividend will equal that of the repatriated dividend. Since after-tax returns are equated in equilibrium, there is no advantage to deferral in this view. One of the first studies to examine the dividend decisions of multinationals is Kopits (1972), who uses aggregate country-level data. Mutti (1981) is able to take advantage of tax return data for subsidiaries and finds that higher US taxes reduce dividend payments. Hines and Hubbard’s (1990) paper is the first in a series of modern studies on the dividend repatriation decision. They are able to take advantage of a data set constructed using three separate US tax forms filed by multinationals in 1984: the basic corporate Form 1120, the foreign tax credit Form 1118, and the controlled foreign corporation Form 5471. This data set details information on the parent company (including whether the parent is in excess or deficit of credit) and the repatriations of the parent CFCs. They not only find that higher taxes on dividends reduce dividend payments, but also that the excess credit position of the parent matters in the repatriation decision; excess credit firms tend to have a higher dividend pay-out ratio. This is inconsistent with the Hartman (1985) hypothesis. Two studies, the first by Altshuler and Newlon (1993) and the second by Altshuler, Newlon, and Randolph (1995), extend the Hines and Hubbard study. The first of these studies uses 1986 tax return data and specifies somewhat more completely the tax price of dividend repatriations. The second study uses a panel of tax data for the years 1980, 1982, 1984 and 1986 to investigate the effect of transitory versus permanent tax changes. Transitory changes are found to influence dividend repatriations, while permanent changes do not. This is consistent with Hartman’s view of dividend repatriation. One other study of dividend behavior focuses on a slightly different issue. Hines (1996a) compares dividend payout rates of foreign and domestic subsidiaries. He finds that foreign subsidiaries tend to have a much higher dividend payout rate than domestic subsidiaries; the additional personal tax that is owed on these dividends implies that the cost of capital from foreign investment may be higher than previously thought. As noted above, a multinational with subsidiaries in high-tax locations will normally do better (from a tax perspective) by financing an investment project by debt so that it can deduct the interest payments in the high-tax location.
6080
International Taxation
273
Grubert (1995) confirms this pattern. Hines (1994a) develops a model in which the opposite (a positive correlation between greater use of debt finance and lower tax locations) may result over a certain range. This is confirmed in his empirical work in which he finds a quadratic relationship between tax rates and debt levels across countries. Although most studies concentrate on the effect of taxes on one form of finance, taxes may cause substitution among different sources of finance. For instance, the 1986 Tax Reform Act (TRA86) restricted the deductibility of interest expenses. Interest expenses deemed to be ‘foreign’ are only allowed to be deducted against foreign, not US, income. The consequence of this is that foreign interest expense will benefit a firm in a deficit of credit position, but not one in an excess credit position. The deficit of credit firm will reduce its taxable income (and maximum credit) by the amount of interest expense; since it has not reached the limit of its foreign tax credit this means that it will reduce its US tax liability. An excess credit firm reduces its taxable income, but also its foreign tax credit by the amount of interest expense; hence, this type of firm does not benefit from foreign interest expense. Two studies (Collins and Shackelford, 1992, and Altshuler and Mintz, 1995) find that firms tended to substitute debt-like instruments for debt after TRA86. Grubert (1995) and Grubert (forthcoming) are the first studies to jointly estimate separate equations for dividend, interest, and royalty payments. Grubert (forthcoming) finds that taxes have a large effect on the composition of repatriations. That is, differential tax treatment of interest, dividends, and royalties is found to influence the form in which income is repatriated. Similarly, Altshuler and Grubert (1996) examine the complex incentives created when repatriation can flow through several entities. Rather than repatriating through different forms of income, however, they examine the flows between a multinational’s CFCs and find that tax incentives have significant effects. Finally, with respect to repatriation decisions, the role of exchange rate gains and losses should be mentioned. As the world moved from an era of fixed to flexible exchange rates, issues of how and when transactions would be translated into the home currency became relevant. One of the first discussions of the issues involved is Musgrave (1975). As she describes, the taxpayer was given much latitude in the translation of profits into the home currency. This can create problems for the taxing authority because the taxpayer will naturally attempt to time the translation so as to minimize taxes. Wahl (1989) notes that TRA86 in the United States tightened up on translation rules so that most hedging transactions are taxed on accrual, leaving the taxpayer little latitude to time the transactions. However, some transactions are still taxed on realization, which may lead to some loss in revenue through judicious timing of the translation.
274
International Taxation
6080
Although most empirical studies tend to confirm that multinationals are sensitive to tax considerations in their financial decisions, Hines (1996b), after a thorough survey of the literature, suggests that a more complete analysis would consider the fact that taxes influence financial and investment decisions simultaneously. This is one avenue for further study. In addition, nontax considerations may also play a major role in financial and investment decisions. As we have noted, the local public finance literature suggests that consideration of the expenditure side of the budget is important. This suggests that such factors as road and transportation networks, communications facilities, the quality of the local workforce (and hence investment in schools), and other public infrastructure investments may be important. Other regulatory issues, such as bankruptcy or bank secrecy laws, may also be a reason that firms willingly pay taxes when deciding where to invest. Finally, a country’s economic and political stability may also be an important consideration. We next turn to issues in intra-multinational transfer pricing. Multinational corporations, usually organized as a set of separate entities, typically involve a parent corporation and a set of subsidiaries. The parent is typically the major stockholder in its subsidiaries, often controlling 100 percent of a subsidiary’s stock. Various transactions may occur between the parent and subsidiary companies within the multinational, such as the sale by a subsidiary of an input that is used in the parent’s production process or sale of a trademark by the parent to a subsidiary. The prices attached to these transactions that occur between corporations within a multinational are referred to as ‘transfer prices’. While transfer pricing occurs (implicitly or explicitly) with any intrafirm transfer, the feature that has made transfer pricing so important and controversial is its possible use to avoid taxes. For instance, suppose that the parent is located in a high-tax country while the subsidiary is located in a low-tax country. Assuming that the multinational is trying to minimize its total tax payments, the multinational will try to price transfers so that most of its profits appear in the low-tax country. For example, if the subsidiary is providing the parent with an input, there is an incentive to charge a very high price for the input. Since this will result in high revenue in the low-tax country and high costs in the high-tax country, the effect will be to transfer profits from the high-tax to the low-tax country. The multinational’s taxes will be lower and its after-tax profits higher than would otherwise be the case. Transfers between entities that make up a multinational firm can be bi-directional. We first consider the transfer pricing decisions of a home country multinational that invests abroad (outbound investment), and then the transfer pricing decision of a foreign multinational that owns a corporation in a home country (inbound investment). For each category, we discuss the general nature of the problem and the empirical literature. Finally, we discuss some solutions that governments have implemented to try to reduce tax
6080
International Taxation
275
avoidance and tax evasion by means of transfer pricing. Transfer pricing can be used to reduce taxes for either the source/territorial or the resident/worldwide tax system. The simplest cases can be illustrated for a multinational that has foreign profits generated in a single foreign country as well as profits generated at home. Abuses under the territorial system are perhaps the most obvious: taxes can be reduced by transferring profits out of the high-tax country and into the low-tax country. A purported advantage of the worldwide system is that this incentive disappears for a multinational that invests in a single foreign country with a tax rate lower than the home country. In this case, income derived from the foreign investment will be taxed at the home country tax rate and the incentive to shift income is eliminated. However, several complications of the tax systems of countries that purport to use the worldwide system of taxation allow multinationals to use transfer pricing to reduce taxes. First, consider a multinational in a low-tax country that invests in a single high-tax country. By definition, this firm would be in an excess credit position. The multinational will not receive a credit in its home country for some of the taxes paid in the high-tax country unless it is able to shift some income back to its low-tax home. The multinational can use transfer prices to shift profits to the home country. Second, since multinationals typically have investments in a variety of foreign countries, the way in which the credit is computed is important. As mentioned above, some countries aggregate income over all foreign countries in determining the limit. In addition, the use of ‘mixer’ companies in countries that use a per-country limitation can also result in income averaging. For these countries, a multinational with a large proportion of income coming from investments in high-tax countries and a small proportion of income coming from investments in low-tax foreign countries will not obtain full credit for foreign taxes paid. This firm would then have an incentive to use transfer prices to shift income from high-tax to low-tax foreign countries and thereby obtain credit for all foreign taxes paid. Third, the use of deferral effectively converts a worldwide tax system into a territorial system, at least until profits are repatriated. Although Subpart F provisions in the United States have limited deferral, the transfer pricing problems associated with territorial tax systems become relevant when a worldwide system incorporates deferral. The evidence on the use of transfer pricing is consistent with tax-minimizing behavior, although the magnitude of abusive transfer pricing appears to be moderate. Outbound investment by US multinationals has been investigated by Harris, et al. (1993), who use Compustat data to investigate whether taxes paid to the US are influenced by the location of the multinational’s profits overseas. Since the US taxes multinationals based on a worldwide system and computes the foreign tax credit by aggregating on a worldwide basis, the multinational can get credit for income tax paid in a
276
International Taxation
6080
country with a tax rate higher than the US rate by judicious use of transfer pricing. It simply needs to shift income from a high tax to a low tax location so as to avoid hitting the credit limit. Harris, et al. find that a multinational that has a subsidiary in a low (high) tax country has a lower (higher) than average ratio of US tax to US assets. This is consistent with the use of transfer pricing to minimize worldwide taxes, although they find that the aggregate effect on US tax revenues is moderate. Hines and Rice (1994) investigate transfer pricing of outbound investment by concentrating on the use of ‘tax havens’ (a set of very low-tax foreign countries) by US multinationals. They find that reported profit rates are sensitive to local tax rates, although they note that this may not be bad for US revenue since the US is now a relatively low-tax country. A US multinational whose foreign source income comes primarily from a high tax country will not be subject to additional US tax. If however, the multinational is able to shift income so that its foreign source income appears to come primarily from a low tax country, the US will gain tax revenue equal to the difference between taxes paid and what would be paid in the US We next consider transfer prices used by foreign corporations operating in the home country (that is, inbound investment) to transfer profits out and so avoid home country taxes. This has become an important topic, particularly in the United States, because the aggregate rate of return for foreign-controlled companies in the US is observed to be much lower than the rate of return of domestically controlled companies. A concern expressed by the US Congress is that foreign-controlled US corporations are not paying their fair share of US taxes. The suggested culprit is transfer pricing. There are several reasons other than transfer pricing that might explain low rates of return of foreign-controlled companies operating in a home country. First, foreign companies may at first experience a lower than average rate of return because of the revaluation of the assets of new acquisitions or because of the start-up costs of a new business. Second, a low average rate of return in any one year may not be indicative of a long-run trend. That is, although foreign companies may have difficulty in adjusting to the nuances of a foreign market at first, one would expect this to change over time as the firms mature. Finally, unexpected changes in exchange rates can have a large effect on profits. An unexpected fall in the dollar, for instance, would increase the cost of components imported into the US and therefore temporarily decrease the profits of a foreign-controlled company in the US. This effect also would be expected to diminish over time. Inbound investment in the US is investigated by Grubert, Goodspeed and Swenson (1993) using both a 1987 cross-section and a 1980-87 panel data set. They use data from the tax returns of US corporations to investigate the difference in taxes paid by foreign-controlled as opposed to US-controlled corporations. The aggregate data suggests a much lower ratio of taxable income
6080
International Taxation
277
to assets for foreign-controlled corporations. However, the authors find that the revaluation of assets after merger or acquisition (captured by an age effect), exchange rate changes and a maturation effect account for about half of the difference. The remaining difference could be due to transfer pricing, and the authors present some evidence that indicates that foreign-controlled companies tend to be more concentrated at zero taxable income than domestic companies. They also remain in the zero-profit state longer than domestic companies. This suggests that transfer pricing may be used to some extent to reduce taxes, although less than feared when the transfer pricing issue first arose in the US Congress. Grubert (1997) updates the study of Grubert, Goodspeed and Swenson by repeating the previous analysis (with some modifications) for a 1993 cross-section and a 1987-1993 panel. He finds that for some specifications purely cross-sectional variables can explain almost 50 percent of the difference in rates of return, rather than the 25 percent explained in the previous study. This appears to be partly due to the fact that US companies are receiving more income from foreign dividends. The panel estimation corroborates the earlier finding of a maturation effect. Overall, Grubert is able to explain somewhat more than the earlier 50 percent (up to 75 percent) of the difference between foreign-controlled and US-controlled corporate returns in the US. Since transfer pricing can be used to evade taxes, governments have naturally developed a set of rules to try to minimize this potential source of tax evasion. The problem is to find an ‘objective’ way of valuing tangible and intangible assets transferred across national boundaries by multinational corporations. The widely accepted international standard is that such transfers be assigned the prices that would have been charged if the transactions had occurred between independent entities. Such prices are referred to as ‘arm’s length’ prices. The basic notion is that a transaction between a parent and its subsidiary should be priced as if it had occurred between two unrelated parties in a competitive market. However, arm’s length transfer prices are not always easy to calculate because comparable transactions by unrelated parties may not exist. This issue is pervasive for intangible assets because the value of most intangible asset arises from market power generated by the intangible. For example, how should McDonald’s price the right to use its golden arches? McDonald’s does not sell use of its golden arches to unrelated parties. The value of the golden arches arises from the rents that the use of this trademark generates. There are no comparable arm’s length prices and alternative methods for pricing this type of transfer must be used. A general framework and some specific standards for transfer pricing are suggested in OECD (1979). Revisions have recently been proposed in OECD (1995). Specific rules that are acceptable to a country’s taxing authority
278
International Taxation
6080
generally vary from country to country but, in general, the prices charged in comparable arm’s length transactions are preferred. (See Ault, 1997, for a discussion of practices in several countries, and Molina Gómez-Arnáu, 1997, for the case of Spain.) When exactly comparable transactions do not exist, the government often provides some guidance in the form of regulations or case law (usually based on OECD, 1979) on the range of transfer prices that will be deemed acceptable. Such guidance may include a cost-plus calculation, reference to some industry average such as a rate of return on assets or a margin on sales, or attempts to adjust ‘inexact’ comparables to obtain transfer prices. Profit-based methods (for example, ‘comparable profits’) as opposed to transactions methods tend to be the most controversial. Some countries do not allow comparable profits methods. The methodology used to determine the proper transfer price has become increasingly sophisticated. Frisch (1989) and Witte and Chipty (1990) suggest the use of the capital asset pricing model to determine a proper return for a project. Appropriate transfer prices are then calculated as the prices necessary for the project to have that rate of return. Horst (1993) suggests using regression analysis to determine an appropriate rate of return. The US Internal Revenue Service (IRS) has adopted an open approach on the methods used to obtain transfer prices. Multinational companies may now propose a method for determining transfer prices. The IRS examines the proposed method and determines whether or not the methodology is acceptable. If the methodology is acceptable, the IRS enters into an ‘advanced pricing agreement’ (APA) with the multinational. The agreement allows the multinational to use the mutually agreed upon methodology to set transfer prices for the firm for a period of 3 to 5 years. The APA may involve the other countries impacted by the agreed transfer price. APAs are also possible in some other countries (for example, Germany and The Netherlands). One of the more subtle elements of corporate international taxation is that the tax system can be used to create subsidies. Although the thrust of the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade (GATT) is to prohibit discrimination between domestic and foreign produced goods, corporate tax systems have been used to subsidize exports and investment. We consider below two specific US tax provisions (foreign sales corporations and sales source rules) that provide subsidies for goods exported from the US. We then consider the general concept of tax holidays, and its relation to tax sparing in tax treaties. The US Congress created Domestic International Sales Corporations (DISCs) in 1971. DISCs were essentially conduits through which export transactions could be recorded. Exports carried out through DISCs received favorable tax treatment. This subsidy was found to be in violation of GATT’s prohibition of export subsidies in 1976. The reaction of the US was to replace DISCs by Foreign Sales Corporations (FSCs), which perform much the same
6080
International Taxation
279
function, but are able to pass muster under GATT rules. As long as title is passed overseas, a portion of FSC income is exempt from US tax; hence, a subsidy is created for a product to be produced domestically and exported rather than manufactured and sold abroad. A second type of export incentive in the US tax code is that produced by the sales source rules (Section 863(b) of the US Internal Revenue Code). These rules allow a multinational to reclassify part of its export income as foreign source. If a multinational is in an excess credit position, the US tax rate times foreign source income is the binding constraint on the foreign tax credit. Hence, each dollar that an excess credit firm is able to reclassify as foreign rather than domestic source will result in extra foreign tax credit equal to the US tax rate. For example, if a multinational is in an excess credit position and faces a US tax rate of 35 percent, each dollar that it is able to reclassify as foreign rather than domestic source will result in savings of $0.35. The rules thus provide an incentive for US excess credit multinationals to export rather than produce abroad. While the US Treasury issues periodic reports on FSCs, little academic literature has investigated the export incentives hidden in corporate tax codes. An early exception is Horst and Pugel (1977). One recent study is Rousslang and Tokarick (1994), who use a general equilibrium model to examine the consequences of the tax-based export incentives. They find that the tax provisions increase the volume of trade but that domestic welfare is worsened because the terms of trade are worsened for the US. Apart from export incentives, a second set of tax subsidies arise because of developing countries’ efforts to attract multinational investment. Many developing countries give multinationals ‘tax holidays’. During periods of tax holiday, multinationals may pay no taxes or, at a minimum, lower taxes than would otherwise be due. Such tax breaks only provide incentives for multinationals to invest in the developing country if the multinational’s home country taxes on a source basis. For countries that tax on a worldwide basis, tax holidays provide no incentive to locate in the developing country since the income of the multinational will be taxed at the home country rate. Recognizing this, some countries (for example, Germany and Japan) that tax on a worldwide basis allow their multinationals credit for such tax holidays; that is, they allow credit for taxes that have not actually been paid. This is often referred to as ‘tax sparing’. Tax sparing provisions are often written into tax treaties between a developed and a developing country. Although most countries grant tax sparing in treaties with many developing countries, the US does not. However, the US has had a set of rules (contained in Section 936 of the US Internal Revenue Code) that provide tax subsidies for corporations that locate in US Possessions (the primary beneficiary being Puerto Rico). In part, Section 936 allows tax sparing, and since Puerto Rico
280
International Taxation
6080
offers tax holidays, US multinationals received tax credits for taxes that were not actually paid to Puerto Rico. The 936 rules were tightened in 1993, however, through a limitation on the allowable tax credit. Further, 1996 legislation began a phase out of Section 936. It is scheduled to be eliminated completely by 2005. While the US Treasury provides periodic reports on the tax treatment of Possessions’ corporations, the academic literature on the effect of Section 936 is sparse. One older study is that of Bond (1981). Grubert and Slemrod (1994) provide a more recent study of the effect of Section 936 in Puerto Rico. Grubert and Slemrod’s findings suggest that firms with high levels of intangible assets (for example, drug companies) located in Puerto Rico because it was relatively easy, through transfer pricing, to shift profits to Puerto Rico. The profits thus shifted gained the tax advantage provided by Section 936.
4. Issues in International Indirect Taxation The destination and origin principles for indirect taxation are analogous to the source and resident principles for direct taxation. The difference between the destination and origin principles is that the destination principle imposes tax where consumption takes place whereas the origin principle imposes tax where production takes place. As with source taxation, one might argue that the origin principle distorts the location of production. As with resident taxation, one might argue that the destination principle causes distortions in relative savings decisions across countries. Despite the analogy of the destination and origin principles for indirect taxation and the source and resident principles for direct taxation, and our previous discussion of the efficiency differences of the source and resident principles for direct taxation, much has been made of the fact that the destination and origin principles of indirect taxation are, under certain conditions, equivalent. This is noted in Cnossen and Shoup (1987) and demonstrated formally in Lockwood, de Meza and Myles (1994a). The equivalence comes from the fact that balanced trade implies that aggregate production and aggregate consumption are the same. Consequently, a destination based tax (on aggregate consumption) and an origin-based tax (on aggregate production) are equivalent. However, this result requires some very strong assumptions, and there are several models, outlined in Keen and Smith (1996), in which the equivalence result fails to hold. One such model is an overlapping generations model of Bovenberg (1994) in which the two principles can have different intergenerational effects. A second situation in which equivalence fails is when countries do not tax all commodities at a uniform rate. See Sinn (1990) and Feldstein and Krugman (1990).
6080
International Taxation
281
Assuming that the equivalence result does not hold brings us back to our discussion concerning efficiency for direct taxation and the trade-off between production efficiency and exchange efficiency. Again appeal might be made to the Diamond and Mirrlees (1971) result that the optimal commodity tax system is characterized by production efficiency, which would suggest a preference for the destination principle. However, the Diamond-Mirrlees framework is one of perfect competition and 100 percent taxation of pure profits. Some interesting new work relaxes some of these assumptions and indicates some scope for origin taxation in an optimal tax system. For instance, Keen and Lahiri (1996) consider a model of Cournot duopolists. As noted in Keen and Smith (1996), part of the difference in this type of setting is that, unlike the Diamond-Mirrlees framework, it is recognized that countries have their own distinct revenue constraints. Again, the relevance of the fiscal federalism literature, which studies the relationship between jurisdictions with distinct revenue constraints, is evident. A somewhat different tact would be to investigate models of illegal activity. For instance, there may be an incentive under destination taxes to bypass legal rules and smuggle goods from low-tax/low-enforcement countries to countries with high and well enforced consumption taxes. Much of the recent interest in these issues has arisen because of the elimination of controls on the movement of both capital and labor in the European Union. (But see also Grubert and Newlon, 1995 for an examination of recent proposals in the US to replace the income tax with a consumption tax.) European countries typically raise a substantial portion of revenue through value-added taxes (VATs). As these countries eliminate controls on the movement of both capital and labor, there is increasing concern about the possibility of cross-border shopping that could result from VAT systems that have different tax rates applied to the same products. A good review of some of the early concerns can be found in Cnossen and Shoup (1987) and Lee, Pearson and Smith (1988); a more recent treatment is that of Keen and Smith (1996). The issues here are whether consumers would engage in cross-border shopping to avoid high taxes, whether competition would force these taxes to some common rate, and the welfare impacts of these possibilities. These issues are directly related to the tax competition literature mentioned earlier, and some papers mentioned there (for example, Mintz and Tulkens, 1986; Kanbur and Keen, 1993) explicitly address tax competition for indirect rather than direct taxes. One practical set of issues for the European Union’s concerns how countries can best make ‘border adjustments’, that is, the rebate of VAT on export and its imposition on import. The required tax adjustments have been made at the border and, hence, the term border adjustments. Cnossen (1983) has proposed that a ‘clearinghouse’ be set up to handle border adjustments. Under the clearinghouse proposal, a country would, in the aggregate, either be net owers or receivers of VAT revenue depending on their trade balance and VAT rates.
282
International Taxation
6080
The function of the clearinghouse would be to determine the net position of each country rather than have countries give or receive VAT on a transaction by transaction basis. The European Commission has considered this proposal, but has not been able to come to agreement. Instead, they moved in 1993 to a transitional system. This system has eliminated border adjustments for consumer purchases for personal use (so that personal consumption purchases are now taxed on the origin principle), although border adjustments are still made for transactions between firms. Keen and Smith (1996) point out a number of problems with the transitional system, and propose an alternative, which they call a Viable Integrated VAT (VIVAT). They compare the VIVAT to the transitional system as well as other systems (including a clearinghouse mechanism), and suggest that the VIVAT is superior. VIVAT, as described by them, is a combination of harmonized VAT rates and different retail sales tax rates. Their proposal combines the origin and destination principles, and offers the advantage of national autonomy in setting taxes (emphasized in the fiscal federalism literature) with the self-policing advantages often ascribed to VAT.
5. Some Suggestions for Future Research To date, work on the efficiency effects of various methods of international taxation have assumed a first-best world. The complexity and many distortions present in the international arena suggest that work that considers a world with distortions other than those caused by the international tax regime would be useful. The administration of international taxes has received relatively little attention. Careful examination of the administrative provisions of tax treaties might provide a useful base for thinking about administrative issues. Application of the arm’s length standard often involves very high transaction costs. Tax agencies experiences with Advanced Pricing Agreements might provide some guidance for alternative systems. It would be important to estimate and compare both the efficiency and transactions costs of the arm’s length standard and other proposed systems. To date most work on international taxation has considered only efficiency effects. Interesting new insights might be obtained by examining equity and public choice considerations. In this context examinations of tax sparing provision might be interesting. Comparisons of the US that does not have tax sparing provisions (except with Possessions) with European countries and Japan that have tax sparing provisions with many developing countries could be revealing.
6080
International Taxation
283
Increases in the flow of financial services and the opening of telecommunication markets raise important new issues regarding the way in which international tax and regulatory regimes interact. While research that introduces regulations as well as taxation would be difficult, such work could provide important new insights. Trade blocks have become increasingly important and, yet, we have no work that tells us the implication of such blocks for international taxation. Close examination of the development of the tax systems of the European Union as the Union becomes more closely integrated would be valuable. Work that considers both the implications of changes for the Union, and for other countries and trading blocks would be informative. To date the literatures on foreign investment and international taxation have been largely distinct. Integration of insights from the two literatures would enhance our understanding of the way in which multinational corporations operate. Models used to discern the effects of international taxes have generally assumed perfect information and abstracted from risk. Such assumptions do not well characterize the international arena. Relaxation of these assumptions would be fruitful.
Bibliography on International Taxation (6080) Aaron, Henry J. (ed.) (1981), The Value-Added Tax: Lessons from Europe, Washington, Brookings Institution. ABA (1984), Unitary Tax: International Taxation - Up for Grabs? (Program Material), Chicago, American Bar Association. Aliber, R.Z. and Click, R.W. (eds) (1993), Readings in International Business: A Decision Approach, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Allegra, F.M. (1994), ‘Section 482: Mapping the Contours of the Abuse of Discretion Standard of Judicial Review’, 13 Virginia Tax Review, 423 ff. Altshuler, Rosanne and Cummins, J. (1997), ‘Tax Policy and the Dynamic Demand for Domestic and Foreign Capital by Multinational Corporations’, Unpublished paper. Altshuler, Rosanne and Fulghieri, Paolo (1994), ‘Dynamic Effects of Foreign Tax Credits on Multinational Corporations’, 47 National Tax Journal, 349-361. Altshuler, Rosanne and Grubert, Harry (1996), ‘Balance Sheets, Multinational Financial Policy, and the Cost of Capital at Home and Abroad’, Unpublished paper. Altshuler, Rosanne and Mintz, Jack M. (1995), ‘U.S. Interest-Allocation Rules: Effects and Policy’, 2 International Tax and Public Finance, 7-35. Altshuler, Rosanne and Newlon, T. Scott (1993), ‘The Effects of U.S. Tax Policy on the Income Repatriation Patterns of U.S. Multinational Corporations’, in Giovannini, A., Hubbard, R.G. and Slemrod, J. (eds), Studies in International Taxation, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Altshuler, Rosanne, Newlon, T. Scott and Randolph, W.C. (1995), ‘Do Repatriation Taxes Matter?
284
International Taxation
6080
Evidence From the Tax Returns of U.S. Multinationals’, in Feldstein, M., J.R.H., Jr and Hubbard, R.G. (eds), The Effects of Taxation on Multinational Corporations, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Alworth, J.S. (1987), ‘Taxation and the Cost of Capital: A Comparison of Six EC Countries’, in Cnossen, S. (ed.), Tax Coordination In The European Community, London: Kluwer Law and Taxation, 253-283. Alworth, J.S. (1988), The Finance, Investment, and Taxation Decisions of Multinational Firms, Oxford, Basil Blackwell. Ambardar, M. (1995), ‘Comment: The Taxation of Deferred Compensation Under I.R.C. 864(c)(6) and Income Tax Treaties: A Rose is Not Always Arose’, 19 Fordham International Law Journal, 736 ff. Andel, N. (1987), ‘Determination of Company Profits’, in Cnossen, S. (ed.), Tax Coordination In The European Community, London, Kluwer Law and Taxation, 287-304. Auerbach, Alan J. (1983), ‘Taxes, Firm Financial Policy, and the Cost of Capital’, 21 Journal of Economic Literature, 905-940. Auerbach, Alan J. and Hassett, K. (1993), ‘Taxation and Foreign Direct Investment in the United States: A Reconsideration of the Evidence’, in Giovannini, A., Hubbard, R.G. and Slemrod, J. (eds), Studies in International Taxation, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Ault, Hugh (1992), ‘Colloquium on Corporate Integration: Corporate Integration, Tax Treaties and the Division of the International Tax Base: Principles and Practices’, 47 New York University Tax Law Review, 565 ff. Ault, Hugh (1997), Comparative Income Taxation: A Structural Analysis, The Hague, Kluwer Law International. Ault, Hugh and Bradford, David F. (1990), ‘Taxing International Income: An Analysis of the U.S. System and its Economic Premises’, in Razin and Slemrod (eds), Taxation in the Global Economy, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 11-54. Avi-Yonah, R.S. (1995), ‘The Rise and Fall of Arm’s Length: A Study in the Evolution of U.S. International Taxation’, 15 Virginia Tax Review, 89 ff. Avi-Yonah, R.S. (1996), ‘The Structure of International Taxation: A Proposal for Simplification’, 74 Texas Law Review, 1301 ff. Avramovich, M. (1995), ‘Development of the Democratic Institutions and the Rule of Law in the Former Soviet Union: Note: Intercompany Transfer Pricing Regulations Under Internal Revenue Code Section 482: The Noose Tightens on Multinational Corporations’, 28 John Marshall Law Review, 915 ff. Azrieli, A. (1993), ‘Improving Arbitration Under the U.S.-Israel Free Trade Agreement: A Framework for a Middle-East Free Trade Zone’, 67 St. John’s Law Review, 187 ff. Barone, S.L. and Zerrenner, K. (1995), ‘Note: Over the Edge: State Taxation of Multinational Corporations in the Wake of Barclays’, 10 St. John’s Journal of Legal Commentary, 343 ff. Bartik, Timothy J. (1985), ‘Business Location Decisions in the United States: Estimates of the effects of Unionization, Taxes, and Other Characteristics of States’, 3 Journal of Business and Economic Statistics, 14-22. Bernard, Jean Thomas and Weiner, Robert J. (1990), ‘Multinational Corporations, Transfer Prices, and Taxes: Evidence from the U.S. Petroleum Industry’, in Razin and Slemrod (eds), Taxation in the Global Economy, Chicago, University of Chicago Press.
6080
International Taxation
285
Betten, Rijkele (1986), ‘OECD Report: Trends in International Taxation: Taxation Issues Relating to International Hiring out of Labor’, 40(7) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 330-334. Bhattacharya, Sudipto (1979), ‘Imperfect Information, Dividend Policy, and the Bird in the Hand Fallacy’, 10 Bell Journal of Economics, 259-270. Biehl, Dieter (1982), ‘Towards a General Theory of Taxing International Transactions: A Taxonomy of International Taxation Principles’, 37(2) Public Finance, 189-205. Bird, Richard M. (1987), ‘Corporate Personal Tax Integration’, in Cnossen, S. (ed.), Tax Coordination in the European Community, London, Kluwer Law and Taxation, 227-251. Bird, Richard M. (1994), ‘Colloquium on NAFTA and Tradition: Commentary: A View From the North’, 49 Tax Law Review, 745 ff. Bird, Richard M. and Mintz, Jack M. (eds) (1992), Taxation to 2000 and Beyond, Toronto, Canadian Tax Foundation. Blatt, W.S. (1986), ‘A Review of Decisions of the United States Court of Appeals for the Federal Circuit: Area Summary: The Federal Circuit’s 1985 Tax Cases: The Exercise of Equity’, 35 American University Law Review, 1097 ff. Block, W. and Walker, M. (1984), ‘Taxation: International Evidence’, in Block, W. and Walker, M. (eds), Taxation: An International Perspective: Proceedings of An International Conference, Vancouver, Fraser Institute, 3-19. Blum, C. (1986), ‘Rollover: An Alternative Treatment of Capital Gains’, 41 Tax Law Review, 385 ff. Blum, C. (1988), ‘How the United States Should Tax Foreign Shareholders’, 7 Virginia Tax Review, 583-696. Blumenthal, Marsha and Slemrod, Joel B. (1995), ‘The Compliance Cost of Taxing Foreign-Source Income: Its Magnitude, Determinants, and Policy Implications’, 2 International Tax and Public Finance, 37-53. Bond, Eric W. (1981), ‘Tax Holidays and Industry Behavior’, 63 Review of Economics and Statistics, 88-95. Bond, Eric W. and Samuelson, Larry (1989), ‘Strategic Behaviour and the Rules for International Taxation of Capital’, 99(398) Economic Journal, 1099-1111. Boskin, Michael J. and Gale, W.G. (1987), ‘New Results on the Effects of Tax Policy on the International Location of Investment’, in Feldstein, M. (ed.), The Effects of Taxation on Capital Accumulation, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Bovenberg, L. (1994), ‘Destination- and Origin-Based Taxation Under International Capital Mobility’, 1 International Tax and Public Finance, 247-273. Bovenberg, L., Anderson, K., Aramake, K. and Chand, S. (1990), ‘Tax Incentives and International Capital Flows: The Case of the United States and Japan’, in Razin and Slemrod (eds), Taxation in the Global Economy, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 283-330. Bradford, David F. (1981), ‘The Incidence and Allocation Effects of a Tax on Corporate Capital’, 15 Journal of Public Economics, 1-22. Brean, D.J.S. (1992), ‘Here or There? The Source and Residence Principles of International Taxation’, in Bird, R.M. and Mintz, J.M. (eds), Taxation to 2000 and Beyond.Canadian Tax Paper, Toronto, Canadian Tax Foundation, 303-333. Brown, F.B. (1993), ‘Federal Income Taxation of U.S. Branches of Foreign Corporations: Separate Entity or Separate Rules?’, New York University Tax Law Review.
286
International Taxation
6080
Burgess, Robin and Stern, Nicholas (1993), ‘Taxation and Development’, 31 Journal of Economic Literature, 762-830. Cameron, R. and Bovykin, V.I.E. (1992), ‘International Banking 1870-1914’, 26 George Washington Journal of International Law and Economics, 221 ff. Campolongo, Alberto (1978), ‘Tassazione Internazionale Per Lo Sviluppo (International Taxation for Development (With English summary)’, 31(1-2) Economia Internazionale, 3-17. Canzoneri, Matthew B. and Rogers (1990), ‘Is the European Community an Optimal Currency Area? Optimal Taxation versus the Cost of Multiple Currencies’, 80 American Economic Review, 419-433. Caves, Richard E. (1982), Multinational Enterprise and Economic Analysis, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Clark, R.G. (1993), ‘Comment: Transfer Pricing, Section 482, and International Tax Conflict: Getting Harmonized Income Allocation Measures from Multinational Cacophony’, 42 American University Law Review, 1155 ff. Cnossen, Sijbren (1983), ‘Harmonization of Indirect Taxes in the EC’, British Tax Review. Cnossen, Sijbren (1987a), ‘Tax Coordination in the European Community: Introduction’, in Cnossen, S. (ed.), Tax Coordination in the European Community, London, Kluwer Law and Taxation, 1-15. Cnossen, Sijbren (1987b), ‘Tax Structure Developments’, in Cnossen, S. (ed.), Tax Coordination in the European Community, London, Kluwer Law and Taxation, 19-55. Cnossen, Sijbren and Shoup, Carl S. (1987), ‘Coordination of Value-Added Taxes’, in Cnossen, S. (ed.), Tax Coordination in the European Community, London, Kluwer Law and Taxation, 59-84. Collins, Julie H. and Shackelford, D.A. (1992), ‘Foreign Tax Credit Limitations and Preferred Stock Issuances’, 30(S) Journal of Accounting Research, 103-124. Collins, Julie H. and Shackelford, D.A. (1995), ‘Corporate Domicile and Average Effective Tax Rates: The Cases of Canada, Japan, the United Kingdom, and the United States’, 2 International Tax and Public Finance, 55-83. Connolly, C.F. (1995), ‘Comment: The New Transfer Pricing and Penalty Regulations: Increased Burdens, and the Search for a Safe Harbor’, 16 University of Pennsylvania Journal of International Business, 339 ff. Corrado, M.G. (1988), ‘Comment: The Supreme Court’s Impact on Swiss Banking Secrecy: Societe Nationale Industrielle Aerospatiale v. United States District Court’, 37 American University Law Review, 827 ff. Coughlin, C.C., Terza, J.V. and Arromdee, V. (1991), ‘State Characteristics and the Location of Foreign Direct Investment within the United States’, 68 Review of Economics and Statistics, 675-683. Coven, G.E. (1993), ‘Corporate Tax Policy for the Twenty-First Century: Integration and Redeeming Social Value’, 50 Washington and Lee Law Review, 495 ff. Cummins, J. and Hassett, K. (1997), ‘The Giant Sucking Sound:Structural Estimates of Factor Substitution from Firm-Level Panel Data on Multinational Corporations’, Unpublished paper. Cummins, J. and Hubbard, R. Glenn (1995), ‘The Tax Sensitivity of Foreign Direct Investment: Evidence From Firm-Level Panel Data’, in Feldstein, M., J.R.H., Jr and Hubbard, R.G. (eds), The Effects of Taxation on Multinational Corporations, Chicago, University of Chicago Press.
6080
International Taxation
287
Cummins, J., Harris, T.S. and Hassett, K. (1995), ‘Accounting Standards Information Flow, and Firm Investment Behavior’, in Feldstein, M., J.R.H., Jr and Hubbard, R.G. (eds), The Effects of Taxation on Multinational Corporations, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Daly, Michael and Weiner, Joann (1993), ‘Corporate Tax Harmonization and Competition in Federal Countries: Some Lessons for the European Community?’, 441 National Tax Journal, 461 ff. Davlin, J.A. (1994), ‘Note: The Uncertainty of Foreign Blocked Income: Trying to Reconcile the 1994 482 Regulations With Procter & Gamble’, 5 Duke Journal of Comparative and International Law, 117 ff. Denys, L.A. (1987), ‘The Proposed Belgian Tax Reform: Aspects of International Taxation’, 41(8-9) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 383-390. Devereux, Michael and Freeman, Harold (1995), ‘The Impact of Tax on Foreign Direct Investment: Empirical Evidence and the Implications for Tax Integration Schemes’, 2 International Tax and Public Finance, 85-106. Devereux, Michael and Pearson (1991), Capital Export Neutrality, Capital Import Neutrality, and European Tax Harmonization: An Empirical Assessment, Cambridge, National Bureau of Economic Research Summer Institute. Diamond, Peter and Mirrlees, J.A. (1971), ‘Optimal Taxation and Public Production I: Production Efficiency’, 61 American Economic Review, 8-27. Dixit, A. (1985), ‘Tax Policy in Open Economies’, in Auerbach, Alan and Feldstein, Martin (eds), Handbook in Public Economics, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 313-374. Doernberg, Richard L. (1985), ‘A Workable Flat Rate Consumption Tax. Iowa University’, 70 Iowa Law Review, 425 ff. Douvier, Pierre Jean (1993), ‘Major Measures Concerning International Taxation: The Finance Act 1993 and Transfer of Assets Abroad’, 47(4) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 214-219. Dutton, John (1982), ‘The Optimal Taxation of International Investment Income: A Comment’, 96 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 373-380. Easson, Alex J. (1991), ‘A New International Tax Order Responding to the Challenge: International’, 45(10) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 465-472. Easson, Alex J. and Jinyan, L. (1986), ‘Taxation of Foreign Business and Investment in the People’s Republic of China’, 7 Journal of International Law and Business, 666 ff. Elitzur, R. Ramy and Mintz, Jack M. (1995), ‘Transfer Pricing Rules and Corporate Tax Competition’, 60 Journal of Public Economics, 401-422. Fargeix, Andr and Perloff, Jeffrey M. (1989), ‘The Effects of Tariffs in Markets with Vertical Restraints’, 26 Journal of International Economics, 99-117. Feldstein, Martin (1994), ‘Taxes, Leverage and the National Return on Outbound Foreign Direct Investment’, Cambridge, National Bureau of Economic Research, Working Paper, No. 4689. Feldstein, Martin (1995), ‘The Effects of Outbound Foreign Direct Investment on the Domestic Capital Stock’, in Feldstein, M., J.R.H., Jr and Hubbard, R.G. (eds), The Effects of Taxation on Multinational Corporations, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Feldstein, Martin (1997), ‘Tax Policy and International Capital Flows’, Cambridge, National Bureau of Economic Research, Working Paper, No. 4851. Feldstein, Martin and Hartman, D. (1979), ‘The Optimal Taxation of Foreign Source Investment Income’, 93 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 613-630.
288
International Taxation
6080
Feldstein, Martin and Krugman, Paul R. (1990), ‘International Trade Effects of Value-Added Tax’, in Razin and Slemrod (eds), Taxation in the Global Economy, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Finnerty, J.J.I. (1993), ‘Note: The “Mother Court” and the Foreign Plaintiff: Does Rule 10b-5 Reach Far Enough’, 62 Fordham Law Review. Fischel, William A. (1975), ‘Fiscal and Environmental Considerations in the Location of Firms in Suburban Communities’, in Mills, Edwin S. and Oates, Wallace E. (eds), Fiscal Zoning and Land Use Controls, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Fischer Zernin, Justus (1987), ‘GATT versus Tax Treaties? The Basic Conflicts between International Taxation Methods and the Rules and Concepts of GATT’, 21(3) Journal of World Trade Law, 39-62. Franson, M. D. (1984), ‘Comment: The Repeal of the Thirty Percent Withholding Tax on Portfolio Interest Paid to Foreign Investors’, 6 Journal of International Law and Business, 930 ff. Freed, A. (1996), ‘Progress versus Protectionism: The Double Taxation of Computer Software in Korea’, 47 Hastings Law Journal, 473 ff. Freiman, B.M. (1991), ‘Comment: The Japanese Consumption Tax: Value-Added Model or Administrative Nightmare?’, 40 American University Law Review, 1265 ff. Frenkel, Jacob A., Razin, Assaf and Sadka, Efraim (1990), ‘Basic Concepts of International Taxation’, Cambridge, National Bureau of Economic Research, Working Paper, No. 3540. Frenkel, Jacob A., Razin, Assaf and Sadka, Efraim (1991), International Taxation in an Integrated World, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Frisch, Daniel (1983), ‘Issues in the Taxation of Foreign Source Income’, in Feldstein (ed.), Simulation Methods in Tax Policy Analysis, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Frisch, Daniel (1989), ‘The BALRM Approach to Transfer Pricing’, 42 National Tax Journal, 261271. Frisch, Daniel and Hartman, D. (1983), ‘Taxation and the Location of U.S. Investment Abroad’, Cambridge, NBER, Working Paper, No. 1241. Froot, K.A. and Hines, J. (1995), ‘Interest Allocation Rules, Financing Patterns, and the Operations of U.S. Multinationals’, in Feldstein, M., J.R.H., Jr and Hubbard, R.G. (eds), The Effects of Taxation on Multinational Corporations, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Galston, N.M. and Smit, H. (1984), Sale of Goods, New York, Matthew Bender. Gammie, M. (1994), ‘Colloquium on NAFTA and Tradition: The Taxation of Inward Direct Investment in North America Following the Free Trade Agreement’, 49 New York University Tax Law Review, 615 ff. Gann, P.B. (1982), ‘The Concept of an Independent Treaty Foreign Tax Credit’, 38 New York University Tax Law Review, 1 ff. Garbarino, C. and Colucci, P.A. (1992), ‘La Tassazione del Reddito Transnazionale’, April American Journal of International Law. Gazur, W.M. (1994), ‘The Forgotten Link: “Control” in Section 482’, 15 Journal of International Law and Business, 1 ff. Gazur, W.M. and Goff, N.M. (1991), ‘Assessing the Limited Liability Company’, 41 Case Western Reserve Law Review, 387 ff. Gentry, William M. (1995), ‘Comment’, in Feldstein, M., J.R.H., Jr and Hubbard, R.G. (eds), The Effects of Taxation on Multinational Corporations, Chicago, University of Chicago Press.
6080
International Taxation
289
Gersovitz (1987), ‘The Effects of Domestic Taxes on Foreign Private Investment’, in Newberry and Stern (eds), The Theory of Taxation for Developing Countries: World Bank. Giovannini, Alberto (1989), ‘National Tax Systems vs. The European Capital Market’, 9 Economic Policy, Giovannini, Alberto (1991), International Capital Mobility and Tax Avoidance, New York, Columbia University Press. Giovannini, Alberto and Hines, J. (1990), ‘Capital Flight and Tax Competition: Are There Viable Solutions to both Problems?’, CEPR Discussion Papers. Giovannini, Alberto, Glenn, H.R. and Slemrod, Joel (eds) (1993), Studies in International Taxation, Chicago, National Bureau of Economic Research. Glautier, M.W.E. and Bassinger, F.W. (1987), A Reference Guide to International Taxation: Profiting From Your International Operations, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Gliksberg, D. (1994), ‘The Effect of the Statist-Political Approach to International Jurisdiction of the Income Tax Regime - The Israeli Case’, 15 Michigan Journal of International Law, 460 ff. Goodspeed, Timothy J. (1989), ‘A Re-Examination of the Use of Ability to Pay Taxes by Local Governments’, 38 Journal of Public Economics, 319-342. Goodspeed, Timothy J. (1995), ‘Local Income Taxation: An Externality, Pigouvian Solution, and Public Policies’, 25 Regional Science and Urban Economics, 279-296. Goodspeed, Timothy J. (1997), ‘Transfer Pricing’, in Warner, Malcolm (ed.), International Encyclopedia of Business and Management. Volume 5, London, Routledge Limited. Goodspeed, Timothy J. and Frisch, Daniel (1989), ‘U.S. Tax Policy and the Overseas Activities of U.S. Multinational Corporations: A Quantitative Assessment’, Mimeo. Gordon, Roger H. (1983), ‘An Optimal Taxation Approach to Fiscal Federalism’, 567 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 586 ff. Gordon, R.H. (1986), ‘Taxation of Investment and Savings in a World Economy’, 76 American Economic Review, 1086-1102. Gordon, Roger H. (1990), ‘Canada-U.S. Free Trade and Pressures for Tax Harmonization’, NBER Working Paper, No. 3327. Gordon, R.H. (1992), ‘Can Capital Income Taxes Survive in Open Economies?’, 47 Journal of Finance, 1159-1180. Gordon, R.H. and Bovenberg, A. Lans (1993), ‘Why is Capital so Immobile Internationally?’, Cambridge, National Bureau of Economic Research, Working Paper, No. 4796. Gordon, R.H. and Jun, J. (1993), ‘Taxes and the Form of Ownership of Foreign Corporate Equity’, in Giovannini, A., Hubbard, R.G. and Slemrod, J. (eds), Studies in International Taxation, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Gordon, R.H. and Mackie-Mason, Jeffrey K. (1995), ‘Why is There Corporate Taxation in a Small Open Economy? The Role of Transfer Pricing and Income Shifting’, in Feldstein, M., J.R.H., Jr and Hubbard, R.G. (eds), The Effects of Taxation on Multinational Corporations, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Gramwell, A., Merrill, P. and Dubert, C. (1996), Taxation of U.S. Corporations Doing Business Aborad: U.S. Rules and Competitiveness Issues, Morristown, New Jersey, Financial Executives Research Foundation, Inc. Green, R.A. (1993), ‘The Future of Source-Based Taxation of the Income of Multinational Enterprises’,
290
International Taxation
6080
80 Cornell Law Review, Grubert, Harry (1995), ‘Royalties, Dividends, and R&D’, Paper presented at the Proceedings of the Eighty-Seventh Annual Conference on Taxation, Columbus, OH. Grubert, Harry (1997), ‘Taxes and the Division of Foreign Operating Income Among Royalties, Interest, Dividends, and Retained Earnings’, Journal of Public Economics, forthcoming. Grubert, Harry and Mutti, John (1991), ‘Taxes, Tariffs and Transfer Pricing in Multinational Corporation Decision Making’, 33 Review of Economics and Statistics, 285-293. Grubert, Harry and Newlon, T. Scott (1995), ‘The International Implications of Consumption Tax Proposals’, 48 National Tax Journal, 619-647. Grubert, Harry and Slemrod, Joel (1994), ‘The Effects of Taxes on Investment and Income Shifting to Puerto Rico’, Cambridge, NBER Working Paper, No. 4869. Grubert, Harry, Goodspeed, Timothy J. and Swenson, D. (1993), ‘Explaining the Low Taxable Income of Foreign-Controlled Companies in the United States’, in Giovannini, A., Hubbard, R.G. and Slemrod, J. (eds), Studies in International Taxation, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Grubert, Harry and Newlon, T. Scott (1997), Taxing Consumption in a Global Economy, Washington, DC, AEI Press. Grundy, M. (1984), The World of International Tax Planning, New York, Cambridge University Press. Hall, Bronwyn H. (1993), ‘R&D; Tax Policy During The 1980s: Success or Failure?’, in Poterba, J.M. (ed.), Tax Policy and the Economy Vol. 7, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Hamilton, Bruce W. (1976), ‘Capitalization of Interjurisdictional Differences in Local Tax Prices’, 66 American Economic Review, 743-753. Hanna, C.H. (1995), ‘The Virtual Reality of Eliminating Tax Deferral’, 12 American Journal of Tax Policyv, 449 ff. Harris, C.M. (1994), ‘The European Community’s Parent-Subsidiary Directive’, 9 Florida International Law Journal, 111 ff. Harris, D.G. (1993), ‘The Impact of U.S. Tax Law Revision on Multinational Corporations’ Capital Location and Income-Shifting Decisions’, 31(S) Journal of Accounting Research, 111-140. Harris, D.G., Morck, Randall, Slemrod, Joel and Yeung, B. (1993), ‘Income Shifting in U.S. Multinational Corporations’, in Giovannini, A., Hubbard, R.G. and Slemrod, J. (eds), Studies in International Taxation, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Hartman, D. (1980), ‘The Effects of Taxing Foreign Investment Income’, 13 Journal of Public Economics, 213-230. Hartman, D. (1981), ‘Domestic Tax Policy and Foreign Investment: Some Evidence’, Cambridge, NBER Working Paper, No. 784. Hartman, D. (1984), ‘Tax Policy and Foreign Direct Investment in the United States’, 37 National Tax Journal, 475-487. Hartman, D. (1985), ‘Tax Policy and Foreign Direct Investment’, 26 Journal of Public Economics, 107-121. Hartman, P.J. (1984), ‘Constitutional Limitations on State Taxation of Corporate Income From Multinational Corporations’, 37 Vanderbilt Law Review. Higinbotham, Harlow N., Asper, D.W., Stoffregen, P.A. and Wexler, R.P. (1987), ‘Effective Application of the Section 482 Transfer Pricing Regulations’, 42 Tax Law Review, 295 ff.
6080
International Taxation
291
Hines, James R., Jr (1988), ‘Taxation and U.S. Multinational Investment’, in Summers, Lawrence H. (ed.), Tax Policy and the Economy, Volume 2, Cambridge, MIT Press. Hines, James R., Jr (1991), ‘The Flight Paths of Migratory Corporations’, 6 Journal of Accounting Auditing, and Finance, 447-479. Hines, James R., Jr (1993), ‘On the Sensitivity of R&D; to Delicate Tax Changes: The Behavior of U.S. Multinationals in the 1980s’, in Giovannini, A., Hubbard, R.G., Slemrod, J. (eds), Studies in International Taxation, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Hines, James R., Jr (1994a), ‘Credit and Deferral as International Investment Incentives’, 55 Journal of Public Economics, 323-347. Hines, James R., Jr (1994b), ‘No Place Like Home: Tax Incentives and the Location of R&D, by American Multinationals’, in Poterba, J.M. (ed.), Tax Policy and the Economy Vol. 7 , Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Hines, James R., Jr (1995a), ‘Taxes, Technology Transfer, and the R&D; activities of Multinational Firms’, in Feldstein, M., J.R.H., Jr and Hubbard, R.G. (eds), The Effects of Taxation on Multinational Corporations, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Hines, James R., Jr (1995b), ‘Forbidden Payment: Foreign Bribery and American Business After 1977', Cambridge, NBER Working Paper, No. 5266. Hines, James R., Jr (1996a), ‘Dividends and Profits: Some Unsubtle Foreign Influences’, 51 Journal of Finance. Hines, James R., Jr (1996b), ‘Tax Policy and the Activities of Multinational Corporations’, Mimeo. Hines, James R., Jr (1996c), ‘Altered States: Taxes and the Location of Foreign Direct Investment In America’, 86 American Economic Review, 1076-1094. Hines, James R., Jr and Hubbard, R. Glenn (1990), ‘Coming Home to America: Dividend Repatriations by U.S. Multinationals’, in Razin and Slemrod (eds), Taxation in the Global Economy, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Hines, James R., Jr and Rice, Edward M. (1994), ‘Fiscal Paradise: Foreign Tax Havens and American Business’, 109 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 149-182. Hodder, James E. and Senbet, Lemma W. (1990), ‘International Capital Structure Equilibrium’, 45(5) Journal of Finance, 1495-1516. Hornberger, W.H. (1994), ‘U.S. Taxation of U.S. Persons Doing Business or Investing in Mexico: An Overview’, 26 St. Mary’s Law Journal, 107 ff. Horst, Thomas (1977), ‘American Taxation of Multinational Firms’, 67 American Economic Review, 376-389. Horst, Thomas (1980), ‘A Note on the Optimal Taxation of International Investment Income’, 94 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 793-798. Horst, Thomas (1982), ‘Reply’, 96 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 381 ff. Horst, Thomas (1993), ‘The Comparable Profits Method’, 14 Tax Notes International, 1443-1458. Horst, Thomas and Pugel, Thomas (1977), ‘The Impact of DISC on the Prices and Profitability of U.S. Exports’, 7 Journal of Public Economics, 72-87. Hreha, K.S. (1990), ‘The Current State of Graduate Education in International Taxation (Report of the 1987-1988 Joint International Accounting Section--American Taxation Association Research Committee on International Taxation)’, in Jones, S.M. (ed.), Advances in Taxation, Greenwich, JAI Press, 249-259.
292
International Taxation
6080
Hubbard, R. Glenn (1993), ‘Comment’, in Giovannini, A., Hubbard, R.G.and Slemrod, J. (eds), Studies in International Taxation, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 231-234. Hudson, D.M. (1984), ‘International and Interstate Approaches to Taxing Business Income’, 6 Journal of International Law and Business, 562 ff. Hufbauer, Gary (1992), U.S. Taxation of International Income: Blueprint for Reform, Washington, DC, Institute for International Economics. Hufbauer, Gary, Elliot, K. and Maldonado, E. (1988), Tax Treaties and American Interests. A Report to the National Foreign Trade Council, Washington, DC. Huizinga, Harry (1994), ‘International Interest Withholding Taxation: Prospects for a Common European Policy’, 1(3) International Tax and Public Finance, 277-291. Huston, J., Miyatake, T. and Griffith, W. (1985), Japanese International Taxation, New York, Matthew Bender. Isenbergh, Joseph (1990a), International Taxation: U.S. Taxation of Foreign Taxpayers and Foreign Income, Boston, Little Brown. Isenbergh, Joseph (1990b), ‘The End of Income Taxation’, 45 Tax Law Review, 283 ff. Jacob, Friedhelm (1984), ‘Unitary Approaches in International Taxation’, 38(3) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 99-120. Jacobson, H.K. (1983), ‘Resources, Regimes, World Order. By Antony J. Dolman, Book Review’, 77 American Journal of International Law, 688 ff. Janeba, Eckhard (1996), ‘Foreign Direct Investment under Oligopoly: Profit Shifting or Profit Capturing?’, 60 Journal of Public Economics, 423-445. Jenkins, G.P. and B.D.W. (1975), ‘Taxation of Income of Multinational Corporations: The Case of the United States Petroleum Industry’, 57 Review of Economics and Statistics, 1-11. Jensen, Michael C. and Meckling, William H. (1976), ‘Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behavior, Agency Costs, and Ownership Structures’, 3 Journal of Financial Economics, 305-360. Jones, S.M. (1990), Advances in Taxation. Volume 3, Greenwich, JAI Press. Kalinka, S. (1993), ‘Acts 1990, No. 1009: The Repeal of Provisions for Separation From Bed and Board Increases the Federal Income Tax Burden of Separated Spouses in Louisiana’, 53 Louisiana Law Review, 597 ff. Kanbur, Ravi and Keen, Michael (1993), ‘Jeux Sans Frontièrs: Tax Competition and Tax Coordination When Countries Differ in Size’, 83 American Economic Review, 877-892. Kaplan, Richard L. (1983), ‘Creeping Xenophobia and the Taxation of Foreign-Owned Real Estate’, 71 Georgetown Law Journal. Kay, John A. and Keen, Michael (1987), ‘Alcohol and Tobacco Taxes: Criteria For Harmonisation’, in Cnossen, S. (ed.), Tax Coordination in the European Community, London, Kluwer Law and Taxation, 85-111. Keely, M.G. (1995), ‘Comment: Barclays Bank PLC v. The Franchise Tax Board: Has the Supreme Court Emasculated the One Voice Doctrine?’, 8 DePaul Business Law Journal, 133 ff. Keen, Michael (1990), Corporate Tax, Foreign Direct Investment and the Single Market, University of Essex. Keen, Michael (1991), ‘Corporate Tax, Foreign Direct Investment and the Single Market’, in Winters, L. and A.V. (ed.), The Impact of 1992 on European Trade and Industry, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Keen, Michael (1992), ‘Harmonization of Taxes on Capital Income’, in Newman, Peter, Milgate,
6080
International Taxation
293
Murray and Eatwell, John (eds), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Money and Finance, London, Macmillan. Keen, Michael and Lahiri, S. (1996), ‘The Comparison Between Destination and Origin Taxation Under Imperfect Competition’, Unpublished paper. Keen, Michael and Smith, Steven D. (1996), ‘The Future of Value Added Taxion the European Union’, Economic Policy, 375-420. Kemsley, D. (1995), The Effect of Taxes on the Choice Between Exports and Foreign Production, New York, Columbia Business School. King, Mervyn A. (1974), ‘Dividend Behavior and the Theory of the Firm’, 41 Economica, 25-34. Kingson, C.I. (1992), ‘U.S. International Taxation, by Joel D. Kuntz and Robert J. Peroni, Book Review’, 26 George Washington Journal of International Law and Economics, 213 ff. Klassen, K., et al. (1993), ‘Geographic Income Shifting by Multinational Corporations in Response to Tax Rate Changes’, 31 Journal of Accounting Research, 141-173. Klein, William A. and Zolt, Eric M. (1995), ‘LLCs, LLPs and the Evolving Corporate Form: A Symposium Sponsored by the University of Colorado Law Review: Business Form, Limited Liability, and Tax Regimes: Lurching Toward a Coherent Outcome?’, 66 University of Colorado Law Review, 1001 ff. Kole, D.V. (1986), ‘Tax Efficient Forex Management, Book Review’, 8 Journal of International Law and Business. Kole, D.V. (1988), ‘Perspective: The Status of United States International Taxation: Another Fine Mess We’ve Gotten Ourselves Into’, 9 Journal of International Law and Business, 49 ff. Kopits, G.F. (1972), ‘Dividend Remittance Behavior Within the International Firm: A Cross-Country Analysis’, 54 Review of Economics and Statistics, 339-342. Kopits, G.F. (1976), ‘Intra-Firm Royalties Crossing Frontiers and Transfer-Pricing Behaviour’, 86 Economic Journal, 791-805. Kozusko, D.D. and J.A.S. (eds) (1991), International Estate Planning Principles and Strategies, American Bar Association. Kurlander, G. (1983), ‘The Economic Recovery Tax Act of 1981: The Foreign Earned Income Exclusion: Redefining the Exception for Amounts Paid by the United States Under IRC @ 911’, 70 Cornell Law Review. Kwall, J.L. (1985), ‘Subchapter G of the Internal Revenue Code: Crusade Without a Cause?’, 5 Virginia Tax Review, 223 ff. LaFrance, M. (1995), ‘The Separate Tax Status of Loan-Out Corporations’, 48 Vanderbilt Law Review. Laity, E.T. (1996), ‘Defining the Passive Income of Controlled Foreign Corporations’, 20 North Carolina Journal of International Law and Commercial Regulation, 293 ff. Lanciano, G.C. (1992), ‘Comment: Procter & Gamble Co. v. Commissioner: Should Foreign Law Control U.S. Tax Liability of U.S. Shareholders?’, 17 Delaware Journal of Corporate Law, 515 ff. Lee, Catherine, Pearson, Mark and Smith, Stephen (1988), Fiscal Harmonization: An Analysis of the European Commision’s Proposals, London, Institute for Fiscal Studies. Leechor, Chad and J.M. (1993), ‘On the Taxation of Multinational Corporate Investment When the Deferral Method is Used by the Capital-Exporting Country’, 51 Journal of Public Economics, 75-96.
294
International Taxation
6080
Levey, M.M. and Vonk, W.J.K. (eds) (1990), ‘Foreign Investment in the United States: Law,Taxation, Finance’, 84 American Journal of International Law, Lipsey, R.E. (1995), ‘Outward Direct Investment and the U.S. Economy’, in Feldstein, M., J.R.H., Jr and Hubbard, R.G. (eds), The Effects of Taxation on Multinational Corporations, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Livingston, Michael (1993), ‘Risky Business: Economics, Culture and the Taxation of High-Risk Activities’, 48 New York University Tax Law Review, 163-232. Lockwood, B., de Meza, D. and Myles, G. (1994a), ‘When are Origin and Destination Regimes Equivalent’, 1 International Tax and Public Finance, 5-24. Lockwood, B., de Meza, D. and Myles, G. (1994b), ‘The Equivalence between Destination and Nonreciprocal Restricted Origin Tax Regimes’, 96 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 696 ff. Lord, C.J. (1986), ‘Stapled Stock and I.R.C. Section 269B: Ill-Conceived Change in the Rules of International Tax Jurisdiction’, 73 Cornell Law Review, Loss, Louis (1989), ‘The Evolving Antarctic Legal Regime: Michigan Yearbook of International Legal Studies: Volume 9, Book Review’, 83 American Journal of International Law, 696 ff. Lowell, C.H., Burge, M. and Briger, P. (1994), Understanding Transfer Pricing, Boston, Waren, Gorham & Lamont. Lyon, A.B.R. (1994), ‘Review of: Studies in International Taxation’, 32 Journal of Economic Literature, 702-703. Lyon, A.B.R. and G.S. (1995), ‘The Alternative Minimum Tax and the Behavior of Multinational Corporations’, in Feldstein, M., J.R.H., Jr., Hubbard, R.G. (eds), The Effects of Taxation on Multinational Corporations, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Lyons, C.M. (1995), ‘The Constitutionality of the Worldwide Combined Reporting Method of Taxation of Multinational Corporations: Barclays Bank v. Franchise Tax Board’, 37 Boston College Law Review, 183 ff. MacKenzie, G.W. (1993), ‘ICSID Arbitration as a Strategy for Levelling the Playing Field Between International Non-Governmental Organizations and Host’,Syracuse Journal of International Law and Commerce. Malinvaud, E. (1989), ‘Comments’, in Giovannini, A. (ed.), National Tax System vs. The European Market: Economic Policy 9. Marx, R.S. (1995), ‘Transforming International Politics: An American Role for the Post Cold War’, 64 University of Cincinnati Law Review, 119 ff. Mason, Z.D. (1994), ‘Implications of the Income Tax Treaty Between the United States and Mexico’, 25 St. Mary’s Law Journal, 1213 ff. McDaniel, P.R. (1984), ‘In Memoriam: Stanley S. Surrey: Celebrating Stanley’s Gifts’, 98 Harvard Law Review. McDaniel, P.R. (1987), ‘Personal Income Taxes: The Treatment of Tax Expenditures’, in Cnossen, S. (ed.), Tax Coordination In The European Community, London, Kluwer Law and Taxation, 319-333. McDaniel, P.R. (1994), ‘Colloquium on NAFTA and Tradition: Formulary Taxation in the North American Free Trade Zone’, 49 Tax Law Review, 691 ff. McDaniel, P.R. and Ault, H.J. (1989), Introduction To United States International Taxation, Norwell, Kluwer Law and Taxation. McDonald, J. (1987), ‘Comment: Anti-Deferred: A Proposal for the Reform of International Tax Law’, 16 Journal of International Law and Business, 248 ff.
6080
International Taxation
295
McIntyre, M.J. (1994), ‘Colloquium on NAFTA and Tradition: Commentary: The Design of Tax Rules for the North American Free Trade Alliance’, New York University Tax Law Review. McIntyre, R.S. (1989), ‘Tax Americana’, 200 New Republic, 18-20. McLure, Charles (1980), ‘The State Corporate Income Tax: Lambs in Wolves’ Clothing?’, in Aaron, H. (ed.), The Economics of Taxation, Washington, Brookings Institution. McLure, Charles (1981), ‘The Elusive Incidence of the Corporate Income Tax: The State Case’, 395 Public Finance Quarterly, 413 ff. McLure, Charles E., Jr (1994), ‘Review of: U.S. Taxation of International Income: Blueprint For Reform’, 32 Journal of Economic Literature, 148-150. Mick, J. (1992), ‘A Proposal for the Indexation of Debt for Inflation (Comment)’, 140 University of Pennsylvania Law Review. Mintz, Jack M. and Tulkens, Henry (1984), ‘Strategic Use of Tax Rates and Credits in a Model of International Corporate Income Tax Competition’, CORE Discussion Paper, No. 9073. Mintz, Jack M. and Tulkens, Henry (1986), ‘Commodity Tax Competition Between Member States of a Federation: Equilibrium and Efficiency’, 29 Journal of Public Economics, 133-172. Misey, R.J. (1992), ‘Simplifying International Jurisdiction for United States Transfer Taxes: Retain Citizenship and Replace Domicile with the Green Cardtest’, Marquette Law Review, Molina Gómez-Arnáu, Pilar (1997), ‘Spanish Rules on Transfer Pricing’, 23 International Tax Journal, 42-61. Mundstock, G. (1993), ‘Section 902 is too Generous’, New York University Tax Law Review. Murfin, A. (1987), ‘Price Discrimination and Tax Differences in the European Motor Industry’, in Cnossen, S. (ed.), Tax Coordination In The European Community, London, Kluwer Law and Taxation, 171-194. Musgrave, Peggy B. (1969), United States Taxation of Foreign Investment Income: Issues and Arguments, Cambridge, MA, International Tax Program, Harvard Law School. Musgrave, Peggy B. (1975), ‘Exchange Rate Aspects in the Taxation of Foreign Income’, 27 National Tax Journal, 405-413. Musgrave, Peggy B. (1987), ‘Interjurisdictional Coordination of Taxes on Capital Income’, in Cnossen, S. (ed.), Tax Coordination In The European Community, London, Kluwer Law And Taxation, 197-225. Muten, L. (1983), ‘Some Topical Issues Concerning International Double Taxation’, in Cnossen, S. (ed.), Comparative Tax Studies: Essays in Honor of Richard Goode, Amsterdam, North-Holland. Mutti, John (1981), ‘Tax Incentives and Repatriation Decisions of U.S. Multinational Corporations’, 31 National Tax Journal, 241-248. Mutti, John (1993), ‘Comment’, in Giovannini, A., Hubbard, R.G.and Slemrod, J. (eds), Studies in International Taxation, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Mutti, John and Grubert, Harry (1985), ‘The Taxation of Capital Income in an Open Economy: The Importance of Resident-Nonresident Tax Treatment’, 28 Journal of Public Economics. Newlon, T. Scott (1987), ‘Tax Policy and the Multinational Firm’s Financial Policy and Investment Decisions’, Unpublished Ph.D. Dissertation, Princeton University, Princeton.
296
International Taxation
6080
Nutter, S.E. (1994), ‘Corporate Foreign Tax Credit, 1990: An Industry Focus’, 13 Statistics of Income Bulletin, 78-106. Oates, Wallace E. (1972), Fiscal Federalism, Princeton, Harcourt, Brace and Jovanovich. Oates, Wallace E. (1994), ‘Federalism and Government Finance’, in Quigley, J.M. and Smolensky, E. (eds), Modern Public Finance, Cambridge, Harvard University Press. Oates, Wallace E. and Schwab, Robert M. (1988), ‘Economic Competition Among Jurisdictions: Efficiency Enhancing or Distortion Inducing?’, 35 Journal of Public Economics, 333-354. OECD (1995), Transfer Pricing Guidelines for Multinational Enterprises and Tax Administrations, Paris, OECD. Office of Management and Budget (1996), Budget of the United States Government, Fiscal Yesr 1997, Analytical Perspectives, Chapter 5, Tax Expenditures, Washington,Office of Management and Budget. Ohlenforst, C.M., Dorrill, J.W. and Christmann, K.A. (1994), ‘Taxation’, 47 SMU Law Review. Ohlenforst, C.M., Dorrill, J.W. and Goodin, K.L. (1995), ‘Taxation’, 48 SMU Law Review. Ondrich, J. and Wasylenko, M. (1993), Foreign Direct Investment in the United States: Issues, Magnitudes, and Location Choice of New Manufacturing Plants, Kalamazoo, MI, W.E. Upjohn Institute. Orland, L. (1991), ‘Exchange, Commentary: Teaching Antitrust after Chicago and Perestroika’, 66 New York University Law Review. Osgood, R.K. (1983), ‘Symposium: The Economic Recovery Tax Act of 1981: The Ages and Themes of Income Taxation: Savings and Investment’, 70 Cornell Law Review. Owens, Jeffrey (1991), ‘International Taxation and International Investment Flows between OECD and Non OECD Countries’, 45(5) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 219-220. Papke, L.E. (1991), ‘Interstate Business Tax Differentials and New Firm Location’, 45 Journal of Public Economics, 47-68. Pires, M. (1989), International Juridical Double Taxation of Income, Norwell, Kluwer Law and Taxation. Plasschaert, Sylvain R.F. (1981), ‘The Design of Schedular and Global Systems of Income Taxation, the International Dimension’, 35(8-9) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 409-416. Pollack, S.D. (1994), ‘Tax Complexity, Reform, and the Illusions of Tax Simplification’, 2 George Mason Law Review, 319 ff. Pomp, R.D. (1994a), ‘Issues in the Design of Formulary Apportionment in the Context of NAFTA’, New York University Tax Law Review. Pomp, R.D. (1994b), ‘The Foreign Tax Credit Limitation: An Analysis of the President’s Tax Proposals’, International Lawyer. Postlewaite, P.F., Collins, M.P. and Macdonald, J.R. (1983), ‘Book Review: International Individual Taxation’, 77 American Journal of International Law, 708 ff. Pratt, K.T. (1995), ‘Federal Tax Sources Recommended for Law School Libraries’, 87 Law Library Journal, 387 ff. Razin, Assaf and Sadka, Efraim (1989), ‘Optimal Incentives to Domestic Investment in the Presence of Capital Flight’, International Monetary Fund, Research and Fiscal Affairs Department, No. 89/79. Razin, Assaf and Sadka, Efraim (1990), ‘Capital Market Integration: Issues of International Taxation’,
6080
International Taxation
297
in Frech, H.E. (ed.), Regulating Doctors’ Fees: Competition, Benefits, and Controls under Medicare, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute. Razin, Assaf and Sadka, Efraim (1991a), ‘International Fiscal Policy Coordination and Competition: An Exposition’, Cambridge, National Bureau of Economic Research, No. 3779. Razin, Assaf and Sadka, Efraim (1991b), ‘Vanishing Tax on Capital Income in the Open Economy’, Cambridge, National Bureau of Economic Research, No. 3796. Razin, Assaf and Sadka, Efraim (1991c), ‘International Tax Competition and the Gains from Tax Harmonization’, 37 Economic Letters, 69-76. Razin, Assaf and Yuen, C.W. (1992), ‘Convergence in Growth Rates: The Role of Capital Mobility and International Taxation’, Cambridge, National Bureau of Economic Research, No. 4214. Razin, Assaf and Yuen, C.W. (1993), ‘Convergence in Growth Rates: A Quantitative Assessment of the Role of Capital Mobility and International Taxation’, Cambridge: National Bureau of Economic Research, No. 4336. Redmiles, L. (1992), ‘International Boycott Participation’, 12 Statistics of Income Bulletin, 88-89. Redmiles, L. (1994), ‘Individual Foreign-Earned Income and Foreign Tax Credit, 1991’, 14 Statistics of Income Bulletin, 113-122. Robin, J. (1988), ‘United They Stand, Divided They Fall: Public Choice Theory and the Tax Code’, 75 Cornell Law Review. Robin, J. (1989), ‘The Grand Illusion: A Neutral System For The Taxation of International Transactions’, 75 Virginia Law Review. Robin, J. (1994), ‘Adding Insult to Injury: The “Enhancement” of § 163(j) and the Tax Treatment of Foreign Investors in the United States’, New York University Tax Law Review. Rose, M. (1987), ‘Optimal Tax Perspective on Tax Coordination’, in Cnossen, S. (ed.), Tax Coordination in the European Community, London, Kluwer Law and Taxation, 113-138. Rosenbloom, D.H. (1994), ‘Sovereignty and the Regulation of International Business in the Tax Area’, 20 Canada-United States Law Journal, 267 ff. Rothman, D.J. and Marx, R.S. (1984), The World of International Tax Planning by Milton Grundy (Review). Rousslang, Donald J. and Tokarick, S.P. (1994), ‘The Trade and Welfare Consequences of U.S. Export-Enhancing Tax Provisions’, 41(4) IMF Staff Papers, 675-683. Rubinfeld, D. (1987), ‘The Economics of the Local Public Sector’, in Auerbach, A.J. and Feldstein, M. (eds), Handbook of Public Economics, vol. 2, Amsterdam, North Holland, 571-646. Rudnick, R.S. (1989), ‘Who Should Pay the Corporate Tax in a Flat Tax World?’, 39 Case Western Reserve Law Review, 965 ff. Sabransky, R. (1995), ‘Notes: Note, Barclays Bank PLC v. Franchise Tax Board: California’s Taxation of Foreign-based Multinational Corporations’, 31 California Western Law Review, 317 ff. Samuels, L.B. and Brown, Patricia A. (1990), ‘Observations on the Taxation of Global Securities Trading’, New York University Tax Law Review Sanford, C. (ed.) (1993), Key Issues inTax Reform, Bath, Fiscal Publications. Sawyer, Adrian J. (1995), ‘International Taxation: A Complete Approach At Last? New Zealand’,
298
International Taxation
6080
49(10) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 472-481. Schenk, D.H. (1994), ‘Colloquium on NAFTA and Tradition: Foreword’, 49 New York University Tax Law Review, 525 ff. Schjelderup, Guttorm (1991), Optimal Taxation, Capital Mobility and Tax Evasion, Norwegian School of Economics and Business Administration. Scholes, Myron S. and Wolfson, Mark A. (1992), Taxes and Business Strategy: A Planning Approach, Englewood Cliffs (NJ), Prentice-Hall. Schwarz, J.C. (1992), ‘Note: Trawling for Taxpayers: Section 6038A and Transfer Pricing Regulations’, 42 Case Western Reserve Law Review, 933 ff. Shaffer, G.C. (1988), ‘An Alternative to Unilateral Immigration Controls: Toward a Coordinated U.S.-Mexico Binational Approach’, 40 Stanford Law Review. Shaviro, Daniel N. (1992), ‘An Economic and Political Look at Federalism in Taxation’, 90 Michigan Law Review. Shuldiner, R. (1992), ‘A General Approach to the Taxation of Financial Instruments’, Texas Law Review in Frech, H. E. (ed.), Regulating Doctors’ Fees: Competition, Benefits, and Controls under Medicare, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute. Sinn, Hans-Werner (1984), ‘Die Bedeutung des Accelerated Cost Recovery System fur den Internationalen Kapitalverkehr (The Importance of the Accelerated Cost Recovery System for International Capital Transfers)’, 37 Kyklos, 542-576. Sinn, Hans-Werner (1990), ‘Tax Harmonization and Tax Competition in Europe’, 34 European Economic Review. Sinn, Hans-Werner (1993), ‘Taxation and the Birth of Foreign Subsidiaries’, in Herberg, H. and Long, N.V. (eds), Trade Welfare, and Economic Policies: Essays in Honor of Murray C Kemp, Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 325-352. Sinn, Stefan (1990), ‘Capital Market Integration: Issues of International Taxation: Comment’, in Siebert, H. (ed.), Reforming Capital Income Taxation, Westview Press, 166-169. Siverson, S.E. (1994), ‘Where a Tax Disadvantage Looms Large: Interest Expense and the American Corporate Return to South Africa’, Pace International Law Review, Slemrod, Joel B. (1988), ‘Effect of Taxation with International Capital Mobility’, in Aaron, Henry J., Galper, Harveu and Pechman, Joseph A. (eds), Uneasy Compromise: Problems of a Hybrid Income-Consumption Tax, Washington, Brookings Institution. Slemrod, Joel B. (1990a), ‘Optimal Taxation and the Optimal Tax System’, 4 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 157-178. Slemrod, Joel B. (1990b), ‘Tax Effects on Foreign Direct Investment in the United States: Evidence From a Cross-Country Comparison’, in Slemrod, J. and Razin, A. (eds), Taxation in the Global Economy, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Slemrod, Joel B. (1992), ‘Here or There? The Source and Residence Principles of International Taxation: Comment’, in Bird, R.M. and Mintz, J.M. (eds), Taxation to 2000 and Beyond. Canadian Tax Paper, Toronto, Canadian Tax Foundation, 333-337. Slemrod, Joel B. (1995), ‘Free Trade Taxation and Protectionist Taxation’, 2(3) International Tax and Public Finance, 471-489. Smith, E.J. (1993), ‘The U.S.-Mexico Tax Treaty’, 8 Florida International Law Journal, 97 ff. Smith, Robert S. (1987), ‘Motor Vehicle Tax Harmonization’, in Cnossen, S. (ed.), Tax Coordination in the European Community, London, Kluwer Law and Taxation, 141-170.
6080
International Taxation
299
Sorensen, Peter Birch (1988), ‘Optimal Taxation of Capital and Labor in a Small Open Economy’, Paper presented at the International Conference On ‘Tax Reform for Tax Neutrality’, University of Bielefeld, Germany, May 30 - June 2, 1988. Sorensen, Peter Birch (1992), ‘Coordination of Capital Income Taxes in the Economic and Monetary Union: What Needs to be Done?’, Mimeo. Sowle, L.A. (1989), ‘International Debt for Equity Swaps: Does Revenue Ruling 87-124 Make Sense? (Comment)’, 83 Northwestern University Law Review. Steines, J.P. (1994), ‘Colloquium on NAFTA and Tradition: Commentary: Income Tax Implications of Free Trade’, 49 New York University Tax Law Review, 675 ff. Stevens, G.V.G. and Lipsey, R.E. (1992), ‘Interactions Between Domestic and Foreign Investment’, 11 Journal of International Money and Finance, 40-62. Stockmann, Frank (1995), ‘Should the Exemption Method Have Priority over the Credit Method in International Tax Law?’, 49(6) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 285-288. Sullivan, Mark (1984), ‘In Memoriam: Stanley S. Surrey: Appendix’, 97 Harvard Law Review. Surrey, Stanley S. (1958), ‘The United States Taxation of Foreign Income’, 1 Journal of Law and Economics, 72-96. Swenson, D. (1994), ‘The Impact of U.S. Tax Reform on Foreign Direct Investment in the United States’, 54 Journal of Public Economics, 243-266. Tanzi, V. and Minassian, T.T. (1987), ‘The European Monetary System and Fiscal Policies’, in Cnossen, S. (ed.), Tax Coordination in the European Community, London, Kluwer Law and Taxation. Tanzi, Vito (1995), Taxation in an Integrating World, Washington, Brookings Institution. Tatarowicz, P.M. and Mims-Velarde, R.F. (1986), ‘Symposium on State and Local Taxation: An Analytical Approach to State Tax Discrimination Under the Commerce Clause’, 39 Vanderbilt Law Review. Tiebout, Charles M. (1956), ‘A Pure Theory of Local Expenditures’, 56 Journal of Political Economy, 416-424. Tillinghast, D.R. (1996), ‘Tax Treaty Issues’, 50 University of Miami Law Review, Trachtman, J.P. (1991), ‘Recent Initiatives in International Financial Regulation and Goals of Competitiveness, Effectiveness, Consistency and Cooperation’, 12 Journal of International Law and Business, 241 ff. U.S. Congress, Joint Commitee on Taxation (1987), General Explanation of the Tax Reform Act of 1986, Washington, Government Printing Office. U.S. Congress, Joint Commitee on Taxation (1991), Factors Affecting the International Competitiveness of the United States, Washington, Government Printing Office. Ulph, D.T. (1987), ‘Tax Harmonisation and Labour Mobility’, in Cnossen, S. (ed.), Tax Coordination in the European Community, London, Kluwer Law and Taxation, 305-317. Utz, S.G. (1994), ‘Taxation Panel: Tax Harmonization and Coordination in Europe and America’, 9 Connecticut Journal of International Law, 767 ff. Vagts, D.F. (1981), ‘Comment: Are There No International Lawyers Anymore?’,75 American Journal of International Law, 134 ff. Vann, Richard J. and Parsons, Ross W. (1986), ‘The Foreign Tax Credit and Reform of International Taxation’, 3(2) Australian Tax Forum, 131-221. Vernon, R. (1977), Storm Over the Multinationals: The Real Issues, Cambridge, Harvard University
300
International Taxation
6080
Press. Wahl, J. (1989), ‘Tax Treatment of Foreign Exchange Gains and Losses and the Tax Reform Act of 1986', 42(1) National Tax Journal, 59-68. Waterland, L.J. (1985), ‘Note: Container Corporation of America v. Franchise Tax Board: The Supreme Court Encourages Apportionment Taxation’, 26 William & Mary Law Review, 683 ff. Weinberg, K. S. (1994), ‘Arbitration Procedures in the United States-German Income Tax’, 12 Boston University International Law Journal, 180 ff. Weiner, Joann (1996a), ‘Using the Experience of the U.S. States to Evaluate Issues in Implementing Formula Apportionment at the International Level’, Dec. 23 Tax Notes International, 2113-2144. Weiner, Joann (1996b), ‘Estimates of How the Unitary Tax Affects Business Investment’, Working Paper, Jan. 3, 1996. Wheeler, J.E. (1988), ‘An Academic Look at Transfer Pricing in a Global Economy’, 87 Tax Notes, 96 ff. Whitman, D.S. (1995), ‘Recent Developments: Barclays Bank v. Franchise Tax Board of California: Worldwide Combined Reporting Survives For State Taxation of Multinational Enterprises’, 3 Tulane Journal of International and Comparative Law, 265 ff. Wildasin, David E. (1986), Urban Public Finance, New York, Harwood Academic Press. Willard, Kristen L. (1994), Essays On International Taxation, Princeton, Princeton University Press. Wilson, G.P. (1993), ‘The Role of Taxes in Location and Sourcing Decisions’, in Giovannini, A., Hubbard, R.G. and Slemrod, J. (eds), Studies in International Taxation, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Wong Pakshong, Michael (1980), ‘The Future Position of Singapore in International Taxation’, 34(4) Bulletin for International Fiscal Documentation, 146-149. Workman, D.J. (1982), ‘Comment: The Use of Offshore Tax Havens for the Purpose of Criminally Evading Income Taxes’, 73 Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 675 ff. Young, Garry (1994), ‘International Competitiveness, International Taxation and Domestic Investment’, 0(148) National Institute Economic Review, 44-48. Young, K.H. (1988), ‘The Effects of Taxes and Rates of Return on Foreign Direct Investment Into the United States’, 41 National Tax Journal, 109-121. Zodrow, George R. (1991), ‘On the “Traditional” and “New” Views of Dividend Taxation’, 44 National Tax Journal, 497-509. Zodrow, George R. and Mieszkowski, Peter (1986), ‘Pigou, Tiebout, Property Taxation, and the Underprovision of Public Goods’, 19 Journal of Urban Economics, 356-370. Zucker, D. (1983), ‘Note: MCA, Inc. v. United States: Judicial Recognition of the Separate Interests Theory’, 5 Journal of International Law and Business, 680 ff.
6110 OPTIMAL TECHNIQUES OF REDISTRIBUTION Christopher Curran Associate Professor, Emory University Department of Economics © Copyright 1999 Christopher Curran
Abstract Legal scholars have often argued that a legal system in providing a ‘level playing field’ for consumers and producers should be designed to help in society’s efforts to achieve an optimal distribution of income. This chapter reviews research by law and economics scholars that challenges this premise. Using neoclassical welfare economics most of these scholars conclude that there exists a taxation scheme that achieves a desired income distribution and is preferred by all members of society to any plan for redistributing income using the legal system. An implication of this research is that economic efficiency and not fairness is the appropriate criteria for evaluating any legal rule. JEL classification: K0, H2 Keywords: Income Redistribution, Taxation
1. Introduction In this chapter we examine the issue of whether income redistribution goals are more efficiently achieved by using the tax system or by incorporating these goals into the design and implementation of a legal system. As stated, this question takes as given that some amount of income redistribution is desirable and ignores the extensive literature on (1) the desirability of income redistribution and (2) the effectiveness of income redistribution in combating poverty. While the problem that remains - that of developing the most cost effective method of achieving the desired income distribution - has a strong production flavor, the answer has important implications both for the study and practice of law. If the arguments of Kaplow and Shavell (1994) and others are correct, then law and economics scholars should adopt their suggestion that ‘it is appropriate for economic analysis of legal rules to focus on efficiency and to ignore the distribution of income in offering normative judgments’ (Kaplow and Shavell, 1994, p. 677). If their analysis is flawed or if, as some authors suggest, traditional neoclassical economics models contain serious deficiencies, then the arguments of Calabresi (1991), Kronman (1980), Kennedy (1982) and Arlen (1992) that the courts should consider income distribution when evaluating legal rules have merit. 301
302
Optimal Techniques of Redistribution
6110
2. Two Lines of Research It is not unusual for legal scholars to assume that courts ought to be concerned with the proper distribution of income. Indeed, given that allowing the courts to consider issues of income distribution in judging cases will increase the demand for the services of lawyers and the legal system, it would be surprising if legal scholars were unanimous in concluding that courts ought to ignore the implications of legal policies on the income distribution (see, for example, Polinsky and Shavell, 1991). Moreover, Friedman’s (1981) and Lott’s (1987) papers imply that a court should consider a party’s wealth when that consideration leads to optimal deterrence. Rather than reviewing all of this literature, this chapter focuses on articles directly addressing the issue of whether it is more efficient to use the legal system or taxation to redistribute income. Heavy reliance on neoclassical economic theory and (usually) mathematical models characterizes the articles contributing to this discussion.
3. Related Literature While Shavell (1981) is the first law and economics scholar to address the issue of the most efficient way to redistribute income, his arguments draw directly from the optimal taxation literature of the 1970s. (See Auerbach, 1985, and Stiglitz, 1985, for thorough reviews of the optimal taxation literature and Drèze and Stern, 1985, for a review of the cost-benefit literature.) Shavell acknowledges his particular intellectual debt to two articles in this literature. In the first, Mirrlees (1971) demonstrates that commodities whose demand are independent of income should not be taxed (with a fixed per unit tax) when there is an optimal income taxation system in place. In the second, Hylland and Zeckhauser (1979, p. 266) demonstrate that ‘in the optimal arrangement, distributional objectives are achieved through the tax system alone’. Moreover, Hylland and Zeckhauser conclude that, in the presence of the optimal income tax, government programs should be adopted based purely on efficiency criteria. Shavell’s 1981 paper reaches a conclusion that echoes that of Hylland and Zeckhauser. In particular, Shavell (1981, p. 414) argues that ‘despite imperfect ability to redistribute income through taxation, everyone would strictly prefer that legal rules be chosen only on the basis of their efficiency’.
4. Legal Scholarship The conclusions of Shavell (1981) are contrary to those made by earlier legal scholars. Scholars such as Ackerman (1973), Kennedy (1976), Michelman
6110
Optimal Techniques of Redistribution
303
(1978), and Kronman (1980) argue that an important role of legal institutions is to redistribute income. Indeed, Kronman (1980, p. 510) argues that the choice between using the legal system and using taxation to redistribute income depends on ‘contextual considerations that are likely to vary from one situation to the next’. Kronman suggests that all of the alleged problems with using courts to redistribute income are equally likely to be problems with taxation. For instance, critics of using the courts to redistribute income claim that there is no reason to believe that judges can correctly assess the distributional consequences of any particular decision. Kronman counters that difficulty in applying egalitarian rules in individual cases does not mean that we cannot use egalitarian principles when designing the legal system. To the claim that the legal system should ‘remain neutral between the aims and activities of its citizens’ (Kronman, 1980, p. 502), Kronman responds that taxation is no more neutral than are the courts and the relative neutrality of the two methods of redistributing income is an empirical issue. Kronman responds in a similar manner to claims that regulation is more injurious to its intended beneficiaries and is more expensive to administer than is taxation by asserting that these are empirical issues than cannot be resolved through the use of theory alone, a conclusion not supported by Shavell (1981).
5. Shavell Forgotten Not only does Shavell’s research offer conclusions contrary to earlier research, it appears to have been ignored by legal scholars during the ten years following its publication. Calabresi (1991), Donohue (1989), Ellis (1982) and Kennedy (1982) all discuss the role of the legal system in achieving the proper distribution of income without mentioning Shavell’s 1981 seminal article. Abraham and Jeffries (1989), who argue that information about a defendant’s wealth should not be considered in determining punitive awards, do not reference Shavell. In their defense, the connection of Shavell’s conclusion to the issue that Abraham and Jeffries discuss is not obvious. Abraham and Jeffries argue that the consideration of a defendant’s wealth is not germane to the issue of punitive damages and invites jury speculation about issues about which they have no information. They argue that traditional arguments that the legal system needs punitive damages in order to deter individuals from inflicting harm for personal satisfaction and to neutralize the effects of underenforcement are incorrect. While Abraham and Jeffries do not point out the connection, their arguments echo those of both Hylland and Zeckhauser (1979) and Shavell (1981) that distributional goals are best achieved through the tax system while government programs - including legal regulation - should ignore distributional goals in favor of efficiency criteria. Thus, by Hylland and Zeckhauser’s and Shavell’s logic one would consider the defendant’s wealth
304
Optimal Techniques of Redistribution
6110
only in cases wealth is correlated with deterrence, a conclusion that matches Abraham and Jeffries’ result.
6. Shavell Remembered Arlen (1992) appears to be the first author to acknowledge Shavell’s 1981 article. While the model that Shavell develops assumes that people are risk neutral, he points out that his results are independent of this assumption. Arlen argues, incorrectly it turns out, that Shavell’s conclusions do not hold when individuals are risk averse. The most recent contributions to this literature are in direct response to what Kaplow and Shavell (1994) and Miceli and Segerson (1995) perceive as a general misunderstanding of Shavell’s 1981 article by legal scholars, including Arlen (1992). In what follows, we discuss Shavell (1981) and Kaplow and Shavell (1994) together because of the similarities in the two articles. We then review Miceli and Segerson (1995). Since the model in Miceli and Segerson (1995) corrects and places Arlen’s results in the context of the Shavell model, we include Arlen (1992) in this discussion.
7. Shavell’s Analysis The arguments in Shavell (1981) and Kaplow and Shavell (1994) are essentially identical. These authors argue that all efforts to redistribute income be these efforts through the legal system or through the tax system - distort work efforts (see Hausman, 1981, for an empirical justification of this point). Redistributing income through the legal system creates additional inefficiencies in the activities affected by the legal rules. Thus, we should be able to construct a new tax schedule that we can combine with efficient legal rules that will have the same distortions of work effort but none of the inefficiencies that arise when we use the legal system to redistribute income.
8. Achieving a Desired Income Distribution Since this result is key, we consider it here in some detail. Shavell (1981) and Kaplow and Shavell (1994) assume that individuals are risk neutral maximizers of expected utility, which is equal to their income net of taxes, expected liability costs, expected damages, and the costs of work effort and care taking. The tax schedule is a function of income while the expected liability and damages are functions of the level of care taken by the individual. In order to simplify the analysis, these authors assume that (1) an individual’s income is a linear
6110
Optimal Techniques of Redistribution
305
function of his work effort and (2) in the aggregate the government returns all taxes collected. Following existing literature, they define the efficient level of care as that care level that minimizes sum of the total costs of care and the expected accident costs. As Shavell (1981, p. 416) and Kaplow and Shavell (1994, p. 678) note, the level of care that is efficient is independent of an individual’s income. These authors show that we can replace any regime having an inefficient legal rule and a tax schedule with a regime with an efficient legal rule and a properly modified tax schedule that raises the same level of taxes. More importantly, they also show that all members of society prefer the regime with the efficient legal rule.
9. Modification of the Tax Schedule The modification to the tax schedule under the inefficient legal rule offers some insight into what drives these results. The modified tax schedule is equal to the tax schedule in the inefficient regime plus the total accident costs in the inefficient regime minus the total accident costs in the efficient regime (see Kaplow and Shavell, 1994, p. 678). Substitution of the new tax schedule into the expected utility function yields the results that the expected utility is the same in the efficient regime (with the modified tax schedule) as it is in the inefficient regime. Moreover, this new tax schedule yields a greater level of revenue. Remember that the modified tax schedule is equal to the old tax schedule plus the efficiency savings that come from switching to the efficient legal rule. Thus, if we rebate these savings uniformly to the population in the form of a lump sum (negative) tax, no-one’s incentive to work is affected and everyone is better off by the amount of the rebate in taxes.
10. Other Reasons for Using the Tax System to Achieve Distributional Goals Kaplow and Shavell (1994, pp. 674-676) offer several other, more traditional reasons for favoring the use of the tax system over the legal system to redistribute income. First, the tax system can allocate the impact of income redistribution on all of the rich and all of the poor. By contrast, using the legal system to redistribute income yields haphazard results. The legal system can only affect those individuals involved in a lawsuit. Moreover, in many cases consumer response is bound to mute or completely negate efforts to use the courts to redistribute income. For instance, individuals bound by contracts will adjust prices to take account of efforts by the courts to redistribute income. Similarly, corporations may well be able to pass on to consumers the income redistribution efforts by the courts. Second, Kaplow and Shavell (1994, p. 675)
306
Optimal Techniques of Redistribution
6110
argue that claims that the legal system should be involved in income redistribution efforts because the political system is unable to achieve the ideal amount of income redistribution do not stand close examination. In particular, the legal system operates under the influence of the politicians and there is no reason to believe that efforts by the courts to redistribute income in ways not intended by the politicians will escape their scrutiny. Thus, Kaplow and Shavell (1994, p. 677) conclude that their analysis ‘suggests that it is appropriate for economic analysis of legal rules to focus on efficiency and to ignore the distribution of income in offering normative judgments’.
11. A General Model Miceli and Segerson (1995) offer the most complete analysis of the issue of role of income distribution in setting efficient levels of care. These authors analyze the role of risk aversion in the Shavell (1981) and Kaplow and Shavell (1994) model. In doing so, they correct and reconcile Arlen’s (1992) results with the other models. Miceli and Segerson argue that of the three potential optimal choice criteria - Pareto efficiency, the Pareto criterion, and aggregate welfare Pareto efficiency is the proper one to use. They define Pareto efficiency by the following choice problem: Max Ui subject to Uv U ov (1) where Ui is the utility level of the injurer, Uv is the utility level of victim, and U ov is some arbitrarily fixed level of utility for the victim. The Pareto criterion has the same definition as (1), except that U ov is set equal to the victim’s original utility level, U( W ov ). Finally, aggregate welfare is the solution to the following choice problem: Max Ui + Uv(2) is where some weight placed on the victim’s utility. Miceli and Segerson (1995, p. 194) illustrate the three concepts with the utility possibilities frontier (UPF) shown in Figure 1. The UPF contains all of the Pareto optimal points. As illustrated in Figure 1, the Pareto criterion and the aggregate welfare each pick points that are subsets of the Pareto optimal points. The authors prefer to use Pareto optimality as their choice criterion for two reasons. First, unlike the other concepts, Pareto optimality does not involve interpersonal comparisons of utility. Second, we can specify any income distribution by varying U ov .
6110
Optimal Techniques of Redistribution
307
Figure 1 The utility possibility curve (UPC) for injurer and victim
12. Definition of Terms Miceli and Segerson (1995, p. 197) define P(X) to be the probability of an accident (where P' > and P'' < 0); X, the injurer’s care level; m, the damages that the victim suffers if there is an accident; Wi and Wv, the injurer’s and victim’s preaccident wealth levels, respectively; D, the damages paid by the injurer in case of an accident; and T, a (positive or negative) transfer from the injurer to the victim that occurs independent of whether an accident occurs. As Miceli and Segerson (1995, p. 197) note, the addition of the variable T allows them to ‘decouple distribution and cost minimization issues’. They then split the analysis into two distinct parts. In the first they derive the first-best care levels while in the second they analyze the ability of various liability rules to give individuals the incentives necessary to take these first-best care levels.
13. Efficient Care Standards Miceli and Segerson (1995) show that in the presence of fully working insurance markets, the first-best care standards are independent of both injurer’s and victim’s wealth levels as long as the policymaker is free to choose the care standard and the amount of the transfer, T. Only in the case where the policymaker can only set the care standard is the care standard a function of the injurer’s wealth. For instance, Arlen (1992) implicitly assumes in her analysis that the amount of the transfer, T, and the amount of damages, D, are preset such that T = D = 0. Figure 2 illustrates the case when the policymaker can only set the care standard. The solid curve labeled UPF1 is the utility
308
Optimal Techniques of Redistribution
6110
possibilities frontier that faces the policymaker who is free to set the care standard and the amount of the transfer. Since the policymaker’s choice set is restricted, the utility possibilities frontier available to the policy maker who can only set the care standard must lie inside the unrestricted UPF at all points except the point where T and D by coincidence equal the levels that would occur in the unrestricted case. In Figure 2 the dashed line labeled UPF2 represents the restricted UPF, while point A represents the one point where T and D equal the values they would have in the unrestricted case. Clearly, there exist solutions on UPF1 where both the victim and the injurer can achieve higher utility levels than they can on the restricted UPF2. Figure 2 Restricted and unrestricted utility possibility curves
14. Efficiency of the Legal Rules By choosing appropriate liability rules society attempts to induce injurers to take the efficient level of care. The potential success of society in achieving this goal while concurrently attempting to reach an ideal distribution of income depends on the number of policy tools available to the policy makers. Miceli and Segerson (1995, pp. 200-202) analyze the efficiency of strict liability and negligence under various assumptions about the choice variables available to the policy makers. As they note, the efficient care level solves Max Ui subject to Uv U ov and X maximized Ui(3) given the liability rule. Miceli and Segerson demonstrate that, when policymakers can set the care standard X, the damage award D, and the transfer from the injurer to the victim T, both strict liability and negligence rules are efficient. The reason for this result is that the policy makers have three tools - X, D, and T - with which to achieve three goals income distribution, cost minimization and efficient incentives for the injurer.
6110
Optimal Techniques of Redistribution
309
Thus, the policy makers can set X to minimize total social cost, D to give the injurer the proper incentives, and T to redistribute income, resulting in society attaining a point somewhere on UPF1, as shown in Figure 2. In contrast, if one or two of the three control instruments are not available to the policymakers, then society can achieve the three goals only by coincidence.
15. An Existence Theorem The results presented by Shavell (1981), Miceli and Segerson (1995) and Kaplow and Shavell (1994) comprise an existence theorem - if society decides to redistribute income, there exists a tax schedule for redistributing income that everyone prefers to any other way of redistributing income, including the use of legal rules or institutions. As Kaplow and Shavell (1994, p. 675) note, the importance of this result to legal scholars is that it demonstrates that it is appropriate to evaluate legal rules only on the basis of efficiency criteria.
Bibliography on Optimal Techniques of Redistribution (6110) Abraham, Kenneth S. and Jeffries, John C. Jr (1989), ‘Punitive Damages and the Rule of Law: The Role of Defendant’s Wealth’, 28 Journal of Legal Studies, 415-425. Ackerman, Bruce (1973), ‘Regulating Slum Housing Markets on Behalf of the Poor: Of Housing Codes, Housing Subsidies and Income Redistribution Policy’, 80 Yale Law Journal, 1093-1197. Arlen, Jennifer H. (1992), ‘Should Defendants’ Wealth Matter?’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 413-429. Hylland, Aanund and Zeckhauser, Richard (1979), ‘Distributional Objectives Should Affect Taxes but Not Program Choice or Design’, 81 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 264-284. Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (1994), ‘Why the Legal System is Less Efficient than the Income Tax in Redistributing Income’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 667-681. Miceli, Thomas J. and Segerson, Kathleen (1995), ‘Defining Efficient Care: The Role of Income Distribution’, 24 Journal of Legal Studies, 189-208. Shavell, Steven (1981), ‘A Note on Efficiency vs. Distributional Equity in Legal Rulemaking: Should Distributional Equity Matter Given Optimal Income Taxation?’, 71 American Economic Review, 414-418.
Other References Auerbach, Alan J. (1985), ‘The Theory of Excess Burden and Optimal Taxation’, in Auerbach, Alan J. and Feldstein, Martin (eds), Handbook of Public Economics, Amsterdam, Elsevier Science Publishers B.V. (North Holland), 61-127.
310
Optimal Techniques of Redistribution
6110
Calabresi, Guido (1991), ‘The Pointlessness of Pareto: Carrying Coase Further’, 100 Yale Law Journal, 1211-1237. Donohue, John J. III (1989), ‘Diverting the Coasean River: Incentive Schemes to Reduce Unemployment Spells’, 99 Yale Law Journal, 549-609. Drèze, Jean and Stern, Nicholas (1985), ‘The Theory of Cost-Benefit Analysis’, in Auerbach, Alan J. and Feldstein, Martin (eds), Handbook of Public Economics, Amsterdam, Elsevier Science Publishers B.V. (North Holland), 909-989. Ellis, Dorsey D., Jr (1982), ‘Fairness and Efficiency in the Law of Punitive Damages’, 56 Southern California Law Review, 1-78. Friedman, David D. (1981), ‘Reflections on Optimal Punishment, or: Should the Rich Pay Higher Fines’, 3 Research in Law and Economics, 185-205. Hausman, Jerry A. (1981), ‘Labor Supply’, in Aaron, Henry J. and Pechman, Joseph A. (eds) How Taxes Affect Economic Behavior, Washington, DC, Brookings Institution, 27-72. Kennedy, Duncan (1976), ‘Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication’, 89 Harvard Law Journal, 1685-1778. Kennedy, Duncan (1982), ‘Distributive and Paternalist Motives in Contract and Tort Law, with Special Reference to Compulsory terms and Unequal Bargaining Power’, 41 Maryland Law Review, 563-658. Kronman, Anthony T. (1980), ‘Contract Law and Distributive Justice’, 89 Yale Law Journal, 472-511. Lott, John R., Jr. (1987), ‘Should the Wealthy Be Able to “Buy Justice?”’, 95 Journal of Political Economy, 1307-1316. Michelman, Frank I. (1978), ‘Norms and Normativity in the Economic Theory of the Law’, 62 Minnesota Law Review, 1015-1048. Mirrlees, J.A. (1971), ‘An Exploration in the Theory of Optimum Income Taxation’, 38 Review of Economic Studies, 175-208. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1991), ‘A Note on Optimal Fines When Wealth Varies Among Individuals’, 81 American Economic Review, 618-621. Shavell, Steven (1982), ‘On Liability and Insurance’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 120-132. Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1985), ‘Pareto Efficient and Optimal Taxation and the New New Welfare Economics’, in Auerbach, Alan J. and Feldstein, Martin (ed.) Handbook of Public Economics, Amsterdam, Elsevier Science Publishers B.V. (North Holland), 991-1042.
6120 PENSIONS Koen Algoed and Frans Spinnewyn University of Leuven © Copyright 1999 Koen Algoed and Frans Spinnewyn
Abstract This chapter discusses the different pension systems. Pension systems are a means of transferring purchasing power from the working phase to the retirement phase of the life cycle. Formal pension systems are organised in two ways. In the funded or the capital-reserve system, the agents save to accumulate a fund which finances an annuity to the survivors. In the pay-as-you-go system, the payment of the pensions to the retired population are financed by the contributions of the working population. It is shown that capital-reserve systems and pay-as-you-go systems, two variants of providing retirement income, may yield the same outcome or may yield allocations differing only in their second order effects. Capital-reserve systems are superior to pay-as-you-go systems in the definition of the future rights of the retired population. Pay-as-you-go systems are better suited to redistribute the burden of major shocks among the working generations and the retired generations. Reforms fixing the individual rights of the retired population conditional on the state of the economy and the record of individual contributions are desirable. Alternatively, adapting the tax status of funded pension plans to the state of the economy in a well-defined way could improve the risksharing properties of the capital-reserve system. JEL classification: H55 Keywords: Overlapping Generations, Pay-as-you-go, Capital Reserve, Aaron’s Rule, Social Risk
1. Saving for Retirement Old-age pension plans are a means of transferring purchasing power from the working phase to the retirement phase of the life cycle. The wages earned while working constitute a claim on the output of the economy. By refraining from consuming part of this claim, output can be devoted to investment or consumption of collective goods.. The contributions to a pension fund are an example. Through the pension fund, these financial means are lent to firms for the acquisition of capital assets or to the 311
312
Pensions
6120
government for providing collective goods. In this way, the retired population derives a claim on the output of the economy, either by sharing in the income appropriated by the capital owners or by sharing in the taxes levied by the government to service the debt. This income finances consumption after retirement. Alternatively, working children can share their claim on the output of the economy with their retired parents. In this way, the parents are given the opportunity to satisfy their consumption needs after retirement. In the extended family, the children care for their parents in the hope of being cared for by their children in old age. On a broader scale, in a formal pension plan part of the wages earned by the working population are transferred to the retired population. In this way, the retired generation obtains a claim on the output of the economy even when they are no longer involved in the production process. Like private saving, old-age pension plans therefore smooth consumption over the life cycle. However, the transfer of purchasing power in a pension plan is conditional on the survival after retirement. Formal pension plans covering large populations redistribute income from the short-lived to the long-lived. In addition to the transfer of purchasing power, formal pension plans offer insurance against longevity. Old-age pensions insure against the risk that the retiree will outlive the amount saved for the provision of retirement income (Bodie, 1990a). In this way, those who have contributed for a pension but die before or live only for a short while after retirement contribute to and increase the retirement income of those who are blessed with a long life. The rate of return for the survivors in a pension plan exceeds the rate of return on saving, the difference being equal to the mortality rate. The reason is that the rights of those who die are transferred to the survivors. Restricting transfers to the survivors is motivated by the fact that only the survivors still have consumption needs. In contrast, the wealth accumulated through saving is bequeathed to the heirs. Due to the stochastic nature of the length of life, the bequest at the time of death has a random component. Using the techniques of insurance, formal pension plans can control for this random component. The exchanges between the young and the old generation are therefore better defined in the formal pension plans than in the extended family.
2. The Capital-Reserve System and the Pay-As-You-Go-System Formal pension plans are organised in two ways. In the funded or the capital-reserve system, the agents save to accumulate a fund which finances an annuity to the survivors. At each point of time, the accumulated fund of a cohort of agents together with the contributions which are still due from the
6120
Pensions
313
surviving members of the cohort before retirement, will meet the future pension rights of the survivors in the cohort. In the pay-as-you-go system, the payment of the pensions to the retired population are financed by the contributions of the working population. When the former exceed the latter, the accounts are balanced either by a subsidy of the government financed by taxes or by running down reserves. A pay-as-you-go system can therefore be viewed as a plan of transfer payments from the working population to the retired population. The contributions made while working, provide the agent with a right to receive a pension while retired. From this description, it is concluded that the distinguishing feature between the capital-reserve system and the pay-as-you-go system is the redistribution of income between generations which takes place in the latter but not in the former (Verbon, 1989; Marchand and Pestieau, 1991). However, this conclusion needs the following qualifications. First, workers, capital owners and the taxing authorities have competing claims on the output. Depending on the organisation of the pension plan and the definition of the pension rights, the income of the retired population will depend on the solution of this basic conflict. If the pensions are linked to the income of the working population, as in the pay-as-you-go system, the old-age pensioners gain from an increase in the wage bill. But the interests diverge when both parties bargain over the share of the wage bill accruing to the old-age pensioners. If the pensions are linked to the income of the capital owners, as in the capital-reserve system, then the working generation increases its share at the expense of the retired generation. Second, the transfers between generations in the formal pension plans are complemented by voluntary transfers or bequests. Abstracting from uncertainties, differences in transfer payments between young and old in the pension plans will be offset by changes in the bequests. This neutrality theorem of Barro (1974) is a variant of Ricardian equivalence of government fiscal actions and is based on the life cycle model of savings (Modigliani and Brumberg, 1954). In this model, a consumption profile has the discounted sum of lifetime after-tax income as one of its arguments. Two after-tax income profiles with the same present value result in the same consumption profile. Two pension plans leading to two different profiles of after-tax income but with the same present value do not change consumption. If consumption does not change, investment and the capital formation are not affected by the choice of the pension plan. Barro’s neutrality result has been criticised by the fact that it may require negative bequests at the individual level in order to establish the neutrality of public actions. This will be the case when at the collective level the burden to the future generations of servicing the public debt is low.
314
Pensions
6120
3. Equivalence of Pension Systems Under Certainty In the comparison of formal pension plans, consider an environment without uncertainty apart from the risk of longevity. In the capital-reserve system, the contributions to a pension plan grow with the interest rate which is linked to the marginal productivity of capital. Samuelson (1958) and Aaron (1966) have shown that the contributions to the pay-as-you-go system also earn a return which is composed of the growth rate of the population (Samuelson’s ‘biological’ rate of interest) and the growth rate of wages. Equivalence on the Golden Rule Path Assume that in the capital-reserve system, the age profile of contributions and benefits of any two succeeding generations are obtained from each other by a parallel vertical shift reflecting the growth rate of wages. It then follows that in the steady state the two systems are equivalent if the interest rate is equal to the sum of population and wage growth rates. This can be established as follows. In the capital-reserve system, the capital which has been accumulated during the working life is equal to the discounted future liability of the pension fund at the date of retirement. Consider a pay-as-you-go system in which contributions and benefits of each individual are equal to those of the capital-reserve system. Compare in the pay-as-you-go system the own contributions of the retiring generation when they started working and the current contributions of the youngest generation. The contributions of the youngest generation have increased at a rate equal to the sum of the growth rate of the population and the growth rate of wages for a period equal to the length of the working life. By assumption, this sum is equal to the rate of interest. It follows that the current contribution of the youngest generation in the pay-as-you-go system is equal to the capitalized value of the contributions of the retiring generation as young workers in the capital-reserve system. By shortening the period for which they were contributing each time by one year, the same holds for each of the older working generations. Similarly, for each of the retired generations, the total transfer payments in the pay-as-you-go system are equal to the present value of the future transfer payments of the pension funds when the current retiring generation will be of the same age. In the pay-as-you-go-system, the older retired generations are less numerous and have a lower pension reflecting the lower wage earned in their working life. By assumption, the sum of these effects is matched by the effect of discounting the future liability of the pension fund in the capital-reserve system. Since at the retirement date, the capitalised contributions are equal to the present value of the liabilities in the capital-reserve system, it follows that the pay-as-you-go system which mimics the capital-reserve system breaks even.
6120
Pensions
315
If the interest rate is equal to the growth rate, the economy is at the golden rule. At the golden rule the consumption per head is maximised. The consumption per head is obtained as the difference between the production per head and the investment per head needed to keep the capital-labour ratio constant. The labour force is measured in efficiency units. Consumption per head is then a function of the capital-labour ratio. There is over-accumulation if the capital-labour ratio in the steady state is larger than the ratio in the golden rule. The golden rule is Pareto superior to any steady state with over-accumulation. This is established as follows. Let the capital stock fall by delaying investment until the capital-labour ratio has fallen to the one in the golden rule. Without investment, the consumption of the generations living in the transition can be increased. In the new steady state satisfying the golden rule, the consumption is larger than in the steady state with over-accumulation. The government debt is adjusted to obtain equality between private financial wealth and the sum of the government debt and the value of the capital stock. There is under-accumulation if the capital-labour ratio in the steady state is smaller than the ratio in the golden rule. In this case, one cannot increase the capital-labour ratio without decreasing the consumption of the generations living in the transition. The steady state with under-accumulation is therefore Pareto efficient. Equivalence off the Golden Rule Path Restricting the analysis to Pareto-efficient situations, we conclude that the rate of return on saving in the capital-reserve system is at least as large as the one in the pay-as-you-go system. By and large, the interest rate has always exceeded the growth rate of the economy. From Aaron (1966) to Feldstein (1976), economists as well as politicians have concluded that for that reason the capital-reserve system is more efficient than the pay-as-you-go system. In this comparison, it is implicitly assumed that government debt is the same in the two systems. In an economy with lump-sum taxation, the equivalence of the two systems is re-established when in the pay-as-you-go system the government debt is reduced by an appropriate amount (Bewley, 1981; Myles, 1995). The argument is based on the life-cycle model stating that the consumption profile is unaffected by a change in the after-tax income profile which does not change its present value. When compared to the capital-reserve system, the pay-as-you-go system has higher taxes before retirement but lower taxes after retirement. If the interest rate exceeds the growth rate of the economy, the two systems yield the same consumption profile for an average tax rate which is larger in the capital-reserve system than in the pay-as-you-go system. The tax rate is increased in the
316
Pensions
6120
capital-reserve system by increasing the taxes needed to service a larger government debt. The same conclusion is obtained when it is assumed that the pay-as-you-go system mimics the capital-reserve system. If the interest rate exceeds the growth rate of the economy, it follows from the previous discussion that per retiring agent the contributions of the working generations in the pay-as-you-go system fall short of his or her accumulated savings in the capital-reserve system. The transfer payments to the retired generations in the pay-as-you-go system exceed the present value of the future liability to a retiring agent in the capital-reserve system. From the equality of the accumulated savings and the present value of future liabilities at the retirement date in the capital-reserve system, it follows that the pay-as-you-go system runs a deficit. When the government subsidy needed to restore the balance is equal to the tax saving from a lower government debt, the two systems are equivalent. The conversion of a pay-as-you-go system to a capital-reserve system shows that, ceteris paribus, the government debt must be larger in the latter than in the former (Townley, 1981; Breyer, 1989; Verbon, 1989). In the transition period, the retired generations receive pension payments equivalent to those they would have received for the fraction of their working life that they contributed under the old system. No generation is therefore sacrificed. The gap needed to compensate these generations is closed by an increase in government debt which is taken up by the pension funds. But then, after the transition period, no generation will benefit from the higher rate of return of the capital-reserve system. The government subsidy which was needed under the pay-as-you-go system is replaced by an increase in the average tax rate to service the larger debt. Although a consensus on the issue of the performance of pension systems has not been reached, we conclude that investment needed to raise the capital stock in a state of under-accumulation can be achieved only by reducing aggregate consumption at the outset. Consider an environment without uncertainty and without distortionary taxation. For a given rate of interest, the utility-maximising consumption profile is chosen within the intertemporal budget of each generation. An increase in the capital stock requires a higher investment rate and, therefore, an adjustment in the consumption profile. An adjustment of an optimal consumption profile is possible only by decreasing the lifetime utility. It then follows that increasing the capital stock is impossible unless at least one generation is made worse off. From this conclusion it does not follow that the different definition of the rights of pensioners in the capital-reserve system and in the pay-as-you-go system is unimportant. The definition of the rights in each of the systems
6120
Pensions
317
and in their variants determines the risk borne by the retirees and the risk sharing between the agents in the economy. In addition, the allocation of pension rights provide different incentives to contribute to a pension system affecting both the level of contributions and the choice of the retirement age. Finally, market imperfections in the form of asymmetric information on survival risks, transaction costs, myopia and free riding must be taken into account.
4. Pension as Retirement Income Insurance Through contributions during the working years, pension plans are designed to protect an economic agent against economic insecurity in retirement. In addition to the longevity risk, the following major sources of retirement income risk can be distinguished (Bodie, 1990a; Disney, 1996). First, the replacement rate inadequacy reflects the risk that the retiree is unable to maintain the same standard of living after retiring as during the pre-retirement years. Consumption is smoothed by linking the pension to some measure of final earnings and the years of service. Occupational pensions of the ‘defined benefit’ form and pensions of civil servants belong to this type. In contrast, personal pensions of the ‘defined contribution’ form depend on the total contributions and investment earnings of the accumulation in the account of the employee. Capital market uncertainty reflects the risk that the retirement income will be inadequate because of poor performance of the capital market. Inflation risk affects the purchasing power of retirement savings. Pay-as-you-go systems are insulated from these two previous sources of risk, since the pension benefits are related to the contributions of the wage earners. Wage income fluctuates less than rental incomes and wages are adjusted to inflation. Finally, by the time the retirement age is reached, the individual risks that either the social insurance provisions in the pay-as-you-go system or the tax status of the pensions in the capital-reserve system have been changed. In defining the rights of the retiree in an optimal pension plan, the reduction of economic insecurity in one direction will imply greater economic insecurity in another direction. The reason is that aggregate production varies from year to year so that the uncertainty on the production side must somehow be reflected on the consumption side. If none of the pension plans dominates the others, agents may participate in pension plans of different types and, in addition, accumulate private wealth for retirement. In particular, human capital and housing property are a hedge against inflation risk (Feldstein, 1983; Summers, 1983). The choice between the various pension instruments and private saving can be described using the
318
Pensions
6120
theory of portfolio selection (Augier, Chaveau and Loupias, 1995). The retirement income in the capital-reserve system depends on the stochastic rate of return of investments in physical capital and the tax status of pension plans. For the retirement income in the pay-as-you-go system, the stochastic rate of return depends on the wage growth, on the population growth and on changing social security provisions. The choice of the mix depends on the expected return and the systematic risk of each alternative. A pension plan with a greater exposure to economic insecurity will compensate the participant with a larger rate of return.
5. Optimal Risk Sharing The final appraisal of the efficiency of a mix of pension instruments should depend on its potential to eliminate idiosyncratic risks at the individual level (Borch, 1962; Fisher, 1983; Townsend, 1994). Optimal risk sharing is achieved when changing consumption levels of individuals living at the same time can be explained by changes in their aggregate endowment. Other peculiarities, in particular whether an individual is retired or not, should have no further explaining power. As a result, the individual consumption levels should move together with the aggregate endowment. Otherwise, a reallocation of endowments is welfare improving. Consider an individual or a small group of individuals with a high income when the income of others is low in a bad state and with a low income when the income of others is high in a good state. Then this group should give to the others in the bad state in return for a gift in the good state. When chosen appropriately, such a reallocation which gives to everybody an income which is lower in the bad state than in the good state is welfare improving for risk averse agents. Everybody’s income as a donor exceeds his or her income as a beneficiary in the reallocation of the endowments. The marginal cost of giving is therefore less than the marginal gain of receiving. From the perspective of optimal risk sharing, the income received by the old age pensioners and the income of the working population should move together. For this reason, Musgrave (1981) proposed a pension plan which determines old-age pensions as a fixed proportion of labour income per worker. Assume that workers transfer a fixed proportion of their income to old-age pensioners, that the ratio of old-age pensioners to workers is constant over time and that the share of labour income in total income is fixed. This definition of pension rights in a pay-as-you-go system is well suited to achieve optimal risk sharing when the growth rate of income is uncertain.
6120
Pensions
319
Note that in a capital-reserve system, capital market risk and inflation risk could be eliminated by the government issuing bonds with a risk-free real rate of return. But from the perspective of optimal risk sharing, insulating the retired population from economic insecurity by shifting aggregate risk completely to the working population is inappropriate. Instead, Merton (1983a) proposed the issuing of bonds with a rate of return linked to the growth rate of per capita consumption. If wages and consumption are perfectly correlated, the proposals of Musgrave and Merton are equivalent. By the equality of the accumulated savings and the present value of future liabilities within each cohort at the time of retirement, the capital-reserve system excludes intergenerational transfers. In contrast, intergenerational transfers required by optimal risk sharing can take place in a pay-as-you-go system operating under a softer budget constraint. It is not guaranteed that the opportunities of a softer budget constraint will be used to improve intergenerational risk sharing. The government may yield to the demands of pressure groups which oppose the welfare improving adjustments. But the risk of government failure in the process of intergenerational risk sharing does not imply that the Pareto inefficient status quo without intergenerational transfers is the best choice. The previous argument in favour of the pay-as-you-go system takes the tax status of pension plans as given. However, the tax status of pension plans has redistributive consequences. By choosing an appropriate tax status and by adjusting taxation to the state of the economy, a capital-reserve system may improve intergenerational risk sharing as well.
6. Limits to Insurance Moral Hazard The link between the benefits of the retiree and the contributions in the working period affects the willingness to contribute in a pension scheme. The high fertility rates in the informal pension schemes is an example. A mandatory pay-as-you-go system which offers a basic (flat rate) pension financed by a payroll tax implies a distortionary tax affecting the choice of the labour input. With distortionary taxes, the pay-as-you-go system and the capital-reserve system may no longer be equivalent (Breyer, 1989; Homberg, 1990; Breyer and Straub, 1993). This conclusion depends on the level of government debt in each of the systems and on the distortionary effects of taxes needed to service the debt. In addition, if one wants to guarantee a minimum income to the retired belonging to the lower income classes for redistributive purposes, then these transfer payments have to be financed by distortionary taxes. Finally, the rights of the pensioners can be defined
320
Pensions
6120
proportionally to the contributions and to the years of service in the pay-as-you-go system as well as in the capital-reserve system. Linking retirement income to the years of service raises problems in the case of early retirement. The optimal retirement date will vary both with the disutility of working and with the worker’s productivity at an older age. Since the latter depends on a variety of random factors, from an insurance point of view it is desirable to adjust the retirement date accordingly without changing retirement income. But since the factors determining the retirement date cannot be measured in an objective way, early retirement demanded by the worker or induced by the employer will result in abuses. In the second best, the retirement income should therefore depend on the years of service (Diamond and Mirrlees, 1986). Adverse Selection Like any insurance contract, pension plans face the problem of adverse selection arising from the asymmetric information about the survival probability. Individuals who privately know that their survival probability is below average may prefer to save in assets instead of life insurance. For them, the rate of return on life insurance is lower since the terms of life insurance policies are based on the average survival probability of the particular group to which the insurance policy is sold. Since the individuals with a lower survival probability do not buy life insurance, the cost to the others increases. The unattractive annuity rates prevent the full development of a market for annuities. Adverse selection can be circumvented by compulsory schemes, in which good and bad risks are pooled (Eckstein, Eichenbaum and Peled, 1985). Employer pension plans and publicly organized pension plans are examples.
7. The Arguments for Publicly Organised Pension Plans The arguments for state intervention in the provision of retirement income are income redistribution, market failures, paternalism and efficiency (Diamond, 1977). Pay-as-you-go systems, unlike capital-reserve systems, usually need the authority of a government. In comparing the relative performance of each system, the need for government intervention on the grounds of these arguments have already been dealt with. We add some comments. In the absence of mandatory social insurance, the lower income classes may not have an incentive to save for retirement income. Welfare assistance cares for people without income. People with a low income during their working life have therefore little to lose when they do not save for retirement income. Unless they accept a dramatic cut in their consumption as workers,
6120
Pensions
321
they will be unable to increase their retirement income by retirement savings above the lost welfare benefit. This free-rider problem is resolved by a mandatory scheme. A redistributive public pension plan will reduce the cost to the low incomes and their willingness to participate in the labour market. In addition, people may be myopic and not save enough for retirement. Information on how much to save and where to invest the savings is costly to obtain. People may therefore accept the coercion of a mandated plan which provides the necessary discipline and offers a reasonable and trustworthy solution to an intricate problem. Adverse selection already requires pooling and does not leave much choice in tailoring a retirement policy to individual preferences. Many do not know or are unsure about their true preferences. The operating expenses of a public scheme are much lower than those of the life insurance industry with large selling costs. All these are additional arguments in favour of government intervention in the provision of retirement income.
8. The Demographic Problem Demographic ageing threatens the financial viability of pay-as-you-go systems. The creation of social security schemes operating on a pay-as-you-go basis in most European countries after the Second World War forced young generations to make transfers to aged generations with the promise of being refunded when their own retirement would come. This operation was easy in an environment of demographic and economic growth. The transfer from the young to the aged population is painful in the current setting with demographic ageing (Marchand and Pestiau, 1991). In order to bring the problem of demographic ageing in the right perspective, it is important to distinguish between the higher lifetime expectancy and the fall in fertility rates. Starting from the capital-reserve system, an increase in the survival probability after retirement requires higher contributions to provide adequate income after retirement for the same retirement age. The same carries over to the pay-as-you-go system. Without changing the contribution rate of the working generations, either the replacement rate must be reduced or the average retirement date has to be increased. The main causes of the falling activity rates of the aged are early retirement and the rise of unemployment among the aged. Changing early retirement incentives by penalising the retired who voluntarily quit the labour force or the firm which induces involuntary unemployment may be needed. But consumption smoothing and risk sharing requires adjustments in all the available instruments to achieve the equilibrium between contributions and liabilities in any pension system.
322
Pensions
6120
As explained above, a fall in population growth will increase the deficit of the pay-as-you-go system which adjusts its contribution and replacement rates to those of a capital-reserve system operating in the same environment. Without corrective measures, this will increase the public debt in the pay-as-you-go-system. The fall in the labour force is due to the declining birth rate which run at high levels from 1946 to the mid 1960s. The fertility rate fell partly because of an increased female participation in the labour force. Since demographic changes are gradual and to some extent predictable many years in advance, it possible to plan ahead by smoothing the contribution rates and by building up reserves in the pay-as-you-go system (Hagemann and Nicoletti, 1989; Marchand and Pestieau, 1991). Transfer payments between countries experiencing differently paced demographic shocks or early repayment of the public debt in countries with large public debt are examples. But note that such measures can be taken in combination with alternative measures affecting the activity rates of the aged and the young in the population and the migration rates. In addition, a fall in the labour force will lower the costs of education of children unless fewer children are provided with more human capital. From the equality of the accumulated contributions and future liabilities of each retiring cohort, it is often claimed that a capital-reserve system offers better protection against demographic changes. But irrespective of the pension system, the dissaving of a large retiring generation exceeds the saving of the smaller succeeding generation. In the transition, the desired consumption claims may be satisfied only if the output is adjusted by changing the capital-labour ratio after an adjustment of the government debt. Otherwise, the income distribution problem between generations may cause inflation eroding the purchasing power of retirement income.
9. Concluding Remarks The basic conflict between the working generations and the retired generations in the division of output cannot be resolved in an easy way. The mode of financing retirement income will affect the outcome of this basic conflict. But, in evaluating the relative merits of each system, compensating effects should be taken into account. As has been shown, two variants of providing retirement income may yield the same outcome or may yield allocations differing only in their second order effects. Any reform of an existing pension scheme should therefore be modest in the setting of its goals. It should not disappoint people by promises which it cannot deliver because of unforeseen compensating effects. As a consequence, any reform should be gradual as well. Although the outcome may not differ very much
6120
Pensions
323
in the long run after agents have adjusted their behaviour, the outcome may imply dramatic changes for the generations living in the transition to the new equilibrium as they are unable to adjust their behaviour. Capital-reserve systems are superior to pay-as-you-go systems in the definition of the future rights of the retired population. Although income security after retirement is desired by each individual, it is not optimal from the risk-sharing point of view to insulate one group of the population from the collective risks which have to be borne by the society as a whole and which have to be shared between generations. Pay-as-you-go systems are well suited to redistribute the burden of major shocks among the working generations and the retried generations. But reforms fixing the individual rights of the retired population conditional on the state of the economy and the record of individual contributions are desirable. Alternatively, adapting the tax status of funded pension plans to the state of the economy in a well-defined way could improve the risk-sharing properties of the capital-reserve system.
Bibliography on Pensions (6120) Aaron, Henry J. (1966), ‘The Social Insurance Paradox’, 32 Canadian Journal of Economics and Political Science, 371-374. Augier, L., Chaveau, T. and Loupias, C (1995), ‘Epargne Privée et Retraite par Répartition dans un Modèle de Croissance Optimale, en Avenir Incertain et avec Générations d’Agents’, 46 Revue Economique, 195-215. Barr, N. (1992), ‘Economic Theory and the Welfare State: a Survey and Interpretation’, 30 Journal of Economic Literature, 675-740. Barro, Robert J. (1974), ‘Are Government Bonds Net Wealth?’, 82 Journal of Political Economy, 1095-1117. Bernheim, B. Douglas and Levin, Lawrence (1989), ‘Social Security and Personal Saving: An Analysis of Expectations’, 79 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 97-102. Bewley, T (1981), The Relation between Social Security, Saving and Investment in a Life-cycle Model, North Western, Department of Economics, Discussion Paper, No. 492. Bodie, Zvi (1990a), ‘Pensions as Retirement Income Insurance’, 28 Journal of Economic Literature, 28-49. Bodie, Zvi (1990b), ‘Inflation Insurance’, 57 Journal of Risk and Insurance, 634-645. Bodie, Zvi, Shoven, John B. and Wise, David A. (eds) (1987), Issues in Pension Economics, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 376 p. Borch, K. (1962), ‘Equilibrium in a Reinsurance Market’, 30 Econometrica, 424-444. Breyer, Friedrich (1989), ‘On the Intergenerational Pareto-efficiency of Pay-as-you-go Financed Pension Systems’, 145 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 643-658.
324
Pensions
6120
Breyer, F. and Straub, M. (1993), ‘Welfare Effects of Unfunded Pension Systems when labor supply is endogenous’, 50 Journal of Public Economics, 77-93. Browning, Edgar K. (1973), ‘Social Insurance and Intergenerational Transfers’, 16 Journal of Law and Economics, 215-237. Chapman, Bruce (1987), ‘Pensions, Sex Discrimination, and the Value of Life after Death’, 7 International Review of Law and Economics, 193-214. Diamond, Peter A. (1965), ‘National Debt in a Neoclassical Growth Model’, 55 American Economic Review, 1126-1150. Diamond, Peter A. (1977), ‘A Framework for Social Security Analysis’, 8 Journal of Public Economics, 275-298. Diamond, Peter A. and Hausman, J.A. (1984), ‘Individual Retirement and Savings Behavior’, 23 Journal of Public Economics, 81-114. Diamond, Peter A. and Mirrlees, J.A. (1978), ‘A Model of Social Insurance with Variable Retirement’, 10 Journal of Public Economics, 295-336. Diamond, Peter A. and Mirrlees, J.A. (1985), ‘Insurance Aspects of Pensions’, in Wise, D.A. (ed.), Pensions, Labor, and Individual Choice, Chicago, IL, University of Chicago Press, 317-356. Diamond, Peter A. and Mirrlees, J.A. (1986), ‘Payroll-Tax Financed Social Insurance with Variable Retirement’, 88 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 25-50. Diamond, Peter A., Helms, L.J. and Mirrlees, J.A. (1980), ‘Optimal Taxation in a Stochastic Economy: a Cobb-Douglas Example’, 14 Journal of Public Economics, 1-29. Disney (1996), ‘Pensions as Insurance’, 21 Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance, 258-270. Dnes, Anthony W. (1981), ‘Structural Change and British Employment Trends’, 8(1) Journal of Industrial Affairs, 40-48. Eckstein, Z., Eichenbaum, M. and Peled, D. (1985a), ‘Uncertain Lifetimes and the Welfare Enhancing Properties of Annuity Markets and Social Security’‘, 26 Journal of Public Economics, 303-326. Eckstein, Z., Eichenbaum, M. and Peled, D. (1985b), ‘The Distribution of Wealth and Welfare in the Presence of Incomplete Annuity Markets’, 100 Journal of Public Economics, 789-806. Fabel, Oliver (1994), The Economics of Pensions and Variable Retirement Schemes, New York, John Wiley and Sons, 221 p. Feldstein, Martin S. (1974), ‘Social Security, Induced Retirement, and Aggregate Capital Accumulation’, 82 Journal of Political Economy, 905-926. Feldstein, Martin S. (1976), ‘Social Security and the Distribution of Wealth’, 71 Journal of the American Statistical Association, 800-807. Feldstein, Martin S. (1978), ‘Do Private Pensions Increase National Savings’, 10 Journal of Public Economics, 277-293. Feldstein, Martin S. (1983), ‘Social Security and Private Savings: Reply’, 90 Journal of Political Economy, 630-642. Fisher, S. (1983), ‘Welfare Aspects of Government Issue of Indexed Bonds’, in Dornbusch, R. and Simonson, M.H. (eds), Inflation, Debt and Indexation, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Gordon, R.H. and Varian, H.R. (1988), ‘Intergenerational Risk Sharing’, 37 Journal of Public Economics, 185-202.
6120
Pensions
325
Green, Jerry R. (1988), ‘Demographics, Market Failure, and Social Security’, in Wachter, M.S. (ed.), Social Security and Private Pensions, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books, 3-16. Gunderson, Morley and Pesando, James (1988), ‘The Case for Allowing Mandatory Retirement’, 14 Canadian Public Policy, 32-39. Gustman, Alan L. and Steinmier, Thomas L. (1991), ‘The Effects of Pensions and Retirement Policies on Retirement in Higher Education’, 81 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 111-115. Hagemann, R.P. and Nicoletti G. (1989), ‘Aging Populations: Economic Effects and Implications for Public Finance’, 12 OECD Economic Studies, 59-110. Hansson, Ingemar and Stuart, Charles (1989), ‘Social Security as Trade Among Living Generations’, 79 American Economic Review, 1182-1195. Homberg, S. (1990), ‘The Efficiency of Unfunded Pension Schemes’, 146 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 640-647. Honig, Marjorie and Reimers, Cordelia (1989), ‘Is It Worth Eliminating the Retirement Test?’, 79 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 103-107. Huerta De Soto, Jesús (1989), ‘Los Planes de Pensiones Privados y sus Fondos Financieros (Private Pensions and their Financial Funding)’, in Martinez Lafuente, Antonio (ed.), Estudios Sobre Planes y Fondos de Pensiones, Ariel, Barcelona, 169-187. Huerta De Soto, Jesús (1994a), Planes de Pensiones Privados (Private Pension Plans), Madrid, San Martín, 294 p. Huerta De Soto, Jesús (1994b), ‘The Crisis of Social Security: An Economic Analysis from the Austrian Perspective’, 5 Journal des Economistes et des Etudes Humaines, 127-155. Hurd, Michael D. (1990), ‘Research on the Elderly: Economic Status, Retirement, and Consumption and Saving’, 28 Journal of Economic Literature, 565-637. Ippolito, Richard A. (1985), ‘The Economic Function of Underfunded Pension Plans’, 28 Journal of Law and Economics, 611-651. Ippolito, Richard A. (1987), ‘Pension Security: Has ERISA had any Effect?’, 11(2) Regulation, 15-22. Ippolito, Richard A. (1988), ‘A Study of the Regulatory Effect of the Employee Retirement Income Security Act’, 31 Journal of Law and Economics, 85-125. Ippolito, Richard A. (1989), The Economics of Pension Insurance, Homewood, Irwin for the University of Pennsylvania, Wharton School, Pension Research Council, 270 p. Keating, Daniel (1991), ‘Pension Insurance, Bankruptcy, and Moral Hazard’, 67 Wisconsin Law Review, 65-108. Krashinsky, Michael (1988), ‘The Case for Eliminating Mandatory Retirement: Why Economics and Human Rights Need Not Conflict’, 14 Canadian Public Policy, 40-51. Marchand, M. and Pestieau P. (1991), ‘Public Pensions: Choices for the Future’, 35 European Economic Review, 441-453. Merton, R.C. (1983a), ‘On Consumption-indexed Public Pension Plans’, in Bodie, Z. and Shoven, J.B. (eds), Financial Aspects of the United States Pension System, Chicago, IL, University of Chicago Press. Merton, R.C. (1983b), ‘On the Role of Social Security as a Means for Efficient Risk-sharing in an Economy where Human Capital is Not Tradeable’, in Bodie, Z. and Shoven, J.B. (eds),
326
Pensions
6120
Financial Aspects of the United States Pension System, Chicago, IL, University of Chicago Press. Modigliani, Franco and Brumberg (1954), ‘Utility Analysis and the Consumption Function: An Interpretation of Cross-section Data’, in Kurihana, K.K. (ed.), Post-Keynesian Economics, New Brunswick, NJ, Rutgers University Press. Musgrave, Richard A. (1981), ‘A Reappraisal of Social Security Financing’, in Skidmore, F. (ed.), Social Security Financing, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Myles, Gareth D. (1995), Public Economics, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 546 p. Peters, W. (1988), ‘A Pension Insurance Model in an Overlapping Generations Model’, 144 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 813-830. Rea, Samuel A., Jr and James E. (1977), Pesando, Public and Private Pensions In Canada: An Economic Analysis, Toronto, University of Toronto Press. Ricardo-Campbell, Rita and Lazear, Adward P. (eds) (1988), Issues in Contemporary Retirement, Stanford, Hoover Institute Press, Stanford University, 427 p. Rothschild, Michael and Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1976), ‘Equilibrium in Competitive Insurance Markets: An Essay on the Economics of Imperfect Information’, 90 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 629-649. Samuelson, Paul A. (1958), ‘An Exact Consumption-Loan Model of Interest With or Without the Social Contrivance of Money’, 66 Journal of Political Economy, 467-482. Samuelson, Paul A. (1975), ‘Optimum Social Security in a Life-cycle Growth Model’, 16 International Economic Review, 531-538. Schmahl, Winfried (ed.) (1989), Redefining the Process of Retirement: An International Perspective, London, Springer, 179 p. Schulenburg, J. Matthias Graf Von Der (1990), ‘Demographischer Wandel, intergenerationale Gerechtigkeit und Stabilität des Generationenvertrages (Demographic Change, Intergenerational Justice and Stability of the Contact Between Generations)’, in Gahlen, B., Hesse, H. And Ramser, H.J. (eds), Theorie und Politik der Sozialversicherung, Schriftenreihe des Wirtschaftswissenschaftlichen Seminars Ottobeuren Bd. 19, Tübingen, Mohr/Siebeck, 269-300. Schulenburg, J. Matthias Graf Von Der and Breyer, F. (1989), ‘Umlagefinanzierte Rentenversicherung bei abnehmender Bevölkerung unter den Bedingungen eines demokratischen Wahlmechanismus (Pension Insurance Financed by Contributions in Times of Decreasing Population Under the Conditions of a Democratic Election Mechanism)’, in Boettcher, Erik, Herder-Dorneich, Philipp and Schenk, Karl-Ernst (eds), Jahrbuch für Neue Politische Ökonomie, Tübingen, Mohr, 126-139. Smith, Sharon P. (1991), ‘Ending Mandatory Retirement in the Arts and Sciences’, 81 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 106-110. Solow, R.M. (1956), ‘A Contribution to the Theory of Economic Growth’, 70 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 65-94. Strauss, Peter J., Wolf, Robert G. and Shilling, Dana (1990), Aging and the Law, Chicago, Commerce Clearing House, 892 p. Summers, Lawrence H. (1983), ‘Observations on the Indexation of Old-age Pensions’, in Bodie, Z. and Shoven, J.B. (eds), Financial Aspects of the United States Pension System, Chicago, IL, University of Chicago Press.
6120
Pensions
327
Townley, P.G.C. (1981), ‘Public Choice and the Social Insurance Paradox: A Note’, 14 Canadian Journal of Economics, 712-717. Townley, P.G.C. and Boadway, Robin W. (1988), ‘Social Security and the Failure of Annuity Markets’, 35 Journal of Public Economics, 75-96. Townsend, Robert M. (1994), ‘Risk and Insurance in Village India’, 3 Econometrica, 539-591. Verbon, Harrie A.A. (1985), ‘On the Independence of Financing Methods and Redistributive Aspects of Public Pensions’, 40 Public Finance, 280-289. Verbon, Harrie A.A. (1987), ‘On the Independence of Financing Methods and Redistributive Aspects of Public Pensions: Reply’, 42 Public Finance, 454-456. Verbon, Harrie A.A. (1988a), The Evolution of Public Pension Scemes, Berlin, Springer, 287 p. Verbon, Harrie A.A. (1988b), ‘Explaining Pay-as-you-go Financed Public Pensions’, 28 Economics Letters, 181-187. Verbon, Harrie A.A. and Van Winden, Frans A.A.M. (1986), ‘Public Pensions and Political Decision Making’, in Graf Von Der Schulenburg, J.-Matthias (ed.), Essays in Social Security Economics, Berlin, Springer, 32-53. Verbon, Harrie A.A. (1989), ‘Conversion Policies for Public Pension Plans in a small open Economy’, in Gustafsson, B.A. and Klevmarken, N.A. (ed.), The Political Economy of Social Security, Amsterdam, North-Holland. Viscusi, W. Kip (1979), Welfare for the Elderly: An Economic Analysis and Policy Prescription, New York, Wiley, 251 p. Wachter, Susan M. (ed.) (1988), Social Security and Private Pensions: Providing for Retirement in the Twenty-First Century, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books, 232 p. Wilson, C. (1977), ‘A Model of Insurance Markets with Incomplete Information’, 16 Journal of Economic Theory, 167-207. Woodford, M. (1989), Equilibrium Models of Endogenous Fluctuations: an Introduction, University of Chicago Discussion Paper. Yaari, M.E. (1964), ‘On the Consumer’s Lifetime Allocation Process’, 5 International Economic Review, 304-317. Yaari, M.E. (1965), ‘Uncertain Lifetime, Life Insurance, and the Theory of the Consumer’, 32 Review of Economic Studies, 137-150.
6200 TAKINGS Thomas J. Miceli and Kathleen Segerson Department of Economics University of Connecticut © Copyright 1999 Thomas J. Miceli and Kathleen Segerson
Abstract This chapter provides an overview of the law and economics literature on government takings of private property under eminent domain. The first part of the chapter addresses questions pertaining to physical acquisitions of property, including the meaning of the public use and just compensation requirements, and the impact of takings for development decisions of landowners. The second part of the chapter turns to the question of whether or when a land use regulation ever becomes so burdensome to the landowner as to require compensation under the takings clause. Regulations that cross this threshold are referred to as regulatory takings. The chapter first discusses the economic justification for government (public) control of externalities, and then considers factors that affect the compensation question, including the intent of the regulation, the impact of the regulation on the landowner, incentives for efficient land use, fairness considerations, and whether capitalization nullifies the need for compensation. JEL Classification: K11, K32, Q24 Keywords: Eminent Domain, Compensation, Regulatory Takings, Police Power, Land Use
1. Introduction This chapter provides an overview of the law and economics literature on government ‘takings’ through acquisition or regulation of private property. Unlike private individuals who must bargain with owners when they wish to acquire property, the government can acquire private property for public use without the owner’s consent provided that it pays just compensation. In the United States, this authority is granted by the ‘takings clause’ of the Fifth Amendment of the Constitution, which states: ‘nor shall private property be taken for public use, without just compensation’. In addition, nearly all state constitutions contain takings clauses (Fischel, 1995b, p. 180). The law and economics literature has addressed a number of issues relating to the government’s taking power, including the economic justification for the 328
6200
Takings
329
government’s power of eminent domain, the meaning of the public use and ‘just’ compensation requirements, and the implications of eminent domain for the land development decisions of property owners. In the first part of this chapter, we provide an overview of these issues and the related literature. In contrast to physical acquisitions or intrusions for which compensation is nearly always paid, government regulation of private property generally does not require compensation. Instead, it is viewed as a legitimate exercise of the government’s police power. There is a long-standing question, however, about whether or when a regulation ever becomes so burdensome to a property owner as to require compensation under the takings clause. Regulations that cross this threshold are referred to as ‘regulatory takings’. In the second part of this chapter, we review the law and economics literature on regulatory takings. We begin by discussing economic justifications for government regulation, and then turn to factors that affect the compensation question, including the nature of the government action and the impact of the regulation on landowners. We argue that various ‘rules’ for determining whether or not compensation should be paid, which appear at first to be different, are in fact consistent under certain conditions. We conclude by proposing compensation rules that balance the incentives of regulators against the incentives of landowners.
A. The Economics of Eminent Domain The Fifth Amendment to the US Constitution guarantees, in part, that the government shall not take private property for public use without paying ‘just compensation’. This seemingly straightforward protection of private property from arbitrary government seizure has generated a large literature attempting to interpret and justify its various components.
2. The Justification for Eminent Domain Eminent domain gives the government the power to acquire property from private individuals through non-consensual transfers. Thus, a private individual’s property is protected by a liability rule, rather than a property rule, vis-à-vis the government (Calabresi and Melamed, 1972). A common justification for this power is that it prevents individuals from refusing to sell their property to the government at a ‘reasonable’ price. This argument is faulty, however, because the subjective value an individual attaches to his or her property is worthy of protection in economic exchange - indeed, an important reason for protecting property by a property rule is to allow individuals to refuse transactions that do not make them better off (Posner, 1992, Ch. 3; Munch, 1976).
330
Takings
6200
Since subjective value is important, and property rules protect subjective value, there must be another justification for eminent domain. The answer is that, when the government is assembling a large amount of land to build a public project like a highway, individual owners whose land is necessary for the project acquire monopoly power in their dealing with the government. That is, they can hold out for prices in excess of their true (subjective) valuation of the land given that it would be costly, once the project is begun, for the government to seek alternative locations (Cohen, 1991). Although the government theoretically could solve this problem by acquiring all the necessary land prior to construction, it would be difficult to conceal the project as the pattern of acquisitions was revealed. Moreover, because the project is publicly funded, it usually is public knowledge well in advance due to the need to appropriate funds. Private developers assembling a large number of properties clearly face the same problem. One argument for why they do not have eminent domain power is that it would be easier for them to acquire the property while disguising their ultimate intent, for example, through the use of ‘dummy’ buyers. The real justification for eminent domain, then, is the need to prevent holdouts, which is a form of transactions cost. This justification is therefore a special case of the argument that property rules are desirable when transactions costs are low and liability rules are desirable when transaction costs are high (Calabresi and Melamed, 1972; Krier and Schwab, 1995; Kaplow and Shavell, 1996).
3. The Public Use Requirement The government’s eminent domain power is restricted by the public use requirement included in the Fifth Amendment (Merrill, 1986a; Paul 1987b; Rubenfeld, 1993; LaCroix and Rose, 1995). One interpretation of this requirement is that the government can only use its taking power to acquire property for the provision of public goods (Ulen, 1992). While this seems to be a natural interpretation of ‘public use’, the economic theory of public goods does not imply that acquiring the inputs for public goods creates a hold-out problem (Cornes and Sandler, 1986, Ch. 5; Cohen, 1991). While coerced contributions to the funding of public goods is necessitated by the free-rider problem, coerced acquisition of the resources used to produce them is not. Another interpretation of the public use requirement is that it is synonymous with the hold-out problem. This view, however, implies that private individuals faced with the hold-out problem also ought to have eminent domain power. Fischel (1995b, pp. 71-73) in fact suggests that private interests (for example, railroads) have often been granted the taking power by legislatures, and courts have been deferential (though not universally so) to this practice. Bouckaert and
6200
Takings
331
De Geest (1995) provide a transactions cost justification for private takings. Epstein (1985, Ch. 12) argues that the presence of a hold-out problem should be a necessary, but not sufficient condition for the public use limitation to be satisfied. In addition, some provision should be made to prevent private interests from acquiring all of the surplus from a forced sale. The basis for this additional requirement is that forced acquisitions with compensation set at market value prevent the owner of the acquired property from realizing both his subjective value, and a share of the gains from the sale (the value of the property in its proposed use minus the owner’s subjective value). To prevent this, Epstein proposes as the second prong of a two-pronged public use test something like the above public goods requirement in order to ensure that the gains from a forced sale accrue widely to the public rather than to a private interest endowed with taking power. Epstein does not, however, use this second prong to argue that private interests should never have taking power. Private interests can legitimately have taking power under Epstein’s public use test if, in addition to facing the hold-out problem, they make some effort to pay a share of the surplus from the taking to the victim of the taking. An example is the Mill Acts, which granted private individuals the right to erect dams for purposes of operating mills provided that they paid flooded upstream owners compensation equal to 150 percent of their market value. Note that this sharing of the surplus, while serving the interest of fairness, also helps to counteract the tendency to overtake under market value compensation (see the next section).
4. Just Compensation The Fifth Amendment allows the government to take private property for public use if it pays just compensation. Courts generally define just compensation to be ‘fair market value’. However, this amount almost certainly undercompensates landowners, possibly by a large amount, since owners do not generally view land and wealth as perfect substitutes, whereas market value compensates them as if they did. Fair market value is not only unfair to landowners, it also potentially leads to an excessive transfer of private property to public use because the government does not have to pay the true opportunity cost of the resources it acquires. (We pursue this point in more detail in the discussion of fiscal illusion below.) Thus, while the hold-out problem precludes the efficient assembly of property through market exchange, eminent domain with market value compensation potentially leads to too much assembly (Munch, 1976; Fischel, 1995a). Of course, the takings clause does not define just compensation to be fair market value, so it is not a necessary feature of eminent domain that it result
332
Takings
6200
in undercompensation. However, the problem with setting compensation equal to the owner’s true valuation is that this amount is unobservable, and owners would clearly have an incentive to overstate it (Knetsch and Borcherding, 1979). Thus, taking measurement costs into account, fair market value may be the best proxy for just compensation. A related issue, suggested by Epstein (1985, Ch. 18), is that money raised to finance compensation is a ‘taking’ from taxpayers for which they receive ‘inkind’ compensation in the form of benefits from the public project. Based on this insight, Fischel (1995b, p. 211) suggested that market value compensation may be the best way to balance ‘the undercompensation of the market-based rule against the greater loss incurred by higher taxes and [foregone] public works that full, consensual compensation would require’.
5. Eminent Domain and Land Use Incentives The feature of eminent domain that has drawn the most attention from economists, especially recently, is its impact on land use incentives. In particular, how does the possible threat of condemnation affect a landowner’s incentive to invest in developing his land? The first formal analysis of this question was by Blume, Rubinfeld and Shapiro (1984). The principal result that they derived (or at least the one that has received the most attention) was that full compensation for takings results in inefficient investment decisions by landowners while no compensation results in efficient incentives. Intuitively, compensation that is positively related to the value of the property, and hence the level of investment in that property, creates a moral hazard problem by providing the landowner insurance against the possibility of a taking. When a taking occurs, a social cost is incurred because an irreversible investment is lost. An efficient investment decision must therefore reflect the likelihood that this cost will be incurred (that is, the probability that a taking will occur). However, as is true of unlimited expectation damages for promisees in contract cases (Cooter, 1985), if the landowner is guaranteed full compensation, he will not incur any private loss if a taking occurs. Hence, he will ignore the possibility of a taking when making his investment decision and overinvest. Blume, Rubinfeld and Shapiro (1984) show that this overinvestment incentive can be eliminated by making the compensation lump-sum, that is, independent of the amount of investment in the property. Since lump-sum compensation is the same regardless of how much the landowner invests, increases in the level of investment lead to increased losses if a taking occurs. Thus, under lump-sum compensation the landowner is not fully insured and hence considers the possibility of a taking when making his investment decision. He thus chooses an efficient level of investment. Note that a special
6200
Takings
333
case of lump sum compensation is no compensation. Thus, Blume, Rubinfeld and Shapiro (1984) conclude that a rule of never paying compensation will lead to efficient landowner investment decisions. Kaplow (1986, 1992) has also endorsed the no compensation result for government takings, and more broadly for many forms of legal change that have distributional and allocative implications. Although no compensation is consistent with efficient land use incentives, several arguments have been made against it. The first and most common objection is that a rule of no compensation allows the government to acquire resources at no cost. This is not a problem if the government is unswervingly devoted to acquiring resources only when it is efficient to do so. Fischel and Shapiro (1988, 1989) refer to such a government as ‘Pigouvian’. However, modern public choice theory suggests that this is unlikely to be the case (Mueller, 1989). A more realistic view treats the government like any other economic agent who responds to economic incentives. If compensation is zero in this case, The resources under the control of the central authority will be perceived to be costless. The opportunity costs will be ignored, and land use regulation without compensation will lead to overproduction of environmental amenities .... (Johnson, 1977, p. 65)
Such a government is said to have ‘fiscal illusion’ (Blume, Rubinfeld and Shapiro (1984). In the current setting, this implies that the government will make its taking decision by comparing the benefit of the public good to the amount of compensation it must pay to the owners of the land that it takes. If it is not required to pay any compensation, it will tend to take property too often since it will view the taking as having positive benefits but no costs. Thus, a rule of zero compensation creates a moral hazard problem for the government. Full compensation can solve this problem and at the same time protect the rights of politically under-represented groups (Paul, 1987a; Epstein, 1985, 1995, Ch. 7; Burrows, 1991; Farber, 1992; Fischel, 1995b; and Yandle, 1995). As noted above, full compensation for takings results in inefficient investment because it allows landowners to ignore the social costs that result if a taking occurs. At the same time, full compensation is necessary to prevent overregulation by the government. In the presence of this trade-off, Fischel and Shapiro (1989) examined a compensation rule under which the level of compensation would be proportional to the value of the property, and they showed that the optimal (second-best) solution requires partial compensation. In contrast, Hermalin (1995) showed that the first-best outcome is attainable under a pair of compensation rules. Under the first, the government pays the landowner compensation equal to the social value of the taking. Note that this rule has the same effect as a property rule in that the owner receives
334
Takings
6200
compensation in excess of his value of the land (assuming that the taking is efficient), implying that the transfer is essentially consensual. The efficiency of this rule is thus consistent with the efficiency of property rules as discussed by Fischel and Shapiro (1988, p. 275). Under Hermalin’s second rule, the landowner has the option to buy back the land for a price equal to its social value. As noted above, actual compensation rules tie payment to the fair market value of the land to the owner rather than its value in public use, and owner’s do not ordinarily have a buy-back option. Thus both of Hermalin’s are purely normative in that they do not explain the actual practice of courts. Breach of contract remedies suggest yet another solution to the trade-off between moral hazard and fiscal illusion, namely, limit compensation to the full value of the land to the owner, evaluated not at the actual level of investment but rather at the efficient level of investment (Cooter, 1985; RoseAckerman, 1992). Note first that this rule will induce efficient behavior by the government because it requires full compensation. In addition, in equilibrium it will induce all landowners to choose an efficient level of investment because compensation is still lump-sum. Even when the government does not have fiscal illusion, there is an argument for paying compensation for takings if the likelihood of a taking depends on the value of the property (Miceli, 1991; Trefzger and Colwell, 1996). The model in Blume, Rubinfeld and Shapiro (1984) assumed that landowners view the probability of a taking as independent of their investment decision. However, in reality, the government may be less likely to take land that is more valuable in private use. For example, by taking undeveloped rather than developed land, it can reduce the social cost of the taking. If landowners anticipate that by increasing their investment in land they can reduce the chance that their land will be taken, they will adjust their investment decisions accordingly. To avoid this problem, Miceli (1991) shows that, even in the absence of fiscal illusion, compensation must be equal to the full value of the land at the optimal level of investment, net of any compensation tax. The intuition for this result is as follows. When the landowner expects zero compensation (or, generally, undercompensation), he will overinvest in order to reduce the probability of a taking. On the other hand, if he expects overcompensation he will underinvest in order to increase the probability of a taking. Only full compensation at the efficient level of investment eliminates these incentives to over- or underinvest. The question is whether landowners in fact view the probability of a taking as being a function of their level of investment. This is unlikely in the context of physical acquisitions of land, which rarely occur. Indeed, the probability of a physical taking is probably near zero for most landowners. However, government regulations preventing certain land uses such as zoning and
6200
Takings
335
environmental restrictions are widespread and generally apply to all plots in a given area. In that case, the probability of a land use restriction that reduces their property values is not necessarily small, and it may be possible for landowners to affect its magnitude by their land use decisions (Miceli and Segerson, 1996, Chs 7 and 8). Thus, this issue is likely to arise in the context of regulatory takings discussed below. The preceding discussion has shown that a compensation rule that pays landowners the full value of their land at the efficient level of investment results in both efficient investment in land and efficient takings decisions when the government has fiscal illusion. One problem with this rule is that it requires courts to be able to calculate the efficient level of investment, a task that may prove difficult in practice. However, this problem has not prevented courts from adopting rules in other areas of the law that require similar calculations. For example, negligence rules require calculation of due standards of care in accident settings (Landes and Posner, 1987, Ch. 4; Cooter and Ulen, 1988, Ch. 8; U.S. v. Carroll Towing, 159 F.2d 169 (1947)). Moreover, existing community standards for ‘normal’ land use can often provide a good proxy for efficient development levels (Fischel, 1985, Ch. 8). Two additional arguments against the no compensation result have been made in the literature. The first was by Michelman (1967) in perhaps the most influential article on takings to date. Michelman used a utilitarian standard for deciding, first, when a government should enact a taking, and second, when it should pay compensation. The standard is based on three factors: efficiency gains, demoralization costs, and settlement costs. Efficiency gains simply represent the social benefits minus the costs of a public project. A necessary condition for enactment of the project under Michelman’s standard is that the project generates efficiency gains. In addition to efficiency gains, Michelman introduced two types of costs. The first is the demoralization costs associated with non-payment of compensation. Demoralization costs represent the total of (1) the dollar value necessary to offset disutilities which accrue to losers and their sympathizers specifically from the realization that no compensation is offered, and (2) the present capitalized dollar value of lost future production (reflecting either impaired incentives or social unrest) caused by demoralization of uncompensated losers, their sympathizers, and other observers disturbed by the thought that they themselves may be subjected to similar treatment on some other occasion (Michelman, 1967, p. 1214). The second type of cost is the settlement (or transaction) costs associated with payment of compensation. Settlement costs represent ‘the dollar value of time, effort, and resources which would be required to reach compensation settlements adequate to avoid demoralization costs’ (Michelman, 1967, p. 1214). Michelman’s standard for compensation is that it should be paid if
336
Takings
6200
settlement costs are less than demoralization costs, and not paid if the reverse is true. Further, the public project should be enacted if and only if the efficiency gain exceeds the lower of the settlement and demoralization costs. Note that this standard is intermediate between the Pareto and Kaldor-Hicks criteria for efficiency. It is more permissive than Pareto since a project should be enacted without compensation if the efficiency gains exceed the demoralization costs and the demoralization costs are less than the settlement costs. However, it is less permissive than Kaldor-Hicks since even if there are efficiency gains, the project should not be enacted if those gains are less than the lower of the settlement and demoralization costs (Fischel and Shapiro, 1988, p. 280). The final argument against the no compensation result is based on the idea that compensation acts as a form of public insurance for risk-averse landowners against the possibility of government expropriation of their property (Blume and Rubinfeld, 1984, 1987; Rose-Ackerman, 1992). The need for public rather than private insurance is that moral hazard and adverse selection problems, and the infrequency of takings, prevent formation of a private insurance market for takings risk. Because of the administrative costs and incentive effects of compensation, however, it should only be paid when landowners are very risk-averse and losses are large.
B. Regulation and Takings Thus far we have focused on physical acquisitions of private property, which have been universally accepted by courts as compensable government takings. There has been much more controversy, however, both in the courts and in the academic literature, over government regulations that reduce private property values and the extent to which these should be compensable (Knetsch, 1983; Epstein, 1985; Paul, 1987a; Fischel, 1995b; and Yandle, 1995). Courts have generally granted the government broad powers to regulate private property in the interest of protecting public welfare. However, some government regulations can become so restrictive as to cause a substantial reduction in the value of private property. When this happens, courts have occasionally found the regulation to be a taking and ordered payment of compensation. The problem is to determine where to set the threshold that separates non-compensable regulations (police power actions) from compensable ones (regulatory takings). We begin our discussion of this question by considering the rationale for the existence of the government’s regulatory power. We then provide an overview of the issues that have arisen in trying to define a threshold for compensable regulatory actions.
6200
Takings
337
6. Justifications for Government Regulation One of the principal uses of the government’s regulatory power is in the context of externalities, or incompatible uses of property (Cornes and Sandler, 1986, Chs 3 and 4). There are, however, private (common law) remedies available for dealing with such incompatibilities. Thus, prior to addressing the question of whether the government should pay compensation for a regulation, we first need to answer the question of why government (public) intervention is economically justified at all. Trespass and nuisance are the principal common law remedies available to property owners faced with violations of their property rights. Trespass ordinarily allows owners to exclude, or enjoin, future intrusions regardless of the benefits to the intruder, whereas under nuisance law the court generally enjoins the intrusion or awards damages only after determining that the victim’s harm is substantial and the nuisance-creating activity is unreasonable (Keeton, et al., 1984, pp. 622-623). According to Merrill (1985), this distinction can be explained in terms of transactions costs. Specifically, when transactions costs between the intruder and the victim are low, trespass is the efficient remedy because it forces the parties to resolve the incompatibility through a voluntary transaction - a solution that guarantees a mutually beneficial outcome. When transactions costs are high, however, nuisance law is the appropriate remedy because the parties may be unable to resolve the dispute through bargaining. In that case, the court conducts a sort of costbenefit analysis before determining if the victim is entitled to relief. In a sense, the court coerces an efficient exchange (a ‘private taking’) or prohibits an inefficient one when bargaining is expected to fail. The case of Boomer v. Atlantic Cement (309 N.Y.S.2d 312 (1970)) illustrates this common law (private) approach to externalities. The preceding theory implies that private remedies initiated by the victim of an externality are available for both low and high transaction costs cases. The question then is where direct government regulation of externalities fits into this scheme. One answer is that if the external cost is dispersed across a large number of victims, then no one victim may have an incentive to seek a private remedy, even when the aggregate cost outweighs the benefit of the injurer’s activity. In that case, the government acts as an ‘agent’ of the victims by regulating the injurer’s activity directly. The government thereby overcomes a collective action problem among victims (Landes and Posner, 1987, Ch. 2). While many regulations are designed to address externality problems, government intervention can be justified on other grounds as well, such as protection of individual rights. For example, laws designed to protect the rights of disabled people, to guarantee free speech, or to ensure equal access or opportunity, can result in requirements that impose costs on property
338
Takings
6200
owners and reduce the value of private property. Alternatively, government regulation (such as public utility regulation) can arise in response to other market failures, including imperfect competition and imperfect information. Regulatory takings issues have arisen in these contexts as well. The preceding discussion identifies situations in which government regulation of private property may be justified, but it does not address the question of whether the landowner should be compensated for the resulting private loss. Although from an economic perspective the distinction between physical invasions and value-reducing regulations is not a meaningful one (Rose-Ackerman, 1992, p. 29), courts have routinely denied compensation for the latter (with some notable exceptions). In the following sections, we review the key issues relating to the question of when compensation should be paid for regulations that reduce the value of private property without physically acquiring it.
7. The Nature of the Government Action As noted, courts have historically granted governments wide powers to regulate without paying compensation, provided that the regulation somehow protects the public interest. This justification for non-payment of compensation thus focuses on the nature of the government action. 7.1 Regulation of ‘Harmful’ or ‘Noxious’ Uses An early case that established the nature of the government action as relevant for the compensation question is Mugler v. Kansas (123 U.S. 623 (1887)). The case concerned a law passed by the State of Kansas prohibiting the operation of breweries because they were public nuisances. The plaintiff argued that operation of his brewery predated the law, and further, that it did not constitute a nuisance. The Court nevertheless upheld the law based on the state’s right to regulate, without compensation, land uses that are injurious to public welfare. Specifically, the Court held that there is no taking if a regulation is aimed at preventing uses that are ‘injurious to the health, morals, or safety of the community’ (Mugler v. Kansas, 1887, 668-669). This argument has become known as the ‘noxious use’ doctrine and remains an important basis for government regulations under the police power. Concern with the nature of the government’s action was re-affirmed in Penn Central Transportation Co. v. City of New York (438 U.S. 104 (1978)). Echoing the noxious use doctrine from Mugler, the court noted that ‘in instances in which a state tribunal reasonably concluded that “the health, safety, morals, or general welfare” would be promoted by prohibiting particular contemplated uses of land, this court has upheld land-use
6200
Takings
339
regulations that destroyed or adversely affected recognized real property interests’ (Penn Central v. City of New York, 1978, p. 125). Thus, according to the Court, if the public benefit of the regulation is sufficiently large, it may not constitute a taking even when the landowner suffers a significant loss. Finally, in Lucas v. South Carolina Coastal Council (112 S. Ct. 2886 (1992)), the Court introduced a provision that would allow the government to avoid paying compensation if it could show that the activity a landowner planned to pursue would be prohibited under the state’s common law of nuisance. Thus, the Court recognized that government actions consistent with nuisance law are non-compensable. This provision of the Lucas decision is known as the ‘nuisance exception’. The academic literature has also looked to the nature of the government action to determine if a regulation should be compensable. Much of the literature is based on property rights principles. Property rights approaches to the takings question typically begin by implicitly defining a distribution of property rights that the law protects. If a government action deprives a property owner of a right protected by this distribution, compensation is due, whereas if it deprives him of an unprotected right, no compensation is due. The ‘harm-benefit’ rule exemplifies this approach (Fischel, 1985, pp. 154155). According to this rule, compensation is not due for regulations that prevent a landowner from imposing an external cost on society (for example, pollution), but compensation is due for regulations that compel the landowner to provide an external benefit (for example, open space). The underlying basis for this distinction is that landowners do not have the right to impose costs, but they do have the right to withhold conferral of benefits. Joseph Sax has offered two theories of takings that fall within this property rights approach. His first theory (Sax, 1964) argues that the government owes compensation when it acquires property rights for use as an enterprise - for example, when it provides a public good; but it does not owe compensation when it merely arbitrates private disputes - for example, when it regulates an externality. (Rose, 1983, advances a similar argument.) According to this view, regulatory takings for the most part fall within the category of noncompensable actions since, as noted above, they generally are aimed at preventing an external cost or correcting a market failure or inequity. Sax’s second theory (Sax, 1971) suggests that the government does not owe compensation for any action that involves the internalization of spillover effects (negative externalities). Bromley adopts a similar view, arguing that compensation for regulations that prevent externalities would represent ‘indemnification for an inability to continue to impose unwanted costs on others’ (Bromley, 1993, p. 677). Like the harm-benefit rule, this view is based on the idea that the law does not protect an individual’s property right when that right infringes on other individuals’ rights. Note that a similar delineation
340
Takings
6200
of property rights underlies the noxious use doctrine (Mercuro, 1992a, p. 3) and the Lucas nuisance exception. The nuisance exception is also a fundamental feature of Richard Epstein’s view of takings law (Epstein, 1985, Ch. 9, 1992; Epstein, et. al., 1992), which holds that landowners should generally receive compensation for regulations except when the offending land use would have been prohibited by the state’s common law of nuisance. Property rights approaches to the compensation question are not necessarily consistent with economic theory, especially those based on the harm-benefit approach. For example, it is well known that there does not exist a meaningful economic distinction between a harm imposed and a benefit conferred, given that a harm is equivalent to a foregone benefit, and a benefit is equivalent to an avoided harm (Coase, 1960; Fischel, 1985, p. 158). What is lacking is a ‘benchmark of neutral conduct’ for defining the threshold between harms and benefits (Michelman, 1967, p. 1197). The basis for harm-benefit rules can be made consistent with economic logic, however, by appealing to administrative, or transaction, costs as a way of identifying such a neutral point. 7.2 Standards of ‘Normal’ Behavior Fischel employs a transaction costs approach in proposing a rule based on a ‘normal behavior’ (Fischel, 1985, Ch. 8, 1995b; Ellickson, 1973, 1977). This rule resembles the harm-benefit rule in that it says that no compensation is due for regulations that prevent ‘subnormal’ land uses, but compensation is due for regulations that compel ‘super-normal’ land uses. The rule differs from the harm-benefit rule in that ‘normal’ behavior is defined according to local community standards based on what a landowner could reasonably expect to do with his land without government restriction. A reasonableness standard for land use thus replaces the arbitrary distinction between a harm and a benefit. The importance of transactions costs to this rule is that, by using normal behavior as the ‘zero compensation’ point, the transactions costs of compelling normal behavior are minimized. In particular, since most people will engage in normal behavior without state intervention, only a few transactions will be needed to fine those who engage in subnormal behavior and to compensate those who undertake supernormal behavior. Wittman (1984) uses a similar transactions cost approach to distinguish compensable from non-compensable regulations. He argues that administrative costs are minimized if compensation is paid only when the government acts inefficiently since ‘we would expect the government to act efficiently more often than not’ (Wittman, 1984, p. 74). In addition to minimizing transaction costs associated with paying compensation, Fischel’s normal behavior standard avoids what he views as a major problem with a rule that conditions compensation solely on the loss in value to the owner (the diminution of value rule) - namely, the possibility of paying compensation for regulations that restrict truly inappropriate land uses
6200
Takings
341
while imposing substantial losses on the landowner, for example, prohibiting pulp mills in residential neighborhoods. Fischel recognizes, however, the need to balance the costs of regulations against their benefits. He therefore argues that forcing ‘super-normal’ behavior on landowners need not require compensation if the benefits of the regulation exceed the cost to the private landowner and the transaction costs are excessive (Fischel, 1985, p. 165). Since the presumption is that requiring landowners to conform with social norms would generate benefits in excess of its costs, Fischel’s rule is essentially one of paying compensation for inefficient regulations and not paying compensation for efficient ones. To the extent that noxious uses and nuisances represent subnormal (inefficient) uses, non-compensation for regulation of these types of activities is consistent with Fischel’s and Wittman’s rules for minimizing transactions costs. Moreover, all of these rules are essentially versions of the harm-benefit approach to defining compensable regulations in that they rely on a distinction between ‘good’ and ‘bad’ behavior by the landowner, which in turn defines a threshold for determining compensation. Thus, while these various theories appear at first to be quite different, they are in fact consistent with each other when the thresholds are defined on the basis of economic principles. In addition, they are consistent with the threshold-based rules proposed by Miceli and Segerson (1994, 1996) (see Section 9 below). 7.3 The ‘Essential Nexus’ Requirement While the foregoing suggests that the nature of the government action can justify uncompensated regulations, courts have required that those actions must bear at least some relationship to the regulated land use. In particular, the doctrine of ‘unconstitutional conditions’ holds that ‘the government may not require a person to give up a constitutional right ... in exchange for a discretionary benefit conferred by the government where the property right sought has little or no reasonable relationship to the benefit’ (Dolan v. City of Tigard, 114 S.Ct. 2309, 2317 (1994)). This condition arises in takings cases when the government requires a landowner to dedicate some property to public use without just compensation in exchange for a permit to develop. In Nollan v. California Coastal Comm’n (438 U.S. 825 (1987)), the Court held that in order for a permit condition to be valid, there must exist an ‘essential nexus’ between the condition (that is, the required dedication of property) and the proposed development for which the permit is sought. The case concerned a state requirement that the Nollans allow public access to their beach in return for a permit to replace an existing beachfront bungalow with a three bedroom house. The State’s interest in imposing the condition of beach access was purportedly to counteract the fact that the larger house proposed by the Nollans would diminish the view of the ocean from the roadway. However,
342
Takings
6200
the Court held that the essential nexus requirement was not met in this case because access to the beach did not serve to enhance the view of the ocean from the road; that is, it did not counteract the impact of the proposed development. The Court re-examined this issue in Dolan v. City of Tigard (1994). While the Court reaffirmed the essential nexus requirement, it also found that mere existence of a nexus was not enough to validate the permit condition. In addition, ‘the degree of the exactions demanded [must] bear the required relationship to the impact of the petitioner’s proposed development’ (Dolan v. City of Tigard, 1994, p. 2318). The Court adopted a ‘rough proportionality’ test to assess this relationship. When the court applied this test to the facts of Dolan, it concluded that the government’s conditions did not bear the required ‘reasonable relationship’ to the impact of the proposed development. Miceli and Segerson (1996, Chapter 4) argue that the essential nexus requirement represents a generalized condition for determining whether or not a government regulation is efficient in cases where landowners have the ability to mitigate the external costs of their proposed development. The regulatory decision is assumed to have two separate components: first, the government decides whether or not to attach conditions to the permit if it is granted, and second, it decides whether or not to grant the permit given those conditions. In this context, the efficiency of the regulatory decision includes efficiency of both the decision of whether or not to grant the permit, and the efficiency of any conditions attached to the permit. The essential nexus and rough proportionality tests in combination can be viewed as an attempt to ensure the efficiency of the permit conditions. In contrast to Miceli and Segerson (1996), Innes (1995, 1997) argues that the essential nexus and proportionality requirements should not be applied in takings cases. He argues instead that the focus should be on providing equal protection to owners of similarly situated land (the equal protection requirement). This argument, however, is based on consideration of the incentives of landowners rather than the efficiency of the regulatory decision (see Section 8.3 below).
8. The Impact of the Regulation on the Landowner In addition to the nature of the government action, the other major factor used to evaluate regulatory takings cases is the impact of the regulation on the landowner. This criterion is best exemplified by Holmes’s diminution of value test.
6200
Takings
343
8.1 The Diminution of Value Test The impact of the regulation on the landowner was first advanced as a test for compensation in Pennsylvania Coal Co. v. Mahon (260 U.S. 393 (1922)), which is one of the most influential takings cases in US history. This case challenged a Pennsylvania statute, the Kohler Act, which prohibited coal companies from any mining that threatened the safety of surface owners due to cave-ins. The majority opinion, written by Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes, found the regulation to be a taking requiring compensation because it went ‘too far’ in reducing the landowner’s rights. Specifically, Holmes’s ruling provided that the government can regulate private property without compensation unless the regulation goes too far in diminishing the value of the property to the owner. This rule is thus referred to as the ‘diminution of value’ test. Holmes did not articulate a general test for establishing when a regulation had gone too far, however, leaving it instead to be determined on a case by case basis. Holmes’s ruling in Pennsylvania Coal marked a watershed in takings law because, prior to this case, takings were usually limited to physical acquisitions of property by the government; most efforts to obtain compensation for ‘mere regulations’ failed, due in large part to the noxious use doctrine (Friedman, 1986). The diminution of value test broke with this tradition by introducing the loss in value to the owner into the equation. It thus ‘put the police power on a continuum with the power of eminent domain’ (Mercuro, 1992a, p. 4). Holmes did not argue for a general rule of compensation because he recognized that the government ‘could hardly go on if to some extent values incident to property could not be diminished without paying for every such change in the law’ (Pennsylvania Coal v. Mahon, 1922, p. 413). At the same time, however, he acknowledged that a rule of no compensation for regulations would, given ‘the natural tendency of human nature’, result in overregulation until ‘at last private property disappear[ed]’. Thus, Holmes recognized the fundamental trade-off between the costs of compensation (a stifled government) and the benefits of compensation (protection of private property and a limitation of government excess): ‘The general rule at least is that while property may be regulated to a certain extent, if regulation goes too far it will be recognized as a taking’ (Pennsylvania Coal v. Mahon, 1922, p. 415). Most takings cases since Pennsylvania Coal have generally applied some form of Holmes’s diminution of value test. An example is the previously cited case of Lucas v. South Carolina Coastal Council (1992), which concerned a developer (Lucas) who had purchased two beachfront lots in South Carolina with the intent of developing them for residential use. Although development was permitted at the time Lucas purchased the lots, the State subsequently passed a law, the Beachfront Management Act, that prohibited development. Lucas acknowledged the state’s right to impose such a law, but he argued that it reduced the value of his property so much that it constituted a taking for
344
Takings
6200
which compensation was due. The South Carolina Supreme Court ruled in favor of the State, based on the broad regulatory powers that have been granted to state and local governments. However, the US Supreme Court reversed the decision and found that compensation was due. Environmental groups had feared such a decision in the belief that the need to pay compensation would greatly reduce the ability of governments to protect the environment against the unrestrained actions of private property owners. However, the decision in Lucas awarded compensation on narrow grounds. In particular, the Court found that compensation was due because ‘when the owner of real property has been called upon to sacrifice all economically beneficial uses in the name of the common good, that is to leave his property economically idle, he has suffered a taking’ (Lucas v. S. Carolina Coastal Council, 1992, p. 2895). Thus, the Court found that the regulation had clearly crossed the threshold set by the diminution of value test and that a taking had therefore occurred. However, the opinion offered no guidance as to the exact location of the threshold. While the diminution of value test has been widely applied, it has been criticized on efficiency grounds. As noted above, for example, if only the loss in property value is considered when deciding whether to compensate, then the resulting outcome may be inefficient since the benefit of the regulation will not be balanced against the cost (the loss in private property value) (Fischel, 1985, pp. 156-157). Similarly, if compensation is not required when the reduction in property value is small, then a government that considers only actual cost outlays rather than social costs, that is, a government with fiscal illusion, will view such regulations as costless and thus overregulate. If some balancing between these two effects is to take place, as proposed in the original Holmes ruling, then a standard for deciding when a regulation has gone ‘too far’ must be available. We will propose such a standard below. 8.2 Investment-Backed Expectations In Penn Central Transportation Co. v. City of New York (1978), the US Supreme Court faced the question of whether the City of New York could prevent the owners of Grand Central Terminal from erecting an office tower over the terminal by declaring it an historical landmark. The Court held that it could without being obliged to pay compensation. In reaching its decision, the Court identified several factors to be weighed in determining whether a regulation constitutes a taking, including the nature of the government action and the economic impact of the regulation on the claimant. The former reflects the noxious use doctrine from Mugler and the latter the diminution of value rule from Pennsylvania Coal. While Holmes did not offer any criterion for determining when a regulation goes too far under the diminution of value rule,
6200
Takings
345
the Penn Central court did. Specifically, the Court said that a regulation ‘may so frustrate distinct investment-backed expectations as to amount to a taking’ (Penn Central v. City of New York, 1978, p. 127), whereas it is not a taking if it does ‘not interfere with interests that [are] sufficiently bound up with reasonable expectations of the claimant to constitute “property” for 5th amendment purposes’ (Penn Central v. City of New York, 1978, pp. 124-125). Thus, a relevant factor for determining whether a regulation requires compensation is whether the regulation interferes with distinct investmentbacked expectations by the claimant. Justice Brennan’s majority opinion in the Penn Central case relied heavily on Michelman’s (1967) view that, in order for a landowner to put his land to productive use, he must have a reasonable expectation of being allowed to retain the fruits of his investment (Mandelker, 1987, pp. 10-13). Nevertheless, Michelman asserts that compensation is not due in every case of investmentbacked expectations (Michelman, 1967, p. 1213). For example, compensation would not be due if demoralization costs are low and settlement costs are high (see the discussion of Michelman above). Miceli and Segerson (1996, Ch. 7) also argue that a rule of paying compensation if and only if the landowner’s expectations are investmentbacked will be inefficient. In particular, they show that it can lead to overinvestment. However, they also show that efficient land use decisions will be made under a ‘good faith’ rule based on ‘reasonable’ (efficient) land use decisions. In particular, in the event of a regulation, such a rule would require compensation for landowners who acted in good faith, either by investing when it was efficient to do so or not investing when investment was inefficient, and it would not require compensation for those who did not act in good faith (Mandelker, 1987). 8.3 Singling Out and Equal Protection An additional factor identified in the Penn Central case for determining when a taking occurs was proposed by Justice Rehnquist in a dissenting opinion. This factor concerns whether the government action applies to a broad class of landowners or whether it ‘singles out’ individuals. Rehnquist noted that ‘Even where the government prohibits a noninjurious use, the court has ruled that a taking does not take place if the prohibition applies over a broad cross section of land and thereby “secure[s] an average reciprocity of advantage”’ (Penn Central v. City of New York (1978, p. 147), Rehnquist dissent, quoting from Pennsylvania Coal v. Mahon (1922, p. 415)). In contrast, regulations that single-out landowners are more likely to be judged a taking according to this criterion. In Agins v. Tiburon (447 U.S. 255 (1980)), the Court similarly held that a landowner subject to a zoning ordinance ‘will share with other owners the benefits and burdens of the city’s exercise of its police power. In assessing
346
Takings
6200
the fairness of the zoning ordinances, these benefits must be considered along with any diminution in market value that the appellants might suffer’ (Agins v. Tiburon, 1980, p. 262). Even Epstein (1995, pp. 134-137), who argues generally in favor of compensation, recognizes that regulations that spread benefits and costs over the same population offer in-kind compensation. The singling out criterion also forms the basis for Michelman’s (1967) proposed fairness standard for compensation: A decision not to compensate is not unfair as long as the disappointed claimant ought to be able to appreciate how such decisions might fit into a consistent practice which holds forth a lesser long run risk to people like him than would any consistent practice which is naturally suggested by the opposite decision. (p. 1223)
Such a rule can be defended by a ‘veil of ignorance’ argument that legitimizes rules that people would have approved prior to learning of their actual position in society (Rawls, 1971, pp. 136-142; Posner, 1980). This rule prevents landowners from being singled out to bear costs for society as a whole, as when a single landowner is compelled to give up his property without compensation to provide a public good (Rose-Ackerman, 1992). At the same time, it allows uncompensated regulations that potentially apply equally to all landowners, such as broadly-based zoning laws. Such a rule therefore depends on the extent to which a regulation applies to few versus many landowners. Singling out can also occur when compensation is not paid for restrictions that are placed on undeveloped land if comparable developed land is exempted from the restriction, that is, when there is not ‘equal protection’ for developed and undeveloped land. In addition to the fairness implications of an equal protection requirement, it can also have efficiency effects. Specifically, because it is often efficient for the government to take undeveloped land before developed land, uncompensated takings can provide an incentive for landowners to develop ‘too early’ in an effort to reduce the likelihood that their land will be taken (Innes, 1995, 1997). For example, a developer might begin construction in an effort to beat an anticipated downzoning (Dana, 1995). This is consistent with the result discussed above that zero compensation will not be efficient if landowners can influence the probability of a taking (Miceli, 1991; Miceli and Segerson, 1996, Chs 7 and 8). Compensating owners of undeveloped land that is taken, or affording equal protection to both developed and undeveloped land, can offset the incentive for premature development (Innes, 1995; Miceli and Segerson, 1996, Ch. 8). Thus, such a rule can achieve both equity and efficiency objectives. However, Miceli and Segerson (1996, Ch. 8) show that, while equal protection is sufficient for efficient incentives, it is not necessary. Other rules are capable of simultaneously satisfying efficiency and equity goals as well.
6200
Takings
347
In some cases, a developer will begin investing in a project only to find that a change in the zoning regulations prevents its completion. While recognizing that local governments need to have some freedom to revise their zoning laws in response to changing circumstances, landowners also need some protection of their sunk investments when a zoning change occurs (Mandelker, 1993, pp. 234-244; Kaplow, 1986). The courts have provided a basis for such protection in the form of ‘vested rights’. A vested right allows the landowner to proceed with the project despite the zoning change under certain conditions. In order for a landowner to acquire a vested right, he generally must have made a ‘substantial’ investment in the property in reliance on a valid building permit. In this sense, his expectations must be ‘investment-backed’ (see the related discussion above). How much investment is necessary to be deemed substantial is not clear. Generally courts engage in a balancing test that weighs the costs and benefits of the zoning change. For example, in addition to making substantial investments, the landowner must have acted in ‘good faith’ by not rushing the development process in an effort to beat an impending zoning change. More generally, the good faith test asks ‘whether a landowner’s conduct was consistent with how a reasonable property owner would have acted in the same circumstances’ (Mandelker, 1993, p. 239). Miceli and Segerson (1996, Chs 7 and 8) show that, if good faith or ‘reasonableness’ are judged on efficiency grounds, then a good faith rule can induce efficient land use decisions by awarding a vested right if development was efficient but not awarding one if development was not efficient. Note, however, that the threat to withhold a vested right if the landowner developed prematurely is only effective if the development is reversible - that is, only if the development process can be halted and the resulting external cost avoided or eliminated if the landowner developed inefficiently. This will not always be possible, as when a landowner harvests timber prematurely, or destroys wildlife in order to avoid the imposition of regulations aimed at preserving the habitat of an endangered species (a practice known as ‘shoot, shovel, and shut up’) (Epstein, 1995, p. 294). In such cases, it may be necessary to promise compensation for the threatened regulation in order to offset the incentive for preemptive development or destruction of wildlife and habitat. The magnitude of compensation cannot be too large, however, for then landowners may have an incentive to delay development inefficiently. One way to ensure efficient incentives is to condition the payment of compensation on efficiency of the landowner’s decision - that is, on whether his decision either to develop or to postpone development was efficient (Miceli and Segerson, 1996, Ch. 8) 8.4 The Role of Capitalization As noted above, an important factor in evaluating the fairness of a regulation is the extent to which it interferes with the landowner’s reasonable
348
Takings
6200
expectations. One issue that arises in this context is whether the threat of a regulation was known to the landowner when he first purchased the land. A frequent argument made against paying compensation for regulations is that when landowners purchased land subject to the threat of a regulation, they paid a price that discounted (or ‘capitalized’) the possibility of that regulation. Consequently, they have already received ‘implicit’ compensation (Posner, 1980). Although this argument owes much to Michelman (1967), courts understood it as far back as 1823 when, in the case of Callender v. Marsh (1 Pick. 417, 430 (1823)), the court said: ‘Those who purchase house lots ... are supposed to calculate the chance of [regulations]..., and as their purchase is always voluntary, they may indemnify themselves in the price of the lot which they buy.’ If the purchase price discounted (or capitalized) the threat of regulation, then the case for compensation is weakened because the landowner ‘got exactly what [he] meant to buy’. Michelman concludes that compensation in this case would be analogous to refunding the price of a losing lottery ticket (Michelman, 1967, p. 1238; Rose-Ackerman, 1992). This is a persuasive argument that has found its way into fairly recent judicial decisions defending rulings against compensation (HFH Ltd. v. Superior Court, 542 P.2d 237 (1975)). Several authors have suggested, however, that the capitalization argument against compensation is flawed (Epstein, 1985, pp. 151-158; Fischel, 1985, pp. 184-186; Fischel and Shapiro, 1988; Miceli and Segerson, 1996, Ch. 6). The reason is that, even if the purchaser had full knowledge of the threat of a regulation when he bought the land (and therefore paid a discounted price), the threat had to arise at some previous point in time, and the owner at that point suffered a capital loss. The only way that the original landowner is fully protected against this capital loss is if any subsequent owner who is regulated expects to receive full compensation, that is, compensation equal to the difference between the value of the property with and without the regulation. Compensation based on other measures, such as the purchase price of the land or reliance expenditures, will not eliminate landowner losses (or gains) even when capitalization occurs (Miceli and Segerson, 1996, Ch. 6).
9. Government Incentives versus Land Use Incentives The above discussion of land use incentives in the presence of a takings threat identified a moral hazard problem associated with compensation. Specifically, paying compensation for the full value of the confiscated land will generally lead to overinvestment by landowners. While this result was first demonstrated in the case of physical takings (Blume, Rubinfeld and Shapiro 1984), the basic logic applies to regulatory takings as well (Miceli and Segerson, 1996, Ch. 3). Specifically, with full compensation landowners will act as if they are fully
6200
Takings
349
insured against the risk of a regulation and hence will overinvest. To remedy this problem, compensation must be lump sum, or independent of the amount that was invested in the land. Since a special case of lump sum compensation is zero compensation, an implication of the Blume, Rubinfeld and Shapiro (1984) model is that zero compensation will lead to efficient land use decisions in the case of regulatory takings as well. If regulatory agencies have fiscal illusion, however, then a rule of no compensation potentially leads to excessive regulation (Epstein, 1985, Ch. 17; Johnson, 1977). This threat is especially severe for groups who are underrepresented in the political process or owners of immobile assets who cannot escape uncompensated regulations (Farber, 1992; Fischel, 1995a;Yandle, 1995). Hence, there is a potential trade-off between two effects: the moral hazard problem - which argues against compensation - and regulatory fiscal illusion - which argues for compensation. Miceli and Segerson (1994) explicitly examine the trade-off between moral hazard and fiscal illusion in the context of regulatory takings by considering a compensation rule that conditions the amount of compensation on whether or not the regulator acted in an efficient manner. They show that a rule under which compensation must be paid if and only if the government made an inefficient regulatory decision (the ‘ex post’ rule) will lead to efficient incentives not only for the regulator but also for the landowner. Under this rule, compensation is full when it is inefficient to impose the regulation ex post, but zero when it is efficient to impose the regulation ex post. This definition of the threshold for compensation induces the regulator to act efficiently because by doing so he can ‘avoid’ paying compensation. Moreover, since compensation is zero for efficient regulations, landowners will make the correct land use decisions as well. In light of this conclusion, Miceli and Segerson (1996, Ch. 5) argue that, under appropriate definitions of ‘noxious use’ and ‘nuisance’, the ex post rule is consistent with both the noxious use doctrine and the nuisance exception. In addition, it is consistent with Fischel’s (1985, Ch. 8) rule of paying compensation for inefficient regulations and not paying compensation for efficient ones (see the discussion above). Finally, it defines a threshold for determining when a regulation goes too far under the diminution of value test. While compensation under the ex post rule hinges on the nature of the government action, Miceli and Segerson (1994, 1996, Ch. 4) show that efficient incentives for both regulators and landowners can also be achieved under an alternative rule that determines compensation on the basis of the efficiency of the landowner’s decision (the ‘ex ante’ rule). Under this rule, compensation is paid if and only if the landowner made an efficient land use decision at the time the that the original investment was made. Note that both the ex post and ex ante rules induce efficiency by both parties for the same reason that negligence rules work in bilateral care accident cases (Landes and Posner, 1987, Ch. 4;
350
Takings
6200
Cooter and Ulen, 1988, Ch. 8). Specifically, they specify a threshold for one of the parties such that, by acting efficiently, that party can ‘avoid liability’. As a result, the other party bears ‘full liability’ in equilibrium and therefore also acts efficiently. Since Miceli and Segerson (1994, 1996, Ch. 4) identify two alternative rules that are efficient, factors other than efficiency can be used to choose between them. Two such factors are fairness and transactions costs. Fairness generally argues for payment of compensation in equilibrium (the ex ante rule), whereas transactions cost considerations argue against compensation (the ex post rule). Note that these options mirror Michelman’s (1967) comparison of demoralization and settlement costs for determining compensation. As noted above, Hermalin (1995) also proposed rules that solve the moral hazard and fiscal illusion problems in the context of full takings. However, in contrast to Hermalin’s proposals, the rules proposed by Miceli and Segerson permit attainment of the first-best outcome even when compensation is tied to the value of the land to the landowner, and the landowner does not have a buyback option. Thus, while both the Miceli-Segerson rules and those of Hermalin induce efficient behavior by both landowners and regulators, the former are more closely linked to actual takings law and hence have greater positive significance. Fischel and Shapiro (1989) also proposed a resolution to the trade-off between moral hazard and fiscal illusion in the context of a constitutional choice (veil of ignorance) model. They concluded that partial compensation for regulations optimally balances the costs of these two problems. However, a partial compensation rule only achieves a second-best solution. In addition, it fails to explain actual decisions of courts, which typically award either zero or full compensation. Note, however, that to the extent that compensation is based on fair market value, which is often less than the subjective value of the property (see Section 4 above), courts might in fact be awarding partial compensation for takings that are found to be compensable. Under this form of partial compensation, the rules proposed by Miceli and Segerson (1994, 1996) would yield second-best outcomes as well.
Acknowledgements We acknowledge the very helpful comments of two reviewers.
Bibliography on Takings (6200) Adelstein, Richard P. (1974), ‘Just Compensation and the Assassin’s Bequest: A Utilitarian Approach’, 122 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1012-1032. Baxter, W. and Altree, L. (1972), ‘Legal Aspects of Airport Noise’, 15 Journal of Law and
6200
Takings
351
Economics, 1-113. Been, Vicki (1991), ‘’Exit’ as a Constraint of Land Use Exactions: Rethinking the Unconstitutional Conditions Doctrine’, 91 Columbia Law Review, 473-545. Benson, Bruce L. (1992), ‘The Development of Criminal Law and Its Enforcement: Public Interest or Political Transfers’, 3 Journal des Economistes et des Etudes Humaines, 79-108. Benson, Bruce L. (1994), ‘Emerging From the Hobbesian Jungle: Might Takes and Makes Rights’, 5 Constitutional Political Economy, 129-158. Translated into Spanish and republished (1995) Las Instituciones y Los Derechos de Propiedad al Emerger de la Jungla Hobbesiana: La Fuerza Quita los Reprinted Derechos y los Crea Libertas, 12, 35-75. Berger, L. (1991), ‘Inclusionary Zoning as Takings: The Legacy of the Mount Laurel Cases’, 70 Nebraska Law Review, 186-228. Blume, L. and Rubinfeld, D. (1984), ‘Compensation for Takings: An Economic Analysis’, 72 California Law Review, 569-624. Blume, L. and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1987), ‘Compensation for Takings: An Economic Analysis’, 10 Research in Law and Economics, 53-104. Blume, L., Rubinfeld, Daniel L. and Shapiro, P. (1984), ‘The Taking of Land: When Should Compensation Be Paid?’, 99 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 71-92. Bouckaert, Boudewijn and De Geest, Gerrit (1995), ‘Private Takings, Private Taxes, Private Compulsory Services: The Economic Doctrine of Quasi Contracts’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 463-487. Bromley, Daniel W. (1993), ‘Regulatory Takings: Coherent Concept or Logical Contradiction’, 17 Vermont Law Review, 647-682. Buchanan, James M. (1972), ‘Politics, Property, and the Law: An Alternative Interpretation of Miller et al. v. Schoene’, 15 Journal of Law and Economics, 439-452. Burrows, Paul (1989), ‘Getting a Stranglehold with the Eminant Domain Clause’, 9 International Review of Law and Economics, 129-147. Burrows, Paul (1991), ‘Compensation for Compulsory Acquisition’, 67 Land Economics, 49-63. Cohen, Lloyd R. (1991), ‘Holdouts and Free Riders’, 20 Journal of Legal Studies, 351-362. Connors, C. (1990), ‘Back to the Future: The ‘Nuisance Exception’ to the Just Compensation Clause’, 19 Capital University Law Review, 139-185. Disheroon, F. (1993), ‘After Lucas: No More Wetland Takings?’, 13 Vermont Law Review, 683-693. Dudley, B. and MacDonald, J. (1995), ‘Lucas v. South Carolina Coastal Council, Takings, and the Search for the Common Good’, 33 American Business Law Journal, 153-178. Durham, James Geoffrey (1985), ‘Efficient Just Compensation as a Limit on Eminent Domain’, 69 Minnesota Law Review, 1277-1313. Echeverria, J. and Dennis, S. (1993), ‘The Takings Issue and the Due Process Clause: A Way Out of a Doctrinal Confusion’, 17 Vermont Law Review, 695-721. Epstein, Richard A. (1985), Takings: Private Property and the Power of Eminent Domain, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 362 p. Epstein, Richard A. (1987), ‘Takings: Descent and Resurrection’, Supreme Court Review, 1-45. Epstein, Richard A. (1992), ‘Ruminations on Lucas v. South Carolina Coastal Council: An Introduction to Amicus Curiae Brief’, 25 Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review, 1225-1232.
352
Takings
6200
Epstein, Richard A., W., Mellor III. C., Bolick, J. Emord and Bullock, S. (1992), ‘David Lucas v. South Carolina Coastal Council: Brief for the Institute for Justice as Amicus Curiae in Support of Petitioner’, 25 Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review, 1233-1258. Farber, Daniel A. (1992), ‘Economic Analysis and Just Compensation’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 125-138. Fischel, William A. (1987), ‘The Economics of Land Use Exactions: A Property Rights Analysis’, 50 Law and Contemporary Problems, 101-113. Reprinted in Stein, Jay M. (ed.) (1996), Classic Readings in Real Estate and Development, Washington, DC, ULI - the Urban Land Institute. Fischel, William A. (1988), ‘Introduction: Utilitarian Balancing and Formalism in Takings’, 88 Columbia Law Review, 1581-1599. Fischel, William A. (1991), ‘Exploring the Kozinski Paradox: Why Is More Efficient Regulation a Taking of Property?’, 67 Chicago-Kent Law Review, 865-912. Fischel, Wiliam A. (1992), ‘Exploring the Kozinsky Paradox: Why is More Efficient Regulation a Taking of Property?’, 67 Chicago-Kent Law Review, 865-912. Fischel, William A. (1995a), ‘The Offer/Ask Disparity and Just Compensation for Takings: A Constitutional Choice Perspective’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 187-203. Fischel, William A. (1995b), Regulatory Takings: Law, Economics, and Politics, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Fischel, William A. (1996), ‘The Political Economy of Just Compensation: Lessons from the Military Draft for the Takings Issue’, Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy. Fischel, William A. and Shapiro, Perry (1988), ‘Takings, Insurance and Michelman: Comments on Economic Interpretations of “Just Compensation” Law’, 17 Journal of Legal Studies, 269-293. Reprinted in Ellickson, Robert, Rose, Carol and Ackerman, Bruce (eds), Perspectives on Property Law, 2dn edn, 514-530, Boston, Little Brown, 1995. Fischel, William A. and Shapiro, Perry (1989), ‘A Constitutional Choice Model of Compensation for Takings’, 9 International Review of Law and Economics, 115-128. Fisher, W. III. (1988), ‘The Significance of Public Perceptions of the Takings Doctrine’, 88 Columbia Law Review, 1774-1794. Fisher, W. III. (1993), ‘The Trouble with Lucas’, 45 Stanford Law Review, 1393-1410. Francis, L (1984), ‘Eminent Domain Compensation in Western States’, 1984 Utah Law Review, 429-484. Frech, H. Edward III (1982), ‘The California Coastal Commissions: Economic Impacts’, in Johnson, Bruce (ed.), Resolving the Housing Crisis: Government Policy, Decontrol and the Public Interest, Ballinger, 259-274. Frech, H. Edward III and Lafferty, Ronald N. (1976), ‘The Economic Impact of the California Coastal Commission: Land Use and Land Values’, in Johnson, Bruce M. (ed.), The California Coastal Plan: A Critique, Institute for Contemporary Studies, 69-91. Frech, H. Edward III and Lafferty, Ronald N. (1978), ‘Community Environment and the Market Value of Single-Family Homes: The Effect of Dispersion of Land Uses’, 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 381-396. Freyer, T. (1981), ‘Reassessing the Impact of Eminent Domain in Early American Economic Development’, 57 Wisconsin Law Review, 1263-1286. Friedman, L. (1986), ‘A Search for Seizure: Pennsylvania Coal Co. v. Mahon in Context’, 4 Law and
6200
Takings
353
History Review, 1-22. Gecker, Frances F. (1987), ‘Comment: The Recovery of Opportunity Costs as Just Compensation: A Takings Analysis of Adequate Protection’, 81 Northwestern University Law Review, 953-1025. Ghosh, Shubha (1997), ‘Takings, the Exit Option and Just Compensation’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 157-176. Goldberg, Victor P., Merrill, Tom and Unumb, Daniel (1987), ‘Bargaining in the Shadow of Eminent Domain: Valuing and Apportioning Condemnation Awards Between Landlord and Tenant’, 34 UCLA Law Review, 1083-1187. Hermalin, Benjamin E. (1995), ‘An Economic Analysis of Takings’, 11 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 64-86. Hippler, T. (1987), ‘Reexamining 100 Years of Supreme Court Regulatory Taking Doctrine: The Principles of ‘Noxious Use’, ‘Average reciprocity of Advantage’, ‘and ‘Bundle of Rights’ for Mugler to Keystone Bituminous Coal’, 14 Boston College Environmental Affairs Law Review, 653-727. Innes, R. (1994), Takings, Compensation and Equal Protection for Owners of Developed and Undeveloped Land, Mimeo, University of Arizona. Innes, R. (1995), ‘An Essay on Takings: Concepts and Issues’, 4 Choices. Innes, R. (1997), ‘Takings, Compensation and Equal Protection for Owners of Developed and Undeveloped Land’, Journal of Law and Economics, forthcoming. Johnson, M. Bruce (1977), ‘Planning without Prices: A Discussion of Land Use Regulation Without Compensation’, in Siegan, Bernard H. (ed.), Planning Without Prices, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books, 63-111. Kaplow, Louis (1986), ‘An Economic Analysis of Legal Transitions’, 99 Harvard Law Review, 509-617. Kaplow, Louis (1987), ‘Optimal Transition Policy: Replacing Horizontal Equity with an Ex Ante Incentives Perspective’, Dissertation accepted by Harvard University Department of Economics. Kaplow, Louis (1992), ‘Government Relief for Risk Associated with Government Action’, 94 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 525-541. Kmiec, D. (1981), ‘Regulatory Takings: The Court Runs Out of Gas in San Diego’, 57 Indiana Law Journal, 45-81. Kmiec, D. (1988), ‘The Original Understanding of the Taking Clause is Neither Weak Nor Obtuse’, 88 Columbia Law Review, 1630-1666. Knetsch, Jack L. (1983), Property Rights and Compensation: Compulsory Acquisitions and Other Losses, Toronto, Butterworths. Knetsch, Jack L. (1990), ‘Environmental Policy Implications of Disparities between Willingness to Pay and Compensation Demanded Measures of Values’,18 Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 227-237. Knetsch, Jack L. and Borcherding, T. (1979), ‘Expropriation of Private Property and the Basis for Compensation’, 29 University of Toronto Law Journal, 237-252. La Croix, Summer and Rose, L. (1995), ‘Public Use, Just Compensation, and Land Reform in Hawaii’, 17 Research in Law and Economics, 17 ff. Levmore, Saul (1990), ‘Just Compensation and Just Politics’, 22 Connecticut Law Review, 285-322. Levmore, Saul (1991), ‘Takings, Torts, and Special Interests’, 77 Virginia Law Review, 1333-1368.
354
Takings
6200
Levmore, Saul and Stuntz, William J. (1990), ‘Remedies and Incentives in Private and Public Law: A Comparative Essay’, 66 Wisconsin Law Review, 483-499. Lodise, John P. (1988), ‘Retroactive Compensation and the Illusion of Economic Efficiency: An Analysis of the First English Decision’, 35 UCLA Law Review, 1267-1290. Lunney, G. (1992), ‘A Critical Reexamination of the Takings Jurisprudence’, 90 Michigan Law Review, 1892-1965. MacKaay, Ejan (1987), ‘Le Paradoxe des Droits Acquis (The Paradox of Acquired Rights)’, in, De ‘l’Ancienne’ à la ‘Nouvelle’ Economie. Essais à l’Occasion de la Dixième Université d’Eté de la Nouvelle Economie, Aix-en-Provence, Librairie de l’Université, 205-219. Mandelker, D. (1987), ‘Investment-Backed Expectations: Is There a Taking?’, 31 Journal of Urban and Contemporary Problems, 3-43. Manheim, K. (1989), ‘Tenant Eviction and the Takings Clause’, 65 Wisconsin Law Review, 925-1019. McKenzie, Richard B. (1986), ‘Eminent Domain: A New Industrial Policy Tool’, 142 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 27-38. Medema, S. (1992a), ‘Making Choices and Making Law: An Institutional Perspective on the Taking Issue’, in Mercuro, Nicholas, Taking Property and Just Compensation: Legal and Economic Perspectives of the Takings Issue, Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers. Medema, Steven G. (1992b), ‘Probing the Legal-Economic Nexus: Takings, 1978-1988', 26 Journal of Economic Issues, 525-534. Medema, Steven G. (1992c), Legal Economic Perspectives on the Taking Issue, Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers. Mercuro, Nicholas (ed.) (1992a), Taking Property and Just Compensation: Legal and Economics Perspectives of the Takings Issue, Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers. Mercuro, Nicholas (1992b), ‘The Takings Issue: A Continuing Dilemma in Law and Economics’, in Mercuro, Nicholas (ed.), Taking Property and Just Compensation: Law and Economics Perspectives of the Takings Issue, Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1-23. Mercuro, Nicholas and Ryan, Thimothy P. (1980), ‘Property Rights and Welfare Economics: Miller et al. v. Schoene Revisited: Reply’, 56 Land Economics, 202-212. Mercuro, Nicholas and Ryan, Thimothy P. (1981), ‘Property Rights and Welfare Economics: Miller et al. v. Schoene Revisited: Reply’, 57 Land Economics, 657-659. Merrill, T. (1986a), ‘The Economics of Public Use’, 72 Cornell Law Review, 61-116. Merrill, T. (1986b), ‘Rent Seeking and the Compensation Principle’, 80 Northwestern Law Review, 1561-1589. Miceli, Thomas J. (1991), ‘Compensation for the Taking of Land Under Eminent Domain’, 147 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 354-363. Miceli, Thomas J. and Segerson, Kathleen (1994), ‘Regulatory Takings: When Should Compensation be Paid?’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 749-776. Miceli, Thomas J. and Segerson, Kathleen (1995), ‘Government Regulation and Compensation for Takings: Implications for Agriculture’, 77 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 1177-1182. Miceli, Thomas J. and Segerson, Kathleen (1996), Compensation for Regulatory Takings: An Economic Analysis with Applications, Greenwich, CT, JAI Press. Michelman, Frank I. (1967), ‘Property, Utility and Fairness: Comments on the Ethical Foundations of
6200
Takings
355
‘Just Compensation’ Law’, 80 Harvard Law Review, 1165-1258. Reprinted in Ackerman, Bruce A. (ed.) (1975), Economic Foundations of Property Law, Boston, Little Brown, 100 ff. Michelman, Frank I. (1988), ‘Takings’, 88 Columbia Law Review, 1600-1629. Munch, Patricia (1976), ‘An Economic Analysis of Eminent Domain’, 84 Journal of Political Economy, 473-497. Paul, E. (1987a), Property Rights and Eminent Domain, New Brunswick, NJ, Transaction Press. Paul, Ellen Frankel (1987b), ‘Public Use: A Vanishing Limitation on Governmental Takings’, in Dorn, James A. and Manne, Henry G. (eds), Economic Liberties and the Judiciary, Fairfax, George Mason University Press, 357-373. Peterson, Andrew A. (1989), ‘The Takings Clause: In Search of Underlying Principles’, 77 California Law Review, 1299-1363. Poirier, M. (1993), ‘Takings and Natural Hazards Policy: Public Choice on the Beachfront’, 46 Rutgers Law Review, 243-347. Rose, Carol M. (1984), ‘Mahon Reconstructed: Why the Takings Issue is Still a Muddle’, 57 Southern California Law Review, 561-599. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1988), ‘Against Ad Hocery: A Comment on Michelman’, 88 Columbia Law Review, 1697-1711. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1992), ‘Regulatory Takings: Policy Analysis and Democratic Principles’, in Mercuro, Nicholas (ed.), Taking Property and Just Compensation: Law and Economics Perspectives of the Takings Issue, Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 25-44. Ross, Thomas W. (1994), ‘Raising an Army: A Positive Theory of Military Recruitment’, 37 Journal of Law and Economics, 109-131. Rowley, Charles K. (1992), ‘The Supreme Court and Takings Judgments: Constitutional Political Economy versus Public Choice’, in Mercuro, Nicholas (ed.), Taking Property and Just Compensation: Law and Economics Perspectives of the Takings Issue, Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 79-124. Rubenfeld, J. (1993), ‘Usings’, 102 Yale Law Journal, 1077-1163. Runge, C. (1993), ‘Economic Implications of Wider Compensation for ‘Takings’ or, What if Agricultural Policies Ruled the World?’, 17 Vermont Law Review, 723-739. Samuels, Warren J. (1974), ‘Commentary: An Economic Perspective on the Compensation Problem’, 21 Wayne Law Review, 113-134. Reprinted in Samuels, Warren J. and Schmid, A. Allen (eds) (1981), Law and Economics: An Institutional Perspective, Boston, Nijhoff, 1981, 188-209. Samuels, Warren J. and Mercuro, Nicholas (1979), ‘The Role and Resolution of the Compensation Principle in Society: Part One - The Role’, 1 Research in Law and Economics, 157-194. Samuels, Warren J. and Mercuro, Nicholas (1980), ‘The Role and Resolution of the Compensation Principle in Society: Part Two - The Resolution’, 2 Research in Law and Economics, 103-128. Sax, Joseph L. (1964), ‘Takings and the Police Power’, 74 Yale Law Journal, 36-76. Sax, Joseph L. (1971), ‘Takings, Private Property and Public Rights’, 81 Yale Law Journal, 149-186. Reprinted in Ackerman, Bruce A. (ed.) (1975), Economic Foundations of Property Law, Boston, Little Brown, 146-158. Schill, M. (1989), ‘Intergovernmental Takings and Just Compensation: A Question of Federalism’,137
356
Takings
6200
University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 829-901. Siegan, Bernard H. (1972), Land Use Without Zoning, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Stake, Jeffrey E. (1995), ‘Loss Aversion and Involuntary Transfers of Title’, in Malloy, Robbin P. and Braun, Christopher K. (eds), Law and Economics: New and Critical Perspectives, New York, Lang, 331-360. Stein, G (1995), ‘Regulatory Takings and Ripeness in Federal Courts’, 48 Vanderbilt Law Review, 1-99. Stoebuck, W. (1969), ‘The Property Right of Access versus the Power of Eminent Domain’, 47 Texas Law Review, 733-765. Stoebuck, W. (1972), ‘A General Theory of Eminent Domain’, 47 Washington Law Review, 553-608. Swank, W. (1976), ‘Note. Inverse Condemnation: The Case for Diminution in Property Values as Compensable Damage’, 28 Stanford Law Review, 779-804. Symposium (1988), ‘Symposium on Takings’, 88 Columbia Law Review, 1581-1794. Thompson, B. (1990), ‘Judicial Takings’, 76 Virginia Law Review, 1449-1544. Tideman, N. (1988), ‘Takings, Moral Evolution, and Justice’, 88 Columbia Law Review, 1714-1730. Tiefer, C. (1996), ‘Controlling Federal Agencies by Claims on Their Appropriations? the Takings Bill and the Power of the Purse’, 13 Yale Journal on Regulation, 501-534. Treanor, W. (1985), ‘The Origins and Original Significance of the Just Compensation Clause of the Fifth Amendment’, 94 Yale Law Journal, 694-716. Trefzger, J. and Colwell, P. (1996), ‘Investor Efficiency in the Face of Takings’, 12 Journal of Real Estate Finance and Economics, 23-35. Ulen, Thomas S. (1992), ‘The Public Use of Private Property: A Dual Constraint Theory of Efficient Government Takings’, in Mercuro, Nicholas (ed.), Taking Property and Just Compensation: Law and Economics Perspectives of the Takings Issue, Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 163-198. Werin, Lars (1978), ‘Expropriation - en Studie i Lagstiftningsmotiv och Ersättningsrättsliga Grundprinciper (Expropriation - A Study in Legislative Motives and Compensatory Basic Principles)’, Svensk Juristtidning, 81-120. Wittman, Donald A. (1995), The Myth of Democratic Failure: Why Political Institutions are Efficient, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Wittman, Donald A. and Grofman, Bernard (eds) (1989), The Federalist Papers: The New Institutionalism and the Old, Edison, NJ, Agathon Press. Yandle, Bruce (1995), Land Rights: The 1990's Property Rights Rebellion, Lanham, MD, Rowman and Littlefield.
Other References Calabresi, Guido and Melamed, A. Douglas (1972), ‘Property Rules, Liability Rules, and Inalienability: One View of the Cathedral’, 85 Harvard Law Review, 1089-1128. Coase, Ronald H. (1960), ‘The Problem of Social Cost’, 3 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-44. Cooter, Robert D. (1985), ‘Unity in Tort, Contract, and Property: The Model of Precaution’, 73 California Law Review, 1-51. Cooter Robert D. and Ulen, Tom (1988), Law and Economics, New York, Harper Collins.
6200
Takings
357
Cornes, R. and Sandler, Todd (1986), The Theory of Externalities, Public Goods, and Club Goods, Cambridge, Cambridge Univ. Press. Dana, D. (1995), ‘Natural Preservation and the Race to Develop’, 143 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 655-708. Ellickson, Robert (1973), ‘Alternatives to Zoning: Covenants, Nuisance Rules, and Fines as Land Use Controls’, 40 University of Chicago Law Review, 681-782. Ellickson, Robert (1977), ‘Suburban Growth Controls: An Economic and Legal Analysis’, 86 Yale Law Journal, 385-511. Epstein, Richard (1995), Simple Rules for a Complex World, Cambridge, Harvard University Press. Fischel, William (1985), The Economics of Zoning Laws, Baltimore, Johns Hopkins University Press. Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (1996), ‘Property Rules versus Liability Rules: An Economic Analysis’, 109 Harvard Law Review, 715-790. Keeton, W.P., Dobbs, D., Keeton, R. and Owen, D. (1984), Prosser and Keeton on the Law of Torts, 5th edn, St. Paul, West. Krier, James and Schwab, Stuart (1995), ‘Property Rules and Liability Rules: The Cathedral in Another Light’, 70 New York University Law Review, 440-483. Landes, William, and Posner, Richard A. (1987), The Economic Structure of Tort Law, Cambridge, Harvard University Press. Mandelker, D. (1993), Land Use Law, 3rd edn, Charlottesville, Michie. Merrill, T. (1985), ‘Trespass, Nuisance, and the Costs of Determining Property Rights’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 13-48. Mueller, Dennis C. (1989), Public Choice II, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Posner, Richard A. (1980), ‘The Ethical and Political Basis of the Efficiency Norm in Common Law Adjudication’, 8 Hofstra Law Review, 487-507. Posner, Richard A. (1992), Economic Analysis of Law, 4th edn, Boston, Little Brown. Rawls, John (1971), A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, Harvard University Press. Rose, Carol (1983), ‘Planning and Dealing: Piecemeal Land Controls as a Problem of Local Legitimacy’, 71 California Law Review, 837-912. Wittman, Donald (1984), ‘Liability for Harm or Restitution for Benefit?’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 57-80.
List of Cases Agins v. City of Tiburon (1980), 447 U.S. 255. Boomer v. Atlantic Cement (1970), 309 N.Y.S.2d 312. Callender v. Marsh (1823), 1 Pick. 417. Dolan v. City of Tigard (1994), 114 S.Ct. 2309. HFH Ltd. v. Superior Court (1975), 542 P.2d 237. Lucas v. South Carolina Coastal Council (1992), 112 S.Ct. 2886. Mugler v. Kansas (1887), 123 U.S. 623. Nollan v. California Coastal Comm’n (1987), 438 U.S. 825. Penn Central Transportation Co. v. City of New York (1978) 438 U.S. 104. Pennsylvania Coal Co. v. Mahon (1922), 260 U.S. 393. U.S. v. Carroll Towing (1947), 159 F.2d 169.
6300 ADMINISTRATIVE LAW © Copyright 1999 Boudewijn Bouckaert and Gerrit De Geest
Bibliography Collected by the Editors Arruñada, Benito (1994), ‘Competencia y Privatización en el Mercado Educativo (Competition and Privatization in the Education Market)’, 59 Boletín del Círculo de Empresarios, 265-275. Arruñada, Benito (1995), ‘Diseño Organizativo y Gestión de Personal en la Sanidad Pública (Organization and Management of Human Resources in the Public Healthcare System)’, in A.E.S. (ed.), Cambios en la Regulación Sanitaria, Barcalona, SG Editores, 64-119. Audretsch, David B., Sleuwaegen, L. and Yamawaki, H. (1989), The Convergence of International and Domestic Markets, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 317 p. Auster, Richard D. and Silver, Morris (1979), The State as a Firm: Economic Forces in Political Development, Den Haag, Martinus Nijhoff, 178 p. Backhaus, Jürgen G. (1977), Public Enterprise: Forms and Functions, Haag & Herchen, 1977 (1st edn), 441 p., 1980 (2nd edn), 535 p. Backhaus, Jürgen G. (1991), ‘Law: Cooperation between Lawyers, Economists and Common Denominator’, 45(10) Wirtschaftswoche, 149-150. Bandin Tomislav (1988), ‘Politicko Jedinstvo kao Faktor Ostvarivanja Dogovorene Ekonomske i Razvojne Politike (Political Unity as a Factor of Implementation of Agreed Economic and Development Policy)’, 1 Ekonomist, 29-31. Bardach, Eugene and Kagan, Robert A. (1982), Going By The Book: The Problem of Regulatory Unreasonableness, Philadelphia, Temple University Press, 375 p. Bawn, Kathleen (1997), ‘Choosing Strategies to Control the Bureaucracy: Statutory Constraints, Oversight, and the Committee System’, 13 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 101-126. Berge, J.B.J.M. Ten (1991), ‘Rechtseconomie en Staatsrecht/Bestuursrecht (Law and Economics and Constitutional/Administrative Law)’, in Hondius, E.H., Schippers, J.J. and Siegers, J.J. (eds), Rechtseconomie en Recht, Zwolle, Tjeenk Willink, 149-162. Bishop, William (1990), ‘A Theory of Administrative Law’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 489-530. Boardman, Anthony E. and Vining, Aidan R. (1989), ‘Ownership and Performance in Competitive Environments: A Comparison of the Performance of Private, Mixed, and State-owned Enterprises’, 32 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-33. Borjas, George J. (1982), ‘The Politics of Employment Discrimination in the Federal Bureaucracy’, 25 Journal of Law and Economics, 271-299. Breyer, Stephen G. (1993), Breaking the Vicious Circle: Toward Effective Risk Regulation, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 127 p.
358
6300
Administrative Law
359
Buxbaum, Hertig and Hirsch, Hopt (eds), European Economic and Business Law, Legal and Economic Analyses on Integration and Harmonization, Berlin, 401 p. Calabresi, Guido (1970), The Costs of Accidents: A Legal and Economic Analysis, New Haven, Yale University Press, 340 p. Clarckson, Kenneth W. and Martin, Donald L. (eds) (1979), The Economics of Nonproprietary Institutions (Supplement 1 to Research in Law and Economics), Greenwood, JAI Press, 330 p. Clarckson, Kenneth W. and Tollison, Robert D. (1979), ‘Toward a Theory of Government Advertising’, 1 Research in Law and Economics, 131-143. Cooter, Robert D. and Topakian, G. (1980), ‘Political Economy of a Public Corporation: The Pricing Objectives of BART’, 13 Journal of Public Economics. Cragg, Michael (1997), ‘Performance Incentives in the Public Sector: Evidence From the Job Training Partnership Act’, 13 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 147-168. Cranor, Carl F. (1993), Regulating Toxic Substances: A Philosophy of Science and the Law, New York, Oxford Press, 252 p. De Kraan, D.J. (1982a), ‘Deregulering: Een Begripsbepaling (Deregulation: A Definition)’, 9 Beleid en Maatschappij, 177-181. De Kraan, D.J. (1982b), ‘Deregulering (Deregulation)’, 62 Economisch-Statistische Berichten, 692-696. Desouza, Patrick J. (1985), ‘Regulating Fraud in Military Procurement: A Legal Process Model’, 95 Yale Law Journal, 390-413. Diver, Colin S. (1983), ‘The Optimal Precision of Administrative Rules’, 93 Yale Law Journal, 65-109. Doel, J. v.d. and Van Velthoven, Ben C.J. (1990), Democratie en Welvaartstheorie (3rd edn) (Democracy and Welfare Economics), Alphen a.d. Rijn, Samsom H.D. Tjeenk Willink, 232 p. Doel, J. v.d. and Van Velthoven, Ben C.J. (1993), Democracy and Welfare Economics: An Introduction Into New Political Economy, 2nd edn, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 212 p. Farber, Daniel A. and Frickey, Philip P. (1988), ‘Integrating Public Choice and Public Law: A Reply to DeBow and Lee’, 66 Texas Law Review, 1013-1019. Ferris, James M. and Graddy, Elizabeth (1994), ‘Organizational Choices for Public Service Supply’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 126-141. Finkelstein, M.O. (1973), ‘Regression Models in Administrative Proceedings’, 86 Harvard Law Review, 1442-1475. Fiorina, M. (1982), ‘Legislative Choice of Regulatory Forms: Legal Process or Administrative Proces?’, 39 Public Choice, 33 ff. Frech, H.Edward III and Lafferty, Ronald N. (1984), ‘The Effect of the California Coastal Commission on Housing Prices’, 16 Journal of Urban Economics, 105-123. Friedman, David D. (1993), ‘The Political Economy of the Decline of American Public Education: Comments’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 371-378.
360
Administrative Law
6300
Gantner, Manfred (1988), ‘Öffentliche (De-)Regulierung im Zusammenhang mit der österreichischen Post- und Telegraphenverwaltung (Public Deregulation of Postal Serevices)’, 8 Finanzwissenschaftliche Diskussionsreihe. Gantner, Manfred (ed.) (1991), Handbuch des öffentlichen Haushaltswesens (The Handbook of Public Budgeting), Vienna, Manz, 416 p. Gantner, Manfred (ed.) (1994), Budgetausgliederung - Fluch(t) oder Segen? (Budgetary Disembodyment - Vice or Virtue?), Vienna, Manz, 232 p. Garcia Villarejo, Salinas, Avelino and Sánchez, Javier (1993), Manual de Hacienda Pública general y de España (Public Treasury Manual), Madrid, Tecnos. Geelhoed, L.A. (1993), ‘Deregulering, Herregulering en Zelfregulering (Deregulation, Re-regulation and Selfregulation)’, in Eijlander, Ph. (ed.), Government and Selfregulation, Deventer, W.E.J. Tjeenk Willink, 33-51. Gimeno Ullastres, Juan A., La Situación de las Facultades de Derecho y Económicas: Análisis y Propuestas (Analysis and Proposals for Law and Economics Schools), Secretaría de Estado de Universidades e Investigación, Ministerio de Educación y Ciencia, 67 p. Gimeno Ullastres, Juan A. and Ruiz Huerta, Jesús, ‘Los Costes de los Servicios Universitarios (The Cost of Universities)’, in X (ed.), La Financiación de la Enseñanza Superior, Madrid, Consejo de Universidades, 181-209. Ginsburg, Douglas H. and Demuth, Christopher C. (1986), ‘White House Review of Agency Rulemaking’, 99 Harvard Law Review, 1075 ff. Greene, Kenneth V. and Moulton, George D. (1986), ‘Municipal Employee Residency Requirement Statutes: An Economic Analysis’, 9 Research in Law and Economics, 185-204. Greenstein, Shane (1993), ‘Procedural Rules and Procurement Regulations: Complexity Creates Tradeoffs’, 9 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 159-180. Grossekettler, Heinz (1984), ‘Verwaltungsstrukturpolitik (Public Administration Structure Policy)’, in Ewers, H.-J. and Schuster (ed.), Probleme der Ordnungs- und Strukturpolitik, Göttingen, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 16-51. Hackney, James R., Jr (1988), ‘A Proposal for State Funding of Municipal Tort Liability’, 98 Yale Law Journal, 389-407. Harmathy, Attila (1980), ‘Allami Támogatások Jogi Kérdéseiröl (Legal Questions on State Subsidies)’, 1 Allam- és Jogtudomány, 33-61. Harmathy, Attila (1983), Szerzödések, Allamigazgatás, Gazdaságirányitás (Contract, Administration, Business Governing), Budapest, Akadémiai Kiadó, 210 p. Hill, Jeffrey S. and Brazier, James E. (1991), ‘Constraining Administrative Decisions: A Critical Examination of the Structure and Process Hypothesis’, 7 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 373-400. Hondius, E.H., Schippers, Joop J. and Siegers, Jacques J. (1991), Rechtseconomie en Recht. Kennismaking met een Vakgebied in Opkomst (Law and Economics: Introduction to a Growing Field of Science), Zwolle, Tjeenk Willink, 201 p. Howard, Philip K. (1994), The Death of Common Sense: How Law is Suffocating America, New York, Random House, 202 p.
6300
Administrative Law
361
Howse, Robert, Prichard, J. Robert S. and Trebilcock, Michael J. (1990), ‘Smaller or Smarter Government?’, 40 University of Toronto Law Journal, 498-541. Johnson, Ronald N. and Libecap, Gary D. (1989), ‘Bureaucratic Rules, Supervisor Behavior, and the Effect on Salaries in the Federal Government’, 5 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 53-82. Kramer, Larry and Sykes, Alan O. (1987), ‘Municipal Liability under Section 1983: A Legal and Economic Analysis’, Supreme Court Review, 249-301. Künneke, R.W. (1986), ‘Privatisation of Municipal Utilities’, 18(5) Openbare Uitgaven, 218-228. Labus Miroljub (1990), ‘Devalvacija i Administrativna Kontrola Cena (Devaluation and Administrative Control of Prices)’, 1 Ekonomska misao, 1-24. Lane, J.-E. (ed.) (1985), State and Market; The Politics of the Public and the Private, London, Sage, 304 p. Mackaay, Ejan (1992), ‘The Public’s Right to Information’, in Korthals Altes, Willem F., Dommering, Egbert J., Hugenholtz, P. Bernt and Kabel, Jan J.C. (eds), Information Law Towards the 21st Century, Deventer, Kluwer, 167-175. Marshall, Robert C., Meurer, Michael J. and Richard, Jean Francois (1994), ‘Multiple Litigants with a Public Good Remedy’, 16 Research in Law and Economics, 151-173. Martin, Dolores Tremewan and Wagner, Richard E. (1978), ‘The Institutional Framework for Municipal Incorporation: An Economic Analysis of Local Agency Formation Commissions in California’, 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 409-425. Mashaw, Jerry L. (1985), ‘Prodelegation: Why Administrators Should Make Political Decisions’, 1 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 81-100. Mashaw, Jerry L. (1990), ‘Explaining Administrative Process: Normative, Positive, and Critical Stories of Legal Devopment’, 6(S) Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 267-298. McCubbins, Mathew D., Noll, Roger G. and Weingast, Barry R. (1987), ‘Administrative Procedures as Instruments of Political Control’, 3 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 243-277. McCubbins, Mathew D., Noll, Roger G. and Weingast, Barry R. (1990), ‘Positive and Normative Models of Procedural Rights: An Integrative Approach to Administrative Procedures’, 6(S) Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 307-332. McGarity, Thomas O. (1991), Reinventing Rationality: The Role of Regulatory Analysis in the Federal Bureaucracy, New York, Cambridge University Press, 384 p. Miller, Geoffrey P., Litt, David, Macey, Jonathan R. and Rubin, Edward L. (1990), ‘Politics, Bureaucracies, and Financial Markets: Bank Entry Into Commercial Paper Underwriting in the United States and Japan,’, 139 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 20 ff. Morgan, Thomas D. (1978), ‘Toward a Revised Strategy for Ratemaking’, 21 University of Illinois Law Forum. Morgan, Thomas D. (1979), ‘Procedural Impediments to Optimal Rate Making’, in Sichel, Werner (ed.), Public Utility Rate Making in an Energy-Conscious Environment, Boulder, Westview Press.
362
Administrative Law
6300
Neelen, G.H.J.M. (1990), ‘Efficiency Differences Between Organizations Within the Public Sector: The Dutch Social Housing Sector’, 2 Tinbergen Institute Research Bulletin, 33-41. Ommeren, F.J. Van (1990), ‘Bestuurscompensatie, Draagkracht en Rechtseconomie (Administrative Compensation, Financial Capacity and Economic Analysis of Law)’, 39(10) Ars Aequi, 682-691. Owen, Bruce M. and Willig, Robert D. (1983), ‘Economic and Postal Pricing Policy’, in Fleishman, J. (ed.), The Future of the Postal Service, New York, Praeger Publishing Company. Pastor, Santos (1988), ‘Elementos para un Análisis Económico de la Justicia: el Gasto Público en Justicia en España’ (Public Expenditure in the Courts: Reflections on Method and Scope), 110 Hacienda Pública Española. Pastor, Santos (1990), ‘A Propósito de la Eficacia del Gasto Público. Notas Sobre una Asignatura Pendiente del Sector Público Español (The Efficiency of Public Expenditure)’, 680 Información Comercial Española, 151-157. Pastor, Santos (1991), ‘Las Políticas de no Intervención Estatal en Economía: una Revisión (The State in a Market Economy: A Review)’, 113 Hacienda Pública Española, 147-159. Pastor, Santos (1993), ‘Composición, Estructura y Características de la Litigiosidad Contencioso-Administrativa: Un Análisis Muestral (Litigation in Contentious-Administrative Courts. An Empirical Analysis)’, 111 Boletín de Información del Consejo General del Poder Judicial, 205-288. Peeters, Bruno (1989), De Continuïteit van het Overheidsondernemen: een Begrippenanalyse en een Kritiek op de Uitvoeringsimmuniteit (The Continuity Principle of Governmental Activities: A Concept Analysis and a Critique on the Execution Immunity), Antwerpen, Maklu, 559 p. Peltzman, Sam (1993), ‘The Political Economy of the Decline of American Public Education’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 331-370. Petrovic Milenko (1995), ‘Funkcije drzave u Savremenoj Trzisnoj Privredi (State Functions in a Contemporary Market Economy)’, 3-4 Ekonomska misao, 207-224. Philipson, Tomas and Posner, Richard A. (1994), ‘Public Spending on AIDS Education: An Economic Analysis’, 37 Journal of Law and Economics, 17-38. Preite, Disiano (1987), ‘Sovrapprezzo, aste Competitive e Mercato Mobiliare’ (Overpricing, Competitive Auctions and Security Market)’, Giurisprudenza commerciale, 882-924. Puy Fraga, Pedro (1992), ‘La Economía Política del Servicio Militar (Political Economy of Recruiting)’, Revista de Derecho Financiero y Hacienda Pública, 471-500. 1ª edición, Boletín de Información del Ministerio de Defensa, nº 227, 1992, páxs 9-29. 2ªre ed., Monografías del Ceseden: Cuatro aspectos de la defensa nacional, Ministerio de Defensa, Madrid, 1993, páxs. 137-165. Puy Fraga, Pedro (1993), ‘O Procedemento Administrativo como Factor na Toma de Decisións Públicas (Comentarios desde a economía política á Lei 30/1992 do 26 de Novembro, de réxime xurídico das administracións públicas e do procedemento administrativo común) (The Role of
6300
Administrative Law
363
Administrative Procedure in Public Decision Making)’, 5 Revista Galega de Administracion Publica, 163-181. Puy Fraga, Pedro (1994), ‘Indices de Voluntariedad para el Servicio Militar: Una Visión desde la Economía Política (Voluntary Indexes from a Political Economy Approach to the Mandatory Military Service)’, in Segado, F. Fernández (ed.), El Servicio Militar: Aspectos Jurídicos y Socioeconómicos, Madrid, Editorial Dikynson, 275-295. Reedición e traducción do artíg.: ‘Indices de voluntariedade e custos do servicio militar: Unha visión desde a economía política’, Revista Galega da Economía, vol. 2, nº 1, 1993, páxs. 231-243. Rogerson, William P. (1989), ‘Profit Regulation of Defense Contractors and Prizes for Innovation’, 97 Journal of Political Economy, 1284-1305. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1986), ‘Reforming Public Bureaucracy through Economic Incentives?’, 2 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 131 ff. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1988), ‘Progressive Law and Economics - and the New Administrative Law’, 98 Yale Law Journal, 341-368. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1990a), ‘Deregulation and Reregulation: Rhetoric and Reality’, 6 Journal of Law and Politics, 287-309. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1990b), ‘Defending the State: A Skeptical Look at “Regulatory Reform” in the Eighties’‘, 61 University of Colorado Law Review, 517-535. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1994a), ‘Consensus Versus Incentives: A Skeptical Look at Regulatory Negotiation’, 43 Duke Law Journal, 1206-1220. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1994b), ‘American Administration Law under Siege: Is Germany a Model?’, 107 Harvard Law Review, 1279-1302. Ryssdal, Stray A.C. (1993), Antitrust Enforcement - An Inquiry into Policy Analysis of Competition Law, Working Paper, Centre for Research in Economics & Business Administration, Bergen, No. 89. Sagoff, Mark (1988), The Economy of the Earth: Philosophy, Law, and the Environment, New York, Cambridge University Press, 271 p. Salinas, Javier, Presupuestos y Financiación de la Unión Europea (Coordination of Budget Policy Through Legislation), Valladolid, Editorial Lex Nova. Salinas, Javier, ‘Racionalidad Económica y Derecho Presupuestario (Economic Rationality and Budget Law)’, 132 Hacienda Pública Española, 21-51. Salinas, Javier (1991), Economía Política del Federalismo Fiscal Español (Political Economy of the Spanish Fiscal Federalism), Madrid, Instituto de Estudios Fiscales. Salinas, Javier (1993), Economía Política Constitucional de los Presupuestos Públicos (Constitutional Political Economy of the Budget), Madrid, Tecnos. Salinas, Javier (1995), ‘Economía Constitucional de la Descentralización del Sector Público en España (Constitutional Economy of Descentralization of the Spanish Public Sector)’, in Capítulo del libro, La Financiación de las Comunidades Autonomas, Análisis y Orientación desde la Teoría del Federalismo Fiscal, Valladolid, Consejeria de Economía, Junta de Castilla y León, 29-54. Salinas, Javier (1996a), ‘Economía Constitucional de la Política Fiscal Española y la Convergencia Europea (Constitutional Economy of Spanish Tax Policy and European Covergence)’, in X (ed.),
364
Administrative Law
6300
Proceedings, XVIII Jornadas de la Dirección General del Servicio Juridico del Estado sobre la Constitución Española y el Ordenamiento Comunitario Europeo, Madrid, Ministerio de Justicia. Salinas, Javier (1996b), Elementos Institucionales de la Organización Territorial del Sector Público en Castilla y León (Institutional Elements of the Public Sector’s Territorial Organization in Castilla and Leon), Valladolid, Consejería de Economía, Junta de Castilla y León. Salvador Coderch, Pablo, Lloveras Y., Ferrer, M.R.Y., Seuba Y. and Torreblanca, J.C (1995), ‘Del Servicio Público al Servicio a la Comunidad (From Public Service to Service for the Community)’, 136 Revista de Administración Pública, 69 ff. Samuels, Warren J. (1993), ‘The Growth of Government’, 7 Critical Review, 445-460. Sanjiao Otero, Francisco Javier (1994), ‘Economía de las Instituciones: Análisis de la Política Museística en ‘Galicia (Economics of Institutions: Policy on Museums in Galicia)’, 3 Dereito, Revista Xurídica da Universidade de Santiago de Compostela, 127-158. Sanjiao Otero, Francisco Javier (1995), ‘Análise Económico das Medidas Públicas para o Fomento do Teatro Privado Galego (Economic Analysis of Public Policy to Promote Private Galician Theatre)’, in Leiceaga, Fernández, Rodríguez, M. Jordán, Iglesias, E. López and Deza, X. Vence (eds), Estudos en homenaxe ó profesor Xose Manuel Beiras Torrado, Universidade de Santiago de Compostela, 439-460. Schenk, Karl-Ernst (1976), ‘Demokratie oder Bürokratie? Dezentralisierung - Selbstverwaltung Entbürokratisierung (Democracy or Bureaucracy? Decentralization, Self-Administration, De-Bureaucratisation)’, in Geißler, H. (ed.), Verwaltete Bürgergesellschaft in Fesseln. Bürokratisierung und ihre Folgen für den Staat, Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft, Frankfurt (M), Berlin Wien. Schenk, Karl-Ernst, Schmidtchen, Dieter and Streit, Manfred E. (eds) (1996), Vom Hoheitsstaat zum Konsensualstaat, Neue Formen der Kooperation zwischen Staat und Privaten Jahrbuch für Neue Politische Ökonomie 15 (From Sovereignity to Consensus, New Forms of Cooperation Between State and Citizens), Tübingen, Mohr. Schwartz, Bernard (1985), ‘Cost-Benefit Analysis in Administrative Law: Does it Make Priceless Procedural Right Worthless?’, 37 Administrative Law Review, 1-14. Schwarzer, Stephan (1985), ‘’Wirtschaftsrecht und Okonomische Effizienz (Commercial Law and Economic Efficiency)’, Wirtschaftspolitische Blätter, 26-31. Siekmann, Hans (1996), ‘Corporate Governance und Offentlich-Rechtliche Unternehmen (Corporate Governance and Public Enterprises)’, in Schenk, Karl-Ernst, Schmidtchen, Dieter Streit, Manfred E. (eds), Vom Hoheitsstaat zum Konsensualstaat, Neue Formen der Kooperation zwischen Staat und Privaten Jahrbuch für Neue Politische Ökonomie 15, Tübingen, Mohr. Spence, David B. (1997), ‘Modeling Away the Delegation Problem’, 7 Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory, 199-219. Spiller, Pablo T. and Ferejohn, John A. (1992), ‘The Economics and Politics of Administrative Law and Procedures: An Introduction’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 1-17.
6300
Administrative Law
365
Sunstein, Cass R. (1983), ‘Is Cost-Benefit Analysis a Panacea for Administrative Law?’, 29 Law School Record, 19-21. Sunstein, Cass R. (1990a), After the Rights Revolution: Reconceiving the Regulatory State, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 284 p. Sunstein, Cass R. (1990b), ‘Political Economy, Administrative Law: A Comment’, 6(S) Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 299-306. Sunstein, Cass R. (1991), ‘Administrative Substance’, 1991 Duke Law Journal, 607-646. Sunstein, Cass R. (1993), ‘Against Interest Group Theory: A Comment (on the Political Economy of the Decline of American Public Education)’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 379-383. Sunstein, Cass R. (1996), ‘Legislative Forward: Congress, Constitutional Moments, and the Cost-Benefit State’, 48 Stanford Law Review, 247-309. Sunstein, Cass R. (1997), Free Markets and Social Justice, New York, Oxford Press, 407 p. Supper, Meinhard (1988), ‘Das Niederösterreichische Landesrecht und die ökonomische Analyse des Rechts (The Law of the Province of Lower Austria and Economic Analysis of Law)’, in Funk, Bernd-Christian (Project Management) (ed.), Deregulierung und Entbürokratisierung am Beispiel, Vienna, Austrian Economic Publishers Company, 43-48. Turnbull, Shann (1995), ‘Best Practice in the Governance of GBEs’, in Gutrie, James (ed.), The Australian Public Sector: Pathways to Change in the 1990s, Sydney, IIR Pty. Limited, 99-109. Vickrey, William (1980), ‘The City as a Firm in Feldstein’, in M.S. and Inman, R.S. (eds), The Economics of Public Services, London, Macmillan, 334-343. Wilson, James Q. (1989), Bureaucracy: What Government Agencies Do and Why they Do It, New York, Basic Books. Wolff, Birgitta (1996), ‘Public-Private Partnerships’, in Schenk, Karl-Ernst, Schmidtchen, Dieter and Streit, Manfred E. (eds), Vom Hoheitsstaat zum Konsensualstaat, Neue Formen der Kooperation zwischen Staat und Privaten Jahrbuch für Neue Politische Ökonomie 15, Tübingen, Mohr. Zalm, G. (1982), ‘Deregulation’, 67 Economisch-Statistische Berichten, 692-696.
7000 CIVIL PROCEDURE: GENERAL Bruce H. Kobayashi and Jeffrey S. Parker Associate Professor of Law and Professor of Law George Mason University School of Law © Copyright 1999 Bruce H. Kobayashi and Jeffrey S. Parker
Abstract The economic analysis of civil litigation has focused on the action of the litigants and on the effects of substantive and procedural rules on their behavior. This chapter focuses on the economic analysis of procedural rules and how these rules alter the incentives of the litigants to file, settle and litigate disputes. Such procedural rules affect the private costs and benefits of litigation through altering the net expected value and loss faced by the plaintiff and defendant. Procedural rules also affect the social costs and benefits of litigation by affecting the both the direct and error costs of litigation. The analysis in the chapter is organized around the US Federal Rules of Civil Procedure, and in reverse chronological order to reflect the economic analyses use of backwards induction to examine civil litigation. Topics examined in depth include sequencing rules, rules that affect the capitalization of litigation over parties and claims, the rules of discovery, and juries. JEL classification: K4, K40 K41 Keywords: Civil Procedure, Civil Litigation, Settlement, Trials
1. Introduction The economic analysis of civil litigation, following upon the pioneering work of Landes (1971), Gould (1973), and Posner (1973), has proven to be a fruitful area. Economic analyses of litigation have focused both upon the actions of parties in civil litigation and upon the effects of substantive and procedural rules on the litigants’ behavior (see Cooter and Rubinfeld, 1989, for a previous survey of the field). This chapter focuses on the economic analysis of procedural rules. Papers in this field generally have examined the effects procedural rules have on error costs and the direct costs of litigation. The length of the reference list annexed to this chapter indicates the extent of academic interest in studying the economic effects of procedural rules, and the consequences of alterations to those rules. 1
2
Civil Procedure: General
7000
2. Organizing Framework The organizing framework for this chapter generally follows the US Federal Rules of Civil Procedure (FRCP). The FRCP, as supplemented by statutory and decisional standards concerning the jurisdiction of courts and the preclusive effects of judgments, regulate most aspects of the civil litigation process, from the general statement of the purpose of the rules to the particularized standards regarding process, pleadings, lawyer sanctions, discovery, the allocation of legal costs, the relationship between multiple parties (including the regulation and certification of class actions), motions, trials and judgments. Since their promulgation in 1938, the FRCP have provided generally uniform rules for the conduct of litigation in the US Federal courts, and similar rules have been adopted in a majority of American states (for a comparison of federal and state procedural rules, see Oakley and Coon, 1986). In addition, the Federal Rules have been frequently revised, and the process of rulemaking itself has become a topic for economic and legal analysis. However, we do not discuss the rules and related topics in numerical order. Rather, because the economic analysis of litigation must be forward looking, and thus proceed using backwards induction, our chapter is organized in reverse chronological order.
3. Topics Covered Topics reviewed in depth in this chapter include sequencing rules, rules that affect the capitalization of litigation over parties and claims, the rules of discovery, and juries. Related areas not addressed in detail in this chapter are treated in other chapters of this volume and earlier volumes. These areas include: other areas of civil procedure, including fee shifting (7300), the litigation/settlement decision (7400) and class actions (7600); the organization of the courts, including jurisdictional issues (7100-7200); criminal procedure (7700); the economics of crime and punishment (8000-8600); arbitration and the private enforcement of law (7500); bankruptcy proceedings (7800); legal error, rules versus standards, and accuracy in adjudication (Volume I, 790), punitive damages (Volume II, 3700), the computing of damages, including the allocations of damages via contribution and indemnity rules (Volume II, 3500); and the production of legal rules and precedent (9000-9900). In addition, issues relating to evidence and information in litigation, including the rules of discovery, attorney client privilege, and advice for litigation, are examined in a companion section on evidence (7900).
7000
Civil Procedure: General
3
4. The Economic Analysis of Procedural Rules Economic analyses of procedural rules generally have proceeded within Posner’s (1973) framework, which conceives the purpose of such rules to be the minimization of the sum of error costs and direct costs. See also Tullock (1975) and Posner (1992) for a general analysis of procedure. Consistent with this framework, Rule 1 of the FRCP directs that the rules be construed and administered to secure the just, speedy, and inexpensive determination of every action. Economic analyses of procedural rules focus on the effect such rules have on the incentives of potential and actual litigants. Thus, the economic analysis of procedural rules must begin with an economic model of litigation.
5. The Economic Model of Litigation The basic economic model of litigation has two parties, a plaintiff (p) that has a potential claim against the defendant (d). The plaintiff’s estimate of the net expected value (NEV) of the claim equals his estimate of the probability (P) that he or she will prevail (Pp) multiplied by the expected award (Dp), net of the marginal costs to the plaintiff of proceeding to the next stage of litigation (Cp). The defendant’s objective function for estimating expected loss (EL) is developed in parallel fashion, as equaling the defendant’s estimate of the probability the plaintiff will prevail (Pd) times the expected award (Dd) plus the defendant’s marginal costs of proceeding to the next stage of litigation (Cd). In the more developed models, several of the variables may be endogenously determined. For example, both litigants’ selections of C may affect their estimates of the outcome, and one litigant’s choice of C may affect the other litigant’s estimate of its own cost of proceeding to the next stage. Most analyses use sequencing models, for which the definition of marginal cost given in the text is the most general case. In the most basic models, this cost is conceptualized as the marginal cost of ‘trial’ over ‘settlement’, though obviously it can be generalized to any of the multiple stages of litigation, and can refer to cooperative, decisional, or unilateral withdrawal outcomes, as developed by Cornell (1990). In processes without discrete formal stages, such as the American discovery process and some Continental trial processes, the most general case will be continuous updating of NEV and EL as each new item of information (for example, each witness or investigation) becomes available. In addition, the litigants can be influenced by effects external to the current litigation - for example, by the precedential or preclusive effects of the judgment in the current litigation on future litigation. In such cases, a current plaintiff’s judgment will produce an external gain to the plaintiff (Gp) while the
4
Civil Procedure: General
7000
defendant will suffer external loss (Ld). Likewise, a defendant’s judgment will produce external gain (Gd) while the plaintiff will suffer an external loss (Lp). The NEV and EL are the primary determinants of the incentives given to litigants in the economic model, including the amount of effort expended during litigation, the trial/settlement decision, the decision to file a suit, and the decision to avoid behavior that would give rise to legal liability. Because procedural rules alter the NEV and EL, these rules will have a central role in determining litigation incentives and outcomes. Because decisions made at earlier stages of litigation are dependent upon the parties’ expectations of the outcomes (and their own and opposing parties’ decisions) during later stages of the litigation, economic analysis begins from the last stage of trial and judgment, and proceeds by backward induction. Thus, we list and discuss topics in reverse chronological order.
6. Trial Courts The last stage of a civil litigation in the court of first instance is the trial and judgment (Cooter and Rubinfeld, 1990). This discussion suppresses the possibility of appellate review, which in the US federal system is governed by a separate set of Federal Rules of Appellate Procedure. Appellate review in the United States is concerned primarily with the correction of legal error and secondarily with factual error. For a discussion of the economic analysis of those topics, see Volume I, Chapter 0790 in this volume.
7. The Choice Between Judge and Jury Trials Trials and judgments are governed by Sections VI and VII of the FRCP (Rules 38-63). Subject to certain motions for the court to set aside the verdict (Rule 50) or order a new trial (Rule 59), judgment is entered as given by the factual findings and legal conclusions of a judge (see Rule 52) or the verdict of a jury (Rule 58). The federal rules allow any party to demand a trial by jury of any issue triable as a matter of federal constitutional right by a jury (Rule 38). Although most American states also provide by state law or constitution for a right to trial by jury in some or all cases, the state courts generally are not bound by the federal constitutional right to jury trial, except in certain cases where they are adjudicating federal claims for which federal law requires a right to jury trial. Rule 39 allows the parties in these cases also to have a trial by the court, by joint consent. Gay, et al. (1989) examine the choice between judge and jury under the assumption that juries are ‘noisier’ adjudicators than judges. Clermont and Eisenberg (1992) examine empirically whether the choice
7000
Civil Procedure: General
5
of judge versus jury produces differing verdicts in product liability cases tried under state law, finding that - contrary to the popular belief - judges, not juries, are more generous to plaintiffs. Further, they do not find that these results are explained by selection bias. In addition to explicit choices by the parties, several of the Rules allow the judge to exercise certain powers even when the case is tried by jury. Rule 49 allows the court to require a jury to return a special verdict, which involves explicit findings upon each of several elements of the claim at issue rather than allowing the jury to return the more common general verdict (see Lombadero, 1996; James, Hazard and Leubsdorf, 1992, p. 377). Rule 50 provides for judgment as a matter of law, which can be used by the judge to preempt or overrule a jury upon the determination that, after being fully heard, there is no legally sufficient basis for a reasonable jury to find for a party on an issue (see McLauchlan, 1973). Rule 56 provides for an equivalent ruling in the pretrial stage by summary judgment, on the basis of pretrial discovery material and written submissions by the parties (see McLauchlan, 1977), and Rule 12 permits a judgment as a matter of law at the earlier pleading stage, in cases where the plaintiff’s claim is legally deficient on its face.
8. Jury Structure and Decision Rule The rules also regulate the size and decision rule used by civil juries, as well as the process through which jurors are selected. Rule 48 specifies that, unless the parties otherwise stipulate, a civil jury shall be not fewer than six nor more than twelve, and that the verdict shall be unanimous. Economic analyses of jury decision making include an examination of how juries process information (Klevorick, Rothschild and Winship, 1984; Froeb and Kobayashi, 1996), and the effect of jury size and alternative decision rules (Klevorick and Rothschild, 1979). Finally, Rule 47 (as supplemented by federal statutes) controls the selection of jurors, including the procedures for examination of jurors during the selection process, and the use of peremptory challenges (see, for example, Schwartz and Schwartz, 1996).
9. Litigation Expenditures A separate literature has bypassed explicit consideration of the jury versus judge decision-making process by modeling the outcome of a trial as being determined by the litigants’ expenditures on litigation. The most common model of litigation expenditures is where the both litigants expend resources to alter the probability of prevailing (see Posner, 1973; Goodman, 1978; Tullock,
6
Civil Procedure: General
7000
1980; Wittman, 1988; Katz, 1988; Hay, 1995; Kobayashi and Lott, 1996). That is, in these models, the marginal cost of future litigation stages Cp and Cd (usually conceptualized as ‘trial versus settlement’) are endogenous choice variables that determine the probability that the plaintiff will prevail P(Cp,Cd). The equilibrium amounts of litigation expenditures depend upon the relative stakes of the parties, and upon the relative merits of the case. The litigation expenditures and probability determined by solving for the Nash equilibria are used as the expected values for earlier stages of litigation. Other articles have examined the relationship between the burden of evidence or decision standard and litigation expenditures. In these models, litigation expenditures that allow a litigant to meet the burden of proof or decision standard serve as a costly signal of liability (see, for example, Rubinfeld and Sappington, 1987).
10. The Trial/Settlement Decision The major decision preceding commencement of a trial is the decision whether to settle the case or proceed to trial. The relative magnitudes of the plaintiff’s NEV and the defendant’s EL are the primary determinants of whether a case settles or whether trial occurs. As noted above, this modeling can be generalized to any stage preceding a decision by the court, or a further commitment to incur litigation expense. Under risk neutrality, the NEV sets the plaintiff’s minimum acceptable settlement offer and the EL the defendant’s maximum settlement bid. In the absence of lawyer-client agency costs, a sufficient (but not necessary) condition for litigation is the perceived absence of a bargaining range, which occurs when the plaintiff’s minimum acceptable offer is greater than the defendant’s maximum bid, that is, NEV > EL, or equivalently: Pp(Dp + Gp + Lp) ! Pd(Dd + Ld +Gd) + Gd ! Lp > Cp + Cd
( 1 ) The above condition identifies two reasons why parties choose to forego settlement and proceed to trial. The first is based on prediction failure. The second is based on consideration of external effects, specifically precedential or preclusive effects of the current litigation on future litigation.
7000
Civil Procedure: General
7
A. The Optimism Model 11. The Prediction Failure Model Under the simplifying assumptions that the litigants have symmetric stakes (Dp = Dd = D) and that there are no external effects (Ld = Lp = Gd = Gp = 0), the condition for trial rather than settlement reduces to the following expression: (Pp ! Pd)D > Cp + Cd (2) This condition illustrates the optimism model of litigation. In such a model, settlement fails to occur because of prediction failure - that is, settlement fails because the parties have mutually inconsistent and relatively optimistic estimates of the probability that the plaintiff will prevail (that is, Pp > Pd). The litigants’ erroneous predictions lead them to behave as if there were no room for a mutually beneficial settlement.
12. The Priest-Klein Selection Model Economists also have modeled the process through which such mutually inconsistent and optimistic predictions are generated. The Priest and Klein (1984) model of case selection is based on the optimism model, and has two major hypotheses. The first and more general hypothesis is that the cases selected for trial are not representative of the population of disputes. Specifically, under the assumptions of symmetric stakes and specific distributional assumptions about the litigants’ estimates of P (specifically that each litigant’s estimate of P is an independent draw from a unimodal distribution centered around the true P), the basic Priest-Klein model predicts that a disproportionate number of cases selected for trial will come from cases that are close to the decision standard. The second hypothesis is a specific prediction for observed case outcomes in the limiting case where the litigants accurately estimate P. Priest and Klein show that under these circumstances the distribution of filed cases around the decision standard becomes approximately symmetric, and the generated plaintiff win rate approximately equals 50 percent. A large number of articles have examined the limiting prediction of a 50 percent win rate, and have presented evidence where the win rate differs from 50 percent. See, for example, Priest (1985), Wittman (1985), Ramsayer and Nakazato (1989), Eisenberg (1990), Hylton (1993), Thomas (1995), Waldfogel (1995), Shavell (1996). See Kessler, Meites and Miller (1996) and Kobayashi (1996) for recent surveys of the literature. While generally rejecting the specific fifty percent hypothesis, this evidence may simply reflect the fact that the
8
Civil Procedure: General
7000
assumptions underlying the limiting case do not hold. Further, empirical studies examining the more general predictions of the Priest-Klein model have found evidence consistent with model (see Kobayashi, 1996).
13. Settlement Failure and Discovery Because the prediction failure model predicts settlement failure because litigants lack information at the time of the final trial/settlement decision, it suggests procedural reforms aimed at increasing pre-trial information. The management of pre-trial information is addressed in Section V of the FRCP (Rules 26-37). The primary rule is Rule 26, which contains the general provisions governing civil discovery. Under Rule 26, litigants are required to respond to requests for information by the adverse party, on the theory that such requests and responses would increase pre-trial information and increase settlement and accuracy in adjudication. However, economic models of discovery have pointed out several problems with the rules. First, the rules shift the costs of gathering information from the requesting to the responding party, and thereby introduce both a potential moral-hazard problem and strategic behavior into the demand for pretrial discovery. Because the costs of responding to a discovery request are, in many cases, larger that the cost of making a request, this externalization predicts that parties will request information well past the point where the marginal value of information outweighs the marginal costs of gathering the information. In addition, the process of discovery can decrease, rather than increase, settlement by making parties more optimistic (see Cooter and Rubinfeld, 1994). Finally, discovery can potentially decrease the amount of information in litigation by providing disincentives for the production and retention of information that might be subject to extensive legal discovery (see Kobayashi, Parker and Ribstein, 1996; see also Hay, 1994 and Sobel, 1989).
14. Amendments to the Discovery Rules The perceived problems of ‘overdiscovery’ predicted by the economic model of litigation have been addressed in several amendments to the discovery rules. In 1983, Rule 26(b) was amended to embody an explicit cost-benefit test that could be applied by the judge to limit discovery. At that same time FRCP 16 was amended to expand the judge’s power to manage the pretrial process in general. However, the economic model suggests that these managerial solutions may be inferior to forcing each litigant to internalize the costs of its own information requests, or at least to pay for the marginal cost of extensive discovery requests (Cooter and Rubinfeld, 1994).
7000
Civil Procedure: General
9
In 1993, Rule 26 was further amended, again in response to concerns regarding litigants’ overinvestment in discovery activity. However, the major change to the rules was to institute a regime of initial disclosures to be made without any request for information from the adverse party (see FRCP Rule 26a; Brazil, 1978; Schwarzer, 1989; Cooter and Rubinfeld, 1995). Applying the economic model, this change is likely to make matters worse. To the extent that cost-shifting is the source of ‘discovery abuse’, these rules exacerbate the problem by allowing the requesting party to externalize the costs of both requesting and responding to requests for information. This effect is magnified by abandonment of code pleading in favor of the broad notice pleading rules contained in the FRCP (Section III, Rules 7-15; see Epstein, 1973a, 1973b, 1974, 1986; Posner, 1973; Katz, 1990; Bone, 1997). Further, to the extent that this rule moves the costs of pretrial discovery into an earlier phase of the litigation, this may have the effect of increasing total costs, and decreasing the marginal costs of trial over settlement. The 1993 amendment was subject to a local option in US federal districts, which has reduced some of the effects of the rule change. Empirical analysis has shown that the busiest federal districts have opted out of the new rule (Kobayashi, Parker and Ribstein, 1996).
B. The External Effects Model 15. External Effects Relative optimism is not the only way in which to generate the absence of a perceived bargaining range. The existence of external effects can cause litigation to occur even if the parties to the litigation agree on the likely outcome of the case. Examples of external effects include the precedential and preclusive effect of litigation, both of which serve to affect litigants’ prospects in future cases (see Galanter, 1974; Rubin, 1977; Che and Yi, 1993 and Kobayashi, 1996; see also Landes and Posner, 1979; Blume and Rubinfeld, 1982; Priest, 1987, 1980; Cooter, 1987; Galanter, 1987). For a more complete discussion of precedent and legal change, see Chapters (9000-9900) of this volume. To illustrate this point, consider the case with symmetric stakes and where the litigants agree on the probability the plaintiff will prevail, that is, Pp = Pd = P. According to the simple optimism model, such a case will settle in order to save the costs of a trial. However, even under these assumptions, litigation may be generated if the current case has implications for future behavior of the litigants involved. The NEV of the lawsuit to the plaintiff equals P(D +Gp) !(1 ! P)Lp ! Cp, and the defendant’s EL = P(D+Ld) !(1 ! P)Gd + Cd. The condition for litigation NEV > EL becomes:
10
Civil Procedure: General
P(Gp ! Ld) + (1 ! P)(Gd ! Lp) > Cd + Cp
7000
(3)
Condition (3) shows that, even when the prospective outcome of a trial is agreed upon by the parties, trials can be generated when the external gains to the winning litigant outweigh the external losses to the losing litigant. In contrast to the sources of trial in the prediction failure and settlement failure models (where information costs prevent litigants from achieving a settlement within an existing bargaining range), external effects cause trials by preventing the existence of a bargaining range due to asymmetries in external effects. Because no mutually beneficial bargain is foregone, these trials are not a failure. In fact, the existence of external effects focuses on the positive and valuable rulemaking function of trials.
16. External Effects and Procedural Rules The model of trial based on external effects also suggests the relevance of a different set of procedural rules - one that focuses on the effects of litigation on future claims and third parties. The FRCP addresses the packaging of claims and parties generally in Rules 13-14 and 17-25. These rules serve as inclusive packaging devices, which operate by giving litigants incentives and opportunities to join parties and claims in order to internalize external effects and to achieve economies of scale in litigation. They include the permissive joinder rules (Rule 18-20), impleader (Rule 14), interpleader (Rule 22), intervention (Rule 24), the rule governing counterclaims (Rule 13), and the rule governing class actions (Rule 23). For an economic analysis of counterclaims, see Landes (1994). For a discussion of various aspects of class actions, see Dam (1975), Rosenfeld (1976), Bernstein (1978), Friedman (1996), and Chapter 7600 of this volume.
17. Common Law Packaging Rules A second major category of packaging rules include the common law rules of precedent, or stare decisis, and the rules of preclusion, or the law of res judicata. The common law rules of res judicata include the doctrines of claim preclusion (also known as merger and bar) and issue preclusion (also known as collateral estoppel). Under the rule of claim preclusion, parties or their privies (that is, predecessors or successors in interest) are precluded from relitigating issues that were or could have been raised in the first action (see, for example, Kobayashi, 1996; Landes and Posner, 1994). Claim preclusion prevents the splitting of claims based on the same out-of-court transaction, thus functioning as mandatory joinder-of-claims rules by their prospective effect on
7000
Civil Procedure: General
11
future litigation. In contrast, issue preclusion (collateral estoppel) is limited to issues that were actually litigated, actually decided, and necessary to the judgment in the first case. In addition, while application of claim preclusion is generally limited symmetrically to persons who were either parties or successors to parties on both sides of the initial litigation, collateral estoppel can operate non-symmetrically, or, as it is termed in legal doctrine, non-mutually, in the sense that collateral estoppel can operate in favor of strangers to the first action, but can operate against only parties or their successors (see Spurr, 1991; Hay, 1993). The existence of non-party preclusion has led to the attempted use of settlement conditioned on vacatur (the eradication of a prior public decision) as a means to eliminate the effect of preclusion (see Fisch, 1991).
18. Offensive Non-Mutual Collateral Estoppel To see the effect of the application of non-mutual collateral estoppel, consider the case where a single defendant faces two different plaintiffs sequentially. Suppose for simplicity that both cases turn on a single issue that determines the outcome. First consider offensive collateral estoppel. If the first plaintiff prevails against the defendant, the defendant is precluded from relitigating the decisive issue against the second plaintiff. Thus, a loss in the first case results in the loss of both cases, and the external effect Ld = (1 ! P)D. In contrast, a win by the defendant against the first plaintiff does not preclude the second plaintiff from relitigating the issue, if the second plaintiff is neither a party nor a privy to the first action. Thus, the only effect on the second litigation would be the precedential gain Gd = (dP D), where dP equals the change in P in the second litigation. If there are no novel issues of law, this gain is likely to be close to zero. And under the assumption that the plaintiffs are not repeat litigants, Lp = Gp = 0. Substituting into the condition for litigation (equation (3)) yields: (1 ! P)D(dP ! P) > Cd + Cp (4) If the precedential change dP is close to zero, condition (4) is unlikely to be satisfied. Thus, there will be little incentive to take such cases to trial. This incentive for settlement has led some to object to offensive non-mutual collateral estoppel on the grounds that such a rule will allow plaintiffs to repeatedly extract large settlements from a common defendant. However, the total effect on settlement amounts from such a rule is unclear (see Hay, 1993). First, the effect of estoppel causes the repeat litigant to capitalize all future litigation into the first litigation. This increase in the stakes causes the repeat litigant to spend a larger amount of resources when he goes to trial. This has
12
Civil Procedure: General
7000
the effect of lowering P, thus moving the bottom of the bargaining range downward. Further, the repeat litigant is likely to take a harder bargaining stance in the first litigation by anticipating its effects on future litigation.
19. Defensive Non-Mutual Collateral Estoppel In contrast, consider the use of defensive non-mutual collateral estoppel with multiple plaintiffs. Again, assume that Lp = Gp = 0. Now Ld = dP D and Gd = PD. Substitution into the condition for litigation (equation (3)) yields: PD ((1 ! P) ! dP) > Cd + Cp (5) In contrast to the rule of offensive non-mutual collateral estoppel with multiple plaintiffs, such a rule increases the likelihood of litigation. In addition, use of such a rule would apply preclusion against a non-party that was represented by a party in the first litigation with low relative stakes, which may increase legal error and increase the amount of litigation (see Spurr, 1991). Thus, the court’s rejection of the latter rule because of due process concerns is consistent with the predictions of economic analysis.
C. The Bargaining Failure Model and Asymmetric Information 20. Bargaining Failure Even within the basic optimism model of litigation, condition (2) is not a necessary condition for litigation. Even if a positive bargaining range is perceived to exist, the parties may fail to settle due to bargaining failure (see, for example, Cooter, Marks and Mnookin, 1982; Gross and Syverud, 1991; Shavell, 1993) or due to the existence of asymmetric information (see, for example, P’ng, 1983, 1987; Bebchuk, 1984; Schweizer, 1989; Spier, 1992, 1994b; Daughety and Reinganum, 1993; Froeb, 1993; Wang, Kim and Yi, 1994). In the former case the litigants fail to agree on a specific bargain even if both litigants agree that a positive bargaining range exists. In the latter case, trials are a necessary cost of avoiding adverse selection problems. In both of these cases, the potential for costly trials represents a calculated cost of strategic behavior aimed at obtaining a better expected settlement.
7000
Civil Procedure: General
13
21. Bargaining Failure and Procedural Rules The existence of asymmetric information in litigation again points to the discovery rules (see the discussion in Part B, above). In addition, economists have examined procedural rules that would increase the incentives for settlement. Under FRCP Rule 68, the defendant can make an offer of judgment. If this offer is not accepted by the plaintiff, and the subsequent judgment is less favorable to the plaintiff, the plaintiff is responsible for the defendant’s costs after making the offer (see Miller, 1986; Anderson, 1994; Anderson and Rowe, 1996; Chung, 1996). However, liberal and early use of Rule 68 is limited by the requirement that the defendant offer not merely settlement but judgment, which can have a preclusive effect in subsequent litigation. Further, under the current rules, it does not allow the plaintiff to recover marginal fees (although many statutes provide for one way fee recovery by plaintiffs). In addition, economists have analyzed contractual settlement devices such as settlement escrows (see, for example, Gertner and Miller, 1995), and the use of mediation and arbitration techniques (see Shavell, 1995).
D. Lawyer-Client and Client-Client Agency Costs 22. Lawyer-Client Agency Costs Finally, trials can be generated due to agency costs between lawyer and client and by agency problems between co-interested clients. A large literature has modeled the consequence of attorney compensation arrangements that give rise to the agency problems in settlement (see, for example, Miller, 1987). Articles examining the incentive effects of contingent fees include, Clermont and Currivan, 1978; Danzon (1983); Lynk (1990, 1994); Miceli and Segerson (1991); Thomason (1991); Dana and Spier (1993); Rubinfeld and Scotchmer (1993); Miceli (1994); Watts (1994); Hay (1996, 1997). Potential solutions to such problems include enforcement of ethical rules or the use of reputational mechanisms (see Gilson and Mnookin, 1984; Smith and Cox, 1985; Yang, 1996).
23. Contribution, Indemnity and Agreements with Multiple Defendants Similarly, litigation and settlement are affected by the rules which allocate liability among multiple defendants. These include the rules of contribution and indemnity (see Easterbrook, Landes, and Posner, 1980; Landes and Posner, 1980; Hause, 1989; Kornhauser and Revesz, 1989, 1990, 1994; Klerman, 1996) and agreements between plaintiffs and defendants (see Bernstein and Klerman,
14
Civil Procedure: General
7000
1995).
E. Effect of the Decision to File a Suit and the Decision to Avoid a Lawsuit 24. Incentives to Avoid Litigation Finally, the NEV and the EL provide incentives during the earlier stages of litigation. The EL, discounted by the probability that a suit will be filed and by the likelihood of settlement, provides deterrence of and incentives for avoidance of behavior subject to legal liability (Polinsky and Rubinfeld, 1988a, 1988b; Cooter and Rubinfeld, 1989; see also Ordover, 1978, 1981, and Hylton, 1990).
25. The Decision to File a Lawsuit Similarly, the NEV of a lawsuit is a primary determinant of whether or not a plaintiff chooses to file a suit. While many analyses of litigation limit their examination of legal claims to those whose NEV is positive, this is not a necessary condition for a suit to be filed. Negative NEV suits may also be filed in order to extract a settlement, and such strategies can be successful when the threat to litigate is credible (see Rosenberg and Shavell, 1985; Nalebuff, 1987; Bebchuk, 1988, 1996; Katz, 1990; Klein, 1990; Miceli, 1993; and Bone, 1997). For general analyses of the relationship between the cost of litigation and private and social incentive to bring a suit, see Schwartz and Tullock (1975); Priest (1982); Shavell (1982b); Menell (1983); Trubek, et al. (1983), Kaplow (1986); Rose-Ackerman and Geistfeld (1987); Hazard (1989); Williams and Williams (1994).
26. The Role of Sequencing of and Exit from Litigation Perhaps one of the most salient features of the FRCP, and one that has been only recently addressed by the economics literature, is the effect of the rules on the timing and sequencing of litigation. While many economic models treat litigation as a timeless decision, the procedural rules lay out a sequence of events that determine how litigation will proceed over time. The timing and sequence of litigation has been shown to have important implications for the NEV of a lawsuit and the behavior of litigants. For example, the ability of litigants to sequentially litigate motions or to separate liability and damage phases of trials have been shown to affect both the cost of litigation and the value of the litigation if litigants are allowed to
7000
Civil Procedure: General
15
exit. Sequencing with easy exit increases the ‘option’ value of litigation by allowing plaintiffs to avoid conditional negative NEV outcomes by exiting the litigation (see Cornell, 1990; Landes, 1993; Chen, Chien and Chu, 1997). In addition, the ability to take motions sequentially can affect the credibility of negative expected value suits (Bebchuk, 1996). Under the FRCP, exit is controlled by Rule 41. Under Rule 41, the plaintiff can unilaterally dismiss an action without order of the court at any time before the adverse party answers. After this, dismissal requires mutual stipulation by all parties, or an order of the court. The application of Rule 41 is a prime example of the tension between the ex ante and ex post effects of procedural rules. Ex post, it is unlikely that a defendant will prevent a plaintiff from abandoning a claim. However, the willingness of the court or the adverse party to allow the plaintiff to easily exit the litigation may be the primary reason the suit was filed in the first place.
27. Lawyer Sanctions The FRCP address this inability to commit through Rule 11, which allows the court to impose sanctions on parties and their attorneys for filing frivolous suits. This rule addresses the commitment problem by allowing the motion for sanctions to survive the dismissal or mooting or the original claim. Thus, Rule 11 allows the motion for sanction to survive as separate action with the sanctions as the incentive to litigate. Economic analyses of sanctions under Rule 11 include Kobayashi and Parker (1993); Polinsky and Rubinfeld (1993); Bebchuk and Chang (1996); and Bone (1997). However, recent amendments to Rule 11 may have reduced the value of Rule 11 as a commitment device. In the 1993 Amendments to the FRCP, the rules were amended to allow the a litigant twenty-one days to withdraw his pleading upon being served with a Rule 11 motion by the adverse litigant. In essence, the new rules allows for free exit, and thus weaken the commitment and deterrent effect of the rules. While the amendments to Rule 11 were designed in large part to decrease the volume of ‘satellite’ litigation over alleged Rule 11 violations, the effect of the rule change may be to increase the number of filed cases, the rate of Rule 11 challenges, and total litigation costs (Kobayashi and Parker, 1993).
16
Civil Procedure: General
7000
28. Fee Shifting Economists have also examined the use of two-way fee shifting (often referred to in America as the ‘English’ rule, in contrast with the general ‘American’ rule that each party bears its own fees, regardless of outcome) to deter low or negative value lawsuits. Because two-way fee shifting imposes extra costs on the losing party, it disproportionately affects low probability lawsuits (see Shavell, 1982a). However, the FRCP has not incorporated two-way shifting of fees and costs, and state experiments have not proven successful or long lived (see Snyder and Hughes, 1990; Hughes and Snyder, 1995). In addition, almost all fee-shifting statutes require the imposition of a judgment. Thus, the use of fee shifting would not necessarily reduce the option value of litigation. That is, if exit is routinely allowed prior to judgment, fee shifting will not serve as a deterrent. Indeed, to the extent that two-way fee shifting would increase the variance in final outcomes, use of such a system would increase the option value of litigation, and thereby increase the supply of filed cases (Cornell, 1990). For a more complete discussion of fee shifting, see Chapter 7300 of this volume. See also, Dewees, Prichard and Trebilcock (1981); Braeutigam, Owen and Panzar (1984); Reinganum and Wilde (1986); Bowles (1987); Katz (1987); Plott (1987); Donohue (1991); Graville (1993); Spier (1994a), and Katz and Beckner (1995).
F. Procedural Rulemaking 29. The Process of Procedural Rulemaking Finally, both the process of procedural rulemaking and the adversarial system itself have been the subject of economic analyses. Indeed, the controversy over the relative merits of party-controlled adversarial presentation and a more ‘managerial’ system of litigation was at the heart of the controversial amendments to the discovery rules, and has been the subject of debate in the academic literature (see McChesney, 1979; Tullock, 1980, 1988; Langbein, 1985). For a recent report of experimental results, see Block and Parker (1996). For a public choice treatment of the common law of procedural rules, see Macey (1994). The controversy over the recent amendments to Rule 11 and 26a have drawn attention to the process through which the rules are revised (see Kobayashi and Parker, 1993; Kobayashi, 1996), and have highlighted the lack of empirical evidence on the performance of procedural rules and systems (see, for example, Galanter, 1983; Walker, 1994). Indeed, the amendment to Rule 26a, which allows individual district courts to opt-out of the discovery rules, the Civil Justice Reform Act of 1990, which encouraged local variations in each
7000
Civil Procedure: General
17
district, and variation in local Federal Court rules and state court rules all provide substantial challenges to the traditional centralized system of rule making that existed in the federal system prior to 1990 (see Kobayashi, Parker and Ribstein, 1996; Solimine and Pacheco, 1997; and Subrin, 1989).
Bibliography on Civil Procedure: General (7000) Anderson, David A. (1994), ‘Improving Settlement Devices: Rule 68 and Beyond’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 225-246. Anderson, David A., and Rowe, Thomas D. (1996), ‘Empirical Evidence on Settlement Devices: Does Rule 68 Increase Settlement?’, 71 Chicago-Kent Law Review, 519-545. Bebchuk, Lucian A. (1984), ‘Litigation and Settlement Under Imperfect Information’, 15 RAND Journal of Economics, 404-415. Bebchuk, Lucian A. (1988), ‘Suing Solely to Extract a Settlement Offer’, 17 Journal of Legal Studies, 437-450. Bebchuk, Lucian A.(1996), ‘A New Theory Concerning the Credibility and Success of Threats to Sue’, 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-26. Bebchuk, Lucian A. and Chang, Howard F. (1996), ‘An Analysis of Fee Shifting Based on the Margin of Victory: On Frivolous Suits, Meritorious Suits, and the Role of Rule 11', 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 371-404. Bernstein, Lisa and Klerman, Daniel (1995), ‘An Economic Analysis of Mary Carter Settlement Agreements’, 83 Georgetown Law Journal, 2215-2270. Bernstein, Roger (1978), ‘Judicial Economy and Class Actions’, 7 Journal of Legal Studies, 349-370. Block, Michael, and Parker, Jeffrey S. (1996), ‘Some Experimental Evidence of the Efficiency of the Adversarial System’, mimeo, George Mason University School of Law. Blume, Lawerence E. and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1982), ‘The Dynamics of the Legal Process’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 405-419. Bone, Robert G. (1997), ‘Modeling Frivolous Suits’, 145 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 519-605. Bowles, Roger A. (1987), ‘Settlement Range and Cost Allocation Rules’, 3 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 177-184. Braeutigam, Ronald, Owen, Bruce and Panzar, John (1984), ‘An Economic Analysis of Alternative Fee Shifting Systems’, 47 Law and Contemporary Problems, 173-185. Brazil, Wayne D. (1978), ‘The Adversary Character of Civil Discovery: A Critique and Proposals for Change’, 31 Vanderbilt Law Review, 1295-1361. Che, Yeon-Koo and Yi, Jong Goo (1993), ‘The Role of Precedents in Repeated Litigation’, 12 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 399-424. Chen, Kong-Pin, Chien, Hung-Ken, and Chu, C.Y. Cyrus (1997), ‘Sequential versus Unitary Trials with Asymmetric Information’, 26 Journal of Legal Studies, 239-258. Chung, Tai-Yeong (1996), ‘Settlement of Litigation under Rule 68: An Economic Analysis’, 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 261-286. Clermont, Kevin M. and Currivan, John D. (1978), ‘Improving the Contingent Fee’, 63 Cornell Law Review, 529-599. Clermont, Kevin M. and Eisenberg, Theodore (1992), ‘Trial by Jury or Judge: Transcending
18
Civil Procedure: General
7000
Empiricism’, 77 Cornell Law Review, 1124-1187. Cooter, Robert D. (1987), ‘Why Litigants Disagree: A Comment on George Priest’s “Measuring Legal Change”’, 3 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 227-234. Cooter, Robert D. and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1989), ‘Economic Analysis of Legal Disputes and Their Resolution’, 27 Journal of Economic Literature, 1067-1097; reprinted in Richard A. Posner and Francesco Parisi (eds) (1996), Law and Economics, Edward Elgar. Cooter, Robert D. and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1990), ‘Trial Courts: An Economic Perspective’ 24 Law and Society Review, 533-548. Cooter, Robert D. and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1994), ‘An Economic Model of Legal Discovery’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 435-463. Cooter, Robert D. and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1995), ‘Reforming to New Discovery Rules’, 84 Georgetown Law Journal, 61-89. Cooter, Robert D., Marks, Stephen and Mnookin, Robert (1982), ‘Bargaining in the Shadow of the Law: A Testable Model of Strategic Behavior’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 225-251. Cornell, Bradford (1990), ‘The Incentive to Sue: An Option Pricing Approach’ 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 173-187. Dam, Kenneth W. (1975), ‘Class Actions: Efficiency, Compensation, Deterrence, and Conflict of Interest’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 47-73. Dana, James D., and Spier, Kathryn E. (1993), ‘Expertise and Contingent Fees: The Role of Asymmetric Information in Attorney Compensation’, 9 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 349-367. Danzon, Patricia M. (1983), ‘Contingency Fees for Person Injury Litigation’, 14 Bell Journal of Economics, 213-224. Danzon, Patricia, M. and Lillard, Lee (1983), ‘Settlement Out of Court: The Disposition of Medical Malpractice Claims’, 12 Journal of Legal Studies, 345-377. Daughety, Andrew F. and Reinganum, Jennifer F. (1993), ‘Endogenous Sequencing in Models of Settlement and Litigation’, 9 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 314-348. Dewees, Donald N., Prichard, J. Robert S. and Trebilcock, Michael J. (1981), ‘An Economics Analysis of Cost and Fee Rules for Class Actions’, 10 Journal of Legal Studies, 155-185. Donohue, III, John J. (1991), ‘The Effects of Fee Shifting on the Settlement Rate: Theoretical Observations on Costs, Conflicts and Contingency Fees’, 54 Law and Contemporary Problems, 195-222. Easterbrook, Frank H., Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1980), ‘Contribution among Antitrust Defendants: A Legal and Economic Analysis’, 23 Journal of Law and Economics, 331-370. Eisenberg, Theodore (1990), ‘Testing the Selection Effect: A New Theoretical Framework with Empirical Tests’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 337-358. Epstein, Richard A. (1973a), ‘A Theory of Strict Liability’, 2 Journal of Legal Studies, 151-204. Epstein, Richard A. (1973b), ‘Pleadings and Presumptions’, 40 University of Chicago Law Review, 556-582. Epstein, Richard A. (1974), ‘Defenses and Subsequent Pleas in a System of Strict Liability’, 3 Journal of Legal Studies, 165-216. Epstein, Richard A. (1986), ‘The Temporal Dimension in Tort Law’, 53 University of Chicago Law Review, 1175-1218. Fisch, Jill E.(1991), ‘Rewriting History: The Propriety of Eradicating Prior Decisional Law Through
7000
Civil Procedure: General
19
Settlement Conditioned on Vacatur’, 76 Cornell Law Review, 589-642. Friedman, David D. (1996), ‘More Justice for Less Money’, 39 Journal of Law and Economics, 211-240. Froeb, Luke M. (1993), ‘The Adverse Selection of Cases for Trial’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 317-324. Froeb, Luke M. and Kobayashi, Bruce H. (1996), ‘Naive, Biased, Yet Bayesian: Can Juries Interpret Selectively Produced Evidence?’, 12 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 257-276. Galanter, Marc (1974), ‘Why the “Haves” Come Out Ahead: Speculations on the Limits of Legal Change’, 9 Law and Society Review, 95-160. Galanter, Marc (1983), ‘Reading the Landscape of Disputes: What We Know and Don’t Know (And Think We Know) About our Allegedly Contentious and Litigious Society’, 31 UCLA Law Review, 4-71. Galanter, Marc (1987), ‘Conceptualizing Legal Change and its Effects: A Comment on George Priest’s ‘Measuring Legal Change’‘, 3 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 235-242. Gay, Gerald D., Grace, Martin F., Kale, Jayrant R. and Noe, Thomas H.(1989), ‘Noisy Juries and the Choice of Trial Mode in a Sequential Signalling Game: Theory and Evidence’, 20 RAND Journal of Economics, 196-213. Gertner, Robert H. and Miller, Geoffrey P. (1995), ‘Settlement Escrows’, 24 Journal of Legal Studies, 87-122. Gilson, Ronald and Mnookin, R. (1984), ‘Disputing through Agents: Cooperation and Conflict Between Lawyers in Litigation’, 94 Columbia Law Review, 509-566. Goodman, John C. (1978), ‘An Economic Theory of the Evolution of the Common Law’, 7 Journal of Legal Studies, 393-406. Gould, John P. (1973), ‘The Economics of Legal Conflicts’, 2 Journal of Legal Studies, 279-300. Graville, H.S.E. (1993), ‘The Efficiency Implications of Cost Shifting Rules’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-18. Gross, Samuel R. (1987), ‘The American Advantage: The Value of Inefficient Litigation’,85 Michigan Law Review, 734-757. Gross, Samuel R. and Syverud, K.D. (1991), ‘Getting to No: A Study of Settlement Negotiations and the Selections of Cases for Trial’, 90 Michigan Law Review, 319-393. Hause, J.C. (1989), ‘Indemnity, Settlement, and Litigation, or I’ll be Suing You’, 18 Journal of Legal Studies, 157-179. Hay, Bruce L. (1993), ‘Some Settlement Effects of Preclusion’, 1993 University of Illinois Law Review, 21-51. Hay, Bruce L. (1994), ‘Civil Discovery: Its Effects and Optimal Scope’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 481-515. Hay, Bruce L. (1995), ‘Effort, Information, Settlement, Trial’, 24 Journal of Legal Studies, 29-62. Hay, Bruce L. (1996), ‘Contingent Fees and Agency Costs’, 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 503-533. Hay, Bruce L. (1997), ‘Optimal Contingent Fees in a World of Settlement’, 26 Journal of Legal Studies, 259-278. Hazard, Geoffrey C., Jr (1989), ‘Authority in the Dock’, 69 Boston University Law Review, 469-476. Hughes, James W. and Snyder, Edward A. (1995), ‘Litigation and Settlement under the English and
20
Civil Procedure: General
7000
American Rules: Theory and Evidence’, 38 Journal of Law and Economics, 225-250. Hylton, Keith N. (1990), ‘The Influence of Litigation Costs on Deterrence under Strict Liability and under Negligence’, 10 International Review of Law and Economics, 161-171. Hylton, Keith N. (1993), ‘Asymmetric Information and the Selection of Cases for Litigation’, 22 Journal of Legal Studies, 187-210. James, Fleming, Hazard, Geoffrey C. and Leubsdorf, J. (1992), Civil Procedure, Boston, Little Brown. Kaplow, Louis (1986), ‘Private versus Social Costs in Bringing Suit’, 15 Journal of Legal Studies, 371-385. Katz, Avery (1987), ‘Measuring the Demand for Litigation: Is the English Rule Really Cheaper?’ 3 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 143-176. Katz, Avery (1988), ‘Judicial Decisionmaking and Litigation Expenditure’, 8 International Review of Law and Economics, 127-143. Katz, Avery (1990), ‘The Effect of Frivolous Lawsuits on the Settlement of Litigation’, 10 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-27. Katz, Avery and Beckner, Clinton F. (1995), ‘The Incentive Effects of Litigation Fee Shifting when Legal Standards are Uncertain’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 205-224. Kessler, Daniel, Meites, Thomas and Miller, Geoffrey (1996), ‘Explaining Deviations from the Fifty-Percent Rule: A Multimodal Approach to the Selection of Cases for Litigation’, 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 233-260. Klein, Cristopher C. (1990), ‘Predation in the Courts: Legal Versus Economic Analysis in Sham Litigation Cases’, 10 International Review of Law and Economics, 29-40. Klerman, Daniel (1996), ‘Settling Multidefendant Lawsuits: The Advantage of Conditional Setoff Rules’, 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 445-462. Klevorick, Alan, and Michael Rothschild (1979), ‘A Model of the Jury Decisionmaking Process’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 141-164. Klevorick, Alan, Rothschild, Michael and Winship, C. (1984), ‘Information Processing and Jury Decision Making’, 23 Journal of Public Economics, 141-164. Kobayashi, Bruce H. (1996), ‘Case Selection, External Effects, and the Trial/Settlement Decision’, in Anderson, David A. (ed.), Dispute Resolution: Bridging the Settlement Gap, Greenwood, JAI Press, 17-49. Kobayashi, Bruce H. and Lott, John R., Jr (1996), ‘In Defense of Criminal Defense Expenditures and Plea Bargaining’, 16 International Review of Law and Economics, 397-416. Kobayashi, Bruce H. and Parker, Jeffrey S. (1993), ‘No Armistice at 11: A Commentary on the Supreme Court’s 1993 Amendments to Rule 11 of the Federal Rules of Civil Procedure’, 3 Supreme Court Economic Review, 93-152. Kobayashi, Bruce H., Parker, Jeffrey S. and Ribstein, Larry E. (1996), ‘The Process of Procedural Reform: Centralized Uniformity versus Local Experimentation’, George Mason University School of Law Working Paper. Kornhauser, Lewis, and Revesz, Richard (1989), ‘Sharing Damages Among Multiple Tortfeasors’, 98 Yale Law Journal, 831-884. Kornhauser, Louis and Revesz, Richard (1990), ‘Apportioning Damages among Potentially Insolvent Actors’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 617-651. Kornhauser, Lewis and Revesz, Richard (1994), ‘Multi-Defendant Settlements: The Impact of Joint and
7000
Civil Procedure: General
21
Several Liability’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 41-76. Landes, William M. (1971), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Courts’, 14 Journal of Law and Economics, 61-107. Landes, William M. (1993), ‘Sequential versus Unitary Trials: An Economic Analysis’, 22 Journal of Legal Studies, 99-134. Landes, William M. (1994), ‘Counterclaims: An Economic Analysis’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 235-244. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1979), ‘Adjudication as a Private Good’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 235-284. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1980), ‘Joint and Multiple Tortfeasors: An Economic Analysis’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 517-555. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1994), ‘The Economics of Anticipatory Adjudication’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 683-719. Langbein, John H. (1985), ‘The German Advantage in Civil Procedure’, 52 University of Chicago Law Review, 823-866. Lombardero, David A. (1996), ‘Do Special Verdicts Improve the Structure of Jury Decision Making’, 36 Jurimetrics Journal, 275-324. Lynk, William J. (1990), ‘The Courts and the Market: An Economic Analysis of Contingent Fees in Class-Action Litigation’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 247-260. Lynk, William J. (1994), ‘The Courts and the Plaintiffs’ Bar: Awarding the Attorney’s Fee in Class-Action Litigation’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 185-210. McChesney, Fred S. (1979), ‘On the Procedural Superiority of a Civil Law System’, 30 Kyklos, 507-510. McLauchlan, William P. (1973), ‘An Empirical Study of Civil Procedure: Directed Verdicts and Judgments Notwithstanding Verdict’, 2 Journal of Legal Studies, 459-468. McLauchlan, William P. (1977), ‘An Empirical Study of the Federal Summary Judgment Rule’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 427-459. Macey, Jonathan R. (1994), ‘Judicial Preferences, Public Choice, and the Rules of Procedure’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 627-646. Menell, Peter S. (1983), ‘A Note on Private versus Social Incentive to Sue in a Costly Legal System’, 12 Journal of Legal Studies, 41-52. Miceli, Thomas J. (1993), ‘Optimal Deterrence of Nuisance Suits by Repeat Defendants’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 135-144. Miceli, Thomas J. (1994), ‘Do Contingent Fees Promote Excessive Litigation?’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 211-224. Miceli, Thomas J. and Segerson, Kathleen (1991), ‘Contingent Fees for Lawyers: The Impact on Litigation and Accident Prevention’, 20 Journal of Legal Studies, 381-399. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1986), ‘An Economic Analysis of Rule 68’, 15 Journal of Legal Studies, 93-125. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1987), ‘Some Agency Problems is Settlement’, 16 Journal of Legal Studies, 189-215. Nalebuff, Barry (1987), ‘Credible Pretrial Negotiation’, 18 RAND Journal of Economics, 198-210. Oakley, John B. and Coon, Arthur F. (1986), ‘The Federal Rules in State Courts: A Survey of State Court Systems and Civil Procedure’, 61 Washington Law Review, 1367-1427. Ordover, Janusz A. (1978), ‘Costly Litigation in the Model of Single Activity Accidents’, 7 Journal of Legal Studies, 243-261. Ordover, Janusz A. (1981), ‘On the Consequences of Costly Litigation in the Model of Single Activity
22
Civil Procedure: General
7000
Accidents: Some New Results’, 10 Journal of Legal Studies, 269-291. Perloff, Jeffrey, Rubinfeld, Daniel L. and Ruud, P. (1996), ‘Antitrust Settlements and Trial Outcomes’, 78 Review of Economics and Statistics, 401 ff. Plott, Charles R. (1987), ‘Legal Fees: A Comparison of the American and English Rules’, 3 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 185-193. P’ng, Ivan P.L. (1983), ‘Strategic Behavior in Suit, Settlement, and Trial’, 14 Bell Journal of Economics, 539-550. P’ng, Ivan P.L. (1987), ‘Litigation, Liability, and Incentives for Care’, 34 Journal of Public Economics, 61-85. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1988a), ‘The Deterrent Effects of Settlements and Trials’, 8 International Review of Law and Economics, 109-116. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1988b), ‘The Welfare Implications of Costly Litigation for the Level of Liability’, 17 Journal of Legal Studies, 151-164. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1993), ‘Sanctioning Frivolous Suits: An Economic Analysis’, 82 Georgetown Law Journal, 397-435. Posner, Richard A. (1973), ‘An Economic Approach to Legal Procedure and Judicial Administration’, 2 Journal of Legal Studies, 399-458. Posner, Richard A. (1992), The Economic Analysis of Law, 4th edn, Boston, Little Brown. Priest, George L. (1980), ‘The Selective Characteristics of Litigation’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 399-422. Priest, George L. (1982), ‘Regulating the Content and Volume of Litigation: An Economic Analysis’, 1 Supreme Court Economic Review, 163-183. Priest, George L. (1985), ‘Reexamining the Selection Hypothesis: Learning from Wittman’s Mistakes’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 215-243. Priest, George L. (1987), ‘Measuring Legal Change’, 3 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 193-226. Priest, George L. and Klein, Benjamin (1984), ‘The Selection of Disputes for Litigation’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-55. Ramsayer, J. Mark and Nakazato, M. (1989), ‘The Rational Litigant: Settlement Amounts and Verdict Rates in Japan’, 18 Journal of Legal Studies, 263-290. Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, Louis L. (1986), ‘Settlement, Litigation and the Allocation of Legal Costs’, 17 RAND Journal of Economics, 555-566. Rose-Ackerman, Susan and Geistfeld, Mark (1987), ‘The Divergence between Social and Private Incentives to Sue: A Comment on Shavell, Menell, and Kaplow’, 16 Journal of Legal Studies, 483-491. Rosenberg, David and Shavell, Steven (1985), ‘A Model in Which Suits are Brought for Their Nuisance Value’, 5 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-13. Rosenfeld, Andrew (1976), ‘An Empirical Test of Class-Action Settlement’, 5 Journal of Legal Studies, 113-120. Rubin, Paul H. (1977), ‘Why is the Common Law Efficient?’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 51-63. Rubinfeld, Daniel L. and Sappington, David E.M. (1987), ‘Efficient Awards and Standards of Proof in Judicial Proceedings’, 18 RAND Journal of Economics, 308-315. Rubinfeld, Daniel L. and Scotchmer, Suzanne (1993), ‘Contingent Fees for Attorneys: An Economic Analysis’, 24 RAND Journal of Economics, 343-356. Schwartz, Edward P. and Schwartz, Warren F. (1996), ‘The Challenge of Peremptory Challenges’, 12 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 325-360.
7000
Civil Procedure: General
23
Schwartz, Warren F. and Tullock, Gordon (1975), ‘The Costs of a Legal System’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 75-82. Schwarzer, William W. (1989), ‘The Federal Rules, The Adversary Process, and Discovery Reform’, 50 University of Pittsburgh Law Review, 703-723. Schweizer, Urs (1989), ‘Litigation and Settlement under Two-Sided Incomplete Information’, 56 Review of Economic Studies, 163-178. Shavell, Steven (1982a), ‘Suit, Settlement, and Trial: A Theoretical Analysis Under Alternative Methods for the Allocation of Legal Costs’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 55-81. Shavell, Steven (1982b), ‘The Social versus the Private Incentive to Bring Suit in a Costly Legal System’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 333-339. Shavell, Steven (1993), ‘Suits versus Settlement when Parties Seek Nonmonetary Judgments’, 22 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-13. Shavell, Steven (1995), ‘Alternative Dispute Resolution: An Economic Analysis’, 24 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-28. Shavell, Steven (1996), ‘Any Frequency of Plaintiff Victory is Possible’, 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 493-501. Smith, Janet K. and Cox, Steven R. (1985), ‘The Pricing of Legal Services: A Contractual Solution to the Problem of Bilateral Opportunism’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 167-183. Snyder, Edward A. and Hughes, James W. (1990), ‘The English Rule for Allocating Legal Costs: Evidence Confronts Theory’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 345-380. Sobel, Joel (1989), ‘An Analysis of Discovery Rules’, 52 Law and Contemporary Problems, 133-159. Solomine, Michael E. and Pacheco, Bryan (1997), ‘State Court Regulation of Offers of Judgement and its Lessons for Federal Practice’, 13 Ohio State Journal on Dispute Resolution, 51-78. Spier, Kathryn E. (1992), ‘The Dynamics of Pretrial Negotiation’, 59 Review of Economic Studies, 93-108. Spier, Kathryn E. (1994a), ‘Pretrial Bargaining and the Design of Fee-Shifting Rules’, 25 RAND Journal of Economics, 197-214. Spier, Kathryn E. (1994b), ‘Settlement, Bargaining, and the Design of Damage Awards’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 84-95. Spurr, Stephen J. (1991), ‘An Economic Analysis of Collateral Estoppel’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 47-61. Subrin, Stephen N. (1989), ‘Local Rules, and State Rules: Uniformity, Divergence and Emerging Procedural Patterns’, 137 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1999-2051. Thomas, Robert E. (1995), ‘The Trial Selection Hypothesis without the 50 Percent Rule: Some Experimental Evidence’, 24 Journal of Legal Studies, 209-228. Thomason, Terry (1991), ‘Are Attorneys Paid What They’re Worth? Contingent Fees and the Settlement Process’, 20 Journal of Legal Studies, 187-223. Trubek, David M., Sarat, Austin, Felstiner, William L.F., Kritzer, Herbert M. and Grossman, Joel B. (1983), ‘The Cost of Ordinary Litigation’, 31 UCLA Law Review, 72-127. Tullock, Gordon (1975), ‘On Effective Organization of Trials’, 28 Kyklos, 745-762. Tullock, Gordon (1980), Trials on Trial: The Pure Theory of Legal Procedure, New York, Columbia University Press. Tullock, Gordon (1988), ‘Defending the Napoleontic Code over the Common Law’, 2 Research in Law and Policy Studies, 3-27.
24
Civil Procedure: General
7000
Waldfogel, Joel (1995), ‘The Selection Hypothesis and the Relationship Between Trial and Plaintiff Victory’, 103 Journal of Political Economy, 229-260. Walker, Laurens (1994), ‘Avoiding Surprise from Federal Civil Rule Making: The Role of Economic Analysis’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 569-593. Wang, Gyu Ho, Kim, Jeong-Yoo and Yi, Jong-Goo (1994), ‘Litigation and Pretrial Negotiation under Incomplete Information’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 187-200. Watts, Alison (1994), ‘Bargaining Through an Expert Attorney’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 168-186. Williams, Philip L. and Williams, Ross A. (1994), ‘The Cost of Civil Litigation: An Empirical Study’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 73-86. Wittman, Donald (1988), ‘Dispute Resolution, Bargaining, and the Selection of Cases for Trial: A Study in the Generation of Biased and Unbiased Data’, 17 Journal of Legal Studies, 313-352. Wittman, Donald (1985), ‘Is the Selection of Cases for Trial Biased?’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 185-214. Yang, Bill Z. (1996), ‘Litigation, Experimentation, and Reputation’, 16 International Review of Law and Economics, 503-521.
Other References Adams, Michael (1981), Ökonomische Analyse des Zivilprozesses (Economic Analysis of Civil Procedure), Königstein/Ts, Athenäum, 130 ff. Adams, Michael (1983), ‘Eine wohlfahrtstheoretische Analyse des Zivilprozesses und der Rechtsschutzversicherungen (An Economic Analysis of Civil Procedure and Legal Aid Insurance)’, 139 Zeitschrift für Schweizerisches Recht, 187-208. Adams, Michael (1986), ‘Der Zivilproze als Folge strategischen Verhaltens’ (On Civil Procedure as a Consequence of Strategic Behavior)’, 7 Zeitschrift für Rechtssoziologie, 212-225. Alexander, Janet Cooper (1994), ‘Judges’ Self Interest and Procedural Rules: Comment’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 647-665. Bone, Robert G. (1994), ‘The Empirical Turn in Procedural Rule Making: Comment’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 595-613. Bowles, Roger A. (1981), ‘Economic Aspects of Legal Procedure’, in Burrows, Paul and Veljanovski, Cento G. (eds), The Economic Approach to Law, London, Butterworths, 191-209. Broder, Josef M. (1978), ‘Citizen Participation in Michigan District Courts’, in Randall, Allan (ed.), Citizen Participation in Natural Resource Decision Making, North Central Research Strategy Committee for Natural Resources, Department of Agricultural Economics, University of Kentucky. Reprinted in Samuels, Warren J. and Schmid, A. Allen (eds) (1981), Law and Economics: An Institutional Perspective, Boston, Nijhoff, 166-178. Brown, John Prather (1985), ‘Alternatives to the Present System of Litigation for Personal Injury’, in Baily, Mary Ann and Cikins, Warren I. (eds), The Effects of Litigation on Health Care Costs, Washington, Brookings Institution, 69-79. Carrington, Paul D. (1979), ‘Adjudication as a Private Good: A Comment’, 8 Journal of Legal
7000
Civil Procedure: General
25
Studies, 303-317. Carroll, Sidney L. and Gaston, Robert J. (1981), ‘A Note on the Quality of Legal Services: Peer Review and Disciplinary Service’, 3 Research in Law and Economics, 251- 260. Chiorazzi, Michael et al. (1988), ‘Empirical Studies in Civil Procedure: A Selected Annotated Bibliography’, 51 Law and Contemporary Problems, 87-207. Conference (1987), ‘Conference on the Law and Economics of Procedure’, 3 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 143-372. Cooper, Edward H. (1994), ‘Discovery Cost Allocation: Comment’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 465-480. Cooter, Robert D. and Ulen, Tom (1989), Law and Economics (Scott Foresman, 1988; 2nd edition, 1996, Japanese translation by Prof. Shozo Ota, introduction by Prof. Koji Shimdo, published by Shoji-Homu. Davis, Otto A. (1979), ‘Public and Private Characteristics of a Legal Process: A Comment’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 285-293. Denzau, Arthur (1979), ‘Litigation Expenditures as Private Determinants of Judicial Decisions: A Comment’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 295-302. Getman, Julius G. (1974), ‘A Critique of the Report of the Shreveport Experiment’, 3 Journal of Legal Studies, 487-497. Goldberg, Victor P. (ed.) (1979), ‘Discussion by Seminar Participants’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 323-398. Huang, Peter H. and Wu, Ho Mou (1992), ‘Emotional Responses in Litigation’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 31-44. Linder, Douglas O. (1989), ‘Some Doubts Concerning the Selection Hypothesis of George Priest’, 37 University of Kansas Law Review, 319-347. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1977), Note, Aldinger v. Howard and Pendent Jurisdiction, 77 Columbia Law Review, 127-152. Miller, Arthur R. (1984), ‘The Adversary System: Dinosaur or Phoenix’, 69 Minnesota Law Review, 1-37. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1989), ‘Comment: Some Thoughts on the Equilibrium Hypothesis’, 69 Boston University Law Review, 561-568. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1994), ‘Economic Analysis of Civil Procedure: Introduction’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 303-306. Nederlands Juristen Blad (1990), Rechtshulp anno 1990, Special Issue, (a number of articles). Nederlands Juristen Blad, (1987), Tussen Kwaliteit en Efficiency in de Rechtspraak (Between Quality and Efficiency in Case Law), Special Issue (a number of articles). Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Che, Yeon-Koo (1991), ‘Decoupling Liability: Optimal Incentives for Care and Litigation’, 22 RAND Journal of Economics, 562-570. Posner, Richard A. (1988), ‘Comment: Responding to Gordon Tullock’, 2 Research in Law and Policy Studies, 29-33. Rowe, Thomas D., Jr (1994), ‘Repealing the Law of Unintended Consequences? Comment’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 615-626. Sarokin, H. Lee (1989), ‘A Comment on Geoffrey Hazard’s Authority in the Dock’, 69 Boston University Law Review, 477-479. Schwarzer, William W (1988), ‘Rule 11 Revisited’, 101 Harvard Law Review, 1013-1025. Shavell, Steven (1989), ‘The Sharing of Information Prior to Settlement of Litigation’, 20 RAND Journal of Economics, 183-195. Symposium (1987), ‘Conference on the Law and Economics of Procedure’, 3 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 143-447.
26
Civil Procedure: General
7000
Symposium (1989), ‘Issues in Civil Procedure: Advancing the Dialogue’, 69 Boston University Law Review, 467-779. White, Lawrence J. (1988), ‘Litigation and Economic Incentives’, 11 Research in Law and Economics, 73-90. Yeazell, Stephen C. (1989), ‘The Salience of Salience: A Comment on Professor Hazard’s Authority in the Dock’, 69 Boston University Law Review, 481-486.
7100 JUDICIAL ORGANIZATION AND ADMINISTRATION Lewis A. Kornhauser Professor of Law, New York University School of Law © Copyright 1999 Lewis A. Kornhauser
Abstract This chapter surveys the economic literature on the functions and structure of courts. Issues concerning appellate courts and collegiality are addressed in a companion chapter. JEL classification: K4 Keywords: Judicial Administration, Court Organization, Judges, Adjudication
1. Introduction Economic analyses of substantive legal rules generally suppress the adjudication of factual and legal disputes that a legal rule might engender. The nature of adjudication, however, will influence greatly both the content of the substantive law and the costs of dispute resolution. An understanding of the structure of adjudication is thus central to an understanding of the effects of legal rules on behavior and on the identification of socially desirable legal rules. In addition, adjudication is a complex task implemented through institutions that vary across time and jurisdiction. The structure of adjudication and questions of judicial organization and administration thus present a rich field of study in their own right. These two approaches to the study of judicial organization raise different, though equally interesting, questions. As yet, no unitary theory has developed to explain the structure of adjudication. The initial economic analyses of these institutions have raised several important questions: (1) What are the functions of adjudication? (2) Why is adjudication public rather than private? (3) Should there be only one system of courts or should there be many? (4) What is the relation among courts, legislature and executive? (5) How do we explain the organizational features of courts such as their jurisdiction and their hierarchical relation? The questions presented by judicial organization and administration are contiguous with those presented by appeal and supreme courts. I adopt a somewhat arbitrary division of topics and relegate discussions of the reasons for appeal, explanations of hierarchy and collegiality to Chapter 7200 Appeal and Supreme Courts. 27
28
Judicial Organization and Administration
7100
2. The Functions of Courts 2.1 What Do Courts Do? Adjudication resolves disputes. Dispute resolution itself consists of at least four different tasks. First, courts must determine the facts of the dispute. Second, they apply the law to those facts. Third, the court may, in some instances, enforce its judgment against one of the parties. Finally, in some instances, the court may have to compel one or more of the parties to submit to the jurisdiction of the court. In some legal systems, the judicial function is limited to these four tasks; in others, courts also make law. In civil law theory, for example, courts simply apply the law announced by legislatures to resolve disputes. Legal theorists in common law countries, by contrast, resolve disputes through the application of law but also promulgate new legal rules; courts thus play a lawmaking function as well. This difference between civil and common law perceptions of adjudication, as well as various structural differences between the two systems, presents a challenge to economic analysts which has yet to be answered. 2.2 Public vs. Private Adjudication Adjudication is commonly considered a quintessential function of government. In recent years, however, there has been a substantial privatization of at least some of these functions through a growing use of arbitration and other ‘private judges’. This phenomenon has prompted scholars to study the extent to which government must supply judicial functions. Landes and Posner (1979) provide one of the earliest inquiries into the choice between private and public provision of adjudicatory services. Working within a common law framework, they identify the judicial functions as both dispute resolution and rule generation. They argue that only the dispute resolution function is suitable for (partial) privatization. Some public provision of dispute resolution might be necessary because (1) enforcement of judgments might require public authority and (2) in some instances, public authority may be necessary to compel one or more parties to submit the dispute to adjudication in the first place. A private market in adjudicatory services, however, would meet all other requirements of a dispute resolution system. They argue that a competitive market would produce competent and impartial judges because both qualities would be necessary to induce all parties to a dispute to consent to adjudication of their dispute by a given judge. Cooter (1983) offers a similar argument. Landes and Posner, however, argue that private provision of rules will not, in general, be desirable. Rule generation is a public good and a private judge who announces a rule will not capture all the benefits that the announcement of a rule creates. Therefore, in a system of private adjudication, rules will be
7100
Judicial Organization and Administration
29
undersupplied. In addition, competing judges may generate competing sets of rules. They do not, however, explain why rules cannot be adequately supplied by legislatures. Shavell (1995) considers the choice of private dispute resolution in the context of an established public system of courts. He addresses two questions: why would parties resort to private dispute resolution? and when is it socially desirable? He distinguishes ex ante invocation of private dispute resolution, in which the parties agree prior to the emergence of a dispute to resort to private resolution of their dispute, from ex post invocation of it, in which the resort to these private methods occurs after the dispute arises. He argues that ex ante invocation is socially desirable for three reasons: (1) it may lower the costs and risks of dispute resolution; (2) it may create better incentives to perform because of the greater accuracy of private resolution; and (3) it may reduce the number of litigated disputes. He argues that ex post invocation of private dispute resolution is not desirable.
3. The General Organization of Courts 3.1 Judicial Motivation Economic models of judicial behavior and of court organization require an assumption concerning the motivations of judges. This requirement presents the central challenge to the economic analysis of courts. Several approaches have been adopted, most of which are surveyed here. A supplementary discussion that emphasizes a distinction between ‘team’ and ‘political’ models of judges appears in Chapter 7200 on Appeal and Supreme Courts. The literature has focused primarily on adjudication in common law jurisdictions. This focus has implied that lawmaking is the judicial function that has received the most motivational attention. In this context, the literature has advanced three different types of answers to the question of judicial motivation. First, one can assume that judges meet their obligations as articulated in some jurisprudential theory of adjudication. Put differently, judges ‘follow the law’. Team models, discussed in Section 2 of Chapter 7200 Appeals and Supreme Courts attempt to ground this adherence to norms in a more economic framework. Second, one can assume that judges seek to implement their own policy preferences subject to constraints such as review by other judges or by legislatures. This political model is discussed at greater length in Section 3 of Chapter 7200. Third, one may assume that, as in political models, judges act self-interestedly but define self-interest differently. The literature surveyed here has largely attempted to infer judicial motivation from the structure of incentives within which the judge works.
30
Judicial Organization and Administration
7100
Aranson (1990) surveys the political science literature that applies the spatial theory of voting to courts and compares it to law and economics approaches to judicial motivation. He suggests three competing views of judicial motivation. The first, that it is rule governed, parallels the first strand mentioned above and discussed at greater length in Section 2 of Chapter 7200. The second, that judicial motivation is rent redistributing, and the third, that it is wealth maximizing, describe systemic tendencies rather than the motivation of particular judges. One might understand ‘rent redistribution’ consistently with the political model discussed in Section 3 of Chapter 7200. Wealth maximization, by contrast, assumes that Posner’s claim that the common law maximizes wealth can be explained in terms of judicial success in pursuit of their common aim. Posner (1973) sketched an approach to the problem of identification of the preferences of judges. He assumed that judges were self-interested and then briefly examined different incentive structures from which he inferred the underlying preferences of the judges. In particular he compared the structure in many states in which judges lack life tenure and aspire to higher political office to the structure of the federal courts in the United States in which the judges have life tenure. These themes were developed in the subsequent literature. Landes and Posner (1980) argue that utility maximizing judges will primarily seek to maximize their power because their performance is too weakly linked to income and promotion for those concerns to have much effect on judicial behavior. They then adopt the number of times a judge is cited in other cases as a measure of his power. They then argue that judges with higher salaries and more secure tenure will have greater power (and hence be cited more often) because higher salaries both attract more competent judges and reduce the judge’s incentives to distort his decisions and because longer tenure reduces turnover and the influence of politics. They then provide an ingenious test of their hypotheses. They create two samples of common law appellate opinions rendered in 1950. First they looked at all 246 tort, contract and property cases decided by the federal appellate courts under their diversity jurisdiction. Second they drew a random sample of 241 tort, property or contract cases decided by state supreme courts in 1950. The number of cases drawn from a specific state matched the proportion of federal cases decided under the law of that state. They then compared the citation rates of state and federal decisions in the two systems. They found only weak support for their hypothesis concerning higher salary and more secure tenure. Federal decisions were more likely to be cited in the state supreme courts of ‘other’ states (that is, states other than the one of which the federal court applied the law) than the decisions of state courts. Cooter (1983) adopted a procedure similar to that of Landes and Posner (1979). He developed a theory of behavior of private judges and used that as a benchmark from which to infer the preferences of public judges. He argued that both public and private judges would care about their reputations among other
7100
Judicial Organization and Administration
31
judges and the bar. Higgins and Rubin (1980) addressed the concern for promotion somewhat more directly. They argued that judges have preferences over policy ‘discretion’ and wealth; these preferences are conditional on their age. They argue that a judge’s ability to satisfy her preferences are constrained in two ways. First, the reversal rate depends on the judge’s policy preferences and the policy preferences of the higher court. Second, wealth depends on the reversal rate (because that affects each judge’s prospect of promotion) and age. They then derive a test for the relative effects of discretion and wealth. They study two samples. The first sample consists of those active district court judges in the eighth federal circuit in 1974 who permitted the release of data on the total number of cases they decided in 1973 and 1974. The second sample consisted of all active district court judges in the fifth federal circuit in 1966. They found that neither age nor seniority explained the reversal rates of the eighth circuit judges. They did find however that the estimated parameter on reversal rate had the predicted sign and was significant at the 10 percent level in a logit estimation of the probability of being promoted. Greenberg and Haley (1986) argue, contrary to the conventional wisdom in general and to Posner (1985) in particular, that low judicial salaries are socially desirable because they signal a greater willingness to accept the non-pecuniary benefits of the judiciary; moreover, they argue that individuals who derive greater non-pecuniary benefits from judging make better judges. Elder (1987) identifies two distinct mechanisms for monitoring judges: political and administrative mechanisms. These mechanisms create different incentives so that one should observe different behaviors in systems with different monitoring mechanisms. Without specifying the judicial objective function precisely, he nevertheless argues that judges deciding criminal cases will produce more trial verdicts under political monitoring than they would under administrative monitoring. He then tests this claim on 1977 data drawn from state criminal courts in 247 districts in seven states. His parameter estimates are consistent with his hypothesis. Cohen (1992) followed up Elder’s approach. He argued that Elder implicitly assumed that each judge sought to maximize his preferences defined in terms of minimizing his workload and his reversal rate. He argues that these preferences also imply that, when the penalty range increases, a judge will increase the penalty of those defendants who request a trial more than they increase the penalty of those who plead guilty. He also argues that judges will be concerned about promotion and that this too will influence the pattern of sentencing. He then considers a sample that consists of all federal antitrust indictments from 1955 through 1980. In 1974, Congress increased the maximum penalties for antitrust violations from $50,000 to $100,000. He finds that promotion concerns are explanatory with respect to fines but not with respect to incarceration.
32
Judicial Organization and Administration
7100
Cohen (1991) exploited the data generated by a ‘natural experiment’ presented by the adoption of new sentencing guidelines by the United States federal courts. He examined 196 decisions by federal district courts that considered the constitutionality of the guidelines. He estimated a probit model of the probability of upholding the guidelines as a function of judicial ideology, caseload, promotion potential and the number of prior decisions for constitutionality. Promotion potential was measured by an index that reflected the (per district court judge) number of open seats on the appellate circuit. He found that the parameters on workload and promotion potential had the predicted sign and were highly significant. Katz (1988) adopts a behavioral approach. He assumes that judges decide cases on the basis of the arguments presented to it. Each party offers arguments in its favor and the court decides in favor of the plaintiff if the plaintiff’s arguments, in light of the ‘underlying’ (or, perhaps, ex ante) merits of the case, outweigh the defendant’s arguments and some random error. He then shows that, when cases are more evenly balanced ex ante, expenditures of each party on litigation rise; and, if judicial decision is more random or variable, each party’s expenditures fall. 3.2 Independence of the Judiciary Economic analysts have devoted much attention to explanations for, and implications of, ‘independent’ judiciaries. An independent judiciary is one that is free from external influence, primarily, political influence. This conception of independence is somewhat at odds with the ascription of a political motivation to judges themselves because independence is generally seen as guaranteeing a more ‘objective’ resolution of disputes. Though the literature has not attended much to this specific problem, there are suggestions that a more general model of constitutional structure might justify an independent branch of politically motivated judges. Most industrialized countries assert the independence of their judiciaries but the structures that guarantee independence differ greatly. In the federal system in the United States, for example, judges have life tenure and their (nominal) salaries cannot be decreased during their lifetime. In many states of the United States, however, judges serve for a term of years; moreover, in many states, they may be elected in either partisan or non-partisan elections. In both the state and federal systems, as in common law jurisdictions generally, judges are, however, drawn from the general bar. In many civil law countries by contrast, law graduates choose to enter practice or the judiciary at the outset of their career; a judicial bureaucracy then creates incentives for that judge. The insulation of that bureaucracy from ‘normal’ politics then determines the extent of judicial independence. This institutional variation across jurisdictions permits a comparative study of judicial independence. As a consequence, studies of
7100
Judicial Organization and Administration
33
independence, unlike studies in other areas of judicial organization, have been primarily comparative in nature. Landes and Posner (1975) offered the earliest discussion of independence. Their argument rests on the claim that an independent judiciary will, in statutory interpretation, enforce the original legislative understanding. Individual legislatures accede to this practice because they want to increase the time a statute prevails. Landes and Posner then claim that the degree of independence should increase with the size of the jurisdiction because larger jurisdictions provide broader scope for rent-seeking. They then attempt to test their theory on data concerning 97 statutes declared unconstitutional by the United States Supreme Court between 1789 and 1972. Ramseyer (1994) extends the analysis of Landes and Posner (1975) by drawing on a comparison of Japan and the United States. Ramseyer defines judicial independence as the extent to which politicians do not manipulate careers of sitting judges. He asks why some politicians provide an independent judiciary and others do not. He claims that a political structure will provide for an independent judiciary if (i) politicians believe that elections will continue indefinitely and (ii) politicians believe that their prospects of continued victory are low. He then does three case studies: the United States which satisfies both antecedent conditions and has an independent judiciary; contemporary Japan which satisfies the first condition but not the second and does not have an independent judiciary; and imperial Japan which satisfied condition (ii) but not condition (i) and did not have an independent judiciary. Cooter and Ginsburg (1996) also deploy comparative data to study the question of judicial independence. They work with a different conception of independence than Ramseyer. Ramseyer’s definition referred to the structure of appointment, pay, promotion and tenure in the judiciary. Cooter and Ginsburg have a more substantive view of independence; they look to the courts’ ability to make law that diverges from the views of the legislature. They argue that the degree of judicial independence will depend on both political and constitutional features of a society. In particular they argue that societies in which a cohesive party dominates politics will be less likely to have judicial independence. On the other hand, the more ‘legislative vetoes’ that the constitution builds into its political process the more independence the courts have. They then asked experts in comparative law to rank the daringness of the judiciary of various countries. They then regressed daringness on the number of vetoes and the duration of the governing coalition. Despite the small sample size, the parameters on both independent variables had the predicted sign and were statistically significant; moreover they explained a substantial part of the variance.
34
Judicial Organization and Administration
7100
3.3 Jurisdiction Case and controversy requirement Courts generally resolve disputes but the dispute must generally be, in some way, ‘live’ and ‘real’. In the United States, this requirement of the existence of a real dispute is embodied in the ‘case or controversy’ requirement of Article III of the Constitution. The requirement, however, is not a peculiarity of United States federal courts. With the exception of some constitutional courts, such as those of France and Germany, that have jurisdiction to issue opinions on the constitutionality of legislation prior to its enactment, most judicial systems require some similar trigger. Why should this be so? And who should be allowed to press a claim concerning a ‘real’ dispute? Jensen, Meckling and Holderness (1986) address this latter question of who should be allowed to press a claim in a live dispute. They argue for limited rules of standing because, they claim, a liberal standing rule increases the costs of engaging in any rule-governed transaction. Landes and Posner (1994) address the first question concerning the justification of a requirement of a concrete case to trigger the adjudicatory power. They extend a model of legal advice developed by Shavell (1988, 1992) and Kaplow and Shavell (1992) to investigate questions concerning the use of attorneys to the question the case or controversy requirement. They focus on the distinction between type 1 and type 2 error - the wrongful attribution of liability to defendants versus the wrongful excusal from liability of defendants. They argue that this distinction can be deployed to explain much of the observed pattern of exceptions to the case or controversy requirement. Specifically, they note that anticipatory adjudication, in violation of the concreteness requirement, increases both errors. They then examine in detail the institutions of declaratory judgments, res judicata, advisory opinions, and preliminary injunctions. Stearns (1995, 1996) argues that the case or controversy requirement serves to restrict the occurrence of cycling that plagues institutions of social choice. For a fuller discussion, see the section on collegiality in Chapter 7200. Specialized courts vs. courts of general jurisdiction Over what disputes should a court have jurisdiction to decide? Two methods for defining the subject matter jurisdiction of courts predominate. First, and most commonly, a court might have jurisdiction over any dispute that arises within a specified geographic area. Virtually all court systems consist primarily of these courts of general jurisdiction. Second, a court might have jurisdiction over disputes with a specified subject matter. Notice that these organizational patterns could be applied to courts of first instance (that find facts as well as apply law) only, to appellate courts only, or to both courts of first instance and to appellate courts. Moreover, in a system with specialized courts of first instance but appeal to
7100
Judicial Organization and Administration
35
courts of general jurisdiction, one could limit appeal to a single general court of jurisdiction or one could allocate non-exclusive jurisdiction to a number of appellate courts. In the United States, one may understand the administrative law structure as establishing administrative agencies as specialized courts to determine the facts and make initial legal rulings that are then appealed to courts of general jurisdictions. Thus most labor disputes, welfare disputes and immigration disputes are first heard in administrative agencies and then, if necessary, appealed to the federal courts of appeals. In these instances, each of the federal courts of appeal has jurisdiction to hear appeals from these specialized tribunals. Many environmental disputes, by contrast, may only be appealed to the US Court of Appeals for the DC Circuit. Finally, there are some specialized courts of appeal such as the tax court and the federal circuit for Court of Appeals for the Federal Circuit which has jurisdiction over patent and other intellectual property disputes. What is the appropriate way to allocate jurisdiction among courts? Posner (1985) argues that specialized appellate courts are likely to be more ideological than courts of general jurisdiction because judges on specialized courts are likely to be more focused on the subject matter of their jurisdiction and hence more likely to be sensitive, and responsive, to controversy. Revesz (1990) analyzes the desirability of vesting appellate authority over administrative agencies in specialized courts. His analysis emphasizes the effect of the nature of the appellate court’s jurisdiction on legislative ability to control agencies. He argues that review by specialized courts reduces the effectiveness of congressional delegation to administrative agencies. He develops a simple principal-agent model in which Congress is the principal and the administrative agency the agent. They have different policy preferences because commissioners in agencies have terms that do not correspond to the terms of the commissioners and because there may be a divergence in preferences between Congress and the President who appoints the head of many agencies. Congress has three mechanisms for the control of agencies: it may overrule particular decisions, it may exercise oversight through one or more committees, and it may alter the agency’s budget. Congress, however, might also use the courts to monitor the agency. Revesz argues that a court of general jurisdiction is a better monitor. 3.4 Court Congestion Comparative law scholars have often noted the variation in ‘litigiousness’ across countries. There is little economic literature that seeks to explain this cross-cultural variation but there is a substantial literature analyzing the causes of ‘congestion’ in the courts of one notably litigious society, the United States. Virtually every proposal to reduce court congestion in the United States federal courts recommends the abolition of diversity jurisdiction which grants
36
Judicial Organization and Administration
7100
federal courts the authority to resolve disputes between citizens of different states, even when they involve only questions of sate law. One justification for diversity is that it prevents discrimination against out-of-state residents. Goldman and Marks (1980) tested this claim by looking at two samples of attorneys drawn from the US District Court for the Northern District of Illinois in 1976. They randomly sampled 200 attorneys tied to specific questions and asked them their reasons for litigating in federal court. They had a 62 percent response rate. In addition they randomly sampled 205 attorneys from the law division of Cook County District Court in 1976; this court had a $15,000 amount a controversy minimum so that the cases within its jurisdiction were reasonably comparable to those within the jurisdiction of the federal court. This survey had only a 37 percent response rate. Only 40 percent of the attorneys in federal court listed local bias as a reason for choosing federal court. Attorneys drawn from state court cases were asked to consider a hypothetical case identical to the one litigated but in which their client was an out-of-state resident. Roughly 25 percent said they would file in federal court. Local bias thus had very little influence on the choice of forum. Noam (1981) attempts to assess the social cost of court congestion by calculating the effects of congestion on criminal sentences and then on the crime rate. He argues that plea bargain reached between prosecutor and defendant will depend on the caseload of the court. The higher the caseload per judge, the lower the average sentence. Moreover, he argues that the per capita crime rate is a function of the average sentence. Using simple specifications of these functional relations he derives an equation that represents the marginal effect of additional resources devoted to the criminal courts. He then estimates his equation using FBI data on crime rates for four types of crimes against property in the District of Columbia. This estimation yields very high marginal returns to increased investment in the court system.
4. Fact-Finding To resolve disputes, courts must determine the facts. A substantial portion of procedural rules govern the fact-finding process. Each of these rules influences the structure of the judicial system because each influences the cost of litigation relative to the cost of settlement and to self-help remedies. (The literature on evidence and the choice between settlement and litigation are summarized elsewhere in this volume.) Some procedural rules play a more central role in the organization of court systems. In this section, I examine the structure of trials and the use of juries, a characteristic element of many but not all court systems.
7100
Judicial Organization and Administration
37
4.1 Sequential vs. Unitary Trials Most disputes present more than one factual issue for resolution. Should these be resolved simultaneously or sequentially? In the United States, factual issues are generally resolved simultaneously, but often the question of liability and the question of remedy are decided sequentially, sometimes by different fact-finders. Landes (1993) presents the primary investigation of this issue. He modifies his own, early model of the choice between settlement and litigation (see Landes, 1971) to analyze several issues concerning the effect of trial structure on the settlement rate. The analysis rests on the insight that a sequential structure to the litigation reduces the expected cost of litigation. Hence, the plaintiff’s incentive to sue increases, which implies that the number of lawsuits will increase. Landes argues further that sequential trials reduce the probability of settlement because they narrow the range of acceptable settlements. 4.2 Juries Many legal systems divide the law-finding (or law-applying) and fact-finding functions of trial courts. These systems delegate fact-finding to a jury, generally a group of lay individuals chosen more or less randomly to decide one case. This procedure raises several questions. Jury selection Bowles (1980) compares the cost of jury trials in Britain to the cost of a system of fact-finding by a three-judge court. The cost of a jury trial consists primarily of the production foregone by persons serving on the jury. Bowles notes that high wage earners will attempt to avoid jury service more vigorously than low wage earners. He concludes that a jury trial will be less expensive if the cost of a judge is more than three times the cost of a juror. He does not, however, correct for the speed of the trial. Martin (1972) also estimates the social cost of the jury system in the United States. He first estimates the occupational distribution of jurors on the assumption that juror days of service are distributed identically to jurors. He then multiplied by the median daily wage rate for each occupation and estimated the social cost at $233 million ( $135 million) in 1958 dollars. He then compares the cost of two systems of jury selection: random selection and a ‘keyman’ procedure in which lists are constructed through consultation with community leaders. He finds that random selection is significantly less expensive because community leaders are more likely to draw jurors from high wage occupations than random selection. Finally Martin argues that voluntary service would reduce costs even further.
38
Judicial Organization and Administration
7100
Jury size and jury voting rules Models of jury size and the effects of jury voting rules must specify how juries deliberate and vote. Many models assume no deliberation. Moreover, until recently, the literature assumed that each juror voted conscientiously; her vote expressed her view of the guilt or innocence of the defendant. When one assumes in addition that each juror is more likely than not to decide correctly and that jurors’ judgments are independent of each other, the Condorcet jury theorem applies and one can easily show first, that a unanimity rule minimizes the probability of wrongful convictions; second, that majority rule maximizes the probability of a correct decision; and third, that, as the number of jurors increases, the probability of wrongful conviction under a unanimity rule decreases towards zero and the probability of a correct decision under majority rule increases towards one. Recently, however, analysts have introduced models of strategic voting by jurors and these models yield dramatically different results. Austen-Smith and Banks (1996) and Feddersen and Pesendorfer (1996) show how radically the assumption of strategic behavior by jurors undermines the Condorcet Jury Theorem. When a juror acts strategically, the information aggregation feature of the Condorcet Jury Theorem disappears because each juror now decides how to cast her vote in light only of those instances in which her vote will be pivotal. As a consequence, as Austen-Smith and Banks show clearly, a juror’s vote may not reveal her actual view concerning the case. Feddersen and Pesendorfer show, more dramatically, that the probability of wrongful conviction may be higher under a unanimity rule than under a different voting rule. These models raise important questions about the appropriate way in which to model juries. These questions parallel those presented in the study of collegial courts, discussed in Chapter 7200, where team models in which judges act in a fashion somewhat analogous to the assumption underlying the naive Condorcet Jury Theorem models contend with political models in which judges act strategically. In the United States, until the 1970s, juries typically consisted of twelve individuals and required unanimity to render a verdict. Then, the United States Supreme Court ruled that neither the number twelve nor unanimity were constitutionally required in state criminal proceedings. These decisions spurred research into the importance of these requirements. Klevorick and Rothschild (1979) provide a model of jury deliberation in order to determine whether non-unanimous juries or unanimous juries of fewer than twelve jurors would yield different verdicts than the ‘standard’, twelve-person unanimous jury. Their analysis uses a stationary Markov model to provide a dynamic model of the majority persuasion hypothesis, derived from Kalven and Zeisal (1966), that the final verdict is the same as the majority position on the first ballot. They offer both a discrete and continuous model of
7100
Judicial Organization and Administration
39
jury deliberation. The cores of the models are identical. The jurors enter the jury room with a view on the merits and cast an initial ballot. The vote then changes incrementally as time passes with one person changing her vote at each instant until unanimity is reached. The transition probabilities are given by the current vote: the probability of one more vote for the plaintiff equals the percentage of jurors who favor the plaintiff’s case. In this model one can calculate both the expected number of jury ballots until unanimity is reached (conditional on the initial vote) and the probability that a non-unanimous jury will agree with a unanimous one. Klevorick and Rothschild show that a move to a requirement of ten votes for judgment rather twelve always alters the probability of conviction by less than 0.0055. Their result, of course, depends critically on the manner in which majority pressure operates in the jury room. When they adopt a different assumption concerning transition probabilities, they calculate that the move to ten for judgment may lead to as many as 1/6 of the cases decided differently. Klevorick and Rothschild also show that this shift substantially reduces the expected number of ballots prior to judgment. Schwartz and Schwartz (1992, 1995, 1996) offer a somewhat different approach to jury decision making. The earliest paper addresses three questions concerning the decision rules of juries. First, why do juries fail to reach a verdict? Second, what verdict will a jury reach when it may convict for lesser included offenses or when multiple offenses are litigated simultaneously? Third, how, if at all, will the jury decision rule alter the charges filed by prosecutors? To this end, they assume that a defendant might be charged with any number of counts within some interval. They consider two regimes. In one the prosecutor chooses one count in the interval, and the jury must choose among three outcomes, conviction on that count, acquittal, or no decision. In the second regime, the prosecutor chooses two counts, one entailing a lesser punishment than the other, and the jury chooses among four outcomes, acquittal on both counts, conviction on the lesser count, conviction on the more severe count, or no decision. In the event of no decision, a retrial before a different jury occurs. Each jury consists of four people, chosen randomly from a population. Each potential juror is an expected utility maximizer, characterized by spatial ‘preferences’ for punishment of the defendant; that is, each juror has an ideal outcome that represents the crime for which she believes the defendant should be convicted. The simple model implies that a defendant always prefers a non-unanimous, super-majority rule to unanimity because his expected verdict is lower under the non-unanimous rule. This result occurs because, though the probability of conviction is greater under non-unanimity, the probability of acquittal rises more rapidly. When the jury may convict on a lesser included offense, the analysis is more complex and less clear-cut. Schwartz and Schwartz (1995) extend the analysis of their prior article in the context of the liability and punishment phases of capital offenses in the
40
Judicial Organization and Administration
7100
United States. They argue that the decision process for fact finding has three elements: the voting rule, the jury selection process, and the characterization of the set of outcomes among which the jury may choose. They argue that, in a multi-stage fact-finding process, the voting rule must be the same in each stage in order to avoid the jury at one stage nullifying the law governing the jury at a different stage. In addition, only reciprocal voting rules will avoid hung juries (where a rule is reciprocal if ‘conviction’ requires c of n votes then ‘acquittal’ requires n - c of n votes). Schwartz and Schwartz (1996) carries the argument of the prior two papers further. They argue that any voting rule should satisfy at least two properties: (1) it should be decisive; and (2) it should satisfy the ‘one person/one vote’ criterion. This second property does not eliminate any anonymous voting rule, whether majority, supermajority, or submajority. (Super and submajority rules would violate neutrality). The first criterion identifies majority rule as the unique decisive voting rule when there are only two possible outcomes. To satisfy the desire to minimize wrongful convictions that the unanimity rule is said to promote, Schwartz and Schwartz argue that the size of the jury should be increased perhaps to 15.
5. Concluding Remarks Economic analysis of judicial organization and administration, though it has greatly increased understanding, is only in its infancy. No question has received an exhaustive treatment and many have not been examined at all. This area suggests a multitude of comparative questions, most of which have not received any attention at all. They are ripe for analysis.
Bibliography on Judicial Organization and Administration (7100) Aranson, Peter H. (1990), ‘Models of Judicial Choice as Allocation and Distribution in Constitutional Law’, Brigham Young University Law Review, 794-826. Austen-Smith, David and Banks, Jeffrey S. (1996), ‘Information Aggregation, Rationality and the Condorcet Jury Theorem’, 90(1) American Political Science Review, 34-45. Backhaus, Jurgen (1992), ‘General Legislation and the Budget: Commentary’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 209-210. Barnard, David (1977), The Civil Court in Action, Butterworths, London, 350 ff. Bowles, Roger A. (1980), ‘Juries, Incentives and Self-Selection’, 20 British Journal of Criminology, 368-376. Brunet, Edward (1985), ‘Measuring the Costs of Civil Justice’, 83 Michigan Law Review, 916-938. Casper, Gerhard and Posner, Richard A. (1974), ‘A Study of the Supreme Court’s Caseload’, 3 Journal
7100
Judicial Organization and Administration
41
of Legal Studies, 339-375. Casper, Gerhard and Posner, Richard A. (1976), The Workload of the Supreme Court, Chicago, American Bar Foundation. Casper, Gerhard and Zeisel, Hans (1972), ‘Lay Judges in the German Criminal Courts’, 1 Journal of Legal Studies, 135-191. Cohen, Mark A. (1991), ‘Explaining Judicial Behavior or What’s ‘Unconstitutional’ about the Sentencing Commission?’, 7 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 183-199. Cohen, Mark A. (1992), ‘The Motives of Judges: Empirical Evidence from Antitrust Sentencing’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 13-30. Cooter, Robert (1983), ‘The Objectives of Private and Public Judges’, 41 Public Choice, 107-132. Cooter, Robert and Ginsburg, Tom (1996), ‘Comparative Judicial Discretion: An Empirical Test of Economic Models’, 16 International Review of Law and Economics, 245-313. Ebner, P. (1982), Reducing Pretrial Delay... A Look at What State and Local Courts Are Doing to Break the Logjam, Santa Monica, Rand Institute of Civil Justice. Elder, Harold W. (1987), ‘Property Rights Structures and Criminal Courts: An Analysis of State Criminal Courts’, 7 International Review of Law and Economics, 21-32. Feddersen, Timothy J. and Pesendorfer, Wolfgang (1996), ‘Convicting the Innocent: The Inferiority of Unanimous Jury Verdicts’, Northwestern University Center for Mathematical Studies in Economics and Management Science Discussion Paper No. 1170. Feeley, Malcolm (1983), Court Reform on Trial: Why Simple Solutions Fail, New York, Basic Books, 251 ff. Flanagan, Robert J. (1987), Labor Relations and the Litigation Explosion, Washington, DC, Brookings Institution, 122 ff. Friedman, David (1979), ‘Private Creation and Enforcement of Law: A Historical Case’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 399-415. Galanter, Marc (1986), ‘The Day After the Litigation Explosion’, 46 Maryland Law Review, 3 ff. Gely, Rafael and Spiller, Pablo T. (1990), ‘A Rational Choice Theory of Supreme Court Statutory Decisions with Applications to the State Farm and Grove City Cases’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 263-300. Gillespie, Robert W. (1976), ‘The Production of Court Services: An Analysis of Scale Effects and Other Factors’, 5 Journal of Legal Studies, 243-265. Goldman, Jerry, Hooper, Richard L. and Mahaffey, Judy (1976), ‘Caseload Forecasting Models for Federal District Courts’, 5 Journal of Legal Studies, 201-242. Goldman, Jerry and Marks, Kenneth S. (1980) ‘Diversity Jurisdiction and Local Bias: A Preliminary Empirical Inquiry, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 93-104 Gravelle, Hugh S.E. (1983), ‘Judicial Review and Public Firms’, 3 International Review of Law and Economics, 187-205. Greenberg, Paul E. and Haley, James A. (1986), ‘The Role of the Compensation Structure in Enhancing Judicial Quality’, 15 Journal of Legal Studies, 417-426. Griffiths, J. (1991), ‘De Rechtbank als Fietsenfabriek’ (The Court as Bicycle Manufacturer)’, 66 Nederlands Juristenblad, 129-130, 445. Hazard, Geoffrey C., Jr (1965), ‘Rationing Justice’, 8 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-10. Higgins, Richard A. and Rubin, Paul H. (1980), ‘Judicial Discretion’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies,
42
Judicial Organization and Administration
7100
129-138. Jensen, Michael, Meckling, William H. and Holderness, Clifford (1986), ‘Analysis of Alternative Standing Doctrines’, 6 International Review of Law and Economics, 205-216. Kalven, Harry and Zeisal, Hans (1966), The American Jury, Boston, Little Brown. Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (1992), ‘Private vs Socially Optimal Provision of Ex Ante Legal Advice’, 8 Journal of Law Economics and Organization, 306-320. Karotkin, Drora (1994), ‘Effect of the Size of the Bench on the Correctness of Court Judgments: The Case of Israel’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 371-75. Katz, Avery (1988), ‘Judicial Decision Making and Litigation Expenditures’, 8 International Review of Law and Economics, 127-143. Klevorick, Alvin K. (1977), ‘Jury Composition: An Economic Approach’, in Siegan, Bernard H. (ed.), The Interactions of Economics and the Law, Lexington, Lexington Books. Klevorick, Alvin K. and Rothschild, Michael (1979), ‘A Model of the Jury Decision Process’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 141-164. Kornhauser, Lewis A. and Sager, Lawrence G. (1986), ‘Unpacking the Court’, 96 Yale Law Journal, 82-117. Landes, William M. (1971), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Courts’, 14 Journal of Law and Economics, 61-107. Landes, William M. (1993), ‘Sequential versus Unitary Trials: An Economic Analysis’, 22 Journal of Legal Studies, 99-134. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1975), ‘The Independent Judiciary in an Interest Group Perspective’, 18 Journal of Law and Economics, 875 ff. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1979), ‘Adjudication as a Private Good’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 235-284. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1980), ‘Legal Change, Judicial Behavior and the Diversity Jurisdiction’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 367 ff. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1994), ‘The Economics of Anticipatory Adjudication’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 683-720. Levin, Martin A. (1975), ‘Delay in Five Criminal Courts’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 83-131. Martin, Donald L. (1972), ‘The Economics of Jury Conscription’, 80 Journal of Political Economy, 680-702. Melumad, Nahum D. and Thoman, Lynda (1990), ‘On Auditors and the Courts in an Adverse Selection Setting’, 28 Journal of Accounting Research, 77-120. Miller, Arthur R. (1984), ‘The Adversary System: Dinosaur or Phoenix’, 69 Minnesota Law Review, 1-37. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1989), ‘Comment: Some Thoughts on the Equilibrium Hypothesis’, 69 Boston University Law Review, 561-568. Noam, Eli M. (1981), ‘A Cost-benefit Model of Criminal Courts’, 3 Research in Law and Economics, 173-183. Noll, Roger G. (1992), ‘Judicial Review and the Power of the Purse: Comment’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 211-13. Pastor, Santos (1990a), ‘Economìa de la Justicia (I) y (II)’ (Economics of the Judicature), 5 and 6 Revista de Economìa Pública. Pastor, Santos (1990b), ‘Economìa de la Justicia en España (The Spanish Courts and the Economic
7100
Judicial Organization and Administration
43
Analysis)’, Revista de Economìa, 4 ff. Pastor, Santos (1991), ‘Informe sobre la Litigación, Recursos y Acceso de los Cuidadanos a la Justicie’ (Report on Litigation, Courts Inputs and Access to Justice)’, In Ministerio De Justicia, Materiales para una Reforma Procesal, Madrid. Posner, Richard A. (1973), ‘An Economic Approach to Legal Procedure and Judicial Administration’, 2 Journal of Legal Studies, 399-458. Posner, Richard A. (1983), ‘Will the Federal Courts of Appeals Survive until 1984? An Essay on Delegation and Specialization of the Judicial Function’, 56 Southern California Law Review, 761-791. Posner, Richard A. (1984), ‘The Meaning of Judicial Self-Restraint’, 59 Indiana Law Journal, 1-24. Posner, Richard A. (1985), The Federal Courts: Crisis and Reform, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 365 p. Posner, Richard A. (1986), ‘The Summary Jury Trial and Other Methods of Alternative Dispute Resolution: Some Cautionary Observations’, 53 University of Chicago Law Review, 366-393. Posner, Richard A. (1989), ‘Coping with the Caseload: A Comment on Magistrates and Masters’, 137 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 2215-2218. Priest, George L. (1989), ‘Private Litigants and the Court Congestion Problem’, 69 Boston University Law Review, 527-559. Ramseyer, J. Mark (1994), ‘The Puzzling (In)dependence of Courts: A Comparative Approach’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 721-47. Revesz, Richard L. (1990), ‘Specialized Courts and the Administrative Lawmaking System’, 138 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1111 ff. Scheiner, Alan Howard (1991), ‘Judicial Assessment of Punitive Damages, the Seventh Amendment, and the Politics of Jury Power’, 91 Columbia Law Review, 142-226. Schwartz, Edward P. and Schwartz, Warren F. (1992), ‘Decision making by Juries Under Unanimity and Supermajority Voting Rules’, 80 Georgetown Law Journal, 775-907. Schwartz, Edward P. and Schwartz, Warren F. (1995), ‘Deciding Who Decides Who Dies: Capital Punishment as a Social Choice Problem’, 1 Legal Theory, 113-148. Schwartz, Edward P. and Schwartz, Warren F. (1996a), Simple Majority Rule for Criminal Jury Trials: The Verdict is Now In, manuscript. Schwartz, Edward P. and Schwartz, Warren F. (1996b), ‘The Challenge of Peremptory Challenges’, 12 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 325 ff. Shanley, Michael G. (1991), ‘The Distribution of Posttrial Adjustments to Jury Awards’, 20 Journal of Legal Studies, 463-481. Shavell, Steven (1988), ‘Legal Advice about Contemplated Acts: The Decision to Obtain Advice, Its Social Desirability, and Protection of Confidentiality’, 17 Journal of Legal Studies, 123-150. Shavell, Steven (1992), ‘Liability and the Incentive to Obtain Information about Risk’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 259-270. Shavell, Steven (1995), ‘Alternative Dispute Resolution: An Economic Analysis’, 24 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-28. Sociaal Cultureel Planbureau (1990), Doelmatig Rechtspreken (Efficient Administration of Justice), S.C.P. 88, ’s-Gravenhage, Staatsdrukkerij, 74 ff. Stearns, Maxwell (1995), ‘Standing Back from the Forest: Justiciability and Social Choice’, 83 California Law Review, 1309-1413.
44
Judicial Organization and Administration
7100
Stearns, Maxwell (1996), ‘How Outcome Voting Promotes Principled Issued Identification: A Reply to Professor John Rogers and Others’, 49 Vanderbilt Law Review, 1045-1067. Straussman, Jeffrey D. (1986), ‘Courts and Public Purse Strings: Have Portraits of Budgeting Missed Something?’, 4 Public Administration Review, 315-351.
7200 APPEAL AND SUPREME COURTS Lewis A. Kornhauser Professor of Law, New York University School of Law © Copyright 1999 Lewis A. Kornhauser
Abstract This chapter surveys the economic literature on judicial appeals and collegiality of courts. More general issues concerning judicial administration and court organization are surveyed in a companion chapter. JEL classification: K4 Keywords: Appellate Courts, Appeals, Adjudication, Supreme Courts
1. Introduction This chapter reviews the literature concerning several issues raised in the economic analysis of appeal and of supreme courts. These issues overlap those considered in Chapter 7100, Judicial Organization and Administration. Appellate courts in general and supreme courts in particular exist only in hierarchically organized court systems. Most of the literature has focused on courts in common law countries. Indeed, most models that extend beyond the simplest features of adjudication do so in the context of the political system of the United States. This review consequently shares the parochial focus of the literature. Analyses of appeal in civil law systems and in the context of different political systems would greatly advance understanding of the subject as they often present different institutional features. At least some civil law systems, for example, allow an appellate court to make an independent assessment of the facts of the case, a judgment denied common law courts. Similarly, the highest courts in some civil law jurisdictions hear substantially more cases than the highest courts in common law countries, a fact that may explain, or be explained by, differences in precedential practice and in the style and content of judicial opinions. 2. Explanations of Hierarchy Appeal, and supreme courts, only arise in court systems which are organized hierarchically. Why does hierarchy occur? Posner (1985) suggested that the primary function of a supreme court was law creation and the insurance of 45
46
Appeal and Supreme Courts
7200
uniformity of application of law among the lower courts. In addition, he argued that, in the United States, concerns about unreviewable power implied that trial courts would be subject to some supervision. These ideas have not been much elaborated in the literature. Rather, two distinct research strategies have emerged from two different models of adjudication. The ‘team’ model assumes that all judges in the system share a common objective function - to maximize the number of ‘correct’ decisions rendered by the system. Hierarchy emerges because it somehow promotes the goal of error minimization. The ‘political’ (or ‘principal-agent’) model assumes that judges differ in their objective functions. Hierarchy arises in this model so that the small set of politically dominant judges can enforce their views on recalcitrant judges lower in the hierarchy. Kornhauser (1995) provides an informal team model that explicitly addresses the question of the optimal organization of n judges into a judicial system. Judges share the goal of minimizing the number of errors; the likelihood of a correct decision depends on the amount of effort the judge invests in deliberation on the case. Moreover, deliberation on a specific case also provides a signal about the correct resolution of ‘nearby’ cases. Because the court faces a resource constraint, the question of optimal organization of judges arises. Kornhauser argues that, in appropriate circumstances, a hierarchy will emerge in which there is (a) division of labor between trial judges who find facts and appellate judges who determine the law; and (b) strict vertical stare decisis so that lower court judges will always adhere to the decisions of higher court judges. Models of hierarchy that emphasize the need for consistency as in Rogers (1995) and Dorf (1995) are team models in which the ‘correct decision’ requires consistency.
3. Team Models of Error Correction Shavell (1995) is the earliest formal model of error correction. Shavell assumes that the state must decide first, whether to establish both trial and appellate courts or trial courts only; and second, how many resources to devote to each level of court that it establishes. The probability of correct decision by a court increases with increased allocation of resources to that court. The state seeks to minimize social costs which consist of the costs of the judicial system and the costs created by wrongly decided cases. A trial court is characterized by the probability (as a function of state resources) that it will render the wrong decision. Litigants know for certain whether a court has correctly decided their case. An appellate court is characterized by two probabilities (as functions of state resources devoted to appeal): the probability q(y) that an incorrect trial decision will be reversed on appeal and the probability r(y) that a correct trial decision will be reversed on appeal. Litigants know with certainty whether the
7200
Appeal and Supreme Courts
47
court has rendered a correct decision. Litigants face a cost to appeal. It is straightforward to see that, if q(y) > r(y) and if the court can impose fees or give subsidies for appeal, then the state can insure that only cases wrongly decided at trial will be appealed. Shavell then characterizes the state’s optimal strategy by showing when appellate courts should be created and how resources should be divided between trial and appellate levels. He also shows that litigant selection of cases is superior to the random review of trial court decision. When a court undertakes random review of lower court cases, it unnecessarily uses resources to reconsider some correctly decided cases; under litigant selection (with the appropriate subsidies and fees), by contrast, only cases that should be reconsidered are in fact reviewed. Cameron and Kornhauser (1996) offer a more strategic model of error correction that formalizes a portion of the argument in Kornhauser (1995). Their paper divides into two distinct parts. First, they identify conditions under which it would be desirable to add an additional level of appeal to a court structure. They define the selectivity of a process as the ratio of the proportion of wrongly decided cases that would be appealed to a new tier to the proportion of correctly decided cases that would be appealed to a new tier. They define the error correction ratio as the ratio of the probability that the new appellate court would reverse a wrongly decided case on appeal to the probability that the new appellate court would uphold a rightly decided case on appeal. They prove that an additional tier of review is desirable if the appeals process is sufficiently selective or sufficiently error correcting. The second part of Cameron and Kornhauser’s argument considers a particular technology of review. The correct decision of a case depends on the defendant’s type which, initially, is known to the defendant but not to the plaintiff. At trial, the plaintiff, but not the court, becomes fully informed about the defendant’s type. A court’s ability to discriminate among defendant types is a function of the effort it invests in the case. Litigants incur a cost each time they appeal. Judges seek first to maximize the number of correct decisions; in addition a judge prefers not to be reversed. Cameron and Kornhauser show that, when litigants select cases for appeal, the hierarchy will have three tiers. They also study the process when the appellate courts select cases for review.
4. Political Models of Review 4.1 Models of Pure Adjudication Political models generally justify appellate review in terms of law making. They do this in large part because the structure of the model requires that interpretation. Each court usually has preferences over policy space. Thus, to
48
Appeal and Supreme Courts
7200
decide a case is to announce a policy, or, put differently, to announce a new legal rule. Cameron (1993) presents the political model of review in its starkest form. There is one supreme court and n lower courts. Each court has spatial preferences over a one-dimensional policy space. There is complete information so that each lower court knows the supreme court’s ideal point and the supreme court knows the location in policy space of the decision of each lower court. Each lower court seeks to maximize its utility which depends only on the final decision in the case it decides; the supreme court wants to maximize its utility which is a function of the decisions in all cases. The game has two stages: in stage 1, each lower court issues a decision; in stage 2, the supreme court selects at most only one case for review. There is a unique equilibrium to this game in which each lower court decides its case by announcing the ideal policy point of the supreme court as its decision and the supreme court reviews no case because it has already achieved its optimum utility. No other pattern of lower court decisions is an equilibrium because, in any other pattern, the lower court that will be reversed on appeal has an incentive to alter its strategy. McNollgast (1995) offers a more elaborate political model, which focuses on conflicts in the policy views of the supreme court, the legislature and the lower courts. To enforce its views the supreme court must both induce lower courts to adhere to its ‘doctrine’ and avoid reversal through legislation. McNollgast extends the model of Cohen and Spitzer (1994). They consider a three stage game in which the supreme court first identifies the range of acceptable decisions in policy space. In stage 2, the lower courts decide whether to adhere to supreme court ‘doctrine’. In stage 3, the supreme court reviews some subset of the lower court decisions; the number of cases reviewed is determined by the supreme court’s budget. Each case presents a single issue in a K-dimensional policy space. Each judge has separable, spatial preferences over this policy space, an assumption that reduces a decision in any given case to the framework outlined in Cameron. That is, each judge’s preferences can be represented by an ideal point in each dimension such that she prefers any decision closer to that ideal point to one further away. The supreme court has preferences defined over the outcomes of all cases decided within the system but each lower court has preferences defined over its case load only. Moreover, the supreme court does not know either the ideal point of any specific court nor the actual decision rendered by a lower court. The supreme court does know the distribution of ideal points of lower courts and it does know whether a lower court has complied with supreme court doctrine. It will thus choose to review some random sample of non-complying lower courts; upon review it will learn their actual decisions. Several results flow from this model. First, in general, some but not all lower courts will comply with supreme court doctrine; compliance, however, results from the threat of enforcement. Second, the game
7200
Appeal and Supreme Courts
49
has a unique Bayesian equilibrium. Third, as the costs of enforcement rise, the supreme court may expand the range of acceptable lower court decisions. 4.2 Models of Adjudication Embedded in a Constitutional System Many if not most cases on the appellate docket do not present common law issues; rather they raise issues of statutory or constitutional interpretation. The decisions of the courts thus rely on, and affect, the decisions of other political actors including administrative agencies, legislatures and the executive. Most applications of the political model to adjudication have concerned these institutional relations. The two earliest applications to adjudication appear to be Ferejohn and Shipan (1990) and Gely and Spiller (1990). They adopt similar but not identical frameworks. Specifically, Ferejohn and Shipan assumed that all political actors had preferences over a one-dimensional policy space while Gely and Spiller assumed that institutional actors had preferences over a multi-dimensional policy space. I set out the Ferejohn and Shipan model here because of its simplicity and because most subsequent models exploit their formulation. Gely and Spiller (1990) is discussed in Section 5 in the context of its interesting model of doctrine. Ferejohn and Shipan analyze the effects of judicial review on the activities of administrative agencies. In addition to the assumption of a one-dimensional policy space, their results depend critically on the sequence in which the institutions act. In their model, the agency acts first. It is then subject to judicial review. The court, in turn, is subject to potential legislative overrides. (They study both the case of overrides that require a presidential veto and those that do not.) They show that judicial review may shift the equilibrium policy towards the policy preferred by the legislature. Eskridge and Ferejohn (1992a, 1992b) use the model in Ferejohn and Shipan to analyze the balance of powers in the US Constitution in general and the effect of INS vs. Chadha, on that balance of power. Chadha ruled that legislative vetoes of administrative action were unconstitutional. According to Eskridge and Ferejohn this ruling shifted power to the agencies; put differently, the decision made Congressional delegations of power to administrative agencies less desirable. The literature employing variants of this political model have proliferated. For instance, Gely and Spiller (1992) present a three-stage game in which, in the first stage, an administrative agency announces an interpretation of a statute; in the second stage the court reviews the agency interpretation; and in the third stage the legislature decides whether to overrule the Supreme court and announce its own policy outcome. Note that in each stage the interpretation is an announcement of a policy. Each actor has spatial preferences over a one dimensional policy space. The model predicts that the court will always pick
50
Appeal and Supreme Courts
7200
that policy that is best for it and just avoids legislative overruling. Gely and Spiller investigate several variants of this structure in which the legislature is modeled somewhat differently. They then test their model on data from the United States National Labor Relations Board and subsequent review. Cohen and Spitzer (1994) apply this political model to the analysis of the effects of another Supreme Court decision, Chevron U.S. A. Inc. v. Natural Resources Defense Council Inc, which required courts to grant more deference to an administrative agency’s own interpretation of statutes it implemented. They assume political actors have preferences over policy-deference pairs. They then show that the Supreme Court’s rulings on deference respond to the relative pattern of policy preferences among the other institutional actors: president, congress, and the appellate court. Toma (1991, 1996) has argued that the congressional budgetary process serves as a means to control the decisions of the Supreme Court by signaling approval or disapproval of the Court’s behavior. Again, both justices and Congress have spatial preferences over policy space. She examines two times series of decisions of the Supreme Court of the United States: one consists of civil liberties cases decided from 1946 through 1988 and the other of economic liberties cases decided over the same time period. She determines the ‘average degree of liberality’ of each of these two yearly portfolios of decision and similarly takes the average ADA rating of the members of the judiciary subcommittee of the Senate and House appropriations committees. For each group of cases, she then regresses the size of the yearly Supreme Court budget on the divergence between the judicial and congressional liberality ratings; she finds a statistically significant pattern with the budget rising when Supreme Court opinions conform more closely to the views of Congress. She then regresses the liberality of the judicial portfolio against the Supreme Court budget, the parameter of which is also statistically significant. 4.3 Some Other Empirical Studies There is a vast American political science literature that seeks to determine the effects of the ‘ideological’ views of the judges on judicial decisions. This literature in general implicitly accepts the political model of adjudication and it generally finds at least some influence of ‘ideology’ on outcome, where the judge’s ideology is measured either by her political affiliation or the affiliation of the appointing president. In this section, I consider three recent studies within the legal-economic framework. The first study, Eisenberg and Johnson (1991), examined 118 federal district court opinions and 66 federal circuit court opinions in racial discrimination cases decided under the fourteenth amendment to the US Constitution. These opinions constituted all opinions on this issue published between 7 June 1976 and 6 February 1988. Eisenberg and Johnson found no
7200
Appeal and Supreme Courts
51
effect of ideology, measured either by party of judge or of appointing president, on outcomes at either the district or appellate level. They attempted to evaluate the effects of the selection of cases for trial on their results by comparing trial success rates and success rates on appeal in the class of cases that they studied to these success rates in other classes of cases. Ashenfelter, Eisenberg and Schwab (1995) (‘AES’) also found no effects of ideology. In a clever research design, they studied 2258 federal civil rights and prisoner cases filed in three federal districts courts in fiscal 1981. Unlike most prior studies, AES examined the effects of ideology not only on cases with published opinions but on all case dispositions. AES determined whether a case settled and, if it did not settle, which party prevailed. They also collected data, including party and party of appointing president, on each of the 47 different judges who sat on some case in the sample. AES then analyzed this data by district. This district analysis permitted them to exploit the federal practice of random assignment of cases to judges. Any observed differences in behavior across judges could be attributed to differences in judges rather than differences in cases. They found that judges had relatively little effect on case disposition. Moreover, ‘ideological’ variables did not explain the small effects observed. Revesz (1997) studied the industry and environmental challenges to EPA rulemaking in the 1970s and the late 1980s through early 1990s. This sample of cases has two features that make it a nearly ideal sample for analysis. First, all such challenges were heard in the Court of the Appeals for the District of Columbia. Second, virtually all challenges to EPA rulemaking are appealed. Given the legal context, there is no opportunity for the agency to settle with dissatisfied litigants. Following AES, Revesz focused on time periods in which a large number of judges had continuous tenure on the Circuit; he restricted his analysis to these judges. He measured the judge’s policy preferences by the party of the appointing president, assuming that Republicans would favor industry challenges and disfavor environmental challenges relative to Democrats. For the late 1980s through early 1990s, he observed that ideology had a clear effect on industry challenges and a more ambiguous effect on environmental challenges. (A different statistical test, however, would likely reveal a stronger ideological effect in environmental challenges.)
5. Modeling Doctrine Courts in common law systems do more than announce an outcome ‘upheld’ or ‘reverse’ to an appeal. An opinions offers a rationale for the decision and it is this rationale which guides the decisions of lower courts. To study appeal, then, the analyst must model this ‘doctrinal’ structure. The literature reveals two distinct approaches to modeling doctrine, approaches that have already
52
Appeal and Supreme Courts
7200
been alluded to in the prior discussion. The importance of the issue, however, merits a brief exposition of the two approaches. One approach, first set forth in Kornhauser (1992b), describes a case as a vector of fact characteristics. Kornhauser then defines a cause of action as a pair (S,f) where S is a class of subsets S of the fact space and f is a collection of functions fS from each subset S into a two-element set that might be interpreted as (proven, unproven) or (for plaintiff, for defendant). Each S in S is an issue. A case is then a collection of causes of action. For plaintiff to prevail on a case, she must prevail on at least one cause of action; to prevail on a cause of action, the plaintiff must prevail on every issue. The approach models doctrine essentially in terms of a partition on the fact space and sees the development of the law in terms of changes in this partition. The approach has been followed in Kornhauser (1995), Cameron and Kornhauser (1996) and Cameron, Siegel, and Songer (1996). The second approach, which adapts the framework of Ferejohn and Shipan and has been employed by Schwartz (1992), Cohen and Spitzer (1994) and McNollgast (1995), assumes that the Supreme Court has preferences over a two-dimensional space. One dimension remains the policy space in the original political model. The second dimension, variously called ‘deference’ or ‘precedent’, explicitly measures the judge’s level of tolerance for deviation from her optimal policy choice. In one sense, this modeling strategy parallels that of the first approach; it also yields a partition of the policy space. More fundamentally, however, this second approach remains inherently ‘political’ and non-legal; it makes no reference to the facts of a case or features of legal discourse that appear in an opinion. Gely and Spiller (1990) offer a variant of this political model of doctrine that acknowledges some of the structure captured in the legal model. In their model, justices (and other political actors) have preferences over a multidimensional policy space. They seek to explain the Court’s choice of grounds - constitutional or non-constitutional - for the Court’s review of agency action. They argue that a constitutional decision restricts the discretion of the agency (or of other political actors) by lowering the dimensionality of the policy space from which the agency may choose a policy. This ingenious idea captures the effect of doctrine without requiring that one model the legal attention to facts and explicit doctrinal structure. In political models, ‘doctrine’ generally serves to explain the extent of discretion granted to lower courts (or administrative agencies). Thus, Cohen and Spitzer (1994) argue that the amount of discretion is a function of the ideological alignment of the Supreme Court relative to other political actors. McNollgast (1995) prove that, as the number of cases in a particular area increases, the amount of discretion granted lower courts never decreases and it may increase.
7200
Appeal and Supreme Courts
53
6. Collegiality Generally, an appeal is decided by a panel of judges rather than a single judge. In the United States, the three judge panels that sit on federal intermediate appeals courts are drawn from a larger bank of judges while the nine justices of the Supreme Court sit en banc. The inverted pyramidal structure of the federal hierarchy in the United States in which the size of the panel deciding a case increases as the case rises through the system is a nearly universal feature of court systems. The highest courts in some civil law countries (for example, the Cour de Cassation in France), however, function similarly to the federal intermediate courts, with each case decided by a panel drawn from a larger bench. Collegiality presents several puzzles. First, why are appellate courts collegial and why does the number of judges increase as one proceeds up the hierarchy? Second, what consequences for adjudication does collegiality have? The economic literature began with Easterbrook (1982) which addressed the second question. 6.1 Why Are Appellate Courts Collegial? Posner (1985, p. 12) offered several reasons for the existence of collegiality on the Supreme Court: (a) multiple judges reduce the costs of poor appointments; (b) a multiplicity of judges reduces the power of any single judge on a court which has vast power; (c) a multiplicity of judges allows the court to benefit from deliberation; and (d) a multiplicity of judges permits the division of the labor of opinion drafting and hence increases the productivity of the court. Kornhauser and Sager (1986) provided a more systematic analysis of the reasons for collegiality. First, they distinguished two conceptions of adjudication: the rendering of judgment and the expression of preferences. They then suggested three different models of collegial adjudication, each of which identified a distinct standard against which to measure judicial performance. (1) One might view collegial courts as engaged in the aggregation of the preferences of the judges on the court and one would measure the quality of the court by its authenticity, the extent to which the court’s judgment correctly reflects the preferences of the judges. (2) One might view collegial courts as engaged in the aggregation of judgments and one would evaluate the court’s procedures in terms of their accuracy, that is, their ability to ‘get the right answer’ however one defines the right outcome. (3) One might view collegial courts as representative institutions that seek to reach the outcome that the represented body would have reached had they deliberated and voted. This representative model suggests two different evaluative measures: fit, which is simply the tendency to arrive at results that the represented group would have reached and reliability, which is the absence of bad surprises.
54
Appeal and Supreme Courts
7200
Kornhauser and Sager reject preference aggregation as an appropriate understanding of adjudication. This eliminates authenticity as an evaluative measure. They then argue that increasing the numbers of judges improves accuracy, fit and reliability. They focus specifically on accuracy and rely on the Condorcet Jury Theorem. Good and Tullock (1984) offers a representation model of Supreme court collegiality. The Justices of the Supreme Court are treated as a representative sample of the population of competent lawyers. Good and Tullock calculate the probability p(r,s) that a case decided by a vote of r to s will fit the decision of the represented group. They determine that p(5,4) = 0.62304 and p(9,0) = 0.99902. 6.2 Consistency and Coherence In the first model of collegiality, Easterbrook (1982) relied on simple social choice arguments to argue that one could not expect the Supreme Court of the United States to generate a consistent body of case law. Easterbrook assumed that each case presented the Court with a choice between two legal rules to govern a particular doctrinal realm. When more than two legal rules were possible and no rule was a Condorcet winner, the Court’s case law would cycle as successive cases challenged the prevailing rule with an alternative that a majority of the Court preferred. Kornhauser and Sager (1986) distinguished between consistent and coherent patterns of decisions. A court that decides cases consistently will decide identical cases identically. The definition of coherence was less clear; a court that decides coherently creates a body of law that exhibits the quality of conceptual unity. They then argued that a panel of judges, each of whom had a consistent view of the law would produce a consistent body of law; but a panel of judges, each of whom had a coherent conception of the law, need not yield a coherent body of decisions. Kornhauser (1992a) extended this analysis. Kornhauser identified three different bases of judicial decision: result-bound, rule-bound, and reason-bound decision. In a result-bound decision process, the court is obligated to respect the results of the prior decisions of the court; in a rule-bound process the court is obligated to respect the rule announced in prior cases while a reason bound court respects the reasons provided in prior decisions. He then argued that, with a rule of strict stare decisis, law in a result-bound judicial system will generally be path dependent and consistent. Stearns (1995) offered an analysis of the development of the law in a collegial court that contained elements of both Easterbrook’s and Kornhauser and Sager’s analysis. Stearns, like Easterbrook, viewed adjudication as rule-bound though he abandoned Easterbrook’s assumption that a case presented only two rules. Stearns, however, emphasized the role of both stare decisis and standing doctrine in ameliorating any cycling problems.
7200
Appeal and Supreme Courts
55
6.3 Voting on Collegial Courts The doctrinal paradox Kornhauser and Sager (1986) noted a paradoxical feature of collegial adjudication which later attracted extensive comment. Specifically, they considered a case that presented two distinct issues for decision. Legal doctrine determines the relation between the decisions on each issue and the decision on the case. In some circumstances, the procedure the court adopts for aggregating votes will determine the outcome of the case. They discussed two procedures: case-by-case adjudication in which each judge registers her view of how the case should be decided and the court aggregates these votes to reach a majority judgment. Alternatively, each judge may register her view on each issue in the case should be decided; the court then aggregates the votes on each issue and applies the legal doctrine to the issue-by-issue results to reach a judgment in the case. Kornhauser (1992b) named this conflict ‘the doctrinal paradox’ and extended this analysis in several ways. Recall the formalization of doctrine in this article that was summarized in Section 5. A single judge decides a case by deciding each legal issue in each cause of action. To prevail on a cause of action, the plaintiff must prevail on each issue; to prevail in the case, she must prevail on at least one cause of action. On a multi-member court, the two different aggregation methods may lead to different results. Kornhauser showed that the doctrinal paradox was distinct from the Condorcet cycle. When the judges’ orderings of outcomes (described as the vector of outcomes on each issue) yield a Condorcet cycle issue-by-issue and case-by-case voting might not conflict. Conversely, when the judges’ orderings produced a Condorcet winner over outcomes, the issue-by-issue result might differ from the case-by-case result. Finally, he analyzed several actual instances in which the doctrinal paradox arose. Rogers (1991) examined and classified all plurality opinions of the United States Supreme Court. He counted approximately 150 such cases. Of these he identified only eight cases in which the vote of one or two justices effectively resulted in a court aggregation of votes on an issue-by-issue, rather than a case-by-case, basis. He argued further that the limited doctirnal incoherence of case-by-case aggregation was normatively preferable to the inconsistency and indeterminacy that may result from issue-by-issue adjudication. Leonard (1984) found a similar paucity of instances of issue-by-issue aggregation in a study of decisions in criminal cases by the highest courts of Alabama, California, Indiana, and New York. Rogers based his argument for case-by-case voting on the grounds that issue-by-issue adjudication may lead to unfair results. Post and Salop (1992) argued that collegial courts should always aggregate votes issue-by-issue. They did so on several grounds. First, they disputed the unfairness of case-by-case aggregation. Second, they argued that case-by-case aggregation led to path-dependent decision making; framed more positively,
56
Appeal and Supreme Courts
7200
they argued that an aggregation procedure should yield the same results regardless of the order in which cases arrive before the court. Third, issue-by-issue aggregation promotes collegial deliberation by inducing the judges to join issue. Post and Salop (1996) expand and clarify their argument in favor of issue-by-issue voting. They note that issue-by-issue voting clarifies the law more quickly than case-by-case voting. Kornhauser and Sager (1993) then extended their earlier analysis of the doctrinal paradox. They emphasized the peculiar nature of actual Supreme Court practice which permitted each judge to count votes as he wished and which suppressed discussion of the aggregation procedure. they argued that the Court should justify its decision on whether to resolve case issue-by-issue or case-by-case because the appropriate decision procedure was context-dependent. Rogers (1996), Stearns (1996) and Post and Salop (1996) then recapitulated the debate over the appropriate aggregation method. Rogers noted importantly that issue-by-issue voting required the Court to identify a set of issues on which each judge should vote and illustrated the complexity of this task. Stearns (1996) argues that in fact agreement on issues is not as difficult as Rogers suggests. Post and Salop (1996) also argue that the identification of issues is less problematic than Rogers asserts. Sincere vs. sophisticated voting Analysis of the doctrinal paradox assumed that each judge voted ‘sincerely’ on each issue regardless of the method of aggregation of the votes on the court. (Defining ‘sincerity’ in the context of multiple issue cases presents difficulties that are addressed in a different voting context in Benoit and Kornhauser (1995).) An assumption of sincerity comports well with a team model; it does not easily fit into a political model. In a political model, a self-interested, rational judge should foresee the results of sincere votes that might be detrimental to the realization of her interests. Spiller and Spitzer (1995) ask whether judges are voting sincerely or with sophistication. They assume a court with one sincere judge and show how that judge can be manipulated by sophisticated judges. In their model, the judges and the legislature play a two-stage game. In stage 1, the Court interprets a statute and in stage 2, the legislature decides whether to overrule the court’s interpretation. All judges and legislators have preferences over a onedimensional policy space. The model predicts that (1) the legislature will frequently overrule the court and (2) coalitions of extremes will often form. They then contend that, as these phenomena are not observed, one should assume that all judges vote with sophistication. Revesz (1997), in his study of environmental decisions by the DC circuit, tested for effects of panel composition on the voting behavior of individual judges. In particular, he asked whether the reversal rate of a judge depended on whether she was in the minority or a majority on the panel. He identified
7200
Appeal and Supreme Courts
57
judicial policy preferences with the party of the appointing president and found substantial differences between the voting behavior of judges in an ideological minority on a panel from those in an ideological majority. Schwartz (1992) does not explicitly address the question of sincere vs. sophisticated voting. He does, however, present a political model of ‘doctrine’ in which each justice acts in a strategic manner. As discussed in Section 4, ‘doctrine’ here refers to a feature of vertical precedent: the probability that a lower court will respect the Supreme Court’s policy announcement in the case. Thus, in this model, justices have preferences over a two-dimensional space. Each justice has an ideal policy; the second dimension measures the degree of precedent that the justice attaches to the policy. The justice’s preferences are for less strict precedent the more distant the announced policy is from his ideal policy. Each case presents the Court with a choice between two policy alternatives. The sequence of the game is as follows. First, the justices vote in reverse order of seniority for one of the two policy alternatives. Second, the senior member of the majority designates an opinion writer who voted for that alternative; the senior member of the minority also designates an opinion writer. Third, each opinion writer drafts an opinion that specifies a level of precedent for the proposed policy. In the fourth stage, the Justices vote between the two policy/precedent pairs represented by the two opinions. The majority vote determines the outcome. Schwartz restricts his analysis to the case in which the Court initially divides five to four between the two policy alternatives. He calculates the range of precedent that is invulnerable to invasion by the minority. The senior member of the majority can then pick an opinion writer that will draft an opinion with the optimal level of precedent from the senior members point of view. Schwartz then illustrates his analysis through a discussion of some reapportionment cases.
7. Discretionary Review The United States Supreme Court has a largely discretionary jurisdiction. This discretion cannot be explained in a team model of error correction when litigants select which cases to appeal, for, as Cameron and Kornhauser (1996) show, the optimal hierarchy will have only three tiers and the highest tier will hear no cases. Discretionary review, however, might be explained in a team model in which the Supreme Court has lawmaking powers. Cameron, Siegal and Songer (‘CSS’) (1996) use a political model to study the Supreme court’s certiorari procedure. They assume that the Supreme Court serves only to correct error. As is typical in political models, both higher and lower courts have preferences over a one-dimensional policy space. As in
58
Appeal and Supreme Courts
7200
Cameron and Kornhauser (1996), each case is characterized by a single parameter and each court is characterized by an ideal point so that defendant should prevail if the value of the case parameter is less than the court’s ideal point. For ease of exposition, CSS assume that the ideal point of the Supreme court lies to the right of the lower court’s ideal point. Consequently, the two courts disagree about the appropriate resolution of the case if its parameter lies in the interval between the two ideal points. The Supreme court has discretionary authority to review but it decides to review the lower court decision on the basis of an index of the parameter rather than the true value which is both known to the lower court and would be revealed to the Supreme Court in the course of a review on the merits. Each court wants to maximize the number of correct decisions (from its point of view); lower courts get disutility from reversal and the Supreme court incurs cost in the event it decides to review a case on the merits. CSS characterize the equilibrium strategies of both lower court and Supreme court. They then present an exploratory analysis of Supreme Court certiorari practice in search and seizure cases between 1972 and 1986. Discretionary review in the US Supreme Court employs a submajority rule of four of the nine justices to trigger review. This submajority review raises interesting legal and strategic questions concerning the behavior of the Justices themselves. Revesz and Karlan (1988) presented a largely legal analysis of this rule (and a ‘Rule of Three’ governing the granting of stays) but their analysis raises a number of issues for economic analysis. They argue that the rule of four creates a legal process with less stable precedent than a process in which discretionary review required a majority.
8. Stare Decisis Stare decisis refers to a set of practices peculiar to Anglo-American courts in which one court adheres to its own prior decisions or to the decisions of a higher court. For a fuller discussion of the legal aspect of these practices, references to the legal literature and the modeling questions they present, see Kornhauser (1998). Several models of horizontal and vertical stare decisis have appeared in the literature. In this section, I shall focus primarily on models of horizontal stare decisis in which a court follows its own prior decisions. Discussions of vertical stare decisis are implicit or explicit in most political models of hierarchy because these models pose as one of the key questions the extent to which lower courts comply with the rulings of higher courts. Vertical stare decisis in a team model is discussed in both Kornhauser (1995) and Cameron and Kornhauser (1996). Kornhauser (1995) argues that vertical stare decisis arises because of the benefits presented by specialization of labor between fact finding and law
7200
Appeal and Supreme Courts
59
making and for error-correction reasons. Cameron and Kornhauser (1996) investigates the error-correction justification in detail. Heiner (1986) argues that stare decisis arises because courts only observe the ‘correct’ answer to specific cases with error. A judge might then do better to announce a decision that is best ‘on average’ (for some class of cases) and adhere to that decision rather than to make a series of errors on a case-by-case basis. Kornhauser (1989) characterized horizontal stare decisis as a practice in which a court adheres to a decision it believes to be wrong. He offers two informal models based on two distinct justifications for the practice. The first model applies to a ‘panel court’ in which each case is decided by one or more judges drawn from a larger bench. If judges have different views of the law then stare decisis serves to reduce legal uncertainty faced by actors governed by the legal rule. The second model assumes a unitary court with an unchanging social objective; the court however faces a world in which the optimal behavior (as viewed from its perspective) changes because some underlying parameters change. Kornhauser’s model modifies that in Blume and Rubinfeld (1982) in which the court, through its announcement of standards of care, seeks to minimize the costs of accidents and the costs of adjustment to new standards. In the Blume and Rubinfeld model, the court does not adopt a practice of stare decisis; rather, as the technology of care shifts, the court adjusts gradually towards the standards that would be optimal in an unchanging world with the new technology. In Kornhauser’s version, a court must announce standards of care in a world in which the technology of accident care is improving at a known rate. The court adheres to stare decisis as long as the standards of care optimal under the new technology are not too far from the old standards. Otherwise it announces new standards that overshoot those currently optimal. Rasmusen (1994) presents a political model for horizontal stare decisis. Rasmusen’s model provides a formal justification for an argument implicit in O’Hara (1993). The court consists of a single judge who decides n + 1 cases and is then replaced by another judge who also decides n + 1 cases. Each judge has preferences over the outcomes of all cases and these preferences differ. Assume that only one of these n + 1 cases is a case of first impression. Under a practice of stare decisis each judge would adhere to the n prior decisions governing n of his cases and n subsequent judges would adhere to the decision he announces in his case of first impression. Rasmusen shows that a practice of stare decisis is an equilibrium to this game.
60
Appeal and Supreme Courts
7200
9. Concluding Remarks The study of judicial organization in general and the nature and function of appeal in particular is in its infancy. Though analysts have begun to investigate the reasons for hierarchy, the nature of the interaction among courts and other political branches, and the internal workings of the courts themselves, most questions remain open or even unaddressed.
Bibliography on Appeal and Supreme Courts (7200) Ashenfelter, Orley, Eisenberg, Theodore and Schwab, Stewart J. (1995), ‘Politics and the Judiciary: The Influence of Judicial Background on Case Outcomes’, 24 Journal of Legal Studies, 257-282. Blume, Larry and Rubinfeld, Daniel (1982), ‘The Dynamics of the Legal Process’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 405 ff. Cameron, Charles M. (1993), New Avenues for Modeling Judicial Politics, University of Rochester Wallis Institute of Political Economy Working Paper. Cameron, Charles and Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1996), ‘Litigant Selection and the Structure of Judicial Hierarch’, mimeo, August. Cameron, Charles M., Siegal, Jeffrey A. and Songer, Donald R. (1996), ‘Signals and Indices in the Supreme Court’s Certiorari Decisions’, mimeo. Cohen, Linda and Spitzer, Matthew (1994), ‘Solving the Chevron Puzzle’, 57 Law and Contemporary Problems, 65 ff. Dorf, Michael C. (1995), ‘Prediction and the Rule of Law’, 42 U.C.L.A. Law Review, 651 ff. Easterbrook, Frank (1982), ‘Ways of Criticizing the Court’, 95 Harvard Law Review, 802-832. Eisenberg, Theodore and Johnson, Sheila Lynn (1991), ‘The effects of Intent: Do We Know How Legal Standards Work?’, 76 Cornell Law Review, 1151 ff. Epstein, Richard A. (1987), ‘Judicial Review: Reckoning on Two Kinds of Error’, in Dorn, James A. and Manne, Henry G. (eds), Economic Liberties and the Judiciary, Fairfax, George Mason University Press, 39-46. Eskridge, William N. and Ferejohn, John (1992a), ‘The Article I, Section 7 Game’, 80 Georgetown Law Journal, 523-564. Eskridge, William N. and Ferejohn, John (1992b), ‘Making the Deal Stick: Enforcing the Original Constitutional Structure of Lawmaking in the Modern Regulatory State’, 8 Journal of Law Economics and Organization, 165-189. Ferejohn, John and Shipan, Charles (1990), ‘Congressional Influence on Bureaucracy’, 6 Journal of Law Economics and Organization, 1-20 (Special Issue). Gely, Rafael and Spiller, Pablo T. (1990), ‘A Rational Choice Theory of Supreme Court Statutory Decisions with Applications to the State Farm and Grove City Cases’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 263-300. Gely, Rafael and Spiller, Pablo T. (1992), ‘The Political Economy of Supreme Court Constitutional Decisions: The Case of Roosevelt’s Court Packing Plan’, 12 International Review of Law and
7200
Appeal and Supreme Courts
61
Economics, 45-67. Good, I.J. and Tullock, Gordon (1984), ‘Judicial Errors and a Proposal for Reform’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 289-298. Heiner, Ronald (1986), ‘Imperfect Decisions and the Law: On the Evolution of Legal Precedent and Rules’, 15 Journal of Legal Studies, 227 ff. Koppen, P.J. van (1990), ‘Cassatieadvocaten en de Selectiekamer (Cassation Lawyers and the Chamber of Selection)’, Nederlands Juristen Blad, 14-26. Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1989), ‘An Economic Perspective on Stare Decisis’, 65 Chicago-Kent Law Review, 63 ff. Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1992a), ‘Modeling Collegial Courts I: Path Dependence’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics; 169-85. Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1992b), ‘Modeling Collegial Courts. II. Legal Doctrine’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 441-70. Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1995), ‘Adjudication by a Resource-Constrained Team: Hierarchy and Precedent in a Judicial System’, 68 Southern California Law Review, 1605 ff. Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1998), ‘Stare Decisis’, in Newman, Peter (ed.), New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law, London, MacMillan. Kornhauser, Lewis A. and Sager, Lawrence G. (1986), ‘Unpacking the Court’, 96 Yale Law Journal, 82-117. Kornhauser, Lewis A. and Sager, Lawrence (1993), ‘The One and the Many: Adjudication in Collegial Courts’, 81 California Law Review, 1 ff. Leonard, David P. (1984), ‘The Correctness Function of Appelate Decision-making: Judicial Obligation in an Era of Fragmentation’, 17 Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review, 299-352. McNollgast (1995), ‘Politics and the Courts: A Positive Theory of Judicial Doctrine and the Rule of Law’, 68 Southern California Law Review, 1631-1683. O’Hara, Erin (1993), ‘Social Constraint on Implicit Collision?: Towards a Gane Recretic Analysis of Stern Decisis’, 24 Seton Hall Law Review, 734 ff. Posner, Richard A. (1982), ‘Toward an Economic Theory of Federal Jurisdiction’, 6 Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy, 41-50. Posner, Richard A. (1985), The Federal Courts: Crisis and Reform, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 365 ff. Post, David and Salop, Steven (1992), ‘Rowing Against the Tidewater: A Theory of Voting by Multi Judge Panels’, 80 Georgetown Law Journal, 743 ff. Post, David and Salop, Steven (1996), ‘Issues and Outcomes, Guidance, and Indeterminacy: A Reply to Professor John Rogers and Others’, 49 Vanderbilt Law Review, 1049-1085. Rasmusen, Eric (1994), ‘Judicial Legitimacy as a Repeated Game’, 10 Journal of Law Economics and Organization, 63-83. Revesz, Richard L. (1997), ‘Environmental Regulation, Ideology, and the D.C. Circuit’, 83 Virginia Law Review. Revesz, Richard L. and Karlan, Pamela (1988), ‘Non Majority Rules and the Supreme Court’, 136 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1067 ff. Rogers, John M. (1991), ‘“I Vote This Way Because I’m Wrong”: The Supreme Court Justice as Epimenides’, 79 Kentucky Law Journal, 439-475. Rogers, John M. (1995), ‘Lower Court Application of the “Overruling Law” of Higher Courts’, 1 Legal Theory, 179 ff. Rogers, John (1996), ‘“Issue Voting” by Multi Member Appellate Courts: A Response to Some Radical Proposals’, 49 Vanderbilt Law Review, 997-1039.
62
Appeal and Supreme Courts
7200
Schwartz, Edward P. (1992), ‘Policy, Precedent, and Power: A Positive Theory of Supreme Court Decision Making’, 8(2) Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 219-52. Shavell, Steven (1995), ‘The Appeals Process as a Means of Error Correction’, 24(2) Journal of Legal Studies’, 379-426. Spiller, Pablo and Spitzer, Matthew (1992), ‘Judicial Choice of Legal Doctrines’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 846 ff. Spiller, Pablo and Spitzer, Matthew (1995), ‘Where is the Sine in Sincere? Sophisticated Manipulation of Sincere Judicial Voters (With Applications to Other Voting Environments)’, 11 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 32-63. Stearns, Maxwell (1995), ‘Standing Back from the Forest: Justiciability and Social Choice’, 83 California Law Review, 1309-1413. Stearns, Maxwell (1996), ‘How Outcome Voting Promotes Principled Issue Identification: A Reply to Professor John Rogers and Others’, 49 Vanderbilt Law Review, 1045-1067. Stith, Kate (1990), ‘The Risk of Legal Error in Criminal Cases: Some Consequences of the Asymmetry in the Right to Appeal’, 57 University of Chicago Law Review, 1-61. Toma, Eugenia (1991), ‘Congressional Influence and the Supreme Court: The Budget as a Signaling Device’, 20 Journal of Legal Studies, 131-146. Toma, Eugenia (1996), ‘A Contractual Model of the Voting Behavior of the Supreme Court: The Role of the Chief Justice’, 16 International Review of Law and Economics, 433-447.
Other References Benoit, Jean-Pierre and Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1995), ‘Assembly-Based Preferences, Candidate-Based Procedures, and the Voting Rights Act’, 68 Southern California Law Review, 1503 ff.
Cases INS vs. Chadha, 462 U.S. 919 (1983) Chevron U.S.A. Inc. v. Natural Resources Defense Council Inc, 467 U.S. 837 (1984)
7300 INDEMNITY OF LEGAL FEES Avery Wiener Katz Georgetown University © Copyright 1999 Avery Wiener Katz
Abstract This chapter surveys the effects of legal fee shifting on a variety of decisions arising before and during the litigation process. Section 2 provides a brief survey of the practical situations in which legal fee shifting does and does not arise. Section 3 analyzes the effects of indemnification on the incentives to expend resources in litigated cases. Section 4 examines how indemnification influences the decisions to bring and to defend against suit, and Section 5 assesses its effects on the choice between settlement and trial. Section 6 addresses the interaction between the allocation of legal fees and the parties’ incentives for efficient primary behavior. Section 7 considers two important variants on simple indemnification: rules that shift costs based on the parties’ settlement negotiations (such as US Federal Rule 68 and the English practice of payment into court), and rules that shift costs based on the margin of victory (such as US Federal Rule 11 and the common law tort of malicious prosecution). Section 8 reviews the brief but instructive empirical literature on legal cost shifting, and Section 9 summarizes the discussion and offers conclusions. JEL classification: K40, K41 Keywords: Litigation, Legal Costs, Legal Fees, Legal Fee Shifting
1. Introduction In most Western legal systems, a party who prevails in litigation is generally entitled to indemnification from the losing party for at least part of his or her economic costs of prosecuting the lawsuit. The amount of litigation expenditures that can be recovered, however, varies substantially both among and within individual regimes. In the United States, the predominant rule awards a prevailing litigant what are officially termed ‘costs’ - typically defined by statute to include filing fees, court reporter charges, printing, copying, and witness fees, and the like - but does not entitle him or her to recover expenditures on attorneys’ fees, which are of far greater magnitude in the usual case. Consequently, US litigants can bear significant expense even when they are ultimately vindicated on the merits. In the other 63
64
Indemnity of Legal Fees
7300
common-law countries, in contrast, and indeed in most of the rest of the Western world, winning litigants are entitled to recover attorneys’ fees as well as other out-of-pocket costs of litigation. As a result, they come closer to being made whole than do winning litigants in the US. The substantial increase in expenditures on litigation and dispute resolution in the United States in recent years has led both policymakers and scholars to advocate a variety of substantive and procedural reforms in the legal system. The rules for allocating attorneys’ fees in civil litigation have drawn particular attention in this regard, with a number of influential commentators recommending a move in the direction of fuller indemnification - or what in the US is usually called, for historical reasons, the ‘English’ or ‘British’ rule. Such recommendations have begun to have influence on both public and private lawmakers; indeed, one of the more prominent and widely supported provisions in the Republican Party’s 1994 ‘Contract with America’ platform would have adopted a modified form of the English rule for federal cases brought under the diversity jurisdiction. But the political debate over litigation costs in the US does not seem to have assimilated the main lesson of the economic literature on the topic - that the effects of cost shifting on the amount and intensity of litigation are substantially more complicated than a superficial consideration of the matter might suggest. Indeed, the current state of economic knowledge does not enable us reliably to predict whether a move to fuller indemnification would raise or lower the total costs of litigation, let alone whether it would better align those costs with any social benefits they might generate. The reason for this agnostic conclusion is straightforward. Legal costs influence all aspects of the litigation process, from the decision to file suit to the choice between settlement and trial to the question whether to take precautions against a dispute in the first place (for a survey of such effects, see Cooter and Rubinfeld, 1989). Furthermore, as Shavell (1982b) has shown, an individual litigant’s incentives to bring suit in a costly legal system do not generally conform to the social optimum; and the divergence between private and social incentives to sue are complex. A plaintiff’s decision to sue imposes an obvious cost on the defendant and on the taxpayers who foot the bill for public legal institutions. Less obviously, it affects litigants in other cases by crowding the courts, by delaying the resolution of other disputes in the system, and, through informational externalities, by altering the expected costs of settlement. It also affects future litigants by increasing the stock of legal precedent, and potential litigants (as well as those who never intend to resort to the courts at all) by influencing the perceived likelihood of sanctions for violating substantive legal duties. Similarly, the decisions to pursue a lawsuit to trial rather than settling, and to litigate more rather than less intensively, generate analogous
7300
Indemnity of Legal Fees
65
external costs and benefits. The combination of all these external effects are too complicated to be remedied by a simple rule of ‘loser pays’. Instead, indemnity of legal fees remedies some externalities while failing to address and even exacerbating others. This chapter, accordingly, surveys the effects of legal fee shifting on a variety of decisions arising before and during the litigation process. Section 2 provides a brief survey of the practical situations in which legal fee shifting does and does not arise. Section 3 analyzes the effects of indemnification on the incentives to expend resources in litigated cases. Section 4 examines how indemnification influences the decisions to bring and to defend against suit, and Section 5 assesses its effects on the choice between settlement and trial. Section 6 addresses the interaction between the allocation of legal fees and the parties’ incentives for efficient primary behavior. Section 7 considers two important variants on simple indemnification: rules that shift costs based on the parties’ settlement negotiations (such as US Federal Rule 68 and the English practice of payment into court), and rules that shift costs based on the margin of victory (such as US Federal Rule 11 and the common-law tort of malicious prosecution). Section 8 reviews the brief but instructive empirical literature on legal cost shifting, and Section 9 summarizes the discussion and offers conclusions. (N.B.: The scholarly literature on fee shifting has flourished in recent years, to the point where it is no longer feasible to discuss every pertinent contribution. For recent surveys of work in the area, see Cooter and Rubinfeld (1989), Anderson (1996), and the symposia appearing in Law and Contemporary Problems (1984) and Chicago-Kent Law Review (1996) respectively.)
2. The Practical Extent of Legal Fee Shifting This chapter does not attempt to survey the law governing fee shifting, either in the US or elsewhere. For such surveys, see Pfennigstorf (1984), Note (1984), or Tomkins and Willging (1986). It should be recognized, however, that there are significant areas of US legal practice that do not follow the traditional American rule. Most important among these are the various federal and state statutes that entitle a successful plaintiff, though not a successful defendant, to court-awarded attorneys’ fees as part of a recovery. Similar ‘one-way’ fee-shifting policies have also been established in both federal and state courts through a combination of statutory interpretation and common law development, though the scope for such interpretations at the federal level was substantially limited by the Supreme Court in Alyeska Pipeline Service Co. v. Wilderness Society. Such provisions and policies, which make up a central part of litigation practice in such fields as civil
66
Indemnity of Legal Fees
7300
rights, consumer, and antitrust law, have only some of the effects of the traditional two-way English rule. Second, both federal and state courts have authority to award indemnification to parties who are victimized by abuse of process, though such authority is typically exercised only in response to egregious behavior. Examples include the provisions in Fed. R. Civ. Proc. 11 dealing with frivolous or improper pleadings, and those in Fed. R. Civ. Proc. 37 relating to discovery abuse. US practice also provides litigants with an ‘offer-of-judgment’ procedure under which a defendant can make a settlement offer to the plaintiff which, if rejected and filed with the court, creates a trigger for partial indemnification. Both of these specialized types of provisions - sanctions for abuse and offers of judgment - are discussed separately in Section 7 below. Conversely, even in jurisdictions following the majority or ‘English’ rule, indemnification for legal costs is substantially less than complete. Court-awarded attorneys’ fees obviously do not compensate for the nonmonetary and psychic costs of litigation. Even the monetary amounts awarded, furthermore, are limited by the judge’s view of what expenditures are reasonable and, in some jurisdictions (for example, British Columbia), by statutory schedule. Such judicial and statutory caps can and often do hold fee awards below the going market rate for legal representation, forcing winning litigants to pay the difference out of anticipated recoveries or their own pockets (indeed, Leubsdorf, 1984, presents evidence that such court-imposed price ceilings were responsible for the historical development of the American rule in the first place). Accordingly, the pure English and American rules discussed below should be understood as ideal polar cases, and the differences among actual jurisdictional practices as ones of degree along a spectrum ranging from lesser to greater indemnification . Additionally, Donohue (1991b) points out that the American rule is a default rule rather than a mandatory one, in that parties are generally free to provide for indemnification through private contract - either at the time they begin their litigation or, for those disputes arising out of a consensual relationship, in their original agreement. He presents anecdotal evidence that such ex ante indemnification terms are widespread, though the provisions he cites seem primarily to be drawn from standardized form contracts and tend to operate asymmetrically in favor of the drafting party: for instance, apartment leases that indemnify landlords but not tenants for attorneys’ fees in the event of a dispute over unpaid rent. The scope for fee shifting in the US, therefore, may be significantly greater than is ordinarily supposed. Conversely, there is no apparent bar in England or in the other jurisdictions following the English rule to a partial settlement or stipulation in which the litigants agree in advance to give up their rights to indemnification ex post. Donohue’s further conjectures that such contractual terms are likely to be efficiency-enhancing and that the pattern of such terms
7300
Indemnity of Legal Fees
67
will help reveal whether the English or American rule is more efficient, however, are more problematic. To the extent that indemnification is provided by a one-sided standardized term, there is no guarantee that it promotes the joint interests of the parties. The nondrafting party may fail to notice the indemnification provision at all; and if he does notice it, he may avoid raising it as an issue for fear of revealing himself as someone who anticipates a dispute. Even when such agreements arise out of arms-length bargaining, furthermore, this does not imply that they are efficient. As Bernstein (1993) and Shavell (1995) have observed in their respective analyses of alternative dispute resolution, because of the divergence of private and social incentives in litigation, the fact that a particular agreement is in the litigants’ ex post interest does not necessarily mean that it is socially efficient. The fact that the parties have come to litigation in the first place, moreover, casts doubt on the presumption that they are bargaining in a Coasian fashion.
3. The Effect of Fee Shifting on Trial and Pretrial Expenditures The standard economic theory of litigation, as developed by Landes (1971), Posner (1973) and Gould (1973), models litigating parties as rational actors who seek to maximize their returns from the litigation process. From this perspective, amounts spent on trial preparation can be seen as a type of private investment. An additional hour of legal research or argumentation is profitable, in this view, only if the marginal return, measured by the change in the expected outcome of trial or settlement, outweighs the cost of the attorney’s time. Plaintiffs, accordingly, will choose to spend legal resources up to the point where their expected recoveries, net of expenses, are maximized; defendants will act so as to minimize total payouts. The precise outcome of this contest depends on how the parties react and adjust to each others’ decisions. One simple and natural assumption is that the litigants reach a Nash equilibrium in expenditure; that is, that each takes the other’s expenditure as given when choosing his own. Whatever the nature of the parties’ strategic interaction, however, the parties’ expenditures are determined in equilibrium by a host of economic and technological factors including the stakes of the case, the marginal cost of legal resources, and the sensitivity of trial outcomes to the parties’ individual efforts. In high-stakes cases in which the outcome is heavily dependent on the parties’ work product, expenditures will be high; in petty cases where the outcome is largely predetermined by legal precedent, expenditures will be low. As Braeutigam, Owen and Panzar (1984) first proved and Katz (1987) subsequently explained, it follows from the standard model that fee shifting encourages greater expenditure in litigated cases. The reasons are twofold.
68
Indemnity of Legal Fees
7300
First, fee shifting increases the stakes of the case by making legal expenditures part of the potential damages. Second, it lowers the expected marginal cost of legal expenditure. Each party, when deciding whether to purchase an additional unit of legal services, will discount its cost by the probability with which she expects to win and to be reimbursed by her opponent. More formally: if we let p denote the probability of liability, A the amount awarded if the plaintiff wins, and x and y the amounts spent by the plaintiff and defendant respectively, then under the American rule a plaintiff will expect to recover p(x, y) A(x, y) !x. Assuming risk-neutrality for the sake of simplicity, it follows she will choose x to satisfy the first-order condition, px A + pA x = 1. The defendant, conversely, expects to pay out pA + y, and will select y to satisfy his first-order-condition, py A + pA y = !1. Under the English rule, in contrast, the plaintiff’s expected recovery is pA ! (1 ! p)(x + y); so her first-order-condition is px(A + x + y) + pAx = 1 ! p. Similarly, the defendant’s expected payout is p(A + x + y), and his first-order-condition is py(A + x + y) + pAy = !p. In all of these equations, the left-hand side represents the marginal private benefit of expenditure, and the right-hand side its marginal cost. Inspection of the equations reveals that the marginal private cost of legal expenditure is lower for both parties under the English rule. If the parties’ expenditure affects the probability of liability (that is, if px and py are positive), the marginal private benefit is also higher; if expenditure affects the amount awarded rather than the probability of liability, marginal benefit is unchanged. Other things being equal, therefore, the English rule makes expenditure more attractive. It should be noted that the marginal-cost effect depends not on the actual probability of liability, but on its perceived probability. It follows that the increase in expenditure under the English rule will be greater the more optimistic are the litigants. In the extreme, parties who regard themselves as very likely to win will perceive litigation as virtually costless and will increase their expenditures accordingly. To the extent that such efforts increase the probability of prevailing, therefore, such optimism will be partially self-fulfilling. Similarly, in other than even cases, the marginal-cost effect will be stronger for the party with the stronger probability of prevailing ex ante. For instance, if both parties regard the initial probability of liability as 90 percent, the plaintiff will discount the expected marginal cost of legal services to 10¢ on the dollar while the defendant discounts it only to 90¢. The stimulus to the plaintiff’s expenditure will accordingly be ten times greater than the stimulus to the defendant’s. Fee shifting, accordingly, reinforces the advantages of the party who is initially favored in litigation. Because of the interaction between the parties’ expenditure decisions, it is not possible to prove that both sides will increase their expenditures under the English rule. The reason for this ambiguity is that a marginal increase in
7300
Indemnity of Legal Fees
69
one side’s expenditure has an ambiguous effect on the other’s; it could either provoke the opponent to respond in kind, or intimidate him into reducing his own efforts. Braeutigam, Owen and Panzar, however, showed that in Nash equilibrium the sum of the parties’ expenditures must increase. The extent of the increase depends on how sensitive p and A are to litigation expenditure, as Plott (1987) has demonstrated. Using a Nash equilibrium model and making some simplifying technical assumptions regarding functional form, he found that if the case outcome depends entirely on factors out of the litigants’ control, the English rule has no effect on expenditure. If case outcome is determined solely by their efforts, conversely, the English rule will cause expenditure to increase without limit. Such effects are mitigated in regimes that limit the amount of fees that can be shifted. For example, under both English and US practice, indemnification is limited to reasonable expenditures. Similarly, some recent US proposals provide that a losing party need not pay any indemnification in excess of his or her own litigation costs. Both of these variations reduce the private benefits of legal expenditure relative to the pure English rule; and as Hughes and Woglom (1996) show, the latter actually operates as a tax on the weaker party’s expenditure, since increases in his spending raise the cap on the indemnification potentially payable to his opponent. Furthermore, while most of the economic literature on litigation expenditure has assumed a Nash equilibrium, a few authors (for example, Hersch, 1990) have argued that it is not reasonable to expect litigants to ignore the effect on the other side’s expenditure when choosing their own. The Nash specification is most appealing when expenditure is simultaneous, when each side must choose how much to spend before learning the opponent’s decision, or when the expenditure decision is largely determined by one’s initial choice of an attorney; it is least appealing when one side can commit to a given level of expenditure and communicate that commitment to the opponent in advance. One can analyze the latter situation using the more general model of conjectural variations - so-called because it allows a party’s decision to depend upon his conjectures regarding how the opponent’s decision varies with his own. Formally, let vx denote the rate at which the plaintiff expects the defendant to respond to her expenditures. This rate could be positive (in which case expenditure would be provocative), negative (in which case expenditure would be intimidating), or zero (as in the Nash model). The plaintiff’s first-order condition then becomes (px + vx py)A + p (A x+ vx A y) = 1 under the American rule, and (px + v x py)(A + x + y) + p (A x+ vx A y) = (1 ! p)(1 + vx) under the English rule. (The analysis for the defendant is symmetric and is omitted for the sake of brevity.) Comparing the first term of each equations, one can see that the stakes effect is still present. The direction of the marginal-cost effect, however, is now ambiguous. Under the English rule, an additional dollar
70
Indemnity of Legal Fees
7300
spent on legal services will cost the plaintiff only 1 - p, after she discounts for the probability of prevailing. But if the plaintiff loses, she will also have to pay the defendant’s costs, and the additional dollar induces him to change his expenditures by vx. If the plaintiff’s expenditure is intimidating, this will lower her marginal cost even further. If her expenditure is sufficiently provocative, however, her marginal cost of legal resources will rise; if it is provocative enough to outweigh the stakes effect, her equilibrium expenditure will fall. It is difficult to judge the empirical importance of the conjectural-variations model. Katz (1988) has shown that in the typical case one party is in a provocative position and the other in an intimidating one. In particular situations, however, expenditure may be very provocative. One such context may be civil discovery, the process through which US litigants are permitted to request information from their adversaries before trial. Expenditures on discovery have risen substantially in recent decades, and it has been widely alleged that much of this increase is an abuse of the system, encouraging both frivolous suits and unfair settlements. The underlying problem, however, may simply be one of incentives. As Cooter and Rubinfeld (1994, 1995) and Cooper (1994) explain, a party seeking discovery can under current American practice impose significant costs on her adversary at relatively low cost to herself - for instance, by issuing a formulaic though burdensome list of interrogatories and document requests, or by resisting requests that could be complied with cheaply. For such types of expenditure, the conjectural variation vx is very large; fee shifting, accordingly, may substantially deter ‘abusive’ behavior of this sort. The analysis in this section has focused on the amount of resources expended in litigated cases. Total expenditures on litigation, however, are the product of two factors: expenditures per litigated case, and the number of cases that are actually litigated. Fee shifting can influence the number of litigated cases in two ways: by influencing the decision to bring the dispute to court in the first place, and by influencing the parties’ incentive to settle cases before trial. The next section of this article discusses the former effect, and Section 5 discusses the latter.
4. Effects of Fee Shifting on the Decisions to File and Contest Lawsuits Consider the case of a consumer who has purchased a defective ballpoint pen and who is in theory entitled to a refund. Because the value of the pen is exceeded by even the most streamlined judicial proceeding, the consumer’s threat to litigate is not credible; and absent procedural devices such as a class action that can allow aggregation of her claim with others, she will be
7300
Indemnity of Legal Fees
71
forced to rely on nonlegal incentives such as the seller’s interest in its reputation for goodwill. If the consumer can recover legal fees along with the value of her refund, however, her threat to sue becomes credible. Shavell (1982a), extending the work of Landes (1971) and Gould (1973) on the incentives to sue, generalized this argument to show that the English rule, and indemnification in general, works to encourage lawsuits by plaintiffs with relatively small claims but relatively high ex ante probabilities of victory. The American rule, conversely, encourages plaintiffs with relatively large claims but lower probabilities of victory. The formal logic of the argument is as follows: let p represent the probability of a plaintiff victory, A the expected award if the plaintiff wins, and c the cost of litigation for each litigant. (To simplify the argument, suppose that this cost is the same for both sides; this will affect the specific point at which the incentives switch, but not the basic intuition of the argument.) Under the American rule, litigation is profitable if (and only if) pA > c; thus, a plaintiff will bring suit if she views her chances as better than the threshold probability pUS c/A. Under the English rule, however, the plaintiff’s expected litigation cost is not c but (1 ! p)2c, since she pays no costs if she wins but 2c if she loses. She will accordingly wish to litigate if pA > (1 ! p)2c, or equivalently, if she views her chances at better than pENG2c/(A + 2c). Algebraic manipulation reveals that c > A/2 implies pUS > pENG > ½, and c
72
Indemnity of Legal Fees
7300
knowledge; as Katz (1990) argues, the English rule may do little to discourage strike suits that cannot be identified as such without a trial). But there is a cost to this ostensible increase in justice. The claim and defenses encouraged by the English rule are low-stakes and high-cost - that is, expensive to try relative to their importance. The claims and defenses encouraged by the American rule may be relative longshots on the merits, but they are relatively cheap to resolve. Moreover, some suits, including those brought to test or clarify the law or to settle matters of principle, may be socially desirable notwithstanding a low ex ante probability of success. Accordingly, legal policy in this area may present a tradeoff between justice and more narrow conceptions of efficiency. Any conclusions regarding the effect of litigation fee shifting on incentives to sue must also take account of the litigants’ expected response to risk. As has been widely recognized, the English rule magnifies the private risk arising from litigation by increasing both the returns from success and the losses from defeat. Thus, it tends to discourage risk-averse parties from bringing or defending lawsuits, regardless of the merits of their positions - a factor that has been stressed by partisans of the American rule. What has been less well recognized, however, is that this same increase in variance can encourage more litigation by the risk-neutral. The reason is that most lawsuits are divided into a series of procedural stages, at each of which it is possible to decide whether to continue depending on how the case is going. Because of this flexibility, as Cornell (1990) has shown, the decision to litigate can be interpreted as the purchase of an option. Just as financial options can sell for a positive price even if the probability of exercising them is low, the option value of litigation can make it profitable to put forward claims with negative expected value. Because the value of an option increases with its variance, the English rule, by increasing both the upside and the downside of litigation, intensifies this incentive. Indeed, if parties can drop arguments before trial without penalty, such enhanced option value could increase litigation even by the risk-averse. Additionally, as the previous section indicated, the English rule indirectly alters incentives to sue through its effects on the expected cost of the individual case. Because indemnification encourages parties to litigate their disputes more intensively, it increases the expected cost of bringing and defending suits ex ante. This will deter parties on the margin of litigation from pursuing their cases, whether they are on the margin because of low stakes, high cost, or low probability. This effect is essentially analogous to a tax on litigation; as both Bowles (1987) and Hause (1989) have observed, to the extent it is empirically significant it could outweigh the effects described above. Unless such increased expenditures improve the quality of judicial decision making, however, they must be counted as a disadvantage of the
7300
Indemnity of Legal Fees
73
English rule. Even if it is deemed desirable to deter litigation by raising its private cost, it is plainly more efficient to do so with an excise tax, which merely transfers wealth from litigants to the public fisc, than by wasting real resources. The same objection applies to any policy of deterring litigation through increased risk, which constitutes a real loss for those on whom it is imposed.
5. Effects of Fee Shifting on the Settlement of Litigation Because the great majority of civil cases are settled rather than tried, and because trial substantially increases the cost of disputes, effects on settlement are a critical factor in any comparison of the English and American rules. As a result, the economic literature on fee shifting has focused on this issue more than any other. The conventional wisdom among practicing attorneys appears to be that a shift toward fuller indemnification would encourage settlement. The conclusions of the scholarly literature, however, cannot be said to offer strong support for this proposition; at best the effects are ambiguous. As a first approximation, fee shifting magnifies the effect of litigants’ optimism, making them less likely to settle. As Landes (1971) and Gould (1973) observed, since litigation is a negative-sum game ex post, parties who accurately assess their chances of victory have a strong collective incentive to avoid the costs of trial. Indeed, in a world of purely Coasian bargaining, there would be no trials at all, since full sharing of information would eliminate any differences of opinion. Because of random variations in information, judgment and temperament, however, some fraction of litigants will inevitably overassess their chances; and it is these optimistic litigants who have an incentive to go to trial. Pessimistic or unbiased parties, in contrast, would prefer to settle. But the degree of optimism necessary for a trial to result depends on how litigation costs are allocated, as the following argument (suggested by Mause, 1969, and formally demonstrated by Shavell, 1982a) shows: under the American rule, a plaintiff who perceives the probability of liability as pP, her stakes as AP, and her costs as cP will insist on receiving a settlement of no less than SP pP AP ! cP. Similarly, a defendant who perceives the probability of liability as pD, his stakes as AD, and his costs as cD will be willing to pay no more than SD pD A D + cD. Settlement is thus possible if (and only if) SP < SD, or equivalently, if the total litigation costs, cP + cD, exceed the difference between the parties’ reservation settlement values, pP AP ! pD AD. Parties whose litigation costs are below this cutoff level, conversely, will prefer to go to trial. Under the English rule, however, the plaintiff’s reservation settlement value becomes
74
Indemnity of Legal Fees
7300
SP pP AP ! (1 ! pP)(cP + cD), and the defendant’s becomes SD pD (AD + cP + cD). Now settlement is possible only if cP + cD > (pP AP ! pD AD)/(1 ! pP + pD). If the plaintiff’s probability estimate pP exceeds the defendant’s probability estimate pD, the parties’ reservation prices will diverge, making settlements less likely. The economic intuition underlying this result is that indemnification internalizes one externality while creating another. Under the English rule, a litigant is forced to take into account the other side’s litigation costs to the extent that she risks losing the case, making her more willing to settle. But conversely, she is freed of her own litigation costs to the extent that she hopes to win, making her less likely to settle. Since litigants are disproportionately drawn from the population of optimists (else they would settle however costs are allocated), the latter effect tends to outweigh the former. Indeed, in the limiting case when both parties are fully confident of winning, neither expects to pay any costs at all and settlement is impossible. This line of argument, however, suggests an important exception to the basic result: in some cases, parties might choose to litigate due to a difference of opinion not over liability but over stakes. A plaintiff who regarded the stakes as sufficiently higher than did the defendant - for example, because she hoped to establish a favorable precedent that could be drawn on in later cases - might refuse all settlements even if the parties agreed on the probability of liability or were both relatively pessimistic. If the parties’ relative optimism about the stakes were enough to outweigh their relative pessimism about probability, fee shifting would encourage settlement and discourage trial. The Landes-Gould model of settlement bargaining (often called the ‘optimism model’ in subsequent literature) is open to the criticism that it is not rigorously grounded in the modern theory of imperfect information games. In particular, it does not explain how the parties can maintain their inconsistent perceptions of the case in the face of negotiation; and its conclusion that nonoptimistic parties will always settle ignores the possibility of strategic behavior and depends on the assumption of collective rather than individual rationality. Accordingly, subsequent writers have often preferred to base their analyses on an alternative bargaining model based on Bayesian inference and on the assumption of rational expectations. In this model, due to Harsanyi and Selten (1972) and introduced into the law and economics literature by Cooter, Marks and Mnookin (1982), trials are caused not by optimism but by uncertainty over the opponent’s reservation settlement value. The logic is that parties uncertain of their opponents’ bottom line will find it individually rational to balance the probability of settlement against its terms - making offers that more combative opponents will reject, in order to improve the return from settlements with those who are more conciliatory, Whether cases settle, therefore, depends on a number
7300
Indemnity of Legal Fees
75
of factors, including the stakes, the cost of litigation and, most importantly, the extent of uncertainty between the parties. A high variance of reservation settlement values means that taking a marginally tougher position sacrifices fewer bargains - lowering the opportunity cost of hard bargaining. More uncertainty thus means less settlement. Despite their differences from the optimism model, however, Bayesian models of settlement (see, for example, Bebchuk, 1984; Reinganum and Wilde, 1986; Talley, 1996) tend to confirm its conclusion that the English rule tends to discourage settlement in disputes revolving around liability, though not in disputes revolving around stakes. The reason is that indemnification magnifies uncertainty in the former set of cases but not in the latter. More precisely, uncertainty about opponents’ reservation values can stem from numerous sources: variations in the private cost and stakes of litigation, in attitudes toward risk and delay, and in private information relevant to the trial outcome. Differences in risk aversion, time preference and stakes are not affected by fee shifting, but differences in private cost and in information relevant to liability are. Fee shifting thus increases the difference between the reservation values of parties with favorable private information and high litigation costs on one hand, and parties with unfavorable information and low litigation costs on the other. This increase in uncertainty leads all types of parties to toughen their overall bargaining positions, lowering the probability of settlement. Ironically, as Polinsky and Rubinfeld (1997) point out, this implies that the English rule actually lowers the average quality of tried cases, since the marginal parties it sends to trial have relatively less favorable private information than those who would litigate absent the prospect of indemnification. The foregoing discussion of both optimism and Bayesian models, however, has assumed risk neutrality and has taken the cost of litigation as given. As the previous sections have observed, indemnification both increases the risks of litigation and raises litigation costs generally. Both effects tend to encourage settlement, thus mitigating and perhaps counteracting the effects of optimism and asymmetric information. Whether indemnification increases or decreases settlement on balance, accordingly, depends on the relative magnitude of competing factors, and cannot be settled theoretically. Even if fee shifting does not alter the probability of settlement, however, it can still influence its amount. As Cooter and Rubinfeld (1994) have argued in the context of legal discovery and Bebchuk and Chang (1996) have argued in the context of offers of judgment, fee shifting can, by equalizing the bargaining power of parties with asymmetric litigation costs, help to move the settlement amount closer to the expected trial outcome. To the extent that trial outcomes are deemed to be just, fee shifting thus may
76
Indemnity of Legal Fees
7300
help promote equity; to the extent that trial outcomes reflect substantive legal norms, fee shifting helps promote incentives for proper primary behavior - a subject more fully explored in the following section.
6. Effects of Fee Shifting on Substantive Behavior The discussion thus far is in a fundamental sense incomplete, since it has focused largely on the procedural costs of litigation. If such costs were one’s only concern, of course, they could be eliminated entirely by abolishing the legal system and all publicly enforceable rights to relief. A central purpose of having a public system of courts, however, is to redress wrongs and to encourage compliance with primary substantive norms such as taking precautions against accidents and keeping one’s promises. Indemnity of legal fees, accordingly, must ultimately be judged on these latter criteria - or more accurately, on whether it increases the social value of substantive enforcement net of process costs. Viewed from this perspective, the English rule initially appears attractive, since it tends to encourage high probability suits and discourage low probability ones. Assuming that the probability of liability is correlated with the actual violation of substantive norms, therefore, indemnification increases the net expected punishment for such violations and thus helps promote substantive compliance. This is easily seen in the case where courts’ liability determinations are error-free, as Rose-Ackerman and Geistfeld (1987) and Polinsky and Rubinfeld (1988) have shown. Consider a potential tortfeasor who can take precautions against an accident that will cause an uncertain amount of damage. Suppose that the possible damage ranges from zero to A, and that the cost of establishing liability following an accident is c. Under the American rule, it follows that the tortfeasor will have inadequate incentives for precaution. In the event that damages turn out to be less than c, the victim will not sue, so the tortfeasor will escape responsibility for a portion of the damages caused. Under the English rule, however, the victim will always have the incentive to sue, so that all accident costs will be fully internalized. Under a rule of negligence as opposed to strict liability, indeed, complete cost internalization can be achieved without incurring any litigation costs at all: defendants will be induced to take optimal care by the threat of litigation, so plaintiffs will never actually have to sue. Conversely, under the American rule, defendants may rationally decide to take excess care - or to abstain from risky though optimal activities - in order to avoid the greater expense of having to defend their behavior in court. Indemnification protects them from such expenses, thus preventing overdeterrence.
7300
Indemnity of Legal Fees
77
This happy outcome, however, depends on the assumption that deserving plaintiffs and defendants always win their cases. In the presence of legal error, as P’ng (1987) and Polinsky and Shavell (1989) have shown, neither the American nor the English rule provides incentives that are first-best optimal. Optimal incentives, rather, require at least two separate policy instruments - one to motivate efficient substantive behavior, and another to promote an efficient amount of litigation. Polinsky and Che (1991) demonstrate that, in general, this means decoupling the amounts paid by losing defendants from those received by victorious plaintiffs. (Indeed, as Polinsky and Rubinfeld (1996) show, decoupling is generally necessary even to achieve the lesser goal of minimizing the litigation costs associated with achieving a given level of deterrence.) Devices combining fines, punitive damages and taxes (positive or negative) on litigation accomplish such decoupling, but the English rule, which merely re-allocates costs between the parties in zero-sum fashion, does not. Furthermore, it is not even the case that the English rule is second-best efficient within the category of zero-sum policy instruments. Kaplow (1993) shows that damage multipliers, such as the treble damage provisions of US antitrust law, provide a cheaper method of achieving any given amount of deterrence. The reason is that damage multipliers provide incentives for private law enforcement to be undertaken by those plaintiffs whose litigation costs are lowest; fee shifting, in contrast, encourages plaintiffs to bring lawsuits without regard to their costs of litigation. One might still ask whether the English rule does better than the American in promoting efficient substantive behavior, notwithstanding the potential availability of alternatives that are superior to both. The answer to this question, however, is ambiguous, as Gravelle (1993), Hylton (1993a, 1993b), and Beckner and Katz (1995) demonstrate in independent formal models. It is possible to draw generalizations regarding when the English rule improves matters, but they depend on the subtle interaction of a number of factors, including whether substantive precaution affects the magnitude of injury or just its probability, the extent to which precaution affects the probability of liability, whether damage awards are sufficient to compensate plaintiffs for their losses, and whether defendants have the opportunity to act strategically by taking just enough care to foreclose litigation. Hylton, for instance, concludes that a one-way fee-shifting rule operating in favor of plaintiffs would be best, but this conclusion depends upon several features of his model (including, perhaps most importantly, the assumption that plaintiff’s care does not affect the expected cost of accidents). Applying such generalizations to individual cases or categories of cases is probably beyond the capacity of either courts or legislatures. As Gravelle concludes, ‘[i]t seems more promising to pursue other, more direct means of correcting the
78
Indemnity of Legal Fees
7300
inefficient incentives for care provided by a costly and imperfect legal system’.
7. Variations on Simple Fee Shifting The foregoing discussion has been premised on the assumption that ‘costs follow the event’ - that is, that any fee shifting that takes place is based solely on who wins the case. Much recent discussion in policy and scholarly circles, however, has focused on two more complicated forms of indemnification. 7.1 Fee Shifting Conditioned on Offers Made in Settlement Both England and a number of American jurisdictions provide a mechanism through which a defendant who would otherwise be obliged to pay for legal expenses can partially avoid the obligation by making a suitable offer of settlement. In England this procedure is called ‘payment into court’ and requires the defendant actually to deposit funds with a court officer; while in the United States, Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 68 and similar court rules merely require the formal filing of what is labeled an ‘offer of judgment’. Under either provision, a defendant who makes such a formal offer is considered the prevailing party for purposes of cost allocation if the plaintiff rejects the offer and then is subsequently awarded a lesser amount at trial. In such an event, the defendant avoids having to pay any costs incurred by the plaintiff subsequent to the offer, and is entitled to indemnification for his own subsequent costs as well. By all accounts, defendants avail themselves of this procedure much more frequently in England than in the US probably because the prospect of shifting liability for ‘costs’ is likelier under the broader English definition of the term to outweigh the disadvantages of making a settlement offer. Similarly, within the US, Rule 68 appears to be used more widely in disputes covered by one-way pro-plaintiff fee-shifting statutes such as Title VII, since the Supreme Court held in Marek v. Chesny, that attorney’s fees shifted under such statutes are to be considered ‘costs’ under Rule 68. Because of the relatively infrequent use of Rule 68 in US courts, a number of American critics have in recent years supported its expansion either by extending its coverage to attorneys’ fees generally, or by making the procedure available to plaintiffs as well as defendants. (It should be noted, however, that providing the procedure to plaintiffs is meaningless to the extent that they are already entitled to collect costs when they prevail; in such circumstances, the opportunity to make an offer of judgment can only advantage defendants.) The recent GOP ‘Contract with America’, for
7300
Indemnity of Legal Fees
79
example, would have established just such a generalized offer-of-judgment rule in federal diversity cases. Such proposals have commonly been supported by the claim that they will reduce expenditures on litigation by encouraging parties to make more reasonable settlement offers and to accept such offers when they are made. Their proponents have also argued that it is fairer to charge the costs of trial to the party who, by refusing a reasonable settlement, causes those costs to be incurred. In general, the economic literature on offers of judgment is substantially less developed than that on pure indemnification; and many interesting questions remain to be fully investigated, including the effect of the procedure on strategic behavior in negotiations. The place to begin any analysis of the offer of judgment, however, is with the observation that it is essentially an option to convert disputes over damages into disputes over liability. To see this, compare two cases: one in which it is clear that the defendant has acted negligently but unclear whether the plaintiff’s injuries are 1000 or 3000 (with the two possibilities being equally likely), and a second in which it is clear that damages are 4000, but an even gamble whether the defendant is liable at all. In both cases, expected damages are 2000, but absent an offer-of-judgment procedure the plaintiff’s position is stronger in the former. She is certain to prevail at trial and to recover some fraction of her costs, even if it is only court fees. In the latter case, she runs the risk of paying both her costs and a portion of the defendant’s. Under Rule 68 or a similar procedure, however, the defendant can convert the former dispute into a partial settlement of 1000 combined with a dispute over whether the defendant is liable for an additional 2000. In this converted dispute, the defendant stands an even chance of avoiding liability for the plaintiff’s costs and of recovering his own. This improves his expected position to what it would be in the case of pure liability, at the plaintiff’s expense. The example illustrates two lessons. First, a rule authorizing defendants but not plaintiffs to make offers of judgment redistributes wealth from plaintiffs to defendants in disputes that are entirely or partly over damages, as both Priest (1982) and Miller (1986) have suggested. Second, such offers have no effect in disputes that are purely over liability. If the only possible trial outcomes are verdicts of zero or 4000, for instance, there is no advantage to the defendant in making a Rule 68 offer of less than the full 4000. If he offers a lesser amount, he will be liable for costs in the event of a plaintiff’s verdict and certain to receive costs in the event of a defendant’s verdict - just as he would if he made no offer at all. Similarly, a less-than-full offer does not affect the possible payoffs for the plaintiff. The defendant could of course offer to settle for the full 4000, but the plaintiff should be happy to accept such an offer whether or not Rule 68 is in force.
80
Indemnity of Legal Fees
7300
The offer-of-judgment procedure, accordingly, cannot affect whether an offer is made or accepted in such cases. With these points taken as caveats, the effects of offer-of-judgment rules are roughly analogous to those of indemnification in general. The possibility that costs will be shifted following a settlement offer both raises the stakes of the case and lowers the perceived marginal cost of legal expenditure, thus increasing incentives to expend resources at trial. The effect is less than under the pure English rule, however, since only post-offer expenditures are liable to be shifted. Similarly, the opportunity to make an offer of judgment increases expected payoffs for plaintiffs who expect to win large awards at trial, and lowers expected payouts of defendants who expect awards to be low, emboldening such parties to pursue litigation. The effect of offers of judgment on the settlement decision depends, like the effect of indemnification generally, on the parties’ attitudes toward risk and on the model of settlement that one thinks appropriate. Under the Landes-Posner-Gould optimism model, offers of judgment tends to lower the chances of settlement between risk-neutral parties, since, as Priest (1982) suggests and Miller (1986) and Chung (1996) confirm, such offers lower the reservation values of optimistic defendants more than they do those of optimistic plaintiffs, thus reducing the potential settlement range. Offers of judgment also increase the risk of litigation, though not as much as pure indemnification does; this encourages risk-averse parties to settle, but risk-preferring parties to litigate. Anderson (1994), who extends the optimism model to include the possibility of bargaining stalemate, reaches similar results. Within Bayesian models of settlement, the outcome appears more complicated. Cooter, Marks and Mnookin (1982) conjecture that an offer-of-judgment rule, by effectively taxing hard offers and subsidizing soft ones, should encourage settlement. Spier (1994), however, in a model in which defendants make offers to plaintiffs with private information, finds that the procedure leads to more settlement than the pure American rule in cases where the plaintiff’s private information relates solely to the size of the award, less settlement than the American rule in cases where the plaintiff’s private information relates solely to the probability of liability, and an ambiguous effect in other cases. She also demonstrates a similar result using a mechanism-design model that, instead of specifying any particular bargaining process, assumes that the parties use a Pareto-efficient trading mechanism in the style of Myerson and Satterthwaite (1983). As with pure indemnification, accordingly, the effect of offers of judgment on settlement probabilities appears to depend on the sources of the underlying dispute.
7300
Indemnity of Legal Fees
81
7.2 Fee Shifting Conditioned on the Margin of Victory In the United States, a variety of statutory and judicially created rules allow courts to award partial or full indemnification in lawsuits in which the losing party’s case is deemed after the fact to be of sufficiently low merit. Such rules include the common-law torts of barratry, abuse of process, and malicious prosecution, the traditional authority of courts of equity to exercise their discretion in the interests of justice, the sanctions for discovery abuse provided by Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 37, and the (just amended) provisions of the Internal Revenue Code requiring the government to pay a taxpayer’s reasonable litigation costs upon a court finding that the government’s position in a tax dispute was substantially unjustified. Similarly, as Pfennigstorf (1984) reports, indemnification awards in most other Western legal systems are likely to be more generous in cases where the loser’s legal or factual position appears weak. The possibility of tying indemnification to the merits of the losing case has attracted increased attention in recent years, in part as a response to the growth of litigation practice under US Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 11. This rule requires persons filing court papers to warrant that their filings are well grounded, and authorizes courts to impose monetary sanctions on parties whose filings are found to be frivolous, harassing, or made for purposes of delay. Limiting fee shifting to cases of particularly low merit has seemed to many commentators an attractive compromise between the English and American rules, since it protects clearly deserving litigants without imposing unnecessary risk on those who bring colorable claims in good faith. As Bebchuk and Chang (1996) have pointed out, the effect of policies such as Rule 11 is to condition fee shifting on the winner’s margin of victory; those who win in a rout receive indemnification, while those who win narrowly do not. They confirm the conventional wisdom in a formal model, showing that such policies, if designed properly, can do a better job than either the English or the American rule at encouraging meritorious suits (and by analogy, defenses) and discouraging frivolous ones. The reason is that such policies make use of the parties’ private ex ante information regarding the merits of the case. A party who loses by a large margin is less likely to have believed ex ante that her case had merit; conversely, one who wins by a large margin is less likely to have believed that her case lacked merit. While the optimal fee shifting rule depends on the distribution of judicial and litigant error, it is possible by altering the threshold for fee shifting to regulate the proportion of potential claims and defenses that are actually brought into the system. Because its effects are zero-sum, however, margin-based fee shifting is still less efficient than policies that decouple one side’s payments from the other side’s recovery (see generally Polinsky and Rubinfeld, 1993). Policies that tax or subsidize individual parties based on
82
Indemnity of Legal Fees
7300
the ex post quality of their case may be best of all; they may also, of course, be the most difficult to administer. While other incentive effects of margin-based fee shifting have not been formally explored, it appears likely that it has analogous consequences to indemnification generally, though in lesser degree. These consequences recapitulate the discussion in earlier sections of this article and can be surveyed in brief. First, to the extent that such policies succeed in encouraging meritorious claims and defenses and discouraging frivolous ones, they will tend to improve incentives for primary substantive behavior. The complications described in Section 6 above, however, remain to be analyzed. It is possible, for instance, that the prospect of shifting litigation costs to the other side following a commanding victory will induce excessive caretaking ex ante, though the benefits of doing so are less than under the pure English rule. Second, margin-based fee shifting will both raise the stakes of litigation and decrease its expected marginal cost, inducing the parties to intensify their efforts at trial. Schmalbeck and Myers (1986) argue that this effect will be relatively minor, since in a truly frivolous case there is little that the parties can do to change the outcome. Their argument is open to question, however, as the substantial amount of litigation effort under Rule 11 illustrates (see, for example, Kobayashi and Parker, 1993, who discuss the incentive effects of recent amendments intended to reduce such ‘satellite’ litigation). While margin-based indemnification has little effect on cases that are clearly contestable or clearly frivolous, in many disputes the colorability of the losing case is less obvious. Parties in such intermediate cases, thus, will have an incentive to increase their expenditures in order to influence the size of the margin of victory. Third, margin-based fee shifting will decrease the likelihood of settlement to the extent that the parties have a difference of opinion regarding the chances of indemnification. Optimistic parties will exaggerate the likelihood that they will win by a large margin and underestimate the likelihood that they will lose by a large margin. The prospect of indemnification will cause such parties to toughen their settlement demands, reducing the range for settlement. Since pessimistic and unbiased parties will have an incentive to settle in any event, the net consequence will be an increase in trials. Similarly, given private information regarding the probability of a one-sided outcome, margin-based fee shifting will increase the variance of the parties’ reservation settlement values, encouraging tougher bargaining and hence fewer settlements. The increased risk of trial, however, works to counteract such effects for risk-averse litigants. In sum, however, the case for at least some margin-based fee shifting appears stronger than the case for indemnification generally, on grounds of
7300
Indemnity of Legal Fees
83
both fairness and efficiency. Parties who lose lawsuits decisively are probably more deserving of sanction than those who lose barely. The social value of litigation is probably higher in close cases, whether measured by the public benefits of legal precedent or by more libertarian considerations. And margin-based fee shifting seems to do a better job at providing improved incentives for primary behavior, and has lower costs in terms of incentives for increased expenditure at trial. In light of the relatively limited theoretical and empirical work on this particular topic, however, these conclusions must be regarded as tentative.
8. Empirical Evidence on the Effects of Fee Shifting Given the complexity and ambiguity of the aforementioned considerations, it would plainly be desirable to have some hard empirical evidence to bring to the policy debate. Unfortunately, such evidence is sparse. Critics of the American rule commonly point to the larger numbers of disputes and higher expenditures on litigation in the US to support their case for reform. But such a crude comparison does not seem especially fruitful in light of the many other significant features that distinguish the American legal system from its counterparts in other Western countries, including economic and demographic factors, differences in substantive rights, procedural practice, the structure of courts and the legal profession, the availability of other financing arrangements such as the contingent fee and prepaid legal services, a high degree of rights-consciousness among individual citizens, and the absence of a comprehensive program of social insurance that would help to channel demands for compensatory relief away from the private legal system. The proper question to ask, therefore, is what effect fee shifting has on litigation expenditures and primary behavior, holding constant other features of the legal environment. But again, answers to this question are hard to come by. Although the US legal system contains a number of pockets of indemnification, these examples have for the most part escaped systematic quantitative inquiry. The evidence on fee shifting, rather, falls into three categories: laboratory research on bargaining behavior by experimental subjects, numerical simulations of litigation behavior based on empirically obtained parameters, and econometric evidence primarily drawn from a single policy experiment: Florida’s experience with the English rule in medical malpractice cases from 1980 through 1985. 8.1 Laboratory Experiments Coursey and Stanley (1988) tested the effects of fee shifting within an experimental setting they designed to simulate the process of bargaining
84
Indemnity of Legal Fees
7300
under threat of trial. They divided their subjects (students at the University of Wyoming) into pairs and instructed them to attempt to divide between themselves a number of tokens that were subsequently convertible into cash. If time expired before the subjects reached agreement, the tokens were divided through a random drawing, intended to represent an uncertain court award. To simulate rational expectations, the subjects were presented with the probability distribution of awards arising from the random drawing, and to simulate the costs of trial, the subjects were collectively fined an amount equaling 40 percent of the total value of the tokens in the event the drawing had to take place. The experimenters conducted negotiations using three different cost allocation rules. Under the simplest procedure, the fine was divided between the two parties equally, in an intended simulation of the American rule. A second group of subjects negotiated under a rule whereby the fine was paid entirely by the party who received the smaller portion of the token in a random drawing; this was intended to simulate the English rule. Yet a third group negotiated under an offer-of-judgment rule intended to simulate Rule 68: the plaintiff paid the entire fine if the draw awarded her an amount less than or equal to the defendant’s last proposal; and the fine was otherwise split equally. The result of this experiment were that subjects settled more frequently under the English than under the American rule. Under Rule 68 settlement was likeliest of all; and in addition the plaintiff was much more likely to be the accepting party. The authors also found that settlements were more favorable to the defendant under Rule 68 than under the English rule, consistent with the theoretical predictions outlined in the previous section. The American rule was most favorable of all for the defendant, though the authors ascribed this result to the behavior of one especially risk-averse individual. These findings are consistent with theoretical models that predict increased settlement on the basis of simple risk aversion. Because the experimental design ruled out the possibility of optimism or private information, however, its results cannot be extrapolated to situations in which such phenomena, which could cause the English rule to reduce settlement, are present. In a separate series of survey experiments, Rowe and various co-authors studied the effects of cost allocation rules on lawyers’ and law students’ responses to a variety of bargaining situations presented by hypothetical tort and civil rights cases. While this experimental design suffered from the weakness that the subjects were not provided with any direct financial incentives, the more realistic nature of the problems and the subjects’ professional status and experience provided at least some motivation to bargain seriously. The results of the experiments, however, were mixed. Rowe and Vidmar (1988) found that there was little difference between the
7300
Indemnity of Legal Fees
85
American rule and a modified Rule 68 (enhanced to cover attorneys’ fees and to allow plaintiffs as well as defendants to make offers) on law students’ willingness to accept offers of settlement, although they did find an effect on the size of counteroffers as well as a difference in plaintiff acceptance rates between modified Rule 68 and a one-way pro-plaintiff rule. Anderson and Rowe (1996) replicated this experiment with practicing lawyers, also examining the subjects’ behavior under an alternative fee shifting rule in which the maker of a rejected offer had to pay the rejecting party’s subsequent reasonable attorneys’ fees. They found that while modified Rule 68 did not appreciably affect plaintiffs’ minimum asks relative to the American rule, it did raise the maximum amounts that defendants were willing to offer. Finally, Rowe and Anderson (1996) considered the effects of a modified Rule 68 on hypothetical bargaining in civil rights cases otherwise governed by a pro-plaintiff rule. They found that replacing this one-way rule with an enhanced Rule 68 significantly lowered plaintiffs’ minimum asks, as well as the gap between plaintiff asks and defendant offers. In all, these results suggest that fee shifting has its strongest effect when it is one-sided and when the favored side is risk averse or liquidity constrained. 8.2 Simulations A number of authors have attempted to estimate the quantitative effects of fee shifting by numerically simulating the behavior of theoretical models. Katz’s (1987) approach is illustrative. He developed algebraic formulas, based on a linear approximation to the standard model of litigation expenditure, that relate the difference in expenditure per case between the English and American rules to two empirical parameters: the ratio of total expenditure to the stakes of the case, and the elasticity with which parties increase their expenditures in response to higher stakes. Using empirical estimates of these parameters taken from the University of Wisconsin’s Civil Litigation Research Project (Trubek et al. 1983), he calculated the likely effects of switching from the American to the English rule, concluding that such a switch would increase expenditures per case in the neighborhood of 125 percent. Such a large increase in cost per case, however, could be expected to lead to a reduction in the number of cases or to increased settlement. In an attempt to measure this anticipated reduction, Hause (1989) extended the Landes-Gould optimism model to allow for variable expenditure, and calculated its numerical behavior for a range of possible parameter values. He concluded that the increased costs per case under the English rule were sufficient to outweigh any effects of optimism, resulting on balance in an increased frequency of settlement. Hersch (1990) recalculated Hause’s simulations under the assumption that trial expenditure is determined in a conjectural-variations rather than a Nash equilibrium. He found that both
86
Indemnity of Legal Fees
7300
settlement and costs per case rose, though by a lesser amount than Hause had estimated. The parameter values Hause and Hersch used, however, were not based on any empirical data. Donohue (1991a) recalculated Hause’s simulations using what he argued were more plausible parameter estimates, and concluded that the English rule would increase trials on balance. Finally, Hylton (1993a, 1993b) used numerical simulation to estimate the effects of fee shifting on primary behavior. He concludes that while litigation is more frequent under the English than the American rule, levels of substantive compliance under the two rules would be similar. Best of all, according to his calculations, is one-way pro-plaintiff fee shifting, which leads to the highest level of compliance and least amount of litigation. These conclusions, however, depend both on the functional form used in his simulations, and on the specific assumptions of his theoretical model. 8.3 Econometric Evidence of Actual Disputes The statistical and econometric evidence on fee shifting, as well as on litigation and settlement more generally, has unfortunately been rather limited. Schwab and Eisenberg (1988) report on a 1976 statute that established one-way pro-plaintiff fee shifting in federal constitutional tort cases (that is, cases in which where the federal government is sued for violating the plaintiff’s constitutional rights). They find some evidence that the statute was followed by a decline in plaintiff success rates at trial and by an increase in trials relative to other federal civil actions, but little evidence of any increase in the number of lawsuits filed. These results suggest that the statute had its primary effect in encouraging plaintiffs to bargain more aggressively in settlement negotiations, consistent with Rowe et al.’s survey experiments as well as with the theoretical predictions of the optimism and Bayesian settlement models discussed in Section 5 above. Because of the relatively low magnitude of their quantitative estimates, however, and because their observations were muddied by the fact that some courts shifted fees on a discretionary basis before the statute was passed, the authors present their findings as tentative. Fournier and Zuehlke (1989) develop an econometric model of settlement behavior in which the plaintiff’s settlement demand and the probability of settlement are jointly determined. Using nonlinear methods that correct for data censoring (that is, the fact that the amount of the demand is only observed when settlement takes place), they estimate their model using data from a nationwide survey of civil federal filings between 1979 and 1981. The data classifies disputes according to the type of legal claim at issue (for example, tort, copyright, antitrust) and includes information regarding the alleged damages and the number of litigants in each case, the mean and variance of trial awards in litigated cases within
7300
Indemnity of Legal Fees
87
each subject-matter classification, and separately prepared estimates of government litigation costs in each case classification, which the authors argue serve as a reasonable proxy for private litigation costs. The coefficients of the resulting equations suggest, not surprisingly, that settlement demands are positively correlated with mean trial awards and alleged damages, and negatively correlated with litigation costs. More interestingly, they also suggest that settlement is more likely in cases and categories with high alleged damages, high mean and variance of trial awards, multiple parties, and low (!) litigation costs. These latter results are at odds with the theoretical predictions of most models of settlement, although the negative relationship between settlement and potential trial awards is consistent with a hypothesis of risk aversion. Because a fraction of the sampled filings were subject to the English rule, Fournier and Zuehlke were able to estimate its effects as well. They find that fee shifting is negatively correlated with both the probability of settlement and the size of the settlement demand, although the latter effect is not statistically significant. This finding lends some support to the predictions of both the optimism and Bayesian models. The filings in their sample governed by the English rule, however, were few in number and concentrated in a few specialized areas, so this evidence cannot be regarded as especially strong. It is possible that this correlation reflects differences in the types of disputes covered by the rule, rather than effects of indemnification. The authors’ unusual findings regarding the other determinants of settlement also call this result into question. More instructive is Hughes’ and Snyder’s research on Florida’s experiment with the English rule in medical malpractice cases. The Florida statute, passed in 1980 with the support of the state medical association, also provided an offer-of-judgment procedure and exempted insolvent parties from the obligation to pay indemnification; it was repealed in 1985 with the support of its original proponents following a series of expensive and well-publicized plaintiff verdicts. In Snyder and Hughes (1990), the authors use a bivariate probit procedure to analyze insurance company data on closed claims filed before, during, and after the period in which the rule was in effect, and estimate the effects of indemnification on plaintiffs’ decisions to drop claims, settlement, and defendants’ expenditure on lawyers. Their findings lend support to several of the theoretical predictions outlined in previous sections of this article. Specifically, they find that in cases governed by the English rule, (1) a significantly higher percentage of claims were dropped at an early stage of the litigation, consistent with the proposition that fee shifting encourages risk-averse and low probability plaintiffs to exit the system; (2) defendants spent significantly more per case, in amounts consistent with Katz’s simulations, in both settled and in litigated cases; (3) holding other case characteristics constant, the likelihood of litigation increased, consistent with the optimism model. Because dropped cases
88
Indemnity of Legal Fees
7300
tended disproportionately to have characteristics that would have made them likelier to go to trial had they remained in the system, however, the authors conclude that the English rule decreased the frequency of litigation on balance. Because of greater expenditure per case, however, total expenditures on litigation still increased. In a subsequent article analyzing the same data set (Hughes and Snyder, 1995), the authors find that the English rule was associated with an increased frequency of plaintiff success rates at trial, increased jury awards, and larger out-of-court settlements. These increases were significant not just statistically but in absolute terms; for instance, the average judgment in litigated cases increased from $25,190 in cases governed by the American rule to $69,390 in cases governed by the English rule. These results appear to be driven by the case selection effects detailed in the first article. The authors suggest that their results vindicate the proposition that indemnification improves the quality of claims brought, although they admit the possibility of an alternative explanation that low-damage cases are merely being driven away by the higher costs of litigation. They conclude that fee shifting, contrary to the assertions of some legal practitioners, is not necessarily an antiplaintiff policy. Rather, it benefits plaintiffs with high-quality or high-damage claims at the expense of those with low-quality or low-damage claims, and possibly at the expense of defendants. These conclusions, if valid, would explain why the financial advantages expected by the Florida statute’s original proponents did not appear to materialize; they would also suggest that the statute improved the deterrent effect of civil liability. Whether such an improvement would be worth the increased litigation expenditures it occasioned, however, and whether it would be replicated in other areas of law with different substantive and procedural characteristics from medical malpractice, remain open questions.
9. Conclusion It is worth mentioning two relatively underinvestigated aspects of fee shifting, the first of which is its interaction with attorney/client fee contracts. US practice is unusual not only in its allocation of costs between plaintiff and defendant, but also in its tolerance of a variety of cost-sharing arrangements between attorney and client, including the contingent fee, which is widely used by tort plaintiffs. While an analysis of the contingent fee is beyond the scope of this article, it is apparent that many of the incentive effects of fee shifting would be altered in its presence. To give just one obvious example, any deterrent effect of indemnification on risk-averse litigants may be substantially lessened in the presence of contingent fees,
7300
Indemnity of Legal Fees
89
since it may be possible to shift some of the increased risk from indemnification to the attorney through adjustments in the contingency arrangement. For another example, the effect of indemnification on trial expenditures may be different under contingent than under hourly fees, since under the former arrangement the attorney’s incentives to devote time to the case are dependent on the trial outcome, while under the latter they are independent. Halpern and Turnbull (1983) discuss some of the incentives of contingent fee contracts under both the English and American rules, and Dewees, Prichard and Trebilcock (1981) analyze some of the additional complications that can arise in class actions, but neither article explicitly focuses on the effects of indemnification. Donohue (1991b) discusses the combined effect of the English rule and contingent fees, but his analysis is limited to effects on the settlement range within the optimism model of settlement, and he presents only numerical examples based on a few parameter values. A systematic analysis of the effects of fee shifting under contingent fee contracts, accordingly, remains to be undertaken. Second, it would be useful to know more about the effects of the English rule on incentives for investigation prior to the onset of litigation. One commonly cited advantage of fee shifting is that, by increasing the penalty for losing at trial, it encourages potential litigants to spend more resources investigating the merits of their claims before officially entering the legal system. This claim is plausible, but the developing economic literature on pre-trial investigation has not yet formally addressed it. While it is possible that this effect could help to make the English rule more efficient than the American, such a conclusion turns on a number of unknown propositions, including whether litigants’ investigative incentives are currently adequate, and whether, given the availability of civil discovery, it is cheaper for investigation to take place before rather than after a lawsuit has been filed. All in all, despite the substantial scholarly and popular attention that the question of indemnity for legal fees has attracted, the number of robust conclusions that can be drawn regarding its consequences are few. Fee shifting does appear to increase legal expenditures per case, in some cases significantly. It also encourages parties with poorly grounded legal claims to settle or to avoid litigating them in the first place, and has a similar effect on litigants who are averse to risk, regardless of the merits of their cases. Aside from these generalizations, most of the other propositions commonly asserted about fee shifting can neither be verified nor rejected. It is unclear whether fee shifting increases the likelihood of settlement, whether it decreases total expenditures on litigation or total payouts by defendants, or whether it on balance improves incentives for primary behavior. It is even unclear whether fee shifting makes it easier for parties with small meritorious claims to obtain compensation, in light of the increased costs per
90
Indemnity of Legal Fees
7300
case that it induces. In this regard, the relative lack of systematic empirical investigation of these questions is particularly lamentable. In light of this state of affairs, and in light of the numerous theoretical demonstrations that fee shifting is a less effective way to promote optimal behavior than other available procedural devices such as decoupling or damage multipliers, one is tempted to conclude that the amount of scholarly attention directed to this topic exceeds its actual social importance. The continued popular and political interest in fee-shifting rules, however, makes this conclusion problematic. While some support for fee shifting arises from its relative simplicity and its status as the international majority rule, much of its continued appeal undoubtedly stems from its association with deeply held notions of corrective justice - and specifically, from the idea that a party who is determined ex post to be in the right should be made financially whole. Counterarguments based on economic efficiency, or indeed on any ex ante perspective, can never entirely rebut this simple yet powerful intuition. Whether the English rule is more just than the American rule, or whether its greater fairness justifies its incentive properties, cannot be settled by lawyers or economists alone. The citizenry as a whole must decide whether the principle of full compensation for victorious litigants outweighs the procedural values of providing citizens with an open forum for grievances and an opportunity to be heard, the uncertainty imposed on those who cannot predict the outcome of court decisions, and the political implications of regulating legal fees through a system of bureaucratic oversight rather than through private contract between attorney and client. Moreover, as Prichard (1988) and Hylton (1996) have observed, rules of cost allocation feed back through the selection of cases to influence the development of other areas of substantive and procedural law. Rules that encourage parties to raise relatively innovative claims and defenses help to break down precedent, while rules that penalize risk-taking and novel arguments help to preserve traditional formal categories. Given the pervasive influence of ostensibly procedural rules on substantive outcomes, it may not be possible to separate the policy of fee shifting from deeper questions of what the law should be.
Bibliography on Indemnity of Legal Fees (7300) Anderson, David A. (1994), ‘Improving Settlement Devices: Rule 68 and Beyond’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 225-246. Bebchuk, Lucian Arye and Chang, Howard F. (1996), ‘An Analysis of Fee Shifting Based on the Margin of Victory: On Frivolous Suits, Meritorious Suits, and the Role of Rule 11', 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 371-403.
7300
Indemnity of Legal Fees
91
Beckner, Clinton F. and Katz, Avery (1995), ‘The Incentive Effects of Litigation Fee Shifting when Legal Standards Are Uncertain’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 205-224. Bowles, Roger A. (1987), ‘Settlement Range and Cost Allocation Rules: A Comment on Avery Katz’s Measuring the Demand for Litigation’, 3 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 177-184. Braeutigam, Ronald R., Owen, Bruce M. and Panzar, John C. (1984), ‘An Economic Analysis of Alternative Fee Shifting Systems’, 47 Law and Contemporary Problems, 173-185. Chung, Tai-Yeong (1996), ‘Settlement of Litigation Under Rule 68: An Economic Analysis’, 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 261-286. Cooper, Edward H. (1994), ‘Discovery Cost Allocation: Comment’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 465-480. Cooter, Robert D. and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1989), ‘Economic Analysis of Legal Disputes and Their Resolution’, 27 Journal of Economic Literature, 1067-1097. Reprinted in Posner, Richard A., Cooter, Robert D. and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1995), ‘Reforming the New Discovery Rules’, 84 Georgetown Law Journal, 61-89. Coursey, Don L. and Stanley, L.R. (1988), ‘Pretrial Bargaining Behavior within the Shadow of the Law: Theory and Experimental Evidence’, 8 International Review of Law and Economics, 161-179. Dewees, Donald N., Prichard, J. Robert S. and Trebilcock, Michael J. (1981), ‘An Economic Analysis of Cost and Fee Rules for Class Actions’, 10 Journal of Legal Studies, 155-185. Dnes, Antony W. and Rickman, Neil (1998), ‘Contracts for Legal Aid’, 5(3) European Journal of Law and Economics. Donohue, John J. (1991a), ‘The Effects of Fee Shifting on the Settlement Rate: Theoretical Observations on Costs, Conflicts, and Contingency Fees’, 54 Law and Contemporary Problems, 194 ff. Donohue, John J. (1991b), ‘Opting for the British Rule; or, If Posner and Shavell Can’t Remember the Coase Theorem, Who Will?’, 104 Harvard Law Review, 1093 ff. Reprinted in Levmore, Saul (1994), Foundations of Tort Law, p 160. Fournier, Gary M. and Zuehlke, Thomas W. (1989), ‘Litigation and Settlement: An Empirical Approach’, 71 Review of Economics and Statistics, 189-195. Gravelle, Hugh S.E. (1993), ‘The Efficiency Implications of Cost Shifting Rules’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-18. Halpern, Paul J. and Turnbull, Stuart M. (1983), ‘Legal Fees Contracts and Alternative Cost Rules: An Economic Analysis’, 3 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-26. Hause, John C. (1989), ‘Indemnity, Settlement, and Litigation, or I’ll Be Suing You’, 18 Journal of Legal Studies, 157-179. Hersch, Philip L. (1990), ‘Indemnity, Settlement, and Litigation: Comment and Extension’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 235-241. Hughes, James W. and Snyder, Edward A. (1995), ‘Litigation and Settlement under the English and American Rules: Theory and Evidence’, 38 Journal of Law and Economics, 225-250.
92
Indemnity of Legal Fees
7300
Hughes, James W. and Woglom, Geoffry R. (1996), ‘Risk Aversion and the Allocation of Legal Costs’, in Anderson, David A. (ed.), Dispute Resolution: Bridging the Settlement Gap, Greenwich, JAI Press, 167-192. Hylton, Keith N. (1993a), ‘Litigation Cost Allocation Rules and Compliance with the Negligence Standard’, 22 Journal of Legal Studies, 457-476. Hylton, Keith N. (1993b), ‘Fee Shifting and Incentives to Comply With the Law’, 46 Vanderbilt Law Review, 1069-1128. Hylton, Keith N. (1996), ‘Fee-Shifting and Predictability of Law’, 71 Chicago-Kent Law Review, 427-459. Kaplow, Louis (1993), ‘Shifting Plaintiffs’ Fees versus Increasing Damage Awards’, 24 Rand Journal of Economics, 625-630. Katz, Avery (1987), ‘Measuring the Demand for Litigation: Is the English Rule Really Cheaper?’, 3 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 143-176. Katz, Avery (1990), ‘The Effect of Frivolous Lawsuits on the Settlement of Litigation’, 10 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-27. Kobayashi, Bruce H. and Parker, Jeffrey S. (1993), ‘No Armistice at 11: A Commentary on the Supreme Court’s 1993 Amendment to Rule 11 of the Federal Rules of Civil Procedures’, 3 Supreme Court Economic Review, 92-152. Leubsdorf, John (1984), ‘Toward a History of the American Rule on Attorney Fee Recovery’, 47(1) Law and Contemporary Problems, 9-36. Mause, Philip (1969), ‘Winner Takes All: A Re-Examination of the Indemnity System’, 55 Iowa Law Review, 26-55. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1986), ‘An Economic Analysis of Rule 68’, 15 Journal of Legal Studies, 93125. Note (1984), ‘State Attorney Fee Shifting Statutes: Are We Quietly Repealing the American Rule?’, 47 Law and Contemporary Problems, 321-346. Pfennigstorf, Werner (1984), ‘The European Experience With Attorney Fee Shifting’, 47 Law and Contemporary Problems, 37-124. Plott, Charles R. (1987), ‘Legal Fees: A Comparison of the American and English Rules’, 3 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 185-92. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Che, Yeon-Koo (1991), ‘Decoupling Liability: Optimal Incentives for Care and Litigation’, 22 Rand Journal of Economics, 562-570. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1993), ‘Sanctioning Frivolous Suits: An Economic Analysis’, 82 Georgetown Law Journal, 397-435. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1996), ‘Optimal Awards and Penalties When the Probability of Prevailing Varies Among Plaintiffs’, 27 Rand Journal of Economics, 269-280. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1997), ‘Does the English Rule Discourage LowProbability-of-Prevailing Plaintiffs?’, 26 Journal of Legal Studies. Prichard, J. Robert S. (1988), ‘A Systematic Approach to Comparative Law: The Effect of Cost, Fee and Financing Rules on the Development of the Substantive Law’, 17 Journal of Legal Studies, 451-475. Priest, George L. (1982), ‘Regulating the Content and Volume of Litigation: An Economic Analysis’, 1 Supreme Court Economic Review , 163-183. Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, Louis L. (1986), ‘Settlement, Litigation, and the Allocation of Litigation Costs’, 17 Rand Journal of Economics, 557-566.
7300
Indemnity of Legal Fees
93
Rosenberg, David and Shavell, Steven (1985), ‘A Model in Which Suits are Brought for their Nuisance Value’, 5 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-13. Rowe, Thomas D. (1984), ‘Predicting the Effects of Attorney Fee Shifting’, 47 Law and Contemporary Problems, 139-171. Rowe, Thomas D. and Anderson, David A. (1996), ‘One-Way Fee Shifting Statutes and Offer of Judgment Rules: An Experiment’, 36 Jurimetrics Journal, 255-273. Rowe, Thomas D. and Vidmar, Neil (1988), ‘Empirical Research on Offers of Settlement: A Preliminary Report’, 51 Law and Contemporary Problems, 13-39. Schmalbeck, Richard L. and Myers, Gary (1986), ‘A Policy Analysis of Fee-Shifting Rules Under the Internal Revenue Code’, 6 Duke Law Journal, 1986, 970-1002. Schwab, Stewart J. and Eisenberg, Theodore (1988), ‘Explaining Constitutional Tort Litigation: The Influence of the Attorney Fees Statute and the Government As Defendant’, 73 Cornell Law Review, 719-784. Shavell, Steven (1982a), ‘Suit, Settlement and Trial: A Theoretical Analysis Under Alternative Methods for the Allocation of Legal Costs’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 55-81. Snyder, Edward A. and Hughes, James W. (1990), ‘The English Rule for Allocating Legal Costs: Evidence Confronts Theory’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 345-380. Spier, Kathryn E. (1994), ‘Pretrial Bargaining and the Design of Fee-Shifting Rules’, 25 Rand Journal of Economics, 197-214. Symposium on Attorney Fee Shifting (1984), 47 Law and Contemporary Problems, 1-354. Symposium on Fee Shifting (1996), 71 Chicago-Kent Law Review, 415-697. Talley, Eric (1996), ‘Liability-Based Fee Shifting Rules and Settlement Mechanisms Under Incomplete Information’, 71 Chicago-Kent Law Review, 461-503. Tomkins, Alan J. and Willging, Thomas E. (1986), Taxation of Attorneys’ Fees: Practices in English, Alaskan, and Federal Courts, Washington, Federal Judicial Center. Trubek, David M., Grossman, Joel B., Felstiner, William L. F., Kritzer, Herbert M. and Sarat, Austin (1983), Civil Litigation Research Project: Final Report, Madison, Wisconsin, Institute for Legal Studies.
Other References Anderson, David A. (ed.) (1996), Dispute Resolution: Bridging the Settlement Gap, Greenwich, CT, JAI Press. Anderson, David A. and Rowe, Thomas D. (1996),‘Empirical Evidence on Settlement Devices: Does Rule 68 Encourage Settlement?’, 71 Chicago-Kent Law Review, 519-545. Bebchuk, Lucian A. (1984). Litigation and Settlement Under Imperfect Information, 15 Rand Journal of Economics, 404-415. Bebchuk, Lucian A. and Chang, Howard F. (1996), The Effect of Offer-of-Settlement Rules on the Terms of Settlement, Manuscript, University of Southern California.
94
Indemnity of Legal Fees
7300
Bernstein, Lisa (1993), ‘Understanding the Limits of Court-Connected ADR: A Critique of Federal Court Annexed Arbitration Programs’, 141 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 2169-2259. Cooter, Robert D. and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1994), ‘An Economic Model of Legal Discovery’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 435-463. Cooter, Robert D. and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1995),‘Reforming the New Discovery Rules’, 84 Georgetown Law Journal, 61-89. Cooter, Robert D., Marks, Stephen and Mnookin Robert (1982), ‘Bargaining in the Shadow of the Law: A Testable Model of Strategic Behavior’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 225-251. Cornell, Bradford (1990),‘The Incentive to Sue: An Option Pricing Approach’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 173-187. Gould, John P. (1973), ‘The Economics of Legal Conflicts’, 2 Journal of Legal Studies, 279-300. Harsanyi, John C. and Selten, Reinhard (1972), ‘A Generalized Nash Solution for Two Person Bargaining Games with Incomplete Information’, 18 Management Science, 80-106. Katz, Avery (1988), ‘Judicial Decisionmaking and Litigation Expenditure’, 8 International Review of Law and Economics, 127-143. Landes, William M. (1971), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Courts’, 14 Journal of Law and Economics, 61-101. Myerson, Roger B. and Satterthwaite, Mark A. (1983), ‘Efficient Mechanisms for Bilateral Trading’, 29 Journal of Economic Theory, 265-281. P’ng, Ivan P.L. (1987), ‘Litigation, Liability, and Incentives to Take Care’, 34 Journal of Public Economics, 61-85. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1988), ‘The Welfare Effects of Costly Litigation for the Level of Liability’, 17 Journal of Legal Studies, 151-164. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1989), ‘Legal Error, Litigation, and the Incentive to Obey the Law’, 5 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 99-108. Posner, Richard A. (1973), ‘An Economic Approach to Legal Procedure and Judicial Administration’, 2 Journal of Legal Studies, 399 ff. Rose-Ackerman, Susan and Geistfeld, Mark (1987), ‘The Divergence Between Social and Private Incentives to Sue: A Comment on Shavell, Menell, and Kaplow’, 16 Journal of Legal Studies, 483-491. Shavell, Steven (1982b), ‘The Social Versus the Private Incentive to Bring Suit in a Costly Legal System’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 333-339. Shavell, Steven (1995), ‘Alternative Dispute Resolution: An Economic Analysis’, 24 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-28.
Cases Alyeska Pipeline Service Co. v. Wilderness Society, 421 US 240 Marek v. Chesny, 105 S.Ct. 3012 (1985)
7400 SETTLEMENT Andrew F. Daughety Department of Economics and Business Administration, Vanderbilt University © Copyright 1999 Andrew F. Daughety
Abstract This survey of modeling of pretrial settlement bargaining organizes current main themes and recent developments. The basic concepts used are outlined as core models and then a number of variations on these core models are discussed. The focus is on papers that emphasize formal models of settlement negotiation and the presentation in the survey is organized in game-theoretic terms, this now being the principal tool employed by analyses in this area, but the discussion is aimed at the not-terribly-technical non-specialist. The survey also illustrates some of the basic notions and assumptions of information economics and of (cooperative and noncooperative) game theory. JEL classification: K41, C70 Keywords: Settlement Bargaining
1. Introduction This survey of the modeling of pretrial settlement bargaining organizes current main themes and recent developments. The basic concepts used are outlined as core models and then a number of variations on these core models are discussed. The emphasis in the survey on main themes and modeling of basic concepts is for two reasons. First, Cooter and Rubinfeld (1989) provide an excellent survey of this literature (in the context of a broader consideration of the economics of dispute resolution and the law) up to that date, while Miller (1996) provides a recent non-technical review addressing policies that encourage settlement. Second, as with much of law and economics, a catalog of even relatively recent research would rapidly be out of date. The focus here is on papers that emphasize formal models of settlement negotiation and the presentation is organized in game-theoretic terms, this now being the principal tool employed by analyses in this area. The discussion is aimed at the not-terribly-technical non-specialist. In this chapter some of the basic notions and assumptions of game theory are presented and applied, but some of the more recent models of settlement negotiation rely on relatively advanced techniques; in those cases, technical
95
96
Settlement
7400
presentation will be minimal and intuition will be emphasized. For the interested reader, a recent source on game theory applications in law and economics is Baird, Gertner and Picker (1994); extensive reviews of that book appear in Huang (1995) and Salant and Sims (1996). Two quite readable books on game theory, modeling and a number of related philosophical issues are Binmore (1992) and Kreps (1990). Finally, chapters seven through nine of Mas-Colell, Whinston and Green (1995) provide the technically sophisticated reader with a convenient, efficient and careful presentation of the basic techniques of modern (non-cooperative) game theory, while chapters thirteen and fourteen provide a careful review of the basics of information economics. What is the basic image that emerges from the settlement bargaining literature? It is that settlement processes act as a type of screen, sorting amongst the cases, presumably causing the less severe (for example, those with lower true damages) to bargain to a resolution (or to do this very frequently), while the more severe (for example, those with higher damages) may proceed to be resolved in court. The fact that some cases go to trial is often viewed as an inefficiency. While this survey adopts this language (as does much of the literature reviewed) one might also view the real possibility of trial as necessary to the development of case law and as a useful demonstration of the potential costs associated with decisions made earlier about levels of care. In other words, the possibility of trials may lead to greater care and to more efficient choices overall. Moreover, the bargaining and settlement literatures have evolved in trying to explain the sources of negotiation breakdown: the literature has moved from explanations fully based on intransigence to explanations focused around information. This is not to assert that trials do not occur because of motives outside economic analysis, just that economic attributes contribute to explaining an increasing share of observed behavior. In the next few sections (comprising Part A) significant features of settlement models are discussed and some necessary notation is introduced; this part ends with a simplified example indicating how the pieces come together. Part B examines the basic models in use, varying the level of information that litigants have and the type of underlying bargaining stories that are being told. Part C considers a range of ‘variations’ on the Part B models, again using the game-theoretic organization introduced in Part A.
7400
Settlement
97
A. Basic Issues, Notions and Notation 2. Overview In this part the important features of the various approaches are discussed and notation that is used throughout is introduced. Paralleling the presentation of the models to come, the current discussion is organized to address: (1) players; (2) actions and strategies; (3) outcomes and payoffs; (4) timing; (5) information and (6) prediction. A last section provides a brief example. Words or phrases in italics are terms of special interest.
3. Players The primary participants (usually called litigants or players) are the plaintiff (P) and the defendant (D); a few models have allowed for multiple P’s or multiple D’s, but for now assume one of each. Secondary participants include attorneys for the two litigants (AP and AD, respectively), experts for the two participants (XP and XD, respectively) and the court (should the case go to trial), which is usually taken to be a judge or a jury (J). Almost all models restrict attention to P and D, either ignoring the others or relegating them to the background. As an example, a standard assumption when there is some uncertainty in the model (possibly about damages or liability, or both) is that, at court, J will learn the truth and make an award at the true value (the award will be the actual damage, liability will be correctly established, and so on). Moreover, J is usually assumed to have no strategic interests at heart, unlike P, D, the A’s and the X’s. Section 15 considers some efforts to incorporate Js decision process in a substantive way. Finally, uncertainty enters the analysis whenever something relevant is not known by at least one player. Uncertainty also arises if one player knows something that another does not know, or if the players move simultaneously (for example, they simultaneously make proposals to each other). These issues will be dealt with in the sections on timing (6) and information (7), but sometimes such possibilities are incorporated by adding another ‘player’ to the analysis, namely nature (N), a disinterested player whose actions influence the other players in the game via some probability rule.
4. Actions and Strategies An action is something a player can choose to do when it is their turn to make a choice. For example, the most commonly modeled action for P or D
98
Settlement
7400
involves making a proposal. This generally takes the form of a demand from P of D or an offer from D to P. This then leads to an opportunity for another action which is a response to the proposal, which usually takes the form of an acceptance or a rejection of a proposal, possibly followed by yet another action such as a counterproposal. Some models allow for multiple periods of proposal/response sequences of actions. When a player has an opportunity to take an action, the rules of the game specify the allowable actions at each decision opportunity. Thus, in the previous example, the specification of allowed response actions did not include delay (delay will be discussed in Section 18). Actions chosen at one point may also limit future actions: if ‘good faith’ bargaining is modeled as requiring that demands never increase over time, then the set of actions possible when P makes a counterproposal to Ds counterproposal may be limited by P’s original proposal. Other possible actions include choosing to employ attorneys or experts, initially choosing to file a suit or finally choosing to take the case to court should negotiations fail. Most analyses ignore these either by not allowing such choices or by assuming values for parameters that would make particular choices ‘obvious’. For example, many analyses assume that the net expected value of pursuing a case to trial is positive, thereby making credible such a threat by P during the negotiation with D; this topic will be explored more fully in Section 16.1. In general, a strategy for a player provides a complete listing of actions to be taken at each of the player’s decision opportunities and is contingent on: (1) the observable actions taken by the other player(s) in the past; (2) actions taken by the player himself in the past; (3) the information the player currently possesses; (4) any exogenous relevant actions that have occurred that the player is aware of (for example, speculations about the award a specific J might choose). Thus, as an example, consider an analysis with no uncertainty about damages, liability, what J will do, and so on, where P proposes, D responds with acceptance or a counterproposal, followed by P accepting the counterproposal or choosing to break off negotiations and go to court. A strategy for P would be of the form ‘propose an amount x; if D accepts, make the transfer and end while if D counterproposes y, choose to accept this if y is at least z, otherwise proceed to court’. P would then have a strategy for each possible x, y and z combination. An analogy may be helpful here. One might think of a strategy as a book, with pages of the book corresponding to opportunities in the game for the book’s owner to make a choice. Thus, a typical page says ‘if you are at this point in the book, take this action’. This is not a book to be read from coverto-cover, one page after the previous one; rather, actions taken by players lead other players to go to the appropriate page in their book to see what
7400
Settlement
99
they do next. All the possible books (strategies) that a player might use form the player’s personal library (the player’s strategy set). There are times when being predictable as to which book you will use is useful, but there can also be times when unpredictability is useful. A sports analogy would be to imagine yourself to be a goalie on the A team, and a member of the B team has been awarded the chance to make a shot on your goal. Assume that there is insufficient time for you to fully react to the kick, so you are going to have to generally move to the left or the right as the kicker takes his shot. If it is known that, in such circumstances, you always go to your left, the kicker can take advantage of this predictability and improve his chance of making a successful shot. This is also sometimes true in settlement negotiations: if P knows the actual damage that D is liable for, but D only knows a possible range of damages, then D following a predictable policy of never going to court encourages P to make high claims. Alternatively, D following a predictable policy of always going to court no matter what P is willing to settle for may be overly costly to D. Mixed strategies try to address this problem of incorporating just the right amount of unpredictability and are used in some settlement models. Think of the individual books in a player’s library as pure strategies (pure in the sense of being predictable) and think of choosing a book at random from the library, where by ‘at random’ we mean that you have chosen a particular set of probability weights on the books in your library. In this sense your chosen set of weights is now your strategy (choosing one book with probability one and everything else with probability zero gets us back to pure strategies). A list of strategies, with one for each player (that is, a selection of books from all the players’ libraries), is called a strategy profile.
5. Outcomes and Payoffs An outcome for a game is the result of a strategy profile being played. Thus, an outcome may involve a transfer from D to P reflecting a settlement or it might be a transfer ordered by a court or it might involve no transfer as P chooses not to pursue a case to trial. If the reputations of the parties are of interest, the outcome should also specify the status of that reputation. In plea bargaining models, which will be discussed in Section 17.4, the outcome might be a sentence to be served. In general, an outcome is a list (or vector) of relevant final attributes for each player in the game. For each player, each outcome has an associated numerical value called the payoff, usually a monetary value. For example, a settlement is a transfer of money from D to P; for an A or an X the payoff might be a fee. For models that are concerned with risk preferences, the payoffs would be in
100
Settlement
7400
terms of the utility of net wealth rather than in monetary terms. Payoffs that are strictly monetary (for example, the transfer itself) are viewed as reflecting risk-neutral behavior on the part of the player. Payoffs need not equal expected awards, since parties to a litigation also incur various types of costs. The cost most often considered in settlement analyses is called a court cost (denoted here as kP and kD, respectively). An extensive literature has developed surrounding rules for allocating such costs to the litigants and the effect of various rules on the incentives to bring suit and the outcome of the settlement process; this is addressed in Section 17.2. Court costs are expenditures which will be incurred should the case go to trial and are associated with preparing for and conducting a trial; as such they are avoidable costs (in contrast with sunk costs) and therefore influence the decisions that the players (in particular P and D) make. Generally, costs incurred in negotiating are usually ignored, though some recent papers reviewed in Sections 11.2 and 18 emphasize the effect of negotiation costs on settlement offers and the length of the bargaining horizon. Unless specifically indicated, assume that negotiation costs are zero. The total payoff for a player labeled i (that is i = P, D, ...) is denoted $i . Note that this payoff can reflect long-term considerations (such as the value of a reputation or other anticipated future benefits) and multiple periods of negotiation. Generally, players in a game maximize their payoffs and thus, for example, P makes choices so as to maximize $P. For convenience, D’s payoff is written as an expenditure (if D countersues, then D takes the role of a plaintiff in the countersuit) and thus D is taken to minimize $D (rather than maximize -$D). While an alternative linguistic approach would be to refer to the numerical evaluation of D’s outcome as a ‘cost’ (which is then minimized, and thereby not use the word payoff with respect to D), the use of the term payoff for D’s aggregate expenditure is employed so as to reserve the word cost for individual expenditures that each party must make. Finally, since strategy profiles lead to outcomes which yield payoffs, this means that payoffs are determined by strategy profiles. Thus, if player i uses strategy si, and the strategy profile is denoted s (that is, s is the vector, or list (s1, s2, ..., sn), where there are n players), then we could write this dependence for player i as $i(s).
6. Timing The sequence of play and the horizon over which negotiations occur are issues of timing and of time. For example: do P and D make simultaneous proposals or do they take turns? Does who goes first (or who goes when)
7400
Settlement
101
influence the outcome? Do both make proposals or does only one? Can players choose to delay or accelerate negotiations? Are there multiple rounds of proposal/response behavior? Does any of this sort of detail matter in any substantive sense? Early settlement models abstracted from any dynamic detail concerning the negotiation process. Such models were based on very general theoretical models of bargaining (which ignored bargaining detail and used desirable properties of any resulting bargain to characterize what it must be) initially developed by Nash (1950). More recent work on settlement negotiations, which usually provides a detailed specification of how bargaining is assumed to proceed (the strategies employed and the sequencing of bargaining play are specified), can be traced to results in the theoretical bargaining literature by Nash (1953), Ståhl (1972) and Rubinstein (1982). Nash’s 1950 approach is called axiomatic while the Ståhl/Rubinstein improvement on Nash’s 1953 approach is called strategic; the two approaches are intimately related. Both approaches have generated vast literatures which have considered issues of interest to analyses of settlement bargaining; a brief discussion of the two approaches is provided in Sections 10 and 11 so as to place the settlement applications in a unified context. The discussion below also addresses the institutional features that make settlement modeling more than simply a direct application of bargaining theory. When considered, time enters settlement analyses in two basic ways. First, do participants move simultaneously or sequentially? This is not limited to the question of whether or not P and D make choices at different points on the clock. More significant is whether or not moving second involves having observed what the first-mover did. Two players who make choices at different points in time, but who do not directly influence each other’s choices (perhaps because the second-mover cannot observe or react to what the first-mover has done) are viewed as moving simultaneously: that my choice and your choice together influence what each of us receives as a payoff (symbolized in the payoff notation as $i(s) for player i) does not make moving at different points in time significant in and of itself. The real point here is whether all relevant decision makers must conjecture what the others are likely to do, or whether some can observe what others actually did. This is because the second-mover is influenced by the first-mover’s choice and because they both know this, which affects the first-mover’s choice as well. Asymmetry in what choices depend upon (in this sense) is modeled as choices being made in a sequence; symmetry is modeled as choices being made simultaneously. As will be seen in the example to be discussed in Section 9, who moves when can make a very significant difference in what is predicted. Note that a sequence of simultaneous decisions is possible (for
102
Settlement
7400
example, P and D both simultaneously make proposals and then both simultaneously respond to the proposals, and so on). A second way that time enters is in terms of the length of the horizon over which decisions are made. The main stream of research in the strategic bargaining literature views the horizon as infinite in length; this is done to eliminate the effect of arbitrary end-of-horizon strategic behavior. Settlement models, on the other hand, typically take the negotiation horizon as finite in length (and often very short, say, two periods). This is done for two reasons. First, while some cases may seem to go on forever, some form of termination actually occurs (cases are dropped, or resolved through negotiation or meet a court date). While setting a court date is not an ironclad commitment, few would argue that an infinite number of continuances is realistic. Second, in the more informationally complex models, this finite horizon restriction helps provide more precise predictions to be made than would otherwise be possible. Thus, in most settlement models there is a last opportunity to negotiate, after which either the case proceeds to trial or terminates (either because the last settlement proposal is accepted or the case is dropped). This is important because court costs are incurred only if the case actually proceeds to trial; that is, after the last possible point of negotiations. If negotiations were to continue during the trial, the ability to use the avoidance of these costs to achieve a settlement obviously is vitiated: as the trial proceeds the portion of costs that are sunk become larger and the portion that is avoidable shrinks. This problem has not been addressed generally, though papers by Spier (1992) and by Bebchuk (1996) consider significant parts of this issue; this is discussed in more detail in Section 18.
7. Information In Shavell (1982), the range over which litigants might bargain when assessments about outcomes may be different is analyzed as a problem in decision theory (a game against nature, N); this raises the issue of who knows what, when, why and how. Shavell’s paper indicated that differences in assessments by P and D as to the likelihood of success at trial, and the likely award, can lead to trial as an outcome. While Shavell’s paper did not consider strategic interaction among the players (for the first paper to incorporate strategic behavior, see P’ng, 1983), the role of information has become a central theme in the literature that has developed since, with special emphasis on accounting for informational differences and consistent, rational behavior. Moving momentarily from theory to empirical analysis, Farber and White (1991) use data from a hospital to investigate whether
7400
Settlement
103
seemingly asymmetrically distributed information influenced settlement rates and the speed with which cases settled; they find that it did. Informational considerations involve what players individually know and what they must guess about (where such guessing presumably involves some form of organized approach). Many of the analyses in the literature use different informational structures (who knows what when) and in this survey a variety of such structures will be presented. As a starting example, consider Pat, who developed an improved framitz (a tool for making widgets). Pat took the tool to the Delta Company (D), with the notion that Delta would manufacture the tool and Pat would become rich from her share of the profits. Delta indicated that the tool was not likely to be financially viable and Pat went back to work on other inventions. Some years later Pat noticed that many people who made widgets were using a slightly modified version of her tool made by Delta. Pat (P) decided to sue Delta (D) for misappropriation of intellectual property, and for convenience assume that while D’s liability is clear, the assessment of a level of compensation to P is less clear. D’s familiarity with the profits made (and experience with creative accounting procedures) means that D has a better idea of what level of total profits might be proved in court. Both P’s attorney and D’s attorney have (potentially similar) estimates of what the court is likely to do with any particular evidence on the level of profits of the tool (how the court, J, might choose to allocate the costs and revenues of the tool to P and D). Simplifying, there are two sources of uncertainty operating here: uncertainty by P and D about J and uncertainty by P about what D knows. First, both P and D cannot perfectly predict what J will choose as an award: here each faces an essentially similar level of uncertainty (there is no obvious reason to assert the presence of an asymmetry in what is knowable). Moreover, we will assume that this assessment of J’s likely actions, while probabilistic, is common knowledge. Common knowledge connotes the notion that were P and D to honestly compare their assessments of J’s likely actions for each possible set of details about the profits made by D, their assessments would be exactly the same, and P and D know that the other knows this, and P and D know that the other knows that the other knows this, and so on (see Aumann, 1976; Geanakoplos and Polemarchakis, 1982, and Binmore, 1992 for two early technical papers and a recent game theory text with an extensive prose discussion of this topic). Thus, P and D have the same information with regard to J; we might call this imperfect or symmetrically uncertain information to contrast it with the clear asymmetry that exists between P and D with respect to the information about revenues and costs that D knows. This latter notion of uncertainty is referred to as asymmetric information, and it is a main attribute of much of the recent work on settlement. Finally, if actual damage was common
104
Settlement
7400
knowledge and if P and D truly knew exactly what J would choose as an award and that were common knowledge, the resulting information condition is called perfect. A nice story which makes the differences in informational settings clear is due to John Roberts of Stanford University. Consider a card game played by at least two people, such as poker. If all hands were dealt face up and no more cards were to be dealt, this would be a situation of perfect information. If, instead, hands are dealt with (say) three cards face up and two cards face down, but no one can look at their ‘down’ cards, this is a setting of imperfect information. Finally, asymmetric information (also called incomplete information) would involve each player being able to privately look at their down cards before taking further actions (asking for alternative cards, betting, and so on). Note that in this last case we see the real essence of asymmetric information: it is not that one party is informationally disadvantaged when compared with the other (as in the case of Pat and Delta) as much as the players have different information from each other. One caution about the foregoing example. The perfect information case seems to be rather pointless: players without the best hand at the table would choose not to bet at all. Perfect information models are really not as trivial, since they significantly clarify what the essential elements of an analysis are and they provide a comparison point to evaluate how different informational uncertainties affect the efficiency of the predicted outcome. Timing in the play of the game is also a potential source of imperfect information. If P and D make simultaneous proposals (which might be resolved by, say, averaging), then when they are each considering what proposal to make they must conjecture what the other might choose to propose: what each will do is not common knowledge. Even if all other information in the analysis were perfect, this timing of moves is a source of imperfect information. The incorporation of informational considerations (especially asymmetric information) has considerably raised the ante in settlement modeling. Why? Is this simply a fad or an excuse for more technique? The answer is revealed in the discussion of the basic models and their variations. As indicated earlier, the problem with analyses that assumed perfect or imperfect information was that many interesting and significant phenomena were either attributed to irrational behavior or not addressed at all. For example, in some cases negotiations fail and a trial ensues, even though both parties may recognize that going to court is very costly; sometimes cases fail to settle quickly, or only settle when a deadline approaches. Moreover, agency problems between lawyers and clients, discovery, disclosure, various rules for allocating court costs or for admitting evidence have all been the subject of models using asymmetric information.
7400
Settlement
105
7.1 Modeling Uncertainty Models with perfect information specify parameters of the problem with no uncertainty attached: liability is known, damages are known, what J will do is known, costs are known, and so on. Imperfect information models involve probability distributions associated with one or more elements of the analysis, but the probability distributions are common knowledge, and thus the occurrence of uncertainty in the model is symmetric. For example, damages are ‘unknown’ means that all parties to the negotiation itself (all the players) use the same probability model to describe the likelihood of damage being found to actually have been a particular value. Thus, for example, if damage is assumed to take on the value dL (L for low) with probability p and dH (H for high) with probability (1 ! p), then the expected damage, E(d) = pdL + (1 ! p)dH is P’s estimate [EP(d)] as well as D’s estimate [ED(d)] of the damages that will be awarded in court. Usually, the court (J) is assumed to learn the ‘truth’ should the case go to trial, so that the probability assessment by the players may be interpreted as a common assessment as to what the court will assert to be the damage level, possibly reflecting the availability and admissibility of evidence as well as the true level of damage incurred. Note that such models are not limited to only accounting for two possible events (for example, perhaps the damage could be any number between dL and dH); this is simply a straight forward extension of the probability model. On the other hand, since P and D agree about the returns and costs to trial, there is no rational basis for actually incurring them and the surplus generated by not going to trial can be allocated between the players as part of the bargain struck. With asymmetric information, players have different information and thus have different probability assessments over relevant uncertain aspects of the game. Perhaps each player’s court costs are unknown to the other player, perhaps damages are known to P but not to D, or the likelihood of being found liable is better known by D than by P. Possibly P and D have different estimates, for a variety of reasons, as to what J will do. All of these differences in information may influence model predictions, but the nature of the differences is itself something that must be common knowledge. Consider yourself as one of the players in the version of the earlier card game where you can privately learn your down cards. Say you observe that you have an Ace of Spades and a King of Hearts as your two down cards. What can you do with this information? The answer is quite a bit. You know how many players there are and you can observe all the up cards. You can not observe the cards that have not been dealt, but you know how many of them there are. You also know the characteristics of the deck: four suits, thirteen cards each, no repeats, and so on. This means that given your down cards you could (at least theoretically) construct probability estimates of
106
Settlement
7400
what the other players have and know what estimates they are constructing about what you have. This last point is extremely important, since for player A to predict what player B will do (so that A can compute what to do), A needs to think from B’s viewpoint, which includes predicting what B will predict about what A would do. To understand this, let us continue with the card game example and consider a simple, specific example (we will then return to the settlement model to indicate the use of asymmetric information in that setting). Assume that there are two players (A and B), a standard deck with 52 cards (jokers are excluded) and the game involves two cards dealt face up and one card dealt face down to each of A and B; only one down card is considered to simplify the presentation. Table 1 shows the cards that have been dealt face up (available for all to see) and face down (available only for the receiver of the cards, and us, to see). For expositional purposes, H, D, C and S stand for hearts, diamonds, clubs and spades while a K represents a King, and so on. Table 1 Hands of Cards for A and B Up
Down
A
4S, KD
KH
B
QH, AC
2C
(Note: entries provide face value of card and suit) By a player’s type we mean their down cards (their private information), so A is a KH while B is a 2C, and only they know their own type. A knows that B is one of 47 possible types (A knows B cannot be a KH or any of the up cards) and, for similar reasons, B knows that A is one of 47 possible types. Moreover, A’s model of what type B can be (denoted pA(tB|tA)) provides A with the probability of each possibility of B’s type (denoted tB) conditional (the vertical line) on A’s type (denoted tA). The corresponding model for B that gives a probability of each possibility of A’s type is denoted pB(tA|tB). Note that all the probability models are formally also conditioned on all the upcards (for example, if we are especially careful we should write pA(tB|tA, 4S, KD, QH, AC ) and pB(tA|tB,4S, KD, QH, AC)), which we supress in the notation employed. In the particular case at hand tA = KH, so once A knows his type (sees his down card) he can use pA(tB|KH) to compute the possibilities about B’s down card (type). But A actually could have worked out his strategy for each
7400
Settlement
107
possible down card he might be dealt (and the possible up cards) before the game; his strategy would then be a function that would tell him what to do for each possible down-card/up-card combination he might be dealt in the game. Moreover, since he must also think about what B will do and B will not know A’s down card (and thus must use pA(tB|tA), instead of pA(tB|KH), as his probability model for what A will use about B’s possible down cards) then this seemingly extra effort (that is, A working out a strategy for each possible type) is not wasted, since A needs to do it anyway to model B modeling A’s choices. What we just went through is what someone analyzing an asymmetric game must do for every player. Finally, for later use, observe that these two probability models are consistent in the sense that they come from the same overall model p(tA, tB) which reflects common knowledge of the deck that was used. In other words, the foregoing conditional probabilities in the previous paragraph both come from the overall joint probability model p(tA, tB) using the usual rules of probability for finding conditional probabilities. So what does this mean for analyzing asymmetric information models of settlement? It means, for example, that if there is an element (or there are elements) about which there is incomplete information, then we think of that element as taking on different possible values (which are the types) and that the players have probability models about which possible value of the element is the true one. For example, if P knows the true damage level, then it has a probability model placing all the probability weight on the true value. If D only knows that it is between dL and dH, then D’s model covers all the possible levels of damage in that interval. The foregoing is an example of a one-sided asymmetric information model, wherein one player is privately informed about some element of the game and the other must use a probability model about the element’s true value; who is informed and the probability assessment for the uninformed player is common knowledge. Two-sided asymmetric information models involve both players having private information about either the same element or about different elements. Thus, P and D may, individually, have private information about what an independent friend-of-the-court brief (still in preparation for submission at trial) may say, or P may know the level of damage and D may know whether the evidence indicates liability or not (this latter example will be discussed further in Section 12.4). 7.2 Consistent versus Inconsistent Priors The card game examples above, in common with much of the literature on asymmetric information settlement models, involve games with consistent priors. A few papers on settlement bargaining appear to use ‘inconsistent’ priors. In this section we discuss what this means.
108
Settlement
7400
A game has consistent priors if each player’s conditional probability distribution over the other player’s type (or other players’ types) comes from the same overall probability model. In the card game example with A and B, we observed that there was an overall model p(tA, tB) which was common knowledge, and the individual conditional probability models pA(tB|tA) and pB(tA|tB) could have been found by using p(t A, tB). This was true because the makeup of the deck and the nature of the card-dealing process were common knowledge. What if, instead, the dealer (a stranger to both A and B) first looked at the cards before they were dealt and chose which ones to give to each player? Now the probability assessments are about the dealer, not the deck, and it is not obvious that A and B should agree about how to model the dealer. Perhaps if A and B had been brought up together, or if they have talked about how to model the dealer, we might conclude that the game would have consistent priors (though long-held rivalries or even simple conversations themselves can be opportunities for strategic behavior). Thus, if there is no underlying p(t A, tB) that would yield pA(tB|tA) and pB(tA|tB) through the standard rules of probability, this is a model employing inconsistent priors. Thus, if P and D both honestly believe they will win, they have inconsistent priors, because the joint probability of both winning is zero. While such beliefs might be held, they present a fundamental difficulty for using models which assert fully rational behavior: how can both players be rational, both be aware of each other’s assessment, aware that the assessments fundamentally conflict, and not use this information to revise and refine their own estimates? The data of the game must be common knowledge, as is rationality (and more, as will be discussed in the next section), but entertaining conflicting assessments themselves is in conflict with rationality. Alternatively put, for the consistent application of rational choice, differences in assessments must reflect differences in private information, not differences in world views. Presented with the same information, conflicts in assessments would disappear. To understand the problem, consider the following example taken from Binmore (1992, p. 477). Let A and B hold prior assessments about an uncertain event (an election). A believes that a Republican will win the election with probability 5/8 and the Democrat will win it with probability 3/8. B believes that the Democrat will win with probability 3/4 and the Republican with probability 1/4. Now if player C enters the picture, he can offer A the following bet: A wins $3 if the Republican wins and pays C $5 if the Democrat wins. C offers B the following bet: B wins $2 if the Democrat wins and pays C $6 if the Republican wins. Assume that A and B are riskneutral, are well aware of each other’s assessments, and stick to the foregoing probabilities and that C pays each of them a penny if they take the
7400
Settlement
109
bets. Then both A and B will take the bets and for any probability of the actual outcome, C’s expected profits are $2.98 ($3 less the two pennies). This is derisively called a ‘money pump’ and works because of the inconsistent priors; that is, neither A nor B update their assessment in response to the assessments that the other is using and is willing to bet with. Now inconsistent priors may occur because one or the other or both think that the other player is irrational. Recent laboratory experiments (see Babcock et al., 1995) have found seemingly inconsistent priors that arise from a ‘self-serving’ bias reflecting anticipated opportunities by players in a settlement activity. However, in an analysis employing incentives and rational choice, introducing something inconsistent with rational behavior creates a problem in terms of the analysis of the model and the comparison of any results with those of other analyses. How important consistent priors are to the analysis has been made especially clear in work on analyzing asymmetric information games. Starting from basic principles of rational decision making, anyone making a choice about something unknown must make some assumptions about what characterizes the unknown thing (usually in the form of a probability distribution). To have two players playing an asymmetric game means, essentially, that they are playing a family of games, one for each possible pair of types (that is, one game for each pair of possible players). But which one are they playing? This is solved by superimposing a probabilistic choice by Nature (N), where each game is played with the probability specified by the overall distribution over types (denoted earlier in the card examples as p(tA, tB)). If this distribution does not exist (that is, if priors are inconsistent), we cannot do this and players are left not properly anticipating which game might be played. This transformation of something difficult to analyze (an asymmetric information game) into something we know how to analyze (a game with imperfect information) won John Harsanyi a share (along with John Nash and Reinhard Selten) of the 1994 Nobel Prize (the original papers are Harsanyi, 1967, 1968a, 1968b). Thus, while players may hold different assessments over uncertain events, the notion of consistent priors limits the causes of the disagreement to differences in things like private information, and not to alternative modes of analysis; thus, players cannot paper-over differences by ‘agreeing to disagree’. It is through this door that a literature, initially spawned by dissatisfaction with the perfect (and imperfect) information prediction that cases always settle, has proceeded to explain a variety of observed behavior with asymmetric information models. One last point before passing on to prediction. Shavell (1993) has observed that when parties seek nonmonetary relief and the bargaining involves an indivisible item, settlement negotiations may break down, even
110
Settlement
7400
if probability assessments are the same. An example of such a case would be child custody in a state with sole custody laws. This survey restricts consideration to cases involving non-lumpy allocations.
8. Prediction The main purpose of all of the settlement models is to make a prediction about the outcome of bargaining, and the general rule is the more precise the prediction the better. The main tool used to make predictions in the recent literature is the notion of equilibrium. This is because most of the recent work has relied upon the notion of non-cooperative game theory, whereas earlier work implicitly or explicitly employed notions from cooperative game theory. The difference is that in a cooperative game, players (implicitly or explicitly) bind themselves ex ante to require that the solution to the game be efficient (‘no money is left on the table’), while the equilibrium of a non-cooperative game does not assume any exogenously enforced contractual agreement to be efficient, and may end up not being efficient. We consider these notions in turn (for a review of laboratory-based tests of bargaining models (see Roth, 1995). 8.1 Nash Equilibrium in Non-Cooperative Games A strategy profile provides an equilibrium if no individual player can unilaterally change their part of the strategy profile and make themselves better off; this notion of equilibrium is often called Nash equilibrium (after Nash, 1951), but its antecedents go far back in history. Using the notation introduced earlier, let s* be an equilibrium profile; for convenience, assume the game has two players, named 1 and 2, so s* = (s1*, s2*) and s1 and s2 are all the other strategies that 1 and 2, respectively, could use. Then player 1 is prepared to stay with s1* if: $1(s1*, s2*) > $1(s1, s2*) for every possible s1 player 1 could choose. Player 2 is prepared to stay with s2* if: $2(s1*, s2*) > $2(s1*, s2) for every possible s2 player 2 could choose. As stated earlier, no player can unilaterally improve his payoff by changing his part of the equilibrium strategy profile.
7400
Settlement
111
Without generating more notation, the above conditions for a Nash equilibrium in a perfect information setting can be directly extended to the imperfect information setting. Here, the payoffs shown in the above inequalities are replaced by expected payoffs (the expectation reflecting the presence of uncertainty in one or more elements in the payoff function). Finally, in the case of asymmetric information, strategies and expectations are dependent upon type, and thus the equations must now hold for every player type and must reflect the individual player’s conditional assessment about the other player(s). This last version is sometimes called a Bayesian Nash equilibrium to emphasize the role that the conditional probability distributions have in influencing the strategies that players use (for more detail, see Mas-Colell, Whinston and Green, 1995, Chapter 8). Note that in all the variations on the definition of Nash equilibrium, there is a reference to no individual choosing to ‘defect’ from the strategy profile of interest. What about coalitions of players? Class action suits involve forming coalitions of plaintiffs, joint and several liability impacts coalitions of defendants and successful (‘real world’) bargaining strategy sometimes requires building or breaking coalitions (see Lax and Sebenius, 1986). Issues of coalitions have been of great interest to game theorists and equilibrium notions have been developed to account for coalition defection from a purported equilibrium strategy profile (see Binmore, 1985; Bernheim, Peleg and Whinston, 1987; Binmore, 1992; Greenberg, 1994, and Okada, 1996 for a small sample of recent work), but this is still an emerging area. 8.2. Cooperative Solutions If two people are to divide a dollar between them (and both get nothing if they do not come to an agreement), then any allocation of the dollar such that each player gets more than zero is a Nash equilibrium, meaning that there is no predictive ‘bite’ to our definition of equilibrium in this bargaining context (prediction improvements, called refinements, exist and often have considerable bite; more on this later). In yet another seminal contribution, Nash (1950) provided a remarkable result that still provides context, and a reference point, for many analyses (cooperative and noncooperative) of bargaining. His approach was to focus on the outcome of the bargaining game and to ignore the details of the bargaining process entirely, thereby also skipping the notion of requiring an equilibrium as the prediction mechanism. He posed the question: what desirable properties (called axioms) should a bargaining solution possess in order that a problem have a unique prediction? As mentioned earlier, by solution we mean that, ex ante, the two players would be prepared to bind themselves to the outcome which the solution provides. This approach is presented in more detail in Section 10.
112
Settlement
7400
Nash’s axioms can be summarized as follows (see Binmore, 1992). First, the solution should not depend on how the players’ utility scales are calibrated. This means that standard models of utility from decision theory may be employed (see, for example, Baird, Gertner and Picker, 1994). If payoffs are in monetary terms, this also means that players using different currencies could simply use an exchange rate to convert everything to one currency. Second, the solution should always be efficient. Third, if the players sometimes agree to one outcome when a second one is also feasible, then they never agree to the second one when the first one is feasible. Fourth, in a bargaining game with two identical players, both players get the same payoffs. The remarkable result is that whether the game is in utilities or money terms, the four axioms result in a unique solution (called the Nash Bargaining Solution or NBS) to the bargaining game. We return to this in Section 10. There is a very important linkage between predictions using refinements of Nash equilibrium and predictions using a cooperative solution. One of the most remarkable and far-reaching results of game theory which emerged over the 1970s and 1980s has been the delineation of conditions under which the equilibria for properly structured non-cooperative games would be (in the lingo, would support) solutions to properly related cooperative games. In our particular case, there are conditions on the data for the strategic approach which guarantee that the equilibrium predicted for that model is the NBS of the associated bargaining problem. In other words, under certain conditions, the non-cooperative equilibrium is an efficient outcome. Since we have not explored the axiomatic or strategic approaches in detail yet, let us consider an example likely to be familiar to most readers: the classic model of the conflict between group and individual incentives captured in the ‘Prisoner’s Dilemma’ (see, Baird, Gertner and Picker (1994)). A variety of non-cooperative formulations have been developed wherein individual choices of strategies lead to the socially optimal outcome. The same techniques have been applied in a variety of settings, including bargaining. Thus, we now have a better understanding of how institutions, incentives and behavior may or may not substitute for artificially imposed binding agreements in achieving an efficient outcome. This also means that sources of inefficiencies (‘money left on the table’, and thus wasted) brought about by institutional constraints, incentives and non-cooperative behavior can be better understood.
7400
Settlement
113
9. An Example of a Model of Settlement Negotiation Before venturing into the section describing the range of settlement models, a brief example will help clarify the concepts raised above. Reconsider Pat and Delta’s negotiation with the following further simplifications and some numerical values. First, assume that the only source of uncertainty is Delta’s liability. Damages are known by all, as are court costs. Moreover, there are no attorneys or experts and J will simply award the actual damage if Delta is found to be liable. Second, we will consider two simple bargaining stories. (1) P makes a demand of D, followed by D accepting or rejecting the demand. Acceptance means a transfer from D to P; rejection means that J orders a transfer from D to P (the two transfers need not be the same) and both parties pay their court costs. Third, it is also common knowledge that if D is indifferent between accepting the proposal and rejecting it, D will accept it. (2) D makes an offer to P, followed by P accepting or rejecting the offer. Acceptance means a transfer from D to P; rejection means that J orders a transfer from D to P (again, the two transfers need not be the same) and both parties pay their court costs. Third, it is also common knowledge that if P is indifferent between accepting the proposal and rejecting it, P will accept it. Let d = 100 be the level of damages and L = 0.5 be the likelihood of D being found liable by J for the damage d. Let court costs be the same for both players with kP = kD = 10. Note that the expected compensation Ld exceeds the plaintiff’s court cost kP, so that should D reject P’s demand in case (1), or offer too little in (2), it is still worth P’s effort to go to trial. Note also that this ignores the possibility of bankruptcy of D. All of the above, that both players are rational (that is, P maximizes, and D minimizes, their respective payoffs) and the bargaining story being analyzed are common knowledge. One final bit of notation: let s be a settlement proposal. 9.1 Analyzing the Case Wherein P Makes a Demand The first task is to find out if settlement is possible (the admissible settlements). We start with D, as P must anticipate D’s choice when faced with P’s demand. D and P know that if the case goes to trial, D will expend either d + kD or kD (110 or 10), the first with probability L and the second with probability (1 ! L); thus D’s expected expenditure at trial (payoff from the outcome go to trial) is Ld + kD (that is, 60). Note that in this circumstance, P’s expected payoff from the outcome labelled trial is Ld ! kP (that is, 40). Thus, D will accept any settlement demand not exceeding this expected expenditure at trial: s < Ld + kD.
(*)
114
Settlement
7400
P wishes to maximize her payoff which depends upon P’s demand and the choice made by D: $P = sP if D accepts the demand sP or $P = Ld ! kP if D rejects the demand. More carefully, using our earlier notation that the indicated payoff depending upon the strategy profile, we would have $P(sP, accept) = sP; that is, the payoff to P from her using the strategy ‘make the settlement demand sP’ and D using the strategy ‘accept’ is the transfer sP. Similarly, we would have $P(sP, reject) = Ld ! kP. In the rest of this example we will suppress this notation when convenient, but understanding it will be of value later. Observe that the maximum settlement demand that P can make (sP = Ld + kD, as shown in inequality (*)) exceeds P’s payoff from court. Thus, P maximizes the expected payoff from the game by choosing Ld + kD as her settlement demand, which D accepts since D cannot do better by rejecting the proposal and facing trial. Thus, to summarize: (1) the players are P and D; (2) the action for P is the demand sP (this is also P’s strategy) while the action for D is to accept or reject and D’s strategy is to accept if sP satisfies the condition (*) and to reject otherwise; (3) the outcomes are settlement and transfer with associated payoffs $P = sP and $D = sP, or proceed to trial and transfer with associated payoffs $P = Ld ! k P and $D = Ld + kD; (4) the timing is that P makes a demand and D chooses accept or reject; (5) information is imperfect in a very simple way in that P and D share the same assessment about the trial outcome with respect to liability. Note that it is unnecessary to model a choice for P about going to court if her demand were rejected because of the assumption that the expected compensation exceeds plaintiff trial costs. Moreover, since nothing in the settlement phase will influence the trial outcome itself should trial occur, J is not a player in a meaningful sense. The prediction (the equilibrium) of this game is that the case settles, the resulting transfer from D to P is Ld + kD (in the numerical example, 60) and the game payoffs are $P = $D = Ld + kD (60). 9.2 Analyzing the Case Wherein D Makes an Offer We now start with P in order to find the admissible settlements. Given the foregoing, P will accept any settlement offer that yields at least what she would get in court: s > Ld ! kP.
(**)
D wishes to minimize its payoff, which depends upon the offer it makes and the choice made by P: $D = sD if P accepts the offer sD or $D = Ld + kD if P rejects the offer. Thus D minimizes its payoff from the game by choosing Ld ! kP as its settlement offer, which P accepts since P cannot do better by rejecting the proposal and going to trial. Thus, to summarize: (1) the players
7400
Settlement
115
are P and D; (2) the action for D is the offer sD (this is also D’s strategy) while the action for P is accept or reject and P’s strategy is to accept if sD satisfies the condition (**) and to reject otherwise; (3) the outcomes are settlement and transfer with associated payoffs $D = sD and $P = sD, or proceed to trial and transfer with associated payoffs $D = Ld + kD and $P = Ld ! kP ; (4) the timing is that D makes an offer and P chooses to accept or reject; (5) information is imperfect in the same way as in the first case. The prediction (the equilibrium) of this game is that the case settles, the resulting transfer from D to P is Ld ! kP (40) and the game payoffs are $P = $D = Ld ! kP (40). 9.3 Bargaining Range and Bargaining Efficiency A clear implication of the foregoing analysis is that who moves last has a significant impact on the allocation of the surplus generated by not going to court. One could think of the process in the following way. D pays Ld to P no matter what procedure is used. P and D then contribute their court costs to a fund (called surplus) which they then split in some fashion. If the bargaining process involves P making a demand and D choosing only to accept or reject, then P gets all the surplus. If the roles are reversed, so are the fortunes. This might suggest that the two cases studied provide the extremes (the bargaining range) and that actual bargaining will yield something inside this range. The answer, we shall see, is maybe yes and maybe no. In the preceding analysis bargaining was efficient (no cases went to trial; again the reader is cautioned to recall the earlier discussion of the use of the word ‘efficiency’) since all information was symmetric and the first mover could make a take-it-or-leave-it proposal (cognizant of the second-mover’s ability to go to trial). Efficiency will fail to hold when we allow for asymmetric information. This will occur not because of mistakes by players, but because of the recognition by both players that information which is asymmetrically distributed will impose a cost on the bargaining process, a cost that often falls on the better informed party.
B. Basic Models of Settlement Bargaining 10. Perfect and Imperfect Information Models: Axiomatic Models for the Cooperative Case The perfect information model (and its first cousin, the imperfect information model), versions of which appear in Landes (1971), Gould (1973) and Posner (1973), is an important starting place as it focuses attention on efficient bargaining outcomes. Many of the earlier models employed risk aversion, which will be addressed in Section 17.1. For now,
116
Settlement
7400
and so as to make the presentations consistent with much of the more recent literature, payoffs will be assumed to be in dollar terms with risk-neutral players. 10.1 Perfect Information We start with the perfect information version. In keeping with the earlier discussion, the following model emphasizes final outcomes and suppresses bargaining detail. While the analysis below may seem like analytical overkill, it will allow us to structure the problem for later, more complex, discussions in this part and in Part C. The players are P and D; further, assume that the level of damages, d, is commonly known and that D is fully liable for these damages. Court costs are kP and kD, and each player is responsible for their own court costs. Each player has an individual action they can take that assures them a particular payoff. P can stop negotiating and go to court; thus the payoff to P from trial is $Pt = d ! kP (note the superscript t for trial) and the payoff to D from trial is $Dt = d + kD. Under the assumption that d ! kP > 0, P has a credible threat to go to trial if negotiations fail. For the purposes of most of this paper (and most of the literature) we assume this condition to hold (the issue of it failing will be discussed in Section 16.1). By default, D can ‘assure’ himself of the same payoff by stopping negotiations, since P will then presumably proceed to trial; no other payoff for D is guaranteed via his individual action. The pair ($Dt, $Pt) is called the threat or disagreement point for the bargaining game (recall that D’s payoff is an expenditure). What might they agree on? One way to capture the essence of the negotiation is to imagine both players on either side of a table, and that they actually place money on the table (abusing the card-game story from earlier, this is an ‘ante’) in anticipation of finding a way of allocating it. This means that D places d + kD on the table and P places kP on the table. The maximum at stake is the sum of the available resources, d + k P + k D, and therefore any outcome (which here is an allocation of the available resources) that does not exceed this amount is a possible settlement. P’s payoff, $P, is his bargaining outcome allocation (bP) minus his ante (that is, $P = bP ! kP). D’s payoff, $D, is his ante minus his bargaining outcome allocation (bD); thus D’s cost (loss) is $D = d + kD ! bD. Since the bargaining outcome (bP + bD) cannot exceed the total resources to be allocated (the money on the table), bP + bD < d + kD + kP, or equivalently, P’s gain cannot exceed D’s loss: $P = bP ! kP < d + kD ! bD = $D. Thus, in payoff terms, the outcome of the overall bargaining game must satisfy: (1) $P < $D; (2) $P > $Pt and 3) $D < $Dt. In bargaining outcome terms this can be written as: (1') bP+ bD < d + kD + kP; (2') bP > d and (3') bD > 0. For the diagrams to come, we restate (2') as bP ! d > 0.
7400
Settlement
117
Figure 1(a) illustrates the settlement possibilities. The horizontal axis indicates the net gain (!$D) or net loss (that is total expenditure, $D) to D. The vertical axis indicates the net gain ($P) or net loss (!$P) to P. The sloping line graphs points satisfying $P = $D while the region to the left of it involves allocations such that $P < $D. The best that D could possibly achieve is to recover his ante d + kD and get kP too; this is indicated at the end of the line at the point (kP, !kP), meaning D has a net gain of k P and P has a net loss of kP. At the other extreme is the outcome wherein P gets all of d + kP + kD, meaning P has a net gain of d + kD which is D’s net loss. Note also that points below the line represent inefficient allocations: this is what is meant by ‘money left on the table’. The disagreement point (!(d + kD), d ! kP) draws attention (observe the thin lines) to a portion of the feasible Figure 1 Settlement Under Perfect Information
set that contains allocations that satisfy inequalities (2) and (3) above. The placement of this point reflects the assertion that there is something to bargain over; if the point were above the line $P = $D then trial is unavoidable, since there would be no settlements that satisfy (2) and (3) above. This triangular region, satisfying inequalities (1), (2) and (3), is the settlement set and the end points of the portion of the line $P = $D which is in the settlement set are called the concession limits; between the concession limits (and including them) are all the efficient bargaining outcomes under settlement, called the settlement frontier. Figure 1(b) illustrates the settlement set as bargaining outcomes, found by subtracting the disagreement point from everything in the settlement set. Doing this helps adjust the region of interest for asymmetries in the threats that P and D can employ. This leaves any remaining asymmetries in power
118
Settlement
7400
or information in the resulting diagram. In the case at hand, the only power difference might appear in the difference between the costs of going to trial; other power differences such as differences in risk preferences, patience, and so on will be discussed in Section 17.1, while informational differences will be discussed in the sections on asymmetric information in Parts B and C. Notice that, in view of (2') and (3'), the vertical (non-negative) axis is labelled bP ! d while the horizontal (non-negative) axis is labelled bD. Moreover, since aggregate trial costs determine the frontier in Figure 1(b), the bargaining problem here is symmetric. The Nash Bargaining Solution (NBS) applies in either picture, but its prediction is particularly obvious in Figure 1(b): recalling the discussion in Section 8.2, requiring the solution to be efficient (axiom 2) and that, when the problem is symmetric the solution is too (axiom 4), means that splitting the saved court costs is the NBS in Figure 1(b). Thus, to find the NBS in Figure 1(a), we add the disagreement point back into the solution from Figure 1(b). Therefore, P’s payoff is d ! kP + (kP + kD)/2 = d + (k D ! kP)/2. D’s net outflow is !(d + kD) + (kP + kD)/2. In other words, D’s payoff (his expenditure) is d + (k D ! k P)/2. The result that players should ‘split the difference’ is always the NBS solution for any bargaining game with payoffs in monetary terms. Observe that if court costs are the same, then at the NBS P and D simply transfer the liability d. If D’s court costs exceed P’s, P receives more from the settlement than the actual damages, reflecting his somewhat stronger relative bargaining position embodied in his threat with respect to the surplus that P and D can jointly generate by not going to court. A similar argument holds for P in the weaker position, with higher costs of going to court: he settles for less than d. 10.2 Imperfect Information This is essentially the same model, so only the variations will be remarked upon. Assume that P and D have the same probability assessments for the two court costs and assume that they also have the same probability assessments over expected damages. This latter possibility could reflect that the level of damages is unknown (for example, as discussed in Section 7.1) but that liability is taken to be assured. Then they both see expected damages as E(d). Alternatively, perhaps damages are known to be d but liability is less clear but commonly assessed to be L; that is, L is the common assessment that D will be held liable for damages d and (1 ! L) is the common assessment that D will not be held liable at all. Then E(d) = dL (an admitted but useful abuse of notation). Finally, if there are common elements influencing the values that d might take on and the likelihood of D being held liable, and if the assessments of the possible values and their joint likelihood is common knowledge, then again we will write the expected
7400
Settlement
119
damages from trial as E(d). Again, this is abusing the notation, but avoids needless technical distinctions. The point is that in an imperfect information setting we simply take the preceding analysis and replace all known parameters with their suitably constructed expectations, yielding the same qualitative results: no trials occur in equilibrium, strong plaintiffs settle for somewhat more than their expected damages, and so forth.
11. Perfect and Imperfect Information Models: Strategic Models for the Non-Cooperative Case Again, we start with the perfect information case. Furthermore, since the actual bargaining procedure is now to be specified, the length of the bargaining horizon now enters into the analysis. The generic style of the models to be considered is that one player makes a proposal followed by the other player choosing to accept or reject the proposal. Concatenating as many of these simple proposal/response sequences as we choose provides the basic story. Some questions, however, remain. First, is the proposer the same player each time? In general we will assume that if there is more than one round of proposal/response, then proposers alternate (an important exception is Spier, 1992, where the plaintiff always proposes; this will be discussed in Section 18). If there is more than one round, the next proposal is often thought of as a counterproposal to the one before it. Second, how many periods of proposal/response will there be? This turns out to be a very significant question. Recall that in the cooperative model P and D were committed to finding an efficient bargaining outcome. Here, no such commitment is made; instead, we want to know when non-cooperative bargaining will be efficient. However, certain types of commitments in strategic models still may occur. The reason this is of interest is that commitment generally provides some power to the player who can make a commitment. For example, if there is one round of proposal/response, then the proposer has the ability to make an all-or-nothing proposal (more carefully put, all-or-court proposal). As was seen in the examples in Section 9, this led to a settlement that was efficient but rather one-sided. In particular, the proposer was able to achieve the point on the settlement frontier that is the responder’s concession limit. This is a reflection of the commitment power that the proposer enjoys of not responding to any counterproposals that the responder might desire to make: these are ruled out by the structure of the game analyzed. This is why this game is often referred to as an ultimatum game. Ultimatum games form the basis for many of the asymmetric information settlement analyses we shall examine.
120
Settlement
7400
Almost at the other end of the spectrum of theoretical bargaining analyses is the Rubinstein infinite-horizon model (Rubinstein, 1982). In this model an infinite number of rounds of proposal/response occur wherein the proposer’s identity alternates. In the settlement setting, each round allows P to choose to break off negotiations and go to trial. Here there are two somewhat more subtle forms of commitment in place of the power to make all-or-nothing proposals. First, if there is a positive interval of time between one round and the next, and if ‘time is money’, meaning (for example) that costs are accruing (perhaps experts are being kept available, or lawyers are accruing time), then the fact that during a round only one proposal is being considered (the proposer’s) provides some power to the proposer. Second, who goes first is still significant. Rubinstein considers a simple ‘shrinking pie’ example wherein each player discounts money received in the future relative to money received now. This encourages both players to want to settle sooner rather than later (all else equal). Thus, delay here yields inefficiency. Rubinstein uses a notion of Nash equilibrium that incorporates the dynamics of the bargaining process (this extra property of equilibrium is called sequential rationality, which will be discussed in more detail in Section 11.1) which results in a unique prediction for the bargaining game. In particular, there is no delay and, if both players are identical, then the player who goes first gets more than half of the amount at stake. Models that shrink the time interval associated with each round find that both sources of power go away as the time interval between proposals becomes vanishingly small. Note that, even with positive intervals, the effect of commitment (in this case, a short-run commitment to a proposal) is not as strong as in the ultimatum game, since counterproposals can occur and players generally cannot bind themselves to previous proposals they have made. In other words, such infinite horizon models can generate efficient settlement at points on the frontier other than the concession limits. In fact, under certain conditions they predict the NBS as the unique equilibrium of the strategic bargaining game. Note that the fact that a strategic model employs perfect information does not guarantee that the predicted outcome is efficient. A particularly striking example of this is contained in Fernandez and Glazer (1991) who consider wage negotiations between a union and a firm under perfect information and yet get inefficient equilibria. The source of the inefficiency is a pre-existing wage contract. This is an unexplored area for settlement bargaining which might yield some interesting results. Finally, a further difference between settlement applications and the general literature on bargaining concerns the incentive to settle as soon as possible, all else equal. Generally, in the settlement context, P wants to settle sooner but D wants to settle later. While countervailing pressures, such as costs that increase with time, may encourage D to settle as early as possible,
7400
Settlement
121
the fact that payment delayed is generally preferred by the payor (due to the time value of money) means that D’s overall incentives to settle soon can be mixed and delay may be optimal. Moreover, as observed in Spier (1992), unlike the Rubinstein model, if both P and D have the same discount rate then the pie itself is not shrinking (assuming no other costs of bargaining). This is because the effect of the opposed interests and the same discount rates is to cancel out. Therefore, in a multiperiod settlement model, delay due to the time value of money does not, in and of itself, imply inefficiency. We will return to this shortly. 11.1 Sequential Rationality Note that in much of the preceding discussion an implicit notion was that a player’s strategy anticipates future play in the game. A strategy is sequentially rational if it is constructed so that the player takes an optimal action at each possible decision opportunity that the player has in the future. Earlier, in the discussion of the disagreement point, sequential rationality was used by P. The threat to go to trial if bargaining failed to satisfy (2) was sequentially rational: it was a credible threat because if P got to that point, he would choose to fulfill the threat he had made. Applying sequential rationality to the strategies players use, and to the analysis players make of what strategies other players might use, means that strategies based on threats that a rational player would not carry out (incredible threats) are ruled out. Many of the improvements in making predictions for asymmetric information models that have occurred over the last fifteen years have involved employing sequential rationality, generally in conjunction with further amplifications of what rational behavior implies. Rubinstein finds a unique prediction in the infinite-horizon alternating offers game (for short, the Rubinstein game) because he predicts Nash equilibria which enforce sequential rationality (called subgame perfect equilibrium; for a discussion of some applications of subgame perfection in law and economics, see Baird, Gertner and Picker, 1994). In the Rubinstein game, even though the horizon is infinite, the (sequentially rational) Nash equilibrium is a unique, specific, efficient bargaining allocation which is proposed and accepted in the first round. Thus, efficiency (both in terms of fully allocating what is available to bargain over as well as doing it without delay) is a result, not an assumption. 11.2 Settlement Using Strategic Bargaining Models in the Perfect Information Case The discussion in Section 9 provides the details of the ultimatum game version of settlement. Since that application technically involved imperfect information (the assessment about liability), a careful treatment means that we would take L = 1, yielding the payoffs for the ultimatum model with P as
122
Settlement
7400
proposer (the P-proposer ultimatum model) to be $P = $D = d + kD, while the D-proposer ultimatum model’s payoffs would be $P = $D = d ! kP. The rest of this section is therefore devoted to the analysis in the infinite horizon case. The tradeoff between D’s natural interest to delay payment and any incentives to settle early (in particular, P’s credible threat to go to court and any negotiation costs borne by D) is explored in the settlement context in Ho Wang, Kim and Yi (1994); they also consider an asymmetric information case which will be discussed in Section 12.4. In the perfect information analysis, D proposes in the first round, but is subject in each round to an additional cost, c, which reflects per period negotiating costs but is charged only if the negotiations proceed to the next period. One could include a cost of this sort for P, too, but it is the difference between P’s and D’s negotiating costs that matters, so letting P’s be zero is not a meaningful limitation. Let ƒ (a fraction between zero and one) be the common discount rate used by the players for evaluating and comparing money flows at different points in time; that is, a player is indifferent between receiving $1 next period and $ƒ this period. Note that this effect could be undone if, at trial, damages were awarded with interest from the date of filing the suit; this does not occur in their model. Wang, Kim and Yi show that if ƒc/(1 ! ƒ2) > d ! kP, then the unique subgame perfect equilibrium is for D to offer ƒ2c/(1 ! ƒ2) to P; if instead ƒc/(1 ! ƒ2) < d ! kP, the unique subgame perfect equilibrium involves D offering ƒ(d ! kP) to P. For a careful proof of this, see Wang, Kim and Yi; for our purposes, let us use some crude intuition (sweeping all sorts of technical details under the rug) to understand this result. Consider D’s viewpoint. The only reason for D to be indifferent between an expenditure in one period and an expenditure in the next period involves the delay cost and the discount rate: indifference as to when to spend s in one of two adjacent periods means the discounted value of waiting, incurring c and then spending s (which is ƒs + ƒc) should just equal the expenditure of s now (that is, ƒs + ƒc = s). Of course, since D only makes a decision every other period this relationship affects P more directly than D. P will find this to be advantageous if c is large enough and if ƒs + ƒc > d ! kP. Assume it is; this means that if costs are high enough to get D to not want to delay (or make an offer that would have P choose to go to trial) the worst that P would get would be ƒ(ƒs + ƒc), which should be the most D would offer; that is, s. Solving ƒ(ƒs + ƒc) = s for s yields s = ƒc/(1 ! ƒ2). If this is large enough, D will make an offer that P will prefer to the payoff from going to trial. Since the offer only has to make P indifferent between two adjacent time periods (when D offers and P accepts or rejects, and when P decides about going to trial or counterproposing), D can offer ƒ(ƒc/(1 ! ƒ2)) and P will accept in the period in which the offer is made if next period ƒc/(1 ! ƒ2) > d ! kP (the equality between the two sides is eliminated as it provides multiple
7400
Settlement
123
predictions, while the strict inequality yields a unique solution; see Rubinstein, 1985). In this sense, ƒc/(1 ! ƒ2) > d ! kP really is a statement that the cost of delay is high from D’s viewpoint, which is why D must offer something higher than the discounted value of going to trial, that is, ƒ(d ! kP). Even if costs are low (that is, ƒc/(1 ! ƒ2) < d ! kP), D must still worry about P’s choice of going to court, but P can no longer exploit D’s cost weakness to further improve the bargain in his favor. Thus, D can offer the discounted value of P’s concession limit, namely ƒ(d ! kP), since P cannot choose to go to court until next period and therefore might as well accept ƒ(d ! kP) now. To summarize, the players are P and D, actions in each period involve proposals followed by accept/reject from the other player, with P able to choose to go to court when it is his turn to propose. Payoffs are as usual with the added provisos concerning the discount rate ƒ reflecting the time value of money, and the per period cost c, for the defendant, which is incurred each time negotiators fail to agree. The bargaining horizon is infinite and information is perfect. The result is that: (1) P and D settle in the first period; (2) the prediction is unique and efficient; (3) if negotiation costs are sufficiently high then the prediction is on the settlement frontier, between the discounted values of the concession limits and (4) otherwise it is at the discounted value of P’s concession limit, reflecting the fact that D moved first. 11.3 The Imperfect Information Case The extension of the ultimatum game results of Section 9 to the imperfect information case parallels the discussion in Section 10.2. This is similarly true for the multiperiod case, which is why this issue has not received much attention.
12. Analyses Allowing for Differences in Player Assessments Due to Private Information In this section we consider models that account for differences in the player’s assessments about items such as damages and liability based on the private information players possess when they bargain. We focus especially on two models: one developed by Bebchuk (1984) and one developed by Reinganum and Wilde (1986). Most of the analyses in the current literature are based on one of these two primary settlement models, both of which analyze ultimatum games and both of which assume one-sided asymmetric information; that is, that there is an aspect of the game (typically a parameter such as damages or liability) about which P and D have different information, and only one of the players knows the true value of the
124
Settlement
7400
parameter during bargaining. Since the model structure is so specific (the ultimatum game) and the distribution of information is so one-sided, we also consider what models with somewhat greater generality suggest about the reasonableness of the two prime workhorses of the current settlement literature. For a survey of asymmetric information bargaining theory, see Kennan and Wilson (1993). For a recent discussion of the settlement frontier under inconsistent priors, see Chung (1996). 12.1 Yet More Needed Language and Concepts: Screening, Signaling, Revealing and Pooling Reaching back to Section 7, a one-sided information model is like a card game where only one player has a down card and knows the value of that card. That player is privately informed and, because of consistent priors, both players know that the probability model being used by the uninformed player is common knowledge. Since the basic bargaining process involves one round of proposal and response, the fact that only one of the players possesses private information about something that is important to both means that when the informed player acts is, itself, important. A screening model (also sometimes called a sorting model) involves the uninformed player making the proposal and the informed player choosing to accept or reject the proposal. A signaling model involves the reverse: the informed player makes the proposal and the uninformed player chooses to accept or reject it. Note that the word ‘signaling’ only means that the proposal is made by the informed player, not that the proposal itself is necessarily informative about the private information possessed by the proposer. Bebchuk’s model is a screening model and Reinganum and Wilde’s model is a signaling model. These are non-cooperative models of bargaining, so our method of prediction is finding an equilibrium (rather than a cooperative solution). In both cases sequential rationality is also employed. Generally, in the case of a screening model this yields a unique prediction. In the case of a signaling model sequential rationality is generally insufficient to produce a unique prediction. The reason is that since the uninformed player is observing the informed player’s action in this case, the action itself may reveal something about the private information of the proposer. To understand this, consider a modification of the card game story from Section 7.1. Here are the hands for players A and B and, as before, only A knows his down card.
7400
Settlement
125
Table 2 Hands of Cards for A and B Up
Down
A
AD, QD, JD, 10D
2H
B
10C, 10S, 9S, 5D, 2C
(Note: entries provide face value of card and suit) To fill out the story, all the above cards have just been dealt, after players put some money on the table, from a standard 52-card deck. The rules are that player A may now discard one card (if it is the down card, this is done without revealing it) and a new card is provided that is drawn from the undealt portion of the deck. A can also choose not to discard a card. If he does discard one, the new card is dealt face up if the discard was an up-card and is dealt face down otherwise. After this, A and B can add money to that already on the table or they can surrender their share of the money currently on the table (‘fold’); for convenience, assume that a player must fold or add money (a player cannot stay in the game without adding money to that already on the table). The cards are then compared, privately, by an honest dealer, and any winner gets all the money while a tie splits the money evenly amongst those who have not folded. The comparison process in this case means that, for player A, a down card that matches his Ace, Queen or Jack card with the same face value (that is, A ends up with two Aces or two Queens or two Jacks) will beat B’s hand, as will any Diamond in conjunction with A’s up cards currently showing. Other draws mean that A will either tie (a 10H) or lose. Before A chooses whether and what to discard, B knows that the down card could be any of 43 cards with equal likelihood. Now if A discards his down card, based on sequential rationality, B knows that it was not an Ace, a Queen, a Jack or a Diamond. This information can be used by B before he must take any action. He may choose to fold, or he may choose to add money, but this decision is now influenced by what he believes to be A’s private information, A’s new down card. These beliefs take the form of an improved probability estimate over A’s type (adjusting for what has been observed). In fact, these assessments are called beliefs, and in an asymmetric information model, players form beliefs based upon the prior assessments and everything that they have observed before each and every decision they make. The addition of the need to account for what beliefs players can
126
Settlement
7400
reasonably expect to hold makes the signaling game more complex to analyze than the screening game. A few more observations about the card game are in order. First, even though this was a signaling game, the signal of discarding did not completely inform the uninformed player of the content of the private information. A strategy for the informed player is revealing if, upon the uninformed player observing the action(s) of the informed player, the uninformed player can correctly infer the informed player’s type. In this sense, each type of player has an action that distinguishes it from all the other types. For example, in the settlement context where P is privately informed about the true level of damages but D only knows the prior distribution, a revealing strategy would involve each possible type of P (each possible level of damages) making a different settlement demand, such as P demands his true damages plus D’s court costs. If instead P always asked for the average level of damages, independent of the true level, plus court costs, then P would be using a pooling strategy: different types of P take the same action and therefore are observationally indistinguishable. In the card game above, A choosing to discard his down card has some elements of a revealing strategy (not all types would choose this action) and some elements of a pooling strategy (there are a number of types who would take the same action). This is an example of a semi-pooling or partial pooling strategy. Notice that if the deck had originally consisted of only the eleven cards AD, KD, QD, JD, 10D, 10C, 10S, 9S, 5D, 2C, 2H, then B could use the action ‘discard’ to distinguish between the private information ‘initial down card = KD’ and ‘initial down -card = 2H’ because discarding the down card is only rational for the player holding a 2H. Thus, discarding or not discarding in this case is a fully revealing action. In this particular example we got this by changing the size of the deck (thereby changing the number of types), but this is not always necessary. In many signaling models, extra effort placed on making predictions, even in the presence of a continuum of types, leads to fully revealing behavior; we will see this in the signaling analysis below. Finally, a revealing equilibrium means that the equilibrium involves the complete release of all private information. In a revealing equilibrium the privately informed player is employing a revealing strategy. In a pooling equilibrium the private information is not released. In other words, at the end of the game, no more is necessarily known by the uninformed player than was known before play began. More generally, in a partial pooling equilibrium, some of the types have been revealed through their actions and some of the types took actions which do not allow us to distinguish them from one another.
7400
Settlement
127
12.2 Where You Start and Where You End As will be seen below, a typical screening model produces partial pooling equilibria as its prediction; in fact, the equilibrium is often composed of two big pools (a bunch of types do this and the rest do that) and is only fully revealing if each pool consists of one type. In other words, if the private information in the model takes on more than two values, some pooling will typically occur in the equilibrium prediction of a screening model. On the other hand, a typical signaling model has all three types of equilibria (revealing, fully pooling, partial pooling) as predictions, but with some extra effort concerning rational inference (called refinements of equilibrium) this often reduces to a unique prediction of a revealing equilibrium. Either one of these types of prediction may be desirable, depending upon the process being analyzed. 12.3 One-Sided Asymmetric Information Settlement Process Models: Examples of Analyses In the subsections to follow we will start with the same basic setting and find the results of applying screening and signaling models. Bebchuk’s 1984 paper considered an informed defendant (concerning liability) responding to an offer from an uninformed plaintiff; Reinganum and Wilde’s 1986 paper considered a plaintiff with private information about damages making a demand of an uninformed defendant. Initially, information will be modeled as taking on two levels (that is, a two-type model is employed) and a basic analysis using each approach will be presented and solved. The result of allowing for more than two types (in particular, a continuum of types) will then be discussed in the context of the alternative approaches. Since most of the discussion earlier in this survey revolved around damages, both approaches will be applied to private information on damages, suggesting a natural setting of an informed P and an uninformed D (note, however, that the earlier example of Pat and Delta was purposely posed with Delta as the informed party to emphasize that the analysis is applicable in a variety of settings). More precisely, the level of damages is assumed to take on the value dL (L for low) or dH (H for high), meaning that P suffers a loss and it takes on one of these two levels, which is private information for P. Moreover, dH > dL > 0. The levels are common knowledge as is D’s assessment that p is the probability of the low value being the true level of damages. If the case were to go to trial then J will find out the true level of damages (whether the damages were equal to dL or equal to dH) and award the true damages to P. Thus ED(d) = pdL + (1 ! p)dH is D’s prior estimate of the expected damages that he will pay if he goes to trial; P knows whether the damages paid will be dL or dH. Should the case go to trial each player pays his own court costs (kP and k D, respectively) and, for simplicity
128
Settlement
7400
again, assume that dL > kP; relaxing this assumption is discussed in Section 16.1. Finally, in each case the structure of the bargaining process is represented by an ultimatum game. In particular, the player who responds will choose to accept the proposal if he is indifferent between the payoff resulting from accepting the proposal and the payoff resulting from trial. Without any more information, D’s a priori (that is, before bargaining) expected payoff from trial is ED(d) + kD; P’s payoff from trial is dL ! kP if true damages are dL, and dH ! kP if true damages are dH. 12.3.1 Screening: A Two-Type Analysis In this model D offers a settlement transfer to P of sD and P responds with acceptance or rejection. For the analysis to be sequentially rational (that is, we are looking for a subgame perfect equilibrium) we start by thinking about what P’s strategy should be for any possible offer made by D in order for him to maximize his overall payoff from the game. If sD > dH ! kP, then no matter whether damages are high or low, P should accept and settle at sD. If sD < dL ! kP, then no matter whether damages are high or low, P should reject the offer and go to trial. If sD is set so that it lies between these two possibilities, that is, dH ! kP > sD > dL ! kP, then a P with high damages should reject the offer, but a P with low damages should accept the offer. This last offer is said to screen the types; note that the offer results in the revelation of the private information. Thus P’s optimal action is contingent upon the offer made; we have found P’s strategy and it involves rational choice. D can do this computation, too, for each possible type of P that could occur, so from D’s viewpoint he models P as having a strategy that depends both on P’s type and upon D’s offer. As always, D’s objective is to minimize expected expenditure and he must make an offer before observing any further information about P; thus, D cannot improve his assessments as occurred in the card game. D knows, however, that some offers are better than others. For example, the lowest offer in the range dH ! kP > sD > dL ! kP, namely sD = dL ! kP, is better than any other offer in that range, since it does not change the result that H-type P’s will reject and L-type P’s will accept, and its cost is least when compared to other possible offers in this range. The expected cost of screening the types is p(dL ! kP) + (1 ! p)(dH + kD) = ED(d) + kD ! p(kP + kD), since the offer elicits acceptance with probability p (the probability of L-types) and generates a trial and attendant costs with probability (1 ! p). The payoff from making offers that both types reject is ED(d) + kD. Finally, the expected cost from making an offer that both types will accept is simply the cost of the offer that the H-type will accept, namely dH ! kP. A comparison of the payoffs from the different possible offers that D could make indicates that it is always better for D to make an offer of at least the L-type’s concession limit (that is, the value of sD specified above, dL !
7400
Settlement
129
kP). It may be optimal to pool the types; that is, to make an offer at the Htype’s concession limit (dH ! kP), which will therefore be accepted by P independent of his actual damages incurred. Finally, comparing the expected cost to D of the screening offer, ED(d) + kD ! p(kP + kD), with the expected cost to D of the pooling offer, dH ! kP, it is optimal to screen the types if ED(d) + kD ! p(kP + kD) < dH ! kP; that is, if: p > (kP + kD)/(dH ! dL + kP + kD).
(SSC)
Inequality (SSC) is the simple screening condition (simple because it considers two types only); it indicates that the relevant comparison between screening the types or pooling them involves total court costs (kP + k D), the difference between potential levels of damages (dH ! dL) and the relative likelihood of H- and L-types. Given court costs and the gap between high and low damages, the more likely it is that P has suffered low damages rather than high damages, the more likely D should be to screen the types and thereby only rarely go to trial (and then, always against an H-type). If the likelihood of facing an H-type P is sufficiently high (that is, p is low), then it is better to make an offer that is high enough to settle with both possible types of plaintiff. Therefore, with pooling there are no trials, but with screening trials occur with probability (1 ! p). Condition (SSC) also suggests that, for a given probability of low-damage Ps and a given gap between the levels of damages, sizable trial costs auger for pooling (that is, settling with both types of P). Finally, the model allows us to compute the efficiency loss and to recognize its source. To see this, imagine the above analysis in the imperfect information setting; in particular, for this setting both P and D do not know P’s type, and they agree on the estimate of damages, ED(d), and that liability of D for the true damages is certain. In the imperfect information version of the D-proposer ultimatum game, D’s optimal offer is ED(d) ! kP, P’s concession limit under imperfect information. Since in that setting P doesn’t know his type, he would settle at ED(d) ! kP rather than require dH ! kP (which is greater than ED(d) ! kP) to avoid trial if he is an H-type. Thus, the difference in D’s payoff under imperfect information (ED(d) ! k P) and that under the asymmetric information analyzed above (ED(d) + kD ! p(kP + kD)) is (1 ! p)(k P + kD). This extra cost to D comes from the fact that D recognizes that P knows his own type and will act accordingly. Note that this is not a transfer to P; it is an efficiency loss. This loss is a share of the surplus that, under perfect or imperfect information, would have been avoided by settling rather than going to trial, and is a loss that is due to the presence of an asymmetry in the players’ information.
130
Settlement
7400
12.3.2. Screening with Many Types The principle used above extends to settings involving finer distinctions among levels of private information. In particular, this subsection will outline the nature of the model when applied to a continuum of types, such as a plaintiff whose level of damages could take on any value between two given levels of damages (that is, d may take on values between, and including, dL and dH; dL < d < dH). This is formally equivalent to Bebchuk’s original model (Bebchuk, 1984), even though his analysis presented a D who was privately informed about liability in a Pproposer setting with known damages. Thus, differences in the presentations between this discussion and Bebchuk’s are due to the shift of the proposer and the source of private information; there are no substantive differences between the analyses. As always, D’s probability assessment of the likelihood of the different possible levels of damages is common knowledge and is denoted p(d), which provides the probability that damages are no more than any chosen value of d. Figure 2 illustrates the intuition behind the analysis. The distribution of possible levels of damages as drawn implies equal likelihood, but this is for illustrative purposes only; many (though not all) probability assessment models would yield similar qualitative predictions. Figure 2 illustrates a level of damages, x, intermediate to the two extremes, dL and dH, and that the fraction of possible damage levels at or below x is given by p(x). Alternatively put, if D offers s = x ! kP, a P who has suffered the level of damages x would be indifferent between the offer and the payoff from going to trial. Moreover, this offer would also be accepted by any P with damages less than x, while any P with damages greater than x would reject the offer and go to trial. The expected expenditure associated with offers that are accepted is sp(x). Note that the particular value x that made the associated P indifferent between settling and going to trial depends upon the offer: x(s) = s + kP. This is accounted for by explicitly recognizing this dependence: if D makes an offer sD, then the expected expenditure associated with accepted offers is sDp[x(sD)]. Figure 2 Screening with a Continuum of Types
7400
Settlement
131
Two observations are in order. First, as sD increases, the ‘marginal’ type x(sD) (also known as the ‘borderline’ type; see Bebchuk, 1984) moves to the right and this would increase p(x(sD)). Thus, this expected expenditure is increasing in the offer both because the offer itself goes up and as it increases, so does the likelihood of it being accepted. Second, while the types of P that reject the offer and go to trial are ‘revealed’ by the award made by J (who learns the true d and awards it), as long as x does not equal dL there is residual uncertainty in every possible outcome of the game: the offer pools those who accept, and their private information is not revealed (other than the implications to be drawn from the fact that they must have damages that lie to the left of x in Figure 2). The fact that the equilibrium will therefore involve only partial revelation is the main difference between the two-type model (where screening reveals types) and the model with a continuum of types. To minimize expected expenditure, D trades off the expected expenditure from settling with the expected expenditure for trial, since the fraction (1 ! p(x(sD)) goes to trial. Under appropriate assumptions on p(x), this latter expenditure is declining in sD, yielding an optimal offer (sD*) for D that makes the type of P represented by the level of damages x(sD*) the marginal type. Thus, ‘P has been screened’. As an example, if all levels of damages are equally likely, as illustrated in Figure 2 above, then as long as the gap between the extreme levels of damages exceeds the total court costs (that is, dH ! dL > kP + kD), the equilibrium screening offer is sD* = dL + kD and the marginal type is a P with level of damages dL + k D + k P; Ps with damages at or below this level accept the offer while those with damages in excess of this level reject the offer. Note that should the gap in levels of damages be less than aggregate trial costs (dH ! dL < kP + kD), then D simply pools all the types with the offer dH ! k P. 12.3.3 Signaling: A Two-Type Analysis This approach employs a P-proposer model in which P makes a settlement demand followed by D choosing to accept or reject the proposal; given the assumptions made in the discussion before subsection 12.3.1, a rejection leads to P going to trial, at which J learns the true level of damages and awards P their value. As discussed in Section 4, in the circumstances of this ultimatum game, D should use a mixed strategy: if demands at or below some level were always accepted, while those above this level were always rejected, some types of P would be compensated more than might be necessary and D would go to court more often than necessary. Here a mixed strategy should respond to the demand made: low demands should be rejected less often than high demands, if only because a high demand is more advantageous to a greater percentage of possible types of Ps, and therefore requires D to be more diligent.
132
Settlement
7400
The notion that lower types (those with lesser damages) of P have an incentive to try to be mistaken for higher types (those with greater damages) plays a central role in the analysis. D’s use of a mixed strategy, dependent upon the demand made, provides a counter-incentive which can make mimicry unprofitable: a greedy demand at the settlement bargaining stage, triggering a greater chance of rejection, may therefore more readily lead to much lower payoffs at trial (where the true level of damages is revealed with certainty and P then must pay his court costs from the award) than would have occurred at a somewhat lower demand. P’s demand is sP, which D responds to by rejecting it with probability rD(sP) or accepting it, which occurs with probability 1 ! rD(sP). Clearly, if the demand is dL + kD, then D should accept this demand as D can do no better by rejecting it. For convenience, we will define sL to be this lowest-type demand, and thus, rD(sL) = 0. On the other hand, if P were to make a demand higher than what would be D’s expenditure at trial associated with the highest type, namely dH + kD, then D should reject any such demand for sure. It is somewhat less clear what D should do with dH + k D, which for convenience we denote as sH. As will be shown below (in both the two-type and the continuum of types models) D’s equilibrium strategy will set rD(sH) to be less than one. This will provide an incentive for greedy Ps to demand at most sH (technically, this is for the benefit of specifying an equilibrium, and it turns out not to hurt D). Since P knows what D knows, P can also construct the rD(sP) function that D will use to respond to any demand sP that P makes. P uses this function to decide what demand will maximize his payoff. While there are demand/rejection probability combinations that can generate all three types of equilibria (revealing, pooling and partial pooling), the focus here is on characterizing a revealing equilibrium. To do this we take our cue from the appropriate perfect information ultimatum game. In those analyses, if it was common knowledge that P was a high type, he could demand and get sH, while if it was common knowledge that P was a low type, he could demand and get sL. Making such demands clearly provides an action that could allow D to infer that, should he observe sL it must have come from a low type, while if he observed sH, it must have come from a high-type. While wishing does not make this true, incentives in terms of payoffs can, so that a low-damage P’s best choice between sL and sH is sL and a high-damage P’s best choice between sL and sH is sH. In particular, consider the following two inequalities (since rD(sL) = 0, the following inequalities employ the notation r for the rejection probability; we will then pick a particular value of r to be the value of D’s rejection strategy, rD(sH)):
7400
Settlement
sL > (1 ! r)sH + r(dL ! kP)
133
(ICL)
and sL < (1 ! r)sH + r(dH ! kP). (ICH) The first inequality, called ICL for the incentive compatibility condition for the low type states that D’s choice of r is such that when P has the low level of damages, his payoff is at least as good when he demands sL as what his payoff would be by mimicking the high-damages P’s demand sH, which is accepted with probability (1 ! r), but is rejected with probability r (resulting in the P of either type going to court). Note that, since J would learn the true type at court, a low-type P gets dL ! kP if his demand is rejected. In other words, on the right is the expected payoff to a P with the low level of damages from misrepresenting himself as having suffered high damages. Inequality ICH (the incentive compatibility condition for the high type) has a similar interpretation, but now it is for the high types: they are also no worse off by making the settlement demand that reflects their true type (the expected cost on the right side of the inequality) than they would be if they misrepresented themselves. When r, sL and sH satisfy both (ICL) and (ICH), then these strategies for D and the two types of P yield a revealing equilibrium. Substituting the values for sL and sH and solving the two inequalities yields the following requirement for r: (dH ! dL)/[(dH ! dL) + (kP + kD)] < r < (dH ! dL)/(kP + kD). While the term on the far right is, by an earlier assumption, greater than 1, the term on the far left is strictly less than one. In fact, for each value of r (pick one arbitrarily and call it r' for now) between the value on the left and one, there is a revealing equilibrium involving the low-damages P demanding sL, the high-damages P demanding sH and D responding via the rejection function with rD(sL) = 0 and rD(sH) = r'. In the equilibrium just posited a low-damage P reveals himself and always settles with D at dL + kD and a high-damage P always reveals himself, possibly (that is, with probability (1 ! r')) settling with D at dH + kD and possibly (with probability r') going to court and achieving the payoff dH ! kP. Note that the strategies for the players are very simple: P’s demand is his damages plus D’s court costs; D’s strategy is to always accept a low demand and to reject a high demand with a given positive, but fractional, probability. For what follows we will pick a particular value of r in the interval, namely, let rD(sH) = (dH ! dL)/[(dH ! dL) + (k P + kD)], the smallest value. There are technical reasons (refinements) that have been alluded to earlier,
134
Settlement
7400
concerning extensions of notions of rationality, to support this choice, but another motivation is that the smallest admissible r, rD(sH), is the most efficient of the possible choices. All the r values that satisfy the incentive conditions (ICL) and (ICH) provide the same expected payoff to D, namely ED(d) + kD. P’s expected payoff (that is, computed before he knows his type) is ED(d) + kD ! (1 ! p)(kP + kD)r, for any r that satisfies both incentive compatibility conditions, so using rD(sH) minimizes the efficiency loss (1 ! p)(kP + kD)r. Note also that using the specified rD(sH) as the rejection probability for a high demand means that the likelihood of rejection is inversely related to total court costs, but positively related to the difference between possible levels of damages. This is because while increased court costs minimize the threat of going to court, an increased gap between dH and dL increases the incentive for low-damage Ps to claim to be high-damage Ps, thereby requiring more diligence on the part of D. D accomplishes this by increasing rD(sH). 12.3.4 Signaling with Many Types While the principle used above extends to the case of a continuum of values of the private information, the extension itself involves considerably greater technical detail. The presentation here will summarize results in much the same manner as used in Section 12.3.2 to summarize screening with a continuum of types. This presentation is based on the analysis employed in Reinganum and Wilde (1986), though that model allows for non-strategic errors (that is, exogenously specified errors) by J and awards that are proportional to (rather than equal to) damages. The basic results developed in the two-type model remain: (1) a revealing equilibrium is predicted; (2) P makes a settlement demand equal to damages plus D’s court cost and (3) D uses a mixed strategy to choose acceptance or rejection. The likelihood of rejection is increasing in the demand made, and therefore in the damages incurred, and is decreasing in court costs. This means that the distribution of levels of damages that go to trial involves, essentially, the entire spectrum of damages, though it consists of preponderantly higher rather than lower damages (relative to the initial distribution). Figure 3 shows an example which starts with the same assessment over damages as envisioned in the continuum screening model in Section 12.3.2. As is shown in the graph displayed in the upper left of Figure 3, again assume that each possible level of damages is equally likely. Following the gray arrow, the graph in the upper right shows the equilibrium settlement demand function for P: it is parallel to the 45° line (the dotted line) and shifted up by the amount kD. Thus, P’s settlement demand function sP(d) = d + kD, where d is P’s type (level of damages actually incurred). Thus, for example, sP(dL) = dL + kD (this is sL on the vertical axis). The graph below the settlement demand function (follow the fat gray arrow) displays D’s
7400
Settlement
135
rejection function. Demands at or below sL are accepted and demands above sL are rejected with an increasing likelihood up to the demand sH = dH + kD. This is rejected with a positive but fractional likelihood (the dot is to show the endpoint of the curve); anything higher yet is rejected with certainty. Finally, following the gray arrow to the lower left of Figure 3, the posterior assessment of damages for cases going to trial is shown. The word posterior is used to contrast it with the assessment D used before bargaining commenced (the prior assessment). The effect of settlement bargaining is to create an assessment model at the start of the next stage of the legal process which is shifted upwards; that is, which emphasizes the higher-damage cases. This contrasts with the resulting distribution of cases that emerge from a screening process. The result of the screening model applied to the ‘box-shaped’ prior assessment shown in Figures 2 and 3 would be a boxshaped posterior assessment model over the types that rejected the screening offer. Figure 3 Signaling with a Continuum of Types
12.4 How Robust are One-Sided Asymmetric Information Ultimatum Game Analyses? As the earlier discussion of the various approaches used in perfect information suggests, model structure and assumptions play an important role in the predictions of the analysis. Is this a problem of ‘tune the dial and get another station’? In some sense it seems to be. Such models seem to provide conflicting predictions which: involve proposing one or the other player’s concession limit (not in between, as the Nash Bargaining Solution
136
Settlement
7400
provided); sometimes fully reveal private information, other times do not; and strongly restrict when and if players can make proposals at all. However, some consistent threads emerge. Asymmetric information will generally result in some degree of inefficiency in the bargaining process due to some use of trial by the players. The extent of inefficiency is related to the nature of the distribution of the information, the range of the possible values that the private information can take on and the level of court costs. Higher court costs encourage settlement and influence the transfer between P and D. Asymmetric information means that the relatively less informed player needs to guard against misrepresentation by the more informed player, and must be willing to employ the threat of court. The signaling model indicated another aspect of this: even though P was informed and made the proposals, it was P who bore an inefficiency cost (D’s expected payoff was what it would have been under imperfect information). This is because the private information that P possesses cannot be credibly communicated to D without a cost being incurred by P via the signaling of the information. Clearly, both models use a highly stylized representation of bargaining. How restrictive is this? While this question is difficult to address very generally, some tests of the robustness of the model structure and the predictions exist. These analyses are of two types. (1) Would changes in sequence matter (who moves when, whether moves must be sequential, what if there were many opportunities to make proposals)? (2) Is the one-sided nature of information important; would each player having information on a relevant attribute of the game affect the outcome in a material way? Papers by Daughety and Reinganum (1993), Wang, Kim and Yi (1994) and Spier (1992) address aspects of the first question above. Daughety and Reinganum provide a two-period model that allows players to move simultaneously or sequentially. Here, P and D can individually make (or individually not make) proposals in the first period and then choose to accept or reject whatever comes out of the first period during a second period; a rejection by either individual of the outcome of the first period means going to court. What comes out of the first period is: (1) no proposal, which guarantees court; (2) one proposal, provided by whomever made it; or (3) an intermediate version of two proposals if both players make one; the intermediate proposal is a general, commonly known function of the two individual proposals. An example of such a ‘compromise’ function would be one that averaged the proposals. Note that this means that if both players make proposals then intermediate outcomes are possible candidates as equilibria of the overall game. The model allows one-sided asymmetric information, but examines both possible cases in which a player is informed. The general result is that players do not choose to wait: they both make proposals in the first period. Thus, formally, the ultimatum structure
7400
Settlement
137
wherein only one player makes a proposal is rejected as inconsistent with endogenously generated timing. However, the unique equilibrium of the game has the same payoffs as either that of the ultimatum signaling game or the ultimatum screening game; which one depends only on the compromise function used and which player is informed. The Wang, Kim and Yi (1994) paper discussed earlier in Section 3.2.2 also contains a continuum-type, one-sided asymmetric information model based on Rubinstein (1985). Wang, Kim and Yi consider the case of an informed P and an uninformed D, with D as first proposer. In subsequent periods proposers alternate. They show that the settlement outcome is consistent with a one-period D-proposer screening ultimatum game as discussed above. Finally, Spier (1992) (discussed in more detail in Section 18 below) also employs a dynamic model (in this case a finite horizon model) with negotiating and trial costs. In her model if negotiating costs are zero then all bargaining takes place in the last period. Together, the three papers provide some limited theoretical support for using the ultimatum game approach to representing one-sided asymmetric information settlement problems. The second issue, concerning one-sided versus two-sided information, is addressed in papers by Schweizer (1989) and Daughety and Reinganum (1994) (Sobel, 1989, also considers a two-sided model, but his interest is discovery; this paper will be discussed in Section 19). Both Schweizer and Daughety and Reinganum consider ultimatum games where P is privately informed about damages and D is privately informed about liability. Schweizer considers a P-proposer model with two types on both sides while Daughety and Reinganum consider both P- and D-proposer models with a continuum of types on both sides. The results are fundamentally the same: the proposer signals and uses the signal to screen the responder. Thus, proposer types are revealed fully and responders are partially pooled. In sum, it would appear that the screening and signaling models have reasonably robust qualitative properties that survive relaxation of some of the underlying structure and that the intuition derived from the separate analyses survives the integration of both types of models in a more comprehensive analysis.
13. Comparing the Two-Type Models: Imperfect and Asymmetric Information This section provides two means of comparison. First, employing specific numerical values, Table 3 presents computations for the same data from imperfect, screening and signaling analyses; it also acts as a convenient summary of the strategies and payoffs for the different models. While the
138
Settlement
7400
results do not purport to indicate magnitudes of differences in the predictions made, it will suggest directional differences. The directional differences will be amplified, based on the two-type analyses provided earlier, as the second means of comparison. Table 3 Ultimatum Game Results Under Imperfect and Asymmetric Information
Data: dH = 75, dL = 25, L = 1, kP = kD = 10, p = 0.5. Thus, ED(d) = 50 and (SSC) is met: p = 0.5 > (kp + kD)/(dH ! dL + kP + kD) = 0.29 Model D-Proposer NBS P-Proposer Imp. Information $D = $P = 50 sD = ED(d) ! kP = 40 sP = ED(d) + kD = 60 $D = 40 $D = 60 $P = 40 $P = 60 efficient efficient no trials no trials Asy. Information Screening sD = dL ! kP = 15 $D = psD + (1 ! p)(dH + kP) = 50 $L = dL ! kP = 15 $H = dH ! kP = 65 inefficient: loss = (1 ! p)(kP + kD) = 10 $D = ED(d) + kD !(1 ! p)(kP + kD) = 50 $P = p$L + (1 ! p)$H = 40 probability of trial = (1 ! p) = 0.5 Signaling
sL = dL + kD = 35 sH = dH + kD = 85 rD(sL) = 0 rD(sH) = (dH ! dL)/(dH - dL + kP + kD) = 0.71 $D = psL + (1 ! p)[(1 ! rD(sH))sH+ rD(sH)sH] = 60 $L = sL = 35 $H = (1 ! rD(sH))sH + (rD(sH))(dH ! kP) =70.71
7400
Settlement
139
inefficient: loss = (1 ! p)(kP+kD)rD(sH) = 7.14 $D = ED(d) + kD = 60 $P = p$L + (1 ! p)$H = 52.86 probability of trial = (1 ! p)rD(sH) = 0.36
Table 3 considers a two-type model wherein P is informed of the true level of damages and D is not. D’s prior assessment on the two levels of damages is that they are equally likely (this is to make comparisons easier). Court costs are the same for the two players and liability by D for damages is certain. Specific values of the data are provided at the top of Table 3. Note that (SSC) holds as shown. D’s expectation of damages [ED(d)] is the common expectation under imperfect information. Table 3 concentrates on the ultimatum game predictions, but the relevant imperfect information NBS is also provided, as shown near the top. Given the information endowments, the only asymmetric information D-proposer model is a screening model and the only P-proposer asymmetric information model is a signaling model. The table provides the proposer’s proposal, the responder’s strategy in the signaling case and the payoffs to the players. Note that $L provides the payoff to a P with low damages while $H provides the payoff to a P with high damages. Finally, in the asymmetric case $P provides the expected payoffs to a P before damages are observed so that ex ante efficiency can be evaluated. The statement ‘efficient’ means that the outcome is on the settlement frontier, while ‘inefficient’ means that the solution lies below the frontier, with the efficiency loss calculated as shown. Finally, the source of inefficiency, that some cases go to trial, is indicated by providing the probability of trial derived from the model used. The example and the formulas in the table indicate that the efficiency losses predicted by the screening and signaling models, as compared with the efficient solutions in the imperfect information model, differ from one another. More generally, as long as p meets the simple screening condition (SSC) of Section 12.3.1, the signaling model predicts less of an efficiency loss than the screening model. This is because while a low-damage P settles out of court in both models, a high-damages P always goes to court under a screening model while they only go to court with a fractional likelihood under the signaling model. Note also, however, that when p does not satisfy (SSC), then the screening model predicts full efficiency while the signaling model still predicts an inefficient outcome. A similar type of comparison could be performed for the ultimatum games involving asymmetric information about the likelihood of liability
140
Settlement
7400
(with damages commonly known). Typically, such analyses assume that D has private information about the true likelihood of being found liable. In the screening model, the higher-likelihood Ds settle and the lower likelihood Ds reject P’s offer and proceed to trial. In the signaling model, the higher likelihood D makes an offer that P accepts while the lower likelihood D makes a lower offer that P rejects with an equilibrium rejection probability. Most notably, in the case wherein there is a continuum of types, the distribution of cases that go to trial include essentially all the D-types (with the preponderance of types being less likely to be held liable). This is worth contrasting with a vast literature which has grown out of a paper by Priest and Klein (1984). Reviewing the literature in this area (mainly empirical studies with a variety of predictions) would take us too far from our main purpose, but a few words are appropriate. The Priest-Klein model employs an inconsistent priors approach to examine the selection of cases that proceed to trial. Their results imply that, as the likelihood of proposal rejection by parties becomes small, then among those cases that do not settle, the likelihood that either P or D wins at trial approaches 50 percent. As Shavell (1993) shows for the two-type screening case, and as is clearly also true for the signaling case (as described above) and the continuum screening case, by varying parameters one can get essentially any prediction about case selection that is desired.
C. Variations on the Basic Models 14. Overview This part locates and briefly reviews a number of recent contributions to the settlement literature. Two cautions should be observed. First, no effort will be made to discuss unpublished work. This is primarily motivated by the fact that such work is, generally, not as accessible to most readers as are the journals that published work has appeared in. There are some classic unpublished papers (some of which have significantly influenced the existing published papers) that are thereby slighted, and my apologies to their authors. Potentially, such a policy also hastens the date of the succeeding survey. Second, the selection to be discussed is a subset of the existing published papers: it is not meant to be comprehensive. Instead, the selection is meant to show ideas that have been raised, or how approaches have been revised. A limited number of papers that address relevant issues, but which are not focused on settlement itself, are also mentioned.
7400
Settlement
141
Following the outline of Part B, papers will be grouped as follows: (1) players; (2) actions and strategies; (3) outcomes and payoffs; (4) timing and (5) information. Not surprisingly, many papers could conceivably fit in a number of categories, and a few cross-references will be made.
15. Players 15.1 Attorneys Watts (1994) adds an attorney for P (denoted AP) to the set of players in a screening analysis of a P-proposer ultimatum game; D is privately informed about expected damages at trial (for a discussion of agency problems in contingent fee arrangements, see Miller, 1987). The main role of AP is expertise: AP can engage, at a cost, in discovery efforts which release some predetermined portion of D’s information. The cost to AP is lower than the cost of obtaining the same information would be to P. Moreover, more precise information about D’s likely type costs more to obtain (for either P or AP) than less precise information (precision is exogenously determined in this model). Before bargaining with D, P can choose whether or not to hire AP, and attorneys are paid on a contingency basis. If hired, AP obtains information about D’s type and then makes a settlement proposal to D. Given the precision of obtainable information and the expertise of AP (that is, AP’s cost of obtaining information as a fraction of P’s cost of obtaining the same information), Watts finds a range of contingency fees that P and AP could agree upon (a settlement frontier for P and AP to bargain over), and that their concession limits decrease as the expected court award in the settlement problem with D increases. 15.2 Judges and Juries As mentioned earlier, J is generally modeled in this literature as learning the truth and making awards equal to the true damages. Early models have allowed for unsystematic error on the part of J. Since the informed player usually computes payoffs at trial on the basis that their true type will be fully revealed in court, something here is needed to indicate how J learns the true type, or if J does not learn the true type, what J does in that event. Thus, what J will know could influence the settlement strategies and outcomes. Daughety and Reinganum (1995) consider a J whose omniscience is parametric (that is, with an exogenously specified probability, J learns the truth; if not, J must infer it based upon P and D’s observable actions) in a continuum-type ultimatum game signaling model, wherein P is informed about damages and D is not. J is a second ‘receiver’ of a signal. If all that is observable to J is the failure of settlement negotiation, then when J observes
142
Settlement
7400
that a case comes to trial, he can infer the distribution of such cases (using the posterior model shown in Figure 3) and pick a best award (note that this means that all the elements of the settlement game are common knowledge to J, as is this fact to P, D and J). If J can also observe P’s settlement demand, then he uses that information, too. The result is that this feeds back into the settlement process, resulting in P making demands to influence J. As J’s dependence on such information increases (omniscience decreases), revelation via the settlement demand disappears as more and more types of P pool by making a high demand (P ‘plays to the judge’). The result can be that, for sufficiently high reliance on observation instead of omniscience, J has even less information than if he could not observe P’s settlement demand at all (and must rely on the posterior distribution of unsettled cases). Influencing J is also the topic of Rubinfeld and Sappington (1987), which while not focused on settlement per se, does model how effort by players can inform J. The setting is nominally a criminal trial, but the point potentially applies to civil cases, too: if innocent Ds should be able to (more readily than guilty Ds) obtain evidence supporting their innocence, then the amount of effort so placed can act as a signal to J of D’s innocence or guilt. This is not a perfect signal, in the sense that the types of D are not fully revealed. As in much of the literature dealing with criminal defendants (this is discussed in more detail in Section 17.4 below), J here maximizes a notion of justice that trades off the social losses from punishing the innocent versus freeing the guilty and accounts for the costs incurred by D in the judicial process. One final note on this topic. There is an enormous literature on jury and judicial decision-making spread across the psychology, political science, sociology and law literatures that has yet to have the impact it deserves on formal models of settlement bargaining. 15.3 Multiple Litigants Many settings involve multiple litigants (for example, airline crashes, drug side-effects, and so on). Che and Yi (1993) and Yang (1996) consider games with two Ps who D faces sequentially; partly these are models of precedent and partly these are models analyzing game-to-game informational links. Damages are correlated over plaintiffs and thus information obtained in bargaining with the first P (P1) influences bargaining with the second P (P2). Che and Yi concatenate two D-proposer ultimatum games, where D faces informed P’s in the two games. Note that when D plays the second ultimatum game, the correlation of levels of damages over plaintiffs means that learning in game one affects D’s strategy in game two, thereby feeding back into D’s game one strategy choice. By allowing for effort applied by all parties to influence the probability of winning, Che and Yi get a ‘frontloading’ effect to influence the precedent-setting case.
7400
Settlement
143
In a two-P model, the outcome of the settlement process with P1 (which can include trial) influences P2’s decisions. Employing a model similar to that of Che and Yi, Yang includes the decision by both informed Ps to initially file their respective cases. Thus, D’s actions with respect to P1, and the likely outcome from going to trial, may deter P2 from filing. Yang finds conditions under which this causes D, in dealing with P1, to be more or less aggressive than the one-P model would find. While more aggressive play (being ‘tough’) against P1 may seem intuitive, less aggressive play is also reasonable if going to trial will reveal information (such as, that P1 had high damages) that encourages P2 to file. Why would this encourage P2, who knows his damage? Assume that P2 is a low-level-of-damages plaintiff. By making a pooling offer to P1, D does not learn P1's type, which ignorance P2 would be aware of. Thus, P2 knows that D is still uninformed, and cannot capitalize on D having received ‘bad news’ that P1 is a high-level-ofdamages plaintiff, shifting his prior assessment about P2 up (recall that D takes damages as correlated). There is a strategic advantage to not being informed if the knowledge of the information places you at a disadvantage. If D remains uninformed then if P2 is low he cannot expect D to overestimate him as high and make a second pooling offer. Kobayashi (1992) considers a two-D model in a plea-bargaining setting; because of the change in payoffs, this will be discussed in more detail in Section 17.4 below.
16. Actions and Strategies 16.1 Credibility of Proceeding to Trial Should Negotiations Fail In the screening examples in Section 12.3 above, an uninformed D made an offer to an informed P with liability commonly known but the level of damages the source of the informational asymmetry. For convenience of exposition, consider the reversed setting with D informed about the likelihood of being found liable at trial, P uninformed, but both commonly knowledgeable about the level of damages (this is the original Bebchuk example). Thus, a screening analysis means a P-proposer ultimatum model. In this context Nalebuff (1987) examines the assumption that P is committed to proceeding to trial after bargaining fails (alternatively put, Nalebuff relaxes the assumption that there is a minimum positive likelihood of liability that, multiplied by the level of damages, would exceed P’s court costs; this is the analogy to our earlier assumption that dL > kP holds). Nalebuff considers cases that, initially, have ‘merit’: EP(d) > kP. Nalebuff appends a second decision by P (concerning whether or not to take the case to trial) to the P-proposer ultimatum game screening model. After observing
144
Settlement
7400
the response by D to the screening demand made by P, P recomputes EP(d) using his posterior assessment; denote this as EP(d| D’s response), meaning P’s expectation of the level of damages which will be awarded in court given D’s choice to accept or reject the offer. Since all types whose true likelihood of liability implied levels of expected damages in excess of that associated with the demand (that is, the more likely-to-be-liable types of D) have accepted the demand, the collection of types of D who would reject the demand by P are those with stronger cases (that is, those that are less likely to be held liable). Thus, P’s new expected payoff from proceeding to trial, EP(d| D’s response) ! kP, is lower than before the bargaining began (EP(d) ! kP). The decision by P as to whether or not to actually litigate after seeing the outcome of the screening offer results in a reversal of some of the predictions made by the original screening model about the impact that changes in the levels of damages and court costs will have on settlement demands and the likelihood of trial. For example, Nalebuff shows that the settlement demand in the relaxed model is higher than that in the model with commitment. Why would this happen? To see why, consider what happens in stages. When P is making his settlement demand, he is also considering the downstream decision he will be making about going to trial and must choose a settlement demand that makes his later choice of trial credible. If P can no longer be committed to going to trial with any D who rejects his screening demand, this means that he will use EP(d| D’s response) to decide about going to trial, and this is now heavily influenced by the presence of ‘tough’ types; those types that are ‘weak’, that is, who have high likelihoods of liability, have accepted P’s offers. Thus, if P raises his settlement demand, some of the intermediate types will pool with the tough types, resulting in EP(d| D’s response) ! kP > 0, making the threat of trial credible. Thus, the effect of relaxing the assumption that P necessarily litigates any case that rejects his settlement demand actually results in an increased demand being made. 16.2 Filing a Claim One potential effect of a cost associated with filing a suit is to provide a disincentive for a P pursuing what is known as a ‘nuisance’ suit. The definition of what a nuisance is varies somewhat, but generally, such a suit has a negative expected value (NEV) to P; that is, EP(d) < kP; such a suit is not one that P would actually pursue to trial should negotiations fail (note that this ignores any psychic benefits that P may derive from ‘having his day in court’ which might make such a suit have a positive expected utility). Clearly, the reason for consideration of NEV suits is the perception that Ps can pursue NEV suits and obtain settlements: the asymmetry of information between an informed P and an uninformed D allows Ps with NEV suits to
7400
Settlement
145
mimic PEV suits (positive expected value suits) and extract a settlement. Two questions have arisen in this context: what contributes to the incentive for plaintiffs to pursue NEV suits and what attributes of the process might reduce or eliminate it. An example may be of use at this point. Consider a D facing three possible types of P, with possible damages dN = 0, dL = $10,000 and dH = $50,000, respectively and with associated likelihoods pN = 0.1, pL = 0.3 and pH = 0.6 (N here stands for ‘nuisance’). Further assume both P and D have court costs of $2,000. The screening equilibrium involves the firm offering $8,000 and settling with the nuisance and the low-damages type and going to court against the high-damages type: the nuisance-type benefitted from the presence of the low-damage type and the expected costs to the firm are higher (an average expected cost of $34,400 per case) than would obtain if the nuisance type had not been present (an average expected cost of $33,600 per case). P’ng (1983), in one of the earliest papers to consider strategic aspects of settlement bargaining, endogenizes both the choice by P to file a case and the choice to later drop the case should bargaining fail; NEV suits are considered, but the level of settlement is exogenously determined in this model. Rosenberg and Shavell (1985) found NEV suits can occur if filing costs for P are sufficiently low when compared with D’s defense costs and if D must incur these costs before P must incur any settlement or trial costs. Bebchuk (1988) provides an asymmetric information (P is informed), Dproposer ultimatum game that specifically admits NEV suits (that is, no assumption is made that all suits are PEV). Filing costs are zero. Bebchuk shows how court costs and the probability assessment of the possible levels of damages influences settlement offers and rates. He finds that when NEV suits are possible, a reduction in settlement offers in PEV cases and an increase in the fraction of PEV cases that go to trial, when compared with an analysis assuming only PEV suits, is predicted. Katz (1990) considers how filing and settlement bargaining affects incentives for frivolous law suits. By a frivolous suit, Katz means one with zero damages and positive court costs; the numerical example above involved a frivolous suit. Katz appends a filing decision made by an informed P to a D-proposer ultimatum game. This is a two-type model (the paper also includes a continuum-type extension) with dL = 0. The modification of the D-proposer model is that the offer is either the highdamage P’s concession limit or zero, so the strategy for D becomes the probability of making the high-damage concession limit offer. P’s filing strategy is whether or not to file; if he files P incurs a cost fP. Of course, once incurred this cost is sunk. Under the assumption that dH ! kP ! fP > 0, and if a condition similar in notion to (SSC) is violated, then in equilibrium both types of Ps file cases, D pools the Ps by offering the high-damage P’s
146
Settlement
7400
concession limit, dH ! k P, to all Ps and all Ps accept. Katz also addresses a case selection issue: such a policy by D will attract frivolous cases, changing the likelihood that a randomly selected case is a frivolous. Thus, the profits from filing a frivolous case will be driven to zero. In this ‘competitive’ equilibrium, Katz shows that the likelihood of trial is not a function of p or kD, but it is increasing in fP and decreasing in ED(d). 16.3 Counterclaims Using an imperfect information model, Landes (1994) shows that counterclaims (suits filed by D against P as part of the existing action by P against D, rather than filed as a separate lawsuit) do not always reduce P’s incentive to sue, and may (by raising the stakes in the game) actually increase the likelihood of the case going to trial. This is based on mutual optimism about each player’s own claim (mutual optimism involves each player expecting to win the action that they initiated; this need not involve inconsistent priors, as discussed in Section 6). Under these conditions the counterclaim reduces the size of the settlement frontier (and possibly eliminates it).
17. Outcomes and Payoffs 17.1 Risk Aversion Most of the earliest analyses allowed for risk aversion by assuming that payoffs were in utility rather than monetary terms. The Nash Bargaining Solution can be applied to such problems (now all four axioms come into play), again yielding a unique solution, though not necessarily where the 45° line crosses the frontier. The solution is efficient (due to axiom 2; see Section 8.2) in perfect and imperfect information cases. The divergence of the solution from the 45° line reflects the relative risk aversion of the two players, with the more risk-averse player receiving a smaller share of the pie (see, for example, Binmore, 1992, pp. 193-194). There is a similar analysis in the perfect information strategic bargaining literature, where risk is introduced into an infinite horizon game by ignoring the time value of money but incorporating a probability of negotiations breaking down. Once again, for players whose preferences over outcomes reflect aversion to risk, the less risk averse player gets the greater share of the pie (see Binmore, Rubinstein and Wolinsky, 1986). In the settlement context, Farmer and Pecorino (1994) view a player’s risk preferences as private information. While trial outcomes are uncertain, the likelihood of the outcomes themselves is common knowledge. P is taken to be risk averse (that is, privately informed of his risk preferences) and D is
7400
Settlement
147
risk neutral and uninformed; the model allows for two types of P (extension to three types is also considered). This is a D-proposer ultimatum model; if the roles of proposer were reversed, then P’s risk aversion would not interfere with an efficient settlement solution, so the order here is crucial to obtaining the possibility of trial. A standard screening condition is found (not unlike (SSC)), but more interesting is the result that increases in the uncertainty of the trial outcome result in the screening condition being more readily met, thereby increasing the likelihood of trial (a result consistent with the earlier analysis involving risk aversion). This occurs because it is the most risk-averse Ps that settle, and the greater the uncertainty the more they are prepared to accept a settlement in lieu of court, which encourages D to make tougher offers. 17.2 Offer-Based Fee Shifting Rules Many settlement papers consider the allocation of court costs (fee shifting) as part of their overall analysis. Typically, comparisons are made between the ‘American’ system (each player pays their own costs) and the ‘British’ system (the loser pays all costs). The very common association in the literature of loser pays with Britain potentially understates the contrast; see Posner (1992) who uses the term ‘English and Continental’ to emphasize that a significant portion of the world uses loser pays. All the discussions in this survey have employed the pay-your-own system. The allocation of court costs is an extensive topic, with a typically suggested result that the loserpays system discourages low-probability-of-prevailing plaintiffs more than the pay-your-own system (see Shavell, 1982), but other observations are that it may (or may not) adversely affect the likelihood of settlement (see Bebchuk, 1984 and Reinganum and Wilde, 1986). A recent extension of the basic fee-shifting discussion to making fee-shifting dependent upon the magnitude of the outcome is discussed in Bebchuk and Chang (1996). Since the general area of fee shifting is a separable topic of its own interest (which is likely to be addressed in a number of other surveys in these volumes), this survey will not attempt to cover it. A related issue is recent work on Rule 68 of the US Federal Rules of Civil Procedure, as an example of a variety of offer-based fee-shifting rules which directly address settlement offers made by defendants and rejected by plaintiffs. First, it should be noted that, under long-standing practice, and also under many state rules of evidence and US Federal Rule of Evidence 408, information on settlement proposals and responses is not generally admissible as evidence at trial; a similar type of restriction usually applies in criminal cases to information about plea bargaining. Rule 68 includes restrictions on the use of settlement proposals at trial.
148
Settlement
7400
Thus, in the case of offer-based fee-shifting, offers are not used in court to infer true damages or actual liability; rather they influence the final payoffs from the game after an award has been made at trial. Rule 68, for example, links settlement choices to post-trial outcomes by penalizing a plaintiff for certain costs (court costs and, sometimes, attorney fees) when the trial award is less favorable than the defendant’s ‘final’ proposal (properly documented). As Spier (1994a) points out, the stated purpose of such a rule is to encourage settlement (Spier also provides other examples of offer-based rules similar in nature to Rule 68). Spier employs screening in a D-proposer ultimatum game. In comparison to the likelihood of settlement without Rule 68, she finds that under Rule 68: (1) disputes by P and D over damages are more likely to settle; and (2) disputes over liability or the likelihood of winning are less likely to settle. Spier also finds that the design of a bargaining procedure and fee-shifting rule that maximizes the probability of settlement yields a rule that penalizes either player for rejecting proposals that were better than the actual outcome of trial, providing some theoretical support for offer-based fee shifting rules such as Rule 68. 17.3 Damage Awards In previous sections of this summary the award at trial has been the level of damages associated with the plaintiff who goes to court. This, minus court costs, becomes P’s threat. This is based on J choosing an award that best approximates P’s damages. Other criteria for choosing awards are also reasonable. For example, J might choose awards that maximize overall social efficiency or that minimize the probability of trial. Polinsky and Che (1991) study decoupled liability: what the defendant pays need not be what the plaintiff receives. By decoupling, incentives for plaintiffs to sue can be reduced, while incentives for potential injurers to improve the level of care can be increased; that is, both goals can be pursued without necessarily conflicting. In particular, they show that the optimal award to P may be less or more than the optimal payment by D. Spier (1994b) considers coupled awards in an asymmetric information setting, and finds that the level of settlement costs influences the nature of the award that minimizes social cost (precaution costs plus litigation costs plus harm). Note that, here, precaution is one-sided: precaution on the part of a potential P is not included. Spier considers a two-type screening D-proposer ultimatum game and allows for two awards, aH and aL, for circumstances where the level of damages is High or Low, respectively, and thus the payoff from trial is the award minus court costs. Spier uses a condition such as (SSC) and shows that, if total court costs are low enough the socially optimal award is equal to the level of damages plus P’s court costs (as D will make a screening offer in those circumstances), while if total court costs are
7400
Settlement
149
sufficiently high, the optimal award is the expected damages plus P’s court costs (as D will be making a pooling offer). Therefore, simply compensating for actual damages is not socially optimal (recall also that court costs are fixed). Moreover, ‘fine tuning’ the award to reflect P’s actual level of damages is socially optimal only if total court costs are not too high. 17.4 Other Payoffs: Plea Bargaining As an example of a significantly different payoff measure, consider negotiations between a defendant in a criminal action and a prosecutor. This type of settlement bargaining, called plea bargaining, has been addressed in a number of papers over the last quarter-century. Early papers in this area are Landes (1971) and Grossman and Katz (1983) who model settlement bargaining between a prosecutor and a defendant. In Landes the payoffs are expected sentence length for the prosecutor versus expected wealth (wealth in two states: under conviction and under no conviction) for the defendant, who is guilty. In Grossman and Katz some defendants may be innocent; the defendants know their guilt or innocence (a two-type model). The defendants seek to minimize the disutility of punishment (they are risk averse) while the uninformed prosecutor maximizes a notion of justice that trades off the social losses from punishing the innocent versus freeing the guilty; the Grossman and Katz analysis is a screening model with innocent defendants choosing trial. More recent work includes Reinganum (1988, 1993) and Kobayashi (1992). Reinganum’s 1988 paper involves two-sided asymmetric information: defendants know their guilt or innocence (two types), while the prosecutor knows the strength of the case; that is, the probability that the case will yield a conviction at trial (a continuum of types). Guilt and evidence are correlated, so there is a relationship between the two sets of types. A special case of this relationship appears in Grossman and Katz and was also employed in Rubinfeld and Sappington, discussed in Section 15.2: innocent defendants can more readily obtain supporting evidence than can guilty ones. The prosecutor’s payoff is social justice minus resource costs while the defendant’s payoff to be minimized is the expected sentence plus the disutility of trial. Reinganum’s 1993 paper uses a similar payoff for D but takes all Ds as guilty and therefore takes the prosecutor’s payoff as expected sentence length minus resource costs. In this latter model the probability of conviction is determined in the equilibrium, influencing the initial choice to engage in criminal behavior by D. Finally, Kobayashi considers conspiracies: there are two defendants (for example, a price-fixing case) who face different (exogenously determined) initial probabilities of conviction based on the existing evidence. Each D can, however, provide information on the other D which increases that
150
Settlement
7400
second D’s likelihood of conviction. Kobayashi assumes that the D with the higher initial conviction probability (the ‘ringleader’) also has more information on the other D (the ‘subordinate’). Here the prosecutor makes simultaneous offers to each D so as to maximize the sum of the expected penalties from the two Ds. Litigation costs are taken to be zero so as to focus on plea-bargaining as information gathering.
18. Timing Four papers have focused especially on the implications of changing the timing assumption in the models used: Spier (1992), Daughety and Reinganum (1993), Wang, Kim and Li (1994) and Bebchuk (1996). The papers by Daughety and Reinganum and by Wang, Kim and Yi were discussed in Section 12.4 above. These two papers (along with Spier’s) analyzed models that contributed some support for the one-sided asymmetric information ultimatum games. The papers by Spier and Bebchuk examine what happens if the settlement interval is subdivided. We consider these two papers in more detail in turn. Spier considers a finite-horizon concatenation of P-proposer ultimatum games, with D informed about damages for which he is liable (a continuumtype model). Spier finds a ‘deadline effect’ in which some cases settle in the last period, and that the distribution of settlements over time can be Ushaped in the sense that some cases settle immediately, some settle in the last possible period and a few settle in between. Spier’s main analysis is different from the other multiperiod models discussed in that the horizon is finite, not infinite, and the model does not allow alternating offers (an infinite horizon model is also considered; see below). Moreover, P, the (initially) uninformed proposer, cannot choose to go to court during the horizon. P incurs two costs: (1) each extra period incurs a negotiating cost and (2) going to trial incurs a court cost. D incurs neither cost, which is not a restrictive assumption in this analysis. Both P and D discount money in future periods at the same discount rate. Thus, the analysis involves subdividing the bargaining period into a sequence of periods and associating a delay cost for each period that settlement is not reached. Since the pie is not shrinking, the delay cost provides a clear incentive to P to settle sooner. On the other hand, P is uninformed and may need to use the approach of the end of the horizon to get D to reveal information. This tradeoff leads to some settlements being made immediately and some being made in the last possible period when D faces the imminent possibility of trial. Spier also considers an infinite-horizon extension, where P may now choose to go to court in each period; this provides a model that allows for an endogenous
7400
Settlement
151
date for trial. The model yields a range of equilibria (this is not unusual in strategic bargaining games with outside alternatives); the range runs from efficient to fully inefficient (all cases go to trial in the second period). Finally, Fournier and Zuehlke (1996) have recently tested the predictions of Spier’s finite horizon model with data from a survey of civil lawsuits from 1979-1981 in US federal courts. They found results that were consistent with computer simulation predictions based on Spier’s analysis. Bebchuk (1996) also examines the effect of subdividing the settlement interval into parts. Costs accrue somewhat differently in his model than in Spier’s. In particular, a player’s costs of negotiation and court are fully subdivided by the number of intervals. Thus, the level of costs incurred is influenced by when an agreement is reached. Bebchuk concatenates a series of settlement predictions using the average of the (one-period) concession limits under perfect information; filing costs for P are zero. Sequential rationality does the rest: with costs subdivided so as to make it credible for P to continue to bargain, Bebchuk finds that NEV suits can be successful if there are a sufficient number of periods and the difference between kP and kD is not too great. Note that D cannot commit not to respond to demands; if he could, then P’s NEV strategy would be unprofitable. While the number of periods in the model is exogenously set, this is suggestive of a strategy for P: increase the number of settlement periods. The notion of credible commitments should work both ways, however. What if D could hire a busy lawyer? Delegation of bargaining authority or the requirement for advice, if credible, is one way for D to make the number of periods smaller. After all, each time P makes a proposal, D must have an attorney carefully evaluate the proposal, a costly and time-consuming activity. This would create credible delay, which is beneficial from the viewpoint of D’s direct monetary interests and now beneficial from the viewpoint of repelling some NEV cases. Thus, this suggests that a game wherein the proposal/response period length and frequency is endogenously determined would be of interest. To the degree that the overall horizon is sub-divided, however, Bebchuk’s main point will still hold: there will be NEV suits that could be successful (again, assuming that filing costs are zero).
19. Information 19.1 Acquiring Information from the Other Player: Discovery and Disclosure Shavell (1989) examines the incentives for informed players to voluntarily release private information in a continuum-type, informed-P, D-proposer ultimatum game. Before D makes a proposal, P can costlessly reveal his
152
Settlement
7400
hidden information to D; he may also choose to stay silent. Shavell shows that silence implies that P’s information involves low types (for example, that P’s level of damages is low). Shavell considers two possibilities: claims by P are costlessly verifiable by D or some types of P cannot make verifiable claims; for convenience, call the first analysis an unlimited verifiable claims (UVC) model and the second a limited verifiable claims (LVC) model (in the LVC model those types of P unable to make verifiable claims is an exogenously specified fraction u). In the UVC model, all Ps whose true type is less than or equal to a given value stay silent while all those above that value make their claims. Since the claims are verifiable, D settles with those types by offering their concession limit and settles with the silent types by offering a settlement offer designed to reflect this group’s types. Thus, there are no trials in equilibrium. Under discovery rights for D that provide mandatory disclosure, all types of P reveal, resulting in a reduced expenditure for D: each type of P settles for their concession limit. In the LVC model there will be trials. The reason is that the silent Ps now include those types who cannot make verifiable claims; some of these will have higher levels of damages than the offer made to the group of silent types, and will thus reject the offer and then go to trial (this relies on the assumption that u is independent of the level of damages). The rest of the silent types will settle, as will those whose claim is both greater and verifiable. Discovery now means that D can settle with (1 ! u) of the possible types of P at their concession limit and must screen the silent types, all of whom have unverifiable claims and, thus, some of whom will proceed to court (if the continuum-type version of (SSC) holds). Again, total D expenditures will generally be reduced from the original LVC payoff. Mandatory disclosure in the LVC case raises the screening offer for the silent group, since those lower types with verifiable claims have settled at their concession limit. Thus, the probability of trial will be reduced relative to the original LVC outcome. Moreover, those with verifiable claims would have settled with or without mandatory disclosure. Sobel (1989) provides a two-sided asymmetric information model that examines the impact of discovery and voluntary disclosure on settlement offers and outcomes; significantly, discovery generates costs and this affects results. He sandwiches one of two possible discovery processes between an initial D-proposer ultimatum game and a final P-proposer ultimatum game. Settlement in the D-proposer model ends the game, while rejection leads to the possibility of either mandatory discovery or no discovery of D’s private information by P. This is then followed by the P-proposer ultimatum game. The cost of disclosure to D is denoted c. In a voluntary disclosure setting, D’s choice to disclose is costly, and therefore might be used by D to signal that the information was credible. By making P the final proposer, P is able
7400
Settlement
153
to extract all the surplus from settlement. Thus, D has no reason to voluntarily disclose information if c > 0. This contrasts with results, for example, by Milgrom and Roberts (1986) who model costless voluntary disclosure and find that such disclosure can be fully revealing. As Sobel observes, this suggests that such a conclusion is sensitive to the assumption that c = 0. Sobel also finds that mandatory disclosure reduces the probability of trial and may bias the selection of cases that go to trial, generating a distribution in which P wins more often. Cooter and Rubinfeld (1994) use an analysis based on an axiomatic settlement model with prior assessments that may be inconsistent; discovery may or may not eliminate inconsistency. For example, discovery may reveal a player’s private information or it may cause a player to adopt an alternative perspective about what may come out of trial. Either way, an NBS is applied to a settlement frontier adjusted by the difference in expected trial payoffs. One of the main results is the proposal of an allocation of discovery costs so as to provide disincentives for abuse by either player. The proposed allocation assigns discovery costs to each party up to a switching point, at which point incremental costs are shifted to the requesting player. 19.2 Acquiring Information from Experts As discussed in Section 15.1, Watts (1994) considers a model with an agent that provides expertise in the sense that they can acquire information for a player more cheaply than the player can themselves. She shows how to view the problem as one of bargaining between the player and the agent and provides some comparative statics about their settlement frontier. In Daughety and Reinganum (1993) a model allowing simultaneous or sequential moves by both players (this is discussed in more detail in Section 12.4) is embedded in a model which allows uninformed players to acquire information from an expert before settlement negotiations begin. The information, which is costly, is what an informed player would know. Thus, a player may start the game already informed (called naturally informed) or start uninformed but able to acquire the information at a cost c > 0; for convenience, assume that court costs are the same for the two players and denote them as k. If both players are uninformed then, in equilibrium, neither will choose to buy the information. This is because informational asymmetry results in some possible cases going to trial while symmetric uncertainty involves no trials. With one of the players naturally informed and one uninformed then, as discussed earlier, depending on the form of the compromise function, the equilibrium involves either payoffs consistent with an ultimatum screening model or payoffs consistent with an ultimatum signaling model. In those conditions which lead to the screening game payoffs, the uninformed player will choose to buy the information if c < k.
154
Settlement
7400
Alternatively, in those conditions which lead to signaling game payoffs, the uninformed player will not acquire the information. Thus, uninformed players will not always choose to ‘re-level the playing field’ by purchasing information; signaling will provide it if a revealing equilibrium is anticipated.
D. Conclusions 20. Summary The modeling of settlement bargaining has been influenced primarily by law, economics and game theory. In many ways it is still developing and expanding, and hopefully deepening. The more recent analyses employ, primarily, a mix of information economics and bargaining theory (both cooperative and non-cooperative) to examine, understand and recommend improvements in legal institutions and procedures. There has been a tug-of-war between the desire to address interesting behavior and the current limited ability to relate seemingly irrational acts to rational choice. As the development of technique has progressively allowed this to be accomplished, and as the intuition as to why seeming irrationality may be rational has driven improvement in technique, a broader picture of what elements contribute to, or impede, dispute resolution has evolved. In this area, I think, it is fair to claim that issues have led techniques, a good thing. If there is an aspect that could use improvement, it is the fact that, to date, there are few empirical or laboratory studies of the details of the settlement process. In an area where 93 percent of the outcomes are partially or totally unobservable by researchers, empirical studies are hard to do, and the few that have been done have undoubtedly involved hard work. The development of improved summary data sources, some available on the Internet, is very exciting, but more studies of settlement bargaining at the actual process level (as in, for example, Farber and White) would also be most helpful. Laboratory studies (experimental economics and related efforts in sociology and psychology) are expanding but the more subtle predictions of some of these models means that laboratory studies have to walk a fine line between being a test of a particular model’s prediction or ending up mainly gauging a subject’s IQ. Such studies are also very labor-intensive (on the part of the researcher), though the recent increased entry of researchers into this area bodes well. Most of the work in this area (covering the last quarter century) has occurred in the last dozen years (and most of that has occurred in the last half-dozen years), indicating an accelerating interest and suggesting that the
7400
Settlement
155
next survey will have a lot more new, useful theory and detailed empirical and laboratory tests to report, a good thing, too. Acknowledgements Support from NSF grants SBR-9223087 and SBR-9596193 is gratefully acknowledged. I thank Jeremy Atack, A. Mitchell Polinsky, Richard Posner, Robert Rasmussen, David Sappington, Steven Shavell, John Siegfried and Kathryn Spier for helpful comments and suggestions on (and corrections of) an earlier draft. I especially thank Jennifer Reinganum for many helpful comments and discussions.
Bibliography on Settlement (7400) Bebchuk, Lucian Arye (1984), ‘Litigation and Settlement under Imperfect Information’, 15 Rand Journal of Economics, 404-415. Bebchuk, Lucian Arye (1988), ‘Suing Solely to Extract a Settlement Offer’, 17 Journal of Legal Studies, 437-450. Bebchuk, Lucian Arye (1996), ‘A New Theory Concerning the Credibility of Success of Threats to Sue’, 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-26. Bebchuk, Lucian Arye and Chang, Howard F. (1996), ‘An Analysis of Fee Shifting Based on the Margin of Victory: On Frivolous Suits, Meritorious Suits, and the Role of Rule 11', 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 371-404. Che, Yeon-Koo and Yi, Jong Goo (1993), ‘The Role of Precedents in Repeated Litigation’, 9 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 399-424. Chung, Tai-Yeong (1996), ‘Settlement of Litigation under Rule 68: An Economic Analysis’, 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 261-286. Cooter, Robert D. and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1989), ‘Economic Analysis of Legal Disputes and Their Resolution’, 27 Journal of Economic Literature, 1067-1097. Cooter, Robert D. and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1994), ‘An Economic Model of Legal Discovery’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 435-463. Daughety, Andrew F. and Reinganum, Jennifer F. (1993), ‘Endogenous Sequencing in Models of Settlement and Litigation’, 9 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 314-348. Daughety, Andrew F. and Reinganum, Jennifer F. (1994), ‘Settlement Negotiations with Two Sided Asymmetric Information: Model Duality, Information Distribution, and Efficiency’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 283-298. Daughety, Andrew F. and Reinganum, Jennifer F. (1995), ‘Keeping Society in the Dark: on the Admissibility of Pretrial Negotiations as Evidence in Court’, 26 Rand Journal of Economics, 203-221. Farber, Henry S. and White, Michelle J. (1991), ‘Medical Malpractice: An Empirical Examination of the Litigation Process’, 22 Rand Journal of Economics, 199-217.
156
Settlement
7400
Farmer, Amy and Pecorino, Paul (1994), ‘Pretrial Negotiations with Asymmetric Information on Risk Preferences’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 273-281. Fournier, Gary M. and Zuehlke, Thomas W. (1996), ‘The Timing of Out-of-Court Settlements, 27 Rand Journal of Economics, 310-321. Gould, John P. (1973), ‘The Economics of Legal Conflicts’, 2 Journal of Legal Studies, 279-300. Grossman, Gene M. and Katz, Michael L. (1983), ‘Plea Bargaining and Social Welfare’, 73 American Economic Review, 749-757. Katz, Avery (1990), ‘The Effect of Frivolous Lawsuits on the Settlement of Litigation’, 10 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-27. Kobayashi, Bruce H. (1992), ‘Deterrence with Multiple Defendants: an Explanation for “Unfair” Plea Bargaining’, 23 Rand Journal of Economics, 507-517. Landes, William M. (1971), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Courts’, 14 Journal of Law and Economics, 61-107. Landes, William M. (1994), ‘Counterclaims: An Economic Analysis’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 235-244. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1987), ‘Some Agency Problems in Settlement’, 16 Journal of Legal Studies, 189-215. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1996), ‘Settlement of Litigation: A Critical Retrospective’, in Kramer, Larry (ed.), Reforming the Civil Justice System, New York, NY, New York University Press. Nalebuff, Barry (1987), ‘Credible Pretrial Negotiation’, 18 Rand Journal of Economics, 198-210. P’ng, Ivan P.L. (1983), ‘Strategic Behavior in Suit, Settlement, and Trial’, 14 Bell Journal of Economics, 539-550. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Che, Yeon-Koo (1991), ‘Decoupling Liability: Optimal Incentives for Care and Litigation’, 22 Rand Journal of Economics, 562-570. Posner, Richard A. (1973), ‘An Economic Approach to Legal Procedure and Judicial Administration’, 2 Journal of Legal Studies, 399-458. Priest, George L. and Klein, Benjamin, (1984), ‘The Selection of Disputes for Litigation’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-56. Reinganum, Jennifer F. (1988), ‘Plea Bargaining and Prosecutorial Descretion’, 78 American Economic Review, 713-728. Reinganum, Jennifer F. (1993), ‘The Law Enforcement Process and Criminal Choice’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 115-134. Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, Louis L. (1986), ‘Settlement, Litigation, and the Allocation of Litigation Costs’, 17 Rand Journal of Economics, 557-566. Rosenberg, David and Shavell, Steven (1985), ‘A Model in which Suits are Brought for their Nuisance Value’, 5 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-13. Schweizer, Urs (1989), ‘Litigation and Settlement under Two Sided Incomplete Information’, 56 Review of Economic Studies, 163-177. Shavell, Steven (1982), ‘Suit, Settlement and Trial: A Theoretical Analysis under Alternative Methods for the Allocation of Legal Costs’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 55-81. Shavell, Steven (1989), ‘Sharing of Information Prior to Settlement or Litigation’, 20 Rand Journal of Economics, 183-195.
7400
Settlement
157
Shavell, Steven (1993), ‘Suit Versus Settlement When Parties Seek Nonmonetary Judgments’, 22 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-13. Sobel, Joel (1989), ‘An Analysis of Discovery Rules’, 52 Law and Contemporary Problems, 133-160. Spier, Kathryn E. (1992), ‘The Dynamics of Pretrial Negotiation’, 59 Review of Economic Studies, 93-108. Spier, Kathryn E. (1994a), ‘Pretrial Bargaining and the Design of Fee-Shifting Rules’, 25 Rand Journal of Economics, 197-214. Spier, Kathryn E. (1994b), ‘Settlement Bargaining and the Design of Damage Awards’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization; 84-95. Wang, Gyu Ho, Kim, Jeong Yoo and Yi, Jong Goo (1994), ‘Litigation and Pretrial Negotiation under Incomplete Information’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, April, 187-200. Watts, Alison (1994), ‘Bargaining through an Expert Attorney’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 168-86. Yang, Bill Z. (1996), ‘Litigation, Experimentation and Reputation’, 16 International Review of Law and Economics, 491-502.
Other References Aumann, Robert J. (1976), ‘Agreeing to Disagree’, 4 Annals of Statistics, 1236-1239. Babcock, Linda, Loewenstein, George, Issacharoff, Samuel and Camerer, Colin (1995), ‘Biased Judgments of Fairness in Bargaining’, 85 The American Economic Review, 1337-1343. Baird, Douglas G., Gertner, Robert H. and Picker, Randal C. (1994), Game Theory and the Law, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Bernheim, B. Douglas, Peleg, Bezalel and Whinston, Michael D. (1987), ‘Coalition Proof Nash Equilibria, I: Concepts’, 42 Journal of Economic Theory, 1-12. Binmore, Ken (1985), ‘Bargaining and Coalitions’, in Roth, Alvin E. (ed.), Game-Theoretic Models of Bargaining, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Binmore, Ken (1992), Fun and Games: A Text on Game Theory, Lexington, MA, DC, Heath and Company. Binmore, Ken, Rubinstein, Ariel and Wolinsky, Asher (1986), ‘The Nash Bargaining Solution in Economic Modelling’, 17 Rand Journal of Economics, 176-188, Fernandez, Raquel and Glazer, Jacob (1991), ‘Striking for a Bargain Between Two Completely Informed Agents’, 81 American Economic Review, 240-252. Geanakoplos, John and Polemarchakis, Heraklis (1982), ‘We Can’t Disagree Foreever’, 28 Journal of Economic Theory, 192-200. Greenberg, Joseph (1994), ‘Coalition Structures’, in Aumann, Robert J. and Hart, Sergiu (eds), Handbook of Game Theory, Vol. 2, Amsterdam, North Holland-Elsevier. Harsanyi, John C. (1967, 1968a, 1968b), ‘Games with Incomplete Information Played with “Bayesian Players”’, 13-14 Management Science, 159-182, 320-334 and 486-502. Huang, Peter H. (1995), ‘Strategic Behavior and the Law: A Guide for Legal Scholars to Game Theory and the Law by Douglass Baird, et al. and Other Game Theory Texts’, 36 Jurimetrics Journal of Law, Science and Technology, 99-114.
158
Settlement
7400
Kennan, John and Wilson, Robert (1993), ‘Bargaining with Private Information’, 31 Journal of Economic Literature, 45-104. Kreps, David M. (1990), Game Theory and Economic Modelling, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Lax, David A. and Sebenius, James K. (1986), The Manager as Negotiator, New York, NY, The Free Press. Mas-Colell, Andreu, Whinston, Michael D. and Green, Jerry R. (1995), Microeconomic Theory, New York, NY, Oxford University Press. Milgrom, Paul and Roberts, John (1986), ‘Relying on the Information of Interested Parties’, 17 Rand Journal of Economics, 18-32. Nash, John F. (1950), ‘The Bargaining Problem’, 18 Econometrica, 155-162. Nash, John F. (1951), ‘Non-Cooperative Games’, 54 Annals of Mathematics, 286-295. Nash, John F. (1953), ‘Two-Person Cooperative Games’, 21 Econometrica, 128-140. Okada, Akira (1996), ‘A Noncooperative Coalitional Bargaining Game with Random Proposers’, 16 Games and Economic Behavior, 97-108. Posner, Richard A. (1992), Economic Analysis of Law, Fourth Edition, Boston, MA, Little, Brown and Company. Roth, Alvin E. (1995), ‘Bargaining Experiments’, in Kagel, John H. and Roth, Alvin E. (eds), The Handbook of Experimental Economics, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press, 253-348. Rubinfeld, Daniel L. and Sappington, David E.M. (1987), ‘Efficient Awards and Standards of Proof in Judicial Proceedings’, 18 Rand Journal of Economics, 308-315. Rubinstein, Ariel (1982), ‘Perfect Equilibrium in a Bargaining Model’, 50 Econometrica, 97-110. Rubinstein, Ariel (1985), ‘A Bargaining Model with Incomplete Information About Time Preferences’, 53 Econometrica, 1151-1172. Salant, Stephen W. and Sims, Theodore S. (1996), ‘Game Theory and the Law: Ready for Prime Time?’, 94 Michigan Law Review, 1839-1882. Ståhl, Ingolf (1972), Bargaining Theory, Stockholm, Economics Research Institute.
7500 ARBITRATION Bruce L. Benson DeVoe Moore Professor and Distinguished Research Professor Department of Economics, Florida State University © Copyright 1999 Bruce L. Benson
Abstract Within the economics literature on arbitration, some studies, generally considering commercial disputes, emphasize arbitration-litigation relationships. For instance, commercial arbitrators often rely on customary commercial law rather than national law, suggesting that arbitration can be a jurisdictional alternative to litigation rather than simply a procedural one. In support of this, the literature demonstrates that arbitration is a potential source of precedent, and is viable without judicial backing. Others studies, mostly dealing with labor disputes, focus on negotiation incentives given alternative forms of compulsory interest arbitration. Arbitration selection processes’ implications for arbitrator behavior and the relative ‘quality’ of arbitration are also considered. JEL classification: K41, J52 Keywords: Arbitration, Customary Law, Private Sanctions, Precedent, Interest Arbitration, Exchangeability
1. Introduction The law and economics literature on contracts and contract enforcement has focused almost exclusively on judicial adjudication (Rubin, 1995, p. 113), despite the fact that the vast majority of contracts are never adjudicated. Outside the realm of law and economics there is a large literature on alternative dispute resolution (ADR) including arbitration, for instance, indicating that even when disputes cannot be resolved through negotiation or mediation, they are directed away from national courts and into arbitration, at least for some large categories of contracts. Lew’s (1978, p. 589) detailed examination of the evidence on international commercial contracts concludes that around 80 percent of these contracts had arbitration clauses at the time of his study, for example, and that over time, ‘more and more [international traders] ... turn to arbitration’. More recent studies confirm this trend: Casella (1992, p. 1), Berger (1994, p. 12) and others report that about 90 percent of all international trade contracts contain arbitration clauses. Similarly, within the United States, arbitration under the auspices of various commercial organizations, or by 159
160
Arbitration
7500
independent arbitrators, perhaps from the American Arbitration Association (AAA), resolve at least three times as many commercial disputes as the common law courts do (Auerbach, 1983, p. 113). Arbitration of disputes between employers (both government and private) and unionized employees has also been routine (and even compulsory for government employees, as well as for some private sector employees, when negotiation proves inadequate) for several decades in the United States. Furthermore, while non-union employees’ disputes were almost never arbitrated before 1970, growing numbers are now resolved by arbitrators (Ware, 1996, p. 1). Arbitration is also used for disputes between businesses and customers. For instance, the New York Stock Exchange formally provided for arbitration in its 1817 constitution, and it ‘has been working successfully ever since’, primarily to rectify disputes between Exchange members and their customers (Lazarus, et al., 1965, p. 27). The Council of Better Business Bureaus (BBB) operates arbitration programs for consumers in many parts of the United States, several automobile manufacturers have contracts with the BBB to arbitrate car owners’ complaints, AAA arbitrators annually resolve thousands of insurance claims, the National Association of Home Builders offers AAA arbitration of buyers’ complaints against association members, medical malpractice arbitration, begun in 1929, is on the rise, and so on (Denenberg and Denenberg, 1981). Non-contract civil disputes are also shifting to arbitration in the United States, in part to avoid litigation costs such as delays due to congested government courts (Bloom and Cavanagh, 1987, p. 35). Indeed, a new private-for-profit court industry, developing since 1979, offers a wide variety of ADR procedures to resolve all kinds of disputes (there were more than 50 such firms in the United States 1992, most with offices in several states (Ray, 1992, p. 191)). These firms are attracting growing numbers of customers (as well as profits and investors (Phalon, 1992, p. 126)), including many who do not contractually stipulate ADR prior to the dispute arising. While arbitration has not attracted much attention in the core of the law and economics literature, there are some exceptions (for example, Landes and Posner, 1979; Bernstein, 1992; Shavell, 1995). Furthermore, expanding ‘law and economics’ to include some contributions from ‘new institutional economics’ and labor economics, reveals considerable analysis of various aspects of arbitration, thus providing the foundations upon which a law and economics approach to understanding arbitration’s functions can be built. There is a much larger literature on arbitration outside of economics, of course, including several journals exclusively concerned with arbitration or ADR, but this review focuses on research by economists or by legal scholars who have adopted a law and economics approach (and at times, contributions from the larger literature referred to in this research), thus leaving out some issues that
7500
Arbitration
161
may be attracting attention in the larger literature and/or of potential but yet unexplored interest from a law-and-economics perspective. The economics literature on arbitration divides, roughly, between labor arbitration and commercial arbitration. However, within this literature, a different (but correlated) division is also apparent. In particular, some studies, mostly concerned with commercial arbitration, emphasize relationships between arbitration and litigation, while other economics research, primarily in the labor literature, focuses on arbitration’s influence on negotiation incentives (explorations of the arbitration process are found in both literatures). The following presentation is organized in reflection of this division. It appears that the reason for the differences in focus arises, at least in part, because commercial arbitration is generally an ex ante voluntary decision by both parties to contractually specify arbitration over litigation in the event of a dispute, while the most widely studied examples of labor arbitration by economists (interest arbitration dealing with public sector employees) are compulsory under statute law. This is probably due to the fact that data on some compulsory arbitration systems can be obtained relatively easily, while data on general grievance arbitration is not nearly as accessible. As a consequence, however, within the economics literature, voluntary commercial arbitration is often depicted as a cooperative endeavor to minimize the costs of dispute resolution, while labor arbitration tends to be characterized as a much more adversarial process. In reality, like commercial arbitration, most private-sector labor arbitration arises through collective bargaining contracts rather than through compulsory statutes, the primary exception being parts of the transportation industry governed by the Railway Labor Act so, as indicated below, the impression taken from the labor economics literature on arbitration may be quite misleading. First, some of the reasons for why law and economics scholars should be interested in arbitration are discussed in Part 2. An important one, at least for commercial law, is that arbitrators often resolve disputes under customary commercial law and/or trade association rules rather than under the statute and/or precedent law of a particular nation. That the choice of arbitration is a jurisdictional issue rather than simply a procedural one might not be accepted if, as is frequently claimed, arbitration is not viable without judicial enforcement of arbitration agreements and rulings, and/or arbitration is simply a compromising process and not a source of legal interpretation and precedent. Therefore, the arguments and evidence regarding these two ‘arbitration versus litigation’ issues are explored in Sections 3 through 6. The arbitration/negotiation relationship as it is depicted in the labor economics literature, primarily in consideration of the effect of alternative forms of compulsory arbitration on incentives to negotiate, is examined in Sections 7 through 10. Arbitration selection processes and their implications for arbitrator
162
Arbitration
7500
behavior and the relative ‘quality’ of arbitration are examined in Section 11, and concluding comments appear in Section 12.
2. Why Should Arbitration be Studied? There are many reasons for more careful consideration of arbitration in the law and economics literature. For instance, the similarities between arbitration and civil litigation are considerable, so perhaps we can learn something about more complex dispute resolution processes by studying arbitration (Ashenfelter, 1987, p. 342; Bloom and Cavanagh, 1987, p. 353). The differences between arbitration and litigation may also be instructive. For example, unlike judges and juries, arbitrators tend to specialize in particular types of disputes. A knowledgeable specialist can render a decision more quickly and with less information transfer from, and therefore less costs incurred by, the disputants, and is less likely to make an error, but Ashenfelter (1987, pp. 342-343) raises another point: since disputants typically have veto power in arbitrator selection, arbitrators competing for business have incentives to develop expertise and render unbiased decisions echoing those of past arbitrators. Thus, as explained below, considerable empirical evidence suggests that arbitrator decisions are statistically ‘exchangeable’. In contrast, US juries are selected for their lack of knowledge in an effort to assure ‘unbiased justice’ (fairness), but the exchangeability of expert arbitrators’ decisions suggests an alternative way to achieve bias-free justice while reducing the likelihood of error or bias: competition between ‘experienced jurors’. Perhaps a more important reason for considering arbitration is to gain a fuller understanding of contracting and contract law. In this regard, the focus on judicial adjudication in the law and economics literature on contracting would be appropriate if court precedents and statutes as interpreted by a nation-state’s courts (as well as court-interpreted trade agreements between nations) was the exclusive source of law shaping contracts. This is not the case, however, at least in the area of commercial contracting (Rubin, 1995; Benson, 1989, 1998a, 1998b; Bernstein, 1992, 1996). For instance, Lew’s (1978, pp. 582-583) examination of international commercial arbitration records demonstrates that arbitrators often ‘denationalize’ disputes, looking instead to a ‘non-national and generally accepted rule or practice appropriate to the question at issue ... developed through the concerted efforts of those concerned with and participating in international commerce’ (Lew, 1978, pp. 582-583). That is, as Berman and Dasser (1990, p. 33) explain, international arbitrators ‘refer to international commercial custom, including contract practices in international trade, as a basis for their award’, and no nation’s law is applied unless the contract specifies it or the parties expect it (also see Trakman, 1983, and Benson, 1992b).
7500
Arbitration
163
Standards of business practice and usage within trade associations and other commercial groups (or a trade association’s explicit internal ‘legislation’ (Bernstein, 1996)) are also the sources of many of the basic rules under which contracts are drawn up and disputes are arbitrated within many countries. Bernstein’s (1992, p. 126) examination of the systematic rejection of state-created law by the diamond industry in favor of its own internal rules (including arbitration institutions and privately produced sanctions) provides a very revealing example: the New York diamond merchants’ ‘Board of Arbitrators does not apply the New York law of contracts and damages, rather it resolves disputes on the basis of trade custom and usage’. Furthermore, despite Bernstein’s (1992, p. 116) contention that ‘the diamond industry is unique in its ability to create and, more important, to enforce its own system of private law’, the same abilities actually exist in many other commercial groups. The fact is that commercial arbitration makes ‘the courts secondary recourse in many areas and completely superfluous in others’ (Wooldridge, 1970, p. 101). Thus, while many contend that law is what judges say it is, this is only true in contracts to the extent that a judge is expected to have the last word on the contract; when adjudication is not sought, perhaps due to the availability of arbitration and the benefits it produces (and/or private sanctions to discourage adjudication, an issue discussed at length below), other behavioral rules can and often will control the contracting parties’ conduct (Rubin, 1995, pp. 118, 124; Bernstein, 1992, 1996; Benson, 1998b, 1998c, 1998d). Furthermore, if government courts are occasionally called upon, thus influencing the expectations of parties to particular kinds of contracts, ‘influence is different from control... [and] One cannot assume, moreover, that the influences flow only in one direction’ (Rubin, 1995, p. 124). Some of the new rules for business behavior that develop through evolving practices, contractual negotiations, and arbitration are likely to be recognized and adopted by judges (Chen, 1992; Benson, 1989, 1990a, pp. 227-229, 1998b), for instance. But even when the courts do not recognize custom as a relevant source of law (perhaps because they conflict with precedents or statutes), a judicial decision does not have to be treated as a permanent determinant of behavioral rules. A contract can specify different types of behavior along with a general arbitration clause, thereby nullifying the future application of the judicial ruling (De Alessi and Staaf, 1991). Thus, an understanding of the evolution of contract law, at least in many areas of commercial activity, requires recognition of arbitration, not only as an ADR, but at least in conjunction with contracts, as a mechanism for nullifying statutes and precedents - that is, as an alternative to legislation and judge-made precedent (Wooldridge, 1970, p. 101; Benson, 1989, 1990a, 1990b, 1992a, 1992b, 1995a, 1998b, 1998c, 1998d; Bernstein, 1992, 1996; Rubin, 1995). This is in sharp contrast to the view that arbitration is essentially a procedural issue (for example, Brunet, 1987), of course, but it is reinforced below when the potential
164
Arbitration
7500
for precedent setting through arbitration is discussed. Before this potential for law creation through arbitration can be fully appreciated, however, an understanding of what motivates the use of arbitration in commercial contract disputes is required.
3. Why is Commercial Arbitration Chosen Rather than Litigation? Any dispute is ‘adversarial’ of course, but in the commercial area, the voluntary use of arbitration is motivated by positive economic incentives. Private arbitration appears to be an attractive substitute for litigation, in part because arbitrators can be selected on the basis of their expertise in matters pertinent to specific disputes, as noted above. Government judges need have no such expertise, so arbitration reduces the uncertainty associated with judicial error and/or bias. This specialization also means that arbitration can be accomplished faster, less formally, and often with less expense than litigation because the parties do not have to provide as much information to the arbitrator as they would to a judge/jury. Another benefit arises when government court time is allocated by waiting, since delay can be devastating to a business. Other potentially important benefits include: (a) arbitration is generally less ‘adversarial’ than litigation so it is more likely to allow continuation of mutually-beneficial repeated-dealing relationships; (b) if desired, privacy can be maintained; and (c) businessmen may wish to avoid the application of state-made law by agreeing to something in a contract that would be overturned in a government court, since an arbitrator looks to the contract first and the contract can specify the relevant law for deciding a case (for example, business practice and custom rather than the statutes or judicial precedents of a particular nation). For elaboration on some or all of these points, see Mentschikoff (1961), Lazarus et al. (1965), Williamson (1979), Trakman (1983), Ashenfelter (1987), Berman and Dasser (1990), Benson (1989, 1990b, 1992b, 1995a, 1998a, 1998b, 1998c), Bernstein (1992, 1996), Currie (1994), Shavell (1995), and Rubin (1995). The potential of mutual gains (lower costs of dispute resolution and/or a larger ‘pie’ to share in the long run) means that there clearly is a ‘cooperative’ element to arbitration as compared to litigation. Despite widespread recognition of at least some of the benefits listed above, a frequent contention is that the defendant can always refuse to engage in arbitration or to accept an arbitration ruling, so the plaintiff must be willing and able to seek judicial (government) enforcement in order to have a credible threat to induce acceptance (see, for example, Willoughby, 1929, p. 56; Lazarus et al., 1965, pp. 31, 125; Landes and Posner, 1979, p. 247; Domke, 1984, p. 27; and Shavell, 1995, p. 3). If this is correct then the contention that arbitration often involves a choice between legal systems may be at least partially
7500
Arbitration
165
undermined. After all, if the primary threat backing arbitration is litigation, then for it to be credible arbitration procedures and awards will have to be acceptable to judges. In sharp contrast, Charny (1990, pp. 409-412) maintains that when a ‘community of transactors recognizes an authoritative nonlegal decisionmaker’ such as an arbitrator, ‘nonlegal sanctions’ will induce the members of the community to accept arbitration and comply with the arbitrator’s judgement; thus, arbitration and nonlegal sanctions are ‘a perfect substitute for legal enforcement’. These nonlegal sanctions are essentially the ‘private’ (as apposed to government-imposed) sanctions discussed in the large economics literature suggesting that bond-posting or hostage-taking (for example, Klein and Leffler, 1981; Williamson, 1983; Kronman, 1985), including the potential loss of reputation (for example, Kreps, 1990; Ellickson, 1991; Milgrom, North and Weingast, 1990; Klein, 1997), provides powerful sources of credibility, and Charny (1990) explains that this analysis also applies for commitments to arbitrate (also see Wooldridge, 1970; Trakman, 1983; Auerbach, 1983; Bernstein, 1992; Benson, 1989, 1992b, 1995a, 1998a, 1998b, 1998c). Perhaps more important than these negative threats, however, are various positive incentives associated with relation-specific reciprocities that arises in repeated dealings (Fuller, 1964, p. 24; Axelrod, 1984; Ellickson, 1991; Trakman, 1983, p. 10; Benson, 1989, 1998c). Indeed, one potential long-term benefit from accepting an unfavorable arbitration award is the reciprocal commitment by a trading partner to accept low cost arbitration and abide by an unfavorable judgement in any future dispute. Of course, private sanctions reinforce such incentives, so the combination can provide strong incentives to arbitrate even without an added ‘legal’ (that is, government-imposed) threat (indeed, reciprocities are valuable assets which can be threatened, and therefore, part of the private sanctions arsenal).
4. Does Commercial Arbitration Rely on Reciprocities and Private Sanctions, or on Legal Sanctions? Those who see legal sanctions as necessary to back arbitration cite United States arbitration history as ‘evidence’ in support of this view. In light of the competing hypotheses that reciprocities and private sanctions create strong incentives to arbitrate, Benson (1995a) re-examines this alleged ‘historical evidence’: that arbitration supposedly was not in widespread use in the United States prior to passage by New York (1920), New Jersey (1923), the federal government of Pennsylvania (1927) and California (1925), Oregon (1925), Massachusetts (1925, 1927) of statutes commanding the common law courts to enforce arbitration agreements and rulings (examples of this contention include Willoughby, 1929, p. 56, and Lucas, 1987, p. 55). Prior to this, it is often alleged (incorrectly, as explained below) that agreements to arbitrate were
166
Arbitration
7500
generally not considered binding under common law until these statutes were passed, and that hostile judges felt free to overturn arbitration decisions if one of the parties chose to litigate (examples include Lazarus et al., 1965, p. 18; Horwitz, 1977; Murray, Rau and Sherman, 1989, p. 435; Allison, 1990, p. 11). A relative lack of litigation in the United States regarding arbitration issues appears to be the evidence that many have looked to in contending that commercial arbitration was not widely used before 1920. It is true that litigation over issues arising in arbitration increased dramatically following passage of the 1920s statutes (see Sturges, 1930), but court records do not provide a clear picture of the historic level of arbitration because the vast majority of arbitration decisions are never appealed, and the statutes themselves may have increased the propensity to appeal rather than the propensity to arbitrate, as explained below. Moreover, an examination of newspapers, merchant letters, and the records of organizations providing arbitration services, such as the New York Chamber of Commerce, clearly demonstrate that commercial arbitration actually was in widespread use in each of the British Colonies almost three centuries before modern arbitration statutes were passed (Auerbach, 1983; Jones 1956; Smith, 1961, pp. 180-188; Odiorne, 1953, 1954). After the revolution, arbitration remained in wide use in all of the states (Auerbach, 1983; Jones, 1956, p. 219; Smith, 1961, pp. 180-188; Odiorne, 1953, 1954). Why? Because ‘Not only did courts, according to one New York merchant, dispense “expensive endless law”; they were slow to develop legal doctrine that facilitated commercial development’ (Auerbach, 1983, p. 33). Common law judges in America were hostile toward arbitration during the eighteenth and early part of the nineteenth century, as they exhibited an increasing willingness to overturn arbitrators’ decisions for issues relating to either law or fact is evident (see Benson, 1995a for cases and references). The use of commercial arbitration developed during the colonial and post-revolutionary periods in spite this hostility, however, suggesting that court backing is not a prerequisite for such arbitration. Later in the nineteenth century, a trend toward less hostility can be detected in several state courts (MacNeil, 1992; Benson 1995a), but arbitration continued to evolve both in states where the courts were relatively receptive and states where judicial acceptance was evolving more slowly (Benson, 1995a). For instance, as New York merchants organized into various associations and exchanges, provisions were always made for the arbitration of disputes among members (Jones, 1956, p. 214), despite New York’s maintenance of the common law doctrine of revocability of arbitration clauses in statutes longer than many other states. The volume of evidence regarding the widespread and growing use of arbitration is particularly heavy for the last four decades of the nineteenth century (Jones, 1956, pp. 214-215; Wooldridge, 1970. p. 101; Auerbach, 1983; Macneil 1992; Benson, 1995a). Indeed, these developments suggest that
7500
Arbitration
167
arbitration was being substituted for litigation, since this period witnessed rising litigation costs due to court congestion and trial delay, as well as increasing uncertainty costs regarding the credibility of state courts’ implicit commitments to support business contracts as ‘the growth of the regulatory state unsettled advocates of commercial autonomy who turned to arbitration as a shield against government intrusion’ (Auerbach, 1983, p. 101; also see Benson, 1995a). Rising litigation costs increased incentives to establish contractual arrangements and organizations (for example, trade associations, commercial exchanges) to govern the process of dispute resolution and insure against litigation (for example, arbitration clauses, arbitration institutions, institutionalized private sanctions). Thus, by the end of World War I, arbitration had clearly made the courts irrelevant for contract disputes by a large segment of the business community in the United States (Wooldridge, 1970, p. 101). Perhaps private sanctions and reciprocities are sufficient to encourage disputants to live up to most ex ante agreements to arbitrate, but to date, most arbitration apparently arises under preexisting agreements (or mandates in the case of compulsory interest arbitration discussed below). Does this mean that arbitration cannot be agreed to after a dispute has already developed, unless a strong (that is, state-backed) sanction can be brought to bear? An alternative explanation for the apparent lack of ex post arbitration may simply be Shavell’s (1995, p. 9) point that the benefits of arbitration are greater when agreed to ex ante than when established ex post. However, he also notes that an ex post agreement to arbitrate can still reduce dispute resolution costs (Shavell, 1995, p. 9). Other potential benefits from ex post arbitration agreements include the possibility that the dispute will be resolved more amicably (arbitration is a less adversarial procedure), that risks of judicial error are reduced, and/or that the parties prefer the application of alternative law (for example, custom, the rules designed in a trade association). Thus, arbitration should also be attractive ex post, and perhaps legal sanctions to explicitly encourage such arbitration would be beneficial. However, there appears to be an evolving trend toward more ex post arbitration even without direct efforts to encourage it through legal sanctioning. For instance, nonmembers of the diamond merchants’ organization who have a dispute with members often request ex post that the diamond industry’s arbitration board hear their cases, and this is done if both parties sign an ex post agreement to arbitrate (Bernstein, 1992, p. 126). Furthermore, the recent and rapid development of private for-profit courts that resolve business disputes, personal injury disputes, divorces, construction warranty disputes, disputes over loan defaults, and so on, as they arise (Pruitt, 1982; Benson, 1990b; Ray, 1992; Phalon, 1992), and the growing scope of arbitration of non-contract civil disputes, both suggest that arbitration can be quite attractive even for disputants who do not precommit, and that private institutions are evolving to provide such services.
168
Arbitration
7500
Additional evidence that reciprocities and/or private sanctions are sufficient to support a great deal of commercial arbitration at least, comes from international commerce. International contracts often expressly exclude litigation and almost always refer disputes to arbitration, and international trade disputes that cannot be resolved through negotiation are almost always arbitrated (for example, Lew, 1978; Trakman, 1983; Berman and Dasser, 1990; Casella, 1992; Berger, 1994; Benson, 1990b, 1992b, 1998c). Certainly, statutes in several nations, as well as various international treaties and agreements mandate court enforcement of international arbitration agreements, but the fact, as David (1985, p. 357) stresses, is that: A sense of fair dealing on one hand, the respect for public opinion on the other, also the fear of being criticized by one’s own community or that non-performance may be interpreted as evidence that one’s business is in a critical financial situation are reasons why arbitral awards are most generally promptly and willingly executed by business people. Such conduct may also be encouraged if the losing party is led to believe that the community will not remain passive in case of non-performance, but that sanctions may be imposed if the award is not executed.
Arbitration is also attractive because international traders generally assume that national courts will not enforce obligations derived solely from customary commercial law (Chen, 1992, p. 100). Indeed, during the medieval period this was particularly true, and as a result, the medieval ‘Law Merchant’ was an almost pure system of privately-arbitrated customary commercial law backed by private sanctions (for example, Trakman, 1983; Berman, 1983; Benson, 1989, 1990b, 1998b, 1998c, forthcoming; Milgrom, North and Weingast, 1990).
5. What are the Consequences of Legal Sanctions for Arbitration? Rejection of the hypothesis that government sanctions are necessary for all successful commercial arbitration does not definitely follow from the refutation of the evidence typically supporting it. Indeed, a middle ground is obviously also possible that may well be consistent with all of the evidence. Rubin (1994, p. 4), for example, suggests that ‘private parties can use many available mechanisms to make agreements self-enforcing ... [but] the law can facilitate the use of these mechanisms ... [by enforcing] arbitration clauses in contracts if parties insert such clauses’. Perhaps positive incentives from reciprocities and/or private sanctions are not strong enough to support arbitration for some (many?) commercial transactions and, therefore, statutes mandating court backing are, on net, beneficial, as is often claimed (for example, Rubin, 1994; Shavell, 1995a; Ware, 1996)? Frequently, however, those who call for
7500
Arbitration
169
arbitration agreements and awards to be enforced by the judicial system look only to the benefits of state backing without considering potential costs. The fact is that when reciprocities and private sanctions provide sufficient sources of credibility for transactors, state-imposed sanctions may actually raise transactions costs (Ashe, 1983; Auerbach, 1983; Trakman, 1983; Benson, 1989, 1990b, 1995a, 1998b; Charny, 1990, pp. 426-429; Bernstein, 1992, pp. 154-157) (note that this appears to be consistent with a similar argument from the labor arbitration literature discussed below, that the availability of compulsory arbitration can raise the transactions costs of negotiations). For instance, an enormous number of court cases were filed as businessmen tried to determine what characteristics of arbitration would be considered “legal” by the courts (Sturges, 1930), and this has continued: the early 1980s were still witnessing a ‘growing number of court challenges to arbitration awards’ (Ashe, 1983, p. 42). Ashe (1983, p. 42) suggests that the increase in appeals reflects the increasing use of lawyers in arbitration because losing attorneys have a stronger tendency to circumvent the arbitrator’s decision than does the losing party who tends to have greater ‘allegiance to the system of arbitration itself’ when lawyers’ ‘advice’ is not involved (that is, there is a principal/agent problem between attorneys and their clients). It is clear that lawyers were rarely involved with commercial arbitration in the United States before the 1920s (indeed, Auerbach, 1983 and Benson, 1995a, contend that the arbitration statutes were passed due to the lobbying efforts of Bar Associations, because lawyers saw arbitration as a growing threat to their business and sought to ‘legalize’ it in order to gain a role in the arbitration process), but as Charny (1990, pp. 388, 403-405) explains, when state-imposed sanctions are available, the demands placed on formal contract writing are increased. If reciprocities and private sanctions alone apply, particularly within narrowly focused commercial organizations, less formality in contracting is required because the parties are intimately familiar with business practice and custom in their particular area of transactions; they understand what a general statement in a contract means, and they can choose an arbitrator with similar intimate understanding. However, a judge is much less likely to have such an understanding, so a contract that may face judicial scrutiny will have to be much more specific and formal in order to avoid a high probability of judicial error (Charny, 1990, pp. 385, 404). Thus, after the modern statutes were passed, some businesses, forced to pay attention to the prospect of judicial review, had to make their arbitration processes compatible with statute and precedent law including court procedure. In order to do so, they had to consult lawyers in drafting contracts and involve lawyers in arbitration (for instance, lawyer representation before AAA arbitration tribunals rose from 36 percent in 1927 to 70 percent in 1938, 84 percent in 1942, and 91 percent in 1947 (Auerbach, 1983, p. 111; Benson,
170
Arbitration
7500
1995a); also see Bernstein, 1992, p. 156 for related discussion about the growing use of lawyers in diamond industry arbitration). The increased likelihood of appeal reflects more than the increasing reliance on lawyers, however. Cohen (1921, p. 150) observed, after New York Arbitration Act’s passage in 1920, that this statute establishes legal machinery for protecting, safeguarding and supervising commercial arbitration. Instead of narrowing the jurisdiction of the Supreme Court it broadens it ... Instead of being ousted of jurisdiction over arbitration, the courts are given jurisdiction over them, and ... the party aggrieved has his ready recourse to the courts.
When the state asserts that it is the source of authority and sanctions for arbitration agreements it implies that rulings from arbitrated commercial disputes are less decisive than they otherwise would be, weakening incentives to abide by arbitrated settlements explicitly subject to potential appeal. Furthermore, there is the possibility that upon appeal a judge will find private sanctions themselves to be illegal (for example, as a restraint of trade). For instance, in Paramount Lasky Corporation vs. United States (282 U.S. 30 (1930)) an explicit agreement to boycott designed to back an arbitration system was struck down. A group of motion picture producers had agreed to place an arbitration clause in all contracts with motion picture exhibitors, and to boycott any exhibitor who refused arbitration or refused to accept an arbitration ruling. Thus, government sanctions can undermine the ability or incentives to use private sanctions (Ashe, 1983, p. 42; Bernstein, 1992, p. 156; Benson, 1989, 1995a, 1998d), and even stifle the development of trust relationships and organizations from which reciprocities and private sanctioning mechanisms often spring (Benson, 1989, 1995a, 1998d; Charny, 1990, p. 428). So the possibility that government sanctions to back arbitration may benefit some parties for whom reciprocities are uncertain and private sanctions provide weak threats does not imply that such sanctions are, on net, beneficial, because they may raise costs to others for whom reciprocities and private sanctions are or could be strong enough.
6. Are Precedents Produced Through Arbitration? Even if the net effect of court backing of arbitration is negative, however, there may be another reason for judicial review. For instance, Brunet (1987, p. 19) contends that ‘the output of conventional litigation should be viewed as a public good - society gains more from litigation than would be produced if litigation were left to the private market’. This presumably is the case because the results of arbitration and other forms of ADR are ‘internal’ to the parties involved (Brunet, 1987, pp. 14-15) so they will either not produce precedent, or will
7500
Arbitration
171
underproduce precedent. Similarly, Landes and Posner (1979, pp. 238, 239, 245) argue that ‘because of the difficulty of establishing property rights in a precedent, private ... judges might deliberately avoid explaining their results because the demand for their services would be reduced by rules that, by clarifying the meaning of the law, reduce the incidence of disputes’; that ‘a problem is that a system of voluntary adjudication is strongly biased against the creation of precise rules of any sort’; and further, that commercial arbitration is ‘not a source of rules or precedents’. Thus, the increasing use of arbitration apparently is eroding ‘the guidance function of the law’ (Brunet, 1987, p. 23). Secrecy is often a characteristic of arbitration. For instance, Bernstein (1992, p. 124) explains that within the diamond industry ‘As long as judgments are complied with, the fact of the arbitration as well as its outcome are officially kept secret’. But this ‘official’ secrecy does not mean that precedents are never created, or that too few rules exist. The parties to the dispute will certainly consider the arbitration result in future dealings under similar circumstances, for instance, and probably have to explain them to trading partners. But more importantly, a diamond bourse (trading club) is ‘an information exchange as much as it is a commodities exchange’. As one author put it, ‘the bourse grapevine is the best in the world. It has been going for years and moves with the efficiency of a satellite communications network. ... Bourses are the fountainhead of this information and from them it is passed out along the tentacles that stretch around the world’ as each local bourse is part of an umbrella organization that, among other things, arbitrates disputes between members of different bourses, enforces arbitration judgments from other bourses, and facilitates the establishment of uniform trading rules throughout the industry (Bernstein, 1992, p. 121). Under such a circumstance, ‘official’ secrecy is probably not much of a constraint on the spread of important information about an arbitration ruling that might provide new precedent. It is clear that in the diamond industry arbitration results do ‘become known through gossip’ (Bernstein, 1992, p. 126) at any rate. Bernstein (1992, pp. 126-127) contends that when diamond industry arbitrators hear complex cases ‘it is difficult to determine what substantive rules of decisions are applied’, and such observations may appear in support of the view that arbitration does not produce effective precedent. However, as Fuller (1981, p. 90) explains, ‘[e]ven if there is no statement by the tribunal of the reasons for its decision, some reason will be perceived or guessed at, and the parties will tend to govern their conduct accordingly’. Thus, precedent of a sort may well be produced even in such an environment. Furthermore, and importantly, it must be recognized that within a customary legal system there are a number of ways for new rules to evolve (for example, through unilateral adoption of behavior that is observed and emulated, through bilateral negotiation and contracting with resulting contract clauses spreading and
172
Arbitration
7500
becoming standardized), besides through precedent (Benson, 1998b), so when a particular arbitration process does not appear to be designed to produce precedent it simply may mean that precedent is a relatively unimportant source of new rules for the relevant group, or that circumstances do not change often enough to require new rules. And importantly, if situations change, making precedent more important, the group is also free to change its arbitration procedures. Thus, as Bernstein (1992, p. 150) explains, diamond dealers have begun to recognize that ‘The lack of written decisions and a tradition of stare decisis makes it difficult to determine in advance the type of sanctioned behavior. In order to increase predictability, many bourses in the world federation have relaxed the norm of complete secrecy. Arbitrators publish written announcements of the principles used to decide novel cases while keeping the parties and other identifying facts secret’. Private dispute resolution mechanisms are very flexible and diverse. They can even accommodate the demands for precedent setting while still meeting demands for privacy. However, privacy is not always as important as some critics of arbitration seem to believe. Landes and Posner (1979), Brunet (1987) and others who see in arbitration a failure to create external benefits appear to take the characteristics of some arbitration and extrapolate them to all arbitration, assuming that arbitration is a much more homogeneous commodity than it really is. But if external benefits are significant there are strong incentives to internalize them, so when precedents become important institutional adjustments are likely to be made. Indeed this provides traders with one of the incentives to form groups such as trade associations and diamond bourses which clearly can internalize the benefits of precedents. Within such an organization, it is easy to imagine a contractual arrangement that creates incentives to minimize disputes by setting clear precedents (for example, consider arbitrators who compete to receive a lump-sum fee under a contract to handle all of the disputes between members of a particular organization over a particular period of time, or arbitrators chosen from the membership of an association who have high opportunity costs if they encourage excessive disputes in the form of time spend away from their business pursuits, and who also personally benefit from clear precedents). Thus, those arbitrators who, as characterized by Landes and Posner (1979, p. 240), ‘tend to promulgate vague standards which give each party to a dispute a fighting chance’ actually do less business. Fuller (1981, pp. 110-111) contends that incentives are exactly the opposite, for instance: ‘Being unbacked by state power ... the arbitrator must concern himself directly with the acceptability of his award. He may be at greater pains than a judge to get his facts straight, to state accurately the arguments of the parties, and generally to display in his award a full understanding of the case’. An obvious hypothesis is that when the environment is a dynamic changing one in which the need for existing rules may be frequently inadequate guides
7500
Arbitration
173
for a new dispute, arbitration rulings are likely to be recorded and/or made known to the relevant group (which certainly is not likely to be the entire ‘public’, of course, but in general, that is not necessary or even desirable - the idea that a single universal system of law is somehow superior to polycentric law with parallel, as well as overlapping and competitive jurisdictions is not consistent with either theory or reality (Benson, 1990a, 1990b, 1992a; Berman, 1983)). This in turn creates incentives for arbitrators to make careful rulings based on past business practices, customs and precedents established within the relevant group. For support of this hypothesis, consider international commercial arbitration. When no clear rule applies from the ‘private international law systems from which the parties come’ arbitrators must determine the appropriate new rule (Lew, 1978, p. 584). To do so, ‘in their desire to ‘denationalize’ the award and make it acceptable and fair, arbitrators often try to show the inherent correctness of their decision in the award itself ... arbitrators may refer to several rules to show how they all lead to the same result’ (Lew, 1978, pp. 584-585). Thus, international arbitration has characteristics often attributed to the common law, as arbiters look to past rulings, practices, traditions, and usage in extending the law to new issues that is, in producing new precedent based on older law. In fact, the general view of international arbitrators is that, ‘owing no allegiance to any sovereign State, international commercial arbitration has a special responsibility to develop and apply the law of international trade’ (Lew, 1978, p. 589). It appears that the misallocation of resources under arbitration is not be as great as Landes and Posner (1979) and Brunet (1987) predict. Indeed, the lawmaking consequences of private arbitration led Wooldridge (1970, p. 104) to suggest that its substantial growth in this century has involved a ‘silent displacement of not only the judiciary but even the legislature’. Furthermore, Bernstein (1992, p. 117) points out that ‘nonlegal norms trump legal rules in a given [voluntary] market only where market participants find that keeping to the industry norms advances their own self-interest. The private regime must be Pareto superior to the established legal regime in order to survive’. (In addition to their contentions that private judging underproduces precedent, however, Landes and Posner, 1979 and Brunet, 1987, p. 21 argue that the common law produces efficient rules as contended by Rubin, 1977 and Priest, 1977, but the validity of this argument has also been subject to considerable attack; this literature is not discussed here, but see for instance, Rizzo, 1980a, 1980b; Aranson, 1986, and Benson, 1990a, 1990b, 1992a, 1996).
174
Arbitration
7500
7. Are there Important Differences in Labor Arbitration Institutions? Non-compulsory labor arbitration in the private sector is also growing, as collective bargaining agreements include arbitration clauses much like many contracts between businessmen do. The development of repeated dealings between unions and firms with institutionalized collective bargaining along with strike and lockout options appears be a sufficient stimuli for arbitration of many grievances and perhaps even contract disputes when negotiations break down. The incentives of the decision-makers must also be recognized. Arbitration may be relatively attractive to union leaders, for instance, because of their legal status. They are in a position of representing everyone in the union, including those who opposed their election and perhaps even campaigned against them. Indeed, they have a legal duty to represent all members, and therefore, in order to avoid a breach of fair representation lawsuit, union officials may pursue grievance arbitration in cases that they would prefer not pursue or would negotiate in the absence of the antagonistic position held by the member with the grievance. Arbitration of such cases is clearly more attractive than the alternatives (a strike or a lawsuit) that may be much more costly for the union as a whole, including the union leader’s supporters. Thus, grievance arbitration may offer union leaders an effective way to avoid controversy and maintain the appearance (and indeed, the reality) of fairness (this suggests that the availability of grievance arbitration may reduce strikes, litigation, and negotiation - the latter is a subject that is widely considered in the labor arbitration literature, and discussed below). There also appears to be incentives to structure grievance arbitration so that benefits of precedents can be internalized. After all, both labor unions and corporate management are likely to recognize that repeated disputes over the same type of issues are costly, and therefore that arbitration which establishes clear precedent is desirable. In this light, consider the incident reported by Bloom and Cavanagh (1986, p. 412): ‘a system known as expedited arbitration was adopted by labor and management in the basic steel industry in 1971. Under this system, unresolved employee grievances that do not require precedent-setting rulings are arbitrated by a rotating panel of young, inexperienced arbitrators (mostly lawyers) who decide the case for a relatively small fee within two weeks of the decision to arbitrate’. When a resolution is expected to be particularly valuable because it will set a precedent, more experienced, more expensive arbitrators are chosen (factors determining the choice of arbitrators are discussed below). This system was established because of rising costs and increasing delays due to a relative shortage of experienced arbitrators. While it has not yet attracted ‘an in-depth study’, it is spreading (Bloom and Cavanagh, 1986, p. 412). United Steel Workers contracts outside the basic steel industry now include it, and it has also been included in some
7500
Arbitration
175
United Mineworker contracts, and is employed in the US Postal Service. Thus, it is instructive for at least three reasons. First, it points to the fact that within an ‘industry’ (the group of employers and the union, not simply the two parties in a particular dispute) the benefits of precedent can be recognized and internalized, even in some types of labor arbitration. Second, it reinforces the fact that arbitration is flexible enough to produce a mix of dispute resolution procedures and outcomes. Third, it suggests that even labor arbitration may have a cooperative element, in contrast to the perception one draws from the economics literature on the subject (Non-union employees’ disputes are also being resolved by arbitrators in growing numbers (Ware, 1996, p. 1)). This perception reflects the fact that the focus of the economics literature on labor arbitration has been on compulsory interest arbitration. Compulsory interest arbitration is almost exclusively a ‘public sector’ phenomena (baseball arbitration and some transportation sector arbitration are among the few exceptions). Yet many of the publications in this interest-arbitration literature begin with a brief discussion of the widespread use of arbitration in commercial areas, perhaps also recognizing that arbitration between individuals and their employers is frequently used to resolve private-sector labor grievances, implicitly suggesting that inferences from their empirical and/or theoretical examination of compulsory public-sector arbitration apply under other institutional arrangements as well. This clearly is not always the case, however. For instance, the compulsory-arbitration focus of the literature might create the impression that labor arbitration in general must rely on state backing or mandates. Much of the literature does not appear to recognize that the institutional environment might create different incentives, although there are a few exceptions. Bloom and Cavanagh (1987, p. 355) and Currie (1989, pp. 365-366) note that private sanctions and expectations of reciprocities may be quite weak for some government employers whose incentives are tied to particular constituencies that may not view an arbitrated (or negotiated) outcome as desirable, for example. Currie (1989, p. 366) also suggests that significant principal/agent problems may arise when imperfectly-monitored self-interested union leaders are bargaining with imperfectly-monitored self-interested government officials (private-sector managers are not perfectly monitored either, but the incentives to monitor public officials are much weaker (Benson, 1995b)). When publicly employed laborers are protected by civil service ‘tenure’ the potential for reciprocities and private sanctions influencing their behavior may also be sharply limited. Thus, the institutional background may be very important, and expanding the scope of the statutes (for example, to mandate arbitration in place of private sector strikes and lockouts) might alter incentives to develop and use labor arbitration institutions voluntarily, as evidenced by some of the things that have happened in commercial arbitration since arbitration statutes were passed in the 1920s.
176
Arbitration
7500
Compulsory arbitration can take different forms, but it often means that strike and lockout options are precluded for public employees by the state, so if one party requests arbitration the other can be forced to accept it. Thus, Stevens (1966), in an early and influential contribution to this literature, describes compulsory arbitration as a bargaining tool in a purely distributional dispute (for example, a zero-sum dispute over the distribution of a fixed ‘pie’ to be divided between employers and a union) that has much in common with a strike or a lockout. In particular, if arbitration is costly then when it is threatened, it can induce the other party to negotiate. Furthermore, he explains that arbitration mechanisms can be designed to encourage negotiated settlements (discourage arbitration), and as demonstrated by the empirical research discussed below, this clearly appears to be the case. He then suggests that arbitration should be designed to impose costs on bargainers in order to encourage voluntary settlements. In fact, following Stevens, it is often contended that the most successful form of compulsory arbitration ‘is one that is not used’ (Long and Feuille, 1974, p. 202). A recommendation that arbitration be made more costly in order to encourage negotiation obviously requires a strong normative belief that negotiated settlements are more desirable than arbitrated settlements (Bloom and Cavanagh, 1987, p. 354; Currie, 1989, p. 364). This norm seems to permeate the economics literature on labor arbitration (with important exceptions, like Bloom and Cavanagh, 1986, 1987; Ashenfelter, 1987, and Currie, 1989). Indeed, as Currie (1989, p. 364) explains, ‘most industrial relations experts believe that settlements reached by the parties themselves are superior to those imposed by an arbitrator’, but without much theoretical basis for the belief. There is some theoretical basis for the conclusion, of course. In particular, as Stevens (1966) alleges, standard interest arbitration as a compromising process tends to ‘chill’ bargaining as it creates incentives for negotiators to misrepresent their true underlying profit- and/or utility-maximizing positions, expecting arbitrators to split the difference between their extreme demands. However, there are alternative theoretical explanations for the relationship between arbitration and negotiation that can produce the same empirical fact and quite different normative implications. Law and economics scholars might anticipate that arguments for encouraging negotiations are based on Coase’s (1960) famous theorem, that if the transactions costs of bargaining are not prohibitive an efficient allocation of resources is achieved through voluntary negotiation. However, the decision to arbitrate obviously implies positive transactions costs for bargaining (perhaps in the form of uncertainty for the union representative regarding the ‘political’ or legal consequences of a negotiated settlement that might be perceived as biased or unfair to some of the membership), and in that context the typical inference drawn from Coase is to lower the cost of negotiating (for example, by clarifying property rights, or in labor arbitration, perhaps by allowing the
7500
Arbitration
177
aggrieved party rather than the elected union leaders to choose a negotiator), not raise the cost of the alternative. Thus, for instance, in the diamond industry, Bernstein (1992, p. 124) explains that parties who submit a dispute to arbitration must first participate in a conciliation proceeding before a conciliation panel that attempts to help the parties negotiate a settlement. Only if such third-party aided negotiation fails can the dispute go to arbitration. This is clearly a mechanism intended to encourage negotiation without raising the cost of arbitration, in sharp contrast to Stevens’ (1966) proposal, and an estimated 85 percent of the diamond-industry disputes submitted to arbitration are settled during this conciliation procedure. Moreover, as Williamson (1979) explains, characteristics of the transaction that determine transactions costs (for example, degree of asset specificity, frequency of the transaction, uncertainty) determine the efficient organizational choice, given ‘market’, ‘bilateral’ (direct negotiation and contracting), and ‘trilateral’ (use of a third-party), or ‘ownership-integration’ governance options. Under these circumstances, if arbitration is used it may be because the transactions costs of negotiation are relatively high, so fair arbitration is a more efficient means of achieving a settlement. Thus, encouraging negotiation by raising the costs of arbitration can reduce efficiency. As Posner (1986, p. 366) notes in his discussion of summary jury trials and other ADR options, the objective should not be to maximize negotiated settlements but to minimize the total costs of the system of achieving settlements, whether voluntarily or through third-party procedures. Perhaps the points made here do not apply to Stevens’ (1966) arguments about compulsory labor arbitration, however. The disputants themselves presumably have not voluntarily designed this governance arrangement if it is mandated by statute (in all likelihood, public sector unions and employers lobbied to influence the statutes, of course, but the statutes may not allow the transaction-specific adjustments in governance organizations that would lead to efficient outcomes (Benson, 1995b)). Compulsory arbitration still may be a cooperative outcome if it is the low-cost dispute resolution mechanism relative to a particular high-transactions-cost negotiation, however. Indeed, Bloom and Cavanagh (1986, p. 409) point out that ‘labor practitioners place greater emphasis [than economic theorists] on arbitration as a mechanism for helping disputants identify and reach efficient outcomes. In their view, arbitrators are professional gatherers and processors of information who play a highly constructive role in a bargaining process which is better treated as a cooperative attempt at problem solving than as direct economic conflict’. Furthermore, Bloom and Cavanagh (1986, p. 421) conclude, from their study of the selection of arbitrators (discussed below), that ‘the similarity of union and employer preferences for different arbitrators suggests that collective bargaining functions more cooperatively than most existing models indicate’. Doubt is cast
178
Arbitration
7500
on the theoretical underpinnings of this hypothesis by considering the assumption that arbitrators split the difference between offers. Farber (1981) raises important theoretical questions regarding the assumption, noting that even empirical evidence of difference splitting would not be sufficient to prove that this is the objective of the arbitrator since parties are likely to position their offers around the expected arbitration award. That is, ‘the expected arbitration outcome shapes the parties’ bargaining positions rather than the reverse’ (Farber, 1981, p. 70). Gibbons (1988) goes even further, modeling arbitration in the context of a three-party game in which arbitrators also learn about the state of the employment relationship from the parties’ offers.
8. Does Final Offer Arbitration Encourage Negotiation (or Discourage Arbitration)? Stevens (1966) and several others propose what has come to known as final offer arbitration (FOA) to overcome the hypothesized tendency for compromising arbitration to ‘chill’ negotiation. FOA requires the arbitrator to choose one or the other of the two sides’ final offers rather than choosing some compromise between them. The idea is that the negotiators will have incentives to move toward relatively reasonable positions before arbitration, but in doing so they are presumably more likely to reach a negotiated settlement on their own. FOA has been implemented in labor arbitration through statute law in a number of places, and as a consequence, it has attracted a good deal of theoretical analysis. Crawford (1979) provides one of the earliest formal theoretical examinations of FOA. He notes that if the arbitrator’s exogenously determined notion of what a settlement should be is known to the two parties then FOA and conventional arbitration will lead to the same outcome in a zero-sum distributional game. Under conventional arbitration neither party would settle for a distribution different from the arbitration outcome so all awards have to correspond to that outcome whether they are achieved through negotiation or arbitration. If the arbitrator selects the final offer closest to his preferred outcome, the same is true, as one party can always improve on any final offer by offering the arbitrator’s preferred settlement. Of course, given positive arbitration costs (that is, if use of arbitration makes the process a negative-sum game), arbitration should actually not be used at all. This might appear to desirable, given the arguments by Stevens (1966), Long and Feuille (1974) and others, but in this case the parties are simply agreeing on what the arbitrator would award anyway, so arbitration is actually the determining factor, not negotiation (Ashenfelter and Bloom, 1984, p. 112).
7500
Arbitration
179
Crawford (1979) also draws on Schelling’s (1963) model of commitment, suggesting that parties find it advantageous to commit to a position that is costly to disavow. Given uncertainty about the strength of the parties’ commitments, the potential for commitment by both parties can lead to a disagreement and therefore to arbitration. Factors that increase the payoff to commitment increase the likelihood of disagreement. Still, the model predicts that FOA should not increase the likelihood of negotiation. Indeed, Crawford (1979, p. 152) suggests that ‘FOA may create a Prisoner’s Dilemma situation and thereby prevent agents who would otherwise cooperate from agreeing on an efficient settlement’. Of course, in a repeated game setting the prisoner’s dilemma outcome of non-cooperation is less likely (Axelrod, 1984), so if the interaction generating the dispute is not viewed by the negotiators as a one-shot game this result may not hold. Nonetheless, Crawford’s framework does not appear support the contention that FOA should increase the propensity to bargain. Actually, Crawford (1979) does raise one point that implies that FOA can be relatively ‘costly’. If negotiations break down, neither final offer may actually be efficient (or equitable, depending on the objectives of the arbitrator and/or the nature of the dispute - the outcome of a zero sum dispute may reflect the arbitrator’s view of equity, for instance). If there are multiple issues involved in the dispute, for example, both final offers may involve inefficient mixes of solutions. Constraining the arbitrator to choose one or the other would, therefore, guarantee an inefficient solution. Crawford (1979) concludes that ‘multiple FOA’ is superior to single FOA arbitration, but under conventional arbitration the arbitrator has a full range of outcomes to consider, so an efficient solution is also possible. If conventional arbitrators are expected to search for an efficient solution (or an equitable distribution in a zero-sum bargain) rather than to split the difference, and if bargaining costs are high, FOA could easily ‘encourage’ more bargaining and more costs than conventional arbitration does, but in this case, the result actually involves higher transactions costs. Thus, whether FOA is desirable or not depends on what bargainers expect arbitrators to do, which in turn should depend on what they actually do Bloom (1981, p. 243). Farber and Katz (1979), and Farber (1980, 1981) offer a different view of compulsory arbitration than Crawford (1979). They assume that the parties are uncertain about arbitrators’ preferences and explain that the likelihood of a bargain depends on the parties’ expectations about the arbitration award and their risk preferences. For instance, similar expectations about arbitration outcomes and significant arbitration costs can produce a contract zone, and Farber and Katz (1979) suggest that a larger the contract zone increases the probability of a bargaining settlement. Divergent expectations (for example, overly optimistic expectations by at least one party), on the other hand, can
180
Arbitration
7500
prevent successful bargaining. However, Farber and Katz (1979) conclude that uncertainty about arbitration’s outcome coupled with risk aversion on the part of at least one party, can also produce a contract zone, while greater certainty about the arbitration award, and hence less risk, may mean that no contract zone exists and arbitration results. Thus, in keeping with Stevens’ contention that arbitration should be structured to encourage negotiation, Farber and Katz (1979) express concern that uncertainty will decline as parties gain experience with arbitration, and that arbitration will become more prevalent over time (this is one variant of the ‘narcotic effect’ hypothesis discussed below). In addition, the relative impact of FOA and conventional arbitration depend on the parties’ attitudes toward risk and their expectations about arbitrator preferences, among other variables. In line with Stevens (1966), Kochan (1980) contends that FOA is more effective at imposing costs on parties if they fail to reach a negotiated settlement. After all, the expected award from FOA is a probability weighted average of two points while the expected conventional award is a probability weighted average of a distribution of potential awards, and by removing the ability of an arbitrator to compromise, the relatively low risk middle part of this distribution is removed. FOA appears to be riskier, and as Farber and Katz (1979) emphasize, uncertainty regarding the behavior of the arbitrator is a source of arbitration costs. But this reasoning is flawed (Farber, 1980; Crawford, 1982; Farber and Bazerman, 1987, 1989). For instance, Farber and Bazerman (1989) point out that the risk of FOA can be manipulated by manipulating offers, and FOA eliminates the high-risk tails of the distribution as well as the low-risk middle. Indeed, they use existing estimates of arbitration behavior, assuming constant absolute risk aversion utility functions and identical normal prior distributions on the arbitrator’s concept of an appropriate award, and conclude that contract zones are unambiguously larger under conventional arbitration than under FOA. Given that identical-expectation contract zones are relatively large, it should take a greater degree of divergent expectations to offset the potential for bargaining under conventional arbitration. Thus, if larger contract zones imply that a voluntary settlement is more likely, negotiation should be more prevalent under conventional arbitration. In contrast to the standard view, however, Bloom (1981) explains that wider contract zones do not necessarily imply a greater likelihood of successful negotiations (a point also made by Crawford, 1981). After all, there may be substantial direct costs of negotiations, as well as uncertainty about settlement points within the contract zone. Indeed, it may be easier to agree if there is one point in the contract zone that both parties prefer to arbitration than if there are a large number of alternatives. Thus, raising the costs and/or uncertainty associated with arbitration may not lead to more negotiated settlements. In this light, Farber and Bazerman’s (1989) finding of larger contract zones under
7500
Arbitration
181
conventional arbitration does not necessarily imply more negotiations, a fact that they recognize. However, they point to another of their results, contending that the best explanation for relatively more negotiated settlements under FOA, as hypothesized by Stevens (1966), comes from their finding that the expected-utility-maximizing-Nash-equilibrium last offers given to an arbitrator (where a negotiator is indifferent between the last offer and the expected arbitration award) are closer under FOA than conventional arbitration. Thus, they conclude that strategically, when equilibrium offers are farther apart the parties are more reluctant to make concessions. If this is the case, then FOA does not appear to raise the cost of arbitration, although it does influence bargaining behavior. An alternative hypothesis, apparently not found in the literature but tentatively proposed above, is that when bargaining costs are high arbitration becomes relatively attractive because arbitrators are expected to search for the efficient (or equitable) solution to a dispute rather than simply splitting the difference, and that FOA constrains such a search so FOA is less attractive (more costly) than conventional arbitration. Note that this hypothesis is consistent with recent empirical findings by Burgess and Marburger (1993) that ‘FOA awards tend to be of “low quality” in the sense that they lie outside the range of negotiated settlements’ in their study comparing baseball player salaries determined through negotiation versus those determined through FOA arbitration. Indeed, A number of empirical testable hypotheses follow from this theoretical literature, and a growing body of empirical research addresses many of them.
9. Do Arbitrators Split the Difference? The ‘split-the-difference’ assumption appears to be key to the conclusion that conventional arbitration chills negotiations (Feigenbaum, 1975; Feuille, 1975; Anderson and Kochan, 1977; Starke and Notz, 1981). In this regard, Bloom (1986) finds that on average, arbitration decisions in his sample appear to be mechanical compromises between the parties’ final offers, but he also emphasizes that there is in fact a substantial amount of unexplained variance in arbitration awards, so that the overall conclusion need not apply to any particular case. His examination of written arbitration decisions also finds a correlation between final offers and the facts in each case (a finding supported by several studies discussed below). That is, negotiators tend to adjust final offers to be consistent with the facts that arbitrators are expected to look at, as Farber (1981) suggests, and therefore arbitrators can use the parties’ final offers as a source of information about facts. Furthermore, Bazerman and Farber’s (1985) study of wage awards by 64 actual arbitrators in 25 simulated
182
Arbitration
7500
conventional arbitration cases clearly suggests that arbitrators look at both final offers and the facts of the case, weighing the facts more heavily than the offers. The facts also are increasingly important as the offers diverge, contradicting ‘the naive split-the-difference view of arbitrator behavior’ (Bazerman and Farber, 1985, p. 76). Farber and Bazerman (1986) report the results of a similar study comparing arbitrator behavior under FOA and conventional arbitration. They assume that the same criteria, determining awards based on facts rather than offers, characterizes arbitrator behavior under different arbitration schemes. Their findings support the assumption: again, conventional arbitration awards are weighted averages of the facts and offers with weights depending on the reasonableness of the offers, and final offer awards are also determined by the facts and the offers. Thus, it appears that arbitrators are generally consistent in their behavior under different arbitration regimes (Farber and Bazerman, 1986, p. 842). Ashenfelter and Bloom (1984) reach similar conclusions about the virtually identical decision processes for arbitrators under conventional arbitration and FOA, using a data sample drawn from New Jersey where public employee disputes can be decided under conventional arbitration if the parties agree to it, but FOA if they do not. Arbitrators, it seems, do much more than split the difference.
10. Does Conventional Interest Arbitration ‘Chill’ Negotiations? Despite the significant evidence that arbitrators do not simply split the difference, there does appear to be empirical evidence of a chilling effect to conventional arbitration. One source of evidence (although there is in fact no strong theoretical linkage (Currie, 1989, p. 364)), is the hypothesized ‘narcotic effect’ (Kochan and Baderschneider, 1978, p. 431) of third-party dispute resolution. It is contended that when compulsory arbitration is available parties become reliant upon it rather than negotiating. Early studies conclude that such an effect exists because, for example, wage settlements appear to be less responsive to market conditions when third-party procedures are employed (for example, Kochan and Baderschneider, 1978; Butler and Ehrenberg, 1981, and Auld, et al., 1981). Bloom and Cavanagh (1987, p. 355) point out that the simple descriptive statistics which appear to support the hypothesis are far from conclusive (also see Anderson, 1981), however, as a complete test of the hypothesis would require establishing serial correlation in the use of arbitration after controlling for heterogeneity across bargaining units. Currie (1989) provides what may be the most sophisticated empirical analysis of the ‘narcotic effect’ hypothesis to date. She finds, controlling for a number of other factors, that bargaining units who used arbitration in the
7500
Arbitration
183
previous round of negotiations are at least 10 percent more likely than other bargaining units to use it in the current round, thus supporting the narcotic-effect hypothesis. Yet, the total number of arbitrations in previous years (her sample included 35 years of compulsory arbitration by teachers in British Columbia) has a negative effect on the probability of arbitration, and variables intended to capture attitudes toward risk, changes in the degree of uncertainty associated with arbitration awards, and differing beliefs about awards do not have significant effects on the probability of using arbitration. Thus, Currie (1989, p. 378) concludes that the typical explanations for a narcotic effect do not appear to hold, so ‘A theoretical explanation of this “stylized fact [positive state dependence]”, perhaps in the context of a dynamic model of arbitration, is badly needed’. Indeed, the result is consistent with the idea suggested above that an experience with arbitration simply reveals that the net benefits of arbitration are higher than previously believed, so when the transactions costs of negotiation prove to be high, those with experience tend to opt for arbitration relatively more quickly. A very similar point is made by Bloom (1981, p. 243), when he observes that if the split-the-difference hypothesis does not hold and arbitration appears to chill negotiation it may be because ‘the parties view this mechanism [compulsory arbitration] as the least costly alternative for establishing a contract’. Of course, if this is the case, the ‘chilling’ of negotiations may well be appropriate from an efficiency perspective, and designing arbitration mechanisms to raise the cost of arbitration is inefficient (another possible explanation for increasing relative use of arbitration might be that union leaders perceive an increasing probability of breach of fair representation lawsuits in light of the perceived increases in the propensity to litigate in the United States, leading union officials to pursue more grievance arbitration in cases that they would prefer to negotiate in the absence of this perceived threat). There is yet another set of studies that probably provides the strongest evidence of a potential chilling effect of conventional arbitration: the growing literature comparing negotiation under FOA and conventional arbitration. It appears that FOA increases the probability of a negotiated settlement (Feuille, 1975; Neale and Bazerman, 1983; Farber and Bazerman, 1989). Thus, Stevens (1966), Farber and Katz (1979), and others who suggest that the nature of the arbitration process influences the likelihood of a bargained outcome appear to be correct. But does this support the contention that arbitration should be structured to encourage negotiation or that FOA is desirable? The answer still depends on the relative costs and benefits of negotiated and arbitrated settlements, as Bloom (1981) suggests. In this regard, the evidence of arbitrator behavior, including evidence from the FOA literature, is instructive. Some characteristics of arbitration behavior have already been discussed, such as the fact that they apparently do not split the difference. However, in order to fully
184
Arbitration
7500
appreciate the reasons for this and other characteristics of arbitrator behavior, we must first look at the arbitrator selection process.
11. How are Arbitrators Selected? Many critics of arbitration and other forms of ADR contend that these private alternatives to litigation will be biased. The proposed reasons for such bias vary, however. Some contend that arbitrators are easily corruptible, so the bias is in favor of the disputant with the most financial resources: ‘If the rendering of verdicts is to be independent of the relative wealth of the litigants, then the provision of judicial services naturally requires separation of the decision-makers gain from that of each litigant. This fact either requires heavy regulation or it requires public provision of the judge directly’ (Mabry, et al., 1977, p. 83). A different bias is seen by Landes and Posner (1979, p. 254) who contend that ‘it might seem that competition would lead to an optimal set of substantive rules and procedural safeguards. But this is incorrect. The competition would be for plaintiffs, since it is the plaintiff who determines the choice among courts having concurrent jurisdiction of his claim. The competing courts would offer not a set of rules designed to optimize dispute resolution but a set designed to favor plaintiffs regardless of efficiency’. Brunet (1987, pp. 31-40) simply concludes that arbitration’s procedures bias results away from ‘quality’, ‘accurate’ results because they do not incorporate as much information as litigation does (Currie, 1994, makes a similar point except that she focuses on the relative use of information in arbitration and negotiation, and she is much more tentative in her normative conclusions). Essentially, he sees ADR procedures as too ‘informal, ambiguous, and not administered in a managerial fashion’ and lacking effective discovery processes (Brunet, 1987, pp. 31-33). All such arguments involve a failure to recognize the potential for creating an arbitrator selection process to avoid such biases. Indeed, as Bloom and Cavanagh (1986, p. 409) explain, ‘one of the most important characteristics of arbitration systems is that they may be designed in different ways’. Not surprisingly, arbitration selection mechanisms actually vary widely. For example, within some organizations a single arbitrator or panel is appointed for a set period to arbitrate all disputes between members. Of course, prescreening occurs because these arbitrators are chosen from a competitive pool by the association through its membership approved selection process. For instance, in the diamond industry, arbitrators are elected from the organization’s membership for two year terms (Bernstein, 1992, pp. 124-125). A different alternative is that contracting parties or organizations preapprove a list of arbitrators, and if a dispute arises, an arbitrator is chosen from the list by some preset mechanism (for example, random selection, rotating selection, selection
7500
Arbitration
185
by a third party such as a governing board of the association). Yet another common selection system gives the parties to a dispute the resumes of odd numbered list of arbitrators from a larger preselected group (for example, preselected by a trade association, or provided by the AAA), with each party having the power to successively veto names until one remains. Thus, a second level of prescreening is added at the disputant level, contributing ‘to the legitimacy of the arbitrator and his award in the eyes of the parties’ (Bloom and Cavanagh, 1986, p. 409). The parties are also given the arbitrator’s résumés, so they know about experience, training, the nature of awards given in the past, and so on. A similar practice, the subject of Bloom and Cavanagh’s (1986) empirical study discussed below, is also common: the parties are given a list and résumés of seven potential arbitrators with the power to veto three and rank the other four, and the arbitrator who is not vetoed by either party and has the highest combined rank is chosen. Another common practice is for both sides of the dispute to provide a list of, say, six arbitrators, and each can then veto any or all of the names on the other party’s list; if all names are vetoed each provides another list and the process is repeated (clearly, this procedure requires that both parties want to arbitrate, so they do not continue to provide unacceptable names). All such systems guarantee the appointment of an arbitrator without requiring explicit agreement by the two parties while still allowing for prescreening of the potential arbitrators. In light of the fact that selection mechanisms allow veto, each party might be expected to support at least some candidates that are expected to be unbiased. In fact, it is widely contended that arbitrators are chosen for their expertise, reflected by their experience and training, as well as for their consistency in deciding cases solely on their merits, and for their impartiality (for example, Elkouri and Elkouri, 1985), but before Bloom and Cavanagh’s (1986) study, little statistical evidence existed to verify this. They examine the selection of arbitrators for 75 public employee disputes in New Jersey. A number of findings are of interest. First, in many cases the union and the employer have similar rankings, suggesting that their preferences for arbitrator characteristics are at least moderately similar. Second arbitrators with perceived biases tend to be eliminated. Thus, arbitrators that exhibit a tendency over time to favor labor are given poorer rankings (generally vetoed) by management and vice versa. Similarly, economists get low rankings by labor, relative to lawyers and labor relations practitioners, perhaps because ‘economists are likely to be heavily influenced by efficiency conditions’ (Bloom and Cavanagh, 1986, p. 418) such as the advantages of competition, mobile labor, and other factors that labor unions tend to undermine. Third, both employees and employers show significant preferences for experience, controlling for impartiality and training. Clearly, while it is not possible to prove that experience reflects arbitratorspecific characteristics such as expertise, it probably does because experience both adds to expertise and is a reflection of past popularity. Fourth, while a
186
Arbitration
7500
number of variables representing impartiality, experience and training appear to be significant, their magnitudes are small, suggesting ‘that the parties are relatively indifferent to many of the arbitrators in the New Jersey system’ (Bloom and Cavanagh, 1986, p. 419). It would appear that the preselected group of 70 arbitrators that each panel of seven in this sample is drawn from are actually perceived to be quite similar. As Ashenfelter (1987) explains, this is precisely what should be expected.
12. Conclusions: ‘Exchangeability’ and the Benefits of Arbitration Given that disputants have the same information about arbitrators and the power to veto any arbitrators that are expected to be biased (Ashenfelter, 1987) explains that arbitrator decisions should be statistically ‘exchangeable’. Furthermore, a number of independent empirical studies tend to verify this exchangeability hypothesis (for example, Ashenfelter and Bloom, 1984; Bazerman and Farber, 1985; Farber and Bazerman, 1986; Ashenfelter, 1987; Bloom, 1986; Faurot and McAllister, 1992; Burgess and Marburger, 1993). Consider for example, Faurot and McAllister’s (1992) study of salary arbitration in major league baseball. They hypothesize that an arbitrator will attempt to base decisions on the same criteria with the same weights as other arbitrators in order to avoid being vetoed, and find that the expected value of the arbitrator’s notion of a fair settlement is significantly influenced by a number of fact-based variables specified in the contract (the Basic Agreement): player performance in the last year, career performance and consistency, recent club performance, and previous compensation (Faurot and McAllister, 1992, p. 710; also see Burgess and Marburger, 1993). Furthermore, while some evidence might appear to suggest that arbitration is biased, a careful examination generally reveals the opposite. For instance, Ashenfelter (1987, pp. 343-345) discusses a sample of New Jersey’s FOA system for police disputes in which the employers win only about a third of the decisions. However, both conventional arbitration and FOA are used in this system, so they can be compared. Recall the evidence discussed above that arbitrators choose conventional awards using a consistent criteria based on the facts, and that FOA arbitrators use the same criteria, choosing the final offer closest to their preferred award. In this light, Ashenfelter (1987) compares conventional and FOA awards and finds that on average, union offers were more reasonable than the employee offers (perhaps because union bargainers were more risk averse, or perhaps because employers were making unreasonable offers for political reasons), so the disproportionate number of union wins reflects bargaining positions, not arbitrator bias, and is actually consistent with the exchangeability hypothesis. He also examines a set of data
7500
Arbitration
187
from the Iowa FOA system for public employees where, in contrast to New Jersey, the employer offers were more frequently chosen, but in this case it appears that the employers’ offers were, on average, the ‘more reasonable’. It is exchangeability, Ashenfelter (1987, p. 341) suggests, that underlies the continued acceptability of labor arbitration systems. Indeed, given the political influence of unions and bureaucratic organizations (Benson, 1995b), it is hard to imagine that compulsory arbitration statutes could survive if they were not perceived by both parties to be beneficial relative to alternatives (strikes, lockouts, litigation, negotiation when transactions costs are high). The view in the commercial arbitration literature that arbitration is a positive-sum process appears apply to compulsory labor arbitration as well. The private sector is responding to the demand for resolution of a wide variety of disputes by offering a wide variety of specialized dispute resolution options. Specialization has desirable consequences in the production of most goods and services. It is reasonable to expect that this is also true for the production of justice. Indeed, many of the efficiency-based arguments against arbitration (for example, that it will produce ‘low quality’ biased judgments, that it cannot efficiently produce precedent) are undermined by the flexibility of arbitration and other ADR options. Furthermore, while there is evidence that appears to support some arguments against at least some arbitration, such as the hypothesis that its availability raises the transactions costs of negotiation, it appears that the evidence is also consistent with other hypotheses. Thus, the evidence to date does not provide strong reasons to be discouraged by the fact that arbitration is being substituted for litigation and legislation.
Acknowledgements I wish to thank Barry Hirsch, Brad Smith, Stephen Ware, Lisa Bernstein, and an anonymous referee for very helpful comments.
Bibliography on Arbitration (7500) Allison, John R. (1990), ‘The Context, Properties, and Constitutionality of Nonconsenual Arbitration: A study of Four Systems’, 1 Journal of Dispute Resolution, 1-101. Anderson, John C. (1981), ‘The Impact of Arbitration: A Methodological Assessment’, 20 Industrial Relations, 129-148. Anderson, John C. and Kochan, Thomas A. (1977), ‘Impasse Procedures in the Canadian Federal Service’, 30 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 282-301. Ashe, Bernard F. (1983), ‘Arbitration Finality: Myth or Reality?’, 38 Arbitration Journal, 42-51.
188
Arbitration
7500
Ashenfelter, Orley (1987), ‘Arbitration Behavior’, 77 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 342-346. Ashenfelter, Orley and Bloom, David E. (1983), ‘The Pitfalls in Judging Arbitrator Impartiality by Win-Loss Tallies Under Final-Offer Arbitration’, 34 Labor Law Journal, 534-539. Ashenfelter, Orley and Bloom, David E. (1984), ‘Models of Arbitrator Behavior: Theory and Evidence’, 74 American Economic Review, 111-124. Auerbach, Jerold S. (1983), Justice Without Law?, New York, Oxford University Press. Auld, D.A.L., Christofides, L.N., Swidinsky, R. and Wilton, David A. (1981), ‘The Effect of Settlement Stage on Negotiated Wage Settlements in Canada’, 34 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 234-244. Bazerman, Max H. and Farber, Henry S. (1985), ‘Arbitrator Decision Making: When are Final Offers Important?’, 39 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 76-89. Benson, Bruce L. (1989), ‘The Spontaneous Evolution of Commercial Law’, 55 Southern Economic Journal, 644-661. Benson, Bruce L. (1990a), ‘Customary Law with Private Means of Resolving Disputes and Dispensing Justice: A Description of a Modern System of Law and Order Without State Coercion’, 9 Journal of Libertarian Studies, 25-42. Reprinted as ‘Law and Order Without State Coercion’, in Veljanovski, Cento (ed.) (1991), Regulation, Regulators and the Market, London, Institute of Economic Affairs, 159-179. Benson, Bruce L. (1990b), The Enterprise of Law: Justice Without the State, San Francisco, Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy. Benson, Bruce L. (1992a), ‘Market Failure versus Government Failure in the Production of Adjudication’, in Bowman, Gary W., Hakim, Simon and Seidenstat, Paul (eds), Privatizing the United States Justice System: Police, Adjudication, and Corrections Services from the Private Sector, Jefferson, NC, McFarland & Co., 203-225. Benson, Bruce L. (1992b), ‘Customary Law as a Social Contract: International Commercial Law’, 2 Constitutional Political Economy, 1-27. Benson, Bruce L. (1995a), ‘An Exploration of the Impact of Modern Arbitration Statutes on the Development of Arbitration in the United States’, 11 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 479-501. Benson, Bruce L. (1998a), ‘Arbitration in the Shadow of the Law’, in Newman, Peter (ed.), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law, London, Macmillan Press; New York, Stockton Press. Benson, Bruce L. (1998b), ‘Evolution of Commercial Law’, in Newman, Peter (ed.), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law, London, Macmillan Press; New York, Stockton Press. Benson, Bruce L. (1998c), ‘Law Merchant’, in Newman, Peter (ed.), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law, London, Macmillan Press; New York, Stockton Press. Benson, Bruce L. (1998d), ‘How the SECEDE in Business Without Really Leaving: Evidence of the Substitution of Arbitration for Litigation’, in Gordon, David (ed.), Secession, State, and Liberty, New Brunswick, New Jersey, Transaction Publishers. Benson, Bruce L. (forthcoming), ‘Law Without the State: The Merchant Courts of Medieval Europe’, in Beito, David T. (ed.), Voluntary City: New Directions for Urban America, Oakland, California, Independent Institute.
7500
Arbitration
189
Berger, Klaus P. (1994), ‘Aufgaben und Grensen der Parteiautonomie in der Internationalen Wirtschaftsscheidsgerichtsbarkeit’, 40 Recht der Internationalen Wirtschaft, 12-18. Berman, Harold J. and Dasser, Felix J. (1990), ‘The “New” Law Merchant and the ‘Old’: Sources, Content, and Legitimacy’, in Carbonneau, Thomas E. (ed.), Lex Mercatoria and Arbitration: A Discussion of the New Law Merchant, New York, Dobbs Ferry, Transnational Juris Publications, 21-36. Bernstein, Lisa (1992), ‘Opting Out of the Legal System: Extralegal Contractual Relations in the Diamond Industry’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 115-157. Bernstein, Lisa (1996), ‘Merchant Law in a Merchant Court: Rethinking the Code’s Search for Immanent Business Norms’, 144 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1765-1821. Bloom, David E. (1980), ‘Customized Final-Offer: New Jersey’s Arbitration Law’, 103 Monthly Labor Review, 30-33. Bloom, David E. (1981), ‘Is Arbitration Really Compatible with Bargaining?’,20 Industrial Relations, 233-244. Bloom, David E. (1986), ‘Empirical Models of Arbitrator Behavior Under Conventional Arbitration’, 68 Review of Economics and Statistics, 578-585. Bloom, David E. and Cavanagh, Christopher L. (1986), ‘An Analysis of the Selection of Arbitrators’, 76 American Economic Review, 408-422. Bloom, David E. and Cavanagh, Christopher L. (1987), ‘Negotiation Behavior Under Arbitration’, 77 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 353-358. Brinig, Margaret F. (1995), ‘Why Can’t a Woman be More Like a Man? Or Do Gender Differences Affect Choice?’, in Simon, Rita J. (ed.),Neither Victim nor Enemy, Lanham, MD, University Press of America. Brunet, Edward (1987), ‘Questioning the Quality of Alternate Dispute Resolution’, 62 Tulane Law Review, 1-23. Burgess, Paul L. and Marburger, Daniel R. (1993), ‘Do Negotiated and Arbitrated Salaries Differ Under Final-Offer Arbitration?’, 46 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 548-559. Butler, Richard and Ehrenberg, Ronald (1981), ‘Estimating the Narcotic Effect of Public Sector Impasse Procedures’, 35 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 3-20. Casella, Alessandra (1992), ‘Arbitration in International Trade’, 721 Center for Economic Policy Research Discussion Paper, London. Charny, David (1990), ‘Nonlegal Sanctions in Commercial Relationships’, 104 Harvard Law Review, 373-467. Chen, J.C. (1992), ‘Code, Custom, and Contract: the Uniform Commercial Code as Law Merchant’, 27 Texas International Law Journal, 91-135. Cohen, Julius H. (1921), ‘The Law of Commercial Arbitration and the New York Statute’, 31 Yale Law Journal, 147-160. Crawford, Vincent P. (1979), ‘On Compulsory Arbitration Schemes’, 87 Journal of Political Economy, 131-160. Crawford, Vincent P. (1981), ‘Arbitration and Conflict Resolution in Labor-Management Bargaining’, 71 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 205-210. Crawford, Vincent P. (1982), ‘Compulsory Arbitration, Arbitral Risk and Negotiated Settlements: A Case Study in Bargaining Under Imperfect Information’, 49 Review of Economic Studies, 69-82.
190
Arbitration
7500
Currie, Janet (1989), ‘Who Uses Interest Arbitration? the Case of British Columbia’s Teachers, 1947-1981', 42 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 363-379. Currie, Janet (1994), ‘Arbitrator Behavior and the Variance of Arbitrated and Negotiated Wage Settlements’, 12 Journal of Labor Economics, 29-40. David, René (1985), Arbitration in International Trade, Deventer, The Netherlands, Kluwer Law and Taxation Publishers. Denenberg, Tai Schneider, and Denenberg, R.V. (1981), Dispute Resolution: Settling Conflicts Without Legal Action, New York, Public Affairs Committee, Inc. Domke, Martin (1984), Domke on Commercial Arbitration. Revised Edition by Wiker, Gabriel M., Willmette, Ill., Gallaghen & Co. Elkouri, Frank and Elkouri, Edna Asper (1985), How Arbitration Works, Washington, DC, Bureau of National Affairs, Inc. Farber, Henry S. (1980), ‘An Analysis of Final Offer Arbitration’, 24 Journal of Conflict Resolution, 683-705. Farber, Henry S. (1981), ‘Splitting-the-Difference in Interest Arbitration’, 35 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 70-77. Farber, Henry S. and Bazerman, Max H. (1986), ‘The General Basis of Arbitration Behavior: An Empirical Analysis of Conventional and Final-Offer Arbitration’, 54 Econometrica, 819-844. Farber, Henry S. and Bazerman, Max H. (1987), ‘Why is there Disagreement in Bargaining?’, 77 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 347-352. Farber, Henry S. and Bazerman, Max H. (1989), ‘Divergent Expectations as a Cause of Disagreement in Bargaining: Evidence from a Comparison of Arbitration Schemes’, 104 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 99-120. Farber, Henry S. and Katz, Harry C. (1979), ‘Interest Arbitration, Outcomes, and the Incentives to Bargain’, 33 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 55-63. Faurot, David J. and McAllister, Stephen (1992), ‘Salary Arbitration and Pre-Arbitration Negotiation in Major League Baseball’, 45 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 697-710. Feigenbaum, Charles (1975), ‘Final Offer Arbitration: Better Theory than Practice’, 14 Industrial Relations, 311-317. Feuille, Peter (1975), ‘Final Offer Arbitration and the Chilling Effect’, 14 Industrial Relations, 302-310. Gibbons, Robert (1988), ‘Learning in Equilibrium Models of Arbitration’, 78 American Economic Review, 896-912. Holzhauer, Rudi W. and Teijl, Rob (1988), ‘Geschillenbeslechting als economisch alternatief (Dispute Settlement as Economic Alternative)’, in Snijders, H.J., et al. (eds),Overheidsrechter gepasseerd, Arnhem, Gouda Quint, 489-499. Horwitz, Morton J. (1977), The Transformation of American Law, 1780-1860, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Jones, William C. (1956), ‘Three Centuries of Commercial Arbitration in New York: A Brief Survey’, 33 Washington University Law Quarterly, 193-221. Kerkmeester, Heico O. and Mulder, R.V. De (1988), Overheidsrechter Gepasseerd (Theoretical Decisionmaking Criteria in Settling a Legal Dispute by a Third Party), Arnhem, Gouda Quint.
7500
Arbitration
191
Kochan, Thomas A. (1980), ‘Collective Bargaining and Organizational Behavior Research’, in Staw, B. and Cummings, L. (eds), Research in Organizational Behavior, Vol. 2, Greenwich, CT, JAI Press. Kochan, Thomas A. and Baderschneider, Jean (1978), ‘Dependence on Impasse Procedures: Police and Firefighters in New York State’, 31 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 431-449. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1979), ‘Adjudication as a Private Good’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 235-284. Lazarus, Steven, Bray, John J., Jr, Carter, Larry L., Collins, Kent H., Giedt, Bruce A., Holton, Robert V., Jr, Matthews, Phillip D. and Willard, Gordon C. (1965), Resolving Business Disputes: The Potential for Commercial Arbitration, New York, American Management Association. Lew, Julian D.M. (1978), Applicable Law in International Commercial Arbitration: A Study in Commercial Arbitration Awards, Dobbs Ferry, New York, Oceana Publications. Long, Gary and Feuille, Peter (1974), ‘Final-Offer Arbitration: Sudden Death in Eugene’, 27 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 186-203. Lucas, Malcolm M. (1987), ‘The Future of Arbitration’, 42 Arbitration Journal, 55-59. Mabry, Rodney H., Ulbrich, Holly H., Macauley, Hugh H., Jr and Maloney, Michael T. (1977), An Economic Investigation of State and Local Judiciary Services, Washington, DC, National Institute of Law Enforcement and Criminal Justice, Law Enforcement Assistance Administration. MacNeil, Ian R. (1992), American Arbitration Law, New York, Oxford University Press. Mentschikoff, Soia (1961), ‘Commercial Arbitration’, 61 Columbia Law Review, 846-869. Milgrom, Paul R., North, D. and Weingast, B. (1990), ‘The Role of Institutions in the Revival of Trade: The Law Merchant, Private Judges, and the Champagne Fairs’, 2 Economic and Politics, 1-23. Murray, John S., Rau, Alan Scott and Sherman, Edward F. (1989), Processes of Dispute Resolution: the Role of Lawyers, New York, Westbury, The Foundation Press. Neale, Margaret A. and Bazerman, Max H. (1983), ‘The Role of Perspective Taking Ability in Negotiating Under Different Forms of Arbitration’, 36 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 378-388. Odiorne, George S. (1953), ‘Arbitration Under Early New Jersey Law’, 8 Arbitration Journal, 117-125. Odiorne, George S. (1954), ‘Arbitration and Mediation Among the Early Quakers’, 9 Arbitration Journal, 161-169. Phalon, Richard (1992), ‘Privatizing Justice’, Forbes, 126-127. Posner, Richard A. (1986), ‘The Summary Jury Trial and Other Methods of Alternative Dispute Resolution: Some Cautionary Observations’, 53 University of Chicago Law Review, 366-393. Pruitt, Gary (1982), ‘California’s Rent-a-Judge Justice’, 5 Journal of Contemporary Studies, 49-57. Ray, Larry (1992), ‘Privatization of Justice’, in Bowman, Gary W., Hakim, Simon and Seidenstat, Paul (eds), Privatizing the United States Justice System: Police Adjudication, and Corrections Services form the Private Sector, Jefferson, NC, McFarland & Co. Rubin, Edward L. (1995), ‘The Nonjudicial Life of Contract: Beyond the Shadow of the Law’, 90 Northwestern University Law Review, 107-131.
192
Arbitration
7500
Rubin, Paul H. (1994), ‘Growing a Legal System in the Post-Communist Economies’, 27 Cornell International Law Journal, 1-47. Shavell, Steven (1995), ‘Alternative Dispute Resolution: An Economic Analysis’, 24 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-28. Smith, Joseph H. (1961), Colonial Justice in Western Massachusetts, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Starke, Frederick A. and Notz, William W. (1981), ‘Pre- and Post-Intervention Effects on Conventional vs. Final Offer Arbitration’, 24 Academy of Management Journal, 832-850. Stevens, Carl M. (1966), ‘Is Compulsory Arbitration Compatible with Bargaining?’, 5 Industrial Relations, 38-52. Sturges, Wesley A. (1930), A Treatise on Commercial Arbitrations and Awards, Kansas City, Vernon Law Book Company. Trakman, Leon E. (1983), The Law Merchant: The Evolution of Commercial Law, Littleton, Colo., Fred B. Rothman and Company. Ware, Stephen J. (1996), ‘Employment Arbitration and Voluntary Consent’, Cumberland School of Law Working Paper, Birmingham, AL, Samford University. Willoughby, William F. (1929), Principles of Judicial Administration, Washington, DC, Brookings Institute. Wittman, Donald A. (1986), ‘Final Offer Arbitration’, Management Science, 1551-1561. X (1979a), ‘Conference: ‘Private Alternatives To the Judicial Process. Proceedings of a Seminar Sponsored by the Liberty Fund and Administered by the Law and Economics Center of the University of Miami School of Law’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 231-415. X (1979b), ‘Seminar: Process Private Alternatives to the Judicial’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 231-418.
Other References Aranson, Peter H. (1986), ‘Economic Efficiency and the Common Law: A Critical Survey’, in Graf von der Schulenberg, J.-Mathais and Skogh, Goran (eds), Law and Economics and the Economics of Legal Regulation, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Press, 51-84. Axelrod, Robert (1984), The Evolution of Cooperation, New York, Basic Books. Benson, Bruce L. (1995b) ‘Understanding Bureaucratic Behavior: Implications from the Public Choice Literature’, 8 Journal of Public Finance and Public Choice, 89-117. Benson, Bruce L. (1996), ‘Uncertainty, the Race for Property Rights, and Rent Dissipation due to Judicial Changes in Product Liability Tort Law’, 8 Cultural Dynamics, 333-351. Berman, Harold J. (1983), Law and Revolution: The Formation of Western Legal Tradition, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Coase, Ronald (1960), ‘The Problem of Social Cost’, 3 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-44. De Alessi, Louis and Staaf, Robert J. (1991), ‘The Common Law Process: Efficiency or Order?’, 2 Constitutional Political Economy, 107-126. Ellickson, Robert C. (1991), Order Without Law: How Neighbors Settle Disputes, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Fuller, Lon (1964), The Morality of Law, New Haven, Conn., Yale University Press. Fuller, Lon (1981), The Principles of Social Order, Durham, NC, Duke University Press.
7500
Arbitration
193
Klein, Benjamin and Leffler, Keith (1981), ‘The Role of Market Forces in Assuring Contractual Performance’, 89 Journal of Political Economy, 615-641. Klein, Daniel B. (ed.) (1997), Reputation: Studies in the Voluntary Elicitation of Good Conduct, Ann Arbor, MI, University of Michigan Press. Kreps, David (1990), ‘Corporate Culture and Economic Theory’, in Alt, James and Shepsle, Kenneth (eds), Perspectives on Positive Political Economy, New York, Cambridge University Press. Kronman, Anthony T. (1985), ‘Contract Law and the State of Nature’, 1 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 5-32. Priest, George L. (1977), ‘The Common Law Process and the Selection of Efficient Rules’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 65-82. Rizzo, Mario J. (1980a), ‘Law Amid Flux: The Economics of Negligence and Strict Liability in Tort’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 291-318. Rizzo, Mario J. (1980b), ‘The Mirage of Efficiency’, 8 Hofstra Law Review, 641-658. Rubin, Paul H. (1977), ‘Why is the Common Law Efficient?’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 51-64. Schelling, Thomas C. (1963), The Strategy of Conflict, London, Oxford University Press. Williamson, Oliver E. (1979), ‘Transaction-Cost Economics: The Governance of Contractual Relations’, 22 Journal of Law and Economics, 233-261. Williamson, Oliver E. (1983), ‘Credible Commitments: Using Hostages to Support Exchange’, 83 American Economic Review, 519-540. Williamson, Oliver E. (1991), ‘Economic Institutions: Spontaneous and Intentional Governance’, 7 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 159-187. Wooldridge, William C. (1970), Uncle Sam, The Monopoly Man, New Rochelle, New York, Arlington House.
7600 CLASS ACTIONS - REPRESENTATIVE PROCEEDINGS Charles Silver Cecil D. Redford Professor University of Texas Law School © Copyright 1999 Charles Silver
Abstract A class action is a representational lawsuit that binds all persons with related claims, including those who were not parties to the proceeding. The procedure enables parties and court systems to enjoy certain benefits that are lost when claims are heard separately. These include reduced litigation costs per claimant, cost-internalization, and improved litigation incentives. The procedure generates these benefits by eliminating the need for collective action and giving class counsel control over claims held by non-parties. Because market discipline is lacking and judges regulate class actions inappropriately, this transfer of control entails serious risks of agency failure and opportunism that are often dealt with inadequately. The contemporary challenge is to reform the procedure in ways that preserve its advantages while reducing its risks and costs. JEL classification: K41 Keywords: Class Action, Consolidation, Representative Litigation, Collective Action, Agency Costs
1. Introduction Most litigation is representative in nature because it is handled by agents, typically though not always attorneys, who advocate and otherwise act on the parties’ behalf. Ordinarily, parties hire their agents directly, using market pressures and contracts to encourage good performance and to mitigate the risks and costs that are predicted to beset any relationship of principal and agent (Stiglitz, 1987). In a percentage of the cases, judges appoint attorneys in the absence of market transactions. This happens mainly when a party is a child, an incompetent, or a person in need of charity. It also happens in certain situations where bargaining impediments prevent lawyers and clients from coming to terms despite perceived opportunities for mutual gain or systemic
194
7600
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
195
needs to aggregate claims. The class action is the paradigm of judicial appointment of representation in this situation. Numerically, class actions make up a small part of an average court’s civil docket. Of the 272,027 civil lawsuits filed in all federal district courts in the United States in 1997, only 1,475 or one-half of one percent were class actions. If all 647 authorized judgeships had been filled, federal district court judges would have received an average of only two new class actions apiece in 1997 (Administrative Office of the United States Courts, 1997). Though comparatively rare, class actions are disproportionately important. They consume far more of judges’ time than other civil suits. Judges have been estimated to spend eleven times as many hours on certified class actions and twice as many hours on non-certified class actions as they do on non-class civil cases (Willging, Hooper and Niemic, 1996). Because class actions also involve far more claimants than other civil suits, these judicial investments can yield enormous economies of scale. Class actions brought to remedy economic harms often encompass thousands or even millions of consumers. Personal injury class actions can also be quite large, especially those that attempt to resolve claims held by persons who may become ill in the future. When judges’ time is amortized across claimants, the economy of the class action is revealed (Bernstein, 1978). Class actions also involve unusually large financial stakes. A study of securities class actions reported that the 105 lawsuits in its sample for 1995 generated settlements averaging US$10,619,174 and totaling US$1,115,013,250 (Martin et al., 1996). Many personal injury class actions have generated settlement funds or settlement offers of US$100,000,000 or more. In 1998, a single antitrust class action yielded a proposed settlement in excess of US$1,000,000,000. Not all class actions seek money damages. Many are brought to achieve social, political, or legal reforms. Targets of reform lawsuits include mainly public and private institutions, such as school districts, large employers, manufacturing plants, welfare agencies, prisons and legislatures, whose operation affects large numbers of individuals. Given their potential to transfer massive amounts of wealth and to reorganize important institutions, it should surprise no one that class actions are politically controversial. Although the federal rule that governs the conduct of these lawsuits in the United States retains the basic structure it received in 1966, there have been many attempts to reform the rule and to reduce the rate at which class actions are brought. Statutes now restrict prisoner class actions, securities cases, consumer cases and lawsuits by legal aid organizations that receive public support. Federal common law also deals with matters like subject matter jurisdiction, notice, and attorneys’ fees in ways that make class actions more difficult to bring.
196
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
7600
Reflecting the importance of class actions, the scholarly literature discussing them is enormous. The history of the procedure, which has its roots in England, its trunk in the United States, and new branches in other countries, has been carefully studied (Yeazell, 1987). Developments in the case law are followed closely. A large and growing empirical literature studies trends in filings, dismissals, settlements, and fee awards (Alexander, 1991; Garth, Nagel and Plager, 1988; Hensler et al., 1985; Martin et al., 1996; Rosenfield, 1976; Willging, Hooper and Niemic, 1996b). The impact of class actions on issuers of securities and securities markets has also been studied (Strahan, 1998; Bohn and Choi, 1996). Finally, a literature emphasizing microeconomics and game theory considers normative justifications for class actions, examines agency problems that arise in them, and suggests avenues for reform (Coffee, 1987b, 1995; Hay, 1997a; Macey and Miller, 1991; Perino, 1997; Rosenberg, 1984, 1987).
A. Legal Basics: What a Class Action is and How One Works 2. The Class Action is a Representational Device, Not a Joinder Device The class action is a procedural device that expands a court’s jurisdiction, empowering it to enter a judgment that is binding upon everyone with covered claims. This includes claimants who, not being named as parties, would not ordinarily be bound. A class-wide judgment extinguishes the claims of all persons meeting the class definition rather than just those of named parties and persons in privity with them, as normally is the case. Judges and scholars sometimes treat the class action as a procedure for joining absent claimants to a lawsuit rather than as one that permits a court to treat a named party as standing in judgment on behalf of them. This is a mistake (Hutchinson, 1983). Class members neither start out as parties nor become parties when a class is certified.
3. How a Class Action Commences A named party begins the process of having a class recognized by filing a pleading in which a class is preliminarily described. Later, a named party files a motion for certification. The motion refines the class definition and requests entry of an order allowing a class action to proceed. In theory, a named plaintiff can ask to have a class of plaintiffs or of defendants certified, and a named defendant has the same two options. In practice, requests by named plaintiffs to certify plaintiff classes greatly outnumber all
7600
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
197
other requests. Defendant classes comprise fewer than 1 percent of all certified class actions, and named defendants rarely ask judges to certify classes of any kind (Willging, Hoper and Niemic, 1996b). A named plaintiff who seeks to stand in judgment for a class is called a putative or actual class representative, depending upon whether the motion for certification has been granted. An attorney appointed to act for a class is called class counsel. Usually, the attorney representing the named plaintiff is appointed class counsel in the order that certifies the class. A person who is not a named party but who falls within a class definition is called an absent class member or an absent plaintiff.
4. The Certification Decision For a lawsuit to proceed on behalf of a class, a judge must certify that certain criteria are met. The named plaintiff must be a member of the class. It must be impracticable for the named plaintiff to join all absent plaintiffs to the lawsuit as named parties. Common questions of law or fact must connect the named plaintiff’s claims with those of the absent plaintiffs. The named plaintiff must also be a typical claimant who, having no significant conflicts of interests with the absent plaintiffs and being assisted by competent counsel, can be relied upon to represent adequately all members of the class. These criteria are repetitive and overlapping. At least one of the following additional criteria must also be met to secure class certification. There must be a risk that an opposing party will be subject to multiple, duplicative, or inconsistent obligations unless a class is certified. There must be a chance that an absent claimant’s ability to protect his interests will be impaired unless a class is certified. The defendant must have subjected all class members to a common practice or course of conduct, justifying a class-wide grant of declaratory or injunctive relief. Or, questions of law or fact common to all class members’ claims must predominate over any individual questions that may arise and the class action must be superior to other available procedures for handling the block of complaints. Judges certify common question class actions far more often than they find any other criteria apply. Approximately two-thirds of all certified class actions fall into the common question category (Willging, Hooper and Niemic, 1996b), which is used for all manner of economic harm cases, including securities and insurance fraud and other deceptive trade practices. These cases typically involve large numbers of claimants who incurred small losses and require mainly evidence about the conduct of defendants (Issacharoff, 1997).
198
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
7600
The law encourages judges to decide certification motions ‘as soon as practicable’ (Federal Judicial Center, 1995). Even so, judges usually decide dispositive substantive motions first. A plaintiff who prevails on a substantive motion will find the chances for certification greatly improved (Willging, Hooper and Niemic, 1996b). Judges also frequently consider class certification and settlement at the same time. This occurs in about one-third of all lawsuits where classes are certified (Willging, Hooper and Niemic, 1996b).
5. Post-Certification Procedures Certification usually triggers additional procedures that are specific to class actions. In common question cases, absent plaintiffs are entitled to notice of the lawsuit and to an opportunity to exclude themselves from it. They also may appear in the lawsuit if they wish. When certification and settlement occur concurrently, absent plaintiffs are entitled to notice, to a complete description of the settlement including attorneys’ fees and expenses that may be paid, to file objections, and usually to exclude themselves. Any settlement that is proposed also must be judicially approved for a judgment to bind all class members. A class action that has been certified for all purposes proceeds toward trial much as any other lawsuit does, and trial rates for certified class actions are comparable to those for other civil suits (Willging, Hooper and Niemic, 1996). The named plaintiff uses ordinary discovery tools to gather information about the merits of class members’ claims. Admissions and dispositive motions are used to remove factual and legal issues from dispute and to identify any remaining factual issues that must be tried. At the trial itself, the named plaintiff must offer evidence sufficient to prove all elements of his individual claim and to support favorable findings on all class-wide issues, including damages (Issacharoff, 1991). The stakes being larger in class actions than conventional lawsuits, the parties devote greater effort to these matters and incur greater expense, but the differences are matters of degree not of kind. Settlement rates for certified class actions also are generally comparable to those for conventional lawsuits, with securities class actions settling more frequently than class actions involving other complaints (Martin et al., 1996; Willging, Hooper and Niemic, 1996b) . Empirical studies have not borne out the charge, often heard in policy discussions, that a judge’s decision to certify a class forces even an innocent defendant to surrender (Priest, 1997). As explained above, judges must review and approve class action settlements after giving absent plaintiffs notice and an opportunity to object. Historically, objections have been infrequent. Few absent plaintiffs take the
7600
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
199
trouble to attend fairness hearings. More file written objections, but the number who write in also is small. As might be predicted, these meager efforts rarely prevent settlements from proceeding. In the past, judges approved without alteration 90 percent of all proposed class settlements to which objections were filed (Willging, Hooper and Niemic, (1996b). Recently, certain abusive or allegedly collusive class action settlements have received widespread press coverage and extensive academic scrutiny (Coffee, 1995a; In Camera, May-June 1993, July-August 1993; Koniak, 1995; Koniak and Cohen, 1996). As a result, judges, who are charged to act as guardians for absent class members, have begun to examine settlements more closely. They have paid special attention to proposed settlements that resolve immature claims of personal injury, that offer class members coupons or discounts instead of cash, or that abridge the right of dissenting class members to opt out. Although these settlements are not impermissible per se (Miller and Singer, 1998), they often signal that class counsel and a settling defendant colluded to the detriment of a class.
B. The Basic Microstructure of the Class Action 6. Separation of Ownership from Control Class actions contain far more class members than class representatives. Consequently, most of the economic value of a class action is attributable to absent plaintiffs’ claims. If a single class representative were to sue on behalf of ninety-nine absent plaintiffs with identical claims, the absent plaintiffs collectively would account for 99 percent of the value of the case. Because representatives with minority interests manage class actions, it is useful to think of classes as litigation groups in which ownership and control of assets are in different hands (Jensen and Meckling, 1976). In this respect, classes resemble stock companies, mutual funds, and innumerable other economic undertakings in which investors play relatively passive roles (Coffee, 1998; Shapiro, 1998; Silver and Baker, 1998). Seeing this resemblance, judges have subjected named plaintiffs to fiduciary duties like those that customarily apply to managers of other enterprises. Judges have also subjected class counsel to fiduciary duties. From an economic perspective, this makes sense. The regulation and incentivizing of counsel affects the likely success of class actions far more than anything having to do with named plaintiffs. As explained, a named plaintiff holds a tiny fraction of the entire economic interest possessed by a class. Often, a named plaintiff’s claim is far too small to justify the expense of litigation, and it is always too small to motivate a named plaintiff to invest resources at
200
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
7600
a level that is optimal for a class. By comparison, class counsel’s interest is usually far larger. Counsel is paid on a contingent basis an amount that reflects the value of the relief recovered by the entire class. In most cases, the fee is a fraction - between 20 and 40 percent - of the common fund (Lynk, 1990, 1994; Martin et al., 1996; Willging, Hooper and Niemic, 1996). Because class counsel holds the largest single stake, it is not surprising that class counsel is the primary decision-maker and the moving economic force in class litigation (Kane, 1987; Miller, 1998). The concentration in class counsel’s hands of economic interest and managerial control accounts both for the attractiveness of class action lawsuits and the risks associated with them. The attraction derives from the possibility of placing a large block of claims, including many that may be too small individually to warrant conventional lawsuits, under the control of someone who is in a position to maximize their value. The risks derive from the possibility that control will be abused for the benefit of the agent in charge.
7. Comparing Class Actions and Other Group Lawsuits Class actions are involuntary or nonconsensual group lawsuits. They begin and, for practical purposes, end without class members’ consent. Other group lawsuits are consensual. They involve multiple clients all of whom contract for representation with the same attorneys. Small voluntary groups greatly outnumber large ones, but entrepreneurial attorneys have built enormous groups with tens of thousands of plaintiffs by using mass-marketing techniques and by actively working referral markets (Resnik, Curtis and Hensler, 1996; Silver and Baker, 1997; Spurr, 1988). Entrepreneurial lawyers play the same role in large voluntary group lawsuits that organizers play in other collective actions (Hardin, 1982). They also use the same techniques as organizers to reduce their costs. For example, they use existing associations, such as labor unions, trade associations, and homeowner groups, to recruit individual plaintiffs and to serve as representative plaintiffs. Still other group lawsuits straddle the consensual/non-consensual divide. These lawsuits are called consolidations. Consolidation occurs when pending cases are routed to a single court for coordinated management. Usually, this occurs when lawsuits involve common facts. For example, claims arising out of airplane crashes, explosions, and other disasters are frequently consolidated. The perception is that such cases can be processed efficiently in tandem (Steinman, 1995a, 1995b).
7600
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
201
Consolidations begin consensually. Plaintiffs employ attorneys and authorize them to file lawsuits. Thereafter, plaintiffs lose control. Judges frequently consolidate cases at defendants’ request and over plaintiffs’ objections. In effect, they force together plaintiffs who would rather remain apart. In federal multi-district litigation, a consolidation order may transfer cases to distant jurisdictions where plaintiffs’ chosen lawyers rarely practice. Judges then subject transferred cases to the control of managing committees. These consist of several lawyers who are selected to handle most tasks for all plaintiffs, including the preparation of master complaints and motions, discovery and settlement negotiations. These lawyers receive supplemental compensation, usually as a result of judicial orders entitling them to shares of other lawyers’ fees (Resnik, Curtis and Hensler, 1996; Silver, 1991b). From an economic perspective, all three kinds of group lawsuit can be analyzed in similar terms. In all, control is separated from ownership and placed in the hands of lawyers with large financial interests. From a practical perspective, however, the three cases differ. When litigation groups form voluntarily, plaintiffs use contracts to govern them. They select attorneys, set their compensation, allocate responsibility for expenses, establish procedures to govern individual and group-wide decision making, create incentives to keep the collective action going, and otherwise take care of the group’s constitutional needs. They also waive conflicts of interests, retain withdrawal rights, and can fire attorneys who perform poorly (Silver and Baker, 1997). By contrast, class actions and consolidations are created by regulation. Judges form them and decide how they will operate. Class actions and consolidations thus operate outside the reach of market forces. Absent plaintiffs cannot fire their appointed representatives when they are dissatisfied with their performance. They cannot sell their interests or join new groups when they disagree with fundamental strategies or decisions, as shareholders in publicly traded corporations can. Nor can they rely on anything analogous to the takeover market to police inefficient management of their claims. Consequently, agency problems can be far more serious in class actions and consolidations than in voluntary group suits (Silver and Baker, 1998; Silver, 1991b).
C. Advantages of Aggregation Litigation groups offer plaintiffs several important advantages. These include economies of scale in litigation costs, greater leverage in settlement negotiations, and conservation of defendants’ assets, all of which can increase plaintiffs’ recoveries.
202
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
7600
8. Economies of Scale Group lawsuits enable plaintiffs to reduce litigation costs per capita by sharing the burden of litigation services that can be used by many plaintiffs. Plaintiffs who sue individually must separately pay for legal and factual investigations, for representation at trial and in settlement negotiations, and for litigation support services such as document preparation, expert witness testimony, and computer simulations. A group of plaintiffs need pay for these services only once, the services being non-rival goods insofar as members of the group are concerned. Plaintiffs who sue together also gain by taking advantage of the specialization of labor when performing tasks such as monitoring counsel’s performance, answering interrogatories, and attending hearings and depositions. By assigning these tasks to claimants who can best handle them, performance can be improved and savings generated that make all plaintiffs better off than they would be if each were responsible for performing every task.
9. Enhanced Bargaining Leverage Most group lawsuits settle. Bargaining power is therefore as important in group lawsuits as in conventional cases. In theory, plaintiffs can often gain leverage in settlement negotiations by joining forces. This happens, most straightforwardly, because groups of plaintiffs will often find it rational to litigate more intensively than individuals. The impact of economies of scale on bargaining power is clearest when individual claims are too small to justify the expense of litigation. In this situation, claims pressed by individual plaintiffs have little settlement value because plaintiffs cannot make credible threats to try their cases. By comparison, the threat value, and therefore the settlement value, of groups of small claims may be relatively great, owing to the feasibility of trying small claims en masse. Economies of scale can increase the settlement value of large claims too. On the standard economic model of the decision to settle or sue, a plaintiff’s minimum demand falls as litigation costs rise. Because aggregation reduces plaintiffs’ litigation costs per capita, it should increase their minimum demands and, correspondingly, the settlement value of their claims. Aggregation also can increase plaintiffs’ demands by increasing the expected value of claims at trial. A claim’s expected value is partly a function of the probability that a plaintiff will prevail in a trial against a defendant. In turn, the probability of winning is a function of the level and quality of litigation support services obtained. If members of plaintiff groups
7600
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
203
save money by sharing the cost of non-rival litigation services, they can afford to purchase more services or services of better quality than plaintiffs who sue by themselves. They can thereby raise the expected value of their claims at trial and improve their prospects in settlement. This may explain why class members have won sizeable settlement payments on claims that failed to generate payments in conventional cases. The class action can bring ‘compensation and closure’ to persons who are otherwise poorly served by the tort system (Tidmarsh, 1998). Even when plaintiffs sue separately, their fortunes often intertwine. Plaintiffs’ attorneys share information about trials and settlements. Factual findings, legal rulings, and verdicts in decided cases inform assessments of the settlement value of cases yet to be resolved (Hensler and Peterson, 1993). Predictably, these connections between separate lawsuits give defendants an edge in litigation. A defendant facing a test case knows that the stakes are greater than just the amount likely to be won by the litigating plaintiff. The amount paid in settlement or lost at the trial of the test case will affect the value of claims held by other plaintiffs who are waiting in the wings. The defendant may therefore find it rational to invest far more in the lawsuit than the litigating plaintiff’s claim alone would warrant. Manufacturers of tobacco products maintained an unbroken record of success in personal injury litigation for four decades by outspending the opposition. When claim values intertwine, a defendant almost certainly will find it economically rational to outspend an attorney who represents a single client. Ordinarily, a plaintiff’s attorney’s fee is a percentage of the client’s recovery Clermont and Currivan (1978). This compensation arrangement gives an attorney no incentive to spend even an amount equal to the expected value of the plaintiff’s claim, the expected fee being far smaller. By itself, the possibility that the trial or settlement of a test case may affect the value of other plaintiffs’ claims will not induce the attorney to spend more. Unless other plaintiffs or their attorneys agree to share litigation expenses, these external effects will be ignored. Aggregation brings the parties’ stakes more nearly into balance and improves the incentives of plaintiffs’ counsel as well. When all claimants participate or are represented in a single lawsuit, the defendant’s exposure is the sum of the expected values of all the claims (or the defendant’s total assets, whichever is less). As a group, the plaintiffs’ stake is the same amount. The investment incentives are still unequal because the attorney representing the plaintiff group stands to earn only a fraction of the plaintiffs’ recovery, usually one-third (Martin et al., 1996). Even so, the plaintiffs’ attorney can credibly threaten to invest significant resources in litigation services that, from the plaintiffs’ perspective, are joint goods. If, as
204
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
7600
seems likely, litigation investments have declining marginal value, the threat to spend heavily will give the defendant pause. Group counsel’s predominant financial interest is and must be the economic force that drives group litigation. The expectancy of receiving a fee that far exceeds the typical class member’s recovery motivates attorneys to make the enormous financial commitments these lawsuits require and to incur the correlative risks. Even so, the size of counsel’s interest has sparked political controversy. Because counsel’s interest dwarfs that of all but the largest class members, for example, institutional investors in securities fraud cases, it often seems that group lawsuits have more to do with paying attorneys than compensating victims. From an economic perspective, this imbalance is not a source of concern. Attorneys who manage large litigation groups are not distinguishable from managers of widely held companies or mutual funds. It would be foolish to limit a manager’s compensation to the amount any individual investor earns in a given period. It would be equally unreasoning to limit class counsel’s fee to the amount recovered by the largest claimant. Such a limitation would undermine counsel’s incentive to invest. This would harm group members, not help them. Of particular concern to a defendant facing a group lawsuit is the possibility that a single trial will adjudicate its entire liability. Ordinarily, a defendant can handle risk far more easily than a plaintiff can. The plaintiff will have an undiversified risk of loss associated with a claim that may be his single largest asset. By contrast, the defendant will face hundreds or thousands of claims, some of which will succeed, some of which will fail, and none of which taken individually will pose a serious threat to the defendant’s solvency. In this situation, the defendant can more easily tolerate the risk of trying cases than can any individual plaintiff. Aggregation turns the tables on defendants. It puts them in the position of being rendered insolvent by a single trial (a high variance event), thereby saddling them with a large, undiversifiable risk. It also forces defendants to go to trial knowing that plaintiffs’ attorneys have strong incentives to invest. Many defendants are willing to pay large sums to avoid facing the prospect of a real trial followed by liquidation.
10. Conservation of Defendants’ Assets When a defendant’s assets (including insurance) are insufficient to cover all plaintiffs’ claims, a group lawsuit can make plaintiffs better off by conserving the defendant’s resources and preserving the going concern value of the defendant’s operations. When claims are litigated in separate forums,
7600
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
205
defendants must retain local counsel in each venue, pay experts to testify concerning the same scientific issues at each trial, suffer the expense of repetitive depositions of managerial personnel, and bear other duplicative costs. These expenditures, which can be reduced when plaintiffs sue in a single proceeding, consume resources, making them unavailable for transfer to plaintiffs. The value of a defendant’s assets also can be diminished when a defendant’s business is liquidated piecemeal rather than as a unit, so that the value of the operation as a going concern is lost. Speaking less than strictly, competing plaintiffs participate in an n-person Prisoner’s Dilemma. If each strives independently for a share of the defendant’s resources, the defendant’s operations will be liquidated piecemeal, going-concern value will be lost, and plaintiffs as a group will net a smaller recovery than they could have realized by keeping the defendant’s operations intact. Just as the possibility of avoiding this race to judgment supports some scholarly justifications of bankruptcy laws (Jackson, 1982), the same prospect may be said to weigh in favor of group lawsuits in cases involving limited funds.
11. A Paretian Defense of Aggregation Figure 1 The Normative Economics of Group Litigation
Figure 1 displays the basic economic logic of group litigation. Where X and Y are potential co-plaintiffs, point A represents their expected joint payoff if each sues the common defendant in a separate lawsuit. The space defined by triangle OGH contains all possible joint payoffs if X and Y combine forces and sue as a group. The smaller triangle AIJ within OGH is the set of possible payoffs from group litigation that are Pareto Superior to A. Curve
206
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
7600
CD contains all possible divisions between X and Y of the expected joint payoff from group litigation. EF is the set of possible divisions of the expected joint payoff that are Pareto Superior to A. A simple normative economic argument for group litigation is that, by joining forces and sharing costs, co-plaintiffs hope to move themselves from A to a point on EF.
12. Why Require Participation? Transaction Costs and Free-Riding Figure 1 raises an important question about non-consensual group lawsuits. Why are they permitted? When plaintiffs stand to gain by joining forces, they can be expected to form groups voluntarily. Presumptively, a plaintiff’s refusal to join a litigation group would indicate that, in the plaintiff’s opinion, any gains that may to flow from cooperation fail to offset the expected costs and risks. It is therefore reasonable to ask why class suits and consolidations should ever occur without the consent of absent plaintiffs. One answer is that class actions and consolidations facilitate mutually beneficial cooperation that is normally frustrated by the high cost of transacting. Transaction costs are a serious problem when a wrongdoer’s conduct inflicts small losses on the members of a large victim population. For example, suppose that a credit card company overcharges millions of cardholders a few dollars apiece by calculating interest incorrectly. For cardholders as a group, the loss is large enough to be worth pursuing, but no individual cardholder has an incentive to organize the group. The prospect of recovering a few dollars would not justify the time or effort even if the likelihood of winning were great. The same problem arises in injunctive cases where litigation may prevent small harms from occurring. Suppose that the members of a large population are exposed to individually small health risks when a toxic substance is disposed of improperly. A lawsuit brought to force the wrongdoer to clean up the waste would protect the entire community and be cost-justified in view of the risk. However, the expected gain to any individual will likely be too small to motivate anyone to bear the expense of organizing a community-wide lawsuit. Class action rules enable plaintiffs to avoid start-up costs that prevent litigation groups from forming. A single named plaintiff can initiate a class action on behalf of all persons with similar claims just by filing an appropriate complaint. However, in keeping with the belief that non-consensual lawsuits are permissible only when start-up costs are high, the rules permit named plaintiffs to use this gambit only when it is impracticable to join absent plaintiffs as parties voluntarily. This may be because the group’s members are numerous and geographically dispersed,
7600
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
207
because claims are too small to motivate anyone to bear the cost of locating and bargaining with potential plaintiffs, or because group members identities are unknown or change over time. By minimizing transaction costs, class action rules enable named plaintiffs to wage advantageous group lawsuits that would not otherwise be brought. Free-riding can also impede the formation of voluntary groups when the object of litigation is a non-exclusive good, that is, a good that will be available to group members and non-members alike. Structural reform lawsuits and other injunctive actions provide the best examples. Structural reforms, including improvements in public housing conditions, increased funding for public schools, and changes in hiring and promotional practices by an employer, automatically benefit everyone who suffered under prior arrangements. Consequently, potential plaintiffs may find it economically rational to free-ride on the efforts of others in these cases. If the lawsuit succeeds, the free-rider obtains the benefit without charge. If the lawsuit fails, the free-rider foregoes the benefit but avoids litigation costs, including the risk of being singled out for recrimination or retaliation by people who oppose the lawsuit. Either way, the free-rider is better off not cooperating. The exceptional case in which a free-rider’s contribution can make the difference between the success and failure of a group lawsuit occurs too rarely to worry about. Free-riding can also be a rational strategy when plaintiffs seek damages, even though a money judgment is an exclusive good. Suppose that X, who is one of one thousand claimants, believes that it is important to preserve the going-concern value of a defendant’s operations, and that X also believes that piecemeal liquidation will not occur if any group containing at least 500 claimants forms. These beliefs may lead X to regard his own participation in a litigation group as inessential and to remain apart from a group if there is any advantage to doing so. If all claimants think like X, there may be no litigation group despite the opportunity for collective gain. Opportunities to gain free information may also cause free-riding. Suppose that X and Y are both injured by the same defective product, that X sues the manufacturer, and that X invites Y to join the suit. If Y is confident that X will prosecute the lawsuit whether or not Y joins, Y may decide to let X sue alone. X’s lawsuit then will be a valuable source of information for Y. Whether X wins, recovers a substantial settlement, or loses, Y will be better able to assess the value of Y’s claim. Y may also be able to take advantage of favorable factual or legal rulings made in the course of X’s suit, as in times past the class action device enabled Y to recover under the judgment obtained by X. The possibility of capitalizing on X’s lawsuit creates opportunities for Y to gain an advantage by waiting on the sidelines.
208
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
7600
13. Non-Paretian Justifications for Non-Consensual Proceedings One also can argue for non-consensual group lawsuits on a variety of non-Paretian grounds. An obvious alternative is a Kaldor-Hicks approach on which the gains of some, be they group members or others, more than offset any losses some plaintiffs incur. The Kaldor-Hicks standard is often described as a potential Pareto improvement (Cooter and Ulen, 1988). An argument of this sort can be grounded in the desire to conserve the resources of the legal system. The claim here is that one would squander judges’ time by requiring them to process related claims individually. The force of this argument is a function of the number of claims and the extent to which they are related. The larger the number and the closer the factual and legal connection, the more society can gain through aggregation (Bernstein, 1978). This insight has spurred many efforts to consolidate related tort lawsuits, such as those arising out of occupational exposure to asbestos (Hensler et al., 1985). The judicial efficiency argument has merit when plaintiffs’ claims are large enough to justify the expense of separate lawsuits. Then, economies of scale can be gained by using a class action or a consolidation to streamline the processing of claims. When plaintiffs’ claims are small, however, the judicial efficiency argument may or may not be persuasive, depending on how it is framed. The distinctive contemporary function of the class suit is to facilitate litigation by claimants who hold small shares of a large controversy, shares that are too small to be litigated individually (Kalven and Rosenfield, 1941). By performing this service, class actions consume judicial resources that would otherwise be spared, it being irrational for individual plaintiffs to sue on their own. A single-minded concern save judicial resources would therefore cause one to oppose small-claim class actions. A slightly different and socially more appropriate concern - a desire that judges’ time be used efficiently would lead to the opposite conclusion. As explained above, certified class actions consume eleven times as many hours as conventional lawsuits, but they increase the rate at which judges can resolve claims hundreds or thousands of times, more than offsetting their marginally greater cost (Willging, Hooper and Niemic, 1996). One must also consider other social costs that would be incurred if wrongs that visit small losses on large numbers of individuals were not policed. Losses imposed on third parties are externalities that producers will ignore unless forced to account for them. By bringing widely dispersed losses home to producers, the class action discourages them from acting in ways that are socially inefficient. It forces them to consider public as well as private production costs (Rosenberg, 1984, 1987; Wright, 1969).
7600
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
209
The cost-internalization function of the class action is independent of its compensatory function and may be served when the latter cannot. Difficulties relating to the identification of class members, the measurement of their individual damages, or the cost of fine-tuning payments, may make it impossible or impracticable to restore claimants to the positions they would have come to but for the wrong. Even so, it may often be possible to deter wrongdoers by measuring aggregate social costs and imposing them on malfeasant defendants. It being as important to avoid losses as it is to compensate victims, an inability to compensate should not by itself prevent a class action from proceeding. Alternatives such as fluid class recoveries and escheat of unclaimed funds should instead be explored.
D. A Digression on the Law of Restitution 14. Why Pay Class Counsel? The preceding sections examined the propriety of drawing plaintiffs into class actions without their consent. This section considers a related issue: why require absent plaintiffs to pay attorneys they never agreed to hire? The answer may seem simple. Unless attorneys are paid to represent absent plaintiffs, they will not do so and there will be no class actions. However, in a legal system committed to freedom of contract, more must be said than this. The usual rule is that people need not pay for services they do not ask to receive. Restitution is rarely required, especially when a provider acts pursuant to a contract with another, as an attorney representing a named plaintiff does. B, who enjoys looking at A’s beautiful yard, has no duty to compensate A’s gardener. The gardener’s only right is to receive the contracted for amount from A. It has been seriously maintained that the practice of allowing class counsel to recover fees from common funds over and above the amounts they agree to accept from named plaintiffs violates the law of restitution (Dawson, 1975). The argument has not persuaded judges to abandon the practice, which is as entrenched as ever. The desire to cure unjust enrichment has led judges to permit attorneys to claim compensation in limited circumstances. Their efforts must confer benefits on non-clients. It must be infeasible or impracticable for them to bargain with non-clients in advance. And it must be difficult for them to prevent non-clients from deriving benefit from their work. These requirements often are met when an attorney brings a class action to a successful close (Silver, 1991a; see also Levmore, 1985). The restitutionary approach caps class counsel’s fee at the market rate or the size of the recovered fund, whichever is less. It allows judges to use any
210
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
7600
payment formula employed in the private market, including percentages, hourly rates, and hybrids of the two. Percentage compensation has long been the norm in common fund class actions. Federal judges began a shift to the hourly-rate based lodestar method in the 1970s, but the experience proved disappointing and most federal courts have shifted back to the percentage approach. The emerging practice is to base fee awards on an established benchmark, usually 25 percent of the recovered fund, and to use the lodestar to make small deviations from this figure in exceptional cases.
E. Disadvantages of Aggregation 15. Paretian Misfires Group lawsuits often have the potential to make litigants worse off than they would expect to be suing on their own. In Figure 1, A represents the expected joint payoff if X and Y wage separate lawsuits. A thus serves as a boundary for Paretian claims about the affects of group lawsuits, but it is not a practical boundary of any kind. It does not restrict the actual allocation of relief. Figure 1 shows this in two ways. First, OGH, the set of possible outcomes of group litigation, includes points that are Pareto Inferior to A. The darkened area to the southwest of A is the set of possible Pareto Inferior payoffs. That such points exist when plaintiffs’ claims have positive expected values in conventional litigation is not controversial. Second, OGH also includes many points that are Pareto Noncomparable to A. When a group secures relief equal to or greater than A, the fruits can be divided between X and Y in a manner that leaves one of them worse off than he or she would have been at A. Thus, X is worse off at C than at A, and Y is worse off at D than at A, even though the expected recovery from group litigation is obtained at both C and D. The rectangles AKGI and ALHJ are the sets of possible Pareto Noncomparable results. The Pareto noncomparable and Pareto inferior outcomes are more than academically interesting. There is good reason to fear they often occur. Empirical evidence shows that class actions often settle for amounts that seem small in relation to the losses claimants incur (Carleton, Weisbach and Weiss, 1996; Martin et al., 1996). Anecdotal evidence further suggests that judges frequently approve distribution plans that divide settlement funds other than in proportion to the size and strength of class members’ claims (Coffee, 1998, 1987a; Koniak, 1995).
7600
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
211
16. Agency Failures and Sub-Optimal Recoveries Whether the goal is compensation or deterrence, the importance of regulating class actions in ways that encourage attorneys to maximize the value of plaintiffs’ claims is clear. If class suits settle too cheaply or plaintiffs lose at trial more often than they should, wrongdoers will escape some of the social costs of their behaviors. Undercompensation and underdeterrence will be the results. A central thesis in the literature is that class actions often settle for too little (Coffee, 1986; Hay, 1997a). There also is evidence that defendants win class-wide trials more often than one would expect. Both results are thought to be due to agency failures that plague class actions. These failures have several sources, including defective incentives, inadequate monitoring, economic asymmetries that favor defendants, lack of market discipline, certification for settlement of classes that could not be certified for trial, and conflicts involving settlements of inventories of signed clients.
17. Defective Incentives and Opportunism The impact of fee arrangements on lawyers’ incentives has been widely studied (Clermont and Currivan, 1978; Johnson, 1980-81), and there is broad agreement that many shortcomings of class action practice can be traced to judges’ use of inappropriate fee arrangements. The lodestar fee formula, which bases compensation on time expended and hourly rates, is a primary culprit. By rewarding effort instead of results, it discourages lawyers from maximizing the value of plaintiffs’ claims and encourages sweetheart deals that make class counsel and defendants better off at absent plaintiffs’ expense (Coffee, 1986, 1995a; Silver, 1992). An ideal fee arrangement would be self-policing. It would harmonize the interests of absent plaintiffs and lawyers, making it in lawyers’ interest to prosecute class actions zealously, as duty requires. The lodestar method fails to align interest with duty. It relies on monitoring to encourage superior performance instead of incentives. A self-interested class member would want to maximize his recovery net of expenses. He would be perfectly willing to pay a larger fee when this would yield a larger expected net recovery. Otherwise, he would prefer to keep for himself money that could be transferred to his attorneys. The lodestar method does not reflect this preference. It transfers money from a class member to an attorney whenever the attorney works more, whether or not the exchange of time for money leaves the class member better off. Moreover, under the lodestar method, even a class member who
212
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
7600
profits from a forced transaction may have a valid complaint. Work by the hour can be done poorly or well, and class members may find it advantageous to pay far more for the latter than the former. Suppose a class could offer a lawyer $1000 for an hour of top-quality work that would increase its expected recovery by $5000 or $200 for an hour of mediocre work that would yield an expected return of $201. Both transactions would leave class members better off, but they would rationally prefer a surplus of $4000 to a surplus of $1. Unfortunately, the lodestar prevents class members from choosing between these exchanges. By holding compensation per hour constant, it motivates a lawyer to perform at the lowest quality level sufficient to generate the stipulated fee. The conventional wisdom is that class members often lose by exchanging money for time when the lodestar method is employed. When a judge decides which hours will be compensated and the hourly rate exceeds a lawyer’s opportunity cost, a lawyer’s incentive is to bill as many hours as a judge is likely to allow. For example, suppose that a lawyer with an opportunity cost of $150 per hour expects a judge to authorize payment at $200 per hour for up to 1000 hours of work. It would be irrational for the lawyer to charge for less than the full 1000 hours. Any time diverted from the class action to other matters would cost the lawyer $50 an hour. The incentive to bill the entire 1000 hours will exist even if the last 100 hours contribute nothing of value to the class. In the example just described, the lawyer could do even better by committing fraud. If the lawyer spent 900 hours on the class action, billed the class for 1000, and spent the 100 hours saved on other cases, the lawyer would gain an additional $15,000 by working on the other cases. Thus does the lodestar method encourage lawyers to falsify billing records and create a related need for monitoring. Unfortunately, if also understandably, in most class actions no one is likely to monitor class counsel closely or well. Judges are reluctant to make careful evaluations of fee records, expenses and lawyers’ activities, especially in the absence of serious complaints from absent plaintiffs. The task is subjective, arbitrary and time-consuming. Absent plaintiffs also lack incentives to bear the cost monitoring entails, and they confront the logic of collective action as well. Scholars have proposed many improvements on the lodestar method, the simplest of which is increased use of contingent percentage compensation arrangements and decreased use of the lodestar. Unfortunately, certain ways of applying the percentage-based approach share the lodestar’s defects because they too sever the connection between reward and return. When class actions settle, attorneys are always paid in cash but absent plaintiffs sometimes receive discount coupons or other in-kind relief (Miller and
7600
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
213
Singer, 1998). The economic value of this relief is difficult to gauge, especially when coupons are not actively traded. To help judges assign the relief a value and justify their requested fees, plaintiffs’ attorneys offer experts’ assessments. Often, these are based on assumptions about utilization rates that are wildly optimistic. Coupon settlements typically benefit class members far less than experts predict (Borenstein, 1996; In Camera, May-June 1993, July-August 1993). By weakening or severing the connection between fees and results, the lodestar method and coupon settlements create opportunities for ‘sweetheart deals’ that are good for defendants and class counsel but bad for absent plaintiffs. Suppose that class counsel expects to win a judgment for $10 million at trial, $2.5 million of which will be paid to counsel as fees. Now suppose the defendant, who privately agrees with the $10 million estimate, offers coupons worth $5 million in settlement of class members’ claims and an additional $3 million in fees. By making the offer, the defendant can save $2 million. By accepting the offer, class counsel can gain $500,000. The loss comes at the expense of class members whose recovery net of fees fall from $7.5 million to $5 million. Not knowing that the negotiators think the case is worth $2 million more, the judge is likely to go along with the deal, especially when expert testimony inflating the value of the coupons is offered. An alternative to the coupon deal is an early settlement at a low price. Suppose a defendant who expects to lose $20 million at trial offers $10 million in settlement, including $3 million in fees, shortly after the complaint is filed. The defendant also threatens to litigate aggressively if the offer is declined. Class counsel will find the offer attractive. Why risk $3 million in fees today in order to win a somewhat larger amount, say, $5 million, two years from now after an expensive fight? If the lawyer has not logged hours sufficient to justify a $3 million fee, announcement of the settlement can be delayed, allowing time for more discovery. A third type of sweetheart deal expands the class definition or broadens the release to make a settlement more valuable for a defendant. When settling, a defendant naturally wants to free itself from liability to the fullest possible extent. To accomplish this, a defendant may ask class counsel to bring additional claimants into a class or to release claims a class was not asserting. For example, a defendant may want to include personal injury claimants in the settlement of a property damage class action, or a defendant may want claims released over which other courts have exclusive jurisdiction. In return, the defendant will offer a small fee increase that, from class counsel’s perspective, will be an unearned bonus (Coffee, 1995a). A fourth type of sweetheart deal uses a reversion to make a defendant’s obligation appear larger than it is. A defendant promises to make a large fund available, say, $20 million, subject to the condition that funds not
214
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
7600
claimed by class members revert to the defendant. The attorneys’ fee is then based on the $20 million. Because claim rates in class actions tend to be low, the defendant is likely to keep a good deal of its money and the attorneys’ fee per dollar of relief actually received by class members is likely to be high. Percentages that vary inversely with settlement size also discourage lawyers from maximizing claim values. Suppose that a lawyer would receive 30 percent of the first $10 million won by a class, 25 percent of the second $10 million, and 20 percent of the third $10 million. Now suppose the defendant offers $20 million in settlement but that class counsel thinks the case is worth $30 million. To reject the offer, class counsel must be willing to risk $5.5 million in fees to win an additional $2 million. On the reasonable assumptions that the higher dollars are riskier than lower dollars, the gamble will attract only risk-preferring attorneys. As a group, plaintiffs’ attorneys are risk-averse. Consequently, they must be paid more to recover risky dollars than dollars that are easy to come by. They must also be paid more in large cases that require great financial commitments and that entail risks that are hard for plaintiffs’ attorneys to diversify. A good fee arrangement would therefore vary directly with the amount of the recovery rather than inversely to it, increasing the fee percentage at the margin as the recovery grows (Stock and Wise, 1993). Such an arrangement would also partially offset the declining marginal value money has for attorneys, a problem of great importance in cases where hundreds of millions or billions of dollars in damages are at stake. A final but fundamental incentive-related shortcoming derives from the possibility of parallel litigation, which prevents class counsel from obtaining a property right in a certified class action. To appreciate this problem, it must be understood that the first class action to settle moots all other similar class actions and that only the attorney handling the settled case is likely to earn a fee. Suppose that two class actions alleging the same violations and brought on behalf of the same individuals are filed in separate courts against the same defendant. Now suppose the defendant makes two low-ball settlement offers, one in each case, subject to the condition that when either offer is accepted the other lapses. Unless the plaintiffs’ attorneys handling the cases collude, a race to settle is likely to occur because only the attorney who accepts first will be paid. To make matters worse, collusion is nearly impossible. If both attorneys reject the low-ball offer, the defendant can simply find a third lawyer, offer him the deal, and agree to settle a class action filed by that lawyer. For collusion to work, it must involve all plaintiffs’ lawyers, an impossibly large coalition.
7600
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
215
It may seem unlikely that a defendant would search for an attorney to represent a class. Yet the phenomenon has happened often enough to have a name: the reverse auction (Coffee, 1995a). The name reflects the defendant’s desire to find the attorney who will sell it immunity from litigation at the lowest price. In a reverse auction, the low bidder gets the sale.
18. Inadequate Monitoring No incentive arrangement can wholly eliminate opportunities for agents to benefit at principals’ expense. It is therefore important for principals to monitor agents. In class actions, absent plaintiffs are unlikely to monitor class counsel as carefully as they should. Monitoring by absent plaintiffs may also lead to undesirable results when it occurs. For these reasons, judges have a duty to examine how class actions are handled. Unfortunately, even they miss many instances of opportunism. There are only four candidates for the job of monitor in a class action: the defendant, the named and absent plaintiffs, the presiding judge, and third parties, such as uninvolved attorneys, who may keep track of the case. The defendant can be ruled out immediately. A party that stands to gain from class counsel’s opportunistic acts cannot be trusted to police them. Nor are named plaintiffs necessarily good monitors. Having chosen or been chosen by the attorneys who lead the class, named plaintiffs may too often give them the benefit of the doubt. Named plaintiffs also, and properly, benefit disproportionately from class settlements. They often receive incentive payments that are intended to compensate them for special risks and costs they incur (Krislov, 1990; Solovy, Kaster and Jiganti, 1990). The availability of these payments may color their judgment. Although harmed by opportunism, absent plaintiffs also cannot be expected to monitor class counsel efficiently. Many or most absent plaintiffs hold stakes that are too small to warrant the expense. It would be irrational to spend $100 monitoring a lawsuit in which one has a $100 interest, but to oversee class counsel effectively an investment of thousands could be required. When expected recoveries are small to begin with, as in class actions they usually are, only class members who ignore economic factors will monitor class counsel actively. Class members with sizeable claims may also be discouraged. First, they often learn that class actions are pending late in the day when settlement notices are delivered. They then face the daunting and expensive task of reconstructing events and finding signs of collusion, an undertaking in which they can expect no help from class counsel or the settling defendant. Second, an absent plaintiff who uncovers wrongdoing cannot privatize the
216
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
7600
entire return. If the size of the settlement should ultimately increase, all class members will share the gain. The private cost of monitoring may exceed the expected private gain even when the expected class-wide return would be far greater. Third, the inability to privatize returns on monitoring creates a free-rider problem within a class. When any absent plaintiff bears the cost of monitoring, all profit. Why, then, should any particular absent plaintiff bear the expense instead of free-riding on others who choose to do so? A further difficulty with relying on absent plaintiffs is that they too can be bought off. A class member who takes a special interest in a case can be made a named plaintiff by class counsel and offered an incentive bonus. Or a defendant can offer to allocate settlement benefits in a way that favors an involved class member. Because the interests of particular plaintiffs always diverge from those of others, an absent plaintiff who serves as a monitor may himself have to be watched. In theory, judges could be excellent monitors. They understand legal and factual issues better than claimants are likely to, and they are increasingly likely to have experience managing complex litigation. In practice, the quality of judicial monitoring is uneven because judges lack appropriate incentives and have limited fact-gathering capabilities. Many judges are overworked, underpaid, and subjected to strong institutional pressures to move cases along. It is unreasonable to expect them to divert time from live matters to class actions that are all but settled. Judges also have to rely on others for most of their information. Yet their usual sources class counsel and defendants - cannot be relied upon to pinpoint evidence that would scuttle a deal. To make matters worse, in many cases the data judges need to answer the crucial question - Is the money enough? - do not exist. The history of previously settled cases may be thin or no one may have collected it. Often, the most comparable cases are other settled class actions that also may be tainted. Many judges are poorly placed to serve as monitors because they are architects of the agreements they are asked to review. Often, judges structure rulings to encourage settlement negotiations, they (and the magistrates or masters they appoint) become deeply involved in the negotiation process, and they use powerful signals about future rulings to soften plaintiffs’ and defendants’ bargaining positions (Resnik, 1982; Schuck, 1986, 1987). This behavior may be motivated by a jumble of forces, including solicitude for plaintiffs facing extraordinary trial delays, pressure to clear dockets, personality quirks, and a desire for the prestige enjoyed by judges who settle big cases. Because trial judges who orchestrate settlements can be expected to approve them, the primary monitors of such settlements must appellate judges.
7600
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
217
Judicial scrutiny of fee requests is also uneven. Monitoring is crucial under the lodestar method, which encourages lawyers to inflate hours and claim excessive hourly rates. It is also tedious and time consuming (Silver, 1992; Tomkins and Willging, 1986). Judges must cast themselves as auditors and examine lawyers’ time sheets and expenses line by line. Many judges short-circuit this process. They either approve fee applications as submitted or they make rough-cut reductions. Some judges also intentionally deviate from market standards when setting hourly rates, believing that market rates are too high. Judicial monitoring is not an especially good means of policing fee-related misconduct (Coffee, 1986; Silver, 1992). Finally, consider other third parties. These may be attorneys whose clients are absent class members who object to a settlement. Or they may be public interest lawyers or public officials, such as attorneys general or consumer protection agencies. There are many cases in which third parties have become beneficially involved, but as a general matter they are in short supply. Class members usually lack incentives to get them engaged. Moreover, private lawyers can usually protect clients with large claims by opting them out. This being the cheaper course, it is the one usually taken. The participation of third parties also can raise several difficulties. First, public officials may intervene to advance political agendas or interests that have little to do with claimants’ welfare. For example, they may oppose certain kinds of lawsuits and, assuming the guise of consumer advocates, they may challenge fee awards to discourage lawyers from bringing more cases. Second, class counsel may co-opt third parties, especially lawyers representing claimaints, by making them co-counsel and offering them fees. Third, third parties may intervene solely to be bought off. There are many lawyers, colloquially referred to as ‘bottom feeders’, who use objections to extort payments. They hold up settlements unless and until class counsel offers to share fees with them, effectively paying them to withdraw. Public officials can also extort payments. They may want settling parties to place funds under their control or to assist them with other endeavors by donating services or cash. One can never be certain that third parties’ motives are pure. Because none of the available candidates has incentives to monitor appropriately, it should not be surprising that objections to proposed class settlement are both rare and rarely successful. Judges approve settlements without modification in 90 percent of the cases where objections are filed. This is true whether an objection concerns the adequacy of a settlement or a proposed award of attorneys’ fees (Willging, Hooper and Niemic, 1996b). What the statistics cannot show may be equally important. Many objections that succeed in altering or forestalling settlements may be strategic or otherwise unwarranted.
218
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
7600
19. Unresolved Economic Asymmetries Fee awards in class actions average just above one-third of the amount recovered. Rarely do they exceed 50 percent (Martin et al., 1996; Willging, Hooper and Niemic, 1996b). Many judges also reduce the size of a fee as a percentage as the size of the recovery rises (Lynk, 1990, 1994). These practices tend to tip the balance of economic power against claimant groups and in favor of defendants. As a practical matter, class members can spend only about 33 cents out of every dollar in controversy to prosecute a lawsuit. This is the amount they can offer their lawyers as fees. By contrast, defendants can spend 100 cents on the dollar or more. Judges do not control defendants’ spending. Because the amount one spends affects one’s chances of winning, free-spending defendants will predictably gain an edge over class members. This advantage should manifest itself at trial, where plaintiffs should lose relatively often, and in settlement, where bargains reflect one’s prospects at trial. Differences in ability to diversify risks and manage litigation costs should strengthen the spending advantage defendants enjoy. Plaintiffs’ attorneys practice mainly in small firms of 10 or fewer lawyers. Plaintiffs’ firms with 25 or more lawyers are exceedingly rare (Stock and Wise, 1993). Firms of this size have limited capital to invest and great difficulty diversifying large risks. For them, class actions, which require cash outlays of $500,000 on average, demand lawyer time worth far more, and take longer than conventional lawsuits to settle, can be bet-the-firm cases. To protect themselves, plaintiffs’ attorneys spend conservatively and otherwise minimize their financial commitments to class actions. They are low-cost operators because they have to be (Coffee, 1986). Defendants find class actions easier to manage. Only large businesses, governmental entities, and other well-heeled institutions are likely to be targets for class actions because only they have the resources or insurance needed to pay large judgments. But the size and wealth that make them attractive targets also enable them to tolerate and diversify litigation risks more easily than plaintiffs’ attorneys can. Being relatively wealthy, defendants usually pay lawyers to defend class actions wholly or partly on the basis of hourly rates. They also reimburse their lawyers for expenses. With their clients absorbing the costs and risks of litigation, defense lawyers have every incentive to turn class actions into protracted lawsuits and frequently do. Every motion a defense lawyer files, every discovery objection and request, every interlocutory appeal, and every other dilatory tactic forces plaintiffs counsel to consume scarce resources. The incentive to force plaintiffs’ counsel to bankrupt themselves may partly
7600
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
219
explain why class actions consume so much more of judges’ time than other lawsuits. Defendants also can take advantage of political connections that are not available to plaintiffs. For example, insurance companies faced with class actions have sought protection from insurance regulators and legislators. In effect, they have sought to cut short litigation by acting in other forums where they enjoy significant advantages. When success outside the courtroom can be a ‘silver bullet’ that puts a conclusive end to litigation, plaintiffs’ attorneys have to respond. But doing so requires more political savvy, greater financial resources and better connections than many of them possess. There are some economic asymmetries that favor plaintiffs. For example, plaintiffs who survive early dispositive motions are entitled to discovery on the merits, and defendants usually possess far more discoverable information than group members do. By requesting this information via discovery requests that are themselves inexpensive to produce, plaintiffs’ attorneys can force defendants to bear the considerable cost of locating, reviewing, and producing it. Particularly costly to defendants is lost managerial time that interrupts its business. Defendants can do little to expose group members to offsetting costs, which means that once discovery gets underway, plaintiffs possess unique leverage. Recognizing this, defendants work hard to prevent discovery from starting and, when their efforts fail, they often settle to avoid discovery costs, whatever the merits of plaintiffs’ claims may be. This threat advantage is a temporary one - it decreases in size as discovery is taken and future costs are converted to sunk costs. Its size also bears no necessary relation to the value of class members’ claims. Finally, defendants can offset plaintiffs’ leverage somewhat by producing documents and witnesses in volume. A plaintiffs’ attorney who is swamped with information may lack the resources needed to sort the wheat from the chaff.
20. Lack of Market Discipline Many of the forces that encourage agents to represent principals well in other contexts are absent from class actions and consolidations. For example, claimants have little or no power to hire or fire lead attorneys or to decide how much they will be paid. Claimants may not control the settlement decision. They cannot sell their claims when they are disappointed with counsel’s performance, as owners who are dissatisfied with managers can sell their shares. Nor in the litigation realm is there an analogue to the takeover market. Attorneys who fail to maximize the value of assets cannot easily be dethroned.
220
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
7600
Because so many market checks are missing, the quality controls that do exist must operate especially well. Primary among these are the choice of counsel itself and counsel’s compensation arrangement. As explained, the latter often misfires because judges use the lodestar method or otherwise fail to compensate counsel appropriately. It is difficult to overstate the importance of the attorney chosen to lead a litigation group. This person must marshal the resources needed to prosecute a case, see that they are used efficiently, and decide important matters of strategy. When a consensual litigation group is built via a referral market, there is reason to expect a qualified person to be given these tasks. Referring lawyers, who serve as brokers for their clients, have an interest in selecting competent lead lawyers who will maximize referral fees by maximizing claimants’ recoveries. Referring lawyers also are potential monitors and sources of future business. Lead lawyers who shirk or settle cheaply can expect criticism from referring lawyers. Lead lawyers who develop bad reputations can expect to be denied future work (Resnik, Curtis and Hensler, 1996; Spurr, 1988). When a judge selects a lead attorney, the danger is greater that an unsuitable individual will be chosen. A judge has no stake in the amount class members recover. Consequently, a judge has no particular interest in selecting a lawyer who can be expected to maximize the value of their claims. Absent a contest for control, a judge has no reason to do other than appoint the attorney who files the class action complaint. Sometimes, it is safe to assume that the attorney who files a complaint is the wrong lawyer for a class. This is true, for example, when a defendant recruits lead counsel. Defendants facing large numbers of individual claimants sometimes see the class action as a means of resolving all their legal difficulties in a single forum at a bargain price. With this goal in mind, they approach one plaintiffs’ firm after another until they find a lawyer who is willing to negotiate a cheap package deal. This is another example of the reverse auction. The law requires judges to cure the problem of inadequate lead counsel. More accurately, it permits them to allow class actions to proceed only when absent plaintiffs are adequately represented. This includes representation by adequate counsel. It is clear that judges can appoint substitute counsel when a defect of counsel is all that stands in the way of class certification. Judges are reluctant to assert this power, for several reasons. First, they rarely see lawyers they recognize as bad apples. Lawyers tend to file lawsuits in courts where they are liked and respected. They also enlist respected local lawyers as co-counsel when they are forced to litigate in unfamiliar courts. A lawyer who is a judge’s favorite or has a judge’s favorite in tow stands a high likelihood of winning appointment.
7600
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
221
Second, many judges like lawyers who are deferential and respectful and who help them by settling cases. It is unreasonable to expect these judges to prefer aggressive lawyers to passive ones. The preference for cooperative attorneys may explain why judges so often give the role of lead counsel to plaintiffs’ lawyers who negotiate settlements before seeking class certification. One study reported that ‘a proposed settlement was submitted to the court before or simultaneously with the first motion to certify’ in 49 percent of class actions certified for settlement (Willging, Hooper and Niemic, 1996b). It also may explain why judges frequently re-appoint certain prominent lawyers who are notorious for settling quickly (Tidmarsh, 1998). Third, judges are rightly concerned about denying lawyers who uncover wrongdoing the reward of serving as class counsel. Unless lawyers are compensated for time spent inventing liability theories and investigating misconduct, they will be discouraged from doing so. The privilege of being appointed class counsel and the contingent right to compensation that comes with the position maintain the incentive to police wrongdoing. Some judges have attempted to stimulate competition for the role of lead counsel and to reduce attorneys’ fees by auctioning the right to represent a class (Macey and Miller, 1991, 1993). The results have been mixed. A judge cannot sell a class action to the highest bidder, a transaction that might be predicted to identify the attorney who can derive the greatest value from a set of claims. They can auction only the right to control the class and, in the event of success, to be paid. The temptation is to sell the lead counsel position to the lawyer willing to handle a case for the smallest fee. This is a serious mistake. The cheapest lawyer is likely to be the one whose opportunity cost is lowest because he cannot attract other business. Such a lawyer would be a poor candidate to represent a class. An attorney who represents an individual client with a large stake, such as an institutional investor, would be better suited for the task. Sophisticated clients with large claims are likely to pick good lawyers. Because they can be expected to perform quality control for themselves, they can provide the same service for a class. A lawyer who represents a large number of clients with small stakes could also be a good choice. The lawyer’s success in the referral market would show that other attorneys think he or she has the ability to run a group suit. Great financial wealth, a history of committing significant resources to lawsuits, and a record of success in high-stakes litigation are also important. Judges should consider indicia of quality in addition to price. Two other quality controls that remain in most class actions are the right to object to proposed settlements and the right to opt out. These rights are not especially meaningful. Absent plaintiffs are likely to object only when the cost of objecting is less than the expected gain. The cost of making anything more than a
222
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
7600
perfunctory objection can be quite large. An absent class member must retain counsel to canvass the record, attempt discovery of class counsel, and argue against approval of a settlement in court. By contrast, the expected payoff from objecting usually is small. It is the difference between the amount being offered and the amount one might recover under a more favorable settlement or trial judgment. Because objectors rarely succeed in changing settlements, the gain is likely to be worth the cost only for plaintiffs whose claims are very large. Even they may be discouraged by the logic of collective action, which creates pressure to free-ride. In most situations, procedural rules entitle absent claimants to exclude themselves from class actions by filing opt out forms. This opt out right bears the same relation to objecting that exit bears to voice (Hirschmann, 1970). In theory, claimants could use their opt out right to guarantee themselves at least the expected value of their claims in conventional litigation (A in Figure 1). Some claimants have significantly increased their recoveries by opting out of class actions and filing conventional lawsuits (Tidmarsh, 1998). The right to opt out may be more efficacious than the right to object, but it generally means that a claimant must litigate alone rather than as part of a second class action that is more efficiently run. For plaintiffs with small claims, this is impracticable, and for plaintiffs with large claims it may be disadvantageous. The empirical findings that class members rarely opt out and that those who do so overwhelmingly have large claims and are represented by counsel are not surprising (Willging, Hooper and Niemic, 1996b). Finally, by opting out absent plaintiffs protect only themselves. Other class members remain exposed to exploitation.
21. Certification of ‘Settlement-Only’ Classes Class actions often are certified and settled at the same time. In approximately one-third of all cases where certification is granted, it is for settlement only (Willging, Hooper and Niemic, 1996b). The set of class actions that are certified for settlement contains two subsets: class actions that would be certified for trial because they meet all the criteria for certification, and class actions that would not be certified for trial because they do not meet the criteria. For shorthand, the latter will be referred to as ‘settlement-only classes’. Sell-outs are especially likely in these cases. To see why, one must understand that plaintiffs’ attorneys need defendants’ cooperation to get settlement-only classes certified. These cases do not meet the requirements for certification. Consequently, certification
7600
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
223
would be denied in these cases if defendants were to object. To obtain defendants’ acquiescence, plaintiffs’ attorneys must make concessions. The magnitude of the concession depends on the size of the fee interest putative class counsel has in the individual cases that will proceed in the absence of a class action. Assume the following: 100 individual plaintiffs will file cases; the attorney seeking to act as class counsel will represent 10 of these; each plaintiff’s case has a settlement value of $500,000; and the attorney will contract with each plaintiff for a 25 percent contingent fee. In this example, the attorney expects to earn $125,000 in fees per case times 10 cases, a total of $1.25 million. The attorney will make nothing off the remaining 90 cases because other lawyers will handle them. Clearly, a class-wide settlement of all 100 cases yielding a fee greater than $1.25 million would be better for the attorney. For example, a fee award of $2.5 million in a class action would be an increase of 100 percent. Therein lies the rub. At a rate of 25 percent, a class-wide recovery in the amount of $10 million would generate a $2.5 million fee. But a $10 million settlement would grossly undervalue the 100 claims, which would generate $50 million in winnings if tried separately. Settlement-only classes create opportunities for defendants to pay class counsel huge premiums while saving themselves enormous sums. Defendants’ opportunities to save money and to purchase class counsel’s cooperation are especially great in so-called ‘futures’ class actions. These lawsuits cover persons whose injuries are latent. For example, persons exposed to a disease-causing substance who are asymptomatic could fall within a futures class. Although many of these persons can be predicted to sue after their injuries ripen, few are likely to retain counsel during the latency period. A futures class action offers a defendant an opportunity to settle all possible claims cheaply before any symptoms appear. By offering a bribe to an attorney who is willing to serve as class counsel, a defendant can settle immature claims for pennies on the dollar.
22. Settlements of Inventories of Signed Clients Attorneys who handle class actions often have inventories of signed clients. In principle, this is good. An attorney who manages to build a client base in a litigation area where other lawyers are competing for business has convinced the market that he is a competent lawyer. The inference of quality is especially strong when an attorney has acquired clients by referral from other lawyers. Concerns arise when an attorney settles a client inventory apart from and on terms that differ from those he negotiates for a class. This is accomplished by excluding the attorney’s signed clients from the class
224
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
7600
action. For example, the class definition may cover only persons who file complaints after a certain date. If class counsel’s signed clients filed before that date, a class-wide settlement would not cover them. When a class action and a block of signed clients settle separately, there is reason to fear that one group may benefit at the other’s expense. Usually, the worry is that the signed clients will exploit the unsigned class members. A wealth transfer from the latter to the former will benefit counsel if fees in the signed clients’ cases are higher than those typically awarded in class actions. A transfer may also smooth the process of settling the client inventory by creating a surplus that can be used to buy off disgruntled clients or to reward lawyers or organizations, such as labor unions, who provided referrals (Coffee, 1995a; Koniak, 1995; Nagareda, 1996b).
23. Maximization-Related Conflicts A subject neglected in the scholarly literature on class actions is the inevitability of conflicts in the process of preparing cases for trial. Although class counsel can often advance all absent plaintiffs’ interests concurrently by supplying them with joint goods, even related claims invariably have idiosyncratic aspects that require individual attention and targeted expenditures. By devoting time and resources to these issues, class counsel neglects the interests of class members who claims lack these characteristics and who would prefer that counsel’s time and resources be spent in ways more likely to be of benefit to them (Rhode, 1982a; Silver and Baker, 1998). Resource allocations on common issues can also require inter-claimant trade-offs, and usually do. Class members with small compensatory claims, such as employees who were recently hired at discriminatorily low wages, may be best off if litigation resources are devoted mainly to the pursuit of punitive damages, pay increases and promotions. This use of resources may not appeal to class members with large compensatory claims, such as long-time employees. They may benefit most from efforts to model the impact of wage discrimination on their lifetime income and retirement plans. Other class members, such as future job applicants, may care only about new job openings. By rejecting a settlement offer, class counsel also trades off the interests of some class members against those of others. Every litigation group contains members with different attitudes toward risk, with different views on the time-value of money, and with different desires for relief. By pursuing a high-risk/high-reward approach to litigation or a low-risk/low-reward approach, class counsel necessarily decides which class members’ preferences will be favored. Class counsel does the same thing by deciding to
7600
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
225
settle for a larger amount tomorrow instead of a smaller amount today and by pressing for dollars rather than in-kind relief or symbolic vindication. Every decision to use time or money for one purpose rather than another or to adopt one litigation strategy instead of another necessarily resolves conflicts among class members’ interests. Maximization-related conflicts inhere in all class actions because there is nothing like the stock market that claimants can use to ameliorate them. Shareholders can freely and cheaply move between different companies and different investments so that their portfolios accommodate their risk preferences, attitudes toward the time value of money, and so on. Claimants cannot move from one class action to another to achieve the same result.
F. Inappropriate Settlement Allocations A recovery can be allocated equitably or inequitably. From a Paretian perspective, allocations on CE and FD in Figure 1 would be inequitable despite being efficient. They would leave some class members worse off than they would have expected to be had they sued on their own. A nascent but developing literature examines the equity of settlement allocations in class actions and other group lawsuits (Coffee 1998; Hay, 1997b; Hazard, 1995; Koniak, 1995; Menkel-Meadow, 1995; Silver and Baker, 1998). Even scholars who care mainly about deterrence agree that it is important to compensate plaintiffs fairly when that can be done at reasonable expense (Rosenberg, 1987, 1996). There is a tendency in the literature to run allocation issues and efficiency issues together. When certain claimants are shortchanged, it may be because others receive too much, because a settlement fund is too small, or because others receive too much and a settlement is was too small. The unique contribution of equity is to set standards for dividing funds, not for overall fund size.
24. Allocation-Related Conflicts Inhere In All Class Actions When it comes to dividing settlement funds, class members’ interests always conflict. In Figure 1, X and Y share an interest in moving away from A in the direction of GH, but they have opposing preferences concerning where on GH they wind up. X prefers divisions to the northwest; Y prefers divisions to the southeast. A group lawsuit is a mixed-motive game in which the interest in cooperating for mutual gain is in tension with the interest in
226
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
7600
getting as much as possible for oneself. The tension exists whether a group seeks injunctive or monetary relief. The number of ways of allocating recoveries and the conflicts they generate make clear the need for standards. If a class containing only members X and Y were to recover $1000, the entire range of options from ($1000,$0) through ($0,$1000) would be available. If member Z were added to the group, the number of possible allocations would expand exponentially. To avoid arbitrariness, judges and lawyers require normative allocation guidelines. Unfortunately, there is no widely accepted, general account of the equity of class action settlements. There are instead many assessments of particular allocations that commentators either found deficient or wished to defend. Many of these assessments rest on deeper principles of equity or distributive justice that are neither made explicit nor carefully examined. For example, a scholar may criticize an allocation plan for ignoring differences in the size and strength of claims without explaining why these differences should matter. Also missing is a cost-benefit analysis of equity. It is more expensive to pay claimants amounts that roughly reflect the size and strength of their claims than it is to engage in damages averaging and pay them equal amounts, and it is more expensive still to distribute payments that reflect fine differences between claimants (Coffee, 1987a, 1998; Silver and Baker, 1998). One therefore wants to know how much cost should be borne to obtain a marginal increase in equity. There is general agreement that the importance of equity increases with claim size. There is also a growing consensus that because class settlements yield less than $400 per claimant on average, often the game is not worth the candle. Between the extremes of large claims and small recoveries, however, there is little agreement as to how much equity is enough. This dissensus has important practical ramifications.
25. Causes of Arbitrary Allocations Class counsel and defendants design allocation plans. In effect, they serve as agenda setters, deciding which of many possible allocations are presented to courts and claimants for consideration. Like other agenda setters, they have considerable power to control outcomes. On the surface, this power may seem wasted on class counsel. Because allocation formulas do not affect the size of fee awards, class counsel might not seem to care how relief is divided. Reality is more complicated than this. Class counsel will receive no fee until a settlement is judicially approved. Approval depends, among other things, upon the judge’s views and the reaction of the class. Class counsel therefore has an interest in selecting
7600
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
227
allocations that satisfy these constituencies. Class settlements also frequently contain ‘walk away’ provisions that condition settlement on an agreed level of claimant participation. When allocating common funds, class counsel may keep the required level of participation in mind. As explained, only class members with large claims are likely to object or opt out. This is why ‘walk away’ provisions usually target large-claim plaintiffs. A rational strategy for class counsel may therefore be to over-compensate large-claim plaintiffs and to shortchange everyone else. This approach enables class counsel to mollify large-claim plaintiffs without risking a revolt by small-claim plaintiffs, who rarely complain. The desire to avoid objections can also lead to class counsel to overcompensate class members who belong to organizations. For example, an asbestos class action may include workers who are union members and workers who are not. Because a union can be an effective advocate of its members’ interests, it may contest a settlement that treats them poorly. Class counsel may therefore be inclined to involve the union in the design and administration of the settlement and to overcompensate its members. A separate dynamic can cause class members with large claims to be underpaid. The typical class contains a small number of persons with sizeable claims and a far larger number whose claims are comparatively small or weak. The latter claims may add little value to the group lawsuit, but they increase greatly the number of mouths to be fed. Unfortunately for class members with large claims, judges are reluctant to deny any subgroup of absent plaintiffs a share of settlement benefits, especially a subgroup that is large. The price of feeding everyone is that plaintiffs with large claims receive less than they should. The weak may also beggar the strong in litigation groups simply because the weak have less at stake. In bargaining situations, the player who stands to lose the most from the failure to reach an agreement can be expected to give up the most to salvage a deal. Plaintiffs with large claims have more at stake than plaintiffs with small claims, often far more. Small-claim plaintiffs can therefore take advantage of them. Risk aversion will predictably cause plaintiffs with large claims to sacrifice even more because the risks attached to large claims are harder to diversify and because large claims constitute a more sizeable portion of plaintiffs’ wealth. Defendants also may have interests in skewing allocation formulas. For example, they may want to direct as much money as possible to claimants who are current customers, suppliers, employees, or shareholders and as little as possible to others (Coffee, 1998). A plaintiffs’ attorney who is indifferent to the manner of allocation will have no reason to resist a defendant’s efforts to direct funds to its favorites.
228
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
7600
26. Possible Allocation Standards The possibility of arbitrary allocation plans makes plain the need for concrete normative guidelines. Many scholars seem to embrace a Paretian standard of equity according to which class members should receive at least the expected value of their claims in conventional litigation. This probably includes most scholars who criticize allocations that ignore factors bearing on the size and strength of claims or that take account of irrelevant factors (Coffee, 1995a; Cramton, 1995; Koniak, 1995; Menkel-Meadow, 1995). They seem to assume that size and strength have the greatest impact on claim values in conventional litigation, and they therefore conclude that when size and strength are ignored, claimants are shortchanged. The merit of the Paretian standard is that it respects the intuition that rational persons would not join litigation groups hoping to make themselves worse off than they are on their own. They would do so expecting collective action to enhance the value of their claims. There are many difficulties with the Paretian standard, however. One is that the value of claims in conventional litigation is not self-evident. It must be assigned, and the data needed to make the assessment may be unavailable. A second is that the proper baseline to begin with may not be the expected value of claims in conventional litigation. Instead, one could start with a claim’s highest expected value in any possible coalition of claimants. Needless to say, this value is not self-evident either. A third is that a commitment to Paretianism may not lead to the conclusion that allocations should reflect only the size and strength of claims. Other factors could also affect the value claims have in conventional litigation, including factors that may have nothing to do with the merits such as sex, age, race, or jury appeal. It is an empirical question which factors matter in particular cases. A fourth difficulty is that a Paretian standard does not tell one how to divide any surplus that exists above the chosen baseline. This shortcoming is especially problematic when class actions include some or solely claims that are too small to litigate individually, as most do. A fifth problem is that claimants who participate in consensual group lawsuits rarely take steps in advance to identify or protect anything that might serve as a baseline for Pareto comparisons. Most such plaintiffs do nothing to provide for the division of settlement funds. They trust their fates to the discretion of their attorneys, reserving only the right to veto settlements as a means of protecting themselves. The veto right is often more illusory than real, however, because plaintiffs rarely have independent counsel to advise them how to use it. Scholars who embrace Paretian standards must also consider how shortfalls should be dealt with. Settlements yield actual values, and actual
7600
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
229
values may be smaller than expected values even when class actions are run efficiently. When a group-wide settlement is too small to pay everyone the amount required by the Paretian baseline, some or all claimants must be shortchanged. The difficulty is in deciding which claimants and how much. Again, the number of possible allocations is exceedingly great.
27. Reform Proposals There is broad agreement that judges should change certain aspects of the way they manage class actions. For example, whether an auction, a contingent percentage or even the lodestar method is used to set fees, most scholars encourage judges to set the terms of compensation up front. Today, judges often delay this matter until class actions settle. This practice requires class counsel to devote significant economic resources to a risky venture with no formal understanding as to the expected return. It also complicates settlement negotiations by leaving an additional and sizeable matter for the negotiators to resolve. The practice also burdens class counsel with a conflict of interests by creating the possibility that an impasse over fees may block an attractive settlement on the merits. Investors in risky undertakings rarely tolerate this degree of uncertainty or conflict. They provide in advance for the division of returns, even when there may be no returns to divide. By doing so, they encourage their agents to work hard for their benefit. Judges presiding over class actions should mimic the market in this regard (Federal Judicial Center, 1995). The practice of setting fees at the end also skews fee awards downward. In hindsight, the risk of loss will naturally seem smaller than it was. It is also more difficult to award large fees when the precise amount of the fee is known. This problem disappears when fees are set before any money is offered in settlement. Another way to improve the class action to use percentage compensation instead of the lodestar method whenever possible and to increase percentages at the margin as the amount recovered rises. By offsetting risk aversion and the declining marginal value of money, this will encourage class counsel to strive for larger recoveries instead of being satisfied with smaller ones. Other reform proposals include giving class members the right to opt out of all settlements (Rutherglen, 1996), forced fee sharing between class counsel and lawyers representing clients who opt out (Coffee, 1987b), improved notice (Woolley, 1997), allowing absent plaintiffs to sue class counsel for malpractice and collusion (Koniak and Cohen, 1996), encouraging judges to decide merits issues before motions for class
230
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
7600
certification (Berry, 1980; Priest, 1997), increased use of injunctions to prevent parallel class litigation (Miller, 1996), restricting opt-out rights (Perino, 1997), and alternative fee arrangements that link counsel’s compensation to fees paid in individual representations (Hay, 1997b).
G. Conclusions 28. The Potential for Good The class action is a procedural device with extraordinary potential for good. It can force product manufacturers and service providers to take account of externalities that they would otherwise ignore, encouraging them to perform more efficiently and compensating victims who would otherwise lack remedies. It can make the procedural system operate more efficiently by enabling judges to process related claims en masse at less cost per claim. It can save claimants’ and defendants’ money by enabling both to take maximum advantage of economies of scale. It can align the stakes of defendants and claimants so that litigation investments are more nearly equal and settlement bargains better reflect the merits of claims.
29. The Potential for Bad The class action also entails important risks and dangers. Conflicts among claimants inhere in all class actions and must be resolved as cases are prepared for trial and settled. Lack of market oversight and improper judicial regulation create opportunities for class counsel and defendants to collude. This can frustrate the cost-internalization function of the class action by enabling wrongdoers to escape the social costs of their conduct. It can frustrate the compensatory function as well by shortchanging claimants. The latter can occur independently of the former as a result of improper allocation plans.
30. The Need for Dispassionate Analysis At the microeconomic level, class actions are fascinating and truly intricate. Agency problems abound, and strategies for dealing with them are often subject to counter-strategies that are difficult to plan for in advance. Compounding the problem is the fact that judges do not always understand or even care about the impact their decisions have on the microstructure of
7600
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
231
the class action. Many decisions, such as those that require individual notice in small-claim class actions and those that announce the homogeneity of injunctive class actions, are patently flawed. Politics also takes a toll, especially when it comes to lawyers’ fees, a subject of great partisan debate in the United States. If the atmosphere surrounding the class action ever cools, it may be possible to reform the device and avoid many excesses.
Acknowledgements Lynn Baker, Sam Issacharoff, John Leubsdorf, Tom Rowe and Patrick Woolley provided helpful comments on this chapter, as did an anonymous reviewer. Vanessa Pogue’s research assistance and Suzanne Hassler’s help preparing the bibliography and proofreading everything were invaluable.
Bibliography on Class Actions - Representative Proceedings (7600) Abraham, Kenneth S. (1987), ‘Individual Action and Collective Responsibility: The Dilemma of Mass Tort Reform’, 73 Virginia Law Review, 845-907. Administrative Office of the United States Courts (1997), Judicial Business of the United States Courts, Washington, DC, The Administrative Office of the United States, 386 p. Alexander, Janet Cooper (1991), ‘Do the Merits Matter? A Study of Settlements in Securities Class Actions’, 43 Stanford Law Review, 497-598. Alexander, Janet Cooper (1998), ‘Contingent Fees and Class Actions’, 47 DePaul Law Review, 347-361. Baughman, Steve (1991), ‘Class Actions in the Asbestos Context: Balancing the Due Process Considerations Implicated by the Right to Opt Out’, 70 Texas Law Review, 211-241. Bernstein, Roger (1978), ‘Judicial Economy and Class Actions’, 7 Journal of Legal Studies, 349-370. Berry, Stephen (1980), ‘Ending Substance’s Indenture to Procedure: The Imperative for Comprehensive Revision of the Class Damage Action’, 80 Columbia Law Review, 299-344. Bertelsen, Bruce I., Calfee, Mary S. and Connor, Gerald W. (1974), ‘The Rule 23(b)(3) Class Action: An Empirical Study’, 62 Georgetown Law Journal, 1123-1172. Bohn, James and Choi, Stephen (1996), ‘Fraud in the New-Issues Market: Empirical Evidence on Securities Class Actions’, 144 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 903-982. Bone, Robert G. (1990), ‘Personal and Impersonal Litigative Forms: Reconceiving the History of Adjudicative Representation’, 70 Boston University Law Review, 213-307. Bone, Robert G. (1993), ‘Statistical Adjudication: Rights, Justice, and Utility in a World of Process Scarcity’, 46 Vanderbilt Law Review, 561-662.
232
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
7600
Bone, Robert G. (1994), ‘Rule 23 Redux: Empowering the Federal Class Action’, 14 Review of Litigation, 79-112. Bordens, Kenneth S. and Horowitz, Irwin A. (1989), ‘Mass Tort Civil Litigation: The Impact of Procedural Changes on Jury Decisions’, 73 Judicature, 22–27. Bordens, Kenneth S. and Horowitz, Irwin A. (1998), ‘The Limits of Sampling and Consolidation in Mass Tort Trials: Justice Improved or Justice Altered?’, 22 Law and Psychology Review, 43-66. Borenstein, Severin (1996), ‘Settling for Coupons: Discount Contracts as Compensation and Punishment in Antitrust Lawsuits,’ 39 Journal of Law and Economics, 379-404. Brunt, Maureen and Fels, Alan (1982), ‘Economics of Class Actions: A Research Design’, in Cranston, Ross and Schick, Anne (eds), Law and Economics, Canberra, Australian National University, 1-9. Buckley, Colin Hugh (1985), ‘Note: A Suggested Remedy for Toxic Injury: Class Actions, Epidemiology, and Economic Efficiency’, 26 William and Mary Law Review, 497-543. Bundy, Stephen McG. and Elhauge, Einer Richard (1991), ‘Do Lawyers Improve the Adversary System? A General Theory of Litigation Advice and its Regulation’, 79 California Law Review, 313-420. Carleton, William T., Weisbach, Michael S. and Weiss, Elliott J. (1996), ‘Securities Class Action Lawsuits: A Descriptive Study’, 38 Arizona Law Review, 491-511. Carr, Jack and Mathewson, Frank, (1990), ‘The Economics of Law Firms: A Study in the Legal Organization of the Firm’, 33 Journal of Law and Economics, 307-330. Cerminara, Kathy L. (1998), ‘The Class Action Suit as a Method of Patient Empowerment in the Managed Care Setting’, 24 American Journal of Law and Medicine, 7-58. Clermont, Kevin M. and Currivan, John D. (1978), ‘Improving the Contingent Fee’, 63 Cornell Law Review, 529-639. Coffee, John C., Jr (1983), ‘Rescuing the Private Attorney General: Why the Model of the Lawyer as Bounty Hunter is Not Working’, 42 Maryland Law Review, 215-288. Coffee, John C., Jr (1986), ‘Understanding the Plaintiff’s Attorney: the Implications of Economic Theory for Private Enforcement of Law through Class and Derivative Actions’, 86 Columbia Law Review, 669-727. Coffee, John C., Jr (1987a), ‘The Regulation of Entrepreneurial Litigation: Balancing Fairness And Efficiency in the Large Class Action’, 54 University of Chicago Law Review, 877-937. Coffee, John C., Jr (1987b), ‘Rethinking the Class Action: A Policy Primer on Reform’, 62 Indiana Law Journal, 625-664. Coffee, John C., Jr (1995a), ‘Class Wars: The Dilemma of the Mass Tort Class Action’, 95 Columbia Law Review, 1343-1465. Coffee, John C., Jr (1995b), ‘The Corruption of the Class Action: The New Technology of Collusion’, 80 Cornell Law Review, 851-857. Coffee, John C., Jr (1998), ‘Conflicts, Consent, and Allocation after AmchemProducts - or, Why Attorneys Still Need Consent to Give Away Their Clients’ Money’, 84 University of Virginia Law Review. Coleman, Jules L. and Silver, Charles (1986), ‘Justice in Settlements’, 4 Social Philosophy and Policy, 102-144.
7600
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
233
Cooper, Edward H. (1996), ‘Rule 23: Challenges to the Rulemaking Process’, 71 New York University Law Review, 13-73. Cooter, Robert (1989), ‘Economics of Bargaining Towards a Market in Unmatured Tort Claims’, 75 Virginia Law Review, 383-411. Cooter, Robert and Ulen, Thomas (1988), Law and Economics, United States, Harper Collins Publishers, 644 p. Cox, James D. (1997), ‘Making Securities Fraud Class Actions Virtuous’, 39 Arizona Law Review, 497-524. Cramton, Roger C. (1995), ‘Individualized Justice, Mass Torts, and “Settlement Class Actions”: An Introduction’, 80 Cornell Law Review, 811-836. Dam, Kenneth W. (1974), ‘Class Action Notice: Who Needs It?’, The Supreme Court Review, 97-125. Dam, Kenneth W. (1975), ‘Class Actions: Efficiency, Compensation, Deterrence, and Conflict of Interest’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 47-73. Dawson, John P. (1974a), ‘Lawyers and Involuntary Clients: Attorney Fees from Funds’, 87 Harvard Law Review 1597-1654. Dawson, John P. (1974b), ‘The Self-Serving Intermeddler’, 87 Harvard Law Review, 1409-1458. Dawson, John P. (1975), ‘Lawyers and Involuntary Clients in Public Interest Litigation’, 88 Harvard Law Review, 849-930. Dewees, Donald N., Prichard, J. Robert S. and Trebilock, Michael J. (1981), ‘An Economic Analysis of Cost and Fee Rules for Class Actions’, 10 Journal of Legal Studies, 155-185. Dole, Richard F., Jr (1971), ‘The Settlement of Class Actions for Damages’, 71 Columbia Law Review, 971-1006. Durand, Anna L. (1981), ‘An Economic Analysis of Fluid Class Recovery Mechanisms’, 34 Stanford Law Review, 173-201. Elhauge, Einer R. (1991), ‘Does Interest Group Theory Justify More Intrusive Judicial Review’, 101 Yale Law Journal, 31-110. Estreicher, Samuel (1996), ‘Federal Class Actions after 30 Years’, 71 New York University Law Review, 1-12. Federal Judicial Center (1995), Manual (Third) for Complex Litigation, St Pauls, West Publishing, 568 p. Friedman, David (1996), ‘More Justice For Less Money: A Step Beyond Cimino’, 39 Journal of Law and Economics, 211-240. Garth, Bryant G. (1987), ‘Studying Civil Litigation Through the Class Action’, 62 Indiana Law Journal, 497-505. Garth, Bryant G., Nagel, Ilene H. and Plager, S. Jay (1988), ‘The Institution of the Private Attorney General: Perspectives from an Empirical Study of Class Action Litigation’, 61 Southern California Law Review, 353–398. Garth, Bryant G. (1992), ‘Power and Legal Artifice: The Federal Class Action’, 26 Law and Society Review, 237-271. Galanter, Marc and Cahill, Mia (1994), ‘’Most Cases Settle’: Judicial Promotion and Regulation of Settlements’, 46 Stanford Law Review, 1339-1391. George, Edward I. and Wecker, William E. (1985), ‘Estimating Damages in a Class Action Litigation’, 3 Journal of Business and Economic Statistics, 132-139.
234
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
7600
Gerard, Robert B. and Johnson, Scott A. (January 1998), ‘The Role of the Objector in Class Action Settlements: A Case Study of the General Motors Truck “Side Saddle” Fuel Tank Litigation’, 31 Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review, 409-435. Goldberg, Michael J. (1988), ‘The Propensity to Sue and the Duty of Fair Representation: A Second Point of View [Tactical Use of the Union’s Duty of Fair Representation: An Empirical Analysis]’, 41 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 456-461. Green, Eric D. (1997a), ‘What Will We Do When Adjudication Ends? We’ll Settle in Bunches: Bringing Rule 23 into the Twenty-First Century’, 44 University of California at Los Angeles Law Review, 1773-1801. Green, Eric D. (1997b), ‘Advancing Individual Rights Through Group Justice’, 30 University of California at Davis Law Review, 791-804. Gross, Samuel R. and Syverud, Kent D. (1991), ‘Getting to No: A Study of Settlement Negotiations and the Selection of Cases for Trial’, 90 Michigan Law Review, 319-393. Grundfest, Joseph A. and Perino, Michael A. (1996), ‘The Pentium Papers: A Case Study of Collective Institutional Investor Activism in Litigation’, 38 Arizona Law Review, 559-622. Hardin, Russell (1982), Collective Action, Baltimore, MD, Johns Hopkins University Press, 248 p. Hartman, Raymond S. and Doane, Michael J. (1987), ‘The Use of Hedonic Analysis for Certification and Damage Calculations in Class Action Complaints’, 3 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 351-372. Hay, Bruce L. (1996), ‘Contingent Fees and Agency Costs’, 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 503-533. Hay, Bruce L. (1997a), ‘Asymmetric Rewards: Why Class Actions (May) Settle for Too Little’, 48 Hastings Law Journal, 479-509. Hay, Bruce L. (1997b), ‘The Theory of Fee Regulation in Class Action Settlements’, 46 American University Law Review, 1429-1474. Hazard, Geoffrey C., Jr (1995), ‘The Settlement Black Box’, 75 Boston University Law Review, 1257-1272. Henderson, James A., Jr (1995), ‘Comment: Settlement Class Actions and the Limits of Adjudication’, 80 Cornell Law Review, 1014-1021. Hensler, Deborah R. (1989), ‘Resolving Mass Toxic Torts: Myths and Realities’, 89 University of Illinois Law Review, 89-104. Hensler, Deborah R. and Peterson, Mark A (1993), ‘Understanding Mass Personal Injury Litigation: A Socio-Legal Analysis’, 59 Brooklyn Law Review, 961-1061. Hensler, Deborah R., Felstiner, William L.F., Selvin, Molly and Ebener, Patricia A. (1985), Asbestos in the Courts: The Challenge of Mass Toxic Torts, Santa Monica, CA, Rand Institute for Civil Justice, 128 p. Hirschmann, Albert O. (1970), Exit, Voice and Loyalty, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 162 p. Hutchinson, Diane Wood. (1983), ‘Class Actions: Joinder or Representational Device?’, 1983 Supreme Court Review, 459-507. In Camera (May-June 1993), 16 Class Action Reports, 3:250-253. In Camera (July-August 1993), 16 Class Action Reports, 4:244-249.
7600
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
235
Issacharoff, Samuel (1991), ‘Administering Damage Awards in Mass-Tort Litigation, 10 Review of Litigation, 463, 470-80. Issacharoff, Samuel (1997), ‘Class Action Conflicts’, 30 University of California at Davis Law Review, 805–833. Jackson, Thomas (1982), ‘Bankruptcy, Non-Bankruptcy Entitlements, and the Creditors’ Bargain’, 91 Yale Law Journal, 857–907. Jensen, Michael C. and Meckling, William H. (1976), ‘Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behavior, Agency Costs and Ownership Structure’, 3 Journal of Financial Economics, 305-311. Johnson., Earl, Jr (1980-81), ‘Lawyers’ Choice: A Theoretical Appraisal of Litigation Investment Decisions’, 15 Law and Society Review, 567–610, 883-910. Kahan, Marcel and Silberman, Linda (1996), ‘Matsushita and Beyond: The Role of State Courts in Class Actions Involving Exclusive Federal Claims’, 1996 Supreme Court Review, 219–283. Kahan, Marcel and Silberman, Linda (1998), ‘The Inadequate Search for “Adequacy” in Class Actions: A Critique of Epstein v. MCA, Inc’., 73 New York University Law Review, 765-792. Kalven, Harry, Jr and Rosenfield, Maurice (1941), ‘The Contemporary Function of the Class Suit’, 8 University of Chicago Law Review, 684-721. Kane, Mary Kay (1987), ‘Of Carrots and Sticks: Evaluating the Role of the Class Action Lawyer’, 66 Texas Law Review, 385-409. Knight, Thomas R. (1988), ‘The Propensity to Sue and the Duty of Fair Representation: Reply’, 41 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 461-464. Koniak, Susan P. (1995), ‘Feasting While the Widow Weeps: Georgine v. Amchem Products, Inc.’, 80 Cornell Law Review (May), 1045-1158. Koniak, Susan P. and Cohen, George M. (1996), ‘Under Cloak of Settlement’, 82 Virginia Law Review, 10510-1280. Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1983), ‘Control of Conflicts of Interest in Class-Action Suits’, 41 Public Choice, 145-175. Kraakman, Reinier, Park, Hyun and Shavell, Steven (1994), ‘When are Shareholder Suits in Shareholders’ Interests’, 82 Georgetown Law Review, 1733-1775. Krislov, Clinton A. (1990), ‘Scrutiny of the Bounty: Incentive Awards for Plaintiffs in Class Litigation’, 78 Illinois Bar Journal, 286-290. Levmore, Saul (1985), ‘Explaining Restitution’, 71 Virginia Law Review, 65-124. Leubsdorf, John (1995), ‘Co-Opting the Class Action’, 80 Cornell Law Review, 1222-1227. Lynk, William J. (1990), ‘The Courts and the Market: An Economic Analysis of Contingent Fees in Class-Action Litigation’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 247–260. Lynk, William J. (1994), ‘The Courts and the Plaintiff’s Bar: Awarding the Attorney’s Fee in Class-Action Litigation’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 185-209. Macey, Jonathan R. (1994), ‘Judicial Preferences, Public Choice, and the Rules of Procedure’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 627-646. Macey, Jonathan R. and Miller, Geoffrey P. (1991), ‘The Plaintiffs’ Attorney’s Role in Class Action and Derivative Litigation: Economic Analysis and Recommendations for Reform’, 58 University of Chicago Law Review, 1-118. Macey, Jonathan R. and Miller, Geoffrey P. (1993), ‘Auctioning Class Action and Derivative Suits: A Rejoinder’, 87 Northwestern University Law Review, 458-470.
236
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
7600
Macey, Jonathan R. and Miller, Geoffrey P. (1995), ‘A Market Approach to Tort Reform Via Rule 23', 80 Cornell Law Review, 909-917. Marcus, Richard L. (1995a), ‘They Can’t Do That, Can They? Tort Reform via Rule 23', 80 Cornell Law Review, 858-908. Marcus, Richard L. (1995b), ‘Confronting the Consolidation Conundrum’, 95 Brigham Young University Law Review, 879-924. Marshall, Robert C., Meurer, Michael J. and Richard, Jean Francois (1994), ‘Multiple Litigants with a Public Good Remedy’, 16 Research in Law and Economics, 151-173. Martin, Denise N., Juneja, Vinita M., Foster, Todd S. and Dunbar, Frederick C. (1996), ‘Recent Trends IV: What Explains Filings and Settlements in Shareholder Class Actions?’, White Plains, NY, National Economic Research Associates, 88 p. McCoid, John C. (1976), ‘A Single Package for Multiparty Disputes’, 28 Stanford Law Review, 707-728. McGovern, Francis E. (1989), ‘Resolving Mature Mass Tort Litigation’, 69 Boston University Law Review, 659-694. Menkel-Meadow, Carrie (1995), ‘Ethics and the Settlements of Mass Torts: When the Rules Meet the Road’, 80 Cornell Law Review, 1159-1221. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1996), ‘Overlapping Class Actions’, 71 New York University Law Review, 514-546. Miller, Geoffrey (1998), ‘Class Actions’, in Newman, Peter (ed.), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law, New York, Stockton Press, Vol. 1 pp. 257–261. Miller, Geoffrey and Singer, Lori (1998), ‘Nonpecuniary Class Action Settlements’, 60 Law and Contemporary Problems, 97-155. Monaghan, Henry Paul (1998), ‘Antisuit Injunctions and Preclusion Against Absent Nonresident Class Members’, 98 Columbia Law Review, 1148-1202. Morawetz, Nancy (1996), ‘Underinclusive Class Actions’, 71 New York University Law Review, 402-438. Mullenix, Linda S. (1991a), ‘Beyond Consolidation: Postaggregative Procedure in Asbestos Mass Tort Litigation’, 32 William and Mary Law Review, 475–585. Mullenix, Linda S. (1991b), ‘Problems in Complex Litigation’, 10 Review of Litigation, 213–230. Mullenix, Linda S. (1994), ‘The Pervasive Myth of Pervasive Discovery Abuse and the Consequences for Unfounded Rulemaking’, 46 Stanford Law Review, 1393-1445. Mullenix, Linda S. (1995), ‘Class Actions, Personal Jurisdiction, and Plaintiffs’ Due Process: Implications for Mass Tort Litigation’, 28 University of California at Davis Law Review, 871-916. Nagareda Richard A. (1996a), ‘In the Aftermath of the Mass Tort Class Action’, 85 Georgetown Law Journal, 295-368. Nagareda, Richard A. (1996b), ‘Turning From Tort to Administration’, 94 Michigan Law Review, 899-981. Perino, Michael A. (1997), ‘Class Action Chaos?: The Theory of the Core and an Analysis of Opt Out Rights in Mass Tort Class Actions’, 46 Emory Law Journal, 85–161. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1981), ‘Contribution and Claim Reduction among Antitrust Defendants: An Economic Analysis’, 33 Stanford Law Review, 447-471.
7600
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
237
Priest, George L. (1997), ‘Procedural versus Substantive Controls of Mass Tort Class Actions’, 26 Journal of Legal Studies, 521-573. Rabin, Robert L. (1995), ‘Continuing Tensions in the Resolution of Mass Toxic Harm Cases: A Comment’, 80 Cornell Law Review, 1037-1044. Ratliff, Jack (1988), ‘Offensive Collateral Estoppel and the Option Effect’, 67 Texas Law Review, 63-101. Resnik, Judith (1982), ‘Managerial Judges’, 96 Harvard Law Review, 374-448. Resnik, Judith (1991), ‘Modern Civil Procedure: Issues in Controversy, from “Cases” to “Litigation”’, 54 Law and Contemporary Problems, 5-68. Resnik, Judith (1995), ‘Aggregation, Settlement, and Dismay’, 80 Cornell Law Review, 918-940. Resnik, Judith, Curtis, Dennis E. and Hensler, Deborah R. (1996), ‘Individuals within the Aggregate: Relationships, Representation, and Fees’, 71 New York University Law Review, 296-401. Rheingold, Paul D. (1968), ‘The MER/29 Story - An Instance of Successful Mass Disaster Litigation’, 56 California Law Review, 116-148. Rhode, Deborah L. (1982a), ‘Class Conflicts in Class Actions’, 34 Stanford Law Review, 1183-1262. Rhode, Deborah L. (1982b), Conflicts of Interest in Educational Reform Litigation, Project Report No. 82-A6, Stanford University, CA, Institute for Research on Educational Finance and Governance, 65 p. Robinson, Glen O. and Abraham, Kenneth S. (1992), ‘Collective Justice in Tort Law’, 78 Virginia Law Review, 1481-1519. Rosenberg, David (1984), ‘The Causal Connection in Mass Exposure Cases: A “Public Law” Vision of the Tort System’, 97 Harvard Law Review, 849-929. Rosenberg, David (1987), ‘Class Actions for Mass Torts: Doing Individual Justice by Collective Means’, 62 Indiana Law Journal, 561–596. Rosenberg, David (1989), ‘Of End Games and Openings in Mass Tort Cases: Lessons from a Special Master’, 69 Boston University Law Review, 695-730. Rosenberg, David (1996), ‘Individual Justice and Collectivizing Risk-Based Claims in MassExposure Cases’, 71 New York University Law Review, 210-257. Rosenfield, Andrew (1976), ‘An Empirical Test of Class-Action Settlement’, 5 Journal of Legal Studies, 113-120. Rowe, Thomas D., Jr (1982), ‘The Legal Theory of Attorney Fee Shifting: A Critical Overview’, 1982 Duke Law Journal, 651-680. Rowe, Thomas D., Jr (1989), ‘Study on Paths to a “Better Way”: Litigation, Alternatives, and Accommodation’, 89 Duke Law Journal, 824-902. Rowe, Thomas D., Jr (1996), ‘Beyond the Class Action Rule: An Inventory of Statutory Possibilities to Improve the Federal Class Action’, 71 New York University Law Review, 186–209. Rubin, Julie (1997), ‘Auctioning Class Actions: Turning the Tables on Plaintiffs’ Lawyers’ Abuse or Stripping the Plaintiff Wizards of Their Curtain’, 52 Business Lawyer, 1441-1467. Rutherglen, George (1996), ‘Better Late Than Never: Notice and Opt Out at the Settlement Stage of Class Actions’, 71 New York University Law Review, 258-295.
238
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
7600
Sachnoff, Lowell E. and Gilbert, Jeffrey T. (1997), ‘Auctioning the Role of Lead Counsel in Class Action Cases to the Lowest Bidder’, in Postgraduate Course in Federal Securities Law, Philadelphia, PA, Amercan Law Institute, 537-543. Saks, Michael J. (1992), ‘Do We Really Know Anything About the Behavior of the Tort Litigation System - and Why Not?’, 140 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1147-1289. Saks, Michael J. and Blanck, Peter David (1992), ‘Justice Improved: The Unrecognized Benefits of Aggregation and Sampling in the Trial of Mass Torts’, 44 Stanford Law Review, 815-851. Sappington, David E.M. (1991), ‘Incentives in Principal-Agent Relationships’, 5 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 45-66. Schuck, Peter (1986), ‘The Role of Judges in Settling Complex Cases: The Agent Orange Example’, 53 University of Chicago Law Review, 337-365. Schuck, Peter H. (1987), Agent Orange on Trial: Mass Toxic Disasters in the Court, Cambridge, MA, Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 363p. Schuck, Peter (1995), ‘Mass Torts: An Institutional Evolutionist Perspective’, 80 Cornell Law Review (May), 941-989. Schwartz, Alan (1989), ‘Commentary on “Towards a Market in Unmatured Tort Claims”: A Long Way Yet to Go’, 75 Virginia Law Review, 423-430. Schwartz, Gary T. (1994), ‘Punitive Damages and Mass Torts: A Comment’, 39 Villanova Law Review, 415-431. Schwarzer, William W. (1995), ‘Settlement of Mass Tort Class Actions: Order Out of Chaos’, 80 Cornell Law Review, 837-844. Shapiro, David L. (1998), ‘Class Actions: The Class as Party and Client’, 73 Notre Dame Law Review, 913-961. Sherman, Edward F. (1987), ‘Class Actions and Duplicative Litigation’, 62 Indiana Law Journal, 507–559. Sherman, Edward F. (1991), ‘Aggregate Disposition of Related Cases: The Policy Issues’, 10 Review of Litigation, 231 272. Siliciano, John A. (1995), ‘Mass Torts and the Rhetoric of Crisis’, 80 Cornell Law Review, 990-1013. Silver, Charles (1991a) ‘A Restitutionary Theory of Attorney’s Fees in Class Actions’, 76 Cornell Law Review, 656-721. Silver, Charles (1991b), ‘Comparing Class Actions and Consolidations’, 10 Review of Litigation, 495-520. Silver, Charles (1992), ‘Unloading the Lodestar: Toward a New Fee Award Procedure’, 70 Texas Law Review, 865-969. Silver, Charles (1993), ‘Incoherence and Irrationality in the Law of Attorneys’ Fees’, 12 Review of Litigation, 301-341. Silver, Charles and Baker, Lynn A. (1997) ‘Mass Lawsuits and the Aggregate Settlement Rule’, 32 Wake Forest Law Review, 733-780. Silver, Charles and Baker, Lynn A. (1998), ‘I Cut, You Chose: The Role of the Plaintiffs’ Attorney in Allocating Settlement Proceeds’, 84 University of Virginia Law Review, 1465-1540. Simon, William (1972), ‘Class Actions - Useful Tool or Engine of Destruction’, 55 Federal Rules Decisions, 375–394.
7600
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
239
Smith, Thomas A. (1994), ‘A Capital Markets Approach to Mass Tort Bankruptcy’, 104 Yale Law Journal, 367-434. Solovy, Jerold S., Kaster, Laura A. and Jiganti, Jeanine M. (1990), ‘The Head of the Class’, National Law Journal (August 27), 13. Spurr, Stephen J. (1988), ‘Referral Practices Among Lawyers: A Theoretical and Empirical Analysis’, 13 Journal of Law and Social Inquiry, 87-109. Steinman, Joan (1995a), ‘The Effects of Case Consolidation on the Procedural Rights of Litigants: What They Are, What They Might Be Part I: Justiciability and Jurisdiction (Original and Appellate)’, 42 University of California at Los Angeles Law Review (February), 717-836. Steinman, Joan (1995b), ‘The Effects of Case Consolidation on the Procedural Rights of Litigants: What They Are, What They Might Be Part II: Non-Jurisdictional Matters’, 42 University of California at Los Angeles Law Review (April), 967-1068. Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1987), ‘Principal and Agent’, in Eatwell, John, Milgate, Murray and Newman, Peter (eds), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, Stockton Press, New York, Vol. 3 pp. 966-972. Stock, James H. and Wise, David A. (1993), ‘Market Compensation in Class Actions Suits: A Summary of Basic Ideas and Results’, 16 Class Action Reports, 584-604. Strahan, Philip E. (1998), ‘Securities Class Actions, Corporate Governance and Managerial Agency Problems’, Federal Reserve Bank of New York, 1-41. Sugarman, Stephen D. (1985), ‘Doing Away with Tort Law’, 73 California Law Review, 555-664. Thomas, Randall S. and Hansen, Robert G. (1993), ‘Auctioning Class Action and Derivative Lawsuits: A Critical Analysis’, 87 Northwestern University Law Review, 423-457. Tidmarsh, Jay (1998), Mass Tort Settlement Class Actions: Five Cases Studies, Washington, DC, Federal Judicial Center, 100 p. Tomkins, Alan J. and Willging, Thomas E. (1986), Taxation of Attorneys’ Fees: Practices in English, Alaskan, and Federal Courts, Washington, DC, Federal Judicial Center, 145 p. Trangsrud, Roger H. (1985), ‘Joinder Alternatives in Mass Tort Litigation’, 70 Cornell Law Review, 779-849. Trangsrud, Roger H. (1989), ‘Mass Trials in Mass Tort Cases: A Dissent’, 89 University of Illinois Law Review, 69-88. Vairo, Georgene M. (1997), ‘Georgine, the Dalkon Shield Claimants Trust, and the Rhetoric of Mass Tort Claims Resolution’, 31 Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review, 79–166. Weinstein, Jack B. (1985), ‘The Role of the Court in Toxic Tort Litigation’, 73 Georgetown Law Journal, 1389-1392. Weiss, Elliott J. and Beckerman, John S. (1995), ‘Let the Money do the Monitoring: How Institutional Investors can Reduce Agency Costs in Securities Class Actions’, 104 Yale Law Journal, 2053-2127. Willging, Thomas E., Hooper, Laural L. and Niemic, Robert J. (1996a), ‘An Empirical Analysis of Rule 23 to Address the Rulemaking Challenges’, 71 New York University Law Review (AprilMay), 74-185.
240
Class Actions - Representative Proceedings
7600
Willging, Thomas E., Hooper, Laural L. and Niemic, Robert J. (1996), Empirical Study of Class Actions in Four Federal District Courts, Washington, DC, Federal Judicial Center, 200 p. Wolfman, Brian (1998), ‘Forward: The National Association of Consumer Advocates’ Standards and Guidelines for Litigating and Settling Class Actions’, 176 Federal Rules Decisions, 370-374. Wolfman, Brian and Morrison, Alan B. (1996), ‘Representing the Unrepresented in Class Actions Seeking Monetary Relief’, 71 New York University Law Review, 439-513. Wolfram, Charles W. (1995), ‘Mass Torts - Messy Ethics’, 80 Cornell Law Review, 1228-1235. Wood, Diane P. (1987), ‘Adjudicatory Jurisdiction and Class Actions’, 62 Indiana Law Journal, 597-624. Woolley, Patrick (1997), ‘Rethinking the Adequacy of Adequate Representation’, 75 Texas Law Review, 571-630. Wright, Gerald A. (1969), ‘The Cost-Internalization Case for Class Actions’, 21 Stanford Law Review, 383-419. Wright, Scott O. and Colussi, Joseph A. (1984), ‘The Successful Use of the Class Action Device in the Management of the Skywalks Mass Tort Litigation’, 52 University of Missouri at Kansas City Law Review, 141–150. X (1982), ‘Conflicts in Class Actions and Protection of Absent Class Members’, 91 Yale Law Journal, 590-614. X (1996), ‘Back to The Drawing Board: The Settlement Class Action and the Limits of Rule 23', 109 Harvard Law Review, 828-845. X (1996), ‘In-Kind Class Action Settlements’, 109 Harvard Law Review, 810-827. Yeazell, Stephen C. (1987), From Medieval Group Litigation to the Modern Class Action, New Haven, CT, Yale University Press, 306 p. Yeazell, Stephen C. (1989), ‘Collective Litigation as Collective Action’, 43 University of Illinois Law Review, 43-44. Yeazell, Stephen C. (1997), ‘The Past and Future of Defendant and Settlement Classes in Collective Litigation’, 39 Arizona Law Review, 687-704.
7700 CRIMINAL PROCEDURE Peter Lewisch Professor of Criminal and Constitutional Law University of Vienna - School of Law © Copyright 1999 Peter Lewisch
Abstract This chapter discusses the economic interpretation of pre-trial settlement and in particular of the ‘plea-bargain’, a procedural instrument aiming at the conservation of enforcement resources and providing a screening device vis-àvis the guilt of possible wrongdoers. In this respect, the paper suggests an institutional comparison with continental legal systems and an analysis of those procedural instruments employed there. Apart from the economic interpretation of pre-trial settlement, the paper presents a more encompassing institutional approach to the criminal procedure covering, inter alia, an economically based interpretation of judicial behavior, evidence, appeals, and also of procedural issues of justice. JEL classification: K40, K42 Keywords: Plea Bargain, Screening Device, Punishment Dilemma, Context Dependant Choices, Appeals, Economics of Justice
1. Introduction Criminal procedure is generally understood as that body of law governing the legal treatment of a criminal deed from the offence until an unappealable decision (acquittal or conviction). The thus defined rules describe the process, by which the guilt of a possible wrongdoer may be legitimately established and a criminal sanction attributed. These rules encompass, inter alia, the determination of factual evidence (the facts of the case in the light of a possible responsibility of a wrongdoer), the proper interpretation of the substantive law applicable to this case, and the sentencing decision, which is the determination of the sanction fitting both the crime and the criminal in the light of requirements of deterrence. Since criminal proceedings concern the attribution of a sanction to an alleged wrongdoer, the lawmaker has to cope with two types of errors; namely type one errors, that is to convict the innocent, and type two errors, that is to acquit the guilty. Most of the legal rules concerning due process, evidence, and appeal can be interpreted in the light of this dichotomy, regularly being based in favor of an avoidance of unwarranted convictions. 241
242
Criminal Procedure
7700
Boundaries between the ‘criminal procedure’ and adjacent areas of the criminal law are amorphous: in many legal systems it is substantive, not procedural law that both assigns the right of prosecution, to either the attorney general and/or the infringed individual, and defines requirements of proof. More generally, substantive law defines the elements constituting the crime and thereby what is to be proven (regularly: beyond reasonable doubt) in the criminal proceedings. By her deliberate definition of the crime, the lawmaker, therefore, enjoys considerable discretion in enlarging or reducing the impact and relevance of procedural rules. In this light, one may characterize the Anglo-American law as being more concerned with procedural guaranties than with substantive ones; the latter playing a key role within the continental system (where the principle of nulla poena sine lege is of paramount importance). Whereas the criminal procedure, almost by definition, presupposes an institutionalized process, by which the responsibility of the alleged wrongdoer is established, many ancient legal systems have lacked the concept both of a public enforcement of criminal deeds and of a regular formalized procedure to be followed when sanctioning. Due to the then existing ‘technological’ infeasibility of properly determining factual truth (the guilt of a wrongdoer), procedural aspects did not reach beyond a few elementary rules: whereas originally many offences were defined such that hardly any determination of factual truth was required (‘Die Tat tötet den Mann’ = ‘the deed kills the man’), subsequent - still ancient - procedures followed, in their rules on evidence, the so-called ‘gebundene Beweiswürdigung’ (‘fixed rules determining evidence’). Further, (criminal) law was originally enforced primarily or even solely by private individuals. Only in subsequent times, criminal procedure turned to an inquisitorial orientation. The type of criminal procedure now predominantly employed is the result of a relatively short history only, commencing with enlightenment and subsequent refinements during the nineteenth century.
2. The Economic Approach to the Criminal Procedure The law and economics contributions to the analysis of criminal procedure are highly economic in spirit being predominantly written by economists, not lawyers. Most of the literature focuses on the enforcement decisions taken by the prosecuting authority and, in close relation therewith, on the economics of the plea bargaining system prevailing in the US. These contributions apply standard economic maximization exercises to procedural issues, but are less concerned with an evaluation and comparison of existing and possible alternative procedural rules in their potential to accomplish certain policy goals. This lack of a genuinely institutional concern for procedural issues beyond plea bargaining is characteristic for both American and European
7700
Criminal Procedure
243
contributions with the notable exception of Tullock (1980) who provides a systematic economic treatment of the criminal procedure, covering the investigative part of the procedure, rules of evidence, expertise, and appeal. Issues also covered in this volume that relate to this chapter are: Civil Procedure: General (7000), Judicial Administration (7100), Settlement (7400), Evidence (7900), the economics of crime and punishment (8000-8600), and the production of legal rules and precedent (9000-9200). The overview presented in this article covers the focus of the pertinent literature. Therefore, major attention will be attributed to the economics of the plea bargaining system in the US (Section 3). Other issues, among those the role of judges and juries, evidence and appeal, are dealt with in the subsequent part (Section 4) of the chapter.
3. The Law and Economics of the Plea Bargaining System The economic literature’s interest with the criminal procedure is inspired by the basic empirical fact that most criminal cases are not decided in a trial but either dismissed in an early stage or ended by pre-trial settlement. Within this first part of the investigative process, regularly being of inquisitorial nature (see Tullock, 1980, p. 137), a government official (the prosecutor) decides on the pursuit of the case in the light of its ‘strength’ (primarily in terms of the evidence available) so that the defendant has little opportunity to influence outcomes by investment in defense resources. Prosecutorial decisions and possible pretrial settlements are, however, done ‘in the shadow of current court practices’ and are, hence, the consequence of (relatively accurate) predictions on the side of the prosecutor as to how courts would decide the case. General The plea bargain is the most prominent form of pre-trial settlement: The accused agrees to plead guilty for (a) certain crime(s) in exchange for a penalty that is considerably lower than that to be expected after trial (normally this reduction already stems from the fact that the accused pleads guilty only for a minor offence or for one single offence out of many more charged; say manslaughter instead of murder). The basic institutional feature behind the plea bargaining system is the prosecutor’s unlimited legal discretion to acquit a case, to settle it or to bring it to trial (see Landes, 1971; Adelstein, 1978a, 1978b, 1979, 1981b). Whereas the prosecutor is legally unconstrained in his enforcement choices, he is controlled by means of the budget assigned to him. The pertinent literature, therefore, views the prosecutor’s decision to enforce the law in a particular case as a maximization activity subject to constraints, namely as one of economizing on resources while aiming, at least in the light
244
Criminal Procedure
7700
of the classic articles, at the maximum degree of overall deterrence. Whereas the mainstream legal interpretation considers the plea bargain as a necessary evil in an overburdened system of criminal law enforcement, prominent law and economics scholars (Landes, 1971; Adelstein, 1981b, and Easterbrook, 1983) suggest an interpretation of the plea bargain as an institutional device congenial for the task of merging the criminal law’s ultimate goal, namely that of being a ‘pricing device’ for crimes, with the scarcity constraint expressed in the limited prosecutorial budget. Since the plea bargain, in any case, requires the consent of the accused, it can, moreover, be conceived as a voluntary transaction, whereby both sides improve their position vis-à-vis the status quo; insofar standard settlement theory, as developed in civil procedure, is applicable. If one perceives the criminal procedure as a market system, see Easterbrook (1983), the plea bargain provides a contractual settlement, whereby the parties agree on the price of the offence. Since, moreover, the probability of a conviction in trial depends on the observable strength of the case and not on factual, but unperceivable innocence, even an innocent defendant may rationally accept such bargain, if she is unlikely to prevail in trial. The law and economics literature does not only analyze the working properties of the plea bargaining system and the influence of certain factors (for example, severity of the crime) on the likelihood of a bargained settlement, but has also suggested to interpret the plea bargaining system as a screening device that allows for a separation of guilty and innocent individuals. Further, the economic contributions are also concerned with a normative evaluation of the plea bargain and with an assessment of possible avenues of its institutional reform. Details Most economic contributions interpret the criminal sanction as the ‘punishment price’ for the criminal act, reflecting the full social cost imposed by these acts. Following this standard economic approach, the optimal price for the offence is defined as the equivalent to the entire harm generated by the offence (see Landes, 1971; Adelstein, 1981b). Both sides, prosecutor and defendant, therefore, orient themselves in their procedural strategies on expected sentences as the (current) prices for the respective crime. Operating under a resource constraint regarding the enforcement and pursuit of criminal cases, they maximize their utility subject to these constraints that exist in terms of their resources (endowments) available. Whereas either side can influence the probability of conviction by resources invested into the case, the plea bargain allows both sides to economize on these resources: The defendant, on the one hand, needs to invest resources for his defense; ultimately, he will expend resources up to the point where marginal benefits equal marginal costs. The prosecutor, on her turn, seeks to maximize the expected number of convictions
7700
Criminal Procedure
245
weighted by their respective sentences, again subject to her budget constraint, in particular Landes (1971) and Easterbrook (1983). The prosecutor, therefore, allocates resources to those cases where outcomes in terms of sentences are more responsive to changes in resources invested and to those where the overall sentence is greater. Provided for the said budget constraint, the prosecutor will dismiss ‘weak’ cases and try to settle cases by plea bargains in order to free resources that he could then shift to cases that are more promising in terms of expected sentences. On this basis, both sides can improve their situation in relation to their expected trial outcome by the settlement of the criminal case outside of courts. Such a settlement is feasible if a certain penalty acceptable to the defendant exceeds the prosecutor’s minimum offer; within this broad bargaining range, the relative strength of the parties will decide upon the negotiated sentence. Consequences The just described general framework, in which the plea bargain is primarily seen as a conservation of resource problem, allows for some concrete conclusions with respect to the influence on a bargained outcome of the probability of conviction in trial, the severity of the crime, each side’s resources and their productivity, the costs of trial and settlement, and ultimately the attitudes toward risk (see Landes, 1971). First, the higher the stakes (expected penalties) in the criminal case, the less important are the costs of trial, that is, as stakes become higher, ceteris paribus, settlements become more difficult. A settlement is, therefore, more probable, the smaller is the sentence in case of a conviction at trial and the more substantial trial costs are vis-à-vis those at a settlement. Second, under the assumption that both prosecutor and defendant hold identical views on the expected outcome of a trial, only risklovers would opt for trial (this result is further increased if the defendant’s estimates of the probability of conviction exceed the prosecutor’s). Third, the more expensive a trial is, the more attractive becomes the plea bargain (that is, the more resources a settlement saves, the more likely is its occurrence). An increase in the defendant’s wealth (see Landes, 1971; see also Kobayashi and Lott, 1996), would also increase resources spent on her defense, reducing thus the probability of conviction, so that, regarding plea bargains, a lower negotiated sentence would be predicted; in the special case of risk neutrality the wealthy defendant’s choice will depend on whether she expects the penalty to be a jail sentence (then: greater investments) or a money fine (then: smaller investments). Regarding the impact of the bail system, those defendants detained during trial are burdened with increased costs of defense so that they face a higher conviction probability in trial and a longer sentence in a settlement, respectively. The thus increased opportunity costs of trial would also lead to an increased settlement rate of detained defendants.
246
Criminal Procedure
7700
Empirical Results Apart from its theoretical analysis, the Landes paper has sparked a series of empirical research both on an individual and the aggregated level, whose results, albeit in the overall consistent with the above mentioned theoretical claims, are not fully conclusive. Landes’ own work (see Landes, 1971), showed that a reduction in the differential between trial costs and settlement costs would yield a higher number of trials. The assumption that higher resource costs of a trial would generate more plea bargains (the propensity to stand trial is higher for defendants released on bail) was only weakly confirmed. Subsequent work by Rhodes (1976), devoting attention to the aggregated level, found that both higher penalty offers in the bargaining process and higher defense resource expenditures increase the likelihood of a trial. Similar research by Weimer (1978) confirmed these results. Focusing on the duration of the prosecutorial pursuit of a case, Forst and Brosi (1977) confirmed the (quite apparent) claim that the ‘strength of the case’ in terms of the evidence against the defendant determines the prosecutor’s attitude towards trial (but did not confirm the authors’ - theoretically inconclusive - claim that prosecutors would direct their resources towards the prosecution of defendants with extensive arrest records). Elder (1989) could show that those factors that reduce the parties’ disagreement on the estimated outcome, increase settlement (in particular, estimates on the ‘strength of the case’). Further, increases in the stakes of the case enhance the likelihood of trial. In contrast, personal characteristics (sex, drug abuse, and so on, except for race) do not significantly affect the settlement decision. Elder’s study, moreover, could not confirm the influence of bail and of a publicly provided defense counsel on the likelihood of trial. Plea Bargaining as a Screening Device An influential economic interpretation of the plea bargaining system beyond that of economizing on resources has been advanced by Grossmann and Katz (1983). The authors propose to view the plea bargaining process as a screening device that separates between innocent and guilty defendants (their further suggestion to view the plea bargain as an insurance device that reduces the scope of errors which would cause greater harm when regular trials are conducted is not deepened here): under the assumption of asymmetric information with respect to actual guilt (the accused is assumed to be systematically better informed than the prosecutor), the plea bargaining system generates a process of self selection of the truly guilty. In the world of this model, all defendants are initially assumed equally risk averse irrespective of their factual guilt. Prosecutors are unable to identify beforehand actual guilt, but may estimate the percentage of actual guilty individuals among the accused. In such a world, the optimal plea bargain will always induce the truly guilty to accept the prosecutor’s offer: Defendants self
7700
Criminal Procedure
247
select such that only the innocent will choose trial whereas guilty defendants reveal their guilt by acceptance of the plea offer. Results change, however, if defendants exhibit different degrees of risk aversion: risk-averse innocent defendants may still improve their position by accepting the plea offer in comparison to a regular trial so that for them the possibility of pre-trial settlement is still attractive. Since these highly risk-averse innocent defendants would not exhibit any behavioral difference to a less risk-averse guilty defendant, both types of defendants would accept the same plea offer. Therefore, if defendants are not equally risk averse, the above described screening property is reduced. In a variant of this approach, Reinganum (1988) examines plea bargains with particular emphasis on asymmetric information regarding the ‘strength of the case’ in terms of the likelihood of conviction. This analysis yields the result that sufficiently weak cases are dismissed not in consideration of resource costs, but of type one and type two error costs. Those cases not dismissed, however, exhibit a higher likelihood of a negotiated guilty plea, the weaker their ‘relative strength’ is. Similarly to the Grossmann and Katz model, also this variant predicts a screening outcome in the sense that (when prosecutor types pool) the defendants separate such that only the guilty accept the plea and only the innocent stand trial. Further, since the strength of a case reflects in the sentence offered in a guilty plea and defendants are more likely to reject higher sentence offers, the likelihood of a trial in fact increases with the strength of the case. If, hence, innocent defendants are, as it appears to be empirically the case, more risk averse than guilty defendants, this screening effect will disappear: Innocent defendants may incorrectly plead guilty only for the sake of avoiding the uncertain penalty pending from trial. It is here where the contribution by Kobayashi and Lott (1996) comes in: the authors demonstrate that the systematic disparity in criminal defence expenditures existing between guilty and innocent defendants allows for a preservation of efficient screening. Analogizing the procedure to a two-stage contest, the authors show that both defense and prosecution expenditures depend on the strength of the defendant’s case. Since innocent defendants enjoy lower defense expenditures, they are less likely to falsely plead guilty in order to avoid trial. It is this mechanism that enlarges the range in which efficient sorting is preserved. Normative Evaluation of the Plea Bargain Economic contributions on the criminal procedure, starting with Landes, have emphasized the linkage of the plea bargaining system with the criminal law’s overall pricing structure. Subsequent contributions have generated both critique and refinements of the original Landes paper and have sparked a more general discussion of the value, strengths, shortcomings, and the specific institutional framework of the plea bargain, and of possible avenues of reform.
248
Criminal Procedure
7700
Easterbrook (1983) has suggested refinements of the Landes paper by proposing to view the criminal procedure as a ‘market system’ constituted by an institutional framework whose essential elements are prosecutorial (and sentencing) discretion and plea bargaining. Following the original Landes position Easterbrook interprets prosecutorial behavior as a maximization activity (ultimately aimed at maximizing the ‘deterrent punch’ out of those resources committed to crime prevention), whereby the prosecutor, in her specific situation, equalizes marginal returns from resources spent in the prosecution of a variety of individual cases. The ‘mix’ of resource inputs into these cases is not determined in abstracto, but depends on current rates of apprehension, the frequency of certain offences and of the respective probabilities of conviction. Changes in this factors influence, therefore, the allocation of prosecutorial resources. The plea bargain is congenial to this system, since it facilitates the market like determination and imposition of the current ‘price of the crime’. On the one hand, the plea bargaining system is thus flexible enough for quick adjustments to changing conditions in terms of current penalty prices. On the other hand, it constitutes a necessary element in the attempt to maximize deterrence out of a given prosecutorial budget. In this view the plea bargain is even superior to the regular trial, since the plea bargain reflects the probabilities case by case and allows for rapid adjustments as conditions determining the price (for example, frequences of offense) change. The discretion in the criminal procedure, in particular by means of a plea bargain, allows the system to produce deterrence with a minimum of allocative inefficiency. This view, inspired by a ‘market-oriented’ general background, has, however become in itself the subject of economically inspired criticism (Schulhofer, 1988). On the one hand, Schulhofer challenges the radical skepticism about the truth value of trials arguing that the proper institutional role of trials within the system of the administration of justice is not to merely distribute acquittals and convictions according to expected probabilities of conviction, but to reveal factual truth; it is this factual accuracy that represents an important factor in the overall administration of the criminal justice system. On the other hand, the criminal procedure in itself is not a market system, but a ‘political system’. Framed as a principal-agent problem, this critique is twofold: most importantly the plea bargaining system allows the prosecutors to use and misuse their prosecutorial discretion in many ways, and the pursuit of their self interest will only rarely harmonize with the public interest irrespective of how this public interest is defined. A certain diversity of incentives with respect to the attractiveness of plea bargain deals also holds true with respect to the defendant’s side: the basic reason for this diversity of interests between the defendant himself and her defense counsel is the fee structure in the US, whereby most defense lawyers work for a fee below market rates and, hence, have a clear selective interest to finish the case earlier rather then later. They
7700
Criminal Procedure
249
will favor a plea bargain. The said critique also affects the fairness properties of plea bargains in general: to be sure, any concluded bargain makes at least one party to the deal better off without harming the position of the other party; otherwise the parties would not have agreed. If we, however, acknowledge a principal-agent problem on the side of the prosecutor (law enforcement as a public good being entrusted to some agency) and a comparable misrepresentation in the defense lawyer-client relation, it becomes less obvious whether those deals concluded by the agents are always in the true interests of their principals. The scope by which this principal-agent problem actually plagues the fairness of concluded plea bargains remains an empirical question though. A more institution-oriented and still highly economic interpretation of the plea bargaining system has been advanced by Adelstein (1981b). Since the precise determination of the ‘punishment price’ (direct material and moral cost of crime), as performed in the criminal procedure, is in itself costly, the cost of this price exaction, in an economic perspective, should be smaller than the crime’s social cost: it is pre-trial settlement, as exemplified in the plea bargain, that constitutes a device for steady innovations in reducing these procedural costs. Seen as a process of continuous adaptations and modifications on punishment prices, the plea bargaining system also allows for a more sophisticated - and more institution oriented - treatment of prosecutorial behavior than under the ‘penalty maximizing’ position advanced by Landes: under the US system, the prosecutor is not an authority entrusted with the goal of maximizing penalties, but with that of promoting justice in terms of penalties that fit the crime. Moreover, the Landes approach tacitly assumes that the prosecutor considers all defendants guilty (or, at least, that the prosecutor is uninterested in the defendants’ actual guilt). Since prosecutors are legally bound to pursue criminal cases such that only guilty individuals are sentenced with a due penalty, the prosecutorial behavior is likely to differ from a simple maximization of output in terms of years sentenced, but to follow the more complex mechanism of steady adaptations described above. Institutional Comparison The economically inspired skepticism towards the American system of the plea bargain does not amount to a general critique of all settlement institutions. Whereas this critique acknowledges the necessity of some such settlement procedure in the light of the costliness of full-scale criminal proceedings, it argues for a systematic reconsideration of all of its institutional details in order to identify the potential of institutional improvement. Such an analysis, in particular the contribution by Adelstein on the comparison to the British settlement system and that by Alschuler (1983), suggests that the current
250
Criminal Procedure
7700
American system of plea bargains may be suboptimal and that various ways of improvement of the institutional status quo exist. Apart from Adelstein’s (1981b) insightful comparison between the American plea bargain and its English equivalent, Alschuler (1983) and Schulhofer (1988) have discussed similarities and differences between the American and the European continental, in particular German, system. Their contributions have, inter alia, emphasized the variety of legal institutions which would allow for a more subtle way of settling those cases that do not deserve a full and costly trial and the actual existence of these institutions even under the continental system that, in principle, is characterized by a strict principle of legality regarding prosecutorial enforcement. Despite the existence of some such comparative research, much more remains to be done. Insofar as these settlement devices involve savings in resources, one has, however, to be aware of the fact that these savings exist (only) in the prosecutor’s time and trouble costs, since under the continental system the prosecutor is not endowed with a budget to be invested at his sole discretion. There are in particular two avenues for further research: hardly any systematic studies exist with respect to various informal ways of settlements under the continental system; not the least because of a lack of official data. Apart from those settlement institutions that are formalized parts of the regular legal system (for example, ‘diversion’), other (‘grey’) variants of settlement only exist in the shadow of the law. Due to the different institutional framework of the continental system, in which the prosecutor is obligated to enforce the law, such ‘negotiated penalties’ are usually performed under inclusion of the judges in regular trials, that is, by an explicit or tacit agreement of all parties involved regarding the negotiated outcome of the trial. The systematic economic treatment of such behavior has to be developed under the rigorous assumption of self-interested motivation by all parties involved, that is, by the judge, the prosecutor, the defendant and his lawyer. Viewed thus it becomes apparent that as long as expectations regarding the expected outcome of the trial overlap, a ‘negotiated’ outcome should be in the self-interest of each party involved: in such a case the judge does not run the risk of reversal in the instance, the prosecutor may grant a discount due to the confession and yet remain within the limits of the agency’s policy of treating like offences alike, and the defendant may obtain a favorable treatment. Since the system would suffer from cheating on the previously agreed upon sanction (say, the judge returns a penalty harsher than that negotiated or the attorney files an appeal despite his prior agreement to the sanction), it requires, for perfect functioning, repeated games with identical players. These conditions are perfectly met, for example, at the Viennese criminal court, where a few specialized lawyers deal with specialized judges and prosecutors. In the shadow of the law, most trials at this Court are in fact negotiated prior to their commencement.
7700
Criminal Procedure
251
Little attention has been devoted to the relation of settlement procedures to substantive law. Under the continental system, the principle of strict enforcement does not allow the prosecutor to leave certain offences or (sub)groups of offences unforced. Therefore, the ‘political decision’ to decriminalize certain offenses, has to be taken by the legislator, not the judiciary (closer observation, however, reveals that even the continental system is open to some such adaptation by the law enforcing institutions). In contrast, under the Anglo-American system, the prosecutor may refrain, by his deliberate choice, from enforcing offences, so that the respective behavior is effectively decriminalized. The prosecutors’ deliberate enforcement policy may render a whole set of offences practically obsolete. Within the Anglo-American world, criminal offences, as they exist on paper, may, therefore, be radically different from those actually enforced (this is the case for example regarding sexual offences). These alternative systems (and, inter alia, the institutional fact that under the continental system neither prosecutors nor judges are elected) require careful examination in an economic and in particular public choice perspective.
4. Courts and Judges The Punishment Dilemma Under most procedural systems, courts (judges and/or juries) decide on the defendant’s guilt and determine the penalty. It is these individuals (professional judges and jurors) who carry out the punishment task. To the extent that such meting out of a penalty is not only experienced as a ‘good’ (say, by deriving some utility from the satisfaction of retributory concepts of punishment), but rather an ‘intrinsic bad’ (intrinsic disutility of inflicting harm on someone), the ‘punishment dilemma’ arises if punishment is seen solely in a response setting (Buchanan, 1975). In her sentencing behavior, the individual encharged with the punishment task will seek to avoid or reduce the intrinsic disutility of punishment that - in this ex post perspective - appears as the arbitrary infliction of harm: whereas the public good of law compliance by deterrence can only be secured by this infliction of punishment ex post, the temptation to punish too leniently in relation to that level of punishment chosen under a ‘constitutional’ perspective is always likely to prevail in a response setting. The very existence of the above described punishment dilemma has consequences both for the individual punishment decision and for the institutional choice of punishment institutions (Buchanan, 1975; Lewisch, 1995, 1997). First, as regards the individual’s punishment decision, the individual judge will weigh the costs and benefits of punishment according to her own perspective, that is, according to her discounting rate. Although hard facts are missing, empirical observations seem to suggest that the discounting
252
Criminal Procedure
7700
rate of lay judges, who are not professionally trained in considering the longterm deterrent effects of punishment on law compliance, expresses rather current motivations and drives, so that lay judges tend to punish more leniently than their professional peers on the bench (the precise determination of the juries’ sentencing behavior, depends, however, on the relation of the punishment dilemma to possible retributive concerns). This perspective also explains why jurors seek to avoid returning a penalty that they consider excessively harsh and prosecutors, aware of this fact, may reduce charges to increase the likelihood of a verdict, preferring a less severe charge with high likelihood of success over a more severe charge that is unlikely to be sentenced. Second, regarding institutional choice, the community would be unable to deter potential criminals if it confines itself, in its punishment institutions, to the response of violations of law, once committed: unduly light punishment would result. Punishment institutions, therefore, must be chosen strategically on the constitutional level (Buchanan, 1975). In particular, taking account of the above dilemma, the seemingly puzzling institutional feature to assign those individuals in a society with the punishment tasks (that is, professional judges) who, in their sentencing behavior, are harsher than the average man in the street, is economically sound. Apart from the punishment dilemma, the selection and the sentencing behavior of juries has only partially attracted attention. Regarding jury conscription, both the criteria and procedures employed for the selection process are the object of economic interest (‘keyman-suggestion versus random selection’). In a particularly economic contribution, Martin (1972) has studied the welfare effects of the jury system that does not pay conscripts according to their opportunity income, analogizing the economic working properties of the respective institutional arrangement to that of army conscription (see also Bowles, 1980). The decision-making mechanism of the jury under alternative voting rules (unanimity and supermajority rules) has, however, not been examined by the published law and economics literature (pertinent working papers are in circulation though). An analytical comparison of legal choices made by single judges and penals has been provided, with reference to work by Condorcet, by the literature on civil procedure (see Schäfer, 1998); particular contributions on the criminal justice system are lacking. For an overview of the use of lay judges in Germany, see Casper and Zeisel (1972). Context Dependent Choices Choices by jurors have found increasing attention by the economically inspired psychological literature (see Kelman, Rottenstreich and Tversky, 1996). This literature investigates, notably by means of experiments, to what extent legal evaluations and choices depend on the set of available judgements. Experiments show that generally observed ‘violations’ of context-independent choices are also present in the realm of judicial choices: experimental data confirm that
7700
Criminal Procedure
253
choices made by jurors exhibit both compromise effects (the same option is evaluated more favorably when seen as an intermediate within the array of options) and contrast effects (an option is evaluated more favorably in the presence of similar options clearly inferior to it than in the absence of such options). In this light, choices by jurors depend, for example, on whether the available options comprise only manslaughter and murder or manslaughter, (regular) murder, and murder under special circumstances. These findings also suggest, as another example of the close linkage of substantive and procedural aspects of criminal law, that a legislative ‘splitting up’ of a crime in distinguishable new categories alters choice behavior by judges regarding previous categories.
5. Evidence Regarding evidence, also on issues of standard of proof and burden of proof, see the contribution by Parker and Kobayashi (in this volume Chapter 7900). With respect to an analysis of specific procedural rules on evidence, it should be emphasized, however, that rules of evidence are not identical for civil and criminal proceedings in most (not all, so the notable exception of the US) legal systems. Differences stem from the more restrictive use of ‘suspect’ evidence in criminal cases (as embodied in the respective constitutional rights/amendments), which, albeit only partially, can be explained on grounds of the increased costliness of type one errors in criminal than in civil cases. Economically inspired literature on the subject is not abundant: Tullock (1980, p. 148) suggests an economic categorization of rules of evidence in criminal proceedings (see Chapter 7900). The thus proposed distinction identifies separate categories of ‘outlawed’ evidence: one group of rules aims at reducing error costs by prohibiting evidence that, being of poor quality, is likely to mislead the court (for example, hearsay or the use of the lie detector). In an economic evaluation, Tullock suggests, however, to admit this ‘poor evidence’ to the trial, but to give it the appropriate (low) weight. A second category of rules seeks to reduce direct costs of the proceedings, in particular those in terms of wasting the court’s time (for example, rules allowing to exclude not-relevant evidence). Category 3 contains rules that serve specific purposes extraneous to the proceedings, for example, the prohibition of torture, the unjustified opening of letters, the unlawful seizure of evidence, or the violation of evidentiary privileges. Regarding this third category, rules of evidence are used to enforce other parts of the law. The justification for such an exclusion and its legitimate scope are, however, disputed even within the law and economics literature. On the one hand, one may argue, as Tullock (1980), that, if both the judicial and police
254
Criminal Procedure
7700
system are unable to sufficiently enforce the pertinent substantive rules (that is, those protecting the outside interest), some such exclusionary evidence rule can be argued for in an economic perspective. On the other hand, one may favor a strict distinction between the proper enforcement of the respective substantive rules and the usage of evidence gained in violation of these rules. In this respect, Posner (1982) considers excessive the exclusion of evidence in a criminal trial seized in violation of the Fourth Amendment (which forbids unreasonable searches and seizures): the costs of exclusion of the thus acquired evidence (in terms of the inability to obtain a conviction on this basis) is likely to exceed the social (in this view of Posner: often negligible) costs of misconduct. According to Posner, the respective exclusionary rules can only be explained on the basis of the ‘technological’ infeasibility of earlier times to properly enforce regulations on searches and seizures. In our times, these (in earlier days infeasible) tort sanctions are available, and their usage would suffice to deter violations. In the example of an unauthorized search in the defendant’s home, Posner proposes to confine ‘legal sanctions’ to a tort remedy aimed at recovering the clean up costs of the apartment. In turn, wherever the illegally gathered evidence was not only unlawfully collected, but is in itself unreliable (such as coerced confessions and involuntary guilty pleas), a ban on its use in criminal trials is economically sound. For a well informed criticism of Posner’s interpretation of exclusionary rules as an excessive sanction for governmental misconduct, see Morris (1982).
6. Arrest, Bail, and Sentencing Behavior On arrest and bail, see Landes (1974), Myers (1981), on issues of court delay Levin (1975), on the statistical analysis of courts’ sentencing behavior Tiffany, Avichai and Peters (1975).
7. Appeals Neither the institution of appeals in the criminal proceedings as such nor specific technical procedural issues have been thoroughly discussed from an economic standpoint. We may refer, however, to the general economic analysis of appeals, as developed in civil proceedings, notably by Tullock (1980, p. 162) and Shavell (1995): when designing a court system with the task of minimizing trial costs plus expected error costs, choice has to be made between investments in the reliability of courts of first instance (by investing resources in, say, the education of trial court judges or the usage of panels) and/or by investments in the accuracy of the appeals courts. Policy choices are regularly a mix between investments on both levels of adjudication. An economic explanation for the
7700
Criminal Procedure
255
use of a second instance is that, whereas costs in the first instance are to be borne in every legal case, the costs of appeal only materialize if an appeal is actually filed: this will only be done by those disappointed litigants who consider such an appeal cost-justified, leading thereby to a separation within disappointed litigants. The specific institutional mix of courts of first instance and of courts of appeal in criminal cases is due to the predominant concern of avoiding type one errors. For the task of correctly determining the facts of the case relatively more resources are invested in courts of first instance than in civil cases. Accordingly, since courts of appeal are unlikely to possess superior knowledge regarding fact finding, errors of fact are largely excluded from revision in the appeal’s process (the opposite generally hold true where the collection of evidence is performed on a less rigorous basis at first instance, as is the case for petty offences). Even the increased accuracy of the trial proceeding, however, cannot fully substitute for the use of the appeal’s process which is more focused on error of law. Whereas the appeal’s process is entrusted, in civil cases, solely to disappointed litigants, the characteristics of the criminal law suggest a review of court rulings of first instance also on a more objectivized (‘ex offo’) basis allowing the courts of instance to review (some) legal mistakes even if they have not been brought up by either side (defendant or prosecutor) in their court motions. The respective institutional arrangements can regularly be observed in various national procedural rules. The regular exclusion of interrogatory appeals in criminal procedure can be explained in the light of the argument by Shavell (1995) that violations of procedural rules, in particular with respect to the gathering of evidence, can best be considered on the basis of the final judgement. If court rulings prior to the final judgement, however, impose particular costs on the defendant, as is the case with arrest, and warrants of arrest, appeals against these court orders are regularly admitted. Insofar as the avoidance of legal mistakes and harmonization of the law within a jurisdiction is concerned, again criminal proceedings differ from civil proceedings: whereas in civil cases, any correction of a judgment, once unappealable, imposes high costs on the prevailing party trusting the validity of the final court judgment, in criminal cases a particular interest exists in finding the accurate judgement. It follows that judicial review of sentences is facilitated in criminal cases even if (already) unappealable; in particular for the sake of eliminating type one errors.
8. Criminal Procedure and the Economics of Justice Economic theories of justice, in particular contractarian contributions (Rawls, 1971; Brennan and Buchanan, 1985), propose to frame the normative discussion regarding the fairness of legal (and also procedural) rules by means
256
Criminal Procedure
7700
of the ‘veil of ignorance’ experiment. If individuals are put behind a veil of ignorance thick enough to screen out all their distinctive properties and features in real life, so that they are unable to identify how their own position will be affected by the rules contemplated, they will opt, based on their own self interest, for rules that can be considered ‘fair’. Whereas the veil as such is only an analytical device, the mechanism behind it may be mimicked in real life when the choice setting for institutional choices is designed such that the principles of generality and extended time dimension are observed. If an individual is likely to assume all feasible positions under a legal rule (today she is plaintiff, tomorrow defendant), there is no room for biased choices; hence the individual will design rules, again based on her own interest in a non-discriminatory manner. In the light of this analytical framework, it is possible to evaluate the fairness properties of procedural rules. Similarly to a comparable exercise undertaken for civil procedural law (see Lewisch, 1998), the normative requirements for a just (‘fair’) criminal procedure, as is enshrined in Article 6 of the European Convention on Human Rights, can be derived from a veil perspective. Research specifically devoted to criminal procedure is, however, necessary.
Bibliography on Criminal Procedure (7700) Adelstein, Richard P. (1978a), ‘The Plea Bargain in Theory: A Behavioral Model of the Negotiated Guilty Plea’, 44 Southern Economic Journal, 488-503. Adelstein, Richard P. (1978b), ‘The Negotiated Guilty Plea: A Framework for Analysis’, 53 New York University Law Review, 783-833. Adelstein, Richard P. (1979), ‘Informational Paradox and the Pricing of Crime: Capital Sentencing Standards in Economic Perspective’, 70 Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 281-298. Adelstein, Richard P. (1981a), ‘Institutional Function and Evolution in the Criminal Process’, 76 Northwestern University Law Review, 1-99. Adelstein, Richard P. (1981b), ‘The Plea Bargain in England and America: A Comparative Institutional View’, in Burrows, Paul and Veljanovski, Cento G. (eds), The Economic Approach to Law, London, Butterworths, 226-252. Aghion, Philippe, Hart, Oliver D. and Moore, John (1992), ‘The Economics of Bankruptcy Reform’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 523-546. Alschuler, Albert W. (1968), ‘The Prosecutor’s Role in Plea Bargaining’, 36 University of Chicago Law Review, 50-112. Alschuler, Albert W. (1983), ‘Implementing the Criminal Defendant’s Right to Trial: Alternatives to the Plea Bargaining System’, 50 University of Chicago Law Review, 931-1050. Bebchuk, Lucian Arye and Chang, Howard F. (1992), ‘Bargaining and the Division of Value in Corporate Reorganization’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 253-279. Becker, Gary S. (1968), ‘Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach’, 76 Journal of Political Economy, 169-217.
7700
Criminal Procedure
257
Boari, Nicola (1997), ‘On the Efficiency of Penal Systems: Several Lessons from the Italian Experience’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 115-126. Bowles, Roger A. (1980), ‘Juries, Incentives and Self-Selection’, 20 British Journal of Criminology, 368-376. Brennan, Geoffrey and Buchanan, James M. (1985), The Reason of Rules - Constitutional Political Economy, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Buchanan, James M. (1975), The Limits of Liberty: Between Anarchy and Leviathan, Miami. Casper, Gerhard and Zeisel, Hans (1972), ‘Lay Judges in the German Criminal Courts’, 1 Journal of Legal Studies, 135-191. Chu, C.Y. Cyrus (1991), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Criminal Proceedings in Civil Law Countries’, 11(1) International Review of Law and Economics, 111-116. Easterbrook, Frank H. (1983), ‘Criminal Procedure as a Market System’, 12 Journal of Legal Studies, 289-332. Elder, Harold W. (1987), ‘Property Rights Structures and Criminal Courts: An Analysis of State Criminal Courts’, 7 International Review of Law and Economics, 21-32. Elder, Harold W. (1989), ‘Trials and Settlements in the Criminal Courts: An Empirical Analysis of Dispositions and Sentencing’, 18 Journal of Legal Studies, 191-208. Forst, Brian and Brosi, Kathleen B. (1977), ‘A Theoretical and Empirical Analysis of the Prosecutor’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 177-191. Froeb, Luke M. (1990), ‘The Adverse Seletion of Cases for Trial’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 317-324. Gentry, James Theodore (1986), ‘The Panopticon Revisited: The Problem of Monitoring Private Prisons’, 96 Yale Law Journal, 353-375. Gould, John P. (1971), ‘The Economics of Legal Conflicts’, 2 Journal of Legal Studies, 279-300. Grossman, Gene M. and Katz, Michael L. (1983), ‘Plea Bargaining and Social Welfare’, 73 American Economic Review, 749-757. Kaplow, Louis (1994), ‘The Value of Accuracy in Adjudication: An Economic Analysis’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 307-401. Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (1994), ‘Accuracy in the Determination of Liability’, 37 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-15. Katz, Avery (1988), ‘Judicial Decisionmaking and Litigation Expenditure’, 8 International Review of Law and Economics, 124-143. Kelman, Mark G., Rottenstreich Yuval and Tversky, Amos (1996), ‘Context-Dependence in Legal Decision Making’, 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 287-318. Kobayashi, Bruce H. (1992), ‘Deterrence with Multiple Defendants: An Explanation for “Unfair” Plea Bargains’, 23 Rand Journal of Economics, 507-517. Kobayashi, Bruce H. and Lott, John R., Jr (1992), ‘Low Probability-High Penalty Enforcement Strategies and the Efficient Operation of the Plea Bargaining System’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 69-77. Kobayashi, Bruce H. and Lott, J.R., Jr (1996), ‘In Defense of Criminal Defense Expenditures and Plea Bargaining’, 16 International Review of Law and Economics, 397-415. Landes, William M. (1971), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Courts’, 14 Journal of Law and Economics, 61-108. Landes, William M. (1974), ‘Legality and Reality: Some Evidence on Criminal Procedure’, 3 Journal of Legal Studies, 287-337.
258
Criminal Procedure
7700
Langbein, John H. (1978), ‘Torture and Plea Bargaining’, 46 University of Chicago Law Review, 3-22. Leder, Mathias (1996), ‘Kommentar zu “Plea-bargaining - der Deal im Strafprozeß” von Claus Ott/Hans-Bernd Schäfer (Comment on Claus Ott/Hans-Bernd Schäfer, Plea-bargaining - the “deal” in criminal proceedings)’, 15 Jahrbuch für Neue Politische Ökonomie, 132-134. Levin, Martin A. (1975), ‘Delay in Five Criminal Courts’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 83-131. Lewisch, Peter (1992), ‘A Case Study on the Legal Regulation of Shoplifting in Austria and the “Criminal Tourism” from the East’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 439-455. Lewisch, Peter (1995), Punishment, Public Enforcement and the Protective State, Wien, New York, Springer. Lewisch, Peter (1997), ‘Doorkeepers of Justice? The Legal Services of Judges and Lawyers in an Economic Perspective’, 18 Rechtstheorie, 1-11. Lewisch, Peter (1998), ‘Ökonomische Analyse des Zivilprozesses (Economic Analysis of Civil Procedure)’, in Mayr, Peter (ed), 100 Jahre österreichische Zivilprozessgesetze, 155-178. Lott, J.R., Jr (1987), ‘Should the Wealthy be Able to “Buy Justice”?’, 95 Journal of Political Economy, 1307-1316. Martin, Donald L. (1972), ‘The Economics of Jury Conscription’, 80 Journal of Political Economy, 680-702. Miceli, Thomas J. (1990), ‘Optimal Prosecution of Defendants Whose Guilt is Uncertain’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 189-201. Miceli, Thomas J. (1991), ‘Optimal Criminal Procedure: Fairness and Deterrence’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-10. Morris, Arval A. (1982), ‘The Exclusionary Rule, Deterrence and Posner’s Economic Analysis of Law’, 57 Washington Law Review, 647-667. Myers, Samuel L., Jr (1981), ‘The Economies of Bail Jumping’, 10 Journal of Legal Studies, 381-392. Noam, Eli M. (1981), ‘A Cost-benefit Model of Criminal Courts’, 3 Research in Law and Economics, 173-183. Ott, Claus and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (1996), ‘“Plea-Bargaining”, der “Deal” im Strafprozeß (Plea-Bargaining)’, in Schenk, Karl-Ernst, Schmidtchen, Dieter and Streit, Manfred E. (eds), Vom Hoheitsstaat zum Konsensualstaat, Neue Formen der Kooperation zwischen Staat und Privaten Jahrbuch für Neue Politische Ökonomie 15, Tübingen, Mohr, 107-126. Palmer, John P. (1984), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Right to a Jury Trial’, 4 International Review of Law and Economics, 29-53. Parker, Jeffrey S. and Kobayashi, Bruce H. (1999), ‘Evidence’ , in Bouckaert, B. and De Geest, G. (eds), Encyclopedia of Law and Economics, Aldershot, Edward Elgar. Pastor, Santos (1990), ‘Economìa de la Justicia (I) y (II) (Economics of the Judicature)’, 5-6 Revista de Economía Pública. Pastor, Santos (1991), ‘Informe Sobre la Litigación, Recursos y Acceso de los Cuidadanos a la Justicie (Report on Litigation, Courts Inputs and Access to Justice)’, in Ministerio De Justicia (ed), Materiales Para una Reforma Procesal, Madrid.
7700
Criminal Procedure
259
Phillips, Llad (1981), ‘The Criminal Justice System: Its Technology and Inefficiencies’, 10 Journal of Legal Studies, 363-380. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1979), ‘The Optimal Tradeoff between the Probability and Magnitude of Fines’, 69 American Economic Review, 880-891. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1984), ‘The Optimal Use of Fines and Imprisonment’, 24 Journal of Public Economics, 89-99. Posner Richard A. (1973), ‘An Economic Approach to Legal Procedure and Judicial Administration’, 2 Journal of Legal Studies, 399-458. Posner, Richard A. (1982), ‘Excessive Sanctions for Governmental Misconduct in Criminal Cases’ (transcript)’, 57 Washington Law Review, 635-646. Rawls, John (1971), A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Reinganum, Jennifer F. (1988), ‘Plea Bargaining and Prosecutorial Discretion’, 78 American Economic Review, 713-728. Rhodes, William M. (1976), ‘The Economics of Criminal Courts: A Theoretical and Empirical Investigation’, 5 Journal of Legal Studies, 311-340. Rhodes, William M. (1977), ‘A Study of Sentencing in the Hennepin County and Ramsey County District Courts’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 333-353. Rubinfeld, Daniel L. and Sappington, David E.M. (1987), ‘Efficient Awards and Standards of Proof in Judicial Proceedings’, 18 Rand Journal of Economics, 303-318. Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (1998), ‘Kein Geld für die Justiz - Was ist uns der Rechtsfrieden wert? (No Money for the Courts - How much Do We Value “Rechtsfrieden”)’, in Bundesministerium für Justiz, Lewisch, Peter and Rechberger Walter (eds), 100 Jahre ZPO - Ökonomische Analyse des Zivilprozesses (100 Years Civil Procedural Code - Economic Analysis of the Civil Procedure, 251-274. Schrag, Joel and Scotchmer, Suzanne (1994), ‘Crime and Prejudice: The Use of Character Evidence in Criminal Trials’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 319-342. Schulhofer, Stephen J. (1988), ‘Criminal Justice Discretion as a Regulatory System’, 17 Journal of Legal Studies, 43-82. Shavell Steven (1995), ‘The Appeals Process as a Means of Error Correction’, 24 Journal of Legal Studies, 379-426. Steenhuis, D.W. (1984), ‘Strafrechtelijk Optreden: Stapje Terug en een Sprong Voorwaarts (Criminal Policy: A Step Backwards and a Jump Ahead)’, in X (ed), Delikt en Delinkwent, Arnhem, Gouda Quint, 4-5. Stuntz, William J. (1991), ‘Warrants and Fourth Amendment Remedies’, 77 Virginia Law Review, 881-943. Tiffany, Lawrence P., Avichai, Yakov and Peters, Geoffrey W. (1975), ‘A Statistical Analysis of Sentencing in Federal Courts: Defendants Convicted After Trial, 1967-1968', 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 369-390. Tullock, Gordon (1980), Trials on Trial: The Pure Theory of Legal Procedure, New York, Columbia University Press. Veljanovski, Cento G. (1986), ‘The Economics of Criminal Law and Procedure’, 23 Coexistence, 137-153. Weimer, David L. (1978), ‘Plea Bargaining and the Decision to go to Trial: The Application of a Rational Choice Model’, 10 Policy Sciences, 124 ff.
260
Criminal Procedure
7700
White, Michelle J. (1994), ‘Corporate Bankruptcy as a Filtering Device: Chapter 11 Reorganizations and Out-of-Court Debt Restructurings’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 268-295. Wils, Wouter P.J. (1997), ‘The Commission Notice on the Non-Imposition of Fines in Cartel Cases: A Legal and Economic Analysis’, 22 European Law Review, 125-140. Wittman, Donald A. (1974), ‘Two Views of Procedure’, 3 Journal of Legal Studies, 249-256.
7800 BANKRUPTCY PROCEEDINGS Francisco Cabrillo Professor of Economics Universidad Complutense de Madrid
Ben W.F. Depoorter Researcher University of Ghent, Faculty of Law © Copyright 1999 Francisco Cabrillo and Ben Depoorter
Abstract Bankruptcy has become a crucial legal institution in market economies all over the world. We try to explain some aspects of bankruptcy law and discover that economic theory provides explanation for many, but not all, attributes of bankruptcy law. Both legal and economic scholars have been engaged in a long series of discussions on the meaning of these attributes. JEL classification: K22, K40 Keywords: Bankruptcy, Liquidation, Reorganization
1. Introduction The word ‘bankruptcy’ originates from the Italian word ‘banca rotta’, an old expression that indicated that the bench of a trader was broken when he was not able to pay his creditors. For a long time bankruptcy has been an important legal institution in market economies. It enables the market system to dispose of inefficient firms and reallocate the assets of insolvent debtors. Also, the possibility of becoming bankrupt has been considered to be a positive incentive for behaving in an efficient way, both for individual traders and company managers. Bankruptcy law has traditionally been researched by lawyers, not economists. But in the last two decades many studies on the economics of bankruptcy proceedings have been published. Behind the technicalities of the legal regulation of bankruptcy lies a clear economic rationality. At the origin of a bankruptcy proceeding there is a financial crisis of an individual or company. Economists analyze bankruptcy law as the legal instrument to achieve the best possible outcome, which implies a minimization of social costs. Traditional legal theory, however, usually focuses its analysis on the
261
262
Bankruptcy Proceedings
7800
fairness and equity aspects of bankruptcy. From a law and economics perspective the efficiency of the bankruptcy procedures are the core of the analysis. Bankruptcy law, as it exists in most countries, can also be understood as a device to increase the efficiency of commercial relationships. In any contract the parties could introduce clauses regulating what should happen in case of default and how the assets of the bankrupt company should be managed. However, the transaction costs of writing and implementing such contracts would be very high. And, since a firm’s balance sheet is something dynamic that changes every day, creditors would be forced to renegotiate their contracts every time new creditors make claims against the debtor’s estate or every time the debtor acquires new assets or pays his previous debts. Therefore, it may be considered efficient to have standard procedures regulating the possible outcomes of a firm’s default (see Aghion, Hart and Moore, 1992). This chapter studies the efficiency of the most relevant aspects of bankruptcy law. Although most bankruptcy codes share many characteristics in their way of dealing with bankruptcy proceedings, each legal system has its own peculiarities and no international economic organization has yet been able to draft an international bankruptcy code. Therefore, this chapter will not focus on any specific national bankruptcy law, but rather will discuss the most relevant general issues while occasionally commenting on some particular national institutions. Also, our main attention will go to business bankruptcy. The issue of personal bankruptcy is touched sporadically, for example in the discussion on discharge in Section 3 (for more on personal bankruptcy, see Apilado, Dauton and Smith, 1978; Shiers and Williamson, 1987; Warren, Sullivan and Westbrook, 1988, 1989, 1994a). The second section of this chapter presents bankruptcy proceedings as a collective action of creditors to recover their credits in the most efficient way. In Sections 3 and 4 the main objectives of bankruptcy and the most relevant costs of a liquidation proceeding are discussed. Sections 5, 6, 7 and 8 deal with some of the economic agents involved in bankruptcy proceedings: the debtor, the creditors and employees. A specific section is devoted to the role of employees as a special type of creditor. The liquidation-reorganization dilemma is discussed in Sections 9 and 10. The final section comments on the possible alternatives to the existing bankruptcy proceedings. The problems of secured credits and bankruptcy priority rights will be taken into account occasionally; they are treated elsewehere in Volume II (Chapter 1500, Security Interests, Creditors’ Priorities and Bankruptcy) and in Volume III (Chapter 5660, Regulation of the Securities Market).
7800
Bankruptcy Proceedings
263
2. The Collective Action of Creditors The meeting of creditors, in most bankruptcy legislation a prerequisite before adopting any final decision concerning the bankrupt firm, may be a good example of the various efficiency aspects in bankruptcy procedure. From a law and economics perspective this compulsory meeting can be understood as a useful means to reduce transaction costs in collective action. Negotiations between various creditors are often difficult and expensive. Although an agreement is certainly not guaranteed in this meeting, procedure costs may be substantially reduced. In more general terms, bankruptcy law can be defined as a set of rules that institutionalizes collective action in debt collection (Jackson, 1986a). When collecting their credits out of a bankruptcy procedure creditors play a non-cooperative game, in which each individual maximizing strategy produces an inefficient outcome. Social costs will increase when each creditor tries to get the highest possible percentage of his credit. These individual strategies cannot raise the value of the debtor’s estate. On the contrary, they reduce the net value of the assets to be distributed among the creditors will be reduced. However, the principle of collective action seems to conflict with another generally accepted principle of bankruptcy law, the existence of secured credit, and the principle according to which bankruptcy law should not change the previous structure of the debtor’s liabilities. An important characteristic of some secured credits - mortgages, for instance - is that creditors can sell off part of the company’s assets, aside from the normal bankruptcy proceedings, in order to collect their credits beforehand. This possibility not only breaks the principle of collective action - such secured creditors are usually not interested in what may happen to other creditors - but may also reduce the net value of the bankrupt company because of piecemeal liquidation. The possible conflict of these two principles should be one of the basic problems to be discussed by any economic analysis of bankruptcy law. Most lawyers and economists acknowledge the existence of such a conflict. Bankruptcy law should offer a solution. In some cases collaterals can be substracted from the assets to be distributed and secured creditors denied the vote in the bankruptcy proceedings. In other cases bankruptcy law can provide the receiver or the administrator the option of paying secured credits by selling assets if the goods given as collateral are considered to be essential for an efficient reorganization or for selling the company as a going concern. The existence of secured credits does not mean, therefore, that the principle of collective action has to be abandoned.
264
Bankruptcy Proceedings
7800
3. The Objectives of Bankruptcy Law The major objective of bankruptcy law is supposed to be the (ex post) maximization of the proceeds. Assuming that more is preferred to less, economic theory holds that bankruptcy law should maximize the total value of the firm ex post. Although an efficient allocation of the debtor’s assets is usually its main objective, bankruptcy law may have other purposes. One objective may be to impose costs on individuals and firm managers, in order to provide them (ex ante) with adequate incentives to perform well (Easterbrook, 1990). Historically these costs were imposed by criminal sanctions to the bankruptcy debtor. Bankrupts went to prison or, in cases of fraudulent bankruptcies, even to the galleys of the scaffold. Contemporary scholars justified these stern measures against fraudulent bankrupts in terms of a rational crime theory. According to Becker (1968) the expected cost of crime has two elements for the criminal: the sanction and the probability of this sanction being imposed. If criminals are risk neutral, a low probability of conviction should be matched to a severe sanction. Adam Smith argued in favor of the highest sanction - the death penalty - for fraudulent bankrupts because, as he puts it, ‘there is no fraud which is more easily committed without being discovered’ (see Cabrillo, 1986). Although imprisonment for insolvency disappeared in the nineteenth century, most criminal codes still attach penalties of imprisonment to certain frauds committed in bankruptcy procedures. Note that these two objectives may conflict with each other (Berkovitch et al., 1993). If only the ex ante objective mattered, there would be nothing wrong with closing down bankrupt firms. From an ex post viewpoint this might be a very bad idea. Even well-managed firms sometimes go bankrupt, due to uncertainty or external factors. Bankruptcy law should de designed to strike the right balance between both objectives (Aghion, Hart and Moore, 1992). In bankruptcy procedures creditors try to capture the highest possible percentage of the value of their credit. Without the rules of bankruptcy law, creditors would adopt non-cooperative strategies which generate an outcome resembling that under a prisoner’s dilemma (on creditor misbehavior and secured credit as a sensible response to the common pool problem, see Picker, 1992). In each case, the dominant strategy, directed to raise the probability of recovering their credits, is non-cooperative. Creditors will waste resources trying to be the first to seize their collateral or to obtain a judgement against the debtor (Jackson, 1986a). This race may lead to premature liquidation of the firm’s assets, which may cause a loss of value for all creditors if the firm is worth more as a whole that as a collection of
7800
Bankruptcy Proceedings
265
pieces (the insight of the ‘collective action’ problem in bankruptcy was raised by Jackson, 1982). Therefore, the virtue of bankruptcy law is that it initiates a collective legal procedure by which all claims against the firm are settled in an orderly fashion (Baird and Jackson, 1985; Ang and Chua, 1980; Bulow and Shoven, 1978; White, 1980). However, critics argue that the common pool argument is overstated because in practice debtors react to threats of loss and dissipate assets prior to bankruptcy, leaving nothing to divide (Bowers, 1990, for empirical support, see LoPucki and Whitford, 1993, and Gilson, 1996). Others have argued that any ex-post collective action problem can be eliminated by the use of ex-ante optimal credit contracts (Adler, 1993), security devices (Picker, 1992) or by relying on the existing nonbankruptcy default rules of secured credit (Bowers, 1991). Another objective of bankruptcy law may be what is generally referred to as ‘discharge of the debtor’. Discharge, the doctrine that frees the debtor’s future income from the chain of previous debt, is a characteristic institution of British and American bankruptcy law, but is rarely encountered in continental law. Discharge was first introduced in England in the Statute of 1906, passed to protect honest bankrupts from the greed of their creditors and in particular to keep them from rotting away in jail. With the certificate of discharge the bankrupt was freed from his debts and allowed to keep a part of his estate to help him make a fresh start (Hoppit, 1987, pp. 19-24). Later the discharge of the debtor became an important chapter of American bankruptcy law and received a significant reinforcement under the Bankruptcy Reform Act of 1978. Discharge may be understood not only as a measure to help the honest debtor, but also as an efficient incentive to avoid asset concealment. Search and transaction costs may be reduced and the efficiency of the procedure is increased. Jackson (1985) uses analytics from psychology and economics to find support of the non waivable right of discharge in several of the characteristics of human behavior. Another justification would be that it eliminates the incentive structure that causes the debtor to become less productive once a large part of his wages start flowing to creditors. Discharge has also been approached as a supplement to the welfare system. The non waivable right to discharge discourages people to use assets that are essential to the minimal wellbeing. By prohibiting the use of welfare payments as collaterals, discharge law renders ‘necessary assets’ valueless (Jackson, 1986b; Posner, 1995, 1997). Also, it discourages high-risk behavior that would be induced by welfare. The right of discharge forces creditors to raise interest rates, because of the weaker position the creditors find themselves in, which discourages some debtors to engage in risky behavior that would be externalized by the taxpayer (Jackson, 1986b).
266
Bankruptcy Proceedings
7800
Some effects of discharge of the debtor remain controversial. Discharge seems to discriminate in favor of debtors with a relatively high stock of human capital and against bankrupts with a relatively high stock of physical capital. Physical assets - and their future returns - are appropriated by creditors. But the future returns of human capital - a substantial part of the debtor’s wages - remain the bankrupt’s property. Distribution of the costs of discharge is also controversial. Debtors, like creditors, want to minimize costs. The right to discharge increases the cost of credit. The fact that creditors will be prevented from collecting some of their debts will be reflected in higher interest rates. Higher risks for creditors will raise the interest rates (on the adverse selection and moral hazard effects of higher interest rates, see Stiglitz and Weiss, 1981). Creditors do not possess the relevant information in order to discriminate between lowrisk and high-risk debtors. Therefore, they will pass higher costs to all consumers. Part of these higher costs, caused by high-risk debtors, will therefore be passed on to low-risk, more reliable debtors. Although favored by those who already have a lot of debt (ex post), the non waivable right of discharge will (ex ante) be rejected by the vast majority of people (Dye, 1986). There is some debate among bankruptcy scholars whether a bankruptcy procedure should preserve the absolute priority of claims (Buckley, 1986; Adler, 1993; Triantis, 1992). Under the absolute priority rule each priority class is paid in full, to the extent that sufficient assets are available, before the next class is paid. General creditors, without security interests or priority status, receive payment if any assets are left over (for effeciency justifications of the instrument of security interests, see Scott, 1977; Jackson and Kronman, 1979; White, 1980, 1989; Buckley, 1986; Triantis, 1992, 1994; Adler, 1993; dissenting, Schwartz, 1981; LoPucki, 1994; see Chapter 1500 for an overview of the debate on the ‘secured credit puzzle’). If the structure of debt priority, as agreed upon by parties, could be violated within bankruptcy, people will be reluctant to invest (Meckling, 1977). Secured creditors, for example, paid for their specific security entitlement by accepting a lower rate of return and should, therefore, be enabled to retain the benefits of their original bargain by receiving an equivalent value for their collateral in bankruptcy (Scott, 1986). Critics argue that the absolute priority rule will induce management, acting on the behalf of shareholders, to engage in risky behavior when a company is close to bankruptcy (on entrenchment and investment incentives, see Chapter 1500, section 28). If things go badly creditors bear the losses. If the firm does well equity holders will reap the profits. Another objective of bankruptcy law is the redistribution among groups of claimants. Redistribution is promoted through the dynamics of a reorganization procedure (Eisenberg, 1989, p. 133; on the redistributive nature of the US bankruptcy code, see, for instance, Bowers, 1991). The
7800
Bankruptcy Proceedings
267
‘objective’ rationale would be that by preserving the going concern value of the company reorganization may enable creditors to capture a higher value than would be possible under liquidation (see Clark, 1981). Although Chapter 11 of the American Bankruptcy law is the best known rehabilitation procedure, most countries have already introduced reorganization procedures in their bankruptcy laws. The positive and negative aspects of reorganization have been widely discussed. Sections 9 and 10 of this chapter will deal with the reorganization-liquidation dilemma. Finally, according to Bufford (1994), bankruptcy serves an important role as a safety net for economies. It prevents secured creditors from collectively initiating a downward spiral of foreclosures and bank faillures which would result in worldwide economic depression, such as in 1933. From this viewpoint, bankruptcy protects imperfect markets and weak economies by allowing debtors to wait out an economic downturn.
4. Reallocation of Assets through Bankruptcy: The Costs of a Liquidation Procedure An efficient legal procedure should minimize social costs. There are three main costs to a liquidation procedure. First of all, the social value of specific - both physical and human - capital assets is reduced when the new allocation of productive resources takes place. Secondly, productive resources remain unemployed during the legal proceedings. Thirdly, a liquidation procedure involves certain litigation expenditures. The bankrupt firm can be sold piecemeal or as a going concern. In piecemeal liquidations, assets are sold in the market and employees move from a bankrupt firm to a more efficient one. This increases social productivity of both physical and human capital. However, part of the value of these capital goods and of employees’ human capital is lost in such a procedure. This loss of value is mainly due to the fact that the productivity of capital invested in a given asset, integrated within a production process, is reduced when this asset is sold piecemeal, as the market value of used capital goods does not reflect the discounted value of the asset’s expected yields in its original production process. Also, there can be a loss of human capital inasmuch as there is a loss of specific knowledge regarding the handling of specific assets under certain conditions. This loss of value of both physical and human capital is used as an argument in favor of reorganization and against liquidation. These costs are considerably lower when the bankrupt company is sold as a going concern. In a world of perfect information and perfect capital markets this would then be the best liquidation procedure for any firm
268
Bankruptcy Proceedings
7800
(Baird, 1986). Any individual or company interested in the insolvent firm would be able to raise all the necessary capital - even if the bankrupt firm is a big public corporation - to buy it. However, in a world of information costs and imperfect capital markets, it may prove very difficult to find partners or banks willing to offer enough capital to buy the firm - especially if it is a big corporation - and piecemeal liquidation will be the outcome of many bankruptcy proceedings of companies that would have survived under new ownership and management. The second cost is created by unemployment of productive resources. If bankruptcy implies that the firm is closed while its assets are being sold, assets will be left idle during the proceedings. The longer the duration of the procedure, the higher the social costs associated to it (on the administrative costs of corporate bankruptcy, Ang, Chua and McConnell, 1982). There is another source of social loss: the obsolescence of capital assets. Replacement value of high technology capital assets - computers, for instance - decreases every day. And again, the longer the duration of the procedure, the higher will be the social costs of unemployment of productive assets because of obsolescence will be. Litigation expenditures are also an important part of the social costs associated with bankruptcies. In any other legal procedure, higher expenses on legal services are assumed to increase the probability of a favorable decision from the court. However, in bankruptcy proceedings, the net value of the debtor’s estate cannot be increased through litigation. High litigation expenditures lower the total net value available for distribution among the creditors. Social costs of litigation in bankruptcy proceedings may be higher if these expenditures are partially paid by government through public subsidies. The overall positive external effect - a reduction of uncertainty and, therefore, reduction of future litigation - explains why partial subsidies paid by government may be efficient. But at the same time subsidies present lower costs to the litigators and thereby provide an incentive to increase litigation in the short run.
5. The Debtor in a Bankruptcy Procedure Originally, bankruptcy law was established to protect the creditor’s interests and proceedings were always initiated by a creditor’s petition. It was not until the nineteenth century when voluntary bankruptcy was introduced in most countries. At present, a substantial number of petitions are filed by debtors; and in some countries, with legal provisions generous to debtors, this number exceeds 50 percent (in Spain, for instance, during the period of
7800
Bankruptcy Proceedings
269
1982-86, debtors initiated more than 80 percent of all bankruptcy proceedings, see Cabrillo, 1986, pp. 75-76). The risk of bankruptcy provides a positive incentive to management. They want to avoid bankruptcy (it creates a bad reputation, and so on) and therefore it is in their own interest to prevent the firm from having large deficits. Both private and public sector enterprises can go bankrupt. Bankruptcies of public sector enterprises are extremely rare. In fact, the absence of the bankrupt threat is one of the most important differences in the incentives for efficient management of private and public enterprises. Normally, a bankruptcy proceeding finds its origin in a financial disequilibrium that compels the debtor to suspend payments. The financial structure of the firm, and more precisely the ratio liabilities/equity, is an important factor to determine the probability of an economic crisis of a firm that might end in bankruptcy. According to the Modigliani-Miller theorem (Modigliani and Miller, 1958), under certain assumptions, the market value of a firm is independent from its capital structure. The risk of insolvency, and therefore of bankruptcy, depends substantially on the value of its current liabilities relative to the value of its liquid assets. If the ratio liabilities/equity increases, the risk of bankruptcy will increase. Ceteris paribus, the rise of this ratio in firms will increase the number of bankruptcy proceedings. Managers and firm owners usually prefer to have debt as a significant part of the firm’s capital structure and not to finance its business just through equity. There are several reasons for this preference. First, a mixed capital structure allows different risks and different returns from the capital invested in the firm. In absence of default risk, the leverage effect of a higher amount of debt would allow higher returns to equity holders. But when default risk is introduced into the model, leverage is associated with a higher probability of bankruptcy. Managers and firm owners try to determine an optimal debt-equity ratio, taking into account both the profits of the leverage effect and the probability of bankruptcy. Secondly, governments are not neutral when it comes down to the assessment of firms’ capital structure. The corporation income tax is imposed on the net income of corporations. Net income is defined as revenues minus costs. This way the fiscal regime actually creates incentives to debt financing of corporations. It can also be argued that a capital structure based on both equity and debt, under the limited liability principle, allows managers and corporation owners to pass a part of the bankruptcy losses to creditors. Thus, in this respect, bankruptcy creates negative externalities. Rational creditors will discount the cost of these negative externalities - the value of the debt multiplied by the probability of default - and charge higher prices and interest rates - or the cost of insurance - to their customers. Debtors, as a
270
Bankruptcy Proceedings
7800
class, will internalize these externalities. In a world where information is imperfect, unreliable debtors, who have a higher probability of default than average, will pass a part of these costs to reliable debtors.
6. Creditors in a Bankruptcy Procedure Most credits or commercial deals involve a risk of default. Although risks are inevitable, they can be reduced through monitoring or transferred to a third party through insurance. Creditors may follow two different strategies when they face the risk of losses caused by bankruptcies. Self-insurance, where a fund to cover possible losses is created, may be one option. Banks and large companies employ self-insurance for bankruptcy losses by having a large number of customers which allows them to pool the risks. Another option is the purchase of credit insurance from an insurance company, which pools the risks of various firms. Such a service is commonly offered in Europe. Insurance companies that specialize in bankruptcy risks usually offer their customers informational services on the financial reliability of their potential clients. Firms that purchase this kind of insurance profit from the economies of scale which are generated by the large number of customers. Insurance companies often share their data on insolvent debtors or debtors with a high default risk. In a stable commercial relationship the risk assumed by the creditor may change at every moment and might be very different from the risk at the beginning of such a relationship. The basic problem for the creditor is how to adopt the most efficient strategy when the risk of losing his credit increases, due to the probability of bankruptcy of the debtor. When the debtor suspects that the probability of bankruptcy is rising, he may try to raise the total value of his debts in order to solve his short-run financial problems. The new debt may reduce the risk of default as it may be able to prevent bankruptcy in the short run. However, at the same time, the overall debt increases and there is some danger of ‘risk alternation’ - the debtor may behave in riskier fashion as a result of the additional obligation (see Kanda and Levmore, 1994). It is uncertain whether the product of the amount of credit times the risk of default will increase or decrease. In a world of perfect information the optimal strategy of a creditor would be to minimize the value of this product when making the decision to offer new credit to his client or to refrain from doing so. But in the real world information is imperfect and asymmetrical. The debtor can discriminate among creditors to help some of them and, at the same time, cause bigger losses to others. Furthermore, all credits are not equal in bankruptcy
7800
Bankruptcy Proceedings
271
proceedings. Creditors’ strategies are therefore more complex than they would be in the case of perfect information and the non-existence of secured credits. There are clear incentives for both the debtor and some creditors to reach agreements that are harmful to other creditors before bankruptcy proceedings begin. Creditors can raise the probability of getting their money back; and the debtor can maximize the expected value of his commercial relationship, discriminating in favor of those creditors that will be able to help him in other businesses. In most legal systems discriminated creditors can file a petition to the court for annulment of payments to other creditors or changes of unsecured credits into secured credits. Usually the formal declaration of bankruptcy has retrospective effect and annuls these agreements. These retrospective effects may impose high costs on both the owners and the managers of the bankrupt firm. Bankruptcy petitions can be used as a threat to force the debtor not to favor some specific creditors and harm others. These threats often play a significant role in creditors’ strategies as there is always uncertainty regarding the relevance of the retrospective effects. When a creditor files a bankruptcy petition, he usually tries to improve his position and recover at least part if his credits. He expects that, at the end of the bankruptcy proceeding the value of his recovered credits will be higher that the procedure costs he will have to pay. More precisely, a creditor will file a bankruptcy petition only if X.P / (1 + r)t > E , where X represents the value of the credit, P the percentage of the credit that he expects to recover if he wins and E the procedure expenditures. The very low value of P for unsecured creditors in many bankruptcy proceedings explains why many creditors decide not to go to court, even in cases where there are illegal agreements between the debtor and some creditors. However, some secured creditors - and especially insurance companies representing unsecured creditors - file the bankruptcy petition and go to court even in cases where the value of E is expected to be higher than the value of the recovered credits. The best explanation for this behavior is to qualify these creditors - especially insurance companies - as long-run utility maximizers. They are prepared to lose money in a single bankruptcy case if these losses allow them to build a reputation of going to court in cases of suspected fraud (Mitchell, 1993). Government can also exert influence on a creditor’s behavior. Firstly, the corporation tax reduces the creditors’ losses caused by bankruptcy. With this tax government shares the risks of companies. The deduction for losses against other income reduces the losses caused by other firms’ bankruptcies in the percentage of the corporation income tax that the company is obliged to pay.
272
Bankruptcy Proceedings
7800
A second result of the corporation income tax is its effect on risk behavior of companies. There is some dissension over the effects of the corporation income tax on risk taking; but most economist think that, if the tax is not progressive and there are no limitations in the magnitude of losses that can be offset, it increases risky behavior by firms. Under this assumption, we should expect two effects on creditors’ behavior. First, creditors should be ready to assume a higher risk and offer more credit to a debtor to help him avoid bankruptcy. Secondly, if there is uncertainty about the distribution of the debtor’s estate or fraud by the debtor, creditors would have an incentive to go to court to recover their credit. Assume that, according to the model sketched in the previous paragraph, when the creditor renounces to go to court he loses the total amount of his credit, X, but can lose X + E. Going to court to recover a credit in bankruptcy proceedings is, therefore, a risky decision, and, when assuming the previous conclusions about taxation and risk taking, we should expect an incentive to go to court as a result of the corporation income tax.
7. Employees in Bankruptcy Proceedings The foundations of current bankruptcy law were developed within an economic framework characterized by private contracts freely undertaken by all parties, often accompanied by only a low level of government control on economic activity. Such is the way that this institution is modeled even today in the majority of countries. However, it would be tantamount to turning a blind eye to reality not to acknowledge that important changes have taken place in the framework of bankruptcy law. Government control and intervention has modified the original concept of most commercial relationships. The position of employees in relation to their company has become very different from the relation of the firm with the rest of its creditors. Employees not only prefer payment of credits for non-paid salaries, but also expect the right to a part of the company assets as indemnity for the loss of their jobs. Some bankruptcy laws even allow employees to levy separate execution against the company by seizure of its assets to assure payment of these credits. The relationship between firms and employees can be explained in terms of the implicit contracts model. According to this approach, implicit contracts within the company-employee relationship protect the employees against fluctuations of their salary. Insurance premiums, a part of these wages, permit them to receive the corresponding indemnity if the situation were to become unfavorable.
7800
Bankruptcy Proceedings
273
When we assume that employees are risk averse, they would prefer to contract this implicit insurance policy as it guarantees them indemnity in case they lose their job when the company goes bankrupt. Therefore, the employee is willing to ‘sacrifice’ a given fraction of his salary for insurance premiums. The economic rationality of the lay-off compensation that employees receive in case of bankruptcy implies two requisites. In the first place, we assume that the employee suffers economic losses from losing his job when the firm is liquidated. Secondly, in the absence of alternatives on the market, the companies themselves are in the best position to play the role of insurer. The damages incurred by a employee when losing his job can be the result of several factors. First of all, transaction costs are inevitable when searching the job market. In a situation of prolonged disequilibrium in the labor market laid off employees may face long periods of unemployment. In some countries the law admits only two forms of lay-offs, either dismissal as a sanction or unjustified lay-off with indemnity. Economically, this indemnity reflects the price that the company pays in order to buy the employee’s ‘property rights’. Another possible way in which the employee might experience damages in case of bankruptcy is through the loss of his company-specific human capital. The employee might, for instance, have been an expert in working a specific machine that only the liquidated firm used. The loss of this type of human capital causes a reduction of the employee’s marginal productivity of labor and consequentially the wages he could negotiate with other companies. The second point to be considered is why the law compels companies to assume, at least partially, the risk of lay-offs. The answer to this question lies in the fact that no company in the market is willing to insure these risks. Thus, we are faced with a problem of risk allocation within the framework of a bilateral contractual relationship. According to this implicit contract model, throughout the period of contract duration, each employee creates a fund through payment of his implicit insurance premiums. The company has at its disposal the sum of the funds corresponding with all employees and acts as an insurance company in its relationship with them. Because of its capacity to reduce risks by means of pooling, it is best placed to provide the insurance in this contractual relationship. Consequently, it is in the interest of efficiency that the employees transfer at least partially their risk of unemployment to the company. In this perspective indemnity to employees in cases of liquidation of the firm in a bankruptcy procedure can be explained in terms of efficiency. In a similar way preferences in payments of both credits for debited salaries and lay-off indemnities can be explained. Preference in collection of
274
Bankruptcy Proceedings
7800
credit basically means an increase in the probability of a specific credit to be paid. If this probability is lower than 1 (as it is always in the case of bankruptcy), the variables to be taken into consideration by employees will no longer be the salary and the prospective indemnity for lay-off, but rather these variables multiplied by the probability of them being actually obtained. Any increase of this probability would permit the firm, therefore, to pay lower wages. Risk-averse employees would, expected values being equal, prefer combinations of higher probabilities and lower wages. With other creditors - banks, large companies or small traders - the risk of insolvencies in credits would be reflected in higher interest rates or higher prices charged to the clients. This would permit each creditor to create his own fund of selfinsurance or to contract an insurance policy for unpaid credits under the conditions offered by the insurance markets. Firms are in the best position to provide insurance to the employees. Preference in collection of credits in case of bankruptcy would thus lend weight to the argument that the transfer of risk from employees to companies is efficient in situations in which the profitability of collection is lower than 1.
8. The Liquidation-Reorganization Dilemma The reform of bankruptcy law has been widely discussed in Europe and the United States in recent years and one outcome of these debates has been the substantial development of the reorganization procedures for bankrupt companies. Advocates of reorganization present it as an efficient procedure that avoids many unnecessary liquidations and reduces the social costs of bankruptcy. However, critics of reorganization find it to be an inefficient procedure that deprives bankruptcy from its main objective, the reallocation of the debtor’s assets to more productive employments through creditors’ collective action. Reorganization, they argue, raises the social costs of default, instead of reducing them (see Section 9). Reorganization basically consists of the implementation of a rehabilitation plan in order to allow a firm to stay in business. Although the best known bankruptcy provisions for reorganization are those contained in Chapter 11 of the American Bankruptcy Code, similar provisions can be found in other countries. In Britain reorganization is referred to as ‘administration’, in Germany ‘vergleich’, in France it is termed ‘reglement aimable’ and ‘redressement judicaire’ and in Italy ‘administrazione controllata’. Each reorganization procedure has its own peculiarities. Some bankruptcy codes (the American Bankruptcy Code, for instance) permit the original management to stay in charge of the firm in most cases. Others, for example the British Insolvency Act of 1986, appoint an administrator to lead
7800
Bankruptcy Proceedings
275
the company during the bankruptcy proceedings. The role of creditors in the proceedings may also differ. Some procedures require the conversion of the debt into stock, while others offer diverse alternatives to the creditors. Credit priorities do not always receive the same treatment. Differences also exist between the voting systems on asset sales or postponement grants to the debtor. Employees play a relevant role in some reorganization proceedings, and almost none in others. But in every case, the main object of the procedure is to put the company on a solid base and to try to guarantee its survival. Should liquidation or reorganization be the main concern of courts and judges in bankruptcy cases? Some codes consider liquidation and reorganization of the firm as alternatives, without showing any special preference for one or the other. Other codes - such as the French law passed in 1985 - favor the rehabilitation of the firm. In any bankruptcy procedure it is essential to valuate the firm’s assets and liabilities in the most accurate way, since the decision between liquidation and reorganization usually depends on this valuation. Most bankruptcy codes are, however, very vague when dealing with the value of a company (on the problem of valuation which is inherent to the fictional sale under reorganization, see Bebchuk, 1988). Judges have therefore significant discretionary powers in a subject they usually know little about. For instance, there is substantial evidence to suggest that, in the United States, the valuation of bankrupt firms by judges in order to consider its possibilities for rehabilitation is systematically too high (Jackson, 1986a, p. 220). This concern has led a number of scholars to seek alternative procedures that provide market-based estimates of a firm’s value (see Section 10). There are two main methods to valuate an insolvent firm: the balance method and the feasibility method. The balance method is static. It uses the market value of assets and liabilities in order to determine whether the company has a positive or negative net worth. A negative net worth would imply liquidation, while a positive net worth would pave the way for reorganization. This method has two inherent problems: first, there is the usual problem with valuation of equipments and inventories when they may have to be sold in the short run. This possibility requires that these evaluations should be made as cautious as possible. For instance, if inventories can be valued at the original cost or at the present market value, the lowest one should be used. Second, the fact that there is a net worth does not guarantee the future survival of the firm in the market. A company whose net worth is positive because it owns expensive equipment or valuable buildings should be liquidated if there is no demand for its product in the market.
276
Bankruptcy Proceedings
7800
The feasibility method is dynamic. It does not focus on the static value of the firm’s assets and liabilities but rather on the probability of survival that a reorganized company would have in a specific market. According to this method a firm should be rehabilitated if the discounted value of its future returns flow is expected to be positive. There are two problems with this method. First of all, the subjective judgements, unavoidable in these evaluations, permit different interest groups to seek rents (more on this in the following section of this article). The second problem is the question how to distribute the stock or debts of the reorganized company to the creditors, when the firm is rehabilitated. However, the use of either method, does not exclude the application of the other. Assume a bankrupt company proposes a reorganization plan. In order to evaluate the plan a feasibility study should be made. If the court opinionated that the company can be rehabilitated the plan will be implemented and the assets can be evaluated as parts of an ongoing business. If, however, the court should not make a feasibility finding, the court should opt for liquidation. In that case the assets should then be valued according to their market value.
9. Why Reorganization? American data from the late 1980s show that as many as nine out of ten small and middle-sized firms fail after going into a Chapter 11 reorganization (for data on firms under reorganization, see Franks and Torous, 1989). Italian ‘administrazione controllata’ has been criticized as a useless and expensive prologue to liquidation or even as a procedure that anaesthetizes creditors. In France the 1985 law is not working as was hoped. And in Britain, where ‘administration’ has been considered to be an improvement of the old bankruptcy law, its relative success has been due to a most efficient system of liquidation that allows the new managers to sell the profitable divisions of the bankrupt firm for better prices. Bankruptcy scholars claim that reorganization is time-consuming, that it involves high administrative costs and often reduces the company’s value (Baird, 1986; Bradley, 1992; Cutler and Summers, 1988; Lopucki and Whitford, 1990, 1993 and Weiss, 1990). It has been debated on philosophical, political and economic grounds because of its role in increasing the accessibility and attractiveness of bankruptcy (DiPieto and Katz, 1983; Lunnie, 1984; Oswald, 1984; for data on the increase in the incidence of business bankruptcy in the United States since the passage of Chapter 11, see Johnson, 1986, p. 668) . Efficiency arguments fail to explain why so many firms with such low probabilities of survival are being reorganized. The existence of interest
7800
Bankruptcy Proceedings
277
groups and rent-seeking behavior, often disguised as public interest efforts, provide one possible explanation. A firm may be conceived as a framework of interests and property rights. Property implies three different rights over the firm: the right to control it; the ownership of the firm’s assets; and the right to take possession of the firm’s profits. According to a complex net of legal provisions and contracts owners have to share these rights with creditors, employees and the government. Discussions over priorities in the use of these rights are a characteristic feature of bankruptcy procedure. Business experience reveals that the preference for reorganization or liquidation is often determined by the property right framework, as defined by law. The interests of secured creditors may be very different from those of unsecured creditors when faced with a choice between liquidation or reorganization. Employees and unions may think that reorganization is the most beneficial outcome for their interests. The incumbent managers may prefer reorganization if the procedure allows them to stay in charge of the reorganized firm (Gilson, 1990; on the motivation of managers to initiate a bankruptcy proceeding, see Baird, 1991; Berkovitz, Israel and Zender, 1993; Rose-Ackerman, 1991). They might be opposed to reorganization if it seems likely that an external administrator will be appointed to lead the firm. All these property rights and interests collide in bankruptcy procedures and each group employs its own strategies. Their relative success will depend on the value of their credits, the nature of the applicable bankruptcy law and the public support they can secure for their demands. Suppose that employees believe - which they almost always do - that reorganization is the most convenient outcome for them. They will follow a strategy that puts pressure on decision makers, local politicians and the media, in order to keep the firm in business. Some laws, like the French bankruptcy code of 1985, goes one step further and assigns an active role to employees in the negotiations. Public choice and rent-seeking models (see, Buchanan, Tollison and Tullock, 1980) offer plausible explanations for the possible success of this strategy and account for the public subsidies that some companies receive in case of reorganization. It is quite common to present the liquidation-reorganization dilemma as a private vs. public interest problem. The complex framework of property rights and interests should be enlarged to include some kind of public interest in the survival of the bankrupt company. Unemployment or deindustrialization in a depressed area, for instance, are the most common arguments which are advanced to justify the public interest in avoiding the liquidation of insolvent private firms. From an efficiency perspective it may be hard to justify these arguments. Bankruptcy law is not the best instrument to deal with problems such as unemployment or deindustrialization. There is
278
Bankruptcy Proceedings
7800
no reason to consider the interests of unemployed employees or local interest groups more ‘public’ or ‘social’ than the welfare of the creditors, the taxpayers or the whole society - which will eventually pay for the misallocation of production factors. The costs of liquidation and reorganization are often misperceived. It may be easy to estimate the shortrun social costs of the liquidation of a firm, especially in cases of high rates of unemployment. It is, however, more difficult to assert the long-run costs of an inefficient allocation of the social production factors. These long-run costs are usually downgraded by the public opinion, and public interest arguments often prevail over the efficiency arguments. Thus, the dilemma of reorganization is that, while it may allow some efficient firms to continue, it facilitates the reorganization of inefficient firms that should be liquidated (White, 1989, pp. 136-137).
10. Alternative Procedures The bargaining based-approach of reorganization, such as found in Chapter 11 of the US Bankruptcy Code, has been criticized extentsively in the literature. Equity holders, have been demonstrated to extract significant value, even in cases where the debt increased the value of the reorganization value (Franks and Torous, 1989). The power of equity holders to block or delay the approval of a reorganization plan would bring about deviations from contractual priority (on the deviations from contractual priority under the existing rules, see Eberhart, Moore and Roenfeldt, 1999; Weiss, 1990; for a formalized model on the mechanisms that underlie the bargaining process, see Bebchuk and Chang, 1992; Baird and Picker, 1991). 10.1 Auctions Alternative solutions to the bargaining based-approach have been suggested to improve the alleged poor results of the reorganization procedure. One possible alternative is to merge the liquidation and reorganization procedures. Several proposals follow this path. It would be possible to sell every bankrupt firm as a going concern, free of debt and pay the creditors, according to the absolute priority rule, with the proceeds. Baird (1986) and Jackson (1986a) argue that bankruptcy reorganizations should be eliminated and replaced by a mandatory auction of the failed firm. (The merits (Hansen and Randall, 1998; Schleifer and Vishny, 1992) and imperfections (Baird, 1993; Cramton and Schwartz, 1991) of an auction regime have received consideration in the litrature.) Roe (1983) suggests an initial public offering of 10 percent of the firms’s new equity on the market to provide the market’s estimate of the value of the firm.
7800
Bankruptcy Proceedings
279
10.2 Options Other proposals suggest that bankruptcy should involve an automatic financial restructuring, where all debts would be converted into equity. The decision whether to liquidate or reorganize would then be left to the incumbent management (Bebchuk, 1988). The Aghion-Hart-Moore procedure is considered to be one of the most interesting alternatives advanced in the literature the past ten years (Aghion, Hart and Moore, 1992, 1994, 1995). This procedure, drawing upon the innovative mechanical scheme of distribution by Bebchuk (1988), consists of cancellation of all of the company’s debt and to offer the creditors the stock of the new all-equity company. The creditors become shareholders in the new all-equity company. (For a critique on the debt-equity swap and the AH-M scheme, see Bufford, 1994, pp. 844-846.) A second version of the model proposes to leave the status of secured creditors unaltered if the value of the collateral is higher than these credits. Only unsecured credits would be transferred into debt. The essence of the procedure remains unaltered. In both cases the bankrupt company becomes solvent and creditors take the decisions concerning the firm as shareholders with voting rights. A trustee would supervise the process, solicit cash and noncash bids for the new all-equity company and allocate the right to shares in this company. In the final step the shareholders vote to select the various cash and noncash bids. These, and other new proposals can certainly add to improved bankruptcy proceedings and to increase the efficiency of bankruptcy law.
11. Conclusion It is impossible to know how bankruptcy law will change in the next few decades. Especially in Europe, the predisposition in favor of reorganization procedures in legislative reform seem to be weakened. For instance, in France, the country with one of the most reorganization-favored bankruptcy codes in Europe, new reforms are initiated to reduce the excessive prorehabilitation bias of the 1985 law. Changing the foundations of traditional bankruptcy law has proven to be much more complicated than expected by most reformers.
Acknowledgements We would like to thank two anonymous referees for fruitful comments and suggestions on an earlier draft.
280
Bankruptcy Proceedings
7800
Bibliography on Bankruptcy Proceedings (7800) Adler, Barry E. (1992), ‘Bankruptcy and Risk Allocation’, 77 Cornell Law Review, 439ff ff. Adler, Barry E. (1993a), ‘An Equity Agency Solution to the Bankruptcy Priority Puzzle’, 22 Journal of Legal Studies, 73-98. Adler, Barry E. (1993b), ‘Financial and Political Theories of American Corporate Bankruptcy’, 45 Stanford Law Review, 311 ff. Aghion, Philippe, Hart, Oliver D. and Moore, John (1992), ‘The Economics of Bankruptcy Reform’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 523-546. Aghion, Philippe, Hart, Oliver D. and Moore, John (1994), ‘Improving Bankruptcy Procedure’, 72 Washington University Law Quarterly, 811-827. Aghion, Philippe, Hart, Oliver D. and Moore, John (1995), ‘Insolvency Reform in the UK: A Revised Proposal’, 11 Insolvency Law and Practice, 4-11. Aivazian, Varouj A. and Callen, Jeffrey L. (1983), ‘Reorganization in Bankruptcy and the Issue of Strategic Risk’, 7 Journal of Banking and Finance, 119-133. Altman, Edward I. (1969), ‘Bankrupt Firms Equity Securities as an Investment Alternative’, 25 Financial Analysts Journal, 129-135. Altman, Edward I. (1984), ‘A Further Empirical Investigation of the Bankruptcy Cost Question’, 39 Journal of Finance, 1067 ff. Ang, James S. and Chua, Jess H. (1980), ‘Coalitions, the Me-First Rule, and the Liquidation Decision’, 11 Bell Journal of Economics, 355-359. Ang, James S., Chua, Jess H. and McConnell, John J. (1982), ‘The Administrative Costs of Corporate Bankruptcy’, 37 Journal of Finance, 219-226. Apilado, Vincent P., Dauten, Joel J. and Smith, Douglas E. (1978), ‘Personal Bankruptcies’, 7 Journal of Legal Studies, 371-392. Aumann, Robert J. and Maschler, Michael (1985), ‘Game Theoretic Analysis of a Bankruptcy Problem from the Talmud’, 36 Journal of Economic Theory, 195-213. Baird, Douglas G. (1986), ‘The Uneasy Case for Corporate Reorganization’, 15 Journal of Legal Studies, 127-147. Baird, Douglas G. (1987a), ‘A World Without Bankruptcy’, Law and Contemporary Problems, 173 ff. Baird, Douglas G. (1987b), ‘Loss Distribution, Forum Shopping and Bankruptcy. A Reply to Warren’, 54 University of Chicago Law Review, 815-834. Baird, Douglas G. (1991), ‘The Initiation Problem in Bankruptcy’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 223-232. Baird, Douglas G. (1992), The Elements of Bankruptcy, New York, Foundation. Baird, Douglas G. (1993), ‘Revisiting Auctions in Chapter 11', 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 633-653. Baird, Douglas G. and Jackson, Thomas H. (1984), ‘Corporate Reorganizations and the Treatment of Diverse Ownership Interests: A Comment on Adequate Protection of Secured Creditors in Bankruptcy’, 51 University of Chicago Law Review, 97-130. Baird, Douglas G. and Jackson, Thomas H. (1985), Cases, Problems and Materials on Bankruptcy, Boston, Little Brown. Baird, Douglas G. and Jackson, Thomas H. (1987), Cases, Problems, and Materials on Security Interests in Personal Property, Mineola, NY, Foundation Press, 889 p.
7800
Bankruptcy Proceedings
281
Baird, Douglas G. and Jackson, Thomas H. (1988), ‘Bargaining after the Fall and the Contours of the Absolute Priority Rule’, 55 University of Chicago Law Review, 738-789. Baird, Douglas G. and Picker, Ronald C. (1991), ‘A Simple Noncooperative Bargaining Model of Corporate Reorganizations’, 20 Journal of Legal Studies, 311-349. Bebchuck, Lucian Arye (1988), ‘A New Approach to Corporate Reorganizations’, 101 Harvard Law Review, 775-804. Bebchuck, Lucian Arye and Chang, H. (1992), ‘Bargaining and the Devision of Value in Corporate Reorganization’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics and Organiszation, 253-79. Bernanke, Ben S. (1981), ‘Bankruptcy, Liquidation and Recession’, 71 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 135-159. Berkovitch, E., Israel, R. and Zender, J. (1993), The Design of Bankruptcy Law: A Case for Management Bias in Bankruptcy Reorganizations, Mimeo, University of Michigan. Betker, Brian L. (1995), ‘Management’s Incentives, Equity’s Bargaining Power and Deviations from Absolute Priority Rule in Chapter 11 Bankruptcies’, 68 Journal of Business, 161-183. Bisbal, Joaquím (1986), La Empresa en Crisis y el Derecho de Quiebras (The Crisis of the Firm and Bankruptcy Law), Bolonia, Real Colegio de España, 383 p. Bisbal Méndez, Joaquim (1994), ‘La Insoportable Levedad del Derecho Concursal (The Unbearable Lightness of Bankruptcy Law)’, 214 Revista de Derecho Mercantil, 843-872. Bowers, James W. (1990), ‘Groping and Coping in the Shadow of Murphy’s Law: Bankruptcy Theory and the Elementary Economics of Failure’, 88 Michigan Law Review, 2097 ff. Bowers, James W. (1991), ‘Whither What Hits the Fan? Murphy’s Law, Bankruptcy Theory, and the Elementary Economics of Loss Distribution’, 26 Georgia Law Review, 27 ff. Bowers, James W. (1993), ‘The Fantastic Wisconsylvania Zero-Bureaucratic-Cost School of Bankruptcy Theory: A Comment’, 91 Michigan Law Review, 1773 ff. Bowers, James W. (1994), ‘Rehabilitation, Redistribution or Dissipation: The Evidence for Choosing Among Bankruptcy Hypotheses’, 72 Washington University Law Quarterly, 955 ff. Bowers, James W. (1995), ‘Of Bureaucrats’ Brothers-in-Law and Bankruptcy Taxes: The Article 9 Filing System and the Market for Information’, 79 Minnesota Law Review, 721 ff. Boyes, William J. and Faith, Roger L. (1986), ‘Some Effects of the Bankruptcy Reform Act of 1978', 29 Journal of Law and Economics, 139-149. Bradley, Michael D. (1992), ‘The Untenable Case for Chapter 11', 101 Yale Law Journal, 1043-1095. Bratton, Dale (1985), ‘Note: The California Agricultural Producer’s Lien, Processing Company Insolvencies, and Federal Bankruptcy Law: An Evaluation and Alternative Methods of Protecting Farmers’, 36 Hastings Law Journal, 609-644. Brimmer, Andrew (1981), ‘Economic Implications of Personal Bankruptcies’, 35 Personal Finance Law Quarterly Report, 187-191.
282
Bankruptcy Proceedings
7800
Buckley, F.H. (1986), ‘The Bankruptcy Priority Puzzle’, 72 Virginia Law Review, 1393-1442. Bufford, Samuel L. (1994), ‘What’s Right about Bankruptcy and Wrong About it’s Critics’, 72 Washington University Law Quarterly, 829-848. Bulow, Jeremy I. and Shoven, John B. (1978), ‘The Bankruptcy Decision’, 9 Bell Journal of Economics, 437-456. Cabrillo, Francisco (1986), ‘Adam Smith on Bankruptcy Law? New Law and Economics in the Glasgow Lectures?’, 8(1) History of Economics Society Bulletin, 40-41. Cabrillo, Francisco (1987), Análisis Económico del Derecho Concursal Español (An Economic Analysis of Spanish Bankruptcy Law), Madrid, Fundación Juan March. Cabrillo, Francisco (1989), Quiebra y Liquidación de Empresas (Bankruptcy and Closing Down of Firms), Madrid, Unión Editorial, 151 p. Cabrillo, Francisco (1993), ‘La teoría económica de la reorganización de las empresas en quiebra (Economic Theory of the Reorganization of Bankrupty Firms)’, 58 Economistas, 62-67. Carlson, David Gray (1987), ‘Is Fraudulent Conveyance Law Efficient?’, 9 Cardozo Law Review, 643-683. Carlson, David Gray (1987), ‘Philosophy in Bankruptcy’, 85 Michigan Law Review, 1341-1389. Chiang, Raymond C. and Finkelstein, John M. (1982), ‘An Incentive Framework for Evaluating the Impact of Loan Provisions on Default Risk’, 49 Southern Economic Journal, 962-969. Chow, Garland and Gritta, Richard D. (1988), ‘Estimating Bankruptcy Risks Facing Class I and II Motor Carriers: An Industry-Specific Approach’, 55 Transportation Practitioners Journal, 352-363. Clark, E. (1981), ‘The Interdisciplinary Study of Legal Evolution’, 90 Yale Law Journal, 12521254. Cooter, Robert D. (1985), ‘Defective Warnings, Remote Causes, and Bankruptcy: Comment on Schwartz’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 737-750. Countryman, Vern (1985), ‘The Concept of Voidable Preference in Bankruptcy’, 38 Vanderbilt Law Review, 713-828. Curme, Michael and Kahn, Lawrence (1990), ‘The Impact of the Threat of Bankruptcy on the Structure of Compensation’, 8 Journal of Labor Economics, 419-447. Cutler, David M. and Summers, Lawrence H. (1988), ‘The Costs of Conflict Resolution and Financial Distress: Evidence from the Texaco-Pennzoil Litigation’, 19 Rand Journal of Economics, 157-172. Daigle, Katherine H. and Maloney, Michael T. (1994), ‘Residual Claims in Bankruptcy: An Agency Theory Explanation’, 37 Journal of Law and Economics, 157-192. DiPieto and Katz (1983), ‘Chapter 11 of The Bankruptcy Code-Use or Abuse?’, 57 Connecticut Bar Journal. Domowitz, Ian and Eovaldi, Thomas L. (1993), ‘The Impact of the Bankruptcy Reform Act of 1978 on Consumer Bankruptcy’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 803-835. Dye, Ronald A. (1986), ‘An Economic Analysis of Bankruptcy Statutes’, 24 Economic Inquiry, 417-428. Easterbrook, F.H. (1990), ‘Is Corporate Bankruptcy Efficient?’, 27 Journal of Financial Economics, 411-18.
7800
Bankruptcy Proceedings
283
Eberhart, A.C., Moore, W.T. and Roenfeldt, R.L. (1990), ‘Security Pricing and Deviations from the Absolute Priority Rule in Bankruptcy Proceedings, 45 Journal of Finance, 1457-70. Eisenberg, Theodore (1981), ‘Bankruptcy Law in Perspective’, 28 UCLA Law Review, 953-999. Eisenberg, Theodore (1987), ‘Bankruptcy in the Administrative State’, 50(2) Law and Contemporary Problems, 3-52. Eisenberg, Theodore (1989), ‘Commentary on “On the Nature of Bankruptcy”: Bankruptcy and Bargaining’, 75 Virginia Law Review, 205-218. Eisenberg, Theodore and Tagashira, Shoichi (1994), ‘Should We Abolish Chapter 11? The Evidence from Japan’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 111-157. Fisher, Timothy C.G. and Martel, Jocelyn (1995), ‘The Creditors’ Financial Reorganization Decision: New Evidence from Canadian Data’, 11 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 112-126. Fletcher, Ian F. (1984), ‘Bankruptcy Notices: Perils and Perplexities’, Journal of Business Law, 355-357. Franks, Julian and Torous, Walter (1989), ‘An Empirical Investigation of U.S. Firms in Reorganization’, 44 Journal of Finance, 747-769. Franks, Julian and Torous, Walter (1994), ‘A Comparison of Financial Recontracting in Distressed Exchanges and Chapter 11 Reorganizations’, 35 Journal of Financial Economics, 349-370. Frost, Christopher (1992), ‘Running the Asylum: Governance Problems in Bankruptcy Reorganizations’, 34 Arizona Law Review, 89 ff. Frost, Christopher (1993), ‘Organizational Form, Misappropriation Risk and the Substantive Consolidation of Corporate Groups’, 44 Hastings Law Journal, 449 ff. Frost, Christopher (1995a), ‘The Bankruptcy Reform Act of 1994 and the Balance of Power in Corporate Reorganizations’, Annual Survey Bankruptcy Law, 297 ff. Frost, Christopher (1995b), ‘Bankruptcy Redistributive Policies and the Limits of the Judicial Process’, 74 North Carolina Law Review, 449 ff. Gertner, Robert H. and Scharfstein, David (1991), ‘A Theory of Workouts and the Effects of Reorganization Law’, 46 Journal of Financial Economics, 1189 ff. Gilson, S. (1988), ‘Management Turnover and Financial Distress’, 25 Journal of Financial Economics, 241-62. Gilson, S. (1990), ‘Bankruptcy, Boards and Blockholders’, 27 Journal of Financial Economics, 355-378. Gilson, S. (1991), ‘Managing Default: Some Evidence on how Firms Choose between Workouts and Chapter 11’, 4 Journal of Applied Corporate Finance, 62-70. Gilson, S., John, K. and Lang, L. (1989), ‘Troubled Debt Restructuring: An Empirical Study of Private Reorganization of Firms in Default’, 26 Journal of Financial Economics, 315-353. Golbe, D.L. (1981), ‘The Effects of Imminent Bankruptcy on Stockholder Risk Preferences and Behavior’, 12 Bell Journal of Economics, 321-328. Goldberg, Victor P. (1985), ‘Economic Aspects of Bankruptcy Law: Comment’, 141 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 99-103. Guatri, Luigi (1986), Crisi e Risanamento delle Imprese (Crisis and Reorganization of the Firms), Milano, Giuffrè, 339 p.
284
Bankruptcy Proceedings
7800
Guttentag, Jack and Herring, Richard (1982), ‘The Insolvency of Financial Institutions. Assessments and Regulatory Disposition’, in Wachtel, P. (ed), Crisis in Economic and Fianncial Structure, Lexington, MA, Heath. Hansen, R.G. and Randall, S. Thomas (1998), ‘Auctions in Bankruptcy: Theoretical Analysis and Practical Guidance’, 18(2) International Review of Law and Economics, 159-186. Harris, Richard A. (1978), ‘The Consequences of Costly Default’, 16 Economic Inquiry, 477-496. Harris, Steven (1982), ‘A Reply to Theodore Eisenberg’s Bankruptcy Law in Perspective’, 30 UCLA Law Review, 327-365. Hart, Oliver D. (1995), Firms, Contracts and Financial Structure, Oxford, Clarendon. Hax, Herbert (1985), ‘Economic Aspects of Bankruptcy Law’, 141 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 80-98. Hudson, John (1990), ‘The Corporate Bankruptcy Decision: Comment’, 4 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 209-211. Hudson, John (1992), ‘The Impact of the New Bankruptcy Code upon the Average Liability of Bankrupt Firms’, 16 Journal of Banking and Finance, 351-371. Ingberman, Daniel E. (1994), ‘Triggers and Priority: An Integrated Model of the Effects of Bankruptcy Law on Overinvestment and Underinvestment’, 72(3) Washington University Law Quarterly, 1341-1377. Iwicki, Matthew L. (1990), ‘Accounting for Relational Financing in the Creditors’ Ex ante Bargain: Beyond the General Average Model’, 76 Virginia Law Review, 815-851. Jackson, Thomas H. (1982), ‘Bankruptcy, Non-Bankruptcy Entitlements, and the Creditors’ Bargain’, 91 Yale Law Journal, 857-907. Jackson, Thomas H. (1984), ‘Avoiding Powers in Bankruptcy’, 36 Stanford Law Review, 725-787. Jackson, Thomas H. (1985a), ‘The Fresh-Start Policy in Bankruptcy Law’, 98 Harvard Law Review, 1393-1448. Jackson, Thomas H. (1985b), ‘Translating Assets and Liabilities to the Bankruptcy Forum’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 73-114. Jackson, Thomas H. (1986a), The Logic and Limits of Bankruptcy Law, Cambridge (MA), Harvard University Press, 287 p. Jackson, Thomas H. (1986b), ‘Of Liquidation, Continuation, and Delay: An Analysis of Bankruptcy Policy and Nonbankruptcy Rules’, 60 American Bankruptcy Law Journal, 399-428. Jackson, Thomas H. (1993), ‘Revisiting Auctions in Chapter 11: Comment’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 655-696. Jackson, Thomas, H. and Kronman, Anthony T. (1979), ‘Secured Financing and Priorities Among Creditors’, 88 Yale Law Journal, 1143-1182. Jackson, Thomas H. and Scott, Robert E. (1989), ‘On the Nature of Bankruptcy: An Essay on Bankruptcy Sharing and the Creditors’ Bargain’, 75 Virginia Law Review, 155-204. Jensen, M. (1991), ‘Corporate Control and the Politics of Finance’, 4 Journal of Apllied Corporate Finance, 13-33. Johnson, Steven B. (1986), ‘Bankruptcy Reform and Its International Competitive Implications’, 9 Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy, 667-681.
7800
Bankruptcy Proceedings
285
Kanda, Hideki and Levmore, Saul (1994), ‘Explaining Creditor Priorities’, 80 Virginia Law Review, 2103-2154. Kelly, Thomas O. III (1983), ‘Compensation for Time Value as Part of the Adequate Protection during the Automatic Stay in Bankruptcy’, 50 University of Chicago Law Review, 305-325. Korobkin, Donald R. (1991), ‘Rehabilitating Values: A Jurisprudence of Bankruptcy’, 91 Columbia Law Review, 717-789. Landers, Jonathan M. (1975), ‘A Unified Approach to Parent, Subsidiairy and Affiliate Questions in Bankruptcy’, 42 University of Chicago Law Review, 589-652. Leff, Arthur A. (1970), ‘Injury, Ignorance and Spite - the Dynamics of Coercive Collection’, 80 Yale Law Journal, 1-46. Reprinted in Kronman, Anthony T. and Posner, Richard A. (eds), The Economics of Contract Law, Boston, Little Brown, 1979, 175-181. Levmore, Saul and Kanda, Hideki (1994), ‘Explaining Creditor Priorities’, 80 Virginia Law Review, 2103-2154. Lopucki, Lynn M. (1982), ‘A General Theory of the Dynamics of the State Remedies/Bankruptcy System’, 58 Wisconsin Law Review, 311-372. Lopucki, Lynn M. (1983), ‘The Debtor in Full Control. Systems Failure notwithstanding Chapter 11 of the Bankruptcy Code?’, 57 American Bankruptcy Law Journal, 99-126. Lopucki, Lynn M. (1994), ‘The Unsecured Creditor’s Bargain’, 80 Virginia Law Review, 18871965. Lopucki, Lynn M. and Whitford, William C. (1990), ‘Bargaining over Equity’s Share in the Bankruptcy Reorganization of Large, Publicly Held Companies’, 139 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 125-196. Lopucki, Lynn and Whitford,William C (1991), ‘Venue Choice and Forum Shopping in the Bankruptcy Reorganization of Large, Publicly Held Companies’, 11 Wisconsin Law Review. Lopucki, Lynn M. and Whitford, William C. (1993), ‘Corporate Governance in the Bankruptcy Reorganization of Large, Publicly Held Companies’, 141 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 699-800. Lopucki, Lynn M. and George G. Triantis (1994), ‘A Systems Approach to Comparing U.S. and Canadian Reorganization of Financially Distressed Companies’, 35 Harvard International Law Journal, 268-343. McCoid, John C. II (1981), ‘Bankruptcy, Preferences, and Efficiency: An Expression of Doubt’, 67 Virginia Law Review, 249-273. Meckling, William H. (1977), ‘Financial Markets, Default and Bankruptcy: The Role of the State’, 41(4) Law and Contemporary Problems, 13-38. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1995), ‘Das Kapital: Solvency Regulation of the American Business Enterprise’, University of Chicago Law and Economics Working Paper. Miller, Merton H. (1977), ‘The Wealth Transfers and Bankruptcy: Some Illustrative Examples’, 41(4) Law and Contemporary Problems, 39-46. Mitchell, Jean (1993), ‘Creditor Passivity and Bankruptcy: Implications for Economic Reform’, in Mayer, C. and Vives, X. (eds), Capital Markets and Financial Intermediation, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Modigliani, Franco and Miller, Merton H. (1958), ‘The Cost of Capital, Corporation Finance and the Theory of Investment’, 48 American Economic Review, 261-297.
286
Bankruptcy Proceedings
7800
Morris, C. Robert, Jr (1970), ‘Bankruptcy Law Reform: Preferences, Secret Liens and Floating Liens’, 54 Minnesota Law Review, 737-774. Nelson, Philip B. (1979), ‘Contracts Between a Firm and Its Constituents during Bankruptcy Crises’, 13 Journal of Economic Issues, 583-604. Nelson, Philip (1981), Corporations in Crisis: Behavioral Observations for Bankruptcy Policy, New York, Praeger. Oswald (1984), ‘The Effect of Chapter 11 on Collective Bargaining’, 35 Lab. Law Journal. Peterson, Richard L. and Aoki, Kiyomi (1984), ‘Bankruptcy Filings before and after Implementation of the Bankruptcy Reform Law’, 36 Journal of Economics and Business, 95-105. Posner, Eric, A. (1995), ‘Contract Law in the Welfare State: A Defense of the Unconscionabilty Doctrine, Usury Laws, and Related Limitations to Freedom of Contract’, 24 Journal of Legal Studies, 307-08. Posner, Eric A. (1997), ‘The Political Economy of the Bankruptcy Reform Act of 1978', 96 Michigan Law Review. Rasmussen, Robert K. (1992), ‘Debtor’s Choice: A Menu Approach to Corporate Bankruptcy’, 71 Texas Law Review, 51 ff. Rasmussen, Robert K. (1994), ‘The Ex ante Effects of Bankruptcy Reform on Investment Incentives’, 72 Washington University Law Quarterly, 1159 ff. Rea, Samuel A., Jr (1984), ‘Arm-breaking, Consumer Credit, and Personal Bankruptcy’, Economic Inquiry, 188-208. Roe, Mark J. (1983), ‘Bankruptcy and Debt: A New Model for Corporate Reorganization’, 83 Columbia Law Review, 527-602. Roe, Mark J. (1989), ‘Commentary on “On the Nature of Bankruptcy”: Bankruptcy, Priority, and Economics’, 75 Virginia Law Review, 219-240. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1991), ‘Risk Taking and Ruin: Bankruptcy and Investment Choice’, 20 Journal of Legal Studies, 277-310. Rowley, Charles, A.I. Ogus (1984), Prepayments and Insolvency, London, Office of Fair Trading. Sayag, Alain and Serbat, Henri (1982), L’Application du Droit de la Faillite. Eléments pour un Bilan (The Application of Bankruptcy Law. Data for an Evaluation), Paris, Librairies Techniques. Schleifer, A. and Vishny, Robert W. (1986), ‘Liquidation Values and Debt Capacity: A Market Equilibrium Approach’, 47 Journal of Finance, 1343-1366. Schleifer, A. and Vishny, R.W. (1992), ‘Liquidation Values and Debt Capacity: A Market Equilibrum Approach’, 47 Journal of Finance, 1343-66. Schwartz, Alan (1981), ‘Security Interests and Bankruptcy Priorities: A Review of Current Theories’, 10 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-37. Schwartz, Alan (1985), ‘Products Liability, Corporate Structure, and Bankruptcy: Toxic Substances and the Remote Risk Relationship’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 689-736. Schwartz, Alan (1993), ‘Bankruptcy Workouts and Debt Contracts’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 595-632. Schwartz, Alan (1997), ‘Contracting About Bankruptcy’, 13 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 127-146. Scott, James H., Jr. (1977), 'Bankruptcy, Secured Debt, and Optimal Capital Structure', 32 Journal of Finance, 1-19.
7800
Bankruptcy Proceedings
287
Scott, Robert E. (1986), ‘Through Bankruptcy with the Creditors’ Bargain Heuristic’, 53 University of Chicago Law Review, 690-708. Scott, Robert E. (1989), ‘Sharing the Risks of Bankruptcy: Timbers, Ahlers, and Beyond’, Columbia Business Law Review, 183-194. Shepard, Lawrence (1984), ‘Personal Failures and the Bankruptcy Reform Act of 1978', 27 Journal of Law and Economics, 419-437. Shiers, Alden F. and Williamson, Daniel P. (1987), ‘Nonbusiness Bankruptcies and the Law: Some Empirical Results’, 21 Journal of Consumer Affairs, 277-292. Slain, John J. and Kripke, Homer (1973), ‘The Interface between Securities Regulation and Bankruptcy: Allocating the Risk of Illegal Securities Issuance between Securityholders and the Issuer’s Creditors’, 48 New York University Law Review, 261-300. Spier, Kathryn E. and Sykes, Alan O. (1996), Capital Structure, Priority Rules, and the Settlement of Civil Claims, Mimeo, August 1996. Stern, Jeffrey (1990), ‘Note: Failed Markets and Failed Solutions: The Unwitting Formulation of the Corporate Reorganization Technique’, 90 Columbia Law Review, 783 ff. Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1972), ‘Some Aspects of the Pure Theory of Corporate Finance: Bankruptcies and Take-Overs’, 3 Bell Journal of Economics, 458-482. Sullivan, A. Charlene and Worden, Debra Drecnik (1990), ‘Rehabilitation or Liquidation: Consumers’ Choices in Bankruptcy’, 24 Journal of Consumer Affairs, 69-88. Sullivan, Teresa A., Warren, Elizabeth and Westbrook, Jay Lawrence (1987), ‘The Use of Empirical Data in Formulating Bankruptcy Policy’, 50(2) Law and Contemporary Problems, 195-235. Sundgren, Stefan (1995), Bankruptcy Costs and Bankruptcy Code, Helsinki, Swedish School of Economics and Business Administration. Sward, Ellen E. (1987), ‘Resolving Conflicts between Bankruptcy Law and the State Police Power’, 63 Wisconsin Law Review, 403-453. Symposium (1977), ‘The Economics of Bankruptcy Reform’, 41(4) Law and Contemporary Problems, Duke University, School of Law. Tarzia, Giuseppe (1983), ‘Credito Bancario e Risanamento dell’Impresa nella Procedura di Amministrazione Straordinaria’ (Credit and the Reorganization of the Firm)’, Giurisprudenza Commerciale, 340-352. Triantis, George G. (1992), ‘Secured Debt Under Conditions of Imperfect Information’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 234-55. Triantis, George G. (1993), ‘A Theory of the Regulation of Debtor-in-Possession Financing’, 46 Vanderbilt Law Review, 901-935. Triantis, George G. (1993), ‘A Theory of the Regulation of Debtor-in-Possession Financing’, 46 Vanderbilt Law Review, 901-935. Triantis, George G. (1994), ‘A Free-Cash-Flow Theory of Secured Debt and Creditor Priorities’, 80 Virginia Law Review, 2155-2168. Triantis, George G. (1996), ‘The Interplay between Liquidation and Reorganization in Bankruptcy: The Role of Screens, Gatekeepers and Guillotines’, 16 International Review of Law and Economics, 101-119. Triantis, George G. and Ronald J. Daniels (1995), ‘The Role of Debt in Interactive Corporate Governance’, 83 California Law Review, 1073-1113.
288
Bankruptcy Proceedings
7800
Trost, J. Ronald (1973), ‘Corporate Bankruptcy Reorganization for the Benefit of Creditors or Stockholders?’, 21 UCLA Law Review, 540-552. Trost, J. Ronald (1979), ‘Business Reorganizations under Chapter 11 of the New Bankruptcy Code’, 34 Business Lawyer, 1309-1346. Tussing, Dale A. (1967), ‘The Case for Bank Failure’, 10 Journal of Law and Economics, 129-147. Warner, Jerold B. (1977a), ‘Bankruptcy Absolute Priority Rule and Pricing of Risky Debt Claims’, 4 Journal of Financial Economics, 239-276. Warner, Jerold B. (1977b), ‘Bankruptcy Costs: Some Evidence’, 32 Journal of Finance, 337 ff. Warren, Elizabeth (1984), ‘Reducing Bankruptcy Protection for Consumers: A Response’, 72 Georgetown Law Journal, 1333-1357. Warren, Elizabeth (1987), ‘Bankruptcy Policy’, 54 University of Chicago Law Review, 775-814. Reprinted in Bankruptcy: Legal and Financial Papers, Bhandari (ed) Cambridge University Press, 1994 and Reprinted in Company Law, Wheeler, S. (ed) Dartmouth Publishing United Kingdom. Warren, Elizabeth (1991), ‘A Theory of Absolute Priority’, New York University Annual Survey of American Law, 9 ff. Warren, Elizabeth (1992), ‘The Untenable Case for Repeal of Chapter 11', 102 Yale Law Journal, 437-479. Warren, Elizabeth (1992), ‘Why Have a Federal Bankruptcy System?’, 77 Cornell Law Review, 1093 ff. Warren, Elizabeth (1993), ‘Bankruptcy Policymaking in an Imperfect World’, 92 Michigan Law Review, 336 ff. Warren, Elizabeth, Sullivan, Teresa and Westbrook, Jay (1983), ‘Limiting Access to Bankruptcy Discharge: An Analysis of the Creditors’ Data’, 59 Wisconsin Law Review, 1091 ff. Warren, Elizabeth, Sullivan, Teresa and Westbrook, Jay (1986), ‘Folklore and Facts: A Preliminary Report from The Consumer Bankruptcy Project’, 60 American Bankruptcy Law Journal, 293 ff. Warren, Elizabeth, Sullivan, Teresa and Westbrook, Jay (1987), ‘The Role of Empirical Data in Formulating a National Bankruptcy Policy’, 50 Law and Contemporary Problems, 195 ff. Warren, Elizabeth, Sullivan, Teresa and Westbrook, Jay (1988), ‘Laws, Models, and Real People’, 13 Law and Social Inquiry, 661 ff. Warren, Elizabeth, Sullivan, Teresa and Westbrook, Jay (1989), As We Forgive Our Debtors: Consumer Credit and Bankruptcy in America, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Warren, Elizabeth, Sullivan, Teresa and Westbrook, Jay (1994a), ‘Consumer Debtors Ten Years Later: A Financial Comparison of Consumer Bankrupts 1981-91', 68 American Bankruptcy Law Journal, 121 ff. Warren, Elizabeth, Sullivan, Teresa and Westbrook, Jay (1994b), ‘The Persistence of Local Legal Culture: Twenty Years of Evidence from the Bankruptcy Courts’, 17 Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy, 801 ff. Warren, Elizabeth and Westbrook, Jay (1994c), ‘Searching for Reorganization Realities’, 72 Washington University Law Quarterly, 3001 ff.
7800
Bankruptcy Proceedings
289
Webb, David C. (1987), ‘The Importance of Incomplete Information in Explaining the Existence of Costly Bankruptcy’, 54 Economica, 137-151. Webb, David C. (1991), ‘An Economic Evaluation of Insolvency Procedures in the United Kingdom: Does the 1986 Insolvency Act Satisfy the Creditor’s Bargain?’, 43 Oxford Economic Papers, 139-157. Weiss, L.A. (1990), ‘Bankruptcy Resolution: Direct Costs and Violation of Priority of Claims’, 27 Journal of Financial Economics, 285-314. Weistart, John C. (1977), ‘The Costs of Bankruptcy’, 41(4) Law and Contemporary Problems, 107-122. Weston, Fred J. (1977), ‘Some Economic Fundamentals for an Analysis of Bankruptcy’, 41(4) Law and Contemporary Problems, 47-65. White, Michelle J. (1980), ‘Public Policy toward Bankruptcy: Me-First and Other Priority Rules’, 11 Bell Journal of Economics, 550-564. White, Michelle J. (1983), ‘Bankruptcy Costs and the New Bankruptcy Code’, 38 Journal of Finance, 477-504. White, Michelle J. (1984), ‘Bankruptcy Liquidation and Reorganization’, in Logue, D.E. (1984) (ed.), Handbook of Modern Finance, Boston, Warren, Gorham and Lamont. White, Michelle J. (1987), ‘Personal Bankruptcy Under the 1978 Bankruptcy Code: An Economic Analysis’, 63 Indiana Law Journal, 1-53. White, Michelle J. (1989), ‘The Corporate Bankruptcy Decision’, 3 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 129-151. White, Michelle J. (1984), ‘Corporate Bankruptcy as a Filtering Device: Chapter 11 Reorganizations and Out-of-Court Debt Restructerings’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 268-295. White, Michelle J. (1995), ‘The Costs of Corporate Bankruptcy: A U.S.-European Comparison’, in Bhandari, Jagdeep S. (ed.), Bankruptcy: Economic and Legal Perspectives. X (1987), ‘Note: “Adequate Protection” and the Availability of Postpetition Interest to Undersecured Creditors in Bankruptcy’, 100 Harvard Law Review, 1106-1124.
Other References Becker, Gary S. (1968), ‘Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach’, 76 Journal of Political Economy,169-217. Buchanan, James M., Tollison, Robert D. and Tullock, G. (1980), Towards a Theory of the Rentseeking Society, College Station, Texas A&M, University Press. Hoppit, Julian (1987), Risk and Failure in English Business, 1700-1800, Cambridge; New York, Cambridge University Press. Stiglitz, Joseph, E. and Weiss, Andrew (1981), ‘Credit Rationing in Markets with Imperfect Information’, 71 American Economic Review, 393-410.
7900 EVIDENCE Jeffrey S. Parker Professor of Law George Mason University School of Law
Bruce H. Kobayashi Associate Professor of Law George Mason University School of Law © Copyright 1999 Bruce H. Kobayashi and Jeffrey S. Parker
Abstract The economic analysis of evidence law is relatively less developed than other areas of the law and economics literature, notwithstanding this subject’s close relationship to other well-developed areas, most notably the economic analysis of procedural rules. This chapter first will develop some of the general issues raised by the economic analysis of evidence within the Anglo-American tradition of adversarial presentation. We will then proceed to consider the existing literature on specific topics in the law of evidence and related problems of pre-trial discovery and trial error. JEL classification: K41, K42 Keywords: Pre-Trial Discovery, Burden of Proof, Accuracy, Hearsay
1. Introduction The economic analysis of evidence law is relatively less developed than other areas of the law and economics literature, notwithstanding this subject’s close relationship to other well-developed areas, most notably the economic analysis of procedural rules (see Friedman, 1998). This state of affairs may be due to the inherent complexity of the subject, as combining the economics of procedural rules with the economics of information, as well as to the diversity of legal approaches to the problems of evidence across different legal traditions and across different jurisdictions within the same legal tradition. Accordingly, this chapter first will develop some of the general issues raised by the economic analysis of evidence within the Anglo-American tradition of adversarial presentation (Section 2), starting from the analysis of our companion chapter on Civil Procedure: General (Chapter 7000). We will then proceed to consider the existing literature on specific topics in the law 290
7900
Evidence
291
of evidence (Section 3) and related problems of pre-trial discovery and trial error (Section 4). Related topics are treated elsewhere in this volume by the companion chapter on civil procedure: general (7000), and by the chapters on fee shifting (7300), the litigation/settlement decision (7400), and class actions (7600); the organization of the courts, including jurisdictional issues (7100-7200); criminal procedure (7700); the economics of crime and punishment (8000-8600); arbitration and the private enforcement of law (7500); bankruptcy proceedings (7800); legal error, rules versus standards, and accuracy in adjudication (7900), punitive damages (Volume III, 3700), the computing of damages, including the allocations of damages via contribution and indemnity rules (Volume III, 3500); and the production of legal rules and precedent (9000-9900).
A. General Considerations In this part, we first survey evidence law doctrine as evolved within the Anglo-American tradition of adversarial presentation, and then develop the basic economic analysis of evidence law within such a tradition, as an outgrowth of the general concern of procedural rules with minimizing the sum of direct costs and error costs, as supplemented by a more extensive consideration of the effects of evidence rules on the production, supply and use of information both within the litigation process and externally.
2. Anglo-American Evidence Law Doctrine Within the Anglo-American legal tradition, evidence law doctrine evolved initially through common-law development. However, in the United States at the present time, evidence law largely has been codified through the vehicle of the Federal Rules of Evidence (FRE), which were adopted in 1975 for use in the US federal courts and, through their adoption in the Uniform Rules of Evidence, now also are substantially in force in the court systems of some 35 of the 50 States, with some variations. (See Uniform Laws Annotated for a list of adopting jurisdictions and treatment of variations.) This provides a degree of uniformity within US evidence law, though some important state court systems continue to follow the common-law approach (as in New York) or have their own distinctive evidence codes (as in California). In this chapter, we will relate evidence law doctrine primarily to the provisions of the FRE. Anglo-American evidence law doctrine concerns itself primarily with questions of admissibility (that is, whether a given item of evidence will be
292
Evidence
7900
admitted to or excluded from consideration by the trier of facts, be it judge or jury), and secondarily with questions of proof and presumptions (determining which litigant will bear the burdens of producing evidence and persuading the finder of fact on a particular issue). Admissibility rules comprise three categories: (1) rules of relevancy, which measure the relationship between offered evidence and the legal issues involved in the litigation (FRE art. 4); (2) rules of ‘reliability’, which regulate the mechanisms and forms by which evidence may be presented, both through witnesses (FRE arts. 6 and 7) and documents (FRE arts. 9 and 10), and include the general rule against hearsay evidence and the exceptions to that rule (FRE art. 8). This usage of the term ‘reliability’ in reference to this family of rules is not uniform in legal sources, but follows the US Supreme Court’s usage in Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals. Other authorities may refer to these rules simply as ‘admissibility’ rules, or in some cases as ‘competency’ or ‘foundational’ rules; (3) so-called ‘extrinsic’ policies of exclusion, most notably the evidentiary privileges for confidential or proprietary information (left by FRE art. 5 to common-law development but codified in most state counterparts). The basic rule of relevancy is a minimal requirement satisfied by a logical argument that a given item of evidence has non-zero probative value, in the Bayesian sense that its admission will affect the probability of a fact of consequence to the litigation (FRE 401). Relevant evidence is presumptively admissible, unless excluded by another rule (FRE 402). Within the doctrine of relevance, minimally relevant evidence may be excluded if its probative value is outweighed by one or more costs, including delay or waste of time, confusion of jurors, or unfairly prejudicial effect. In addition to a general power in the court to exclude relevant evidence on such grounds (FRE 403), the law gives specific treatment to several categories of evidence ordinarily so excluded, including evidence of ‘character’, meaning an individual’s propensity to act in certain ways (FRE 404-406, 412; but see FRE 413-15 (reversing the traditional rule for allegations of sexual assault or child molestation in both civil and criminal cases), evidence of subsequent changes to an injury-causing condition (FRE 407), and evidence of settlement or plea negotiations, liability insurance coverage, and the like (FRE 408-411). Reliability rules also can exclude minimally relevant evidence that fails to conform to requirements of admissible form or source. This category includes two basic types of rules, the first being ‘threshold’ showings sometimes referred to as ‘competency’ or ‘foundational’ requirements - that the evidence stems from a ‘reliable’ source, which in the case of witnesses
7900
Evidence
293
requires that testimony be limited to personal sense impressions (‘first-hand’ or ‘personal’ knowledge) and generally excludes non-expert opinion (FRE 602, 701), and in the case of documents requires ‘authentication’ of the document (FRE art. 9) and prefers original documents to secondary evidence of their contents (FRE art. 10, the ‘Best Evidence’ rule). The second type of rule in this category is the general rule against hearsay, defined as an out-of-court statement offered to prove the truth of the matter asserted by the statement (FRE 801-802) and its many exceptions (see FRE 803-807) that admit statements made under conditions thought to provide ‘circumstantial guarantees of trustworthiness’ (FRE 807, stating the open-ended ‘residual’ exception to the hearsay rule). Both types of reliability rules, and especially the hearsay rule, are rationalized and developed in legal authority by reference to the value of in-court (or some instances, pre-trial) adversarial testing of the credibility of evidentiary sources. Extrinsic policies of exclusion - paradigmatically, the evidentiary privileges - may exclude otherwise relevant and reliable evidence in order to encourage or protect some relationship or activity ‘extrinsic’ to the issues in litigation, such as certain governmental functions, the provision of confidential legal, medical, or personal advice, or the productive use of private or commercial information. In this instance, the rule of exclusion explicitly recognizes a tradeoff between the accuracy of litigation fact-finding and a perceived external benefit, or in some instances an offsetting internal benefit, such as improving the quality of legal representation. In addition to the evidentiary privileges, some of the special rules of relevancy excluding evidence of subsequent remedial measures, insurance, compromise negotiations, or the like, are sometimes rationalized by reference to an extrinsic policy of encouraging safety, insurance against risk, settlement, and so on. Proof and presumption rules (see FRE art. 3) are concerned with the allocation and procedural effect of burdens and standards of proof. Generally speaking, the substantive law casts the burden of proof for every element of a claim upon the complaining party (the plaintiff in civil cases and the government in criminal cases) in both of two senses: (1) the burden of production or ‘going forward’, which allocates the burden of adducing some evidence on the point in question (though this burden can be shifted by operation of a ‘presumption’); and (2) the burden of persuasion, or ‘risk of non-persuasion’, which specifies the party who will lose in the event that the quality of evidence falls beneath the pertinent standard of proof. Aside from specifying the verbal formulae to be used in instructing the trier of fact, and the procedural effects of legally deficient failures of proof, the Anglo-American law of evidence (and procedure) has virtually nothing to say on the subject of proof as distinguished from admissibility. Unless the issue is resolved as a matter of law, determinations of fact by juries are
294
Evidence
7900
formally unreviewable by either trial or appellate judges in the United States, and determinations of fact by trial court judges are reviewed under a highly deferential standard on appeal. The concept of the rules is sharply to distinguish determinations of fact from determinations of law.
3. General Economic Analysis of Evidence Law As a species of procedural rule, evidence rules can be approached initially through the economic framework postulated by Posner (1973) of minimizing the sum of error costs and direct costs, both public and private. As with procedural rules in general, the coercive and sequential aspects of the litigation process present potential strategic use of evidence rules by litigants to influence opposing litigants’ costs or to degrade the accuracy of judicial determinations (see Friedman, 1992), perhaps resulting in excessive expenditures by both the litigants and the court (see Posner, 1992, p. 586), as well as inaccurate decisions (see Tullock, 1980). However, evidence rules are distinguished from other procedural rules by being focused solely upon the fact-finding aspect of the litigation process. This characteristic has two major implications for the economic analysis of evidence rules that have been identified in the literature: (1) the internalization of most factual error costs; and (2) the effect of evidence rules on information supply, both within litigation and externally. 3.1 Internalization of Error Costs Aside from the precedential effect of evidentiary rulings themselves, error costs associated with inaccurate fact-finding in litigation tend to be internalized to the immediate parties, thus diminishing the social interest in the accuracy of any particular litigated outcome, unless such errors are systematically biased (see Kaplow, 1994; Kaplow and Shavell, 1994, 1996; Parker, 1995; Rasmusen, 1995). Furthermore, in the absence of external effects, and with the competitive provision of evidence to the court by adversarial parties motivated by symmetrical stakes, there is reason to doubt whether relying on information provided by interested parties systematically degrades the accuracy of factual determinations, even assuming strategic behaviors. Milgrom and Roberts (1986) demonstrate this result under the assumption of symmetrical and costless access to information by the parties. The same theoretical result is extended to symmetrical but costly access by Froeb and Kobayashi (1993, 1996) (see also McAfee and Reny, 1992; Shin, 1998; and Lewis and Poitevin, 1997), and is consistent with recent experimental findings comparing adversarial with non-adversarial presentation in terms of both revelation of hidden information and accuracy
7900
Evidence
295
of litigated outcomes (Block et al., 1998; Parker and Lewisch, 1998). However, these results are qualified by reference to the assumption of symmetrical access and verification of parties’ reports, which highlights the potential importance of the pretrial discovery process as eliminating or diminishing the case of private asymmetrical information in one party (see, for example, Cooter and Rubinfeld, 1994; Hay, 1994; Jost, 1995; Sobel, 1989; and the discussion in the companion Chapter 7000 of this work). Subject to those qualifications, the economic analysis of evidence law has tended to focus on the functions of evidence rules in regulating either direct costs to the parties and the court, or a different class of error costs occasioned by systematic bias or other agency costs on the part of the public decision-maker. From this perspective, many aspects of both proof and the admissibility rules of relevancy and reliability have been explained (or criticized) in terms of their operation on the marginal product of parties’ and courts’ expenditures (see Posner, 1973, 1992, § 21.8; Gibbons and Hutchinson, 1982; Rubinfeld and Sappington, 1987; Miceli, 1990; Friedman, 1992; Davis, 1994; Hay and Spier, 1997), as reinforcing the institutional specialization implied by the division of decision-making authority within tribunals, including the internalization of fact-finding error by design (Parker, 1995), or as controlling bias on the part of decision makers (Posner, 1992, p. 521; Shrag and Scotchmer, 1994). 3.2 Effects on Information Supply The second major distinguishing feature of the economic analysis of evidence law concerns the effects of evidence rules (and related rules of pre-trial discovery) on the supply of information both within litigation and externally. This is most transparent in the case of evidentiary privileges, which are based explicitly upon considerations of encouraging the generation of certain types of information by protecting against compelled disclosure, and as such define a class of intellectual property (Easterbrook, 1981; see also Gould, 1980; Kitch, 1980; and Stigler, 1980). While some evidentiary privilege rules may have entirely external effects on information production (as balanced against direct and error costs internally), both the attorney-client privilege and the related ‘work product’ doctrine (which protects against compelled disclosure of the fruits of litigation inputs by litigants and lawyers) appear to be endogenous to the litigation fact-finding process, and therefore may contribute either positively or negatively to direct costs and error costs. Existing literature expresses differing points of view on the social consequences of these effects (see Allen et al., 1994; Bundy and Elhauge, 1991; Kaplow and Shavell, 1989, 1990, 1992; Shavell, 1988). However, the effect of evidence and discovery rules on information supply is more general than the rules of privilege. First, compelled disclosure of information in litigation can affect the incentives of both
296
Evidence
7900
parties and non-parties to produce information ex ante. Thus, rules compelling an interested party to disclose harmful information to the court or adversary (either by formal order or by default on a burden of proof) may reduce incentives to produce any information, or bias the production function (see Kobayashi, Parker and Ribstein, 1996; Shavell, 1989), and, by extension, one or both incentives may also affect even disinterested non-parties, essentially by imposing a ‘tax’ on information through its expropriation in the litigation process (see Parker, 1995). Second, even in the absence of compulsion, as in the case of compensated expert testimony, the rules of admissibility can affect the external supply of information available for use in litigation, by influencing the marginal incentives of prospective expert witnesses to produce certain forms of expert opinion (Parker, 1995; see also Elliott, 1989).
B. Specific Topics in the Economic Analysis of Evidence Law In this section, we will survey the existing law and economics literature by reference to the main problems addressed in Anglo-American evidence law doctrine, under the following divisions: (a) relevance and prejudice; (b) statistical evidence; (c) burdens of proof, presumptions, and accuracy; (d) knowledge, opinion, and expert testimony; (e) the hearsay rule; and (f) evidentiary privilege. As will be demonstrated by this survey, relatively few of the institutional details of the law of evidence have been analyzed by the law and economics literature to date.
4. Relevance and Prejudice The doctrine of relevancy and its counterweights (discussed in section II.A above) appears designed to operate upon both error costs and direct costs to the parties and the court, by focusing all evidence on the matters of fact identified as decisive by the substantive law (FRE 401). Presumably, this improves the efficiency of law enforcement and contributes positively to the accuracy of adjudication (see generally Kaplow, 1994). In addition, relevancy standards may operate to reduce agency costs in the form of fact-finder bias, by depriving the fact-finder of access to information on non-relevant grounds of decision (see Posner, 1992, p. 521). This same concept of controlling agency cost in the form of bias is carried over into the joint case of evidence that has both probative value and ‘prejudicial’ effect (conceived for this analysis as extrinsic grounds of decision), for which the law (FRE 403) requires the judge to make an explicit cost-benefit analysis (see Gibbons and Hutchinson, 1982, discussing
7900
Evidence
297
the British counterpart to FRE 403). In addition, more specific rules carry the same concept into identified types of evidence, most notably the general rule against ‘character’ (propensity) evidence (FRE 404) and the recent exception for sex crimes (FRE 412-415), which is analyzed within this framework by Schrag and Scotchmer (1994). Similar considerations may underlay the additional rules disfavoring the admission of evidence of remedial measures taken after an injury-producing event, settlement negotiations, and the like (FRE 407-411) (see Daughety and Reinganum, 1995; Rasmusen, 1998). Alternatively, those rules could be analyzed in whole or in part by analogy to rules of evidentiary privilege, as seeking to reduce the ‘taxation’ effect of admissibility on the conduct in question, which produces both information and other goods that may have external benefits, as in the case of remedial measures improving safety (FRE 407), or endogenous benefits to the litigation process, as in the case of settlement negotiations (FRE 408), for which both non-disclosure and inadmissibility may contribute positively to the quality of legal representation (see generally Allen et al., 1990). Relevancy rules may also operate on direct costs as constraining strategic behaviors by litigants that could result in excessive trial expenditures (see Posner, 1992, pp. 564-566; Tullock, 1980), or as one of several mechanisms for rationing access to trial time. Under the traditional Anglo-American system, parties can present evidence at trial without general limit, except through the rules of relevance, under which the judge may exclude even relevant evidence as cumulative or a ‘waste of time’ (FRE 403). In more recent years, this function has been supplemented by more extensive case ‘management’ by American trial judges, both before and at trial (see the companion Chapter 7000 of this work).
5. Statistical Evidence There is a large body of interdisciplinary literature, mostly outside the law and economics field, discussing the use of probabilistic reasoning and statistical methods in assessing both admissibility and proof (for example, Cohen, 1981; Fairley, 1973; Fienberg, 1989; Finkelstein and Fairley, 1970; Kaye, 1979, 1981; Kornstein, 1975; Lempert, 1977; Nesson, 1985; Schum, 1986; Shaviro, 1989; Tillers and Schum, 1988; Tribe, 1971; see generally Anderson and Twining, 1991; Schum, 1994). As part of this literature, there is debate concerning whether and to what extent statistical findings should be admitted into evidence, especially in criminal cases of disputed identification. In American law, this problem has been addressed through the standards applicable to expert testimony (see Part D, below) and as an application of the relevancy-prejudice balancing analysis of FRE 403. The relatively hostile
298
Evidence
7900
attitude of American courts toward admissibility may reflect the bias inherent in the selection of disputes for litigation, and for trial versus settlement (see generally Gould, 1973; Priest and Klein, 1984). Statistical methods generally assume random events, while litigation selects unique events non-randomly, and substantive law generally attaches significance to unique events rather than mean outcomes, though it has been argued that this may be inefficient in some settings (see Kaplow and Shavell, 1996). However, where the substantive law effectively requires all events to be random as to some variable (as perhaps in alleged discrimination in jury selection, employment, or the like), or states a standard related to mean outcomes rather than unique non-random events, then the case for admission of statistical findings is stronger.
6. Burdens of Proof, Presumptions, and Accuracy The debate noted in the previous subsection also embraces questions concerning the evaluation whether a body of evidence meets specified standards of proof, which tend to be stated in terms suggesting probabilistic analysis, as in ‘more probable than not’ (the ‘preponderance’ standard applicable in most civil cases), ‘clear and convincing evidence’ (a higher standard for certain civil cases such as fraud that may have external effects on reputation), and ‘beyond a reasonable doubt’ (the highest standard, applied in criminal cases). (See the sources cited above and Lombardero (1996), which considers joint probability determinations.) Strictly speaking, this debate has limited significance to the law of evidence or the law of procedure, especially in jury cases, because the sufficiency of evidence to meet a particular standard is evaluated legally through the rule of ‘substantial evidence’, which essentially asks whether a jury rationally could accept the evidence as sufficient - a highly deferential rule that insulates all but the most egregious factual errors from review by trial or appellate judges, thus minimizing the law’s concern with factual accuracy in particular cases. In contrast, the selection of standards of proof is considered a legal question, which from the economic perspective appears to rest upon whether error costs are symmetrical, with the higher standards predicated on the assumption that false positive errors are more costly than false negative errors in certain settings (see Kaplow, 1994; Kaplow and Shavell, 1994; Posner, 1992, p. 553). However, error costs may also depend upon factors other than the standard of proof (see Davis, 1994, arguing that both the parameters of the underlying population and characteristics of fact-finding technology may affect the optimal standard of proof).
7900
Evidence
299
Distinguishable from the standard or quality of proof is the selection of which party bears the burden of proof in terms of both ultimate persuasion and initial production of evidence (see Rubinfeld and Sappington, 1987; Miceli, 1990; Hay and Spier, 1997; Sanchirico, 1997b). The casting of the burden of proof may affect both error costs and direct costs. The general rule of casting the burdens of both production and persuasion upon plaintiffs may operate to reduce direct costs by providing an incentive to avoid litigation in the first instance (see Posner, 1992), and may operate within the litigation to reduce incentives for strategic behavior by forcing plaintiffs to internalize more of the direct cost of obtaining the transfer payment they seek, though the advent of compelled pre-trial discovery from the adversary tends to re-introduce both strategic behavior and moral hazard problems (see, for example, Cooter and Rubinfeld, 1994; Easterbrook, 1989). Even aside from discovery procedures, casting the burden of production on the party bearing relatively higher costs of production may increase both direct and error costs. Presumptions, under the standard analysis (see FRE 301-302), operate to shift the burden of production rather than persuasion, usually by allowing the party bearing the burden to substitute proof of a different ‘basic fact’ for direct proof of the ‘presumed fact’ required by substantive law (see Epstein, 1973). From an economic perspective, presumptions would appear to be based upon both a high factual correlation between the basic and presumed facts, coupled with a disparity in the costs of producing evidence of the two facts, at least in some circumstances.
7. Knowledge, Opinion and Expert Testimony The ‘reliability’ rules of admissibility also can operate on both error costs and direct costs (see Gross, 1987), though they also may have effects on information supply and in some instances may be influenced by the interest in policing strategic behaviors by litigants. The basic reliability rules of ‘competency’ and ‘authentication’ require that witness testimony be confined to ‘facts’ based upon the witness’s first-hand ‘knowledge’ (personal sense impression) as distinguished from ‘opinion’, and that documents be shown to be authentic before their contents may be considered. In both instances, the evidence is required to meet a threshold ‘quality’ standard before it is admitted to consideration. Thus, these rules can operate both on error costs (assuming that the legal standard of quality is positively related to accuracy) and on direct costs, by channeling the litigants’ efforts away from lower quality evidence and toward higher quality evidence, thus increasing the productivity of the parties’ expenditures at trial and reducing
300
Evidence
7900
strategic behaviors consisting of introducing ‘low quality’ evidence that imposes rebuttal costs on the adverse litigant (see Posner, 1992, pp. 564-566). The most significant of these rules is the requirement that witness testimony be based upon first-hand knowledge (FRE 602) and its negative correlative in the rule generally excluding non-expert opinion (FRE 701). One economic explanation for these rules is that they embody the economic logic of specialization within the institutional setting of trial, by separating raw information inputs from the inferential function performed by the trier of fact (see Parker, 1995), thus arguably reducing both error costs (if juries and judges are more accurate in drawing conclusions than witnesses) and direct costs, to the extent that litigants are prevented from introducing the ‘lower quality’ second-hand information or witness conclusions. The rules permitting expert testimony (see FRE 702-705), generally cast in the form of opinion, may be based upon the similar logic that experts, within their fields of professional specialization, may possess a comparative advantage over juries and judges in drawing conclusions from the available data (see Parker, 1995). However, the standards defining the permitted scope of expert testimony have been controversial. By the logic of permitting expert testimony, neither judges not juries are well-equipped to evaluate when it actually provides a comparative advantage in fact-finding, and so there has been a tendency to look toward external standards of ‘general acceptance’ in the expert’s field. These rules in turn have been criticized as permitting strategic behavior by parties within the litigation (see Elliott, 1989) and as encouraging rent-seeking behaviors by both litigants and testifying experts (Parker, 1995), and recently have been modified by the US Supreme Court in Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals, to place more emphasis on internalized admissibility standards and adversarial testing of scientific expert testimony. An alternative to exclusive reliance upon adversarial presentation is provided by the court’s authority to appoint its own ‘neutral’ expert (FRE 706). However, Froeb and Kobayashi (1993, 1996) have shown theoretically that the court-appointed expert does not reduce either direct or error costs from the alternative of competitive and selective presentation by adverse parties, even if the fact-finder is both naive and biased. Furthermore, their analysis suppresses considerations of public-choice problems or agency costs in the judge or expert, which would tend to strengthen their results in the direction of favoring adversarial presentation. Their assumption of symmetrical access in the parties does not appear to be a severe limitation in the context of expert opinion testimony, which by definition does not rest upon private factual information and is supplied in an explicit competitive labor market.
7900
Evidence
301
8. The Hearsay Rule Like the other ‘reliability’ rules, the rule against hearsay evidence (an out-of-court statement offered to prove the truth of the matter asserted by the statement) (see FRE 801-802) appears designed to reduce by direct and error costs by preferring in-court testimony (presumably of higher quality, see Tribe, 1974, for a legal treatment of quality issues) to the secondary ‘hearsay’ evidence, and by requiring the proponent of the evidence to bear the higher cost of producing the higher quality of evidence. The status of the hearsay rule as a rule of preference rather than a rule of absolute exclusion is indicated by the many exceptions to the general rule (FRE 803-807) and important categories of defined non-hearsay statements (FRE 801(d)), notably including statements by adverse litigants, former testimony, business or governmental records, and spontaneous declarations, among others. However, the rationale of the basic rule has been criticized by Friedman (1992), who argues that the cost of producing the higher-quality non-hearsay evidence should be placed upon the opposing party, in order to reduce strategic uses of hearsay objections to exclude evidence having some net probative value (see also Kaplow, 1980). This analysis assumes that hearsay evidence passing the relevancy balancing test of FRE 403 will contribute positively to accuracy, and that the proponent is not uniquely advantaged over the opponent in the cost of producing the non-hearsay evidence, and does not address strategic behaviors by proponents under this alternative regime, or consider possible effects on external supply.
9. Evidentiary Privileges The law of evidentiary privileges explicitly incurs some measure of direct and error costs within litigation fact-finding in order to achieve the ‘extrinsic’ benefit of encouraging information production by securing property rights against compelled disclosure of information generated in the course of specified relationships or activities. The protected activities traditionally included confidential communications between attorney and client, physician or psychotherapist and patient, priest and penitent, law enforcement officers and informants, and between spouses, as well as trade secrets and government secrets. Recent legislation in some US jurisdictions has extended such protection to news reports and their sources and a wide of counseling relationships. More broadly conceived, this category of rules might be thought to include the constitutional privilege against self-incrimination and the exclusionary rule applied to evidence obtained
302
Evidence
7900
through illegal search and seizure by the government, though those topics conventionally are treated as part of the law of criminal procedure (see Chapter 7500 of this volume). Within the law and economics literature, only the attorney-client privilege and the related ‘work product’ doctrine (protecting against compelled disclosure of litigation inputs by lawyers and litigants) have received extensive consideration. These rules may have differing and more complex characteristics than the other types of privilege, which are most conceived as having only negative influences on the cost and accuracy of litigation fact-finding, to be balanced against positive external benefits widely diffused throughout the society. In contrast with that simpler analysis, both the attorney-client privilege and the work product doctrine may operate to improve the quality of legal representation, and in that way reduce both error costs and direct costs within litigation, in addition to whatever external benefits (or costs) ensue (see Allen et al., 1990; Bundy and Elhauge, 1991; Kobayashi, Parker and Ribstein, 1996). Suppressing these possible internal benefits to the litigation process itself, a series of papers by Shavell (1988) and Kaplow and Shavell (1989, 1990) questions the social desirability of protecting the confidentiality of legal advice in a variety of settings. The Kaplow-Shavell analysis is criticized by Allen et al. (1990), on the ground that it overlooks the constructive role of confidential client communications in assisting lawyers’ development of alternative legal grounds for the litigant’s case, which might not be discovered and developed in the absence of the privilege. They advance a similar analysis of the work product doctrine as enabling lawyers to overcome a ‘joint production’ problem (that is, that lawyers’ investment may produce both positive and negative information regarding the client), extending the previous work by Easterbrook (1981) treating the work product doctrine as a species of intellectual property protection.
Bibliography on Evidence (7900) Allen, Ronald J., Grady, Mark F., Polsby, Daniel and Yashko, Michael S. (1990), ‘A Positive Theory of the Attorney Client Privilege and the Work Product Doctrine’, 19(2) Journal of Legal Studies, 359-397. Anderson, Terence and Twining, William (1991), Analysis of Evidence, Boston, Little Brown. Block, Michael K., Parker, Jeffrey S., Vyborna, Olga and Dusek, Libor (1998), Fact-Finding Efficiency in Legal Procedure: An Experimental Comparison of Adversarial Versus Inquisitorial Regimes, George Mason University School of Law, Working Papers in Law and Economics, No. 98-3. Boari, Nicola (1997), ‘On the Efficiency of Penal Systems: Several Lessons from the Italian Experience’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 115-126.
7900
Evidence
303
Bundy, Stephen M. and Elhauge, Einer Richard (1991), ‘Do Lawyers Improve the Adversary System? A General Theory of Litigation Advice and Its Regulation’, 79 California Law Review, 313-420. Cohen, L. Jonathan (1981), ‘Subjective Probability and the Paradox of the Gatecrasher’, Arizona State Law Journal, 627 ff. Cooper, Edward H. (1994), ‘Discovery Cost Allocation: Comment’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 465-480. Cooter, Robert D. and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1994), ‘An Economic Model of Legal Discovery in the U.S.’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 435-463. Daughety, Andrew F. and Reinganum, Jennifer F. (1995), ‘Keeping Society in the Dark: On the Admissibility of Pretrial Negotiations as Evidence in Court’, 26 Rand Journal of Economics, 203-221. Davis, Michael L. (1994), ‘The Value of Truth and the Optimal Standard of Proof in Legal Disputes’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 343-359. Easterbrook, Frank H. (1981), ‘Insider Trading, Secret Agents, Evidentiary Privileges, and the Production of Information’, 1981 Supreme Court Review, 309-365. Easterbrook, Frank H. (1989), ‘Comment: Discovery as Abuse’, 69 Boston University Law Review, 635-648. Elliott, E. Donald (1989), ‘Toward Incentive-Based Procedure: Three Approaches for Regulating Scientific Evidence’, 69 Boston University Law Review, 487-511. Epstein, Richard A. (1973), ‘Pleadings and Presumptions’, 40 University of Chicago Law Review, 556 ff. Fairley, William B. (1973), ‘Probabilistic Analysis of Identification Evidence’, 2 Journal of Legal Studies, 493-513. Fienberg, Stephen E. (ed.) (1989), The Evolving Role of Statistical Assessments as Evidence in the Courts, New York, Springer, 357 p. Finkelstein, M.O. and Fairley, William B. (1970), ‘A Bayesian Approach to Identification Evidence’, 83 Harvard Law Review, 489 ff. Friedman, Richard D. (1992), ‘Toward a Partial Economic, Game Theoretic Analysis of Hearsay’, 76 Minnesota Law Review, 723-796. Friedman, Richard D. (1998), ‘Economic Analysis of Evidentiary Law: An Underused Tool, an Underplowed Field’, 19 Cardozo Law Review. Froeb, Luke M. and Kobayashi, Bruce H. (1993), Competition in the Production of Costly Information: An Economic Analysis of Adversarial versus Court-Appointed Presentation of Expert Testimony, George Mason University School of Law, Working Papers in Law and Economics, No.93-5. Froeb, Luke M. and Kobayashi, Bruce H. (1996), ‘Naive, Biased, Yet Bayesian: Can Juries Interpret Selectively Produced Evidence?’, 12 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 257-276. Gibbons, T. and Hutchinson, A.C. (1982), ‘The Practice and Theory of Evidence Law - A Note’, 2 International Review of Law and Economics, 119-126. Gould, John P. (1973), ‘The Economics of Legal Conflicts’, 2 Journal of Legal Studies, 279-300. Gould, John P. (1980), ‘Privacy and the Economics of Information’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 827 ff.
304
Evidence
7900
Grady, Mark F., Allen, Ronald J. and Polsby, Daniel (1990), ‘A Positive Theory of the Attorney-Client Privilege and the Work-Product Doctrine’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 359 ff. Gross, Samuel R. (1987), ‘Loss of Innocence: Eyewitness Identification and Proof of Guilt’, 16 Journal of Legal Studies, 395-453. Hay, Bruce L. (1994), ‘Civil Discovery: Its Effects and Optimal Scope’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 481-515. Hay, Bruce L. and Spier, Kathryn E. (1997), ‘Burdens of Production in Civil Litigation: An Economic Perspective’, 26 Journal of Legal Studies, 413-432. Holm, Hakan J. (1995), ‘Computational Cost of Verifying Enforceable Contracts’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 127-140. Huber, Peter W. (1989), ‘A Comment on “Toward Incentive-Based Procedure: Three Approaches for Regulating Scientific Evidence” by E. Donald Elliott’, 69 Boston University Law Review, 513-516. Jost, Peter J. (1995), ‘Disclosure of Information and Incentives for Care’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 65-85. Kaplow, Louis (1980), ‘Note, the Theoretical Foundation of the Hearsay Rules’, 93 Harvard Law Review, 1786-1815. Kaplow, Louis (1994), ‘The Value of Accuracy in Adjudication: An Economic Analysis’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 307-401. Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (1989), ‘Legal Advice about Information to Present in Litigation: Its Effects and Social Desirability’, 102 Harvard Law Review, 565-615. Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (1990), ‘Legal Advice about Acts Already Committed’, 10 International Review of Law and Economics, 149-159. Kaplow, Louis and Shavell Steven (1992), ‘Private versus Socially Optimal Provision of Ex-Ante Legal Advice’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 306-320. Kaplow, Louis and Shavell Steven (1994), ‘Accuracy in the Assessment of Liability’, 37(1) Journal of Law and Economics, 1-16. Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (1996), ‘Accuracy in the Assessment of Damages’, 39 Journal of Law and Economics, 191-209. Kaye, David (1979), ‘The Laws of Probability and the Law of the Land’, 47 University of Chicago Law Review, 34 ff. Kaye, David (1981), ‘Paradoxes, Gedanken Experiments and the Burden of Proof: A Response to Dr. Cohen’s Reply’, Arizona State Law Journal, 635 ff. Kitch, Edmund W. (1980), ‘The Law and Economics of Rights in Valuable Information’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 683 ff. Kobayashi, Bruce H., Parker, Jeffrey S. and Ribstein, Larry E. (1996), The Process of Procedural Reform: Centralized Uniformity versus Local Experimentation, George Mason University School of Law Working Papers in Law and Economics. Kornstein, Daniel J. (1975), ‘A Bayesian Model of Harmless Error’, 5(1) Journal of Legal Studies, 121-145. Lempert, Richard (1977), ‘Modeling Relevance’, 75 Michigan Law Review, 1021 ff. Levmore, Saul and Stuntz, William J. (1990), ‘Remedies and Incentives in Private and Public Law: A Comparative Essay’, 66 Wisconsin Law Review, 483-499. Lewis, Donald E. (1983), ‘Economic Aspects of the Parole Decision’, 22 Australian Economic Papers, 259-279.
7900
Evidence
305
Lewis, Tracy and Poitevin, Michel (1997), ‘Disclosure of Information in Regulatory Proceedings’, 13 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 50-74. Lombardero, David A. (1996), ‘Do Special Verdicts Improve the Structure of Jury Decision Making?’, 36 Jurimetrics Journal, 275-324. McAfee, R. Preston and Reny, Philip J. (1992), ‘Correlated Information and Mechanism Design’, 60 Econometrica, 395-421. Miceli, Thomas J. (1990), ‘Optimal Prosecution of Defendants Whose Guilt Is Uncertain’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 189-202. Milgrom, P. and Roberts, John (1986), ‘Relying on the Information of Interested Parties’, 17 Rand Journal of Economics, 18-32. Nesson, Charles R. (1985), ‘The Evidence or the Event? On Judicial Proof and the Acceptability of Verdicts’, 98 Harvard Law Review, 1357 ff. Parker, Jeffrey S. (1995), ‘Daubert’s Debut: The Supreme Court, the Economics of Scientific Evidence, and the Adversarial System’, 4 Supreme Court Economic Review, 1-56. Parker, Jeffrey S. and Lewisch, Peter (1998), ‘Materielle Wahrheitsfindung im Zivilprozess (The Revelation of Truth in Civil Procedure)’, in X (ed.), 100 Jahre ZPO: Okonomische Analyse des Zivilprozesses, Wien, Manz. Posner Richard A. (1973), ‘An Economic Approach to Legal Procedure and Judicial Administration’, 2 Journal of Legal Studies, 399-458. Posner Richard A. (1992), Economic Analysis of Law (4th edn), Boston, Little Brown. Priest, George W. and Klein, Benjamin (1984), ‘The Selection of Disputes for Litigation’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-55. Raeder, Myrna S. (1998), ‘Cost-Benefit Analysis, Unintended Consequences and Evidentiary Policy: A Critique and a Rethinking of the Application of a Single Set of Evidence Rules to Civil and Criminal Cases’, 19 Cardozo Law Review. Rasmusen, Eric (1995), ‘Predictable and Unpredictable Error in Tort Awards: The Effect of Plaintiff Self-Selection and Signaling’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 323-345. Rasmusen, Eric (1998), ‘Mezzanatto and the Economics of Self-Incrimination’, 19 Cardozo Law Review. Rubinfeld, Daniel L. and Sappington, David E.M. (1987), ‘Efficient Awards and Standards of Proof in Judicial Proceedings’, 18 Rand Journal of Economics, 308-315. Sanchirico, Chris William (1997a), ‘The Burden of Proof in Civil Litigation: A Simple Model of Mechanism Design’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 431-447. Sanchirico, Chris William (1997b), ‘Evidence Production, Adversarial Process and the Private Instigation of Suits’, mimeo, Columbia University Economics Department. Sanchirico, Chris William (1997c), Enforcement by Hearing: An Integrated Model of Evidence Production, mimeo, Columbia University Economics Department. Schrag, Joel and Scotchmer, Suzanne (1994), ‘Crime and Prejudice: The Use of Character Evidence in Criminal Trials’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 319-342. Schum, David A. (1986), ‘Probability and the Processes of Discovery, Proof, and Choice’, 66 Boston University Law Review, 825-876. Schum, David A. (1994), The Evidential Foundations of Probabilistic Reasoning, New York, John Wiley.
306
Evidence
7900
Schwartz, Robert L. (1989), ‘There is no Archbishop of Science - A Comment on Elliott’s Toward Incentive-Based Procedure: Three Approaches for Regulating Scientific Evidence’, 69 Boston University Law Review, 517-525. Setear, John K. (1989), ‘The Barrister and the Bomb: The Dynamics of Cooperation, Nuclear Deterrence, and Discovery Abuse’, 69 Boston University Law Review, 569-633. Shapira, Ron A. (1998), ‘Economic Analysis of the Law of Evidence: A Caveat’, 19 Cardozo Law Review. Shavell, Steven (1988), ‘Legal Advice About Contemplated Acts: The Decision to Obtain Advice, its Social Desirability, and the Protection of Confidentiality’, 17 Journal of Legal Studies, 123-150. Shavell, Steven (1989), ‘Optimal Sanctions and the Incentive to Provide Evidence to Legal Tribunals’, 9 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-11. Shaviro, Daniel N. (1989), ‘Statistical Probability Evidence and the Appearance of Justice’, 103 Harvard Law Review, 530-554. Shaviro, Daniel N. and Koehler, Jonathan J. (1990), ‘Veridical Verdicts: Increasing Verdict Accuracy Through the Use of Overtly Probabilistic Evidence and Methods’, 75 Cornell Law Review, 247-279. Shin, Hyun Song (1998), ‘Adversarial and Inquisitorial Procedures in Arbitration’, 29 Rand Journal of Economics, 378-405. Sobel, Joel (1989), ‘An Analysis of Discovery Rules’, 52(1) Law and Contemporary Problems, 133-160. Spier, Kathryn E. and Hay, Bruce L. (1996), ‘Burdens of Production in Civil Litigation: An Economic Perspective’, 26 Journal of Legal Studies. Spiotto, James E. (1973), ‘Search and Seizure: An Empirical Study of the Exclusionary Rule and its Alternatives’, 2 Journal of Legal Studies, 243-278. Stigler, George J. (1980), ‘An Introduction to Privacy in Economics and Politics’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 623 ff. Tillers, Peter and Schum, David A. (1988), ‘Charting New Territory in Judicial Proof: Beyond Wigmore’, 9(3) Cardozo Law Review, 907-966. Tribe, Laurence H. (1971), ‘Trial by Mathematics: Precision and Ritual in the Legal Process’, 84 Harvard Law Review, 1329-1393. Tribe, Laurence H. (1974), ‘Triangulating Hearsay’, 87 Harvard Law Review, 957 ff. Tullock, Gordon (1980), Trials on Trial, New York, Columbia University Press. Tullock, Gordon (1988), ‘Defending the Napoleontic Code over the Common Law’, 2 Research in Law and Policy Studies, 3-27. Weinstein, Jack B. (1989), ‘What Discovery Abuse? A Comment on John Setear’s the Barrister and the Bomb’, 69 Boston University Law Review, 649-657. X (1980), ‘Note: The Theoretical Foundation of the Hearsay Rules’, 93 Harvard Law Review, 1786-1815.
Cases Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals, Inc., 509 U.S. 579 (1993)
8000 PUBLIC ENFORCEMENT OF LAW A. Mitchell Polinsky Stanford University
Steven Shavell Harvard University © Copyright 1999 A. Mitchell Polinsky and Steven Shavell
Abstract This chapter discusses the theory of the public enforcement of law - the use of public agents (inspectors, tax auditors, police, prosecutors) to detect and to sanction violators of legal rules. We first present the basic elements of the theory, focusing on the probability of imposition of sanctions, the magnitude and form of sanctions, and the rule of liability. We then examine a variety of extensions of the central theory, including accidental harms, costs of imposing fines, mistake, marginal deterrence, settlement, self-reporting, repeat offenses and incapacitation. JEL classification: K14, K42 Keywords: Law Enforcement, Crime, Deterrence
1. Introduction In this chapter we consider the theory of the public enforcement of law - the use of public agents (inspectors, tax auditors, police, prosecutors) to detect and to sanction violators of legal rules. Of course, private parties also play an important role in law enforcement, by providing information to public authorities and also by initiating their own legal actions (notably, tort suits), but to maintain focus we restrict attention here to public enforcement activity. (On private enforcement, see generally Landes and Posner, 1987, and Shavell, 1987c; and on private versus public enforcement, see Becker and Stigler, 1974; Landes and Posner, 1975, and Polinsky, 1980a.) In Sections 2 through 4, we present the basic elements of the theory of public enforcement of law. Our concern is with the probability of imposition of sanctions, the magnitude and form of sanctions, and the rule of liability. In Sections 5 through 16 we then examine a variety of extensions of the central theory, including accidental harms, costs of imposing fines, mistake, marginal deterrence, settlement, self-reporting, repeat offenses and incapacitation.
307
308
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
Before proceeding, we note that economically-oriented analysis of public law enforcement dates from the eighteenth century contributions of Montesquieu (1748), Beccaria (1770), and, especially, Bentham (1789), whose analysis of deterrence was sophisticated and expansive. But, curiously, after Bentham (1789), the subject of enforcement lay essentially dormant in economic scholarship until the late 1960s, when Becker (1968) published a highly influential article, which has led to a voluminous literature.
2. The Basic Framework An individual (or a firm) chooses whether to commit an act that for simplicity is assumed to cause harm with certainty (see Section 5 on uncertain harm). If he commits the act, he obtains some gain, and also faces the risk of being caught, found liable and sanctioned. The rule of liability could be either strict under which the individual is definitely sanctioned - or fault-based - under which he is sanctioned only if his behavior fell below a fault standard. The sanction that he suffers could be a monetary fine, a prison term, or a combination of the two. Whether an individual commits a harmful act is determined by an expected utility calculation. He will commit the act if that would raise his expected utility, taking into account the gain he would derive and the probability, form, and level of sanction that he would then face. We will usually first examine the assumption that individuals are risk neutral with respect to sanctions, that is, that they treat an uncertain sanction as equivalent to its expected value; but we will also consider alternative assumptions. Social welfare generally is presumed to equal the sum of individuals’ expected utilities. An individual’s expected utility depends on whether he commits a harmful act, on whether he is a victim of someone else’s harmful act, and on his tax payment, which will reflect the costs of law enforcement, less any fine revenue collected. If individuals are risk neutral, social welfare can be expressed simply as the gains individuals obtain from committing their acts, less the harms caused, and less the costs of law enforcement. (The assumption that individuals’ gains always are credited in social welfare could be relaxed without affecting most of our conclusions. The principal difference that altering the assumption would make is that more acts would be treated as socially undesirable and that optimal sanctions and enforcement effort would increase.) We assume, as is conventional, that fines are socially costless to employ because they are mere transfers of money (but in Section 6 we consider fines that are costly to impose), whereas imprisonment involves positive social costs because of the expense associated with the operation of prisons and the disutility due to imprisonment (which is not naturally balanced by gains to others).
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
309
The enforcement authority’s problem is to maximize social welfare by choosing enforcement expenditures or, equivalently, a probability of detection, the level of sanctions and their form (a fine, prison term, or combination), and the rule of liability (strict or fault-based).
3. Optimal Enforcement Given the Probability of Detection We consider here optimal enforcement given the assumption that the probability of detection is fixed (the probability will be treated as a policy instrument in the next section). Thus, we ask about the optimal form and level of sanctions under strict and fault-based liability, and about how the two liability rules compare. Strict Liability Assume initially that fines are the form of sanction and that individuals are risk neutral. Then the optimal fine is the harm h divided by the probability of detection p, that is, h/p; for then the expected fine equals the harm (observe that p(h/p) = h). If, for example, the harm is $1,000 and the probability of detection is 25 percent, the optimal fine is $4,000, and the expected fine is $1,000. This fine is optimal because, when the expected fine equals the harm, an individual will commit a harmful act if, but only if, the gain he would derive from it exceeds the harm he would cause. Essentially this basic and fundamental formula was noted by Bentham (1789, p. 173) and it has been observed by many others since. If individuals are risk averse with regard to fines, one would expect the optimal fine to be lower than in the risk-neutral case for two reasons. First, this reduces the bearing of risk by individuals who commit the harmful act. Second, because risk-averse individuals are more easily deterred than risk-neutral individuals, the fine does not need to be as high as before to achieve any desired degree of deterrence. (However, for subtle reasons that we will not address here, the optimal fine could, in principle, be higher when individuals are risk averse.) Next assume that imprisonment is the form of sanction, with social costs incurred in imposing sanctions. In this case, there is not a simple formula for the optimal imprisonment term (see Polinsky and Shavell, 1984). The optimal term could be such that there is either underdeterrence or overdeterrence, compared to socially ideal behavior. On one hand, a relatively low imprisonment term, implying underdeterrence, might be socially desirable because it means that imprisonment costs are reduced for those individuals who commit harmful acts. On the other hand, a relatively high term, implying overdeterrence, might be socially desirable because it means that imprisonment costs are reduced due to fewer individuals committing harmful acts, even if
310
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
some of these deterred individuals would have obtained gains exceeding the harm. (The possible optimality of overdeterrence strikes us as more theoretical than real, however.) Now consider the combined use of fines and imprisonment. Here, the main point is that fines should be employed to the maximum extent feasible before resort is made to imprisonment. In other words, it is not optimal to impose a positive imprisonment term unless the fine is maximal. (The maximal fine might be interpreted as the wealth of an individual.) The rationale for this conclusion is that fines are socially costless to impose, whereas imprisonment is socially costly, so deterrence should be achieved through the cheaper form of sanction first. This point is noted by Bentham (1789, p. 183) and Becker (1968, p. 193); see also Polinsky and Shavell (1984). To amplify, suppose that the fine f is less than the maximal fine fm and that a positive prison term t is employed. Raise f toward fm and lower t so as to keep the disutility of the combined sanctions constant. Then deterrence and the amount of harm will not change, but the cost of imposing the imprisonment sanction will fall, raising social welfare. Hence, it must be optimal for the fine to be maximal before imprisonment is used. (Observe that this argument holds regardless of individuals’ attitudes toward risk of either fines or imprisonment.) Fault-Based Liability Assume again that fines are the form of liability. Then the same formula for the fine that we said was optimal under strict liability - namely, h/p, the harm divided by the probability of detection - will lead to compliance with the fault standard (assuming that the fault standard is optimally selected). For example, suppose that the harm is $1,000, and that an individual would be found at fault if he failed to take a precaution costing less than $1,000 that could have prevented the harm. Furthermore, suppose such a precaution exists that costs $700. If the probability of detection is 25 percent, then a fine of $4,000 for being at fault would induce the individual to take a precaution costing less than $1,000; in particular, he would prefer to spend $700 on the precaution and escape liability than not to take the precaution and bear an expected fine of $1,000. Observe that the optimal fine of $4,000 in the preceding example is not unique. Any higher fine also would induce compliance with the fault standard, as would some lower fines (as long as the expected value of the fine exceeds $700, or whatever is the expense of the precaution that costs less than $1,000). Note that higher fines do not lead to a problem of overdeterrence because parties can escape fines by complying with the fault standard. (However, if mistakes occur in the legal process, they might be induced to spend excessively on precautions; see Section 8 below). If individuals are risk averse, they are more easily deterred than if they are risk neutral, so the fine does not need to be as high to induce compliance with the fault standard. Moreover, assuming that compliance occurs, no one actually
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
311
is sanctioned because no one is found at fault (assuming, as we do here, that there are no mistakes). Thus, fault-based liability has the attractive feature that it can accomplish desired deterrence of harm-creating conduct without imposing risk on risk-averse individuals (Shavell, 1982). Next, consider imprisonment as the sanction; see Shavell (1987a). Here, for essentially the reasons given in the case of fines, any sanction above a threshold level will ensure compliance with the fault standard, and the minimum sanction necessary to induce compliance is higher the lower is the probability of detection. Also (Shavell, 1985), fault-based liability again can accomplish deterrence without the actual imposition of sanctions, which would be socially costly. Finally, consider the joint use of fines and imprisonment. In this case, it does not matter what the combination of sanctions is, provided that the sanctions achieve compliance with the fault standard. In particular, it is not advantageous for society to employ maximal fines before resorting to imprisonment because compliance means that sanctions are never imposed. Comparison of Liability Rules Because sanctions are not imposed under fault-based liability (in the absence of mistakes), this form of liability has an advantage over strict liability when the sanction is the fine and individuals are risk-averse, or when the sanction is imprisonment. However, fault-based liability is more difficult to administer. Namely, to apply fault-based liability, the enforcement authority must have more information than under strict liability: it must be able to calculate optimal behavior to determine the fault standard and it must ascertain whether the fault standard was met. Under strict liability, the authority need only ascertain harm. (Moreover, for reasons we discuss in Section 7 below, strict liability encourages better decisions by injurers regarding their level of participation in harm-creating activities.)
4. Optimal Enforcement Including the Probability of Detection We now consider the optimal system of enforcement when expenditures on enforcement, and hence the probability of detection, are allowed to vary. Consideration of this issue originated with Becker (1968); the early writers on enforcement (including Bentham, 1789) did not examine the issue of the choice of enforcement effort. Strict Liability Assume first that the sanction is a fine and that individuals are risk neutral. Then the optimal level of the fine is maximal and the optimal probability is low
312
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
(in a sense to be described). The basic explanation for this conclusion is that if the fine were not maximal, society could save enforcement costs by simultaneously raising the fine and lowering the probability without affecting the level of deterrence. Suppose, for example, that the fine initially is $4,000 and that the probability of detection is 25 percent. Now raise the fine to $10,000, presuming that the maximal fine is at least this high, and lower the probability of detection to 10 percent. Then the expected fine remains equal to $1,000, so that deterrence is maintained, but expenditures on enforcement are significantly reduced, implying that social welfare rises. This process can be continued, and social welfare augmented, as long as the fine is below the maximal level fm. Becker (1968) suggested this result (although much of his analysis implicitly presumes that the fine is not maximal); Carr-Hill and Stern (1979, pp. 280-309) and Polinsky and Shavell (1979) note it explicitly. The optimal probability is low in that there is some underdeterrence; that is, the optimal p is such that the expected fine pfm is less than the harm h (Polinsky and Shavell, 1984). The reason for this result is that if pfm equals h, behavior will be ideal, meaning that the individuals who are just deterred obtain gains essentially equal to the harm. These are the individuals who would be led to commit the harmful act if p were lowered slightly. That in turn must be socially beneficial because these individuals cause no net social losses (because their gains essentially equal the harm), but reducing p saves enforcement costs. How much pfm should be lowered below h depends on the saving in enforcement costs from reducing p compared to the net social costs of underdeterrence that will result if p is lowered non-trivially. If individuals are risk averse, the optimal fine generally is less than maximal, as first shown in Polinsky and Shavell (1979) (and elaborated upon in Kaplow, 1992). This is because the use of a very high fine would impose a substantial risk-bearing cost on individuals who commit the harmful act. Another more particular explanation involves reconsidering the argument that we used in the risk-neutral case. If the fine f is less than fm, it is still true that f can be raised and p lowered so as to maintain deterrence, but because of risk aversion, this implies that pf falls, meaning that fine revenue falls. The reduction in fine revenue reflects the disutility caused by imposing greater risk on risk-averse individuals. If individuals are sufficiently risk averse, the decline in fine revenue associated with greater risk-bearing could more than offset the savings in enforcement expenditures from reducing the probability of detection, implying that social welfare would be lower. Next, assume that the sanction is imprisonment and that individuals are risk neutral in imprisonment, that is, the disutility of imprisonment is the same for each additional year. (We did not discuss individuals’ attitudes toward the risk of imprisonment in Section 3 because the points we made there did not depend on this consideration.) Then the optimal imprisonment term is maximal
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
313
(Shavell, 1991b). The reasoning behind this result parallels that used to show that the optimal fine is maximal when individuals are risk neutral in fines. Specifically, if the imprisonment term is raised and the probability of detection lowered so as to keep the expected sanction constant, neither individual behavior nor the costs of imposing imprisonment are affected (by construction, the expected prison term is the same), but enforcement expenditures fall. Suppose instead that individuals are risk averse in imprisonment. In other words, the disutility of each year of imprisonment grows with the number of years in prison, perhaps because imprisonment becomes increasingly difficult to tolerate. In this case there is a stronger argument for setting the imprisonment sanction maximally than when individuals are risk neutral (Polinsky and Shavell, 1997). This is because, when the imprisonment term is raised, the probability of detection can be lowered even more than in the risk-neutral case without reducing deterrence. Thus, not only are there greater savings in enforcement expenditures, but also the social costs of imposing imprisonment sanctions decline because the expected prison term falls. Last, suppose that individuals are risk preferring in imprisonment, that is, the disutility of each year of imprisonment falls with the number of years in prison. This assumption seems particularly important: the first years of imprisonment may create special disutility, due to brutalization of the prisoner, or due to the stigma effect of having been imprisoned at all. Additionally, the fact that individuals discount the future disutility of imprisonment makes earlier years of imprisonment more important than later ones. If individuals are risk preferring in imprisonment, the optimal sanction may well be less than maximal (Polinsky and Shavell, 1997). In particular, the type of argument used above does not necessarily apply. When the sanction is raised, the probability that maintains deterrence cannot be lowered proportionally, implying that the expected prison term rises. Because the resulting increased cost of imposing imprisonment sanctions might exceed the savings in enforcement expenditures from lowering the probability, the optimal prison term might not be maximal. When the probability of detection is set optimally, together with the imprisonment term, underdeterrence may well result, not only to save enforcement expenditures, but also to reduce the costs of imposing imprisonment sanctions. (In theory, however, overdeterrence could be optimal for the reason mentioned in Section 3 - that overdeterrence could reduce the costs of imprisonment.) Now consider the situation when both fines and imprisonment are employed as sanctions. Recall that under the optimal enforcement policy, the fine must be maximal, for otherwise it cannot be desirable to employ imprisonment. The main point we wish to make is that, unlike when imprisonment is used alone, the optimal imprisonment term may not be maximal even if individuals are risk neutral or risk averse in imprisonment. Suppose that individuals are risk
314
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
neutral in imprisonment and fines. Then if the imprisonment term is raised and the probability of detection is lowered so as to keep the expected imprisonment term constant, deterrence declines because the expected fine falls (due to the reduction in the probability). Hence, to maintain deterrence, the probability cannot fall proportionally. But this implies that the expected prison term, and the costs of imposing imprisonment, are higher than previously. Only if the savings in enforcement costs are sufficiently large, therefore, is it socially desirable to raise the imprisonment sanction. Fault-Based Liability The least expensive way to accomplish compliance with the fault standard is to use the highest possible sanction and, given this sanction, the lowest probability of detection that deters individuals who would be at fault. The reason is that, if all individuals who would be at fault are deterred, the only cost incurred is associated with the setting of the probability; this cost is minimized by using the maximal sanction and a correspondingly low probability. Note that this is true regardless of whether the sanction is a fine or imprisonment and regardless of individuals’ attitudes toward the risk of fines or of imprisonment. Comparison of Rules As we emphasized earlier, under fault-based liability sanctions are not actually imposed (in the absence of mistakes), which is an advantage over strict liability when the sanction is a fine and individuals are risk averse, and is always an advantage when the sanction is imprisonment. Moreover, this advantage of fault-based liability implies a second advantage: it may allow a further savings in enforcement expenditures over that under strict liability. For example, suppose that the sanction is a fine and that injurers are risk averse. Then, as we have emphasized, the optimal fine under strict liability generally is not maximal, due to risk-bearing by injurers. This implies that the probability of detection needed to achieve any given level of deterrence is higher than if the fine were maximal. Under fault-based liability, however, the optimal fine is maximal despite the risk aversion of injurers (because the fine is not actually imposed), meaning that a lower probability can be employed. However, to decide which liability rule is preferable, these advantages of fault-based liability would have to be weighed against the disadvantages of this rule relative to strict liability that we mentioned at the end of Section 3 (one of which, as noted, will be discussed in Section 7). This concludes the presentation of the basic theory of public enforcement of law. We now turn to various extensions and refinements of the analysis.
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
315
5. Accidental Harms As we noted at the outset, we assumed that individuals decide whether or not to commit acts that cause harm with certainty, that is, they decide whether or not to cause intentional harms. In many circumstances, however, harms are accidental - they occur only with a probability. For instance, if a driver speeds, he only creates a likelihood of a collision; or if a firm stores toxic chemicals in a substandard tank, the firm only creates the probability of a harmful spill. Essentially all that we have said above applies in a straightforward way when harms are accidental. If individuals are risk neutral, sanctions are monetary, and the expected sanction equals harm, then induced behavior will be socially optimal; further, the optimal magnitude of sanctions is maximal if individuals are risk neutral because this allows enforcement costs to be saved; and so forth. Our general conclusions from above can thus be interpreted to apply both when harms are intentional and cause harm for sure, as well as when actions alter the risk of harm. There is, however, an additional issue that arises when harm is uncertain: a sanction can be imposed either on the basis of the commission of a dangerous act that increases the chance of harm - storing chemicals in a substandard tank - or on the basis of the actual occurrence of harm - only if the tank ruptures and results in a spill. In principle, either approach can achieve optimal deterrence. To illustrate, suppose that the substandard tank has a 10 percent chance of rupturing, in which case the harm would be $10 million; the expected harm from using the tank therefore is $1 million. If injurers are risk neutral and sanctions are imposed only when harm occurs, deterrence will be optimal if, as usual, the expected sanction equals the harm of $10 million. Alternatively, if sanctions are imposed on the basis of the dangerous act of using the substandard tank, deterrence will be optimal if the owner of the tank faces an expected sanction equal to the expected harm due to his use of the substandard tank, $1 million. Several factors are relevant to the choice between act-based and harm-based sanctions (Shavell, 1993). First, act-based sanctions need not be as high to accomplish a given level of deterrence, and thus offer an underlying advantage over harm-based sanctions because of limitations in parties’ assets. In the example in the preceding paragraph, the owner of the storage tank might be able to pay the $1 million required if sanctions are act-based but not the $10 million required if sanctions are harm-based. Second, and closely related, because act-based sanctions need not be as high to accomplish deterrence, they offer an advantage over harm-based sanctions when parties are risk averse. Third, act-based sanctions and harm-based sanctions may differ in the ease with which they can be applied. In some circumstances, act-based sanctions may be simpler to impose (it might be less difficult to determine whether an oil shipper properly maintains its vessels’ holding tanks than to detect whether one
316
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
of the vessels leaked oil into the ocean); in other circumstances, harm-based sanctions may be easier (a driver who causes harm might be caught without difficulty, but not one who speeds). Fourth, it may be hard to calculate the expected harm due to an act, but relatively easy to ascertain the actual harm if it eventuates; if so, this constitutes an advantage of harm-based liability.
6. Costs of Imposing Fines We inquire in this section about the implications of costs borne by enforcement authorities in imposing fines. Our principal observation is that such costs should raise the level of the fine. We assume for simplicity that the probability of detection is fixed, that liability is strict, and that individuals are risk neutral. In this setting, recall from Section 3 that the optimal fine is h/p, the harm divided by the probability of detection. Now let there be a public cost k of imposing a fine. The optimal fine then becomes h/p + k; the cost k should be added to the fine that would otherwise be desirable (Becker, 1968, p. 192 and Polinsky and Shavell, 1992). The intuition behind this result is that, if an individual commits a harmful act, he causes society to bear not only the immediate harm h, but also, with probability p, the cost k of imposing the fine - that is, his act results in an expected total social cost of h + pk. If the fine is h/p + k, the individual’s expected fine is p[(h/p) + k] = h + pk, leading him to commit the harmful act if and only if his gain exceeds the expected total social cost of his act. For example, suppose the harm is $1,000, the probability of detection is 25 percent, and the cost of imposing the fine is $500. An individual’s harmful act causes society to bear expected total social costs of $1,125 - the harm of $1,000 plus a 25 percent chance of the $500 cost of imposing a fine. If the fine is set equal to $4,500, the individual’s expected fine also will equal $1,125. Additionally, observe that, not only does the state bear costs when fines are imposed, so do individuals who pay the fines (such as legal defense expenses). The costs borne by individuals, however, do not affect the formula for the optimal fine. Individuals properly take these costs into account, because they bear them.
7. Level of Activity We have been assuming that the sole decision that an individual makes is whether to act in a way that causes harm when engaging in some activity. In many contexts, however, an individual also makes a choice about his activity
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
317
level - that is, not only does he choose whether to commit a harmful act when engaging in an activity, he also chooses whether to engage in that activity or, more generally, at what level to do so. For example, besides deciding how to behave when driving (whether to exercise care in changing lanes), an individual also chooses how many miles to drive; the number of miles driven is the individual’s level of activity. Similarly, not only does a firm decide how to conduct its operations during production (whether to pollute), it also chooses its level of production; the output of the firm is its level of activity. The socially optimal activity level is such that the individual’s marginal utility from the activity just equals the marginal expected harm caused by the activity. Thus, the optimal number of miles driven is the level at which the marginal utility of driving an extra mile just equals the marginal expected harm per mile driven. The determination of the optimal level of activity presumes that individuals act optimally when engaging in the activity - for example, that they drive with appropriate care. Thus, in determining the optimal level of activity, an individual’s marginal utility from the activity is compared to the expected harm that results when he acts appropriately when engaging in the activity. Often this expected harm is positive even when a party acts optimally, because the cost of precautions (or, equivalently, the gain or savings from not taking precautions) exceeds the expected reduction in harm that taking the precautions would bring about. Will parties’ choices about their activity levels be socially correct under the two major forms of liability? The answer is that under strict liability, their choices about activity levels will be correct, but under fault-based liability, they generally will participate in activities to a socially excessive extent. Under strict liability, parties will choose the optimal level of activity because they will pay for all harm done. They will choose the optimal number of miles to drive because they will pay for all harm per mile driven. Under fault-based liability, however, parties generally do not pay for the harm they cause because, as we have discussed, they will be induced to behave so as not to be found at fault. Consequently, when deciding on their level of activity, they will choose an excessive level. They will not take into account the harm that each additional mile of driving causes, and therefore they will drive too much. The interpretation of the preceding points in relation to firms is that under strict liability the product price will reflect the expected harm caused by production, so that the price will reflect the full social cost of production. Hence, the amount purchased, and thus the level of production, will tend to be socially optimal. However, under fault-based liability, the product price will not reflect harm, but only the cost of precautions; thus, the amount sold, and the level of production, will be excessive. A related comment is that safety regulations and other regulatory requirements are often framed as standards of care that have to be met, but
318
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
which, if met, free the regulated party from liability. Hence, regulations of this character are subject to the criticism that they lead to excessive levels of the regulated activity. Making parties strictly liable for harm would be superior to safety regulation with respect to inducing socially correct activity levels. The tendency of parties to choose an excessive level of activity under fault-based liability, but not under strict liability, constitutes a fundamental advantage of strict liability; it was first emphasized in Shavell (1980) and Polinsky (1980b). This advantage, note, is stronger the greater is the harm engendered by engaging in the activity (given that behavior is optimal when engaging in the activity). Thus, for activities for which expected harm is likely to be substantial, the disadvantage of fault-based liability will be significant.
8. Mistakes Errors of the two classic types can occur in public enforcement of law. First, an individual who should be found liable might mistakenly not be found liable - a Type I error. Second, an individual who should not be found liable might mistakenly be found liable - a Type II error. For an individual who has been detected, let the probabilities of these errors be 01 and 02, respectively. Given the probability of detection p and the chances of Type I and Type II errors, an individual will commit the wrongful act if and only if his gain g net of his expected fine if he does commit it exceeds his expected fine if he does not commit it, namely, when g ! p(1 ! 01)f > ! p02f, or, equivalently, when g > (1 ! 01 ! 02)pf. The first point to note is that, as emphasized in Png (1986), both types of error reduce deterrence: the term (1 ! 01 ! 02)pf is declining in both 01 and 02. The first type of error diminishes deterrence because it lowers the expected fine if an individual violates the law. The second type of error, when an individual is mistakenly found liable, also lowers deterrence because it reduces the difference between the expected fine from violating the law and not violating it. In other words, the greater is 02, the smaller the increase in the expected fine if one violates the law, making a violation less costly to the individual. Because mistakes dilute deterrence, they reduce social welfare (see generally Kaplow and Shavell, 1994a). Specifically, to achieve any level of deterrence, the probability p must be higher to offset the effect of errors. It should also be noted that, were one to take into account an individual’s decision whether to engage in an activity (like driving), Type II errors have the additional effect of discouraging socially desirable participation in the activity. Now consider the optimal choice of the fine. Given any probability of detection, the dilution in deterrence caused by errors requires a higher fine to restore deterrence. If the probability and the fine are variable, then, as
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
319
explained in Section 4, the optimal fine is maximal. Somewhat surprisingly, the optimal fine remains maximal despite mistakes, by essentially the argument used previously: if the fine f were less than maximal, then f could be raised and the probability p lowered so as to keep deterrence constant, but saving enforcement costs. Now consider the possible risk aversion of individuals. As we emphasized in Section 4, the optimal fine under strict liability generally is less than maximal when individuals are risk averse, because lowering the fine from the maximum level reduces the bearing of risk. Introducing the possibility of mistakes may increase the desirability of lowering the fine because, due to Type II errors, individuals who do not violate the law are subject to the risk of having to pay a fine (Block and Sidak, 1980). Indeed, because the number of persons who do not violate the law often would far exceed the number who do, the desire to avoid imposing risk on the former group can lead to a substantial reduction in the optimal fine. Next, consider imprisonment and mistake. In this regard, our conclusions parallel those with respect to fines in several respects. Notably, mistakes of both types dilute the deterrent effects of imprisonment; and the optimal imprisonment term is maximal if individuals are risk neutral or risk averse in imprisonment but generally is not maximal if they are risk preferring in imprisonment. We have not yet commented on fault-based liability. Here, an important implication of mistake is that some individuals will bear sanctions even if they comply with the fault standard. Hence, the results regarding the optimal probability of detection and the sanction under strict liability apply to some extent under fault-based liability as well. Moreover, as stressed by Craswell and Calfee (1986), individuals will often have a motive to take excessive precautions in order to reduce the chance of being found erroneously at fault. Finally, observe that, although we have treated the probabilities of error as fixed, they can be influenced by procedural choices. For example, prosecutorial resources can be increased in order to reduce the probability of a Type I error, or the standard of proof can be raised to reduce the chance of a Type II error (although this presumably increases Type I errors). Because the reduction of both types of error increase deterrence, expenditures made to reduce errors may be socially beneficial (Kaplow and Shavell, 1994a).
9. General Enforcement In many settings, enforcement may be said to be general in the sense that several different types of violations will be detected by an enforcement agent’s activity. For example, a police officer waiting at the roadside may notice a driver who litters as well as one who goes through a red light or who speeds, and a tax auditor may detect a variety of infractions when he examines a tax
320
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
return. To investigate such situations, suppose that a single probability of detection applies uniformly to all harmful acts, regardless of the magnitude of the harm. (The contrasting assumption is that enforcement is specific, meaning that the probability is chosen independently for each type of harmful act.) The main point that we want to make is that in contexts in which enforcement is general, the optimal sanction rises with the severity of the harm and is maximal only for relatively high harms; this point was first made in Shavell (1991b) (Mookherjee and Png, 1992a is closely related). To see this, assume that liability is strict, the sanction is a fine, and injurers are risk neutral. Let f(h) be the fine given harm h. Then, for any given general probability of detection p, the optimal fine schedule is h/p, provided that h/p is feasible; otherwise - for high h (all h such that h/p > fm) - the optimal fine is maximal. This schedule is obviously optimal given p because it implies that the expected fine equals harm, thereby inducing ideal behavior, whenever that is possible. The question remains whether it would be desirable to lower p and raise fines to the maximal level for the low-harm acts for which h/p is less than maximal. The answer is that if p is reduced for the relatively low-harm acts (and the fine raised for them), then p - being general - is also reduced for the high-harm acts for which the fine is already maximal, resulting in lower deterrence of these acts. The decline in deterrence of high-harm acts may cause a greater social loss than the savings in enforcement costs from lowering p. To express this point differently, p must be sufficiently high to avoid significant underdeterrence of high-harm acts (for which fines are maximal). But since this p also applies to less harmful acts, the fines for them do not need to be maximal in order to appropriately deter them. The result that, when enforcement is general, sanctions should rise with the severity of harm up to a maximum also holds if the sanction is imprisonment and if liability is fault-based. The underlying reasoning is the same as that given above.
10. Marginal Deterrence In many circumstances, a person may consider which of several harmful acts to commit, for example, whether to release only a small amount of a pollutant into a river or a large amount, or whether to kidnap a person or also to kill the kidnap victim. In such contexts, the threat of sanctions plays a role in addition to the usual one of attempting to deter individuals from committing harmful acts: for individuals who are not deterred, sanctions influence which harmful acts individuals choose to commit. Notably, such individuals will have a reason to commit less harmful rather than more harmful acts if expected sanctions rise with harm. Deterrence of a more harmful act because its sanction exceeds that
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
321
for a less harmful act is sometimes referred to as marginal deterrence (it apparently was so named by Stigler, 1970). Other things being equal, as observed by Beccaria (1770, p. 32) and Bentham (1789, p. 171), it is socially desirable that enforcement policy creates marginal deterrence, so that those who are not deterred from committing harmful acts have a reason to moderate the amount of harm that they cause. This suggests that sanctions should rise with the magnitude of harm and, therefore, that sanctions should not generally be maximal. However, fostering marginal deterrence may conflict with achieving deterrence generally: in order for the schedule of sanctions to rise steeply enough to accomplish marginal deterrence, sanctions for less harmful acts may have to be so low that individuals are not deterred from committing some harmful act. We have two additional observations to make about marginal deterrence. First, marginal deterrence can be promoted by increasing the probability of detection as well as the magnitude of sanctions. For example, kidnappers can be better deterred from killing their victims if more police resources are devoted to apprehending kidnappers who murder their victims than to those who do not. (But in circumstances in which enforcement is general, the probability of detection cannot be independently altered for acts that cause different degrees of harm.) Second, marginal deterrence is naturally accomplished if the expected sanction equals harm for all levels of harm; for if a person is paying for harm done, he will have to pay appropriately more if he does greater harm. Thus, for instance, if a polluter’s expected fine would rise from $100 to $500 if he dumps five gallons instead of one gallon of waste into a lake, where each gallon causes $100 of harm, his marginal incentives to pollute will be correct. For formal analyses of marginal deterrence, see Shavell (1992), Wilde (1992), and Mookherjee and Png (1994).
11. Principal-Agent Relationship Although we have assumed that an injurer is a single actor, injurers often are more appropriately characterized as collective entities, and specifically as a principal and the principal’s agent. For example, the principal could be a firm and the agent an employee; or the principal could be a contractor and the agent a subcontractor. When harm is caused by the behavior of principals and agents, many of the conclusions of our prior analysis are not fundamentally altered; they simply carry over to the sanctioning of principals. Notably, if a risk-neutral principal faces an expected fine equal to harm done, he will in effect be in the same position vis-à-vis his agent as society is vis-à-vis a single potential violator of law (see Newman and Wright, 1990 on a closely related point). Consequently,
322
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
the principal will behave socially optimally in controlling his agents, and in particular will contract with them and monitor them in ways that will give the agents socially appropriate incentives to reduce harm (but see Arlen, 1994). Another result that carries over to the principal-agent context is that it often will be desirable for society to tolerate some degree of underdeterrence in order to conserve enforcement resources. A question about enforcement that arises when there are principals and agents is the allocation of financial sanctions between the two parties. It is apparent, however, that the particular allocation of sanctions does not matter when, as would be the natural presumption, the parties can reallocate the sanctions through their own contract. For example, if the agent finds that he faces a large fine but is more risk averse than the principal, the principal can assume it; conversely, if the fine is imposed on the principal, he will retain it and not impose an internal sanction on the agent. Thus, the post-contract sanctions that the agent bears are not affected by the particular division of sanctions initially selected by the enforcement authority. The allocation of monetary sanctions between principals and agents would matter, however, if some allocations allow the pair to reduce their total burden. An important example is when a fine is imposed only on the agent and he is unable to pay it because his assets are less than the fine (see Sykes, 1981, and Kornhauser, 1982). Then, he and the principal (who often would have higher assets) would jointly escape part of the fine, diluting deterrence. The fine therefore should be imposed on the principal rather than on the agent (or at least the part of the fine that the agent cannot pay). A closely related point is that the imposition of imprisonment sanctions on agents may be desirable when their assets are less than the harm that they can cause, even if the principal’s assets are sufficient to pay the optimal fine (see Polinsky and Shavell, 1993). The fact that an agent’s assets are limited means that the principal may be unable to control him adequately through use of contractually-determined penalties, which can only be monetary. For example, a firm may not be able, despite the threat of salary reduction or dismissal, to induce its employees never to rig bids. In such circumstances, it may be socially valuable to use the threat of personal criminal liability and a jail sentence to better control agents’ misconduct.
12. Settlements Although we have thus far assumed that when a liable injurer is discovered he is sanctioned in some automatic fashion, in practice he must be found civilly or criminally liable in a trial, and before this occurs, he commonly settles in lieu of trial. (In the criminal context, the settlement usually takes the form of
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
323
a plea bargain, an agreement in which the injurer pleads guilty to a reduced charge.) Given the prevalence of settlements, it is important to consider how they affect deterrence and the optimal system of public enforcement, and whether settlements are socially desirable. There are two general reasons why parties might prefer an out-of-court settlement to a trial (see generally the survey by Cooter and Rubinfeld, 1989; and for some recent discussions of plea bargaining, see, for example, Reinganum, 1988, and Miceli, 1996). First, a trial is costly to the parties in terms of time and/or money. Second, settlements eliminate the risks inherent in the trial outcome, a benefit to parties who are averse to such risks. These advantages of settlement to the parties suggest that settlement is socially valuable, but the effect of settlement on deterrence is a complicating factor. Specifically, settlements dilute deterrence: for if injurers desire to settle, it must be because the expected disutility of sanctions is lowered for them (see generally Polinsky and Rubinfeld, 1988). The state may be able to offset this settlement-related reduction in deterrence by increasing the level of sanctions; if so, settlements need not compromise the overall level of deterrence. Settlements may have other socially undesirable consequences. First, they may result in sanctions that are not as well tailored to harmful acts as would be true of court-determined sanctions. For example, if injurers have private information about the harm that they have caused, settlements will tend to reflect the average harm caused, whereas trial outcomes may better approximate the actual harm. Thus, the distribution of sanctions meted out through settlements will not be as good in terms of inducing injurers to take proper precautions (high-harm injurers will be underdeterred, and vice versa). Second, settlements hinder the amplification and development of the law through the setting of precedents, a factor of occasional relevance; and settlements also sometimes allow defendants to keep aspects of their behavior secret, which can reduce deterrence. Third, settlements for prison terms can result in increases in public expenditures on jail if defendants are risk averse in imprisonment. On the social desirability of settlement, see, for example, Shavell (1997a) and Spier (1997).
13. Self-Reporting We have assumed that individuals are subject to sanctions only if they are detected by an enforcement agent, but in fact parties sometimes disclose their own violations to enforcement authorities. For example, firms often report violations of environmental and safety regulations, individuals usually notify police of their involvement in traffic accidents, and even criminals occasionally turn themselves in.
324
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
We explain here why it is generally socially desirable for the structure of enforcement to be such as to encourage self-reporting (see Kaplow and Shavell, 1994b). Self-reporting can be induced by lowering the sanction for individuals who disclose their own infractions. Moreover, the reward for self-reporting can be made small enough that deterrence is only negligibly reduced. To amplify, assume for simplicity that the sanction is a fine f, that the probability of detection is p, and that individuals are risk neutral. If an individual commits a violation and does not self report, his expected fine is pf. Suppose the fine if an individual self-reports is set just below pf, say at pf ! 0, where 0 > 0 is arbitrarily small. Then the individual will want to self-report but the deterrent effect of the sanction will be (approximately) the same as if he did not self-report. For example, suppose that the fine if an individual does not self report is $1,000 and that the probability of detection is 10 percent, so the expected fine is $100. If the fine for self-reporting is slightly below $100, such as $95, or even $99, individuals will self-report but deterrence will barely be reduced. Given that self-reporting can be induced essentially without compromising deterrence, why is self-reporting socially advantageous? There are two basic reasons. First, self-reporting reduces enforcement costs because, when it occurs, the enforcement authority does not have to identify and prove who the violator was. If a company reports that it caused pollution, environmental enforcers do not need to spend as much effort trying to detect pollution and establishing its source. Second, self-reporting reduces risk, and thus is advantageous if injurers are risk averse. Drivers bear less risk because they know that if they cause an accident, they can (and will be led to) report this to the police and suffer a lower and certain sanction, rather than face a substantially higher sanction (for hit and run driving) imposed only with some probability.
14. Repeat Offenders In practice, the law often sanctions repeat offenders more severely than first-time offenders. We explain here why such a policy may be socially desirable. Note first that sanctioning repeat offenders more severely cannot be socially advantageous if deterrence always induces first-best behavior. If the sanction for polluting and causing a $1,000 harm is $1,000, then any person who pollutes and pays $1,000 is a person whose gain from polluting (say the savings from not installing pollution control equipment) must have exceeded $1,000. Social welfare therefore is higher as a result of his polluting. If such an individual polluted and was sanctioned in the past, that only means that it was socially desirable for him to have polluted previously. Raising the current sanction because of his having a record of sanctions would overdeter him now.
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
325
Accordingly, only if deterrence is inadequate is it possibly desirable to condition sanctions on offense history to increase deterrence. But deterrence often will be inadequate because, as we emphasized in Section 4, it will usually be worthwhile for the state to tolerate some underdeterrence in order to reduce enforcement expenses. Given that there is underdeterrence, making sanctions depend on offense history may be beneficial for two reasons. First, as developed in Polinsky and Shavell (1996), the use of offense history may create an additional incentive not to violate the law: if getting caught violating the law implies not only an immediate sanction, but also a higher sanction for any future violation, an individual will be more deterred from committing a violation presently. Second, as studied, for example, in Rubinstein (1979) and Polinsky and Rubinfeld (1991), making sanctions depend on offense history allows society to take advantage of information about the dangerousness of individuals and the need to deter them: individuals with offense histories may be more likely than average to commit future violations, which might make it desirable for purposes of deterrence to impose higher sanctions on them. There is also an incapacitation-based (see Section 16) reason for making sanctions depend on offense history. Repeat offenders are more likely to have higher propensities to commit violations in the future and thus more likely to be worth incapacitating by imprisonment.
15. Imperfect Knowledge about the Probability and Magnitude of Sanctions Although we have implicitly assumed that injurers know the probability and magnitude of sanctions, this is not always the case. Individuals frequently have imperfect knowledge of these variables; that is, they have estimates, or more likely, subjective probability distributions, describing the true probability of a sanction and its true magnitude. They might not know the true probability of a sanction for several reasons: because the enforcement authority refrains from publishing information about the probability (perhaps hoping that individuals will believe it to be higher than it is in fact); because the probability is variable, depending on factors that individuals do not fully understand (the probability of a tax audit, for example, is influenced by a large number of considerations); and because probabilities seem to be difficult for individuals to assess. Also, individuals may have incomplete knowledge of the true magnitude of sanctions, particularly if the magnitudes of sanctions are not fixed by law, but are to some degree discretionary. The implications of injurers’ imperfect knowledge are straightforward. First, to predict how individuals behave, what is relevant, of course, is not the
326
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
actual probability and magnitude of a sanction, but the perceived levels or distributions of these variables. Second, to determine the optimal probability and magnitude of a sanction, account must be taken of the relationship between the actual and the perceived variables (on which, see, for instance, Bebchuk and Kaplow, 1992, and see Kaplow, 1990b, on learning about sanctions). For example, suppose that there is a delay of at least a year before individuals fully comprehend a change in the probability of enforcement. Then if enforcement resources are increased so as to make the probability, say, 15 percent rather than 10 percent, there might not be a significant increase in deterrence for some time, making such an investment less worthwhile. Or, for instance, suppose that the sanction for some act, such as robbery, is variable (say from one month of jail time to 10 years), and that individuals’ perceptions are quite rough, not based on true averages but more on the possible range. Then increasing the average sentence might have very little effect on deterrence, but increasing the probability substantially might still augment deterrence. The psychology and learning process (see Sah, 1991) by which individuals assimilate and formulate perceived probabilities of sanctions and their magnitude are important, therefore, to determining how deterrence works and what optimal policy is.
16. Incapacitation Our discussion of public enforcement has presumed that the threat of sanctions reduces harm by discouraging individuals from causing harm - that is, by deterring them. However, an entirely different way for society to reduce harm is by imposing sanctions that remove parties from positions in which they are able to cause harm - that is, by incapacitating them. Imprisonment is the primary incapacitative sanction, although there are other examples: individuals can lose their drivers licenses, preventing them from doing harm while driving; businesses can lose their right to operate in certain domains, and the like. We focus here on imprisonment, but what we say applies to incapacitative sanctions generally; on the economic theory of incapacitation, see Shavell (1987b). To better understand the role of public enforcement when sanctions are incapacitative, suppose that the sole function of sanctions is to incapacitate; that is, sanctions do not deter. (Deterrence might not occur if, for instance, individuals’ gains from harmful acts exceed the expected sanctions, given the relevant range of the probabilities and magnitudes of the sanctions.) We assume that the social goal is as before, to maximize gains from acts less harm, and less the costs of enforcement and sanctions, including the costs of keeping individuals in prison.
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
327
The optimal sanction to impose on an individual who is apprehended is determined by comparing the expected harm, net of gains, he would cause if not in prison to the private and public costs of imprisonment. If the expected net harm exceeds the costs of imprisonment, he should be put in prison and kept there as long as this condition holds. Thus, the optimal sanction as a function of expected net harm is zero up to a threshold - the point at which expected net harm equals the costs of imprisonment - and then rises discontinuously to the length of time during which the person’s net expected harm exceeds imprisonment costs. Jail should only be used to incapacitate individuals whose net harm is relatively high. Two points about the incapacitative rationale are worth making. First, there is evidence that suggests that the expected harm caused by individuals declines with their age. Thus, from the incapacitative standpoint, individuals should be released from jail when their dangerousness falls below the cost of incapacitation. Second, as a matter of logic, the incapacitative rationale might imply that a person should be put in jail even if he has not committed a crime - because his danger to society makes incapacitating him worthwhile. This would be true, for example, if there were some means accurately to predict a person’s dangerousness independently of his actual behavior. In practice, however, the fact that a person has committed a harmful act may be the best basis for predicting his future behavior, in which case the incapacitation rationale would suggest imposing a jail term only if the individual has committed an especially harmful act. Last, we comment on the relationship between optimal enforcement when incapacitation is the goal versus when deterrence is the goal. First, when incapacitation is the goal, the optimal magnitude of the sanction is independent of the probability of apprehension. In contrast, when deterrence is the goal, the optimal sanction depends on the probability - the sanction generally is higher the lower is the probability. Second, when incapacitation is the goal, the sanction rises discontinuously with the magnitude of harm (from zero to a positive amount), but when deterrence is the goal the sanction rises continuously with harm. Third, when deterrence is the goal, the probability and magnitude of sanctions depend on the ability to deter, and if this ability is limited (as, for instance, with the enraged), a low expected sanction may be optimal. However, a high expected sanction still might be called for to incapacitate.
328
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
17. Conclusion It may be worthwhile summarizing the main points that we have made in this chapter: (a) When the probability of detection is for some reason fixed, the benchmark level of the optimal fine is the harm divided by the probability of detection, for this results in an expected fine equal to the harm. However, costs incurred by the public in collecting the fine should be added to the benchmark level of the fine, and risk aversion of injurers should usually lower the level of the fine. (b) When the probability of detection may be varied, high sanctions may be optimal, for this allows a relatively low probability to be employed and thereby saves enforcement costs. Indeed, the optimal fine is in principle maximal for this reason if individuals are risk neutral in wealth, and the optimal imprisonment term is maximal if individuals are risk neutral or risk averse in imprisonment. More realistically, optimal sanctions are not maximal when individuals are risk averse in wealth or risk preferring in imprisonment (as well as for the general enforcement reasons discussed in Section 9), although the motive to set sanctions at relatively high levels in order to reduce enforcement costs still applies. (c) Optimal enforcement tends to be characterized by some degree of underdeterrence relative to first-best behavior, because this conserves enforcement resources. More precisely, by lowering the probability of detection from a level that would lead to first-best behavior, the state reduces enforcement costs, and although more individuals commit the harmful act, these individuals do not cause social welfare to decline substantially because their gains are nearly equal to the harm. (d) The use of fines should be exhausted before resort is made to costlier sanctions, notably imprisonment. (e) An advantage of fault-based liability over strict liability is that costly sanctions - fines when individuals are risk averse, and imprisonment - are imposed less often: under fault-based liability, injurers generally are induced (in the absence of mistakes) to obey fault standards, and therefore ordinarily do not bear sanctions. Under strict liability, however, injurers are sanctioned whenever they are caught. (f) An advantage of strict liability over fault-based liability is that it is easier to apply. Another advantage is that injurers’ activity-level decisions generally will be better: under strict liability, injurers’ activity levels will tend to be optimal because injurers will pay for harm that they cause. But under fault-based liability, their activity levels will tend to be excessive because they generally will not pay for harm that they cause (because they will be led to behave without fault).
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
329
These and other basic conclusions about the public enforcement of law that we have described in this essay are now, for the most part, well-established in the economic literature on enforcement. However, an important aspect of this subject that has received relatively little attention is the behavior of public enforcers themselves. Because our focus was on deriving socially optimal public enforcement policies, we assumed, as is conventional, that public enforcers act so as to maximize social welfare. A logical step to take next would be to re-examine optimal enforcement policies when public enforcers behave in a self-interested manner. Although some effort already has been devoted to this inquiry, much remains to be done.
Acknowledgments Polinsky’s research was supported by the Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences (through National Science Foundation grant #SBR-960123) and the John M. Olin Program in Law and Economics at Stanford Law School. Shavell’s research was supported by the John M. Olin Center for Law, Economics, and Business at Harvard Law School. This essay previously appeared with a less comprehensive bibliography in Peter Newman (ed.), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and The Law, London, Macmillan Reference Ltd. (1998).
Bibliography on Public Enforcement of Law (8000) Adelstein, Richard and Miceli, Thomas J. (1997), ‘Toward a Comparative Economics of Plea Bargaining’, Manuscript. Allingham, Michael G. and Sandmo, Agnar (1972), ‘Income Tax Evasion: A Theoretical Analysis’, 1 Journal of Public Economics, 323-338. Altrogge, Phyllis and Shughart, William F. (1984), ‘The Regressive Nature of Civil Penalties’, 4 International Review of Law and Economics, 55-66. Andenaes, Johannes (1966), ‘The General Preventive Effects of Punishment’, 114 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 949-983. Andenaes, Johannes (1971), ‘Deterrence and Specific Offenses’, 38 University of Chicago Law Review, 537-553. Andenaes, Johannes (1974), Punishment and Deterrence, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press. Anderson, Lee G. and Lee, Dwight R. (1986), ‘Optimal Governing Instrument, Operation Level, and Enforcement in Natural Resource Regulation: The Case of the Fishery’, 68 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 678-690. Andreoni, James (1991), ‘Reasonable Doubt and the Optimal Magnitude of Fines: Should the Penalty Fit the Crime?’, 22 RAND Journal of Economics, 385-395.
330
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
Andreoni, James, Erard, Brian and Feinstein, Jonathan (1998), ‘Tax Compliance’, Journal of Economic Literature, forthcoming. Arlen, Jennifer A. (1994), ‘The Potentially Perverse Effects of Corporate Criminal Liability’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 833-867. Arlen, Jennifer. (1997), ‘Corporate Crime and Its Control’, U.S.C. Law School Working Paper Series, Working Paper No. 97-2, forthcoming in The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law. Arlen, Jennifer and Kraakman, Reinier (1997), ‘Controlling Corporate Misconduct: An Analysis of Corporate Liability Regimes’, 72 New York University Law Review, 687-779. Avio, Kenneth L. (1975), ‘Recidivism in the Economic Model of Crime’, 13 Economic Inquiry, 450-456. Avio, Kenneth L. (1987), ‘Clemency in Economic and Retributive Models of Punishment’, 7 International Review of Law and Economics, 79-88. Avio, Kenneth L. and Clark, C. Scott (1976), Property Crime in Canada: An Econometric Study, Toronto, University of Toronto Press. Ayres, Ian and Levitt, Steven D. (1998), ‘Measuring the Positive Externalities from Unobservable Victim Precaution: An Empirical Analysis of Lojack’, Quarterly Journal of Economics, forthcoming. Baldry, Jonathan C. (1980), ‘Crimes Punishable by Imprisonment: A Note’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 617-619. Baldry, J.C. (1984), ‘The Enforcement of Income Tax Laws: Efficiency Implications’, 60 Economic Record, 156-159. Basu, Kaushik, Bhattacharya, Sudipto and Mishra, Ajit (1992), ‘Notes on Bribery and the Control of Corruption’, 48 Journal of Public Economics, 349-359. Bebchuk, Lucian Arye and Kaplow, Louis (1992), ‘Optimal Sanctions When Individuals Are Imperfectly Informed About the Probability of Apprehension’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 365-370. Bebchuk, Lucian Arye and Kaplow, Louis (1993), ‘Optimal Sanctions and Differences in Individuals’ Likelihood of Avoiding Detection’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 217-224. Beccaria, Cesare (1770), On Crimes and Punishments, and Other Writings. Bellamy, Richard (ed.), Davies, Richard, et al. (trans.), New York, Cambridge University Press, 1995. Becker, Gary S. (1968), ‘Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach’, 76 Journal of Political Economy, 169-217. Becker, Gary S. and Landes, William M. (eds) (1974), Essays in the Economics of Crime and Punishment, New York, Columbia University Press. Becker, Gary S. and Stigler, George J. (1974), ‘Law Enforcement, Malfeasance, and Compensation of Enforcers’, 3 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-18. Ben-Shahar, Omri (1997), ‘Playing Without a Rulebook: Optimal Enforcement When Individuals Learn the Penalty Only by Committing the Crime’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 409-421. Ben-Shahar, Omri and Harel, Alon (1995), ‘Blaming the Victim: Optimal Incentives for Private Precautions Against Crime’, 11 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 434-455. Ben-Shahar, Omri and Harel, Alon (1996), ‘The Economics of the Law of Criminal Attempts: A Victim-Centered Perspective’, 145 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 299-351.
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
331
Benson, Bruce L. and Baden, John (1985), ‘The Political Economy of Government Corruption: The Logic of Underground Government’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 391-410. Benson, Bruce L., Kim, Iljoong and Rasmussen, David W. (1994), ‘Estimating Deterrence Effects: A Public Choice Perspective on the Economics of Crime Literature’,61 Southern Economic Journal, 161-168. Bentham, Jeremy (1789), ‘An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation’, in The Utilitarians, Rept. Garden City, NY, Anchor Books, 1973. Besanko, David and Spulber, Daniel F. (1989), ‘Delegated Law Enforcement and Noncooperative Behavior’, 5 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 25-52. Block, Michael K. (1991), ‘Optimal Penalties, Criminal Law and the Control of Corporate Behavior’, 71 Boston University Law Review, 395-419. Block, Michael K. and Feinstein, Jonathan S. (1986), ‘The Spillover Effect of Antitrust Enforcement’, 68 Review of Economics and Statistics, 122-131. Block, Michael K. and Lind, Robert C. (1975a), ‘Crime and Punishment Reconsidered’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 241-247. Block, Michael K. and Lind, Robert C. (1975b), ‘An Economic Analysis of Crimes Punishable by Imprisonment’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 479-492. Block, Michael K. and Sidak, Joseph Gregory (1980), ‘The Cost of Antitrust Deterrence: Why Not Hang a Price Fixer Now and Then?’, 68 Georgetown Law Journal, 1131-1139. Block, Michael Kent, Nold, Frederick Carl and Sidak, Joseph Gregory (1981), ‘The Deterrent Effect of Antitrust Enforcement’, 89 Journal of Political Economy, 429-445. Bone, John (1985), ‘On Substituting a Socially Costless Penalty for Costly Crime’, 5 International Review of Law and Economics, 239-246. Bose, Pinaki (1995a), ‘Anticipatory Compliance and Effective Regulatory Activity’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 151-159. Bose, Pinaki (1995b), ‘Regulatory Errors, Optimal Fines, and the Level of Compliance’, 56 Journal of Public Economics, 475-484. Bowles, Roger and Garoupa, Nuno (1997), ‘Casual Police Corruption and the Economics of Crime’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 75-87. Brown, William W. and Reynolds, Morgan O. (1973), ‘Crime and “Punishment”: Risk Implications’, 6 Journal of Economic Theory, 508-514. Burnovski, Moshe and Safra, Zvi (1994), ‘Deterrence Effects of Sequential Punishment Policies: Should Repeat Offenders be More Severely Punished?’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 341-350. Cadot, Olivier (1987), ‘Corruption as a Gamble’, 33 Journal of Public Economics, 223-244. Cameron, Samuel (1988), ‘The Economics of Crime Deterrence: A Survey of Theory and Evidence’, 41 Kyklos, 301-323. Cameron, Samuel (1989), ‘On the Welfare Economics of Capital Punishment’, 28 Australian Economic Papers, 253-266. Campbell, Donald T. and Ross, H. Laurence (1988), ‘The Connecticut Crackdown on Speeding: Time-Series Data in Quasi-experimental Analysis’, in Overman, E. Samuel (ed.), Methodology and Epistemology of Social Science: Selected Papers, Chicago and London, University of Chicago Press, 222-237. Carlin, Paul and Sandy, Robert (1990), ‘The Value of Time and the Effect of Fines on Child Car Safety Seat Usage’, 22 Applied Economics, 463-476.
332
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
Carr-Hill, R.A. and Stern, N.H. (1979), Crime, the Police and Criminal Statistics: An Analysis of Official Statistics for England and Wales Using Econometric Methods, London, Academic Press. Chu, C.Y. Cyrus (1979), ‘Crime and Punishment with Possible Post-Offense Compromise’, 17 Academia Economic Papers, 131-167. Chu, C.Y. Cyrus (1990), ‘Plea Bargaining with the IRS’, 41 Journal of Public Economics, 319-333. Chu, C.Y. Cyrus (1991), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Criminal Proceedings in Civil-Law Countries’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 111-116. Chu, C.Y. Cyrus (1993), ‘Oscillatory vs. Stationary Enforcement of Law’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 303-315. Chu, C.Y. Cyrus and Jiang, Neville (1993), ‘Are Fines More Efficient than Imprisonment?’, 51 Journal of Public Economics, 391-413. Chu, C.Y. Cyrus, Hu, Sheng-cheng and Huang, Ting-yuan (1997), ‘Punishing Repeat Offenders More Severely!’, Manuscript. Chwe, Michael Suk-Young (1990), ‘Why Were Workers Whipped? Pain in a Principal-Agent Model’, 100 Economic Journal, 1109-1121. Clotfelter, Charles T. (1977), ‘Public Services, Private Substitutes, and the Demand for Protection Against Crime’, 67 American Economic Review, 867-877. Clotfelter, Charles T. (1983), ‘Tax Evasion and Tax Rates: An Analysis of Individual Returns’, 65 Review of Economics and Statistics, 363-373. Coffee, John C., Jr (1980), ‘Corporate Crime and Punishment: A Non-Chicago View of the Economics of Criminal Sanctions’, 17 American Criminal Law Review, 419-476. Cohen, Mark A. (1986), ‘The Costs and Benefits of Oil Spill Prevention and Enforcement’, 13 Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 167-188. Cohen, Mark A. (1987), ‘Optimal Enforcement Strategy to Prevent Oil Spills: An Application of a Principal-Agent Model with Moral Hazard’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 23-51. Cohen, Mark A. (1989a), ‘The Role of Criminal Sanctions in Antitrust Enforcement’, 7 Contemporary Policy Issues, 36-46. Cohen, Mark A. (1989b), ‘Corporate Crime and Punishment: A Study of Social Harm and Sentencing Practice in the Federal Courts, 1984-1987’, 26 American Criminal Law Review, 605-660. Cohen, Mark A. (1992), ‘Environmental Crime and Punishment: Legal/Economic Theory and Empirical Evidence on Enforcement of Federal Environmental Statutes’, 82 Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 1054-1108. Cook, Philip J. (1977), ‘Punishment and Crime: A Critique of Current Findings Concerning the Preventative Effects of Punishment’, 41 Law and Contemporary Problems, 164-209. Cook, Philip J. (1980), ‘Research in Criminal Deterrence: Laying the Groundwork for the Second Decade’, in Morris, Norval and Tonry, Michael (eds), 2 Crime and Justice: An Annual Review of Research, University of Chicago Press, 211-268. Cook, Philip J. (1983), ‘Costs of Crime’, in Kadish, Sanford H. (ed.), 1 Encyclopedia of Crime and Justice, New York, The Free Press, 373-378. Cook, Philip J. (1986), ‘The Relationship Between Victim Resistance and Injury in Noncommercial Robbery’, 15 Journal of Legal Studies, 405-416.
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
333
Cook, Philip J. (1987), ‘The Economics of Criminal Sanctions’, in Friedland, M.L. (ed.), Sanctions and Rewards in the Legal System: A Multidisciplinary Approach, Toronto, University of Toronto Press, 50-78. Cook, Philip J., Molliconi, Stephanie and Cole, Thomas B. (1995), ‘Regulating Gun Markets’, 86 Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 59-92. Cooter, Robert D. and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1989), ‘Economic Analysis of Legal Disputes and Their Resolution’, 27 Journal of Economic Literature, 1067-1097. Cox, Gary W. (1994), ‘A Note on Crime and Punishment’, 78 Public Choice, 115-124. Craswell, Richard and Calfee, John E. (1986), ‘Deterrence and Uncertain Legal Standards’, 2 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 279-303. Daniel, Kermit, and Lott, John R., Jr (1995), ‘Should Criminal Penalties Include Third-Party Avoidance Costs?’, 24 Journal of Legal Studies, 523-534. Das-Gupta, Arindam and Mookherjee, Dilip (1995), ‘Tax Amnesties in India: An Empirical Evaluation’, Institute for Economic Development, Boston University, Discussion Paper No. 53. Dau-Schmidt, Kenneth G. (1990), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Criminal Law as a Preference-Shaping Policy’, Duke Law Journal, 1-38. Davis, Michael L. (1988), ‘Time and Punishment: An Intertemporal Model of Crime’, 96 Journal of Political Economy, 383-390. Dickens, William T. (1986), ‘Crime and Punishment Again: The Economic Approach with a Psychological Twist’, 30 Journal of Public Economics, 97-107. Diver, Colin S. (1980), ‘A Theory of Regulatory Enforcement’, 28 Public Policy, 257-299. Dye, Ronald A. (1986), ‘Optimal Monitoring Policies in Agencies’, 17 RAND Journal of Economics, 339-350. Earnhart, Dietrich (1997), ‘Enforcement of Environmental Protection Laws Under Communism and Democracy’, 40 Journal of Law and Economics, 377-402. Ehrlich, Isaac (1972a), ‘The Deterrent Effect of Criminal Law Enforcement’, 1 Journal of Legal Studies, 259-276. Ehrlich, Isaac (1972b), ‘Participation in Illegitimate Activities: A Theoretical and Empirical Investigation’, 80 Journal of Political Economy, 521-565. Ehrlich, Isaac (1975), ‘The Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment: A Question of Life and Death’, 65 American Economic Review, 397-417. Ehrlich, Isaac (1981), ‘On the Usefulness of Controlling Individuals: An Economic Analysis of Rehabilitation, Incapacitation and Deterrence’, 71 American Economic Review, 307-332. Ehrlich, Isaac (1982), ‘The Optimum Enforcement of Laws and the Concept of Justice: A Positive Analysis’, 2 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-27. Ehrlich, Isaac (1996), ‘Crime, Punishment, and the Market for Offenses’, 10 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 43-67. Ehrlich, Isaac and Brower, George D. (1987), ‘On the Issue of Causality in the Economic Model of Crime and Law Enforcement: Some Theoretical Considerations and Experimental Evidence’, 77 AEA Papers and Proceedings, 99-106 Eide, Erling (1994), Economics of Crime: Deterrence and the Rational Offender, Amsterdam, Elsevier. Eide, Erling (1995), ‘RDEU Models of Crime’, University of Oslo Working Papers, WP No. C1.
334
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
Eide, Erling (1997), ‘Economics of Criminal Behavior: Survey and Bibliography’, University of Oslo Working Papers, WP No. C5. Elzinga, Kenneth G. and Breit, William (1976), The Antitrust Penalties: A Study in Law and Economics, New Haven, Yale University Press. Epple, Dennis and Visscher, Michael (1984), ‘Environmental Pollution: Modeling Occurrence, Detection, and Deterrence’, 27 Journal of Law and Economics, 29-60. Evans, William N., Neville, Doreen and Graham, John D. (1991), ‘General Deterrence of Drunk Driving: Evaluation of Recent American Policies’, 11 Risk Analysis, 279-289. Faith, Roger L. and Tollison, Robert D. (1983), ‘The Pricing of Surrogate Crime and Law Enforcement’, 12 Journal of Legal Studies, 401-411. Feinstein, Jonathan S. (1990), ‘Detection Controlled Estimation’, 33 Journal of Law and Economics, 233-276. Fenn, Paul and Veljanovski, Cento G. (1988), ‘A Positive Economic Theory of Regulatory Enforcement’, 98 Economic Journal, 1055-1070. Forst, Brian and Brosi, Kathleen B. (1977), ‘A Theoretical and Empirical Analysis of the Prosecutor’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 177-191. Fowles, Richard and Loeb, Peter D. (1989), ‘Speeding, Coordination, and the 55-MPH Limit: Comment’, 79 American Economic Review, 916-921. Franzoni, Luigi Alberto (1995), ‘Negotiated Enforcement and Criminal Deterrence’, University of Bologna, Manuscript. Franzoni, Luigi Alberto (1997a), ‘Amnesties, Settlements and Optimal Tax Enforcement’, University of Bologna, Manuscript. Franzoni, Luigi Alberto (1997b), ‘Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance’, preliminary version, forthcoming in International Encyclopedia of Law and Economics. Franzoni, Luigi Alberto (forthcoming), ‘Punishment and Grace: On the Economics of Permanent Amnesties’, Public Finance/Finances Publiques. Friedman, David D. (1981), ‘Reflections on Optimal Punishment, or: Should the Rich Pay Higher Fines?’, 3 Research in Law and Economics, 185-205. Friedman, David and Sjostrom, William (1993), ‘Hanged for a Sheep - The Economics of Marginal Deterrence’, 22 Journal of Legal Studies, 345-366. Furlong, William J. (1987), ‘A General Equilibrium Model of Crime Commission and Prevention’, 34 Journal of Public Economics, 87-103. Garoupa, Nuno (1995), ‘Optimal Law Enforcement and Imperfect Information’, University of York, Discussion Paper 95/96. Garoupa, Nuno (1997a), ‘The Theory of Optimal Law Enforcement’, 11 Journal of Economic Surveys, 267-295. Garoupa, Nuno (1997b), ‘The Economics of Organized Crime and Optimal Law Enforcement: the Urge for a Tougher Policy’, Universitat Pompeu Fabra, Barcelona, Manuscript. Garoupa, Nuno (1997c), ‘The Role of Moral Values in the Economic Analysis of Crime: A General Equilibrium Approach’, Universitat Pompeu Fabra, Barcelona, Manuscript. Garoupa, Nuno (forthcoming), ‘Prison, Parole and the Criminal Justice Act 1991', 18 Research in Law and Economics. Gibbons, Thomas (1982), ‘The Utility of Economic Analysis of Crime’, 2 International Review of Law and Economics, 173-191. Gibbs, Jack P. (1975), Crime, Punishment and Deterrence, New York, Elsevier.
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
335
Goel, Rajeev K. and Rich, Daniel P. (1989), ‘On the Economic Incentives for Taking Bribes’, 61 Public Choice, 269-275. Graetz, Michael J., Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, Louis L. (1986), ‘The Tax Compliance Game: Toward an Interactive Theory of Law Enforcement’, 2 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 1-32. Graves, Philip E., Lee, Dwight R. and Sexton, Robert L. (1989), ‘Statutes Versus Enforcement: The Case of the Optimal Speed Limit’, 79 American Economic Review, 932-936. Graves, Philip E., Lee, Dwight R. and Sexton, Robert L. (1990), ‘A Note on Drinking, Driving and Enforcement Costs’, 56 Southern Economic Journal, 793-796. Greenberg, Joseph (1984), ‘Avoiding Tax Avoidance: A (Repeated) Game Theoretic Approach’, 32 Journal of Economic Theory, 1-13. Grieson, Ronald E. and Singh, Nirvikar (1990), ‘Regulating Externalities Through Testing’, 41 Journal of Public Economics, 369-387. Grossman, Gene M. and Katz, Michael L. (1983), ‘Plea Bargaining and Social Welfare’, 73 American Economic Review, 749-757. Gyapong, Anthony O. and Gyimah Brempong, Kwabena (1988), ‘Factor Substitution, Price Elasticity of Factor Demand and Returns to Scale in Police Production: Evidence from Michigan’, 54 Southern Economic Journal, 863-878. Gyimah Brempong, Kwabena (1987), ‘Economies of Scale in Municipal Police Departments: The Case of Florida’, 69 Review of Economics and Statistics, 352-356. Gyimah Brempong, Kwabena (1989), ‘Functional Substitution Among Crimes: Some Evidence’, 15 Eastern Economic Journal, 129-140. Hannan, Timothy H. (1982), ‘Bank Robberies and Bank Security Precautions’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 83-92. Harel, Alon (1994), ‘Efficiency and Fairness in Criminal Law: The Case for a Criminal Law Principle of Comparative Fault’, 82 California Law Review, 1181-1229. Harris, Milton and Raviv, Artur (1978), ‘Some Results on Incentive Contracts with Applications to Education and Employment, Health Insurance, and Law Enforcement’, 68 American Economic Review, 20-30. Hawkins, Gordon (1969), ‘Punishment and Deterrence: The Educative, Moralizing, and Habituative Effects’, 1969 Wisconsin Law Review, 550-565. Hawkins, Keith O. (1982), Environment and Enforcement, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Hellman, Daryl A. (1980), The Economics of Crime, New York, St. Martin’s Press. Hellman, Daryl A. and Alper, Neil O. (1990), Economics of Crime: Theory and Practice, Needham Heights, Simon and Schuster, Ginn Press. Henszey, Benjamin N. and Roadarmel, Richard L. (1981), ‘A Comparative Analysis of State Individual Income Tax Enforcement Procedures’, 34 National Tax Journal, 207-216. Hui-Wen, Koo and Png, I.P.L. (1994), ‘Private Security: Deterrent or Diversion?’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 87-101. Hylton, Keith N. (1996), ‘Optimal Law Enforcement and Victim Precaution’, 27 RAND Journal of Economics, 197-206. Jacob, Herbert (1980), ‘Deterrent Effects of Formal and Informal Sanctions’, 2 Law and Policy Quarterly, 61-80. Jones, Carol Adaire (1989), ‘Standard Setting with Incomplete Enforcement Revisited’, 8 Journal of Policy Analysis and Management, 72-87.
336
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
Kahan, Dan M. (1997), ‘Social Influence, Social Meaning, and Deterrence’, 83 Virginia Law Review, 349-395. Kambhu, John (1989), ‘Regulatory Standards, Noncompliance and Enforcement’, 1 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 103-114. Kan, Steven S. (1996), ‘Corporal Punishments and Optimal Incapacitation’, 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 121-130. Kaplow, Louis (1990a), ‘A Note on the Optimal Use of Nonmonetary Sanctions,’ 42 Journal of Public Economics, 245-247. Kaplow, Louis (1990b), ‘Optimal Deterrence, Uninformed Individuals, and Acquiring Information about Whether Acts are Subject to Sanctions’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 93-128. Kaplow, Louis (1990c), ‘Optimal Taxation with Costly Enforcement and Evasion’, 43 Journal of Public Economics, 221-236. Kaplow, Louis (1992), ‘The Optimal Probability and Magnitude of Fines for Acts that Definitely are Undesirable’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-11. Kaplow, Louis (1994), ‘The Value of Accuracy in Adjudication: An Economic Analysis’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 307-401. Kaplow, Louis (1996), ‘How Tax Complexity and Enforcement Affect the Equity and Efficiency of the Income Tax’, 49 National Tax Journal, 135-149. Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (1994a), ‘Accuracy in the Determination of Liability’, 37 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-15. Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (1994b), ‘Optimal Law Enforcement with Self-Reporting of Behavior’, 102 Journal of Political Economy, 583-606. Karpoff, Jonathan M. and Lott, John R., Jr (1993), ‘The Reputational Penalty Firms Bear from Committing Criminal Fraud’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 757-802. Katyal, Neal Kumar (1997), ‘Deterrence’s Difficulty’, 95 Michigan Law Review, 2385-2476. Keeler, Theodore E. (1994), ‘Highway Safety, Economic Behavior, and Driving Environment’, 84 American Economic Review, 684-693. Keenan, Donald C. and Rubin, Paul H. (1982), ‘Criminal Violations and Civil Violations’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 365-377. Kenkel, Donald S. (1993a), ‘Do Drunk Drivers Pay Their Way? A Note on Optimal Penalties for Drunk Driving’, 12 Journal of Health Economics, 137-149. Kenkel, Donald S. (1993b), ‘Drinking, Driving, and Deterrence: The Effectiveness and Social Costs of Alternative Policies’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 877-913. Klevorick, Alvin K. (1985a), ‘Legal Theory and the Economic Analysis of Torts and Crimes’, 85 Columbia Law Review, 905-920. Klevorick, Alvin K. (1985b), ‘On the Economic Theory of Crime’, in Pennock, J. Roland and Chapman, John W. (eds), Nomos XXVII: Criminal Justice, New York, New York University Press, 289-309. Klitgaard, Robert (1988), Controlling Corruption, Berkeley, University of California Press. Knoeber, Charles R. (1978), ‘Penalties and Compensation for Auto Accidents’, 7 Journal of Legal Studies, 263-278. Kobayashi, Bruce H. (1992), ‘Deterrence with Multiple Defendants’,23 RAND Journal of Economics, 507-517.
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
337
Kobayashi, Bruce H. and Lott, John R., Jr (1992), ‘Low-Probability-High-Penalty Enforcement Strategies and the Efficient Operation of the Plea-Bargaining System’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 69-77. Kobayashi, Bruce H. and Lott, John R., Jr (1996), ‘In Defense of Criminal Defense Expenditures and Plea Bargaining’, 16 International Review of Law and Economics, 397-416. Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1982), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Choice Between Enterprise and Personal Liability for Accidents’, 70 California Law Review, 1345-1392. Kraakman, Reinier (1986), ‘Gatekeepers: The Anatomy of a Third-Party Enforcement Strategy’, 2 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 53-104. Kramer, Samuel (1990), ‘An Economic Analysis of Criminal Attempt: Marginal Deterrence and the Optimal Structure of Sanctions’, 81 Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 398-417. Landes, William M. (1971), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Courts’, 4 Journal of Law and Economics, 61-107. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1975), ‘The Private Enforcement of Law’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-46. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1987), The Economic Structure of Tort Law, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Landsberger, Michael and Meilijson, Isaac (1982), ‘Incentive Generating State Dependent Penalty System: The Case of Income Tax Evasion’, 19 Journal of Public Economics, 333-352. Lave, Charles A. (1985), ‘Speeding, Coordination, and the 55 MPH Limit’, 75 American Economic Review, 1159-1164. Lave, Charles A. (1989), ‘Speeding, Coordination, and the 55 MPH Limit: Reply’, 79 American Economic Review, 926-931. Layton, Allan P. (1983), ‘The Impact of Increased Penalties on Australian Drink/Driving Behaviour’, 19 Logistics and Transportation Review, 261-266. Layton, Allan P. (1984), ‘The Impact of Increased Penalties on Australian Drink/Driving Behavior - A Procedural Note’, 20 Logistics and Transportation Review, 187-189. Lee, Dwight R. (1983), ‘On Substituting a Socially Costless Penalty for Costly Detection’, 3 International Review of Law and Economics, 179-185. Lee, Dwight R. (1985), ‘Policing Cost, Evasion Cost, and the Optimal Speed Limit’, 52 Southern Economic Journal, 34-45. Leung, Siu Fai (1991), ‘How to Make the Fine Fit the Corporate Crime? An Analysis of Static and Dynamical Optimal Punishment Theories’, 45 Journal of Public Economics, 243-256. Leung, Siu Fai (1995), ‘Dynamic Deterrence Theory’, 62 Economica, 65-87. Levitt, Steven D. (1997a), ‘Private Information as an Explanation for the Use of Jail Sentences Instead of Fines’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 179-192. Levitt, Steven D. (1997b), ‘Using Electoral Cycles in Police Hiring to Estimate the Effect of Police on Crime’, 87 American Economic Review, 270-290. Levitt, Steven D. (forthcoming a), ‘Juvenile Crime and Punishment’, Journal of Political Economy. Levitt, Steven D. (forthcoming b), ‘Why do Increased Arrest Rates Appear to Reduce Crime: Deterrence, Incapacitation, or Measurement Error?’, Economic Inquiry.
338
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
Levy, David T. and Asch, Peter (1989), ‘Speeding, Coordination, and the 55 MPH Limit: Comment’, 79 American Economic Review, 913-915. Lewin, Jeff L. and Trumbull, William N. (1990), ‘The Social Value of Crime?’, 10 International Review of Law and Economics, 271-284. Linder, Stephen H. and McBride, Mark E. (1984), ‘Enforcement Costs and Regulatory Reform: The Agency and Firm Response’, 11 Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 327-346. Lott, John R., Jr (1987), ‘Should the Wealthy be Able to “Buy Justice”?’, 95 Journal of Political Economy, 1307-1316. Lott, John R., Jr (1990a), ‘The Effect of Conviction on the Legitimate Income of Criminals’, 34 Economics Letters, 381-385. Lott, John R., Jr (1990b), ‘A Transaction-Costs Explanation for Why the Poor Are More Likely to Commit Crime’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 243-245. Lott, John R., Jr (1991), ‘When Does Learning about a Crime Produce External Benefits?’, The Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania, Manuscript. Lott, John R., Jr (1992a), ‘An Attempt at Measuring the Total Monetary Penalty from Drug Convictions: The Importance of an Individual’s Reputation’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 159-187. Lott, John R., Jr (1992b), ‘Do we Punish High Income Criminals too Heavily?’, 30 Economic Inquiry, 583-608. Lott, John R., Jr and Roberts, Russell D. (1989), ‘Why Comply: One-Sided Enforcement of Price Controls and Victimless Crime Laws’, 18 Journal of Legal Studies, 403-414. Lott, John R., Jr and Roberts, Russell D. (1995), ‘The Expected Penalty for Committing a Crime: An Analysis of Minimum Wage Violations’, 30 Journal of Human Resources, 397-408. Lui, Francis T. (1986), ‘A Dynamic Model of Corruption Deterrence’, 31 Journal of Public Economics, 215-236. Luksetich, William and White, Michael (1982), Crime and Public Policy: An Economic Approach, Boston, Little, Brown. McChesney, Fred S. (1980), ‘On the Economics of Antitrust Enforcement’, 68 Georgetown Law Journal, 1103-1111. McPheters, Lee R. and Stronge, William B. (eds) (1976), The Economics of Crime and Law Enforcement, Springfield, IL, Thomas. Malik, Arun S. (1990), ‘Avoidance, Screening and Optimum Enforcement’, 21 RAND Journal of Economics, 341-353. Malik, Arun S. (1992), ‘Enforcement Costs and the Choice of Policy Instruments for Controlling Pollution’, 30 Economic Inquiry, 714-720. Melumad, Nahum D. and Mookherjee, Dilip (1989), ‘Delegation as Commitment: The Case of Income Tax Audits’, 20 RAND Journal of Economics, 139-163. Miceli, Thomas J. (1991), ‘Optimal Criminal Procedure: Fairness and Deterrence’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-10. Miceli, Thomas J. (1994), ‘Prison and Parole: Minimizing the Cost of Non-monetary Sanctions as Deterrents’, 16 Research in Law and Economics, 197-211. Miceli, Thomas J. (1996), ‘Plea Bargaining and Deterrence: An Institutional Approach’, 3 European Journal of Law and Economics, 249-264. Montesquieu, Charles (1748), The Spirit of the Laws, Rept. edn, Berkeley, University of California Press, 1977.
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
339
Mookherjee, Dilip (1997), ‘The Economics of Enforcement’, in Bose, Amitava, Rakshit, Mihir and Sinha, Anup (eds), Issues in Economic Theory and Policy, Essays in Honor of Tapas Majumdar, New Delhi, Oxford University Press, 202-249. Mookherjee, Dilip and Png, Ivan (1989), ‘Optimal Auditing, Insurance, and Redistribution’, 104 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 399-415. Mookherjee, Dilip, and Png, I.P.L. (1990a), ‘Eliminating Corruption: An End in Itself?’, John E. Anderson Graduate School of Management at UCLA, Business Economics Working Paper No. 90-23. Mookherjee, Dilip and Png, I.P.L. (1990b), ‘Enforcement Costs and the Optimal Progressivity of Income Taxes’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 411-431. Mookherjee, Dilip and Png, I.P.L. (1992a), ‘Monitoring vis-à-vis Investigation in Enforcement of Law’, 82 American Economic Review, 556-565. Mookherjee, Dilip, and Png, I.P.L. (1992b), ‘Rights and Regulations: How and How Much to Enforce?’, John E. Anderson Graduate School of Management at UCLA, Business Economics Working Paper No. 92-1. Mookherjee, Dilip and Png, I.P.L. (1994), ‘Marginal Deterrence in Enforcement of Law’, 102 Journal of Political Economy, 1039-1066. Mookherjee, Dilip, and Png, I.P.L. (1995), ‘Corruptible Law Enforcers: How Should they be Compensated?’, 105 Economic Journal, 145-159. Nagin, Daniel and Waldfogel, Joel (1995), ‘The Effects of Criminality and Conviction on the Labor Market Status of Young British Offenders’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 109-126. Nash, John (1991), ‘To Make the Punishment Fit the Crime: The Theory and Statistical Estimation of a Multi-Period Optimal Deterrence Model’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 101-110. Newman, Harry A. and Wright, David W. (1990), ‘Strict Liability in a Principal-Agent Model’, 10 International Review of Law and Economics, 219-231. Ordeshook, Peter C. (1990), ‘Crime and Punishment: Are One-Shot, Two-Person Games Enough?’, 84 American Political Science Review, 573-575. Parker, Jeffrey S. (1989), ‘Criminal Sentencing Policy for Organizations: The Unifying Approach of Optimal Penalties’, 26 American Criminal Law Review, 513-593. Pashigian, B. Peter (1975), ‘On the Control of Crime and Bribery’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 311-326. Png, I.P.L. (1986), ‘Optimal Subsidies and Damages in the Presence of Judicial Error’, 6 International Review of Law and Economics, 101-105. Png, Ivan P.L. and Zolt, Eric (1989), ‘Efficient Deterrence and the Tax Treatment of Monetary Sanctions’, 9 International Review of Law and Economics, 209-217. Polinsky, A. Mitchell (1980a), ‘Private versus Public Enforcement of Fines’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 105-127. Polinsky, A. Mitchell (1980b), ‘Strict Liability vs. Negligence in a Market Setting’, 70 American Economic Review, 363-370. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1988), ‘The Deterrent Effects of Settlements and Trials’, 8 International Review of Law and Economics, 109-116. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1989), ‘A Note on Optimal Public Enforcement with Settlements and Litigation Costs’, 12 Research in Law and Economics, 1-8.
340
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1991), ‘A Model of Optimal Fines for Repeat Offenders’, 46 Journal of Public Economics, 291-306. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1979), ‘The Optimal Tradeoff between the Probability and Magnitude of Fines’, 69 American Economic Review, 880-891. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1984), ‘The Optimal Use of Fines and Imprisonment’, 24 Journal of Public Economics, 89-99. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1991), ‘A Note on Optimal Fines When Wealth Varies Among Individuals’, 81 American Economic Review, 618-621. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1992), ‘Enforcement Costs and the Optimal Magnitude and Probability of Fines’, 35 Journal of Law and Economics, 133-148. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1993), ‘Should Employees Be Subject to Fines and Imprisonment Given Existence of Corporate Liability?’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 239-257. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1996), ‘Repeat Offenders and the Theory of Deterrence’, John M. Olin Center for Law, Economics, and Business, Harvard Law School, Discussion Paper No. 188; John M. Olin Program in Law and Economics, Stanford Law School, Working Paper No. 134. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1997), ‘On the Disutility and Discounting of Imprisonment and the Theory of Deterrence’, John M. Olin Center for Law, Economics and Business, Harvard Law School, Discussion Paper No. 213; John M. Olin Program in Law and Econ., Stanford Law School, Working Paper No. 146; Forthcoming in Journal of Legal Studies. Posner, Richard A. (1980a), ‘Optimal Sentences for White-Collar Criminals’, 17 American Criminal Law Review, 409-418. Posner, Richard A. (1980b), ‘Retribution and Related Concepts of Punishment’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 71-92. Posner, Richard A. (1985), ‘An Economic Theory of the Criminal Law’, 85 Columbia Law Review, 1193-1231. Pyle, David J (1983), The Economics of Crime and Law Enforcement, London, Macmillan. Pyle, D.J. (1995), ‘The Economic Approach to Crime and Punishment’, 6 Journal of Interdisciplinary Economics, 1-22. Rasmusen, Eric (1995), ‘How Optimal Penalties Change with the Amount of Harm’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 101-108. Rasmusen, Eric (1996), ‘Stigma and Self-Fulfilling Expectations of Criminality’, 39 Journal of Law and Economics, 519-543. Ray, Subhash C. (1989), ‘Legal Control of Drunken Driving: A Time Series Study of California Data’, 5 International Journal of Forecasting, 515-522. Reder, M.W. (1974), ‘Citizen Rights and the Cost of Law Enforcement’, 3 Journal of Legal Studies, 435-455. Reinganum, Jennifer F. (1988), ‘Plea Bargaining and Prosecutorial Discretion’, 78 American Economic Review, 713-728. Reinganum, Jennifer F. (1993), ‘The Law Enforcement Process and Criminal Choice’,13 International Review of Law and Economics, 115-134. Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, Louis L. (1984), ‘An Equilibrium Model of Tax Compliance with a Bayesian Auditor and Some “Honest” Taxpayers’, California Institute of Technology, Social Science Working Paper.
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
341
Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, Louis L. (1985), ‘Income Tax Compliance in a Principal-Agent Framework’, 26 Journal of Public Economics, 1-18. Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, Louis L. (1988), ‘A Note on Enforcement Uncertainty and Taxpayer Compliance’, 103 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 793-798. Reynolds, Robert J. (1980), ‘The Economics of Antitrust Enforcement: Theory and Measurement’, 68 Georgetown Law Journal, 1121-1130. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1975), ‘The Economics of Corruption’, 4 Journal of Public Economics, 187-203. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1978), Corruption: A Study in Political Economy, New York, Academic Press. Ross, H. Laurence (1975), ‘The Scandinavian Myth: The Effectiveness of Drinking-and-Driving Legislating in Sweden and Norway’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 285-310. Ross, H. Laurence (1977), ‘Deterrence Regained: The Cheshire Constabulary’s “Breathalyser Blitz”’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 241-249. Ross, H. Laurence (1984), ‘Social Control Through Deterrence: Drinking-and-Driving Laws’, 10 American Review of Sociology, 21-35. Ross, H. Laurence (1992), ‘The Law and Drunk Driving’, 26 Law and Society Review, 219-230. Ross, H. Laurence and Blumenthal, Murray (1974), ‘Sanctions for the Drinking Driver: An Experimental Study’, 3 Journal of Legal Studies, 53-61. Rottenberg, Simon (ed.) (1973), The Economics of Crime and Punishment, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research. Rubin, Paul H. and Zwirb, Robert (1987), ‘The Economics of Civil RICO’, 20 U.C. Davis Law Review, 883-912. Rubinstein, Ariel (1979), ‘An Optimal Conviction Policy for Offenses that May Have Been Committed by Accident’, in Brams, S.J., Schotter, A. and Schwödiauer, G. (eds), Applied Game Theory, Wurzburg, Physica-Verlag, 406-413. Rubinstein, Ariel (1980), ‘On an Anomaly of the Deterrent Effect of Punishment’, 6 Economics Letters, 89-94. Russell, Clifford S., Harrington, Winston and Vaughan, William J. (1986), Enforcing Pollution Control Laws, Washington, DC, Resources for the Future. Sah, Raaj K. (1991), ‘Social Osmosis and Patterns of Crime’, 99 Journal of Political Economy , 1272-1295. Schmidt, Peter and Witte, Ann D. (1984), An Economic Analysis of Crime and Justice: Theory, Methods, and Applications, New York, Academic Press. Schroyen, Fred (1997), ‘Pareto Efficient Income Taxation Under Costly Monitoring’, 65 Journal of Public Economics, 343-366. Schwartz, Warren F. (1980), ‘An Overview of the Economics of Antitrust Enforcement’, 68 Georgetown Law Journal, 1075-1102. Scotchmer, Suzanne (1987), ‘Audit Classes and Tax Enforcement Policy’, 77 American Economic Review, 229-233. Scotchmer, Suzanne and Slemrod, Joel (1987), ‘Optimal Obfuscation in Tax Enforcement’, Graduate School of Public Policy, University of California, Berkeley, Working Paper. Segerson, Kathleen and Tietenberg, Tom (1992a), ‘Defining Efficient Sanctions’, in Tietenberg, T.H. (ed.), Innovation in Environmental Policy, Aldershot, Edward Elgar, 53-73.
342
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
Segerson, Kathleen and Tietenberg, Tom (1992b), ‘The Structure of Penalties in Environmental Enforcement: An Economic Analysis’, 23 Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 179-200. Seidman, Louis Michael (1984), ‘Soldiers, Martyrs, and Criminals: Utilitarian Theory and the Problem of Crime Control’, 94 Yale Law Journal, 315-349. Shapiro, Perry and Votey, Harold L., Jr (1984), ‘Deterrence and Subjective Probabilities of Arrest: Modeling Individual Decisions to Drink and Drive in Sweden’, 18 Law and Society Review, 583-604. Shavell, Steven (1980), ‘Strict Liability versus Negligence’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-25. Shavell, Steven (1982), ‘On Liability and Insurance’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 120-132. Shavell, Steven (1985), ‘Criminal Law and the Optimal Use of Nonmonetary Sanctions as a Deterrent’, 85 Columbia Law Review, 1232-1262. Shavell, Steven (1987a), ‘The Optimal Use of Nonmonetary Sanctions as a Deterrent’, 77 American Economic Review, 584-592. Shavell, Steven (1987b), ‘A Model of Optimal Incapacitation’, 77 American Economic Review , 107-110. Shavell, Steven (1987c), Economic Analysis of Accident Law, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Shavell, Steven (1990), ‘Deterrence and the Punishment of Attempts’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 435-466. Shavell, Steven (1991a), ‘Individual Precautions to Prevent Theft: Private versus Socially Optimal Behavior’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 123-132. Shavell, Steven (1991b), ‘Specific versus General Enforcement of Law’, 99 Journal of Political Economy, 1088-1108. Shavell, Steven (1992), ‘A Note on Marginal Deterrence’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 345-355. Shavell, Steven (1993), ‘The Optimal Structure of Law Enforcement’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 255-287. Shavell, Steven (1997a), ‘The Fundamental Divergence between the Private and the Social Motive to Use the Legal System’, 26 Journal of Legal Studies, 575-612. Shavell, Steven (1997b), ‘The Optimal Level of Corporate Liability Given the Limited Ability of Corporations to Penalize Their Employees’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 203-213. Shleifer, Andrei and Vishny, Robert W. (1993), ‘Corruption’, 108 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 599-617. Sigman, Hilary (1995), ‘Midnight Dumping: An Empirical Analysis of Illegal Waste Oil Disposal’, Department of Economics, UCLA, Manuscript. Skogh, Göran (1973), ‘A Note on Gary Becker’s “Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach”’, 75 Swedish Journal of Economics, 305-311. Skogh, Göran and Stuart, Charles (1982a), ‘A Contractarian Theory of Property Rights and Crime’, 84 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 27-40. Skogh, Göran and Stuart, Charles (1982b), ‘An Economic Analysis of Crime Rates, Punishment, and the Social Consequences of Crime’, 38 Public Choice, 171-179. Slemrod, Joel and Yitzhaki, Shlomo (1987), ‘The Optimal Size of a Tax Collection Agency’, 89 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 183-192.
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
343
Sloan, Frank A., Reilly, Bridget A. and Schenzler, Christoph M. (1994), ‘Tort Liability versus Other Approaches for Deterring Careless Driving’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 53-71. Snyder, Donald (1989), ‘Speeding, Coordination, and the 55-MPH Limit: Comment’, 79 American Economic Review, 922-925. Snyder, Edward A. (1990), ‘The Effect of Higher Criminal Penalties on Antitrust Enforcement’, 33 Journal of Law and Economics, 439-462. Spier, Kathryn E. (1997), ‘A Note on the Divergence between the Private and the Social Motive to Settle under a Negligence Rule’, 26 Journal of Legal Studies, 613-621. Stigler, George J. (1970), ‘The Optimum Enforcement of Laws’, 78 Journal of Political Economy, 526-536. Swanson, Timothy M. (1991), ‘Enforcement of Environmental Regulation’, in Weigel, Wolfgang (ed.), Economic Analysis of Law - A Collection of Applications, Vienna, Österreichischer Wirtschaftsverlag, 67-78. Sykes, Alan O. (1981), ‘An Efficiency Analysis of Vicarious Liability under the Law of Agency’, 91 Yale Law Journal, 168-206. Tauchen, Helen, Witte, Ann Dryden and Griesinger, Harriet (1994), ‘Criminal Deterrence: Revisiting the Issue with a Birth Cohort’, 76 Review of Economics and Statistics, 399-412. Thurow, Lester (1970), ‘Equity vs. Efficiency in Law Enforcement’, 18 Public Policy, 451-459. Tullock, Gordon (1967), ‘The Welfare Costs of Tariffs, Monopolies and Theft’, 5 Western Economic Review, 224-232. Tullock, Gordon (1969), ‘An Economic Approach to Crime’, 50 Social Science Quarterly, 59-71. Tullock, Gordon (1974), ‘Does Punishment Deter Crime?’, 36 The Public Interest, 103-11. United States Sentencing Commission (1995), Federal Sentencing Guidelines Manual, 1995 Edition, St. Paul, MN, West Publishing. Usher, Dan (1987), ‘Theft as a Paradigm for Departures from Efficiency’, 39 Oxford Economic Papers, 235-252. van den Haag, Ernest (1982), ‘The Criminal Law as a Threat System’, 73 Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 769-785. Veljanovski, C.G. (1982), ‘The Market for Regulatory Enforcement’,Economic Journal, Supplement, 123-129. Veljanovski, Cento G. (1983), ‘Regulatory Enforcement - An Economic Case Study of the British Factory Inspectorate’, 5 Law and Policy Quarterly, 75-96. Veljanovski, Cento G. (1984), ‘The Economics of Regulatory Enforcement’, in Hawkins, Keith and Thomas, John M. (eds), Enforcing Regulation, Boston, Kluwer-Nijhoff, 171-188. Viscusi, W. Kip (1986a), ‘Market Incentives for Criminal Behavior’, in Freeman, Richard B. and Holzer, Harry J. (eds),The Black Youth Employment Crisis, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 301-346. Viscusi, W. Kip (1986b), ‘The Risks and Rewards of Criminal Activity: A Comprehensive Test of Criminal Deterrence’, 4 Journal of Labor Economics, 317-340. Votey, Harold L., Jr (1982), ‘Scandinavian Drinking-Driving Control: Myth or Intuition?’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 93-116.
344
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
Votey, Harold L., Jr and Phillips, Llad (1972), ‘Police Effectiveness and the Production Function for Law Enforcement’, 1 Journal of Legal Studies, 423-436. Waldfogel, Joel (1993), ‘Criminal Sentences as Endogenous Taxes: Are They “Just” or “Efficient”?’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 139-151. Waldfogel, Joel (1995), ‘Are Fines and Prison Terms Used Efficiently? Evidence on Federal Fraud Offenders’, 38 Journal of Law and Economics, 107-139. Weinblatt, J., Spiegel, Uriel, Hakim, Simon and Ben-Zion, Uri (1983), ‘Crime Prevention Policies and Externalities: A Theoretical Analysis’, 38 Public Finance, 110-131. Wilde, Louis L. (1992), ‘Criminal Choice, Nonmonetary Sanctions, and Marginal Deterrence: A Normative Analysis’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 333-344. Wilkinson, James T. (1987), ‘Reducing Drunken Driving: Which Policies are Most Effective?’, 54 Southern Economic Journal, 322-334. Wilson, James Q. (1983), Thinking About Crime, 2nd edn, New York, Basic Books. Wilson, James Q. and Herrnstein, Richard J. (1985), Crime and Human Nature, New York, Simon and Schuster. Witte, Ann D. and Woodbury, Diane F. (1985), ‘The Effect of Tax Laws and Tax Administration on Tax Compliance: The Case of the U.S. Individual Income Tax’, 38 National Tax Journal, 1-14. Yohe, Gary W. (1982), ‘Fines as Economic Incentives - An Alternative Variable Control’, 2 International Review of Law and Economics, 95-109. Zolt, Eric M. (1989), ‘Deterrence via Taxation: A Critical Analysis of Tax Penalty Provisions’, 37 UCLA Law Review, 343-387.
8100 ECONOMICS OF CRIMINAL BEHAVIOR Erling Eide Professor, Faculty of Law, University of Oslo © Copyright 1999 Erling Eide
Abstract Models of criminal behavior, where a person is assumed to act rationally on the basis of costs and benefits of legal and illegal opportunities, are presented in this chapter. Most of these models are similar to models of portfolio choice and of supply of labor. The empirical studies that are surveyed use various types of regression analyses and employ data from states and police regions down to campuses and individuals. Most studies corroborate the hypothesis that the probability of punishment, and to a lesser degree also the severity of punishment, has a deterrent effect on crime. The effects of various economic factors are less clear, although unemployment seems to increase crime. Methodological problems relating to the assumption of rationality, to statistical identification of equations, to measurement errors, and to operationalization of theoretical variables are discussed. JEL classification: K42 Keywords: Crime, Punishment, Sanctions, Rational Choice
1. Introduction Theories of crime are abundant. Various mental, physical, developmental, economic, social, cultural, and other causes have been launched as explanations of why people offend. Concepts like depravity, insanity, abnormality, deviance and deprivation are used to characterize those who commit crimes. During the last 30 years economists have invaded the field using their all-embracing model of individual rational behavior, where a criminal act is preferred and chosen if the total pay-off, including that of sanctions and other costs, is higher than that of legal alternatives. Offenders are primarily not regarded as deviant individuals with atypical motivations, but rather as simple, normal persons like the rest of us. The theory of deterrence thus obtained is regarded as nothing but a special case of the general theory of rational behavior under uncertainty. Assuming that individual preferences are constant, the model can be used to predict how changes in the probability and severity of sanctions and in various socioeconomic factors may affect the amount of crime. Even if most of those who violate certain laws differ systematically from those who abide by the same 345
346
Economics of Criminal Behavior
8100
laws, the former, like the latter, do respond to incentives, that is, to sanctions and economic conditions. Empirical tests with increasing statistical rigour and refinement have been carried out on the basis of this theory. Whereas the general preventive effects of sanctions for a long time have occupied a main position in penal legislation and sentencing policy, such effects were almost totally neglected in criminology and modern sociology until the late 1960s. Criminologists have been more interested in rehabilitation and treatment, and many are still reluctant to accept studies of deterrence in general and models of criminal behavior based on rational choice in particular. However, scholars who are reluctant to accept the assumption of rational choice, still find interest in the rather rigorous empirical studies in the economics of crime literature (Andenaes, 1975), and sociologists have in recent years been inspired to carry out similar research. Below, mainly studies made by economists are included.
2. The Basic Model Theories of criminal behavior based more or less on the assumption of rational choice were proposed by Beccaria and Bentham. Bentham ([1788] 1843, p. 399) wrote that ‘the profit of the crime is the force which urges man to delinquency: the pain of the punishment is the force employed to restrain him from it. If the first of these forces be the greater, the crime will be committed; if the second, the crime will not be committed.’ From the beginning of this century interest in their point of view dwindled as a plethora of other theories were developed. The main idea of Bentham was vitalized and modernized in the pathbreaking article on Crime and Punishment by Becker (1968), who suggests that ‘a useful theory of criminal behavior can dispense with special theories of anomie, psychological inadequacies, or inheritance of special traits and simply extend the economist’s usual analysis of choice’ (p. 170). He argues that criminals are like anyone else, and assumes that an individual behaves as if he is a rational utility maximizer. As the total outcome of a criminal act is uncertain, Becker employs the usual assumption that people act as if they were maximizing expected utility, and also that utility is a positive function of income. The individual’s expected utility E[U] from committing an offense is: E[U] = PU(Y ! f ) + (1 ! P)U(Y), (1) where U(@) is the individual’s von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function, P is the subjective probability of being caught and convicted, Y is the monetary plus psychic income (that is, the monetary equivalent) from an offense, and f is the monetary equivalent of the punishment. The individual will commit the offense if the expected utility is positive, and he will not if it is negative. The common assumption of stable preferences provides a solid foundation for generating
8100
Economics of Criminal Behavior
347
predictions about responses to various changes in parameters and, according to Becker, prevents the analyst from succumbing to the temptation of simply postulating the required shift in preferences in order to ‘explain’ all apparent contradictions to his predictions. Analysis of comparative statics shows that increases in either the probability or the severity of punishment might change the expected utility from being positive to being negative. For society as a whole Becker introduces a ‘supply of offense function’, where the two factors have an effect on the total amount of crime. Whereas Becker considers the income and punishment equivalents of an offense separated from other income, later authors, in accordance with Brown and Reynolds (1973), take the individual’s initial income position as a point of reference. Expected utility becomes E[U] = PU(W ! f) + (1 ! P)U(W+g), (2) where W is present income and g is gains from crime. Here, the crime will be committed if the expected utility is higher than the utility of the initial income W. Furthermore, it is sometimes assumed that the offender in case of conviction might retain some gain from the offense. Becker demonstrated that if the elasticity of the expected utility with respect to the probability of punishment exceeded the elasticity of the expected utility with respect to conviction (both in absolute values), the offenders were risk lovers. Empirical studies by Becker and others corroborated this result. As shown by Brown and Reynolds (1973) equation (2), at variance with equation (1), does not imply such a conclusion.
3. Extensions of the Basic Model Later, several types of economic models of crime have been developed, all of which draw on the theory of supply and the theory of behavior towards risk. The simplest one is very similar to models of portfolio choice, where a person’s wealth is allocated between various risky and non-risky projects. In the economics of crime version of this model the illegal alternatives are considered as risky mainly because of uncertainty about punishment. Allingham and Sandmo (1972), Kolm (1973), and Singh (1973) have constructed such models for tax evasion, where the individual is confronted with the problem of deciding what proportion of income not to report to the tax authorities. At variance with Becker’s model where the income of crime is a parameter, here the income of criminal activity is a function of the proportion of the exogenous income not reported. Both the probability and the severity of punishment are found to deter crime for a risk averse person. For risk lovers, the effect of the severity of punishment is uncertain. An increase in the severity will have similar effects for illegal
348
Economics of Criminal Behavior
8100
activities as a wage decrease in labor supply models will have for legal activities. Two effects obtain: a substitution effect and an income effect. The substitution effect of a more severe punishment will consist in less crime. The sign of the income effect will depend on individual attitude towards risk. For a risk lover the income effect is positive, and the total effect on crime of a change in severity becomes indeterminate. The effects of changes in gains from crime and in exogenous income depend on whether there is decrease or increase in the risk aversion or risk preference. For the common assumption of decreasing absolute risk aversion an individual will allocate a larger proportion of his income to tax cheating the higher his exogenous income and the higher the gains from crime. Heineke (1978) has presented a somewhat different type of model where the individual allocates his time (and not his wealth or income) between legal and illegal activities. The individual’s income is assumed to be equal to the sum of three elements: exogenous income, the monetary and monetized benefits and costs of legal activities, and the monetary and monetized benefits and costs of illegal activities. (Monetization implicitly takes place if an individual, having to choose between actions involving non-monetary gains and losses, acts rationally according to certain axioms.) If convicted, this income is reduced by a factor that represents the monetary and monetized costs of crime. Here, some of the individuals may choose to specialize in either legal or illegal activities, whereas others may choose a mix of the two. A marginal increase in the probability or the severity of sanctions will affect the optimal mix of activities, whereas such an increase may be insufficient to have an effect on individuals who have specialized in one of the two activities. Assuming leisure time not to be fixed, the same comparative statics results as for the portfolio choice model are obtained. The reason for this similarity is the monetization of psychic benefits, and the high degree of independence between the types of activities. In addition, for some attitudes towards risk, it turns out that an increase in returns to legal activity increases time allocated to both types of activities. Several authors, first and foremost Ehrlich (1973), have studied the latter type of model, but with the additional restriction that time allocated to leisure is fixed (and thus independent of returns and costs for legal and illegal activities). The assumption of a fixed leisure time obviously requires that the time allocated to legal and illegal activity changes in opposite direction (and with equal amounts), but the effects of changes in some of the parameters are also different from the previous model. Whereas the effects on crime of changes in exogenous income and gains to crime are the same as above, the effects of changes in the severity of sanctions become inconclusive without further restrictions on some parameters. The portfolio model of time allocation with non-fixed leisure time has been somewhat extended by Wolpin (1978) and by Schmidt and Witte (1984), who have introduced four possible criminal justice states, each taking place with a
8100
Economics of Criminal Behavior
349
certain probability. In these models the effects of changes in sanctions, and in gains and losses of crime become more ambiguous than in the previous models. Especially, and somewhat surprisingly, illegal activity will decrease with increasing unemployment under the standard assumption of decreasing absolute risk aversion. The explanation is that unemployment implies a lower income, and therefore a higher risk aversion, and then again a lower expected utility of crime. Under risk neutrality time allocated to illegal activity is not affected by a change in the expected employment rate. Baldry (1974) introduces the assumption that a person has to choose between zero or a given number of hours of legal work per week. Transforming the Ehrlich model into a nonlinear programming model, he obtains unambiguous predictions of the effects on crime of changes in sanctions and economic variables. If one is not willing to accept the assumption that all psychic factors associated with legal and illegal activities can be monetized, one has to use utility functions where time allocations and their attributes are introduced explicitly. Block and Heineke (1975a) have studied a model where a vector of attributes of the penalty, interpreted as the length of sentence, is included in the utility function. In this model one obtains considerably more ambiguous results than for the previous models. Unless one is willing to make strong assumptions about individual preferences, it is not possible to decide whether criminal activity will decrease or increase as a result of changes in the probability of punishment, of changes in returns to legal and to illegal activity, and of changes in exogenous income. Block and Heineke (1975a) have shown that changes in legal and illegal remuneration lead to changes in illegal activity that are composed of stochastic counterparts of the substitution and income effects of traditional supply and demand theory. But the similarity is not close. Even if one assumes that illegal activity is inferior (that is, that such activity is decreasing with income), it is not possible to sign the relevant terms. Increasing the penalty, for instance, will not unambiguously deter crime. Witte (1980, p. 59) and Schmidt and Witte (1984) have studied a simplified version of their several sanctions model where time spent in legal income-generating activity (work), time spent in illegal income-generating activity (theft, and so on), time spent in legal consumption activities, and time spent in illegal consumption activities (drug use, assaultive activities, and so on) are separate arguments in the individual’s utility function. Here too, similar inconclusive results are obtained. When benefits and costs of legal activities are risky, even more ambiguous results are obtained. The standard assumption that people maximize expected utility is appealing because it follows from the von Neumann-Morgenstern axioms of individual behavior that many scholars regard as reasonable, or at least as a fruitful hypothesis. However, many laboratory experiments have shown that people do
350
Economics of Criminal Behavior
8100
not always choose in accordance with these axioms, in particular Lattimore, Baker and Witte (1992), who included burglaries in a set of risky prospects to choose between. As a result, various alternative forms of preference functions that are non-linear in the probabilities have been proposed. Eide (1995) has substituted the assumption of rank-dependent expected utility for the ordinary expected utility in various models of criminal behavior. In the latter study it is shown that the qualitative results of comparative statics analyses are the same for both types of assumptions. Summing up the comparative static results so far, an increase in the probability of clear-up or arrest has, regardless of the sign of the attitude towards risk, a negative effect on the supply of crime. The effect of an increase in the conviction rate, given arrest, is indeterminate without further assumptions, and the same holds true for an increase in the probability of imprisonment given conviction. However, reasonable assumptions will produce the same conclusions as for the unconditional probability of arrest or conviction. These results constitute a certain support for the probability part of the deterrence hypothesis. For any attitude towards risk in Beckers’s model, an increase in the severity of punishment has a negative effect on the supply of crime. For the group of portfolio choice models as a whole the severity part of the deterrence hypothesis hinges upon the question of attitude towards risk. The effect of more severe sanctions is especially uncertain for risk lovers, whereas risk averters in most models offend less when sanctions increase. Furthermore, a positive shift in punishment in the several-sanctions model and in the labor supply model with non-monetized attributes can cause an increase in crime for any attitude towards risk. In the latter model, the restriction necessary to generate this effect is that the income effects must be greater than the substitution effects. The labor supply models with non-monetized attributes give inconclusive effects also for changes in the other parameters that are studied. For the other models the effects of changes in the gains to crime, in exogenous income, and in income from legal activities depend on the individual’s attitude towards risk. As a whole, one may conclude that the effects of changes in the environment depend on the individual’s attitude towards risk. If one is willing to stick to the rather common assumption of decreasing absolute risk aversion, and also that psychic effects can be monetized, and that there is just one type of sanctions, the effects are clear: crime is deterred by increases in the probability and in the severity of punishment, and enhanced by increases in exogenous income, and in gains from both legal and illegal activities. The reason why increases in various incomes and gains increases crime is that punishment in the case of decreasing absolute risk aversion produces a smaller reduction in expected (total) income. For risk-neutral people an increase in the probability or severity of punishment and a decrease in the gains to crime will
8100
Economics of Criminal Behavior
351
reduce the supply of crime, whereas changes in exogenous income, and in the remuneration of legal activity have no effect. Here, changes in the latter income components do not change the bite of punishment. A crucial assumption in the studies mentioned above seems to be the Bernoulli distribution of the probability of punishment. Introducing a more general distribution of risk into the Becker-type model of Block and Lind (1975a), Baldry (1980) concludes that the ‘standard’ deterrence results cannot be derived. A good survey of the main contributions to the development of the economic models of crime is found in Schmidt and Witte (1984).
4. The Benefits and Costs of Crime Various studies have elaborated on the benefits and costs of crime. The gains and losses included in the economic models of criminal behavior are usually meant to represent all kinds of benefits and costs that have an effect on the people’s decisions. People are assumed to allocate time to criminal activity until marginal benefits equal marginal costs. For some people marginal benefits are probably always lower than marginal costs, and we then have a law-abiding person. Others will specialize in crime, whereas most of us possibly commit an offense now and then. The kinds of gains obtained from a criminal act vary, depending on the type of crime and the individual criminal: some are monetary, obtained from theft, robbery, insurance fraud, and so on. Others are psychic, such as the thrill of danger, peer approval, retribution (bank robbery), sense of accomplishment, or ‘pure’ satisfaction of wants (rape). For some property crimes the prices obtained on markets of stolen goods are of importance. Among the costs one may distinguish between material costs (equipment, guns, vehicles), psychic costs (guilt, anxiety, fear, dislike of risk), expected punishment costs and opportunity costs. The punishment costs include all formal and informal sanctions, as well as pecuniary costs arising from lawsuits (lost income and lawyer’s fee). The formal sanctions include fines, various forms of incarceration, and so on. The more severe these sanctions are, the higher the cost. The informal sanctions include any personal inconveniences connected with arrest, suit and conviction. The sanctions related to the social stigma caused by arrest and formal sanctions must be added. The nuisance associated with appearing in court, and the reactions of employer, family and friends, might have a stronger effect than formal sanctions. The opportunity cost of crime consists of the net benefit (gross benefit minus cost) of the legal activity forgone while planning, performing and
352
Economics of Criminal Behavior
8100
concealing the criminal act. The lower an individual’s level of income, the lower is his opportunity cost of engaging in illegal activity. The amount a person can earn in the legal sector may depend upon age, sex, race, education, training, region, rate of unemployment, IQ, and so on. People able to earn only a rather low wage will have a low opportunity cost of crime, the cost of giving up legal income. We would therefore expect that among criminals there are more young people, men, blacks, low-paid workers, and so on than in the population at large. This is in fact what crime statistics tell us, but more refined empirical studies are necessary to substantiate such relationships. Many individual characteristics might have an effect on benefits and costs. Individual rates of discount might be important. The gains from crime often occur immediately, whereas punishment is something that might come in the future, and stretched over a long period of time. A high discount rate will therefore tend to increase crime. The probability of punishment will be different for different people. Some are more clever than others at concealing the offense and eluding the police. There are also differences in abilities of defending oneself in court, or in engaging good lawyers. The attitude towards risk will also have an effect. A high rate of recidivism is in accordance with the model of rational choice. If for an offender preferences are stable and the opportunities available remain the same, the degree of criminal activity will not tend to decrease after a conviction. Recidivism is thus not necessarily a result of erratic behavior or lack of self-control, but rather a result of rational choice. Moreover, several factors that count in favor of crime are increased by imprisonment: additional criminal skills are acquired, and opportunities of legal income are reduced. If it was rational to commit a crime in the first place, it is all the more so after having served a prison sentence. If the sentence has increased the criminal’s evaluation of how probable or severe sanctions might be, or if he or she has obtained some benefit from prison education schemes, the tendency to recidivism will be counterbalanced.
5. Are Criminals Really Rational? Exaggerating somewhat the differences between sociologists and economists, one may say that the first consider crime as deviant behavior whereas the latter consider it as rational. Figure 1 illustrates the main elements characterizing an individual’s choice situation according to the theory of rational choice. The individual has a feasible set of courses of action, some of which are illegal. The environment, including sanctions and wages, determines the outcomes of the various courses of action. The individual is assumed to choose the course of action that best satisfies its preferences. Preferences include not only wants, but
8100
Economics of Criminal Behavior
353
also norms. The guilt of acting in conflict with norms is part of the costs of crime. Figure 1 Rational Choice With Norms
In theories of economics of crime, norms are seldom studied, or even mentioned. Preferences as a whole are usually assumed to be constant, and authors do not find it necessary, or do not feel competent to discuss norms. Traditional criminological theories, on the other hand, suggest that the individual’s environment has a significant impact on people’s preferences, especially on norms, but also on wants. Theories about culture conflict, cultural deviance, anomie and learning relate individual preferences to various characteristics of the society. Other theories suggest that preferences are inherited or dependent on age, gender, race, intelligence and other personal characteristics. In the literature of economics of crime these various theories are often neglected, and the main question studied is how the environment produces incentives to commit, or not to commit, crimes. In a very broad sense a deterrent is any factor that exerts a preventive force against crime. Sanctions may have an effect on crime either by causing fear or by influencing norms. The combination of these effects is in parts of the literature on crime called ‘general prevention’ (Andenaes, 1975). In economics of crime one focuses on the effects of law enforcement on the outcomes of actions, and thereby on illegal behavior. This is the deterrence mechanism in the narrow sense. The possibility that law enforcement or other aspects of the environment might affect individual norms and wants, for example, by
354
Economics of Criminal Behavior
8100
conditioned aversion as suggested by the behavioral perspective, is given less attention. An interesting question is whether the model of rational choice is in conflict with, a substitute for, a supplement to, or a general framework for other theories of crime. Carr-Hill and Stern (1979) emphasize that the economic and criminological approaches should be seen as complementary rather than conflicting. They maintain that the economic approach isolates the importance of the probabilities and magnitude of reward and punishment, and shows how they can be treated formally. The criminological approach takes these for granted and indicates how different groups might view and react to these probabilities, rewards, and punishments. These two approaches are related to the issue of opportunity vs. motivation as explanation of crime. Economists and others who focus on costs and benefits of crime in a rational choice framework, also take into account that crime presupposes potential victims. The better the opportunities of hitting valuable and low-risk targets, the more crime there is. Those who more or less explicitly dismiss the theory of rational choice often focus on the motivation of individuals, assuming that behavior is determined by individual characteristics and by the norms of the groups to which they belong. The opportunity approach is an element in the market models of crime, where the number of offenses is determined by the interaction of potential offenders, who are seeking the best targets, and potential victims, who by measures of private protection seek to be less attractive or vulnerable to crime (compare Ehrlich, 1981, 1982, 1996, and Cook, 1986). Several authors have discussed whether people have sufficient information about the environment and about outcomes of actions to make rational choices. Becker and others maintain that even if choices are based on subjective beliefs that are wrong, the choices are meaningful from a subjective point of view, and behavior can be explained and understood on this basis. One may argue that this is not a satisfactory answer to the claim that people have cognitive limitations, and that they stick to ‘satisficing’ and not to maximization. The studies of Caroll and Weaver (1986), Tunnell (1992), and Nagin and Paternoster (1993) suggest that Simon’s theory of bounded rationality might be a better representation of offenders’ behavior than the rational choice theory, a conclusion that is supported by Niggli (1994). It has also been argued that the simple rational choice theory is inadequate because people’s behavior is determined by procedural rationality, in which an individual is portrayed as a follower of rules established by history or social relations, or by expressive rationality, in which an individual, through symbolic acts, demonstrates to himself and others his self-conception and worth. There is disagreement about how serious such criticism is for the use of the rational choice theory in studies of crime. Ehrlich (1973, p. 532) maintains that ‘[s]ince
8100
Economics of Criminal Behavior
355
those who hate need not respond to incentives any differently than those who love or are indifferent to the well-being of others, the analysis ... would apply ... to crimes against the person as well as to crime involving material gains’.
6. Empirical Studies In a great number of empirical studies the theoretical models of criminal behavior have been tested, and the effect on crime of the probability and severity of punishment, and of benefits and costs of legal and illegal activities has been estimated. The influence of norms, tastes, and abilities, corresponding to constitutional and acquired individual characteristics, have in some cases been studied indirectly by including variables like age, race, gender, and so on. A variety of equation specifications and estimation techniques have been used, and the studies have been based on data from countries and states down to municipalities, campuses, and individuals. Analogously to the terms psychometric studies, cliometric studies, and so on it seems appropriate to introduce the term ‘criminometric studies’ to characterize this field of research. The subject matter is crime, and it gives the field a somewhat distorted and too limited range to call these studies econometric, although this is what is usually done. The studies are rooted in a general theory of rational choice, and not in some rational choice theory presumably limited to economics. In the framework of norm-guided rational behavior norms may depend on the environment. In most criminometric studies norms, as well as wants, are assumed to be constant, and often also equal among individuals. Becker (1976, p. 5) expresses a rather common attitude by stating that ‘[s]ince economists generally have little to contribute, especially in recent times, to the understanding of how preferences are formed, preferences are assumed not to be very different between wealthy and poor persons, or even between persons in different societies and cultures’. With this assumption it is relatively easy to test other parts of the theory, such as hypotheses about the effect of sanctions, and of gains and losses of legal and illegal activities. If preferences differ among individuals, estimates of the effects of sanctions will be relevant for an ‘average’ person. The explicit assumption that individual preferences are constant, distinguish criminometric studies from most other studies in criminology. There are good reasons to carry out empirical studies of criminal behavior at the individual level instead of an aggregated level. In the first place it is at best controversial to posit that behavior is anything but individual. Second, the theoretical models that are developed are based on individual rational choice. Third, as will be discussed below, studies based on aggregated data require a number of additional assumptions of questionable validity. Fourth, the
356
Economics of Criminal Behavior
8100
statistical identification problem is less serious when individual behavior is studied. Using aggregated data one faces the problem of distinguishing between the effect of the probability of arrest on the amount of crime and the effect of the amount of crime on the probability of arrest. In empirical studies at the individual level it can reasonably be assumed that the probability and severity of punishment is determined without being influenced by the actions of a given individual. Thus, the deterrence variables can be considered to be exogenous to the individual’s choices, and the problem of simultaneity inherent in macro studies is absent. Unfortunately, empirical tests of these models by use of information on individuals are few. The application of the theoretical models to empirical studies is intricate (Manski, 1978), and suitable data are scarce. The data we have are mainly self-reports on criminal activity, and records of criminal activity compiled by the criminal justice system. The most serious problem with the latter type of data is that they do not constitute representative samples of the population, but are biased in the sense that only convicted persons are included. It is hardly possible to test a general theory of rational criminal behavior by studying only one subgroup of the offenders. A related problem is that most available data sources include information only about choices made, and not about those available, but not chosen. It is difficult, if not impossible, to test a theory of rational choice if the choice set in this way is limited. Whereas such data are of limited interest for studies of general deterrence, that is, of effects on people in general, they are useful for studies of special deterrence, that is, of effects on the individuals that are punished. The bulk of criminometric studies consists of cross-section regression analyses based on macro data. Some of them are rather broad, including many types of regional areas, estimation techniques and types of crime, whereas others concentrate on particular types of crime, such as property crimes or hijacking. A few of them address special questions, such as the effect of police ‘aggressiveness’ in patrolling, or the influence of income differentials. Time series studies are less numerous, and employ mostly data on total crime. The majority of these empirical studies of crime have been evaluated in various surveys. In an annotated bibliography Beyleveld (1980) reviews a number of investigations of correlations between crime and deterrence variables, in addition to 35 cross-sectional and 31 time-series econometric studies of crime. A thorough review of the empirical evidence of general deterrence is also given by Nagin (1978), who comments on 24 correlation and econometric studies, all but two also covered by Beyleveld. Taylor (1978) concentrates upon six major econometric studies, whereas Pyle (1983) reviews the same studies and about 15 others. A shorter, but somewhat more up to date review is Cameron (1988), and a more recent comprehensive survey is found in Eide (1994). Reviews of certain parts of the literature are found in Passell and Taylor (1977), Fisher and Nagin (1978), Klein, Forst and Filatov (1978), Nagin (1978), Vandaele (1978).
8100
Economics of Criminal Behavior
357
6.1 Empirical Effects of Punishment Variables In empirical studies the measures used to represent the probability of punishment include the probabilities of arrest, of clearance, of conviction, and of conviction given arrest. The severity of punishment is represented by fines, by the length of sentence, or by time served. Witte (1980) and Schmidt and Witte (1984) have employed individual data on post-release activities of a random sample of 641 men released from prison in North Carolina. The effects on crime of measures of both the probability and the severity of punishment are found to be more or less negative. Myers (1983), using a sample of 2127 individuals released from US Federal prisons, finds that severity of punishment has a statistically significant negative effect on crime, whereas the probability measure (the ratio of previous prison commitments to previous convictions) has a positive effect. Higher wages are found to reduce recidivism. Trumbull (1989) has used data on about 2000 offenders released from prisons in North Carolina to study recidivism and special deterrence. He finds that none of the deterrence variables (probabilities of arrest, conviction and imprisonment, and length of sentence) are statistically significant. Trumbull finds this result natural, since the sample consists only of individuals who, whatever the probability and severity of punishment, have chosen to engage in illegitimate activities. However, an increase in an offender’s own previous sentence length has a significant negative effect on crime, a result that corroborates the hypothesis of special deterrence. Higher earnings on the first job after release has a negative effect on crime. Quite unexpectedly, so has unemployment. Viscusi (1986b) uses an approach common in labor economics in the studies of hazardous jobs to estimate the risk/reward trade-off for illegal activities. In labor markets increasing health risks are often rewarded by some amounts of money in addition to non-risk wages. Treating the probability and severity of punishment in the same manner as the probability and severity of injury are treated in analyses of hazardous jobs, Viscusi is able to estimate the effects of changes in these variables. A survey of 2358 inner-city minority youths from Boston, Chicago and Philadelphia constitutes the data employed. Viscusi finds that the premiums obtained for criminal risks are strong and quite robust. In his framework this is interpreted as a corroboration of the general deterrence hypothesis. Studies of tax cheating based on individual data by Clotfelter (1983), Slemrod (1985), Witte and Woodbury (1985) and Klepper and Nagin (1989a) all conclude that both the probability and the severity of punishment have negative effects upon crime. Many studies of correlation between crime rates and punishment based on aggregated data appeared in the late 1960s and early 1970s. Using mostly US data on the state or municipal level these studies indicate a negative association between the certainty of arrest and the crime rate for different crime categories. But crime rates are not generally found to vary with the severity of
358
Economics of Criminal Behavior
8100
imprisonment, although in some studies a deterrent effect is obtained for homicide and a couple of other crime categories. A necessary condition for interpreting the results of these correlation studies, mostly carried out by sociologists, as estimates of deterrence is, of course, that there is a one-way causation from punishment to crime, and none in the opposite direction. The many subsequent cross-section criminometric studies allowed for a two-way causation by various specifications of the general model C = f(P, S, Zj),
(3)
P = g(C, R, Zk),
(4)
R = h(C, Zl), (5) where C = crime rate (number of crimes per population), P = probability of punishment, S = severity of punishment, R = resources per capita of the Criminal Justice System (CJS), and Zj, Zk, Zl = vectors of socioeconomic factors. The crime function (3) assumes that the crime rate is a function of the probability and the severity of punishment; equation (4) assumes that the probability of punishment is a function of the crime rate and the resources allocated to the CJS; and equation (5) assumes that the resources allocated to the CJS is a function of the crime rate. Various socioeconomic factors are included as explanatory variables in all three equations. In some studies police resources is included as an explanatory variable in the crime function. Among the first simultaneous regression analyses in this field we find Ehrlich (1972), Phillips and Votey (1972) and Orsagh (1973). The first major cross-section study appearing after Becker’s theoretical article was Ehrlich (1973). He studies seven types of crimes in the US based on data for all states from 1940, 1950 and 1960. He finds that the probability of imprisonment has a statistically significant negative effect on all types of crime, and, except for murder, not less for crimes against the person than for other crimes. The severity of punishment has a similar effect, but here only about half of the estimates are statistically significant. Crime is also found to be positively related to median family income (presumably more assets to steal) and to income differentials. Ehrlich’s study has been thoroughly scrutinized by several authors, some of whom have given harsh evaluations of his work. Revisions, replications and extensions of Ehrlich’s studies by Forst (1976), Vandaele (1978), and Nagin (1978) resulted in more moderate deterrent effects of the probability and severity of punishment. Moreover, Forst found that by introducing variables thought to be correlated with the punishment variables, such as population migration and population density, the punishment variables became statistically insignificant. Nagin found that incapacitation could explain
8100
Economics of Criminal Behavior
359
a large part of the apparent deterrent effect. In a fierce attack on Ehrlich’s study Brier and Fienberg (1980) conclude an empirical investigation of the Ehrlich type that no deterrence effect of sanctions were found. A response to the criticism from these and other authors is found in Ehrlich and Mark (1977). Despite critical remarks by various authors, there is now a long list of studies similar to the one by Ehrlich. The great majority of correlation studies and cross-section regression analyses show a clear negative association between punishment variables and the crime rate. Almost without exception the coefficients of the punishment variables (which usually are the elasticities of the crime rates with respect to the punishment variables) are negative, and in most of the cases significantly so. Furthermore, the estimated elasticities have rather high values. Eide (1994) summarizes such estimates of 20 cross-section studies based on a variety of model specifications, types of data and regression techniques (Ehrlich, 1973; Sjoquist, 1973; Swimmer, 1974; Danziger and Wheeler, 1975; Phillips and Votey, 1975, 1981; Chapman, 1976; Forst, 1976; Mathieson and Passell, 1976; Blumstein and Nagin, 1977; Thaler, 1977; Avio and Clark, 1978; Heineke, 1978; Holtman and Yap, 1978; Mathur, 1978; Vandaele, 1978; Wilson and Boland, 1978; Carr-Hill and Stern, 1979; Myers, 1980, 1982; Furlong and Mehay, 1981; Sesnowitz and Hexter, 1982; Willis, 1983; Schuller, 1986; Trumbull, 1989). Eide finds the median value of the 118 estimates of elasticities of crime rates with respect to various measures of the probability of punishment to be about !0.7. The median of the somewhat fewer severity elasticities is about !0.4. The rates of clearance by arrest are usually considered to be better measures of the certainty of sanction than the rates of conviction (Andenaes, 1975, p. 347). The median of the elasticities of arrest is found to be somewhat smaller than the median of the elasticities of conviction, but the difference is not great. Almost all criminometric time series studies give additional firm support to the hypothesis that the probability of punishment has a preventive effect on crime. The results concerning the effect of the severity of punishment is somewhat less conclusive. Wahlroos (1981), using Finnish data, finds that the severity of punishment has a statistically significant deterrent effect on larceny, but not on robbery. Cloninger and Sartorius (1979), using data from the city of Houston in the US, obtains a negative, but not statistically significant effect of the mean sentence length. Wolpin (1978), using a time-series for England and Wales in the period 1894-1967, finds that the estimates of the effects of the length of sentences differ among types of crime, and are often not statistically significant. Schuller (1986) on the other hand, using Swedish data, finds a negative effect of the average time in prison. In an international comparison of crime between Japan, England and the US, Wolpin (1980) obtains firm support for the deterrent effect of the severity of punishment. These diverging results are not surprising. The theories surveyed above tell us that if there is a significant proportion of risk lovers in the population, and/or if the income
360
Economics of Criminal Behavior
8100
effect is greater than the substitution effect, and/or the effects of legal activities are risky, and/or household protection expenditures are inversely related to the severity of punishment, an increase in the severity of punishment may well cause crime to increase on the macro level. If, however, in spite of these crime increasing effects, macro studies show that crime is reduced when punishment becomes more severe, there is all the more reason to believe in a deterrent and/or a norm formation effect of punishment. Among the several empirical studies concentrating on just one type of crime, it is worth noticing that Landes (1978) obtained firm support for the deterrence hypothesis for hijacking. In a study of draft evasion in the US, Blumstein and Nagin (1977) avoid four of the main objections against criminometric studies (see discussion of objections below): draft evaders are likely to be well informed about possible sanctions; data are relatively error free; as draft evasion can happen only once, there is no danger of confounding incapacitation effects with deterrence effects; simultaneity problems caused by over-taxing of the Criminal Justice System are unlikely because draft evasion was given priority in the relatively well staffed federal courts. The authors consider that their results provide an important statistical confirmation of the existence of a deterrent effect. They find, however, that the severity of the formal sanction has a modest effect on draft evasion compared to the stigma effect of being arrested and convicted. The economic model of crime suggests that changes in benefits and costs of committing a particular type of crime might have effects on other types of crime. If, for instance, the probability of being convicted for robbery increases, some robbers might shift to burglary. One crime is substituted for another, just as people buy more apples instead of oranges when the price of oranges goes up. Such substitution effects between crimes have been estimated by Heineke (1978), Holtman and Yap (1978) and Cameron (1987b). A certain number of statistically significant effects are found, indicating that some crimes are substitutes whereas others are alternatives. As a whole, criminometric studies clearly indicate a negative association between crime and the probability and severity of punishment. The result may be regarded as a rather firm corroboration of the deterrence explanation obtained from the theory of rational behavior: an increase in the probability or severity of punishment will decrease the expected utility of criminal acts, and thereby the level of crime. It should be remembered, however, that in some studies the effect of an increase in the severity of punishment is not statistically different from zero, and a statistically significant positive effect has also occasionally been obtained.
8100
Economics of Criminal Behavior
361
6.2 Empirical Effects of Income, Norm and Taste Variables In accordance with the theoretical models, most criminometric studies contain income variables representing some of the benefits and costs of legal and/or illegal activities. Looking first at the benefits of legal activities, the great variety of proxies applied is striking: median family income, median income, labor income to manufacturing workers, mean family income, mean income per tax unit, mean income per capita, and so on. No systematic relationship appears between the income measures applied and the estimates obtained. Although the hypothesis that an increase in legal income opportunities decreases crime is not rejected in most of the studies, others would not reject the inverse hypothesis that an increase in legal income opportunities would increase crime. This ambiguity in results might be due to the fact that the income measures used represent benefits not only of legal activities, but also of illegal ones: Higher legal incomes (mostly wages) tend to make work more attractive than crime, but to the extent that higher legal income in a region produces a greater number of more profitable targets for crime, the same empirical income measure may be positively correlated with criminal activity. In addition, high legal incomes also mean high incomes foregone when incarcerated, a cost of crime that will have a negative effect on crime. If these mechanisms are at work simultaneously, and their relative strength not universally constant, it is not surprising that the results of various studies differ. The theory is not necessarily deficient, but the methods applied do not distinguish between the two mechanisms. The main problem is that the incomes of legal and illegal activities are highly correlated, and that it is difficult (or impossible?) to find empirical measures that with enough precision can distinguish between their effects. The impact of income is further obfuscated by the fact that private security measures increase with income, while higher income probably reduces the marginal utility of each piece of property, and therefore also the measures taken to protect property. These problems of correlation are not present in studies where individual data are employed, such as Witte (1980) and Myers (1980). The estimates of the effects of gains to crime underscore the problem of finding good empirical measures for theoretical variables. Whereas Ehrlich uses median family income as a measure of gains to crime, other authors use the same measure to represent legal income opportunities. A variety of other measures of gains have been used, with diverse estimated effects on crime. A large income differential may indicate that crime is a comparatively rewarding activity for the very low income group (that may find a lot to steal from the very rich). Estimates of the effect on crime of income differentials also vary across studies. It is interesting to note, however, that a study which includes variables of both legal and illegal income opportunities in addition to one of income differential (Holtman and Yap, 1978), obtains significant estimates of the expected signs for all three variables. Also Freeman (1995)
362
Economics of Criminal Behavior
8100
finds that wages from legitimate work and measures of inequality have the expected effects on crime. Unemployment is usually included in criminometric studies as a proxy for (lack of) legal income opportunities. Unemployment will make crime more attractive if the alternative is a life in poverty. The estimates of the effect of unemployment on crime, however, are positive in some studies, and negative in others. A comprehensive survey by Chiricos (1987) demonstrates that unemployment in most studies seems to increase crime. He has reviewed 63 aggregate studies published in major journals of economics, sociology and criminology containing 288 estimates of the relationship between unemployment and crime. He finds that 31 percent of the estimates were positive and statistically significant, whereas only 2 percent were negative and statistically significant. Most of the non-significant estimates were positive. A similar conclusion is obtained in a survey by Freeman (1995). Chiricos finds little support for the hypothesis that unemployment decreases the opportunity for criminal activity because of fewer and better protected criminal targets, an hypothesis that has been launched in order to explain why in some studies a negative relationship is obtained. Another explanation of such a negative association, suggested by Carr-Hill and Stern (1973), is that unemployed fathers stay at home and keep an eye on their delinquent sons. Furthermore, differences in results might be the variability in unemployment insurance schemes. In some places unemployment insurance is only slightly below ordinary legal income, and in addition, some of the formally unemployed receive income from short term jobs. According to economic models of crime, the number of offenses will then not increase when unemployment increases. A decrease may even occur. But if unemployment hits people without such income opportunities, crime will increase. According to criminal statistics the well-to-do are less likely to commit crimes than the poor. Lott (1990c) provides a survey of various explanations of this fact. In an empirical study of ex-convicts Lott (1992a) finds that the reduction in income from conviction is extremely progressive, a result that corroborates the hypothesis that an increase in the costs of committing crimes has a negative effect on the amount of crime. 6.3 Effects of Norm and Taste Variables In most studies various sociodemographic variables have been included. Unfortunately, the reasons for including many of these variables are often not thoroughly discussed. For instance, an explanation of how differences in preferences (tastes) for legal and illegal activities may vary between groups of people are often lacking. The various choices of empirical measures probably reflect the availability of data. The estimated coefficients on the proportion of non-whites in the population are usually found to be positive. It is difficult to
8100
Economics of Criminal Behavior
363
decide whether this result reflects differences in norms, in tastes, in abilities, or in income opportunities. The high proportion of non-whites might also be the result of a tendency among the police to concentrate search for offenders to this group. The predominance of young people among those arrested and convicted suggest that age would be a very important factor in explaining crime. In many studies such an effect is not found. One reason might be that there is not enough variability in the proportion of youth between statistical units to produce precise estimates. Also possible is that crime among young people is not a consequence of their preferences (lack of socialization, and so on), but of their meager legal income opportunities that possibly is adequately represented by other variables. Young people are perhaps not different, just poorer. Population density is in most cases found to be a statistically significant explanatory variable. Population density may reflect various phenomena, such as differences in social control, psychic diseases, and so on. The studies reviewed are hardly suitable for a discussion of which of these mechanisms may be at work. Some studies use police expenditures or the number of police officers as possible deterrent variables instead of measures of probability and/or severity of punishment. Many of these studies show that police activity has a negligible, and sometimes positive, effect on crime. On the other hand, Buck et al. (1983), including both police presence and arrest rates as explanatory variables, find that the former rather than the latter has a deterrent effect. The studies concluding that police activities have a minor effect have tempted some authors to dismiss deterrence as an efficient means against crime. It must be kept in mind, however, that in the theoretical models the deterrence variables are the probability and the severity of punishment, and not the police. There are at least two interpretations of the minor effect on crime of expenditures on the police. Either these expenditures do not have a noticeable effect on the probability of punishment, or such expenditures result in a higher proportion recorded of crimes, a fact that decreases the probability of punishment registered in the data used. In some studies routine activity and situational opportunity are included as main explanations of crime (compare Cohen, Felson and Land, 1980). Chapman (1976), for instance, finds that the female participation rate in the labor market, a proxy for the proportion of unguarded homes, has a significant positive effect. It has been argued that the rational choice framework might be relevant for certain property crimes, but not for violent crimes that are considered to be ‘expressive’ and not ‘instrumental’. Undoubtedly, the degree of ‘expressiveness’ differs among crimes. Many empirical studies may be interpreted as support for the view that threat of punishment also has a preventive effect on expressive crime. At least substantial elements of
364
Economics of Criminal Behavior
8100
rationality are revealed in a study of mugging by Lejeune (1977), in a study of rape and homicide by Athens (1980), and in a study of spouse abuse by Dobash and Dobash (1984). Although the effect of punishment may differ among types of crime, evidence so far indicates that the rational choice framework is relevant for all types of crime, and that analyses rejecting a priori that some particular types of crime are deterrable are inadequate.
7. Methodological Problems and Criticism Objections to economic studies of criminal behavior have been many and occasionally fierce, see for example, Blumstein, Cohen and Nagin (1978), Orsagh (1979), Brier and Fienberg (1980), Prisching (1982), and Cameron (1988). In particular, studies based on aggregated data have been criticized. In addition to attacks on the assumption of rational behavior, the main criticism relates to interpretations of empirical results, to statistical identification of equations and unobserved heterogeneity, to measurement errors, and to operationalization of theoretical variables. 7.1 Interpretation of Empirical Results It has been argued that many studies do not take into consideration that more certain or more severe punishment may prevent crime by two different mechanisms: either directly as a cost, or indirectly through norm formation. A type of crime that is cleared up more and more seldom, or sanctioned more and more leniently, will easily be considered as not very serious by the population. Individual norms may adjust accordingly, people’s crime aversion decrease, and consequently the level of crime increases. It seems true that in most empirical studies no effort is made to distinguish between this mechanism and the more direct deterrence effect of an increase in punishment. Results are often interpreted as a deterrent effect, and not as a general prevention effect where also the indirect norm formation mechanism is included. Can criminometric studies possibly distinguish between the two mechanisms? In cross-section studies one can imagine that people living in regions where the clear-up probability is low tend to consider crime as less serious than do people in other regions. If such differences in norm formation exist, they are probably more predominant the longer the distance between the regions that are compared, for instance in international comparisons, or in studies of states in the US. It is not probable that norm formation differ among the districts within a rather small region, especially if news about punishment can be assumed to be more or less the same, and mobility of people is high. The effect on crime of variation in the severity of punishment found in studies using data from rather small areas within a region can therefore hardly be explained
8100
Economics of Criminal Behavior
365
by a norm formation mechanism. Where one obtains a negative relationship between the crime rate and the clear-up probability when data representing counties of only one state (Chapman, 1976; Avio and Clark, 1978; Trumbull, 1989), or of police districts in a metropolitan area (Mathieson and Passell, 1976; Thaler, 1977; Furlong and Mehay, 1981), one will have reason to believe that the norm formation mechanism must be of minor importance. The same holds true for some studies of substitution of crime which show that an increase in punishment of one type of property crime will have a statistically significant effect on the number of other property crimes. It is not probable that a higher probability of being punished for burglary has any effect on the norms regarding robbery. It is more reasonable to think that robbery is substituted for burglary because of a change in relative costs. Even if the importance of each mechanism is regarded as uncertain, the estimates obtained in various studies are still of interest. Not only from a political point of view, but also from a scholarly one, it may be useful to know that the probability of punishment has a certain negative effect on crime, notwithstanding the mechanism(s) involved. Another possible uncertainty concerning the evaluation of results is that there might exist an underlying phenomenon, unknown and/or not studied, a phenomenon that at the same time produces a low crime rate and a high probability of punishment. Individual norms may create such a relationship. If people in one region appreciate each others’ welfare more than on average, they will both have a relatively strong aversion against criminal infringements against others, and a high interest in clearing up crimes in order to decrease crime in general. If such differences in norms exist, they must be rooted in cultural differences of some kind. Possibly, such differences can develop if regions are situated far from each other, or if distance in time is substantial. For the smaller regions, such differences seem less realistic. Theories of criminal behavior show that a whole series of ‘causes’ may be involved, and that recorded differences in crime between regions, gender, races, drug abuse, and so on might be related to more fundamental explanations of crime, involving norms, wants, opportunities and circumstances. The intricacy of relationships shows the difficulty in interpreting the estimates of the effects on crime of such variables. 7.2 Identification and Unobserved Heterogeneity If, in an empirical study, one finds that crime rates and probabilities of punishment are negatively correlated, one cannot easily distinguish between the hypothesis that higher probabilities of punishment cause lower crime rates (equation (3)), or the hypothesis that higher crime rates cause lower probabilities of punishment (because of police overloading, equation (4)). If such a simultaeneity exists it is not acceptable to use the method of ordinary
366
Economics of Criminal Behavior
8100
least squares (OLS) to estimate each equation. Using the Hausman test Layson (1985) and Trumbull (1989) have for homicide found that simultaneity was not a problem in their data, and OLS could be applied. If simultaneity is present, the standard procedure to identify the first relation, the crime function, consists of introducing exogenous variables that have an effect on the probability of punishment, but not on the crime rate. In an excellent discussion of the (im)possibility of identifying the crime function in macro studies, Fisher and Nagin (1978, p. 379) declare that they know of no such variables. The consequence of this view is that all attempts of identification in empirical macro studies are illusory. The equations may be technically identified, but by false assumptions. Using panel data for police districts, Aasness, Eide and Skjerpen (1994) claim to have solved this problem. In studies based on individual data, the question of identification is much less serious, see above. It is interesting to note that in the cross-section studies reviewed by Eide (1994) the method of ordinary least squares tend to give smaller estimates of the elasticities of crime with respect to the probability and severity of sanctions than do the methods of 2 stages least squares, full information maximum likelihood, and other more advanced methods. This is what might be expected if a simultaneous equation bias is present. The difference in estimates is, however, not great. Cornwell and Trumbull (1994) point to the fact that aggregate cross-section econometric techniques do not control for unobserved heterogeneity. Addressing this problem by use of a panel dataset of North Carolina counties, they obtain more modest deterrent effects of the arrest and conviction rates than those obtained from cross-section estimation. 7.3 Measurement Errors Since a substantial part of all crimes is not registered by the police, one may have serious doubts about the results of empirical studies based on official statistics. However, the problem of underreporting is not damaging to empirical research if the rate at which actual crimes are reported is constant across regions (in cross-section studies) or over the years (in time-series studies). This seems to be an implicit assumption in most studies. Blumstein, Cohen and Nagin (1978) explain how differences in ‘dark numbers’ between observational units create a spurious negative association between the recorded crime rate and the probability of clearance. Aasness, Eide and Skjerpen (1994) introduce, in addition to the recorded crime rate, a latent variable for the real crime rate, and relates the latter to the former by a linear function and a stochastic term. By this procedure measurement errors are given an explicit stochastic treatment, that allows for a distribution of ‘dark numbers’ among police districts. The existence of a substantial dark number of crime, has fostered a certain interest in using victimization studies to obtain more reliable data. These
8100
Economics of Criminal Behavior
367
studies give more or less similar results as those based on recorded crimes. A prominent example is Goldberg and Nold (1980) who find that the reporting rate, and thus the probability of clearance, has a great impact on the amount of burglaries. Another comprehensive study is Myers (1982) who obtains almost the same estimates of the effects of sanction variables by correcting crime rates by victimization data. 7.4 Wrong Beliefs If people have wrong beliefs, one may also question the validity of estimates of the effects of punishment variables and various socio-economic factors. Presumably, the true risk of sanction is not known to the individual. Empirical studies suggest that people tend to overestimate the average risk, while at the same time believing that the risk they themselves run is lower than average. Offenders, however, seem to be better informed. Wilson and Herrnstein (1985, p. 392) refer to a study where over two thousand inmates of jails and prisons in California, Michigan and Texas were interviewed about their criminal careers. The study revealed a close correspondence between the actual and perceived risk of imprisonment in Michigan and Texas, whereas a somewhat weaker correspondence was found in California. The study further corroborated the theoretical result that an increase in the probability of imprisonment will decrease crime. Even if beliefs to some extent are wrong, macro studies might still be of some value. It may well be that some persons do not observe a given change, and also that they have been mistaken in their beliefs. But the gradual change from very lenient to very harsh punishment will certainly be registered by at least a part of the population, and behavior will change, more or less, as already explained. 7.5 Various Operationalizations Many studies give weak arguments for the choice of theoretical variables (for example, of variables of punishment, benefits and costs), and of their empirical measures. Orsagh (1979) argues that the great diversity of variables in empirical criminology shows that no good theory exists, and that macro studies of the usual kind have little interest. The objection is certainly relevant, but the consequence is not necessarily that such analyses should be avoided. Problems of operationalization do not make a theory irrelevant. Better than to drop such studies is to continue the theoretical discussion about determinants of crime, and produce more empirical studies, in order to improve the foundation for choosing acceptable measures of theoretical constructs. If various operationalizations produce similar results, there is reason to believe that the theory is robust to such differences. Then, one might even conclude that the theory is quite good, despite the fact that each and every formal test of significance is of limited value.
368
Economics of Criminal Behavior
8100
The studies reviewed above reveal quite consistent results as far as the sign of effects of the punishment variables is concerned. The insensitivity of these results to various operationalizations is comforting. The effects of income variables are less consistent, a result that might either imply that economic factors do not have a uniform effect on crime or that some, or all, of the operationalizations tried so far are unacceptable. Several measures of punishment variables have been employed. When only one type of sanctions is included, one would expect that the effect assigned to this variable really includes effects of punishment variables correlated with the one included. A better alternative is to use several sanctions simultaneously, as proposed and employed by Witte (1980) and others.
8. Future Research The reasons why people are more or less law-abiding are manifold. The norm-guided rational choice framework seems to provide a suitable framework for discussing various theories of crime, including characteristics of individuals and circumstances (Cornish and Clarke, 1986, p. 10). The framework allows for a simultaneous consideration of many possible determinants of crime. The abstract model is a means of gaining insight into the elements of rational behavior, and it permits filling bits of information into a broader context. In criminometric studies it might be useful to distinguish between norm variables (representing desires for various courses of action), want (or taste) variables (representing preferences for various outcomes), ability variables (representing intellectual, psychic and physical characteristics), punishment variables (representing the probability and severity of punishment), individual economic variables (representing legal and illegal income opportunities) and environmental variables (other than punishment and economic variables). A survey of variables used in various empirical studies of crime organized according to this typology is given in Eide (1994). Variations in crime among individuals are traditionally related to gender, age, race, and so on. A deeper understanding must be sought in variations in norms and wants, in abilities, and in the opportunities, rewards and costs determined by the environment. Variations in crime among individuals may be caused by differences in all these elements of the rational choice framework. Certain individuals may have more crime-prone (or less crime-averse) norms than others. The special norm structure may be a result of genetic, biological or psychological characteristics, an effect of lack of socialization, or a consequence of cultural conflict, cultural deviance, or anomie. Inherited or acquired abilities may restrict legal activities more than illegal ones. In an empirical study of college students Nagin and Paternoster (1993) found that both individual differences (poor self-control) and
8100
Economics of Criminal Behavior
369
the costs and benefits of crime were significantly related to crime. The formidable task for the future may be found in a proposition for social science research by the Nobel Prize Winner Niko Tinbergen (who should not be confused with J. Tinbergen who has won the Nobel Memorial Prize in economics) that four levels of analysis should be put together: the biological (genetical), the developmental (how an individual is socialized), the situational (how the environment influences behavior), and the adaptive (how a person responds to the benefits and costs of alternative courses of action).
Bibliography on Economics of Criminal Behaviour (8100) Aasness, Jörgen, Eide, Erling and Skjerpen, Terje (1992), ‘A Criminometric Study Using Panel Data and Latent Variables’, 74 Central Bureau of Statistics Oslo, Discussion Paper. Aasness, Jörgen, Eide, Erling and Skjerpen, Terje (1993), ‘Criminometrics, Latent Variables, and Panel Data’, in Haagen, K., Bartholomew, D.J. and Deistler, M. (eds), Statistical Modelling and Latent Variables, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 1-16. Aasness, Jürgen, Eide, Erling and Skjerpen, Terje (1994), ‘Criminometrics, Latent Variables, Panel Data, and Different Types of Crime’, 124 Statistics Norway, Discussion paper. Adams, Michael (1992a), ‘Den Teufel mit Belzebub Austreiben - Wie man den Markt für Rauschgifte Zerstört’, 12 Kriminalistik, Zeitschrift für die Gesamte Kriminalistische Wissenschaft und Praxis, 757-761. Adams, Michael (1992b), ‘Drugs Supply’, 20(8) Garda Review, 14-15. Reprinted in 1 The Police Journal, 1993, 42-47. Adams, Michael (1993), ‘Drug Enforcement in Germany and Abroad - A New Way to Destroy the Market for Drugs’, 17(1) International Journal of Comparative and Applied Criminal Justice, 203-210. Adams, Michael and Shavell, Steven (1990), ‘Zur Strafbarkeit des Versuchs’, Goltdammer’s Archiv für Strafrecht, 337-386. Adelstein, Richard P. (1978a), ‘The Negotiated Guilty Plea: A Framework for Analysis’, 53 New York University Law Review, 783-833. Adelstein, Richard P. (1978b), ‘The Plea Bargain in Theory: A Behavioral Model of the Negotiated Guilty Plea’, 44 Southern Economic Journal, 488-503. Adelstein, Richard P. (1979), ‘The Moral Costs of Crime: Prices, Information and Organization’, in Gray, Charles M. (ed), The Costs of Crime, Beverly Hills, CA, Sage Publications, 233-252. Ahamad, B. (1967), ‘An Analysis of Crimes by the Method of Principal Components’, 16 Applied Statistics, 17-35. Allingham, Michael G. and Sandmo, Agnar (1972), ‘Income Tax Evasion: A Theoretical Analysis’, 1 Journal of Public Economics, 323-338. Allison, John P. (1972), ‘Economic Factors and the Rate of Crime’, 48 Land Economics, 193-196. Andenaes, Johannes (1975), ‘General Prevention Revisited: Research and Policy Implications’, 66 Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 338-365.
370
Economics of Criminal Behavior
8100
Anderson, A.B., Harris, A.R. and Miller, J. (1983), ‘Models of Deterrence Theory’, 12 Social Science Research, 236-262. Anderson, R.W. (1976), The Economics of Crime, London, Macmillan, 71 p. Andreoni, J. (1995), ‘Criminal Deterrence in the Reduced Form: A New Perspective on Ehrlich’s Seminal Study’, 33 Economic Inquiry, 476-483. Andreano, Ralph and Siegfried, John J. (eds) (1980), The Economics of Crime, Cambridge, Schenkman, 426 p. Antunes, G. and Hunt, A. Lee (1973), ‘The Deterrent Impact of Criminal Sanctions: Some Implications for Criminal Justice Policy’, 51 Journal of Urban Law, 145-161. Antunes, George and Hunt, A. Lee (1973), ‘The Impact of Certainty and Severity of Punishment on Levels of Crime in American States: An Extended Analysis’, 64 Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 486-493. Asch, Peter and Levy, David T. (1987a), ‘The Drinking Age and Traffic Safety’, 11(2) Regulation, 48-52. Asch, Peter and Levy, David T. (1987b), ‘Does the Minimum Drinking Age Affect Traffic Fatalities?’, 6 Journal of Policy Analysis and Management, 180-192. Athens, Lonnie H. (1980), Violent Criminal Acts and Actors: A Symbolic Interactionist Study, Boston, Routledge and Kegan Paul, 104 p. Avio, Kenneth L. (1973), ‘An Economic Analysis of Criminal Corrections: The Canadian Case’, 6 Canadian Journal of Economics, 164-178. Avio, Kenneth L. (1975), ‘Recidivism in the Economic Model of Crime’, 13 Economic Inquiry, 450-456. Avio, Kenneth L. (1979), ‘Capital Punishment in Canada: A Time-Series Analysis of the Deterrent Hypothesis’, 12 Canadian Journal of Economics, 647-676. Avio, Kenneth L. and Clark, C. Scott (1976), Property Crime in Canada: An Econometric Study, Toronto, University of Toronto Press. Avio, Kenneth L. and Clark, C. Scott (1978), ‘The Supply of Property Offences in Ontaria: Evidence on the Deterrent Effect of Punishment’, 11 Canadian Journal of Economics, 1-19. Badford, R.S. (1989), ‘Going to the Island: A Legal and Economic Analysis of the Medieval Icelandic Duel’, 67 Southern California Law Review, 615-644. Bailey, William C. (1978), ‘The Deterrent Effect of Arrest and Conviction on Crime Rates in Indian States and Territories’, 17 Annales Internationales de Criminologie, 21-50. Baldry, Jonathan C. (1974), ‘Positive Economic Analysis of Criminal Behaviour’, in Ceujler, A.J. (ed), Economic Policies and Social Goals, London, Martin Robertson, p171-198. Baldry, Jonathan C. (1980), ‘Crimes Punishable by Imprisonment: A Note’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 617-619. Baldus, D. and Cole, J.W. (1975), ‘A Comparison of the Work of Torsten Sellin and Isach Ehrlich on the Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment’, 85 Yale Law Journal, 170-186. Balkin, Steven and McDonald, John F. (1981), ‘The Market for Street Crime: An Economic Analysis of Victim-Offender Interaction’, 10 Journal of Urban Economics, 390-405. Barnett, Arnold (1978), ‘Crime and Capital Punishment: Some Recent Studies’, 6 Journal of Criminal Justice, 291-303. Barnett, Harold C. (1976), ‘The Economics of Crime - A Comment’, 34 Review of Social Economy, 81-87. Barnett, Randy E. and Hagel, John III (1977), Assessing the Criminal. Restitution, Retribution, and the Legal Process, Cambridge, Ballinger Publishing, 403 p.
8100
Economics of Criminal Behavior
371
Bartel, Ann P. (1975), ‘An Analysis of Firm Demand for Protection Against Crime’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 443-478. Bartel, Ann P. (1979), ‘Women and Crime: An Economic Analysis’, 17 Economic Inquiry, 29-51. Barthold, Thomas A. and Hochman, Harold M. (1988), ‘Addiction as Extreme Seeking’, 26 Economic Inquiry, 89-106. Beccaria, C. (1971), ‘On Crime and Punishment (1764)’, in Grupp, S.E. (ed.), Theories of Punishment, Bloomington, IN, Indiana University Press, 117-137. Beccaria-Bonesara, C. (1958), An Essay on Crime and Punishment, New York, Oceania Pub. (1764). Becker, Gary S. (1962), ‘Irrational Behavior and Economic Theory’, 70 Journal of Political Economy, 1-13. Becker, Gary S. (1968), ‘Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach’, 76 Journal of Political Economy, 169-217. Becker, Gary (1976), The Economic Approach to Human Behavior, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Becker, Gary S. and Landes, William M. (eds) (1974), Essays in the Economics of Crime and Punishment, New York, Columbia University Press, 268 p. Becker, Gary S. and Stigler, George J. (1974), ‘Law Enforcement, Malfeasance, and Compensation of Enforcers’, 3 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-18. Ben-Shahar, Omri and Harel, A. (1996), ‘The Economics of the Law of Criminal Attempts: a Victim-Centered Perspective’, 145(1) University of Pennsylvania Law Review, p299-351. Benson, Bruce L. (1981), ‘A Note on Corruption of Public Officials: The Black Market for Property Rights’, 5 Journal of Libertarian Studies, 305-311. Benson, Bruce L. (1984), ‘Guns for Protection and Other Private Sector Responses to the Fear of Violent Crime’, in Kates, Don, Jr (ed), Firearms and Violence: Issues of Regulation, Cambridge, MA, Ballinger Press, 329-356. Benson, Bruce L. (1986), ‘Guns for Protection and Other Private Sector Responses to Government’s Failure to Control Increasing Violent Crime’, 8 Journal of Libertarian Studies, 75-109. Benson, Bruce L. (1995), ‘Privatization in Criminal Justice’, in Independent Policy Report, Oakland, Independent Institute. Benson, Bruce L. and Baden, John (1985), ‘The Political Economy of Government Corruption: The Logic of Underground Government’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 391-410. Benson, Bruce L. and Rasmussen, David W. (1991), ‘The Relationship Between Illicit Drug Enforcement Policy and Property Crimes’, 9 Contemporary Policy Issues, 106-115. Benson, Bruce L. and Rasmussen, David W. (1992), ‘Illinois’ War on Drugs: Some Uninbeuded Consequences’, 48 Heartland Policy Study, Chicago, Heartland Institute. Benson, Bruce L. and Rasmussen, David W. (1995a), ‘Illicit Drugs and Crime’, in Independent Policy Report, Oakland, Independent Institute, 56 p. Benson, Bruce L. and Rasmussen, David W. (1995b), ‘Crime and Punishment’, in Denslow, David A., Scoggins, J.F. and Shermyen, Anne (eds), The Economy of Florida, Gainesville, FL, Bureau of Economic and Business Research, 99-116. Benson, Bruce L., Kim, Iljoong and Rasmussen, David W. (1994), ‘Estimating Deterrence Effects: A Public Choice Perspective on the Economics of Crime Literature’,61 Southern Economic Journal, 161-168.
372
Economics of Criminal Behavior
8100
Benson, Bruce L., Kim, Iljoong, Rasmussen, David W. and Zuehlke, Thomas W. (1992), ‘Is Property Crime Caused by Drug Use or Drug Enforcement Policy?’, 24 Applied Economics, 679-692. Benson, Bruce L., Kim, Iljoong, Rasmussen, David W. and Zuehlke, Thomas W. (1993), ‘An Economic Analysis of Recidivism Among Drug Offenders’, 60 Southern Economic Journal, 169-183. Bentham, Jeremy ([1788] 1843), ‘Principles of Penal Law’, 1 Works, 399 ff. Beron, Kurt J. (1988), ‘Applying the Economic Model of Crime to Child Support Enforcement: A Theoretical and Empirical Analysis’, 70 Review of Economics and Statistics, 382-390. Beyleveld, Deryck (1980), A Bibliography on General Deterrence Research, Westmead, Saxon House. Block, Michael K. and Gerety, Vernon E. (1995), ‘Some Experimental Evidence on Differences between Student and Prisoner Reactions to Monetary Penalties and Risk’, 24 Journal of Legal Studies, 123-138. Block, Michael K. and Heineke, J.M. (1975a), ‘A Labor Theoretic Analysis of the Criminal Choice’, 65 American Economic Review, 314-325. Block, Michael K. and Heineke, J.M. (1975b), ‘Factor Allocation under Uncertainty: An Extension’, 41 Southern Economic Journal, 526-530. Block, Michael K. and Lind, Robert C. (1975a), ‘An Economic Analysis of Crimes Punishable by Imprisonment’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 479-492. Block, Michael K. and Lind, Robert C. (1975b), ‘Crime and Punishment Reconsidered’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 241-247. Blumstein, Alfred and Nagin, Daniel S. (1977), ‘The Deterrent Effect of Legal Sanctions on Draft Evasion’, 29 Stanford Law Review, 241-276. Blumstein, Alfred, Cohen, Jacqueline and Nagin, Daniel (eds) (1978),Deterrence and Incapacitation: Estimating the Effects of Criminal Sanctions on Crime Rates, Washington, DC, National Academy of Sciences. Bowers, William J. (1974), ‘A Causal Framework for the Analysis of Deterrence and Related Processes’, in Akers, Ronald L. and Sagarin, Edward (eds), Crime Prevention and Social Control, New York, Praeger Publishers, 22-38. Bowers, William J. and Pierce, Glenn L. (1975), ‘The Illusion of Deterrence in Isach Ehrlich’s Research on Capital Punishment’, 85 Yale Law Journal, 187-208. Bowers, William J. and Salem, Richard G. (1972), ‘Severity of Formal Sanctions as a Repressive Response to Deviant Behaviour’, 7 Law and Society Review, 427-441. Brier, Stephen S. and Fienberg, Stephen E. (1980), ‘Recent Econometric Modeling of Crime and Punishment: Support for the Deterrence Hypothesis’, 4 Evaluation Review, 147-191. Brotman, B.A. and Fox P. (1988), ‘The Impact of Economic Conditions on the Incidence of Arson: Comment’, 55 Journal of Risk and Insurance, 751-754. Brown, William W. and Reynolds, Morgan O. (1973), ‘Crime and “Punishment”: Risk Implications’, 6 Journal of Economic Theory, 508-514. Brumm, H.J. and Cloninger D.O. (1995), ‘Violent Crime and Punishment: An Application of the LISREL Model’, 27 Applied Economics, 719-725. Buck, Andrew J. et al. (1987a), ‘A Disaggregated Study of Police Clear-up Rates for England and Wales’, 16 Journal of Behavioral Economics, 1-18.
8100
Economics of Criminal Behavior
373
Buck, Andrew J. et al. (1987b), ‘Substitution Between Offence Categories in the Supply of Property Crimes: Some New Evidence’, 11 International Journal of Social Economics, 48-60. Buck, Andrew J. and Hakim, Simon (1981), ‘A Simultaneous Equation System of Crime and Police’, 3 Statistica, 449-457. Buck, Andrew J., Hakim, Simon and Spiegel, Uriel (1985), ‘The Natural Rate of Crime by Type of Community’‘, 43 Review of Social Economy, 245-259. Buck, Andrew J., Gross, Meir, Hakim, Simon and Weinblatt, J. (1983), ‘The Deterrence Hypothesis Revisited’, 13 Regional Science and Urban Economics, 471-486. Burnovski, M. and Safra, Z. (1994), ‘Deterrence Effects of Sequential Punishment Policies: Should Repeat Offenders be more Severely Punished?’, 14 International Journal of Industrial Organization, 341-350. Bustos Gisbert, Antonio (1995), El Debate sobre la Legalización de las Drogas Blandas: un Análisis Formalizado (Making Drugs Legal: A Formal Analysis), 155 p. Cameron, Samuel (1986), ‘An Empirical Study of Malicious False Fire Alarm Calls’, 6 International Review of Law and Economics, 33-44. Cameron, Samuel (1987a), ‘A Disaggregated Study of Police Clear Up Rates for England and Wales’, 16(4) Journal of Behavioral Economics, 1-18. Cameron, Samuel (1987b), ‘Substitution between Offence Categories in the Supply of Property Crime: Some New Evidence’, 14(11) International Journal of Social Economics, 48-60. Cameron, Samuel (1988), ‘The Economics of Crime Deterrence: A Survey of Theory and Evidence’, 41 Kyklos, 301-323. Cameron, Samuel (1989a), ‘Police Cost Function Estimates for England and Wales’, 21 Applied Economics, 1279-1289. Cameron, Samuel (1989b), ‘Victim Compensation does not Increase the Supply of Crime’, 16 Journal of Economic Studies, 52-59. Cameron, Samuel (1991), ‘Non-monotonic Supply of Crime Functions: A Replicatory Study’, 131 Cahier Economique de Bruxelles, 305-317. Carlin, Paul and Sandy, Robert (1990), ‘The Value of Time and the Effect of Fines on Child Car Safety Seat Usage’, 22 Applied Economics, 463-476. Caroll, J. and Weaver, F. (1986), ‘Shoplifters’ Perceptions of Crime Opportunities: A Process-tracing Study’, in Cornish, D.B. and Clarke, R.V. (eds), The Reasoning Criminal, New York, Berlin, Heidelberg, Tokyo, Springer-Verlag, 18-38. Carr-Hill, R.A. and Stern, N.H. (1973), ‘An Econometric Model of the Supply and Control of Recorded Offences in England and Wales’, 2 Journal of Public Economics, 289-318. Carr-Hill, R.A. and Stern, H.H. (1979), Crime, The Police and Criminal Statistics, London, Academic Press. Cassone, Alberto and Marchese, Carla (1995), ‘Tax Amnesties as Special Sales Offers: the Italian Experience’, 50 Public Finance/Finances Publiques, 51-66. Chalmers, J.A. and Shelton, R.B. (1975), ‘An Economic Analysis of Riot Participation’, 13 Economic Inquiry, 322-336. Chaloupka, Frank J., Saffer, Henry and Grossman, Michael (1993), ‘Alcohol Control Policies and Motor-Vehicle Fatalities’, 22 Journal of Legal Studies, 161-186. Chapman, Jeffrey I. (1976), ‘An Economic Model of Crime and Police: Some Empirical Results’, Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency, 48-63. Chiricos, Theodore G. (1987), ‘Rates of Crime and Unemployment: An Analysis of Aggregate Research Evidence’, 34 Social Problems, 187-212.
374
Economics of Criminal Behavior
8100
Chu, C.Y.C (1993), ‘Oscillatory vs. Stationary Enforcement of Law’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 303-315. Cloninger, Dale O. (1975), ‘The Deterrence Effect of Law Enforcement: An Evaluation of Recent Findings and Some New Evidence’, 34 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 323-335. Cloninger, Dale O. (1987), ‘Capital Punishment and Deterrence: A Revision’, 16(4) Journal of Behavioral Economics, 55-57. Cloninger, Dale O. (1991), ‘Lethal Police Response as a Crime Deterrent: 57-City Study Suggests a Decrease in Certain Crimes’, 50 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 59-69. Cloninger, Dale O. (1992), ‘Capital Punishment and Deterrence: a Portfolio Approach’, 24 Applied Economics, 635-645. Cloninger, Dale O. (1994), ‘Enforcement Risk and Deterrence: A Re-examination’, 23 Journal of Socio-Economics, 273-285. Cloninger, Dale O. and Sartorius, Lester (1979), ‘Crime Rates, Clearance Rates and Enforcement Effort: The Case of Houston, Texas’, 4 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 389-402. Clotfelter, C.T. (1983), ‘Tax Evasion and Tax Rates: An Analysis of Individual Returns’, 65 Review of Economics and Statistics, 363-373. Coate, Douglas and Grossman, Michael (1988), ‘Effects of Alcoholic Beverage Prices and Legal Drinking Ages on Youth Alcohol Use’, 31 Journal of Law and Economics, 145-171. Coelen, Stephen P. and McIntyre, Robert J. (1986), ‘An Econometric Model of Pronatalist and Abortion Policies’, 94 Journal of Political Economy, 1077-1101. Cohen, Jacqueline (1978), ‘The Incapacitative Effect of Imprisonment: A Critical Review of the Literature’, in Blumstein, Cohen and Nagin (eds), Deterrence and Incapacitation: Estimating the Effects of Criminal Sanctions on Crime Rates, Washington, DC, National Academy of Sciences, 187-243. Cohen, Lawrence E., Felson, Marcus and Land, Kenneth (1980), ‘Property Crime Rates in the United States: A Macrodynamic Analysis 1947-1977 with Ex Ante Forecasts for the Mid-1980s’, 86 American Journal of Sociology, 90-118. Cohen, Mark A. (1987), ‘Optimal Enforcement Strategy to Prevent Oil Spills: An Application of a Principal-Agent Model with Moral Hazard’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 23-51. Cohen, Mark A. (1990), ‘A Note on the Cost of Crime to Victims’, 27 Urban Studies, 139-146. Cohen, Mark A. (1992), ‘Environmental Crime and Punishment: Legal/Economic Theory and Empirical Evidence on Enforcement of Federal Environmental Statutes’, 82 Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 1054-1108. Cohen, Mark A. and Alexander, Cindy R. (1996), ‘New Evidence on the Origins of Corporate Crime’, 17 Managerial and Decision Economics, 421-435. Cohen, Mark A. and Simpson, Sally S. (1997), ‘The Origins of Corporate Criminality: Rational Individual and Organizational Actors’, in Lofquist, William S., Cohen, Mark A. and Rabe, Gary (eds), Debating Corporate Crime, Cincinnati, OH, Anderson Publishing. Cohen, Mark A., Lofquist, William S. and Rabe, Gary (eds) (1997), Debating Corporate Crime, Cincinnati, OH, Anderson Publishing.
8100
Economics of Criminal Behavior
375
Coleman, Jules L. (1985), ‘Crime, Kickers and Transaction Structures’, in Pennock, Roland J. and Chapman, John W. (eds), Nomos XXVII: Criminal Justice, Granite Impex. Confraria, João (1989), ‘Aspectos de Abordagem Economica do Comportamento Criminal (Aspects of the Economic Analysis of Criminal Behaviour)’, Scientia Juridica, 171-182. Cook, Philip J. (1977), ‘Punishment and Crime: A Critique of Current findings Concerning the Preventative Effects of Punishment’, 41(1) Law and Contemporary Problems, 164-209. Cook, Philip J. (1986), ‘The Demand and Supply of Criminal Opportunities’, in Tonry, Michael and Morris, Norval (eds), Crime and Justice: An Annual Review of Research, Chicago and London, The University of Chicago Press, 1-28. Cook, Philip J. and Zarkin, Gary A. (1985), ‘Crime and the Business Cycle’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 115-128. Cooter, Robert D. (1991), ‘Lapses, Conflict, and Akrasia in Torts and Crimes: Towards An Economic Theory of the Will’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 149-164. Corman, Hope and Joyce, Theodore (1990), ‘Urban Crime Control: Violent Crimes in New York City’, 71 Social Science Quarterly, 567-584. Corman, Hope, Joyce, Theodore and Lovitch, Norman (1987), ‘Crime, Deterrence and the Business Cycle in New York City: A VAR Approach’, 69 Review of Economics and Statistics, 695-700. Cornish, Derek B. and Clarke, Ronald V. (eds) (1986), The Reasoning Criminal: Rational Choice Perspectives on Offending, New York, Berlin, Heidelberg, Tokyo, Springer-Verlag. Cornwell, C. and Trumbull, W.N. (1994), ‘Estimating the Economic Model of Crime with Panel Data’, 76 Review of Economics and Statistics, 360-366. Cowell, Frank A. (1990), Cheating the Government: The Economics of Evasion, Cambridge, MIT Press, 267 p. Cox, G.W. (1994), ‘A Note on Crime and Punishment’, 78 Public Choice, 115-124. Craig, Steven G. (1987), ‘The Deterrent Impact of Police: An Examination of a Locally Provided Public Service’, 21 Journal of Urban Economics, 298-311. Craig, Steven G. and Heikkila, Eric J. (1989), ‘Urban Safety in Vancouver: Allocation and Production of a Congestible Public Good’, 22 Canadian Journal of Economics, 867-884. Curran, Christopher and Dwyer, Gerald P., Jr (1989), ‘The Effect of the Double Nickel Speed Limit on Death Rates’, in Faure, Michael and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds), Essays in Law and Economics: Corporations, Accident Prevention and Compensation for Losses, Antwerpen, Maklu, 117-156. Danziger, Sheldon and Wheeler, David (1975), ‘The Economics of Crime: Punishment or Income Distribution’, 33 Review of Social Economy, 113-131. Darrough, M.N. and Heineke, J.M. (1979), ‘Law Enforcement Agencies as Multi-Product Firms: An Econometric Investigation of Production Costs’, 34 Public Finance, 176-195. Dau-Schmidt, Kenneth G. (1984), ‘Sentencing Antitrust Offenders: Reconciling Economic Theory with Legal Theory’, 9 Wm. Mitchell Law Review, 75 ff. Dau-Schmidt, Kenneth G. (1990), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Criminal Law as a Preference Shaping Policy’, 40 Duke Law Journal, 1-38. Davis, Michael L. (1988), ‘Time and Punishment: An Intertemporal Model of Crime’, 96 Journal of Political Economy, 383-390.
376
Economics of Criminal Behavior
8100
De Albuquerque, Klaus (1984), ‘A Comparative Analysis of Violent Crime in the Caribbean’, 33(3) Social and Economic Studies, 93-142. Deutsch, Joseph, Hakim, Simon and Spiegel, Uriel (1990a), ‘Learning by Criming: Theoretical Analysis and Empirical Evidence’, 45 Public Finance, 59-69. Deutsch, Joseph, Hakim, Simon and Spiegel, Uriel (1990b), ‘The Effects of Criminal Experience on the Incidence of Crime’, 49 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 1-5. Deutsch, Joseph, Hakim, Simon and Weinblatt, J. (1987), ‘A Micro Model of the Criminal’s Location Choice’, 22 Journal of Urban Economics, 198-208. Deutsch, Joseph, Spiegel, Uriel and Templeman, J. (1992), ‘Crime and Income Inequality: An Economic Approach’, 201 Atlantic Economic Journal, 46-54. Dickens, William T. (1986), ‘Crime and Punishment Again: The Economic Approach with a Psychological Twist’, 30 Journal of Public Economics, 97-107. Diiulio, John J., Jr (1996), ‘Help Wanted: Economists, Crime and Public Policy’, 10 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 3-24. Dobash, R.E. and Dobash, R.P. (1984), ‘The Nature and Antecedents of Violent Events’, 24 British Journal of Criminology, 269-288. Du Bois, W.E.B. (1987), ‘The Negro Criminal’, 16(1-2) Review of Black Political Economy, 17-31. Ehrlich, Isaac (1979), ‘The Economic Approach to Crime’, Criminology Review Yearbook, vol. 1, Messinger, S.L. and Brittner E. (eds), Beverley Hills, Sage Publications, 25-60. Ehrlich, Isaac (1972), ‘The Deterrent Effect of Criminal Law Enforcement’, 1 Journal of Legal Studies, 259-276. Ehrlich, Isaac (1973), ‘Participation in Illegitimate Activities: A Theoretical and Empirical Investigation’, 81 Journal of Political Economy, 521-565. Ehrlich, Isaac (1975a), ‘The Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment: A Question of Life and Death’, 65 American Economic Review, 397-417. Ehrlich, Isaac (1975b), ‘Deterrence: Evidence and Inference’, 85 Yale Law Journal, 209-227. Ehrlich, Isaac (1976), ‘Rejoinder’, 85 Yale Law Journal, 368-369. Ehrlich, Isaac (1977a), ‘Capital Punishment and Deterrence: Some Further Thoughts and Additional Evidence’, 85 Journal of Political Economy, 741-788. Ehrlich, Isaac (1977b), ‘The Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment: Reply’, 67 American Economic Review, 452-458. Ehrlich, Isaac (1981), ‘On the Usefulness of Controlling Individuals: An Economic Analysis of Rehabilitation, Incapacitation, and Deterrence’, 71 American Economic Review, 307-322. Ehrlich, Isaac (1982), ‘The Market for Offences and the Public Enforcement of Laws: An Equilibrium Analysis’, 21 British Journal of Psychology. Ehrlich, Isaac (1996), ‘Crime, Punishment and the Market for Offenses’, 10 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 43-67. Ehrlich, Isaac and Brower, George D. (1987), ‘On the Issue of Causality in the Economic Model of Crime and the Law Enforcement: Some Theoretical Considerations and Experimental Evidence’, 77 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 99-110. Ehrlich, Isaac and Gibbons, Joel C. (1977), ‘On the Measurement of the Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment and the Theory of Deterrence’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 35-50.
8100
Economics of Criminal Behavior
377
Ehrlich, Isaac and Randall, Mark (1978), ‘Deterrence and Economics: A Perspective on Theory and Evidence’, in Yinger, J.M. and Cutler, S.J. (eds), Major Social Issues, New York, 172-188. Ehrlich, Isaac in co-operation with Mark, R. et al. (1977), ‘Fear of Deterrence: A Critical Evaluation of the “Report of the Panel on Research on Deterrent and Incapacitative Effects”’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 293-316. Eide, Erling (1981), ‘Kritikk av Noen Forutsetninger i Kriminalmeldingen (Critique of Some Assumptions in the Report on Crime)’, Lov og Rett, 312-323. Eide, Erling (1994), Kriminal¢konomi (Economics of Crime), Stavanger, Rogaland Mediesenter, 158 p. Eide, Erling (1995), ‘RDEU Models of Crime’, Institutt for Privatrett, University of Oslo, Working Paper Law and Economics, C1. Eide, Erling, in cooperation with Jørgen Aasness and Terje Skjerpen (1994), Economics of Crime: Deterrence and the Rational Offender, Contributions to Economic Analysis, Amsterdam, Oxford and Tokyo, North-Holland, 334 p. Ellickson, R.C. (1996), ‘Controlling Chronic Misconduct in City Spaces: Of Panhandlers, Skid Rows, and Public-Space Zoning’, 105 Yale Law Journal, 1165-1248. Entorf, von Horst (1996), ‘Kriminalität und Ökonomie: Übersicht und neue Evidenz (Crime and Economy: Survey and New Evidence)’,116 Zeitschrift für Wirtschafts- und Sozialwissenschaften, 417-450. Fadaei Tehrani, Reza (1989), ‘The Costs of Crime: Unemployment and Poverty’, 16(12) International Journal of Social Economics, 34-243. Fattah, E.A. (1983), ‘Critique of Deterrence Research with Particular Reference to the Economic Approach’, 25 Canadian Journal of Criminology, 79-90. Feichtinger, G., Forst, Ch.V. and Piccardi, C. (1993), ‘A Nonlinear Dynamic Model for the Dynastic Cycle’, 165 Forschungsbericht/Research Memorandum. Fisher, Franklin M. and Nagin, D. (1978), ‘On the Feasibility of Identifying the Crime Function in a Simultaneous Model of Crime Rates and Sanction Levels’, in Blumstein, Cohen and Nagin (eds), Deterrence and Incapacitation: Estimating the Effects of Criminal Sanctions on Crime Rates, Washington, DC, National Academy of Sciences, 361-399. Fisher, Sethard (1987), ‘Economic Development and Crime: Two May Be Associated as an Adaptation to Industrialism in Social Revolution’, 46 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 17-34. Fleisher, B. (1966), The Economics of Delinquency, New York, Quadrangle. Forst, Brian (1976), ‘Participation in Illegitimate Activities: Further Empirical Findings’, 2 Policy Analysis, 477-492. Forst, Brian (1977), ‘The Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment: A Cross-State Analysis of the 1960's’, 5 Minnesota Law Review, 743-767. Fox, J.A. (ed.) (1981), Methods in Quantitative Criminology, New York, London, Academic Press. Freeman, Richard B. (1987), ‘The Relation of Criminal Activity to Black Youth Employment’,16(1-2) Review of Black Political Economy, 99-107. Freeman, Richard B. (1995), ‘The Labor Market’, in Wilson, James Q. and Petersilia, Joan (eds), Crime, San Fransisco, Institute for Contemporary Studies, 171-191. Freeman, Richard B. (1996), ‘Why do so many Young American Men Commit Crimes and What Might we do About it?’, 10 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 25-42.
378
Economics of Criminal Behavior
8100
Frey, Bruno S. (1988), ‘Fighting Political Terrorism by Refusing Recognition’, 7 Journal of Public Policy, 179-188. Frey, Bruno S. and Buhofer, Heinz (1988), ‘Prisoners and Property Rights’, 31 Journal of Law and Economics, 19-46. Friedman, D.D. (1991), ‘Impossibility, Subjective Probability, and Punishment for Attempts’, 20 Journal of Legal Studies, 1790-1860. Friedman, D. and Sjostrom, W. (1993), ‘Hanged for a Sheep - The Economics of Marginal Deterrence’, 22 Journal of Legal Studies, 165-192. Friedman, Joseph, Hakim, Simon and Spiegel, Uriel (1989), ‘The Difference between Short and Long Run Effects of Police Outlays on Crime: Policing Deters Criminals Initially, but Later They May Learn by Doing’, 48 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 177-191. Friedman, Lee S. (1979a), ‘The Use of Multiple Regression Analysis to Test for a Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment: Prospects and Problems’, in Messinger, Sheldon L. and Bittner, Egon (eds), Criminology Review Yearbook 1, Beverly Hills, Sage Publications. Friedman, Lee S. (1979b), ‘The Use of Multiple Regression Analysis to Test for a Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment: Prospects and Problems’, in Messinger, Sheldon L. and Bittner, Egon (eds), Criminology Review Yearbook, Beverly Hills, Sage Publications, 61-87. Furlong, William J. (1987), ‘A General Equilibrium Model of Crime Commission and Prevention’, 34 Journal of Public Economics, 87-103. Furlong, William J. and Mehay, Stephen L. (1981), ‘Urban Law Enforcement in Canada: an Empirical Analysis’, 14 Canadian Journal of Economics, 44-57. Gallo, Joseph C., Dau-Schmidt, Kenneth G. and Craycraft, Joseph (1997), ‘The First Century of Department of Justice Antitrust Enforcement’, 12 Review of Industrial Organization. Garoupa, Nuno (1996), ‘Prison, Parole and the Criminal Justice Act 1991', 18 Research in Law and Economics. Garoupa, Nuno (1997), ‘A Note on Private Enforcement and Type I Error’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 423-429. Garoupa, Nuno and Bowles, R. (1997), ‘Casual Police Corruption and the Economics of Crime’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 75-87. Geyikdagi, Yasar M. and Geyikdagi, Necla V. (1986), ‘The Economics of Street Crime’, 33 Rivista Internazionale di Scienze Economiche e Commerciali, 813-818. Ghali, Moheb A. et al. (1983), ‘Economic Factors and the Composition of Juvenile Property Crimes’, 15 Applied Economics, 267-281. Gibbons, T. (1982), ‘The Utility of Economic Analysis of Crime’, 2 International Review of Law and Economics, 173-191. Gibbs, J. (1975), Crime, Punishment and Deterrence, New York, Elsevier. Ginsburg, Douglas H. and Shechtman, P. (1993), ‘Blackmail: An Economic Analysis of the Law’, 141 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1849 ff. Glaeser, E.L., Sacerdote, B. and Scheinkman, J.A. (1996), ‘Crime and Social Interactions’, 11 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 274-279. Goff, B.L. and Tollison R.D. (1993), ‘Using (Im)perfect Markets to Catch Criminals’, 21 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 31-41. Goldberg, Itzhak and Nold, Frederik C. (1980), ‘Does Reporting Deter Burglars? An Empirical Analysis of Risk and Return in Crime’, Review of Economics and Statistics, 424-431.
8100
Economics of Criminal Behavior
379
Good, David H. and Pirog Good, Maureen A. (1987a), ‘A Simultaneous Probit Model of Crime and Employment for Black and White Teenage Males’, 16(1-2) Review of Black Political Economy, 109-127. Good, David H. and Pirog Good, Maureen A. (1987b), ‘Employment, Crime, and Race’, 5(4) Contemporary Policy Issues, 91-104. Good, David H., Pirog Good, Maureen A. and Sickles, Robin C. (1986), ‘An Analysis of Youth Crime and Employment Patterns’, 2 Journal of Quantitative Criminology, 219-236. Graves, Philip E., Lee, Dwight R. and Sexton, Robert L. (1989), ‘Statutes versus Enforcement: The Case of the Optimal Speed Limit’, 79 American Economic Review, 932-936. Greenberg, David F. and Kessler, Ronald C. (1981), ‘Panel Models in Criminology’, in Fox, J.A. (ed), Methods in Quantitive Criminology, New York, London, Academic Press. Greenberg, David F., Kessler, Ronald C. and Logan, Charles H. (1979), ‘A Panel Model of Crime Rates and Arrest Rates’, American Sociological Review, 843-850. Greenberg, Stephanie W. and Rohe, William M. (1986), ‘Informal Social Control and Crime Prevention in Modern Urban Neighborhoods’, in Taylor, Ralph B. (ed), Urban Neighborhoods: Research and Policy, New York, Praeger Publishers, 79-118. Greenwood, Michael J. and Wadycki, Walter J. (1973), ‘Crime Rates and Public Expenditures for Police Protection: Their Interaction’, 31 Review of Social Economics, 138-151. Greenwood, Michael J. and Wadycki, Walter J. (1975), ‘Crime Rates and Public Expenditures for Police Protection: A Reply’, 33 Review of Social Economics, 81-84. Grogger, Jeffrey (1990), ‘The Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment: An Analysis of Daily Homicide Counts’, 85 Journal of the American Statistical Association, 295-303. Grogger, Jeffrey (1991), ‘Certainty vs. Severity of Punishment’, 29 Economic Inquiry, 297-309. Gyimah Brempong, Kwabena (1986), ‘Empirical Models of Criminal Behavior: How Significant a Factor is Race?’, 15 Review of Black Political Economy, 27-43. Hann, Robert G. (1976), Deterrence and the Death Penalty: A Critical Review of the Research of Isaac Ehrlich, Ottawa, Ontario, Research Division of the Solicitor-General of Canada. Hashimoto, Masanori (1987), ‘The Minimum Wage Law and Youth Crimes: Time-Series Evidence’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 443-464. Hawkins, Gordon (1971), ‘Punishment and Deterrence: The Educative, Moralising and Habituative Effects’, in Stanley E. Grupp (ed), Theories of Punishment, Bloomington, IN, Indiana University Press, 163-180. Heineke, J.M. (1975), ‘A Note on Modelling the Criminal Choice Problem’, 10 Journal of Economic Theory, 113-116. Heineke, J.M. (ed) (1978),Economic Models of Criminal Behaviour, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 391 p. Hellman, D.A. (1980), The Economics of Crime, New York, St. Martin’s Press. Hellman, Daryl A. and Alper, Neil O. (1990), Economics of Crime: Theory and Practice, Needham Heights, Simon and Schuster, Ginn Press, 226 p. Hersch, Philip L. and Netter, Jeffrey M. (1984), ‘The Effects of Crime Rates on Time Served in Prison: An Empirical Analysis’, 39 Public Finance, 314-320. Hershbarger, R.A. and Miller, R.K. (1988), ‘The Impact of Economic Conditions on the Incidence of Arson: A Reply’, 55 Journal of Risk and Insurance, 755-757.
380
Economics of Criminal Behavior
8100
Hill, John K. and Pearce, James E. (1990), ‘The Incidence of Sanctions against Employers of Illegal Aliens’, 98 Journal of Political Economy, 28-44. Hirsch, Werner Z. and Rufolo, Anthony M. (1985), ‘Economic Effects of Residence Laws on Municipal Police’, 17 Journal of Urban Economics, 335-348. Hoenack, Stephen A. and Weiler, William (1980), ‘A Structural Model of Murder Behavior’, 70 American Economic Review, 327-341. Hoenack, Stephen A., Kurdle, Robert and Sjøquist, David (1978), ‘The Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment: A Question of Identification’, 4 Policy Analysis, 491-527. Holtmann, A.G. and Yap, L. (1978), ‘Does Punishment Pay?’, 33 Public Finance, 90-97. Howsen, Roy M. and Jarrell, Stephen B. (1987), ‘Some Determinants of Property Crime: Economic Factors Influence Criminal Behavior but Cannot Completely Explain the Syndrome’, 46 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 445-457. Hull, B.B. and Bold, F. (1995), ‘Preaching Matters: Replication and Extension’, 27 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 143-149. Jarrell, Stephen B. and Howsen, Roy M. (1990), ‘Transient Crowding and Crime: The More ‘Strangers’ in an Area, the More Crime Except for Murder, Assault and Rape’, 49 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 483-494. Kaplan, L.J. and Kessler, P. (eds) (1976), An Economic Analysis of Crime: Selected Readings, Springfield, Charles Thomas. Karpoff, Jonathan M. and Lott, John R., Jr (1993), ‘The Reputational Penalty Firms Bear from Committing Criminal Fraud’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 757-802. Kenkel, Donald S. (1993), ‘Drinking, Driving, and Deterrence: The Effectiveness and Social Costs of Alternative Policies’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 877-913. Klein, Lawrene R., Forst, Brian and Filatov, Victor (1978), ‘The Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment : An Assessment of the Estimates’, in Blumstein, Cohen and Nagin (eds), Deterrence and Incapacitation : Estimating the Effects of Criminal Sanctions on Crime Rates, Washington, DC, National Academy of Sciences, 336-360. Klepper, Stephen and Nagin, Daniel S. (1989a), ‘The Criminal Deterrence Literature: Implications for Research on Taxpayer Compliance’, in J.T. Scholz et al. (eds), Paying Taxes: An Agenda for Compliance Research, Philadelphia, University of Philadelphia. Klepper, Steven and Nagin, Daniel S. (1989b), ‘The Anatomy of Tax Evasion’, 5 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 1-24. Klevorick, Alvin K. (1985), ‘On the Economic Theory of Crime’, in Pennock, J. Roland and Chapman, John W. (eds), Nomos XXVII: Criminal Justice, Granite Impex Ltd, 289-312. Kobayashi, Bruce H. (1992), ‘Deterrence with Multiple Defendants: an Explanation for “Unfair” Plea Bargaining’, 23 Rand Journal of Economics, 507-515. Kobayashi, Bruce H. and Lott, John R., Jr (1992), ‘Low Probability-High Penalty Enforcement Strategies and the Efficient Operation of the Plea-Bargaining System’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 69-77. Kobayashi, Bruce H. and Lott, John R., Jr (1996), ‘In Defense of Criminal Defense Expenditures and Plea Bargaining’, 16 International Review of Law and Economics. Kolm, S.-C. (1973), ‘A Note on Optimal Tax Evasion’, 2 Journal of Public Economics, 265-270. Komesar, Neil K. (1973), ‘A Theoretical and Empirical Study of Victims of Crime’, 2 Journal of Legal Studies, 301-321. Koskela, Erkki and Viren, Matti (1993), ‘An Economic Model of Auto Thefts in Finland’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 179-191.
8100
Economics of Criminal Behavior
381
Landes, William M. (1978), ‘An Economic Study of U.S. Aircraft Hijacking, 1961-1976', 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-31. Lattimore, P.K. (1992), ‘The Influence of Probability on Risky Choice: A Parametric Examination’, 17 Journal of Economics, Behavior and Organization, 377-400. Lattimore P.K., Baker, J.R. and Witte, A.D. (1992), ‘The Influence of Probability on Risky Choice: A Parametric Examination’, 17 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 377-400. Layson, Stephen K. (1983), ‘Homicide and Deterrence: Another View of the Canadian Time Series Evidence’, 16 Canadian Journal of Economics, 52-73. Layson, Stephen K. (1985), ‘Homicide and Deterrence: A Reexamination of the United States Time Series Evidence’, 52 Southern Economic Journal, 68-89. Layton, Allan P. (1983), ‘The Impact of Increased Penalties on Australian Drink/Driving Behaviour’, 19 Logistics and Transportation Review, 261-266. Lazos, Vaios (1996), ‘E Kambyle Adiaforias enos Eglematos (The Indifference Curve of a Crime)’, 6 Aissymnetes. Lejeune, R. (1977), ‘Management of a Mugging’, 6 Urban Life, 123-148. Leung, S.F. (1995), ‘Dynamic Deterrence Theory’, 6 Economica, 65-87. Lewin, Jeff L. and Trumbull, William N. (1993), ‘Neither Boxed in nor Circular: A Reply’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 233-235. Lewisch, Peter (1992), ‘A Case Study on the Legal Regulation of Shoplifting in Austria and the “Criminal Tourism” from the East’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 439-455. Liu, Yih Wu and Bee, Richard H. (1983), ‘Modeling Criminal Activity in an Area in Economic Decline: Local Economic Conditions are a Major Factor in Local Property Crimes’, 42 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 385-392. Loftin, Colin and McDowall, David (1982), ‘The Police, Crime and Economic Theory: An Assessment’, American Sociological Review, 393-401. Logan. Charles H. (1975), ‘Arrest Rates and Deterrence’, 56 Social Science Quarterly, 76-89. Logan, Charles H. (1982), ‘Problems in Ratio Correlation: The Case of Deterrence Research’, 60 Social Force, 791-810. Lott, John R., Jr (1987), ‘Juvenile Delinquency and Education: A Comparison of Public and Private Provision’, 7 International Review of Law and Economics, 163-175. Lott, John R., Jr (1990a), ‘Getting Tough on White-Collar Criminals’, 13(1) Regulation, 18-19. Lott, John R., Jr (1990b), ‘The Effect of Conviction on the Legitimate Income of Criminals’, 34 Economic Letters, 381-385. Lott, John R., Jr (1990c), ‘A Transaction-Costs Explanation for Why the Poor are More Likely to Commit Crime’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 243-245. Lott, John R., Jr (1992a), ‘Do we Punish High Income Criminals too Heavily?’, 30 Economic Inquiry, 583-608. Lott, John R., Jr (199b2), ‘An Attempt at Measuring the Total Monetary Penalty from Drug Convictions: The Importance of an Individual’s Reputation’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 159-187. Lott, J.R., Jr and Roberts, R.D. (1995), ‘The Expected Penalty for Committing a Crime: An Analysis of Minimum Wage Violations’, 30 Journal of Human Resources, 397-408.
382
Economics of Criminal Behavior
8100
Lupia, Arthur and McCubbins, Mathew D. (1994), ‘Learning from Oversight: Fire Alarms and Police Patrols Reconstructed’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 96-125. Manski, Charles, F. (1978), ‘Prospects for Inference on Deterrence through Empirical Analysis of Individual Criminal Behaviour’, in Blumstein, Cohen and Nagin (eds), Deterrence and Incapacitation: Estimating the Effects of Criminal Sanctions on Crime Rates, Washington, DC, National Academy of Sciences, 400-424. Marceau, Nicolas (1997), ‘Self-Selection and Violence in the Market for Crime’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 193-201. Mathieson, Donald and Passell, Peter (1976), ‘Homicide and Robbery in New York City: An Economic Model’, 5 Journal of Legal Studies, 83-98. Mathur, Vijay K. (1978), ‘Economics of Crime: An Investigation of the Deterrent Hypothesis for Urban Areas’, 60 Review of Economics and Statistics, 459-466. McChesney, Fred S. (1993), ‘Boxed in: Economists and Benefits from Crime’,13 International Review of Law and Economics, 225-231. McCormick, Robert E. and Tollison, Robert D. (1986), ‘Crime and Income Distribution in a Basketball Economy’, 6 International Review of Law and Economics, 115-124. McPheters, Lee R. (1978), ‘Econometric Analysis of Factors Influencing Crime on the Campus’, 6 Journal of Criminal Justice, 47-52. McPheters, Lee R. and Strange, W.B. (eds) (1976), The Economics of Crime and Law Enforcement, Springfield, Charles R. Thomas. McPheters, Lee R., Mann, Robert and Schlagenhauf, Don E. (1984), ‘Economic Response to a Crime Deterrence Program: Mandatory Sentencing for Robbery with a Firearm’, 22 Economic Inquiry, 550-570. Meera, A.K. and Jayakumar M.D. (1995), ‘Determinants of Crime in a Developing Country: A Regression Model’, 27 Applied Economics, 455-460. Meier, R.F. (ed) (1985), Theoretical Methods in Criminology, Beverly Hills, Sage Publications. Melossi, Dario (1987), ‘Political Business Cycles and Imprisonment Rates in Italy: Report on a Work in Progress’, 16(1-2) Review of Black Political Economy, 211-218. Miceli, Thomas J. (1996), ‘Plea Bargaining and Deterrence: An Institutional Approach’, 3 European Journal of Law and Economics, 249-264. Michaels, Robert J. (1976), ‘Noncriminal Deviance and Mental Hospitalization: Economic Theory and Evidence’, 5 Journal of Legal Studies, 387-433. Michaels, Robert J. (1988), ‘Addiction, Compulsion, and the Technology of Consumption’, 26 Economic Inquiry, 75-88. Myers, Samuel L., Jr (1980), ‘Why are Crimes Underreported? What is the Crime Rate? Does it Really Matter?’, 6 Social Science Quarterly, 23-43. Myers, Samuel L., Jr (1982), ‘Crime in Urban Areas: New Evidence and Results’, 11 Journal of Urban Economics, 148-158. Myers, Samuel L., Jr (1983), ‘Estimating the Economic Model of Crime: Employment versus Punishment Effects’, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 157-175. Myers, Samuel L., Jr (1984a), ‘Do Better Wages Reduce Crime? A Research Note’, 43 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 191-195. Myers, Samuel L., Jr (1984b), ‘Race and Punishment: Directions for Economic Research’, 74 American Economic Review, 288-292. Nagin, Daniel S. (1978), ‘General Deterrence: A Review of the Empirical Evidence’, in Blumstein, Cohen and Nagin (eds), Deterrence and Incapacitation: Estimating the Effects of Criminal Sanctions on Crime Rates, Washington, DC, National Academy of Sciences, 95-139.
8100
Economics of Criminal Behavior
383
Nagin, Daniel S. and Paternoster, Raymond (1991a), ‘The Preventive Effects of the Perceived Risk of Arrest: Testing an Expanded Conception of Deterrence’, 29 Criminology, 561-587. Nagin, Daniel S. and Paternoster, Raymond (1991b), ‘On the Relationship of Past to Future Participation in Delinquency’, 29 Criminology, 169-189. Nagin, Daniel S. and Paternoster, R.A. (1993), ‘Enduring Individual Differences and Rational Choice Theories of Crime’, 27 Law and Society Review, 467-496. Nagin, Daniel S. and Waldfogel, Joel (1995), ‘The Effects of Criminality and Conviction on the Labor Market Status of Young British Offenders’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 109-126. Neher, Philip A. (1978), ‘The Pure Theory of Muggery’, 68 American Economic Review, 437-445. Nickerson, Gary W. (1983), ‘Analytical Problems in Explaining Criminal Behavior: Neoclassical and Radical Economic Theories and an Alternative Formulation’, 15(4) Review of Radical Political Economy, 1-23. Niggli, Marcel Alexander (1994), ‘Rational Choice Theory and Crime Prevention’,3 Studies on Crime and Crime Prevention, 83-103. Opp, Karl Dieter (1989), ‘The Economics of Crime and the Sociology of Deviant Behaviour: A Theoretical Confrontation of Basic Propositions’, 42 Kyklos, 405-430. Orsagh, Thomas (1973), ‘Crime, Sanctions and Scientific Explanation’, 64 Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 354-361. Orsagh, Thomas (1979), ‘Empirical Criminology: Interpreting Results Derived from Aggregate Data’, 16 Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency, 294-306. Otto, Hans-Jochen (1982), Generalprävention und externe Verhaltenskontrolle, Wandel vom sociologischen zum ökonomischen Paradigma in der nordamerikanischen Kriminologie? (General Prevention and External Control of Behavior, Evolution from Sociological to Economic Paradigm in the North American Criminology?), Freiburg, Max-Planck-Institut für ausländisches und internationales Strafrecht, 323 p. Ozenne, Tim (1974), ‘The Economics of Bank Robbery’, 3 Journal of Legal Studies, 19-51. Packer, Herbert L. (1968), The Limits of the Criminal Sanction, Stanford, Hoover Institute Press, Stanford University, 366 p. Palmer, Jan (1977), ‘Economic Analysis of the Deterrent Effect of Punishment: A Review’, 14 Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency, 4-21. Parker, Robert N. and Horwitz, Allan V. (1986), ‘Unemployment, Crime, and Imprisonment: A Panel Approach’, 24 Criminology, 751-771. Passell, Peter (1975), ‘The Deterrent Effect of the Death Penalty: A Statistical Test’, 28 Stanford Law Review, 61-80. Passell, Peter and Taylor, John B. (1977), ‘The Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment: Another View’, 67 American Economic Review, 445-451. Pastor, Santos (1994), ‘La Exigibilidad de las Normas y la Resolución de Conflictos (Law Enforcement and Dispute Resolution)’, 3 Iuris: Quaderns de Política Jurídica, 155-174. Paternoster, Raymond, Saltzman, Linda E., Chiricos, Theodore E. and Waldo, Gordon P. (1982), ‘Perceived Risk and Deterrence: Methodological Artifacts in Perceptual Deterrence Research’, 73 Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 1238-1258. Payne, M. and Furnham, A. (1990), ‘Perceptions of Crime and Delinquency in Barbados’, 39 Social and Economic Studies, 135-150.
384
Economics of Criminal Behavior
8100
Peltzman, Sam (1989), ‘The Failure of Enforcement’, British Journal of Addiction. Phillips, D. (1980), ‘The Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment: New Evidence and Old Controversy’, 86 American Journal of Sociology, 81-139. Phillips, Llad (1987), ‘Race and Crime: Comments’, 16 Review of Black Political Economy, 219-221. Phillips, Llad and Votey, Harold L., Jr (1972), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Deterrent Effect of Law Enforcement on Criminal Activity’, 63 Journal of Criminal Law, Criminology and Police Science, 330-342. Phillips, Llad and Votey, Harold L., Jr (1975), ‘Crime Control in California’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 327-349. Phillips, Llad and Votey, Harold L., Jr (1981), The Economics of Crime Control, Beverly Hills, CA, Sage Publications. Phillips, Llad and Votey, Harold L., Jr (1984), ‘Black Women, Economic Disadvantage, and Incentives to Crime’, 74 American Economic Review, 293-297. Phillips, Llad and Votey, Harold L., Jr (1987a), ‘Crimes by Youth: Deterrence and Moral Compliance with the Law’, 5(4) Contemporary Policy Issues, 73-90. Phillips, Llad and Votey, Harold L., Jr (1987b), ‘Rational Choice Models of Crimes by Youth’, 16 Review of Black Political Economy, 129-187. Phillips, Llad, Votey, Harold L., Jr and Howell, John (1976), ‘Handguns and Homocide: Minimizing Losses and the Costs of Control’, 5 Journal of Legal Studies, 463-478. Phillips, Llad, Votey, Harold L., Jr and Maxwell, Darold (1972), ‘Crime, Youth and the Labor Market: An Economic Study’, 80 Journal of Political Economy, 491-504. Png, Ivan Paak-Liang (1987), ‘Litigation, Liability, and Incentives for Care’, 34 Journal of Public Economics, 61-85. Png, Ivan Paak-Liang and Mookherjee, D. (1992), ‘Monitoring vis-à-vis Investigation in Enforcement of Law’, 82 American Economic Review, 556-565. Png, Ivan Paak-Liang and Mookherjee, D. (1994), ‘Marginal Deterrence in Enforcement of Law’, 102 Journal of Political Economy, 1039-1066. Png, Ivan Paak-Liang and Mookherjee, D. (1995), ‘Corruptible Law Enforcers: How Should They be Compensated?’, 105 Economic Journal, 145-159. Pogue, Thomas F. (1975), ‘Effects of Police Expenditure on Crime Rates: Some Evidence’, 3 Public Finance Quarterly, 14-44. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1979), ‘The Optimal Tradeoff between the Probability and Magnitude of Fines’, 69 American Economic Review, 880-891. Polinsky, Mitchell A. (1978), ‘[Economics and Law:] Discussion’, 68 American Economic Review: Papers and Proceedings, 435-436. Prisching, Manfred (1982), ‘Sozioökonomische Bedingungen der Kriminalität. Über empirische Divergenzen und theoretische Kontroversen (Socio-economic Conditions of Criminality. On Empirical Divergencies and Theoretical Controversies)’, 65 Monatsschrift für Kriminologie und Strafrechtsreform, 163-176. Pyle, David J. (1979a), ‘Crime Rates and Police Expenditure’, in Maunder, P. (ed), Case Studies in the Economics of Social Issues, London, Heinemann, 61-76. Pyle, David J. (1979b), The Economics of Crime and Law Enforcement: A Selective Biblipography (+ Supplement 1980), SSRC Public Sector Study Group, Bibliography Series No. 1, 216 p. Pyle, David J. (1983), The Economics of Crime and Law Enforcement, London, Macmillan, 216 p.
8100
Economics of Criminal Behavior
385
Radford, R.S. (1989), ‘Going to the Island: A Legal and Economic Analysis of the Medieval Icelandic Duel’, 62 Southern California Law Review, 615 ff. Rasmussen, David W. and Benson, Bruce L. (eds) (1994), The Economic Anatomy of a Drug War: Criminal Justice in the Commons, Lanham, MD, Rowman and Littlefield. Rasmussen, David W., Benson, Bruce L. and Sollars, David L. (1993), ‘Spatial Competition in Illicit Drug Markets: The Consequences of Increased Drug Enforcement’, 23 Review of Regional Studies, 219-236. Rizzo, Mario J. (1979), ‘The Cost of Crime to Victims: An Empirical Analysis’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 177-205. Robert, Philippe and Godefroy, Thierry (1977), Le Coût du Crime ou l’Economie Poursuivant le Crime (The Cost of Crime or Economics Prosecuting Crime), Genève, Masson, 225 p. Rogers, A.J. III(1973), The Economics of Crime, Illinois, Dryden Press. Ross, H. Laurence (1977), ‘Deterrence Regained: The Cheshire Constabulary’s “Breathalyser Blitz”’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 241-249. Ross, H. Laurence and LaFree, Gary D. (1986), ‘Deterrence in Criminology and Social Policy’, in Smelser, Neil J. and Gerstein, Dean R. (eds), Behavioral and Social Science: Fifty Years of Discovery, Washington, DC, National Academy Press, 129-152. Ross, Laurence H. (1975), ‘The Scandinavian Myth: The Effectiveness of Drinking-and-Driving Legislating in Sweden and Norway’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 285-310. Rottenberg, Simon (ed) (1973),The Economics of Crime and Punishment, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 232 p. Rovens, R. and Prinsen, P.J. (1984), ‘Extra Politie-inzet en Rijden onder Invloed (More Police and Drunken Driving)’, 52 WODC. Rubin, Paul H. and Kau, James B. (1975), ‘Economic and Ideological Factors in Political Decision Making: The 1980 Election’, 24 Public Choice, 385-388. Saffer, Henry and Chaloupka, Frank J. (1989), ‘Breath Testing and Highway Fatality Rates’, 21 Applied Economics, 901-912. Saffer, Henry and Grossman, Michael (1987a), ‘Beer Taxes, the Legal Drinking Age, and Youth Motor Vehicle Fatalities’, 16 Journal of Legal Studies, 351-374. Saffer, Henry and Grossman, Michael (1987b), ‘Drinking Age Laws and Highway Mortality Rates: Cause and Effect’, 25 Economic Inquiry, 403-417. Sah, R.K. (1991), ‘Social Osmosis and Patterns of Crime’, 99 Journal of Political Economy, 1272-1295. Sandelin, Bo and Skogh, Göran (1986), ‘Property Crimes and the Police: An Empirical Analysis of Swedish Data’, 88 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 547-561. Sansarricq, Frank (1990), ‘Crime and Economic Development in a Small, Open Economy’, 27 Keio Economic Studies, 41-49. Schmidt, Peter and Witte, Ann D. (1984), An Economic Analysis of Crime and Justice: Theory, Methods, and Applications, New York, Academic Press, 416 p. Schmidt, Peter and Witte, Ann D. (1989), ‘Predicting Criminal Recidivism Using “Split Population” Survival Time Models’, 40 Journal of Econometrics, 141-159. Schuller, Bernd-Joachim (1986), Ekonomi och Kriminalitet: En Empirisk Undersöking av Brottsligheten i Sverige (Economics and Criminality: Empirical Research in Sweden), Economiska studier utgivna av Nationalekonomiska institutionen vid Göteborgs Universitet, 17 ff.
386
Economics of Criminal Behavior
8100
Schwartz, Warren F., Baxter, Keith and Ryan, David (1984), ‘The Duel: Can These Gentlemen be Acting Efficiently?’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 321-335. Sesnowitz, Michael L. and Hexter, Lawrence (1982), ‘Economic Determinants of Theft: Some Empirical Results’, 10 Public Finance Quarterly, 489-498. Shavell, Steven (1989), ‘Specific versus General Enforcement of Law’, Program in Law and Economics, Harvard Law School, Disc. Paper No. 58. Shavell, Steven (1990), ‘Deterrence and the Punishment of Attempts’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 435-466. Shavell, Steven (1992), ‘A Note on Marginal Deterrence’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 345-355. Silver, Morris (1975), ‘A Critical Survey of the Recent Econometric Literature on Deterrence’, in Ernest van den Haag and Robert Martinson (eds), Crime Deterrence and Offender Career, New York, City College of the City University of New York, 136-172. Singh, B. (1973), ‘Making Honesty the Best Policy’, Journal of Public Economics, 257-263. Sjoquist, David Lawrence (1973), ‘Property Crime and Economic Behavior: Some Empirical Results’, 63 American Economic Review, 439-446. Skogh, Göran (1973), ‘A Note on Becker’s “Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach”’, 75 Swedish Journal of Economics, 305-311. Skogh, Göran and Stuart, Charles (1982a), ‘A Contractarian Theory of Property Rights and Crime’, 84 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 27-40. Skogh, Göran and Stuart, Charles (1982b), ‘An Economic Analysis of Crime Rates, Punishments and the Consequences of Crime’, 38 Public Choice, 171-179. Slemrod, J. (1985), ‘An Empirical Test of Tax Evasion’, 67 Review of Economics and Statistics, 67, 232-238. Sloan, Frank A., Reilly, Bridget A. and Schenzler, Christoph M. (1995), ‘Effects of Tort Liability and Insurance on Heavy Drinking and Drinking and Driving’, 38 Journal of Law and Economics, 49-77. Snyder, Edward A. (1990), ‘The Effect of Higher Criminal Penalties on Antritrust Enforcement’, 33 Journal of Law and Economics, 439-462. Sollars, David L., Benson, Bruce L. and Rasmussen, David W. (1994), ‘Drug Enforcement and Deterrence of Property Crime Among Local Jurisdictions’, 22 Public Finance Quarterly, 22-45. Soloman, H. (1977), ‘The Economist’s Perspectives on Economic Crime’, 14 American Criminal Law Review, 641-649. Solow, R.M. (1977), ‘Leff’s Swindling and Selling: the Spanish Prisoner and Other Bargains’, 8 Bell Journal of Economics, 627-629. Sommers, Paul M. (1985), ‘Drinking Age and the 55 MPH Speed Limit’, 13(1) Atlantic Economic Journal, 43-48. Stevans, Lonnie K. (1988), ‘An Empirical Model of Property Crime: Deterrence versus Redistribution’, 10 Journal of Post Keynesian Economics, 572-584. Sullivan, R.F. (1973), ‘The Economics of Crime: An Introduction to the Literature’, 19 Crime and Delinquency, 138-149. Sutinen, Jon G. and Andersen, Peder (1985), ‘The Economics of Fisheries Law Enforcement’, 61 Land Economics, 387-397. Swimmer, Eugene R. (1974), ‘Measurement of the Effectiveness of Urban Law Enforcement - A Simultaneous Approach’, 40 Southern Economic Journal, 618-630.
8100
Economics of Criminal Behavior
387
Tauchen, Helen and Witte, Ann Dryden (1995), ‘The Dynamics of Domestic Violence’, 85 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 414-418. Tauchen, Helen, Witte, Ann D. and Griesinger, Harriet (1994), ‘Criminal Deterrence: Revisiting the Issue With a Birth Cohort’, 76 Review of Economics and Statistics, 399-412. Taylor, J.B. (1978), ‘Econometric Models of Criminal Behavior: A Review’, in Heineke, J.M. (ed.), Economic Models of Criminal Behavior, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 35-81. Thaler, Richard H. (1977), ‘An Econometrie Analysis Of Property Crime: Interaction Between Police and Criminals’, 8 Journal of Public Economics, 37-51. Theroux, Richard and Umbeck, John R. (1987), ‘Drunken Driving, Hit-and-Runs, and Bribery’, 11(2) Regulation, 44-47. Thompson, James W. and Cataldo, James (1986), ‘Market Incentives for Criminal Behavior: Comment’, in Freeman, Richard B. and Holzer, Harry J. (eds), The Black Youth Employment Crisis, Chicago, IL, University of Chicago Press, 347-351. Tittle, Charles R. (1978), ‘Comment on “Deterrence: Theory versus Practice”’,16 Criminology, 31-35. Tittle, Charles R. and Logan, Charles H. (1973), ‘Sanctions and Deviance: Evidence and Remaining Questions’, 7 Law and Society Review, 371-392. Tittle, Charles R. and Rowe, A.R. (1974), ‘Certainty of Arrest and Crime Rates: A Further Test of the Deterrence Hypothesis’, 52 Social Forces, 455-462. Tittle, Charles R. and Rowe, Alan R. (1978), ‘Arrest and Crime: More on the Deterrence Problem’, in Flynn, Edith Elisabeth and Conrad John P. (eds), The New and the Old Criminology, New York, Praeger, 85-95. Trumbull, William N. (1989), ‘Estimations of the Economic Model of Crime Using Aggregate and Individual Level Data’, 56 Southern Economic Journal, 423-439. Tulder, Frank Van (1985), Criminaliteit, Pakkans en Politie (Criminality, Chance of Being Caught and Police), Sociaal Cultureel Planbureau, Cahier no. 45, s-Gravenhage, Staatsdrukkerij. Tulder, Frank Van (1986), ‘Kosten en Baten van Twee Vormen van Criminaliteitsbestrijding (Costs and Benefits of Two Types of Crime Combat)’, 71 Economisch-Statistische Berichten, 172-179. Tullock, Gordon (1969), ‘An Economic Approach to Crime’, 50 Social Science Quarterly, 59-71. Tullock, Gordon (1974), ‘Does Punishment Deter Crime?’, The Public Interest, 103-111. Tullock, Gordon (1976), ‘The Economics of Crime: Punishment or Income Redistribution - Comment’, 34 Review of Social Economy, 81-82. Tunnell, K.D. (1992), Choosing Crime: The Criminal Calculus of Property Offenders, Chicago, Nelson-Hall. Usher, Dan (1986), ‘Police, Punishment, and Public Goods’, 41 Public Finance, 96-115. Van den Haag, Ernest (1975), ‘Deterrence, Deterrability and Effective Sanctions’, in Van den Haag, Ernest and Martinson, Robert (eds), Crime Deterrence and Offender Career, New York, City College of the City University of New York, 1-99. Van den Haag, Ernest and Martinson, Robert (eds) (1975), Crime Deterrence and Offender Career, New York, City College of the City University of New York. Vandaele, Walter (1978), ‘Participation in Illegitimate Activities: Ehrlich Revisited’, in Blumstein, Cohen and Nagin (eds), Deterrence and Incapacitation: Estimating the Effects of Criminal Sanctions on Crime Rates, Washington, DC, National Academy of Sciences, 270-335.
388
Economics of Criminal Behavior
8100
Viren, Matti (1990), ‘A Note on Finnish Property Criminality’, 17 International Journal of Social Economics, 55-59. Viren, Matti (1994), ‘A Test of an Economics of Crime Model’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 363-370. Viscusi, W. Kip (1986a), ‘Market Incentives for Criminal Behavior’, in Freeman, Richard B. and Holzer, Harry J. (eds), The Black Youth Employment Crisis, Chicago, IL, University of Chicago Press, 301-346. Viscusi, W. Kip (1986b), ‘The Risks and Rewards of Criminal Activity: A Comprehensive Test of Criminal Deterrence’, 4 Journal of Labor Economics, 317-340. Votey, Harold L., Jr (1969), Economic Crimes: Their Generation, Deterrence and Control, Washington, DC, US Department of Commerce. Votey, Harold L., Jr (1982), ‘Scandinavian Drinking-Driving Control: Myth or Intuition ?’,11 Journal of Legal Studies, 93-116. Votey, Harold L., Jr and Phillips, Llad (1973), ‘Social Goals and Appropriate Policy for Corrections: An Economic Appraisal’, 1 Journal of Criminal Justice, 219-240. Votey, Harold L., Jr and Phillips, Llad (1974), ‘The Control of Criminal Activity: An Economic Analysis’, in Claser, Daniel (ed), Handbook of Criminology, Chicago, Rand McNally & Co., 1055-1093. Wadycki, Walter J. and Balkin, Steven (1979), ‘Participation in Illegitimate Activities - Forst’s Model Revisited’, 8 Journal of Behavioral Economics, 151-163. Wahlroos, Björn (1981), ‘On Finnish Property Criminality: An Empirical Analysis of the Post War Era Using an Ehrlich Model’, 83 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 553-562. Waldfogel, Joel (1994), ‘Does Conviction Have a Persistent Effect on Income and Employment?’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 103-119. Wang, William K.S. (1976), ‘The Metaphysics of Punishment - An Exercise in Futility’, 13 San Diego Law Review, 306-330. Weissel, Erwin (1994), ‘Der Rechtsbruch als Regel- oder Sonderfall (Unlawfulness as a Normal or a Special Case)’, 6 Zeitschrift für Rechtsvergleichung. Wickström, Bengt-Arne (1989), ‘Comment: The Speed Limit as Life Saver’, in Faure, Michael and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds), Essays in Law and Economics: Corporations, Accident Prevention and Compensation for Losses, Antwerpen, Maklu, 157-161. Wilde, L.L. (1992), ‘Criminal Choice, Nonmonetary Sanctions, and Marginal Deterrence: A Normative Analysis’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 333-344. Williams, Allan F., Rich, Robert F., Zador, Paul L. and Robertson, Leon S. (1975), ‘The Legal Minimum Drinking Age and Fatal Motor Vehicle Crashes’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 219-239. Williams, Allan F., Zador, Paul L., Harris, Sandra S. and Karpf, Ronald S. (1983), ‘The Effect of Raising the Legal Minimum Drinking Age on Involvement in Fatal Crashes’, 12 Journal of Legal Studies, 169-179. Willis, K.G. (1983), ‘Spatial Variations in Crime in England and Wales: Testing an Economic Model’, 17 Regional Studies, 261-272. Wilson, James Q. and Boland, Barbara (1978), ‘The Effect of the Police on Crime’, 12 Law and Society Review, 367-390. Wilson, James Q. and Herrnstein, Richard J. (1985), Crime and Human Nature, New York, Simon and Schuster, 639 p. Withers, Glenn (1984), ‘Crime, Punishment and Deterrence in Australia: An Empirical Investigation’, 60 Economic Record, 176-185.
8100
Economics of Criminal Behavior
389
Witte, Ann Dryden (1980), ‘Estimating the Economic Model of Crime with Individual Data’, 94 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 57-84. Witte, Ann Dryden (1983), ‘Estimating the Economic Model of Crime: Reply [to Myers]’, 98 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 167-175. Witte, Ann Dryden and Tauchen, Helen (1994), ‘Work and Crime: An Exploration Using Panel Data’, 49 Public Finance (suppl.), 155-167. Witte, Ann Dryden and Woodbury, Diane (1985), ‘The Effect of Tax Laws and Tax Administration on Tax Compliance: The Case of the U.S. Individual Income Tax’, 38 National Tax Journal, 1-13. Wittman, Donald A. (1982), ‘Efficient Rules in Highway Safety and Sports Activity’, 72 American Economic Review, 78-90. Wolpin, Kenneth I. (1978), ‘An Economic Analysis of Crime and Punishment in England and Wales, 1894-1967', 86 Journal of Political Economy, 815-840. Wolpin, Kenneth I. (1978), ‘Capital Punishment and Homicide in England: A Summary of Results’, 68 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 422-427. Wolpin, Kenneth I. (1980), ‘A Time Series-Cross Section Analysis of International Variation in Crime and Punishment’, 62 Review of Economics and Statistics, 417-423. Yaniv, Gideon (1988), ‘Crime and Punishment: A Note on Instrumental Violence’, 17 Journal of Behavioral Economics, 143-148. Young, T. J. (1993), ‘Unemployment and Property Crime: Not a Simple Relationship’, 52 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 413-415. Zimring, Franklin E. (1972), ‘The Medium is the Message: Firearm Caliber as a Determinant of Death from Assault’, 1 Journal of Legal Studies, 97-123. Zimring, Franklin E. (1975), ‘Firearms and Federal Law: The Gun Control Act of 1968', 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 133-198. Zimring, Franklin E. (1977), ‘Determinants of the Death Rate from Robbery: A Detroit Time Study’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 317-323. Zimring, Franklin E. (1984), ‘Youth Homicide in New York: A Preliminary Analysis’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 81-99. Zimring, Franklin E. and Zuehl, James (1986), ‘Victim Injury and Death in Urban Robbery: A Chicago Study’, 15 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-40.
8200 ALTERNATIVE SANCTIONS. CRUEL SANCTIONS © Copyright 1999 Boudewijn Bouckaert and Gerrit De Geest
Bibliography Collected by the Editors Adams, Michael (1994), ‘Heroin vom Staat - Kollektiver Wahnsinn oder das gesuchte Konzept zur Zerstörung des Drogenmarktes? (Provision of Heroin by the State - Social Madness or a Concept to Destroy the Drug Market?)’, März Zeitschrift für Rechtspolitik, 106-111. Adelstein, Richard P. (1979), ‘Informational Paradox and the Pricing of Crime: Capital Sentencing Standards in Economic Perspective’, 70 Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 281-298. Avio, Kenneth L. (1979), ‘Capital Punishment in Canada: A Time-Series Analysis of the Deterrent Hypothesis’, 12 Canadian Journal of Economics, 647-676. Avio, Kenneth L. (1987a), ‘Clemency in Economic and Retributive Models of Punishment’, 7 International Review of Law and Economics, 79-88. Avio, Kenneth L. (1987b), ‘The Quality of Mercy: Exercise of the Royal Prerogative in Canada’, 13 Canadian Public Policy, 366-379. Avio, Kenneth L. (1988a), ‘Measurement Errors and Capital Punishment’, 20 Applied Economics, 1253-1262. Avio, Kenneth L. (1988b), ‘Capital Punishment: Statistical Evidence and Constitutional Issues’, 30 Canadian Journal of Criminology, 331-349. Avio, Kenneth L. (1990), ‘Retribution, Wealth Maximization, and Capital Punishment: A Law and Economics Approach’, 19 Stetson Law Review, 373-409. Avio, Kenneth L. (1993), ‘Economic, Retributive and Contractarian Conceptions of Punishment’, 12 Law and Philosophy, 249-286. Avio, Kenneth L. (1995), ‘Economic, Contractarian and Discourse Arguments against Efficient Torture’, in Peczenik, Aleksander and Karlsson, Mikael M. (eds), Archives on Rights and Social Philosophy 58, ‘Law, Justice and the State:I’, Stuttgart, Franz Steiner, 265-272. Bartling, Hartwig (1974), ‘Zur Ökonomie der Kriminalitätsbekämpfung. Eine Integration der Resozialisierung in die Kriminalökonomie (On the Economics of Criminal Policy: An Integration of Resocialization)’, Zeitschrift für Wirtschafts- und Sozialwissenschaften, 313-333. Benson, Bruce L. (1984), ‘Guns for Protection and Other Private Sector Responses to the Fear of Violent Crime’, in Kates, Don, Jr (ed.), Firearms and Violence: Issues of Regulation, Cambridge, MA, Ballinger, 329-356. Benson, Bruce L. (1986), ‘Guns for Protection and Other Private Sector Responses to Government’s Failure to Control Increasing Violent Crime’, 8 Journal of Libertarian Studies, 75-109. Benson, Bruce L. (1986), ‘The Lost Victim and Other Failures of the Public Law Experiment’, 9 Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy, 399-427.
390
8200
Alternative Sanctions. Cruel Sanctions
391
Benson, Bruce L. (1992), ‘The Development of Criminal Law and Its Enforcement: Public Interest or Political Transfers’, 3 Journal des Economistes et des Etudes Humaines, 79-108. Benson, Bruce L. (1994), ‘Are Public Goods Really Common Pools: Considerations of the Evolution of Policing and Highways in England’, 39 Economic Inquiry, 249-271. Benson, Bruce L. (1995a), ‘Appendix Oakland, Independent Institute’, in Brakel, Samuel Jan (ed.), Prisons and Corrections, Independent Policy Report. Benson, Bruce L. (1995b), Privatization in Criminal Justice, Independent Policy Report, Oakland, Independent Institute. Benson, Bruce L. (1996), ‘Restitution in Theory and in Practice’, 12 Journal of Libertarian Studies, 75-98. Benson, Bruce L. and Rasmussen, David W. (1991), ‘The Relationship Between Illicit Drug Enforcement Policy and Property Crimes’, 9 Contemporary Policy Issues, 106-115. Benson, Bruce L. and Rasmussen, David W. (1992), Illinois’ War on Drugs: Some Unintended Consequences, Heartland Policy Study, Chicago, Heartland Institute, No. 48. Benson, Bruce L. and Rasmussen, David W. (1995), Illicit Drugs and Crime, Independent Policy Report, Oakland, Independent Institute. Benson, Bruce L. and Rasmussen, David W. (1995), ‘Crime and Punishment’, in Denslow, David A., Scoggins, J.F. and Shermyen, Anne (eds), The Economy of Florida, Gainesville, FL, Bureau of Economic and Business Research, 99-116. Benson, Bruce L., Kim, Iljoong, Rasmussen, David W. and Zuehlke, Thomas W. (1993), ‘An Economic Analysis of Recidivism Among Drug Offenders’, 60 Southern Economic Journal, 169-183. Benson, Bruce L., Rasmussen, David W. and Sollars, David L. (1995), ‘Police Bureaucrats, Their Incentives, and the War on Drugs’, 83 Public Choice, 21-45. Bergstrom, T. (ed.) (1990), ‘On the Economics of Crime and Confiscation’, 4(3) Journal of Economic Perspectives, 171-178. Cameron, Samuel (1989), ‘On the Welfare Economics of Capital Punishment’, 28 Australian Economic Papers, 253-266. Cameron, Samuel (1993), ‘The Demand for Capital Punishment’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 47-59. Cassone, Alberto and Marchese, Carla (1995), ‘Tax Amnesties as Special Sales Offers: the Italian Experience’, 50 Public Finance/Finances Publiques, 51-66. Chressanthis, George A. (1989), ‘Capital Punishment and the Deterrent Effect Revisited: Recent Time Series Econometric Evidence’, 18(2) Journal of Behavioral Economics, 81-97. Clarf, Stevens H., Freeman, Jean L. and Koch, Gary G. (1976), ‘Bail Risk: A Multivariate Analysis’, 5 Journal of Legal Studies, 341-385. Cloninger, Dale O. (1987), ‘Capital Punishment and Deterrence: A Revision’, 16(4) Journal of Behavioral Economics, 55-57. Cook, Philip J. (1977), ‘Punishment and Crime: A Critique of Current Findings Concerning the Preventative Effects of Punishment’, 41(1) Law and Contemporary Problems, 164-209. Cover, James Peery and Thistle, Paul D. (1988), ‘Time Series, Homicide, and the Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment’, 54 Southern Economic Journal, 615-622.
392
Alternative Sanctions. Cruel Sanctions
8200
Daniel, S. (1979), ‘Social Science and Death Penalty Cases’, 1 Law and Policy Quarterly, 336-372. Donohue, John J. III (1981), An Evaluation of the Constitutionality of S. 114, the Proposed Federal Death Penalty Statute, Hearings before the U.S. Senate Judiciary Committee. Ehrlich, Isaac (1975), ‘The Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment: A Question of Life and Death’, 65 American Economic Review, 397-417. Ehrlich, Isaac (1981), ‘On the Usefulness of Controlling Individuals: An Economic Analysis of Rehabilitation, Incapacitation and Deterrence’, 71 American Economic Review, 307-332. Ehrlich, Isaac and Gibbons, Joel C. (1977), ‘On the Measurement of the Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment and the Theory of Deterrence’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 35-50. Ehrlich, Isaac and Randall, Mark (1977), ‘Fear of Deterrence: A Critical Evaluation of the "Report of the Panel on Research on Deterrent and Incapacitative Effects"’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 293-316. Friedman, David D. (1981), ‘Reflections on Optimal Punishment or: Should the Rich Pay Higher Fines?’, 3 Research in Law and Economics, 185-205. Garland, David (1990), Punishment in Modern Society: A Study in Social Theory, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Garoupa, Nuno (1996), ‘Prison, Parole and the Criminal Justice Act 1991', 18 Research in Law and Economics. Grogger, Jeffrey (1990), ‘The Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment: An Analysis of Daily Homicide Counts’, 85 Journal of the American Statistical Association, 295-303. Kan, Steven S. (1996), ‘Corporal Punishments and Optimal Incapacitation’, 15 Journal of Legal Studies, 121-130. Kaplow, Louis (1990), ‘A Note on the Optimal Use of Nonmonetary Sanctions’, 42 Journal of Public Economics, 245-247. Landes, William M. (1973), ‘The Bail System: An Economic Approach’, 2 Journal of Legal Studies, 79-105. Lang, Kevin and Bell, Duran (1987), ‘An Economic Model of the Intake Disposition of Juvenile Offenders’, 32 Journal of Public Economics, 79-99. Langbein, John H. (1976), ‘The Historical Origins of the Sanction of Imprisonment for Serious Crime’, 5 Journal of Legal Studies, 35-60. Lempert, Richard O. (1981), ‘Desert and Deterrence: An Assessment of the Moral Basis for Capital Punishment’, 79 Michigan Law Review, 1177-1231. Lott, John R., Jr (1990), ‘The Effect of Conviction on the Legitimate Income of Criminals’, 34 Economic Letters, 381-385. Macho-Stadler, I. (1987), ‘Contratos Basados en Mecanismos de Control y Sanciones Severas: Modelización y Limitaciones (Contracts Based on Monitoring and Severe Punishment)’, 4(2) Revista Española de Economía, 291-310. Macho-Stadler, I. (1993), ‘Penalties within the Moral Hazard Problem’, 44(3) Metroeconomica, 239-257. McAleer, Michael and Veall, Michael R. (1989), ‘How Fragile are Fragile Inferences? A Re-evaluation of the Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment’, 71 Review of Economics and Statistics, 99-106.
8200
Alternative Sanctions. Cruel Sanctions
393
Miceli, Thomas J. (1994), ‘Prison and Parole: Minimizing the Cost of Non-monetary Sanctions as Deterrents’, 16 Research in Law and Economics, 197-211. Michaels, Robert J. (1976), ‘Noncriminal Deviance and Mental Hospitalization: Economic Theory and Evidence’, 5 Journal of Legal Studies, 387-433. Myers, Samuel L., Jr (1981), ‘The Economies of Bail Jumping’, 10 Journal of Legal Studies, 381-392. Palmer, John P. (1977), ‘Economic Analysis of the Deterrent Effect of Punishment: A Review’, 14 Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency, 4-21. Posner, Richard A. (1980), ‘Retribution and Related Concepts of Punishment’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 71-92. Rasmussen, David W. and Benson, Bruce L. (eds) (1994), The Economic Anatomy of a Drug War: Criminal Justice in the Commons, Lanham, MD, Rowman and Littlefield.. Rasmussen, David W., Benson, Bruce L. and Sollars, David L. (1993), ‘Spatial Competition in Illicit Drug Markets: The Consequences of Increased Drug Enforcement’, 23 Review of Regional Studies, 219-236. Schneider, A.L. and Ervin, L. (1990), ‘Specific Deterrence, Rational Choice, and Decision Heuristics: Applications in Juvenile Justice’, 71 Social Science Quarterly, 585-601. Shavell, Steven (1985), ‘Criminal Law and the Optimal Use of Nonmonetary Sanctions as a Deterrent’, 85 Columbia Law Review, 1232-1262. Shavell, Steven (1987), ‘A Model of Optimal Incapacitation’, 77 American Economic Review, 107-110. Shavell, Steven (1987), ‘The Optimal Use of Nonmonetary Sanctions as a Deterrent’, 77 American Economic Review, 584-592. Sollars, David L., Benson, Bruce L. and Rasmussen, David W. (1994), ‘Drug Enforcement and Deterrence of Property Crime Among Local Jurisdictions’, 22 Public Finance Quarterly, 22-45. Votey, Harold L., Jr (1979), ‘Detention of Heroin Addicts, Job Opportunities, and Deterrence’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 585-606. Wolpin, Kenneth I. (1978), ‘Capital Punishment and Homicide in England: A Summary of Results’, 68 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 422-427.
8300 THE ECONOMICS OF PRISONS Kenneth L. Avio Professor of Economics, University of Victoria © Copyright 1999 Kenneth L. Avio
Abstract This chapter scans the English language research on prisons published since Becker’s (1968) seminal paper. After first describing the economic nature of prison and parole, issues concerning comparative institutional analysis and organizational design are discussed, including the role of private prisons. Empirical evidence on production functions for prisons, recidivism and offender rehabilitation programs is reviewed. A brief overview of policy issues and suggestions for future research concludes the survey. JEL classification: K14 Keywords: Economics of Crime, Prisons, Corrections, Recidivism, Rehabilitation
1. Introduction From a public policy perspective, the normative theory of the economics of crime may be interpreted in terms of the following questions: (1) How many resources should be devoted to the criminal justice system? (2) How should those resources be allocated between the various branches of the system (police, courts, and so on)? (3) How should each branch allocate its resources amongst competing uses? Conceptually these questions are addressed by simultaneously choosing values of policy control variables to minimize the overall social cost of crime, defined as the (net) direct harm from offenses plus the cost of operating the criminal justice system, subject to the various subsystem production functions and the supply of offenses functions (Becker, 1968). This chapter highlights the third question in the efficiency hierarchy as applied to prisons (correctional institutions), with explicit consideration given to the institutional framework within which the question is posed. Alternatives exist to the model alluded to in the previous paragraph. Ehrlich (1982) permits goals such as retribution to be reflected in the social cost function, with the degree of retribution related to the number of unpunished offenders and to the severity of their crimes (also see Miceli, 1991). Other economists (notably Shoup, 1964 and Thurow, 1970) emphasize conflicts between efficiency and equity in the provision of protection services. The optimization framework itself is inconsistent with the classical retributive 394
8300
The Economics of Prisons
395
justification of punishment. Adam Smith ([1791] 1976, pp. 79, 87-91) suggestively remarks that the private demand for punishment is independent of any consideration of social advantage. In contrast to economic models, Kantian inspired retributive (‘just desert’) models and their cousins (for example, the ‘restorative’ theory of Cragg, 1992; the Rawlsian-inspired ‘rectification’ theory of Adler, 1991; the ‘restitutive’ theory of Barnett, 1977, 1998, Ch. 8, 10, 11) generally argue that punishment can and must be justified independent of the consequences as measured in a social cost function (Duff, 1986, 1996). Economic and retributive models each have difficulty rationalizing certain policies adopted or at least acknowledged by most modern penal systems: economic prescriptions appear inconsistent with constitutional constraints on cruel and unusual punishments; classical retributive models specify punishments which may be insufficient for deterrence. Constitutional contractarian models applied to punishment can rationalize independent constraints on social cost minimization (Avio, 1993b), and will be implicitly assumed in what follows. A seemingly natural way to organize this survey is in accordance with the individual purposes of imprisonment: incapacitation, rehabilitation, specific deterrence (the deterrent effect on released offenders of having served an imprisonment term), general deterrence and retribution. The problem is that the literature cannot be easily sorted in this way (consider, for example, how the topic of prison privatization might fit within such a framework). The alternative adopted here is to organize the survey in terms of the ‘operational’ topics treated in the literature, beginning with the economic nature of prisons and parole. Issues concerning comparative institutional analysis and organizational design are then discussed, followed by various empirical topics including production functions for correctional institutions, recidivism (a variously defined measure related to the criminal activity of released inmates), offender rehabilitation programs, and labor markets for former prison inmates. An overview of policy issues concludes the survey. Discussion is limited for the most part to research by economists and/or to authors taking a law and economic perspective. The reader is forewarned that general deterrence is not systematically covered here, as this would entail surveying the vast theoretical and empirical literature on offender supply functions, and undertaking that would greatly increase the lenght and scope of this chapter.
2. Prisons Conceptualized Prisons provide protection services to society. In principle, these services could be replaced or supplemented by a less resource absorbing system of monetary penalties and/or corporal punishments, the sanctions of choice throughout most of human history. But constitutional constraints in modern democracies limit
396
The Economics of Prisons
8300
corporal punishments, and the wealth constraints of most offenders relative to the social value of the harm they create renders sole reliance on fines inefficient (Polinsky and Shavell, 1984; Shavell, 1985, 1987a, 1987b; Garoupa, 1997). Moreover, Levitt (1997) notes that the authorities may not even know the wealth level of offenders, and may be unable to distinguish between individuals with different subjective disutilities of prison terms. This latter fact is important because the threat of imprisonment must ultimately lie behind any fine. Since the typical criminal has a relatively low disutility of prison term, ‘the fine must be low relative to the jail sentence to be incentive compatible’ (ibid., 1997, p. 181). But relatively low fines will induce other types of agents to become offenders. Nevertheless, a case can be made that fines are underutilized in Western societies, although less so in Europe than in the US. Benson (1996) favors a system of fines as restitution for victims. He argues that the coerced supply of offender labor services may overcome the wealth constraint (at a cost), while the incentive for victims to cooperate in the prosecution of offenders increases the effectiveness of the police and courts. Conversely, convicted offenders may be induced to commit more crimes to pay off their initial fine, and the promise of fines as restitution may lead to overzealous prosecution by victims. For the remainder of this essay, the relative efficiency of incarceration as a criminal sanction is assumed. Modern prisons may be viewed as multi-product firms providing incarceration days and rehabilitation opportunities (Avio, 1973). The threat of incarceration has a putative general deterrent effect on prospective offenders (Lewis, 1986) whereas incarceration prevents inmates from committing crimes against those outside the prison walls. This incapacitation effect may be partly offset by an increased number of ‘new’ criminals if the returns to crime increase as incarcerated offenders are temporarily removed from the criminal market (Cook, 1977; Ehrlich, 1981). The rehabilitation effect acknowledges that a convicted offender’s proclivity for crime may decrease as a result of the incarceration experience, as well as by virtue of the fact that age has an independent effect upon criminality. The school for crime syndrome, criminal stigmatization and the natural depreciation of human capital while offenders are incarcerated all pull in the opposite direction. Thus the rehabilitation effect may more properly be labelled a ‘training’ effect, which from a social standpoint may be either positive or negative. Insofar as this is forecasted by potential offenders, the actual discounted expected costs of engaging in current crime may increase or decrease. This result is tempered by the widely held belief that offenders as a whole tend to discount the future more heavily than non-offenders (Herrnstein, 1983; Wilson, 1983, pp. 223-249; Wilson and Herrnstein, 1985, pp. 166-172, 416-422; Gill, 1994).
8300
The Economics of Prisons
397
3. Parole Miceli (1994) presents a model of the prison where the optimal lengths of the incarceration and parole periods for individual offenders are chosen by a central authority. The goal is to minimize the cost of a given level of deterrence, conditional upon a predetermined probability of conviction. Parole reduces social costs by prompting prison inmates to behave and by decreasing the number of person-days of incarceration supplied. On the other hand, a system utilizing parole and/or probation reduces the costs of crime to potential offenders and reduces the incapacitation effect. The efficient punishment balances these costs and benefits, and typically requires a period of imprisonment followed by supervised release, as opposed to either probation (immediate release) or unconditional release following incarceration. Miceli demonstrates that the socially optimal policy varies across individual offenders. Garoupa (1996) generalizes these results in a model which includes the net gains to offenders in the social welfare calculation. The information and coordination requirements in the Miceli model are substantial. This point is brought home in the recognition that the model may be understood in terms of either a determinate or an indeterminate sentencing regime. (In the latter, the trial judge sentences offenders to prison for an indefinite period; parole authorities determine when the inmate is to be released.) The behavior of all agents is invariant to the institutional framework given the rational expectations assumption: potential offenders know prior to committing offenses the incarceration/parole mix they will receive if convicted, and the effort they will exert to comply with prison rules. Introducing informational imperfections in the form of a failure on the part of the authorities to correctly perceive the good behaviour efforts of confined inmates does not change the basic results of the Miceli model (Garoupa, 1996, p. 26). An analysis assuming a random component in the relationship between good behavior effort and subsequent proclivity to recidivate would presumably yield similar qualitative implications. Miceli concludes that a grid-style sentencing scheme such as that promulgated by the US Sentencing Commission, which leaves little room for consideration of the full range of offender-specific characteristics, increases the cost of providing a given level of deterrence. These costs are defined to exclude consideration of retribution and disparities in punishment, factors which in part motivate grid-type sentencing systems (Parker and Block, 1989; Parker, 1989; see Easterbrook, 1983, for a market-analogy argument favoring discretion in sentencing). In a somewhat different context, Garoupa’s (1996) model is used to examine the effects of the UK Criminal Justice Act, 1991, which raised the upper and lower bounds for the proportion of the sentence that may be served on parole. The social welfare effects of the law are found to be ambiguous.
398
The Economics of Prisons
8300
Lewis (1979, 1983), in an attempt to provide an empirically feasible guide to parole officials, seeks to establish the optimal parole period given exogenously determined conviction rates and original sentence lengths. The maximand consists of ‘the expected cost to society ... during the period of the original sentence as a function of the number of months served prior to parole’ (Lewis, 1979, p. 382). The model is simulated under a range of assumptions concerning the impact of time served in prison on the rate at which released offenders return to crime (the recidivism rate) while on parole. Neither Lewis (1979, 1983), Miceli (1994) nor Garoupa (1996) account for the impact and effects of inmate training on the rate at which released offenders return to crime. This consideration requires abandoning Becker’s (1968) static framework, and including social investments in inmate training as a new choice variable (Avio, 1975). Limited progress has been made with highly stylized two-period models of punishment (Rubenstein, 1980; Davis, 1988; Polinsky and Rubinfeld, 1991; Nash, 1991; Burnovski and Safra, 1994). These papers explicitly or implicitly assume that punishment is by fine, and ignore recidivistic behaviour. The theme of dynamic efficiency and recidivism is taken up in Flinn (1986) and Leung (1995), but in-prison investments in human capital and their impact on recidivism remain unanalyzed. A dynamic general equilibrium model has yet to be developed.
4. Organizational Design Several commentators note that the current decentralized criminal justice system is not expected to be efficient. Insofar as the decision variables at issue (overall prison budget, sentence lengths, training opportunities, parole release) are chosen by different decision centers, each with a different mandate, it is unlikely that the resulting product mix would be efficient. With the legislature setting the overall prison budget and the courts and parole authorities determining the level of confinement days, prisons are left with zero degrees of freedom in selecting the level of support that affects post-release behavior. The product mix could be efficient if the courts and parole authorities were to select appropriate sentence lengths for the given budget. But since the mandate of the courts is weighted more toward the provision of retribution (indeed, in some regimes judges are determined by popular vote), and the parole authorities have limited flexibility in determining the actual length of stay of prisoners, the decreed sentence lengths and consequent level of rehabilitation services would not in general be expected to be efficient for any given budget. A system of indeterminate sentences alleviates the coordination and informational problems inherent in a decentralized penal system (Avio, 1973), while remaining consistent with the efficiency thrust of the Miceli (1994)
8300
The Economics of Prisons
399
model. The confinement and training decisions become centralized, and maximum incentives for offenders to avail themselves of rehabilitation opportunities are provided. The general rejection of such programs for all but repeat violent offenders is based upon several factors: the difficulties with protecting the civil rights of inmates under such a regime; the frustrations arising from several decades of inconclusive research on inmate rehabilitation; a perceived lack of success in predicting recidivism on an individual offender basis; and an increased emphasis on retribution as the primary goal of punishment. Former UK Home Secretary Howard (1996) proposed a hybrid determinate/indeterminate sentencing scheme reminiscent of ‘three strikes and you’re out’ regimes while retaining the benefits of ‘marginal deterrence’ (Stigler, 1970). Under this scheme, repeat violent offenders would automatically receive life sentences, while the trial judge sets a minimum period intended to satisfy the need for retribution and deterrence. Once that period is served, penal authorities would determine whether and when the inmate is released. Upon release, offenders would be subject to recall for the rest of their lives. An earlier proposal for a two-part penalty scheme was proposed by Tabasz (1974) to alleviate the retribution-rehabilitation conflict. The first part of the sentence targets retribution. It would be determinate, independent of offender characteristics, of relatively short duration and served in an environment devoid of amenities. The offender would then pass on to a different environment to serve out the second, indeterminate stage directed to the rehabilitation goal. Again the purpose of the indeterminate sentence is to align the incentives of the offender with society’s goal of minimizing the overall time-discounted social costs of crime. Tabasz suggests that the condition for release be some readily visible sign of achievement on the part of the offender such as the attainment of a definable educational or vocational training goal. One difficulty with two-part penalty schemes is that the various penal functions (retribution, rehabilitation, deterrence) do not map separately into the determinate and indeterminate portions of the sentence. Any ‘hardening’ of the inmate during the first stage would presumably have to be rectified during the second, and since loss of liberty represents an important component of incarcerative punishment, the retributive function is in play during both phases. If the first phase is thought to fulfill the offender’s debt to society, then imposition of the second may be constitutionally impermissible. Of course, this latter objection may apply to any sentencing scheme that incorporates goals other than retribution, a term (like ‘debt to society’) of art. Roper (1986) proposes a different solution to the decentralization-coordination problem. He conceptualizes prison output as the delivery of a crime-free offender over the period of the court-rendered sentence. Taking this period as a constraint, Roper’s prison decides whether to keep the offender in custody over the entire sentence or to release him early. As Roper
400
The Economics of Prisons
8300
puts it, ‘the essence of the [prison’s] role [is] to assess the risks uniquely associated with the probability of a given offender reoffending’ (ibid., p. 91). The author goes on to suggest that the prison enter into contracts with prospective parolees; the prisoner agrees to desist from criminal activities for the duration of the sentence, while the authorities provide financial support, rehabilitation services, employment assistance, and so on, and release the inmate on parole. If the released offender violates a contract term, then he or she is liable not only for the new criminal charge, if any, but also for a civil contracts suit. The argument is presented in terms of a private (for-profit) prison, but a state operated prison could function in the same manner. While Roper’s proposal represents an interesting attempt to correct the principal-agent problem between the state and the offender, as well as the decentralization problem, substantial difficulties remain. First, since most prisoners are judgement proof, the contract remedy must stipulate a return to prison. This penalty would be independent of any sentence levied for the crime causing the contract violation. But it is unlikely that the courts would permit such a remedy. As an alternative, the contract could promise a financial reward subject to forfeit. This avoids the dubious remedy of confinement, but may serve to entice prospective offenders into committing crime in the first place. Second, independent of remedy, the courts may not recognize the validity of such contracts; what economists define as a voluntary transaction may not fall within the range recognized by the courts, given that the offender is bargaining for his freedom and ipso facto is under duress. Nardulli (1984) and Giertz and Nardulli (1985) take up the decentralization issue from the perspective of the fiscal federalism literature (also see Benson and Wollan (1989) and Benson (1990, 1994a), where the common pool/property rights nature of the decentralization problem is identified). These authors view judges as rendering inefficiently severe sentences as the result of a free-rider problem emanating from a misalignment of incentives and cost-bearing. Citizens of the local government derive benefits (protection and retribution) from longer sentences, which happen to be specified by local authorities. However, the costs of providing prison services may be partly shifted from one sentencing jurisdiction onto another via prison financing by a senior level of government. Thus the local demand for confinement is not fully constrained by the cost of delivery. The tendency to prison overcrowding in the federal part of the system, and underbuilding in the local part, follows directly. The short-run solution proposed by Giertz and Nardulli (1985) is to allocate total available prison space to individual sentencing jurisdictions, while continuing with the current division of cost and sentencing responsibilities. This would to an extent defuse free-riding behavior, but one could imagine disagreeable (and constitutionally questionable) inequities in sentencing arising from the constraint. For example, suppose only shoplifters are predicted to
8300
The Economics of Prisons
401
appear before a court during some period, so that relatively harsh sentences are compatible with the given space allocation. Then if an armed robber unexpectedly appears in court, he will either receive a comparatively light sentence or else one of the previously convicted shoplifters must be released earlier than expected. Unless judges accurately forecast the distribution of upcoming cases, a shortage or surplus of prison space would develop, leading to disparities in sentences actually served for offenders committing the same crime. This argument could apply to a senior administrative jurisdiction as well, but the greater number of cases reduces the risk of prediction errors. The long-run solution offered by Giertz and Nardulli is to hold local jurisdictions responsible for their full share of the cost of incarceration. An alternative is for the senior fiscal authority to impose a mandatory grid sentencing scheme upon all courts within its jurisdiction, thus to some extent negating the free-rider problem. Gillespie (1983) proposes a market for prison space administered by a centralized correctional authority. This market would facilitate the efficient transfer of prison space from local jurisdictions with excess supply to those with excess demand. Jurisdictions comprised of citizens with relatively heavy demand for long-term sentences backed by a willingness to pay would purchase access to penal space from other jurisdictions. Not only would the pricing mechanism overcome the short-run deficits or surpluses but the market-determined price would signal the social value of new prison space, and hence rationalize the construction of new correctional facilities. Gillespie argues that equity concerns can be addressed by altering the initial allocation according to whatever equity criterion is adopted. With appropriately identified prices and initial allocations, this system appears similar to one giving local authorities a portion of the state budget to be spent by them as they desire: on penal space at the state institution, on space at the local level, or on some other public expenditure (Nardulli, 1984). Would the Gillespie proposal lead to the same results as a centralized sentencing and prison-supply agency? Probably not, simply because income distribution across the local political units would affect the demands for prison space. For given sentences, the various market-oriented systems should cost less than the standard first-come, first-served, free-rider system. But regardless of the efficiency implications, introducing a market for prison space would predictably exacerbate inequities in sentencing across jurisdictions. Other things equal, low-income sub-units would presumably impose relatively short sentences and sell their space allocations to high-income sub-units, which would impose relatively severe sentences. A general equilibrium formulation of Gillespie’s model would also have to consider the possibility that offenders might change their geographical areas of operation in response to differential expected punishments.
402
The Economics of Prisons
8300
5. Privatization A more fundamental argument for the inefficiency of publicly-operated prisons stems directly from the theory of bureaucracy/public choice literature. Profit-maximization, and its concomitant for non-market production, cost minimization, may not be adopted as the operational goal of the public entity. Some models of bureaucratic behavior assume or imply cost efficiency, whereas other do not. Niskanen (1971) argues that bureaus seek to maximize bureau size, and hence overproduce; but whatever output they provide will be at least cost if the bureau is budget-constrained. Other models (for example, Williamson, 1964) posit that bureau heads will optimize with respect to private objectives, and therefore cost minimization cannot be expected. The debate over private prisons typically draws on the latter genre of models, deemphasizing decentralization and informational difficulties. Privatization and the profit motive, it is argued, removes the wedge between output and returns for public employees, thus reducing agency costs. The standard private prison contract bases remuneration for the corporate prison upon the number of person-days of confinement supplied, subject to the provision of some standard level of amenities. Thus the corporate prison has no incentive to provide rehabilitation opportunities, except insofar as the latter act to decrease the current cost of confinement (Schmidt and Witte, 1984, pp. 345-346). If rehabilitation activities affect post-release criminality, then regardless of market structure the standard per-diem contract is inferior to one that pays the private prison in accordance with the recidivism success of its releasees (Avio, 1993a). Appropriately designed remuneration schemes harness the power of the market to stimulate the discovery of imprisonment methods that minimize long-run social costs. The argument has been extended to incorporate the possibility that the corporate prison operating under the traditional remuneration scheme might perversely seek to stimulate recidivism (Gentry, 1986; Avio, 1991). Under the standard contract provisions, the value of the prison corporation depends to an extent upon the continued influx of inmates, which could be enhanced by (clandestinely) providing negative training. A flow of new offenders sufficient to keep individual prisons operating at the minimum of their average cost curves, while simultaneously requiring the construction of new facilities, would maximize profit opportunities. This argument is conditional upon the exercise of market power. Established prison firms would seem to be in an advantageous position to capture managerial and construction contracts for new prisons. Of course, the incentive structure embedded in the public prison system may be equally inimical to social welfare. Whether the weak or the strong form of the argument against per-diem contracts is applied, the debate over private prisons exhibits a kind of
8300
The Economics of Prisons
403
symmetry: private prisons are socially superior to public prisons because the former seek efficiencies in the drive to maximize profits; public prisons are superior to private prisons because they are not driven by the profit motive. Some privatization advocates recognize the difficulty with the standard prison contract, but attempts to explain away this quasi-paradox are unsatisfactory and reveal the inconsistency: Logan (1987, p. 39) argues that rather than maximizing profits, private prisons really seek to maximize convenience subject to some minimal profit constraint; Brakel (1988, p. 34, n.92) argues that line employees of the private prison, whose actions have the greatest potential to affect post-release behavior, are too distant from profit centers to act in accordance with the profit motive. But in the same breath, adherence to the profit motive with the attendant efficiencies is given as the overarching rationale for prison privatization. The increasing popularity of private prisons in policy circles is attributable to more than the general privatization fashion alone. The modern conceptualization of prisons as a benign warehouse has replaced the ‘corrections’ model in professional circles. This follows the retrenchment on treatment oriented programs in the 1980s. The prison-as-warehouse conceptualization is consistent with both the static neoclassical and the Kantian-inspired retributive models discussed earlier. In the former, prisons are simply the institutions society employs to effect the restriction of liberty necessary to attain the efficient amount of crime through deterrence and incapacitation. In Kantian retributive models, justice requires punishment in a rights-respecting environment; the moral autonomy of the individual demands that no attempt be made to ‘force’ rehabilitation. The underlying function of prisons remains the same, a function that could equally well be provided by an institution operating under market incentives. Non-economic arguments may ultimately decide the scope that private prisons are allowed to play. A feeling of unease accompanies the thought of government delegating to private individuals the authority to punish (Dilulio, 1988, 1990). Regulations such as those included in the American Bar Association’s Model Code and Model Statute for Private Incarceration may be necessary to protect the civil liberties of offenders (Robbins, 1989). Benson (1990, 1994b) extends the argument. The potential for success with prison privatization in terms of technological efficiency is so great, that once bureaucratic resistance and other obstacles to private prisons are overcome, society may increasingly come to rely on incarceration as a means of social control. For example, special interest groups may press for the expanded imprisonnment of illegal aliens to control labor supply (Benson, 1994b, pp. 66-72). Prison privatization then poses a threat to both overall allocative efficiency and to individual liberty. To date, the empirical evidence comparing private and public management of adult secure facilities has been scant and somewhat unsatisfactory. The
404
The Economics of Prisons
8300
number of surveys of these studies (McDonald, 1990; Thomas and Logan, 1993; Sellers, 1993, Ch. 4; Sichor, 1995, Ch. 9; USGAO, 1991, 1996) nearly equals the number of studies, simultaneously reflecting the youthfulness of the private prison industry (the first modern adult secure facility went under private management in 1983), the difficulty of the research, and interest in the topic. The studies typically consist of cost and quality comparisons of matched institutions (see, for example, Edwards, 1996). Thomas (1996) notes that comparisons of similarly designed facilities will not necessarily account for the cost-saving innovations that private prisons should bring, as design is itself a major source of efficiencies. Also, recidivism rates of the various institutions are typically ignored (see Hatry, 1989, for an exception). Econometric work on private prisons has yet to be undertaken. Given the growth of the industry (from fewer than 3,000 [rated capacity] beds under contract in 1983 to over 84,000 in the US, UK and Australia at the end of 1996), the time is ripe for sophisticated quantitative research.
6. Linear Programming Models The empirical test of propositions relating to correctional institutions requires a priori modelling. Although unmodified linear programming imposes severe technology constraints, interesting questions can be addressed using this technique. In the tradition of a systems analysis of prisons (Blumstein and Larson, 1969), Tabasz (1975) constructs a linear programming model of the US Federal Bureau of Prisons. The goal is to allocate different types of offenders to different types of institutions and to different sentence lengths in a manner that maximizes net social benefits subject to the capacity of the prison system and the flow of convicted offenders. In all, 2,700 decision variables are specified. Only benefits to incapacitation and rehabilitation are imputed, and the capital costs of prisons are ignored. The results indicate that prison resources should be concentrated on relatively young and dangerous offenders: inmates over 45 years of age are assigned to ‘probation’ (immediate release). The model cannot directly indicate how many resources should be allocated to the prison system, but it does give an approximation to the benefit-cost ratio potentially generated by prisons (8.51 in the ‘standard’ version of the model applying 1973 data (ibid., p. 129)). This estimate, which at face value rationalizes the build-up in prison capacity that began in the US in the 1970s (Blumstein, 1995), should not be taken too seriously. The relatively primitive nature of the data available to Tabasz required strong assumptions, particularly those related to the rates of crime commission, the social costs of crime, and the rehabilitative effects of incarceration. The methodology also imposes an interpretive constraint: the results do not necessarily reflect actual net benefits
8300
The Economics of Prisons
405
attained, but the potential benefits if decision variables are chosen optimally. Nonetheless, this study anticipates later attempts to evaluate the prison system as a whole (see Section 12 below). Linear programming may also be used to identify the relative efficiency levels of individual prisons. The operations research tool known as Data Envelopment Analysis, a non-stochastic frontier methodology, is applied by Ganley and Cubbin (1992, Ch. 5) for this purpose. The underlying linear program is constructed to embody a varying returns to scale technology. Analysis of 33 UK local prisons and remand centers for the financial year 1984-85 suggests that 13 of the establishments were ‘technically inefficient relative to the peer prisons on the cost frontier’ (ibid., p. 66). On average the operating costs of the inefficient institutions could be reduced by about 12 percent. Prison cost studies comparing this method with the econometric methods discussed below would be helpful.
7. Econometric Models of Prisons A major policy issue illuminated by economic theory concerns the appropriate size of prisons. For example, in Canada in the 1960s new prisons were built to accommodate about 450 inmates. In the next decade several government reports advocated even smaller institutions. Since little was known about the cost-effectiveness of prisons, this debate occurred in what was largely an empirical vacuum. Conceptualizing the prison as an economic entity leads to traditional cost and production analysis with the potential to systematically address questions such as returns to scale in the provision of prison services. Block and Ulen (1979) estimate long- and short-run prison cost functions for the state of California using elementary functional forms. The short-run results (using time-series data for each of two maximum security institutions) suggest that average costs are minimized at surprisingly large inmate populations (for example, 5,700 for San Quentin, as estimated over the years 1948-1964 (Block and Ulen, 1979, p. 200)). A 1971-1972 cross-section of jails yields a long-run cost curve indicating approximately constant returns to scale. Both the short- and long-run analyses abstract from the rehabilitative dimension of prison output; expenditures specifically earmarked for rehabilitation are eliminated from the cost data. Schmidt and Witte (1984) (also see McGuire and Witte, 1978; Trumball and Witte, 1981-82a,1981-82b; Kritzer, 1981-82) present a comprehensive econometric analysis of US federal and California prison systems from the midto late-1970s. Short- and long-run average cost functions are derived. The short-run results for each of 22 federal and 8 California prisons are derived from estimated labor demand equations corresponding to homothetic
406
The Economics of Prisons
8300
generalized Cobb-Douglas production functions. Several of the cost functions are found to be inconsistent with economic theory. The authors ascribe this result to altered operating methods within given institutions over the sample period. For those institutions conforming to economic theory, the majority are found to have short-run average costs which decrease as inmate populations increase. This finding is particularly robust for older, fortress-type institutions. While economies of scale are indicated, it would be imprudent to draw policy implications concerning the crowded conditions in many institutions today as crowding was not a widespread phenomenon during the sample period. The impact of rehabilitation activities on costs is diverse, and ‘may depend critically on the nature of the particular institution being studied’ (Schmidt and Witte, 1984, p. 335). The authors summarize their results for the entire sample of federal and California institutions: ‘costs generally increase until a certain level of rehabilitative activities is provided and then decline thereafter’ (ibid., p. 345). Anecdotal evidence suggests that prison work experience uniquely reduces the level of violence within prisons, probably by fostering a prisoner sub-culture that rewards co-operative behavior (Fleisher, 1989, pp. 26-27; 1995, pp. 262-270). Unfortunately Schmidt and Witte lump prison work experience with educational programs and counselling services in constructing the rehabilitation activities variable (Schmidt and Witte, 1984, p. 305). A long-run cost function is estimated using pooled quarterly data over the mid-1970s for a subset of six federal institutions found to possess similar technologies. Estimated average costs are asymmetrically U-shaped, with a higher penalty on institutions housing fewer than the efficient capacity of 1075 inmates. In this subset of prisons, rehabilitation activities are found to have no statistically significant impact on long-run average costs. This result is puzzling, especially since all but one of these institutions have short-run cost functions sensitive to this variable. Several service quality variables are found to be significant. The authors conclude that ‘the minimum-cost-sized prison will probably house between 700 and 1500 inmates’ (Schmidt and Witte, 1984, p. 363) and that ‘providing single cells for inmates and rather substantial amounts of living space may actually decrease the cost of operating prisons’ (ibid., p. 362). Taken as a whole, these studies are indicative of the important role that econometric analysis can play in analyzing policy questions related to the management of prisons. Several extensions come easily to mind. Comparison of the costs and technologies of private and public prisons would be helpful in the ongoing privatization debate. Econometric studies of the cost-effectiveness of prison industries should be undertaken. Linking rehabilitation outcomes with current costs would enhance the value of the studies. The data requirements for this latter task would be substantial but not impossible, as the next two sections suggest.
8300
The Economics of Prisons
407
8. Statistical Models of Recidivism Serving time in prison, as well as participating in various prison and post-release programs, may have either a positive or negative effect upon the activities of released prison inmates. Nailing down the specifics of the relationships is clearly an important factor in evaluating overall social policies towards crime as well as in evaluating specific programs for incarcerated and paroled offenders. If, for example, predictions of future behavior of individual convicted offenders prove to be sufficiently reliable, then a program of ‘selective incapacitation’ becomes feasible, if not ethically acceptable (Greenwood and Turner, 1987). The extensive literature addressing criminal recidivism has for the most part been the preserve of criminologists, sociologists and psychologists. Here the contributions of economists Peter Schmidt and Anne Witte are noted (also see Myers, 1980a, 1983). In a series of articles (Witte and Schmidt, 1977, 1979; Sickles, Schmidt and Witte, 1979; Schmidt and Witte, 1980, 1989) and books (Schmidt and Witte 1984, 1988), Schmidt and Witte and their associates exhaustively analyze follow-up microdata on releasees from North Carolina prisons. Since the theoretically relevant dependent variables - time devoted to criminal activity and the intensity thereof - cannot be observed, a number of proxy recidivism variables are employed. These include the traditional binary ‘success-failure’ measure, categories of crimes leading to reconviction, seriousness of crimes leading to reconviction, total length of prison sentences received during the follow-up period, length of time from release to first arrest leading to conviction, and length of time from release to first return to prison. Different statistical models (qualitative variable models, survival time models) are used as appropriate for the different dependent variables studied. The polytymous logit model is used to analyze a random sample of 641 inmates in North Carolina prisons in 1969 and 1971, with follow-up periods averaging 37 months (Schmidt and Witte, 1984, Ch. 3). The seriousness of criminal activity, as measured by whether the most serious reconviction (if any) was a misdemeanour or a felony, and the type of criminal activity (crime against the person, against property, or ‘other’, including drug crime) are analyzed with respect to various personal characteristics and histories of individual inmates (excluding, for some unstated reason, time served for the sample sentence). The likelihood of reconviction is found to vary significantly with the number of previous convictions, age at release (older offenders have lower probabilities of reconviction), length of the follow-up period, and alcohol or hard drug use (ibid., p. 45). Surprisingly, none of these same variables are significant predictors of the type and the seriousness of offenses for which reconvictions are obtained. On the other hand, the type and the seriousness of previous offenses are found to be related to the type and seriousness respectively
408
The Economics of Prisons
8300
of subsequent convictions, but not the overall probability of reconviction. Consistent with the criminal career syndrome, some evidence of offenders switching from property crime to personal crime is found. A more refined indicator of the seriousness of new offenses, the total length of time sentenced for recidivist offenses, is analyzed by the same authors (Schmidt and Witte, 1984, Ch. 5) using two samples: that used in the previously reported research, and a cohort group consisting of all individuals released in North Carolina during the first six months of 1975 (25-31 month follow-up). The censored nature of the dependent variable suggests a Tobit analysis. In both samples, the dependent variable is found to vary in the predicted direction with the youthfulness of the offender, a history of alcohol abuse, the number of previous convictions, unsupervised release, and a sample incarceration for a crime against property (Schmidt and Witte, 1984, p. 73). The estimation sample is used to predict the dependent variable for a validation sample. Separating the samples into various race, gender and age groupings substantially improves the prediction reliability for most subgroups, as there appears to be considerable variability in the significance of different explanatory variables across the subgroups. The predicted total time sentenced for the entire validation sample using the best model for each subgroup is insignificantly different from the actual value of total time sentenced, suggesting an important tool for correctional planning. The overall results show the superiority of the more sophisticated models as compared with binary ‘success-failure’ models. The second set of models employed by Schmidt and Witte treat survival time - the length of time from release to recidivism. Not only is this variable of interest in itself, but ignoring information on length of time to recidivism (however defined) is statistically inefficient. The authors’ extensive analyses (the present discussion is limited to Schmidt and Witte, 1988) utilize various formulations found in the increasingly sophisticated criminogenic literature. Carr-Hill and Carr-Hill (1972) apparently were the first authors to apply survival models in this context, as well as innovations of their own. The data consist of two cohorts of approximately 9,500 individuals each released from all state prisons in North Carolina in separate 12 month periods, with follow-ups ranging from 46 to 81 months. Data limitations, as well as the needs of the correctional authorities supplying the data, dictated the dependent variable: the length of time from release to return to prison. (The length of time from release to first rearrest leading to conviction is analyzed in Schmidt and Witte, 1984, Ch. 7.) Estimation using distributions with monotonic hazard rates proved inadequate. This is unsurprising since recidivism hazard rates first rise and then rather quickly fall. The best overall results apply individual characteristics as explanatory variables to ‘split population’ models, thereby permitting the probability of recidivism to follow a generating process distinct from that for recidivist survival times. The best fit is found for ‘a logit lognormal model, in which the probability of eventual recidivism follows a logit
8300
The Economics of Prisons
409
model and the timing of return follows a lognormal distribution’ (Schmidt and Witte, 1988, p. 19). Those models which utilize individual characteristics as explanatory variables for each of the two recidivism outcomes yield the following results: race and gender affect the probability of eventual recidivism but not its timing, whereas indicators of the nature of the previous offense affect the timing of recidivism but not its probability (ibid., p. vii); age on release, the number of prior convictions and a history of alcohol abuse affect in the predicted direction both the probability of eventual recidivism and the mean time until recidivism; finally, the length of the sample incarceration increases the probability of a return to crime and shortens survival time. These latter results appear consistent with the school for crime theory (see Myers, 1980a, for a qualitatively similar conclusion with a sample of parolee data) but selectivity bias renders this interpretation somewhat problematic. The authors recommend the use of non-parametric methods (Cox’s proportional hazards model) to first identify the appropriate explanatory variables, and then the use of parametric models to yield the best predictions. The predictions are generally superior to those elsewhere in the literature (Schmidt and Witte, 1988, p. 15), although the use of explanatory variables does not improve predictions for random samples of releasees. Moreover, the authors emphasize that their best models (predicting false positive rates of 47 percent and false negatives of 28 percent) are unsatisfactory for implementing a policy of selective incapacitation. One can conclude that there is value in using sophisticated models in predicting recidivism for random samples of released offenders, but that the models are not yet sufficiently refined for application to individuals. Schmidt and Witte note that further experimentation with non-linear formulations of the explanatory variables will probably lead to explaining a higher degree of the variation in the dependent variables (about 10 percent in the current study), and thus boost prediction accuracy (Schmidt and Witte, 1988, p.150). Another suggestion is to take more seriously the economic model of crime by including explanatory variables measuring the certainty and severity of punishment as well as environmental variables representing legitimate and illegitimate opportunities. Suppose, for example, that during the follow-up period there is variation across the relevant geographic jurisdictions and/or over time in police activity. Further, suppose that this leads to variation in the objective probability of arrest. The economic model suggests that the pattern of criminal behavior of released inmates as well as that of individuals with no previous criminal record would be affected. Prediction accuracy could be impaired (and the model mispecified) if the standard criminal justice control variables are excluded. Data limitations may intrude (ibid., p. 85). But even if the local communities in which released offenders reside are unobserved, risk and punishment variables can probably be constructed on an aggregated
410
The Economics of Prisons
8300
geographical basis for each period during the follow-up. Examples of survival-time recidivism research employing environmental variables are Visher, Lattimore and Linster (1991) studying paroled California youths, and Kim et al., (1993) examining Florida drug offenders. On a more micro level, Schmidt and Witte (1988, pp. 9-11) note that the complexion of their research results could be attributable in part to police and prosecutors targeting offenders with certain personal characteristics, as well as to the characteristics themselves affecting criminal activity. Sorting out the simultaneity problems remains an important part of the research agenda in the economics of prisons.
9. The Evaluation of In-Prison Rehabilitation Programs Psychologists, criminologists, sociologists and public policy commentators have contributed to the extensive literature on the rehabilitation of convicted offenders. This topic shades into a discussion of the overall causes of crime. No attempt will be made here to address the larger question, nor should the discussion be considered a survey of anything but a select subsample of the rehabilitation literature. The limited number of contributions by economists on the direct evaluation of rehabilitation programs is taken up in this section and the next. On the important question of research design, laboratory-like experiments comparing outcomes for randomly selected program and control groups are generally not possible in the criminal justice context (some exceptions are discussed below). Researchers typically are forced to resort to quasi-experimental designs, which designate ‘a group of individuals (the comparison group) that is as much like the group of program participants studied as possible’ (Grizzle and Witte, 1980, p. 259). The difficulty is that subjects in the two groups may differ in some characteristic that affects post-release activities. This dictates that the researcher must have in mind an underlying model of criminal and recidivistic behavior. In this section a quasi-experimental program evaluation is contrasted with one employing a ‘predicted-versus-actual’ method. Witte (1977) employs a quasi-experimental design to evaluate a program in which a non-random sample of inmates in North Carolina prisons work on day-passes with various local industries. The sample consists of men on the ‘work release’ program in 1969 or 1971. The experiences of the evaluation group are compared with those of a nonparticipating group who appear to be equally eligible for the program. Multiple regression techniques are used to correct for differences in personal characteristics across the two samples. The author finds no programmatic impact on the decision to return to crime, but a marked beneficial effect on the seriousness of crimes committed during the follow-up period. This latter result is confirmed by the logit and tobit analyses
8300
The Economics of Prisons
411
of Schmidt and Witte (1984, pp. 34-35, 68) utilizing work release as a binary explanatory variable. The results here further indicate that participation in work release is significantly related to neither the type of post-release criminal activity (crime against the person or against property), nor to survival time. Schmidt and Witte (1979, 1980, 1984, Ch. 8) use a statistical model estimated from a data set consisting of information on all 4,881 inmates released from North Carolina prisons during the first six months of 1975 to evaluate a comprehensive release program for youthful offenders in North Carolina (the Sandhills Vocational Evaluation and Job/Educational Development program). The estimated model is employed to predict criminality indicators for each of the Sandhills participants (489 participants released over the period February 21, 1975 through February 21, 1977); program evaluation proceeds from a comparison of the predicted effects with the actual criminality indicators for participants. The advantage of this ‘predicted versus actual’ method is that no matched comparison group is needed. But as the authors stress, the reliability of the evaluation depends crucially on the accuracy of the model and on the implicit assumption that the relevant prison unit does not differ significantly ‘from the system norm in a way not controlled for by our models’ (Schmidt and Witte, 1984, p. 135). Some weak statistical evidence is found suggesting that the Sandhills program reduces the amount of recidivism during the first six months of the follow-up period. (Using a smaller sample from a different estimation, the authors also find that the program reduces the total time sentenced during the follow-up period, that is, the seriousness of follow-up criminal activity (ibid., pp. 130-133.) This study conveys what can be accomplished by way of program evaluation with suitably specified statistical models. In their later study (Schmidt and Witte, 1988, Ch. 8), however, the view is less optimistic. Here an estimated model is again used to predict survival times for nonrepresentative subsamples, including participants in the previously discussed work-release program. The results significantly underpredict recidivism for this group (ibid., p. 138). The authors attribute this not to program effects, but rather to ‘work release participants hav[ing] different characteristics than nonparticipants ... our model does not adequately capture the effects of these characteristics on time until recidivism’ (ibid., p. 138). As Schmidt and Witte note, perhaps the safest and most efficient use of the predicted versus actual models is in conjunction with experiments: such models can be used to justify the initiation of costly experimental studies, as well as to indicate the factors that must be controlled. In the event that true- or quasi-experiments are impractical, the predicted versus actual approach provides a relatively low-cost but not altogether reliable alternative. Research refining and systematizing this method is called for. Turning from methodological to substantive issues, what kinds of in-prison rehabilitative programs work, if any? The ‘Nothing Works’ doctrine initiated
412
The Economics of Prisons
8300
in Martinson’s well-known paper (Martinson, 1974, previewing Lipton, Martinson and Wilks, 1975) ushered in an era of pessimism in penology. After reviewing the results of 231 papers (the majority dealing with programs of a therapeutic nature) published between 1945 and 1967, Martinson concluded that there was little evidence that rehabilitation programs work. This sweeping generalization was echoed by the Panel of Research on Rehabilitative Techniques of the National Research Council (US), which restated Martinson’s conclusion: ‘it appears that nothing works or at least that there have not been any consistent and persuasive demonstrations of anything that works’ (Sechrest, White and Brown, 1979, p. 27). This conclusion has not gone unchallenged (for example, Halleck and Witte, 1977; Gendreau and Ross, 1987; Mair, 1991), but ‘Nothing Works’ remains a part of penological lore. One response follows the lead of the second report of the Panel of Research on Rehabilitative Techniques (Martin, Sechrest and Redner, 1981) in questioning whether the strength and degree of implementation of in-prison programs are sufficient for definitive tests. Lattimore and Witte (1985), responding to Englander (1983) (also see Englander, 1985), note that many vocational programs are poorly designed, rather weak in intervention (for example, a training program of short duration), and poorly and incompletely implemented (for example, inmates dropping in and out of programs). Lattimore, Witte and Baker (1990) attempt to evaluate a vocational rehabilitation program for young property offenders in which care is taken to address these difficulties. The program consists of six integrated in-prison sub-programs (ibid., p. 120, Table 1) any or all of which may have been completed by members of the sample. The sample consists of 591 selected North Carolina male inmates aged 18-22 enrolled in the umbrella project sometime between June 1983 and May 1986. The subjects were randomly partitioned by prison officials into an experimental group and a control group. The two groups differed in their exposure to the various parts of the umbrella project and in their completion records for the various component parts of the project. Only 16 percent of the experimental group began all of the program components, that is, the umbrella program was only weakly implemented. Nevertheless, some programmatic effects were still evident: an examination of survival times indicates that the program reduced post-release arrests by about 10 percentage points for releasees who had been out over about 600 days (ibid., p. 128, Fig. 2). Moreover, the survival history of those who completed a vocational program was significantly better than for those who did not, a result the authors could not account for in terms of their sociodemographic and criminality measures. Unfortunately, doubts were recently cast on these results by one of the co-authors of the original paper: ‘unpublished longer-term follow-up results show no significant differences in criminal activities between the experimental and the control groups’ (Witte, 1997, p. 226).
8300
The Economics of Prisons
413
10. Manpower Programs for Former Prison Inmates Perhaps partly in response to the ‘Nothing Works’ dialogue, the attention of economists has largely shifted from in-prison rehabilitation programs to assistance programs for released prisoners. Cook (1975) (also see Hardin, 1975; Marks and Vining, 1986), after reviewing various labor market studies of parolees, as well as his own study utilizing a data set (collected and analyzed by Evans, 1968) consisting of 327 male parolees from Massachusetts penitentiaries in 1959, notes that (1) ‘discrimination is not an important factor in the work experience of parolees’ (Cook, 1975, p. 18); (2) the quality of jobs, and not the quantity, is crucial in determining the employment record of released offenders; (3) success in the job market for released offenders leads to lower recidivism rates; and (4) in-prison therapeutic, educational and job-skills programs have little effect upon post-release success. Even though remedial education and vocational training programs ‘have demonstrated success in providing prisoners and parolees with measurably increased academic and vocational skill’ (ibid., pp. 47-48), they have typically not been successful in reducing recidivism rates. (Witte and Reid, 1980, obtain similarly pessimistic results in examining the labor market performance of a group of ex-inmates not limited to parolees.) The survey by Long and Witte (1981, p. 128) is unequivocal: ‘Evaluations of vocational training and remedial education programs in prison, parole, or probation settings have almost uniformly found that such programs have insignificant effects on both labor market performance and criminality.’ The hypothesis is that the programs have not improved the job-opportunities of offenders, even though they have improved their skill levels. Released offenders either are unable to find the better jobs or, if found, they cannot keep them because of inadequate preparation for the demands of such work. Cook (echoed by Witte and Reid, 1980) concludes that the evidence suggests job search and on-the-job training programs should be given priority. Whether the prospect of improved legitimate job opportunities would act to reduce the initial deterrent effectiveness of punishment remains a concern. Cook notes that increasing the probability of punishment may be an appropriate offset. Such a substitution would not be costless, however, and again points to an analysis stressing the dynamic and general equilibrium modelling of crime. Borus, Hardin and Terry (1976) (also see Hardin, 1975) utilize a quasi-experimental design to evaluate a Michigan job-placement program for selected parolees. The authors find that program participants did not fair better in terms of various indicators of job-market success, and in fact ‘fared worse, on the average ... as to hours employed, gross earnings, and take-home pay’ (Borus, Hardin and Terry, 1976, p. 394). Apparently no attempt was made to directly compare the recidivism experience of program participants with
414
The Economics of Prisons
8300
non-participants. This aspect was addressed in the following study, yielding a similarly pessimistic conclusion. Mallar and Thornton (1978) report on a program (LIFE - ‘Living Insurance for Ex-Offenders’) seeking to establish whether transitional aid programs and/or job-placement assistance for ex-prisoners reduce recidivism for theft crimes (also see Myers, 1983). A non-random sample of 432 high-risk prisoners from Maryland’s state prisons released into the Baltimore area in the early 1970s was randomly partitioned into four treatment groups: one receiving direct financial aid ($60/week for three months); one receiving job-placement assistance (for up to one year); one receiving both; and a control group receiving no assistance of either type. The authors conclude: ‘The provision of financial aid led to a large and statistically significant reduction in theft rearrests, while the provision of job-placement services proved to be singularly ineffective in reducing recidivism’ (Mallar and Thornton, 1978, p. 224). Subjects in the financial aid group were less likely to be employed full time, especially during the first quarter after release, and more likely to be enrolled in school or a training program. The authors speculate that this apparent investment in human capital may widen the differential in recidivism response over time. It also appears that the transitional aid group achieved higher paying jobs, leading the authors to suggest that transitional aid permitted subjects to invest more in job search. Finally, the authors demonstrate the benefit/cost viability of the direct aid program. Broadly similar results with respect to the job-placement component were obtained in an expanded version of the LIFE program (named TARP, ‘Transitional Aid Research Project’; see Rossi, Berk and Lenihan, 1980). This program applied a controlled experimental design to all released inmates (not just parolees) from Georgia and Texas state prisons. The transitional aid component also appeared to be unsuccessful, but the authors attribute this to work disincentive effects not in place for the LIFE program (for additional comment see Long and Witte, 1981, pp. 129-130, and Englander, 1983, pp. 28-29). Again, these studies do not address the question whether the prospect of transitional financial aid would eventually reduce the initial deterrent effectiveness of punishment. The National Supported Work Program (Hollister, Kemper and Maynard, 1984; Couch, 1992) placed subjects in a variety of supportive and subsidized work environments commensurate with their backgrounds. The emphasis was on developing work habits in accordance with a graduated stress concept of job-market preparation. As one author describes it: ‘Stress within the working environment increased gradually during the training period until it simulated the workplace norms of the private sector. At that point, not more than 18 months after entry, individuals who received the services ... had to attempt a transition to unsubsidized employment’ (Couch, 1992, p. 381). Over the period from March 1975 to July 1977, 2,276 ex-offenders, one of four subject groups,
8300
The Economics of Prisons
415
were randomly assigned to either an experimental group or a control group, with regular nine-month follow-ups extending to three years. All subjects had been incarcerated sometime during the six months preceeding enrollment in the program, and the average length of time served was four years. Less than 10 percent of this group exhausted the allowable time in the program. The results indicate no reduction in recidivism among the ex-offender experimental group as a whole, and no measurable labor market effects (Piliavin and Gartner, 1984). An eight year follow-up (Couch, 1992) indicates no improvement in labor market success for disadvantaged youths (the ex-offender group did not receive the long-term follow-up). Other large-scale studies (for example, the Mathematica Policy Research, Inc. study of the Job Corps (Mallar et al., 1982) and the Abt Associates review of the Job Training Partnership Act (JTPA) programs (Orr et al., 1996)) do not identify an ex-inmate subgroup for analysis. As the concluding sections of this chapter attest, the rich research possibilities inherent in large longitudinal data sets are ushering in a new era of empirical research on criminal behavior (see, for example, Tauchen, Witte and Griesinger, 1994) and recidivism. At the same time, the research design of experimental studies will continue to improve (Witte, 1993). Weitekamp and Kerner (1994) sensibly call for an integration of longitudinal and experimental studies. This method would seem to have considerable potential for evaluating specific programs for inmates and ex-inmates. Pending the outcome of these hybrid studies, the conflicting results found in even the limited subsample of the literature discussed above suggests that a magic one-size-fits-all rehabilitation bullet does not exist. Offenders differ in their motivations as well as in their abilities, proclivities and backgrounds. Moreover, ‘success’ itself will only be found by choosing carefully from amongst different outcome measures, and then measured only in small magnitudes. Finally, it bears noting that even if ‘Something Works’, the corresponding implementation may be globally suboptimal either because of high direct program costs, or because of the implicit added incentive for individuals to enter the criminal market.
11. Criminal and Legitimate Labor Markets for Former Prison Inmates Results obtained from specific in-prison rehabilitation programs and manpower programs for released offenders have been weak and inconsistent. This, coupled with the substantial increase in the proportion of the US population incarcerated over the last two decades makes the wide-scale implementation of costly rehabilitation programs unlikely. Consequently, recent economic research focuses on the general effects of incarceration, independent of prison programs, on subsequent criminal and legitimate labor market activities of
416
The Economics of Prisons
8300
released offenders. Various kinds of empirical information and estimation strategies are employed. Grogger (1991) uses panel data on California arrestees to attempt to determine the effect of imprisonment on future criminality as well as to estimate the incapacitative effect of prison. Since estimates of the proportion of all young California males arrested at some point reach as high as one-third, the sample of arrestees offers a more representative picture than data on prison releasees alone (see Witte, 1980 and Myers, 1983). Grogger’s empirical results suggest that imprisonment has a criminogenic effect (‘each additional month spent in prison increases average arrests by about 2 percent’ (Grogger, 1991, p. 304)) which may be attributed to either negative training or negative labor market signalling. Moreover, under the assumption that sanction expectations are formed entirely from one’s own historical involvement with the justice system (that is, ‘specific’ as opposed to ‘general’ deterrence), ‘the criminogenic effect of imprisonment is nearly three times as great as the deterrent effect’ (ibid.). Prison is also found to have an incapacitative effect - each month reduces the average individual’s criminal activity roughly in proportion to the time spent in prison. As Grogger notes (ibid., p. 299), the interpretation of the results depends crucially upon whether arrests are an appropriate measure of criminal activity. In addition, unobserved fixed characteristics could also bias the results. For example, a penchant for violence could be correlated with both longer sentences for any given crime category as well as with greater post-incarceration criminality. The following studies address this type of complication. Freeman (1992) employs the National Longitudinal Survey of Youth and other surveys to estimate the long-run impact of incarceration on future legitimate employment of young US males. After standardizing for observed personal characteristics of individuals in the sample, he finds that incarceration in 1980 had a substantial negative impact on whether one was employed in any given subsequent year (to 1988) and on the total number of subsequent weeks worked. ‘For the entire eight-year period, incarceration in 1980 reduced subsequent work weeks by 27 percent for blacks and 22 percent for all youth’ (ibid., p. 217). Only one-third of the negative employment effect is attributed to the exclusionary impact of current incarceration on currrent employment. Freeman tests whether his results might be due to some unobserved characteristic correlated with both criminality and labor market fitness (such as functional illiteracy) by utilizing data on the pre- and post-incarceration employment experience of individuals. Adapting an omitted variables regression model, Freeman finds that incarceration continues to have a substantial impact on subsequent employment, although the impact is reduced by up to one-half (ibid., p. 225). Freeman cautions that these results do not imply that a random person assigned a criminal record would necessarily have the predicted subsequent employment experience. Rather, the statistics indicate
8300
The Economics of Prisons
417
what happened to those who chose crime. In other words, the data remain consistent with rational decision making by far-sighted individuals facing the risk of incarceration and the potential loss of legitimate income. Freeman’s results may be compared with those of Grogger (1995), who again studies a sample of young male California arrestees. All individuals in the sample were arrested at least once between 1973 and early 1987. Grogger seeks to determine the effects of contact with the criminal justice system on subsequent legitimate labor market outcomes. He obtains a comparison sample of non-offenders by partitioning the sample in accordance with the date of first arrest. The treatment sample consists of young California males first arrested prior to 1985, and the comparison sample consists of those first arrested in 1985 or later. Quarterly data on earnings and employment from 1980 through 1984 are merged with each individual’s criminal justice history. To eliminate the impact of unobserved variables correlated with arrests, Grogger applies the fixed-effects estimator to a distributed lag model. Unobserved correlated factors are found to have a large effect on labour market outcomes, whereas arrests are found to have a relatively modest and short-lived impact on earnings and employment. (‘After six-quarters the effect (of an arrest) is insignificantly different from zero’ (ibid. p. 61).) The impact of incarceration is also noted, although the results here are somewhat unreliable because the relatively long prison sentences may lead to regression results that simply reflect a contemporaneous enforced exclusion from the labor market. The results relating to jail sentences are more reliable, as their duration is typically of one year or less. Jail sentences are found to have an impact on subsequent earnings and employment, but again these are characterized as relatively short-lasting when compared with Freeman’s results. Grogger notes (ibid., p. 70) that this may be due to the differences in sentence lengths for the two sample: long sentences (Freeman’s sample) may have long-lasting effects, whereas short sentences (Grogger’s sample) have relatively short-lasting effects. Insofar as the empirical results do conflict, different rationalizations of criminal activity would be in order. Freeman’s results may be interpreted as indicating a relatively moderate impact of arrests and incarceration on labor market prospects. Studies using empirical measures of actual sentence lengths served would be helpful in determining whether the supply-side argument or the demand-side argument is stronger. Other papers bearing on the impact of incarceration on earnings and employment stress the independent deterrent effect of criminal stigmatization, a byproduct of contact with the criminal justice system. Rasmussen (1996) presents two models of criminal stigmatization. The moral hazard model has employers unwilling to pay the market wage to ex-offenders because of their lower net productivity (contribution to product less thievery from the firm and other destructive behaviors), whereas in the adverse selection model a criminal record signals exogenously lower gross productivity (for example, lower
418
The Economics of Prisons
8300
intelligence). Applied to the economics of prisons, the moral hazard effect reflects the negative training discussed earlier: time spent in prison increases the offender’s productivity as a criminal. Any deterrent effect of stigmatization would be expected to be greater for those with the highest education and greatest job market prospects. Lott (1992b) finds for a sample of US federal larceny and theft offenders (typically involving government property or postal offenses) that ‘a one-month increase in sentence length causes a 5.5 to 32 percent greater reduction in postconviction income’ (ibid., p. 597). Waldfogel (1994a) similarly employs a sample of white-collar criminals to demonstrate that the reduction in job market prospects from imprisonment is due primarily to stigma, and not stalled experience growth or job displacement. Waldfogel cautions that his results may not be generalizable to offenders whose pre-conviction jobs do not involve substantial trust, and whose convictions are for crimes other than fraud and larceny. (For example, Lott (1992a) finds that longer sentences do not affect the post-imprisonment legitimate income of drug offenders.) To the extent that crime becomes more concentrated in an underclass composed of individuals who have little in the way of job market aspirations and opportunities, the deterrent effect of any criminal stigma may become insignificant. As well, the stigma measured by the disapproval of one’s friends and neighbours will probably fall as the proportion of the population incarcerated increases, thus decreasing the deterrent effectiveness of punishment (Freeman, 1996, pp. 32-33). Other papers more relevant to the impact of conviction than incarceration include Lott (1990), Freeman (1986), Grogger (1992), Waldfogel (1994b) and Nagin and Waldfogel (1995).
12. Public Policy Broadly Conceived Is the criminal justice system administering sentence lengths that might be considered efficient? Waldfogel (1993) constructs a static model of optimal sentencing where the planner chooses sentences to minimize the direct social harm from crime and the cost of imposing punishment. Optimal sentences are derived after making strong simplifying assumptions on functional forms and the relationships between variables. The results (corrected to account for an interpretive error noted in Pyle, 1995, p. 13), suggest that actual sentences in the US for 1984 are somewhat shorter than optimal sentences, but nevertheless are closer to the optimum than would be called for by a strictly retributive (proportionate to the harm) sentencing scheme. Alternatively, using relatively weak assumptions one can infer the social values of the harms imposed by crimes as implicit in current sentences. Waldfogel (1993) finds these implicit valuations correspond closely with estimates of actual harms as given by Cohen (1988).
8300
The Economics of Prisons
419
Since Waldfogel (1993) takes the probabilities of punishment as exogenous, his analysis does not reach the question of whether the optimal number of offenders is incarcerated. A more comprehensive analysis is needed to address what is perhaps the most important public policy issue concerning the economics of prisons: Do prisons pay? Piehl and Dilulio (1995) (also see Dilulio and Piehl, 1991) review the literature and present some estimates. The idea is to use self-reports of incarcerated offenders to estimate the amount of crime such offenders would have committed if not incarcerated, and then, after pricing these crimes, to compare the ‘saved’ social costs attributable to incarceration with the direct costs (capital and operating) of incarceration. The self-reports come from surveys constructed to minimize biased and inaccurate reporting. (The earliest reliable surveys were completed by the Rand Corporation (see the discussion in Visher, 1986).) Since the distribution of offender reports are heavily skewed, the result depends upon whether the experience of the median, mean or whichever other offender’s experience is taken as the basis for the estimate. For example, in one recent report (Piehl and Dilulio, 1995, p. 25, Table 3), the benefit-cost ratio for prisons ranges from 64.02 to 0.07, depending upon where in the distribution the sampling is done. Moreover, this method does not impart a social value to retribution, nor does it capture deterrent and replacement effects. It takes as a baseline the unlikely prospect that offenders would simply be released unsupervised if not incarcerated. The omission of replacement effects is particularly troubling since it works in an opposite direction to that of the deterrent, retribution and incapacitation effects. The implication is that the derived benefit-cost ratios are not necessarily a lower bound for whatever part of the distribution is sampled. Limiting the estimates to crime categories with low replacement rates should give more reliable estimates, but identifying these categories is a problem. Whereas incarcerated drug dealers are rapidly replaced on the streets, and intra-familial murderers are not, the situation is not so clear with respect to many other crimes. Moreover, there are undoubtedly differences in prison populations across geographical jurisdictions. The age-distribution of offenders, the crime mix, and so on ... are all affected by numerous variables (legitimate labor market opportunities, the allocation of police resources) not accounted for in the analysis, thus making inferences for jurisdictions other than that from which the sample was obtained, or indeed for the same jurisdiction at a different time, somewhat problematic. Since age markedly affects the proclivity for crime, the criminal career profile should also be taken into account (Blumstein and Cohen, 1987). For example, a sampled offender on the downward slope of the age-criminality curve will report crime figures that, if extrapolated forward, will lead to an upwardly biased estimate of the benefits from incarceration. Finally, all downstream costs related to incarceration are ignored in this type of analysis. If offenders form their expectations of the risk and costs of punishment primarily from their own experiences, then failing to
420
The Economics of Prisons
8300
incarcerate the sampled offender would lower his perception of the riskiness of criminal activity, and lead to increases in the amount of future crime. The training effects (whether positive or negative) of imprisonment and any stigma and job-market effects are also included from considaration. Very few selfreport studies attempt to adjust for all present concerns except deterrence and downstreams effects. His ‘best guess’ point estimate of the incarceration elasticity of aggregate crime is 0.16 (Spelman, 1994, p. 220). That is, a 1 percent increase in the prison population is predicted to reduce the level of crime by about 0.16 percent. An alternative methodology more in keeping with the economic model is presented in Levitt (1996) (also see Marvell and Moody, 1994). Levitt estimates offense supply functions using (a proxy for) prison population as an explanatory variable. If prison populations were exogenous, in principle the coefficient could be used to capture incapacitation, deterrence and replacement effects. But Levitt rightly notes that prison populations depend to an extent upon the level of offenses, so that simultaneity problems intrude (Hersch and Netter, 1984, and Cameron, 1989, attempt to estimate the impact of offenses on sentence lengths and prison populations). Levitt employs instrumental variables reflecting prison overcrowding legislation, and thus attempts to isolate the one-way impact of incarceration on crime rates. The estimation indicates that ‘each additional prisoner leads to a reduction of between five and six reported crimes. Including unreported crimes raises the total to fifteen’ (Levitt, 1996, p. 345). This number is very close to the median numbers obtained from self-report surveys, although only incapacitation effects are accounted for in the latter studies. Levitt demonstrates that his estimates lead to a benefit-cost ratio for the marginal prisoner that exceeds unity, and suggests that the current level of imprisonment (in the US) is ‘roughly efficient’ (ibid., p. 324). Levitt’s paper will undoubtedly excite controversy (see, for example, Donohue and Siegelman, 1998). If the various subsystems of the criminal justice system do not adjust rapidly to exogenous shifts, then lagged offense rates would be expected to have an impact upon the demand for overcrowding litigation. This would call into question a crucial assumption in the model. Levitt presents numbers indicating otherwise (Levitt, 1996, pp. 334-336), and presents econometric tests supporting the overidentifying restrictions (ibid., p. 340). Perhaps an equally important consideration is whether Levitt has faithfully interpreted the model he seeks to implement. For Ehrlich (1973) as for Becker (1968), the supply of offenses function includes offender risk variables. Thus the appropriate imprisonment variable included in the offense supply equations is a measure of the expected cost of punishment, conditional upon conviction. Proxies typically used for this theoretical measure are based upon average sentence lengths received or served, not prison populations per se. While not implausible, the argument that potential offenders form their
8300
The Economics of Prisons
421
sanction expectations on the basis of observations of prison populations requires independent justification. Donohue and Siegelman (1998) employ both the incapacitation and aggregate offense-supply models to calculate cost-benefit ratios from imprisonment in the U.S. The goal is to establish whether a continuation of the huge run-up in the proportion of the population incarcerated over the last quarter century is cost justified. The authors, after reviewing the applicable studies, adopt offense elasticities of approximately 0.15 (also see Wilson, 1994). Attaching cost figures to these estimates suggests that further increases in the proportion incarcerated is unjustified for the US, but recent levels may be justified. These calculations do not take into account the possible criminogenic impact of current incarcerations. If imprisonment increases the criminality of released prisoners, then the US may be incarcerating at excessive rates. Donohue and Siegelman (1998) argue that certain pre-school enrichment programs are a more cost efficient alternative for reducing the level of crime.
13. Additional Topics This chapter has not attempted to canvass all topics that could be included in a survey of the economics of prisons. Notable exclusions are prison industries (Barnes, 1921; Auerbach et al., 1988), industrial relations in prisons (Staudohar, 1976; Wynne, 1978; Peterson, 1981; Zimmer and Jacobs, 1981), litigation of prisoner suits (Brown, 1992), racial disparities in the prison population and in recidivism (Myers, 1980a, 1980b, 1992; Freeman, 1986, 1988; Myers and Sabol, 1988; Cameron, 1989; Dilulio, 1994; Langan, 1994), class-based models of prison use (Andrews, 1993), various alternatives to imprisonment and to standard methods of incarceration (fines, community-based sanctions, electronic monitoring, bootcamps, corporal punishments (Langbein, 1977; Polinsky and Shavell, 1984; Waldfogel, 1995; Benson and Rasmussen, 1995; Avio, 1995; Kan, 1996)) and economic factors in the origins of prison systems (Langbein, 1976; Conley, 1981; Lewis, 1988, 1990; Nicholas, 1990). The economics of prisons has come a long way since Becker (1968) regenerated the interest of economists in crime. Further progress will require developments in both theoretical and empirical spheres, including the specification and estimation of dynamic structural models of criminal behaviour. The many simplifying assumptions of existing models must be relaxed, and the relationships between the various crime categories and between criminal and legitimate labour markets better understood. Studies of countries other than the US are necessary for establishing the generality of the empirical findings. ‘Protracted prospective’ longitudinal data sets (Janson, 1994) must be constructed on representative individuals, with information that
422
The Economics of Prisons
8300
includes sentence lengths actually served and activities undertaken while imprisoned, as well as on the more standard variables. In general, one could argue that the punishment theories developed by economists and within which the economics of prisons is embedded need to pay more attention to the stylized facts uncovered by longitudinal studies: (i) most crimes are committed by youths; (ii) only a small number of these youths persist in criminal activity as they age; but (iii) these same people are responsible for the bulk of serious crimes (for discussion see Farrington, Ohlin and Wilson, 1986; Moffitt, 1994). The theoretical models developed in economics do not appear to satisfactorily address these facts. One policy implication is that more attention is paid to influencing the lifetime profile of established criminals than attending to the prevention of such careers in the first place. Similarly, the underlying legal and social institutions providing the background environment for criminal activity require careful examination (Witte, 1993). Akerlof and Yellen (1994) provide an illustrative model that points in the right direction (also see Becker, 1996), a model which implicates ‘community policing’ (Campbell, 1994). Finally, given their comparative advantage, economists have quite naturally confined themselves to the impact of the law and its administration on the incentives implicit in fixed preferences, that is, to short-run ‘carrot and stick’ approaches to modifying criminal behavior. Perhaps a more complete picture of human nature than that depicted in the economic model of crime is warranted. It may now be time to explore the longrun preference-shaping impact of the law (Dau-Schmidt, 1990; Friedman, 1993; Robinson, 1994) and education (Witte, 1996, 1997; Usher, 1997), along with the role of habituation in that process (Wilson, 1994; Dilulio, 1996). We know little about how and why a shared moral order is developed and maintained (Robinson, 1994). This change in perspective, calling as it does for an examination of the relationship between socialization and individuation, suggests a return to a relatively neglected part of the research program laid out in Adam Smith ([1791] 1976). Analysis of the social institutions that inculcate self-command, and which otherwise function as civilizing forces in our society (Muller, 1993; Wilson, 1993), should be part and parcel of the research strategy adopted by social scientists to help understand and control crime.
Bibliography on the Economics of Prisons (8300) Adler, Jacob (1991), The Urgings of Conscience: A Theory of Punishment, Philadelphia, PA, Temple University Press. Akerlof, George A. and Yellen, Janet L. (1994), ‘Gang Behavior, Law Enforcement, and Community Values’, in Aaron, Henry J., Mann, Thomas E. and Taylor, Timothy (eds), Values and Public Policy, Washington, DC, The Brookings Institution, 173-209.
8300
The Economics of Prisons
423
Andrews, Marcellus (1993), ‘Schools, Jails and the Dynamics of an Educational Underclass: Some Dreadful Social Arithmetic’, 22 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 121-132. Auerbach, Barbara J., Sexton, George E., Farrow, Franklin C. and Lawson, Robert H. (1988), Work in American Prisons: the Private Sector Gets Involved, Washington, DC, U.S. Department of Justice, National Institute of Justice, Office of Communication and Research Utilization (prepared by Criminal Justice Associates under subcontract from Abt Associates, Inc.). Avio, Kenneth L. (1973), ‘An Economic Analysis of Criminal Corrections: The Canadian Case’, 6 Canadian Journal of Economics, 164-178. Avio, Kenneth L. (1975), ‘Recidivism in the Economic Model of Crime’, 13 Economic Inquiry, 450-456. Avio, Kenneth L. (1991), ‘On Private Prisons: An Economic Analysis of the Model Contract and Model Statute for Private Incarceration’, 17 New England Journal on Criminal and Civil Confinement, 265-300. Avio, Kenneth L. (1993a), ‘Remuneration Regimes for Private Prisons’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 35-45. Avio, Kenneth L. (1993b), ‘Economic, Retributive and Contractarian Conceptions of Punishment’, 12 Law and Philosophy, 249-286. Avio, Kenneth L. (1995), ‘Economic, Contractarian and Discourse Arguments against Efficient Torture’, in Peczenik, Aleksander and Karlsson, Mikael M. (eds), 58 Archives on Rights and Social Philosophy, ‘Law, Justice and the State: I’, Stuttgart, Franz Steiner Verlag, 265-272. Barnes, Harry Elmer (1921), ‘The Economics of American Penology as Illustrated by the Experience of the State of Pennsylvania’, 8 Journal of Political Economy, 617-642. Barnett, Randy E. (1977), ‘Restitution: a New Paradigm of Criminal Justice’, 87 Ethics, 279-301. Barnett, Randy E. (1998), The Structure of Liberty: Justice and the Rule of Law, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Becker, Gary S. (1968), ‘Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach’, 76 Journal of Political Economy, 169-217. Becker, Gary S. (1996), ‘Norms and the Formation of Preferences’, in Becker, Gary S. (ed), Accounting for Tastes, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 225-230. Benson, Bruce L (1990), The Enterprise of Law: Justice Without the State, San Francisco, Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy. Benson, Bruce L. (1994a), ‘Are Public Goods Really Common Pools? Considerations of the Evolution of Policing and Highways in England’, 32 Economic Inquiry, 249-271. Benson, Bruce L. (1994b), ‘Third Thoughts on Contracting Out’, 11 Journal of Libertarian Studies, 44-78. Benson, Bruce L. (1996), ‘Restitution in Theory and in Practice’, 13 Journal of Libertarian Studies, 44-78. Benson, Bruce L. and Rasmussen, David W. (1995), ‘Crime and Punishment’, in Denslow, David A., Scoggins, J.F. and Shermyen, Anne (eds), The Economy of Florida, Gainesville, FL, Bureau of Economic and Business Research, 99-116. Benson, Bruce L. and Wollan, Laurin A., Jr (1989), ‘Prison Overcrowding and Judicial Incentives’, 3 Madison Paper Series, 1-22.
424
The Economics of Prisons
8300
Block, Michael K. and Lind, Robert C. (1975), ‘An Economic Analysis of Crimes Punishable by Imprisonment’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 479-492. Block, Michael K. and Ulen, Thomas S. (1979), ‘Cost Functions for Correctional Institutions’, in Gray, Charles M. (ed.), The Costs of Crime, Beverly Hills, CA, Sage Publications, 187-209. Blumstein, Alfred (1995), ‘Prisons’, in Wilson, James Q. and Petersilia, Joan (eds), Crime, San Francisco, ICS Press, 387-419. Blumstein, Alfred and Cohen, Jacqueline (1987), ‘Characterizing Criminal Careers’,237 Science, 985991. Blumstein, Alfred and Larson, Richard (1969), ‘Models of a Total Criminal Justice System’, 17 Operations Research, 199-232. Borus, Michael E., Hardin, Einar and Terry, Patterson A. (1976), ‘Job-Placement Services for Ex-Offenders: An Evaluation of the Michigan Comprehensive Offender Manpower Program (COMP) Job-Placement Efforts’, 11 Journal of Human Resources, 391-401. Bowman, Gary W., Hakim, Simon and Seidenstat, Paul (eds) (1992), Privatizing the United States Justice System: Police, Adjudication and Corrections Services from the Private Sector, Jefferson, NC, Transaction Publishers. Bowman, Gary W., Hakim, Simon and Seidenstat, Paul (eds) (1993), Privitazing Correctional Institutions, New Brunswick, NJ, Transaction Publishers. Brakel, Samuel J. (1988), ‘Privatization’ in Corrections: Radical Prison Chic or Mainstream Americana?’, 14 New England Journal on Criminal and Civil Confinement, 1-39. Brown, Jennifer G. (1992), ‘Posner, Prisoners, and Pragmatism’, 66 Tulane Law Review, 1117-1178. Burnovski, Moshe and Safra, Zvi (1994), ‘Deterrence Effects of Sequential Punishment Policies: Should Repeat Offenders be More Severely Punished?’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 341-350. Cameron, Samuel (1989), ‘Determinants of the Prison Population: An Empirical Analysis’, 16(8) International Journal of Social Economics, 17-25. Campbell, John (1994), ‘Policing Crime’, 4 Federal Reserve Bank of Boston Regional Review, 6-11. Carr-Hill, G.A. and Carr-Hill, R.A. (1972), ‘Reconviction as a Process’, 12 British Journal of Criminology, 35-43. Cohen, Mark (1988), ‘Pain, Suffering and Jury Awards: A Study of the Cost of Crime to Victims’, 22 Law and Society Review, 537-556. Conley, John A. (1981), ‘Revising Conceptions about the Origin of Prisons: The Importance of Economic Considerations’, 62 Social Science Quarterly, 247-258. Cook, Philip J. (1975), ‘The Correctional Carrot: Better Jobs for Parolees’, 1 Policy-Analysis, 11-54. Cook, Philip J. (1977), ‘Punishment and Crime: A Critique of Current Findings Concerning the Preventative Effects of Punishment’, 41(1) Law and Contemporary Problems, 164-209. Couch, Kenneth A. (1992), ‘New Evidence on the Long-Term Effects on Employment Training Programs’, 10 Journal of Labor Economics, 380-388. Cragg, Wesley (1992), The Practice of Punishment: Towards a Theory of Restorative Justice, London, Routledge & Kegan Paul. Dau-Schmidt, Kenneth G. (1990), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Criminal Law as a Preference Shaping Policy’, 40 Duke Law Journal, 1-38.
8300
The Economics of Prisons
425
Davis, Michael (1988), ‘Time and Punishment: An Intertemporal Model of Crime’, 96 Journal of Political Economy, 383-390. Dilulio, John J., Jr (1988), ‘What’s Wrong with Private Prisons?’, 92 Public Interest, 66-83. Dilulio, John J., Jr (1990), ‘The Duty to Govern: A Critical Perspective on the Private Management of Prisons and Jails’, in McDonald, Douglas C. (ed), Private Prisons and the Public Interest, New Brunswick, Rutgers University Press. Dilulio, John J., Jr (1994), ‘The Question of Black Crime’, 117 The Public Interest, 3-32. Dilulio, John J., Jr (1996), ‘Help Wanted: Economists, Crime and Public Policy’, 10 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 3-24. Dilulio, John J., Jr and Piehl, Anne Morrison (1991), ‘Does Prison Pay?’, 9 Brookings Review, 28-35. Donohue, John J., III and Siegelman, Peter (1998), ‘Allocating Resources Among Prisons and Social Programs in the Battle Against Crime’, 27 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-43. Duff, R.A. (1986), Trials and Punishment, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Duff, R.A. (1996), ‘Penal Communications: Recent Work in the Philosophy of Punishment’, 20 Crime and Justice: A Review of Research, 1-97. Easterbrook, Frank H. (1983), ‘Criminal Procedure as a Market System’, 12 Journal of Legal Studies, 289-332. Edwards, Glyn (1996), ‘Public Crime, Private Punishment: Prison Privatization in Queensland’, 23 International Journal of Social Economics, 391-408. Ehrlich, Isaac (1973), ‘Participation in Illegitimate Activities: A Theoretical and Empirical Investigation’, 81 Journal of Political Economy, 521-565. Ehrlich, Isaac (1981), ‘On the Usefulness of Controlling Individuals: An Economic Analysis of Rehabilitation, Incapacitation and Deterrence’, 71 American Economic Review, 307-332. Ehrlich, Isaac (1982), ‘The Optimum Enforcement of Laws and the Concept of Justice: A Positive Analysis’, 2 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-27. Englander, Frederick (1983), ‘Helping Ex-offenders enter the Labor Market’, 106 Monthly Labor Review, 25-30. Englander, Frederick (1985), ‘Reply’, 108A Monthly Labor Review, 49-50. Evans, Robert, Jr (1968), ‘The Labor Market and Parole Success’, 3 Journal of Human Resources, 201-212. Farrington, David P., Ohlin, Lloyd E. and Wilson, James Q. (1986), Understanding and Controlling Crime: Toward a New Research Strategy, New York, Springer-Verlag. Fleisher, Mark S. (1989), Warehousing Violence, Newbury Park, CA, Sage Publications. Fleisher, Mark S. (1995), Beggars and Thieves, Madison, WI, University of Wisconsin Press. Flinn, Christopher (1986), ‘Dynamic Models of Criminal Careers’, in Blumstein, Alfred, Cohen, Jacqueline, Roth, Jeffrey A. and Visher, Christy A. (eds), Criminal Careers and “Career Criminals’, Vol. II, Washington, DC, National Academy Press, 356-379. Freeman, Richard B. (1983), ‘Crime and Unemployment’, in Wilson, James Q. (ed), Crime and Public Policy, San Francisco, Institute for Contemporary Studies Press, 89-106. Freeman, Richard B. (1986), ‘Who Escapes? The Relation Between Churchgoing and Other Background Factors to the Socioeconomic Performance of Black Male Youths from Inner-City Tracts’, in Freeman, Richard B. and Holzer, Harry J. (eds), The Black Youth Employment Crisis, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 353-376.
426
The Economics of Prisons
8300
Freeman, Richard B. (1988), ‘The Relation of Criminal Activity to Black Youth Employment’, in Simms, Margaret C. and Myers, Samuel L., Jr (eds), The Economics of Race and Crime, New Brunswick, Transaction Books, 99-107. Freeman, Richard B. (1992), ‘Crime and the Employment of Disadvantaged Youths’, in Peterson, George E. and Vronman, Wayne (eds), Urban Labor Markets and Job Opportunity, Washington, DC, Urban Institute Press, 201-237. Freeman, Richard B. (1995), ‘Crime and the Job Market’, in Wilson, James Q. and Petersilia, Joan (eds), Crime, San Francisco, CA, ICS Press. Freeman, Richard B. (1996), ‘Why Do So Many Young American Men Commit Crimes and What Might We Do About It?’, 10 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 25-42. Friedman, Lawrence M. (1993), Crime and Punishment in American History, New York, Basic Books. Funke, G.S. (1985), ‘The Economics of Prison Crowding’, 478 Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 86-99. Ganley, J.A. and Cubbin, J.S. (1992), Public Sector Efficiency Measurement: Applications of Data Development Analysis, Amsterdam, North-Holland. Garoupa, Nuno (1996), Prison, Parole and the Criminal Justice Act 1991, Manuscript, University of York. Garoupo, Nuno (1997), ‘The Theory of Optimal Law Enforcement’, 11 Journal of Economic Surveys, 267-295. Gendreau, Paul and Ross, Robert R. (1987), ‘Revivification of Rehabilitation: Evidence from the 1980s’, 4 Justice Quarterly, 349-407. Gentry, James Theodore (1986), ‘The Panopticon Revisited: The Problem of Monitoring Private Prisons’, 96 Yale Law Journal, 353-375. Giertz, J. Fred and Nardulli, Peter F. (1985), ‘Prison Overcrowding’, 46(1) Public Choice, 71-78. Gill, Richard T. (1994), ‘The Importance of Deterrence’, 117 Public Interest, 51-56. Gillespie, Robert F. (1983), ‘Allocating Prison Space: An Economic Approach Incorporating Efficiency and Equity’, 40 Illinois Business Review, 3-11. Greenwood, Peter and Turner, Susan (1987), Selective Incapacitation Revisited, Santa Monica, Rand Corporation. Grizzle, Gloria A. and Witte, Ann D. (1980), ‘Criminal Justice Evaluation Techniques: Methods Other Than Random Assignment’, in Kleenin, Malcolm W. and Teilmann, Katherine S. (eds), Handbook of Criminal Justice Evaluation, Beverly Hills, CA, Sage Publications, 259-302. Grogger, Jeffrey (1991), ‘Certainty vs. Severity of Punishment’, 29 Economic Inquiry, 279-309. Grogger, Jeffrey (1992), ‘Arrests, Persistent Youth Joblesness, and Black/White Employment Differentials’, 74 Review of Economics and Statistics, 100-106. Grogger, Jeffrey (1995), ‘The Effect of Arrests on the Employment and Earning of Young Men’, 110 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 51-71. Grogger, Jeffrey (1997), ‘Incarceration-Related Costs of Early Childbearing’, in Maynard, Rebecca A. (ed), Kids Having Kids: Economic Costs and Social Consequences of Teen Pregnancy, Washington, DC, The Urban Institute Press. Halleck, Seymour L. and Witte, Ann D. (1977), ‘Is Rehabilitation Dead?’, 23 Crime and Delinquency, 372-382.
8300
The Economics of Prisons
427
Hardin, Einar (1975), ‘Human Capital and the Labor Market Success of New Parolees’, in, 1975 Proceedings of the Business and Economics Section, American Statistical Association, 330-335. Hatry, Harry P. (Principal investigator) (1989), ‘Comparison of Privately and Publicly Operated Corrections Facilities in Kentucky and Massachusetts’, prepared by The Urban Institute under grant from the Office of National Institute of Justice, US Department of Justice, Washington, DC. Herrnstein, Richard J. (1983), ‘Some Criminogenic Traits in Offenders’, in Wilson, James Q. (ed), Crime and Public Policy, San Francisco, Institute for Contemporary Studies Press, 31-49. Hersch, Philip L. and Netter, Jeffrey M. (1984), ‘The Effects of Crime Rates on Time Served in Prison: An Empirical Analysis’, 39 Public Finance, 314-320. Hollister, Robinson G., Kemper, Peter and Maynard, Rebecca A. (1984), The National Supported Work Demonstration, Madison, WI, University of Wisconsin Press. Howard, Michael (1996), ‘In Defence of Prisons’, June 22nd The Economist, 56-57. Janson, Carl-Gunner (1994), ‘A Case for a Longitudinal Study’, in Weitekamp, Elmar G. and Kerner, Hans-Jürgen (eds), Cross-National Longitudinal Research on Human Development and Criminal Behavior, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 409-422. Kan, Steven S. (1996), ‘Corporal Punishments and Optimal Incapacitation’, 15 Journal of Legal Studies, 121-130. Kaplow, Louis (1990), ‘A Note on the Optimal Use of Nonmonetary Sanctions’, 42 Journal of Public Economics, 245-247. Kim, Il Joong, et al. (1993), ‘An Economic Analysis of Recidivism among Drug Offenders’, 60 Southern Economic Journal, 169-183. Kritzer, Herbert M. (1981-1982), ‘Problems in Estimating the Optimal-Costs Prison Size: A Comment’, 16 Law and Society Review, 139-142. Langan, Patrick A. (1994), ‘No Racism in the Justice System’, 117 Public Interest, 48-51. Langbein, John H. (1976), ‘The Historical Origins of the Sanction of Imprisonment for Serious Crime’, 5 Journal of Legal Studies, 35-60. Langbein, John H. (1977), Torture and the Law of Proof: Europe and England in the Ancient Regime, Chicago, IL, University of Chicago Press. Lattimore, Pamela K. and Witte, Ann D. (1985), ‘Programs to aid Ex-offenders: We don’t know “Nothing Works”’, 108A Monthly Labor Review, 46-50. Lattimore, Pamela K., Witte, Ann D. and Baker, Joanna R. (1990), ‘Experimental Assessment of the Effect of Vocational Training on Youthful Property Offenders’, 14 Evaluation Review, 115-133. Lee, Tahirih V. and Searle-White, Joshua (1991), ‘Prisoner’s Dilemma Meets Glasnost: A Comparative Advantage Solution to the United States Prison Crisis’, 24 Cornell International Law Journal, 25-56. Leung, Siu Fai (1995), ‘Dynamic Deterrence Theory’, 62 Economica, 65-87. Levitt, Steven D. (1996), ‘The Effect of Prison Population Size on Crime Rates: Evidence From Prison Overcrowding Litigation’, 107 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 319-351. Levitt, Steven D. (1997), ‘Incentive Compatibility Constraints as an Explaination for the Use of Prison Sentences Instead of Fines’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 179-192. Lewis, Donald E. (1979), ‘The Optimal Parole Period’, 2 Economics Letters, 381-386.
428
The Economics of Prisons
8300
Lewis, Donald E. (1983), ‘Economic Aspects of the Parole Decision’, 22 Australian Economic Papers, 259-279. Lewis, Donald E. (1986), ‘The General Deterrent Effect of Longer Sentences’, 26 British Journal of Criminology, 47-62. Lewis, Frank D. (1988), ‘The Cost of Convict Transportation from Britain to Australia, 1796-1810', 41 Economic History Review, Second Series, 507-524. Lewis, Frank D. (1990), ‘Australia: An Economical Prison? A Reply’, 43 Economic History Review, Second Series, 477-482. Lipton, Douglas W., Martinson, Robert and Wilks, Judith (1975), The Effectiveness of Correctional Treatment: A Survey of Treatment Evaluation Studies, New York, Praeger Publishers. Logan, Charles H. (1987), ‘The Propriety of Proprietary Prisons’, 51 Feceral Probation, 35-40. Long, Sharon K. and Witte, Ann D. (1981), ‘Current Economic Trends: Implications for Crime and Criminal Justice’, in Wright, Kevin N. (ed), Crime and Criminal Justice in a Declining Economy, Cambridge, MA, Oelgeschlager, Gunn and Hain, 69-143. Lott, John R., Jr (1990), ‘The Effect of Conviction on the Legitimate Income of Criminals’, 34 Economic Letters, 381-385. Lott, John R., Jr (1992a), ‘An Attempt at Measuring the Total Monetary Penalty from Drug Convictions: The Importance of an Individual’s Reputation’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 159187. Lott, John R., Jr (1992b), ‘Do We Punish High Income Criminals too Heavy?’, 30 Economic Inquiry, 583-608. Mair, George (1991), ‘What Works - Nothing or Everything? Measuring the Effectiveness of Sentences’, 30 Home Office Research Bulletin, 3-8. Mallar, Charles D., Kerachsky, Stuart, Thornton, Craig and Long, David (1982), Evaluation of the Economic Impact of the Job Corps Program: Third Follow-up Report, Princeton, NJ, Mathematica Policy Research, Inc. (Final Report). Mallar, Charles D. and Thornton, Craig V.D. (1978), ‘Transitional Aid for Released Prisoners: Evidence from the LIFE Experiment’, 13 Journal of Human Resources, 208-236. Marks, Denton and Vining, Aidan R. (1986), ‘Prison Labor Markets: The Supply Issue’, 19(1) Policy Sciences, 83-111. Martin, Susan E., Sechrest, Lee B. and Redner, Robin (eds) (1981), New Directions in the Rehabilitation of Criminal Offenders, National Research Council, Washington, DC, National Academy Press. Martinson, Robert (1974), ‘’What Works’ - Questions and Answers about Prison Reform’, 25 Public Interest, 22-54. Marvel, Thomas and Moody, Carlisle (1994), ‘Prison Population Growth and Crime Reduction’, 10 Journal of Quantitative Criminology, 109-140. McDonald, Douglas C. (1990), ‘The Cost of operating Public and Private Correctional Facilities’ in McDonald, Douglas C. (ed), Private Prisons and the Public Interest, New Brunswick, NJ, Rutgers University Press. McGuire, William J. and Witte, Ann D. (1978), ‘An Estimate of an Average Cost Curve for Large Scale Correctional Institutions’, Working Paper, Department of Economics, University of North Carolina.
8300
The Economics of Prisons
429
Melossi, Dario (1987), ‘Political Business Cycles and Imprisonment Rates in Italy: Report on a Work in Progress’, 16(1-2) Review of Black Political Economy, 211-218. Miceli, Thomas J. (1991), ‘Optimal Criminal Procedure: Fairness and Deterrence’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-10. Miceli, Thomas J. (1994), ‘Prison and Parole: Minimizing the Cost of Non-monetary Sanctions as Deterrents’, 16 Research in Law and Economics, 197-211. Moffitt, Terrie E. (1994), ‘Natural Histories of Delinquency’, in Weitekamp, Elmar G. and Kerner, Hans-Jürgen (eds), Cross-National Longitudinal Research on Human Development and Criminal Behavior, Dordrecht, Kluwer, 3-61. Morris, Norval (1974), The Future of Imprisonment, Chicago, IL, University of Chicago Press, 144 ff. Moyle, Paul (ed) (1994), Private Prisons and Police:Recent Australian Trends, Leichhardt, NSW, Pluto Press. Muller, Jerry Z. (1993), Adam Smith in his Time and Ours: Resigning the Decent Society, New York, The Free Press. Myers, Samuel L., Jr (1980a), ‘The Rehabilitation Effect of Punishment’, 18 Economic Inquiry, 353-366. Myers, Samuel L., Jr (1980b), ‘Black-White Differentials in Crime Rates’, 10 Review of Black Political Economy, 133-152. Myers, Samuel L., Jr (1983), ‘Estimating the Economic Model of Crime: Employment versus Punishment Effects’, 94 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 157-166. Myers, Samuel L., Jr (1992), ‘Crime, Entrepreneurship, and Labor Force Withdrawal’, 10 Contemporal Policy Issues, 84-97. Myers, Samuel L., Jr and Sabol, William J. (1988), ‘Unemployment and Racial Differences in Imprisonment’, in Simms, Margaret C. and Myers, Samuel L., Jr (eds), The Economics of Race and Crime, New Brunswick, NJ, Transactions Books, 189-209. Nagin, Daniel and Waldfogel, Joel (1995), ‘The Effects of Criminality and Conviction on the Labor Market Status of Young British Offenders’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 109126. Nardulli, Peter F. (1984), ‘The Misalignment of Penal Responsibilities and State Prison Crises: Costs, Consequences, and Corrective Actions’, 17 University of Illinois Law Review, 365-387. Nash, John F. (1991), ‘To Make the Punishment Fit the Crime: The Theory and Statistical Estimation of a Multi-Period Optimal Deterrence Model’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 101-110. Nicholas, Stephen (1990), ‘Australia: An Economical Prison? Comments’, 43(3) Economic History Review, Second Series, 470-476. Niskanen, William A. (1971), Bureaucracy and Representative Government, Chicago, Aldine-Atherton. Orr, Larry R., Bloom, Howard S., Bell, Stephen H., Doolittle, Fred, Lin, Winston and Cave, George (1996), Does Training for the Disadvantaged Work? Evidence from the National JTPA Study, An Abt Associates Study, Washington, DC, Urban Institute Press. Parker, Jeffrey S. (1989), ‘Criminal Sentencing Policy for Organizations: The Unifying Approach of Optimal Penalties’, 26 American Criminal Law Review, 513-604. Parker, Jeffrey S. and Block, Michael K. (1989), ‘The Sentencing Commission, P.M. (Post-Mistretta). Sunshine or Sunset?’, 27 American Criminal Law Review, 289-329.
430
The Economics of Prisons
8300
Pastor, Santos (1994), ‘La Exigibilidad de las Normas y la Resolución de Conflictos (Law Enforcement and Dispute Resolution)’, 3 Iuris: Quaderns de Política Jurídica, 155-174. Peterson, Andrew A. (1981), ‘Deterring Strikes by Public Employees: New York’s Two for One Salary Penalty and the 1979 Prison Guard Strike’, 34(4) Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 545-562. Piehl, Anne Morrison and Dilulio, John J., Jr (1995), ‘Does Prison Pay? Revisited’, 13 Brookings Review, 21-25. Piliavin, Irving and Gartner, Rosemary (1984), ‘The Impacts of Supported Work on Ex-offenders’, in Hollister, Robinson G. Jr, Kemper, Peter and Maynard, Rebecca A. (eds), The National Supported Work Demonstration, Madison, WI, University of Wisconsin Press. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1991), ‘A Model of Optimal Fines for Repeat Offenders’, 46 Journal of Public Economics, 491 ff. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1984), ‘The Optimal Use of Fines and Imprisonment’, 24 Journal of Public Economics, 89-99. Pyle, D.J. (1995), ‘The Economic Approach to Crime and Punishment’, 6 Journal of Interdisciplinary Economics, 1-22. Rasmussen, David W. and Benson, Bruce L. (eds) (1994), The Economic Anatomy of a Drug War: Criminal Justice in the Commons, Lanham, MD, Rowman and Littlefield. Rasmussen, Eric (1996), ‘Stigma and Self-Fulfilling Expectations of Criminality’, 39 Journal of Law and Economics, 519-543. Reiss, Albert J., Jr and Roth, Jeffrey A. (eds) (1993), Understanding and Preventing Violence, V. 1-4, Panel on the Understanding and Control of Violent Behavior, National Research Council, Washington, DC, National Academy Press. Robbins, Ira R. (1989), ‘The Legal Dimensions of Private Incarceration’, 38 American University Law Review, 531-854. Robinson, Paul H. (1994), ‘A Failure of Moral Courage’, 117 Public Interest, 40-48. Roper, Brian A. (1986), ‘Market Forces, Privatisation and Prisons: A Polar Case for Government Policy’, 13 International Journal of Social Economics, 77-92. Rossi, Peter H., Berk, Richard A. and Lenihan, Kenneth J. (1980), Money, Work, and Crime: Experimental Evidence, New York, Academic Press. Rubenstein, Ariel (1980), ‘On an Anomaly of the Deterrent Effect of Punishment’, 6 Economics Letters, 89-94. Schmidt, Peter and Witte, Ann D. (1979), ‘Models of Recidivism and an Illustration of Their Use in Evaluating Correctional Programs’, in Sechrest, Lee, White, Susan D. and Brown, Elizabeth D. (eds), The Rehabilitation of Criminal Offenders: Problems and Prospects, Washington, DC, National Academy of Sciences, 210-224. Schmidt, Peter and Witte, Ann D. (1980), ‘Evaluating Correctional Programs: Models of Criminal Recidivism and an Illustration of their Use’, 4 Evaluation Review, 585-600. Schmidt, Peter and Witte, Ann D. (1984), An Economic Analysis of Crime and Justice: Theory, Methods, and Applications, New York, Academic Press, 416 ff. Schmidt, Peter and Witte, Ann D. (1988), Predicting Criminal Recidivism Using Survival Models, New York, Springer-Verlag. Schmidt, Peter and Witte, Ann D. (1989), ‘Predicting Criminal Recidivism Using “Split Population” Survival Time Models’, 40 Journal of Econometrics, 141-159.
8300
The Economics of Prisons
431
Sechrest, Lee, White, Susan D. and Brown, Elizabeth D. (eds) (1979), The Rehabilitation of Criminal Offenders: Problems and Prospects, Washington, DC, National Academy of Sciences. Sellers, Martin P. (1993), The History and Politics of Private Prisons: A Comparative Analysis, Rutherford, NJ, Fairleigh Dickinson University Press. Shavell, Steven (1985), ‘Criminal Law and the Optimal Use of Nonmonetary Sanctions as a Deterrent’, 85 Columbia Law Review, 1232-1262. Shavell, Steven (1987a), ‘A Model of Optimal Incapacitation’, 77 American Economic Review, 107-110. Shavell, Steven (1987b), ‘The Optimal Use of Nonmonetary Sanctions as a Deterrent’, 77 American Economic Review, 584-592. Shoup, Carl S. (1964), ‘Standards for Distributing a Free Govermental Service: Crime Prevention’, 19 Public Finance, 383-392. Sichor, David (1995), Punishment for Profit: Private Prisons/Public Concerns, Thousand Oaks, CA, Sage Publications. Sickles, Robin C., Schmidt, Peter and Witte, Ann D. (1979), ‘An Application of the Simultaneous Tobit Model: A Study of the Determinants of Criminal Recidivism’, 31 Journal of Economics and Business, 166-171. Smith, Adam ([1791] 1976), ‘The Theory of Moral Sentiments’, in D.D. Raphael and A.L. Macfie (eds), Volume I of The Glasgow Edition of the Works and Correspondence of Adam Smith, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Spelman, William (1994), Criminal Incapacitation, New York, Plenum Press. Staudohar, Paul D. (1976), ‘Prison Guard Labor Relations in Ohio’, 15(2) Industrial Relations, 177-190. Stigler, George J. (1970), ‘The Optimum Enforcement of Law’, 78 Journal of Political Economy, 526-536. Tabasz, Thomas F. (1974), ‘Penology, Economics, and the Public: Toward an Agreement’, 5 Policy Sciences, 47-55. Tabasz, Thomas F. (1975), Toward an Economics of Prisons, Lexington, KY, Heath. Tauchen, Helen, Witte, Ann D. and Griesinger, Harriet (1994), ‘Criminal Deterrence: Revisiting the Issue With a Birth Cohort’, 76 Review of Economics and Statistics, 399-412. Thomas, Charles W. (1996), Letter to the Subcommittee on Crime, Committee on the Judiciary, House of Representatives, Washington, DC. Thomas, Charles W. and Logan, Charles, H. (1993), ‘The Development, Present Status, and Future Potential of Correctional Privatization in America’, in Bowman, Gary W., Hakim, Simon and Seidenstat, Paul (eds), Privatizing Correctional Institutions, New Brunswick, Transaction Publishers, 213-240. Thurman, Quint (1988), ‘Taxpayer Noncompliance and Attribution Theory: An Experimental Vignette Approach’, 43(1) Public Finance, 147-156. Thurow, L. (1970), ‘Equity vs. Efficiency in Law Enforcement’, 18 Public Policy, 451-459. Trumball, William N. and Witte, Ann D. (1981-82a), ‘Determinants of the Costs of Operating Large-Scale Prisons with Implications for the Cost of Correctional Standards’, 16 Law and Society Review, 115-146. Trumball, William N. and Witte, Ann D. (1981-82b), ‘Problems in Estimating the Optimal-Cost Prison Size: A Reply’, 16 Law and Society Review, 143-146.
432
The Economics of Prisons
8300
United States Government Accounting Office (USGAO) (1991), Private Prisons: Cost Savings and BOP’s Statutory Authority Need to be Resolved, Report to the Subcommittee on Crime, Committee on the Judiciary, House of Representatives, Letter Report, GAO/GGD-91-21. United States Government Accounting Office (USGAO) (1996), Private and Public Prisons: Studies Comparing Operational Costs and/or Quality of Service, Report to the Subcommittee on Crime, Committee on the Judiciary, House of Representatives, Letter Report, GAO/GGD-96-158. Usher, Dan (1997), ‘Education as a Deterrent to Crime’, 30 Canadian Journal of Economics, 367384. Viscusi, W. Kip (1986), ‘The Risks and Rewards of Criminal Activity: A Comprehensive Test of Criminal Deterrence’, 4 Journal of Labor Economics, 317-340. Visher, Christy A. (1986), ‘The Rand Inmate Survey: A Reanalysis’, in Blumstein, Alfred, Cohen, Jacqueline and Roth, Jeffrey A. (eds), Career Criminals and ‘Criminal Careers’, Vol. II, Washington, DC, National Academy Press, 161-211. Visher, Christy A., Lattimore, Pamela K. and Linster, Richard L. (1991), ‘Predicting the Recidivism of Serious Youthful Offenders Using Survival Models’, 29 Criminology, 329-366. Waldfogel, Joel (1993), ‘Criminal Sentences as Exogenous Taxes: Are they “Just” or “Efficient”?’ 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 139-151. Waldfogel, Joel (1994a), ‘The Effect of Criminal Conviction on Income and the Trust “Reposed in the Workmen”’, 29(1) Journal of Human Resources, 162-181. Waldfogel, Joel (1994b), ‘Does Conviction Have a Persistent Effect on Income and Employment?’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 103-119. Waldfogel, Joel (1995), ‘Are Fines and Prison Terms Used Efficiently? Evidence on Federal Fraud Offenders’, 38 Journal of Law and Economics, 107-139. Weitekamp, Elmar G.M. and Kerner, Hans-Jürgen (1994), Cross-National Longitudinal Research on Human Development and Criminal Behavior, Dordrecht, Kluwer. Werden, Gregory J. and Simon, Marilyn J. (1987), ‘Why Price Fixers should go to Prison’, 32(4) Antitrust Bulletin, 917-937. Wilde, Louis L. (1992), ‘Criminal Choice, Nonmonetary Sanctions, and Marginal Deterrence: A Normative Analysis’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 333-344. Williamson, Oliver E. (1964), The Economics of Discretionary Behavior: Managerial Objectives in a Theory of the Firm, Englewood Cliffs, NJ, Prentice-Hall. Wilson, James Q. (1983), Thinking About Crime, New York, Basic Books. Wilson, James Q. (1993), The Moral Sense, New York, The Free Press. Wilson, James Q. (1994), ‘Culture, Incentives, and the Underclass’, in Aaron, Henry J., Mann, Thomas E. and Taylor, Timothy (eds), Values and Public Policy, Washington, DC, The Brookings Institution, 54-80. Wilson, James Q. and Herrnstein, Richard J. (1985), Crime and Human Nature, New York, Simon and Schuster. Witte, Ann D. (1977), ‘Work Release in North Carolina - A Program That Works!’, 41 Law and Contemporary Problems, 230-251. Witte, Ann D. (1980), ‘Estimating the Economic Model of Crime with Individual Data’, 94 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 57-84.
8300
The Economics of Prisons
433
Witte, Ann D. (1993), ‘Some Thoughts on the Future of Research in Crime and Delinquency’, 30 Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency, 513-525. Witte, Ann D. (1995a), ‘Crime and Education’, Wellesley College Working Paper. Witte, Ann D. (1995b), ‘Urban Crime: Issues and Policies’, Wellesley College Working Paper. Witte, Ann D. (1996), ‘Urban Crime: Issues and Policies’, 7 Housing Policy Debate, 731-748. Witte, Ann D. (1997), ‘Crime’ in Jere, Behrman and Nevzer, Stacey (eds), The Social Benefits of Education, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 219-246. Witte, Ann D. and Reid, Pamela A. (1980), ‘An Exploration of the Determinants of Labor Market Performance for Prison Releasees’, 8(3) Journal of Urban Economics, 313-329. Witte, Ann D. and Schmidt, Peter (1977), ‘An Analysis of Recidivism, using the Truncated Lognormal Distribution’, 26 Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, 302-311. Witte, Ann D. and Schmidt, Peter (1979), ‘An Analysis of the Type of Criminal Activity Using the Logit Model’, 16 Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency, 164-179. Wynne, John M. (1978), ‘Unions and Bargaining among Employees of State Prisons’, 101 Monthly Labor Review, 10-16. Zimmer, Lynn and Jacobs, James B. (1981), ‘Challenging the Taylor Law: Prison Guards on Strike’, 34(4) Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 531-544.
8400 ORGANIZED CRIME AND ILLEGAL MARKETS Gianluca Fiorentini Dipartimento di Scienze Economiche Università di Bologna © Copyright 1999 Gianluca Fiorentini
Abstract This chapter discusses some of the most influential definitions of organized crime focusing on the differences between ordinary illegal firms and governance structures which supply public services such as the protection of property rights and the enforcement of contracts. The chapter further investigates the relations between the structural features of organized crime and the basic working rules of illegal markets. In this respect, the economic justifications to make markets illegal are discussed as second-best policies in serious cases of asymmetric information and externalities. To understand the origin of organized crime we analyze the implications of the proprietary theory of government. Moreover, to understand the internal structure of organized crime we concentrate on the role of input specificity in performing illegal transactions. A brief discussion of the deterrence policies against organized crime concludes the chapter. JEL classification: K14, K40, K42 Keywords: Illegal Behavior, Enforcement of Law, Illegal Markets, Rent Seeking
1. Introduction After a brief description of the plan of the work the next section analyzes some influential economic definitions of organized crime. We start focusing on the differences between ordinary illegal firms and governance structures. The former supply private goods in illegal or irregular markets while the latter provide public goods such as the protection of property rights and the enforcement of contracts. On this basis we analyze the relations between the structural features of organized crime and the basic working rules of illegal markets. The purpose of Section 3 is to explore the implications of the proprietary theory of government for the analysis of organized crime. Building on the rent-seeking literature we also discuss contributions on the competition between organizations for the control of a given area. The starting point of such models is that if property rights are weakly enforced by 434
8400
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
435
the legitimate government there will be greater incentives to invest in destructive activities against other criminal organizations or legal firms exposed to violent threats. Finally, we show how such a rent-seeking approach to the origin of organized crime allows one to draw some implications on its role in influencing the long-run growth of the economy. Section 4 investigates the relations between different forms of regulatory intervention of the legitimate government and the firms’ choice to shift their activities to irregular markets. To develop this point, we consider the related literature on the empirical analysis of the irregular markets building on direct surveys and on indirect monetary methods. In Section 5, we deal with the role of organized crime in illegal markets when it completely substitutes legitimate governments in most of their basic functions. In this area the literature suggests that there is a positive relation between the volume of transactions in illegal markets and the influence of organized crime in legitimate business activities. For this reason, we report on the economic justifications to limit transactions in illegal markets. In particular, we focus on the contributions explaining prohibitions to exchange goods in terms of second-best policies in serious cases of asymmetric information and externalities. In Section 6, we discuss how organized crime is involved in legal markets. In this respect we concentrate on three distinct activities: the supply of illegal inputs to legal firms, the manipulation of public funds and the joint production of legitimate and illegitimate outputs. In Section 7, we focus on the internal structure of organized crime in the supply of basic inputs required to compete in illegal markets such as protection from police enforcement and money laundering. As for the internal structure, much work has dealt with the enforcement of secrecy codes in shaping the internal rules of organized crime. Similarly, the literature on vertical integration deals primarily with the degree of specificity of the inputs to explain different organizational models. In this setting particular attention is paid to understand how the authority is distributed between downstream firms active in the markets for illegal outputs and upstream governance structures specialized in supplying protection services. Section 8 analyzes some of the main deterrence policies taken up against organized crime. We start discussing the classic defense of organized crime as a monopolistic supplier of illegal goods based on its interest in minimizing the use of violence and in restricting the output levels. To further understand this issue, we briefly describe the effects of the legalization of illegal markets on the barriers to entry and on the equilibrium output. Taking as given the border between legal and illegal markets, we examine some more specific policy issues. In this area, we discuss the relative costs and benefits of addressing deterrence activities against suppliers and purchasers of illegal goods and the merits of enforcement policies exploiting conflicts between the two parties. Finally, we report on
436
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
8400
the literature dealing with the broad theme of policy design against organized crime with specific reference to the cases when different organizations interact strategically.
2. Definitions of Organized Crime Fiorentini and Peltzman (1995b) discuss three main economic definitions of organized crime. Here we follow broadly their discussion, but we add a fourth definition that builds on the differences between Schelling (1971) and Gambetta (1988). One of the first definitions can be traced back in the report of the President’s Commission on Law Enforcement and Administration of Justice (1967). According to such a definition the core business of organized crime is the supply of illegal goods and services. More specifically, Cressey (1967) - one of the experts working for the Commission - suggests that the differences between ordinary illegal firms and organized crime is that the latter specializes in activities for which there is an autonomous demand, while the former more often undertake purely predatory activities. As a whole, the report admits that organized crime practices coercion against other agents (firms, unions, police agencies) but this is more related to its activities in legal markets that are relatively marginal. In this respect, an occasional use of violence can be explained with the need to invest in military technology to protect property rights in illegal markets, and with the relatively low marginal costs in using such assets once they are in place. The above definition correctly points at the crucial relation between illegal markets and the more general influence of organized crime on the allocation of resources in illegal activities. However, it suffers from three limitations. First, it is purely descriptive and does not provide a convincing economic explanation for such a relation. Second, it builds on an idea of organized crime as a highly integrated firm - both vertically and horizontally – that operates monopolies in various stages of the production and distribution of illegal commodities. Third, it misses the difference between the role of organized crime as a firm supplying illegal goods to final consumers and as a governance structure imposing regulations and supplying public goods to independent illegal firms. Starting from these criticisms, Schelling (1971) suggests that the core business of organized crime is to impose its protection to other legal and illegal firms under the threat of violence. To practice extortion organized crime must reach a monopolistic control over the supply of violence, at least in a limited area, as its services necessarily include protection against other competing organizations. Similarly, those who provide protection services have to control the supply of corruption to local police agencies to reduce the threat
8400
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
437
of competing organizations calling for police intervention against them. To explain the main differences between illegal firms and organized crime, Schelling (1971) discusses the features of those markets where the latter typically develops a governmental authority. The first feature of such markets is that victimized firms should be unable to protect themselves. This explains why illegal or irregular markets are privileged areas for the control of organized crime as illegal firms are less likely to call for police protection. Second, victims should find it difficult to hide themselves. Accordingly, organized crime concentrates most of its extortion on illegal firms that supply goods to final consumers and not on other organizations specialized in appropriative activities. Third, organized crime is more likely to impose extortion on firms whose profits are easily observable. In fact, without an independent auditing authority, monitoring problems may lead to continuous conflicts. Fourth, Schelling notices that organized crime is more likely to practice extortion on illegal firms the higher their asset specificity both in terms of site specificity and of capital embodied in customer relations. For this reason, independent restaurants and shops operating at a local level are often victims of organized crime. Fifth, illegal or legal firms are more likely to end up under the control of organized crime if the payments imposed are tax deductible, imposed on all competitors and if they can be shifted onto the final consumers. This explains why organized crime often covers its core business with legitimate commercial activities as this allows levying taxes supplying overpriced inputs to the victimized firms. Finally, organized crime typically succeeds in becoming a governance structure if the victims of extortion are individuals or small firms. This is because the risk of police intervention increases more than proportionally with the number of agents who know the details of the extortion. At the end of his paper, Schelling (1971) introduces a qualification of his thesis, which has been developed by Gambetta (1993), and constitutes the basis for a third definition of organized crime. Schelling notices that often illegal firms call for organized crime intervention to provide the public services required to stay in business (for example, corruption of police officers or enforcement of collusive agreements). In this perspective, the tax levied on the protected firms represents the price voluntarily paid for the above services. Gambetta (1993) builds on this intuition and argues that organized crime operates as a governance structure mostly addressed to the underworld so that its activities cannot be reduced to the supply of illegal goods. Compared to Schelling, Gambetta goes further in denying the coercive character of the relationships between organized crime and illegal firms, and suggests that its core business is the supply of trust, that is of a more stable institutional setting for illegal firms. Such supply does not
438
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
8400
involve only the protection of property rights and the enforcement of contracts, but also the provision of barriers against entry and the organization of collusive agreements. Since there is a voluntary demand for these services, the coercive elements in the relations between organized crime and illegal firms are in its need to use violence occasionally to preserve its reputation as an authority to solve disputes or to enforce contracts. The idea that organized crime does not only supply illegal goods to final consumers and that behind extortion one can see implicit contracts with illegal firms is coherent with the available evidence on its internal organization (Anderson, 1979). In particular, this study shows that organized crime operates as a firm mainly to cover up its governance activities, but even such role is limited to the provision of intermediate inputs to other small illegal firms. Moreover, to extract most of the rents accruing to the firms using its services organized crime usually enforces a strict control on the number of competitors under its protection. More recently Alexander (1997) proposes three settings to describe the relationships between organized crime and the firms under its control which differ for the degree of coercion imposed by the former. First, a ‘leviathan’ model where a racketeer can extract surplus from small competitive firms. Second, a model where a ‘dominant firm’ colludes with a racketeer in imposing coercion over smaller competitors. Third, a ‘cartel’ model where groups of legal firms demand the enforcement services of organized crime. The ‘leviathan’ model builds on the idea that when organized crime acts as a racketeer it can force all firms to adopt a monopolistic price in the downstream market because its information set is complete and its threats are credible (Rubin, 1973). Hence, the ‘leviathan’ can extract all profits through firm-specific sales taxes and lump-sum taxes negatively related with each firm’s marginal costs. This model predicts that organized crime will levy higher firm-specific taxes on the most efficient firms to force them to a greater reduction of their output. The ‘dominant firm’ model builds on the idea that large firms often may be interested in calling for the intervention of a racketeer to impose sales taxes on rival firms. To maximize profits, tax rates are set to a level that the surviving fringe firms have marginal costs just below those of the dominant firm. It follows that the latter extracts more rents from the taxes than from producing the fringe output. Finally, the ‘cartel’ model builds on some evidence that legal firms in different industries establish associations and acquire the services of organized crime as an enforcer of collusive agreements. Comparing these different settings with the available data on the tax levied by organized crime on legal firms, Alexander finds out that the former often imposes a two-part tax. The first component is a lump-sum tax creating an entry barrier for relatively small new entrants and the second is a
8400
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
439
sales tax to control for overproduction. However, the relatively low level of both rates, and especially of the sales tax, is interpreted as evidence of weak or no discrimination against more efficient firms, and therefore is more easily reconciled with the ‘cartel’ model. Moreover, the organization enforcing the cartel charges legal firms for the purchase of packaging labels thereby monitoring the market shares of the participants. Finally, the reported evidence indicates that firms belonging to the association, and therefore purchasing the cartel enforcement services, are more stable over the long run. Hence, the levy imposed by organized crime is compensated in terms of higher and/or more stable profits over time. Reuter (1983) provides a fourth definition of organized crime as a hierarchical structure characterized by long-run horizon, and with an involvement in multiple illegal activities. Such an inductive definition relies more on the author’s empirical studies of organized crime activities in different industries than on an attempt to deduct new elements to build a general theory. In this respect, Reuter denies that organized crime can be seen as a firm active in illegal markets since its protection extends to legal firms, its activities include the control of public procurements, and its investments in legal businesses often represent the largest share of its assets. Analogously, Reuter does not fully accept Schelling’s idea of organized crime as an authority with a coercive control over the allocation of resources in illegal and irregular markets. Indeed, in his empirical work Reuter shows how difficult it is for a central authority to control entry in such markets and more generally to regulate illegal firms. This is because entry barriers are often low, the costs of monitoring decentralized firms are high, and the threat of such firms calling for police intervention against large organizations is often credible. Arguably, the main lesson that can be drawn from Reuter’s contributions is that there are a few economic elements which can be used to characterize organized crime (hierarchy, economies of scale and scope, specific capital assets, durability). However, such elements cannot be used to design deterrence policies against organized crime without a careful investigation of its internal structure and of the fundamentals of the specific markets involved.
3. The Proprietary Theory of the State and the Origin of Organized Crime After Schelling (1971) who put forward the view of organized crime as a governance structure, other authors analyzed the relations between the origin of organized crime and the different activities of legitimate government. In this respect, Anderson (1995) suggests that there are three main factors for the emergence of organized crime: the investment in
440
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
8400
military technology to enforce legislation, the definition of regulatory measures including direct public intervention, and the legislative definition of illegal markets. In this section we discuss the effects of a relatively weak investment in military technology on the origin of criminal organizations specialized in predatory activities. To do so, we follow the analysis of those economists who applied to the activities of legitimate government the same conceptual framework used by Schelling for organized crime. For instance, Baumol (1990) proposes a proprietary theory of the government where the ruling class is made of agents whose objective is to extract rents from their subjects under given institutional constraints such as winning the next elections and/or preserving their tax base. To meet these constraints, legitimate governments have to provide at least some public services in exchange for the taxes they levy. Such services are those primarily required for a system of decentralized markets to operate (protection of property rights and enforcement of contracts) and are the same as those supplied by organized crime to firms in irregular or illegal activities. Hence, Grossman (1995), following Gambetta (1993), builds his model on the close analogy between the taxes levied by the legitimate government and the extortionary duties levied by organized crime, as both share some elements of coercion and of voluntary transactions. More precisely, Grossman (1995) assumes that firms and individuals can purchase the above public services from the legitimate government or from organized crime. In such a setting, the emergence of organized crime has a positive effect as it reduces the monopolistic power of the legitimate government. However, it may have negative consequences in terms of resources wasted in the competitive process to establish the monopoly over coercion. One of the worst possibilities for the victimized firms is when the two enforcers collude imposing revenue-maximizing taxes to their subjects. On the normative side, Grossman shows that as the ruling class appropriates the tax revenue there will be no widespread opposition to the growth of organized crime that reduces the fiscal pressure. Conversely, if the contest between organized crime and the government makes it possible for the former to become the new ruling class, it is rational for the victims to oppose its growth because it will eventually restore a monopolistic supply of public goods. In the proprietary theory of government, organized crime becomes a competitor in setting taxes and providing public goods only because the latter has been unable or unwilling to invest enough resources in military technology. Baumol (1990) notices that in doing so the government indirectly provides incentives to other groups to specialize in appropriative activities rather than in productive ones. The most frequently used framework to investigate appropriative activities is that of rent-seeking contests (Hirschleifer, 1988). In these models competitors invest their
8400
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
441
resources to win the exclusive right to extract economic rents through extortion. Hence, if the monopolistic control over the supply of violence is relatively weak, entrepreneurs will invest in appropriative activities as long as they are more profitable than productive ones. Skaperdas and Syropoulos (1995) combine this rent-seeking literature with the proprietary theory of government to investigate the origin of organized crime. In their model agents can choose to invest in appropriative or productive activities in an anarchy situation where none has the exclusive right to use coercive means and where agents are characterized by a comparative advantage in one of the two activities. The possibility to appropriate other agents’ property is modeled in a rent-seeking contest where the larger the asymmetry between agents’ productivity in military technology, the smaller the overall investment in such technology. This is because agents with a lower productivity are aware that their investment has little or no effect on their final share of resources. The outcome of the static game with no exit is that agents specialized in productive activities end up with a smaller share of the total output. Furthermore, in a more sophisticated setting, where agents with a comparative advantage in productive activities have an exit option, there is a progressive self-selection of agents in more homogeneous communities with a loss of productive capacity in those with a greater proportion of agents specialized in appropriative activities. When agents specialized in productive activities are complements to each other, they have a greater bargaining power as their exit further reduces the size of the pie. Finally, in a dynamic setting if there is no clear competitive advantage in the use of the military technology, all agents have strong incentives to invest in such technology. Here, the ongoing conflict reduces the effective protection of property rights and the returns from productive activities. In its turn, this induces exit or deters entry of new agents specialized in productive activities. Even this process does not provide sufficient incentives to reduce the investment in military technology as cooperative agreements do not represent equilibria of the rent-seeking game. Indeed, small initial differences in investment bring about large differences in the final pay-off. Hence, the model suggests that, due to the high returns of investing in violence at the beginning of the interaction, it is crucial that a group of agents emerges from the beginning as the most productive in using the military technology to deter other groups’ initiatives.
4. Regulatory Policies and Irregular Markets Anderson (1995) suggests a second relation between the activities of legitimate government and those of organized crime based on the features of
442
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
8400
the regulatory regime imposed on legal firms. There are two institutional elements involved in this relation. First, a high degree of regulation increases the compliance costs for legal firms and may induce them to switch some activities to irregular markets where property rights are defined and contracts are enforced by organized crime. Moreover, as firms operating in irregular markets often increase their market shares due to their lower costs this brings larger parts of the productive system under the control of organized crime. Second, as noticed by Tanzi (1995), regulation is usually coupled with a high degree of bureaucratic discretion and this provides strong incentives to shift potentially productive resources into corruption. Since the supply of corruption is more efficiently managed through monopolies or collusive agreements to avoid a dissipation of resources, this represents an incentive for criminal organizations to acquire some control over the allocation of public resources. Along these lines, Smith (1976) investigates the effects of regulation on the size of the irregular markets building on the assumption that there is an unavoidable conflict between the objectives of the government in passing legislation and those of the economic agents who strive to minimize costs. The main purpose of the model is to show that the effects of any regulatory measure can be understood only taking into account the incentives of the regulated agents to shift resources into irregular markets. More specifically, Smith focuses on taxation as an instance of cost-increasing regulation because it is relatively easy to be measured and because of greater data availability. He elaborates a relatively simple two-market model, where goods in the legal and irregular markets are imperfect substitutes for consumers due to an expected sanction if discovered trading in the latter. In this setting Smith analyzes the effects of changes in taxation and in enforcement activities over the equilibrium in both legal and irregular markets. The reduction in the output level in the legal market, due to an increase in taxation, is understated if one does not take into account the possibility for producers to trade in irregular markets. Moreover, no clear effects of a tax increase can be derived for the equilibrium price in both legal and irregular markets. This is because legal and illegal goods are substitutes in consumption and in production so that a change in the price on the legal market (due to increased regulation) has effects on the shape of the demand and supply curves in both markets. Overall, the effect of a tax increase on the profit levels for firms dealing in both markets depends on how they distribute their output across the two. More definite results can be obtained only for firms dealing exclusively in the legal market as an increase in production costs reduces, ceteris paribus, the unitary profits. Smith also provides an empirical analysis of the effects of an increase in regulatory standards on the volumes traded in both legal and irregular markets for distilled spirits. The main result is that demand and supply respond more to
8400
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
443
changes in tax rates than to changes in market prices with no relation with government regulation. Indeed, both consumers and producers substitute between legal and irregular markets after a change in the regulatory costs. Smith also finds a positive correlation between tax rates and prices in the legal market: the shift of producers and consumers to the illegal market has a greater effect on the supply curve (shifting it upward) than on demand (shifting it downward) in the legal market. In a similar vein, Anderson (1995) examines other regulatory measures that provide incentives for legal firms to invest in irregular markets and therefore to create a market for the public services supplied by organized crime. First, there is regulation aimed at increasing quality standards which often involves a limited supply of licenses or permits (building, commercial, professional, polluting) or other entry barriers. In these circumstances organized crime tries to control the distribution of the licenses using its comparative advantage in centralizing corruption and/or in enforcing cartels among incumbent firms. Second, there is price control regulation or interventions to set subsidies, quotas or other constraints to exchange. In these cases organized crime avoids quality standards and/or reports non-existing output taking advantage of its protection against the enforcement of police agencies. According to the New York State ‘Organized Crime Task Force’ Report (1989) the involvement of organized crime in the allocation of public funds is a consequence of two distinct sources of comparative advantage. First, in bribing and threatening public officers and, second, in coordinating collusive agreements between firms and the public administration. When such collusive agreements take place, organized crime succeeds in extracting rents from both public purchasers and private suppliers. According to Grossman (1995), in these collusive agreements greater stability is often obtained when electoral support is provided in exchange for a reduction in the enforcement efforts. In these circumstances the criminal organization can also manage to direct the enforcement activities against its rivals. It follows that while the enforcement agencies meet their targets in terms of quantitative indicators, the incumbent obtains further positive externalities. Moreover, both sides strengthen their fiduciary relationships and reduce the incentives to act opportunistically. On similar lines, Tanzi (1995) observes that collusive agreements between local politicians and criminal organizations become less stable in case of fiscal crises as the latter reduce the possibility to activate public expenditure without a corresponding increase in the fiscal pressure. In such a case it is unlikely that public administrations succeed in appropriating large rents from direct interventions without reducing their electoral support. A greater political instability may therefore decrease the incentives for criminal organizations to collude with politicians as their expected stay in power is shortened.
444
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
8400
To measure the size of irregular markets and the potential threat they represent for the activities of the legitimate government some authors attempted to overcome the complex methodological problems due to a lack of reliable data. In this perspective, Feige (1994) proposes a definition of the illegal economy which includes all transactions that violate specific statutory rules concerning the scope of what is regarded as legitimate trade. On the other hand, irregular activities include all transactions which belong to the area of the legal economy as defined above, but violate statutory and/or administrative rules related to one or more of the following areas: property relationships, commercial licensing, labor contracts, torts, financial credit and social security. Feige describes two lines of research aimed at measuring the size of the irregular markets. First, the direct approach based on the analysis of tax auditing and other reports concerning the level of compliance with fiscal legislation and regulatory standards as a whole. Second, the indirect approach based on the analysis of macroeconomic indexes over time. As for the latter, Tanzi (1983) develops a currency approach which builds on the assumption that irregular transactions are mostly undertaken via cash payments. Accordingly, one can detect changes in the irregular transactions observing, ceteris paribus, changes in the demand for liquidity. Similar in spirit is the approach proposed by Feige (1989) which builds on the assumption that the Fischer quantity equation holds through time. On this basis, knowing the amount of liquidity, the level of prices, and the velocity of rotation, one obtains relatively good estimates of the total transactions taking place in the system. Comparing such total transactions with the nominal GDP one could approximate the transaction volume in the irregular markets. Feige also discusses other lines of research that adopt an indirect approach but rely on real variables from national accounts and labor market data. In this group of contributions, Macafee (1982) and Park (1979) propose a quantitative analysis of the irregular markets which relies on the discrepancy between national expenditure and national income as it can be related to unreported income from illegal or irregular transactions. Analogously, Contini (1981) tries to estimate the overall size of the irregular markets looking at changes in the labor force participation rate with respect to a standard level which is assumed to be observable in the absence of illegal or irregular activities. Although the above authors admit that the lack of reliable data represents a serious obstacle to measure the size of the informal economy, building on these results Schneider (1994) proposes an approach to investigate how that size is related to the overall burden of taxation and to the level of regulation. More precisely, Schneider shows that increases in fiscal pressure or in regulatory intensity (the number of existing laws) and in the complexity of the tax system (a Herfindahl-Hirschman concentration measure of the revenue sources) are all strongly related the size of the illegal and irregular
8400
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
445
markets. Moreover, Schneider’s results suggest that even a decline in the fiscal pressure is not a sufficient condition for a reduction of the size of the irregular economy if it is not followed by a fall in the indexes of regulatory complexity and intensity. Related to this literature on the size of the shadow economy, Reuter (1984) tries to quantify the multiplier effect of the expenditure in illegal markets on the economy as a whole. In a first model he assumes that illegal goods are produced by foreign criminal agents and therefore can be regarded as imports in national accounts. For this reason, purchases of illegal goods have no impact on national income. Then Reuter assumes that the producers of illegal goods are domestic so that the expenditure on such goods becomes an export to another country, as they do not emerge in official statistics. In such a case an increase in the demand for illegal goods is similar to a purely exogenous demand shock as it originates outside the regular economy. Assuming that the expenditures in illegal goods result in income for the domestic producers, the multiplier is lower because it depends negatively on the differences in saving propensities between producers and consumers of illegal goods.
5. Organized Crime and Illegal Markets The neo-institutional literature focuses on the effects of different mechanisms for defining and protecting property rights and for enforcing contracts to explain market performances. In one of the leading contributions to this literature Demsetz (1967) notices that the participants in illegal markets should in principle self-protect their property rights. Indeed, if the government does not provide the basic services required to support the working of decentralized markets private agents willing to trade have to substitute it. As most rent-seeking literature suggests, in similar situations it is likely that after a competition among private agents or groups one of them will emerge as the specialized supplier. Schelling (1971) notices that after such an authority becomes established it is likely that its activities will also include the use of violence and corruption and the provision of inputs at regulated prices. Furthermore, when illegal organizations with large specific assets protect themselves from the police and from other opportunistic behaviors they often generate a positive spillover to other producers not only in the same line of product but also in related markets. It follows that they will find it convenient to exploit these economies of scale and scope. Eventually, when large investments are sunk in protecting property rights and enforcing contracts, such organizations may have sufficient incentives to compete with the legitimate government for the right to provide the above services even for agents active in legal markets.
446
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
8400
Building on this perspective, Paul and Wilhite (1994) show that the full social cost of making goods or services illegal should also take into account the dissipation of resources invested in the attempt to establish a monopoly in the supply of protection and enforcement services. In this respect, even agents not interested in obtaining a monopoly position but willing to protect their endowments are forced to invest intensively in that direction. In order to derive their main result, Paul and Wilhite discuss Becker and Stigler’s (1974) claim that an increased enforcement against producers of illegal goods on average increases their profits. The authors argue that to draw such a clear-cut conclusion one should address directly the effects on producers’ costs of the increased enforcement and, more to our point, on the resources wasted in the attempt to monopolize the illegal market. Paul and Wilhite claim that producers are not attracted by the price increase brought about by the government-induced supply restriction, but by the perspective to obtain rents from the monopolistic control of the illegal markets. Hence, the main consequence of a lack of public enforcement of property rights is to increase the investment in military technology and in corruption. Given these negative consequences, different economic justifications have been offered to explain relatively low levels of public enforcement. Traditionally, authors like Buchanan (1973) or Rubin (1973) stress that in most instances markets are made illegal for paternalistic reasons, that is because consumers do not fully understand the consequences of their actions. According to this view, such markets would have usually reached an efficient equilibrium as agents transact voluntarily and there are no significant imperfections such as external effects from production or consumption. In a different perspective, Rose-Ackerman (1985) explains the decision of making transactions illegal as a second-best policy to reduce the negative effects of market imperfections. Rose-Ackerman proposes two arguments to limit the rights of exchange on efficiency grounds, and a third argument which has to do with the intrinsic limits of the technology used to enforce the ban. First, goods such as body organs or human blood need costly quality controls which make it difficult for purchasers to evaluate the available alternatives. Moreover, even if purchasers were able to discriminate, such goods are often demanded in such an urgency that their bargaining power is negligible. Hence, Rose-Ackerman argues that to avoid excessive ex post litigation over the terms, the government might declare such contracts illegal on efficiency grounds. Following this argument, one could object that if the government’s objective is to increase the standards of quality, measures aimed at reducing entry but not blocking it completely (for example, licenses) should be used to deter producers who would specialize in low quality supply. However, licensing practices tend to discourage particularly low-income consumers and to shift their demand to irregular
8400
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
447
markets where non-licensed suppliers operate. Hence, the government’s ban could be further rationalized as a measure to avoid negative redistributive effects from the attempt to regulate such markets. The second efficiency argument to make markets illegal is that the production and/or consumption of illegal goods with a voluntary demand can give rise to negative external effects, which are not accounted for by the parties involved. For instance, the consumption of heavy drugs may lead to the impossibility for consumers to face their obligations using their legal incomes and therefore increase the number of thefts and other predatory crimes. In its turn, this would force other agents to invest in defensive measures that increase the opportunity costs of holding property and trading. Moreover, the consumption of drugs may lead to a worsening of consumers’ health conditions to a point that they cannot cover the resulting medical expenses and therefore require some sort of public or charitable intervention. Rose-Ackerman also suggests an additional and subtler source of externality arising from the imperfections of the enforcement mechanisms. Her example is centered on the trade of species in danger of extinction. In such a case the purpose of the ban is to deter further killing of endangered animals and, on efficiency grounds, this should not be extended to animals killed in the past. However, due to the impossibility of detecting differences between animals killed in different periods of time, all transactions are banned. In this respect, the suppliers of new animals in danger of extinction create a negative externality for the owners of animals killed in the past. The example could be regarded as trivial due to the relatively small dimension of such a market compared to other illegal markets, but its logic can be extended to cover other interesting cases. For instance, in the market for illegal drugs, a similar external effect can be relevant as most economists (Moore, 1973; White and Luksetich, 1983) suggest that an appropriate regulatory practice would be to increase the price only for new consumers to discourage their consumption. At the same time the deterrence policy should interfere less with the market price for old consumers not to create rents for producers and traders. However, as most illegal drugs are characterized by very small hoarding costs, it is virtually impossible to enforce a discriminatory regime against new consumers, as the old ones would have too great incentives to enter the trade. As arbitrage would then be declared illegal, it is likely that organized crime would take over from old consumers at least for the large-scale trade.
6. Organized Crime and Legal Markets Although most economists agree that the larger share of activities of organized crime is linked with the provision of governance services for firms
448
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
8400
involved in irregular or illegal markets, some influential contributions investigate its intervention in legal markets. For instance, Reuter (1987) and Gambetta and Reuter (1995) investigate the enforcement of cartel agreements in industries with auction markets managed by public administrations (for example, waste disposal, road construction, building). Such markets are often highly competitive due to the relatively low level of specific inputs and cartel agreements are unstable as it is difficult to detect and to sanction defections. The role of organized crime is therefore to increase the stability of such agreements threatening to punish the firms who defect. On similar lines, Gambetta (1988) suggests that a separate service provided by organized crime to legal firms is protection from entry of new competitors. This is because it is neither in the interest of the incumbent firms nor of organized crime to allow entry, since this would ultimately reduce the rents that are at least in part appropriated by the latter. Organized crime activities in legal markets extend also to the direct investment and management of legitimate businesses. In this respect, Anderson (1979) suggests that the main reason for organized crime to start legitimate business activities is that these activities allow organized crime to exploit economies of scale and scope related to its illegal activities. First, members of the organize crime need a source of legitimate income to hide their true business. Analogously, in the supply of illegal goods or services there is a need for places to trade so that small shops, bars and restaurants are used to cover activities related to loan-sharking or illegal betting. Second, illegal activities often produce outputs or use inputs that are also needed in the legal ones (transportation, communications, warehousing) so that it is profitable to integrate the two. Third, organized crime needs to launder at least part of its profits. To do so through a business activity under its control reduces the risks involved in money laundering. Fourth, the legitimate business can be seen as an occasion to diversify the organization’s portfolio with investments characterized by a different mix of risk and returns. Fiorentini and Peltzman (1995b), following Schelling (1967), discuss the features of the legitimate activities in which it is more likely to observe direct investments by organized crime. In this respect, profits from illegal activities are often invested in industries with relatively mature technologies and protected from international competition. In more competitive settings the comparative advantages of organized crime in legal businesses (monopolistic control of the input markets and especially of the labor unions, availability of capital at low cost and direct threats to rival firms) are not likely to be relevant. For instance, large multinational firms active in open markets often compete over product and process innovations and/or financial diversification. Also Gambetta and Reuter (1995) discuss the market features more likely to elicit the intervention of organized crime,
8400
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
449
reaching similar conclusions. In particular, they find that such intervention can be observed in markets with low barriers to entry both in terms of sunk capital and product differentiation. Anderson (1979) notices that in the debate on organized crime’s legitimate activities opinions differ on how much coercion is used against legal firms. According to the report of the President’s Commission on Law Enforcement and Administration of Justice (1967), organized crime disrupts competition through predatory practices and represents a serious threat for all legal firms involved. On the contrary, MacMichael (1971) suggests that the possibility for organized crime to take advantage of these practices is limited by the greater visibility of legal activities. Indeed, there are increasing risks of losing profits from both legal and illegal activities due to a more active police enforcement as legal firms are more likely to call for its intervention. More generally, although an increase in the transactions under control of organized crime has negative consequences for the development of a given area, it may not be always appropriate to concentrate deterrence efforts to prevent money laundering. Fiorentini and Peltzman (1995b) suggest that when criminal organizations obtain a high level of illegal profits one should compare the relative social losses from their investment in other illegal activities or in legal ones. This is because, even if an extremely costly deterrence mechanism could prevent their laundering, illegal profits would be invested in other illegal activities or in other countries. Hence, for a given level of enforcement, one must face a trade-off between reducing the area of legal transactions under control of criminal organizations and reducing the area of the illegal transactions.
7. Internal Structure and Vertical Integration of Organized Crime One of the first studies of the internal structure of organized crime is Jennings (1984). In his view, the central function of organized crime is to require its members to take an oath not to cooperate with the police and to enforce such an oath by punishing those who fail to comply with it. However, since the relative monitoring and enforcing costs are high and rapidly increasing with the number of members and markets involved, organized crime core business is concentrated in relatively few activities. Moreover, Jennings shows that the enforcement of the oath is valuable only if the illegal activities of organized crime require specialized agents working in teams and running substantial risks if one betrays the others. On the contrary, if the illegal activities are mainly performed individually, the enforcement of the oath is relatively useless. Also Gambetta (1988) draws attention to the relevance of secrecy in shaping the internal structure of
450
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
8400
organized crime not only to avoid detection from the police, but also to manage different sources of intelligence which can be used to maximize its profits. In this respect, Gambetta notices that the comparative advantage of organized crime in selling its protection services is much greater when those on the demand side know little of its internal structure as the organization would be more exposed to police intervention. A recent development in the analysis of the internal structure of organized crime is Polo (1995) who models the latter as a hierarchical organization where the principal hire agents to carry out tasks usually requiring to commit serious crimes. The main problem of the principal is to design a set of incentives constraining agents’ opportunistic behavior in absence of legal contracts. To solve this problem the principal offers contracts where the enforcement of the terms depends on the credibility of the mechanism to sanction the agents who defect. More generally, the economic literature on the vertical structure of organized crime begins with Schelling (1971) who suggests that the latter integrates downstream with illegal firms’ markets when one or more of the following conditions apply: First, when the downstream markets are natural monopolies so that the implicit contracts described in Polo (1995) are particularly subjected to the opportunistic behavior of the illegal firms that might threaten the governance role of organized crime. Second, when there are external effects mainly due to the need to supply violence and corruption which can be internalized through integration. In these circumstances a centralized control avoids duplications of costs and reduces the dissipation of resource in appropriative activities. Third, when financing illegal firms’ activities through an integrated structure allows for a more efficient portfolio strategy (Rubin, 1973). Fourth, when contracts may become source of evidence against the agents who sign them. In other words, the impossibility to use detailed contracts in dealing with complex transactions reduces the advantages of the market over an integrated structure. Fifth, when the illegal firms enjoy large informative advantages and are able to hide most of their profits. However, some authors (Reuter, 1983; New York State Organized Crime Task Force, 1989) stress that there are limits to the benefits of increasing the area of economic transactions directly managed by a centralized organization. According to Reuter, the main limit of such organization has to do with the rapidly increasing costs of monitoring and coordinating agents with conflicting interests. In this respect, the need to keep a centralized control over the use of violence and the fact that police agencies invest more intensively against large-scale organizations might explain the emergence of relatively small local monopolies. Indeed, the first condition provides incentives to reach a monopolistic control while the second limits it to a local area. Second, precisely because the property rights over resources
8400
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
451
used in illegal activities can only be enforced at very high costs, to concentrate such rights in a centralized organization increases the negative consequences of police enforcement. An analogous reasoning holds for the human capital integrated in large organizations which is at greater risk in case of violation of the secrecy code. Third, in some illegal markets it is virtually impossible to impose a centralized control because of the low level of the barriers to entry. Finally, there might be a structural instability in the financial flows used in illegal activities due to the police enforcement against money laundering which can discourage large-scale sunk investments even by risk-neutral agents. More recently Dick (1995) develops a framework to analyze the issue of the vertical integration in different institutional settings. In particular, Dick focuses on the illegal firms’ choice between buying protection from a specialized organization and producing it internally. To investigate such issue, Dick suggests an decomposing the total transaction costs between production and organizational costs. Production costs are typically lower in a specialized organization due to economies of scale and scope and would call for market supply by a non-integrated producer. On the contrary, the organizational costs to coordinate inputs in specific uses and to adjust to unforeseen contingencies are lower in an integrated structure because of the high specificity of the assets involved. Building on this general framework, Dick (1995) suggests that small firms active in illegal markets are usually interested in buying protection from organized crime only if the latter is not specific to the local market. In such a case protection is more efficiently provided inside the illegal firms so that one of them will enforce the rules underlying the working of the illegal markets. Conversely, illegal firms will buy protection from specialized organizations when their expected time horizon is sufficiently long so that it is worthwhile to define and enforce complex market transactions. Such a longer time horizon is often observed when illegal firms and organized crime share a common culture, for instance due to ethnic networks, so that transaction costs are low and self-enforcing agreements are more likely to be feasible. Finally, illegal firms will self-supply protection if there is a high degree of uncertainty over the terms of the transactions. This explains why organized crime supplies protection to illegal firms dealing with victimless activities where the activities are easily observable, while self-protection is the rule for organizations involved in appropriative activities.
452
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
8400
8. Normative Analysis Buchanan (1973) introduces a controversial argument in the analysis of the deterrence strategies against organized crime. His basic assumption is that organized crime tends to control, directly or indirectly, the allocation of resources in illegal markets. In such a role it operates approximately as a monopolist whose interest is to block entry of new competitors and to limit output. Accordingly, a legislator willing to minimize the level of transactions in illegal markets should not target its deterrence policies against organized crime, which helps to pursue a similar objective. Buchanan also evaluates the distributive effects of a monopolistic structure characterized by a large share of surplus invested in other illegal activities. In his view, such distributive effects do not represent a sufficient reason to concentrate deterrence efforts against organized crime. Indeed, if there are economies of scale in the production of illegal goods a monopoly reduces the opportunity costs as it requires fewer resources per unit of output. Buchanan’s analysis deals only with the role of organized crime in illegal markets and not in predatory activities. This means that his model does not address the negative effects of organized crime’s supply of violence and corruption. This notwithstanding, compared to other supply structures one can argue that illegal monopolists prefer lower levels of violence and corruption precisely because they internalize such external effects. Schelling (1967), building on his analysis of organized crime as a coercive authority, suggests that the first priority of any deterrence policy should be to legalize as many illegal markets as possible. The idea behind this is that only by reducing the rents available in the illegal markets can one limit organized crime’s role as a governance structure for firms active in legal, irregular and illegal activities. Moreover, among the social costs of making some markets illegal one should consider that profits are used to bribe enforcement agencies and the public administration and that potential victims are led to invest in appropriative activities. To strengthen his thesis Schelling suggests that organized crime is unlikely to keep its control of the legalized markets since they are not characterized by high barriers to entry. Following the same reasoning, Tanzi (1995) proposes reducing the areas of direct public intervention because they are often run through auction markets where organized crime operates as the enforcer of collusive agreements between legal firms and the public administration. Given the particular relevance of the features of police interventions in explaining the size of illegal markets, several economists analyzed the specific deterrence policies adopted against the criminal organizations running such markets. In this respect, Fiorentini and Peltzman (1995b) report that in most illegal markets (drugs, betting, loan sharking,
8400
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
453
prostitution, smuggling, counterfeiting) police agencies concentrate their efforts on agents involved in productive and trading activities more than on consumers. This is probably due to the recognition that demand is voluntary, and therefore if consumption gives rise to relatively low negative externalities, to target consumers would impose on them a rather high welfare loss. Moreover, if one takes into account the enforcement costs, consumers are often too many and too dispersed to be an efficient target for effective deterrence efforts. On similar lines, most empirical studies on industries where irregular activities involve a large size of resources show relatively low levels of entry barriers and asset specificity (New York State Organized Crime Task Force, 1989). This makes it difficult to design a deterrence policy against producers or traders as they are easily replaced by new organizations. To reduce the consequences of this problem Lott and Roberts (1989) suggest that the police should try to exploit the conflicts between parties involved in illegal transactions. This follows the analogy with those irregular markets where transactions violate price or safety regulations (house rents, loan sharking) and where one of the two contracting parties can be given enough incentives to denounce the other. A similar strategy, centered upon the use of potential conflicts between agents in the same organization, has been extensively used in fighting organized crime through informants’ protection schemes. These difficulties in targeting small illegal firms can explain why most resources are used to contrast the organizations involved in large-scale trading of illegal goods, in financing other illegal firms’ activities, in laundering the profits from such activities and in bribing public officials. Indeed, all these activities involve human and physical capital assets extremely specific and rather difficult to be replaced in the short run. However, large organizations are also more reactive against the enforcement activities of the legitimate government as they have much more at stake. Hence, especially if such reactions take the form of increased corruption and violence against the police agencies (Fiorentini, 1995) it might be advisable to address part of the deterrence efforts against consumption strengthening the enforcement on the demand side. This is especially so if such policies are targeted against markets with a high demand elasticity (Becker and Murphy, 1988). To specify appropriate deterrence policies aimed at reducing illegal transactions, agencies should also consider the strategic interactions between criminal organizations. In this respect, if there is a monopolistic or oligopolistic supply the allocative and distributive effects of an increase in the deterrence effort depend on the market structure emerging after the enforcement. For instance, if the market becomes competitive and barriers to entry are eliminated, in the long run more illegal goods will be traded at the new equilibrium (Buchanan, 1973). On the contrary, if the entry barriers are
454
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
8400
not lowered, strong enforcement activities against an incumbent may favor the surviving organizations increasing their profitability and therefore their capacity to supply violence and corruption (Cellentani, Marelli and Martina, 1995). In similar situations it is likely that an increased deterrence effort will lead to greater resources invested in corruption and violence. Finally, the design of effective deterrence policies should take into account that organized crime’s supply of services to legal, irregular and illegal firms is a relevant source of income in areas with large-scale unemployment. For this reason, although the aggregate negative consequences of organized crime activities on the growth of the legal economy are extremely large, there are problems in eliciting continuous support for the fight against it. This is not only because organized crime can directly threaten its opponents and corrupt police agencies, but also because it can buy support with distributive policies implemented jointly with local politicians (Grossman, 1995). Accordingly, most communities where organized crime plays a relevant role can be described using a prisoners’ dilemma framework where individual agents are damaged in the short run by its disappearance and are therefore unable to coordinate themselves to reach more efficient outcomes.
Bibliography on Organized Crime and Illegal Markets (8400) Adams, Michael (1991), ‘Wie Zerstört man den Markt für Rauschgifte?’, Zeitschrift für Rechtspolitik, 202-204. Reprinted in 9 Zeitschrift für die Polizei, 1992, p. 4-6. Adams, Michael (1993), ‘Neues vom Drogenmarkt?’, 12 Kriminalistik, Zeitschrift für die gesamte kriminalistische Wissenschaft und Praxis, 755-757. Adams, Michael (1994), ‘Heroin an Süchtige? - Ein Abschliessender Schlagabtausch’, Zeitschrift für Rechtspolitik, 421-426. Alexander B. (1997), ‘The Rational Racketeer: Pasta Protection in Depression Era Chicago’, 40 Journal of Law and Economics, 175-202. Anderson A. (1979), The Business of Organized Crime: A Cosa Nostra Family, Stanford, Hoover Institute Press, Stanford University. Anderson A. (1995), ‘Organized Crime, Mafias and Governments’, in Fiorentini, Gianluca and Peltzman, Sam (eds), The Economics of Organized Crime, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Arlacchi, Pino (1987), ‘Effects of the New Anti-Mafia Law on the Proceeds of Crime and on the Italian Economy’, in Alessandrini, Sergio and Dallago, Bruno (eds), The Unofficial Economy: Consequences and Perspectives in Different Economic Systems, Aldershot, Gower, 247-255. Atkinson, Scott E., Sandler, Todd and Tschirhart, John (1987), ‘Terrorism in a Bargaining Framework’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-21. Backhaus, Jürgen G. (1979), ‘Defending Organized Crime? A Note’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 623-631.
8400
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
455
Backhaus, Jürgen G. (1980), ‘Kein Aufruf zur Verteidigung des Organisierten Verbrechens (With English Summary) (No Call in Defense of Organized Crime)’, 136 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 658-672. Baumol, William J. (1990), ‘Entrepreneurship: Productive, Unproductive, and Destructive’, 98(5) Journal of Political Economy, 893-921. Becker, G. and Murphy K. (1988), ‘A Theory of Rational Addiction’, 96 Journal of Political Economy, 675-700. Becker, G. and Stigler, George J. (1974), ‘Law Enforcement, Malfeasance, and Compensation of Enforcers’, 3 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-18. Benson, Bruce L. (1994), ‘Third Thoughts on Contracting Out’, 11 Journal of Libertarian Studies, 44-78. Benson, Bruce L. and Baden, John A. (1985), ‘The Political Economy of Government Corruption: The Logic of Underground Government’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 391-410. Benson, Bruce L. and Rasmussen, David W. (1991), ‘The Relationship Between Illicit Drug Enforcement Policy and Property Crimes’, 9 Contemporary Policy Issues, 106-115. Benson, Bruce L. and Rasmussen, David W. (1992), Illinois’ War on Drugs: Some Unintended Consequences, Heartland Policy Study, Chicago, Heartland Institute, No. 48. Benson, Bruce L. and Rasmussen, David W. (1995), Illicit Drugs and Crime, Independent Policy Report, Oakland, Independent Institute. Benson, Bruce L., Kim, Iljoong, Rasmussen, David W. and Zuehlke, Thomas W. (1992), ‘Is Property Crime Caused by Drug Use or Drug Enforcement Policy?’, 24 Applied Economics, 679-692. Benson, Bruce L., Kim, Iljoong, Rasmussen, David W. and Zuehlke, Thomas W. (1993), ‘An Economic Analysis of Recidivism Among Drug Offenders’, 60 Southern Economic Journal, 169-183. Benson, Bruce L., Rasmussen, David W. and Sollars, David L. (1995), ‘Police Bureaucrats, Their Incentives, and the War on Drugs’, 83 Public Choice, 21-45. Brenner, Reuven (1990), ‘The Long Road from Serfdom, and how to Shorten it’, 17(2) Canadian Business Law Journal, 195-226. Reprinted in Maruyana, M. (ed.)(1993), Management Reform in Eastern and Central Europe, Aldershot, Dartmouth, 81-109. Brenner, Reuven (1994), Labyrinths of Prosperity, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press. Brenner, Reuven and Brenner, Gabrielle A. (1990), Gambling and Speculation, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Reprinted in French edition by Presses Universitaires de France, 1993. Buchanan, James M. (1973), ‘A Defense of Organized Crime’, in Andreano, Ralph and Siegfried, John J. (eds), The Economics of Crime, Cambridge, Schenkman. Cellentani G., Marrelli, M. and Martina, Riccardo (1995), ‘Cartel Stability and ‘Optimal’ Deterrence Policy’, in Fiorentini, Gianluca and Peltzman, Sam (eds), The Economics of Organized Crime, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Contini, Bruno (1981), ‘Labor Market Segmentation and the Development of the Parallels Economy’, 33 Oxford Economic Papers, 401-412.
456
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
8400
Cressey D. (1967), The Structure and Functions of Criminal Syndicates, Washington, Government Printing Office. Appendix A of the President’s Commission on Law Enforcement and Administration of Justice, Task Force Report: Organized Crime. D’Antonio, Mariano and Scarlato, Margherita (1993a), ‘L’Économia del Crimine. Parte I: Il Ruolo Economico (The Economics of Crime. Part I: Economic Role)’, 27(3) Economia e Lavoro, 107-122. D’Antonio, Mariano and Scarlato, Margherita (1993b), ‘L’Économia del Crimine. Parte II: La Dimensione del Mercato (With English Summary) (The Economy of Crime: Part II: Market Dimension)’, 27(4) Economia e Lavoro, 3-29. Dawid, H. and Feichtinger, G. (1995), On the Persistence of Corruption/Forschungsbericht, Research Memorandum, Vienna, Institute for Econometrics, Operation Research and Systems Theory, University of Technology, No. 186. Demsetz, H. (1967), ‘Toward a Theory of Property Rights’, 57 American Economic Review, 347-359. Dick, Andrew R. (1995), ‘When Does Organized Crime Pay? A Transaction Cost Analysis’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 25-45. Ehrlich, Isaac (1972), ‘Participation in Illegitimate Activities: A Theoretical and Empirical Investigation’, 80 Journal of Political Economy, 521-565. Feige, Edgar L. (1989), The Underground Economies: Tax Evasion and Information Distortion, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Feige, Edgar L. (1994), ‘The Underground Economy and the Currency Enigma’, 49 Public Finance, 119-136. Fiorentini, Gianluca (1995), ‘Oligopolistic Competition in Illegal Markets’, in Fiorentini, Gianluca and Peltzman, Sam (eds), The Economics of Organized Crime, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Fiorentini, Gianluca and Peltzman, Sam (1995a), ‘Introduction’, in Fiorentini, Gianluca and Peltzman, Sam (eds), The Economics of Organized Crime, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Fiorentini, Gianluca and Peltzman, Sam (eds) (1995b), The Economics of Organized Crime, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Fletcher, George P. (1985), ‘A Transaction Cost Theory of Crime?’, 85 Columbia Law Review, 921-930. Gambetta, Diego (1988), ‘Fragments of an Economic theory of the Mafia’, 29 Archives Européennes De Sociologie, 127-145. Gambetta, Diego (1993), ‘The Sicilian Mafia: The Business of Private Protection’, Cambridge, Harvard University Press. Gambetta, Diego and Reuter, Peter (1995), ‘Conspiracy Among the Many: Organized Crime in Legitimate Industries’, in Fiorentini, Gianluca and Peltzman, Sam (eds), The Economics of Organized Crime, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Giusti, Jorge (1991), ‘The Economic and Social Significance of Narcotics’, 0(45) Cepal Review, 137-167. Gragnani, A., Feichtinger, G. and Rinaldi, S. (1994), ‘Dynamics of Drug Consumption: A Theoretical Model’, 94-77 Working Paper. Gragnani, A., Rinaldi, S. and Feichtinger, G. (1995), ‘Slow-Fast Limit Cycles in Controlled Drug Markets’, 185 Forschungsbericht/Research Memorandum.
8400
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
457
Grossman, Herschel I. (1995), ‘Rival Kleptocracies: The Mafia versus the State’, in Fiorentini, Gianluca and Peltzman, Sam (eds), The Economics of Organized Crime, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Hirschleifer, J. (1988), ‘The Analytics of Continuing Conflict’, 76 Synthese, 201-233. Ichniowski, Casey and Preston, Anne (1989), ‘The Persistence of Organized Crime in New York City Construction: Economic Perspective’, 42(4) Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 549-565. Im, Eric Iksoon, Cauley, Jon and Sandler, Todd (1987), ‘Cycles and Substitutions in Terrorist Activities: A Spectral Approach’, 40 Kyklos, 238-255. Jennings, William P., Jr (1984), ‘A Note on the Economics of Organized Crime’, 10(3) Eastern Economic Journal, 315-321. Johnson, Bruce M. (1985), Taking Care of Business: The Economics of Crime by Heroin Abusers, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books, 278 p. Kleiman, Mark A.R. (1989), Marijuana: Costs of Abuse, Costs of Control, Westport, Greenwood, 197 p. Landes, William M. (1978), ‘An Economic Study of U.S. Aircraft Hijacking, 1961-1976', 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-31. Lee, Barbara A. and Chelius, James R. (1989), ‘Government Regulation of Labor Management Corruption: The Casino Industry Experience in New Jersey’, 42(4) Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 536-548. Levine, Daniel, Stoloff, Peter and Spruill, Nancy (1976), ‘Public Drug Treatment and Addict Crime’, 5 Journal of Legal Studies, 435-462. Levy, Peter B. (1989), ‘The Waterfront Commission of the Port of New York: A History and Appraisal’, 42(4) Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 508-523. Lott, John R., Jr (1992), ‘An Attempt at Measuring the Total Monetary Penalty from Drug Convictions: The Importance of an Individual’s Reputation’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 159-187. Lott, John R., Jr and Roberts, R.D. (1989), ‘Why Comply: One-Sided Enforcement of Price Control and Victimless Crime Laws’, 18 Journal of Legal Studies, 405-414. Macafee (1982), ‘A Glimpse of the Hidden Economy in the National Accounts’, 316 Economic Trends, 81-87. MacMichael D. (1971), The Criminals as Businessmen: A Discussion of the Legitimate Business Operation of Organized Crime Figures, Mimeo, Stanford Research Institute. Magaddino, Joseph P. and Medoff, Marshall H. (1982), ‘A Reanalysis of Deterrence and Gun Control’, 10(2) Atlantic Economic Journal, 50-53. Miron, Jeffrey A. and Zwiebel, Jeffrey (1991), ‘Alcohol Consumption During Prohibition’, 81 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 242-247. Moore M. (1973), ‘Policies to Achieve Discrimination on the Effective Price of Heroin’, 63 American Economic Review, 378-396. Morselli, Ricardo and Vannini, Marco (1997), ‘Estimating a Crime Equation in the Presence of Organized Crime: Evidence from Italy’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 89-113. New York State Organized Crime Task Force (1989), Corruption and Racketeering in the New York City Construction Industry, New York. Norton, Desmond A.G. (1988), ‘On the Economic Theory of Smuggling’, 55 Economica, 107-118.
458
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
8400
Ozenne, Tim (1974), ‘The Economics of Bank Robbery’, 3 Journal of Legal Studies, 19-51. Park T. (1979), Reconciliating Between Personal Income and Taxable Income, Washington, DC, Bureau of Economic Analysis. Pashigian, B. Peter (1975), ‘On the Control of Crime and Bribery’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 311-326. Pastor, Santos (1986), ‘Heroína y Política Criminal: Un Enfoque Alternativo (Heroin and Criminal Policy: An Alternative Approach)’, in X (ed.), La Problemática de la Droga en España; Análisis y Propuestas Político-Criminales, Madrid, IUC y Edersa. Pastor, Santos (1987), ‘Liberty versus Security: Should Drugs be Illegal?’, in Rolston, B. and Tomlinson, M. (eds), Civil Rights, Public Opinion and the State, Belfast, European Group for the Study of Deviance and Social Control. Paul C. and Wilhite A. (1994), ‘Illegal Markets and the Social Costs of Rent-seeking’, 79 Public Choice, 105-115. Polo M. (1995), ‘Internal Cohesion and Competition among Criminal Organizations’, in Fiorentini, Gianluca and Peltzman, Sam (eds), The Economics of Organized Crime, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. President’s Commission on Law Enforcement and Administration of Justice (1967), The Challenge of Crime in a Free Society, Washington. Ramseyer, J. Mark (1991), ‘Indentured Prostitution in Imperial Japan: Credible Commitments in the Commercial Sex Industry’, 7 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 89-116. Rasmussen, David W. and Benson, Bruce L. (eds) (1994), The Economic Anatomy of a Drug War: Criminal Justice in the Commons, Lanham, MD, Rowman and Littlefield. Rasmussen, David W., Benson, Bruce L. and Sollars, David L. (1993), ‘Spatial Competition in Illicit Drug Markets: The Consequences of Increased Drug Enforcement’, 23 Review of Regional Studies, 219-236. Reuter, Peter (1983), Disorganized Crime: The Economics of the Visible Hand, London, MIT Press, 233 p. Reuter, Peter (1984), ‘The Economic Significance of Illegal Markets in the United States: Some Observations’, 1 Economia e Lavoro, 135-142. Reuter, Peter (1987), Racketeering in Legitimate Industries: A Study in the Economics of Intimidation, Santa Monica, Rand Corporation. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1985), ‘Inalienability and the Theory of Property Rights’, 85 Columbia Law Review, 931-969. Rubin, Paul H. (1973), ‘The Economic Theory of the Criminal Firm’, in Rottenberg, Simon (ed.), The Economics of Crime and Punishment, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 155-166. Savona, Ernesto (1990), ‘Un Settore Trascurato: l’Análisi Economica della Criminalità, del Diritto Penale e del Sistema di Giustizia Penale (A Neglected Sector: Economic Analysis of Crime, Criminal Law and the System of Criminal Justice)’, Sociologia del Diritto, 255-277. Schavell, Steven and Spier, Kathryn E. (1996), ‘Threats Without Binding Commitment’, 5461 National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper. Schelling, Thomas C. (1967), ‘Economic Analysis and the Criminal Enterprise’, 7 Public Interest, 61-78.
8400
Organized Crime and Illegal Markets
459
Schelling, Thomas C. (1971), ‘What is the Business of organized crime?’, 20 Journal of Public Law, 71-84. Schelling, Thomas C. (1976), ‘Economic Analysis of Organized Crime’, in Kaplan, L.J. and Kessler, D. (eds), An Economic Analysis of Crime: Selected Readings, Springfield, Charles Thomas. Schneider, Friedrich (1994), Can the Shadow Economy be Reduced through Major Tax Reforms’, 49 Public Finance, 137-152. Skaperdas, S. and Syropoulos, C. (1995), ‘Gangs as Primitive States’, in Fiorentini, Gianluca and Peltzman, Sam (eds), The Economics of Organized Crime, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Smith, R. (1976), ‘The Legal and Illegal Markets for Taxed Goods: Pure Theory and Application to State Government Taxation of Distilled Spirits’, 27 Journal of Law and Economics, 393-435. Sollars, David L., Benson, Bruce L. and Rasmussen, David W. (1994), ‘Drug Enforcement and Deterrence of Property Crime Among Local Jurisdictions’, 22 Public Finance Quarterly, 22-45. Sommers, Paul M. (1982), ‘Deterrence and Gun Control: A Reply’, 10(2) Atlantic Economic Journal, 54-57. Sommers, Paul M. (1984), ‘The Effect of Gun Control Laws on Suicide Rates’, 12(1) Atlantic Economic Journal, 67-69. Spier, Kathryn E. and Shavell, Steven (1996), ‘Threats Without Binding Commitment’, National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper. Tanzi, V. (1983), ‘The Underground Economy in the United States’, IMF Staff Papers, 238-305. Tanzi, V. (1995), ‘Corruption: Arm’s Length Relationships and Markets’, in Fiorentini, Gianluca and Peltzman, Sam (eds), The Economics of Organized Crime, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Taylor, Robert (1995), ‘A Game Theoretic Model of Gun Control’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 269-288. Templeman, Joseph (1984), ‘The Effect of Gun Control Laws on Suicide Rates: A Comment’, 12(4) Atlantic Economic Journal, 71 ff. Wagstaff, Adam and Maynard, Alan (1988), Economic Aspects of the Illicit Drug Market and Drug Enforcement Policies in the United Kingdom, London, Her Majesty’s Stationary Office, 156 p. Weichman, Dennis, Green, Gary and Bae, Ronald (1987), ‘The Death Penalty: A Study in General Deterrence’, 1 Research in Law and Policy Studies, 187-194. White M. and Luksetich, William (1983), ‘Heroin, Price Elasticity and Enforcement Strategies’, 21 Economic Inquiry, 557-564.
8500 CORRUPTION Roger Bowles School of Social Sciences University of Bath © Copyright 1999 Roger Bowles
Abstract This chapter reviews the literature on corruption, which is both vast and diverse. Analytically, corruption has been of great interest to economic theorists in recent years because it is an archetypal problem of asymmetric information involving collusion between agents and ‘outsiders’ against principals, or between supervisors and agents against principals. Most of the models up to now have been essentially static, but recent papers have shown that there is a real prospect of developing dynamic models which can explain the persistence of corruption. JEL classification: K14, K42 Keywords: Bureaucratic Corruption, Private Sector Corruption, Illegal Behaviour
1. Introduction Corruption has been around for just about as long as institutions of any sort. In the times of the Greek and Roman empires, for example, corruption was widespread (MacMullen, 1988). Indeed, the corruption of tax officials was so common at that time that it was found expedient to ‘privatize’ tax collection by auctioning rights to collect taxes (Webber and Wildavsky, 1986). Modern democratic government emerged from earlier structures which were ‘rotten to the core’, and the professionalisation of the civil service in the nineteenth century in England was aimed in part at eliminating the sapping effects of corruption on public servants. In the present day, corruption ‘scandals’ are widely reported in the press from almost all walks of life including politics, government and business. The sums involved can range from tiny payments or even small personal favours to bribes running into millions of dollars. Corruption can be distinguished from ‘fraud’, ‘embezzlement’ and ‘extortion’. The essence of corruption is that two individuals or groups act in concert to further their own interests at the expense of a third party. Fraud, or extortion, by contrast involves an individual or group acting unilaterally to further their own interests at the expense of others. In the language of principal-agent theory this entails collusion between the agent and supervisor 460
8500
Corruption
461
against the principal. There are, nevertheless, many everday situations in which such collusion occurs, even when it is at the expense of the principal, where there would be no (legal) presumption that corruption has occurred. A patient and doctor, for example, may ‘collude’ against the insurer responsible for the costs of treatment by agreeing for the patient to have more costly medicine than is necessary. This might be considered corrupt if the doctor has a financial interest in the provision of medicine, but otherwise it would probably be called just another ‘agency cost’ (Bowles and Rickman, 1998). A good deal of ‘corporate hospitality’ involves the provision of private benefits to individuals in the hope that the closer personal relationships it fosters will prove a ‘worthwhile investment’. Another everday instance of the ‘grey area’ between honest and corrupt transactions is where a consumer can benefit by paying ‘over the odds’ for additional service which directly benefits the employee of a firm but not the firm itself. In some service sectors, such as hairdressing or hotels, gratuities are regarded as normal and acceptable. In other sectors, such as refuse collection, gratuities may be discouraged or even prohibited. In many jurisdictions corruption is a criminal offence, although it is clear from the relevant legislation that there are difficulties in defining it and in setting standards of evidence for it as an offence. In England and Wales, for example, the Prevention of Corruption Act 1916 (the act which governs public sector corruption in Britain today) coverage extends to members, officers or servants of a public body. Any ‘gift, loan, fee, reward, or advantage whatever’ will count as corruption if it is in consideration of any act or admission by the public servant. The penalties for the offence can amount to seven years imprisonment or a fine or both, in addition to repaying the amount involved. On a second offence a person stands to lose various rights to vote and may lose any compensation or pension rights to which a public position might otherwise entitle them. As a measure of the response of the legislature to difficulties in seeking successful convictions for the offence, in some circumstances the burden of proof lies on a public employee who has received a payment to show that a suspicious transaction was not corrupt. Under US law the position is a little different. There is not an outright ban on receiving rewards. The US Department of Defense directive 55007 allows gratuities when they are a ‘part of a customary exchange of social amenities between personal friends and relatives when motivated by such relationships and extended on a personal basis’ (Adams, 1981). Though there are many countries in which bribing officials is illegal, it was only in 1997 that 34 countries signed an agreement aimed at eradicating bribery of foreign officials by making such payments a criminal offence and ceasing the practice of making them tax deductible (Tanzi and Davoodi, 1998).
462
Corruption
8500
In many countries there may be conflict between social custom and practice on the one hand and the letter of the law on the other. Many cultures rely on the giving of gifts as a symbol of a mutuality of interest. The dividing line between recognising a mutual obligation of support and doing favours expressly in exchange for a reward can be a fine one (Klitgaard, 1991). It is in part because of this ambiguity that some authors have argued that the definition of corruption should be refined to include a wider morality and allow for obligations to others (Palmier, 1983; Lewis, 1996). In everday use corruption is a term which conveys an element of moral disapproval. It represents an unwelcome deviation from some desired state of the world. Officials or politicians taking bribes are portrayed as ruthless and selfish people exploiting their office for their own private interests at the expense of the wider public good. It is implicit in most discussion of this kind that elimination of corrupt transactions would self-evidently improve welfare. Corruption in this kind of sense is widely recognized as a ‘problem’ in many countries today. Indices measuring the degree of corruption in the countries of the world are widely published: Business International and Political Risk Services publishes an annual index, International Country Risk Guide; see also Business International Corporation (1984). In an academic context corruption is a term used in many disciplines (including anthropology, sociology, politics, public administration and development studies) and can refer to a very wide diversity of activities and states of affairs. Shleifer and Vishny (1993), for example, ‘define government corruption as the sale by government officials of government property for personal gain’. But this is a much narrower definition of corruption than the classical authors of political theory such as Plato and Aristotle used (Bouckaert, 1996). For them, and for some more recent authors such as Andreski (1978), corruption was not so much a class of illegal practices as a kind of complete subversion to which states and civilisations were vulnerable. In this more classical sense corruption conveys the idea of wrecking or destroying institutions. The more recent use of the term does not have this same connotation, although authors differ widely in the moral content they give the term. For purposes of this review we take a ‘middle of the road’ view, by defining corruption more widely than Shleifer and Vishny but less broadly than Plato and Aristotle. We include private sector institutions but make rather little reference to the corruption by rulers of the basic machinery of the state.
2. The Literature on Corruption The literature on corruption is both vast and diverse. There is a journal (Corruption and Reform) which has been running since 1987 for which it
8500
Corruption
463
represents a focus of study, whilst a number of journals have devoted special issues to the subject, some recent examples being: Stato e Mercato (April 1992); Crime, Law and Social Change (1994-95); Informacion Comercial Espanola (May 1995); Indian Journal of Public Administration (July-September, 1995); European Journal on Criminal Policy and Research (vol 3(2), 1995); and Journal of Law and Society (March 1996). Over the past decade corruption has attracted attention also within the mainstream economics literature as theorists have become increasingly interested in the structure of organizations and agency problems. The impetus for the rapidly growing interest in corruption on the part of economists in recent years is usually traced back to the pioneering work of Rose-Ackerman (1975, 1978a). Texts on microeconomics and on the economics of organisations are increasingly likely to contain discussion of agency problems (Katz and Rosen, 1994) and even corruption itself (Brickley, Smith and Zimmerman, 1996). It is this strand of literature on which we focus here for the most part. In contemporary economics the notion of corruption is often used in a fairly narrow and technical way to refer to a particular type of opportunistic behaviour which rational agents will follow. In particular corruption results as a cooperative outcome in games involving three or more players, where two (or more) players can collude at the expense of a third party. Bribes to officials are thus readily explained as transactions in which both buyer and seller of a favour benefit at the expense of the organisation or hierarchy within which the official works. This same basic principal-agent model has many applications, such as to the ‘agency problems’ resulting from the divorce between ownership and control of firms. Lazy managers indulging their workers’ preferences for an easy life make life more agreeable for both the manager and the workers at the expense of the profits remaining for the firm’s shareholders (Katz and Rosen, 1994). Such behaviour is often described as collusion rather than as corruption, even though it meets most definitions of corruption (Tirole, 1986, 1992). A survey of the literature on corruption could be organised in many ways. It could be based on discipline or on the type of corruption or on dimensions of corruption such as causes and consequences. We opt here for organisation around various strands in the economics literature on the topic. Sections 3 and 4 set out a basic, or generic, model of corruption giving a flavour of contemporary work in the field. Section 5 explores the Public Choice approach. Section 6 explores some of the applications of corruption models to private sector firms. Section 7 reviews bureaucratic corruption and Section 8 concentrates on political corruption. Section 9 is concerned with ‘macro’ models of corruption which focus on the consequences of corruption for investment levels, growth rates and so on. Section 10 reviews policy to combat corruption. Section 11 reviews the analysis of corruption in LDCs and Section 12 concludes.
464
Corruption
8500
3. Basic Economic Analysis of Corruption A natural starting point for the economic analysis of corruption is to treat it as any other crime and to apply to it the standard economic model of crime developed originally in Becker (1968) and extended subsequently by many authors such as Polinsky and Shavell (1979, 1984). In this basic model the persons contemplating corruption take account of the expected benefits in the form of bribes, favours or payment in kind and compare the monetary equivalent of these gains with the expected costs in the form of a probability that they will be detected and the monetary sum (or equivalent) of the punishment should they be convicted. Such a formulation has close parallels with the application of the Becker model to the economics of tax evasion by Allingham and Sandmo (1972). Corruption is predicted to occur if the net expected gain is positive. The important element in corruption which is missing in the earlier applications of the Becker model is, of course, that both sides to a corrupt transaction are ususally committing a crime and not just one side. In the tax evasion model the taxpayer has private information not available to the tax official and all that is entailed analytically is a calculation on the part of the taxpayer as to whether, or how much of the information, to disclose. In a corruption model, each side has to be persuaded that it is worthwhile for both sides to collude in sharing information which will not be disclosed to third parties. A simple algebraic formulation helps crystalize ideas on this basic model and forms a useful base on which more sophisticated models can be constructed. We suppose that a citizen stands to enjoy a rent, R. The ‘rent’ can take a great many forms: it might be an unpaid tax liability, or avoidance of a term of imprisonment, or the supernormal profits from the receipt of monopoly rights and so on: it could be as simple as the gain from having a document processed. A bureaucrat (or regulator or politician or another citizen) is in a position to decide whether or not the rent is to be enjoyed by the citizen. In exchange for a bribe B the bureaucrat promises to bestow the monopoly right, to process the document or to keep the incriminating information secret or whatever. There is nevertheless a risk, in the form of a probability, p, known to both the citizen and the bureaucrat, that payment of the bribe will be detected by a third party in which case both parties to the corruption will be liable for punishment. For the citizen, discovery will mean liability to pay a fine F whilst for the bureaucrat it will mean liability to pay a fine G and to repay the bribe B. To keep the model simple, assume both parties are risk neutral so that the calculation of expected gains and losses need contain no reference to utility levels. Assume also that both parties to the corruption are sincere, so that we can ignore both the possibility that the citizen is trying to lure the bureaucrat
8500
Corruption
465
into an illegal act and also any fear the citizen might have that the bureaucrat will renege on the corrupt agreement and spill the beans after taking the bribe. For the citizen, payment of a bribe will be worthwhile iff: (1 ! p)(R ! B) ! p(F + B) > 0 (1) The first term refers to the case where the bribe goes undetected so that the citizen enjoys the rent net of the bribe paid. The second term refers to the case where the bribe is detected and the citizen, who has already paid a (non-recoverable) bribe, is fined for corruption. Condition (1) can be rearranged in the form of an upper bound, BU, on the size of bribe the citizen will find it worthwhile paying: (2) BU < R(1 ! p) ! pF For the bureaucrat, the calculation is that taking the bribe is worthwhile provided that: (1 ! p)B ! pG > 0, (3) where, again, the first term refers to the case where the bribe is undetected and the second term to the consequence of detection. We asume that the bureaucrat assigns the same value, p, to the probability of detection as does the citizen. The condition can then be rearranged in the form of a lower bound, BL, on the bribe which will induce the bureaucrat to conspire in the corruption: BL > pG / (1 ! p) (4) Corruption is assumed to occur in this simple model if there exists a bribe at which the citizen and the official both find themselves better off. This condition is satisfied if and only if the upper bound for the citizen exceeds the lower bound for the official, that is BU > BL. This is equivalent to the requirement that: R(1 ! p) ! pF > pG / (1 ! p), or that: R > [pG + pF(1 ! p)] / [(1 ! p)2] (5) The ‘enforcement parameters’ p, F and G describing the probability of detection and the size of the punishment, have to be viewed against the prospective gain to the citizen from corruption. Corruption occurs so long as the rent at stake is sufficiently large to offset the expected punishment.
466
Corruption
8500
4. Implications of the Basic Model Many of the main findings from the corruption literature are at least implicit in the formulation of the previous section, namely: 1. There is nothing to prevent a ‘rotten core’. Corruption will occur if the lower bound from (4) is below the upper bound on willingness to pay a bribe derived in (2). 2. As condition (5) indicates, this is equivalent to requiring that the rent at issue is sufficiently high relative to the parameters p, F and G defining the probability of detection and the punishment structure. In policy oriented models it is common to specify either the fines as related in some way to the size of the rent at issue and/or to consider a group of citizens across whom the value of R varies. In this way it is possible to model the extent of corruption rather than modelling a (binary) choice problem for an isolated citizen who either indulges in corruption or avoids it; 3. Increasing the fine for citizens, F, will tend to reduce corruption since it raises the cost of detection and thus reduces the net pay-off from corruption: BU falls while BL remains constant; 4. Likewise for the penalty, G, imposed on officials: this time BL rises while B U remains constant, with the result that corruption again becomes less profitable; 5. Increasing the probability of detection, p, simultaneously reduces BL and raises BU and thus erodes the difference (BU ! BL) on which corruption depends; 6. There is in the transaction at least some of the character of a bilateral monopoly, so long as neither side can readily contact alternative buyers or sellers. The size of the bribe may thus be indeterminate, requiring the introduction of some assumption about the bargaining which will take place between the citizen and the bureaucrat; 7. Introducing competition into the model, for example through allowing the citizen to canvass a range of (corruptible) bureaucrats, may result in Bertrand competition between officials driving bribes down to the competitive level. Corrupt officials try to attract bribes by offering more attractive or cheaper terms than their competitors with the result that the bribe gets driven down close to zero (Shleifer and Vishny, 1993). We consider some of these findings and further extensions in sections below concerned with more sophisticated models of corruption. One obvious extension is to consider the monetary cost to the bureaucrat of being detected not just in the form of a court-imposed fine, but as putting at risk the bureaucrat’s pension rights and any wage premium (relative to available
8500
Corruption
467
alternative job openings) she is earning as a bureaucrat (see Becker and Stigler, 1974). A second line of development is to introduce a layer of officials (supervisors or auditors) whose responsibility is to detect corruption by ‘front-line’ officials. In these multi-tier hierarchies it is possible to specify different kinds of ‘supervisory technology’ and to distinguish ‘systemic’ corruption from corruption specific to a single tier (Bac, 1998). Another extension is to consider corruption in a dynamic model rather than in a purely static way. Individuals who sense that corruption is potentially profitable for them may seek to ‘regularize’ corrupt arrangements so as to minimize the risk of being surprised by detection and to reduce transactions costs to a minimum. The systematic corruption of police by organized criminals can be interpreted in this way as can various political arrangements, including bureaucratic corruption in the ‘old Soviet’ type of economy (Shleifer and Vishny, 1992). From a policy perspective the central question to which this basic model can most readily be applied is the choice of an optimal level of resources to put into the detection of corruption and the choice of an optimal fine. As in other areas, the tendency of this optimal law enforcement model, as pioneered by Becker (1968) and reviewed recently by Garoupa (1997), is to produce solutions suggesting high, possibly maximal, fines and comparatively low probabilities of detection. There are two reasons why these sorts of results tend to emerge. First, fines represent transfer payments rather than real resource costs so that, other things equal, it is usually judged better to rely on the deterrent power of the fine rather than on a high probability of being caught (Polinsky and Shavell, 1984). Secondly, in an area such as corruption where the incentives to report the crime are small, if not non-existent, it is likely to be extremely costly to raise the probability of detection significantly. One drawback of this model, albeit one which is shared by most models of corruption, is the difficulty of collecting empirical data which could be used to test it. The probability of detection, for example, would require information about the proportion of offences involving corruption in which an individual is detected and convicted. But one of the central features of corruption is that it is, in essence, a cooperative venture which both participants have every incentive to keep secret. It is thus extremely difficult to identify either particular instances of it or its extent in aggregate. From an analytical perspective the question becomes one of how individuals might construct or update (subjective) estimates of probabilities in such circumstances, a matter which is discussed in some of the literature on information, and particularly on the value of message services (see ch. 5 of Hirshleifer and Riley, 1992). There are very obvious parallels with the analysis of the ‘underground’ or
468
Corruption
8500
‘black’ economy: ingenious indirect methods may be used to make estimates of how widespread are the transactions at issue, but nobody really knows (Pyle, 1992).
5. Corruption and Public Choice Whilst the analysis of behaviour under uncertainty has provided a comparatively straightforward line of approach, as we have shown in the previous two sections, there has been a parallel line of intellectual enquiry which has also been influential in the development of our understanding of corruption. The application of economic reasoning to public bodies and political processes has resulted in the development of an analysis of government and bureaucracy which stresses the critical role played by individual interests and objectives in the shaping of these institutions. The formulation of ideas which came to be known as the theory of public choice showed a recognition that public policy could not be thought of simply as the pursuit by pure-minded automata of ‘the public interest’ but rather represented the outcome of decisions by individuals (be they politicians, bureaucrats or interest groups) with their own interests and their own agenda. Early analyses in this vein were the work of Downs (1957) on the motives of politicians and of Niskanen (1974) on bureaucrats. The ‘public choice’ approach emphasizes the role played by the private interests of all the players involved in the formulation and execution of policy. For surveys of the public choice approach see Mueller (1979), or Cullis and Jones (1992). The capture of politicians by interest groups is studied by Becker (1983). Corruption is something which fits very naturally into a picture of the world in which politicians, bureaucrats and citizens are all busily searching for strategies for pursuing their own private motives at the expense of others, whether they be taxpayers, other citizens or whatever. It might be noted also that principal-agent models of the kind reviewed in Section 2 above are quite close in spirit to the Public Choice approach, although they tend to a higher degree of abstraction. The analysis of rent seeking provides a fertile ground for creating a motivation for corruption. Standard references on rent seeking are Tullock (1967), Kreuger (1974), Posner (1975), Bhagwati (1982) and Tollison (1982). For applications of rent-seeking to corruption see Blomqvist and Mohammad (1986) and Mbaku (1992). Rational individuals assumed to be maximizing their own net benefits without further reference to ethical constraints may come to regard corruption almost as a moral imperative. The individual seeking monopoly rights will probably consider corruption as a possible substitute for (or complement to) other tactics such as political lobbying or capturing bureaucrats. Corruption comes then to be chosen if it represents part
8500
Corruption
469
of a cost-minimizing strategy. A natural extension of this rent-seeking approach to the analysis of corruption is suggested in Bowles (1998) in which a citizen seeking rents considers various possible ‘pathways’ to achieve her goal. The more pathways there are, the more opportunity there is to acquire the rent at a lower cost, such as corrupting an official or a politician or whatever may be regarded as alternatives to seeking the rents through some ‘legitimate’ channel such as legislative change or the exercise of an official’s discretion. Are there any limits to this pursuit of individual self interest other than possibly rather ineffective external controls? Is corruption inevitable if it pays? Just about the only device through which any such limits can be imposed is to suppose that individuals may incur some subjective costs or ‘stigma’ when acting dishonestly. This approach borrows the term coined by analysts seeking to explain apparently irrational instances of honesty in other spheres, as in Akerlof (1980) and Benjamini and Maital (1985). It may look contrived, but it is often the only practicable way of filling the ‘moral vacuum’ created by the economic approach and explaining why people may desist from corruption even when it appears ‘profitable’.
6. Private Sector Corruption Within what one might term the ‘purely private’ sector, corruption has been studied rather less than its public sector counterpart, although that is not necessarily a reason for supposing that it is less widespread than in the public sector. A private sector engineering contractor, for example, may find it expedient to pay bribes to a prospective private sector buyer for just the same reasons they pay bribes to government officials or politicians. Data deficiencies are particularly acute in this field, since it is only really from reports of court cases that remotely reliable evidence is likely to emerge. Whilst a public body might seek to publicize anti-corruption efforts and successes to demonstrate a tough anti-corruption policy, the private firm might prefer to resolve matters away from the public eye in order to avoid the bad publicity and loss of reputation which disclosures of corruption might bring. There are many different forms corruption in the private sector can take: we review a brief selection here. Insider trading scandals occur from time to time on most of the major financial markets, and they sometimes involve corruption. The insider, say the accountant of a major company or a senior executive of the firm who has seen the firm’s provisional profit results, holds information which when published will, or at least might, move the firm’s share price. Rather than trade in the shares herself, the accountant or executive might contemplate selling the relevant information to a third party who is in a position to make profitable,
470
Corruption
8500
but less obvious, use of it by buying or selling shares in the firm. Any such sale of information would be regarded in most countries as corrupt, even though there are some economists who would regard such transactions as being conducive of market efficiency for the most part, and would argue that the main beneficiaries of a prohibition of a ban on insider information are financial market professionals rather than the firm’s shareholders (Manne, 1966; Baye, 1997). Valuation of goods, services or assets is clearly an area where there is scope for corruption. The valuer can ‘create a rent’ by overvaluing an item, since the owner of the item might stand to gain in creditworthiness as a result or might get a better price if selling the item. This creates an opportunity for collusion between the owner and the valuer of the item at the expense of the buyer. Examples of this kind of collusion can be found in markets for sports players, where the manager of a club buying a player takes a bribe from the club selling a player (or from the player’s agent) to overestimate the player’s value. They can be found also in the financial markets where a stock analyst is entertained lavishly by a firm hoping that the analyst will publish a positive report about the prospects for the firm’s share price. In a somewhat similar vein was the ‘payola’ scandal in which record companies used to pay bribes to DJs for playing records by the company’s artists on the radio. Pechlivanos (1995) refers to the example of the American Honda Motor Company whose managers received kickbacks from prospective franchisees. Andvig’s study (1995) of the North Sea Oil industry makes use of reports from six trials in the British courts of so-called ‘information brokers’. Ten of the thirteen defendants in these trials were found guilty: punishments ranged from six months to three years in prison plus fines and compensation orders from about £40,000 to £500,000. Spending on the procurement of equipment for the North Sea is very high, at around £13 billion per annum. Those involved in the award of contracts for the supply of this equpiment have information about bids and tenders which is potentially of substantial value to the firms competing for supply contracts. Monopoly power is likely to be a pre-condition for private sector corruption. A well informed competitive market will leave little room for it since, at least in the longer run, corrupt firms will have higher costs and thus be unable to survive. But a privatized utility might, for example, enjoy a local monopoly in the provision of some service. It is quite imaginable that the employee of the utility will exploit this monopoly for private gain, say, by arranging connection to a power or telephone network unusually quickly for a premium. A number of commentators in the literature on privatization have, indeed, argued that the elimination of waste and inefficiency on the part of public utilities requires not only a transfer of assets from public to private hands but also the introduction of elements of competition to break down the
8500
Corruption
471
local monopoly power which is what enables the utilitity’s employees to ‘hold up’ their customers (Kay and Thompson, 1986).
7. Bureaucratic Corruption Public sector bureaucracies often have considerable powers and areas of discretion: they are often in a monopoly supply position and their employees are often tempted to make strategic use of these advantages for their own ends. Anecdotes are legion. There is the immigration official checking papers who can be persuaded with a $20 tip to ignore some real or imaginary inconsistency. There are ships which cannot enter certain ports until they supply customs officials with amounts of whisky and cigarettes as spelled out on a schedule sent in advance of their arrival. There are hospitals in some countries where patients cannot get drugs without paying bribes to staff. And so on. A hard-bitten economist, or world traveller for that matter, would think it naive to imagine anything else. Even the less cynical would agree that there are dangers that the pursuit of the ideal of public interest might sometimes slip in favour of the pursuit by bureaucrats of their private goals. It is perhaps inevitable then that public administration should have a rather tainted reputation when it comes to corruption. But as the examples above illustrate, in many cases the corruption is not an occasional lapse by an official but a deeply-embedded modus vivendi. We consider in this section two particular areas of bureacracy where allegations are often made and a good deal has been written. 7.1 Corruption of Tax Officials Tax evasion has been widely studied, and it has for long been known that tax administrations are particularly vulnerable to collusion between taxpayers who underdeclare their income and tax officials who may be bribed to overlook these underdeclarations when reporting to the tax authority. As we remarked in Section 1 above, corruption of this kind was the motivation for the development of ‘tax farming’ from the days of the Greek and Roman empires until comparitively recently. To give a sense of how deep-seated tax corruption might be, Chu (1990) reports the results of a 1981 survey by the city government of Taipei in which 94 percent of the taxpayers polled admitted to paying off tax officials in exchange for collusion in tax evasion. Interviews with the group of accountants involved in the preparation of tax returns appeared to confirm that taxpayer dishonesty was widespread and that almost a half of the tax officials with whom the accountants dealt would actively solicit payoff.
472
Corruption
8500
Contemporary models of corruption of tax administration are usually constructed in two stages. At stage 1, the taxpayer makes a declaration of income following the standard Allingam and Sandmo (1972) approach, that is by comparing the expected costs and benefits of declaring different proportions of true income. The tax administration, meanwhile, selects an audit probability for the taxpayer (which may be declaration-dependent) to maximize its revenue net of the costs of audit. In the Graetz-Reinganum-Wilde (1986) model, a Nash equilibrium is established which makes the policies followed by the taxpayer and the tax administration mutually compatible. At stage 2 the possibility is introduced that the tax auditor can suppress the result of audits and thereby shield the taxpayer from a penalty for underdeclaring income (Cadot, 1987; Chander and Wilde, 1992). The auditor who chooses to take a bribe herself runs the risk of detection. The tax administration thus has two layers of auditing: audit of the taxpayer and audit of the auditors. Auditing of either kind is costly, and the administration’s problem is to figure out how best to split its resources between the two kinds of audit work. Models of this kind are inevitably rather complex, since there are many sets of assumptions the analyst can make and there are many interactions which can be explored. For example the split of the taxpayer’s gain from underdeclaration between the taxpayer and the auditor can be treated as exogenous, as in Chander and Wilde (1992) but is endogenized in other models such as Virmani (1987), Goswami, Sanyal and Gang (1991) and Besley and Maclaren (1993) (see also Flatters and MacLeod, 1995 and Toma and Toma, 1992). Despite their analytical sophistication, these models gloss over many important practical problems. The ease with which tax auditors can be investigated, for example, will depend on the quality of information and record keeping. If taxpayer files can be (strategically) lost, if tax auditors have discretion about which taxpayer returns to investigate or if the auditor is subject to influence via the political system, then the model misses important interactions. But this demonstrates simply that the tax official has to maintain a delicate balance between various forces. The contemporary models have made a good start on modelling this tension, but there remains plenty of scope for ‘fine tuning’. Tirole (1996), for example, has developed a model in which a reputation for corruption may be difficult to shake off, and this is a development which might have an interesting application in the tax field. 7.2 Police Corruption Police enjoy the same privilege as tax officials, namely access to public resources with which to investigate illegal activities or earnings which individuals wish to keep secret. The temptations to collude in keeping the secret may be very great and there have undoubtedly been occasions when
8500
Corruption
473
police corruption has been widespread. An early economic study of corruption was the work of Becker and Stigler (1974) who had been asked to find ways of reducing corruption amongst Chicago police (for a recent summary of their work see Brickley, Smith and Zimmerman, 1996). Models of police corruption can be distinguished by whether they deal with ‘one-off’ or repeated incidents of corruption. Bowles and Garoupa (1997), for example, treat ‘casual’ police corruption as a one-shot game, involving isolated instances of a citizen and a police officer who are strangers to each other. There are many instances, however, where it is alleged that corruption is not of a ‘one off’ kind but is more deeply embedded in a continuing relationship. Schelling (1967) gives as an example an illegal wire-service gambling syndicate in Miami. Regular payments were made to police not only in respect of protection of syndicate members from arrest but also in exchange for systematic intimidation by police of bookmakers outside the syndicate. Another example is the illegal drugs market where producers and suppliers may establish a regular working relationship with enforcement agents (see Klitgaart, 1988, and Lupsha, 1991). These dynamic elements call for a repeat play treatment. There are interesting parallels between continuing corrupt relationships and the discussion of alternative forms of contracting between firms using the notion of transactions costs (Williamson, 1979; Deakin and Michie, 1997). Corruption cannot be supported by legally enforceable contracts and yet corrupt agents are clearly able to sustain viable long-term relationships.
8. Political Corruption The powers of government to create and/or to protect rents have been a rich source of study for those interested in corruption. It was Lord Acton who famously claimed that ‘Power tends to corrupt and absolute power corrupts absolutely’. The power to enact legislation carries with it the possibility of creating rents. The prospect for the amoral individual of being able to participate in the processes by which rents are created and distributed may express itself in a wide variety of ways, some at least of which can be regarded as corrupt. Abuse of this power has occurred frequently, most notably with monarchs and autocratic (often military) governments rather than with democratic governments. Kings in mediaeval England, for example, would grant trading and many other monopolies simply to raise cash for their own purposes, whether noble or otherwise. Similar sorts of claims have sometimes been made about socialist economies and about countries with military governments. For review of these and other issues in the sphere of political corruption (see
474
Corruption
8500
Amuwo, 1986; Benson, 1978, Brooks, 1978 and other contributors to Heidenheimer, 1978; and Coldham, 1995). In a modern democracy politicians are not usually in a position to be able to enact legislation purely for their own private benefit. But they may be able to wield influence over the legislative process, and such influence makes them vulnerable to corruption by those groups who will be affected. The asking of leading questions in the legislature and the exploitation of membership of influential committees or subcommittees are two of the more obvious ways of exerting pressure on the shape of legislation. The corruption element obviously arises when the politician ‘sells’ this influence to an interested party. The grey area between explicit selling of influence and more subtle routes through which influence can be exploited is sometimes referred to as ‘sleaze’. It is in an effort to counter this kind of sleaze which has prompted the Nolan Committee to press for greater disclosure of the outside interests of British Members of Parliament. Consultancies and sponsorship can significantly undermine the credibility of the claim by politicians that they are pursuing the public interest. The power to enforce legislation is likewise open to manipulation and abuse. Governments make decisions all the time about the public resources to be made available for the agencies responsible for enforcing legislation. Influence over the way the resources are used and over agency priorities will often have a market value since a greater intensity of enforcement is likely to be of advantage to some party. Pressure for law enforcement is, of itself, entirely legitimate. But if the pressure is wielded in return for payments of some kind then we have corruption. The power to influence public sector contracting with the private sector for the provision of goods and services is an area where corruption is sometimes alleged to occur. In large-scale civil engineering projects, ‘political factors’ sometimes play a role in deciding which contractor gets the job as well as more traditional criteria such as tender price or track record. Giving a role to such factors is a way of creating a space for political influence to carry weight and thus a market value. In effect it is allowing the politician to collude with outside interests against the bureaucrats responsible for procurement. It thus creates the possibility of corruption since it gives the outsider the incentive to bribe the politician to wield power over the bureaucrat (Becker, 1983). This is a subtly different form of corruption from the one considered in the ‘regulatory capture’ tradition in which the regulator (the bureaucrat) and the outside interest collude against the politician or the public interest. Collusion between regulators and regulated industries, in the form of regulatory capture, against the interests of consumers and/or taxpayers has been explored by Stigler (1971), Peltzman (1976) and many others. Corruption in this context, as elsewhere, could range from the payment of cash bribes through to
8500
Corruption
475
regulators expecting employment in the regulated industry on retirement from the public service: the ‘revolving doors’ arrangement, on which see Adams (1981) and Breyer and Steward (1979). The expanding literature on public sector procurement has concerned itself with the structure of contracts and incentives in these ‘hierarchical’ models, where there are three or more parties involved and a number of forms collusion could take. The standard theoretical work in microeconomics in this area is Laffont and Tirole (1993), which draws on earlier work on multilevel hierarchies by Tirole (1986, 1992), Laffont (1990) and Koffman and Lawarree (1993).
9. Consequences of Corruption Many ‘macro’ studies of corruption have been concerned with the causes and consequences of corruption at an aggregate level. These studies can be thought of as complements to, rather than as alternatives to, the essentially micro models of behaviour reviewed here thus far. The consequences of corruption have been widely discussed and authors have reached widely differing conclusions. The conventional wisdom is that corruption is harmful, and for some authors this seems almost self-evidently to be the case. A recent paper, for example, Tanzi and Davoodi (1998) carries the title ‘Road to Nowhere: How Corruption in Public Investment Hurts Growth’ (see further Alam, 1990; Ades and Di Tella, 1995, 1998; Mauro, 1995, 1998, and Klitgaard, 1998). The general thrust of the argument is that corruption harms growth by reducing the incentives to invest. This distorts the allocation of resources and leads to underinvestment and poor growth rates. Some authors, however, argue that corruption may be as good a device for screening projects as anything else. In this view the most profitable amongst a group of competing projects will generate the greatest possible bribe and thus have the best chance of succeeding. The only difference is that most of the monopoly profits are appropriated by the corrupt persons choosing between the projects rather than by the firms proposing them. More technically, this ‘neutrality’ view suggests that corruption is not inefficient but may redistribute income. Yet others argue that corruption may be positively beneficial (Leff, 1964). Corrupt bureaucrats who respond to payments for services rendered may work harder and process matters more quickly than they would if they relied purely on their public services salary. But it should be stressed that this is rather a minority view. Even if the outcomes of selection processes for projects will be the same whether or not corruption occurs, it is more efficient to use an honest
476
Corruption
8500
procedure because of the resource costs of secrecy. Bribes themselves may be only transfer payments and thus irrelevant from an allocative perspective, but real resources are involved in arranging and protecting bribe offers, and these represent real costs which could be avoided. Making corruption illegal raises the costs of corruption and thus some of the rents potentially created by projects get dissipated by rent-seeking behaviour (Shleifer and Vishny, 1993). There are parallels with the continuing debate about the resource costs of rentseeking more generally: see for example the debate about how transfers are treated in cost-benefit analysis, about how the costs of crime are to be treated and about the distortion of the results of cost-benefit analysis by vested interests in the decision-making processes of government (see Weingast, Shepsle and Johnsen, 1981; Lee, 1983; Lewin and Trumbell, 1993; McChesney, 1993, and Jones and Cullis, 1996). As well as theoretical arguments about corruption being harmful, there has been some empirical literature pointing in the same direction. Mauro (1995), using data for a wide cross-section of countries, argues that, holding income constant, countries with higher rates of corruption (as measured by the standard business indicators of corruption referred to above) have a lower ratio of both total and private sector investment to income. Tanzi and Davoodi (1998) take a rather different tack in arguing that countries with high levels of corruption will engage in particularly high rates of public investment, and will be particularly subject to low rates of return on these investments. The argument is that corruption may encourage projects which are inefficient but rewarding to corrupt politicians.
10. Control of Corruption When it comes to measures to control corruption, results tend to be dictated by the structure of the model of behaviour employed. Nevertheless there are a number of recurring strands in discussion of the strategies which can be used to combat corruption. The basic principal-agent model of corruption rather naturally inclines to the search for ‘top-down’ solutions. The victim in these models is the principal (the government) and the corrupt parties are bureaucrats and citizens. Principals who suspect themselves to be vulnerable to ‘agency problems’ can, speaking in general, take various kinds of defensive action (Ross, 1973; Grossman and Hart, 1983; and Hirshleifer and Riley, 1992). The ‘Mechanism Design’ literature invites the principal to design a grand scheme of things which anticipates the corrupt behaviour and makes it unprofitable. This scheme is implemented through contracts for bureaucrats which are constructed in a way which would make it irrational for the bureaucrat to take
8500
Corruption
477
bribes (Lui, 1986; Cadot, 1987; and Mookherjee and Png, 1995). Methods for ‘designing corruption out of the system’ have long been sought. The ‘selling the store’ solution (see Rasmusen, 1994) is a rather extreme example, but has relevant historical parallels in the use of ‘tax farming’ contracts by tax revenue departments for many centuries. The literature also recognizes that there are some circumstances in which it will either be infeasible to prevent corruption (Koffman and Lawarree, 1993) or non-optimal (Olsen and Torsvik, undated). A second common theme is the use of auditing methods to monitor the quality of the reporting behaviour of agents in hierarchies. Many tax and police authorities have a ‘vigilance’ or ‘special investigations’ branch with the express task of identifying and pursuing corrupt officers. This approach has its drawbacks because most of the factors which encourage ‘front line’ officers to behave corruptly apply equally when it comes to an auditing tier. The audit reveals potentially valuable information which someone is prepared to pay bribes to suppress (Border and Sobell, 1987). Likewise, if corruption is endemic within an institution then it is likely that any findings of corruption will be liable to suppression (see Bac, 1996a, 1996b, 1998). An early application of this approach is the argument of Becker and Stigler (1974) that by paying police a salary higher than the prevailing market wage it would be possible to create an incentive on the part of officers to retain their job. In such an environment, the prospect of being found guilty of taking bribes acts as a powerful threat since it would result in loss, over the rest of the officer’s career, of the rents created by the wage premium. The excess supply of prospective police officers this premium would cause is dealt with by ‘selling’ the posts. This payment can be interpreted as a bond posted by the officer: the honest officer keeps the bond in the form of a premium wage whilst the dishonest officer forfeits it. A third theme which recurs quite commonly is the introduction of competition as a means of attacking corruption. In this view, corruption is fostered wherever there is a single source of supply. By opening up alternatives, the capacity of the bureaucrat or tax official to hold up the citizen is reduced and the willingness to pay bribes correspondingly lowered. This might entail opening ‘multiple windows’, so that a citizen can contact a different official if the first one tries to elicit a bribe (Shleifer and Vishny, 1993). It might equally entail opening up an economy to foreign trade in order to prevent a domestic producer wielding monopoly power (Ades and Di Tella, 1995). A fourth theme is the use of administrative devices within organisations to discourage corruption. Many police and tax departments have a policy of moving officers around quite frequently in order to prevent them from becoming too familiar with an area. In terms of the relational contracting literature this can be interpreted as an effort to raise the transactions costs of dealing corruptly rather than honestly. By frequently disrupting the pattern it
478
Corruption
8500
may be possible, at the cost of having to give on-the-job training more frequently, to impose higher ‘set-up’ costs on those wishing to corrupt officers.
11. Corruption in LDCs In their folklore at least, many developing countries experience substantial corruption. Many contributions have been made by sociologists and other policy analysts (including some work by economists) to what has become a substantial literature on the subject of corruption in LDCs: for general reviews see Beenstock (1979), Winston (1979), Macrae (1982), Jagannathan (1986, 1988), Andvig (1989), Ward (1989), Alam (1989, 1990, 1995) and Charlick (1992). An obvious question, of course, is whether there is anything about corruption in developing countries to distinguish it from corruption elswehere. The short answer to this is probably no: the institutions involved are the same (business, bureaucracies and governments) and the incentives for the individuals concerned are similar. The same kind of analysis can thus, at least in principle, be applied. But this is probably too glib. There are special reasons why corruption in LDCs is of particular concern and there are also reasons why it may take a rather different form and may impose greater costs than its counterpart in the North. Development aid has in many cases been diverted for their own private use by corrupt politicians and bureaucrats. Partly as a defensive measure against criticisms from the taxpayers funding aid budgets, a quest for ‘good governance’ is now high on the priority list of many international agencies, and anti-corruption programmes have become an essential item for many of the poorer countries (see, for example, United Nations, 1989; World Bank, 1992; Doig, 1995). This quest can be problematic, however. There are some countries where corruption has become deeply embedded, in part as a response to very low civil service salaries. Just to survive and support their families, officials may need to moonlight or to take bribes. Clearly any serious effort to reduce corruption in such an environment can only work if part of the policy is to raise civil service salary levels. But this tends to raise public expenditure and, other things equal, may intensify what is already a serious debt problem. One could argue, therefore, that in countries where it is difficult to raise money through taxes to pay officials a little bribery is no bad thing because it is one way of getting citizens to support public sector officials. This is not a very attractive argument to economists looking for first best equilibria or to moral crusaders but it probably helps explain why corruption is sometimes tolerated. A further reason for treating corruption as a ‘special’ problem for LDCs is that institutional differences resulting from different cultural and political
8500
Corruption
479
traditions can create some ambiguity about the definition of corruption. Critics have argued that much of the literature of the 1950s and 1960s was judgmental and morally critical, and that care is needed when studying corruption in LDCs to avoid an ethnocentric view in which corruption is viewed as an aberration of post-colonial societies which would eventually disappear as these countries evolved towards a more Western form (Clarke, 1983; Werner, 1983; and Lewis, 1996). Many of the studies have been concerned with particular countries or regions: Kaufer (1989), Kennedy (1989), Sands (1989, 1990), Kolenda (1990); Rocca (1992), and Wong (1992)on China; Halayya (1985), Goswami, Sanyal and Gang, 1991), Wade (1982) on India; Carino (1986) and Gleason (1995) on Asia; Grayson (1984) on Mexico; Maingot (1994) on the Southern Hemisphere; Werlin (1973) and Le Vine (1975) on Ghana; Amuwo (1986) on Niger; Reno (1995) on Sierra Leone; Ouma (1991) on Uganda; Gould (1980) and Szeftel (1983) on Zaire; Makumbe (1994) on Zimbabwe; Ekpo (1979) on Sub-Saharan Africa and Kotecha and Adams (1981), Theobald (1993) and Mbaku (1994) on Africa more generally.
12. Concluding Remarks Corruption is a very widespread phenomenon and takes a great variety of forms. It is difficult, for this reason, to define very exactly. It is also something which is very difficult to prevent. It is illegal virtually everywhere, in some of its forms, but its victims often are unaware that it is taking place. Both parties to a corrupt transaction have an incentive to avoid disclosure since both will usually have been acting illegally. Thus, even establishing that it has occurred may be very costly. Even when corruption is suspected it is very often difficult to adduce legally convincing evidence since parties to corrupt transactions can comparatively easily cover their tracks by using tactics which offer ambiguity and are susceptible to multiple explanations. It is not, however, in any respect a ‘victimless crime’. Analytically, corruption has been of great interest to economic theorists in recent years because it is an archetypal problem of asymmetric information involving collusion between agents and ‘outsiders’ against principals, or between supervisors and agents against principals. Most of the models up to now have been essentially static, but recent papers have shown that there is a real prospect of developing dynamic models which can explain the persistence of corruption. Much of the future for application of these models will probably be in the fields of the economic analysis of the operation of government and political institutions. But corruption remains an area which will continue to be
480
Corruption
8500
of interest to scholars of law and economics because it raises fascinating issues about the enforcement of law in the broadest sense.
Acknowledgments The author gratefully acknowledges detailed and constructive comments on an earlier draft from three referees. The usual disclaimer applies.
Bibliography on Corruption (8500) Adams, G. (1981), The Politics of Defense Contracting - The Iron Triangle, New Brunswick, NJ, Transaction. Adams, G. (1991), Odious Debts - Loose Lending, Corruption and the Third World’s Environmental Legacy, London, Earthscan Publications. Adediji, O. (1991), ‘Role of Government in Bureaucratic Corruption in the Case of Politicisation of the Civil Service’, 25 Quarterly Journal of Admininistration, 208-219. Ades, A. and Di Tella, R. (1995), Competition and Corruption, 169 Applied Economics Discussion Paper, University of Oxford, UK. Ades, A. and Di Tella, R. (1998), ‘National Champions and Corruption: Some Unpleasant Interventionist Arithmetic’, 108 Economic Journal. Alam, M. Shahid (1989), ‘Anatomy of Corruption: An Approach to the Political Economy of Underdevelopment’, 48 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 441-456. Alam, M. Shahid (1990), ‘Some Economic Costs of Corruption in LDCs’, 27 Journal of Development Studies, 89-97. Alam, M. Shahid (1995), ‘A Theory of Limits on Corruption and Some Applications’, 48 Kyklos, 419-435. Alatas, S.H. (1990), Corruption - its Nature, Causes and Functions, Aldershot, Avebury. Ali, S. (1985), Corruption: a Third World Perspective, Lahore, Aziz Publishers. Amuwo, K. (1986), ‘Military-Inspired Anti-Bureaucratic Corruption Campaigns: an Appraisal of Niger’s Experience’, 24 Journal of Modern African Studies, 285-301. Andreski, S. (1978), ‘Kleptocracy as a System of Government in Africa’, in Heidenheimer, Arnold J., Jophnson, Michael and Le Vine, Victor (eds), Political Corruption: A Handbook, New Brunswick, NJ, Transaction Press. Andvig, Jens C. (1989), ‘Korrupsjon i Utviklingsland (Corruption in Developing Countries)’, 23 Nordisk Tidsskrift für Politisk Ekonomi, 51-70. Andvig, Jens C. (1991), ‘The Economics of Corruption: A Survey’, 46 Studi Economici, 57-94. Andvig, Jens C. (1995), ‘Corruption in the North Sea Oil Industry: Issues and Assessments’, 23 Crime, Law and Social Change, 289-313. Andvig, Jens C. and Moene, Karl Ove (1990), ‘How Corruption May Corrupt’, 13 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 63-76. Anechiarico, F. and Jacobs, James B. (1994), ‘Visions of Corruption Control and the Evolution of American Public Administration’, 54 Public Administration Review, 465-473.
8500
Corruption
481
Antoci, Angelo and Sacco, Pier Luigi (1995), ‘A Public Contracting Evolutionary Game with Corruption’, 61 Journal of Economics (Zeitschrift für Nationalökonomie), 89-122. Bac, M. (1996a), ‘Corruption and Supervision Costs in Hierarchies’, 22 Journal of Comparative Economics, 99-118. Bac, M. (1996b), ‘Corruption, Supervision and the Structure of Hierarchies’, 12 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization. Bac, M. (1998), ‘The Scope, Timing, and Type of Corruption’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics. Banfield, Edward C. (1975), ‘Corruption as a Feature of Governmental Organization’, 18 Journal of Law and Economics, 587-605. Basu, Kaushik, Bhattacharya, Sudipto and Mishra, Ajit (1992), ‘Notes on Bribery and the Control of Corruption’, 48 Journal of Public Economics, 349-359. Beck, P.J. and Maher, M.W. (1986), ‘A Comparison of Bribery and Bidding in Thin Markets’, 20 Economics Letters, 1-5. Beenstock, Michael (1979), ‘Corruption and Development’, 7 World Development, 15-24. Benson, Bruce L. (1981), ‘A Note on Corruption of Public Officials: The Black Market for Property Rights’, 5 Journal of Libertarian Studies, 305-311. Benson, Bruce L. (1988a), ‘An Institutional Explanation for Corruption of Criminal Justice Officials’, 8 Cato Journal, 139-163. Benson, Bruce L. (1988b), ‘Corruption in Law Enforcement: One Consequence of ‘The Tragedy of the Commons’ Arising with Public Allocation Processes’, 8 International Review of Law and Economics, 73-84. Benson, Bruce L. and Baden, John (1985), ‘The Political Economy of Government Corruption: The Logic of Underground Government’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 391-410. Benson, Bruce L. and Rasmussen, David W. (1995), Illicit Drugs and Crime, Independent Policy Report, Oakland, Independent Institute. Benson, G.C.S. (1978), Political Corruption in America, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Besley, T. and McClaren, J. (1993), ‘Taxes and Bribery: the Role of Wage Incentives’, 103 Economic Journal, 119-141. Blomqvist, Ake and Mohammad, Sharif (1986), ‘Controls, Corruption, and Competitive Rent Seeking in LDCs’, 21 Journal of Development Economics, 161-180. Bouckaert, Boudewijn (1996), ‘Political Corruption’, Sept. 96 Mimeo. Bowles, Roger A. (1998), ‘Minimising Corruption in Tax Affairs’, in Sandford, Cedric (ed.), More Key Issues in Tax Reform, Bath, Fiscal Publications. Bowles, Roger A. and Garoupa, Nuno (1997), ‘Casual Police Corruption and the Economics of Crime’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 85-87. Brenner, Reuven (1994), Labyrinths of Prosperity, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press. Brooks, R.C. (1978), ‘The Nature of Political Corruption’, in Heidenheimer, Arnold J., Jophnson, Michael and Le Vine, Victor (eds), Political Corruption: A Handbook, New Brunswick, NJ, Transaction Press. Buscaglia, Edgardo (1995), ‘Judicial Reform in Latin America: The Obstacles Ahead’, 4 Journal of Latin American Affairs, 8-16. Cadot, Olivier (1987), ‘Corruption as a Gamble’, 33 Journal of Public Economics, 223-244. Carino, Ledivina V. (ed.) (1986), Bureaucratic Corruption in Asia: Causes, Consequences, and Controls, Quezon City, Philippines, JMC Press.
482
Corruption
8500
Chander, Parkash and Wilde, Louis L. (1992), ‘Corruption in Tax Administration’, 49 Journal of Public Economics, 333-349. Chang, Ching Hsi (1995), ‘Party Enterprises, Members’ Ethics, and Party Corruption: An Application of the Rotten Kid Theorem (In Chinese, with English summary)’, 23 Taiwan Economic Review, 25-42. Charlick, R. (1992), ‘Combatting Corruption in an Era of Political Liberalization - Implications for Donor Agencies’, 7 Corruption and Reform, 283 ff. Chu, C.Y.C. (1990), ‘Income Tax Evasion with Venal Tax Officials - the Case of Developing Countries’, 45 Public Finance, 392-408. Clarke, M. (ed.) (1983), Corruption: Causes, Consequences and Control, London, Frances Pinter. Clutterbuck, R. (1995), Drugs, Crime and Corruption: Thinking the Unthinkable, Basingstoke, Macmillan. Coldham, S. (1995), ‘Legal Responses to State Corruption in Commonwealth Africa’, 39 Journal of African Law, 115-126. Dernburg, Thomas F. (1992), ‘A Note on Data Corruption and Monetary Fiscal Policy Regimes’, 16 Journal of Economics and Finance, 147-153. Dey, Harendra Kanti (1989), ‘The Genesis and Spread of Economic Corruption: A Microtheoretic Interpretation’, 17 World Development, 503-511. Deysine, A. (1980), ‘Political Corruption: a Review of the Literature’, 8 European Journal of Political Research, 447-462. Doig, A. (1995), ‘Good Government and Sustainable Anti-corruption Strategies: a Role for Independent Anti-Corruption Agencies?’, 15 Public Administration and Development, 151-166. Dudley, Leonard and Montmarquette, Claude (1987), ‘Bureaucratic Corruption as a Constraint on Voter Choice’, 55 Public Choice, 127-160. Ekpo, M. (1979), Bureaucratic Corruption in Sub-Saharan Africa: Toward a Search of Causes and Consequences, Washington, University Press of America. Elliott, K. (ed.) (1997), Corruption in the World Economy, Washington, DC, Institute for International Economics. Farrell, A. (1992), Crime, Class and Corruption - the Politics of the Police, London, Bookmarks. Feichtinger, Gustav and Wirl, Franz (1994), ‘On the Stability and Potential Cyclicity of Corruption in Governments Subject to Popularity Constraints’, 28 Mathematical Social Sciences, 113-131. Fennell, P. (1983), ‘Local Government Corruption in England and Wales’, in Clarke, M. (ed.), Corruption: Causes, Consequences and Control, London, Frances Pinter. Fennell, P. and Thomas, P. (1983), ‘Corruption in England and Wales: an Historical Analysis’, 11 International Journal of the Sociology of Law, 167-189. Flatters, Frank and MacLeod, W. Bentley (1995), ‘Administrative Corruption and Taxation’, 2 International Tax and Public Finance, 397-417. Franklin, Daniel (1981), ‘Bribery and Corruption in East West Trade’, 23 ACES Bulletin, 1-71. Friedman, Alan E. and Schwartz, T. (1990), ‘Power and Greed - Inside the Teamsters Empire of Corruption’, 5 Corruption and Reform.
8500
Corruption
483
Galasi, Péter and Kertesi, Gábor (1990), ‘Korrupció és Tulajdon, Tanulmány a Tulajdonjogok Közgazdaságtanának Köreböl (Corruption and Property)’, 4 Közgazdasági Szemle, 389-425. Galeotti, Ginaluigi and Merlo, A. (1994), ‘Political Collusion and Corruption in a Representative Democracy’, 49 Public Finance, 232-243. Gambetta, Diego (1993), The Sicilian Mafia: The Business of Private Protection, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Gardiner, J. A. (1986), ‘Controlling Official Corruption and Fraud [in the US]: Bureaucratic Incentives and Disincentives’, 1 Corruption and Reform, 33-50. Garoupa, Nuno and Bowles, R. (1997), ‘Casual Police Corruption and the Economics of Crime’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 1-16. Gleason, G. (1995), ‘Corruption, Decolonization and Development in Central Asia’, 3 European Journal on Criminal Policy and Research, 38-47. Goodman, Timothy (1994), ‘Political Corruption: The Payoff Diminishes’, 5 American Enterprise, 19-27. Goswami, O., Sanyal, A. and Gang, I.N. (1991), Taxes, Corruption and Bribes - a Model of Indian Public Finance in Markets in Developing Countries - Parallel, Fragmented and Black, San Francisco, ICS Press. Gould, David J. (1980), Bureaucratic Corruption and Underdevelopment in the Third World: the Case of Zaire, New York, Pergamon Press. Gould, David J. and Amaro Reyes, Jose A. (1983), The Effects of Corruption on Administrative Performance, World Bank Staff Working Paper, Washington, DC, The World Bank, No. 580. Graetz, Michael J., Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, L.L. (1986), ‘The Tax Compliance Game: Toward an Interactive Theory of Law Enforcement’, 22 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 1-32. Gray, C.W. and Kaufmann, D. (1998), ‘Corruption and Development’, 35 Finance and Development, 7-10. Grayson, G.M. (1984), ‘An Overdose of Corruption: the Domestic Politics of Mexican Oil’, 13 Caribbean Review, 22-49. Halayya, M. (1985), Corruption in India, New Delhi, Affiliated East-West Press. Hasen, Richard L. (1993), ‘An Enriched Economic Model of Political Patronage and Campaign Contributions: Revising Supreme Court Jurisprudence’, 14 Cardozo Law Review, 1311 ff. Heidenheimer, A.J. (1978), Political Corruption: Readings in Comparitive Analysis, New York, Rinehart and Winston. Hepworth, N. (1995), ‘Fraud and Corruption’, 15 Public Money and Management, 4-6. Huang, Peter H. and Wu, Ho-Mou (1994), ‘More Order without More Law: A Theory of Social Norms and Organizational Cultures’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 390-406. Hutchinson, John (1969), ‘The Anatomy of Corruption in Trade Unions’, 8 Industrial Relations, 135-150. Jacobs, James B. and Thacher, Thomas D., II (1989), ‘Attacking Corruption in Union Management Relations: A Symposium’, 42 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 501-507. Jacoby, N., Nehemkis, P. and Eells, R. (1977), Bribery and Extortion in World Business, New York, Macmillan.
484
Corruption
8500
Jagannathan, N. Vijay (1986), ‘Corruption, Delivery Systems, and Property Rights’, 14 World Development, 127-132. Jagannathan, N. Vijay (1988), ‘Corruption, Delivery Systems and Property Rights: Rejoinder’, 16 World Development, 1393-1394. Jain, R.B. (1983), ‘Fighting Political Corruption: the Indian Experience’, 3 Calcutta Journal of Political Studies, 1-22. Jones, P. (1993), Combatting Fraud and Corruption in the Public Sector, London, Chapman and Hall. Kaminsky, A.Z. (1989), ‘Coercion, Corruption and Reform - State and Society in the Soviet-type Socialist Regime’, 1 Journal of Theoretical Politics, 77-102. Kaufer, Erich (1989), ‘Market Clearing by Corruption: The Political Economy of China’s Recent Economic Reforms: Comment’, 145 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 127-129. Kennedy, William P. (1989), ‘Market Clearing by Corruption: The Political Economy of China’s Recent Economic Reforms: Comment’, 145 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 130-132. Klitgaard, Robert (1984), ‘Managing the Fight against Corruption: a Case Study’, 4 Public Administration and Development, 77-98. Klitgaard, Robert (1988), Controlling Corruption, Berkeley, University of California Press, 220 p. Klitgaard, Robert (1990), Tropical Gangsters, New York, Basic Books. Klitgaard, Robert (1991), ‘Gifts and Bribes’, in Zeckhauser, R. (ed.), Strategy and Choice, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Klitgaard, Robert (1998), ‘International Cooperation Against Corruption’, 35 Finance and Development, 3-6. Kolenda, H. (1990), ‘One Party, Two Systems - Corruption in the People’s Republic of China and Attempts to Control it’, 4 Journal of Chinese Law, 187-232. Kotecha, K.C. and Adams, R.W. (1981), African Politics: the Corruption of Power, Washington, University Press of America. Kowalewski, D., Leitko, T. and Leonard Rosen (1991), ‘Revolving Doors, Corporate Performance and Corruption of Markets’, 18 Critical Sociology, 92-110. Kurer, Oskar (1993), ‘Clientelism, Corruption, and the Allocation of Resources’, 77 Public Choice, 259-273. Laffont, J.J. (1990), ‘Analysis of Hidden Gaming in a Three Level Hierarchy’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization. Lambert-Mogiliansky, A. (1995), ‘Indirect Monitoring and Corruption’, Mimeo, Stockholm University. Le Vine, V. T. (1975), Political Corruption: the Ghana Case, Stanford, Hoover Institute Press, Stanford University. Lee, Barbara A. and Chelius, James R. (1989), ‘Government Regulation of Labor Management Corruption: The Casino Industry Experience in New Jersey’, 42 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 536-548. Leff, N. (1964), ‘Economic Development through Bureaucratic Corruption’, 1964 American Behavioral Scientist, 8-14. Lewis, D.J. (1996), Political Corruption: the Ghana Case, Occasional Paper, Centre for Development Studies, University of Bath.
8500
Corruption
485
Lien, Da Hsiang Donald (1987), ‘Asymmetric Information in Competitive Bribery Games’, 23 Economics Letters, 153-156. Lien, Da Hsiang Donald (1990), ‘Corruption and Allocation Efficiency’, 33 Journal of Development Economics, 153-164. Lui, Francis T. (1985), ‘An Equilibrium Queuing Model of Bribery’,93 Journal of Political Economy, 760-781. Lui, Francis T. (1986), ‘A Dynamic Model of Corruption Deterrence’, 31 Journal of Public Economics, 215-236. Lupsha, P.A. (1991), ‘Drug Lords and Narco-Corruption - the Players Change but the Game Continues’, 16 Crime, Law and Social Change, 41-58. MacRae, John (1982), ‘Underdevelopment and the Economics of Corruption: A Game Theory Approach’, 10 World Development, 677-687. Magnusson, Lars (1989), ‘Corruption and Civic Order Natural Law and Economic Discourse in Sweden during the Age of Freedom’, 37 Scandinavian Economic History Review, 78-105. Maingot, Anthony P. (1994), ‘Confronting Corruption in the Hemisphere: A Sociological Perspective’, 36 Journal of Interamerican Studies and World Affairs, 49-74. Makumbe, J. (1994), ‘Bureaucratic Corruption in Zimbabwe: Causes and Magnitude of the Problem’, 19 Africa Development, 45-60. Marjit, S. (1997), ‘On Controlling Crime with Corrupt Officials’, 34 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 163-172. Mauro, Paolo (1995), ‘Corruption and Growth’, 110 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 681-712. Mauro, Paolo (1996), The Effects of Corruption on Growth, Investment, and Government Expenditure, IMF Working Paper, Washington, IMF, No. 96/98. Elliott (1997) (ed.) op. cit. Mauro, Paolo (1998), ‘Corruption: Causes, Consequences, and Agenda for Further Research’, 35 Finance and Development, 11-14. Mbaku, John Mukum (1992), ‘Bureaucratic Corruption as Rent Seeking Behavior’, 38 Konjunkturpolitik, 247-265. Mbaku, John Mukum (1994), ‘Bureaucratic Corruption and Policy Reform in Africa’, 19 Journal of Social, Political and Economic Studies, 149-176. Mills, Edwin S. (1987), ‘Bureaucratic Corruption as a Constraint on Voter Choice: Comments’, 55 Public Choice, 161-162. Mookherjee, D. and Png, Ivan Paak-Liang (1995), ‘Corruptible Law Enforcers: How should they be compensated?’, 105 Economic Journal, 145-159. Morris, S.D. (1991), Corruption and Politics in Contemporary Mexico, Tuscaloosa, University of Alabama Press. Moteiro, J.B. (1966), Corruption: Control of Maladministration, Bombay, Manaktalas. Murphy, Kevein M., Shleifer, Andre and Vishny, Robert W. (1993), ‘Why is Rent Seeking so Costly to Growth?’, 83 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 409-420. Myerson, Roger B. (1993), ‘Effectiveness of Electoral Systems for Reducing Government Corruption: A Game Theoretic Analysis’, 5 Games and Economic Behavior, 118-132. Myrdal, Gunnar (1989), ‘Corruption as a Hindrance to Modernization in South Asia’, in Heidenheimer, Arnold J., Jophnson, Michael and Le Vine, Victor (eds), Political Corruption: A Handbook, New Brunswick, NJ, Transaction Press, 406-407.
486
Corruption
8500
Nas, Tevfik F., Price, Albert C. and Webber, Charles T. (1986), ‘A Policy oriented Theory of Corruption’, 80 American Political Science Review, 107-119. Olsen, T. and Torsvik, G. ‘Collusion and Renegotiation in Hierarchies: the Case of Beneficial Corruption’, Mimeo, University of Bergen, Bergen, Norway. Ouma, S.O.A. (1991), ‘Corruption in Public Policy and its Impact on Development: the Case of Uganda since 1979', 11 Public Administration and Development, 473-490. Palmier, L. (1983), ‘Bureaucratic Corruption and its Remedies’, in Clarke, M. (ed.), Corruption: Causes, Consequences and Control, London, Frances Pinter. Palmier, L. (1989), ‘Corruption in the West Pacific’, 2 Pacific Reviewv, 11-23. Pechlivanos, L. (1995), ‘Sustainability of Corruption and Optimal Deterrence’, Mimeo, Boston University. Peters, John G. and Welch, Susan (1980), ‘The Effects of Charges of Corruption on Voting Behavior in Congressional Elections’, 74 American Political Science Review, 697-708. Png, Ivan Paak-Liang and Mookherjee, D. (1995), ‘Corruptible Law Enforcers: How Should They Be Compensated?’, 105 Economic Journal, 145-159. Punch, M., van der Vijer, K. and van Vliet, K. (1993), Coping with Corruption in a Borderless World, Boston, Kluwer. Quansah, E.K. (1994), ‘The Corruption and Economic Crime Act, 1994 of Botswana’, 38 Journal of African Law, 191-196. Ragazzi, Giorgio (1993), ‘I Confini della Corruzione Politica (The Boundaries of Political Corruption. With English summary)’, 48 Studi Economici, 125-150. Rasmusen, Eric (1994), Games and Information, 2nd edn, Cambridge, MA and Oxford, Blackwell. Rasmusen, Eric and Ramseyer, J. Mark (1994), ‘Cheap Bribes and the Corruption Ban: A Coordination Game among Rational Legislators’, 78 Public Choice, 305-327. Rasmussen, David W. and Benson, Bruce L. (eds) (1994), The Economic Anatomy of a Drug War: Criminal Justice in the Commons, Lanham, MD, Rowman and Littlefield. Reder, Melvin W. (1975), ‘Corruption as a Feature of Governmental Organization: Comment’, 18 Journal of Law and Economics, 607-609. Reno, W.S.K. (1995), Corruption and State Politics in Sierra Leone, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Rinaldi, S., Feichtinger, G. and Wirl, F. (1994), ‘Corruption Dynamics in Democratic Systems’, 168 Forschungsbericht/Research Memorandum. Rocca, Jean Louis (1992), ‘Corruption and Its Shadow: An Anthropological View of Corruption in China’, 0 China Quarterly, 402-416. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1975), ‘The Economics of Corruption’, 4 Journal of Public Economics, 187-203. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1978a), Corruption: A Study in Political Economy, New York, Academic Press. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1978b), Corruption: A Study in Political Economy, New York, Academic Press. Reprinted as ‘Problem Der Ökonomischen Theorie’, in C. Fleck and Helmut Kuzmics (eds), Korruption: Zur Soziologie. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1994), ‘Reducing Bribery in the Public Sector’, in Trang, Duc V. (ed.), Corruption and Democracy, Budapest, Institute for Constitutional and Legislative Policy, 21-28.
8500
Corruption
487
Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1995), ‘Second Generation Issues in Transition: Corruption’, in Bruno, Michael and Pleskovic, Boris (eds), Proceedings of The World Bank Annual Conference on Development Economics 1995, Washington, 373-380. Rose-Ackerman, Susan and Montias, J.M., ‘Corruption in Soviet Type Economies: Theoretical Considerations’, in Rosefielde, Steven (ed.), Economic Welfare and the Economics of Soviet Socialism: Essays in Honor of Abram Bergson, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Rottenberg, Simon (1975), ‘Corruption as a Feature of Governmental Organization: Comment’, 18 Journal of Law and Economics, 611-615. Ruggiero, V. (1994), ‘Corruption in Italy: an Attempt to Identify the Victims’, 33 Howard Journal of Criminal Justice, 319-337. Sah, R.K. (1987), Persistence and Pervasiveness of Corruption, The World Bank, Conference on Political Economy: Theory and Policy Implications, June 17-19, 1987, Washington, DC, The World Bank. Sands, Barbara N. (1989), ‘Market Clearing by Corruption: The Political Economy of China’s Recent Economic Reforms’, 145 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 116-126. Sands, Barbara N. (1990), ‘Decentralizing an Economy: The Role of Bureaucratic Corruption in China’s Economic Reforms’, 65 Public Choice, 85-91. Santhanam Committee (1994), Report by the Committee on Prevention of Corruption, Government of India, Ministry of Home Affairs. Schaffer, B. (1986), ‘Access: a Theory of Corruption and Bureaucracy’, 6 Public Administration and Development, 357-376. Schelling, T. (1967), ‘Criminal Enterprise’ in ‘Task Force Report: Organised Crime’, President’s Commission on Law Enforcement and Administration of Justice, Washington, DC. Schmidt, Kurt (1969), ‘Zur Okonomik der Korruption (On the Economics of Corruption. With English summary)’, 89 Schmollers Jahrbuch für Wirtschafts und Sozialwissenschaften, 129-149. Schwalbe, Ulrich (1994), ‘Gewerkschaften und Korruption (Corruption and Trade Unions. With English summary)’, 114 Zeitschrift für Wirtschafts- und Sozialwissenschaften, 617-634. Seagull, L.M. (1994), ‘Whistleblowing and Corruption Control: the GE case22’, (4) Crime, Law and Social Change, 381-390. Sexton, Jean (1989), ‘Controlling Corruption in the Construction Industry: The Quebec Approach’, 42 Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 524-535. Shavell, Steven and Spier, Kathryn E. (1996), ‘Threats Without Binding Commitment’, 5461 National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper. Shleifer, A. and Vishny, Robert W. (1992), ‘Pervasive Shortages under Socialism’, 23 Rand Journal of Economics. Shleifer, A. and Vishny, Robert W. (1994), ‘Politicians and Firms’,109 Quarterly Journal of Economics. Shleifer, Andrei and Vishny, Robert W. (1993), ‘Corruption’, 108 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 599-617. Sisk, David E. (1982), ‘Police Corruption and Criminal Monopoly: Victimless Crimes’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 395-403.
488
Corruption
8500
Spier, Kathryn E. and Shavell, Steven (1996), ‘Threats Without Binding Commitment’, National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper. Spiller, P. (1990), ‘Politicians, Interest Groups, and Regulators: A Multi-Principals Agency Theory of Regulation (or ‘let them be bribed’)’, 33 Journal of Law and Economics, 65-101. Strauss, D.A. (1994), ‘Corruption, Equality and Campaign Finance Reform’, 94 Columbia Law Review, 1369-1389. Szeftel, M. (1983), ‘Corruption and the Spoils System in Zambia’, in Clarke, M. (ed.), Corruption: Causes, Consequences and Control, London, Frances Pinter. Szymanderski, Jacek (1995), ‘Moral Order and Corruption in Transition to the Market: Popular Beliefs and Their Underpinnings’, 7 Communist Economies and Economic Transformation, 249-257. Tanzi, V. (1995), ‘Corruption, Governmental Activities, and Markets’, 32 Finance and Development, 24-26. Tanzi, V. and Davoodi, H. (1998), ‘Roads to Nowhere: How Corruption in Public Investment Hurts Growth’, 12 Economic Issues, IMF. Theobald, R. (1990), Corruption, Development and Underdevelopment, Basingstoke, Macmillan. Theobald, R. (1993), ‘Lancing the Swollen African State: Will it Alleviate the Problems of Corruption?’, 32 Journal of Modern African Studies, 701-706. Tirole, Jean (1996), ‘A Theory of Collective Reputations (with applications to the persistence of corruption and to firm quality)’, 63 Review of Economic Studies, 1-22. Toma, Eugenia Froedge and Toma, Mark (1992), ‘Tax Collection with Agency Costs: Private Contracting or Government Bureaucrats?’, 59 Economica, 107-120. Trivedi, Vishwapati (1988), ‘Corruption, Delivery Systems and Property Rights: A Comment’, 16 World Development, 1389-1391. Tunstall, Allan W. (1992), ‘Corruption! At Flemington Markets? A Case Study in Public Policy’, 60 Review of Marketing and Agricultural Economics, 57-67. United Nations (1989), Corruption in Government, New York, United Nations. van de Mortel, E. and Cornelisse, P.A. (1994), ‘The Dynamics of Corruption and Black Markets: an Application of Catastrophe Theory’, 49 Public Finance, 195-210. Vance, M.A. (1982), Corruption in Politics in the US: a bibliography, Monticello, IL, Vance Bibliographies. Virmani, Arvind (1987), ‘Tax Evasion, Corruption and Administration: Monitoring the People’s Agents under Symmetric Dishonesty’, Mimeo, Development Research Department, The World Bank, Washington, DC. Wade, Robert (1982), ‘The System of Administrative and Political Corruption: Canal Irrigation in South India’, 18 Journal of Development Studies, 287-328. Ward, Peter M. (ed.) (1989), Corruption, Development and Inequality: Soft Touch or Hard Graft?, London, Routledge, 191 p. Werlin, Herbert H. (1973), ‘The Consequences of Corruption: The Ghanaian Experience’, 88 Political Science Quarterly, 71-85. Werner, S.B. (1983), ‘New Directions in the Study of Administrative Corruption’, 1983 Public Administration Review, 146-154. Williams, R.J. (1981), ‘Political Corruption in the United States’, 29 Political Studies, 126-129.
8500
Corruption
489
Winston, Gordon C. (1979), ‘The Appeal of Inappropriate Technologies: Self Inflicted Wages, Ethnic Price and Corruption’, 7 World Development, 835-845. Wong, Kar Yiu (1992), ‘Inflation, Corruption, and Income Distribution: The Recent Price Reform in China’, 14 Journal of Macroeconomics, 105-123.
Other References Akerlof, G.A. (1980), ‘A Theory of Social Custom of which Unemployment may be One Consequence’, 94 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 749-795. Allingham, M. and Sandmo, A. (1972), ‘Income Tax Evasion: A Theoretical Analysis’, 1 Journal of Public Economics, 323-38. Barzel, Y. (1996), ‘Parliament as a Wealth Maximizing Institution: the Right to the Residual and the Right to Vote’, mimeo, presented at European Association of Law and Economics Conference, Haifa, Israel. Baye, M.R. (1997), Managerial Economics and Business Strategy, Chicago, Irwin. Becker, G.S. (1968), ‘Crime and Punishment: an Economic Approach’, 76 Journal of Political Economy, 169-217. Becker, G.S. (1983), ‘A Theory of Competition among Pressure Groups for Political Influence’, 98 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 371-400. Becker, G. and Stigler, G. (1974), ‘Law Enforcement, Malfeasance, and the Compensation of Enforcers’, 3 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-18. Benjamini, Y. and Maital, S. (1985), ‘Optimal Tax Evasion and Optimal Tax Evasion Policy’, in Gartner, W. and Wenig, A. (eds), The Economics of the Shadow Economy, Berlin, Springer Verlag, 245-264. Bhagwati, J. (1982), ‘Directly Unproductive Profit-Seeking (DUP) Activities’, 90 Journal of Political Economy, 1982. Border, K.C. and Sobell, J. (1987), ‘Samurai Accountant: A Theory of Auditing and Plunder’, 54 Review of Economic Studies, 525-540. Bowles, R.A. (1997), ‘Reform of Legal Aid and the Solicitors’ Profession’, 5 Hume Papers, 1997. Bowles, R.A. and Rickman, N. (1998), ‘Asymmetric Information, Moral Hazard and the Insurance of Legal Expenses’, 23 Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance, 196-209. Breyer, S. and Steward, R. (1979), Administrative Law and Regulatory Policy, Boston: Little, Brown & Co. Brickley, J.A., Smith, C.W. and Zimmerman, J.L. (1996),Organizational Architecture: A Managerial Economics Approach, Chicago, Irwin. Business International Corporation (1984), Introduction to the Country Assessment Service, New York, BIC. Calvo, G.A. and Wellisz, S.H. (1978), ‘Supervision, Loss of Control and the Optimal Size of the Firm’, 86 Journal of Political Economy, 943-952. Cohen, S. and Eimicke, W.B. (1995), ‘Ethics and the Public Administrator’, 537 Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Sciences, 97-108. Cullis, J.G. and Jones, P.R. (1992), Public Finance and Public Choice, London, McGraw-Hill. Deakin, S. and Michie, J. (eds) (1997), Contracts, Co-operation and Competition, Oxford, Oxford University Press.
490
Corruption
8500
DeSouza, P. (1985), ‘Regulating Fraud in Military Procurement: A Legal Process Model’, 95 Yale Law Journal, 390-413. Downs, A. (1957), An Economic Theory of Democracy, New York, Harper & Row. Eide, E. (1994), Economics of Crime: Deterrence and the Rational Offender, North Holland. EMF Foundation (1991), World Competitiveness Report, Cologny/Geneva, EMF Foundation. Garoupa, N. (1997), ‘The Theory of Optimal Law Enforcement’, 11 Journal of Economic Surveys, 267-295. Grossman, S. and Hart, O. (1983), ‘An Analysis of the Principal Agent Problem’, 52 Econometrica, 1-45. Hirshleifer and Riley (1992), The Analytics of Information and Uncertainty, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Jabbra, J.G. and Dwivedi, O.P. (ed.) (1989), Public Sector Accountability, Connecticut, Kumatian Press. Jones, P.R. and Cullis, J.G. (1996), ‘Legitimate and Illegitimate Transfers: Dealing with ‘Political’ Cost-Benefit Analysis’, 16 International Review of Law and Economics, 247-258. Katz and Rosen (1994), Microeconomics, Illinois, Irwin. Kay, J.A. and Thompson, D.J. (1986), ‘Privatisation: a Policy in Search of a Rationale’, 96 Economic Journal, 18-32. Koffman, F. and Lawarree, J. (1993), ‘Collusion in Hierarchical Agency’, 61 Econometrica, 629-656. Krueger, A.O. (1974), ‘The Political Economy of the Rent-Seeking Society’, 64 American Economic Review, 291-303. Laffont, J.-J. and Tirole, J. (1993), A Theory of Incentives in Procurement and Regulation, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Lee, D.R. (1983), ‘Monitoring and Budget Maximization in the Control of Pollution’, 21 Economic Inquiry, 565 ff. Lewin, J.L. and Trumbell, W.N. (1993), ‘Neither Boxed in nor Circular: a Reply to Professor McChesney’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 233 ff. MacMullen, R. (1988), Corruption and the Decline of Rome, New Haven, Yale University Press. Manne, H. (1966), Insider Trading and the Stock Market, New York City, The Free Press. McChesney, F.S. (1993), ‘Boxed in: Economists and benefits from crime’, 3 International Review of Law and Economics, 225-232. Mueller, D. (1979), Public Choice, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Myrdal, G. (1968), Asian Drama: An Inquiry into the Poverty of Nations, vol II, New York, Pantheon. Niskanen, W.A. (1974), Bureaucracy and Representative Government, Chicago, Aldine. Pauly, M. (1970), ‘Efficiency, Incentives and Reimbursement for Health Care’, 7 Inquiry, 114-131. Peltzman, S. (1976), ‘Toward a More General Theory of Regulation’, 19 Journal of Law and Economics, 211-40. Polinsky, A.M. and Shavell, S. (1979), ‘The Optimal Trade-off between the Probability and Magnitude of Fines’, 69 American Economic Review, 880-891. Polinsky, A.M. and Shavell, S. (1984), ‘The Optimal Use of Fines and Imprisonment’, 69 Journal of Public Economics, 880-891.
8500
Corruption
491
Posner, R. (1975), ‘The Social Costs of Monopoly and Regulation’, 83 Journal of Political Economy. Pyle, D.J. (1992), ‘The Economics of Taxpayer Compliance’, 5 Journal of Economic Surveys, 163-198. Ross, S. (1973), ‘The Economic Theory of Agency: The Principal’s Problem’, 63 American Economic Review, 134-139. Stigler, G.J. (1971), ‘The Economic Theory of Regulation’, 2 Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, 3-21. Tirole, J. (1986), ‘Hierarchies and Bureaucracies: On the Role of Collusion in Organizations’, 2 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 181-214. Tirole, J. (1992), ‘Collusion and the Theory of Organizations’, in Laffont, J.-J. (ed.), Advances in Economic Theory: Sixth World Congress, vol II, Econometric Society Monographs, no. 21, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Tirole, J. (1994), ‘The Internal Organization of Government’, 46 Oxford Economic Papers, 1-29. Tollison, R.D. (1982), ‘Rent Seeking: a Survey’, 35 Kyklos, 575-602. Tullock, G. (1967), ‘The Welfare Costs of Tariffs, Monopolies and Theft’, 5 Western Economic Journal. Webber, C. and Wildavsky, A. (1986), A History of Taxation and Expenditure in the Western World, New York, Simon & Schuster. Weingast, B.R., Shepsle, K.A. and Johnsen, C. (1981), ‘The Political Economy of Costs and Benefits: A Neoclassical Approach to Distribution Politics’, 89 Journal of Political Economy, 642 ff. Williamson, O.E. (1979), Transaction Cost Economics: The Governance of Contractual Relations, New York, Free Press. Wilson, J.Q. (1989), Bureaucracy: What Government Agencies Do and Why They Do It, New York, Basic Books. World Bank (1992), Governance and Development, Washington, DC, World Bank.
8600 CORPORATE CRIMINAL LIABILITY John R. Lott, Jr John M. Olin Visiting Law and Economics Fellow University of Chicago Law School © Copyright 1999 John R. Lott, Jr
Abstract This chapter reviews the economic literature on corporate crime. Economists have discussed and answered a number of questions about corporate crime in only few years time span. Perhaps this unusual success is due to the questions involving corporations being so similar to other crime issues, previously analysed. However, a number of questions remain largely unexplored. Why do certain firms commit crimes while others do not? What are the social costs imposed by the very high corporate criminal penalties? How does the criminal justice process shape the organisation of firms? JEL classification: K22, K14, K42 Keywords: Corporate Crime, Firm, US Sentencing Guidelines
1. Introduction The economic analysis of corporate crime only started gaining momentum during the last half dozen years. Of course, one notable exception to this rule is Posner’s textbook on the Economic Analysis of Law (1992), though the discussion of corporate criminality is relegated to issues such as whether firms should obey the law or maximise profits. (It is also puzzling to report how economists still fail in providing a conclusive definition of a firm. For example, while I am sure that it is not done intentionally, definitions of organised crime appear to be interchangeable with definition of firms (see, for example, Dick, 1995)). The catalyst for this was the debate over and the subsequent adoption in 1991 of the US government’s corporate sentencing guidelines. The research itself has largely focused on theoretical questions raised by the guidelines (for example, what should be included in calculating the social cost of crimes committed by corporations or whether it should be the firm and/or its managers who are penalised), descriptive empirical evidence on how corporate penalties have changed over time, and some evidence indicating what factors predispose firms to violate the law.
492
8600
Corporate Criminal Liability
493
2. The Theory The basic principle behind the economics view of legally imposed sanctions is to ensure that those who break the law internalise the externalities that they impose upon others. Several questions arise in this context: (1) how large is the externality, (2) upon whom should the penalty be imposed, and (3) should the penalty take the form of criminal or civil sanctions or possibly just through the loss of reputation. While the issue of criminal harm is the same for crimes by firms and individuals (see for example Becker, 1968 or Friedman, 1981), the debate among economists over what should be included in corporate penalties largely arises from the sentencing commission’s guidelines, which explicitly include some notion of the third-party spillover effects from crimes like financial or consumer fraud (United States Sentencing Commission, Chapter Eight - Sentencing of Organisations, U.S.S.C. § 8 C5.5, November 1, 1991). In part this interest arises because fraud cases involve almost half of all corporate crimes (Alexander and Cohen, 1996a, p. 427). Upward departures from the guidelines are also required when any corporate crime involves a ‘substantial risk to the integrity or continued existence of a market’ (United States Sentencing Commission, Chapter Eight - Sentencing of Organisations, U.S.S.C. Proposed Addition to the Sentencing Guidelines, § 8.12, July, 1988). Some economists, such as Tom Ulen (1996), defend the theory behind the guidelines by arguing that criminal penalties are required to ensure that offending firms internalize the losses imposed on buyers because frauds cause both consumers and firms to take costly defensive actions. In this discussion, fraud affects third parties like a tax, raising both the costs of production by firms and lowering the price that consumers are willing to pay. While Ulen accepts that there is an optimal amount of fraud, criminal penalties should account for these third party losses whenever there is more than the ‘socially optimal amount of fraud taking place’ (p. 358). How one knows when these frauds are greater than the optimal number is not clear, though most of this discussion identifies dead-weight losses whenever frauds effect third-party behaviour. The question of how large the criminal penalties should be are then a function of those parameters that determine the dead-weight loss from taxes (for example, the elasticity of demand). An alternative position argues that third parties should normally be seen as benefiting from the frauds committed against others (Daniel and Lott, 1995; Lott, 1996). For example, if after a fraud other firms’ customers desire that they acquire more reputation because the customers learn that the existing level of reputation produced less quality assurance than they had previously believed, the revelation of the fraud allows them to better equate the marginal benefits and costs from buying quality assurance. The
494
Corporate Criminal Liability
8600
distinction drawn here is whether the fraud changes the underlying probability with which other frauds will occur or whether it merely provides other firms’ customers with better information to evaluate their own situation. Given that few frauds are likely to innovate new methods of perpetrating the deception that will then be copied by imitators, few frauds will alter the underlying probability of other frauds occurring. An interesting debate concerns whether it might be more efficient to impose penalties on the principals instead of simply holding agents directly liable for their actions. Kraakman (1984b) suggests that part of the reason may have to do with monitoring costs. For example, corporate liability may be efficient if the government is better at monitoring corporations and these corporations are good at monitoring agents. Salzburg (1991) and Polinsky and Shavell (1993) point out that the penalties imposed upon the firm may not always be large enough to produce the efficient level of deterrence, thus justifying an additional penalty being imposed upon the agents (while Salzburg merely provides a verbal argument on this issue, Polinsky and Shavell provide the formal model behind this reasoning). Salzburg (1991) also advocates prosecuting corporations because it reduces the prosecutor’s burden of investigation and conviction and avoids various preceived procedural problems, though in the end this argument amounts to little more than a claim that both firms and individuals should be prosecuted because it is possible to do so. Arlen (1994) suggests that penalties on principles may have the unintended effect of inducing principals to expend less effort monitoring, since their own monitoring of principals may increase the likelihood of detection. Unless corporations are compensated for its monitoring efforts through penalty reductions that offset the higher probability of prosecutions that result from the internal monitoring, the private return to monitoring will fall below the social return. Davis (1996) raises the issue of how the possibility that agents’ actions can create liability for a firm’s principals thus alter agents’ compensation. He asks whether agents actually prefer government rules that increase their liability. His conclusion is that there are reasonable assumptions about the agent’s risk neutrality and how the earning depend on legal and illegal profits, where agents will prefer legal liability. However, whatever the answer to these questions, the central question still remains: should corporate criminality even exist. While there are philosophical arguments over whether a corporation as compared to individuals can have intent (Parker, 1996), economists have largely debated whether criminal sanctions are necessary to ensure that corporations internalize the externalities that their illegal behaviour creates. Block (1991), Karpoff and Lott (1993), Fischel and Sykes (1996) and Parker
8600
Corporate Criminal Liability
495
(1996), ask whether civil penalties might be preferred. Not only do criminal proceedings require higher levels of proof than civil proceedings but, for firms, the ultimate penalty is the same in either case: fines. Civil prosecution provides other benefits ranging from compensation of victims, law enforcement efficiencies, and the ability of apparently obtaining the same stigma produced by criminal prosecution though at a lower cost (Parker, 1996, pp. 387-389). One question still persists: might the government be better suited to imposing particularly large penalties on individuals because the government can use imprisonment while private firms are limited to monetary damages? While this is true, it misses the central point. Criminal charges can still be pursued against individual agents even if the case against the firm is handled civilly (Fischel and Sykes, 1996).
3. Empirical Evidence Empirical corporate crime studies take several forms. Either they measure the size of the criminal penalties and how the US Sentencing Guidelines have altered these penalties, test which characteristics are exhibited by firms engaging in crime, measure firm profitability from crime, or examine whether the US Sentencing Guidelines have moved penalties closer towards efficiency. Penalties prior to the guidelines appear to have exhibited many patterns consistent with optimal penalty theory (Cohen, 1996). Not only did firms creating greater harm face greater sanctions, but individual liability was also greater when the organisation was unable to compensate for the harm done. Interestingly, for the crimes with the largest losses, the penalty that the courts imposed suggested a belief that the probability of detection was higher for those crimes (Cohen, 1991 and Lott, 1991, p. 440). An easy optimal penalty explanation appears to exist for this. For example, large oil spills are virtually certain to be detected, but tiny ones (for example, the discharging of ballast) are most likely to be unnoticed. The sentencing guidelines turned much of this pre-existing structure on its head, with the multiple now instead increasing with the size of the harm. The guidelines also have dramatically increased criminal penalties. Early estimates indicated increases of 20, 30 or 40 times over previous penalties, and changes as high as 50 to 100 fold for a few select crimes (Cohen, 1991). Others produced estimates of at least twenty-fold (Block, 1991 and Lott, 1991). With fraud being the largest category of corporate crime and one of the areas with the biggest increases in penalties under the guidelines, much of the recent empirical evidence has focused on it. Analysing the Sentencing
496
Corporate Criminal Liability
8600
Commission’s concerns that the penalties for fraud have been too low, economists sought to investigate whether traditional emphasis on legally imposed penalties underestimated the true penalty. To evaluate this, Karpoff and Lott (1993) measured the extent of reputational penalties for fraudulent firms prior to the 1991 corporate guidelines. An allegation that a corporation had defrauded stakeholders or the government corresponds to an economically and statistically significant loss in the market value of the common stock. On average, very little of this loss, in the order of 6.5 percent, can be attributed to the accused firm’s expected legal fees and penalties. It is possible to compute larger portions of the loss that could reflect higher expected penalties for future frauds and the lost value of the cheating firm’s profits from committing fraud. But even under extremely unrealistic assumptions, one third of the loss remains. (Yet, firms are not the only entities to suffer from reduced earnings when they commit fraud. White collar criminal face large reductions in legitimate earnings when they are convicted of fraud (Lott, 1992). The average criminal convicted of fraud faces almost a 40 percent drop in legitimate earnings when he returns to the workforce. Similar drops are also observed for embezzlement, larceny and theft.) Large reputational penalties are associated with frauds committed against stakeholders, government agencies, and investors. In contrast, the reputational loss for frauds involving regulatory violations, in which firms have not violated an implicit or explicit contract with a stakeholder or investor, is negligible (see also Block, 1991). The evidence is consistent with the market penalty for fraud being systematically related to the cost imposed on parties with whom the firm does business. Because of their large size, reputational effects play an important role in disciplining firms that commit fraud. There appear to be very similar reputational penalties when either criminal or civil cases are filed (Block, 1991). For fraud, the average decrease in common stock value exceeds the US Sentencing Commission’s estimates of victim losses by more than 100 times. The Sentencing Commission reports that Department of Justice prosecutors believe the probability of convicting a corporate fraud is between 20 and 57 percent, implying an optimal ratio of actual penalty to social costs of between 1.75 and 5 (Lott, 1996, pp. 374-375). Yet, as mentioned above, the expected total penalty far exceeds the Commission’s estimated loss borne by the victims, and this holds even at 1980’s levels of criminal fines. Thus, unless these numbers are off by a very large magnitude, the past efforts to substantially increase criminal penalties for corporate fraud were completely misguided. Some evidence indicates that managers conceal bad news from the market (Arlen and Carney, 1992), indirectly supporting a ‘last period hypothesis’, in which misconduct results from poor performance on the part
8600
Corporate Criminal Liability
497
of the firm. Yet, other findings suggest no actual or expected deterioration in firm profitability prior to a fraud (Karpoff and Lott, 1993). A study by Alexander and Cohen (1996a) examines other aspects of firms’ performance prior to a fraud, as measured by the firm’s assets, employment and sales. With the exception of environmental crimes, they find no relationship between these measures and whether a fraud is going to occurs. Antitrust penalties have been studied extensively by economists, and up until recently, when it was displaced by environmental crimes, it involved the second largest number of cases. Asch and Seneca (1975, 1976) provided the earliest evidence in this area by investigating whether the prior performance of firms charged with antitrust violations differed relative to their Fortune 500 counterparts. Surprisingly, Asch and Seneca found a significant negative relationship between collusion and several alternative measures of performance such as growth in sales and return on assets over the five years before the date of the relevant plea or court finding. Staw and Szwajkowski (1975) attempt to explain this result as lower profitability leading to collusion. (However, since these studies rely on actual government suits, there is always the nagging question of whether the government can accurately tell which firms if any are engaging in antitrust violations.) Game theory has also suggested essentially limitless explanations for firm behavior. A number of recent game-theoretic models suggest that with asymmetric information it can be profitable for some firms to acquire a reputation for toughness in order to discourage later entry. One may view these models as providing a method of understanding what factors increase the likelihood that firms commit crimes, though initial empirical evidence provides little support that these models will be particularly useful. Lott and Opler (1996) identify institutional arrangements that firms must undertake to ensure the credibility of any predatory commitments. Simply hiring managers who value market share or output maximisation is not sufficient if the manager can be removed whenever it actually becomes necessary to engage in predation. It is also required that the firms make removing the manager difficult. In addition, the incumbent manager should be rewarded for increasing output as opposed to increasing short-term profits. A study of firms charged with predation failed to yield any support that allegedly predatory firms are organised as these game-theoretic models imply. If anything, the reverse seems to be frequently true. Alleged predators more often are large firms with managerial compensation schemes relying heavily on short-term profits (Lott and Opler, 1996, pp. 362-363), with this last fact hardly seeming consistent with any known notion of predation. Just as Bork (1978, pp. 347-364) argues, the general picture is consistent with the laws being used to harass large profitable firms.
498
Corporate Criminal Liability
8600
4. Conclusion Economists have discussed and answered a number of questions about corporate crime in only few years time span. Perhaps this unusual success is due to the questions involving corporations being so similar to other crime issues, previously analysed. However, a number of questions remain largely unexplored. Why do certain firms commit crimes while others do not? What are the social costs imposed by the very high corporate criminal penalties? How does the criminal justice process shape the organisation of firms? These are areas that should lend themselves to very interesting future research.
Bibliography on Corporate Criminal Liability (8600) Alexander, Cindy R. and Cohen, Mark A (1996a), ‘New Evidence on the Origins of Corporate Crime’, 17 Managerial and Decision Economics, 421-435. Alexander, Cindy R. and Cohen, Mark A. (1996b), Why Do Corporations Become Criminals? An Agency Explanation, Working paper. Arlen, Jennifer H. (1991), ‘Controlling Corporate Torts: Strict Liability Versus Negligence Reconsidered’, Working Paper Version. Arlen, Jennifer H. (1994), ‘The Potentially Perverse Effects of Corporate Criminal Liability’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 832-867. Arlen, Jennifer H. (1995), ‘Commentary on Rewarding Whistleblowers: The Costs and Benefits of an Incentive-Based Compliance Strategy’, in Daniels, Ronald and Morck, Randall (eds), Corporate Decision-Making in Canada, 635-647. Arlen, Jennifer H. and Carney, William J. (1992), ‘Vicarious Liability for Fraud on Securities Markets: Theory and Evidence’, 25 University of Illinois Law Review, 691-740. Reprinted in Andersen, Peder, Vibeke, Jensen and Mortensen, Jørgen Birk (eds) (1993), Governance by Legal and Economic Measures, Copenhagen, Gad. Arlen, Jennifer H. and Kraakman, Reinier H. (1997), ‘Controlling Corporate Misconduct: A Comparative Analysis of Alternative Corporate Incentive Regimes’, 72 New York University Law Review, 687-779. Asch, Peter and Seneca, J.J. (1975), ‘Characteristics of Collusive Firms’, 23 Journal of Industrial Economics, 223-237. Asch, Peter and Seneca, J.J. (1976), ‘Is Collusion Profitable?’, 58 Review of Economics and Statistics, 1-12. Baysinger, G. (1991), ‘Organization Theory and the Criminal Liability of Organizations’, 71 Boston University Law Review, 341-376. Becker, Gary S. (1968), ‘Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach’, 76 Journal of Political Economy, 169-217. Becker, Gary S. and Stigler, George J. (1974), ‘Law Enforcement, Malfeasance and Compensation of Enforcers’, 3 Journal of Legal Studies, 1 ff. Block, Michael K. (1991), ‘Optimal Penalties, Criminal Law, and the Control of Corporate Behaviour’, 71 Boston University Law Review, 395-420. Bork, Robert H. (1978), The Antitrust Paradox: A Policy at War Itself, New York, Basic Books.
8600
Corporate Criminal Liability
499
Braithwaite, John (1986), ‘Consumers as Victims of Corporate Crime’, in Wheelwright, Ted (ed.), Consumers, Transnational Corporations and Development, Sydney, University of Sydney, Transnational Corporations Research Project, 331-342. Byam, John I. (1982), ‘The Economic Inefficiency of Corporate Criminal Liability’, 73 Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 582-603. Cochran, Philip L. and Nigh, Douglas (1987), ‘Illegal Corporate Behavior and the Question of Moral Agency: An Empirical Examination’, in Frederick, William C. (ed.), Empirical Studies of Business Ethics and Values. V, Greenwich, CT, JAI Press, 73-91. Coffee, John C., Jr (1980), ‘Corporate Crime and Punishment: A Non-Chicago View of the Economics of Criminal Sanctions’, 17 American Criminal Law Review, 419-476. Coffee, John C. (1981), ‘’No Soul to Damn: No Body to Kick’: An Unscandalized Inquiry Into the Problem of Corporate Punishment’, 79 Michigan Law Review, 386 ff. Coffee, John C. (1991), ‘Does ‘Unlawful’ Mean ‘Criminal’?: Reflections of the Disappearing Tort/Crime Distiction in American Law’, 71 Boston University Law Review, 193 ff. Cohen, Mark A. (1989), ‘Corporate Crime and Punishment: A Study of Social Harm and Sentencing Practice in the Federal Courts, 1984-1987', 26 American Criminal Law Review, 605-660. Cohen, Mark A. (1991), ‘Corporate Crime and Punishment: An Update on Sentencing Practice in the Federal Courts, 1988-1990', 71(2) Boston University Law Review, 247-280. Cohen, Mark A. (1992a), ‘Sentencing Guidelines and Corporate Criminal Liability in the US’, 4 Business and the Contemporary World, 140-157. Cohen, Mark A. (1992b), ‘Environmental Crime and Punishment: Legal/Economic Theory and Empirical Evidence on Enforcement of Federal Environmental Statutes’, 82 Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 1054-1108. Cohen, Mark A. (1996), ‘Theories of Punishment and Empirical Trends in Corporate Criminal Sanctions’, 17 Managerial and Decision Economics, 399-412. Cohen, Mark A., Ho, Chih-Chin, Jones, Edward D. III. and Schleich, Laura M. (1988), ‘Organizations as Defendants in Federal Court: A Preliminary Analysis of Prosecutions, Convictions and Sanctions, 1984-1987', 10 Whittier Law Review, 103-124. Dana, D. (1996), ‘The Perverse Incentives of Environmental Audit Immunity’, 81 Iowa Law Review, 969 ff. Daniel, Kermit and Lott, J.R. Jr (1995), ‘Should Criminal Penalties Include Third Party Avoidance Costs?’ 24 Jounal of Legal Studies, 523-534. Daniels, Ronald J. and Howse, Robert (1995), ‘Rewarding Whistleblowers: The Costs and Benefits of an Incentive-Based Compliance Strategy’, in Daniels, Ronald and Morck, Randall (eds), Corporate Decision-Making in Canada, Calgary, University of Calgary Press, 525-549. Dau-Schmidt, Kenneth G. (1984), ‘Sentencing Antitrust Offenders: Reconciling Economic Theory with Legal Theory’, 9 Wm. Mitchell Law Review, 75 ff. Davis, Mike L. (1996), ‘The Impact of Rules Allocating Legal Responsibilities between Principals and Agents’, 17 Managerial and Decision Economics, 413-420. Dick, Andrew R. (1995), ‘When Does Organised Crime Pay? A Transaction Cost Analysis’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 25-46.
500
Corporate Criminal Liability
8600
Dickens, William T. (1989), ‘Employee Crime and the Monitoring Puzzle’, 7 Journal of Labor Economics, 331-347. Eaton, B. Curtis and White, William D. (1982), ‘Agent Compensation and the Limits of Bonding’, 20 Economic Inquiry, 330 ff. Fischel, Daniel R. and Sykes, Alan O. (1996), ‘Corporate Crime’, 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 319-350. Friedman, David D. (1981), ‘Reflections on Optimal Punishment, Or: Should the Rich Pay Higher Fines?’, in Zerbe, Richard O. (ed.), Research in Law and Economics, Vol.. 3, Greenwich, CT, JAI Press, 185-230. Gallo, Joseph C., Dau-Schmidt, Kenneth G. and Craycraft, Joseph (1997), ‘The First Century of Department of Justice Antitrust Enforcement’, 12 Review of Industrial Organization. Karpoff, Jonathan M. and Lott, J.R., Jr (1993), ‘The Reputational Penalty Firms Bear from Committing Criminal Fraud’, 36(2) Journal of Law and Economics, 757-802. Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1982), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Choice Between Entreprise and Personal Liability for Accidents’, 70 California Law Review, 1345 ff. Kraakman, Reinier H. (1984a), ‘The Economic Functions of Corporate Liability’, in Hopt, Klaus J. and Teubner, Gunther (eds), Corporate Governance and Directors’ Liabilities, New York, de Gruyter, 178-207. Kraakman, Reinier H. (1984b), ‘Corporate Liability Strategies and the Costs of Legal Controls’, 93 Yale Law Journal, 857 ff. Kraakman, Reinier H. (1986), ‘Gatekeepers: The Anatomy of a Third-Party Enforcement Strategy’, 2 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 53 ff. Landes, William M. (1983), ‘Optimal Sanctions for Antitrust Violations’, 50 University of Chicago Law Review, 652-678. Leung, S.F. (1991), ‘How to Make the Fine Fit the Corporate Crime? An Analysis of Static and Dynamic Optimal Punishment Theories’, 45 Journal of Public Economics, 243-256. Levmore, Saul (1982), ‘Monitors and Freeriders in Commercial and Corporate Settings’, 92 Yale Law Journal, 49-83. Lofquist, William S., Cohen, Madeline and Rabe, Gary (1996), Debating Corporate Crime: An Interdisciplinary Examination of the Causes and Control of Corporate Misconduct, Cincinnati, OH, Anderson Publishing. Lott, J.R., Jr (1991), ‘Optimal Penalties versus Minimising the Level of Crime: Does it Matter Who is Correct?’, 71 Boston University Law Review, 439-446. Lott, J.R., Jr (1992), ‘Do We Punish High Income Criminals Too Heavily?’, 30 Economic Inquiry, 583-608. Lott, J.R., Jr (1996), ‘The Level of Optimal Fines to Prevent Fraud When Reputations Exist and Penalty Clauses are Unenforceable’, 17 Managerial and Decision Economics, 363-380. Lott, John R. and Opler, Tim C. (1996), ‘Testing Whether Predatory Commitments are Credible’, 69 Journal of Business, 339-382. Macey, Jonathan R. (1991), ‘Agency Theory and the Criminal Liability of Organizations’, 71 Boston University Law Review, 315 ff. Metzger, Michael R. (1984), ‘Corporate Criminal Liability for Defective Products: Policies, Problems, and Prospects’, 73 Georgetown Law Journal, 1-88.
8600
Corporate Criminal Liability
501
Newman, Harry A. and Wright, David W. (1990), ‘Strict Liability in a Principal-Agent Model’, 10 International Review of Law and Economics, 219 ff. Parker, Jeffrey S. (1989), ‘Criminal Sentencing Policy for Organizations: The Unifying Approach of Optimal Penalties’, 26 American Criminal Law Review, 513-604. Parker, Jeffrey S. (1996), ‘Doctrine for Destruction: The Case of Corporate Criminal Liability’, 17 Managerial and Decision Economics, 381-398. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1993), ‘Should Employees be Subject to Fines and Imprisonment Given the Existence of Corporate Liability?’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 239-257. Posner Richard A. (1992), Economic Analysis of Law (4th edn), Boston, Little, Brown and Company. Ryan, Patrick J. (1991), ‘Strange Bedfellows: Corporate Fiduciaries and the General Law Compliance Obligation in Section 2.01(a) of the American Law Institute’s Principle of Corporate Governance’, 66 Washington Law Review, 413-502. Salzburg, Stephen A. (1991), ‘The Control of Criminal Conduct in Organisations’, 71 Boston University Law Review, 421-438. Segerson, Karen and Tietenberg, Thomas (1992), ‘The Structure of Penalties in Environmental Enforcement: An Economic Analysis’, 23 Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 179-200. Shavell Steven (1997), ‘The Optimal Level of Corporate Liability Given the Limited Ability of Corporations to Penalize Their Employees’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics. Snyder, Edward A. (1990), ‘The Effects of Higher Criminal Penalties on Antitrust Enforcement’, 33 Journal of Law and Economics, 439-462. Staw, B.M. and Szwajkowski, E. (1975), ‘The Scarcity-munificence Component of Organisational Environments and the Commission of Illegal Acts’, 20 Administrative Science Quarterly, 345-354. Stone, C. (1975), Where the Law Ends: The Social Control of Corporate Behavior, New York, Harper and Row. Stone, C. (1980), ‘The Place of Entreprise Liability in Controlling Corporate Conduct’, 90 Yale Law Journal, 1-77. Straachan, J.L., Smith, D.B. and Beedles, W.L. (1983), ‘The Price Reaction to (Alleged) Corporate Crime’, 18 Financial Review, 121-132. Sykes, Alan O. (1981), ‘An Efficiency Analysis of Vicarous Liability Under the Law of Agency’, 91 Yale Law Journal, 168 ff. Sykes, Alan O. (1984), ‘The Economics of Vicarous Liability’, 93 Yale Law Journal, 1231 ff. Ulen, Thomas S. (1996), ‘The Economics of Corporate Criminal Liability’, 17 Managerial and Decision Economics, 351-362. Van Altena, A.R., Schippers, Joop J. and Siegers, Jacques J. (1990), ‘Rechtseconomie en Economisch Strafrecht (Law and Economics and Economic Criminal Law)’, in X (ed.), Facetten van Economisch Strafrecht: Opstellen over Economisch Strafrecht, Arnhem, Gouda Quint, 163-182.
9000 GENERAL CHARACTERISTICS OF RULES Louis Kaplow Harvard Law School and National Bureau of Economic Research © Copyright 1999 Louis Kaplow
Abstract This chapter addresses two fundamental characteristics of rules. The first concerns the degree of precision, detail, or complexity they embody: how finely are different sorts of behavior to be distinguished? A second aspect of legal commands concerns when a given level of detail is provided - at the time of promulgation (‘rules’) or subsequent to individuals’ actions, in the context of adjudication (‘standards’). These aspects of rules are considered from a perspective that focuses upon information costs and dissemination: different sorts of legal commands involve differing costs of formulation and application by private parties (deciding upon their own conduct) and adjudicators, and the character of laws also influences how well parties actually will understand the law and conform their conduct accordingly. The discussion encompasses related questions involving the role of precedent, the evolution of the law over time, legal uncertainty and accuracy in adjudication. This chapter also addresses the separate problem of how changes in legal rules should apply to prior behavior or preexisting investments - issues of retroactivity and transition. JEL classification: K40 Keywords: Rules, Precision, Complexity, Transitions, Retroactivity, Standards
1. Introduction Legal rules serve many functions: channeling behavior (for example, tort law, environmental law, criminal law), providing background rules (much of contract, commercial and corporate law), and defining obligations and eligibility for benefits (tax law, social welfare provisions). This chapter, following existing research, focuses on the first type of law. The relevance (or irrelevance) of the analysis to other types of law will usually be apparent, and some comments about the differences in contexts will be noted. The most commonly noted characteristic of rules concerns the degree of precision, detail, or complexity they embody: how finely are different sorts of behavior to be distinguished? Such matters may arise in defining the scope of a legal command, providing for exceptions, adjusting sanctions based upon aggravating and mitigating circumstances, and so on. A related aspect of legal 502
9000
General Characteristics of Rules
503
commands concerns when a given level of detail is provided - at the time of promulgation (‘rules’) or subsequent to individuals’ actions, in the context of adjudication (‘standards’). These aspects of rules are considered from a perspective that focuses upon information costs and dissemination: different sorts of legal commands involve differing costs of formulation and application by private parties (deciding upon their own conduct) and adjudicators, and the character of laws also influences how well parties actually will understand them and conform their conduct accordingly. This approach is used to illuminate choices about the degree of precision (or complexity) with which legal commands are formulated and between rules and standards. These subjects, in turn, encompass related questions involving the role of precedent, the evolution of the law over time, legal uncertainty and accuracy in adjudication. After outlining the main ideas concerning these topics, this chapter addresses the separate problem of how changes in the law should apply to prior behavior or preexisting investments - issues of retroactivity and transition - and considers some other aspects of rules that have been addressed in the economic analysis of law.
A. Precision of the Law 2. Precision of the Law: The Problem The precision of a legal command is taken here to refer to the degree of detail or differentiation involved. For example, an environmental regulation is more precise if more types of pollutants or sources of pollution are distinguished. A negligence regime is more precise if the standard of care is more finely tailored to different types of actors in different contexts. A damages scheme is more precise the greater the extent to which damages are designed to reflect the particular harm done to a particular victim. The greater the degree of precision, the greater will be the costs of formulating legal commands and applying them in adjudication and of parties interpreting them for purposes of deciding how to conform behavior to the law. But it does not follow that the costs of precision - any more than costs of litigation or of pollution control - should be minimized: the simplest rules might permit all acts, require equal reduction of pollutants regardless of their toxicity, or require the same speed limits on all roads. Rather, the degree of precision should be optimized, which makes an economic analysis particularly useful. Before proceeding, it is worth noting that greater precision in legal commands - higher levels of detail, more distinctions recognized in rules and exceptions - is a primary source of legal complexity, which is broadly condemned. The subject of the next section, whether a legal command is
504
General Characteristics of Rules
9000
formulated as a rule or a standard (the latter leaving more open to subsequent adjudication and thus being more difficult to interpret), also may bear on what is often described as legal complexity. A number of other sources of complexity could be considered, but they have received little attention in the literature. Most obviously, poorly drafted laws and legal opinions will be more confusing; it will be more costly to extract less information. Although this problem is often serious, analysis of it is straightforward. More subtle are problems like those confronted under tax laws wherein parties may devise complicated schemes to circumvent simple legal commands. In this setting, complexity may be unavoidable. Moreover, it is possible that greater complexity will reduce costs: if a more complex regime successfully discourages transactional manipulations, parties might in the end spend less in learning the intricacies of legal rules and in making convoluted arrangements.
3. Effects of Precision on Legal Costs and on Behavior The presentation here follows most closely the model in Kaplow (1995a) (see also Ehrlich and Posner, 1974; Diver, 1983). First, we can consider the effects of precision on legal costs. It is straightforward that greater precision tends to increase them: more detailed laws tend to be more costly for the government to promulgate, for parties to interpret, and for enforcers to apply. The second factor - private interpretation costs - involves some subtlety, because parties will incur such costs only if they find it in their interest to do so. For example, extremely complex details may be ignored by almost everyone. Second, more precise commands - those that differentiate behavior more precisely - will generally result in better behavior. If pollutants are differentiated and subject to particularized sanctions, rather than grouped together and subject to a single sanction (reflecting, say, the average harm they cause), there will be two beneficial results. Activities that are more harmful will be subject to higher sanctions than otherwise, which will efficiently deter additional undesirable activity. Similarly, less harmful activities will face lower sanctions, avoiding inefficient overdeterrence. These behavioral benefits are related to private legal costs, because the benefits can arise only if private actors expend the resources necessary to learn whether their particular activity is of a more or less harmful type, and thus subject to a higher or lower sanction. If the cost of determining the relevant sanction - which may involve learning about the content of legal commands or about the nature of one’s own activity (such as by testing the chemical content of discharges) - is too high, individuals will not learn about the legal rules. Individuals with rather low benefits may simply forgo activities, even though there is some chance that they may be subject to low sanctions or no sanction,
9000
General Characteristics of Rules
505
in which case their activities would be worth undertaking. Individuals with high benefits may simply act, even though there is some chance that they may face a very high sanction, in which case they will regret their decision. Individuals with intermediate benefits, however, will tend to acquire information and then to act accordingly - that is, to proceed if the sanction is low and abstain if the sanction is high. Given the nature of this problem, it is natural to ask whether private parties’ incentives to acquire information will be socially appropriate. It turns out that in the simplest case, in which liability is strict and there are no predictable errors in adjudication, private and social incentives are aligned (for the familiar reason that private actors bear all the social costs of their activities, here including the cost of acquiring information). More generally - if there is legal error, if individuals may misestimate the value of information, if information facilitates circumvention of legal sanctions, or if a negligence regime governs private incentives may be excessive or inadequate (see Shavell, 1988a; Kaplow, 1990; Kaplow and Shavell, 1992). Having stated how parties will behave and what costs will be incurred when laws are more detailed, it is possible to characterize when greater precision is desirable. At the broadest level, the lower the information costs and the greater the variation in harm caused by different individuals’ actions, the larger will be the net benefit of precision in legal commands. To offer more insight, it is helpful to consider some special cases. First, suppose that formulation costs are low (perhaps because a single rule will apply to a large number of actions) and that adjudication costs are low (perhaps because harm occurs only with a low probability or because violations are enforced with a low probability/high sanction strategy, as suggested by Becker, 1968). In this case, more precise laws tend to be desirable as long as information is not prohibitively costly for actors to obtain. The reason is that the actors have the option of not obtaining information. Those who do make expenditures to become informed will be only those for whom the expected behavioral benefit is large - individuals whose acts will be significantly desirable if they are not in fact very harmful but significantly undesirable if they are of the more harmful type. For example, consider a complex rule scheme that regulates routes over which hazardous substances may be transported. Most drivers - those who never or rarely carry significant amounts of such substances - will ignore the rules. Those who regularly transport hazardous materials, however, will undertake the necessary effort to learn the rules and conform their behavior. Their information costs may be high, but the benefits from better controlling their activity will be even larger. One implication of this analysis is that the existence of high total compliance expenditures is not an unambiguous sign of excessively detailed or complex rules. Low total expenditures may indicate that few individuals bother
506
General Characteristics of Rules
9000
to learn the details of the law, in which case any additional formulation or adjudication costs would largely be wasted. High total expenditures, on the other hand, reflect that many individuals contemplate actions the desirability of which is contingent upon the type of their act; in this case, saving compliance costs by eliminating the law’s precision may be a mistake because significant behavioral benefits will be sacrificed. Another implication of the analysis is that widespread noncompliance need not indicate that rules are unduly complex; as long as the few for whom the rules are most important do learn the details, the benefits of precision will be achieved at little cost with regard to others. As a second case, suppose that private information costs are low (perhaps most individuals already know the details of their actions and how they might be sanctioned) but that the cost of differentiating acts in adjudication would be high (because it is hard for the state to learn the details of individuals’ behavior). In this case, more refined legal commands may or may not be desirable. For example, additional costs may be repeatedly incurred in adjudication even though few individuals’ behavior would be affected as a result of greater detail in the law. The distinction between this case and the foregoing one is that the state must make additional expenditures on adjudication even when the ex ante benefit of improved behavior would be small, because the state will not know when this is true; by contrast, when only ex ante information costs are high, private parties will incur them selectively.
4. Relationship of the Precision of the Law to the Accuracy of Adjudication The precision of the law has a direct connection to the accuracy of adjudication, a topic explored in Kaplow (1994a) and Kaplow and Shavell (1994, 1996a). The former subject can be taken to refer to the precision of the law on the books and the latter question to the precision with which the law actually is applied. At the time they act, individuals will be induced to become more informed about the details of their situation only if, in a subsequent adjudication, their behavior will in fact be differentiated from that of others. If, instead, individuals’ acts will be assigned to different legal categories largely at random, or if no effort will be made to refine the classification of acts, the situation is much as if the law itself did not make the refined distinctions in the first place. Many topics of procedure - discovery, the use of experts, evidentiary rules, summary judgment, juries, appeals, burdens of proof - and many substantive rules - notably, concerning which categories of damages may be established and whether damages are determined by individualized evidence or by standardized tables - may thus be illuminated by analysis similar to that presented here. A central concern when assessing these features of adjudication is parties’ incentives in litigation to make expenditures on their own behalf: it often may
9000
General Characteristics of Rules
507
be the case that parties, if freely permitted to undertake further efforts in litigation, will spend excessively because the private benefits from favorably influencing the outcome will exceed any social benefits from enhanced precision in applying legal rules.
5. Related Issues and Literature The preceding discussion may be extended in a number of ways. Spier (1994) incorporates settlement bargaining. The interesting complication is that application of a more precise rule in adjudication may make information that is possessed by only one party relevant to the outcome. By thereby creating a situation involving asymmetric information, settlement becomes less likely. Thus, greater precision may be accompanied by increased litigation costs. Kaplow (1995a) briefly considers costly sanctions - monetary payments made by risk-averse individuals and nonmonetary sanctions. Few generalizations are possible. For risk-averse actors who do not become informed, greater differentiation may increase risk-bearing costs, although, as noted in Kaplow and Shavell (1996a), more precise damage awards may reduce the risks borne by uninsured victims. Kaplow (1990) examines the case in which some individuals know how the law differentiates among acts but others do not. In this case, there is no general deterrence rationale favoring lower sanctions for individuals who mistakenly commit violations, but reducing their sanctions may be optimal when sanctions are socially costly, because the lower rate of compliance by mistaken individuals results in sanctions being imposed more often. Kaplow (1995a) extends the analysis to regimes of self-reporting, as is common with much environmental and safety regulation as well as with many forms of taxation. Self-reporting tends to be efficient when individuals’ information costs are much lower than the government’s; increasing precision in a self-reporting regime has the confounding effect of inducing some individuals to acquire information not to determine how better to behave but solely to determine how best to report their conduct. Most applied work on complexity and compliance costs is in the field of taxation. Empirical work is extensive: see, for example, Long and Swingen (1987), Arthur D. Little (1988), Slemrod (1989), Blumenthal and Slemrod (1992). Analysis of the benefits of precision in the tax context is qualitatively different from that presented here because the benefits of fine-tuning taxpayers’ payments typically involve matters of distributive equity and minimizing adverse incentive effects of taxation rather than of optimally controlling harm-causing behavior (see, for example, Yitzhaki, 1979; Kaplow, 1994c, 1996). The most obvious simplifying devices in the United States income tax code are the standard deduction (which taxpayers may take instead of itemizing
508
General Characteristics of Rules
9000
particular deductions) and the use of floors (which forbid small amounts of deductions); they are analyzed in Kaplow (1994b) and Slemrod and Yitzhaki (1994). The discussion here, like much analysis in law and economics, emphasizes the role of legal commands in providing incentives to govern parties’ behavior ex ante. Modifications to the analysis would be required when adjudication concerns future behavior, as in the granting of licenses, enjoining harm-causing behavior, incarcerating dangerous individuals, or determining eligibility for government benefits. In particular, the benefit of precision in adjudication will be greater than otherwise because the outcome will affect future activity directly (perhaps in addition to influencing ex ante incentives), and concerns about whether individuals will learn the relevant details of the law may be less relevant. Finally, it is worth noting that the benefits of more detailed rules are relevant to wholly private ordering, as in contractual arrangements (contingencies can be distinguished more precisely, and provisions may provide reasonably complete specifications or be more open-ended) or in the internal organization of firms. As a result, work on the economics of contracting and organizations, wholly apart from analysis of the law, can illuminate issues concerning the design of legal rules, and conversely.
B. Rules versus Standards 6. Rules versus Standards: The Problem The choice between rules and standards has long received attention from legal commentators and more recently has been addressed from an economic perspective. The presentation here will follow Kaplow (1992a); a number of the points, particularly concerning the effects of rules and standards on legal costs and on behavior, can also be found in the prior economic analyses by Ehrlich and Posner (1974) and Diver (1983). An initial obstacle in analyzing rules and standards involves matters of definition. Usage varies greatly (which is no surprise since most dictionaries offer definitions of each term that use the other), and logically distinct issues are often combined or confused. For purposes of economic analysis, it is useful to define the difference between rules and standards as involving exclusively the distinction between whether the law is given content ex ante or ex post. Thus, a rule might list hazardous substances that may not be released into the water supply whereas a standard may only proscribe releases of hazardous substances, leaving the determination of which substances are hazardous to adjudication, after releases have occurred. This distinction between rules and standards is obviously one of degree, although it often is convenient to discuss it as an all-or-nothing choice. A law
9000
General Characteristics of Rules
509
is more rule-like the greater the extent to which it provides advance guidance: it may, for example, provide a partial list or state criteria to be used, either of which will ease the application of the legal norm to particular behavior. Moreover, even a given formal specification will have a different character depending upon what is understood about the mode of adjudication and upon what other information is available in advance. For example, if everyone knows that an adjudicator is likely to rely upon a recent government study that indicates the degree of danger posed by potentially hazardous substances, the situation will be almost the same as that under a rule that incorporated the study’s results. For present purposes, such a situation will be viewed as essentially rule-like, as the economic analysis depends upon the extent to which content - as understood by private parties and adjudicators - has actually been provided in advance, not upon the wording of legal commands. (It thus can be seen that the generation and dissemination of information, even when not explicitly embodied in a legal rule, is an important aspect of the law.) Finally, it is important to distinguish the question of the degree to which content is determined ex ante from the preceding subject, which concerns the degree of precision with which a law is formulated or applied. Often, commentators assume that standards are inherently more precise or subtle than rules because standards leave open the possibility of considering all possible factors whereas rules, no matter how detailed, provide a definitive resolution that is not open to reconsideration. But this assumption implicitly contemplates that adjudicators will devote virtually unlimited resources in applying standards. Such an outcome is irrational, implausible, and inconsistent with the actual operation of legal systems. For example, tax codes and many safety regulations are far more detailed and context-dependent than, say, the results that would be produced by a jury that was presented with the open-ended question of what tax payment or safety regime was appropriate. As a result of law, custom, or the application of common sense, an adjudicator may well consider far less than all conceivably relevant factors. In an ordinary negligence dispute involving modest stakes, parties will not commission numerous expert studies; nor will the adjudicator commit substantial time to consider all possibilities. Thus, it is a matter of choice how much detail will be incorporated in rules and standards, and it is hardly the case that rule-like systems tend to be particularly simple and standard-like schemes extremely precise in actual operation. The main point for present purposes is that the question of how much refinement is optimal when formulating and applying the law - legal precision - is logically and, to a great extent, practically distinct from the question whether a given degree of precision is best specified in advance (rules) or left to adjudication (standards). In the end, one can combine the following analysis of rules versus standards with the preceding analysis of the optimal precision of the law to determine what sort of legal command is best.
510
General Characteristics of Rules
9000
7. Effects of Rules and Standards on Legal Costs and on Behavior Rules are defined as legal commands that provide greater specification in advance. Hence, the initial cost of formulating rules will be greater than the cost of formulating standards. It will be necessary, for example, to undertake studies to determine which substances are hazardous and to determine appropriate thresholds of safety if a rule listing hazardous substances is to be promulgated. Such efforts can be avoided (for the moment) under a standard that merely proscribes the release of hazardous substances and leaves their determination to subsequent proceedings. On the other hand, rules will be cheaper for private parties to interpret when deciding upon their own conduct and for adjudicators to apply to past behavior. Precisely because more has been determined in advance, there will be less need for parties to conduct their own studies and to predict legal outcomes and for adjudicators to devote effort to determine whether a violation should be deemed to have occurred. If a rule specifies which substances may be discharged, actors and adjudicators need merely consult the list to apply a rule, whereas substantial inquiry may be necessary under a standard. The same reasoning concerning the ease of application suggests that rules will tend to produce behavior more in conformity with legal norms than would equivalent standards. Because parties will be able to learn the governing norms more cheaply and accurately in advance, they will tend to behave more in accord with such norms. (This raises the question, explored in Kaplow and Shavell (1992) and noted above, whether private parties’ incentives to learn about the law will be socially appropriate.) When guidance is easier to obtain, fewer parties will be deterred from behavior that actually is not objectionable, because they will have greater confidence that such behavior will not be subject to legal sanctions. More parties will be deterred from truly undesirable behavior because they are less likely to proceed in the mistaken belief that the prospect of being sanctioned is remote. It is important to observe that the desirable effect of rules on behavior may hold even when standards turn out to be more precise in actual adjudication, for any refinement embodied in the application of standards will influence behavior only to the extent parties are able to predict the relevant details in advance, and often parties will not make such precise predictions. (The point that details tend to be helpful only when parties find it in their interest to learn them was emphasized in the preceding section on the precision of legal rules.) Combining these effects, one can see that rules tend to be preferable when particular activities are frequent, and standards do best when behavior varies so greatly that any particular scenario is relatively rare. The reason is that the added cost of rules, at the formulation stage, is borne once, whereas the relative benefits of rules - lower costs and greater compliance for private actors and
9000
General Characteristics of Rules
511
lower costs of adjudication - may arise often or almost never, as the case may be. Thus, for dry cleaning and automotive fluids, it would be best to specify permitted disposal techniques in advance, for the many small establishments would be unlikely to be able to determine the effects on their own and, even if they could, the costs of each obtaining information on the matter would be great; also, redundant costs would be incurred in inevitable enforcement proceedings. But in the case substances that are rarely used, it may not be worthwhile to specify the range of permitted and prohibited disposal techniques in advance because most scenarios involving potentially hazardous action may never arise. In this regard, it should be noted that the frequency of activity may be great even if reported adjudications in a field are few. For example, rules might lead countless individuals to comply with the law at very low cost. Even when compliance is imperfect (or when harm nonetheless arises and is subject to a regime of strict liability), there may be little adjudication despite frequent activity because the probability of harm is low, detection of harm is unlikely, or most legal disputes are quickly settled. Conversely, disputes may appear to be frequent but not indicate that conditions are favorable to the use of rules. For example, there are many negligence disputes but some types may involve unique situations that, ex ante, were unlikely ever to arise. Finally, the costs and benefits of rules and standards are important for determining the optimal effort to devote to formulating rules and to applying rules and standards in adjudication. All else equal, the greater the frequency of the behavior to be governed, the more valuable it will be to formulate the law with greater care. Conversely, to the extent that an adjudication is relevant to only a single case, it will not be very valuable to expend substantial resources to consider myriad factors in order to reach a precise determination - unless a precedent is to be set, as discussed below. That individuals may have difficulty predicting refined decisions with any accuracy will strengthen this point. These considerations reinforce the previous observation that, in fact, rules often will be more precise and subtle than standards, taking into account how the latter will actually be applied.
8. Precedent, Other Legal Interpretations, and the Evolution of Legal Commands Precedent may be seen as the (perhaps partial) conversion of a standard into a rule. Whether after accumulated experience or as a result of hearing a single case, a tribunal may issue a statement that will govern future adjudication. At that point, and to that extent, a rule will have been established. Similarly, even less authoritative legal interpretations, ranging from discussions in judicial
512
General Characteristics of Rules
9000
opinions to public statements of enforcement agencies, will tend to guide future behavior and adjudications to some degree. Once the analysis of standards - the state of affairs before the precedent - and of rules - after the precedent - is understood, the study of precedent (and other legal interpretations) is straightforward. A few particular factors, however, deserve some elaboration. It is worth asking why the use of precedent is superior to an earlier announcement of rules. After all, the primary burden of using a rule, incurring additional formulation costs, is ultimately borne when the precedent is established. But in the interim, before the precedent is announced, the benefits of cheaper and better guidance of behavior and simpler adjudication - are forgone. This point is particularly striking when an important, open legal question is identified many years or decades before a precedent is finally announced. The primary advantage of delay is that more information may be collected in the interim - information about the optimal legal command or about the importance of resolving an issue. But many precedents are announced with little more information than existed initially. Moreover, the most efficient way to collect information may be to commission a study in the first place rather than to wait until a case happens to appear before the relevant tribunal (when all that is then learned is the single data point from that case or perhaps a handful of data points). Also, once more information does become available through whatever means, it is not clear why the legal system should not make an announcement immediately rather than waiting still further. It should be noted that making initial legal commands more rule-like does not imply that they cannot be changed if new information becomes available. The prospect of change does reduce the benefit of rules, but it does not follow that there will be no benefit from providing guidance in the interim. Indeed, many detailed regimes that are designed by regulatory agencies have a more rule-like character, with occasional revision, and detailed statutes, such as tax codes, are made precise but often revised later. (And, of course, precedents themselves are extended, narrowed, and reversed.) With standards, change may occur implicitly, but the prospect of change will accordingly increase the cost and difficulty of prediction. Substantial developments that call for significantly different legal commands may be apparent, making prediction under standards easier, but also presenting a clear case for adjusting rules. It is hardly the case that operative legal commands in heavily rule-governed domains (like tax and environmental regulation) and the interpretation of important precedents change slowly compared, say, to applications of the negligence rule. For prior economic analyses of precedent, emphasizing that the body of precedent can be analogized to a capital stock that depreciates over time, see Landes and Posner (1976) and Posner (1992). See also Landes and Posner’s (1994) discussion of the related subject of anticipatory adjudication, in which
9000
General Characteristics of Rules
513
a party may seek a legal decision before undertaking an activity, so as to avoid the need to wait for a precedent.
9. Related Issues and Literature Other law and economics work that is addressed directly to the subjects considered herein includes Ogus (1981) (discussing rules formulated in quantitative terms), and Ogus (1992) (emphasizing private actors greater ability to predict rules than standards). The choice between rules and standards is closely related to the problem of legal uncertainty. Indeed, if rules are defined as the extent to which legal commands are given content ex ante and thus the ease with which private parties can predict how the law will apply to their conduct, legal uncertainty might be viewed as simply a measure of the extent to which a legal command is standard-like. Uncertainty about the negligence rule has received the greatest attention in the literature (see Calfee and Craswell, 1984; Craswell and Calfee, 1986, and Shavell, 1987). Because the negligence rule has an all-or-nothing (discontinuous) character - taking slightly more care will exonerate an actor from what otherwise would be significant liability - uncertainty about the legal standard may tend to produce excessive care (although it is also possible that great uncertainty will produce too little care). The suggestion that malpractice liability results in overly defensive medicine is one example. For empirical evidence, see Kessler and McClellan (1996). Kahan (1989) shows that these issues would not arise if negligent actors were not responsible for all the harm they caused, but only for the incremental increase in harm due to their negligence. Also, in considering legal uncertainty, it would be appropriate to extend the present analysis and that in prior work on the negligence rule to take explicit account of risk-bearing costs. As noted when addressing legal precision, the discussion here focuses on the role of law in providing incentives to control parties’ ex ante behavior. When future behavior (licenses, injunctions, incarceration, benefit eligibility) is involved, the analysis will differ. Indeed, the difference between ex ante and ex post formulation may be moot, as a definitive resolution will in any event precede the relevant effect of a legal decision. There are, nonetheless, similar questions about the benefits of wholesale decision making, as in stating a rule for a class of cases rather than adjudicating the same question repeatedly. And the foregoing analysis remains applicable to the extent adjudication will influence ex ante incentives in addition to regulating future behavior (such as in the case of incarceration). There are other functions of law as well. Much of contract law and related fields is concerned with providing rules of form or background rules that leave
514
General Characteristics of Rules
9000
parties free to transact as they wish (see, for example, Baird and Weisberg, 1982). Because the purpose of such law is different - law is largely facilitating rather than constraining - the analysis would have to be different. Nonetheless, it seems that in contexts where transactions are frequent, the benefit of greater ex ante formulation - through rules - would be larger. Yet another concern with some bodies of law is to constrain fraud. In some instances (notably, tax evasion) greater specificity in advance might be problematic because parties will better be able to evade legal norms. Both uncertainty and complexity, discussed previously, may be desirable precisely because parties will be less able to predict the law. Apart from normative analysis, one can inquire into lawyers’ and legal institutions incentives to formulate legal commands. In this regard, conflicts between private and social interest may be noted. For example, lower legal costs save social resources but may reduce the demand for lawyers (see, for example, White, 1992). And legislation might be designed with an eye to attracting campaign contributions rather than serving the public interest (see, for example, Doernberg and McChesney, 1987). Regulators may be more concerned with their own costs in formulating and applying rules than in private costs (see, for example, Diver, 1983). Finally, the present discussion may be situated in the large literatures in the areas of legal philosophy and public choice which examine the rule of law and in particular address the use of rules to constrain official discretion. For a reasonably comprehensive treatment of rules that attends to functional concerns, see Schauer (1991).
C. Changes in Legal Rules: Transitions and Retroactivity 10. Transitions and Retroactivity: The Problem Transition rules, including a determination of whether a law is to apply retroactively, concern not the form and content of substantive legal commands but instead how the problem of legal change is to be addressed. The most common problem of legal change concerns the fact that investments and other actions often have effects in the future, at which time the governing legal regime may be different. Changes in the law will affect, positively or negatively as the case may be, the returns from prior actions. This raises the question whether losses from legal change should be compensated or otherwise mitigated (as through grandfather provisions that exempt prior investments or phase-ins that implement the change only gradually) and, analogously, whether gains from legal change should be subject to windfall taxation or otherwise reduced.
9000
General Characteristics of Rules
515
As first analyzed carefully in the context of tax reform by Graetz (1977), these problems arise even when new legislation is nominally prospective. For example, if a tax subsidy is repealed, a prior investment that benefited on a continuing basis from the subsidy will become less valuable even if none of the prior subsidy payments must be returned to the government. The possibility of explicit retroactivity does, however, expand the potential scope for transition issues: even completed transactions might subsequently be rewarded or penalized when laws change. The general problem of transition, analyzed in Hale (1927), Samuels (1974), and Kaplow (1986, 1987, 1992b), arises much more widely and with more common elements than is usually appreciated. Basically, whenever there is uncertainty concerning government policy - about statutory change, new regulation or deregulation, court decisions, government spending priorities, takings of private property for public use, tariffs, and so on - the resolution of the uncertainty will create winners and losers. Thus, all government action (unless fully anticipated), government inaction (that is not fully anticipated that is, when change had a positive probability that was not realized), and even changes in the prospect for action in the future, will tend to affect the value of prior investments. The potentially affected investments include physical and financial assets, investments in human capital, and choices of location and occupation, among others. As this general description suggests, an important aspect of the transition problem concerns the ex ante choice of private actors - individuals and firms under uncertainty. The prospect of legal change (like that of any other change) will affect both investment incentives and the imposition of risk, and these incentive effects and risk-bearing costs will in turn be influenced by whether transition relief is anticipated and provided. The immediately following analysis considers the question of optimal government transition policy, taking as given the actual change in the law that might occur and its desirability. The focus is on how transition relief affects the behavior and wellbeing of private parties and, accordingly, its effect on social welfare. Subsequent discussion will take up concerns about possible government misbehavior in changing the law and how different transition policies may influence government activity.
11. Effects of Transitions and Transition Relief on Private Actors’ Incentives and on Risk-bearing Costs Begin by considering the case in which private actors are risk-neutral (which may be approximately true for large, widely-owned enterprises that are the subject of much legal regulation). Suppose that there is some prospect, say, a 50 percent chance, of an adverse legal change: a firm’s product might be
516
General Characteristics of Rules
9000
banned if it turns out that the product is dangerous. Anticipating such a possibility - and assuming for the moment that there will be no compensation, exemption, or other relief to those investing prior to the transition - private parties will invest less than they would otherwise. Half the time they will earn some positive return and the other half of the time they will earn no return (and, indeed, they may lose their initial investment). Now suppose instead that investors anticipate that there will be complete transition relief, say, full compensation. In this case, investors expect a positive return for sure, so they are more likely to invest - or to invest at a larger scale than if there were to be no relief. As Blume, Rubinfeld and Shapiro (1984) first showed formally in the takings context, the prospect of such relief induces inefficient overinvestment. The key point is that a private loss in such instances corresponds to a real social loss. If a product is too dangerous and must be banned, sunk investments that are valuable only for producing such a product will be of no subsequent social value. Hence, insulating investors from such risks is inefficient, just as it would be inefficient to insulate investors from the prospect that their products might become obsolete or lose out to better products of competitors. As noted by Hale (1927), Samuels (1974), Graetz (1977), and Kaplow (1986, 1987, 1992b), from the perspective of investors, the risk of future government action is similar to various market risks and natural risks (earthquakes, hurricanes). Private decisions are efficient when actors bear the full costs and benefits of their actions. Transition relief thus does not correct an externality; it creates one. This analysis of transition relief may be extended to determine when retroactive application of legal changes is efficient (see Kaplow, 1986, 1987, 1992b). If a product is banned because it is discovered to be dangerous, it is probably the case that past production of the product resulted in danger as well. Thus, imposing retrospective liability will tend to be efficient, in order for investors ex ante to have had the proper incentives to take safety into account. By contrast, if a pollutant is to be regulated because it damages a newly introduced crop strain, there is no reason to impose retrospective liability, for the decision to regulate the pollutant does not suggest that the pollutant previously caused some social harm. To generalize, when the government discovers new information about conditions that have long been in existence, retroactive application in some form will often be necessary to provide the right ex ante incentives, but when there is a change in circumstances that makes future use undesirable without affecting the desirability of past conduct, retroactivity will be inefficient. Similar reasoning suggests that transition relief is inefficient even when private actors are risk averse (see Kaplow, 1986, 1987, 1992b). In this case, relief has the advantage of reducing risk-bearing costs. But private arrangements - diversified ownership, insurance, contractual risk allocations,
9000
General Characteristics of Rules
517
and the like - also may be available. Moreover, these mechanisms have systematic advantages over transition relief. First, they often are implemented in ways that preserve incentives, in full or in part. For example, insurance premiums are greater the more assets are covered, so investors contemplating expansion in the face of some risk will bear the expected loss ex ante through higher insurance payments. In other cases, private risk mitigation is partial precisely to preserve incentives; absent other market imperfections (notably, adverse selection), private risk-sharing arrangements tend to be efficient. Transition relief generally lacks these features. Second, even if transition relief were only partial, private parties would undertake actions to further mitigate risk; such actions may worsen their incentives (moral hazard), but some of the resulting cost would be borne by the government. Again the analogy to market risks can be made: just as government relief (as in the case of disaster relief) tends to be inefficient for ordinary risks (see Arnott and Stiglitz, 1991; Kaplow, 1991), so government relief against government-created risks tends to be inefficient with regard to private investment and risk-mitigation incentives.
12. Related Issues The analysis assumes that transition policy will be anticipated by investors and actually implemented by the government. To the extent such policy is embodied in constitutional provisions or strong norms that guide legal reform, the assumption is plausible. More generally, a government is unlikely to succeed in the long run in getting investors to expect one transition policy while often implementing another. Problems of credible commitment may make it difficult to establish a desired transition policy. To consider a familiar analogy, some governments regularly offer ex post relief when natural disasters strike, which has the effect of encouraging individuals to, say, invest excessively in building on flood plains. A possible solution to this political commitment problem is for the government either to regulate such activity (limiting investment in high-risk areas) or to compel the purchase of insurance in advance at actuarially fair rates (the insurance premiums would discourage excessive investment and the fact that victims have paid for compensation in advance would eliminate the pressure for ex post relief). Most of the discussion here, like most in various literatures that address transition issues - ranging from tax reform to deregulation - emphasizes the case in which investors suffer transition losses. But it was noted at the outset that transition gains arise with similar frequency. The analysis of both possibilities is symmetric: just as providing relief for losses will encourage overinvestment, imposing windfall taxes on gains (or otherwise reducing them) will produce underinvestment. Few if any windfall gains - or losses - are really
518
General Characteristics of Rules
9000
pure windfalls. It tends to be best for investors to bear all the gains and losses they cause, with any risk mitigation being contractually arranged to provide for the most effective limitation of adverse incentive effects. Another question of transition policy concerns the means of relief. One can compensate losers (and tax winners) in whole or in part, grandfather prior investors (that is, provide some exemption from new rules), or curtail the new policy (as by delay or phase-in or implementing reform only partially). With regard to ex ante incentives and mitigation of risk, all of these approaches are similar, to the extent that they provide the same degree of effective relief. (For example, a phase-in that reduces gains and losses by half has effects like that of 50 percent compensation and 50 percent windfall taxation.) With regard to future behavior, however, compensation and windfall taxation are generally superior to other forms of relief. Grandfathering, for example, might exempt existing producers of dangerous products, allowing the danger to continue (but perhaps not to grow); delaying implementation would similarly permit some future harm. By contrast, immediate elimination of the danger accompanied by compensation would avoid this difficulty. As in the discussion of rule formulation, the present analysis is most applicable to laws that regulate behavior. Contract rules that serve as defaults are quite different. If a default rule is changed, it may well be that the prior rule should govern preexisting contracts, for parties may have failed to make special provision in their contracts precisely because they knew they could rely upon background rules. On the other hand, if a default is changed because new analysis suggests that most parties have a different preference than previously suspected, and if many contracts are silent simply because of the cost of making special provision, it could be best to apply the new default to preexisting agreements.
13. Effects on Government Behavior of Requiring Transition Relief The foregoing analysis takes as given a particular legal change, assumes that it is well conceived, and asks how transition relief affects private behavior. But it cannot be assumed that government always acts appropriately, and transition relief may affect the behavior of government. One familiar argument is that transition relief - in particular, requiring compensation - provides the government proper incentives because then government bears the full costs of its actions. One can make the analogy to tort liability when both injurers’ and victims’ behavior affects accident costs. For analysis of this tort problem, see Shavell (1980), and for application to the transition context see Kaplow (1986, 1987); for a similar discussion, see Blume, Rubinfeld and Shapiro (1984). No liability - or schemes that provide no
9000
General Characteristics of Rules
519
compensation when injurers behave well, a negligence-type rule, or that deny compensation when victims behave improperly, contributory or comparative negligence rules - is best for victims’ incentives (like investors’ incentives, above), whereas full liability - strict or otherwise - is best for injurers’ incentives. If one can assume that the government (the ‘injurer’) always behaves properly, then a regime that denies compensation is best for the incentives of investors (the ‘victims’). But if one cannot make this assumption about government behavior, one may wish to impose liability on the government - for example, by requiring compensation. Unless some tribunal can determine when the government or investors misbehaved, which is likely to be very difficult in most transition contexts (and which involves courts second-guessing legislative, executive, agency, or their own actions), it must be recognized that any solution will be a compromise: if some relief is required, government’s incentives may improve but investors’ incentives will be worse. This argument, however, is incomplete (see Kaplow, 1986, 1987). The implicit assumption is that the government, like a private investor, receives the benefits from its actions. But the benefits of most government action - banning hazardous products, improving tort rules, building highways - are received by private citizens. Thus, making the legislature or an agency pay for transition losses (in addition to paying for direct costs, as in building a highway) when few if any of the benefits are directly received might systematically skew decisions against any change. Once benefits as well as costs are considered, it is not obvious that even a highly imperfect government is generally biased in favor of change when no compensation or other relief is required. For any bias whether for or against change - to exist, there must be some asymmetry in the government’s treatment of costs and benefits. Some theories of government action (see Downs, 1957 and Olson, 1965), suggest that the most effective political interest groups are those on whom gains or losses are concentrated. Other theories are concerned with the majority exploiting the minority. Still others (see Niskanen, 1971), emphasize bureaucrats’ desire to enhance their budget or prestige. Thus, whether requiring compensation would make government behavior better or worse depends upon which theories of government behavior are most plausible, whether it is the benefits or the costs that are more concentrated, and other factors (see also Quinn and Trebilcock, 1982). Another concern with government behavior involves the problem of pure expropriation (see Kaplow, 1987). It is familiar from public economics that the most efficient government tax is a one-time capital levy, in which capital (more broadly, savings, assets in any form) is taken and the government promises never to repeat the action. As long as the expropriation is wholly unanticipated, there will be no adverse ex ante incentive effects; likewise, if it will never be repeated, there will be no future distortions in behavior. Levmore (1993) offers
520
General Characteristics of Rules
9000
this as a basis for a more favorable view toward retroactive taxation. But it has long been recognized that governments would find it difficult to engage in such inconsistent behavior. Rather, there needs to be some commitment - whether through constitutional means or long-established norms - that the government will not expropriate, and governments that deviate from such a path will be unlikely to be able to provide investors with confidence for the future. In principle, expropriation can be distinguished from other government action. As noted when addressing private incentives, it is efficient for investors to anticipate and respond to the prospect that new information or changed circumstances will affect what government regulation is optimal, just as new developments will influence the market directly in ways that investors should take into account. Anticipating expropriation, however, is inefficient ex ante. The benefit arises from transferring resources to the government, not from providing proper incentives for private behavior. To be sure, some taxation is required, to fund public goods and services and to accomplish redistribution. Particularly with regard to redistribution, it would improve efficiency if taxpayers did not anticipate having to pay taxes, as such anticipation results in distortion of behavior. But this problem is largely unavoidable. Successful economies seem to have succeeded, for the most part, in avoiding expropriation. The mechanism by which this is accomplished is not that clear; no system prohibits taxation or legal changes, and constitutional or other strong compensation requirements are limited. (For example, in the United States, the government must compensate a landowner whose building is taken for a highway, but a high capital income or wealth tax is not legally proscribed.) The development of strong norms seems to play a greater role in successful economies, but such norms cannot succeed unless the relevant audience can understand which legal reforms are improper in the relevant respect. A variant of the expropriation problem arises when the government is involved with ordinary contractual behavior and related activity. In fact, most governments accomplish many of their purposes - building roads, procuring military equipment, hiring employees - through ordinary market transactions. (In some countries, state enterprises are common; these too, however, often use ordinary contractual means of paying workers and purchasing other necessary inputs.) Moreover, most governments, despite the availability of sovereign immunity from private suits, voluntarily subject themselves to a legal regime under which their contracts have a binding effect similar to that of private contracts. This avoids problems of opportunism, both large and small. Some commentators have analogized legislation and other government law-making to government contracts (see, for example, Graetz, 1977; Kaplow, 1986, 1987; Ramseyer and Nakazato, 1989; Logue, 1996). Thus, sometimes the government uses subsidies to induce certain behavior rather than explicit contracts under which it pays for a promise to undertake certain activity. If the
9000
General Characteristics of Rules
521
subsidy is terminated, this might be viewed as a breach of an implicit contract. Of course, subsidies are routinely terminated. When governments use ongoing subsidies to encourage an activity rather than entering into a long-term contract to pay for a given amount of the activity, they are choosing to use a more flexible mechanism, allowing the possibility of change without compensation. To impose a norm or constitutional requirement that all law be treated as if it were a binding contract would not add to the government’s options; it would eliminate one. (Actually, it may have no effect at all, as laws could simply be written to expire unless extended or with some other loophole providing the government a way to avoid any binding obligation.)
14. Additional Issues Transition relief is sometimes favored because it may make it politically feasible to implement desirable reform. For example, efficient deregulation might be opposed by protected incumbents, who could be bought out with compensation (see Tullock, 1978; see also Usher, 1995, addressing compensation for takings). The problem is that, ex ante, special interest groups would have a greater incentive to seek inefficient rules, knowing that even if the rules were subsequently repealed they would benefit from transition relief (see Kitch, 1977; Quinn and Trebilcock, 1982; McKenzie, 1986; Kaplow, 1987, 1992b). Thus, it is not obvious that a policy of buying out such political opposition would in the long run produce better or worse laws and lead to more or less resources being wasted on rent-seeking activity. Another problem concerns changes in political power that may produce legal changes that do not reflect real changes in information or circumstances (although legal reforms may reflect shifts in perceptions or in value judgments). Small changes in beliefs may produce large legal changes (as when an opposition party gains a few percentage points in support and comes into power), and such change may be frequent. Ex ante behavior that is desirable from the perspective of one party’s policies may be undesirable from the perspective of the other’s. Use of transition relief will tend to cause investors to put more weight on the status quo, something unlikely to be favored by a subsequent regime seeking change. Analysis of social welfare in such instances is difficult.
522
General Characteristics of Rules
9000
15. Literature The first careful analysis of many issues concerning legal transitions appears to be Hale (1927). For a general analysis of changing legal rules in a variety of contexts, see Kaplow (1986, 1987, 1992b). Most writing by legal academics on the subject focuses on takings or on tax reform. With respect to takings, Michelman (1967) offers an important early analysis, although it does not take the economic approach as far as subsequent work. Baxter and Altree (1972) advance a ‘first-in-time’ approach to address the problem of airport noise; they are among the first to pursue directly the problem of the adverse incentive effects of compensation. Blume, Rubinfeld and Shapiro (1984) analyze incentive effects of compensation in a formal model and Blume and Rubinfeld (1984) consider risk, although these authors do not integrate the two analyses or systematically consider private risk mitigation. Kaplow (1986, 1987) discusses takings in the context of analyzing the transition problem more generally. For additional work, with emphasis on the problem of the government’s incentives, see, for example, Fischel and Shapiro (1989) and Hermalin (1995). For an empirical analysis of the effect of requiring compensation on government behavior, see Cordes and Weisbrod (1979). Feldstein (1976a, 1976b) and Graetz (1977) offer the first substantial treatments of tax transitions, followed by Kaplow (1986, 1987, 1992b), who more explicitly analyzes effects of relief on investors’ incentives and private risk mitigation, compares alternative transition mechanisms, and addresses institutional problems with government decision making. This latter problem is also considered by Ramseyer and Nakazato (1989) and Logue (1996), who are both favorable toward relief because of concerns about government misbehavior. Levmore (1993) is more favorable to (uncompensated) retroactivity because of the possibility of an efficient capital levy. The particular problem of transition to a consumption tax is addressed in Graetz (1979), Kaplow (1986, 1987, 1995b), Sarkar and Zodrow (1993) and Bradford (1996). Another subject receiving increased attention is deregulation and other regulatory changes (see Quinn and Trebilcock, 1982; Kolbe, Tye and Myers, 1993; Kaplow, 1993).
9000
General Characteristics of Rules
523
D. Additional Topics 16. Additional Topics There are a number of other dimensions along which many legal rules vary that are sufficiently general to warrant independent study. Because these subjects are addressed in other fields within law and economics, the present discussion will be brief. Each of the topics considered involves the general question whether laws should identify certain conduct as permitted or prohibited or should instead impose fines, provide for private liability, or use other means of aligning private and social interests so as to induce parties to make efficient choices on their own. Strict Liability Versus Negligence The choice between strict liability and negligence has received much attention. Similar issues arise involving defenses based upon victim behavior. And other areas of law present analogous questions: namely, is a party responsible for all harm caused, or is the party responsible only if behavior was improper (and, then, only to the extent of any additional harm caused by the inappropriate action)? The latter type of law requires both defining a norm of behavior (which may be done ex ante, as a rule, or ex post, as a standard, and which may be done in a simple or precise manner), and both types of law require provisions governing the measurement of harm. This sort of choice involves many of the issues considered here, as well as concerns for the frequency of litigation, victims’ incentives, and other factors (see Brown, 1973; Shavell, 1980, and Chapter 3100 on strict liability versus negligence in tort). Property Versus Liability Rules The distinction between property and liability rules involves remedies: if one party wishes to infringe the legal rights of another, must the acting party first obtain permission (or else be subject to extreme sanctions and the possibility of injunction, if feasible) - a property rule - or may the party simply act and pay damages - a liability rule? This scheme is first explored in detail by Calabresi and Melamed (1972) and has subsequently been expanded in Kaplow and Shavell (1996b). Other relevant work includes Ellickson (1973), Polinsky (1979, 1980) and Krier and Schwab (1995). The problem of bargaining under asymmetric information has attracted disproportionate attention, beginning with Samuelson (1985) and followed, for example, by Farrell (1987), Shavell (1988b), Johnston (1995), Ayres and Talley (1995a, 1995b) and Kaplow and Shavell (1995, 1996b). See Chapter 3800 on property versus liability rules.
524
General Characteristics of Rules
9000
Acknowledgments I am grateful for comments from Steven Shavell and the referees, research assistance from Enrique Arana, Judson Berkey and Jerry Fang, and support from the John M. Olin Center for Law, Economics and Business at Harvard Law School.
Bibliography on General Characteristics of Rules (9000) Arthur D. Little (1988), Development of Methodology for Estimating the Taxpayer Paperwork Burden, Final Report to the Department of the Treasury, Washington, DC, Internal Revenue Service. Baird, Douglas G. and Weisberg, Robert (1982), ‘Rules, Standards and the Battle of the Forms: A Reassessment of §2-207', 68 Virginia Law Review, 1217-1262. Baxter, William F. and Altree, Lillian R. (1972), ‘Legal Aspects of Airport Noise’, 15 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-113. Blume, Lawrence and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1984), ‘Compensation for Takings: An Economic Analysis’, 72 California Law Review, 569-628. Blume, Lawrence, Rubinfeld, Daniel L. and Shapiro, Perry (1984), ‘The Taking of Land. When Should Compensation be Paid?’, 99 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 71-92. Blumenthal, Marsha and Slemrod, Joel B. (1992), ‘The Compliance Cost of the U.S. Individual Income Tax System: A Second Look After Tax Reform’, 45 National Tax Journal, 185-202. Bouckaert, Boudewijn and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (1995), ‘Mistake of Law and the Economics of Legal Information’, in Bouckaert, Boudewijn and De Geest, Gerrit (eds), Essays in Law and Economics II: Contract Law, Regulation, and Reflections on Law and Economics, Antwerpen, Maklu, 217-245. Bradford, David F. (1996), ‘Consumption Taxes: Some Fundamental Transition Issues’, in Boskin, Michael J. (ed.), Frontiers of Tax Reform, Stanford, Hoover Institution Press. Calfee, John E. and Craswell, Richard (1984), ‘Some Effects of Uncertainty on Compliance with Legal Standards’, 70 Virginia Law Review, 965-1003. Cordes, Joseph J. and Weisbrod, Burton A. (1979), ‘Governmental Behavior in Response to Compensation Requirements’, 11 Journal of Public Economics, 47-58. Coulange, Pierre (1990), ‘La Production de Droit (The Production of Legal Rules)’, 3 Journal des Economistes et des Etudes Humaines, 277-302. Coulange, Pierre (1990), Analyse Économique de la Production de Droit (Economic Analysis of the Production of Legal Rules), PhD, Aix-en-Provence, Université d’Aix-Marseille III, Faculté d’Economie Appliquée. Craswell, Richard and Calfee, John E. (1986), ‘Deterrence and Uncertain Legal Standards’, 2 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 279-303. Diver, Colin S. (1983), ‘The Optimal Precision of Administrative Rules’, 93 Yale Law Journal, 65-109. Doernberg, Richard L. and McChesney, Fred S. (1987), ‘On the Accelerating Rate and Decreasing Durability of Tax Reform’, 71 Minnesota Law Review, 913-962.
9000
General Characteristics of Rules
525
Ehrlich, Isaac and Posner, Richard A. (1974), ‘An Economic Analysis of Legal Rulemaking’, 3 Journal of Legal Studies, 257-286. Feldstein, Martin (1976a), ‘On the Theory of Tax Reform’, 6 Journal of Public Economics, 77-104. Feldstein, Martin (1976b), ‘Compensation in Tax Reform’, 29 National Tax Journal, 123-130. Fisch, Jill E. (1997), ‘Retroactivity and Legal Change: An Equilibrium Approach’, 110 Harvard Law Review, 1055-1123. Fischel, William A. and Shapiro, Perry (1989), ‘A Constitutional Choice Model of Compensation for Takings’, 9 International Review of Law and Economics, 115-128. Graetz, Michael J. (1977), ‘Legal Transitions: The Case of Retroactivity in Income Tax Revision’, 126 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 47-87. Graetz, Michael J. (1979), ‘Implementing a Progressive Consumption Tax’, 92 Harvard Law Review, 1575-1661. Graetz, Michael J. (1985), ‘Retroactivity Revisited’, 98 Harvard Law Review, 1820-1841. Hale, Robert L. (1927), ‘Value and Vested Rights’, 27 Columbia Law Review, 523-529. Hermalin, Benjamin E. (1995), ‘An Economic Analysis of Takings’, 11 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 64-86. Hutter, Michael (1989), Die Produktion von Recht. Eine selb streferentielle Theorie der Wirtschaft, angewandt auf den Fall des Arzneimittelpatentrechts (The Production of Law. A Selfreferential Theory of the Economy, applied to the Case of Pharmaceutical Patent Law), Tübingen, J.C.B. Mohr, p. 213. Kahan, Marcel (1989), ‘Causation and Incentives to Take Care Under the Negligence Rule’, 18 Journal of Legal Studies, 427-447. Kaplow, Louis (1986), ‘An Economic Analysis of Legal Transitions’, 99 Harvard Law Review, 509-617. Kaplow, Louis (1987), Optimal Transition Policy: Replacing Horizontal Equity With an Ex Ante Incentives Perspective, dissertation accepted by Harvard University Department of Economics, Cambridge, MA. Kaplow, Louis (1990), ‘Optimal Deterrence, Uninformed Individuals, and Acquiring Information About Whether Acts are Subject to Sanctions’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 93-128. Kaplow, Louis (1992a), ‘Rules versus Standards: An Economic Analysis’, 42 Duke Law Journal, 557-629. Kaplow, Louis (1992b), ‘Government Relief for Risk Associated with Government Action’, 94 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 525-541. Kaplow, Louis (1993), ‘An Ex Ante Perspective on Deregulation, Viewed ex post’, 15 Resource and Energy Economics, 153-173. Kaplow, Louis (1994a), ‘The Value of Accuracy in Adjudication: An Economic Analysis’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 307-401. Kaplow, Louis (1994b), ‘The Standard Deduction and Floors in the Income Tax’, 50 Tax Law Review, 1-31. Kaplow, Louis (1994c), ‘Accuracy, Complexity, and the Income Tax’, Working Paper No. 4631, Cambridge, MA, National Bureau of Economic Research. Kaplow, Louis (1995a), ‘A Model of the Optimal Complexity of Legal Rules’, 11 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 150-163.
526
General Characteristics of Rules
9000
Kaplow, Louis (1995b), ‘Recovery of Pre-Enactment Basis Under a Consumption Tax: The USA Tax System’, 68 Tax Notes, 1109-1118. Kaplow, Louis (1996), ‘How Tax Complexity and Enforcement Affect the Equity and Efficiency of the Income Tax’, 49 National Tax Journal, 135-150. Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (1992), ‘Private versus Socially Optimal Provision of Ex Ante Legal Advice’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 306-320. Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (1994), ‘Accuracy in the Determination of Liability’, 37 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-15. Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (1996a), ‘Accuracy in the Assessment of Damages’, 39 Journal of Law and Economics, 191-210. Kessler, Daniel and McClellan, Mark (1996), ‘Do Doctors Practice Defensive Medicine?’, 111 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 352-390. Kitch, Edmund W. (1977), ‘Can We Buy Our Way Out of Harmful Regulation?’, in Martin, Donald L. and Schwartz, Warren F. (eds), Deregulating American Industry: Legal and Economic Problems, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Kolbe, A. Lawrence, Tye, William B. and Myers, Stewart C. (1993), Regulatory Risk: Economic Principles and Applications to Natural Gas Pipelines and Other Industries, Boston, Kluwer Academic Press. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1976), ‘Legal Precedent: A Theoretical and Empirical Analysis’, 19 Journal of Law and Economics, 249-307. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1994), ‘The Economics of Anticipatory Adjudication’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 683-719. Levmore, Saul (1993), ‘The Case for Retroactive Taxation’, 22 Journal of Legal Studies, 265-307. Logue, Kyle D. (1996), ‘Tax Treatments, Opportunistic Retroactivity, and the Benefits of Government Precommitment’, 94 Michigan Law Review, 1129-1196. Long, Susan B. and Swingen, Judyth A. (1987), ‘An Approach to the Measurement of Tax Law Complexity’, 8 Journal of the American Tax Association, 22-36. MacKaay, Ejan (1979), ‘Les Notions Floues ou l’Economie de l’Imprécision (Fuzzy Concepts or the Economics of Imprecision)’, 12 Langages, 33-50. MacKaay, Ejan (1980), ‘Le Nozione “Fluide” Ovvero l’Economia Dell’Imprecisione (Fuzzy Concepts or the Economics of Imprecision)’, Informatica e Diritto, 253-274. McKenzie, Richard B. (1986), ‘Tax/Compensation Schemes: Misleading Advice in a Rent-Seeking Society’, 48 Public Choice, 189-194. Michelman, Frank I. (1967), ‘Property, Utility and Fairness: Comments on the Ethical Foundations of ‘Just Compensation’ Law’, 80 Harvard Law Review, 1165-1258. Munzer, Stephen R. (1977), ‘Retroactive Law’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 373-397. Ogus, Anthony I. (1981), ‘Quantitative Rules and Judicial Decision Making’, in Burrows, Paul and Veljanovski, Cento G. (eds), The Economic Approach to Law, London, Butterworths, 210-225. Ogus, Anthony I. (1992), ‘Information, Error Costs and Regulation’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 411-421. Posner, Richard A. (1992), Economic Analysis of Law (4th edn), Boston, Little, Brown and Company. Quinn, John and Trebilcock, Michael J. (1982), ‘Compensation, Transition Costs, and Regulatory Change’, 32 University of Toronto Law Journal, 117-175.
9000
General Characteristics of Rules
527
Ramseyer, J. Mark and Nakazato, Minoru (1989), ‘Tax Transitions and the Protection Racket: A Reply to Professors Graetz and Kaplow’, 75 Virginia Law Review, 1155-1175. Russell, A.M. and Rickard, J.A. (1987), ‘A Model of Tax Evasion Incorporating Income Variation and Retroactive Penalities’, 26 Australian Economic Papers, 254-264. Samuels, Warren J. (1974), ‘Commentary: An Economic Perspective on the Compensation Problem’, 21 Wayne Law Review, 113-134. Sarkar, Shounak and Zodrow, George R. (1993), ‘Transitional Issues in Moving to a Direct Consumption Tax’, 46 National Tax Journal, 359-376. Schauer, Frederick (1991), Playing by the Rules: A Philosophical Examination of Rule-Based Decisionmaking in Law and in Life, New York, Oxford University Press. Schwartz, Gary T. (1983), ‘New Products, Old Products, Evolving Law, Retroactive Law’, 58 New York University Law Review, 796-852. Shavell, Steven (1988a), ‘Legal Advice about Contemplated Acts: The Decision to Obtain Advice, Its Social Desirability, and the Protection of Confidentiality’, 17 Journal of Legal Studies, 123-150. Shavell, Steven (1988b), ‘Property Rights and the Rule of Liability in a Simple Bargaining Model’, unpublished manuscript, on file with the Harvard Law School Library, Cambridge, MA. Skogh, Göran (1985), ‘Rättssäkerhet I Marknadsekonomin (Legal Certainty in the Market Economy)’, in X. (ed.), Rättssäkerhet och Demokrati, Ratios förlag. Slemrod, Joel B. (1989), ‘Complexity, Compliance Costs, and Tax Evasion’, in Roth, Jeffrey A. and Scholz, John T. (eds), Taxpayer Compliance, Volume 2: Social Science Perspectives, Philadelphia, University of Pennsylvania Press. Slemrod, Joel B. and Yitzhaki, Shlomo (1994), ‘Analyzing the Standard Deduction as a Presumptive Tax’, 1 International Tax and Public Finance, 25-34. Slot, P.J. (1983), Regelen en Ontregelen. Oratie Leiden (Regulating and De-regulating), Kluwer, Deventer. Spier, Kathryn E. (1994), ‘Settlement Bargaining and the Design of Damage Awards’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 84-95. Tullock, Gordon (1978), ‘Achieving Deregulation - A Public Choice Perspective’, 2 Regulation, 50-54. Usher, Dan (1995), ‘Victimization, Rent-Seeking and Just Compensation’, 83 Public Choice, 1-20. Walz, W. Rainer (1988), ‘Rechtssicherheit und Risikozuweisung bei Steuerrechtsänderungen Verbotene Rückwirkung, gebotene Übergangsregelung, richterliche Vertragsanpassung’ (Legal Certainty and Risk Allocation for Changes in Tax Law - Illegal Retroaction, Transitional Rules), Recht und Risiko, 252-286. White, Michelle J. (1992), ‘Legal Complexity and Lawyers’ Benefit from Litigation’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 381-395. Yitzhaki, Shlomo (1979), ‘A Note on Optimal Taxation and Administrative Costs’, 69 American Economic Review, 475-480.
528
General Characteristics of Rules
9000
Other References Arnott, Richard and Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1991), ‘Moral Hazard and Nonmarket Institutions: Dysfunctional Crowding Out or Peer Monitoring?’, 81 American Economic Review, 179-190. Ayres, Ian and Talley, Eric (1995a), ‘Solomonic Bargaining: Dividing a Legal Entitlement to Facilitate a Coasean Trade’, 104 Yale Law Journal, 1027-1117. Ayres, Ian and Talley, Eric (1995b), ‘Distinguishing Between Consensual and Nonconsensual Advantages of Liability Rules’, 105 Yale Law Journal, 235-253. Becker, Gary S. (1968), ‘Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach’, 76 Journal of Political Economy, 169-217. Brown, John (1973), ‘Toward an Economic Theory of Liability’, 2 Journal of Legal Studies, 323-350. Calabresi, Guido and Melamed, A. Douglas (1972), ‘Property Rules, Liability Rules, and Inalienability: One View of the Cathedral’, 85 Harvard Law Review, 1089-1128. Downs, Anthony (1957), An Economic Theory of Democracy, New York, Harper. Ellickson, Robert C. (1973), ‘Alternatives to Zoning: Covenants, Nuisance Rules, and Fines as Land Use Controls’, 40 University of Chicago Law Review, 681-781. Farrell, Joseph (1987), ‘Information and the Coase Theorem’, 1 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 113-129. Johnston, Jason Scott (1995), ‘Bargaining Under Rules versus Standards’, 11 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 256-281. Kaplow, Louis (1991), ‘Incentives and Government Relief for Risk’, 4 Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 167-175. Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (1995), ‘Do Liability Rules Facilitate Bargaining? A Reply to Ayres and Talley’, 105 Yale Law Journal, 221-233. Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (1996b), ‘Property Rules versus Liability Rules: An Economic Analysis’, 109 Harvard Law Review, 713-790. Krier, James E. and Schwab, Stewart J. (1995), ‘Property Rules and Liability Rules: The Cathedral in Another Light’, 70 New York University Law Review, 440-483. Niskanen, William A. (1971), Bureaucracy and Representative Government, Chicago, Aldine, Atherton. Olson, Mancur (1965), The Logic of Collective Action; Public Goods and the Theory of Groups, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Polinsky, A. Mitchell (1979), ‘Controlling Externalities and Protecting Entitlements: Property Right, Liability Rule, and Tax-Subsidy Approaches’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-48. Polinsky, A. Mitchell (1980), ‘Resolving Nuisance Disputes: The Simple Economics of Injunctive and Damage Remedies’, 32 Stanford Law Review, 1075-1112. Samuelson, William (1985), ‘A Comment on the Coase Theorem’, in Roth, Alvin E. (ed.), Game-Theoretic Models of Bargaining, New York, Cambridge University Press. Shavell, Steven (1980), ‘Strict Liability Versus Negligence’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-25. Shavell, Steven (1987), Economic Analysis of Accident Law, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.
9100 CONSTITUTIONAL LAW Stefan Voigt Max-Planck-Institute for Research into Economic Systems, Jena (Germany) © Copyright 1999 Stefan Voigt
Abstract The chapter discusses both the normative and the positive approach towards the economic analysis of constitutional law. With regard to the normative branch, Buchanan’s approach is shortly presented and evaluated. With regard to the positive branch, it is differentiated between research which is interested in explaining the choice of constitutional rules on the one hand and research which is interested in explaining the outcomes that (alternative) constitutional rules bring about on the other. Concerning the first research direction, a distinction between explicit and implicit constitutional change is proposed. Concerning the second direction, concepts such as the separation of powers, unicameral vs. bicameral systems and direct-democratic institutions are discussed. The entry closes with a proposal to complement the two existing branches with an ‘art of constitutional political economy’ which is conjectured to make the economic analysis of constitutional law more relevant in real world processes of constitutional choice. JEL classification: K0 Keywords: Normative Constitutional Economics, Positive Constitutional Economics, Constitutional Rights, Economic Growth
1. Introduction The economic analysis of constitutional law has not been one of the most researched topics within law and economics. The special issue of the International Review of Law and Economics on ‘Constitutional Law and Economics’ (1992) is rather exceptional. The research program known as ‘constitutional economics’ or ‘constitutional political economy’ has primarily been developed by scholars emanating from public choice, that is, ‘the application of economics to political science’ (Mueller, 1989, p. 1). James M. Buchanan, the most prominent proponent of constitutional economics, has described law and economics as a related subdiscipline that remained, however, closer to orthodox economic theory because the standard efficiency norm remains central to it (Buchanan, 1987a, p. 586). Scholars of constitutional economics have broadened the standard research program of economics: 529
530
Constitutional Law
9100
Standard economics is interested in the analysis of choices within rules, thus assuming rules to be exogenously given and fixed. Constitutional economics broadens this research program by analyzing the choice of rules using the standard method of economics, that is, rational choice. Buchanan defines constitutions in their most basic sense as ‘a set of rules which constrain the activities of persons and agents in the pursuits of their own ends and objectives’ (Buchanan, 1977, p. 292). Defined as such, quite a few rule systems could be analyzed as constitutions: a firm’s partnership agreement as well as the statute of a church. Although such rule systems have indeed been analyzed from the point of view of constitutional economics (for a firm’s constitution, see Gifford, 1991, or Vanberg, 1992), the rule system analyzed most often remains the constitution of the state. Two broad avenues in the economic analysis of constitutions can be conceived of: (1) The normative branch of the research program is interested in legitimizing the state and the actions of its representatives. In other words: it is interested in identifying conditions under which the outcomes of collective choices can be judged as ‘fair’ or ‘efficient’. (2) The positive branch of the research program is interested in explaining (a) the emergence and modification of constitutional rules and (b) the outcomes that are the consequence of (alternative) constitutional rules (for a similar demarcation of the topic, see Mueller, 1996). The chapter is organized as follows: Part A will be devoted to normative constitutional economics whereas Part B will deal with positive constitutional economics. The chapter closes with an outlook.
A. Normative Constitutional Economics 2. Methodological Foundations Normative constitutional economics could deal with a variety of questions, for example: (1) How should societies proceed in order to bring about constitutional rules that fulfill some criterion like being ‘just’ or ‘efficient’? (2) What contents should the constitutional rules have? (3) Which issues should be dealt with in the constitution - and which should be left to sub-constitutional choice? (4) What characteristics should constitutional rules have? and many more. Buchanan answers none of these questions directly but hopes to offer a conceptual frame that would make them answerable. The frame is based on social contract theory as developed most prominently by Hobbes. According to Buchanan (1987b, 249), the purpose of this contractarian approach is justificatory in the sense that ‘it offers a basis for normative evaluation. Could the observed rules that constrain the activity of ordinary polititics have emerged from agreement in constitutional contract? To the extent that this question can
9100
Constitutional Law
531
be affirmatively answered, we have established a legitimating linkage between the individual and the state.’ The value-judgment that nobody’s goals and values should a priori be more important than those of anybody else, that is, normative individualism, is the basis of Buchanan’s entire model. One implication of this norm is that societal goals cannot exist. According to this view, every single individual has the right to pursue her or his own ends within the frame of collectively agreed upon rules. Therefore, a collective evaluation criterion that compared the societal ‘is’ with some ‘ought’ cannot exist since there is no such thing as a societal ‘ought’. But it is possible to derive a procedural norm from the value judgment stated. Buchanan borrowed this idea from Wicksell (1896): agreements to exchange private goods are judged as advantageous if the involved parties agree voluntarily. The agreement is supposed to be ‘efficient’, ‘good’ or ‘advantageous’ because the involved parties expect to be better off with the agreement than without it. Often, the exchange activities are considered to be taking place only between two parties, the seller and the buyer. Buchanan follows Wicksell who had demanded the same evaluation criterion for decisions that affect more than two parties, at the extreme an entire society. Rules that have consequences for every single member of a society can only be looked upon as advantageous if every single member of that society has voluntarily agreed to them. This is the Pareto criterion applied to collectivities. Deviations from the unanimity principle could occur during a decision process on the production of collective goods, but this would only be within the realm of the Buchanan model as long as the constitution itself provided for a decision rule below unanimity. Deviations from the unanimity rule would have to be based on a provision that was brought about unanimously.
3. Giving Efficiency Another Meaning Normative constitutional economics thus re-interprets the Pareto criterion in a twofold way: it is not outcomes but rules or procedures that lead to outcomes which are evaluated using the criterion. The evaluation is not carried out by an omniscient scientist or politician but by the concerned individuals themselves: ‘In a sense, the political economist is concerned with “what people want”’ (Buchanan, 1959, p. 137). In order to find out what people want Buchanan proposes to carry out a consensus test. The specification of this test will be crucial as to which rules can be considered legitimate. In 1959, Buchanan had factual unanimity in mind and those citizens that expect to be worse off due to some rule changes would have to be factually compensated. This test would thus be equivalent to a modified Kaldor-Hicks-criterion. In the meantime, Buchanan seems to have changed his position: hypothetical consent deduced
532
Constitutional Law
9100
by an economist will do in order to legitimize some rule (see, for example, Buchanan 1977, 1978, 1986). This position can be criticized because a large variety of rules seem to be legitimizable depending on the assumptions of the scientist who does the process. Scientists arguing in favor of an extensive welfare state will most likely assume risk-averse individuals while scientists who argue for cuts in the welfare budgets will assume people to be risk-neutral.
4. Critical Evaluation of Normative Constitutional Economics The possibility of hypothetical consent crucially depends on the information assumptions. Buchanan and Tullock (1962, p. 78) introduced the veil of uncertainty in which the individual cannot make any long-term predictions on her or his future socioeconomic position. Rawls’ (1971) veil of ignorance is more radical because the consenting individuals are asked to decide on proposed rules as if they did not have any knowledge on their individual fate. Rawls’ veil is thus more demanding on the individuals. Both veils assume a rather curious asymmetry concerning certain kinds of knowledge: on the one hand, the citizens are supposed to know very little about their own socioeconomic position, but on the other, they are supposed to have at their disposal a consistent theory concerning the working properties of alternative constitutional rules (Reisman, 1990, pp. 23-30 describes the differences between the two conceptions of the veil). In order to discuss the usefulness of the conceptual frame, suppose for a moment that it is impossible to legitimize a currently valid constitutional rule and that some constitutional economist has proposed an alternative rule for which she has ascertained a hypothetical consent. Further suppose that it is impossible to transform the hypothetical consent into majorities with which the constitution could be changed. Clearly, the non-legitimizable status quo would prevail over the legitimate constitutional rule.
B. Positive Constitutional Economics Positive constitutional economics can be divided into two parts. On the one hand, it is interested in explaining the outcomes that result from (alternative) rule sets. Here, constitutional rules are part of the explanans. On the other hand, it is interested in explaining the emergence and modification of constitutional rules. In that case, they are the explanandum.
9100
Constitutional Law
533
5. Constitutional Rules as Explanandum 5.1 Procedures for Generating Constitutional Rules Constitutional rules can be analyzed as the outcome of certain procedures used to bring them about. Elster’s (1991, 1993) research program concerning constitutional economics puts a strong emphasis on hypotheses of this kind. He inquires about the consequences of time limits for constitutional conventions, about how constitutional conventions that simultaneously serve as legislature allocate their time between the two functions, about which effects the regular information of the public concerning the progress of the constitutional negotiations has and about how certain supermajorities and election rules can determine the outcome of conventions (Elster, 1991, p. 30). Some of Riker’s articles (1983, 1984) can also be interpreted as an encouragement to search for hypotheses of this kind. He calls for an extension of traditional rational-choice theory pointing to the fact that in its traditional form it is incapable of taking into account dynamic and creative processes which structure the decision room of the actors. This part of constitutional economics does not offer a general perspective on the process of constitution-making (Elster, 1993, p. 174). There is, however, a large number of case studies (see, for example, the volume edited by Goldwin and Kaufman, 1988). 5.2 The Relevance of Preferences and Restrictions for Generating Constitutional Rules Procedures are a modus of aggregating inputs and can therefore never bring about constitutional rules by themselves. It is therefore only a logical step to analyze whether a bunch of potentially relevant variables can explain the choice of certain constitutional rules. There are good reasons - and some empirical evidence - to assume that (1) the individual preferences of the members of constitutional conventions will directly enter into the deliberations, and that (2) the preferences of all the citizens concerned will be recognized in the final document in quite diverse ways. This would mean that rent-seeking does play a role even on the constitutional level, a conjecture that is often excluded by representatives of normative constitutional economics. McGuire and Ohsfeldt (1986, 1989a, 1989b) have tried to explain the voting behavior of the Philadelphia delegates as well as those of the delegates to the 13 state ratifying conventions that led to the US Constitution. Their statistical results show that merchants, western landowners, financiers and large public-securities holders, ceteris paribus, supported the new constitution, whereas debtors and slave owners, ceteris paribus, opposed it (ibid., 1989a, p.175).
534
Constitutional Law
9100
5.3 Explicit Constitutional Change The two approaches towards constitutions as explananda just sketched are rather static. A third approach focuses on explaining the modifications of constitutions over time. Constitutional change that results in a modified document will be called explicit constitutional change here whereas constitutional change that does not result in a modified document - that is, change that is due to a different interpretation of formally unaltered rules - will be called implicit constitutional change. One approach towards explaining long-run explicit constitutional change focuses on changes of the relative bargaining power of organized groups. Due to a comparative advantage in using violence (see North, 1981), an autocrat is able to establish government and secure a rent from that activity. As soon as an (organized) group is convinced that its own cooperation with the autocrat is crucial for the maintenance of the rent, it will seek negotiations with the autocrat. Since the current constitution is the basis for the autocrat’s ability to appropriate a rent, the opposition will strive after changing it. In this approach, bargaining power is defined as the capability to inflict costs on your opponent. The prediction of this approach is that a change in (relative) bargaining power will lead to modified constitutional rules (Voigt, 1997). Explicit constitutional change can be sought by interest groups who try to convince legislators to change the constitution. If constitutional change is only sought in a disequilibrium, the interest group seeking change must perceive its own relevance as having changed. Boudreaux and Pritchard (1993) analyze the hitherto 27 amendments to the US Constitution from an economic perspective. They begin with the conjecture that a lobby-group interested in constitutional change principally has two possibilities of seeking its realization: it can either lobby for a simple law or it can lobby for constitutional change. The second option is, however, more expensive. The trivial prediction of rational choice theory is that the group will choose the option with the higher expected utility. In order to be able to make predictions about the option chosen, it is therefore necessary to specify the cost and benefit categories implied. Boudreaux and Pritchard specify two categories and predict a demand for constitutional change in cases in which the costs of maintaining an interest group over time are high, and today’s opposition is weak but expected to be strong in the future. 5.4 Implicit Constitutional Change Implicit constitutional change has been defined as a changed constitutional interpretation that occurs although the formal constitutional document remains unchanged. This means that the conceptual separation between choice of rules on the one hand and choice within rules on the other has been factually blurred. This possibility must be disturbing to the proponents of normative constitutional economics. To adherents of positive constitutional economics, it
9100
Constitutional Law
535
amounts to an analytical difficulty because the identification of what is analyzed as the valid ‘constitution’ either as explanandum or as explanans becomes more difficult. At the same time, the possibility of implicit constitutional change also becomes an object of inquiry. It can be asked which variables determine the scope and extent of the implicit constitutional change to be expected. Suppose a constitution in the sense of constitutionalism exists and the government branches are legislature, executive and judiciary. If all government representatives have at their disposal a certain latitude concerning the interpretation of the constitution, it can be argued that all branches can bring about implicit constitutional change. If an independent judiciary exists, it seems plausible to assume that it has most latitude in causing implicit constitutional change because it has the power to judge the constitutional conformity of the actions of the other two government branches. It can now be argued that the judiciary is subject to a number of constraints among which those laid down in the original constitutional document play a rather marginal role. Instead, the current preferences of the other branches are more relevant restrictions. There are various factors that determine the latitude that justices have in bringing about implicit constitutional change. Cooter and Ginsburg (1996) show that it depends on the number of chambers whose consent is needed to pass fresh legislation. The higher its number, the more difficult it will be for the other branches to correct implicit constitutional change by changing the constitutional document explicitly. They further show (ibid.) that it depends on the existence of a ‘dominant disciplined party’. If such a party exists, it will be more difficult for the justices to bring about implicit constitutional change. Other variables that influence the amount of implicit constitutional change include the following: (1) If implicit constitutional change can only be prevented by changing the document explicitly, the necessary majority becomes a factor. The more inclusive it is, the more difficult it will be to prevent such change. (2) The possibility of referenda should be another explanatory variable. If the population at large can overturn the justices, they have an incentive not to deviate too drastically from the preferences of the median voter. (3) The extent of implicit constitutional change should be higher in common-law systems than in continental-law systems because in the first group decisions by justices become directly applicable law (see also Voigt, 1999).
6. Constitutional Rules as Explanans In the previous section of this chapter, constitutional rules have been analyzed as explananda. Such an analysis is only of interest if it can be shown that constitutional rules are themselves relevant to bringing about certain results or
536
Constitutional Law
9100
patterns that concern economists or social scientists in general, in other words: if constitutions matter. Possible explananda include per capita income, its growth rate, but also income distribution. 6.1 The Separation of Powers The analysis of economically relevant consequences of the separation of powers has long been neglected almost entirely. In a survey article, Posner (1987) writes that the separation of powers increases the transaction costs of governing. This would hold for welfare-enhancing as well as for redistributive or even exploitative measures. North and Weingast (1989) use the British case of the seventeenth century to demonstrate that the separation of powers can secure property rights because it is one way for the governing to credibly commit themselves. Brennan and Hamlin (1994) develop a ‘revisionist view’ of the separation of powers. To make their point, they draw on standard monopoly models used in economics and distinguish between a horizontal and a vertical separation of powers. Starting out with a monopoly, the introduction of the horizontal separation amounts to two (or more) suppliers competing for demand and thus to the introduction of duopoly (or oligopoly). The equilibrium price will then be below the monopoly price and consumer rent will subsequently increase. A vertical separation of powers also entails a division of the original monopoly, albeit in a different way: now single functions of the process are divided; there is, for example, one monopolistic firm that produces certain goods and a second monopolistic firm that distributes it. Brennan and Hamlin call this functional separation of powers too. The (individually) maximizing strategies of the vertically separated firms will at best lead to the monopoly price, but usually the price will even be higher and the accruing consumer rent will thus be lower than in the original monopoly. Brennan and Hamlin argue that the separation of powers doctrine as conventionally understood is equivalent to the functional separation of powers and will therefore not protect citizens from exploitation by the governed. The horizontal separation of powers could, instead, have beneficial results. In order to unfold, it needs to entail an ‘exit’ option for citizens as well as the absence of strong externalities between competing states. 6.2 Unicameral vs. Bicameral Systems A first attempt to compare the differential effects of unicameral and bicameral legislatures dates back to Buchanan and Tullock (1962, Ch. 16). In their analytical frame, that decision rule is optimal which leads to a minimum of interdependence costs which are defined as the sum of decision-making costs and those external costs an actor has to bear in case his individually most preferred outcome is not the outcome of the collective choice. They conjecture that in comparison with unicameral systems bicameral systems have higher
9100
Constitutional Law
537
decision costs and continue: ‘on the other hand, if the basis of representation can be made significantly different in the two houses, the institutions of the bicameral legislature may prove to be an effective means of securing a substantial reduction in the expected external costs of collective action without incurring as much added decision-making costs as a more inclusive rule would involve in a single house’ (ibid., p. 235f.). The larger the majority required to reach a certain decision, the lower the external costs connected with that decision because the number of opponents to a decision is negatively correlated with the required majority. On the other hand, it will become increasingly difficult to reach a decision at all because the decision costs are positively correlated with the required majority. One possibility of keeping the external costs down is to require a supermajority (say of 3/4 or 5/6) in the single-house system. Supermajorities in a single-house system and simple majorities in a two-house system can thus be considered as alternatives. Buchanan and Tullock now conjecture that - given identical external costs - the decision costs would be lower in a bicameral than in a unicameral system. Miller and Hammond (1989) inquire into the effects of bicameralism and the executive veto - which is sometimes simply considered the third chamber - on stability in the sense that it reduces the probability of cycling majorities à la Condorcet or Arrow (1951). They conclude that bicameralism and the executive veto increase stability. The stability-enhancing effect of bicameralism depends on some preference difference between the two chambers. Levmore (1992) somewhat changes the focus of the analysis when he conjectures that a bicameral system might be better suited than a corresponding qualified majority in a unicameral system to reduce the power of the agenda setter. Bicameral systems are often interpreted as a break against overly active legislatures. Levmore relates this interpretation to the concept of federalism in a double sense: First, all federations have a bicameral legislature. Secondly, ‘(f)ederalism is likely to increase the chance of regulation because federal arrangements nearly always create some overlap in jurisdictional responsibilities so that there are multiple sources of regulation’ (ibid., p. 159). According to Levmore, federations tend to produce active legislatures but come systematically along with bicameral systems which tend to reduce legislator activism. Concerning the effects of bicameral systems, one could analyze whether the legislative activity in bicameral systems is indeed lower than in unicameral ones, whether this is reflected in government consumption of economic output and whether there are even different growth rates. For a clear-cut comparative analysis of institutions the description of the exact functioning of the institutions to be compared is, however, primordial. One would have to inquire how a mediation committee influences the functioning of a bicameral system and how a presidential veto influences the decision and the external costs. More general inquiries into the (economic) effects of the separation of powers could
538
Constitutional Law
9100
try to proceed by way of comparative institutional analysis, that is, by comparing common features of constitutions which do know a separation of powers with those which do not. 6.3 Direct-Democratic vs. Representative Institutions Representatives of normative constitutional economics ask on what rules the members of a society could agree behind a veil of uncertainty. If they agree on a democratic constitution, they would further have to specify whether and to what extent they want to combine representative with direct-democratic elements. In order to make an informed decision, the citizens would be interested to know whether there are systematic relationships between these institutions and the patterns that they are interested in. In a number of papers, Bruno Frey and his various co-authors argue that referenda are a feasible and effective institution for having the preferences of a society’s members reflected in the public goods bundle produced by the politicians. Referenda could make politicians’ cartels directed against the voters ineffective (Frey, 1994, p. 338). In 39 percent of the referenda that took place in Switzerland between 1848 and 1990, the majority among the population was different from the majority in Parliament (Frey and Bohnet, 1994, p. 73) which is interpreted as a proof of the hypothesis of a better reflection of voters preferences via referenda. Pommerehne already showed in 1978 that ceteris paribus tax rates are lower when taxpayers decide for themselves on the bundle of public goods supplied (for an overview over comparative studies, see Pommerehne, 1990). Additionally, taxpayer honesty is positively correlated with voters’ chances to participate directly in the choice of the bundle of public goods to be supplied (Pommerehne and Frey, 1992). 6.4 Individual Rights and Economic Growth The question of whether societies whose constitutions grant individual rights to their citizens grow faster than societies that do not has often been answered using ‘democracy’ as a proxy for individual rights. The results of those studies have been mixed at best (for a survey, see Przeworski and Limongi, 1993). Bhalla (1994) proposes to search for a relationship not between democracy and growth rates but between political, civil and economic rights on the one hand and growth rates on the other. He finds a positive correlation not only between individual liberty and economic growth but also between political and civil rights and enrollment in secondary schools and a negative one between political and civil rights and infantile mortality. Bhalla shows that the availability of human capital is a necessary but not a sufficient condition for sustained economic growth. This will only occur if economic liberties come along with human capital. His study is thus also a challenge of the so-called new growth theory. Up to now, the most comprehensive study on the relationship between
9100
Constitutional Law
539
individual economic liberties and growth is due to Gwartney, Lawson and Block (1996). For the period between 1975 and 1995, 103 countries are evaluated on an index comprising 17 components that puts special emphasis on the security of property rights and the freedom to contract. Two results are of special interest in this context: (1) There is a clearcut positive relation between individual economic liberty and per-capita income. There is reason to hypothesize that this not merely a correlation but also a causality: countries scoring best on the index of economic liberties first carried out liberalization and became wealthy only later on. (2) Economic liberties are also significantly correlated with a society’s rates of economic growth. Countries that liberalized most between 1975 and 1995 without exception secured positive growth rates. To sum up: Economic liberties seem to enhance economic growth. Direct-democratic rights tend to make sure that citizen preferences are better reflected in policy outcomes. A federal structure might help to tame Leviathan and make the economic liberties more secure. Some normative conclusions thus almost seem to suggest themselves. Before drawing them, one needs, however, to clarify the conditions that have to be fulfilled in order to implement any of the above institutions successfully.
C. Outlook John Neville Keynes proposed a tripartite division of political economy, introducing the ‘art of political economy’ besides the more standard positive and normative branches. This art deals with possibilities of reducing differences between ‘Is’ and ‘Ought’ (Keynes, 1955). It almost suggests itself to conceive of an ‘art of constitutional political economy’ analogously. This art would itself have to have a positive foundation: knowledge about the possibilities to modify constitutions intentionally is primordial for such a third branch. If one thinks that constitutional economics is potentially relevant for real world constitution writers, then one must be disappointed with the degree to which insights from this research program have entered into the newly written constitutions of Central and Eastern Europe. In order to become more relevant, it seems essential to work on the third branch. A central presumption of both branches presented in Sections 2 and 3 is that constitutional rules constrain human behavior and that they can therefore be relevant for explaining it. Representatives of the new institutional economics would broaden this presumption and claim that institutions in general constrain human behavior. It thus almost suggests itself to plead for an integration of constitutional economics into the new institutional economics. Whereas Brennan and Hamlin (1995) argue that one can conceptualize the ‘new institutionalism’ as a subordinate research program, one can also argue exactly
540
Constitutional Law
9100
the other way round: if one does not start with the assumption that constitutional design is possible to a large extent and if one is furthermore critical of the assumed hierarchy of rules, and rather points to the complex interdependence between informal constraints and formal rules (North, 1990) or between internal and external institutions (Kiwit and Voigt, 1995), one would tend to conceptualize constitutional economics as part of the new institutional economics.
Bibliography on Constitutional Law (9100) Arrow, Kenneth (1951), Social Choice and Individual Values, New York, Wiley. Bhalla, Surjit (1994), Freedom and Economic Growth: A Virtuous Cycle?, Nobel Symposium, Uppsala University. Boudreaux, Donald J. and Pritchard, A.C. (1993), ‘Rewriting the Constitution: An Economic Analysis of the Constitutional Amendment Process’, 62 Fordham Law Review, 111-162. Brennan, Geoffrey and Hamlin, Alan (1994), ‘A Revisionist View of the Separation of Powes’, 6(3) Journal of Theoretical Politics, 345-368. Brennan, Geoffrey and Hamlin, Alan (1995), ‘Constitutional Political Economy: The Political Philosophy of Homo Economicus?’, 3(3) The Journal of Political Philosophy, 280-303. Buchanan, James M. (1959), ‘Positive Economics, Welfare Economics, and Political Economy’, 2 Journal of Law and Economics, 124-38. Buchanan, James M. (1975), The Limits of Liberty - Between Anarchy and Leviathan, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Buchanan, James M. (1977), Freedom in Constitutional Contract - Perspectives of a Political Economist, College Station and London, Texas A&M University Press. Buchanan, James (1978), ‘A Contractarian Perspective on Anarchy’, in Pennock, J. Roland and Chapman, John W. (eds), Anarchism: Nomos XIX, New York, New York University Press, 29-42. Buchanan, James (1986), ‘Political Economy and Social Philosophy’, in Buchanan, James M., Liberty, Market and State - Political Economy in the 1980s, New York, 261-274. Buchanan, James M. (1987a), ‘Constitutional Economics’, in Eatwell, J., Milgate, M. and Newman, P. (eds), The New Palgrave - A Dictionary of Economics, London and Basingstoke, Macmillan, Vol. 1, 585-588. Buchanan, James M. (1987b), ‘The Constitution of Economic Policy’,77 American Economic Review, 243-250. Buchanan, James M. and Tullock, Gordon (1962), The Calculus of Consent - Logical Foundations of Constitutional Democracy, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press. Cooter, Robert D. and Ginsburg, Tom (1996), ‘Comparative Judicial Discretion: An Empirical Test of Economic Models’, 16(3) International Review of Law and Economics, 295-313. Elster, Jon (1991), Arguing and Bargaining in two Constituent Assemblies, The Storrs Lectures.
9100
Constitutional Law
541
Elster, Jon (1993), ‘Constitution-Making in Eastern Europe: Rebuilding the Boat in the Open Sea’, 71(1/2) Public Administration, 169-217. Frey, Bruno S. (1994), ‘Direct Democracy: Politico-Economic Lessons from Swiss Experience’, 84 American Economic Review, 338-342. Frey, Bruno S. and Bohnet, Iris (1994), ‘Democracy by Competition: Referenda and Federalism in Switzerland’. Gifford, Adam (1991), ‘A Constitutional Interpretation of the Firm’, 68 Public Choice, 91-106. Goldwin, Robert A. and Kaufman, Art (eds) (1988), Constitution-Makers on Constitution- Making, Washington, DC, American Enterprise Institute. Gwartney, James, Lawson, Robert, and Block, Walter (1996), Economic Freedom of the World: 1975 - 1995. Vancouver et al., The Fraser Institute et al. International Review of Law and Economics (1992), Special Issue on Constitutional Law and Economics 12(2). Keynes, John Neville (1955), The Scope and Method of Political Economy, New York, Kelley. Kiwit, Daniel and Voigt, Stefan (1995), ‘Überlegungen zum Institutionellen Wandel unter Berücksichtigung des Verhältnisses interner und Externer Institutionen’, 46 ORDO, 117-147. Levmore, Saul (1992), ‘Bicameralism: When are Two Decisions Better than One?’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 145-162. McGuire, Robert A. and Ohsfeldt, Robert L. (1986), ‘An Economic Model of Voting Behavior over Specific Issues at the Constitutional Convention of 1787', 46 Journal of Economic History, 79-111. McGuire, Robert A. and Ohsfeldt, Robert L. (1989a), ‘self-Interest, Agency Theory, and Political Voting Behavior: The Ratification of the United States Constitution’, 79 American Economic Review, 219-234. McGuire, Robert A. and Ohsfeldt, Robert L. (1989b), ‘Public Choice Analysis and the Ratification of the Constitution’, in Grofman, Bernard and Wittman, Donald (eds), The Federalist Papers and the New Institutionalism, New York, Agathon, 175-204. Miller, Gary J. and Hammond, Thomas H. (1989), ‘stability and Efficiency in a Separation-of-Powers Constitutional System’, in Grofman, B. and Wittman, Donald (eds), The Federalist Papers and the New Institutionalism, New York, Agathon Press, 85-99. Mueller, Dennis C. (1989), Public Choice II, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Mueller, Dennis C. (1991), ‘Constitutional Rights’, 7 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organisation, 313-333. Mueller, Dennis C. (1996), ‘Constitutional Public Choice’, in Mueller, Dennis C. (ed.), Perspectives on Public Choice, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 124-146. North, Douglass C. (1981), Structure and Change in Economic History, New York, Norton. North, Douglass C. (1990), Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance, Cambridge, Cambrdige University Press. North, Douglass C. and Weingast, Barry W. (1989), ‘The Evolution of Institutions Governing Public Choice in 17th Century England’, 49 Journal of Economic History, 803-832. Pommerehne, Werner W. (1990), ‘The Empirical Relevance of Comparative Institutional Analysis’, 34 European Economic Review, 458-468.
542
Constitutional Law
9100
Pommerehne, Werner W. and Frey, Bruno S. (1992), ‘The Effects of Tax Administration on Tax Morale’, paper presented at the Conference on Tax Administration and Tax Evasion of the International Seminar in Public Economics (ISPE), El Escorial (June). Posner, Richard A. (1987), ‘The Constitution as an Economic Document’, 56(1) George Washington Law Review, 4-38. Przeworski, Adam, Limongi, F. (1993), ‘Political Regimes and Economic Growth’, 7(3) Journal of Economic Perspectives, 51-69. Rawls, John (1971), A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, Belknap. Reisman, David (1990), The Political Economy of James Buchanan, College Station, Texas A & M. Riker, William H. (1983), ‘Political Theory and the Art of Heresthetics’, in A. Finifter (ed.), Political Science: the State of the Discipline, Washington, DC, American Political Science Association, 47-67. Riker, William H. (1984), ‘The Heresthetics of Constitution-Making: The Presidency in 1787, with Comments on Determinism and Rational Choice’, 78 American Political Science Review, 1-16. Vanberg, Viktor J. (1992), ‘Organizations as Constitutional Systems’, 3 Constitutional Political Economy, 223-253. Voigt, Stefan (1997), ‘Bargaining for Constitutional Change’, Discussion Paper 02/97 of the Max-Planck-Institute for Research Into Economic Systems, Jena, Germany. Voigt, Stefan (1999), ‘Implicit Constitutional Change - Changing the Meaning of the Constitution Without Changing the Text of the Document’, 8 Journal of Law and Economics. Wicksell, Knut (1896), Finanztheoretische Untersuchungen, Jena, Fischer.
9200 JUDGE-MADE LAW Paul H. Rubin Department of Economics, Emory University © Copyright 1999 Paul H. Rubin
Abstract A major positive claim in the law and economics literature, due first to Posner, is that the common law is economically efficient. However, mechanisms to explain this putative efficiency are lacking. Posner’s hypothesis is that judges gain utility from efficient decisions, and are constrained so that other decision criteria are limited. Evolutionary models of the law were devised to provide another mechanism for such efficiency, but these models, while proving very useful for some purposes, have not achieved this goal. Indeed, there are now evolutionary models of legal change driven by rent seeking by lawyers and others which lead to inefficient results. There is also a literature on multi-judge interactions, showing conditions under which such interactions will or will not lead to consistent results. At the heart of economic analysis of law is a mystery that is also an embarrassment: how to explain judicial behavior in economic terms....Posner (1993, p. 2)
JEL classification: K00, K41 Keywords: Common Law, Judges, Legal Evolution, Legal Efficiency, Efficiency of the Common Law
1. Introduction As the quotation in the abstract indicates, explanation of the behavior of judges is one of the most important but also most difficult problems facing law and economics scholars. This is because judicial opinions are the result of utilitymaximizing behavior and economists are unable to specify the details of judges’ (or anyone else’s) utility functions. Consequently, it has proven difficult to develop a theory that explains why judges make the decisions that we observe, though, as we discuss below, many have tried. Because of the difficulty of explaining decisions in terms of utility functions, there have also been attempts to use evolutionary models to explain outcomes. In these models, the form of law is due to factors involving wealth-maximizing behavior of actors in the 543
544
Judge-Made Law
9200
legal process such as litigants or attorneys, and judges play a minor role. The structure of this chapter is as follows: I first consider briefly arguments regarding the efficiency of common law. I then discuss utility-maximizing models of judicial behavior. I next consider the evolutionary models. The following section discusses models of multi-judge behavior.
2. Efficiency of Common Law A basic question for law and economics is the efficiency of law. Hayek (1960, 1973), although writing before the law and economics movement and writing from another perspective, had argued that common or judge made law was better than statute law (see Christiansen, 1990, for an attempt to reconcile Hayekian arguments with law and economics). More recently, Posner (1992) has of course argued often and forcefully that the common law is efficient. His arguments are based on examination of particular legal doctrines. The difficulty of this method is that often the conclusion regarding the efficiency of a particular rule depends on unmeasured transactions costs of various sorts; if Posner’s intuition about relative magnitudes of costs is incorrect, then doctrines he claims are efficient may not be so. Nonetheless, his analysis has been the intellectual spark behind the growth of law and economics, and questions of efficiency of the sort he was the first to raise have dominated the literature. Much of this literature may be considered as detailed attempts to answer the positive efficiency question first posed by Posner, and much of the rest aims at deriving normative conclusions as to what is efficient. Others are less certain that common law is efficient. Tullock (1971, 1980) has long argued that the English common law process is less efficient than Continental processes. Rizzo (1980a, 1980b) argues from an Austrian perspective that the amount of information needed for judges to achieve efficiency is excessive, although Rubin (1980) in a critique argues that Rizzo’s criticism might apply to efficiency in all of economics, not merely in law and economics. Aranson (1992) argues that it is impossible for judges to seek efficiency because the calculations required are equivalent to those required to make central planning work. Hadfield (1992b) has argued that because judges see only a biased sample of potential cases, depending on the rules in existence, it is impossible for judges to move towards efficiency, even if they desire to do so. Much of the literature in law and economics consists of attempts to examine particular legal doctrines and attempt to determine if they are efficient. (Much of my own work is of this type; see for example Rubin, 1983.) This method of analysis is fundamentally different from efficiency analysis in other branches of economics. There, a process (market competition) is postulated and it is shown that the process leads to efficient outcomes. Economists do not generally examine consumers to see if they are equating ratios of marginal utilities to
9200
Judge-Made Law
545
prices, or firms to see if they are charging marginal cost. Rather, the process by which outcomes are generated is shown to lead to efficiency. It is for this reason that many economists are uncomfortable with the efficiency arguments of law and economics. Nonetheless, because this is the standard method in law and economics, any analysis of the efficiency of any particular body of law can be considered as evidence for or against Posner’s hypothesis. If some law is found efficient, then this is evidence for the hypothesis. If some law is found inefficient, or if there are proposals for reform, then this is evidence against the hypothesis. In this sense, all of law and economics is aimed at testing this fundamental hypothesis. Scholars are of course aware of this difficulty, and have sought to identify a process that would lead to efficiency. The two candidates are utility maximization by judges and evolutionary models. I discuss each. As we will see, there is no definitive demonstration in the literature of a mechanism that would lead to efficiency. This has led many to conclude that the law is not so efficient as Posner believes.
3. Utility Maximization The first argument regarding utility maximization by judges was in Posner (1992, first edition, 1973). The argument (elaborated in Posner, 1993) is that judges are so insulated from personal factors and from interest group and other pressures that the only remaining decision factor is efficiency. The only other candidate is income redistribution, and judges lack the tools needed for such redistribution. This explanation was and is not terribly convincing to economists because it ultimately relies on judicial tastes for efficiency and economists prefer not to explain behavior on this basis. There have been some attempts to model judicial utility functions in terms of economically relevant and observable variables. The first such effort was by Higgins and Rubin (1980). They argued that promotion to a higher position was an element of judicial utility functions, that promotion was more likely if the judge was reversed less, and that the value of promotion was reduced as the judge became older. However, in their sample they were unable to find any relation between age or any other factor and reversal, and only a weak relation between reversal and promotion. In two articles, Cohen continued to examine promotion possibilities for federal judges. His argument was that if the Justice Department recommended a judge, then promotion was more likely. In Cohen (1991) he examined voting on the constitutionality of the US Sentencing Commission and found that judges voting for constitutionality were more likely to be promoted; the Justice Department favored this position. In Cohen (1992) he found that judges who imposed more severe antitrust sanctions, again in line with the desires of the
546
Judge-Made Law
9200
Department, were more likely to be promoted. Thus, there is evidence for normal utility maximization by judges. The problem is that it is difficult to see how these results generalize to explain other types of decisions, including common law decisions. Macey (1994) has argued that many rules of procedure are aimed at maximizing judicial utility - for example by emphasizing procedure, where judges have a comparative advantage, over substance, where they do not. Landes and Posner (1980) examined differences between state court judges and federal court judges. Their hypothesis was that since federal judges are paid more and have life tenure, we would expect higher quality people to occupy these positions and write better opinions. Their measures of quality had to do with citations to opinions as discussed in Landes and Posner (1976) and with use of opinions in legal casebooks. Except for the last measure, they found little difference. Other variables such as age and the political party appointing the judge also had little influence. Ashenfelter, Eisenberg and Schwab (1995) examined the extent to which judicial decisions are influenced by the political party appointing the judge and other elements of the judges’ personal background. They find little or no influence. Thus, if we believe that these characteristics influence the judges’ utility function, this may be taken as an argument that this aspect of utility has little impact. It is apparent that there is little evidence regarding the effect of utility maximization on the mass of case outcomes. This is clearly an area for future research.
4. Evolutionary Models The evolutionary models are attempts to explain judicial behavior without resort to utility functions. Initially, these models aimed at explaining Posner’s putative observation that the common law was efficient. It is fair to say that the models failed in this endeavor, perhaps because the law is not so efficient as Posner argued. Nonetheless, these models have had an important impact on the literature because they have called attention to forces other than judicial preferences in explaining the law. The evolutionary models are ultimately based on the model of the litigation process first set forth by Landes (1971). The first paper applying an evolutionary model to the common law was Rubin (1977). Following Landes (1971) Rubin argued that most cases are settled, rather than litigated, and that it is only litigated cases that can lead to legal change. Cases are settled when the expected value to the plaintiff of a case is less than the expected cost to the defendant, which is generally true if stakes are symmetric. However, inefficient laws can sometimes create asymmetric stakes because the inefficiency means that there are deadweight losses that cannot be bargained away in the settlement process. That is, an inefficient rule creates a loss to one party that is greater than the gain to the other because of
9200
Judge-Made Law
547
future stakes in similar type cases. Thus, litigation becomes more likely when rules are inefficient, and so inefficient rules are subject to greater selection pressure, and more likely to be overturned. (Note that this model, like many of its successors, depends on parties having ongoing interests in disputes of a certain sort, rather than merely in the matter at hand.) Following this initial contribution were several extensions and modifications. Priest (1977) argued that inefficient rules generated larger stakes and so were more likely to be litigated, again subjecting them to increased selection pressure. Goodman (1979) argued that efficient precedents were worth more to parties who would benefit than inefficient precedents were worth to their beneficiaries, and that parties to whom a decision was worth more would spend more litigating and so would be more likely to win. In other words, efficient precedents were more likely to win in litigation and survive than were inefficient precedents. Katz (1988) expanded on this notion in the context of presenting a model of litigation expenditures. Terrebonne (1981) also presented a model of efficient legal evolution. Other scholars began critically examining these models. Landes and Posner (1979) in a symposium paper published in the Journal of Legal Studies argued that the earlier models had erred by modeling precedent as an all or nothing issue, when the proper question was whether a precedent was stronger or weaker. That is, litigation might strengthen or weaken a precedent without overturning it completely. Thus a party with an interest in overturning an inefficient precedent would also have to consider the possibility that litigation could strengthen as well as weaken the precedent. This consideration greatly weakens the evolutionary pressures for efficiency. Parsons (1983) combined Priest’s point (that inefficient precedents would lead to increasing litigation) with the Landes and Posner point (that precedents that were litigated might become entrenched) to argue that there is a tendency for the common law to become ‘reckless’ - to favor rules that inefficiently lead to increased accidents. Cooter et al. (1979) presented a model in which movement towards efficiency could only occur if judges sought such a movement. In a more elaborate examination of the issue, Cooter and Kornhauser (1980) present a complex evolutionary model in which there are some tendencies towards efficiency, but in which both efficient and inefficient rules will be observed at any time. This model, and alternative definitions and implications of efficiency, are discussed in Kornhauser (1980). Von Wagenheim (1993) presents a model with similar results. Hirshleifer (1982), building on Rubin’s discussion of inefficiency when stakes in precedent are asymmetric, provided what may be the most useful and influential criticism of the evolutionary models. Recall that in the original Rubin (1977) model and in some others, including Goodman (1979) and Landes and Posner (1979) evolutionary forces moved the law towards efficiency only if the party with an interest in efficiency had an ongoing interest in the
548
Judge-Made Law
9200
form of the law. Hirshleifer generalized this point to show that the law could come to favor whichever party could most easily organize and mobilize resources for litigation of unfavorable precedents. This movement would be independent of efficiency. Rubin (1982) uses this point to argue that common law was more like statute law than many want to admit: interest groups could use either common or statute law to achieve their goals. He argued that the apparent efficiency of the common law was because most common law was developed at a time when organization of interest groups was expensive, and that more recently both common and statute law have been subject to interest group pressures. Crew and Twight (1990) expanded on this point and found common law less subject to rent seeking than statute law. Rowley and Brough (1987) find that contract and property might be expected to be efficient, but not tort. Bailey and Rubin (1994) have extended this theme in a formal model of the influence of interest groups on the law, and Rubin and Bailey (1994) have shown that plaintiffs’ attorneys have been responsible for the shape of modern tort law, using an evolutionary mechanism to shape the law. An interesting question worthy of future exploration is the extent to which other interest groups have found litigating for precedent worthwhile. Heiner (1986) explains stare decisis and other features of the law as a result of human imperfect decision making. Because attempts to achieve optimality in each decision might lead to erroneous decisions in many cases, it may be more efficient to rely on rather simple rules that minimize the potential costs of error. An interesting set of hypotheses regarding legal evolution is in Roe (1996). Roe argues that the notion of evolution towards efficiency is an important determinant of legal form, but it is not the only determinant. He incorporates three subsidiary notions into an efficiency framework - the importance of initial conditions (borrowed from chaos theory), path dependence and evolutionary accidents. The result of these processes would be that laws would be well but not perfectly adapted. However, while these notions are interesting, as Roe himself admits, they do not as of yet provide refutable hypotheses. It would be interesting to see if these propositions can be generalized to provide some implications. What can we say about the evolutionary models? They have not succeeded in the original task of providing an explanation for common law efficiency. However, by demonstrating the difficulty of achieving this goal, they have helped understand when the law may be efficient and when it is likely not to be efficient. Moreover, an important component of the evolutionary models was their focus on the litigation decision as driving legal evolution. Other models of legal evolution, both economic and non-economic, either leave mechanisms for evolution unspecified or assume that the preferences of judges are the driving forces. The economic models were the first to focus on the motives of litigants, realizing that judges can decide only those cases that come before them. As Elliott (1985, p. 71), in an important study of the history of evolutionary models, indicates: ‘Moreover, the economic school of evolution has broadened
9200
Judge-Made Law
549
our view of the legal system to include the role of litigants, as well as judges, in making law.’ The literature associated with Priest and Klein (1984) on selectivity bias in case selection is a result of the focus on litigants’ decisions, which has come out of the evolutionary models; for a discussion, see Priest (1980). (For an analysis of theories of legal evolution from 1880-1940 (which thus omits analysis of the economic theories) see Hovenkamp, 1985.) Aranson (1986) summarizes the assumptions of several of the evolutionary models. He shows that many combinations of assumptions have not been examined, and thus provides clues for further research. There is much useful research to be done on evolutionary models of legal change.
5. Multi-Judge Interactions Matters become more complex when more than one judge is involved in a decision or sequence of decisions. Multiple judges may be involved because a judicial panel may consist of more than one judge; because different judges may hear similar cases at different times; or because the appellate process may involve judges at different levels of a judicial hierarchy hearing the same case. One issue that appears when panels of judges hear a matter is the potential for inconsistency. Easterbrook (1982) was the first to point out that the Arrow theorem (which shows that there is no way of aggregating preferences that is not subject to some flaw, and that, for example, majority voting can lead to cycles: A defeats B, B defeats C, C defeats A) also applies to judicial voting; see also Easterbrook (1984). Kornhauser has written extensively on issues that arise in multi-judge settings, both alone and with Sager. Kornhauser and Sager (1986) apply the Condorcet Jury Theorem to the context of judicial panels and show that increasing the number of judges on a panel will increase the accuracy of the outcome. In addition, they argue that multi-judge panels can act consistently (in the sense of avoiding cycles) but that multi-judge panels may act incoherently, in the sense that the pattern of decision will not satisfy community principles of coherent explanation. In two related papers Kornhauser (1992a, 1992b) investigated several additional characteristics of collegial courts. He emphasized the dichotomous nature of common law adjudication. He argued further that judges had to respect the results rather than the rules or rationales of prior decisions. In this context, he showed that, except under implausible conditions, a legal system will be path dependent; that is, the state of the law at any time will be a result of the order in which the court has heard disputes. This path dependence, however, will not lead to inconsistency if the legal system observes strict stare decisis. Next, Kornhauser observed that common law practice incorporates two distinct ways of aggregating judgments of multiple judges: courts may resolve
550
Judge-Made Law
9200
matters on a case-by-case or on an issue-by-issue basis. Kornhauser shows that there is a ‘doctrinal paradox’ in that these two methods may lead to different outcomes. He shows that the doctrinal paradox is distinct from the Condorcet paradox. Kornhauser and Sager (1993) extend the analysis of the doctrinal paradox in several ways. They observe, for instance, that in actual practice each judge decides how to aggregate the votes of other members on the court and that this may affect the outcome. Kornhauser (1995) considers the hierarchical structure of courts systems. It explains many of the features of the US judicial system through a simple production model. Kornhauser assumes that judges in the system form a team, in that they all want the same goal, the maximization of the ‘number of correct answers subject to its resource constraint’. Then the structure of the production function explains the pattern of precedent observed and the specialization of trial courts to fact finding and appellate courts to review of law. Other features, such as the lack of specialization of courts by subject matter, are not explained by the model. Miceli and Cosgel (1994) and Rasmusen (1994) have argued that judges’ behavior is based on a tradeoff between writing decisions they prefer and the possibility of reversal, either by higher courts or by future judges. O’Hara (1993) analyzes why appellate judges choose to follow precedents in the absence of any formal rule mandating adherence to precedent. She explains this behavior as the result of a repeated game between different appellate judges, each of whom follows the precedents established by his or her colleagues’ decisions in order to avoid triggering a ‘punishment’ phase. In this punishment phase the precedents established by the errant judge’s decisions are ignored by his or her colleagues. Shavell (1995) argues that the structure of the appellate process is a low cost method of error correction, since only a subset of cases are examined for error through an appeal.
Bibliography on Judge-Made Law (9200) Alexander, Janet Cooper (1994), ‘Judges’ Self Interest and Procedural Rules: Comment’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 647-665. Alpa, Guido, Pulitini, Francesco, Rodota, Stefano and Romani, Franco (1982), Interpretazione Giuridica e Analisi Economica (Legal Interpretation and Economic Analysis), Milano, Giuffrè, 662 p. Aranson, Peter H. (1986), ‘Economic Efficiency and the Common Law: A Critical Survey’, in Graf von der Schulenburg, J.-Matthias and Skogh, Göran (eds), Law and Economics and the Economics of Legal Regulation, Dordrecht, Kluwer, 51-84. Aranson, Peter H. (1992), ‘The Common Law as Central Economic Planning’, 3 Constitutional Political Economy, 289-317. Armitage, Thomas C. (1985), ‘Economic Efficiency as a Legal Norm’, 7 Research in Law and Economics, 1-27.
9200
Judge-Made Law
551
Ashenfelter, Orley, Eisenberg, Theodore and Schwab, Stewart J. (1995), ‘Politics and the Judiciary: The Influence of Judicial Background on Case Outcomes’, 24 Journal of Legal Studies, 257-81. Backhaus, Jürgen G. (1989), ‘Efficient Statute Law’, in Faure, Michael and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds), Essays in Law and Economics. Corporations, Accident Prevention and Compensation for Losses, Antwerpen, Maklu, 23-32. Bailey, Martin J. and Rubin, Paul H. (1994), ‘A Positive Theory of Legal Change’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 467-77. Benson, Bruce L. (1990), The Enterprise of Law: Justice Without the State, San Francisco, Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy. Benson, Bruce L. (1992), ‘Market Failure versus Government Failure in the Production of Adjudication’, in Bowman, Gary, Hakim, Simon and Seidenstat, Paul (eds), Privatizing the United States Justice System: Police, Adjudication, and Corrections Services from the Private Sector, Jefferson, NC, McFarland & Co., 203-225. Benson, Bruce L. (1995), ‘An Exploration of the Impact of Modern Arbitration Statutes on the Development of Arbitration in the United States’, 11 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 479-501. Benson, Bruce L. (1996), ‘Uncertainty, the Race for Property Rights, and Rent Dissipation due to Judicial Changes in Product Liability Tort Law’, Cultural Dynamics. Benson, Bruce L. and Wollan, Laurin A., Jr (1991), ‘Increasing Judicial Responsibility can Reduce Prison Overcrowding’, in Tipp, Stacey L. (ed.), America’s Prisons: Opposing Viewpoints, San Diego, Greenhaven Press, 139-144. Blume, Lawrence E. and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1982), ‘The Dynamics of the Legal Process’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 405-420. Bruce, Christopher J. (1984), ‘Testing the Hypothesis of Common Law Efficiency: The Doctrine of Informed Consent’, 6 Research in Law and Economics, 227-265. Bruce, Christopher J. (1988), ‘The Adjudication of Labor Disputes as a Private Good’, 8 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-19. Buchanan, James M. (1978), ‘Law and the Invisible Hand’, in Siegan, Bernard H. (ed.), The Interaction of Economics and the Law, Lexington, Lexington Books. Carrington, Paul D. (1979), ‘Adjudication as a Private Good: A Comment’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 303-317. Che, Yeon Koo and Yi, Jong Goo (1993), ‘The Role of Precedents in Repeated Litigation’, 9 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 399-424. Christiansen, Gregory B. (1990), ‘Law as a Discovery Procedure’, 9 Cato Journal, 497-530. Chubb, Larry L. (1989), ‘Economic Analysis in the Courts: Limits and Constraints’, 64 Indiana Law Journal, 769-801. Clark, Robert C. (1981), ‘The Interdisciplinary Study of “Legal Evolution”’, 90 Yale Law Journal, 1238-1274. Cohen, George M. (1985), ‘Posnerian Jurisprudence and Economic Analysis of Law: The View from the Bench’, 133 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1117-1166. Cohen, Mark A. (1991), ‘Explaining Judicial Behavior or What’s “Unconstitutional” about the Sentencing Commission?’, 7 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 183-199. Cohen, Mark A. (1992), ‘The Motives of Judges: Empirical Evidence from Antitrust Sentencing’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 13 ff. Cooter, Robert D. (1983), ‘The Objectives of Private and Public Judges’, 41 Public Choice, 107-132. Cooter, Robert D. (1987), ‘Liberty, Efficiency, and Law’, 50 (4) Law and Contemporary Problems,
552
Judge-Made Law
9200
141-163. Cooter, Robert D. (1990), The Structural Approach to Adjudicating Social Norms: Evolution of the Common Law Reconsidered, Working Paper, School of Law, University of California at Berkeley. Cooter, Robert (1992), ‘The Minimax Constitution as Democracy’, 12 (2) International Review of Law and Economics, 292-94. Cooter, Robert D. and Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1980), ‘Can Litigation Improve the Law without the Help of Judges?’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies,139-163. Cooter, Robert D. and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1989), ‘Economic Analysis of Legal Disputes and Their Resolution,’ 27 (3) Journal of Economic Literature, 1092 ff. Cooter, Robert D., Kornhauser, Lewis A. and Lane, D. (1979), ‘Liability Rules, Limited Information, and the Role of Precedent’, 10 Bell Journal of Economics, 366-373. Cramton, Roger C. (1959), ‘The Supreme Court and the Decline of State Power’, 2 Journal of Law and Economics, 175-189. Crew, Michael A. and Twight, Charlotte (1990), ‘On the Efficiency of Law: A Public Choice Perspective’, 66 Public Choice, 15-136. Culp, Jerome M. (1987), ‘Judex Economicus’, 50(4) Law and Contemporary Problems, 95-140. Davis, Otto A. (1979), ‘Public and Private Characteristics of a Legal Process: A Comment’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 285-293. Daynard, Richard A. (1971), ‘Use of Social Policy in Judicial Decision-Making’, 56 Carnell Law Review, 919-950. De Alessi, Louis (1985), ‘Property Rights and the Judiciary’, 4 Cato Journal, 805-811. Reprinted in Dorn, James A. and Manne, Henry G. (eds) (1987), Economic Liberties and the Judiciary, Fairfax, George Mason University Press, 175-181. Denzau, Arthur (1979), ‘Litigation Expenditures as Private Determinants of Judicial Decisions: A Comment’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 295-302. Dicke, Hugo and Hartung, Hans (1986), ‘Externe Kosten von Rechtsvorschriften (External Effects of Legal Rules)’, in Möglichkeiten und Grenzen der ökonomischen Gesetzesanalyse, Tübingen, J.C.B. Mohr, 123 ff. Easterbrook, Frank H. (1982), ‘Ways of Criticizing the Court’, 95 Harvard Law Review, 802 ff. Easterbrook, Frank H. (1984), ‘The Supreme Court, 1983 Term, Foreword: The Court and the Economic System’, 98 Harvard Law Review, 4-60. Easterbrook, Frank H. (1992), ‘Some Tasks in Understanding Law through the Lens of Public Choice: General Panel Commentary’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 284-288. Eisenberg, Melvin Aron (1988),The Nature of the Common Law, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 204 ff. Ellickson, Robert C. (1989), ‘A Hypothesis of Wealth-Maximizing Norms: Evidence from the Whaling Industry’, 5 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 83-97. Elliott, E. Donald (1985), ‘The Evolutionary Tradition in Jurisprudence’, 85 Columbia Law Review, 38-94. Epstein, Richard A. (1980), ‘The Static Conception of the Common Law’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 253-275. Epstein, Richard A. (1982), ‘The Social Consequences of Common Law Rules’, 95 Harvard Law Review, 1717-1751. Epstein, Richard A. (1987), ‘Judicial Review: Reckoning on Two Kinds of Error’, in Dorn, James A.
9200
Judge-Made Law
553
and Manne, Henry G. (eds), Economic Liberties and the Judiciary, Fairfax, George Mason University Press, 39-46. Fox, Eleanor M. (1986), ‘The Politics of Law and Economics in Judicial Decision Making: Antitrust as a Window’, 61 New York University Law Review, 554-588. Friedman, David (1979), ‘Private Creation and Enforcement of Law: A Historical Case’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 399-415. Gerhart, Peter M. (1982), ‘The Supreme Court and Antitrust Analysis: The (Near) Triumph of the Chicago School’, 1982 Supreme Court Review, 319-349. Goldberg, Victor P. (ed.) (1979), ‘Discussion by Seminar Participants’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 323-398. Golbert, J.P. and Lowenstein, Paul (1982), ‘The Court and the Marketplace: Who Should Regulate Whom?’, 34 Baylor Law Review, 39-65. Goodman, John C. (1979), ‘An Economic Theory of the Evolution of the Common Law’, 7 Journal of Legal Studies, 235 ff. Greenwalt, Kent (1977), ‘Policy, Rights and Judicial Decision’, 11 Georgia Law Review, 991-1053. Hadfield, Gillian K. (1992a), ‘Incomplete Contracts and Statutes: Commentary’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 257-259. Hadfield, Gillian K. (1992b), ‘Biases in the Evolution of Legal Rules,’ 80 Georgetown Law Journal, 583-616. Harris, Peter (1985), ‘Difficult Cases and the Display of Authority’, 1 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 209-221. Hayek, Friedrich A. (1960), The Constitution of Liberty, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Hayek, Friedrich A. (1973), Law, Legislation, and Liberty, 1 Rules and Order, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Hazard, Geoffrey C., Jr (1979), ‘Adjudication as a Private Good: A Comment’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 319-321. Heiner, Ronald A. (1986), ‘Imperfect Decisions and the Law: On the Evolution of Legal Precedent and Rules’, 15 Journal of Legal Studies, 227-261. Higgins, Richard S. and Rubin, Paul H. (1980), ‘Judicial Discretion’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 129-138. Hirshleifer, Jack (1982), ‘Evolutionary Models in Economics and Law’, 4 Research in Law and Economics. Holmes, Oliver Wendell (1880), The Common Law, Boston, Little Brown. Hovenkamp, Herbert (1985), ‘Evolutionary Models in Jurisprudence,’ 64 Texas Law Review, 645-685. Kaplow, Louis (1987), ‘Antitrust, Law and Economics, and the Courts’, 50 (4) Law and Contemporary Problems, 181-216. Katz, Avery (1988), ‘Judicial Decisionmaking and Litigation Expenditure’, 8 International Review of Law and Economics, 127-143. Kennedy, Duncan (1981), ‘Cost-Reduction Theory as Legitimation’,90 Yale Law Journal, 1275-1283. Kenny, Paul (1982), ‘Economic Analysis and Efficiency in the Common Law’, in Cranston, Ross and Schick, Anne (eds), Law and Economics, Canberra, Australian National University, 42-58. Kobayashi, Bruce H. and Lott, John R., Jr (1994), ‘Judicial Reputation and the Efficiency of the Common Law’, mimeo, George Mason University. Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1980), ‘A Guide to the Perplexed Claims of Efficiency in the Law’, 8 Hofstra Law Review, 591-639.
554
Judge-Made Law
9200
Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1989a), ‘An Economic Perspective of Stare Decisis’, 65 Chicago-Kent Law Review, 63-92. Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1989b), ‘Response to Macey’, 65 Chicago-Kent Law Review, 115-122. Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1992a), ‘Modeling Collegial Courts I: Path Dependence’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 169-185. Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1992b), ‘Modeling Collegial Courts. II. Legal Doctrine’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 441-470. Kornhauser, Lewis (1995), ‘Adjudication by a Resource-Constrained Team: Hierarchy and Precedent in a Judicial System’, 68 Southern California Law Review, 1605 ff. Kornhauser, Lewis (1996), ‘Notes on the Logic of Legal Change’, in David Braybrooke (ed.), Social Rules: Origin, Character, Logic, Change, Westview Press. Kornhauser, Lewis and Sager, L. (1986), ‘Unpacking the Court’, 96 Yale Law Journal, 82ff. Kornhauser, Lewis A. and Sager, Lawrence G. (1993), ‘The One and the Many: Adjudication in Collegial Courts’, 81 California Law Review, 1 ff. Kornhauser, Lewis, Cooter, Robert and Lane, D. (1979), ‘Liability Rules, Limited Information, and the Role of Precedent’, 10 Bell Journal of Economics, 366 ff. Kübler, Friedrich (1990), ‘Effizienz als Rechtsprinzip - Überlegungen zum rechtspraktischen Gebrauch ökonomischer Argumente (Efficiency as Legal Principle - Considerations for the Legal Practice Use of Economic Arguments)’, in Baur, Jürgen F., Hopt, Klaus J. and Mailänder, Peter K. (eds), Festschrift für Ernst Steindorff, Berlin, de Gruyter, 687-704. Landes, William M. (1971), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Courts’, 14 Journal of Law and Economics, 61-107. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1976), ‘Legal Precedent: A Theoretical and Empirical Analysis’, 19 Journal of Law and Economics, 249-307. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1979), ‘Adjudication as a Private Good’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 235-284. Landes, William and Posner , Richard (1980), ‘Legal Change, Judicial Behavior, and the Diversity Jurisdiction, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 367-386. Landes, William and Posner, Richard (1987), The Economic Structure of Tort Law, Cambridge, Harvard University Press. Latin, Howard (1987), ‘Legal and Economic Considerations in the Decisions of Judge Breyer’, 50 (4) Law and Contemporary Problems, 57-86. Liebeler, Wesley J. (1985), ‘A Property Rights Approach to Judicial Decision Making’, 4 Cato Journal, 783-804. Reprinted in Dorn, James A. and Manne, Henry G. (eds) (1987), Economic Liberties and the Judiciary, Fairfax, George Mason University Press, 153-174. Liebermann, Yehoshua (1986), ‘Economic Efficiency and Making of the Law: The Case of Transaction Costs in Jewish Law’, 15 Journal of Legal Studies, 387-404. Linder, Douglas O. (1989), ‘Some Doubts Concerning the Selection Hypothesis of George Priest’, 37 University of Kansas Law Review, 319-347. Macey, Jonathan R. (1989), ‘The Internal and External Costs and Benefits of Stare Decisis’, 65 Chicago-Kent Law Review, 93-113. Macey, Jonathan R. (1994), ‘Judicial Preferences, Public Choice, and the Rules of Procedure’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 627-46. Magat, Wesley A. (1987), ‘Howard Latin’s Analysis of the Legal and Economic Considerations in the Decisions of Judge Breyer’, 50 Law and Contemporary Problems, 87-93. Mcnollgast (1992), ‘The Theory of Interpretive Canon and Legislative Behavior: Commentary’, 12
9200
Judge-Made Law
555
International Review of Law and Economics, 235-238. Mendelson, Wallace (1961), ‘The Politics of Judicial Supremacy’, 4 Journal of Law and Economics, 175-185. Miceli, Thomas J. and Cosgel, Metin M. (1994), ‘Reputation and Judicial Decision-Making’, 23 Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 31-51. Michelman, Frank I. (1978), ‘Norms and Normativity in the Economic Theory of Law’, 62 Minnesota Law Review, 1015-1048. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1989), ‘Comment: Some Thoughts on the Equilibrium Hypothesis’, 69 Boston University Law Review, 561-568. O’Hara, Erin (1993), ‘Social Constraint or Implicit Collusion?: Toward a Game Theoretic Analysis of Stare Decisis’, 24 Seton Hall Law Review, 736-778. Parsons, Wes (Student Contribution) (1983), ‘The Inefficient Common Law’, 92 Yale Law Journal, 863-887. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1988), ‘The Deterrent Effects of Settlements and Trials’, 8 International Review of Law and Economics, 109-116. Pollock, Stewart G. (1988), ‘Economic Analysis at Work in Judicial Decision-Making’,Annual Survey of American Law, 133-136. Posner, Richard A. (1980), ‘The Ethical and Political Basis of the Efficiency Norm in Common Law Adjudication’, 8 Hofstra Law Review, 487-507. Posner, Richard A. (1981a), ‘A Reply to Some Recent Criticisms of the Efficiency Theory of the Common Law’, 9 Hofstra Law Review, 775 ff. Posner, Richard A. (1981b), ‘The Present Situation in Legal Scholarship’, 90 Yale Law Journal, 1113-1130. Posner, Richard A. (1985), The Federal Courts: Crisis and Reform, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 365 ff. Posner, Richard A. (1992), Economic Analysis of Law, 4th edn, Little, Brown, Boston. Posner, Richard A. (1993), ‘What do Judges Maximize? (The Same Thing Everybody Else Does),’ 3 Supreme Court Economic Review, 1-41. Priest, George L. (1977), ‘The Common Law Process and the Selection of Efficient Rules’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 65-82. Priest, George L. (1980), ‘Selective Characteristics of Litigation’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 399 ff. Priest, George L. (1981b), ‘The New Scientism in Legal Scholarship: A Comment on Clark and Posner’, 90 Yale Law Journal, 1284-1295. Priest, George (1985), ‘The Invention of Enterprise Liability: A Critical History of the Intellectual Foundations of Modern Tort Law’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 461-528. Priest, George L. (1987), ‘Measuring Legal Change’, 3 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 193-225. Priest, George L. and Klein, Benjamin (1984), ‘The Selection of Disputes for Litigation’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 1 ff. Rasmusen, Eric (1994), ‘Judicial Legitimacy as a Repeated Game’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 63-83. Richter, Rudolf (1987), ‘The Efficiency of the Common Law: A New Institutional Economics Perspective: Comment’, in Pethig, Rudiger and Schlieper, Ulrich (eds), Efficiency, Institutions, and Economic Policy: Proceedings of a Workshop Held by the Sonderforschungsbereich 5 at the University of Mannheim, June 1986, New York, Springer, 123-125. Rizzo, Mario J. (1979), ‘Uncertainty, Subjectivity and the Economic Analysis of Law’, in Rizzo, Mario
556
Judge-Made Law
9200
J. (ed.), Time, Uncertainty and Disequilibrium, Lexington, Lexington Books, 71-89. Rizzo, Mario J. (1980a), ‘The Mirage of Efficiency’, 8 Hofstra Law Review, 641-658. Rizzo, Mario J. (1980b), ‘Law Amid Flux: The Economics of Negligence and Strict Liability in Tort’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 291 ff. Rizzo, Mario J. (ed.) (1980c), ‘Symposium: Change in the Common Law: Legal and Economic Perspectives. A Symposium Sponsored by The Institute for Humane Studies and the Liberty Fund’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 189-427. Rizzo, Mario J. (1980d), ‘Can There be a Principle of Explanation in Common Law Decisions? A Comment on Priest’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 423-427. Rizzo, Mario J. (1985), ‘Rules versus Cost-Benefit Analysis in the Common Law’, 4 Cato Journal, 865-884. Reprinted in Dorn, James A. and Manne, Henry G. (eds) (1987), Economic Liberties and the Judiciary, Fairfax, George Mason University Press, 1987, 225-244. Rizzo, Mario J. and Arnold, Frank S. (1987), ‘An Economic Framework for Statutory Interpretation’, 50 Law and Contemporary Problems, 165-180. Roberts, Neal A. (1980), ‘Beaches: The Efficiency of the Common Law and Other Fairy Tales’, 28 UCLA Law Review, 169-196. Roe, Mark J. (1996), ‘Chaos and Evolution in Law and Economics’, 109 Harvard Law Review, 641-668. Romano, Roberta (1992), ‘Judicial Choice of Legal Doctrines: Comment’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 47-58. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1987), ‘Tullock and the Inefficiency of the Common Law’, in Rowley, Charles K. (ed.), Democracy and Public Choice: Essays in Honor of Gordon Tullock, Oxford, Blackwell, 181-185. Rowley, Charles K. (1987), ‘Comment: A Public Choice Perspective on Judicial Pragmactivism’, in Dorn, James A. and Manne, Henry G. (eds), Economic Liberties and the Judiciary, Fairfax, George Mason University Press, 219-224. Rowley, Charles K. and Brough, Wayne (1987), ‘The Efficiency of the Common Law: A New Institutional Economics Perspective’, in Pethig, Rudiger and Schlieper, Ulrich (eds), Efficiency, Institutions, and Economic Policy: Proceedings of a Workshop Held by the Sonderforschungsbereich 5 at the University of Mannheim, New York, Springer, 103-121. Rubin, Paul H. (1977), ‘Why is the Common Law Efficient?’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 51-63. Rubin, Paul H. (1980), ‘Decision Making and the Efficiency of Law: A Comment on Rizzo’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 319-334. Rubin, Paul H. (1982), ‘Common Law and Statute Law’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 205-223. Rubin, Paul H. (1983), Business Firms and the Common Law. The Evolution of Efficient Rules, New York, Praeger, 189 ff. Rubin, Paul H. and Bailey, Martin J. (1994), ‘The Role of Lawyers in Changing the Law’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 807 ff. Sajó, András (1981), ‘A Gazdaság jogi Szabályozásának egy Lehetséges útja (A Possible Way of Legal Regulation of the Economy)’, 4 Jogtudományi Közlöny, 297-308. Sajó, András (1987), ‘A jog a Gazdaság Szabályozástechnikái Közt (Law as One of the Regulating Means of the Economy)’, 3 Jogtudományi Közlöny, 126-132. Samuels, Warren J. and Mercuro, Nicholas (1984), ‘Posnerian Law and Economics on the Bench’, 4 International Review of Law and Economics, 107-130. Samuels, Warren J. and Mercuro, Nicholas (1986), ‘Wealth Maximization and Judicial
9200
Judge-Made Law
557
Decision-Making: The Issues Further Clarified’, 6 International Review of Law and Economics, 133-137. Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (1989), ‘Allokationseffizienz als Grundprinzip des Zivilrechts (Allocative Efficiency as Basic Principle of Civil Law)’, in Ott, Claus and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (eds), Allokationseffizienz in der Rechtsordnung, Berlin, Springer, 1-24. Scheppele, Kim Lane (1988), Legal Secrets, Equality and Efficiency in the Common Law, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 363 ff. Schwartz, Edward P. (1992), ‘Policy, Precedent, and Power: A Positive Theory of Supreme Court Decision Making’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 219-252. Shapiro, Martin (1972), ‘Toward a Theory of Stare Decisis’, 1 Journal of Legal Studies, 125-134. Shavell, Steven (1995), ‘The Appeals Process as a Means of Error Correction’, 24 Journal of Legal Studies, 379 ff. Shepsle, Kenneth A. (1992), ‘Congress is a “They”, not an “It”: Legislative Intent as Oxymoron’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 239-256. Simpson, A.W.B. (1979), ‘The Horwitz Thesis and the History of Contracts’, 46 University of Chicago Law Review, 533-601. Sinder, Janet (1987), ‘Economists as Judges: A Selective, Annotated Bibliography’, 50 (4) Law and Contemporary Problems, 279-286. Smith, Steven D. (1984), ‘Rhetoric and Rationality in the Law of Negligence’, 69 Minnesota Law Review, 277-323. Spiller, Pablo T. and Spitzer, Matthew L. (1992), ‘Judicial Choice of Legal Doctrines’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 8-46. Spitzer, Matthew L. (1992), ‘Jurisprudence and Formal Models’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 295-296. Sunstein, Cass R. (1992), ‘Public Choice, Endogenous Preferences’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 289-291. Terrebonne, R. Peter (1981), ‘A Strictly Evolutionary Model of Common Law’, 10 Journal of Legal Studies, 397 ff. Tullock, Gordon (1971), The Logic of the Law, New York, Basic Books. Tullock, Gordon (1980), Trials on Trial: The Pure Theory of Legal Procedure, New York, Columbia University Press. Varat, Jonathan D. (1986), ‘Review Essay: Economic Ideology and the Federal Judicial Task (Review of The Federal Courts: Crisis and Reform by Richard A. Posner), 74 California Law Review, 649-674. Veljanovski, Cento G. (1985), ‘The Role of Economics in the Common Law’, 7 Research in Law and Economics, 41-64. Von Wangenheim, Georg (1993), ‘The Evolution of Judge Made Law’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 381-411. Wald, Patricia M. (1987), ‘Limits on the Use of Economic Analysis in Judicial Decisionmaking’, 50 (4) Law and Contemporary Problems, 225-244. Whichard, Willis P. (1987), ‘A Common Law Judge’s View of the Appropriate Use of Economics in Common Law Adjudication’, 50 (4) Law and Contemporary Problems, 253-263. Williams, Stephen F. (1980), ‘The Static Conception of the Common Law: A Comment’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 277-289. Wilson, James G. (1986), ‘Justice Diffused: A Comparison of Edmund Burke’s Conservatism with the Views of Five Conservative, Academic Judges’, 40 University of Miami Law Review, 913-975.
558
Judge-Made Law
9200
Wittman, Donald (1989), ‘Why Democracies Produce Efficient Results’, 97 Journal of Political Economy, 1395-1424. X (1987), ‘Note: Judge Frank H. Easterbrook: A Faithful Adherent of the Law and Economics Approach Advocates by Professor Frank H. Easterbrook’, 50 (4) Law and Contemporary Problems, 265-277.
9300 PRODUCTION OF LEGAL RULES BY AGENCIES AND BUREAUCRACIES Georg von Wangenheim University of Hamburg © Copyright 1999 Georg von Wangenheim
Abstract The main questions which the literature on rule production by agencies and bureaucracies deals with are: To what extent should legislators delegate rule making to bureaucracy? How can procedural rules curb an agency’s discretion in making substantive rules? Do legislators select bureaucratic decisions for oversight randomly or on the basis of complaints? Who exactly controls bureaucracy: some and which elements in the legislature or the judiciary? How does the process of bureaucratic rule making work inside an agency? This article reviews the literature with a special emphasis on the effect of procedural rules and on the spatial representation of the interplay between the bureaucracy and the legislature. It concludes by pointing out that more research should be conducted on the process of rule making within agencies and the underlying preferences. JEL classification: D73, H11, K23, K29 Keywords: Theory of Bureaucracy, Spatial Approaches to Politics, Procedural vs Substantive Rules, Principal-Agent Theory
1. Introduction The central question posed in the literature on the production of rules by agencies is how the discretion of law-making agencies can be curbed. The political preferences of bureaucracies are most often taken to be exogenously given. These may be the personal political preferences of the director of the single agency or may reflect the influence of interest groups. The influence of interest groups is hardly ever modeled explicitly in this literature. Based on more or less complete answers to the central question, explanations are given for why a legislator may want to delegate law-making power to bureaucracies and how control of this delegated power is to be organized. The key normative question is how much delegation there ought to be. However, answers given to this question barely rely on the positive analyses mentioned herein.
559
560
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
9300
Current positive law and economics analyses of how agencies and bureaucracies (these two terms are used as synonyms herein) produce legal rules differ substantially from approaches applied to other law-making institutions. These analyses do not follow the Public Choice approach commonly used to explain the production of legal rules by legislators; nor do they follow the evolutionary approaches mostly used to explain production of rules by the court system. Theories dealing with bureaucratic law making do not derive, accordingly, one utility maximizing position of the bureaucratic decision makers (which are hardly ever modeled as multiple individuals); nor do these theories rely on the assumption that inefficient legal rules are challenged more often than efficient ones (so that the average of legal rules evolves towards a rather efficient state.) Only if the study of production of rules by the legislator concentrates on consequences of more than one institution needed to pass a law, do strong similarities with the approaches to bureaucratic rule production arise; no such similarities occur between theories of bureaucratic rule making and the evolutionary approach. Comparing the literature on decision making by agencies and bureaucracies with the research on the production of legal rules by the legislator on the one side, and rule production by the judiciary on the other, not only demonstrates how the approaches to very similar problems differ, but also underlines a problem which only seems to be purely semantic: bureaucratic rule making and bureaucratic adjudication are analytically distinct, as are legislative rule making and judicial adjudication. If bureaucratic decisions are rule making, the Public Choice approach suggests itself for tackling bureaucratic rule making; if they are adjudication, an evolutionary approach seems to be more appropriate. The problem arises in much of the theoretical literature and holds true for many empirical studies. Single bureaucratic decisions or entire classes of bureaucratic decisions are often analyzed without having any thought about whether these decisions are rule making or adjudication. The reason for the reluctance to distinguish between rule making and adjudication may be that the distinction is not as clear in American administrative law (see, for example, Rugge, 1987), as it would seem from the Administrative Procedures Act (5 U.S.C. §551 (4)-(7)). This lack of clarity may be a problem in other jurisdictions as well. As a result, very few authors in the field reviewed here mention the distinction at all (for example, Lupia and McCubbins, 1994b). It is therefore often not possible to restrict this review to the literature on bureaucratic rule making; research with regard to decisions made in single cases has to be referred to in many places. Likewise, some of the literature reviewed here may overlap with the literature discussed in the articles on regulation of contracts and on environmental regulation. Yet the emphasis of this chapter will be different: it deals with the ‘production of legal rules by agencies and bureaucracies’,
9300
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
561
that is, with the rule-making activities of agencies and bureaucracies. I will, however, avoid making too many references to scholarly works on bureaucracies in general, if there is no specific relation to rule making (for an overview of this literature with special reference to Public Choice arguments see Benson, 1995). The chapter is organized as follows: Sections 2 and 3, respectively, review the literature that describes how procedural rules, by framing the production of substantive rules by agencies, facilitate the control of agencies by their principal, that is, the legislator, and writings comparing the different ways in which the legislator is able to control a rule-making agency. The following two sections, 4 and 5, concentrate on the literature breaking down the legislator into its different institutions, including the courts in the analysis of constraints to bureaucratic rule production. Section 4 deals with econometric studies while Section 5 presents the spatial approach to the topic. Section 6 surveys works that ask normatively whether there ought to be delegation of rule production to agencies and bureaucracies at all. Section 7 reviews the few inquiries into the interior process of agencies which produce rules and Section 8 concludes.
2. Curbing Bureaucratic Discretion by Procedural Rules Two distinct phenomena bring about bureaucratic discretion: one, the inability of legislative institutions to control perfectly the activities of bureaucracies at reasonable costs; the other, the need for cooperative action by legislative institutions, to sanction an agency or to replace bureaucratic rules by new statutory rules. Although a clear distinction between these phenomena cannot be maintained in reviewing all the publications, the first phenomenon is dealt with in this and the next section; the second in Sections 4 and 5. As stressed by McCubbins, Noll and Weingast (1987) (‘McNollgast’), the principal-agent relationship between legislators and bureaucracies cannot be dealt with appropriately by the mere reference to general principal-agent models of the Laffont-Tirole-Holmström-Milgrom type. The reason is that ex post sanctions, which are imposed after the bureaucracy deviates from the political preferences of the politicians, are far too limited, in view of low probabilities of detection, high monitoring costs, and the costs which legislators themselves must bear to impose sanctions (work, political backlash for poorly working agencies, further deterioration of the agency’s work). Note however, that Mitnick (1975) emphasizes that one has to be careful with short- and long-run costs and benefits from control here: strict control by the principal may run up more costs than benefits in the short
562
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
9300
run, but be profitable in the long run because agents become ‘educated’ by control, and strict control may result in a self-selection of ‘good’ agents. In McCubbins, Noll and Weingast (1989), the authors extend the reasons for the inappropriateness of the general principal-agent model to embrace the phenomenon to be discussed extensively in Section 5 of this chapter: the need for coordination among several institutions if control of bureaucratic rule production is to be exercised by the shadow of overriding statutory legislation. McNollgast argue that the remaining, large problems of compliance may be partly solved by procedural rules. In this respect, procedural rules governing the agency’s soliciting of information and the consequences of not doing so properly are most important: they may ensure that agencies base their decisions on large sets of information which would also be sufficient for legislative control. Soliciting information can only be successful if those who are better informed have enough incentives to disclose their information. This is, of course, the case if the stakes of affected groups in an issue are high or the issue is highly controversial. These variables, however, fail to be within the control of the legislator. The legislator is forced, thus, to concentrate on enacting procedural rules that modify the costs and the effectiveness of providing information to the bureaucracy. McNollgast study such procedural rules. Public disclosure requirements facilitate political intervention of interest groups at early stages in the rule-making process, even earlier than in the legislative process. Thus, political intervention of interest groups may allow ex ante control of bureaucratic rule production. Elaborate rules of procedure result in high costs of rent seeking and, accordingly, favor those groups which have large resources to spend on representation. On the other hand, budget subsidies for poorly represented groups favor these groups, instead. Next, the discretion of the agency is limited by evidentiary standards, which refer to how evidence must be processed to come to a decision. Burden-of-proof rules may favor or hamper groups which base arguments on unclear cause-effect relationships. Further, ‘ex parte’ rules serve to prohibit direct informal communication between private parties and an agency during the formal rule-making process. These rules variously provide for sanctions against prohibited ex parte communications, that run a gamut up to, at the extreme, imposing a final decision against the infringing group. Ex parte rules enable politicians to participate in the rule-making process, at least as brokers of communication. Also, politicians may exert direct pressure on agencies. For all these procedural rules to enable politicians to exert ex ante control, a judicial remedy for their infringement must be sufficiently likely to occur. This can be achieved by decentralized enforcement of these rules if private parties are able to sue at low costs.
9300
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
563
McNollgast not only examine ways in which procedural rules and interest groups interact to curb decision making by bureaucrats and agencies, but also argue that politicians are not constrained to granting a policy which is currently favorable to some interest groups. McNollgast suggest politicians are able to ensure, for the future, that changes of legal (agency-made) rules are favorable to the interest groups which constitute the original coalition. This ‘autopilot’ for future decisions relieves the enacting coalition of the problem that future political majorities might favor other interest groups. The problem of ‘slack’ of future legislators as being opposed to regulatory slack in rule making is particularly stressed by Horn and Shepsle (1989) and by Steunenberg (1992). They emphasize that there is a trade-off between these two kinds of slack because constraints on either the agency or future legislators require freedom to act by the other institution. McNollgast allow, against the thrust of their argument, that the control of agencies exercised by the interest groups may evolve in an unexpected direction, or be impeded altogether, if the interest groups that are engaged in the original deal with the legislator cease to exist. Macey (1992) discounts the importance of this caveat for three reasons, all related to the design of a newly-formed agency, and thus strengthens the thrust of McNollgast’s argument: first, when interest groups agree with the legislator to institute a regulatory agency, the agreement is likely to cover institutional rules about what parties may influence the future agency’s decisions and the ways influence can be exerted. For example, the influence of poorly organized groups may be secured by facilitating access, to individuals with an interest, to agency hearings or judicial review of agency decisions. Levine (1992) criticizes this argument on the basis that, while one may predict that liberalized standing will increase the degree of interference of the courts with regulatory drift, one is unable to predict easily the direction of this interference. This argument apparently neglects the results of evolutionary approaches to the common law (compare the literature following Rubin, 1977 and Priest, 1977), where predictions on the directions of judicial rule making are certainly possible, even if the court system is not systematically biased in some direction. If the court system is known to be biased, it is obvious that one may predict in what direction judge-made law will evolve. Second, limiting the jurisdiction of a newly-installed agency to the regulation of a small number of industries, or even to part of a single industry, assures that expertise in the agency in this specialized field mainly will be recruited from the same industries or part of an industry. As a result, the points of view held by the agency and industry will usually concur. Accordingly, at least regulation in favor of the regulated industry is stable over time.
564
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
9300
Third, when agencies compete for jurisdiction with each other, they seek out the support of constituents and hence will not deviate from the preferences of their constituency. The agency and its constituent interest group(s) thus mutually support each other in order to further their own raison d’être and improve their chances to survive over time. This mutual support together with the procedural rules mentioned above serve as an autopilot for rule making by the agency. A similar argument had already been forwarded by Benson (1981), Benson (1983a), and Benson (1983b) although Benson did not set forth the argument in terms of curbing regulative drift. Benson focuses on the size of the bureau and the problem of over-regulation. Johnson and Libecap (1994) drive home the argument that the rank and file of bureaucrats are interested in the duration of their agency to a point that they become an influential interest group in shaping long-run trends in bureaucratic institutions. With particular reference to the third argument (mutual support of regulator and regulated industry), Macey (1992) rejects Shepsle’s (1992) view (also expressed by Horn and Shepsle, 1989, and by Steunenberg, 1992), that more emphasis should be placed on the trade-off between the regulatory and legislative slack. Macey claims that there is no such trade-off, but interest groups with political clout, which participate in the original, political decision to set up an agency, retain their political power by this mutual support and continue to exert a like influence on the legislator as well as on the agency. Although both of the papers of McNollgast give case studies as empirical examples of their theory, Robinson (1989) casts severe doubts on the empirical relevance of McNollgast’s argument. McNollgast argue that procedural provisions serve mainly as a curb on the discretion of agencies. Robinson points out that even most of the examples cited by McNollgast do not support their theory, much less do the examples introduced by Robinson himself. He contends, however, that McNollgast’s approach could be very useful. If the empirical relevance of the argument were shown, it could substantially change and advance the understanding of the legal-administrative process. In a related study, Rose-Ackermann (1995) compares how procedural rules enable interested (third) parties to control and interfere with bureaucratic rule making in Germany and the US. Contrary to the situation in the US, in Germany individual citizens hardly have any chance to control rule production by bureaucracies; this control only extends to applications of the rules. Rule making by bureaucracies in Germany is typically under the influence of well-organized interest groups, in the same informal way as statutory legislation is in both countries. Only in the US do procedural rules give the power to control bureaucratic rule making to interested parties which are not politically powerful in the legislative process anyway.
9300
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
565
Hamilton and Schroeder (1994) call into question this entire line of reasoning. They ask why agencies would follow procedural rules more strictly than substantive rules. Though they do not enter into a theoretical discussion of the point of view, they do provide some empirical evidence that procedural rules are, in fact, circumvented. Agencies leave substantive rules incomplete and fill the gaps with extensive directives, guidance documents and policy memoranda, which fail to be rules in a formal sense and are not subject to formal rule-making procedures that require the participation of interest groups, in particular of those groups which are protected by procedural rules.
3. Police-Patrol Control versus Fire-Alarm Control An issue closely related to the question of how procedural rules give control over bureaucratic rule making to third parties is the question of how legislators can best control agencies. The problem posed is whether legislators want to take a random sample of bureaucratic activity (including its rule-making activity) in the same manner in which a police patrol randomly inspects the streets; or whether legislators want to look at bureaucratic decisions only when and where someone protests against a particular decision with vehemence, in the same manner in which the fire department takes action only after someone sounds a fire alarm. I refer to this question as the optimal-type-of-control problem. The leading articles that discuss the optimal-type-of-control problem (for an overview of the consequential literature until 1990 see Ogul and Rockmann, 1990) are McCubbins and Schwartz (1984) and Weingast (1984). These articles argue that, in general, Congress prefers fire-alarm to police-patrol oversight, because the costs of the monitoring activities are partly transferred from Congress itself to interested groups and individuals. However, citizens harmed by violations of legislative goals are not always represented by well-organized groups and, accordingly, are unable to sound alarms loud enough to obtain redress of grievances. The authors answer this criticism by referring to arguments like those in the previous section herein: disadvantaged groups often have public spokesmen; problems of collective action are overcome by legislation which favors the organization of interest groups, particularly affected by collective action problems; extensive constituent-service by congress(wo)men opens up review procedures. In the optimal-type-of-control literature, there is no discussion of the social costs of fire-alarm oversight, but one might speculate that it is socially cheaper. With fire-alarm oversight, individuals, who are affected by bureaucratic rule making and will notice it anyway, detect regulatory slack;
566
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
9300
with police-patrol oversight, legislators must fund specialized individuals to scrutinize bureaucratic decisions for which they have little inherent regard. The argument might, however, be weakened if one takes into account a problem like dispersed damages in tort law: the adverse effects of regulatory slack may be so dispersed, that sounding a fire alarm is too costly for anyone other than specialists hired to search for regulatory slack. This assumption, again, throws the argument partly back to the discussion of the previous section herein. It is, however, unclear whether asymmetric degrees of organization among opposing interest groups can be completely offset by procedural rules. Hopenhayn and Lohmann (1996) study the results of asymmetric access to review procedures for a particular kind of fire-alarm oversight, where an agency’s decision can be (partly) controlled before adverse effects on social welfare occur. A fire alarm can be sounded either: (i) only if the agency has allowed some regulated activity although the activity decreases social welfare; or (ii) in addition to this condition also if the agency prohibits a regulated activity although the activity would increase social welfare. If the political institutions rely on this kind of fire-alarm oversight, less activities will be allowed in case (i) than in case (ii). Hence, there may be adverse social welfare effects due to reliance on fire-alarm oversight, as opposed to some symmetric oversight system, possibly a police-patrol system. Aberbach (1990) questions the theoretical findings of McCubbins and Schwartz (1984) and Weingast (1984) on factual grounds. They argue that Congress prefers fire-alarm to police-patrol oversight; he offers empirical evidence that Congress has increasingly used police-patrol oversight instead of only fire-alarm oversight. Ogul and Rockmann (1990) explain this finding by pointing to the greater resources employed by Congress (in particular more staff) to scrutinize agencies, where less means are allocated to new legislative activity because congress(wo)men have, in general, fewer opportunities to obtain name recognition through new legislation. Lupia and McCubbins (1994a, 1994b) develop formal models of both police-patrol and fire-alarm oversight. They explore under what conditions each kind of control is superior to no oversight from the viewpoint of Congress-as-principal. The hardly surprising conditions they derive for police-patrol oversight being superior to no oversight are: large differences between an agency’s and legislators’ preferences; and low costs of oversight. Fire-alarm oversight is superior to no oversight: when high penalties are imposed for false fire alarms; or where the preferences of legislators and of interested groups or individuals that may pull the fire alarm are close to each other. Due to the disparate structure of their two models, Lupia and McCubbins fail to compare the two kinds of oversight with one another. After making exactly this point (Bawn, 1994), Bawn (1997) constructs
9300
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
567
another formal model to carry out this comparison. This model again mainly restates the arguments of McCubbins and Schwartz (1984) in a formal way. By emphasizing that marginal costs of oversight are lower for members of the committee with jurisdiction over the agency than for other members of the chamber, she adds, however, the insight that the latter will prefer more fire-alarm-like or (as Bawn calls it in a slightly broader sense) statutory control. Both Lindsay (1976) and Holmström and Milgrom (1991) express fundamental doubts as to whether an optimal degree of control over agencies can be defined merely by taking into account direct costs of control. They stress that agents that have multiple tasks, which the principal can monitor to different degrees, tend to carry out only tasks for which they will get credit, namely those tasks which the principal can monitor. Such agents neglect the tasks which the principal cannot monitor. By distorting the allocation of the agent’s efforts, additional oversight may thus lead to indirect costs. As there is no common denominator in which to measure the net benefits reaped in the public sector, such as profits, the problem they discuss is particularly relevant to government bureaucracies.
4. Who Controls Bureaucratic Discretion: Econometric Approaches While the literature discussed so far concentrates on how to overcome bureaucratic discretion by assuming a dichotomy between agencies and the legislature (as a unitary actor), many authors also ask who exactly controls the bureaucracy: which particular institution among several engaged in the legislative process? Or none of them, but an independent judiciary? Two strands of literature, only loosely intertwined, must be distinguished: econometric studies (discussed in this section) and theoretical arguments based on sequential games which describe strategic choices made between policies, represented by different points in a given policy space (discussed in Section 5). Among the econometric approaches this article surveys, some authors ask which of several possible institutions controls an agency. Other authors test whether a particular institution controls an agency’s decisions or not. A typical and prominent example for the first type of approach is Moe (1985) (also compare Moe, 1987). He takes the National Labor Relations Board (NLRB) as an example of an agency which could be influenced by the political preferences of the President of Congress and of the courts. His analysis clearly shows that all these institutions are important (changes in political orientation have a significant impact on the decisions of the NLRB), but the President has the most impact on the NLRB. The NLRB is
568
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
9300
not a prominent example of rule production by agencies because its decisions are nearly all adjudicatory. Notwithstanding this limitation, Moe’s paper may well be labeled as path-breaking: it lays ground for later econometric studies to inquire which institutions wield the most power over agencies that makes rules. Beck (1987) employs a model less ambitious in comparing the power wielded over agencies by different institutions but more directly focused on rule production. He studies to what extent the US President is able to influence rule making within the Federal Reserve. In particular, he tests whether monetary policy of the Federal Reserve supports a political business cycle favorable to incumbent presidents. His findings are that the Fed does not actively support such cycles by inducing political monetary cycles but that it passively accepts such cycles induced by fiscal policy. Accordingly, Beck asserts that the President of the US exerts a certain but limited degree of power to control the Fed. Probably the most extensive and detailed econometric study of bureaucratic rule production is conducted by Magat, Krupnick and Harrington (1986, p. 8). Their book aims at clarifying which factors influence bureaucratic decisions with regard to rule making. They test fourteen hypotheses derived from different theoretical approaches to bureaucratic rule making. Unfortunately, few of the results of the study are statistically significant, but most parameters do have the sign which should be expected from the theoretical argument. The same caveat holds for the work of Hamilton and Schroeder (1994), who study how much an agency will resort to ‘informal’ rule making (in the form of directives, guidance documents and policy memoranda issued by an agency) in order to avoid the control of formalized rule-making procedures. Based on studies of the Food and Drug Administration (FDA), Olson (1995, 1996) compares not so much which political institutions exert power in controlling agencies; rather she contrasts different approaches to predict bureaucratic behavior. In particular, she compares capture theory (agencies are controlled by the industries they are supposed to regulate), public interest theory (agencies are the benevolent pursuers of social welfare), and Congressional control theory (legislative institutions, modeled by Olson as a unitary actor, control agencies). She finds that the behavior of one and the same agency is best explained by different theories or even by different combinations of theories for different industries which are regulated. Accordingly, she suggests that unless subsequent empirical studies focus on the micro-level trade-offs which face regulators, it is impossible to get a clear answer as to what are the important incentives in bureaucratic rule production. In order to formulate better explanations or even predictions of bureaucratic behavior, future research must be more sensitive to different
9300
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
569
regulatory actions and their specific constraints and trade-offs for the regulator. Hammond and Knott (1996) altogether reject econometric analyses of which institutions control the bureaucracy based on the correlation between, on the one hand, changes in preferences of an institution, and on the other hand, changes in policy of the agency. As they point out, it is impossible for one institution to control an agency without the cooperation of the other institutions. Thus, future empirical work on political control should incorporate the interplay of preferences of the controlling institutions. These authors do not develop, however, an operational measure of the power wielded by institutions over agencies, although they consider such a measure to be indispensable to conduct empirical studies.
5. Who Controls Bureaucratic Discretion: Spatial Approaches The literature reviewed in Sections 2 and 3 explained the discretion exercised by bureaucrats by highlighting the superior information which agencies possess and explored the ways in which control of the bureaucracy is achieved. The literature discussed in this section takes a game-theoretic approach. This approach is based on preferences in a given policy space to show that bureaucratic discretion exists even without asymmetric information. The basic idea developed in this body of literature is that an agency can be sanctioned, for example, by new legislation that overrules decisions of an agency or interferes with the resources of the agency, only if more than one of the institutions agree to apply sanctions. If n institutions are needed to sanction an agency and every institution has single-peaked preferences in the policy space, Pareto sets of dimension n - 1 or less result. Within these Pareto sets, the agency is free to act because every change in policy makes at least one institution better off; accordingly, this ‘winning’ institution will be reluctant to sanction the agency. As legislative procedures become more complicated than simple acceptance by all relevant institutions, the models are formed as sequential games. In these games, institutions can veto, accept or amend proposals from institutions with the right to take the initiative, according to (a simplified version of) the constitution. The starting point for this discussion is the paper by Weingast (1981). He develops a spatial policy model (one and two policy dimensions) that explains the bounds of agencies’ decisions on regulation. Based on three examples (airlines, telecommunications and nuclear power), he studies the interplay between possibly more than one Congressional (sub)committee; interest groups which form the clientele of both the (sub)committee(s) and the agency controlled by the (sub)committee(s); and sometimes (namely if he
570
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
9300
makes appointments to the agency himself) the President. Weingast shows how this interplay restricts the range of discretion of the agency. Weingast and Moran (1983) take the same approach to explain why there is scant evidence of Congressional oversight. They put forth this approach as an alternative to the dominant view in the literature at the time that this lack of evidence is due to major imperfections in the oversight exercised by Congress, due to Congress’s lack of information. This approach argues, alternatively, that Congressional oversight is near perfect; accordingly, agencies do not even attempt to deviate from the preferences of the legislature. Weingast and Moran demonstrate that their theory explains better than an imperfect-oversight theory would why Congress was extraordinarily active in its oversight of the Federal Trade Commission (FTC) in 1979-80, after a turnover in the members of the appropriate Senate subcommittee: the FTC temporarily lacked sufficient information on new constraints imposed on its discretion by new Senate subcommittee members, and the FTC deviated involuntarily from the preferences of the subcommittee. Finally, Weingast and Moran test their theory econometrically. Their econometric analysis is challenged by Muris (1986) and successfully defended by Weingast and Moran (1986). Econometric support for their theory is also offered in the paper of Faith, Leavens and Tollison (1982). They reject the claim of Katzmann (1980) (who relies exclusively on a non-statistical analysis of interviews conducted on members of the FTC) that the decisions of the FTC are independent of Congressional influence and of efforts to maximize the budget of the Commission. Instead, they offer compelling econometric evidence that both the House and the Senate have a substantial impact on the selection of cases by the FTC, though the impact of the Senate seems to vanish after sweeping reforms were carried out in 1970 on the FTC. In ensuing years, the approach of Weingast has been criticized, mainly for its simplifying assumptions on Congressional legislative procedures (see for example, Moe, 1987). Complicating assumptions, however, were only introduced into the model in the early 1990s. Two papers, by Ferejohn and Shipan (1990) and Gely and Spiller (1990), written independently of each other, incorporate in the model judicial review of administrative decisions, as well as Presidential veto to Congressional override of both decisions of agencies and judicial review of decisions of agencies. The preferences of agencies are assumed to be identical to those of the President (this flaw is overcome by Steunenberg, 1992). Ferejohn and Shipan allow for an override of a Presidential veto by a two-thirds majority in Congress which is modeled as a unicameral legislative body. In a different vein, Gely and Spiller abstract from the opportunity to override a Presidential veto but treat the House and the Senate as two different (unitary) agents and extend the model to a two-dimensional policy space. A final important difference between the
9300
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
571
two models is that judicial control is restricted to replacing the agency’s issuance of new rules by the status quo ante in the paper of Ferejohn and Shipan. In variations of the model of Gely and Spiller, the courts act as a kind of super-agency able to replace the agency’s choice of a new rule with whatever policy the courts prefer most (subject to the threat of new legislation). Ferejohn and Shipan deduce that the next (namely judicial) step in the control of policy making by agencies restricts the power of agencies, and makes agencies more responsive to the preferences of the current (not the originally enacting) legislature. In a comment to this article, Spitzer (1990) studies some cases in which agencies have preferences which differ from those of the President. In another comment, Rose-Ackerman (1990) expresses the criticism that it is unclear why Congress should allow its own committee to deviate as much from Congress’s own preferences as is assumed in the Ferejohn and Shipan paper and, more related to the general approach adopted by Ferejohn and Shipan, that it might substantially increase the agency’s and the court’s discretion and influence to abandon the assumption of costless Congressional action. The paper by Gely and Spiller yields the same result with respect to judicial control over an agency: the reduction in the discretion of an agency is substantially greater if courts are able to impose the policy they prefer most. Allowing the President to have preferences different from those of an agency forces Gely and Spiller to introduce a second dimension in the policy space. Only then can they demonstrate how an increase in the number of institutions that must cooperate to enact a statute increases the dimension of the Pareto set which defines the discretion of an agency. They apply their model to two cases decided by the Supreme Court. The examples show how the ruling of an agency changes after and due to a change in the preferences of the legislature. Formalizing the presentation of the spatial approach, thus far most often based on a graphical exposition, Hammond and Knott (1996) show that any number of dimensions of the policy space and a complete model of US institutions are tractable by this approach. They set forth a formal model. They include all five institutions most relevant to American legislation: the House, the Senate, the relevant committees of both (some multi-person institutions are even divided into their members) and the President. They include two alternative procedures of legislation: majority of House and Senate and approval by President as well as 2/3 majority of the House and Senate. The judiciary is added in an informal way, which may be more appropriate than the alternative approaches chosen by Ferejohn and Shipan (1990) and Gely and Spiller (1990). The power of the judiciary is reduced to stretch the set of legal policies constraining the agency in the direction preferred by the judiciary. And Hammond and Knott include in their model
572
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
9300
the President’s ability or inability to fire an agency director. Complicating the assumptions in the analysis does not provide new insights into how, in theory, bureaucratic discretion changes when additional institutions are included in the model. But they offer the insight that the results of less comprehensive models are not due to their simplifying assumptions. The stress in the paper of Hammond and Knott is, however, laid on the conclusion that it is impossible to give a clear answer to the question of who really controls an agency; control is exerted by the interplay of institutions. Thus, they reject empirical studies into the power of controlling institutions if such studies are based on correlations between changes in the preferences of the allegedly controlling institutions and agency policy. A general problem in the literature is, of course, that the assumptions on information about the preferences of other agents are as strong as they are for most models of sequential games. One should not overemphasize this problem, though, because spatial approaches to bureaucratic discretion have to be seen as a complement to the literature basing the explanation of bureaucratic discretion on incomplete information. While the earlier articles, which take spatial approaches (this section) or optimal-type-of-control approaches (Section 3) to bureaucratic discretion include but references to the other approach, only Epstein and O’Halloran (1995) integrate both spatial and optimal-type-of-control approaches in one formal model. These authors assume that only interest groups and the agency are completely informed about the state of the world and hence know what policy they prefer most. The legislator (modeled as a unitary actor and thus re-simplified as compared to the newer spatial literature) only knows its most preferred policy as a function of the true state of the world. When an agency proposes a policy change to the legislator, the legislator may accept or reject the proposal, but not amend it. From the legislator’s perfect knowledge of the preferences of the other actors, the rule proposed by the agency, and the reaction of the interest groups (which sound a fire alarm or not), the legislator is able to deduce a piece of information about the true state of the world and react accordingly. The most important result derived from this model is that the legislator can deduce the most information from the reaction of an interest group if the legislators’ most preferred policy lies between those of the agency and the interest group. Less information can be deduced if the interest groups’ most preferred policy is at the center. No information can be deduced if the agency’s most preferred policy is at the center. The reaction of more interest groups increases the information deduced by the legislator only if the interests of the additional groups differ more than, and in the same direction as, the preferences of the legislators differ from the most preferred policy of the agency.
9300
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
573
6. Ought there be a Delegation of Rule-Making Power to Agencies and Bureaucracies? While the literature discussed thus far looks at the positive questions of how bureaucratic discretion in rule production can best be controlled by the legislature (Sections 2 and 3) and which particular institution controls agencies (Sections 4 and 5), other authors ask more fundamentally whether there ought to be delegation of rule making to the bureaucracy from the point of view of the legislature or society. Since answers to the positive questions mentioned above are mostly based on fire-alarms control by the same interest groups which influence the legislation, most authors neglect the problems discussed by the capture theory of regulation. They do not even perceive them as problems, if capture works in favor of the same groups in both legislation and bureaucratic rule making. This is different for the normative question discussed in this section. Imperfect control of agencies can only be used as an argument against having a delegation of rule-making authority from the legislator to the bureaucracy for three reasons: (1) a bureaucrat (agency director) has political preferences differing from those of the legislator; (2) a bureaucrat (agency director) exploits his superior knowledge for his own non-political advantage as described by Niskanen (1971, 1975) (also compare Migué and Belanger, 1974); (3) an agency gets captured by the regulated industry more than the legislator. The first reason vanishes if the legislator can choose the bureaucrat. The second reason either coincides with the third or does not systematically interfere with the content of rules produced by agencies except for the case where some rules allow collusion of an agency with the regulated industry or firm and consequential rent sharing while other rules do not allow this. An example for such a case is discussed by Laffont and Tirole (1990). They conclude that for the case of price regulation it might be reasonable not to delegate to the agency the decision between (average-)cost-plus pricing and marginal-cost pricing with a transfer to the firm(s) covering the fixed costs. The third reason is discussed more extensively. Contradicting Page (1981), Wiley (1986) argues (the argument is reinforced in Wiley, 1988) that there is no general evidence that regulated entities have a disproportionate influence upon regulatory agencies. Accordingly, the decision to delegate regulatory rule making to an agency ought to rest mainly on the agency’s advantages and disadvantages in dealing with specific rule production as compared to the legislator himself. This argument is refuted by Spitzer (1988) who claims with reference to Fiorina (1977, pp. 15-29) that rule making by agencies is more apt to capture by interest groups than rule making by the legislator because the latter uses the agency to shirk responsibility for the costs imposed by regulation, while
574
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
9300
claiming credit for the benefits at the same time (also compare Vaubel, 1991, who applies the same argument to the supranational European legislative institutions; and Moe, 1989). Wiley (1988) points to the many other reasons for a legislator to delegate specific rule making to a bureaucracy in order to reduce the importance of the argument of Spitzer (1988). Referring to better responsiveness of the law to specific local conditions, Mashaw (1985) supports this pro-delegation position. Bawn (1995) compares costs and benefits faced by the legislator from delegation of rule making in a formal model. She shows that the legislator will balance marginal costs incurred as a result of a loss of control through the delegation with marginal benefits reaped as a result of the better fit between agency decisions and specific cases. Her model uses quite specific functional forms but can be generalized easily. Spulber and Besanko (1992) argue that a problem similar to capture may arise from the way the regulator and the regulated firm or industry interact. If the former is able to commit to some environmental quality standard, that is, if the regulator is a Stackelberg leader, then it is sufficient to choose an agency director with political preferences similar to those of the legislator. However, if the regulator is unable to commit to a specific environmental quality standard but is likely to adapt the standard to the firm’s or industry’s activities (levels of output and levels of pollution), that is, if the relationship between regulator and regulated industry or firm is Nash, then an optimizing legislator will choose an agency director with preferences deviating from its own and will enact statutory limits to bureaucratic standard setting. The answer which Spulber and Besanko give to the question as to whether or not statutory limits ought to be imposed on regulatory discretion depends upon whether the relationship between the regulator and the regulated firm or industry is Stackelberg or Nash. In addition, their answer to the question in what direction these limits should be erected also depends on the circumstances of the specific case. As stressed by Arvan (1992), the ambiguities can only be cleared up by empirical studies. The result of Spulber and Besanko (1992) are ambiguous even though they abstract from important aspects influencing the degree of ex ante statutory constraints on regulatory agencies, such as judicial review, problems of incomplete information on the technology (legislators have to know the technology up to one parameter which does not influence complementarity or substitutiveness of pollution abatement and production costs), and incomplete knowledge of the preferences of other political actors (Ross, 1992). If non-delegation is assumed to be the only alternative, the question whether there ought to be a delegation of rule-making power to agencies and bureaucracies is only incompletely answered. In his structural approach to law, Cooter (1996a) (also 1994a, 1996b) argues that, among rule-making
9300
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
575
bodies, agencies should make as few rules as possible because they do not follow social norms to the extent that courts do or at least ought to. Following social norms which evolve from efficient incentive structures (that is, social settings in which spillovers to groups not engaged in the social formation of the norms do not exist nor do evolutionary traps resulting from non-convexities exist) are better than rules issued by law makers such as legislators or regulatory agencies and bureaucracies (that is, constructivist law makers in a Hayekian sense.) Kaplow (1992), too, deals with the role of the courts in the question of whether to delegate rule-making authority to agencies. Yet he does not see rule production by courts as an alternative to rule production by agencies. Rather, he emphasizes that non-delegation is only possible if the legislator includes overly general clauses in statutes. Thus, courts are forced to deduce concrete standards from the general clauses and do so necessarily after the regulated firm or industry has acted, whereas rules set by agencies are promulgated before a regulated firm or industry acts. Regulation by ex post standards is inferior to (bureaucratic) regulation by rules if and only if the costs measured per case of formulating ex ante rules which are readily applicable outweigh the costs which result from less precise standards. Thus, if and only if the law under review is relevant to frequent behavior of a clearly distinguishable type, bureaucratic regulation through rules will be superior to regulation by standards which courts interpret from statutes. With the same problem in mind, Fiorina (1982, 1986) tries to develop a model that shows how legislative decisions to delegate rule interpretation (and thereby making of new, less abstract rules) to the courts or to an agency depend on the substantive preferences of the legislators. Unfortunately, all his results depend on incorrect graphical representations of expected utilities of legislators and, in the 1982 article, also on the assumption of bell-shaped utility functions of legislators (compare also Nichols, 1982). Accordingly, the results are not reported herein. Finally, Rubin and Cohen (1985) mention a third alternative to delegation of rule making to agencies. Law (in particular regulatory statutes) should be made more concrete and enforced by private firms and not by state agencies for several reasons: the legislator (the state) must merely formulate policies on a general, aggregate level and does not have to deal with specific technologies. These technologies can be decided upon by the private law enforcer who signs a contract to pay some (positive or negative) per unit tax on the aggregate level of pollution or safety or other regulatory targets. Then, he may require firms to abide by a standard or to pay a fee sufficient to cover the tax. Hence, which technology is used becomes a decision subject to market forces. The private enforcer has stronger (monetary) incentives than an agency. The rules governing the relationship between the firms and
576
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
9300
the enforcer become more efficient because evolutionary theory of efficient common law is applicable as both sides have long-lasting economic stakes in these rules. The basic idea of the paper is to make existing substantive regulation a property right (entitlement) of the private enforcement agency, and the absence of some regulation a property right of the regulated industry. The property right becomes valuable for the enforcer by paying him some money for avoided (statistical) damages (for example, saved statistical lives) and making the enforcer liable for (statistical) damages. Property rights being thus clearly defined will be reallocated in a Pareto-optimal way by Coasean bargaining.
7. The Rule-Production Process Itself Little has been written in the law and economics literature on how rules are actually produced by agencies and bureaucracies, although taking this approach might substantially clarify the relevance of different arguments with respect to control of bureaucratic rule production by the legislator and its branches. One of the few examples of this approach is the paper contributed by McCubbins and Page (1986). They conclude that decentralized incentives within agencies are too flexible for congress(wo)men who want close control over an agency and, perhaps more importantly, that incentives in an agency are such that agencies do not strive for positive overall results but for countable ‘beans’ (for example, a ban on dioxin instead of the improvement of public health). If research were to take these insights into account, the models constructed to predict the degree and relevance of bureaucratic discretion would gain in explanatory power. In developing concise models of bureaucratic rule production, law and economics scholars might have to take a close look at general descriptions of the rule-making process, such as the book of Kerwin (1992) and case studies like those of Fox (1987) and McGarity (1991). And more descriptive studies of this kind might be needed. Kerwin thoroughly describes the legal background and actual process of rule making at the federal level in the US. Though he does not make a consistent theoretical approach, let alone rely on economic theory, his study is very helpful as a starter and as background knowledge for any scholar not wholly familiar with the US institutions. On the basis of three cases, Fox describes how decision making in the FTC changes with the chairman of the Commission. McGarity studies the effects of having different types of employees working for regulatory agencies. He contrasts the ‘techno-bureaucratic rationality’ for rule making of one group of employees with the ‘comprehensive analytical rationality’ of the other. The former group, professionals who typically have technical or legal
9300
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
577
training, draft rules without paying much attention to economic trade-offs. The latter group, young economists trained in an anti-regulative atmosphere, entered agencies during the 1970s. McGarity uses the term ‘comprehensive’ to stress that the ideal pursued by this second group is an open-ended decision-making process based on the quantitative comparison of all possible routes to a goal, which in turn may be defined as quantitative cost-benefit analysis. Based on a large number of case studies, he discusses different institutional settings within bureaucracies which may promote or hinder the relevance of cost-benefit analysis to bureaucratic rule making. Yet McGarity notes that at first, many of the analysts with thorough microeconomic training went too far in replacing pro-regulation biases of techno-bureaucrats with anti-regulation biases. In his opinion, the different but equally-strong biases of the young economists neither furthered their goals nor overcame traditional and still-dominant engineering and legal orientations to bureaucratic rule making. Were case studies such as those of Fox and McGarity to be turned into models of bureaucratic behavior (adding the preference side to the constraints thus far discussed in the literature), much would be gained in understanding, predicting and evaluating rule production by agencies. An early theoretical approach, which unfortunately did not find many followers, is the study conducted by Breton and Winetrobe (1982). They explain the reason for the lack of economic discussion of what happens inside bureaucracies (both public and private!) is a seeming absence of property rights and competition in bureaucratic interactions. Introducing a theory of trust as an instrument which backs intertemporal contracts, they succeed in establishing an analogy to a pure barter economy. Concentrating on Schumpeterian competition instead of neoclassical price competition, they even construct market-like ‘networks’ within bureaucracies. By combining trust and Schumpeterian competition, they can explain not only many of the alleged inefficiencies in bureaucracies but also the existence of particularly efficient bureaucratic organizations which replace market exchanges to a greater degree than transaction cost arguments are able to justify. Unfortunately, it seems that it would be difficult to apply this innovative theory to rule production by public bureaucracies. Johnson and Libecap (1994) make further progress (based on more-standard, neoclassical assumptions) toward understanding what happens inside bureaucracies but, like Breton and Winetrobe, they do not concentrate on rule making. Notwithstanding these problems with positive approaches, some articles and books deal with normative questions of how rules ought to be made by agencies and on what arguments decisions of agencies should be based. For example, Breyer (1985) emphasizes that it, of course, would be most appropriate to base regulation entirely on simple economic models, but that this is often impossible because resulting policies would lack practicability.
578
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
9300
Still, economic models ought to be used to organize regulators’ analyses and focus their attention on the relevant questions (McGarity, 1991 is clearly supportive of this point). Ribstein and Kobayashi (1996a, 1996b) discuss a different kind of rule production by agencies. These authors look at agencies which only draft rules which a legislator subsequently may enact or amend. In particular, they discuss the effects and the efficiency of the National Conference of Commissioners on Uniform State Laws (NCCUSL), which provides fully-formulated drafts of statutes to state legislatures. They claim that this procedure may have advantages over enacting federal laws but that it is clearly worse than free competition among diverse state laws, which would result in an evolution towards the most efficient laws (for example, other jurisdictions copy provisions out of corporations code of Delaware because many firms choose to incorporate in that jurisdiction). These authors allow that model codes facilitate competition between jurisdictions and overall law making by exploiting economies of scale. Yet they point out that private institutions such as the American Bar Association draft model laws more dispassionately. Agencies like the NCCUSL are claimed to be too easily influenced by interest groups. The reviewer comments that the reference which these authors make to capture theory is relevant only if the agencies have a monopoly of the supply of model laws for if they do not, private institutions are free to provide additional competing drafts.
8. Conclusion Both the positive and the normative literature on the rule production by agencies and bureaucracies is still incomplete, and further work is necessary and seems to be promising. Substantial progress has been made in the positive literature concerning the constraints of regulatory rule production. Yet it is still particularly difficult to derive a complete microeconomic model which describes or predicts the rule-producing behavior of agencies because the political preferences of agencies and bureaucracies have hardly been discussed outside capture theory. Capture theory suffers from weak econometric support and, if taken seriously, would make many of the problems posed in the literature based on positive political theory obsolete. Bureaucratic preferences obviously are not determined by a single individual but are the result of a decision-making process within a bureaucracy. Models of this process would substantially facilitate understanding and prediction of the rule-making behavior of agencies. On the normative side, due to the lack of complete positive theories on bureaucratic decision making constrained by legislative and judicial
9300
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
579
oversight, arguments often do not seem to be too strong because normative conclusions cannot be based on a clear relationship between institutional settings and their welfare effects. Hence, much of this literature must be based on ideological premises concerning the behavior of agencies and bureaucracies.
Acknowledgements I am indebted to two anonymous referees who draw my attention to parts of the literature which escaped my eyes and to Juan Javier Del Granado and Elizabeth Sullivan for editing my paper intensely. All remaining errors are, of course, mine.
Bibliography on Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies (9300) Aberbach, Joel (1990), Keeping a Watchful Eye, Washington, Brookings Institution. Arvan, Lanny (1992), ‘Delegation, Commitment, and the Regulatory Mandate: Comments’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 159-164. Bagnoli, Mark and McKee, Michael (1991), ‘Controlling the Game: Political Sponsors and Bureaus’, 7 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 229-247. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1991), ‘The Short Life and Resurrection of SEC Rule 19c-4', 69 Washington University Law Quarterly, 565 ff. Reprinted in 1992 Securities Law Review 377. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1995), ‘Incorporating State Law Fiduciary Duties Into the Federal Insider Trading Prohibition’, 52 Washington and Lee Law Review, 1189 ff. Reprinted in Corporate Practice Commentator, 38, 1996, 1. Bawn, Kathleen (1994), ‘Bureaucratic Accountability For Regulatory Decisions: Comment on Lupia and McCubbins’, 57 Law and Contemporary Problems, 139-142. Bawn, Kathleen (1995), ‘Political Control versus Expertise: Congressional Choices About Administrative Procedures’, 89 American Political Science Review, 62-73. Bawn, Kathleen (1997), ‘Choosing Strategies to Control the Bureaucracy: Statutory Constraints, Oversight, and the Committee System’, 13 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 101-126. Beck, Nathaniel (1987), ‘Elections and the Fed: Is there a National Monetary Cycle?’, 31 American Journal of Political Science, 194-216. Benson, Bruce L. (1981), ‘Why are Congressional Committees Dominated by “High Demand” Legislators?’, 48 Southern Economic Journal, 68-77. Benson, Bruce L. (1983a), ‘The Economic Theory of Regulation as an Explanation of Policies Toward Bank Mergers and Holding Company Acquisitions’, 28 Antitrust Bulletin, 839-862. Benson, Bruce L. (1983b), ‘High Demand Legislative Committees and Bureaucratic Output’, 11 Public Finance Quarterly, 259-281.
580
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
9300
Benson, Bruce L. (1989), ‘Further Thoughts on Rent Seeking, Bureaucratic Output, and the Price of Complements’, 63 Public Choice, 279-281. Benson, Bruce L (1990), The Enterprise of Law: Justice Without the State, San Francisco, Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy. Benson, Bruce L. (1994), ‘Third Thoughts on Contracting Out’, 11 Journal of Libertarian Studies, 44-78. Benson, Bruce L (1995), ‘Understanding Bureaucratic Behavior: Implications from the Public Choice Literature’, 13 Journal of Public Finance and Public Choice/ Economia delle Scelte Pubbliche, 89-117. Benson, Bruce L. and Greenhut, Melvin L. (1986), ‘Interest Groups, Bureaucrats and Antitrust: An Explanation of the Antitrust Paradox’, in Grieson, Ronald E. (ed.), Antitrust and Regulation, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books, 53-90. Benson, Bruce L. and Mitchell, Jean (1988), ‘Rent Seekers Who Demand Government Production: Bureaucratic Output and the Price of Complements’, 56 Public Choice, 3-16. Benson, Bruce L., Greenhut, Melvin L. and Holcombe, Randall (1987), ‘Interest Groups and the Antitrust Paradox’, 6 Cato Journal, 801-817. Benson, Bruce L., Rasmussen, David W. and Sollars, David L. (1995), ‘Police Bureaucrats, Their Incentives, and the War on Drugs’, 83 Public Choice, 21-45. Bos, P.V.F. (1994), ‘Van Ontvoogding naar Ontgoocheling of van Interstatelijkheid naar Communautaire Dimensie? (From Guardianship to Illusion or From a State to a Community Perspective)’, 69 Nederlands Juristen Blad, 906-911. Breton, Albert and Winetrobe, Ronald (1982), The Logic of Bureaucratic Conduct, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Breyer, Stephen G. (1985), ‘Economists and Economic Regulation’, 47 University of Pittsburgh Law Review, 205-218. Centner, Terence J. (1995), ‘Organically-Produced Food Products: Regulations from the European Union and the United States Set the Stage for Imports’, 7(4) Journal of International Food and Agribusiness Marketing, 41-58. Centner, Terence J. and Lathrop, K.W. (1996), ‘Differentiating Food Products: Organic Labeling Provisions Facilitate Consumer Choice’, 1 Drake Agricultural Law Review, 30-50. Cooter, Robert D. (1994a), ‘Structural Adjudication and the New Law Merchant: A Model of Decentralized Law’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 215-231. Reprinted under the title, ‘The Structural Approach to Decentralizing Law: A Theory of Games and Norms’, in a book edited by Gerard Hertig. Cooter, Robert D. (1994b), ‘Decentralized Law for a Complex Economy’, 23 Southwestern Law Review, Hayek Symposium, 443-451. Cooter, Robert D. (1996a), ‘Decentralized Law for a Complex Economy: The Structural Approach to Adjudicating the New Law Merchant’, 144 University of Pennsylvania Law Review. Cooter, Robert D. (1996b), ‘The Theory of Market Modernization of Law’, 16 International Review of Law and Economics, 141-172. Eckert, Ross D. (1981), ‘The Life Cycle of Regulatory Commissioners’, 24 Journal of Law and Economics, 113-120.
9300
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
581
Eijlander, Ph. (1996), ‘Regulering van de Kwaliteit van Zorginstellingen (Regulating the Quality of Care Organizations)’, in Gestel, R.A.J. van et al. (eds), Markt en Wet, Deventer, W.E.J. Tjeenk Willink, 209-219. Epstein, David and O’Halloran, Sharyn (1995), ‘Theory of Strategic Oversight: Congress, Lobbyists, and the Bureaucracy’, 11 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 227-255. Faith, Roger L., Leavens, Donald R. and Tollison, Roger D. (1982), ‘Antitrust Pork Barrel’, 25 Journal of Law and Economics, 329-342. Ferejohn, John A. (1987), ‘On a Structuring Principle for Administrative Agencies’, in McCubbins, Mathew D. and Sullivan, Terry (eds), Congress: Structure and Policy, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Ferejohn, John A. and Shipan, Charles (1990), ‘Congressional Influence on Bureaucracy’, 6(S) Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 1-20. Fiorina, Morris P. (1977), Congress: Keystone of the Washington Establishment, New Haven, CT, Yale University Press. Fiorina, Morris P. (1982), ‘Legislative Choice of Regulatory Forms: Legal Process or Administrative Process?’, 39 Public Choice, 33-66. Fiorina, Morris P. (1986), ‘Legislator Uncertainty, Legislative Control, and the Delegation of Legislative Power’, 2 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 33-51. Fox, Eleanor M. (1987), ‘Chairman Miller, the Federal Trade Commission, Economics, and Rashomon’, 50(4) Law and Contemporary Problems, 33-55. Frech, H. Edward III and Samprone, Joseph C., Jr (1980), ‘The Welfare Loss of Excess Nonprice Competition: The Case of Property-Liability Insurance Regulation’, 13 Journal of Law and Economics, 429-440. Fuchs, Edward Paul and Anderson, James E. (1987), ‘Institutinalizing Cost-Benefit Analysis in Regulatory Agencies’, in Nagel, Stuart S. (ed.), Research in Public Policy Analysis and Management, Volume 4, Greenwich, CT, JAI Press, 187-211. Gely, Rafael and Spiller, Pablo T. (1990), ‘A Rational Choice Theory of Supreme Court Statutory Decisions with Applications to the State Farm and Grove City Cases’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 263-300. Greenhut, Melvin L. and Benson, Bruce L. (1989), American Antitrust Law in Theory and in Practice, Aldershot, Avebury. Grier, Kevin (1984), The Political Economy of Monetary Policy, PhD dissertation. Hamilton, James T. and Schroeder, Christopher H. (1994), ‘Strategic Regulators and the Choice of Rulemaking Procedures: The Selection of Formal vs. Informal Rules in Regulating Hazardous Waste’, 57 Law and Contemporary Problems, 111-160. Hammond, Thomas H. and Knott, Jack H. (1996), ‘Who Controls the Bureaucracy?: Presidential Power, Congressional Dominance, Legal Constraints and Bureaucratic Autonomy in a Model of Multi-Institutional Policy-Making’, 12 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 119-166. Hatzis, Aristides N. (1998), ‘Mancur Olson, Jr (1932-1998)’, 1 Episteme and Koinonia. Hatzis, Aristides N. (1999), ‘Rent-Seeking and Vested Interests’, in O’Hara, Phillip (ed.), Encyclopedia of Political Economy, London, Routledge. Holmström, Bengt and Milgrom, Paul R. (1991), ‘Multitask Principal-Agent Analysis: Incentive Contracts, Asset Ownership, and Job Design’, 7 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 24-52.
582
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
9300
Hopenhayn, Hugo and Lohmann, Susanne (1996), ‘Fire Alarm Signals and the Political Oversight of Regulatory Agencies’, 12 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 196-213. Horn, Murray J. (1995), The Political Economy of Public Administration - Institutional Choice in the Public Sector, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Horn, Murray J. and Shepsle, Kenneth A. (1989), ‘Commentary: Administrative Process and Organizational Form as Legislative Responses to Agency Costs’, 75 Virginia Law Review, 499-508. Johnson, Ronald N. and Libecap, Gary D. (1994), The Federal Civil Service System and the Problem of Bureaucracy, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Kaplow, Louis (1992), ‘Rules Versus Standards: An Economic Analysis’, 42 Duke Law Journal, 557-629. Kaplow, Louis (1995), ‘A Model of the Optimal Complexity of Legal Rules’, 11 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 150-163. Katzmann, Robert A. (1980), Regulatory Bureaucracy: The Federal Trade Commission and Antitrust Policy, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Kerwin, Cornelius (1992), Rulemaking: How Government Agencies Write Law and Make Policy, Washington, DC, CQ Press. Kobayashi, Bruce H. and Ribstein, Larry E. (1996), ‘Evolution and Spontaneous Uniformity: Evidence from the Evolution of the Limited Liability Company’, 34 Economic Inquiry. Laffont, Jean-Jacques and Tirole, Jean (1990), ‘The Politics of Government Decision Making: Regulatory Institutions’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 1-31. Landy, Marc K., Roberts, Mark J. and Thomas, Stephen R. (1990), The Environmental Protection Agency: Asking the Wrong Questions, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 309 p. Lemieux, Vincent (1991), Les Relations de Pouvoir dans les Lois - Comparaison entre les Gouvernements du Québec de 1944 à 1985 (Power Relations in Laws - Comparison Between Quebec Governments from 1944 to 1985), Sainte-Foy, Presses de l’Université Laval. Levine, Michael E. (1992), ‘Organizational Design and Political Control of Administrative Agencies: Comment’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 119-125. Lewis, Tracy and Poitevin, Michel (1997), ‘Disclosure of Information in Regulatory Proceedings’, 13 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 50-73. Lindsay, Cotton M. (1976), ‘A Theory of Government Enterprise’, 84 Journal of Political Economy, 1061-1077. Lupia, Arthur and McCubbins, Mathew D. (1994a), ‘Learning from Oversight: Fire Alarms and Police Patrols Reconstructed’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 96-125. Lupia, Arthur and McCubbins, Mathew D. (1994b), ‘Designing Bureaucratic Accountability’, 57 Law and Contemporary Problems, 91-126. Macey, Jonathan R. (1992), ‘Organizational Design and Political Control of Administrative Agencies’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 93-110. MacKay, Robert J., Miller, James C., III and Yandle, Bruce (1987a), ‘Public Choice and Regulation: An Overview’, in MacKay, Robert J., Miller, James C., III and Yandle, Bruce
9300
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
583
(eds), Public Choice and Regulation: A View from Inside the Federal Trade Commission, Stanford, Hoover Institute Press, Stanford University, 3-12. MacKay, Robert J., Miller, James C., III and Yandle, Bruce (eds) (1987b), Public Choice and Regulation: A View from Inside the Federal Trade Commission, Stanford, Hoover Institute Press, Stanford University, 363 p. Magat, Wesley A., Krupnick, A. and Harrington, W. (1986), Rules in the Making: A Statistical Analysis of Regulatory Agency Behavior, Washington, Resources for the Future. Mashaw, Jerry L. (1985), ‘Prodelegation: Why Administrators Should Make Political Decisions’, 1 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 81-100. McCubbins, Mathew D. and Page, Talbot (1986), ‘The Congressional Foundations of Agency Performance’, 51 Public Choice, 173-190. McCubbins, Mathew D. and Page, Talbot (1987), ‘A Theory of Congressional Delegation’, in McCubbins, Mathew D. and Sullivan, Terry (eds), Congress: Structure and Policy, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. McCubbins, Mathew D. and Schwartz, T. (1984), ‘Congressional Oversight Overlooked: Policy Patrols vs. Fire Alarms’, 28 American Journal of Political Science, 165-179. McCubbins, Mathew D., Noll, Roger G. and Weingast, Barry R. (1987), ‘Administrative Procedures as Instruments of Political Control’, 3 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 243-277. McCubbins, Mathew D., Noll, Roger G. and Weingast, Barry R. (1989), ‘Structure and Process, Politics and Policy: Administrative Arrangements and the Political Control of Agencies’, 75 Virginia Law Review, 431-482. McGarity, Thomas O. (1991), Reinventing Rationality - The Role of Regulatory Analysis in the Federal Bureaucracy, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Migué, Jean-Luc and Belanger, Gerard (1974), ‘Towards a General Theory of Managerial Discretion’, 17 Public Choice, 27-43. Miller, James C., III (1989), The Economist as Reformer: Revamping the FTC, 1981, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 110 p. Mitnick, Barry M. (1975), ‘The Theory of Agency: The Political Paradox and Regulatory Behaviour’, 24 Public Choice, 27-47. Mitnick, Barry M. (1980), Political-Economy of Regulation, New York, Columbia University Press. Moe, Terry M. (1985), ‘Control and Feedback in Economic Regulation: The Case of the NLRB’, 79 American Political Science Review, 1094-1117. Moe, Terry M. (1987), ‘An Assessment of the Positive Theory of Congressional Dominance’, 12 Legislative Studies Quarterly, 475-520. Moe, Terry M. (1989), ‘The Politics of Bureaucratic Structure’, in Chubb, John and Peterson, Paul (eds), Can the Government Govern?, Washington, Brookings Institution. Muris, Timothy J. (1986), ‘Regulatory Policymaking at the Federal Trade Commission: The Extent of Congressional Control’, 94 Journal of Political Economy, 884-889. Nichols, Albert L. (1982), ‘Legislative Choice of Regulatory Forms. A Comment on Fiorina’, 39 Public Choice, 67-71. Niskanen, William A. (1971), Bureaucracy and Representive Government, Chicago, Aldine-Atherton.
584
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
9300
Niskanen, William A. (1975), ‘Bureaucracts and Politicians’, 18 Journal of Law and Economics, 617-643. Noll, R. (1971), Reforming Regulation: An Evaluation of the Ash Council Proposals, Washington, Brookings Institution. Ogul, Morris S. and Rockmann, Bert A. (1990), ‘Overseeing Oversight: New Departures and an Old Problem’, 15 Legislative Studies Quarterly, 5-24. Ogus, Anthony I. (1995), ‘Economics and Law Reform: Thirty years of Law Commission Endeavor’, 11 Law Quarterly Review, 407-420. Olson, Mary (1995), ‘Regulatory Agency Discretion among Competing Industries: Inside the FDA’, 11 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 379-408. Olson, Mary (1996), ‘Substitution in Regulatory Agencies: FDA Enforcement Alternatives’, 12 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 376-407. Page, William H. (1981), ‘Antitrust, Federalism, and the Regulatory Process: A Reconstruction and Critique of the State Action Exemption After Midcal Aluminium’, 61 Boston University Law Review, 1099-1138. Parisi, Francesco (1995), ‘Public Choice Theory and International Institutions: One More Comment on Richard Falk’, 1 International Legal Theory, 45-48. Parisi, Francesco (1997), The Market of Votes: Coasian Bargaining in an Arrovian Setting, George Mason University Law and Economics Working Paper Series, No. 97-05. Parisi, Francesco (1998a), A Property-Right Theory of Democratic Voting, George Mason University Law and Economics Working Paper Series, #98-04. Parisi, Francesco (1998b), ‘The Market for Votes: Coasian Bargaining in an Arrovian Setting’, 6 George Mason Law Review, 745-766. Posner, Richard A. (1972), ‘The Behavior of Administrative Agencies’, 1 Journal of Legal Studies, 305-347. Provopoulos, George and Zambaras, Athanassios (1991), ‘Testing for Causality Between Government Spending and Taxation’, 68 Public Choice, 277-282. Rasmussen, David W. and Benson, Bruce L. (eds) (1994), The Economic Anatomy of a Drug War: Criminal Justice in the Commons, Lanham, MD, Rowman and Littlefield.. Ribstein, Larry E. and Kobayashi, Bruce H. (1996a), ‘An Economic Analysis of Uniform State Laws’, 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 131-199. Ribstein, Larry E. and Kobayashi, Bruce H. (1996b), ‘Uniform Laws, Model Laws and Limited Liability Companies’, 66 University of Colorado Law Review, 947-999. Robinson, Glen O. (1989), ‘Commentary: Political Uses of Structure and Process’, 75 Virginia Law Review, 483-498. Rose, Jonathan (1985), ‘Executive Oversight of Rulemaking in Arizona: The Govenor’s Regulatory Review Counsel - the First Three Years’, Arizona State Law Journal, 425-491. Rose, Jonathan (1985), ‘Nonlawyer Practice before Federal Administrative Agencies Should be Encouraged’, 37 Administrative Law Review, 363-373. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1978), Corruption, New York, Academic Press. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1979), Political Corruption, New York, Academic Press. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1990), ‘Comment (on Ferejohn and Shipan’s “Congressional Influence (on Bureaucracy)”’, 6(S) Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 21-27.
9300
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
585
Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1995), Controlling Environmental Policy, New Haven and London, Yale University Press. Ross, Stephen F. (1992), ‘Delegation, Commitment, and the Regulatory Mandate: Comment’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 155-158. Rubin, Paul H. and Cohen, Mark A. (1985), ‘Private Enforcement of Public Policy’, 3(1) Yale Journal on Regulation, 167-193. Rugge, Dale R. (1987), ‘Judicial Review of Environmental Protection Agency Rule Promulgation Clean Air Act State Implementation Plan Requirement’, 27 Natural Resources Journal, 723-737. Shepsle, Kenneth A. (1992), ‘Organizational Design and Political Control of Administrative Agencies: A Comment: Bureaucratic Drift, Coalition Drift, and Time Consistency’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 111-118. Simon, Herbert A., Smith, D.W. and Thompson, Victor A. (1950/1991), Public Administration, (2nd edn), New York, Alfred A. Knopf. Smith, Janet Kiholm (1982a), ‘Production of Licensing Legislation: An Economic Analysis of Interstate Differences’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 117-137. Smith, Janet Kiholm (1982b), ‘An Analysis of State Regulations Governing Liquor Store Licensees’, 25 Journal of Law and Economics, 301-320. Spiller, Pablo T. and Tiller, Emerson H. (1997), ‘Decision Costs and the Strategic Design of Administrative Process and Judicial Review’, 16 Journal of Legal Studies, 347-370. Spitzer, Matthew L. (1988), ‘Antitrust Federalism and Rational Choice Political Economy: A Critique of Capture Theory’, 61 Southern California Law Review, 1293-1326. Spitzer, Matthew L. (1990), ‘Extensions of Ferejohn and Shipan’s Model of Administrative Agency Behavior’, 6(S) Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 29-43. Spulber, Daniel F. and Besanko, David A. (1992), ‘Delegation, Commitment, and the Regulatory Mandate’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 126-154. Stalon, Charles G. (1986), ‘Analysis and Synthesis in Quasi-Judicial Multimember Regulatory Agencies’, in Saltzman, Sidney and Schuler, Richard E. (eds), The Future of Electrical Energy: A Regional Perspective, New York, Greenwood Press, 330-339. Steunenberg, Bernard (1992), ‘Congress, Bureaucracy, and Regulatory Policy Making’, 8 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 673-694. Van Damme, E.E.C. (1996), ‘Marktwerking en Herregulering (Markets and Re-regulation)’, in Gestel, R.A.J. van et al. (eds), Markt en Wet, Deventer, W.E.J. Tjeenk Willink, 19-43. Vaubel, Roland (1991), ‘A Public Choice View of International Organizations’, in Vaubel, Roland and Willet, Thomas D. (eds), The Political Economy of International Organizations, Boulder, CO, Westview Press, 27-45. Waline, M. (1965), ‘Quelques Facteurs Sociologiques de l’Evolution Actuelle du Droit (Some Sociologic Factors of Actual Evolution of Law)’, in X (ed.), Mélanges Offerts à René Savatier. Weingast, Barry R. (1981), ‘Regulation, Reregulation, and Deregulation: The Political Foundations of Agency Clientele Relationships’, 44 Law and Contemporary Problems, 147-177.
586
Production of Legal Rules by Agencies and Bureaucracies
9300
Weingast, Barry R. (1984), ‘The Congressional-Bureaucratic System: A Principal Agent Perspective (With Applications to the SEC)’, 44 Public Choice, 147-191. Weingast, Barry R. and Moran, Mark J. (1983), ‘Bureaucratic Discretion or Congressional Control? Regulatory Policymaking by the Federal Trade Commission’, 91 Journal of Political Economy, 765-800. Reprinted in Mackay, Robert J., Miller, James C., III and Yandle, Bruce (eds) (1987), Public Choice and Regulation: A View form Inside the Federal Trade Commission, Stanford, Hoover Institution Press, 30-62. Weingast, Barry R. and Moran, Mark J. (1986), ‘Congress and Regulatory Agency Choice: Reply’, 94 Journal of Political Economy, 890-894. Wiley, John Shepard, Jr (1986), ‘A Capture Theory of Antitrust Federalism’, 99 Harvard Law Review, 713-789. Wiley, John Shepard, Jr (1988), ‘A Capture Theory of Antitrust Federalism: Reply to Professors Page and Spitzer’, 61 Southern California Law Review, 1327-1341.
Other References Rubin, Paul H. (1977), ‘Why is the Common Law Efficient’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 51-63. Priest, George L (1977), ‘The Common Law Process and the Selection of Efficient Rules’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 65-82.
9400 SELF-REGULATION Anthony Ogus University of Manchester © Copyright 1999 Anthony Ogus
Abstract Self-regulation encompasses a wide range of arrangements, from private ordering without resort to legal rules to state-enforced systems of delegated rules. Transaction cost analysis has been used to explain how private ordering emerges, and principal-agency theory to indicate the advantages, but also the difficulties, of state delegation. While public choice theory, as supported by empirical studies, suggests that rent-seeking is inherent in delegated self-regulatory regimes, institutional structures capable of controlling this phenomenon can be envisaged. JEL classification: D45, D71, K20 Keywords: Self-Regulation, Private Ordering, Decentralized Law-Making, Regulatory Competition
1. Introduction Self-regulation, understood narrowly as law formulated by private agencies to govern professional and trading activities, has been rigorously criticised by lawyers and economists alike. From a legal perspective, it is seen as an example of modern ‘corporatism’, the acquisition of power by groups which are not accountable to the body politic through the conventional constitutional channels (Schmitter, 1985). The capacity of such groups to make rules governing the activities of members of an association or profession may itself constitute an abuse if they lack democratic legitimacy (Page, 1986). The potential for abuse may become intolerable if, and to the extent that, the rules affect third parties (Cane, 1987). Further, if the group’s functions cover policy formulation, interpretation of the rules, adjudication and enforcement (including the imposition of sanctions) as well as rule making, this conflicts with basic notions of separation of powers (Harden and Lewis, 1986). For their part, economists have traditionally focused on how self-regulatory powers may be exercised to impede competition on the supply side of the market. Barriers to entry may be created, thereby raising prices and conferring rents on incumbent practitioners; standards governing practice may be devised more to confer utility on suppliers than to meet consumer preferences (Shaked 587
588
Self-Regulation
9400
and Sutton, 1981a). And the prospect of gaining such advantages may lure groups into spending resources to persuade legislatures to grant them self-regulatory powers - a social deadweight loss (Tullock, 1967). While criticisms such as these may be appropriate in some circumstances, they are based on a very incomplete picture of self-regulation. The modern law and economics literature has been concerned to explore a much broader conception of the phenomenon and in so doing to identify institutional arrangements which may escape, or meet, the traditional criticisms and which thereby may be conducive to allocatively efficient outcomes. A survey of this literature must necessarily begin with an investigation of the nature of self-regulation.
2. The Nature of Self-Regulation In its most literal sense, and as it used in psychology (Carver and Scheier, 1981), self-regulation means acting according to one’s own volition, and not as a response to an external constraint. Thus interpreted, the concept would cover an infinite number of self-imposed behavioural standards, including those determined internally by the management of a firm. Although the latter may have no legal significance, they are not irrelevant to discussions of regulatory systems (Bardach and Kagan, 1982; Cheit, 1990). The internal standards are designed to ensure quality of the kind which will meet consumer preferences. On the assumptions of competition between suppliers, adequate information possessed by consumers and an absence of externalities, there is no need to render the standards legally enforceable. When used in a legal context, the ‘self’ in ‘self-regulation’ is not used in the literal sense. Rather it connotes some degree of collective constraint, other than that directly emanating from government, to engender outcomes which would not be reached by individual market behaviour alone (Black, 1996). It is also normally taken to imply ‘a fairly well established and generally recognised set of rules, whether customary or reduced to writing, in accordance with which the activity is regulated’ (Cane, 1987). There is, nevertheless, a multitude of institutional arrangements which fall somewhere between government regulation on the one hand and individual, unconstrained behaviour on the other and which can therefore be treated as self-regulation (Rees, 1988; Cheit, 1990). The possibilities can be considered on two spectra depicting, respectively, degrees of autonomy from government and legal force (Page, 1986; Baggott, 1989). The first ranges from, at one extreme, rules private to firms, groups or organizations to, at the other, those approved by a government minister or some independent public authority; in between, representatives of the public interest may participate in, but not
9400
Self-Regulation
589
conclusively determine, the decision making. The second encompasses varying degrees of legal force. The rules may be: formally binding, non-compliance leading to public law or private law sanctions; codes of practice which presumptively apply unless an alleged offender can show that some alternative conduct was capable of satisfactorily meeting the regulatory goals; norms the breach of which leads to non-legal sanctions, such as ostracism; or standards compliance with which is purely voluntary.
3. Spontaneous Private Legal Ordering In its most complete sense, and thus at one end of the spectra described above, self-regulation involves a system of private ordering, without any form of state intervention; that is, without any imposition of rules by those with political power. This phenomenon is covered by other chapters (notably Spontaneous Emergence of Law, 9500, and Non-Legal Sanctions, 0780) and the treatment here is consequently brief - for a valuable overview of the literature, see Klein (1997). Economic explanations of how informal systems emerge are epitomized by studies of primitive societies (Benson, 1988). The basis is reciprocity: individuals recognise the benefits they will derive from behaving in accordance with others’ expectations. Such reciprocity may be reflected in individual agreements but, as standards of behaviour, will spread to other members of a group as property rights when the benefits of doing so exceed the costs of defining those rights. While originally disputes may be resolved by force, individuals will normally find non-violent methods (for example, arbitration or mediation) to be cheaper; and ostracism from the group will generally be an adequate sanction for non-compliance. Analysis of this kind has been used to explain other historical self-ordering arrangements, including: the Maghribi Traders (Greif, 1989); the Law Merchant (Benson, 1989; Milgrom, North and Weingast, 1990); medieval Iceland (Friedman, 1979); and the mining camps in the American West (Anderson and Hill, 1979; Umbeck, 1981). In more modern contexts, equivalent systems can emerge within groups to reduce the costs of drafting commitments and of establishing and activating enforcement systems (Charny, 1990). The expectation is that such cost savings will be significant where the group is small enough for informal control - generally requiring continuing face-to-face interaction - but where also power is broadly dispersed (Ellickson, 1993). Illustrative studies are those on diamond traders (Bernstein, 1992) and neighbour disputes (Ellickson 1991). Within a broader social setting decentralized law making encounters the problem that some individuals will tend to free-ride on the enforcement of others. This may be only partly solved by the internalization of norms, and thus
590
Self-Regulation
9400
public institutions (courts) are necessary to identify situations requiring stateimposed incentives (Cooter, 1996). Nevertheless, informal systems also occur in international trading environments (Benson, 1992; see also Schanze, 1988). Here there is an increased need to accommodate the system to inter-group interaction. The co-existence of groups creates incentives for each to compete to attract or hold members and a form of mutual insurance emerges to prevent individuals taking advantage of other individuals and then escaping to another group (Benson, 1993). A not insignificant part of the literature addresses the normative issue of choice between public and private ordering. Some (for example, Friedman, 1973; Rothbard, 1973; Benson, 1990) reveal a hostility to almost all instances of state-imposed law, arguing from public choice theory that it is predominantly motivated by pressure for wealth transfers and undermines the incentives of the reciprocity-based system of property rights. But, apart from the important reminder that the consequences of government failure may be more severe than market failure, it is not clear that these contributions add much to the debate which has taken place within the mainstream of law and economics (Katz, 1996), and which has its origin in the Coase Theorem (Coase, 1960). The ability of consensual bargaining to achieve efficient outcomes is a function of transactions costs, thus suggesting that the normative question of when private ordering should prevail should be determined by an analysis of how those costs impact on any given situation. Self-regulation may, therefore, be an appropriate solution where bargaining, at low cost, can occur between risk-creators and those affected; occupational health and safety provides a familiar example (Rees, 1988; Ogus, 1995; though for reservations, see Baldwin, 1987).
4. Self-Regulation as Delegation of State Law-Making Powers In the previous section, we examined systems of private ordering which emerge independently of state intervention. As a legal phenomenon, self-regulation is more usually analysed as a deliberate delegation of the state’s law-making powers to an agency, the membership of which wholly or mainly comprises representatives of the firms or individuals whose activities are being regulated. Public interest arguments for such delegation can be derived from principal-agent theory (Tuohy and Wolfson, 1978). Once the principal (normally, the legislature) has decided that an activity ought to be regulated on grounds of market failure, for example externalities or information asymmetries, the question arises what form of regulation is appropriate. That can be assessed by reference to such variables as the costs of information upon which the rule-making decisions are to be based and those of monitoring compliance and enforcing the rules. The principal may rationally conclude that
9400
Self-Regulation
591
these costs would be minimised if the tasks of rule-formulation, monitoring, adjudication and enforcement were to be conferred on a self-regulatory agency (hereafter SRA) (Trebilcock, 1983; Cane, 1987). Since SRAs typically command a greater degree of expertise and technical knowledge of practices and innovatory possibilities within the relevant area than the principal, information costs for the formulation and interpretation of standards are lower. Secondly, for the same reasons, monitoring and enforcement costs are also reduced, as are the costs to the regulatees of dealing with regulators, given that such interaction is likely to be fostered by mutual trust. This aspect is particularly important where, as with advertising, it is difficult to define the desired behaviour with precision and an adversarial relationship between regulator and regulatee is likely to be counterproductive (Baggott and Harrison, 1986). In addition, to the extent that the processes of, and rules issued by, SRAs are less formalized than those of public regulatory regimes, there are likely to be savings in the costs (including those attributable to delay) of amending rules. Finally, the administrative costs of the regime are normally internalized in the trade or activity which is subject to regulation; in the case of independent, public agencies, they are typically borne by taxpayers. Delegation to SRAs should thus reduce the principal’s costs of regulation; to what extent will they confer benefits of the kind which regulation is supposed to foster? Take a situation in which the quality of products or services cannot be observed by consumers prior to purchase. Although individual firms will be motivated to provide signals of quality (for example, product warranties), this may be very costly or - where the characteristics of quality are not easily definable - not feasible. It then becomes in the joint interest of the suppliers, as represented by the SRA, to maintain quality by self-regulation (Gehrig and Jost, 1995). And since, in such circumstances, attempts by consumers themselves to measure quality will also be costly and/or futile, such regulation will confer a benefit on them by obviating the need for measurement (Barzel, 1982). Once such a regime of self-regulation has been established, individual suppliers have an incentive to supply (at lower cost) lower quality, but since the reputation of other firms will be affected by defaulters the SRA will be motivated to enforce the standards. On the basis of this analysis, it has been predicted that viable self-regulatory regimes will emerge where monitoring costs for the SRA are low, the number of local markets is small, and customers are relatively mobile as between suppliers (Gehring and Jost, 1995). At the same time, there is every reason to expect that SRAs will use their law-making power to benefit their members in ways which are not consistent with the public interest (Horowitz, 1980). As has been formally demonstrated (Shaked and Sutton, 1981a), the self-regulatory rules may create barriers to entry and thus confer significant rents on incumbent practitioners. The latter
592
Self-Regulation
9400
include non-financial benefits, for example, a quiet life, as well as monetary income (Lees, 1966). Most obviously rent may be obtained where the SRA has the power to issue licences and therefore to determine the qualifications of those who engage in the activity (Moore, 1961). But there are also a variety of other ways in which ‘quality’ standards may be used to promote the interests of the regulatees, rather than those of the public. For example, most professional associations have, at some time or another, prohibited their members from advertising, ostensibly on the ground that ‘touting’ for business is incompatible with the ethical nature of professional practice (OECD, 1985). As we have seen, such bans can eliminate wasteful consumer searches on elusive quality characteristics (Barzel, 1982), but they can also inhibit comparative price shopping, thus generating monopoly rents for practitioners (Trebilcock, 1982). Secondly, restrictions can be imposed on the legal form used by professional firms (for example, insisting on partnerships and prohibiting corporations) or on the participation of professionals from other disciplines in the firm (OECD, 1985). Both forms of control can add to client costs insofar as they inhibit productive efficiency of the firm (Evans, 1980) and, in some cases, make it necessary for consumers to deal with two or more firms, rather than one (Quinn, 1982). The quality imposed by SRAs may exceed that which presumptively will meet consumers’ preferences and not be justified by externalities; and the excessive cost will be borne by consumers (Trebilcock, 1983). Other welfare losses can arise from the tendency of SRAs to discourage diversity and experimentation (Ostry, 1978; White, 1979). In the light of public choice theory, rent-seeking explanations of regulation are, of course, commonplace (Tollison, 1982). If rule-making remains with the legislature or an independent agency, interest groups representing the regulatees have the task of exerting influence on those institutions and diverting them away from public interest goals or other, competing private interest claims. Of course, delegation of the regulatory powers to SRAs relieves the groups of this task and the relative absence of accountability and external constraints maximizes the possibilities of rent-seeking - ‘with self-regulation, regulatory capture is there from the outset’ (Kay, 1988). Governments are motivated to maintain or extend the use of self-regulation because, while they may derive political benefits from measures which appear to benefit consumers and others, the costs are not revealed in any public accounts (Trebilcock, 1983). And it is difficult for the cost-bearers both to determine the amount of wealth transfers and to coordinate their activities in opposing them (Van den Bergh and Faure, 1991). Although, as we shall see in the next section, there is considerable empirical evidence to support this theory of self-regulation, it has not gone unchallenged. Dingwall and Fenn argue that it cannot explain the persistence and stability of entry restriction; other forces must be at work to prevent pressure from
9400
Self-Regulation
593
potential entrants building up to an intolerable level (Dingwall and Fenn, 1987). Such forces may lead to the emergence of illegal (or ‘informal’) markets (De Soto, 1989), or of reasonably close, but unregulated, substitutes (Fisher, 1997). Indeed, it may be an inherent feature of regulation that it cannot control every margin of adjustable behaviour, and thus rents are dissipated as firms seek to trade on these uncontrollable margins (Cheung, 1974). Weingast also finds it hard to reconcile the theory with the fact that many of the self-imposed restrictions can dissipate rents or seem designed to increase a perception of quality maintenance at the expense of greater rents (Weingast, 1980). Drawing on Arrow’s public interest analysis (Arrow, 1963), he sees self-regulation as performing a symbolic informational function: as a consequence of the uncertainties both as to quality in the unregulated market and to the effects of regulation there is a tendency for SRAs to adopt policies which improve observable features of the activity and give the appearance of service uniformity.
5. Sector-Specific Studies Some studies of self-regulatory systems support the notion of spontaneous, private ordering described above. For example, there are incentives for banks voluntarily to become members of private protective and certifying agencies (Gorton and Mullineaux, 1987; Gehring and Jost, 1995), and for voluntary ‘best practice’ auditing and other standards to be diffused among different SRAs (Belcher, 1996). In the advertising industry, self-regulation has emerged as the suppliers have perceived the benefit to be obtained from acquiring public creditability for their products and from creating an image of professional responsibility (Baggott and Harrison, 1986). But these researchers also highlight the problem of enforcement: SRAs begin to adopt an aggressive stance only where there was perceived to be a threat of intervention by public agencies. The same phenomenon has been observed with the self-regulation of commodity exchanges (Pirrong, 1995; see also Page, 1987; Fishman, 1993; Black, 1997). Investigations of occupational health and safety systems, as they have increasingly shifted towards decentralised standard-setting by local arrangements between employers and employees, suggest this has been effective when the systems can be related to nationally established standards and are supported by knowledge that the arrangements will be enforced (Dawson et al., 1988). But there has been a decline in protection against risks created by small or non-unionised firms (Baldwin, 1987; Smith and Tombs, 1995). Beginning with the pioneering work of Friedman and Kuznets (1945), published at the end of the Second World War, most attention has been given to regimes governing the professions (for a valuable survey of studies relating
594
Self-Regulation
9400
to the medical professions, see Gravelle, 1985). Typically the regimes involve SRAs having the power to issue licences and therefore the ability to restrict entry (see Kessel, 1970, for a study on how control by the SRA was used for the benefit of members of the profession). The prediction that this will enable incumbent practitioners to earn rents is difficult to substantiate because it is necessary to disentangle supra-competitive profits from higher earnings which represent legitimate compensation for higher educational costs and greater responsibilities. Nevertheless when such variables are controlled for, researchers have found strong evidence of rents being earned by eyeglass suppliers (Benham and Benham, 1975), dry cleaners (Plott, 1965), lawyers (Holen, 1965; Lees, 1966; Domberger and Sherr, 1989; Curran, 1993) and dentists (Holen, 1965; Shepard, 1978; Wilson, 1987). Studies on other medical professions (Holen, 1965; White, 1979; Wilson, 1987; Curran, 1993) and architects (Button and Fleming, 1992) are less conclusive. In a general study, Maurizi found that there was a significant correlation between licensing regimes and monetary returns for about half of the systems examined (Maurizi, 1974). Exacerbation of shortages in the supply of practitioners (Hogan, 1979), maldistribution of such supply (Holen, 1965; Boulier, 1980; Pashigian, 1980) and poorer quality of service (Caroll and Gaston, 1979) are other welfare effects found to have resulted from licensing regimes. Ongoing professional standards, established by SRAs, have also enabled them to protect anti-competitive practices: for example, fee regulation and restrictions on advertising which limit price competition (Benham, 1972; Office of Fair Trading, 1982; Domberger and Sherr, 1989; Van den Bergh and Faure, 1991); and ‘professional ethics’ which serve the wellbeing of practitioners rather than their clients and mask prohibitions on cost-saving innovation (Gravelle, 1985; Trautwein and Rönnau, 1993).
6. Competitive Self-Regulation The above discussion suggests that, on certain key assumptions, systems of spontaneous private legal ordering can generate efficient outcomes but that state-delegated systems of self-regulation can lead to adverse welfare effects. The crucial factor which distinguishes the two systems is that the act of state delegation normally involves conferring on the SRA a monopoly power to legally constrain supply in the relevant market. We have seen (Baggott and Harrison, 1986; Pirrong, 1995) that the threat of state intervention may, to some extent, mitigate the harmful effects of monopolization. A useful analogy may here be drawn with the theory of contestable markets which indicates that, under certain conditions, efficient pricing and production can be forced upon a monopolistic supplier by the threat
9400
Self-Regulation
595
of competition, just as much as by actual competition (Baumol, Panzar and Willig, 1982). But the necessary conditions - notably the ability of the entrant costlessly to leave the market - are rarely met in practice (Waterson, 1988). Similarly, on cost grounds, SRAs may not regard the threat of state intervention as credible. An alternative solution to the problem presents itself: if the principal objection to SRAs is that they are able to exploit their monopolistic control of supply so as to enable practitioners to earn rents, then why not force SRAs to compete with one another, so that the rents will be eliminated (Kay and Vickers, 1990; Ogus, 1995)? Such competition would obviously prevent SRAs creating barriers to entry. But it should also constrain SRAs to formulate standards which meet consumer preferences at lowest cost since, assuming consumers have adequate information to make appropriate comparisons, they will choose the combination of price and self-regulatory standards which most closely corresponds to those preferences. Competition of this kind is inherent in systems of private ordering: suppliers compete to attract consumers by the quality (as well as the price) of their products and services. Quality is, to some extent at least, a consequence of standards and other forms of control imposed internally by the management of a firm. The standards may reflect public regulatory requirements but more often they are voluntary, representing the firm’s response to assumed consumer demand and, in some cases, incorporating industry-wide practices. To signal to consumers the relationship between standards and quality, some form of voluntary accreditation or certification can be used (Bardach and Kagan, 1982). Suppliers who aim at different quality standards, and have difficulty in communicating that fact to consumers, will have an incentive to establish a rival certification system. Competing self-regulatory regimes may thus emerge. Thus envisaged, competitive self-regulation is, in essence, no different from competition between national public regulatory regimes (Bratton et al., 1997). If there is mutual recognition of national standards and freedom of trade, consumers can choose between the different quality standards imposed by the national systems in accordance with their own preferences. Provided that they are informed as to the relevant national compliance certificate, competition between national regulatory regimes should induce standard-setters to meet those preferences (Kay and Vickers, 1990). The policy implication of this analysis is that where the public interest arguments for the state delegating its regulatory powers are strong (see above), it should not grant monopoly power but rather enable two or more SRAs within a given supplier group to formulate alternative regimes (Ogus, 1995; for the effects of competition between professionals and para-professionals, see Shaked and Sutton, 1981b). Although there is a risk of cartelization, most industries are sufficiently heterogeneous for this purpose. An alternative is to retain the
596
Self-Regulation
9400
monopoly but force different SRAs to compete ex ante to acquire the right to control supply by self-regulation. Competing applicants would be required to include their self-regulatory rules as part of the bid; and, as with other public franchises (Demsetz, 1968), the competition should force applicants to offer regimes consistent with the public interest. There are, nevertheless, potential problems with these solutions. Consumers - more precisely marginal consumers (Schwartz and Wilde, 1979) - must be able to attribute general quality characteristics to certificates generated by the competing self-regulatory regimes; otherwise there will be a ‘race to the bottom’ (Akerlof, 1970). Secondly, there must be no significant externalities arising from their purchasing behaviour. The importance of information asymmetries and externalities and, in relation to the franchising solution, the need to scrutinize competing bids suggest that in many areas some residual form of state intervention will be optimal. It remains to consider this issue more generally.
7. Mixed Systems As was indicated in the discussion of the nature of self-regulation, there is a wide range of possible institutional arrangements between public regulation on the one hand and pure private ordering on the other. In an effort to realize many of the benefits of self-regulation but controlling the costs which result from SRA rent-seeking, some jurisdictions have adopted what has been referred to as ‘coregulation’ (Grabosky and Braithwaite, 1986): SRAs regulate with some oversight or ratification by government, or officials representing the public interest (see for example Page, 1987). The main problem is that of informational asymmetry between the public agency and the SRA. The latter can withhold vital information unless there is confidence that it will be used to reach regulatory solutions which favour its members (Quirk, 1981). Typically, also, the SRA retains monopolistic control of enforcement. In an important contribution to the literature, Ayres and Braithwaite argue, instead, for ‘enforced self-regulation’ (Ayres and Braithwaite, 1992; see also Braithwaite, 1982). Under this model, a public agency negotiates with individual firms regulations that are particularized to each firm, with the threat of an imposition of less tailored standards if it fails to cooperate. While the firm may thus formulate the rules, they are enforced by the public agency. The advantages are clear: as with other privately ordered systems, the rules are tailored to match the firm’s circumstances and are less costly to adapt; there are incentives to identify least-cost solutions, which should encourage regulatory innovation; and firms would be more committed to the rules than if imposed externally. Moreover, the very fact of individualization avoids the monopoly problem. On the other hand, the administrative costs would be high. This
9400
Self-Regulation
597
suggests that, for such a regime to be cost-effective, the firm must be large and the activity to be regulated must be one in which efficiency requires significantly differentiated standards (Latin, 1985).
Acknowledgements I acknowledge with gratitude the very helpful comments of two anonymous referees.
Bibliography on Self-Regulation (9400) Adelstein, Richard P. (1992), ‘Charles E. Lindblom’, in Samuels, Warren J. (ed.), New Horizons in Economic Thought: Appraisals of Leading Economists, Cheltenham, Edward Elgar, 202-226. Anderson, Terry L. and Hill, Peter J. (1979), ‘American Experiment in Anarcho-Capitalism: The Not so Wild, Wild West’, 3 Journal of Liberation Studies, 9-19. Barzel, Yoram (1982), ‘Measurement Costs and the Organisation of Markets’, 25 Journal of Law and Economics, 27-48. Belcher, Alice (1996), ‘The Invention, Innovation and Diffusion of Self-Regulation in Corporate Governance’, 47 Northern Ireland Law Quarterly, 322-334. Benham, Lee (1972), ‘The Effect of Advertising on the Price of Eyeglasses’, 15 Journal of Law and Economics, 337-352. Benham, Lee and Benham, Alexandra (1975), ‘Regulating Through the Professions: A Perspective on Information Control’, 18 Journal of Law and Economics, 421-447. Benson, Bruce L (1988), ‘Legal Evolution in Primitive Societies’, 144 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 772-788. Benson, Bruce L. (1989), ‘The Spontaneous Evolution of Commercial Law’, 55 Southern Economic Journal, 644-661. Benson, Bruce L (1990), The Enterprise of Law: Justice Without the State, San Francisco, Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy. Benson, Bruce L. (1992), ‘Customary Law as a Social Contract: International Commercial Law’, 3 Constitutional Political Economy, 1-27. Benson, Bruce L. (1993), ‘The Impetus for Recognizing Private Property and Adopting Ethical Behavior in a Market Economy: Natural Law, Government Law, or Evolving Self-Interest’, 6 Review of Austrian Economics, 43-80. Bernstein, Lisa (1992), ‘Opting Out of the Legal System: Extralegal Contractual Relations in the Diamond Industry’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 115-158. Blair, Roger D. and Rubin, Stephen (eds), Regulating the Professions: A Public-Policy Symposium, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Boulier, B.L. (1980), ‘An Empirical Examination of the Influence of Licensure and Licensure Reform on the Geographical Distribution of Dentists’, in Rottenberg, Simon (ed.), Occupational Licensure and Licensure Regulation, American Enterprise Institute, 73-97.
598
Self-Regulation
9400
Braithwaite, John (1982), ‘Enforced Self Regulation: A New Strategy for Corporate Crime’, 80 Michigan Law Review, 1466-1507. Button, Kenneth and Fleming, Michael (1992), ‘The Effects of Regulatory Reform on the Architectural Profession in the United Kingdom’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 95-116. Caroll, Sidney L. and Gaston, Robert J. (1979), ‘State Occupational Licensing Provisions and Quality of Service: The Real Estate Business’, 1 Research in Law and Economics, 1-13. Charny, David (1990), ‘Nonlegal Sanctions in Commercial Relationships’, 104 Harvard Law Review, 373-467. Cheit, Ross E. (1990), Setting Safety Standards: Regulation in the Public and Private Sectors, University of California Press. Cheung, Steven N.S. (1974), ‘A Theory of Price Control’, 17 Journal of Law and Economics, 53-72. Cooter, Robert D. (1996), ‘Decentralized Law for a Complex Economy: The Structural Approach to Adjudicating the New Law Merchant’, 144 University of Pennsylvania Law Review. Curran, Christopher (1993), ‘ The American Experience with Self-Regulation in the Medical and Legal Professions’, in Faure, Micheal, Finsinger, Jörg, Siegers, Hacques and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds), Regulation of Professions: A Law and Economics Approach to the Regulation of Attorneys and Physicians in the US, Belgium, Netherlands, Germany and the UK, Maklu, Antwerpen, 47-87. De Soto, Hernando (1989), The Other Path: The Invisible Revolution in the Third World, New York, Harper and Row. Dingwall, Robert and Fenn, Paul (1987), ‘A Respectable Profession? Sociological and Economic Perspectives on the Regulation of Professional Services’, 7 International Review of Law and Economics, 55-64. Domberger, Simon and Sherr, Avrom (1989), ‘The Impact of Competition on Pricing and Quality of Legal Services’, 9 International Review of Law and Economics, 41-56. Ellickson, Robert C. (1991), Order Without Law: How Neighbours Settle Disputes, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Ellickson, Robert C. (1993), ‘Property in Land’, 102 Yale Law Journal, 1315-1400. Evans, Robert G. (1980), ‘Professionals and the Production Function: Can Competition Policy Improve Efficiency in the Licensed Professions?’, in Rottenberg, Simon (ed.), Occupational Licensure and Regulation, American Enterprise Institute. Friedman, David (1973), The Machinery of Freedom: Guide to Radical Capitalism, New York, Harper and Row. Friedman, David (1979), ‘Private Creation and Enforcement of Law: A Historical Case’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 399-415. Friedman, Milton and Kuznets, S. (1945), Income from Independent Professional Practice, New York, National Bureau of Economic Research. Gehrig, Thomas and Jost, Peter J. (1995), ‘Quacks, Lemons and Self-Regulation: A Welfare Analysis’, 7 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 309-235. Gorton, Gary and Mullineaux, Donald J. (1987), ‘The Joint Production of Confidence: Endogenous Regulation and Nineteenth Century Commercial Bank Clearinghouses’, 19 Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 457-468. Gravelle, Hugh (1985), ‘Economic Analysis of Health Service Professions: A Survey’, 20 Social Sciences and Medicine, 1049-1061.
9400
Self-Regulation
599
Greif, Avner (1989), ‘Reputation and Coalitions in Midieval Trade: Evidence on the Maghribi Traders’, 49 Journal of Economic History, 857-882. Holen, Arlene S. (1965), ‘Effects of Professional Licensing Arrangements on Interstate Labor Mobility and Resource Allocation’, 73 Journal of Political Economy, 492-498. Horowitz, Ira (1980), ‘The Economic Foundations of Self-Regulation in the Professions’, in Blair, Roger D. and Rubin, Stephen (eds), Regulating the Professions: A Public-Policy Symposium, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Katz, Avery (1996), ‘Taking Private Ordering Seriously’, 144 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1754-1763. Kay, John (1988), ‘The Forms of Regulation’, in Seldon, Arthur (ed.), Financial Regulation - or Over-Regulation, Institute of Economic Affairs, 33-42. Kessel, Reuben A. (1970), ‘The A.M.A. and the Supply of Physicians’, 35 Law and Contemporary Problems, 267-283. Klein, Daniel B. (ed.) (1997), Reputation: Studies in the Voluntary Elicitation of Good Conduct, University of Michigan Press. Kissam, P.C. (1980), ‘Anti-Trust Law, the First Amendment, and Professional Self-Regulation of Technical Quality’, in Blair, Roger D. and Rubin, Stephen (eds), Regulating the Professions: A Public-Policy Symposium, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Lees, D.S. (1966), The Economic Consequences of the Professions, London, Institute of Economic Affairs, 48 p. Maurizi, Alex R. (1974), ‘Occupational Licensing and the Public Interest’, 82 Journal of Political Economy, 399-413. Milgrom, Paul R., North, Douglass, C. and Weingast, Barry R. (1990), ‘The Role of Institutions in the Revival of Trade: the Law Merchant, Private Judges, and the Champagne Fairs’, 2 Economics and Politics, 1-23. Moore, Thomas G. (1961), ‘The Purpose of Licensing’, 4 Journal of Law and Economics, 93-117. Ogus, Anthony (1995), ‘Rethinking Self-Regulation’, 15 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 97-108. Ostry, Sylvia (1978), ‘Competition Policy and the Self- Regulating Professions’, in Slayton, Philip and Trebilcock, Michael J. (eds), The Professions and Public Policy, Toronto, University of Toronto Faculty of Law. Pashigian, B. Peter (1980), ‘Has Occupational Licensing Reduced Geographical Mobility and Raised Earnings?’, in Rottenberg, Simon (ed.), Occupational Licensure and Regulation, American Enterprise Institute. Paul, Chris W. (1982), ‘Competition in the Medical Profession: An Application of the Economic Theory of Regulation’, 48 Southern Economic Journal, 559-569. Pirrong, Stephen Craig (1995), ‘The Self Regulation of Commodity Exchanges: The Case of Market Manipulation’, 38 Journal of Law and Economics, 141-206. Plott, Charles R. (1965), ‘Occupational Self-Regulation: A Case-Study of the Oklahoma Dry Cleaners’, 8 Journal of Law and Economics, 195-222. Quinn, John (1982), ‘Multidisciplinary Legal Services and Preventive Regulation’, in Evans, Robert G. and Trebilcock, Michael J. (eds), Lawyers and the Consumer Interest: Regulating the Market for Legal Services, London, Butterworths, ch.11. Rees, Joseph (1988), Reforming the Workplace: A Study of Self-Regulation in Occupational Safety, University of Pennsylvania Press.
600
Self-Regulation
9400
Rothbard, Murray N. (1973), For a New Liberty, London, Macmillan. Schanze, Erich (1988), ‘Regulation by Consensus: The Practice of International Mining Agreements’, 144 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 152-171. Shaked, Avner and Sutton, John (1981a), ‘Heterogeneous Consumers and Product Differentiation in a Market for Professional Services’, 15 European Economic Review, 159-177. Shaked, Avner and Sutton, John (1981b), ‘The Self-Regulating Profession’, 47 Review of Economic Studies, 217-234. Shepard Lawrence (1978), ‘Licensing Restrictions and the Cost of Dental Care’‘, 21 Journal of Law and Economics, 187-201. Smith, Denis and Tombs, Steve (1995), ‘Beyond Self-Regulation: Towards a Critique of Self-Regulation as a Control Strategy for Hazardous Activities, 32 Journal of Management Studies, 619-636. Trautwein, Hans-Michael and Rönnau, Andreas (1993), ‘Selfregulation of the Medical Profession in Germany: A Survey’, in Faure, Michael, Finsinger, Jörg, Siegers, Jacques and Van den Bergh, Roger (eds), Regulation of Professions: A Law and Economics Approach to the Regulation of Attorneys and Physicians in the US, Belgium, Netherlands, Germany and the UK, Antwerpen, Maklu, 249-306. Trebilcock, Michael J. (1982), ‘Competitive Advertising’, in Evans Robert G. and Trebilcock, Michael J. (eds), Lawyers and the Consumer Interest: Regulating the Market for Legal Services, London, Butterworths, ch. 5. Trebilcock, Michael J. (1983), ‘Regulating Service Quality in Professional Markets’, in Dewees, Donald N. (ed.), The Regulation of Quality: Products, Services, Workplaces and The Environment, Butterworths, ch. 4. Tuohy, Carolyn and Wolfson, Alan (1978), ‘Self-Regulation: Who Qualifies?’, in Slayton, Philip and Trebilcock, Michael J. (eds), The Professions and Public Policy, Toronto, University of Toronto Faculty of Law. Umbeck, John (1981), A Theory of Property Rights with Applications to the Californian Gold Rush, Iowa State University Press. Van den Bergh, Roger and Faure, Michael G. (1991), ‘Self Regulation of the Professions in Belgium’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 165-182. Weingast, Barry R. (1980), ‘Physicians, DNA Research Scientists, and the Market for Lemons’, in Blair, Roger D. and Rubin, Stephen (eds), Regulating the Professions: A Public-Policy Symposium, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. White, William D. (1979), Dynamic Elements of Regulation: The Case of Occupational Licensure’, 1 Research in Law and Economics, 15-33. Wilson, R.A. (1987), ‘Returns to Entering the Medical Profession in the UK’, 6 Journal of Health Economics, 339-363.
Other References Akerlof, George, A. (1970), ‘The Market for “Lemons”: Qualitative Uncertainty and the Market Mechanism’, 84 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 488-500. Arrow, Kenneth (1963), ‘Uncertainty and the Welfare Economics of Medical Care’, 53 American Economic Review, 941-973.
9400
Self-Regulation
601
Ayres, Ian and Braithwaite, John (1992), Responsive Regulation: Transcending the Deregulation Debate, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Baggott, Rob and Harrison, Larry (1986), ‘The Politics of Self-Regulation: The Case of Advertising Control’, 14 Policy and Politics, 143-160. Baggott, Rob (1989), ‘Regulatory Reform in Britain: The Changing Face of Self-Regulation, 67 Public Administration, 435-454. Baldwin, Robert (1987), ‘Health and Safety at Work: Consensus and Self-Regulation’, in Baldwin, Robert and McCrudden, Christopher (eds), Regulation and Public Law, London, Weidenfeld and Nicholson, ch.7. Bardach, Eugene and Kagan, Robert A. (1982), ‘Mixing Public and Private Regulation’, in Graymer, LeRoy and Thompson, Frederick (eds), Reforming Social Regulation: Alternative Public Policy Strategies, London, Sage Publications, ch.10. Baumol, William, J., Panzar, John C. and Willig, Robert D. (1982), Contestable Markets and the Theory of Industry Structure, New York, Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. Black, Julia (1996), ‘Constitutionalising Self-Regulation’, 59 Modern Law Review, 24-55. Black, Julia (1997), Rules and Regulators, Oxford, Clarendon Press. Bratton, William, Mccahery, Joseph, Picciotti, Sol and Scott, Colin (eds) (1997), International Regulatory Competition and Coordination: Perspectives on Economic Regulation in Europe and the United States, Oxford, Clarendon Press. Cane, Peter (1987), ‘Self Regulation and Judicial Review’, 6 Civil Justice Quarterly, 324-347. Carver, Charles, S. and Scheier, Michael F. (1981), Attention and Self-regulation: A Control Theory Approach to Human Behavior, Berlin, Springer-Verlag. Coase, Ronald H. (1960), ‘The Problem of Social Cost’, 3 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-44. Dawson, Sheila, Willman, Paul, Clinton, Alan and Bamford, M. (1988), Safety at Work: The Limits of Self-Regulation, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Demsetz, Harold (1968), ‘Why Regulate Utilities?’, 11 Journal of Law and Economics, 55-65. Fisher, Andrew (1997), ‘The Licensing of Taxis and Minicabs’, 7 Consumer Policy Review, 158-161. Fishman, James J. (1993), ‘A Comparison of Enforcement of Securities Law Violations in the UK and US’, Company Lawyer, 163-172 Grabosky, Peter and Braithwaite, John (1986), Of Manners Gentle: Enforcement Strategies of Australian Business Regulatory Agencies, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Harden, Ian and Lewis, Norman (1986), The Noble Lie: The British Constitution and the Rule of Law, New York, Hutchinson. Hogan, Daniel B. (1979), Regulation of Psychotherapists: A Study in the Philosophy and Practice of Professional Regulation, Cambridge, MA, Ballinger. Kay, John and Vickers, John (1990), ‘Regulatory Reform: An Appraisal’, in Majone, Giandomenico (ed.), Deregulation or Re-regulation: Regulatory Reform in Europe and the United States, London, Frances Pinter. Latin, Howard (1985), ‘Ideal versus Real Regulatory Efficiency: Implementation of Uniform Standards and “Fine-Tuning” Regulatory Reforms’, 37 Stanford Law Review, 1267-1332. OECD (1985), Competition Policy and the Professions, Paris, Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development.
602
Self-Regulation
9400
Office of Fair Trading (1982), Opticians and Competition, HMSO. Page, Alan C. (1986), ‘Self-Regulation: The Constitutional Dimension’, 49 Modern Law Review, 141-167. Page, Alan C. (1987), ‘Financial Services: The Self-Regulatory Alternative’, in Baldwin, Robert and McCrudden, Christopher (eds), Regulation and Public Law, London, Weidenfeld and Nicholson, ch.13. Quirk, Paul J. (1981), Industry Influence in Federal Regulatory Agencies, Princeton University Press. Schmitter, Philippe C. (1985), ‘Neo-Corporatism and the State’, in Grant, Wyn (ed.), The Political Economy of Corporatism, London, Macmillan, 32-62. Schwartz, Alan and Wilde, Louis L. (1979), ‘Intervening in Markets on the Basis of Imperfect Information: A Legal and Economic Analysis’, 127 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 630-682. Tollison, Robert D. (1982), ‘Rent Seeking: A Survey’, 35 Kyklos, 575-602. Tullock, Gordon (1967), ‘The Welfare Costs of Tariffs, Monopolies and Theft’, 5 Western Economic Journal, 224-232. Waterson, Michael (1988), Regulation of the Firm and Natural Monopoly, Oxford, Basil Blackwell.
9500 SPONTANEOUS EMERGENCE OF LAW: CUSTOMARY LAW Francesco Parisi George Mason University School of Law © Copyright 1999 Francesco Parisi
Abstract In the ‘social contract’ framework, customary rules can be regarded as an implied and often non-verbalized exercise of direct legislation by the members of society. Those legal systems that grant direct legal force to customary rules regard custom as a primary, although not exclusive, source of law. In such legal traditions, courts enforce customary rules as if they had been enacted by the proper legislative authority. Custom thus amounts to a spontaneous norm which is recognized by the legal system and granted enforcement as a proper legal rule. Judicial recognition of spontaneous norms amounts to a declaratory (rather than constitutive) function that treats custom as a legal fact. The legal system ‘finds’ the law by recognizing social norms, but does not ‘create’ the law. The most notable illustration is the system of international law, where, absent a central legislative authority, custom stands next to treaties as a primary source of law. (See, for example, Article 38 (1) of the Statute of the International Court of Justice; and Restatement 102 of the Foreign Relations Law of the United States.) Whenever they are granted legitimate status in a legal system, customary rules are usually given the same effect as other primary sources of law. Although often subordinated to formal legislation, customary rules derive their force from the concurrence of a uniform practice and a subjective belief that adherence to them is obligatory (opinio iuris), without necessarily being formally incorporated into any written body of law. For this reason, they are usually classified as ‘immaterial’ sources of law (Brownlie, 1990). This notion implies that the custom remains the actual source of law even after its judicial recognition. In this setting, the judicial decisions that recognize a custom offer only persuasive evidence of its existence and do not themselves become sources of law. In turn, this prevents the principle of stare decisis from crystallizing customary law. Modern legal systems generally recognize customary rules that have emerged either within the confines of positive legislation (consuetudo secundum legem) or in areas that are not disciplined by positive law (consuetudo praeter legem). Where custom is in direct conflict with legislation 603
604
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
9500
(that is, custom contra legem) the latter normally prevails. In some instances, however, a custom supersedes prior legislation (that is, abrogative custom), and some arguments have been made in support of emerging practices that conflict with obsolete provisions of public international law (desuetudo, or abrogative practice) (Kontou, 1994). The theoretical and practical significance of these forms of spontaneous social order, which compete with enacted law in influencing human choice, are discussed below. JEL classification: K00 Keywords: Customary Law, Spontaneous Law, Social Norms
1. Introduction Legal theorists define custom as a practice that emerges outside of legal constraints, and which individuals and organizations spontaneously follow in the course of their interactions out of a sense of legal obligation. Two categories of social practices are generally distinguished: (a) Practices that reflect mere behavioural patterns. In legal jargon, such behaviour is a mere usage; in economic terms it simply represents an equilibrium convention. A mere behavioural regularity does not generate a customary rule. (b) Practices that reflect an internalized belief that the practice is necessary or socially desirable. These practices are considered necessary for social well-being and are treated as proper legal custom, often entering the legal system as primary sources of law. The terminology used in the legal and economic literature should be contrasted with the terminology employed in sociological literature (see, for example, Weber, 1978, pp. 319-320). What is legally termed a mere usage is defined in sociological literature as a custom (Sitte), in the sense of a typically uniform activity that is not considered to be socially necessary. Convention the sociological notion closest to the legal concept of custom - amounts to conduct manipulated by express approval or disapproval by other members of the group, but lacking the enforceability that characterizes a legal custom.
A. The Theory of Spontaneous Law 2. The Formative Elements of a Customary Rule According to the theory of customary law, individual actors gradually come to embrace norms that they view as requisite to their collective wellbeing. An
9500
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
605
enforceable custom emerges from two formative elements: (a) a quantitative element consisting of a general or emerging practice; and (b) a qualitative element reflected in the belief that the norm generates a desired social outcome. 2.1 The Quantitative Element The quantitative requirements for the formation of customary law concern both the length of time and the universality of the emerging practice. Regarding the time element, there is generally no universally established minimum duration for the emergence of customary rules. Customary rules have evolved from both immemorial practice and a single act. Still, French jurisprudence has traditionally required the passage of forty years for the emergence of an international custom, while German doctrine generally requires thirty years (see Tunkin, 1961; Mateesco, 1947). Naturally, the longer the time required to form a valid practice, the less likely it is for custom to effectively anticipate the intervention of formal legislation, and to adapt to changing circumstances overtime. Regarding the condition of universality, international legal theory is ambivalent. Charney (1986) suggests that the system of international relations is analogous to a world of individuals in the state of nature, dismissing the idea that unanimous consent by all participants is required before binding customary law is formed. Rather than universality, recent restatements of international law refer to ‘consistency’ and ‘generality’ (see D’Amato, 1971). Where it is impossible to identify a general practice because of fluctuations in behavior, the consistency requirement is not met (see Asylum (1950) pp. 276-277; and Wimbledon (1923), Ser. A, no. 1). Similarly, more recent cases in international law restate the universality requirement in terms of ‘increasing and widespread acceptance’ (see, for example, Fisheries Jurisdiction (1974), pp. 23-26; North Sea Continental Shelf (1969), p. 42), allowing special consideration for emerging general norms (or local clusters of spontaneous default rules) that are expected to become evolutionarily stable over time. With regard to rules at the national or local level, the varying pace with which social norms are transformed suggests that no general time or consistency requirement can be established as an across-the-board condition for the validity of a custom. Some variance in individual observation of the practice should be expected because of the stochastic origin of social norms. A flexible time requirement is particularly necessary in situations of rapid flux, where exogenous changes are likely to affect the incentive structure of the underlying relationship. 2.2 The Qualitative Element The second formative element of a customary rule is generally identified by the phrase opinio iuris ac necessitatis, which describes a widespread belief in the desirability of the norm and the general conviction that the practice represents an essential norm of social conduct. This element is often defined in terms of
606
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
9500
necessary and obligatory convention. (Kelsen, 1939, 1945; D’Amato, 1971; Walden, 1977). The traditional formulation of opinio iuris is problematic because of its circularity. It is quite difficult to conceptualize that law can be born from a practice which is already believed to be required by law. The practical significance of this requirement is that it narrows the range of enforceable customs: only those practices recognized as socially desirable or necessary will eventually ripen into enforceable customary law. Once there is a general consensus that members of a group ought to conform to a given rule of conduct, a legal custom can be said to have emerged when some level of spontaneous compliance with the rule is obtained. As a result, observable equilibria that are regarded by society as either undesirable (for example, a prisoner’s dilemma uncooperative outcome) or unnecessary (for example, a common practice of greeting neighbours cordially) will lack the subjective and qualitative element of legal obligation and, therefore, will not generate enforceable legal rules.
B. The Emergence of Spontaneous Law According to the traditional legal approach to customary law, two elements are generally required for the emergence of a binding custom: (1) the practice should emerge out of the spontaneous and uncoerced behaviour of various members of a group, and (2) the parties involved must subjectively believe in the obligatory or necessary nature of the emerging practice (opinio iuris). To an economist, the first element corresponds to the rather standard assumption of rational choice. The second element may be appraised as a belief of social obligation, emerging in response to game inefficiencies, to support behavioural rules that avoid aggregate losses from strategic behaviour. The law and economics literature has examined some additional structural conditions for the emergence of customary law, which will briefly be analyzed below. (For a more extensive analysis, see Parisi, 1998b.)
3. Structural Symmetry and Incentive Alignment The literature on social norms focuses on non-contractual mechanisms and considers the situations that are more easily governed by spontaneous law. Under symmetrical conditions, norms that maximize group welfare also maximize individual expected payoffs. Thus, no one has any reason to challenge the emerging norm. Paradoxically, therefore, there is no need for law or norm enforcement in an environment characterized by perfect incentive alignment, as contracts or relationships are self-enforcing (Klein, 1996).
9500
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
607
In the presence of perfect incentive alignment, cooperation will result in both the case of repeated games in which the players are faced with high discount factors, and in one-shot games. It is worth noting that situations characterized by symmetric payoffs or role reversibility do not present an opportunity for strategic preference revelation. The expected costs and benefits of alternative rules are the same among the members of the group. Each individual has an incentive to agree to a set of rules that maximize the aggregate welfare of the group, consequently maximizing his expected share of wealth. True preferences will therefore be revealed in situations of stochastic symmetry. Conversely, strategic choices are more likely to characterize real life situations with misaligned individual incentives. Additionally, in the absence of perfect incentive alignment, the discount factor plays an important role. In situations where the probability of future interaction is relatively high, the discount factor captures two analytically distinct elements. First, it acts as a function of the players’ time preference. Second, the discount factor is a function of the probability of future interactions. The discount factor’s role in evolutionary models is therefore critical. Environments promoting a high probability of future interaction and low time preference are therefore more likely to induce optimizing equilibria. In the case of a one-shot game, on the other hand, the probability of future interaction is zero, so that the expected value of future cooperation is also zero (see, generally, Axelrod, 1984). Another area of research in the customary law literature considers the role of morality and internalized obligations as a means for inducing cooperation in conflict games (see, for example, Gauthier, 1986; Ullmann-Margalit, 1977). Internalization of the norm is a source of spontaneous compliance. For example, individuals internalize obligations when they disapprove and sanction other individuals’ deviations from the rule, or when they directly lose utility when the norm is violated. In this setting, Cooter (1994a) suggests that a legal custom will successfully evolve when the ex ante individual incentives are aligned with the collective public interest. Cooter (1994a, p. 224) calls this proposition the ‘alignment theorem’.
4. Stochastic Symmetry and Role Reversibility Traditionally, strategic preference revelation is viewed as a hindrance to the spontaneous emergence of cooperation. Such a problem is likely to be minimized in situations of role reversibility or stochastic symmetry (Parisi, 1995). Similar to a Rawlsian veil of ignorance, role reversibility and stochastic symmetry induce each member to agree to a set of rules that benefits the entire group, thus maximizing her expected share of the wealth.
608
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
9500
These conditions in fact occurred during the formative period of the medieval law merchant (lex mercatoria), when traveling merchants acted in the dual capacity of buyer and seller. If they articulated a rule of law which was favourable to them as sellers, it could have the opposite effect when they acted as buyers, and vice-versa. This role reversibility changed an otherwise conflicting set of incentives (buyer versus seller) into one that converged toward symmetrical and mutually desirable rules. The law merchant therefore illustrates a successful system of spontaneous and decentralized law (see Benson, 1989, 1990; Greif, 1989). Fuller (1969, p. 24) observes that frequent role changes foster the emergence of mutually recognized and accepted duties ‘in a society of economic traders. By definition the members of such a society enter direct and voluntary relationships of exchange. ... Finally, economic traders frequently exchange roles, now selling, now buying. The duties that arise out of their exchanges are therefore reversible, not only in theory but in practice.’ Certainly, the emergence of consensus for a given rule does not exclude the possibility of subsequent opportunistic deviation by some individuals when roles are later reversed. This is a typical enforcement problem, however, and the possibility of strategic defection does not undermine the rule’s qualitative features. The general acceptance of or acquiescence to a custom depends primarily on its anticipated effect on the group. Those strategies that maximize the expected payoff for each participant if reciprocally undertaken evolve into norms. This conception of spontaneous law is examined by Stearns (1994, pp. 1243-1244), who observes that if the participants were unable to devise rules governing future interactions, and unforeseen circumstances placed them in a forced market relationship requiring post-contractual negotiations, courts and legislatures might have a comparative advantage over the participants in devising market facilitating rules. Unlike market participants, courts and legislatures choose from among alternative solutions as if the underlying events had not yet occurred, without attempting to strategically maximize the advantage caused by unforeseen circumstances (see also Shubik, 1987). Where rules are breached following role reversal, norms play a collateral yet crucial role in sanctioning case-by-case opportunism. Conditions of role reversibility, coupled with norms that generate disincentives to adopt opportunistic double standards, are therefore likely to generate optimal rules via spontaneous processes. The group’s ability to impose a sanction obviously depends on an individual’s accountability for his past behaviour. Benson (1992d, pp. 5-7) explores the role of reputation in situations of repeated market interaction, observing that reputation serves as a source of collective knowledge regarding past actions.
9500
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
609
5. Induced Symmetry and Reciprocity Constraints Prisoner’s dilemma-type games are plagued by the dominance of opportunistic behaviour because of the potential accessibility of off-diagonal, non-cooperative outcomes. Schotter (1981), Lewis (1969) and Leibenstein (1982) analyze the role of conventions in correcting prisoner’s dilemma situations. Among the devices capable of correcting prisoner’s dilemma-type games, the players can bind their strategic choices to those of their opponents, drastically changing the equilibrium of the game. Ensuring automatic reciprocity by binding a player’s strategy to that of his opponent eliminates access to off-diagonal outcomes and renders the reward for unilateral defection unobtainable. Just as no rational player will employ defection strategies in the hope of obtaining higher payoffs from unilateral cheating, neither will a rational player be induced to select defection strategies as a merely defensive tactic. Automatic reciprocity mechanisms thus guarantee a shift toward optimizing cooperation. As pointed out by Parisi (1997), ancient customs of retaliation, based on conceptions of symmetry and punitive balance, provide an intriguing illustration of the principle of reciprocity at work (see, for example, Exodus 21:23; and Code of Hammurabi Paragraphs 108 and 127). Parisi (1998a) considers another example of a reciprocity constraint. Art. 21 (1)b of the 1969 Vienna Convention, which articulates an established custom of reciprocity, creates a mirror-image mechanism in the case of unilateral reservations in the process of treaty ratification: ‘A reservation established with regard to another party ... modifies those provisions to the same extent for that other party in its relations with the reserving state.’ The effects of this automatic reciprocity mechanism are similar to a tit-for-tat strategy without the need for active retaliation by states: whenever a treaty is modified unilaterally in favour of one state, the result will be as if all the other states had introduced an identical reservation against the reserving state. By imposing a symmetry constraint on the parties’ choices, this rule offers a possible solution to prisoner’s dilemma problems. Parisi (1998a) further observes that, while the principle of reciprocity solves conflict situations characterized by a prisoner’s dilemma structure (in both symmetric and asymmetric cases), alone it is incapable of correcting other strategic problems. When a conflict occurs along the diagonal possibilities of the game (such that the obtainable equilibria are already characterized by symmetric strategies), a reciprocity constraint will not eliminate the divergence of interests between the players and will not affect the results of the game. The dynamic process of norm formation may unveil the existence of a ‘tilt point’ beyond which emerging beliefs become stable and self-sustaining. In light of reciprocal constraints undertaken by other members of the community, individuals who frequently exchange roles in their social interactions have incentives to constrain their behaviour to conform to socially optimal norms of
610
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
9500
conduct. Buchanan (1975) insightfully anticipated this result, suggesting that an even stronger logic explains the emergence of cooperation in situations of induced reciprocity. In both cases, the non-idealistic and self-interested behaviour of human actors will generate optimal norms.
6. Articulation Theories in the Formation of Customary Law Notable scholars have considered the conditions under which principles of justice can emerge spontaneously through the voluntary interaction and exchange of individual members of a group. As in a contractarian setting, the reality of customary law formation relies on a voluntary process through which members of a community develop rules that govern their social interaction by voluntarily adhering to emerging behavioural standards. In this setting, Harsanyi (1955) suggests that optimal social norms are those that would emerge through the interaction of individual actors in a social setting with impersonal preferences. The impersonality requirement for individual preferences is satisfied if the decision makers have an equal chance of finding themselves in any one of the initial social positions and they rationally choose a set of rules to maximize their expected welfare. Rawls (1971) employs Harsanyi’s model of stochastic ignorance in his theory of justice. However, the Rawlsian ‘veil of ignorance’ introduces an element of risk aversion in the choice between alternative states of the world, thus altering the outcome achievable under Harsanyi’s original model, with a bias toward equal distribution (that is, with results that approximate the Nash criterion of social welfare). Further analysis of the spontaneous formation of norms and principles of morality can be found in Sen (1979), Ullmann-Margalit (1977) and Gauthier (1986). Legal theorists and practitioners have addressed a similar issue when considering the requirements of opinio iuris. In attempting to solve one of the problems associated with the notion of opinio iuris, namely the troublesome problem of circularity, legal scholars (notably, D’Amato, 1971) have considered the crucial issue of timing of belief and action in the formation of customary rules. The traditional approach emphasizes the awkward notion that individuals must believe that a practice is already law before it can become law. This approach basically requires the existence of a mistake for the emergence of a custom: the belief that an undertaken practice was required by law, when instead, it was not. Obviously, this approach has its flaws. Placing such reliance on systematic mistakes, the theory fails to explain how customary rules can emerge and evolve overtime in cases where individuals have full knowledge of the state of the law. In this context, legal theorists have proposed to look past the notions of opinio iuris and usage concentrating on the qualitative element of
9500
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
611
‘articulation’. Consistent with the predicament of the economic models, articulation theories suggest that greater weight should be given to beliefs that have been expressed prior to the emergence of a conflict. Here, it is interesting to point out a strong similarity between the legal and the economic models. Articulations that are made prior to the unveiling of conflicting contingencies can be analogized to rules chosen under a Harsanyian veil of uncertainty. States and individuals will have an incentive to articulate and endorse norms that maximize their expected welfare. Given some degree of uncertainty as to the future course of events, the emerging rules will be such as to maximize the expected welfare of the community at large. Conversely, rules that are articulated after an outburst of conflict may be strategically biased. Once the future is disclosed to them, parties will tend to articulate rules that maximize their actual welfare, rather than the expected welfare to be derived from an uncertain future. Thus, ex ante norms should be given greater weight in the adjudication process. This predicament seems to be contradicted by the empirical and anecdotal evidence on commercial customary law. Bernstein (1996) examines customary rules that have developed in various modern commercial trades. Her findings seem to indicate that in the adjudication of business disputes, commercial tribunals tend to enforce customary rules that are quite different from the business norms spontaneously followed by the parties in the course of their relationship. Rather, customary rules develop around practices developed during the conflictual phase of a relationship. In this setting, Bernstein distinguishes between relationship norms and end-of-the-game norms. When adjudicating a case, courts are faced with parties who have reached the end point in their relationship. The end-of-the-game norms of the conflictual phase thus tend to be enforced, while the cooperative norms developed in the course of their relationship remain outside the domain of adjudication.
C. The Failures of Customary Law According to the popular paradigms of economic analysis, decentralized market processes have a comparative advantage over centralized allocative mechanisms in the creation of efficient equilibria. Customary law formation can be analogized to a decentralized decision making process, with a comparative advantage over centralized processes in the creation of efficient rules. Customary rules are generally accepted by the community, with a larger share of rules followed spontaneously by the community and a consequent reduction in law enforcement costs. In the decentralized dynamic of spontaneous law, individual decision makers directly perceive the costs and benefits of alternative rules, and reveal their preferences by supporting or
612
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
9500
opposing their formation. The formative process of customary law proceeds through a purely inductive accounting of subjective preferences. Through his own action, each individual contributes to the creation of law. The emerging rule thus embodies the aggregate effects of independent choices by various individuals that participate in its formation. This inductive process allows individuals to reveal their preferences through their own action, without the interface of third-party decision makers. The analogy between customary rules and spontaneous market equilibria, however, calls for an assessment of the potential insufficiencies of the spontaneous processes of law formation. I will proceed by setting out some hypotheses for failure and discussing their potential scope of application in the area of customary law. The literature in this area is relatively thin and much work still needs to be done to develop a coherent theory of spontaneous law.
7. Path Dependence and the Idiosyncracies of Customary Law Norms and conventions vary from place to place. Any theory about the efficiency of spontaneous law should explain the diversity of norms and conventions across time and space. In my view, there are two primary ways to provide such an explanation. The first is to look for idiosyncratic environmental or institutional factors which might attribute to the diversity of observed rules. If the underlying social, economic, or historical realities are found to be different from one another, different norms or conventions should be expected. Rules, norms and conventions develop in response to exogenous shocks through a natural process of selection and evolution. This ‘survival of the fittest’ explanation would suggest that whatever exists in equilibrium is efficient, given the current state of affairs. This belief, borrowed from Darwinian evolutionism, is pervasive in the law and economics literature and, when applied to spontaneous law, risks becoming a tautological profession of faith. Ironically, we should note that the originators of such a claim, socio-biologists, have now widely refuted its validity. The second way to reconcile the efficiency claim to the observed diversity of spontaneous rules is to consider the role of path dependence in the evolution of norms and conventions. Following Roe (1996) and his definition of path dependence in law, evolution toward efficiency may be seen as taking place with some random component. Random historical and natural events (the random element of chaos theory) determine the choice of the initial path. This may be the case particularly where initial choices are made under imperfect information. Evolution then continues toward efficiency along different paths, with results that are influenced and constrained by the initial random conditions.
9500
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
613
If we agree that path dependence has something to do with the emergence and evolution of customary law, we should follow this logic to its conclusion, revisiting the very foundations of the efficiency claim. The main question is whether path dependence could ever lead to inefficient results. According to current research (Roe, 1996), path dependence may lead to inefficient equilibria. Once a community has developed its norms and conventions, the costs of changing them may outweight the benefits. Less efficient rules may persist if the transition to more efficient alternatives is costly. Thus, if one allows for some randomness and path dependence, norms and conventions, although driven by an evolution-toward-efficiency dynamic, may stabilize around points of local, rather than global, maximization. Our history, in this sense, constrains our present choices. We may wish we had developed more efficient customs and institutions, but it would be foolish now to attempt to change them. The claim of efficiency of spontaneous law thus becomes a relative one vis-à-vis the other sources of law. The point then becomes that of weighing the relative advantages of spontaneous law-making against the attributes of engineered legislation, taking full account of the pervasive public choice and information problems underlying such alternatives.
8. Rational Abstention and Norm Manipulation A public choice analysis of customary law should consider the vulnerability of norms and customs to the pressure of special interest groups. This line of analysis - relatively undeveloped in the current literature - should search for parallels between the legislative process and the dynamic of norm formation. In that setting, the opportunity for collective beliefs and customs to be manipulated by special interest groups should be analyzed. Any claim that customary sources are superior to proper legislation will have to rest on a solid understanding of the relative sensibility of each source to possible political failures. The application of a well-known theorem of public choice to the study of customary law generates very interesting results. Unlike legislation in a representative democracy, customary law rests on the widespread consensus of all individuals affected by the rule. If principal-agent problems are likely to arise in a political world characterized by rational ignorance and rational abstention of voters, no such problems appear to affect customary sources. Individuals are bound by a customary rule only to the extent that they concurred - actively or through voluntary acquiescence - in the formation of the emerging practice. Imperfect information, however, may induce voluntary acquiescence - or even active concurrence - to an undesirable practice. Economic models of cascade or bandwagon behaviour have shown how inferior paths can be
614
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
9500
followed by individuals who rely on previous choices undertaken by other subjects, and value such observed choices as signals of revealed preference. Economic models have shown that, when information is incomplete, excessive weight can be attached to the signal generated by others. Others’ choices may be followed even when the agent’s own perception conflicts with the content of the observed signal. In this way, a biased or mistaken first-mover can generate a cascade of wrong decisions by all his followers, with a result that may prove relatively persistent under a wide array of conditions. Cascade arguments may also unveil the relative fragility of spontaneous sources of law in light of the possible manipulation of collective beliefs through biased leadership. If information is imperfect, the input of politically biased first-movers may generate undesirable norms. These norms may persist because of the weight attached to the choices of our predecessors. Thus, once generated, wrong beliefs may become stable and widespread in any community of imperfect decision makers.
9. Collective Action Problems in Customary Legal Regimes Another potential weakness of customary law is revealed by the application of a collective action framework to the study of the formation and enforcement of customary rules. We can start the analysis by observing that legal rules and law enforcement are public goods. In the case of customary rules, collective action problems may thus arise at two distinct stages: first, in the formative process of customary rules; and second, in the enforcement of the emerged customs. The process of a custom formation relies on the spontaneous and widespread acceptance of a given rule by the members of a group. Individuals often face a private cost when complying with the precepts of the rule, and they generally derive a benefit because of the compliance of others with existing rules. Thus, the formation of customary law can be affected by a public good problem. When discussing the conditions under which customary rules can effectively develop, I illustrated the analysis with a game-theoretic framework. The public good problem considered here is in many respects similar to the strategic tension that we have examined in the context of customary law formation. If individuals face a private cost and generate a public benefit through norm creation, there will be a suboptimal amount of norms created through spontaneous processes. Any individual would like others to observe a higher level of norm compliance than he or she observed. The resulting level of norm compliance would thus be suboptimal. Collective action problems in the formation of customary rules have traditionally been corrected by norms which sanctioned opportunistic double standards, and by metarules imposing reciprocity constraints on the parties.
9500
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
615
The issue has only marginally been addressed in the economic literature. The reader may look at Hirshleifer (1982) who discusses enforcement by the sanction of one time retaliation by defection in a prisoner’s dilemma setting; and Witt (1986) who discusses enforcement by costly retaliation and other punishment not depending on repeat interactions. More serious collective action problems emerge in the enforcement of spontaneous norms. If the enforcement of norms is left to the private initiative of individual members of the group, a large number of cases will be characterized by a suboptimal level of enforcement. Punishing violators of a norm creates a public good because of the special and general deterrent effect of the penalty. Yet if imposition of the penalty is left to private initiative, punishers would be willing to enforce norms only to the point at which the private marginal cost of enforcement equals its private marginal benefit. This equilibrium obviously diverges from the social optimum, where enforcement would be carried out until the marginal cost equals the social, rather than private, marginal benefit. This consideration explains why the customs of ancient societies recognized and sanctioned only a limited category of wrongs. Generally speaking, only those wrongs that had a well-identified victim were likely to be addressed through a system of private law enforcement. For the system of private law enforcement to function properly, it was necessary for the victim or his clan to have a strong interest in carrying out the punishment. This also explains why other categories of wrong with a broader class of victims tend to emerge during more advanced stages of legal development, when law enforcement is delegated to a central authority. In sum, collective action problems may be pervasive in the enforcement of customary rules, with a consequential risk that enforcement will be suboptimal. This conclusion suggests that the decentralized process of law formation may be successfully coupled with a centralized mechanism of law enforcement. In this way, the advantages that customary sources have in gathering diffuse information will be available, free from the collective action problems that typically affect decentralized processes of law enforcement.
10. Adjudicating Social Norms According to the theory of spontaneous law, customary law has a comparative advantage over the other institutional sources. The intellectual basis of this claim is related to the proposition that any social arrangement that is voluntarily entered upon by rationally self-interested parties is beneficial to society as a whole. The inductive process which underlies spontaneous law builds upon the role of individuals giving direct effect to their revealed preferences, without the
616
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
9500
interface of third-party decision makers. To the extent that social practices have emerged under competitive conditions (that is, so long as there is an implicit cost for indulging in inefficient equilibria) without Pareto-relevant externalities, we may be able to draw plausible conclusions regarding the desirability of emerging customs. It is in this latter sense that custom may reclaim full dignity as a source of law. The evolutionary and game-theoretic appraisals of the lawmaking process have shed new light on the normative foundations of spontaneous law, but they require an appropriate analysis of the incentive structure in the originating social environment (Cooter, 1992). Evolutionary theories of cooperation have indeed explained the ability of rationally self-interested individuals to cooperate for the sake of mutual gain. Evolutionarily stable cooperative strategies serve efficiency goals and may emerge as social norms recognized by the community to be obligatory. Once emerged, customary rules generate the expectations of the other members of society and those expectations in turn demand judicial enforcement. In some instances, peer pressure and spontaneous processes of norm internalization will support their enforcement. The legal system may further this process by recognizing and enforcing welfare-maximizing social norms. In this regard, Cooter (1994a) argues that legal recognition and enforcement should consequently be denied in the case of non-cooperative practices, under a test that amounts to a structural analysis of the social incentives that generated the norm. He further argues that in the process of common law adjudication, a distinction must necessarily be made between cooperative norms and non-cooperative practices. Courts are not specialized in the adjudication of most norms. They must therefore resort to a structural approach, first inquiring into the incentives underlying the social structure that generated the norms, rather than attempting to weigh their costs and benefits directly.
11. Local Information and Evolutionary Traps When the private incentives of the parties diverge from the collective good and the parties cannot enter into binding and enforceable social contracts, inefficient social interactions may follow. These situations may generate suboptimal Nash equilibria as the benefit pursued by each individual player is insufficient to compensate for the harm suffered by the other players. While at times benefitting a few members of the group, strategies of this kind may result in a net social loss for the collectivity. Generally considered undesirable, they may be condemned from the other members of the group. In this way, rules that are expected to harm the aggregate wellbeing of the community will not be supported by a belief of social necessity. By discouraging the adoption of
9500
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
617
socially suboptimal strategies, the group ethic may serve to destabilize undesirable stalls in the evolutionary process. Therefore, those societies that foster a strong group ethic will maintain a comparative advantage over others. Whenever the societies operate in an intergroup environment marked by strong competition, competing societies will adopt the norms of societies with the comparatively strong group ethic, or else they will suffer negative selection. In a different setting, one may also think of a group ethic evolving to correct for evolutionary stalls and to stabilize individual behaviour on a point of global maximization (Hirshleifer, 1982). Figure 1 illustrates a possible scenario for an evolutionary trap, where, even in the absence of any strategic interaction between individuals, global maximization is facilitated by the existence of norms. Whenever the non-convexity of individual preferences does not permit a progressive shift from B to A without a utility loss, the point of local maximization B may be characterized as a behavioural trap. In these situations, individuals face a ‘no pain, no gain’ dilemma. Individuals are at a point of local maximization and - because of imperfect knowledge or perhaps inertia in their consumption or behavioural habits - are unlikely to shift to a different optimizing point without external incentives. Imperfect information, in this context, implies that individuals may have complete information about where they are, but not necessarily about where they are going - such that the preferences that are revealed through the observed choices of the parties may not be used as an absolute proxy for individual optimization. Figure 1 The Utility-Enhancing Norm
618
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
9500
When this type of evolutionary stall persists in a group, social norms of acceptable behaviour may emerge (Levy, 1988). Those who depart from these norms may be subjected to sanctions (condemnation). Individuals, perhaps even the large majority of individuals in society, may be trapped in behaviour B due to incomplete (ly known) preferences over neverexperienced alternatives. It would then be utility enhancing for society (or other members within the group who have obtained information over the alternative states of the world) to influence the consumption choices of other individuals by stigmatization or punishment, in order to lead the individual out of his or her trap. Such stigmatization - one may observe: paternalistic in nature - may well evolve spontaneously in societies because it makes individuals and society as a whole better off. In an evolutionary setting, societies that developed such norms - be them social, ethical, or moral in nature - will enjoy a comparative advantage over other societies. Despite the general economic motion which views constraints as ‘bads’ for optimization problems, Figure 1 thus shows the possibility of a utility-enhancing constraint capable of correcting a suboptimal equilibrium obtained in a point of local maximization along a non-convex preference set. Within a local optimization setup, moral constraints may supply information not otherwise revealed by the local surface. Together with social norms and group standards, moral constraints transmit the accumulated wisdom of past experience to individual decision makers. In this framework, norms of tradition, morality, and group ethics do not conflict in any general way with the economic paradigms of efficiency and optimization. Evolution assures that practices which are socially inferior (in the sense that they do not make a cost-justified contribution to human wellbeing) are less frequently adopted because they are labelled as immoral, socially inappropriate, or ethically wrong. Of course, evolutionary processes are never completed, and their task is only stochastically accomplished. Still, the strong correlation between activities and institutions that are efficient, and the community’s moral approval of them, should not be underestimated. Many activities that are generally considered immoral (for example, stealing, cheating, lying, and so on) are also inefficient in that they dissipate human wealth. While counterexamples exist in which ‘morally condemned’ behaviour actually contributes to overall human welfare, social norms and moral principles of the type described above should be considered ‘rules of thumb’ principles of conduct for individuals who operate in a world of imperfect information and limited cognitive competence (see, Heiner, 1983; Frank, 1987; Parisi, 1995).
9500
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
619
Bibliography on Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law (9500) Ackerman, Bruce A. (1986), ‘Law, Economics and the Problem of Legal Culture’, 66 Duke Law Journal, 929-947. Adelstein, Richard P. (1979), ‘The Moral Costs of Crime: Prices, Information and Organization’, in Gray, Charles M. (ed.), The Costs of Crime, Beverly Hills, CA, Sage Publications, 233-252. Adelstein, Richard P. (1981), ‘Institutional Function and Evolution in the Criminal Process’, 76 Northwestern University Law Review, 1-99. Adelstein, Richard P. and Peretz, Steven I. (1985), ‘The Competition of Technologies in Markets for Ideas: Copyright and Fair Use in Evolutionary Perspective’, 5 International Review of Law and Economics, 209-238. Alchian, Armen A. (1950), ‘Uncertainty, Evolution and Economic Theory’, 58 Journal of Political Economy, 211-221. Arthur, W. Brian (1988), ‘Self-Reinforcing Mechanisms in Economics’, in Anderson, Philip W. et al. (eds), The Economy as an Evolving Complex System, Reading, MA, Addison-Wesley. Axelrod, R. (1981), ‘The Emergence of Cooperation Among Egoists’, 75 American Political Science Review, 306-318. Axelrod, R. (1984), The Evolution of Cooperation, New York, Basic Books. Bailey, Martin J. and Rubin, Paul H. (1994), ‘A Positive Theory of Legal Change’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 467-477. Barnes, David W. and Stout, Lynn A. (1992), Economics of Constitutional Law and Public Choice, St. Paul’s West Publishing. Barry, B.M. (1995), Justice as Impartiality, Oxford, Clarendon. Bell, John W. (1977), ‘Averting a Crisis in Product Liability: An Evolutionary Process of Socioeconomic Justice’, 65 Illinois Bar Journal, 640-648. Benson, Bruce L (1990), The Enterprise of Law: Justice Without the State, San Francisco, Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy. Benson, Bruce L. (1988), ‘Legal Evolution in Primitive Societies’, 144 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 772-788. Benson, Bruce L. (1989a), ‘The Spontaneous Evolution of Commercial Law’, 55 Southern Economic Journal, 644-661, reprinted in Klein, Daniel B. (ed.), Reputation: Studies in the Voluntary Enforcement of Good Behavior, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press. Benson, Bruce L. (1989b), ‘Enforcement of Private Property Rights in Primitive Societies: Law Without Government’, 9 Journal of Libertarian Studies, 1-26. Benson, Bruce L. (1990), ‘Customary Law With Private Means of Resolving Disputes and Dispensing Justice: A Description of a Modern System of Law and Order Without State Coercion’, 9 Journal of Libertarian Studies, 25-42. Reprinted in ‘Law and Order Without State Coercion’, in Veljanovski, Cento (ed.) (1991), Regulation, Regulators and the Market, London, Institute of Economic Affairs, 159-179. Benson, Bruce L. (1991a), ‘An Evolutionary Contractarian View of Primitive Law: The Institutions and Incentives Arising Under Customary American Indian Law’, 5 Review of Austrian Economics, 65-89. Benson, Bruce L. (1991b), ‘Reciprocal Exchange as the Basis for Recognition of Law: Examples from American History’, 10 Journal of Libertarian Studies, 53-82.
620
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
9500
Benson, Bruce L. (1992a), ‘Market Failure Versus Government Failure in the Production of Adjudication’, in Bowman, Gary W., Hakim, Simon and Seidenstat, Paul (eds), Privatizing the United States Justice System: Police, Adjudication, and Corrections Services from the Private Sector, Jefferson, NC, McFarland & Co., 203-225. Benson, Bruce L. (1992b), ‘The Evolution of Values and Institutions in a Free Society: The Under-Pinnings of a Market Economy’, 5 International Journal on the Unity of Sciences, 411-442. Reprinted in Radnitzky, Gerard and Bouillon, Hardy (eds) (1995),Values and the Social Order Vol.I, Aldershot, Avebury, 87-125. Benson, Bruce L. (1992c), ‘The Development of Criminal Law and Its Enforcement: Public Interest or Political Transfers’, 3 Journal des Economistes et des Etudes Humaines, 79-108. Benson, Bruce L. (1992d), ‘Customary Law as a Social Contract: International Commercial Law’, 2 Constitutional Political Economy, 1-27. Benson, Bruce L. (1992e), ‘Customary Indian Law: Two Case Studies’, in Anderson, Terry L. (ed.), Property Rights and Indian Economics, Lanham , MD, Rowman and Littlefield Press. Benson, Bruce L. (1993), ‘The Impetus for Recognizing Private Property and Adopting Ethical Behavior in a Market Economy: Natural Law, Government Law, or Evolving Self-Interest’, 6 Review of Austrian Economics, 43-80. Benson, Bruce L. (1994), ‘Legal Philosophy’, in Boettke, Peter J. (ed.), The Elgar Companion to Austrian Economics, London, Edward Elgar, 270-275. Benson, Bruce L. (1994), ‘Emerging from the Hobbesian Jungle: Might Takes and Makes Rights’, 5 Constitutional Political Economy, 129-158. Translated into Spanish and republished (1995) Las Instituciones y Los Derechos de Propiedad al Emerger de la Jungla Hobbesiana: La Fuerza Quita los Reprinted Derechos y los Crea Libertas, 12, 35-75. Benson, Bruce L. (1995), ‘Competition Among Legal Institutions: Implications for the Evolution of Law’, in Gerken, Luden (ed.), Competition Among Institutions, London, Macmillan, 153-175. Benson, Bruce L. (1995), ‘An Exploration of the Impact of Modern Arbitration Statutes on the Development of Arbitration in the United States’, 11 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 479-501. Berlin, I. (1970), ‘Two Concepts of Liberty’, in Berlin, I. (ed.), Four Essays on Liberty, New York, NY, Oxford University Press. Berman, Harold J. and Dasser, Felix J. (1990), ‘The “New” Law Merchant and the “Old”: Sources, Content, and Legitimacy’, in Carbonneau, Thomas E. (ed.), Lex Mercatoria and Arbitration: A Discussion of the New Law Merchant, New York, Dobbs Ferry, Transnational Juris Publications. Bernstein, Lisa (1996), ‘Merchant Law In a Merchant Court: Rethinking the Code’s Search for Immanent Business Norms’, 144 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1765 ff. Binmore, Ken and Samuelson, Larry (1994), ‘An Economist’s Perspective on the Evolution of Norms’, 150 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 45-63. Boyd, R. and Richerson, P.J. (1992), ‘Punishment Allows the Evolution of Cooperation (or Anything Else) in Sizable Groups’, 13 Ethology and Sociobiology, 171-195. Boyd, R. and Richerson, P.J. (1994), ‘The Evolution of Norms: An Anthropological View’, 150 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 72-86.
9500
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
621
Bromley, Daniel W. (1989), ‘Institutional Change and Economic Efficiency’, 23 Journal of Economic Issues, 735-759. Brownlie, Ian (1990), Principles of Public International Law, 4th edn, Oxford, Clarendon Press. Buchanan, James M. (1975), The Limits of Liberty: Between Anarchy and Leviathan, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Buchanan, James M. (1979), ‘General Implications of Subjectivism in Economics’, in X (ed.), What Should Economists Do?, Indianapolis, Liberty Press. Buchanan, James M. (1991), ‘The Foundations for Normative Individualism’, in X (ed.), The Economics and the Ethics of Constitutional Order, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press. Buchanan, James M. (1994), ‘Choosing What to Choose’, 150 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 123-135. Buxbaum, Hertig and Hirsch, Hopt (1996) (eds), European Economic and Business Law, Legal and Economic Analyses on Integration and Harmonization, Berlin, Springer, 401 p. Cassone, Alberto and Marchese, Carla (1994), ‘Indulgenze Religiose: un’Analisi Economica’, 2-3 Economia delle Scelte Pubbliche, 191-209. Charney, J.I. (1986), ‘The Persistent Objector Rule and the Development of Customary International Law’, 56 British Yearbook of International Law, 1 ff. Christiansen, Gregory B. (1990), ‘Law as a Discovery Procedure’, 9 Cato Journal, 497-530. Clark, Robert C. (1981), ‘The Interdisciplinary Study of “Legal Evolution”’, 90 Yale Law Journal, 1238-1274. Clay, Karen (1997), ‘Trade Without Law: Private-Order Institutions in Mexican California’, 13 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 202-231. Coleman, Jules L. (1992), Risks and Wrongs, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Contending with Hayek (1994), On Liberalism, Spontaneous Order and The Post-Communist Societies in Transition, Bern, Peter Lang. Cooter, Robert D. (1989), ‘Kin Groups and the Common Law Process’, in Larmour, Peter (ed.), Customary Land Tenure: Registration and Decentralisation in Papua New Guinea, Monograph XXIX, Papua New Guinea Institute of Applied Social and Economic Research, 33-50. Cooter, Robert D. (1991), ‘Inventing Market Property: The Land Courts of Papua New Guinea’, 25 Law and Society Review, 759-801. Cooter, Robert D. (1992), ‘Against Legal Centrism’ 81 California Law Review, 425 ff. Cooter, Robert D. (1993), ‘Against Legal Centrism: Review of Robert C. Ellickson’s Order Without Law’, 81 California Law Review, 417 ff. Cooter, Robert D. (1994a), ‘Structural Adjudication and the New Law Merchant: A Model of Decentralized Law’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 215-231. Reprinted under the title, ‘The Structural Approach to Decentralizing Law: A Theory of Games and Norms’, in a book edited by Gerard Hertig. Cooter, Robert D. (1994b), ‘Decentralized Law for a Complex Economy’, 23 Southwestern Law Review, Hayek Symposium, 443-451. Cooter, Robert D. (1996), ‘Decentralized Law for a Complex Economy: The Structural Approach to Adjudicating the New Law Merchant’, University of Pennsylvania Law Review.
622
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
9500
D’Amato, A. (1971), The Concept of Custom in International Law, Ithaca, NY, Cornell University Press. Eger, Thomas (1996), ‘Die Evolution von Recht als Prozeß der Selbstorganisation (The Evolution of Law as a Process of Self-Organization)’, in Priddat, B.P. and Wegner, G. (eds), Zwischen Institution und Evolution. Neue Ansätze in der ökonomischen Theorie, Marburg, Metropolis, 211-244. Eger, Thomas and Weise, Peter (1995), ‘Die Evolution von Normen aus Unordnung, Ein synergetisches Modell (The Evolution of Norms out of Disorder, A Synergetic Model)’, in X. (ed.), Ökonomie und Gesellschaft. Jahrbuch 11, Markt, Norm und Moral, Frankfurt/New York, 192-209. Eisenberg, Melvin Aron (1988),The Nature of the Common Law, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Ellickson, R.C. (1991), Order Without Law: How Neighbors Settle Disputes, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Ellickson, R.C. (1994), ‘The Aim of Order Without Law’, 150 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 97-100. Elliott, E. Donald (1984), ‘Holmes and Evolution: Legal Process as Artificial Intelligence’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 113-146. Elliott, E. Donald, Ackerman, Bruce A. and Millian, John C. (1985), ‘Toward a Theory of Statutory Evolution: The Federaliza tion of Environmental Law’, 1 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 313-340. Epstein, Richard A. (1980), ‘The Static Conception of the Common Law’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 253-275. Epstein, Richard A. (1992), ‘The Path to the T. J. Hooper: The Theory and History of Custom in the Law of Tort’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-38. Fortier, V. (1991), La Fonction Normative des Notions Floues (The Normative Functions of the Vagueness Notions), Aix-Marseille, Presses Universitaires d’, 755 p. Frank, Robert H. (1987), ‘If Homo Economicus Could Choose his Utility Function, Would He want one with a Conscience?’, 77 American Economic Review, 593-604. Frank, Robert H. (1994), Passions Within Reason: The Strategic Role of Emotions, New York, W.W. Norton. Frech, H. Edward III (1972), ‘The Public Choice Theory of Murray N. Rothbard: A Modern Anarchist’, 14 Public Choice, 143-154. Fried, Charles, Summers, Robert S., Tullock, Gordon and Arrow, Kenneth J. (1982), ‘Commentary on Hirshleifer Paper’, 4 Research in Law and Economics, 61-208. Friedman, David D. (1979), ‘Private Creation and Enforcement of Law: A Historical Case’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 399-415. Fudenberg, Drew and Maskin, Eric (1986), ‘The Folk Theorem in Repeated Games with Discounting or with Incomplete Information’, 54 Econometrica, 533-554. Fuller, Lon L. (1969), The Morality of Law. Revised Edition, New Haven, CT, Yale University Press. Galanter, Marc (1987), ‘Conceptualizing Legal Change and Its Effect: A Comment on George Priest’s “Measuring Legal Change”’, 3 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 235-241. Gauthier, David Peter (1986), Morals by Agreement, Oxford, Clarendon. Goldberg, Victor P. (1974), ‘Institutional Change and the Quasi-Invisible Hand’, 17 Journal of Law and Economics, 461-492. Reprinted in Goldberg, Victor P. (ed.) (1989), Readings in the Economics of Contract Law, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 169-173.
9500
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
623
Goodman, John C. (1978), ‘An Economic Theory of the Evolution of the Common Law’, 7 Journal of Legal Studies, 393-406. Gordon, Wendy J. (1992), ‘Of Harms and Benefits: Torts, Restitution, and Intellectual Property’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 449-482. Grady, Mark F. (1992), ‘Toward a Positive Economic Theory of Antitrust’, 30 Economic Inquiry, 225 ff. Grady, Mark F. (1995), ‘Legal Evolution and Precedent’, 3 Annual Review of Law and Ethics, 147 ff. Greif, Avner (1989), ‘Reputation and Coalitions in Medieval Trade: Evidence on the Maghribi Traders’, 49 Journal of Economic History, 857 ff. Hardin, Garrett (1968), ‘The Tragedy of the Commons’, 162 Science, 1243 ff. Harsanyi, John C. (1955), ‘Cardinal Welfare Individualistic Ethics, and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility’, 63 Journal of Political Economy, 315 ff. Hart, Herbert Lionel A. (1961), The Concept of Law, Oxford, Clarendon. Hayek, Friedrich A. von (1955), The Counterrevolution of Science, New York, NY, Free Press. Hayek, Friedrich A. von (1960), The Constitution of Liberty, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Hayek, Friedrich A. von (1967), ‘The Results of Human Action but not of Human Design’, in X (ed.), Studies in Philosophy, Politics and Economics, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Hayek, Friedrich A. von (1989), The Fatal Conceit, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Heiner, Ronald A. (1983), ‘Origin of Predictable Behavior’, 73 American Economic Review, 561-595. Hesse, Günter (1980), ‘Der Property-Rights-Ansatz. Eine ökonomische Theorie der Veränderung des Rechts? (The Property Rights Approach. An Economic Theory of Legal Change?)’, 195 Jahrbuch für Nationalökonomie und Statistik, 481 ff. Hesse, Günter (1983), ‘Zur Erklärung der Änderung von Handlungsrechten mit Hilfe der ökonomischen Theorie (The Explanation of the Change of Property Rights with Aid from Economic Theory)’, in Schüller, Alfred (ed.), Property Rights und Ökonomische Theorie, München, Vahlen, 79-109. Hirshleifer, Jack (1982), ‘Evolutionary Models in Economics and Law: Cooperation versus Conflict Strategies’, 4 Research in Law and Economics, 1-60. Hirshleifer, Jack and Coll Martinez, Juan Carlos (1988), ‘What Strategies can Support the Evolutionary Emergence of Cooperation?’, 32 Journal of Conflict Resolution, 367-398. Holmes, Oliver Wendell (1980), The Common Law, Boston, Little Brown. Hovenkamp, Herbert J. (1983), ‘The Economics of Legal History’, 67 Minnesota Law Review, 645-697. Huang, Peter H. and Wu, Ho-Mou (1994), ‘More Order without More Law: A Theory of Social Norms and Organizational Cultures’, 10 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 390-406. Jaffe, Austin J. (1988), ‘Toward an Evolutionary Theory of Trade Associations: The Case of Real Estate Appraisers’, 16 American Real Estate and Urban Economics Association Journal, 230-256. Janis, M.W. (1993), An Introduction to International Law, New York, Little Brown and Co..
624
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
9500
Josserand, L. (1937), Un Ordre Juridique Nouveau (A New Juridical Order), Dalloz, 41 p. Kelsen, Hans (1939), ‘Théorie du Droit International Coutumier’, 1 Revue Internationale de la Théorie du Droit (New Series), 263 ff. Kelsen, Hans (1945), General Theory of Law and State, New Jersey, Lawbook Exchange. Kennedy, Duncan (1981), ‘Cost-Reduction Theory as Legitimation’,90 Yale Law Journal, 1275-1283. Kitch, Edmund W. (1987), ‘Law and the Economic Order’, in Lipson, Leon and Wheeler, Stanton (eds), Law and the Social Sciences, New York, Russel Sage Foundation, 109-149. Kitch, Edmund W. (1991), ‘Business Organization Law: State or Federal?’, in Buxbaum, Richard M., Hertig, Gerard, Hirsch, Alain and Hopt, Klaus J. (eds), European Business Law, Berlin, Walter de Gruyter, 35 ff. Kitch, Edmund W. (1996), ‘Competition Between Securities Markets: Good or Bad?’, in X (ed.), The Future for the Securities Market: Legal and Regulatory Aspects, Oxford, Clarendon, 233 ff. Klein, B. (1996), ‘Why Hold-Ups Occur: The Self-Enforcing Range of Contractual Relationships’, 34 Economic Inquiry, 444 ff. Klein, B. and Leffler, K. (1981), ‘The Role of Market Forces in Assuring Contractual Performance’, 89 Journal of Political Economy, 615-641. Kobayashi, Bruce H. and Ribstein, Larry E. (1996), ‘Evolution and Spontaneous Uniformity: Evidence from the Evolution of the Limited Liability Company’, 34 Economic Inquiry. Kontou, N. (1994), The Termination and Revision of Treaties in the Light of New Customary International Law, Oxford, Clarendon. Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1992), ‘Are There Cracks in the Foundations of Spontaneous Order? Book Review of Ellickson, Order without Law’, 67 New York University Law Review, 647 ff. Kraus, Jody S. (1997), ‘Segal Design and the Evolution of Commercial Norms’, 16 Journal of Legal Studies, 377-411. Krauss, Michael I. (1994), ‘La Réglementation Contre le Marché dans le Développement de Normes (Regulation against the Market in Norms Formation)’, 5 Journal des Economistes et des Etudes Humaines, 573-599. Kronman, Anthony T. (1985), ‘Contract Law and the State of Nature’, 1 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 5-32. Kubasek, N. (1985), ‘The Artificiality of Economic Models as a Guide for Legal Evolution’, 33 Cleveland State Law Review, 505-512. Kunz, Harald (1985), ‘Zur Entstehung und Verhaltenswirkung sozialer Normen, mit einigen Argumenten für eine Ökonomisch rationale Kriminalpolitik (On the Evolution and the Incentive Effect of Social Norms, with Some Arguments for an Economic Rational Crime Policy)’, 68 Monatsschrift für Kriminologie und Strafsrechtsreform, 202-215. Larmore, Charles E. (1987), ‘Liberalism and the Neutrality of the State’, in Larmore, Charles E. (ed.), Patterns of Moral Complexity, Cambridge, New York. Lehmann, Michael (1982), ‘Ökonomie, Sozialbiologie - Humanwissenschaften. Über die Notwendigkeit und Möglichkeit einer interdisziplinären Grundlagenforschung (Economics, Social Biology - Human Sciences. About the Necessity and Possibility of an Interdisciplinary Fundamental Reform)’, Der Betriebs-Berater, 1997-2004. Lehmann, Michael (1986), ‘Evolution in Biologie, Ökonomie und Jurisprudenz (Evolution in Biology, Economics and Jurisprudence)’, 17 Rechtstheorie, 463-477.
9500
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
625
Lehmann, Michael (1993), ‘Das Prinzip Wettbewerb. Ein gemeinsames Gesetz der Evolution für Biologie, Ökonomie und Wirtschaftsrecht (The Competition Principle. A Common Law of Evolution for Biology. Economics and Commercial Law)’, in McGuire, Michael T. (ed.), Der Faktor Mensch im neuen Europa, Luchterhand, Neuwied et. al., 241-258. Leibenstein, Harvey (1982), ‘The Prisoners’ Dilemma in the Invisible Hand: An Analysis of Intrafirm Productivity’, 72 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 92 ff. Lemieux, Pierre (1983), Du Libéralisme à l’Anarcho-capitalisme (From Liberalism to Anarcho-Capitalism), Paris, Presses Universitaires de France (PUF). Lemieux, Pierre (1988), L’Anarcho-Capitalisme (What is Anarcho-Capitalism?), Paris, Presses Universitaires de France (PUF). Leoni, B. (1991), Freedom and the Law, 3rd edn, Indianapolis, Liberty Fund. Levy, D. (1988), ‘Utility-Enhancing Consumption Constraints’, 4 Economics and Philosophy, 69-88. Levy, D. (1992), ‘Adam Smith and the Texas A&M; Rats’, in Levy, D. (ed.), The Economic Ideas of Ordinary People: From Preferences to Trade, New York, NY, Routledge. Lewis, D. (1969), Convention: A Philosophical Study, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Leyd, L., Leydesdoff, L.A., Besselaar, P.V. and Allen, P.M. (1994), Evolutionary Economics and Chaos Theory: New Directions in Technology Studies, New York, St. Martin’s Press. Libecap, Gary D. (1978), ‘Economic Variables and the Development of the Law: The Case of Western Mineral Rights’, 38 Journal of Economic History, 338-362. Loasby, Brian J. (1976), Choice, Complexity, and Ignorance: An Enquiry into Economic Theory and the Practice of Decision-Making, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Mackaay, Ejan (1988), ‘L’Ordre Spontané Comme Fondement du Droit - un Survol des Modèles de l’Émergence des Règles dans une Société Civile (Spontaneous Order as Foundation of Law - A Survey of Models of the Emergence of Rules in Civil Society)’, 22 Revue Juridique Themis, 347-383. Mackaay, Ejan (1989), ‘L’Ordre Spontané comme Fondement du Droit - un Survol des Modèles de l’Emergence des Règles dans la Société Civile (Spontaneous Order as the Foundation of Law - A Survey of Models of the Emergence of Rules in Civil Society)’, 3 Revue Internationale de Droit Economique, 247-287. Mackaay, Ejan (1995), ‘Mededinging, Welvaart en Federalisme (Competition, Welfare and Federalism)’, in Kanning, Walter (ed.), Liber Amicorum voor Arnold Heertje, Leiden, Stenfert Kroese, 93-100. Mateesco, N.M. (1947), La Coutume dans les Cycles Juridiques Internationaux, Paris. McAdams, H. (1997), ‘The Origin, Development, and Regulation of Norms’, 96 Michigan Law Review, 338 ff. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1993), ‘Ritual and Regulation: A Legal Economic Interpretation of Selected Biblical Texts’, 22 Journal of Legal Studies, 477-501. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1993), ‘Contracts of Genesis’, 22 Journal of Legal Studies, 15-45. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1994), ‘The Legal-Economic Analysis of Comparative Civil Procedure, the Legal-Economic Approach to Biblical Interpretation’, 150 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 755 ff. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1995a), ‘Verbal Feud in the Hebrew Bible: Judges 3:12-30 and 19-21', 55 Journal of Near Eastern Studies, 105 ff.
626
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
9500
Miller, Geoffrey P. (1995b), ‘J as Constitutionalist: A Legal-Economic Interpretation of Exodus 17:8-16 and Related Texts’, 70 Chicago-Kent Law Review, 1829 ff. to be republished in Lindgren, James and Miller, Laurent Geoffrey (eds), Ancient Law: the New Learning (tentative title) (1996) Miller, Geoffrey P. (1996a), A Riposte Form in the Song of Deborah, Manuscript. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1996b), ‘Foreword: The Development of Ancient Near Eastern Law’, 70 Chicago-Kent Law Review, 1623 ff. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1996c), ‘Ancient Law: the New Learning (tentative title) (1996) Constitutionalist: A Legal-Economic Interpretation of Exodus 17:8-16 and Related Texts’, 70 Chicago-Kent Law Review, 1829 ff. To be republished in Lindgren, James and Miller, Lauren Geoffrey (eds). Miller, Geoffrey P. (1996d), ‘The Song of Deborah: A Legal-Economic Analysis’, 144 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 2293 ff. Miller, Geoffrey P. (1998), ‘A Riposte Form in the Song of Deborah’, in Frymer-Kensky, Tikva, Levinson, Bernard and Matthews, Victor (eds), Gender and Law in the Hebrew Bible and the Ancient Near East, Shefheld Academic Press. Miller, Geoffrey P., Lindgren, James and Laurent Mayali (1995), ‘Why Ancient Law?’, 70 Chicago-Kent Law Review, 1465 ff. Mueller, Dennis C. (1989), ‘A Just Social Contract’, in Mueller, Dennis C. (ed.), Public Choice II, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Noreau, Pierre (1993), Droit Préventif - Le Droit au-Delà de la Loi (Preventive Law - Law Beyond Legislation), Montréal, Éditions Thémis. O’Driscoll, Gerald P., Jr and Rizzo, Mario J. (1986), ‘Subjectivism, Uncertainty, and Rules’, in Kirzner, Israel M. (ed.), Subjectivism, Intelligibility and Economic Understanding. Essays in Honor of Ludwig M. Lachmann on his Eightieth Birthday, London, Macmillan, 252-267. Ott, Claus and Schäfer, Hans-Bernd (1991), Emergence and Construction of Efficient Rules in the Legal System of German Civil Law, Paper Presented at the European Law and Economics Association. Parisi, Francesco (1994), ‘Autonomy and Private Ordering in Contract Law’, 1 European Journal of Law and Economics, 213-227. Parisi, Francesco (1995), ‘Toward a Theory of Spontaneous Law’, 6 Constitutional Political Economy, 211-231. Parisi, Francesco (1996a), ‘Normative Knowledge and Self-Enforcing Rules in International Law’, 2 International Legal Theory, 27-30. Parisi, Francesco (1996b), ‘Law as a Voluntary Enterprise’, in Ratnapala, S. and Moens, G. (eds), The Jurisprudence of Liberty, London, Butterworths. Parisi, Francesco (1997), The Genesis of Liability in Ancient Law, George Mason University Law and Economics Working Paper Series, 97-07. Parisi, Francesco (1998a), ‘Customary Law’, in Newman, Peter (ed.), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law, New York, Macmillan, 572-578. Parisi, Francesco (1998b), ‘The Economics of Customary Law: Lessons From Evolutionary Socio-Biology’, in Ott, Claus and von Wangenheim, Georg (eds), Essays in Law and Economics IV, Antwerpen, Maklu, 245-269. Parisi, Francesco (1998c), ‘Opinio Iuris Revisited: A Law and Economics Perspective (Forthcoming)’, 4 International Legal Theory.
9500
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
627
Parisi, Francesco (1999), ‘The Cost of the Game: A Topology of Social Interactions (Forthcoming)’, European Journal of Law and Economics. Parisi, Francesco and Ribstein, Larry E. (1998), Choice of Law, New York, Macmillan. Pollock, F. (1929), First Book of Jurisprudence, 6th edn, London, Macmillan. Popper, Karl R. (1995), The Open Society and Its Enemies, 5th edn, London, Routledge. Posner, Eric A. (1996a), ‘Law, Economics and Inefficient Norms’, 145 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1697-1744. Posner, Eric A. (1996b), ‘Norms, Formalities, and the Statute of Frauds: A Comment’, 144 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1971 ff. Posner, Richard A. (1980), ‘A Theory of Primitive Society, with Special Reference to Law’, 23 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-53. Posner, Richard A. (1981), The Economics of Justice, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 415 p. Priest, George L. (1981), ‘The New Scientism in Legal Scholarship: A Comment on Clark and Posner’, 90 Yale Law Journal, 1284-1295. Priest, George L. (1987), ‘Measuring Legal Change’, 3 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 193-225. Prigogine, Ilya and Stengers, Isabelle (1984), Order Out of Chaos: Man’s New Dialogue with Nature, Boulder, CO, New Science Library. Rapoport, Anatol (1987), ‘Prisoner’s Dilemma’, in X (ed.), The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, New York, McGraw-Hill. Rawls, John (1971), A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Raz, J. (1986), The Morality of Freedom, Oxford, Clarendon. Reese, David A. (1989), ‘Does the Common Law Evolve?’, 12 Hamline Law Review, 321-353. Ress, G. (1994), ‘Ex Ante Safeguards Against Ex Post Opportunism in International Treaties: Theory and Practice of International Public Law’, 150 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 279-303. Ribstein, Larry E. and Kobayashi, Bruce H. (1995), ‘Uniform Laws, Model Laws and Limited Liability Companies’, 66 University of Colorado Law Review, 947-999. Ribstein, Larry E. and Kobayashi, Bruce H. (1996), ‘An Economic Analysis of Uniform State Laws’, 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 131-199. Ridley, Matt (1997), Origins of Virtue: Human Instincts and the Evolution of Cooperation, New York, Viking. Rizzo, Mario J. (1980), ‘Symposium: Change in the Common Law: Legal and Economic Perspectives. A Symposium Sponsored by The Institute for Humane Studies and the Liberty Fund’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 189-427. Roe, Mark J. (1996), ‘Chaos and Evolution in Law and Economics’, 109 Harvard Law Review, 641-668. Rubin, Paul H. (1982), ‘Symposium: Evolutionary Models in Economics and Law’, 4 Research in Law and Economics, 218 ff. Rubin, Paul H. (1983), Business Firms and the Common Law. The Evolution of Efficient Rules, New York, Praeger, 189 p. Rubin, Paul H. (1993), ‘Private Mechanisms for the Creation of Efficient Institutions for Market Economies’, in Somogyi, Laszlo (ed.), The Political Economy of The Transition Process in Eastern Europe, Cheltenham, Edward Elgar.
628
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
9500
Rubin, Paul H. (1994), ‘Growing A Legal System in the Post-Communist Economies’, 27 Cornell International Law Journal, 1-47. Rubin, Paul H. (1996), Promises, Promises: Contracts in Russia and Other Post-Communist Economies, Shaftesbury Papers, Edward Elgar and the Locke Institute. Rubin, Paul H. (in press), Growing a Legal System, with Special Reference to the Post-Communist Economies’ Center for International Reform and the Informal Sector, Working Paper, No. 63. Rubin, Paul H. and Tesche, Jean (in press), ‘Enforcement of Agreements in Russia, in the Rule of Law and Economic Reform in Russia’, in Sachs, Jeffrey (ed.), Boulder, Westview Press, 912 ff. Ruhl, J.B. and Ruhl, H.J., Jr (1997), ‘The Arrow of the Law in Modern Administrative States: Using Complexity Theory to Reveal the Diminishing Returns and Increasing Risks the Burgeoning of Law Poses to Society’, 30 University of California at Davis Law Review, 405 ff. Salmond, J.W. (1966), Jurisprudence (12th edn), London, Sweet & Maxwell. Santagata, Walter (1995), ‘Istituzioni per il Mercato dell’Arte: Artisti e Mercanti tra Regole, Convenzioni e Allocazioni dei Diritti (Institutions for the Market of Works of Art: Artists and Merchants among Rules, Conventions and Allocation of Rights)’, Economia Pubblica, 87-115. Savatier René (1959), Les Méthamorphoses Economiques et Sociales du Droit Civil Aujourd’hui (The Economic and Sociologic Metamorphoses of Civil Law Today). Schlicht, Ekkehart (1993), ‘Koordinationskosten und “Social Capital” (Co-ordination Costs and Social Capital)’, in Schlieper, Ulrich and Schmidtchen, Dieter (eds), Makro, Geld & Institutionen, Tübingen, 95-100. Schmidt Trenz, Hans Jorg and Schmidtchen, Dieter (1994), ‘Theorie optimaler Rechtsräume. Die Regulierung sozialer Beziehungen durch die Kontrolle von Territorium (Theory of Optimum Legal Areas)’, 13 Jahrbuch für Neue Politische Ökonomie, 7-29. Schmidtchen, Dieter (1995), ‘Die Zwillingsideen der Evolution und der spontanen Bildung einer Ordnung (The Twin Ideas of Evolution and Spontaneous Order)’, in Francke, H.-H. (ed.), Ökonomischer Individualismus und Freiheitliche Verfassung, Freiburg, 239-271. Schotter, Andrew (1981), Economic Theory of Social Institutions, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Schwartz, Warren F. et al. (1984), ‘The Duel: Can These Gentlement be Acting Efficiently?’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 321 ff. Scott Kenneth E. (1994), ‘Bounded Rationality and Social Norms’, 150 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 315-319. Selten, Reinhard (1978), ‘The Chain-Store Paradox’, 9 Theory and Decision, 127-159. Sen, Amartya K. (1979), ‘Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioural Foundations of Economic Theory’, in Hahn, F. and Hollis, M. (eds), Philosophy and Economic Theory, Oxford, Clarendon. Shubik, Martin (1987), Game Theory in the Social Sciences: Concepts and Solutions, 4th edn, Boston, MA, The MIT Press. Shughart, William F., II and Tollison, Robert D. (1985), ‘Corporate Chartering: An Exploration in the Economics of Legal Change’, 23 Economic Inquiry, 585-599. Simpson, Alfred William Brian (1979), ‘The Horwitz Thesis and the History of Contracts’, 46 University of Chicago Law Review, 533-601.
9500
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
629
Smith, James Charles (1977), ‘Book Review of Morton J. Horwitz the Transformation of American Law (1780-1860)’, 53 Wisconsin Law Review, 1253-1276. Stearns, M.L. (1994), ‘The Misguided Renaissance of Social Choice’, 103 Yale Law Journal, 1219 ff. Terrebonne, R. Peter (1981), ‘A Strictly Evolutionary Model of Common Law’, 10 Journal of Legal Studies, 397-407. Tietzel, Manfred (1986), ‘Zur Entstehung des Privateigentums (On the Evolution of Private Property)’, 37 Ordo, 105-127. Trakman, Leon E. (1983), The Law Merchant: The Evolution of Commercial Law, Littleton, CO, Fred B. Rothman and Company. Tucker, A.W. (1950), A Two-Person Dilemma, Unpublished manuscript. Reprinted in: Straffin, P. (1980) ‘The Prisoner’s Dilemma’, UMAP Journal, 101 ff. Tullock, Gordon (1987), Private Wants, Public Means - An Economic Analysis of the Desirable Scope of Government, Lanham (MD), University Press of America. Tunkin, G.I. (1961), ‘Remarks on the Juridical Nature of Customary Norms in International Law’, 49 California Law Review, 419 ff. Turnbull, Shann (1977), Impact of Mining Royalties on Aboriginal Communities in the Northern Territory, First Report, Parliamentary Paper, Canberra, Australian Government Publishing Service, No. 135/1978, Oct.. Turnbull, Shann (1978), Economic Development of Aboriginal Communities in the Northern Territory Second Report, Self-sufficiency (with Land Rights), Parliamentary Paper, Canberra, Australian Government Publishing Service, No. 438/1978. Turnbull, Shann (1980), Economic Development of Aboriginal Communities in the Northern Territory: A Study in Two Parts, Department of Aboriginal Affairs, Canberra, Australian Government Publishing Service. Turnbull, Shann (1986), ‘When Land Owns People’, 43 (4) Et cetera: A Review of General Semantics, 389-392. Udehn, Lars (1996), The Limits of Public Choice: A Sociological Critique of the Economic Theory of Politics, London, Routledge. Ullman-Margalit, Edna (1977), The Emergence of Norms, Oxford, Clarendon. Vanberg, Viktor J. (1993), ‘Rational Choice, Rule-Following and Institutions: An Evolutionary Perspective’, in Gustafson, B., Knudsen, C. and Maki, U. (eds), Rationality, Institutions and Economic Methodology, London, Routledge, 171-200. Vaughn, Karen I. (1982), Can Democratic Society Reform Itself: The Limits of Constructive Change, George Mason University Working Paper. Versteeg, J. Russell (1989), ‘Law and the Security of Homeric Society (A Response to Richard A. Posner)’, 10 Journal of Legal History, 265-284. Voigt, Stefan (1991), ‘Die Evolutionsorientierte Theorie der Verfassung - Bemerkungen zum Ansatz von Hayeks (The Evolutionary Theory of Constitution. Remarks on Hayek’s Approach)’, 40 Zeitschrift für Wirtschaftspolitik, 93-107. Voigt, Stefan (1993), ‘On the Internal Consistency of Hayek’s Evolutionary oriented Constitutional Economics - Some General Remarks’, 3 Journal des Economistes et des Etudes Humaines, 461-476. Wagner, Richard E. (1992), ‘Crafting Social Rules: Common Law vs. Statute Law, Once Again’, 3 Constitutional Political Economy, 381 ff. Walden, R.M. (1977), ‘The Subjective Element in the Formation of Customary International Law’, 12 Israel Law Review, 344 ff.
630
Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law
9500
Waldron, Jeremy (1993), ‘Theoretical Foundations of Liberalism’, in Waldron, Jeremy (ed.), Liberal Rights: Collected Papers, 1981-1991, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Wangenheim, Georg v. (1995), Die Evolution von Recht. Ursachen und Wirkungen haeufigkeitsabhaengigen Verhaltens in der Rechtsfortbildung (The Evolution of Law. Causes and Effects of Frequency Dependend Behaviour in Legal Evolution), Tübingen, Mohr/Siebeck. Warren, Elizabeth (1981), ‘Trade Usage and Parties in the Trade: An Economic Rationale for an Inflexible Rule’, 42 University of Pittsburgh Law Review, 515 ff. Watrin, Christian (1996), ‘Der Wettbewerb der Ordnungen als Entdeckungsverfahren für eine nachhaltige Entwicklung (Korreferat) (Sustainable Development and Competition Among Economic Systems as a Discovery Process)’, in Gerken, Lüder (ed.), Ordnungspolitische Grundfragen einer Politik der Nachhaltigkeit/Walter Eucken Institut, Baden-Baden, 103-113. Weber, M. (1978), Economy and Society, Berkeley, University of California Press. Weise, Peter (1996), ‘Verhaltenskoordination durch soziale Normen und Kräfte (Co-ordination of Behaviour by Social Norms and Forces)’, in Priddat, B.P. and Wegner, G. (eds), Zwischen Institution und Evolution. Neue Ansätze in der ökonomischen Theorie, Marburg, Metropolis, 187-209. Weise, Peter and Eger, Thomas (1995), ‘Die Evolution von Normen aus Unordnung, Ein synergetisches Modell (The Evolution of Norms out of Disorder, A Synergetic Model)’, 11 Ökonomie und Gesellschaft, 192-209. Williams, Stephen F. (1980), ‘The Static Conception of the Common Law: A Comment’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 277-289. Williamson, O.E. (1983), ‘Credible Commitments: Using Hostages to Support Exchange’, 73 American Economic Review, 519 ff. Wilson, James Q. (1993), The Moral Sense, New York, NY, Free Press. Witt, Ulrich (1986), ‘Evolution and Stability of Cooperation without Enforceable Contracts’, 39 Kyklos, 245-266. Witt, Ulrich (1988), ‘Eine Individualistische Theorie der Entwicklung Ökonomischer Institutionen (An Individualistic Theory of the Evolution of Economic Institutions)’, 9 Jahrbuch für Neue Politische Ökonomie, 72-95. Wolfke, K. (1993), Custom in Present International Law, 2nd edn, Amsterdam, Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Cases Fisheries Jurisdiction (U.K. v. Ice), 1974 I.C.J. 3 (July 25). North Sea Continental Shelf (F.R.G. v. Den.) (F.R.G. v. Neth.), 1969 I.C.J. 3 (Feb. 20). Asylum (Colom. v. Peru), 1950 I.C.J. 266, 275, 277 (Nov. 20). S.S. Wimbledon, 1923 P.C.I.J. (ser. A), No. 1, at 25.
9600 CONFLICT OF LAWS AND CHOICE OF LAW Erin Ann O’Hara and Larry E. Ribstein George Mason University School of Law © Copyright 1999 Erin Ann O’Hara and Larry E. Ribstein
Abstract We discuss the law and economics of conflict of laws and choice of law, focusing on the law in the US. We first consider choice of law when the parties have not effectively chosen their governing law by contract. We address four questions: (1) Why do courts ever apply anything other than the law of the forum? (2) If a court sometimes applies foreign law, is a rule-based or more modern standard-based approach to its choice preferable? (3) Why have so many states abandoned rule-based approaches in favor of standard-based ones? and (4) Is there any real practical difference between the First Restatement and modern approaches? We then discuss costs and benefits of enforcing parties’ contractual choice of law provisions. We conclude that permitting parties to choose the governing law that best fits their transactions and future private disputes can enhance jurisdictional competition and help restore predictability to the conflict of laws problem. JEL classification: K33 Keywords: Conflict of Laws, Choice of Law, Private International Law
1. Introduction When a legal dispute involves parties, property or events located in more than one government jurisdiction, and the substantive laws of those jurisdictions differ, whose substantive laws govern the rights and obligations of the parties? As barriers to migration and trade between jurisdictions fall, choice of law increasingly complicates transaction and litigation planning and provides new opportunities for private ordering. Until approximately forty years ago, all courts in the United States applied the territorial rules embodied in the First Restatement of Conflicts when they resolved inter-jurisdictional disputes. The rules, which address most litigation subjects, are premised on a ‘vested rights’ theory. A party’s rights vest, if at all, at a particular place and point in time. Only that state has the power to create the rights relied on by the plaintiff (Beale, 1935; Brilmayer, 1995). Tort issues, for example, are governed by the law of the ‘place of the wrong’, which is defined for a variety of tortious activities. Contract validity, necessary forms, 631
632
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
9600
and substantial performance issues are treated according to the law of the place of contracting, while details of performance are governed by the place of performance. Property issues are resolved according to the law of the situs of the property (Restatement (First) Conflict of Laws, 1934). Accordingly, although an interstate dispute is litigated in a Massachusetts court, the court might apply the substantive law of another state to resolve that dispute. Several decades ago, however, conflicts scholars began increasingly to criticize the territorial approach to choice of law. The First Restatement Rules were condemned as arbitrary, because there is no a priori reason why states’ powers should stop at their borders as prescribed by vested rights theory (Brilmayer, 1995). Indeed, conflicts scholars searched the case law for places where the choice of law under the First Restatement led to intuitively unsatisfying results (Cavers, 1933; Currie, 1958a, 1958b; Ehrenzweig, 1956). Tort immunities as applied to common domiciliaries is one such place (Ely, 1981). Under the First Restatement, a husband’s ability to recover for an injury caused by his wife’s negligence while they were on vacation in another state is governed by the law of the place of the injury, even though the marital domicile is the only state which really has an interest in compensating this husband or preserving this family’s harmony. As another example, some have advocated a place of sale rule for products liability cases to better enable manufacturers to charge customers for the varying levels of care and liability they are subject to in differing places. Because products can be moved anywhere, the First Restatement’s place of injury rule ends up causing customers in states with lesser tort protections to help pay for the increased tort protections of customers in other states (Kozyris, 1987; McConnell, 1988; O’Hara and Ribstein, 1997; Solomine, 1989). Defenders of the First Restatement dismissed these occasional unsatisfying results and instead focussed on the general benefits of rules. Rules promote predictability, uniformity, ease of application, and judicial restraint, while discouraging forum-shopping (Reese, 1972; Rosenberg, 1968). In reality, however, a number of ‘escape devices’ sometimes enabled courts to avoid First Restatement rules when they really wanted to. One method found in every rule-based system is characterization (North and Fawcett, 1992): how the forum court characterized a case, as one of tort or contract for example, determines the choice of law. Where ambiguities arose, judges were free to choose a more preferred governing law. In addition, a public policy exception in the First Restatement permitted courts to avoid applying any foreign law that violated the public policy of the forum. Critics argued that these and other escape devices deprived the First Restatement rules of the very benefits they purported to confer (Brilmayer, 1995). As discussed later in this section, however, subsequent empirical studies cast some doubt on the strength of critics’ claims.
9600
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
633
In any event, critics argued that courts should replace the rule-based approach with a more sensible basis for choosing governing law. As detailed later in this section, some advocated maximizing the ability of states to give effect to important policies, while others promoted the use of the better or more ‘progressive’ states’ laws. Still others proffered personal rights-based approaches to choice of law. Most of the critics favored standard over rule-based approaches. As a consequence of widespread First Restatement criticism, a significant majority of US state courts have abandoned the traditional approach in favor of one of several alternative approaches to choice of law. As of 1989, only fourteen US states purported to follow the First Restatement (Solomine, 1989), and each of the others has adopted one of at least four alternative approaches. Consensus has clearly disappeared. Part A will consider four questions regarding choice of law when the parties have not effectively chosen their governing law by contract. First, why do courts ever apply anything other than the law of the forum? Second, if a court sometimes applies foreign law, is a rule-based or standard-based approach to its choice preferable? Third, why have so many states abandoned rule-based approaches in favor of standard-based ones? Finally, is there any real practical difference between the First Restatement and modern approaches? After all, if the standard-based choices do not differ systematically in practice from the First Restatement, the academic debate seems irrelevant. Moving to contractual choice of law, Part B discusses the costs and benefits of enforcing parties’ choice of law. Permitting parties to choose the governing law that best fits their transactions and future private disputes can enhance jurisdictional competition and help restore predictability to the conflicts of law problem. As indicated in this Introduction, we focus on choice of law by US states. The same basic economic principles apply, of course, to international choice of law. Although a detailed examination is beyond the scope of this article, we note some international comparisons and implications at relevant points of our article. We also note at the outset that choice of law within the US may have very different implications from choice of law in Europe given legal harmonization under European Community directives and regulations. Nor do we discuss arbitration. An arbitration clause in an agreement is a type of forum selection. The choice of law governing the agreement may be as significant as choice of law in other contexts. On the other hand, the arbitrator may not be bound to apply any specific body of law, especially under the European approach of ‘de-localised’ arbitration (Dicey, 1980, pp. 583-585).
634
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
9600
A. The Conflict of Laws Problem 2. Forum Law: The Costs and Benefits Forum law has at least two efficiency advantages over applying foreign law. First, it is easier to ascertain. Because the judges and lawyers who are licensed to practice in the jurisdiction have previously made significant capital investments learning the details of forum law, the costs of applying that law to any given case are generally lower than the alternatives. Second, the precedent created by applying forum law provides valuable information to primary actors as well as courts and litigators regarding future legal treatment of the issues. In contrast, an investment in foreign law is less valuable locally because foreign precedent is less binding and therefore less important in guiding local conduct or judicial decisions (Thiel, 1996). An interesting question thus arises: why should a court ever apply the laws of another state? One reason is to enhance predictability. If actors can rely on the application of the law of a particular state, they can structure transactions and other activities and avoid inappropriate or inefficient laws. This, in turn, forces states to internalize the costs of inferior laws, thereby promoting competition among jurisdictions for more efficient substantive rules (O’Hara and Ribstein, 1997). Ex ante reliance on Delaware corporations law, for example, is only attainable if New York courts commit themselves to applying Delaware law to the internal affairs of a Delaware corporation. A lex fora approach to choice of law therefore impedes pre-litigation predictability. Conflicts scholars have, however, questioned the benefits of predictability by doubting whether people respond to differing legal standards in such contexts as accidents and child abuse (Sterk, 1994; Symposium, 1997). If governing laws do not provide marginal deterrent value in these contexts, then ex ante predictability is not sufficiently valuable to justify the increased costs of applying foreign law. On the other hand, empirical evidence indicates that governing tort standards do affect aggregate behavior (Bruce, 1984; Landes, 1982; Landes and Posner, 1987). In particular, repeat players, including manufacturers and insurance companies, pay careful attention to differing laws. Moreover, the actual uncertainty created when the plaintiff can forum-shop for the applicable law is debatable. Actors can predict that disputes will likely be governed by the most plaintiff-favoring law in the set of possible fora for disputes. And, even if parties cannot be certain which forum will ultimately be chosen, in the event of litigation they can proceed with probabilistic expectations. Although the outcome of a plaintiff’s forum-shopping law may not be very predictable ex ante in many circumstances, it is often not clearly less predictable than anticipating what law a court will apply under default choice of law standards which, as discussed below, can be vague and open-ended.
9600
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
635
Another disadvantage to a forum law rule is that it encourages forum-shopping which can produce inefficiencies. Differing substantive laws create disparities across jurisdictions regarding plaintiffs’ expected gains from litigation. Forum shopping is generally regarded as skewing the litigation process toward plaintiffs and distributing litigation unevenly across jurisdictions (Sterk, 1994). States with more plaintiff-favoring laws end up being swamped with litigation, while lawyers in states with relatively more defendant-protecting laws face a lower demand for their services. A third reason for applying foreign law is to take advantage of foreign jurisdictions’ comparative regulatory advantages (Posner, 1992; O’Hara and Ribstein, 1997). Suppose, for example, that a South Carolina driver collides with a Florida driver in New York City. Presumably New York adopts traffic and tort laws to encourage an optimal level of care in New York. If a defendant is sued in South Carolina and the court applies South Carolina traffic and tort laws to the suit, then the effectiveness of New York’s laws are watered down, given that drivers from all over the country traverse the streets of New York. If everyone is subject to New York standards of liability, then New York can better tinker with its own laws to encourage the standard of care it seeks. Brilmayer (1995, p. 15) describes the tendency of courts across the world to sometimes consider foreign law as ‘virtually universal’. In the US, only two states, Kentucky and Michigan, explicitly embrace a lex fora approach (Solomine, 1989). Indeed, the United States Supreme Court has held that application of forum law is unconstitutional if the forum has no substantial interest or connection to the litigation (Home Insurance Co. v. Dick). This result is supported by our conclusion that the benefits of predictability, regulatory efforts and jurisdictional competition probably outweigh the costs of applying forum law in many interstate contexts.
3. Rule vs. Standard-based Approaches Assuming that a court should sometimes apply foreign law, should choice of law decisions be based on rules or a standard? Rules provide predictability, enhance planning and help ensure uniform treatment of similarly situated litigants. In contrast, standards are often better at generating just results in individual cases. Because the costs of overdeterrence and underdeterrence can differ according to the context, rules may be preferable in some areas, while standards may be preferable in others. As mentioned earlier, the First Restatement rules seemed arbitrary in some contexts. But will a standard-based approach improve choice of law overall? And if a standard-based approach is preferable, what should the governing standard be? States that have abandoned the First Restatement have usually
636
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
9600
adopted one of three alternative standards: (1) Leflar’s ‘better law’; (2) interest analysis; or (3) the ‘most significant relationship’ test. Leflar (1966a, 1966b) says that courts should give significant weight to the ‘better law’ when faced with the choice, and the better law is generally the one that achieves the most justice, which is courts’ primary obligation. Interest analysts advocate that choice of law should advance state policies behind their laws. Each state thinks its laws are ‘better’ in general. Consequently, courts should determine which states have an interest in applying their laws to this dispute, given the domiciles of the parties and the location of property and events leading to litigation. As originally conceived, states intend to protect or compensate only their own domiciliaries with their laws, not foreign residents. And a state has a regulatory interest in conduct occurring only within its borders. Brainard Currie, the originator of interest analysis, argued that the forum always should apply its own law when it is ‘interested’ in the outcome of the dispute. If no state has an interest in the outcome, the forum should still apply its own law because it is cheaper than applying foreign law. Foreign law should be applied only when the foreign state is interested and the forum state is disinterested (Currie, 1959). Baxter (1963), offered an alternative ‘balance of state interests’ approach. Under this approach, courts should use interest analysis to maximize the joint effectuation of state policies. If two or more states are ‘interested’ in the outcome of a dispute, a court should determine which state stands to lose most if its policies are ignored, and then apply the law of that state. In other words, in the face of a conflict, Baxter proposed that courts minimize social costs, as those costs are perceived by the individual interested states. The drafters of the Second Restatement took a third approach. They concluded that courts should apply the law of the state with ‘the most significant relationship’ to the parties, property and events involved in the dispute. In making this determination, courts should consider a number of factors, including ‘the needs of the interstate and international systems’; ‘the relevant policies of the forum’; ‘the relevant policies of other interested states and the relative interests of those states in the determination of the particular issue’; ‘the protection of justified expectations’; ‘the basic policies underlying the particular field of law’; ‘certainty, predictability and uniformity of result’; and ‘ease in the determination and application of the law to be applied’ (Restatement (Second) Conflict of Laws, 1971). This test approach is similar to the ‘most significant relationship’ test used in Europe, except that the latter provides somewhat more guidance in selecting the applicable jurisdiction (Scoles and Hay, pp. 45-47). Each of the three standards used in American courts has significant problems. Leflar’s approach allows judges significant leeway for application of outcome-determinative choice of law rules. Moreover, judges’ varying
9600
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
637
preferences undermine predictability. The same can be said of the Second Restatement test, which gives no indication of how much weight to give to each of the numerous factors (Brilmayer, 1995). Interest analysis is more complicated. The narrow range of state interests recognized by Currie fails adequately to promote the purported goal of the standard. A state’s substantive goals reach far beyond compensating its plaintiffs or protecting its defendants. Often a state is attempting to achieve a sensitive balance between competing interests. Viewing the state’s interests behind its substantive laws ignores important choice of law concerns such as protecting party expectations and interstate harmony and preventing forum shopping (Brilmayer, 1980). On the other hand, while modern interest analysts advocate considering the state’s true interests behind its laws (Kramer, 1990, 1991a, 1991b), this reduces any predictability the approach might otherwise provide (Brilmayer, 1995) since many factors can motivate state decision making. Moreover, the idea of state interests becomes problematic from a public choice perspective (O’Hara and Ribstein, 1997). States are not monolithic entities. Individual legislators vote for very different reasons, and the state government officials, including judges, who influence the application of the laws have their own concerns. Interest groups that lobby for laws are often trying to achieve purposes very different from the ‘public policies’ stated by the legislators themselves. Baxter’s comparative impairment approach to interest analysis further complicates the choice. Baxter advocates applying the law of the state with the most to lose if its laws are ignored. However, this calculation is often impossible. Suppose, for example, that two states have interests in applying their laws to a contract dispute. Under State A’s laws, spendthrifts can void their contracts. Under State B’s laws, spendthrifts contracts are enforceable against the spendthrifts. C, a spendthrift from state A, borrows money from D, a creditor from state B. C fails to repay the loan and D sues to enforce the loan contract. Under interest analysis, state B has an ‘interest’ in compensating its creditor, while State A has an interest in protecting its spendthrift. Which state’s policy suffers greater impairment if its laws are ignored? If such conflicts arise frequently, at least one of the states necessarily will end up having difficulty protecting its residents. The standard-based approaches have proved unsatisfying. A better solution might be to retain the First Restatement rules with periodic modifications to avoid frequent arbitrary results. Indeed, Posner (1992) has argued that the First Restatement, for all its faults, had the virtue of enabling states to exercise their comparative regulatory advantages. For example, by defining and then applying the ‘place of the wrong’ to tort suits, states usually could apply their laws to tortious conduct within their states, and could therefore ensure that actors took optimal levels of care. The First Restatement situs rule for property enabled the
638
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
9600
state where the land was located to regulate its use. Title questions are also resolved by the law of the place of property, a clear rule easing the tracking of titles and therefore facilitating the transfer of property to its highest valued use. Finally, contract validity issues are governed by the place of contracting, and the detailed rules tended to protect those who contract within their own borders. Those who reached across borders were on notice of being subject to the differing protections outside their states. The rule minimized the costs of gathering personal and legal information for those, such as consumers, who transacted business locally. Details of performance were governed by the state with the greatest regulatory concern, where those details were to be performed. The choice between rules and standards also may be viewed from a contractual perspective. Part B, below, discusses the enforcement of express choice of law clauses. A related issue is the appropriate default rules to supply in the absence of express contract in order to facilitate private bargaining. Standards provide ‘tailored’ defaults that fit specific situations, while rules provide ‘untailored’ defaults that apply across a range of cases (Ayres, 1993). In general, untailored rules can reduce contracting costs by decreasing uncertainty as to the rule applied in the absence of contracting. Tailored defaults, by attempting to anticipate the parties’ actual preferences, can reduce the need for costly customized contracting (Whincop and Keyes, 1998, pp. 525-526). But untailored choice-of-law rules, because they only choose legal systems rather than specific rules, may actually do a good job of anticipating the parties’ preferences in the usual case, as distinguished from the odd cases courts actually decide (Whincop and Keyes, 1998, Ch. 3). Any choice of law approach should take into account concerns for harmonizing state interests, protecting party expectations, minimizing costs of legal information, as well as allowing states to exercise their comparative regulatory advantages. But a rule-based system under which the drafters take these concerns into account to the extent feasible also could promote uniformity and thereby minimize forum shopping. Compared to the standard-based alternatives that have received court attention, the First Restatement likely provides much greater predictability despite its escape devices, and would be even better if these devices were narrowed.
4. Coordination Problems with Rule-Based Approaches If the First Restatement approach to choice of law is so superior, why have most states abandoned it? In other words, why have the states been unable in recent decades to coordinate choice of law to achieve increased uniformity and predictability? Unless the states collectively adopt or retain choice of law rules, the primary benefits of those rules are lost. A few conflicts scholars have
9600
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
639
advocated a return to a rule-based approach that would yield net benefits across states, perhaps with legislative encoding of a new Restatement to foster cooperation (Rosenberg, 1981; Scoles and Hay, 1992). But individual rules do not always benefit the state or judge that is supposed to follow them, and interstate enforcement problems may have led to the breakdown of choice of law rules. In other words, courts face an unresolved prisoner’s dilemma in the choice of law context. In general, as the late Judge Breitel once explained in an unpublished speech (Sterk, 1994), judges first ask themselves who deserves to win. Then they assess how much cost to jurisprudence is likely imposed if they manipulate the system to get that outcome. If costs will be borne by future worthy litigants, judges will apply rules with less preferred outcomes for the present litigants. In other words, future litigants constrain judges in the present case to a general application of rules, including procedural ones. Judges who are nevertheless tempted to violate the precedents of other judges are constrained by reputational sanctions imposed by colleagues and higher courts (O’Hara, 1993). But choice of law is different. Issues arise in many factual contexts involving people and events from different places, and sufficiently infrequently that the specific issue seldom arises again. Because the precedential value of a given choice of law decision is quite limited, costs to future litigants of reduced predictability in that factual context are slight. And colleagues and higher courts are much less likely to attempt to vigilantly protect choice of law precedents than they are to protect precedents that shape forum substantive law. Even if rules are generally preferred to standards, formulating a comprehensive set that leaves all states better off than they are under choice of law anarchy might prove difficult to formulate (Sterk, 1994). Perhaps more importantly, judges are always tempted to defect from individual rules in favor of local litigants (Hay, 1992), or to apply more easily ascertained local laws. While other states may suffer as a consequence, they are unlikely to pressure the deciding state to prevent these defections. The classic tit-for-tat enforcement strategies (Axelrod, 1984) would be difficult to implement, especially because monitoring of other states’ choice of law decisions is costly. Even with monitoring, escape devices allow states in some contexts to defect while feigning cooperation under the rules. When defections are difficult to detect, enforcement becomes much more difficult, and bargains are likely to unravel for at least a while (Friedman, 1971; Green and Porter, 1984). Moreover, it might be years before an interstate dispute arises in the disadvantaged state enabling retaliation against the state that originally defected. Larger plaintiff-favoring states, which were the first to abandon the First Restatement, have more opportunity to defect because they handle a larger volume of interstate litigation.
640
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
9600
In a few areas where cooperation among the states really matters, interstate compacts have been formed on a piecemeal basis. For example, state taxation of corporations and child custody disputes are now treated with relatively uniform choice of law provisions. Where cooperation is important but has proven unsuccessful, Congress can step in and federalize the substantive law, as it has done, for example, regarding both bankruptcy and products liability for vaccine manufacturers. For better or worse, choice of law problems are mooted once the federal government imposes uniform federal laws. Finally, private parties can enhance predictability and uniformity to some extent with choice of law provisions in their contracts (Kobayashi and Ribstein, 1998). What is left may not be worth coordinating, at least on the grand scale of a new Restatement. Of course, some coordination persists in smaller rural states. The First Restatement states are clustered together in the south, including Maryland, Virginia, West Virginia, Tennessee, Alabama, North Carolina, South Carolina and Georgia (Solomine, 1989). These states share a relatively distinct economy and culture that may limit a majority of interactions to people and events in one of the other First Restatement states, perhaps enhancing cooperation. Alternatively, coordination in these states may have more to do with a shared conservative legal culture. In any event, it is not surprising that the First Restatement broke down across a majority of states as legal realism permeated the law, beginning with the larger, plaintiff-favoring states. The benefits to achieving preferred results in individual cases outweighed the costs to individual judges’ preferences of ignoring the settled choice of law rules.
5. Do the Choice of Law Approaches Matter in Practice? The academic debate over choice of law loses relevance if court decisions do not vary significantly under the alternative regimes. Some commentators have suggested that the approaches to choice of law followed within the US make no difference in the end. (This does not, of course, apply to the different choice of law approaches in the international setting.) Sterk (1994), for example, argues that courts care about ensuring that deserving parties win their cases. In contrast, the choice-of-law theorists concern themselves with a host of issues that do not concern the courts. The courts therefore cannot be expected to take any of the approaches seriously. In fact, Leflar (1977) points out his casual impression that courts often make a choice of law determination, and then rely on the choice of law theories that support the court’s conclusion. Even assuming that each state is committed to a single choice of law approach, systematic differences in chosen law between the modern approaches might be difficult to detect, if the modern approaches leave judges effectively unconstrained. One might predict, then, that results differ between First
9600
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
641
Restatement states and states adopting modern approaches, but not among states that have adopted each of the modern approaches. Alternatively, if First Restatement escape devices also leave judges unconstrained, then no differences among states would be found based on choice of law approach. It has also been suggested that the modern approaches are more pro-resident, pro-forum, and pro-recovery in principle than the relatively neutral First Restatement (Brilmayer, 1980) and that, because each of the modern approaches rests on theoretically distinct grounds, some of the modern approaches display these biases more than others (Borchers, 1992). Three empirical papers have attempted to test for systematic differences across states according to choice of law approaches for torts. Solomine (1989) studied 227 cases retrieved from a Westlaw computer search of all published US state supreme court and federal court of appeal cases that explicitly reviewed choice of law determinations in torts. He compared those decisions made according to the First Restatement with those decided according to one of the modern theories. Solomine found that the modern theories resulted in choices of law that were more likely to favor residents, recovery and forum law than did the First Restatement. It may seem surprising that Solomine would find differences across jurisdictions, at least with regard to recovery-favoring rules. After all, Priest and Klein (1984) demonstrated convincingly that disputes that are actually litigated are biased toward those that are on the margin. Plaintiff win rates should tend toward 50 percent. Even if they vary due to asymmetric information or stakes, win rates should not vary systematically across courts. But choice of law questions might be sufficiently inexpensive and preliminary in the litigation process that results may vary at the margin across jurisdictions. Borchers (1992) followed with a more extensive study, and ascertained confidence intervals to test the significance of variations across choice of law methodologies. Borchers classified each state by choice of law approach, and then collected 800 published state and federal cases, including those reported at both the trial and appellate level. In the First Restatement states, he retrieved every case found on-line from 1960. In the modern approach states, he retrieved all cases found subsequent to the shift in methodology. Borchers attempted to ascertain the differences both between the First Restatement and modern states as a group and among the specific methodologies applied in the modern states. When the modern states taken together were compared with the First Restatement states, Borchers’ results confirmed Solomine’s. The modern approach states were significantly more pro-recovery, resident and forum favoring in their choice of laws. However, Borchers found essentially no statistically significant variations across the modern approaches. He found significant variation only with respect to recovery-favoring rules. The Second Restatement and Leflar states were statistically distinguishable from each other,
642
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
9600
with the Leflar states generating more recovery-favoring outcomes. Borchers’ results were seriously qualified, however, by the fact that neither the Second Restatement nor the Leflar states produced choices statistically distinguishable from interest analysis. Borchers concludes (p. 379), ‘Courts do not take the new approaches seriously. Because all of the competitors to the First Restatement start from different analytic premises, if courts were faithful to their tenets they would inevitably generate different result patterns. Yet in practice the outcomes are largely indistinguishable.’ Thiel (1996), a trained econometrician, criticized Borchers’ methodology for lacking a regression analysis that could control for legal culture. Pro-recovery and pro-plaintiff results can come partly from the modern choice of law approach, but could also be affected by systematic differences in the general legal culture of the First Restatement and modern approach states. At the same time, the states that have adopted the same choice of law methodology might have positively correlated legal cultures. To separate out these influences on choice of law decisions, Thiel used Borchers’ state classifications, and remeasured the differences, using variables that might control the estimates for the influence of legal culture. Thiel found that while the modern approach states clearly use forum law more often than states using the First Restatement, there was little difference at the margin between the two groups of states with respect to recovery-favoring choice of law determinations. Thiel believes that the results indicate that plaintiffs push lawsuits to where their prospects of prevailing on choice of law rulings are about equal in all states. Thiel’s most interesting results are found in comparing states according to modern methodology. Unlike Borchers, Thiel’s regressions produced statistically significant variations across the modern approaches with respect to forum and recovery-favoring choice of law. As predicted by theoretical analyses of modern methodologies (Borchers, 1992), the point estimates of the differences indicate that the Leflar states are relatively strongest in their generosity to plaintiffs and preference for forum law. The interest analysis states also show a strong bias toward choice of forum law, and are relatively strongest in favoring local parties. More empirical studies could help clarify the choice of law debate. In the conflicts field, as least as much as any other, legal academics make bald statements claiming that various approaches or rules will work in particular ways or have specific effects on primary behavior. Those statements are supported at best with slight anecdotal evidence. The field is ripe for empiricists who can cut through the legal and academic thicket to view the landscape.
9600
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
643
B. Contractual Choice of Law We have so far discussed only the default choice of law rules that apply in the absence of contract. Enforcing clauses in contracts that select the applicable law has several possible benefits (Ribstein, 1993; Whincop and Keynes, 1998, Ch. 3).
6. Benefits of Enforcing Contractual Choice of Law Eliminating Inconsistency The parties may contract for choice of law in order to eliminate problems that arise when inconsistent mandatory rules otherwise might be applied to different aspects of or parties to the contract, such as shareholder voting rules and the rights of franchisees. Clarifying the Applicable Law Contracting for choice of law enables the parties easily to determine what law governs the transaction. Uncertainty about the applicable law that results from the choice of law default rules discussed above prevents the parties from easily determining the standard of conduct to which they should conform or how to price contract rights and duties. Uncertainty at the time of litigation can increase both the costs and frequency of litigation. In particular, the uncertainty may increase the parties’ gains from litigating rather than settling (Priest and Klein, 1984). This is not only privately more costly for the parties, but also imposes costs on the judicial system that are borne by taxpayers generally. Jurisdictional Competition Enforcing contractual choice of law is particularly useful in fostering jurisdictional competition for more efficient laws across states (Kobayashi and Ribstein, 1998; Ribstein 1993). Competition works both by encouraging states to develop new terms to attract new legal business, and by encouraging states to retain legal business by efficiently revising their laws. Jurisdictional competition was first observed with regard to corporations, where a clear choice of law rule, the internal affairs rule in the US, compels application of the law of the state of incorporation (see Section 8, below). This rule encourages corporations to select the applicable law. Commentators have debated whether this process is a ‘race to the bottom’ in which the states attract incorporation business by exploiting principal-agent problems resulting from the separation of ownership and control (Cary, 1974) or a ‘race to the top’ that is disciplined by efficient capital markets (Winter, 1977). For empirical evidence favoring the race to the top hypothesis, see Carney (1993), Romano (1985), Dodd and
644
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
9600
Leftwich (1980). For studies of the role of jurisdictional competition in the transition from special chartering to general incorporation, see Shughart and Tollison (1985) and Butler (1985). As Tiebout recognized, the ability of people and firms to exit jurisdictions whose policies they do not like motivates governments to reflect voters’ preferences (Tiebout, 1956; Frey and Eichenberger, 1995; Gerken, 1995; Kerber and Vanberg, 1995). Thus, the demand side of jurisdictional competition requires, among other things, that actors are mobile (Easterbrook, 1983; Tiebout, 1956; Fischel, 1987). For example, with regard to corporations, foreign incorporation imposes registration costs, exposes firms to suits in remote jurisdictions and makes unavailable intrastate financing that is exempt from the federal securities laws. Close corporations ordinarily lack incentives to incur these costs because they can get most of what they want by adapting the default provisions of their resident-state’s law (Ayres, 1992a; but see Ribstein, 1995a). Large multistate firms, on the other hand, pay these costs anyway in all but one state in which they transact business and have scale economies that can absorb the costs. The supply side of state competition requires that states have incentives to compete for formation business (Daniels, 1991). The states provide their law free of charge at taxpayer expense. If states cannot internalize the benefits from efficient contract rules, they may have inadequate incentives to devote legislative and judicial resources to developing and maintaining efficient contract rules. The standard explanation of the state competition for corporate law is based on the states’ incentives to earn franchise and related fees from incorporating firms (Romano, 1985). They can also earn revenue if enforcing choice-of-law attracts firms’ operations to the state. Either of these mechanisms would, in effect, give the state property rights in application of its law. In analyzing the supply side of state competition, it is necessary to disaggregate the ‘state’ and determine what motivates politicians to compete. Contracting parties’ ability to exit the state is a necessary but not sufficient basis for efficient competition. It is also necessary that this exit be translated into incentives for politicians. Whatever the benefits to states by participating in interstate competition, it is not clear that taxpayers can motivate state legislators to draft state-of-the-art legislation solely in order to maximize state revenues, particularly given legislators’ costs of producing this legislation. No individual taxpayers can capture enough benefits from legislative action to justify expending resources on legislation. Also, legislators may not be able to capture benefits from engaging in the competition because other jurisdictions easily can free-ride on their efforts by copying successful legislation (Rose-Ackerman, 1980). At the same time, legislators incur costs in competing to provide state law. In particular, because legislators can earn contributions and other support from affected parties by brokering changes in mandatory rules, they do not have strong incentives to lead the movement toward more
9600
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
645
enabling rules. Third, legislators face an unfavorable balance of risks and rewards. They take the risk that the legislation will fail to accomplish its objectives or will alienate groups that otherwise would have supported them, while their successes can be copied easily by other states. For discussions of legislators’ weak incentives to innovate, see Rose-Ackerman (1980), Ayres (1992b), Carney (1993), MacIntosh (1993), Ribstein and Kobayashi (1996). State competition to supply law may, however, be driven by lawyers rather than legislatures (Ribstein, 1994, 1995). Lawyers not only wield the conventional power of a cohesive interest group but, in most states, draft complex business statutes. Lawyers have an incentive to make their state a standard for commercial contracts in order to attract more litigation business to the state’s courts and increase the value of advice on and expertise in the state’s law. However, as the price for assisting in the competition of state laws, lawyers may reduce the demand for these rules by pressing for rules that favor lawyers, such as by offering open-ended default rules that discourage settlement and increase litigation (Macey and Miller, 1987; White, 1992; Priest and Klein, 1984). Accordingly, lawyers may have an interest in preventing the parties from simplifying choice of law by contracting in advance to be governed by a particular law. On the other hand, lawyers are constrained by jurisdictional competition. In general, lawyers would support rules that reduce demand for law up to the point that the reduction in demand exceeds their benefits from the rules. Demand may be reduced by inefficient legal rules that cause parties to move their legal business to other states, federal courts and arbitrators. The extent to which states compete to supply non-corporate law depends significantly on whether interest groups in those states can protect their benefits from mandatory rules from erosion by state competition. Under standard interest group theory, state legislation is determined by the relative strength of the various groups that the legislation helps and hurts (Olson, 1965; McCormick and Tollison, 1981; Tollison, 1988). To be sure, states can successfully compete only by making their underlying legal rules generally attractive to contracting parties. Thus, a state could not win a competition to attract, say, franchise law business simply by adopting a pro-franchisee law. However, the state might be able to help franchisees by imposing retroactive burdens on existing franchise contracts. Groups helped by such laws might oppose vigorous choice-of-law competition. States’ incentives to compete therefore depend on how well organized are groups that favor mandatory rules, the costs and benefits to competing groups of applying contract-friendly enabling rules rather than protective mandatory rules, and lawyers’ benefits from competing for law business. Thus, for example, Delaware may be in a good position to compete to supply law in part because it has a highly organized commercial bar but no well-organized competing groups.
646
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
9600
The quantity and quality of state competition ultimately depend on the legal rules regarding contractual choice of law. Politicians may protect themselves by, for example, restricting enforcement of contractual choice law. While the courts may have considerable discretion to interpret the legislature’s statutes, they can do little in the face of a statute that explicitly invalidates choice of law clauses. Even if the statute does not invalidate exit by choice of law, judges may have their own incentives to maximize the value of interest group deals by protecting them from dilution by party choice of law. After all, judges clearly have some incentive to respond to legislators’ interests to the extent that the latter control judges’ salary and tenure. If so, judges can be expected to act to increase the durability and value of legislators’ interest group deals by enforcing them within the state (Anderson et al., 1989; Crain and Tollison, 1979; Landes and Posner, 1975). Although legislators and judges may attempt to block contractual choice of law, contracting parties to some extent have the last say. They may, among other things, choose the fora in which disputes are decided and completely exit jurisdictions that are hostile to contractual choice of law. These moves, in turn, put pressure on courts and legislators to enforce contractual choice (Kobayashi and Ribstein, 1998). Jurisdictional Competition and Evolutionary Theories Contractual choice of law may lead to a process of legal evolution. As to legal evolution generally, see Benson (1995), Kerber and Vanberg (1995). Alchian (1950) observed that a study of the ‘adaptive mechanism’ of the market may be more fruitful than that of ‘individual motivation and foresight’. Under this theory, individuals and firms who have an incentive to minimize their transaction and information costs and an ability to choose legal regimes that accomplish this goal will cause the law to move toward efficiency. For example, corporate law evolved from the sale of corporate charters by state legislators to largely enabling statutes and alternative forms of limited liability business forms because of the pressure of jurisdictional competition (Butler, 1985; Shughart and Tollison, 1985). There is also evidence of such evolution with respect to the demand for statutory forms (Ribstein, 1995a) and the demand for uniform statutory provisions (Kobayashi and Ribstein, 1996). This evolutionary theory suggests that the conditions for efficiency may exist even if this outcome could not be predicted ex ante based on a study of the incentives of legislators or other key actors. It may be indeterminate whether the mechanisms for efficient competition are in place, and therefore impossible to determine ex ante whether competition among unknown alternatives will produce more efficient results than applying a centralized rule. Nevertheless, it may be more efficient to facilitate jurisdictional competition by enforcing contractual choice of law in order to
9600
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
647
promote a process of discovering more efficient alternatives (Hayek, 1948; Vihanto, 1992; Kobayashi, Parker and Ribstein, 1994; Gerken, 1995). Contractual choice of law is also likely to be superior to other alternatives, such as the adoption of uniform or national laws, precisely because differing state laws foster experimentation (Ribstein and Kobayashi, 1996; Kobayashi and Ribstein, 1996). Moreover, diverse environments may suggest differing optimal rules, and choice of law enables parties to choose the rule that fits best with their contracting situation (Posner and Scott, 1980; Easterbrook, 1983; Baysinger and Butler, 1985; Romano, 1985). On the other hand, enforcing contractual choice of law might not lead to efficient competition if state legislators engage in ‘herd’ behavior’ by ignoring their private information generated by other states’ experiences and simply adopting prior laws. (For theoretical treatments of herd behavior, see Banerjee, 1992; Bikhchandani, Hirshleifer and Welch, 1992; Scharfstein and Stein, 1990.) However, evidence from the evolution of statutory forms for closely-held firms indicates that legislators do not simply follow-the-leader but rather apply new information in adopting legislation (Ribstein, 1995a).
7. Costs of Contractual Choice of Law Notwithstanding the above arguments, there are also reasons why enforcing contractual law may lead to inefficient results (Ribstein, 1993). Evasion of Mandatory Rules Enforcing contractual choice of law arguably can lead to externalization of costs where it permits contracting parties to evade mandatory rules that are intended to address specific bargaining problems that can lead to such externalization. This may be the case, for example, where the parties are attempting to escape prohibitions on contract terms such as fiduciary duty waivers, usurious interest rates, termination-at-will or noncompetition provisions. The argument against enforcing the contractual choice-of-law in these situations may seem to be precisely the same as that supporting the mandatory rule itself. However, there are several reasons for permitting the parties to opt out of locally mandatory rules by contractually choosing the applicable law or forum. First, where several jurisdictions’ laws may apply, the parties’ choice of law is not obviously less appropriate than any other basis of selecting the applicable law. Second, evasion of mandatory rules is constrained by the fact that avoidance requires applying a state law rather than solely the voluntary act of contracting parties. That the chosen state’s law applies to its own residents reduces state legislators’ incentives to engage in this sort of conduct. Accordingly, this
648
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
9600
danger of enforcing contractual choice of law exists mainly where most victims live outside the state. Third, the enacting legislature may not have intended to preclude contracting for the applicable law or forum. In particular, a mandatory rule may not make sense to the extent that it precludes efficient bargains. The parties arguably indicate that the mandatory rule is costly when applied to them by their willingness to incur the costs of contracting for choice of law. Thus, courts generally should enforce contractual choice of law or forum even to the extent that it overrides a locally mandatory rule (Buckley and Ribstein, 1998; Whincop and Keyes, 1998a, Ch. 4, 1998b). Information Assymmetry and Protecting Contracting Parties Enforcing contractual choice of law arguably may lead to externalization of costs because the party responsible for the term is probably more well-informed concerning the chosen law. Indeed, such information asymmetries may skew interstate competition because states may tailor their rules to suit the more informed party. However, information asymmetry is arguably not a problem where the effect of the law selection clause is to choose a legal regime that literally enforces the contract; in long-term contracts negotiated by sophisticated and knowledgeable parties who have the ability and incentive to read the contract carefully or hire an attorney to do so; or where firms are subject to market incentives to disclose and to constraints on cheating (Schwartz and Wilde, 1979). In any event, regulators could minimize information costs by mandating disclosure of unusual and significant law-selection terms in some circumstances. Similarly, enforcing contractual choice of law is arguably inefficient where the choice-of-law clause can be characterized as an ‘adhesion’ contract imposed by one party on another. This argument also has been used to justify broad regulation of corporate governance. However, this is not the case merely because of the parties’ acceptance of a standard term, particularly where the contract chooses the entire local law of a particular jurisdiction. A state’s entire law as to a complex contract probably will not operate unfairly against one of the parties on all or most of the many issues that could arise in the future.
8. Enforcement of Contractual Choice of Law This section considers the extent to which choice of law provisions are enforced in United States courts.
9600
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
649
Common Law The common law, as summarized in Restatement (1971), § 187(1) provides for enforcement of the parties’ contractual choice of law as to interpretation issues the parties could have resolved by contract. Under Restatement § 187(2), the contract is not enforced as to issues such as validity, where choice of law matters most, if: (a) the chosen state has no substantial relationship to the parties or the transaction and there is no other reasonable basis for the parties’ choice, or (b) application of the law of the chosen state would be contrary to a fundamental policy of a state which has a materially greater interest than the chosen state in the determination of the particular issue and which, under the rule of §188, would be the state of the applicable law in the absence of an effective choice of law by the parties. Courts and commentators have not clearly articulated a rationale for these limitations on enforcement of contractual choice of law (Ribstein, 1993). The ‘substantial relationship’ test in subsection (a) seems to have no function other than to increase the parties’ cost of exit from mandatory rules and, therefore, to reduce the likelihood of efficient interstate competition. For example, it is not clear why any mutually agreed choice would not be prima facie ‘reasonable’. The test conceivably could be defended on the ground that it addresses externalization of costs by states whose law is applied. But even if the particular contract at issue does not relate to the contractually selected state, the state might still be subject to market discipline where the applied law has substantial application within the applying state. In other situations, such as corporate law, the state is otherwise subject to market discipline in formulating its law. With respect to the vague ‘fundamental policy’ exception in subsection (b), the Restatement gives as examples ‘illegal’ contracts or rules ‘designed to protect a person against the oppressive use of superior bargaining power’ (Restatement, 1971, p. 568). This appears to track potential concerns about bargaining power and information asymmetries (see Section 7, above). Alternatively, this ground for non-enforcement may just invite courts to determine and effectuate the underlying goal of the interest groups that promoted the law. In general, courts applying the US Restatement (Second) rule have quite generally enforced contractual choice of law (Ribstein, 1993). Thus, in practice, the US rule is close to the rule favoring enforcement articulated in the leading UK case of Vita Food Products Inc. v. Unus Shipping Co.. That case enforced a provision applying English law though there was nothing to connect the contract with England except the choice of law clause.
650
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
9600
Statutory Law Several states, including California, Illinois, Delaware, New York and Texas, have promulgated statutes that, to varying degrees, clarify the enforcement of contractual choice of law clauses (Ribstein, 1994). These choice-of-law statutes provide some evidence both of jurisdictional competition to supply law and of the determinants of such competition. The laws do not generate obvious gains for legislators. They do not generate franchise fee or other obvious income for the state. Nor do they even appear to benefit firms and individuals residing or doing business in the enacting states since such parties do not need the statute to secure jurisdiction in or to justify contractual enforcement of the law of the enacting states. However, the laws are understandable in light of the role of lawyers in promoting jurisdictional competition (see Section 6). Lawyers’ role also helps explain differences among the four statutes. The broadest statute is in Delaware, where lawyers clearly dominate. In the larger commercial states such as Texas, other powerful interest groups clearly would want to protect local mandatory laws from erosion by interstate competition. Corporate Internal Affairs Rule In contrast to the rule applied to other contractual relationships, the parties’ rights regarding the internal governance of a corporation usually are determined by the law selected by the parties - that is, the law of the state of incorporation (Restatement, 1971, § 302(2). The conflicts rules that apply to corporations therefore differ substantially from those which apply to non-corporate contracts. This ignores the fact that corporations and other types of firms are fundamentally similar in the sense of being alternative devices for minimizing transaction costs (Williamson, 1985; Coase, 1937). Nor do the costs and benefits of applying contractual choice of law discussed above differ significantly according to whether corporate or non-corporate contracts are involved (Ribstein, 1993). For example, parties to non-corporate contracts, like those to corporations, would benefit from being permitted to shop for the applicable law, from the certainty of applying a contractually selected law, and from applying the same law to all parties to interstate contracts. On the other side of the ledger, corporations present the same potential problems as other contracts regarding potential evasion of mandatory rules, as indicated by commentators such as Cary (1974) who have condemned interstate competition for corporate law as a ‘race to the bottom’. Although corporations do clearly identify the applicable law through their centrally filed certificates or articles of incorporation, this does no more than justify analogous requirements for non-corporate contracts. The fact that corporate shares are traded on efficient securities markets that discount significant contract terms plainly does not justify a distinction between closely held corporations and other types of contracts.
9600
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
651
The different treatment of corporations and other types of contracts with regard to enforcement of contractual choice of law may be due at least partly to the long acceptance of the legal fiction that a corporation is a legal ‘person’ created and endowed with certain attributes by the chartering state (Ribstein, 1995b). This characterization is conducive to application of contractual choice of law because it seems to give greater weight to the parties’ jurisdictional choice than would characterizing the corporation as a mere contract. The entity theory helped create a legal momentum toward enforcement of contractual choice of law in corporations that has never been opposed by coordinated interest groups. In other words, the special choice-of-law rule for corporations, which has been instrumental in ensuring efficient state default rules and enforcement of contracts in firms, ironically may be attributable to the fact that the corporation traditionally has been viewed as a legal person rather than an ordinary contract. There is a potential tension between the corporate internal affairs rule and the choice of law statutes discussed above. Those statutes arguably permit the parties to a corporation to select the law other than of the state of incorporation. This raises the question of whether states should be able to, in effect, bundle their lawmaking and adjudication services by insisting that their corporate law applies only to parties who have formally incorporated in the state and, therefore, paid the franchise tax (Ribstein, 1994). Fees and taxes arguably play a role in giving states an incentive to compete to provide law, depending on the role of lawyers in promoting in this competition (see Section 6, above). Constitutional law The federal government in a federal system has an important role with respect to contractual choice of law. For broad-based discussions of the economics of federalism, see Hayek (1948), Riker (1964), Shapiro (1972), Rose Ackerman (1980, 1981), Cover (1981), Kitch (1981), Macey (1990) and Carney (1993). This section discusses Constitutional provisions that mandate enforcement of choice of law contracts. Other potential effects of federal law are discussed below. The commerce clause of the US Constitution, §8, cl.3, provides in part that Congress has the power ‘[t]o regulate Commerce ... among the several states’. The ‘negative implication’ of this clause is that only Congress, and not the individual states, can regulate such commerce (see Cooley v. Board of Wardens). The Supreme Court has endorsed an exportation-of-costs theory of the commerce clause which holds that if the costs of state regulation fall mostly on interest groups outside the state while the benefits accrue to those within it, the legislature lacks incentives to consider both costs and benefits in enacting laws (Posner, 1992, pp. 638-644; Fischel, 1987; Levmore, 1983). From an efficiency standpoint, cost exportation subverts interest group interaction within
652
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
9600
the enacting jurisdiction that otherwise would cause laws to tend toward Kaldor-Hicks efficiency. The cost-exportation theory arguably justifies invalidation under the commerce clause of state statutes to the extent that they prevent enforcement of choice-of-law clauses. This targets a particular application of state law that generally tends to benefit concentrated in-state groups while imposing costs on out-of-state firms or interest groups (Ribstein, 1993). It is significant in that regard that such clauses tend not to be enforced when they are in form contracts that are used on a national scale rather than within a single state (Ribstein, 1993). This theory is arguably supported by two Supreme Court cases on state anti-takeover laws, Edgar v. Mite Corp. and CTS Corp. v. Dynamics Corp. of America. Edgar struck down on Commerce Clause grounds a state law which imposed conditions, including approval by a state agency, on interstate tender offers, while CTS held under the commerce clause that an interstate tender offer could be regulated by the law of the state of incorporation. These cases are best rationalized on the basis that regulation of a corporate contract which is inconsistent with the law of the contractually selected state - that is, the law of the state of incorporation - is invalid under the commerce clause. Even if the commerce clause technically applies in this situation, its application may be unnecessary in the long run. Costs ultimately may be borne inside the state even if they initially fall on nonresidents (Kitch, 1981), and laws hurt out-of-state groups invite retaliation by other states (Levmore, 1983). The full faith and credit clause, US Constitution art. IV, §1, provides in part that ‘Full Faith and Credit shall be given in each State to the public Acts, Records, and judicial Proceedings of every other State’. This requires states to respect the laws of other states at least to the extent of having a principled basis for refusing to the follow the law in a particular case (see Allstate Insurance Co v. Hague). However, this principle does not directly protect individuals’ rights to freedom of contract. Some early ‘full faith and credit’ cases involving fraternal benefit associations held that the association’s formation state law or charter must apply in order to ensure that a single legal regime applies to all association members (see, for example, Supreme Council of the Royal Arcanum v. Green, enforcing increase in assessment rate pursuant to association’s constitution). However, given the limited objectives of the full faith and credit clause discussed above, it is unlikely that this authority would be broadly applied today to compel enforcement of choice of law clauses. At most, these cases might justify applying a single rule, such as the law of the one state that has overwhelming contacts with the transaction even if this is not the law the parties selected.
9600
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
653
Federal Law Congress is explicitly empowered under the full faith and credit and commerce clauses to regulate choice of law. A federal choice of law rule could preserve state power and reinforce private contracts similar to commerce clause protection of contractual choice of law. However, any Congressional action would have to emerge from a competition among interest groups. There is probably no group that would gain enough from a general rule validating choice-of-law clauses to organize support for such a law. Congress may fail to act only to avoid negative interest group pressure (Macey, 1990) rather than because action would be inefficient. This suggests that it may be better to rely on the Supreme Court’s power under the Constitution to lift state burdens on interstate commerce.
Bibliography on Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law (9600) Anderson, Gary M. et al. (1989), ‘On the Incentives of Judges to Enforce Legislative Wealth Transfers’, 32 Journal of Law and Economics, 215 ff. Ayres, Ian (1992a), ‘Judging Close Corporations in the Age of Statutes’, 70 Washington University Law Quarterly, 365 ff. Ayres, Ian (1992b), ‘Making a Difference: The Contractual Contributions of Easterbrook and Fischel’, 59 University of Chicago Law Review, 1391 ff. Ayres, Ian (1993), ‘Preliminary thoughts on Optimal Tailoring of Contractual Rules’, 3 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal, 1 ff. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1984), ‘Trade Usages in International Sales of Goods: An Analysis of the 1964 and 1980 Sales Conventions’, 24 Virginia Journal of International Law, 619 ff. Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1986), ‘Comity and Sovereign Debt Litigation: A Bankruptcy Analogy’, 10 Maryland Journal of International Law and Trade, 1 ff. Baxter, William F. (1963), ‘Choice of Law and the Federal System’, 16 Stanford Law Review, 1 ff. Beale, Joseph H. (1935), A Treatise on the Conflict of Laws. Benson, Bruce L. (1992), ‘Customary Law as a Social Contract: International Commercial Law’, 2 Constitutional Political Economy, 1-27. Benson, Bruce L. (1995), ‘Competition Among Legal Institutions: Implications for the Evolution of Law’, in Gerken, Luden (ed.), Competition Among Institutions, London, Macmillan, 153-175. Borchers, Patrick (1992), ‘The Choice of Law Revolution: An Empirical Study’, 49 Washington and Lee Law Review, 357 ff. Boyd, James (1996), ‘Environmental Liability Reform and Privatization in Central and Eastern Europe’, 3 European Journal of Law and Economics. Brilmayer, Lea (1980), ‘Interest Analysis and the Myth of Legislative Intent’, 78 Michigan Law Review, 392 ff. Brilmayer, Lea (1995), Conflict of Laws, Boston, Little Brown. Bruce, Christopher J. (1984), ‘The Deterrent Effects of Automobile Insurance and Tort Law: A Survey of the Empirical Literature’, 6 Law and Policy, 67 ff.
654
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
9600
Buckley, Francis H. and Ribstein, Larry E. (1998), Marriage and Choice of Law (Unpublished manuscript). Butler, Henry N. (1985), ‘Nineteenth-Century Jurisdictional Competition in the Granting of Corporate Privileges’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 129 ff. Carney, William J. (1993), ‘The ALI’s Corporate Governance Project: the Death of Property Rights?’ 61 George Washington Law Review, 898 ff. Carney, William J. (1997), ‘The Political Economy of Competition for Corporate Charters’, 26 Journal of Legal Studies, 303 ff. Cary, William L. (1974), ‘Federalism and Corporate Law: Reflections upon Delaware’, 83 Yale Law Journal, 663 ff. Cavers, David (1933), ‘A Critique of the Choice-of-Law Problem’, 47 Harvard Law Review, 173 ff. Coase, Ronald H. (1937), ‘The Nature of the Firm’, 4 Economica, 386-405. Cover, Robert M. (1981), ‘The Uses of Jurisdictional Redundancy: Interest Ideology and Innovation’, 22 William and Mary Law Review, 639 ff. Crain, W. Mark and Tollison, R.D. (1979), ‘Constitutional Change in an Interest Group Perspective’, 8 Journal of Legal Studies, 165 ff. Currie, Brainard (1958a), ‘Survival of Actions: Adjudication versus Automation in the Conflict of Laws’, 10 Stanford Law Review, 205 ff. Currie, Brainard (1958b), ‘Married Women’s Contracts: A Study in Conflict-of-Laws Method’, 24 University of Chicago Law Review, 227 ff. Currie, Brainard (1959), ‘Notes on Methods and Objectives in the Conflict of Laws’, 1959 Duke Law Journal, 171 ff. Daniels, Ronald J. (1991), ‘Should Provinces Compete: The Case for a Competitive Corporate Law Market’, 36 McGill Law Journal, 130 ff. Dezalay, Yves and Garth, Bryant G. (1995), ‘Merchants of Law as Mortal Entrepreneurs: Constructing International Justice from the Competition for Trasnational Business Disputes’, 29 Law and Society Review, 27-64. Dicey, Albert Venn (1980), Dicey and Morris on the Conflict of Laws, London, Stevens. Dodd, Peter and Leftwich, Richard (1980), ‘The Market for Corporate Charters: Unhealthy Competition versus Federal Regulation’, 53 Journal of Business, 259 ff. Easterbrook, Frank H. (1983), ‘Antitrust and the Economics of Federalism’, 26 Journal of Law and Economics, 23 ff. Ehrenzweig, Albert (1956), ‘Parental Immunity in the Conflict of Laws: Law and Reason versus the Restatement’, 23 University of Chicago Law Review, 474 ff. Ely, John Hart (1981), ‘Choice of Law and the State’s Interest in Protecting Its Own’, 23 William and Mary Law Review, 173-217. Fischel, Daniel R. (1987), ‘From MITE to CTS: State Anti-Takeover Statutes, the Williams Act, the Commerce Clause, and Insider Trading’, 47 Supreme Court Review. Frey, Brumo S. and Eichenberger, Reiner (1995), ‘Competition among Jurisdictions: The Idea of FOCJ’, in Gerken, Luden (ed.), Competition Among Institutions, London, Macmillan, 209-229. Green, Edward J. and Porter, Robert H. (1984), ‘Noncooperative Collusion Under Imperfect Price Information’, 52 Econometrica, 87 ff. Hay, Bruce L. (1992), ‘Conflicts of Laws and State Competition in the Product Liability System’, 80 Georgetown Law Journal, 617 ff.
9600
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
655
Henry, Sherrye P. and Bainbridge, Stephen M. (1984), ‘Nationalizations - Standard of Compensation’, 24 Virginia Journal of International Law, 993 ff. Joustra, Carla (1992), ‘Cross Border Consumer Complaints in Private International Law’, 15(4) Journal of Consumer Policy, 431-443. Kitch, Edmund W. (1981), ‘Regulation and the American Common Market’, in Tarlock, A. Dan (ed.), Regulation, Federalism and Interstate Commerce 9. Kobayashi, Bruce H. and Ribstein, Larry E. (1996), ‘Evolution and Spontaneous Uniformity: Evidence from the Evolution of the Limited Liability Company’, 34 Economic Inquiry. Kobayashi, Bruce H. and Ribstein, Larry E. (1998), ‘Contract and Jurisdictional Competition’, in Buckley, F.H. (ed.), Fall and Rise of Freedom of Contract, NC, Duke Univ Press. Kobayashi, Bruce H., Parker, Jeffrey S. and Ribstein, Larry E. (1994), The Process of Procedural Reform, George Mason University Law and Economics Working Paper, 96-5. Kötz, Hein (1986), ‘Rechtsvereinheitlichung - Nutzen, Kosten, Methoden, Ziele (Law Harmonization - Benefits, Costs, Methods, Goals)’, 50 Rabels Zeitschrift für Ausländisches und Internationales Privatrecht, 483-507. Kozyris, John P. (1987), ‘Choice of Law for Products Liability: Whither Ohio?’, 48 Ohio State Law Journal, 377 ff. Kramer, Larry (1990), ‘Rethinking Choice of Law’, 90 Columbia Law Review, 277 ff. Kramer, Larry (1991a), ‘Return of the Renvoi’, 66 New York University Law Review, 979 ff. Kramer, Larry (1991b), ‘More Notes on Methods and Objectives in the Conflict of Laws’, 24 Cornell International Law Journal, 245 ff. Leflar, Robert (1966a), ‘Choice-Influencing Considerations in Conflicts Law’, 41 New York University Law Review, 267 ff. Leflar, Robert (1966b), ‘Conflicts Law: More On Choice Influencing Considerations’, 54 California Law Review, 1584 ff. Leflar, Robert (1977), ‘Choice of Law: A Well-watered Plateau’, 41 Law and Contemporary Problems, 10 ff. Levmore, Saul (1983), ‘Interstate Exploitation and Judicial Intervention’, 69 Vanderbilt Law Review, 568-569. Macey, Jonathan R. (1990), ‘Federal Deference to Local Regulators and the Economic Theory of Regulation: Toward a Public Choice Explanation of Federalism’, 76 Vanderbilt Law Review, 265 ff. Macey, Jonathan R. and Miller, Geoffrey P. (1987), ‘Toward an Interest-Group Theory of Delaware Corporate Law’, 65 Texas Law Review, 469 ff. MacIntosh, Jeffrey G. (1993), The Role of Interjurisdictional Competition in Shaping Canadian Corporate Law: A Second Look, University of Toronto Law and Economics Working Paper Series, WPS 18. Malysiak, James T. (1973), ‘Toward a Substantive Private International Law of Trademarks: The Lessons of the Carl Zeiss Litigation’, 82(5) Yale Law Journal, 1072-1091. McConnell, Michael W. (1988), ‘A Choice of Law Approach to Products-Liability Reform’, in Olson, Walter (ed.), New Directions in Liability Law, New York, The Academy of Political Science. Nagel, Bernhard (1992), ‘Von der Lex Mercatoria zur Lex Laboris, zur Rechtlichen Bewältigung der Internationalen Arbeitsbeziehungen (Lex Mercatoria and Lex Laboris. On the Legal Analysis of
656
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
9600
International Work Relations)’, in Däubler, Wolfgang, Bobke, Manfred and Kehrmann, Karl (ed.), Festschrift für Albert Gnade, Köln, Bund-Verlag. North, P.M. and Fawcett, J.J. (1992), Cheshire and North’s Private International Law, London, Butterworths. O’Hara, Erin and Ribstein, Larry E. (1997), ‘Interest Groups, Contracts and Interest Analysis’, 48 Mercer Law Review, 765-774. Parisi, Francesco (1995), ‘Toward a Theory of Spontaneous Law’, 6 Constitutional Political Economy, 211-231. Parisi, Francesco (1996a), ‘Normative Knowledge and Self-Enforcing Rule in International Law’, 2 International Legal Theory, 27-30. Parisi, Francesco (1996b), ‘Law as a Voluntary Enterprise’, in Ratnapala, S. and Moens, G. (eds), The Jurisprudence of Liberty, London, Butterworths, 111-128. Parisi, Francesco (1997), ‘The Economics of Customary Law: Lessons From Evolutionary Socio-Biology’, in Ott, Claus and von Wangenheim, Georg (eds), Essays in Law and Economics IV, Antwerpen, Maklu. Parisi, Francesco (1998a), ‘Customary Law’, in Newman, Peter (ed.), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law, London, Macmillan. Parisi, Francesco (1998b), ‘The Cost of the Game: A Topology of Social Interactions’, 6 European Journal of Law and Economics. Parisi, Francesco (1998c), ‘Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law’, in X., Encyclopedia of Law and Economics, Cheltenham, Edward Elgar and University of Gent. Reese, Willis (1972), ‘Choice of Law: Rules or Approach’, 57 Cornell Law Review, 315 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. (1993), ‘Choosing Law by Contract’, 18 Journal of Corporation Law, 245 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. (1994), ‘Delaware, Lawyers and Choice of Law’, 19 Delaware Journal of Corporate Law, 999 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. (1995a), ‘Statutory Forms for Closely Held Firms: Theories and Evidence from LLCs’, 73 Washington University Law Quarterly, 369 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. (1995b), ‘A Critique of the Uniform Limited Liability Company Act’, 25 Stetson Law Review, 313 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. (1995c), ‘The Constitutional Conception of the Corporation’, 4 Supreme Court Economic Review, 95 ff. Ribstein, Larry E. and Kobayashi, Bruce H. (1995), ‘Uniform Laws, Model Laws and Limited Liability Companies’, 66 University of Colorado Law Review, 947-999. Ribstein, Larry E. and Kobayashi, Bruce H. (1996), ‘Economic Analysis of Uniform State Laws’, 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 131 ff. Riker, William H. (1964), Federalism: Origin, Operation, Significance, Boston, Little Brown . Romano, Roberta (1985), ‘Law as Product: Some Pieces of the Incorporation Puzzle’, 1 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 225 ff. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1980), ‘Risk Taking and Reelection: Does Federalism Promote Innovation?’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 593 ff. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1981), ‘Does Federalism Matter? Political Choice in a Federal Republic’, 89 Journal of Political Economy, 152 ff. Rosenberg, Maurice (1968), ‘Comments on Reich v. Purcell’, 15 UCLA Law Review, 641-647.
9600
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
657
Rosenberg, Maurice (1981), ‘The Comeback of Choice-of-Law Rules’, 81 Columbia Law Review, 946 ff. Rubin, Paul H. (1993), ‘Private Mechanisms for the Creation of Efficient Institutions for Market Economies’, in Somogyi, Laszlo (ed.), The Political Economy of the Transition Process in Eastern Europe, Cheltenham, Edward Elgar. Rubin, Paul H. (1994), ‘Growing A Legal System in the Post-Communist Economies’, 27 Cornell International Law Journal, 1-47. Santagata, Walter (1995), ‘Istituzioni per il Mercato dell’Arte: Artisti e Mercanti tra Regole, Convenzioni e Allocazioni dei Diritti (Institutions for the Market of Works of Art: Artists and Merchants among Rules, Conventions and Allocation of Rights)’, Economia Publica, 87-115. Schenk, Karl-Ernst (1978), ‘Grenzüberschreitende Unternehmensformen in den Ost-West-Wirtschaftsbeziehungen (Transnational forms of Enterprises in East-West Economic Relations, with A. Wass von Czege)’, in Schiller, Karl (ed.), Technologietransfer durch Ost-West-Kooperation, Ökonomische Studien aus den Institut für Außenhandel und Überseewirtschaft, Bd. 27, Stuttgart/New York, 1-12. Schenk, Karl-Ernst (1988), ‘Technologietransfer, Joint Ventures und Transaktionskosten. Möglichkeiten und Grenzen strategischer Allianzen von Unternehmen in und zwischen Ost und West (Transfer of Technologies, Joint Ventures and Transaction Costs. Opportunities and Boundaries of Strategic Alliances by Enterprises of East and West)’, in Dürr, E. and Sieber, H. (eds), Weltwirtschaft im Wandel, Festgabe für E. Tuchtfeldt, Bern-Stuttgart, 595-606. Schenk, Karl-Ernst (1991), ‘Internationale Kooperationen und Joint Ventures. Theoretische und strategische Grundlagen ((International Cooperations and Joint Ventures. Theoretical and Strategical Foundations)’, in Schoppe, S.G. (ed.), Kompendium der Internationalen Betriebswirtschaftslehre, München-Wien, 153-184. Schmidt Trenz, Hans Jorg (1990), Außenhandel und Territorialität des Rechts. Grundlegung einer Neuen Institutionenökonomik des Außenhandels (Trade and Territoriality of Law), Baden-Baden, Nomos. Schmidtchen, Dieter (1993), ‘Neue Institutionenökonomik internationaler Transaktionen (New Institutional Economics of International Transaktions)’, in Schlieper, Ulrich and Schmidtchen, Dieter (eds), Makro, Geld and Institutionen, Tübingen, 57-84. Schmidtchen, Dieter (1995), ‘Territorialität des Rechts, Internationales Privatrecht und die privatautonome Regelung internationaler Sachverhalte. Grundlagen eines interdisziplinären Forschungsprogramms (Territoriality of Law, International Private Law, and Private Autonomous Order of International Relations)’,59(1) Rabels Zeitschrift für Ausländisches und Internationales Privatrecht, 56-112. Schmidtchen, Dieter and Schmidt-Trenz, Hans-Jorg (1990), ‘The Division of Labor is Limited by the Extent of the Law: A Constitutional Approach to International Private Law’, 1(3) Constitutional Political Economy, 49-71. Schmidtchen, Dieter and Schmidt-Trenz, H.-J. (1990), ‘The Division of Labor is Limited by the Extent of the Law. A Constitutional Economics Approach to International Private Law’, 1(3) Constitutional Political Economy, 49-71. Scoles, Eugene and Hay, Peter (1992), Conflict of Laws, St. Paul, Minn.,West Publishing Co. Shapiro, Martin M. (1972), ‘Toward a Theory of Stare Decisis’, 1 Journal of Legal Studies, 125 ff.
658
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
9600
Shughart, William F., II and Tollison R.D. (1985), ‘Corporate Chartering: An Exploration in the Economics of Legal Change’, 23 Economic Inquiry, 585 ff. Solomine, Michael (1989), ‘An Economic and Empirical Analysis of Choice of Law’, 24 Georgia Law Review, 49 ff. Sterk, Stewart E. (1994), ‘The Marginal Relevance of Choice of Law Theory’, 142 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 949 ff. Streit, Manfred E. and Voigt, Stefan (1993), ‘The Economics of Conflict Resolution in International Trade’, in Friedmann, D. and Mestmäcker, E.J. (eds), Conflict Resolution in International Trade, Baden-Baden, Nomos, 39-77. Symposium (1997), ‘Choice of Law: How It Ought to Be’, 48 Mercer Law Review, 623 ff. Thiel, Stuart E. (1996), Choice of Law and the Home Court Advantage: Evidence (Unpublished Manuscript). Vihanto, Martti (1992), ‘Competition Between Local Governments as a Discovery Procedure’, 148 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 411 ff. Voigt, Stefan (1992), Die Welthandelsordnung zwischen Konflikt und Stabilität - Konfliktpotentiale und Konfliktlösungsmechanismen (The World Trade System between Conflict and Stability), Freiburg. Watson, Alan (1974), Legal Transplants: An Approach to Comparative Law, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Whincop, Michael J. (1997), ‘Putting the “Private” Back into Private International Law: Default Rules and the Proper Law of the Contract’, 21 Melbourne University Law Review, 515 ff. Whincop, Michael J. (1998), ‘Statutes’ Domains in Private International Law: An Economic Theory of the Limits of Mandatory Rules’, 20 Sydney Law Review, 435 ff. Whincop, Michael J. and Keyes, Mary E. (1998), Policy and Pragmatism in the Conflict of Laws (Unpublished Manuscript). White, Michelle J. (1992), ‘Legal Complexity and Lawyers’ Benefit from Litigation’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 381 ff. Williamson, Oliver E. (1985), The Economic Institutions of Capitalism, New York, NY, Free Press. Winter, Ralph A. (1977), ‘State Law, Shareholder Protection, and the Theory of the Corporation’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 251 ff.
Other References Alchian, Armen A. (1950), ‘Uncertainty, Evolution, and Economic Theory’, 58 Journal of Political Economy, 211 ff. Axelrod, Robert (1984), The Evolution of Cooperation, New York, Basic Books. Banerjee, Abhijit (1992), ‘A Simple Model of Herd Behavior’, 107 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 797-817. Baysinger, Barry D. and Butler, Henry N. (1985), ‘The Role of Corporate Law in the Theory of the Firm’, 28 Journal of Law and Economics, 179 ff. Bikhchandani, Sushil, Hirshleifer, David and Welch, Ivo (1992), ‘A Theory of Fads, Fashion, Custom, and Cultural Change as Informational Cascades’, 100 Journal of Political Economy, 992 ff.
9600
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
659
Friedman, James (1971), ‘A Non-cooperative Equilibrium for Supergames’, 28 Review of Economic Studies, 1 ff. Gerken, Luder (ed.) (1995), Institutional Competition: An Orientative Framework, in Competition among Institutions, 1-31. Hayek, F.A. (1948), Individualism and Economic Order, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Kerber, Wolfgang and Vanberg, Viktor (1995), ‘Competition among Institutions: Evolution within Constraints’, in Gerken, Luder (ed.), Institutional Competition: An Orientative Framework, in Competition among Institutions, 33-64 . Landes, Elisabeth (1982), ‘Insurance, Liability and Accidents: A Theoretical and Empirical Investigation of the Effect of No-Fault Accidents’, 25 Journal of Law and Economics, 49 ff. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1975), ‘The Independent Judiciary in an Interest Group Perspective’, 18 Journal of Law and Economics, 875 ff. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1987), The Economic Structure of Tort Law, Cambridge, MA, Harvard Univ. Press, 14-19. McCormick, R. and Tollison, R. (1981), Politicians, Legislations and the Economy, an Inquiry into the Interest-GroupTheory of Government, Boston, M. Nijhoff-Kluwer. O’Hara, Erin (1993), ‘Social Constraint or Implicit Collusion: Toward A Game Theoretic Analysis of Stare Decisis’, 24 Seton Hall Law Review, 736 ff. Olson, Mancur (1965), The Logic of Collective Action, Boston, MA, Harvard University Press. Posner, Richard A. (1992), Economic Analysis of Law, 4th edn, Boston, Little Brown. Posner, Richard A. and Scott, Kenneth (1980) (eds), Economics of Corporation Law and Securities Regulation, Boston, Little Brown, 384 p. Priest, George and Klein, Benjamin (1984), ‘The Selection of Disputes for Litigation’, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, 1 ff. Restatement (First), Conflict of Laws (1934). Restatement (Second), Conflict of Laws (1971). Scharfstein, David and Stein, J. (1990), ‘Herd Behavior and Investment’, 80 American Economic Review, 465 ff. Schwartz, Alan, and Wilde, Louis A. (1979), ‘Intervening in Markets on the Basis of Imperfect Information: A Legal and Economic Analysis’,127 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 630638. Tiebout, Charles M. (1956), ‘A Pure Theory of Local Expenditure’, 64 Journal of Political Economy, 416 ff. Tollison, Robert (1988), ‘Public Choice and Legislation’, 74 Virginia Law Review, 339 ff.
Cases Cooley v. Board of Wardens, 53 U.S. 299 (1851) Supreme Council of the Royal Arcanum v. Green, 237 U.S. 531 (1915) Home Insurance Co. v. Dick, 281 U.S. 397 (1930) Vita Food Products Inc. v. Unus Shipping Co. A.C. 277 (1939) Allstate Insurance Co v. Hague, 449 U.S. 302 (1981) Edgar v. Mite Corp., 457 U.S. 624 (1982)
660
Conflict of Laws and Choice of Law
CTS Corp. v. Dynamics Corp. of America, 481 U.S. 69 (1987).
9600
9700 FEDERALISM Robert P. Inman Professor of Finance and Economics, Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania
Daniel L. Rubinfeld Robert L. Bridges Professor of Law and Professor of Economics, University of California, Berkeley © Copyright 1999 Robert P. Inman and Daniel L. Rubinfeld
Abstract With a topic such as federalism that has been so widely debated from so many perspectives, it would be impossible to provide a comprehensive review of the literature. Rather, we provide a particular perspective, one that balances the twin goals of political participation and economic welfare. To fashion such a balance, we first review the potential virtues of each federalist structure. We conclude that political participation rises with increased decentralization, but economic efficiency first rises and then falls. It is when efficiency declines that we face a trade-off. The choice of an ‘optimal’ level of decentralization ultimately depends upon the relative importance one places upon the competing federalist values of economic efficiency and political participation. JEL classification: K33, H11 Keywords: Political Participation, Voting by Feet, Tiebout, Decentralization
1. Introduction Federalism is today a topic of intense intellectual debate in many countries throughout the world. In Europe, the former Soviet Union, South Africa and elsewhere the view that good government will involve a blending of local and central governmental decision making is now well accepted. With a topic such as federalism that has been so widely debated from so many perspectives, it would be impossible to provide a comprehensive review of the literature. Rather, we provide a particular perspective, one that balances the twin goals of political participation and economic welfare. A carefully-specified theory of federalism has many useful applications: to government expenditure policy (Martinez-Vasquez, 1994), to tax policy
661
662
Federalism
9700
(Inman and Rubinfeld, 1996), to deficit policies (Inman, 1990), or to regulatory policy (Rose-Ackerman and Mashaw, 1984). Confederations of small governments have been praised by many - from Plato and Aristotle, through Rousseau, Montesquieu, Smith and Mills, to contemporary federalist legal and economic scholars - as that political institution most likely to encourage a trio of social virtues: political participation, protection of the sovereign rights of citizens and economic efficiency. On participation and the virtues of small governments see Pateman (1970, pp. 46, 110, 111 and Frug (1980). On economic efficiency and the positive role of small governments see Smith (1776) and Tiebout (1956). Other scholars have been more skeptical. The Federalist Papers (particularly at No. 47), the intellectual blueprint for the US Constitution, raises serious doubts about the virtues of loose confederations of small governments. Leading contemporary social scientists from political science (Robert Dahl and William Riker) and economics (Joseph Schumpeter and Paul Samuelson) have lent theoretical support to the Federalists’ concerns. On small governments and their consequences for meaningful political participation, see Schumpeter (1943), Dahl (1956), and Dahl and Tufte (1973). On the potential inability of small governments to protect group rights, see Riker (1964). For a discussion of why small governments might be economically inefficient, see Samuelson (1954). Like the Federalists, these scholars have argued that a strong, democratically elected central government is generally the more effective means to ensure political participation, protection of the rights of citizens, and more efficient and equitable resource allocations. Which level of government is best suited to make public policies, given that we want those policies to be democratically decided, respectful of personal rights, and economically efficient? A considered answer - whether for Europe’s new Economic Union, the new South African Constitution, or to the regulation of anticompetitive firm behavior within the United States or the Economic Union - requires a careful balancing of the benefits and costs of decentralized and centralized political structures. To fashion such a balance, it is essential that we first review the potential virtues of each federalist structure. We begin by defining what is meant by decentralized and centralized federalist structures. In this chapter, governments will be defined as ‘decentralized and state’ or ‘centralized and national’ according to the combination of two constitutional decisions. The first decision - called the partition decision - divides the single national citizenry into states. Following the partition decision, there will be a group of separate state governments and one central government to which each state will send (for simplicity) one representative to a central legislature, the single
9700
Federalism
663
policymaking body of the central government. Policy decisions made by state governments will be decided by their separate legislatures. Adding another legislative chamber or an executive with a veto to our analysis will only improve the ability of federalist systems to meet the participation, sovereignty and efficiency objectives. For an analysis of the effects of bicameral legislatures on government performance, see Levmore (1992). For an analysis of the effects of a president with veto powers on government performance, see Fitts and Inman (1992). Courts and legislatures are concerned with the second constitutional decision - the assignment decision - which allocates final political responsibility for choices over a social or economic policy to either the legislature of the central government or to the legislatures of each of the separate states. If the assignment decision allocates ultimate responsibility for a social or economic policy to the states (or their localities), then we describe policymaking for this class of government decisions as ‘state’ or ‘decentralized’. In contrast, if the assignment decision gives final responsibility for a social or economic policy to the central government, then we describe policymaking for these assigned responsibilities as ‘national’ or ‘centralized’. Together, these two constitutional decisions define the essential federalist - decentralized or centralized - structure of the government. We realize, of course, that federalist structures may have decentralized and centralized components, as, for example, when the central government mandates the form and function of certain decentralized government activities. The much debated virtues of these decentralized or centralized governmental structures include democratic political participation and enhanced economic efficiency. Which federalist structure or combination of structures favors which virtues given the realities of the political and economic marketplace? We review the arguments and the contemporary evidence in Parts A (participation) and B (economic efficiency) below. Not surprisingly, neither a centralized nor a decentralized structure maximizes public participation and economic efficiency all the time. Which structure is preferred turns on a balancing of these values. In Part C we discuss briefly how a society might set that balance.
664
Federalism
9700
A. Political Participation 2. The Benefits of Participation Political participation is defined as ‘actions through which ordinary citizens of a political system influence or attempt to influence (political) outcomes’ (Nagel, 1980, p. 1). Actions include voting, debating, marching, picketing, contributing, and passive and armed resistance. The aim of these actions is to influence the direction of government policy. Active citizens may be successful in moving public policies closer to their preferred outcomes because of their participation. In this case, citizens are said to have influence. Or active citizens may be unsuccessful, their political actions having no effect on policy outcomes. In this case, the citizens have attempted, but failed, to influence political outcomes. The benefits to citizens of their own, and others’, participation can be divided into three categories: instrumental or utilitarian, developmental or educative, and intrinsic or consumptive. In the utilitarian view, perhaps argued most directly in the work of Bentham and James Mill, political participation serves a specific function; to ensure that government maximizes aggregated citizen utility or welfare. In democratic societies, political participation is the necessary check on abuses of citizen welfare by ill-informed or even greedy elected officials. Political participation guarantees that abusive elected officials will be exposed and defeated at the next election. For the utilitarians, political participation’s value is fundamentally instrumental; it plays, in the words of Pateman (1970), a ‘protective function’ for the public welfare. For Jean-Jacques Rousseau and John Stuart Mill, political participation was instrumental to another, perhaps more important, end: it protected citizen liberties. While both Rousseau and Mill acknowledged the instrumental value of participation in protecting private economic interests and ensuring good (efficient) government, they extended the argument of the utilitarians to include participation’s protective value for personal freedom as well. Participation ensures that no one individual or group is master over any other - ‘The rights and interests of every or any person are only secure from being disregarded, when the person interested is himself able, and habitually disposed, to stand up for them’ (Mill, 1960, p. 186; see Pateman, 1970, Chapter 2, particularly pp. 26-27, for a summary of the arguments of J.S. Mill and J. Rousseau in favor of political participation). For many scholars, however, participation does much more than just protect private economic interests and personal liberties. Aristotle, Rousseau, J.S. Mill, de Tocqueville, and contemporary commentators such
9700
Federalism
665
as Dewey and Pateman view citizen political participation as serving an important educative function as well. By participating in the political process the individual learns that his private interests are intimately linked to the interests of others. This knowledge leads to a willingness to compromise, to put private interests aside and to call upon values of justice and common good when making public choices. There may be beneficial spillovers to private decision making, too. Having recognized and accepted the validity of others’ interests in the public arena, we may be more accepting of those interests in our private dealings. Simply put, we may be different people - more tolerant, less selfish - after political participation. Finally, political participation may provide direct consumptive benefits to those who participate. From those who simply like to hear the sound of their own voice or revel in controlling others, to those who take genuine satisfaction in having contributed to a cause they feel is worthy, the act of political participation offers many a personal consumption benefit. How else might we explain widespread voting in national elections? (Ordeshook and Riker, 1973, Ch. 3). While perhaps not the most compelling argument for increased political participation, it should not be ignored.
3. Metrics of Political Participation If political participation is an activity to be valued, how do we know if there is more or less of it within society? The instrumental, or influence, effects of individual political participation can be measured by a metric of political power. At one extreme, the individual fully controls the outcome, while at the other the individual has no influence over the outcome. If one person controls the outcome, then, of course, all others must be powerless (see Nagel, 1975, for a detailed discussion). The participatory, or ‘actions’, effects of political participation can be measured by a metric of political effort. One plausible effort metric would be the hours, or the hourly equivalent of dollar contributions, given by the individual to political activity. Whether an individual engages in political activity and whether those activities translate into political influence depends on the individual’s personal desires to participate and to have power, and on how society’s political environment translates individual participatory activity into influence. Important attributes of the political environment will include the political institutions that define voting rights, freedom of expression and access to elected officials and the legislature. Also important is the number of citizens who can participate in public decision making.
666
Federalism
9700
As a theoretical matter, one would expect that participation would be higher in local politics simply because the benefits of influence are greater the fewer the number of disparate constituents. However, individual political effort is not so easily predicted. When participatory effort is more productive in producing political influence, as it is likely to be in small democratic states, individuals might actually participate for fewer hours, choosing to allocate some of their increased ‘political productivity’ into other, non-political activities. Ultimately, how political institutions and the population of the nation and its states affect political influence and political effort is an empirical question. Certainly the early (Aristotle, Rousseau, J.S. Mill) and contemporary (Pateman, Frug) advocates of participatory politics see the small, democratic state as most conducive to high values of influence and effort for the average citizen.
4. Measuring Participation How will the two constitutional decisions central to setting the federalist structure - the partition decision and the assignment decision - affect the level of political participation in a society? The answer is ultimately empirical: How do political influence and participatory effort change as political decision-making moves from large central governments to smaller, decentralized states and local polities? Participation theorists have not hesitated to make predictions, typically arguing that a federalist system with a large number of small states with substantial policy responsibilities will increase the political influence of each citizen and generate increased political effort as well. There is little doubt that this is true for political influence, especially in societies with strong guarantees of equal political rights. Less certain, however, is the relationship between political effort and the size of states with decision making power; it is not difficult to present arguments that effort may rise, fall, or even remain unchanged as federalist systems become more decentralized. The empirical evidence on how political influence and participatory effort change as the governmental structure becomes decentralized is sparse, but what is available generally supports the prediction that both influence and effort will rise as the size of government declines. Within-country comparisons of political influence and effort across small and large governments seem the most appropriate testing ground of the participation hypothesis. (See Dahl and Tufte, 1973, pp. 44-53, for a review and critique of the cross-national evidence on size and participation.) First, citizens surveyed in five countries (United States, Britain, West Germany, Italy, and
9700
Federalism
667
Mexico) all reported making greater effort to understand, and having more success in understanding, local rather than national political issues. In the surveyed countries, citizen efforts to influence government were also typically two to three times higher for local than for national governments. In supporting evidence, a detailed survey of political participation across Swedish cities found average citizens in small communities were more aware of local politics than their counterparts in middle-sized cities and both knew more basic local political facts than large city residents. Second, political effectiveness or influence - at least as perceived by citizens - also seems to increase as governments get smaller in size. Again, the five nation survey finds that citizens feel much more influential at the local than at the national level; typically, half of the citizens in the surveyed countries felt they had no influence over national policies while only 25 to 30 percent felt powerless at the local level. A more detailed analysis of the US subsample showed a significant positive correlation between an index of political powerlessness and size of government (Finifter, 1970, pp. 389-410). Indirect evidence from the Swedish study also implies that citizen influence declines as governments get larger; the gap between the percentage of citizens and the percentage of elected officials who would support a tax increase increases as communities get larger. Finally, evidence from the United States, the Netherlands and Switzerland all show that politics in larger communities, states and cantons are increasingly dominated by organized interest groups or political parties. While such groups make participation easier for some citizens, they may also it more difficult for others. If so, then Rousseau’s concern that participation becomes more unequal as governments get larger is confirmed. Any final conclusions regarding the effects of institutional decentralization on participatory effort and political influence must await more complete empirical analyses. Nonetheless, theoretical argument and the current empirical evidence lead us to the tentative conclusion that smaller governments, and thus more decentralized federalist structures, are likely to encourage the valued goal of greater political participation.
B. Federalism and Economic Efficiency 5. The Pros and Cons of Decentralization Using the economic efficiency criterion to choose the appropriate federalist structure is a complex endeavor involving a comparison of the economic benefits and costs of assigning responsibility to each level of government: in the US, to the national or central level, the state level, or the local
668
Federalism
9700
government level. In a federal system there are two important dimensions to economic efficiency. First, interjurisdictional efficiency involves the appropriate allocation of individuals and other resources, such as capital, among the different jurisdictions. Interjurisdictional efficiency is achieved when the public activities of these interacting governments satisfy the collective demands of individuals living in different jurisdictions at a minimum economic cost. A full analysis would also include the economic costs of politically deciding what those policies should be and ensuring that the politically decided policies are what the government actually provides. These latter costs have been identified elsewhere as the transactions costs of government. They include the costs of selecting legislators, the decision-making costs of setting a policy, and the monitoring costs of ensuring that the policy is put in place (see Breton and Scott, 1978). Second, intrajurisdictional efficiency requires a choice of public activities which satisfies the collective demand within a given jurisdiction, measured as the willingness to pay for those activities for all individuals within the jurisdiction, and again does so at minimum costs. In our complex federal system both interjurisdictional and intrajurisdictional inefficiencies can arise; the former because of spillovers the decisions and actions of individuals within one jurisdiction can have effects on individuals located in other jurisdictions that are not accurately reflected in the marketplace - and the latter because the political process may not generate outcomes within a jurisdiction which maximize the wellbeing of its residents, that is, create political inefficiencies. In a broad sense, the choice of the appropriate jurisdiction to be responsible for a government activity involves a trade-off - the larger the jurisdiction the less likely that there will be spillovers from one jurisdiction to the next, but the more likely that the political process will lead to a misallocation of resources within jurisdictions. A decentralized system of governments is ideal from the point of view of intrajurisdictional efficiency, since assigning economic responsibility to the smaller and more homogeneous of the jurisdictions increases the likelihood that services provided and regulations promulgated will be consistent with the desires of each and every member of the population. In other words, in a decentralized system of governments, local tastes for public goods are likely to be less disparate than national tastes. The resulting reduction in the inefficiency of providing public goods (since citizens with similar tastes would prefer to consumer the same level of public goods) has been characterized as the decentralization theorem by Wallace Oates. Unfortunately, decentralization has its disadvantages, due primarily to the spillovers that are likely to arise when jurisdiction size is small. A less
9700
Federalism
669
decentralized system with larger jurisdictions can minimize the spillovers involved, while at the same time taking advantage of the lower cost of promulgating and enforcing certain regulations or dispensing the benefits of public programs, and the lower cost of obtaining and using information. Our analysis of the political economy of federalism begins with a critique of the arguments for a strongly decentralized system. While we agree that a focus on the presence of substantial spillovers is appropriate, we stress the fact that decentralization will not guarantee an optimal public sector mix even when no spillovers are present. We believe that a complete theory of federalism cannot rely solely on the ‘Tiebout Model’, an ideal model of a fiscal competition between many independent local governments. Appropriately specified, Tiebout’s decentralized model of governmental competition is formally analogous to the purely competitive market model with complete information used to study market competition between private firms. In the Tiebout model, government policies are determined by market, or economic, exchange alone. Unfortunately, the assumptions needed to ensure that governmental competition is fully analogous to efficient private market competition are very strong, and may not hold in realistic public economies (see, for example, Rubinfeld, 1987.) A more appropriate analytic framework - based upon political models of state government decision making and interstate bargaining - yields, we feel, more appropriate conclusions as to the likely economic performance of decentralized public environments. In the section that follows we study how such systems are likely to work. We conclude that when viewed as a political rather than market process, decentralized federalism may be economically inefficient. This conclusion suggests the need to consider a more centralized environment, using the central, or national, government to set policy. To be consistent, however, the analysis of central government performance must use the same political model that found inefficiencies at the decentralized level. This we do by explaining how central government regulatory policies also might be inefficient - indeed, potentially worse, for political reasons, than the inefficient state and local policies which the central policies had hoped to correct.
6. The Tiebout Approach According to one view, the world of decentralized, competitive governments will allow for a national regulatory marketplace, in which individuals move among local jurisdictions or states to select the regulatory combination that they most desire. Just as a private market place forces suppliers to produce
670
Federalism
9700
their goods at the lowest cost, and to provide the goods most desired by consumers, so too will the pressure of taxpayers shopping, through exit and relocation, force governments to be efficient in their provision of public goods and public goods and services. According to this view, public activities should be decentralized, except when there are significant economic spillovers from the regulating jurisdiction to its neighbors. When spillovers result, decentralized governments may ignore important economic costs or benefits which will lead them to over- or underprovide the activity. In these instances central government review is appropriate. We must be clear, however, about the assumptions built into the Tiebout model of decentralized governments on which this model relies. Each household and business is highly mobile and chooses to reside in the jurisdiction that offers the tax-expenditure-regulation package that it most prefers. As typically specified, five conditions define the competitive Tiebout public economy: 1. Publicly provided goods, services, and regulatory activities are provided at minimum average cost. (If assumption 1 holds, there is an efficient population size which minimizes the average cost per household of providing that government activity. This rules out using Tiebout competition to allocate ‘pure public’ goods, those goods where additional users of the government’s facility does not reduce the consumption benefits enjoyed by previous users. Typical examples of a pure public good include defense, television or radio signals, and new knowledge. Goods which can be allocated by the Tiebout competitive process are those goods where more users reduce, proportionally, the benefits enjoyed by current users. Rather than pure public goods, these goods are congested public goods. Education, highways, police protection and parks are examples. The efficient scale of operation for such goods must be sufficiently small (for example, 15,000 in population) so that each household can find a suitable jurisdiction in which to reside. Existing evidence suggests that this constraint can be met for many government services; see, for example, Ladd and Yinger, 1989, pp.83, 85.) 2. There is a perfectly elastic supply of political jurisdictions, each capable of replicating all attractive economic features of its competitors. (This assumption ensures that efficient alternatives exist; this is the task of public sector entrepreneur-politicians who run against, and defeat, inefficient incumbents; competitive political entrepreneurs play a role analogous to take-over ‘artists’ in the private market. Or public sector entrepreneurs can appear as enterprising real estate developers who build new jurisdictions -
9700
Federalism
671
analogous to ‘new entrants’ in a private market - to draw away dissatisfied residents from inefficient governments; see Epple and Zelenitz, 1981.) 3. Mobility of households and businesses among jurisdictions is costless. 4. Households and businesses are fully informed about the fiscal and regulatory policies of each jurisdiction. (Assumptions 3 and 4 ensure that when possible inefficiencies arise, households and businesses can move to otherwise similar jurisdictions without those inefficiencies.) 5. There are no interjurisdictional externalities or spillovers. (Assumption 5 ensures that all public regulatory activities can be provided within these efficient jurisdictions - larger governments or intergovernmental cooperation is not required. In the end, a regulated economy satisfying assumptions 1 to 5, and organized as a fully decentralized network of competing jurisdictions, will maximize economic efficiency. Citizens and businesses can consume their preferred levels of the public regulatory activity with a minimum expenditure of production and transactions costs.)
7. Critiquing Tiebout While a useful starting point, the Tiebout model does not provide a complete theory of federalism. The assumptions 1 through 5 may arguably apply to a local public activity such as rent control, which is imposed in California in only a relatively few cities, thereby leaving most households the opportunity to move to non-rent control jurisdictions as they see fit. However, the assumptions are less likely to hold for more centralized activities, where choices are more limited and moving is more costly. If assumptions 2 through 5 do not hold, we must rethink the optimality of complete decentralization. The model of perfectly competitive private markets has long been an appealing paradigm for economists, in part because some real world markets do actually seem to operate in that manner, and in part because if they do, the efficiency consequences seem clear. Neither of these reasons applies without qualification to the Tiebout framework for competitive governments, however. Consider assumption 2, that there is a perfectly elastic supply of political jurisdictions. The model of perfectly competitive markets yields an efficient allocation of resources in part because firms are free to make the efficient choices of inputs and outputs, and in part because entry into and exit from an industry are free. In the Tiebout model, competitive governments fill the role of firms. But governments may be constrained by internal politics when making their input and output choices, and free entry of new governments is by no means assured in actual public goods economies. (See generally, Epple
672
Federalism
9700
and Zelenitz (1981), arguing that limited entry permits competitive governments to maximize public ‘monopoly profits’ from the provision of public goods and public regulations and the level and allocation of those profits will be determined politically within the jurisdiction.) For example, an entrepreneur cannot simply invest his capital to build a new city. If assumption 2 does not hold, four potentially adverse consequences for economic efficiency are likely to arise. First, with a limited supply of jurisdictions each government is likely to contain citizens with different views of what constitutes the government’s best policy. If so, local politics becomes important. If local decisions are made by majority rule, the outcome will not necessarily be economically efficient (see Bergstrom et al., 1988). Second, when the economy can no longer replicate attractive local jurisdictions, economic rents can be earned. The presence of these publicly created rents associated with the desirability of some locations over others can in turn create a tension between the fiscal entrepreneurs who wish to develop new communities and the owners of the desirable locations. As a result, there is no guarantee that the market for land and for other scarce resources will be economically efficient. Third, when private sector job opportunities are not identical in all locations, productive private sector employment may be sacrificed as labor is attracted to less efficient locations for fiscal reasons. The consequence is a less efficient private economy (see Buchanan and Goetz, 1972, for the initial presentation of this argument and the summaries in Boadway and Flatters, 1982, and Wildasin, 1986). Fourth, once the supply of jurisdictions is fixed, the analogy of the decentralized model of federalism to anonymous free market competition is no longer valid. Each local government may be aware of the potential effect of its action on other jurisdictions. It will then act strategically in making its decisions on the basis of its best guess as to how other jurisdictions will respond. In this framework the actions of each local jurisdiction, even if small, can have a substantial effect on the welfare of the rest of the decentralized world. Essentially, a self-interested decision by those in power in one jurisdiction can result in a series of distortions that arise throughout the effected network of other jurisdictions. For example, a decision by one jurisdiction to offer a tax break to attract new business could lead to a competition in which many jurisdictions offer a variety of tax business tax benefits. While it is difficult to predict the exact consequence of the rather complex behavioral patterns that can arise when these strategic interactions are taken into account, it seems clear that an efficient outcome is unlikely to arise. States may, for example, underprovide welfare services, or more
9700
Federalism
673
generally to underprovide public services in which they have particular production advantages and therefore should provide in abundance (see Gramlich and Laren, 1984, on welfare competition among states, and Pestieau, 1977). This could occur because a state realizes that by providing a high level of welfare benefits it is likely to attract new low-income residents from nearby states, thus adding substantially to its cost of providing such benefits. States might also provide substantial tax benefits to attract business, or at least to avoid losing business to other competing states, and in the process undertax business capital and overtax the residential base (see, for example, Break, 1967, pp. 23-24; Oates, 1972, pp. 142-143; for a review of the more recent literature, see Inman and Rubinfeld, 1996). An equivalent phenomenon can occur with respect to regulatory policies. States might relax their environmental controls to encourage business migration, or simply to forestall the loss of business because other states had or were about to relax their environmental regulations. This argument has been developed by Cumberland (1981); see also Fischel, 1975, p.119), and more generally, Oates and Schwab (1986). Note that the competitive process which leads to a uniformity of regulation among states is not consistent with the advantages of the diversity associated with the Tiebout model, nor is it likely to be efficient. The result could be a ‘race to the bottom’ resulting in an equilibrium in which environmental regulations are ‘undersupplied’. (The uniformity of occupational regulation is described in Stigler, 1971, p. 130.) For a more general argument that the regulatory actions of individual states may not result in an optimal federal system, given the incentives that determine political choice, see Rose-Ackerman (1981), also Revesz (1992). Assumption 3, that citizens and businesses are costlessly mobile between political jurisdictions, is also problematic. The assumption applies best to suburban jurisdictions among which individuals and firms have a good deal of mobility. When the number of cities and towns within a metropolitan area is substantial, families and firms have significant choice in their provision of public goods and public regulations. Empirical evidence supporting the Tiebout hypothesis has focused entirely on this local public sector. For studies of household relocation, see Gramlich and Rubinfeld (1982), who used survey data for Michigan and concluded that their results were ‘reasonably consistent with a Tiebout interpretation: in large metropolitan areas there is quite extensive grouping; in smaller areas, there is some grouping’ (pp. 554-555). Oates (1972, pp. 162-179) studied the metropolitan New Jersey region, using tests of the capitalization of public goods differentials into property values, and concluded that public goods preferences could explain migration among neighboring cities and towns. For evidence that businesses are sensitive to local taxes and services when
674
Federalism
9700
relocating within a metropolitan area, see Bartik (1988) and McConnell and Schwab (1990), suggesting that environmental regulations are not an important factor affecting business location decisions. Activities of local governments in metropolitan areas - save those with significant spillovers are likely to meet the competitive test (see Courant and Rubinfeld, 1981). Yet much economic activity occurs at the state level, where assumption 3 is unlikely to hold. Studies of migration show that most household moves are within metropolitan areas, not between states. Those who do move between states are typically job motivated, and are not primarily seeking a more attractive public service/public regulation environment (Easterbrook, 1983, pp. 35 n. 28). (See also the detailed evidence on interstate and interregional location of households reviewed in Greenwood, 1986.) If assumption 3 does not apply, then the model cannot guarantee overall (that is, market plus public sector) efficiency. Assumption 4, that households and businesses are fully informed, presents another problem for the Tiebout argument. Households and firms must have reasonably accurate information about the tax, spending, and regulatory policies of the communities in which they will reside. Yet, it is often difficult for individuals and firms to ascertain the implications of regulations within their own jurisdiction, let alone make a reasonable judgment about the public activities that will exist in other jurisdictions at a future point in time after which they have relocated. Stigler (1971, p. 130) has argued, ‘(t)he voter’s expenditure to learn the merits of individual policy proposals and to express his preferences ... are determined by expected costs and returns’ and that, in the case of regulatory policy, this cost-benefit calculus dissuades voters from discovering very much. When we view the location decision as involving a choice of public sector packages, and we take into account the fact that other jurisdictions are likely to be changing those packages over time, the informational demands that must be satisfied for the competitive system of governments to work effectively seem very great. When assumption 4 no longer holds, that is, when there is incomplete information about the costs and levels of regulatory activity, an important principal-agent problem arises. Households and firms have two options: go it alone and risk being exploited by better informed fiscal entrepreneurs and local factors of production, or hire an agent to protect household and firm interests. Complications arise when information about agent performance is costly and some deceitful agents survive, or when the expertise provided by agents to households and firms cannot itself be kept private. To the extent the market for ‘agents’ works perfectly - all inefficient or exploitive providers are exposed, and only truthful agents survive - the final outcome will still be efficient, but some fiscal surplus will be allocated to the agents
9700
Federalism
675
as payment for services performed. Such payments can be made as a contingent fee conditional on the performance of the agent in managing the purchase of the public good, or as a competitively determined lump-sum payment to a previously identified - by reputation or certification - ‘truthful’ agent. In both instances there will emerge externalities in the market for agents that can cause an inefficient level of information to be provided about the fiscal performance of the Tiebout communities. When information about agent performance or abilities is available at no cost, then agent efforts can be fully monitored (avoiding all problems of moral hazard) and agent abilities will be fully known (avoiding all problems of adverse selection). The agent market can then work perfectly. When information about agents is costly, however, there is no guarantee that the efficient agent market will arise (see Holmstrom, 1985). Similarly, when the information provided by the agents to households cannot be kept private, then there will be externality-caused inefficiency in the information market. The final assumption, requiring no spillovers, is an important real world violation of the Tiebout framework that may require central government intervention. A spillover or externality arises when the activities of a jurisdiction affect directly the wellbeing of an individual or firm in another jurisdiction and the decision making of the first jurisdiction does not take these effects on others into account. For a discussion of public goods externalities see Williams (1966) and Brainard and Dolbear (1967) among others. This literature is critically reviewed and extended by Pauly (1970). For a discussion of tax externalities see the survey in Inman and Rubinfeld (1996). One occurs when a spillover offers a positive benefit to a neighboring community, for example, through the regulation of socially damaging air pollution emitted by a locally valuable firm. When such positive spillovers exist, state and local governments may provide too little of the activity. The converse case provides a third example. Here a socially productive firm produces only local pollution, for example, a garbage or nuclear waste site. The incentive is for the local community to impose stringent regulations on such a firm so as to force its relocation onto a neighboring community. A negative regulatory externality results. If the neighboring communities respond with similar regulations, the firm may have no place to go, even though it is in the interests of all jurisdictions to have the firm locate in at least one locality. With negative spillovers, there may be too much state and local activity. For an illustration of this point with respect to the regulation of solid wastes, see David and Lester (1989). In these circumstances, a federal or state set of uniform standards may be preferred by all. In fact, uniform national regulation not only can take advantage of economies of scale in administration, it can also produce scale economies of production and distribution for firms, while at the same time
676
Federalism
9700
reducing their location costs (see Rose-Ackerman, 1994). Augmentation of national standards by states or localities can be allowed, but only if the additional regulations do not generate spillovers by benefiting local households and businesses at the expenses of nonresidents. The general point is clear: when assumption 5 is violated, there is no guarantee that decentralized competition will produce an efficient allocation of public and private resources. Our review of the assumptions of the Tiebout framework lead us to conclude that the analogy between the model of competitive governments and the model of competitive markets is not sufficiently strong to serve as the basis of a theory of federalism. If we are to have a compelling efficiency basis for drawing the lines between decentralized and centralized governmental policy it must be found in an analysis based upon paradigms other than Tiebout’s model of public sector competition. Our discussion in the next two sections seeks to provide that paradigm.
8. The Politics of State Legislative Policy Economic efficiency demands that state public activities be efficient both with respect to the preferences of residents of the state (intrajurisdictional efficiency) and with respect to the preferences of residents outside the state (interjurisdictional efficiency). Separate political institutions exist through which each dimension of efficiency might be achieved. State legislatures and their appointed state agencies are the means through which residents within a state might hope to obtain intrajurisdictional efficiency. Interstate cooperative agreements struck between residents, or their elected agents, of neighboring states are the means to interjurisdictional efficiency. We consider the potential of each, beginning with an analysis of state legislative processes. When elected representatives join together in a state legislature, they are free to fashion coalitions and set regulatory policies as they wish, subject only to the constraint that decisions receive the approval of a majority of legislators. Majority-rule legislatures making decisions over multiple public policies must resolve a fundamental structural defect: the propensity of the majority-rule process to cycle from one policy outcome to another. This fundamental observation regarding majority rule processes has been well recognized at least since the work of De Condorcet (1785) and is known popularly as the paradox of voting: even though majority rule leads a legislature to vote for policy A over policy B, and for policy B over policy C, it is certainly possible, and often likely, that policy C will be defeat policy A. Arrow (1963) proves that this paradox of voting is a symptom of a more
9700
Federalism
677
fundamental problem with all democratic processes: there is no guarantee that such processes can find a best outcome or are immune to manipulation. Thus, the design of political institutions will almost inevitably be a search among the second-best. For a survey of this literature in the context of the new political economy, see Inman (1987). When no winning coalition is capable of holding its majority against small policy variations offered by a losing minority, then either no decision will be made or final policy outcomes will be random and uncertain. If legislatures are to reach decisions, additional legislative institutions must be discovered for overcoming this inherent instability of the majority-rule process. Two institutional approaches are commonly used by legislatures. The first assigns agenda-setting powers to a small subset of members, say the speaker of the house or a key legislative committee. Other members in the legislature then simply vote - up or down - on the items in the approved agenda. Most likely, policies will be approved by a bare majority - a minimal winning coalition - in this strong agenda-setter legislature. For articulation of the general theory of how this process overcomes cycling, see Baron and Ferejohn (1989). For a careful description of what legislative institutions are used to assign agenda control, see Shepsle (1979). There is an extensive literature which tests for the direct influence of agenda-setters - typically congressional committees - on policy outcomes; see Krehbiel (1992) for a critical but balanced review. A second strategy shares agenda-setting powers among all members, giving each legislator a right to select his most preferred policy in that policy area most germane to the legislator’s constituents. This second approach to legislative decision making involves each legislator deferring to the preferred policies of all other legislators, provided the other legislators defer to the legislator’s own policy requests. The guiding principle here is a norm of deference - ‘You scratch my back, I’ll scratch yours’ - and it typically results in legislative proposals which are approved unanimously. For this reason such legislatures are often called ‘universalistic’. The guiding theory can be found in Weingast (1979) and Niou and Ordeshook (1985). The theory has been developed for, and its applications must be limited to, understanding how legislative bodies allocate government projects and government regulations what has been called distributive politics (see Lowi, 1969). A norm of deference is not an appropriate model for predicting how legislatures will decide redistributive policies such as welfare or progressive taxation, politics where one group constituents must lose to another. Details regarding the legislative institutions needed to enforce the norm of deference can be found in Weingast and Marshall (1988) for the details of how such a legislative norm of deference might be enforced.
678
Federalism
9700
A single legislator uncertain as to whether she will be one of the lucky winners in the bare majority legislature will typically favor the more open rules of the universalistic legislature. Intuitively, the universalistic legislature is preferred because under universalism activities that benefit the legislator’s district are nearly certain to be chosen, and a substantial portion of the costs will be borne by other districts. (If benefits exceed average project costs in a majority of districts - a likely case - then a legislature run by a norm of deference will be the preferred legislative institution. Weingast (1979) and Niou and Ordeshook (1985) prove exactly when this outcome holds. See also Schwartz (1989) or Inman and Fitts (1990), both of whom extend the analysis to legislative projects of variable size. The conclusion that legislators prefer universalism to bare-majority rule extends to this more general case. Universalistic state legislatures operating under a norm of deference run a significant risk that their public activities will be economically inefficient, however. Consider, for example, the typical case of a state regulation which raises industry prices within a state, effectively reducing output below competitive levels. Those who benefit from such a regulation are state residents who own capital and other ‘specialized’ factors of production employed in the regulated industry. Those who lose are the state’s consumers who buy the output of the regulated industry and the state’s taxpayers who pay for the regulatory bureaucracy. Assume further that the industry would be competitive, pricing at marginal cost, if unregulated, but would act as a profit-maximizing cartel if regulated. The cartel would choose to maximize its profits by raising its price above the competitive level, and by reducing its output. Three conclusions follow from this framework. First, industry producers within the state prefer to be at a regulated output near the cartel profit-maximizing level, because as regulation nears this level industry profits, the ‘marginal benefits’ of regulation to the interest groups that own the specialized inputs that gain from regulation, are maximized. Second, state consumers of industry output prefer the competitive output, for at zero industry regulation, the tax costs and lost consumer benefits from regulation - the ‘marginal costs’ of regulation - are minimized. Finally, any regulation of a competitive industry is inefficient from the perspective of all state residents, because the additional cost to state taxpayers and consumers everywhere greater than the additional benefit to state producers. How then will a universalistic state legislature set government policy for the state? Under the norm of deference each elected state representative is allowed to propose a state policy which maximizes the returns to his constituents. Consider how one legislator (perhaps with a group of other legislators representing similar districts) might view an activity when all of
9700
Federalism
679
the benefits, but only a small fraction of the state’s costs, are felt within the district(s). In this case, constituents would internalize all of the marginal benefits, while constituents will take into account only a small fraction of the marginal costs. For the affected legislator(s), the preferred activity would be a higher than efficient output. But not all legislators will propose inefficient activities. Only those legislators from districts whose local economy has concentrated benefits will find the activity to be in their interests. When they do, state politics will generate an intrajurisdictional inefficiency. States with strong political parties capable of disciplining party members or states with strong governors capable of mobilizing broad-based citizen support may be able to control these intrajurisdictional inefficiencies of universalistic legislatures, but not perfectly. Consider first the ability of strong political parties to control policy. By definition strong parties form a stable legislative majority. Members who might be tempted to deviate from the party’s platform can be disciplined so that deviations will not occur. Government policy will therefore be the policy which is in the interests of the stable, majority party. In this stylized framework, only those producers in legislative districts belonging to the majority party will be favored. Minority party districts will receive no benefits. When proposing an activity for their constituents, representatives in the majority party will be required by the party to consider the effects of their proposed activity on constituents in all districts controlled by the party. From the perspective of the majority party, therefore, an activity in one district will still provide benefits to party constituents, but will now impose only a fraction (perhaps slightly greater than 50 percent) of the total cost of the activity on party members. From the majority party’s perspective, the preferred activity level in a party-controlled district will be an efficient level, where party marginal benefits equal party marginal costs. Because the party preferred level internalizes the costs to party members, the inefficiency must be less than the inefficiency created by the universalistic legislature. The loss of intrajurisdictional efficiency declines accordingly. Put simply, by internalizing more of the costs of government activity, strong political parties can improve the efficiency performance of state regulations. For empirical evidence that strong political parties may have controlled legislative inefficiencies, see Inman and Fitts (1990, pp. 111-115). Political parties may even promote full economic efficiency. This limiting case occurs if the political party controls all representatives in the legislature. Here there is an incentive for all districts to elect a representative to the stable majority party, since this is their only way to join the controlling coalition and to receive constituent benefits. With a single stable majority party, therefore,
680
Federalism
9700
there is strong pressure towards full economic efficiency. Wittman (1989) makes this argument. Strong governors can also improve the efficiency performance of state regulations. Michael Fitts and Robert Inman present an analysis of executive leadership in economic policy where the executive who has access to needed political resources - appointment powers, control over appropriated budgets, and an executive veto - and with the appropriate political incentive - running in a national or state-wide election - will seek efficient economic reform. Using appointment powers and discretionary executive authority over policies and the budget, the governor can fashion a reform coalition in which each member district agrees to sacrifice its inefficient policy for a compensating executive-controlled substitute policy. Facing a universalistic legislature, executive-led reform will improve economic efficiency for all state residents. A successful reform package must share the benefits of this reduced inefficiency with residents in the original district and the rest of the state’s taxpayers and consumers. On balance, reform makes all residents in the state better off, thereby increasing the governor’s chances for re-election. But only strong governors, those with sufficient executive-controlled resources to pay compensation to those districts made worse off, can hope to achieve reform. Even then reform will typically fall short of full efficiency. We conclude that state politics will often encourage inefficient governmental activities for state residents, and that these intrajurisdictional inefficiencies are likely to be greatest in those states with weak political parties and weak executives. Importantly, these intrajurisdictional inefficiencies occur even when there are no spillovers to citizens outside the state. Matters are even worse, however, when there are spillovers, for here even strong political parties and strong governors will find it politically useful to support the (now nationally) inefficient activity. The case of activities with out-of-state spillovers involves interjurisdictional inefficiency. As with the case of intrajurisdictional inefficiency, the marginal benefits continue to reflect the benefits to residents within the state. The marginal costs, however, now encompass the national marginal costs to the residents of the state (state marginal costs plus the marginal costs of lost consumer benefits to out-of-state residents). These national marginal costs are greater than the statewide marginal costs discussed previously because they reflect the additional lost consumer surplus suffered by out-of-state residents. Government policy remains a political decision within the state, however, set by the balancing of state constituents’ marginal benefits and costs. Large interjurisdictional inefficiencies can remain even when strong parties and strong governors successfully control their own state’s intrajurisdictional inefficiencies. Even though the inefficient regulation
9700
Federalism
681
declines with a strong party (or strong governor), significant interjurisdictional inefficiencies may remain. Even a fully efficient state government setting policy efficiently within the state could impose large interjurisdictional inefficiencies on out-of-state citizens; the ‘state’ of OPEC is a prominent example.
9. Coasian Interjurisdictional Bargains Might we imagine a political response from neighboring states to correct these interjurisdictional spillovers? Economists have designed systems of grants (matching and non-matching, specific and general) as well as tax and subsidy arrangements which can greatly increase the effiency of a decentralized system. However, a more distinctive approach, which we pursue in depth here, is the facilitation of interstate agreements, or Coasian bargains, to remove interjurisdictional inefficiencies. The bargain would require the out-of-state residents to ‘compensate’ the producers from the regulating state for the profits they lose when the inefficient regulation is removed. As Coase and others have pointed out, there are sufficient benefits to in-state and out-of-state consumers and taxpayers harmed by the activity that compensation can be paid to the state-created cartel, with the out-of-state residents remaining better off. In practice, such compensation would be paid through an interstate agreement with neighboring states paying compensation to the regulating state, with the resulting compensation then passed on by that state’s governor or legislature to within state producers. But we expect such a Coasian bargain between out-of-state consumers and within-state producers will be hard to effect. Successful Coasian bargains require five assumptions to be met: 1. there are no, or very small, resource costs associated with the bargaining process; 2. preferences over bargaining outcomes and the resources of households are common knowledge; 3. bargaining agents perfectly represent the economic interests of their constituents; 4. all bargaining agreements are costlessly enforceable; and 5. the parties can agree to a division of the bargaining surplus. Only when assumptions 1 through 5 hold will interjurisdictional efficiency be achieved. How likely are these assumptions to be valid?
682
Federalism
9700
On its face, assumption 1 seems defensible. The institutions for bargaining - elected state officials - are already in place, and the marginal costs of applying these institutions to one additional political agreement are likely to be very small, but only to a point. Legislatures do not solve all problems in every year. The legislative agenda is limited, and at some point it simply does not pay to bring additional policies to the floor for consideration. Those policies which will be excluded are likely to be the marginal problems, those which have only a small effect on the economic wellbeing of voters. Even if 1 holds, assumptions 2 to 5 may fail. If the preferences of the participants to the bargain are not common knowledge (2 no longer holds), then there may be a strategic advantage to concealing costs and benefits, demanding greater compensation from the agreement if you represent the ‘winning’ state or offering less compensation if you represent one of the ‘losing’ states. If both parties adopt the ‘conceal’ position, however, no agreement may be forthcoming. In choosing their bargaining strategy, jurisdictions must assess the extent to which other parties are likely to make concessions. In game theoretic terms, the parties try to assess the threat points of the other parties - the minimum offer that they are willing to accept in order to accept a negotiating offer. In addition, they try to estimate the extent to which the other party will be willing to make concessions prior to reaching their threat point. If the parties make poor estimates of each other’s threat point, or miscalculate the chances that the other party will accept a compromise offer, they may take a hard line in the bargaining process. Clearly, therefore, Coasian bargainers will not be immune to possibilities for strategic behavior when they negotiate, and to the extent that they succumb, Coasian bargaining may break down (see Polinsky, 1980; Crawford, 1982; and Kreps and Wilson, 1982). Such attempts at free-riding behavior are likely to undo a Coasian bargain when preferences are not common knowledge and the number of states with affected consumers is large. (For the first treatment of the effects of group size on voluntary agreements see Olsen (1965). The effect of group size and other variables on bargaining has been studied extensively through the use of experiments (see, for example, Hoffman and Spitzer, 1982; also Bagnoli and McKee, 1991. Even if consumer preferences and industry profits are common knowledge, there is no guarantee that state elected officials will choose to make the constituents of the Coasian bargain better off (3 no longer holds). While the favored industry is well represented in its state (why else would there be regulation?), consumers of the product may not be so fortunate in their states. They may be in the minority in a majority rule state. In contrast to private market agreements, here the affected parties are heard only if generally elected representatives choose to make their case.
9700
Federalism
683
Assumption 4 is perhaps the least problematic of the five Coase assumptions. If states do reach an agreement and sign an interstate compact, typically the agreement is legally enforceable (see Ellickson, 1979). Ellickson discusses the idea of creating a series of public property rights and duties to encourage bargaining solutions to environmental spillovers. Note that monitoring costs, a serious problem in many contracts, are not likely to problem here. States which have agreed to curtail their monopoly overcharge regulation will know if they have been paid compensation. Consumer states which pay compensation will be able to observe if the regulating state has reintroduced regulation. For a discussion of the importance of monitoring costs to contract enforcement, see Williamson (1985). Enforcement difficulties arise only when important contingencies which might affect the agreement cannot be foreseen in advance. For example, if a future event occurs which alters the benefits and costs of a particular policy, then the state choosing the activity may decide to break the previous interstate agreement. Arguably the most important and perhaps least appreciated source of bargaining failure is the loss of assumption 5. Even if 1 through 4 hold, the parties may not be able to agree as to how the economic surplus generated by the bargaining process can be divided. Each Coasian bargain does two things: it establishes an efficient exchange thereby creating economic surplus, and it distributes that surplus among the bargaining parties. Proponents of Coase emphasize the first outcome and have largely ignored the important difficulties of the second. Yet it is well known that the division of any economic pie is a bargaining problem which may have no solution. When redistribution games might have equilibrium outcomes is an important topic of recent economic research; see Rubinstein (1982) and more recently Binmore, Rubinstein and Wolinsky (1986). The often observed result in ‘divide-the-pie’ games that bargaining breaks down because the proposed division is not ‘fair’ illustrates the point. In such situations, one state rejects an economically beneficial offer from another state because the proposed offer violates the first state’s exogenous, and no doubt politically motivated, sense of economic fairness. What is seen as an exogenous norm of fairness in a one-time game may be a rational endogenously chosen strategy in a repeated political game. For example, a governor seeking re-election cannot appear ‘weak’ when bargaining with another state. If the money involved in a regulatory agreement is modest relative to the overall state budget - as it is likely to be then the political symbolism of the ‘share’ from the divide-the-pie game may be far more important for re-election prospects than the actual dollars involved. If so, and if both governors must demand more than 50 percent, then agreement will not be possible. (For evidence from the experimental
684
Federalism
9700
literature that a sense of fairness is crucial to the ability of parties to reach agreement, see Roth, 1985.) Strategic interplay becomes even more complicated, and agreement less likely, as the number of bargaining states increases beyond two. This is true even if preferences are fully known and the free-rider problem is not at issue (see Haller, 1986). We conclude that economically inefficient policies are likely at the state and local level. Our analysis of state and local political institutions reveals strong political pressures towards favoring narrow, geographically concentrated interests at the expense of more diffused interests. While strong political parties and powerful governors have a political incentive to internalize the costs, even in these states some inefficiencies will remain for residents. For evidence that state regulations are politically motivated, and in particular, are more likely for geographically concentrated industries and occupations, see Stigler (1971). These intrajurisdictional regulatory inefficiencies are compounded when the effects of government activity spill over onto consumers in other states. In these instances, even strong political parties and governors have a political incentive to choose activities. The hope that voluntary interstate compacts might control these interjurisdictional inefficiencies seems to us to be very optimistic. The assumptions required for such Coasian agreements are very demanding and unlikely to hold in practice. This seems particularly so when the efficiency costs on any one individual are small, costs are not common knowledge and are diffused over groups in many states, the affected individuals are themselves a minority within a state, and state politicians treat the division of proceeds from the bargain as a signal of their political ‘toughness’. (For evidence of the difficulties states have in fashioning Coasian agreements, even when the number of states is few, see Kolstad and Wolak, 1983, and Coates and Munger, 1995.) When any one of the assumptions 1 to 5 fail to hold, Coasian agreements will not arise and state created interjurisdictional regulatory inefficiencies will remain.
10. The Politics of Central Government Legislative Policy Within federalist public economies, whenever state and local governments are economically inefficient, it is appropriate to ask whether the central government might do a better job (see, for example, Oates, 1972, particularly chs 1 and 2). But the comparison must be a consistent one, allowing for potential political inefficiencies at both the state and federal levels of government. Deciding whether to centralize regulatory policy at the
9700
Federalism
685
national level first requires an analysis of how the national legislature will set such policies. The effects of state regulatory policies on industries and consumers outlined previously generalizes to central government regulatory policymaking as well. In this instance industries are concentrated in particular congressional districts or states: tobacco in North Carolina, defense production in Washington and California, automobiles in Michigan. Like their counterparts in state government, congressional legislators have an incentive to look for central government activities which will benefit households and firms located in their districts. However, such national activities will have significant costs for US taxpayers, costs which may exceed the benefits. Whether such economically inefficient activities will be legislated in the central authority depends upon the institutions of legislative decision making. If the legislature is ‘universalistic’, then we can expect it to favor inefficient activities. (For evidence that US congressional institutions have supported a universalistic legislative process, see Weingast and Marshall (1988); see also Silberman and Durden’s (1976) study of the labor market regulations and Kalt and Zupan’s (1984) study of environmental regulations.) As with state legislatures, reform of policymaking will require strong presidential leadership and/or political parties capable of controlling the inefficient policy demands of members. Given that state and central legislatures face the same political pressures to choose inefficient activities, and neither seems, at the moment at least, institutionally well-equipped to resist those pressures, we conclude that neither states nor the central government can be preferred unambiguously as the appropriate domain for choosing economic activities. The current evidence shows economic inefficiencies arising from choices at both levels of government. All this said, there remains a final argument, a variant of Justice Brandeis’ famous plea for ‘states as laboratories’, which we feel tries to tip the balance in favor of decentralizing policy for economic efficiency. Here the laboratory is the state legislature and the experiment is the political ability of a state’s governor or a strong political party to control the legislature’s excesses. Under our analysis, those states with strong governors or strong political parties will typically have more efficient policies. If so, they become models of ‘good government’ which other states might copy. Recent research by Besley and Case (1995) suggests that residents do use the economic performance of neighboring states as a ‘yardstick’ against which to measure the performance of their own political process, typically the governor. Governors who fail to control legislative inefficiencies face a significantly lower chance of re-election. Only the decentralization of
686
Federalism
9700
regulatory policy to the states will give this process of political ‘yardstick’ competition a chance to promote efficiency.
C. Balancing Participation and Efficiency in a Federalist System 11. Conclusion We have concluded to this point that political arguments and the current evidence on participation appear to support the use of small decentralized governments to maximize citizen political participation. However, a more centralized alternative can be supported by economic arguments and evidence concerning the economic efficiency of governmental activity. As a result, trade-offs between the potentially competing values of political participation and economic efficiency may be required when evaluating the optimality of a federalist structure. How are such choices to be made? The analyses in sections A and B can be used to clarify the potential trade-off between the federalist values of political participation and economic efficiency. Consider how economic efficiency, measured in the dollars of economic output, is likely to change as the public sector becomes more decentralized through the assignment of responsibility to more and more, and thus smaller and smaller, governments. Economic benefits rise as responsibility for policy moves from a single central government to the assignment of responsibility to lower level governments, but only to a point. Efficiency improves because decentralization limits the reach of inefficient government activities; rather than the country as a whole bearing the burden of inefficiency, only residents within a state are so burdened. Further, interstate political competition may point the way to more intrajurisdictionally efficient policies. But as we decentralize, we also increase the likelihood of interjurisdictional inefficiencies - that is, spillovers. Moving initially from a centralized structure, the gains from intrajurisdictional efficiencies exceed any losses from interjurisdictional inefficiencies. Eventually, however, inefficient spillovers come to dominate, and the overall performance of the economy declines. There is a similar relationship between decentralization and the extent of political participation. Consistent with our theoretical and empirical analysis in Part B, greater decentralization is likely to increase political participation, though perhaps at a decreasing rate. Combining our efficiency and participation analysis, we conclude that political participation rises with increased decentralization, but economic efficiency first rises and then falls. It is when efficiency declines that we face
9700
Federalism
687
a trade-off. Increasing decentralization initially allows efficiency and participation to both increase, but beyond a point more political participation through decentralization must mean less economic efficiency. The choice of an ‘optimal’ level of decentralization ultimately depends upon the relative importance one places upon the competing federalist values of economic efficiency and political participation; alternative weightings for the values of efficiency and participation will dictate different federalist structures. For example, if efficiency is weighted more highly than participation, the optimal federalist structure will move away from a fully decentralized system so as to increase efficiency and reduce participation. We look forward, with anticipation, to seeing how these federalism issues will be resolved in the emerging constitutions throughout the world.
Bibliography on Federalism (9700) Arrow, A. Kenneth (1963), Social Choice and Individual Values, New York, Wiley. Bagnoli, Mark and McKee, Michael (1991), ‘Voluntary Contribution Games: Efficient Provision of Public Goods’, 29 Economic Inquiry, 351. Baron, David and Ferejohn, John (1989), ‘Bargaining in Legislatures’, 83 American Political Science Review, 1182. Bartik, Timothy (1988), ‘The Effects of Environmental Regulation on Business Location in the United States’, 19 Growth and Change, 22-44. Bergstrom, Theodore, Rubinfeld, Daniel, Roberts, Julia and Shapiro, Perry (1988), ‘A Test for Efficiency in the Supply of Public Education’, 35 Journal of Public Economy, 289. Besley, Timothy and Case, Anne (1995), ‘Incumbent Behavior: Vote-Seeking, Tax-setting, and Yardstick Competition’, 85 American Economic Review, 25. Binmore, Kenneth, Rubinstein, Ariel and Wolinsky, Asher (1986), ‘The Nash Bargaining Solution in Economic Modelling’, 17 Rand Journal of Economics, 176-188 . Boadway, Robin and Flatters, Frank (1982), ‘Efficiency and Equalization Payments in a Federal System of Government’, 15 Canadian Journal of Economics, 613. Brainard, William C. and Dolbear, F. Trenery (1967), ‘The Possibility of Oversupply of Local Public Goods’, 75 Journal of Political Econonomy, 86. Break, George (1967), Intergovernmental Fiscal Relations in the United States,Washington, DC, Brookings Institute, 23-24. Breton, Albert and Scott, Anthony (1978), The Economic Constitution of Federal States, Toronto, University of Toronto Press. Buchanan, James M. and Goetz, Charles (1972), ‘Efficiency Limits of Fiscal Mobility: An Assessment of the Tiebout Model’, 1 Journal of Pubic Econonomy, 25. Coase, Ronald (1960), ‘The Problem of Social Costs’, Journal of Law and Economics, 1-44. Coates, Dennis and Munger, Michael (1995), ‘Strategizing in Small Group Decision-Making: Host State Identification for Radioactive Waste Disposal Among Eight Southern States’, 82 Public Choice, 1.
688
Federalism
9700
Cooter, Robert (1982), ‘The Cost of Coase’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-34. Courant, Paul and Rubinfeld, Daniel (1981), ‘On the Welfare Effects of Tax Limitation’, 16 Journal of Public Economy, 289. Crawford, Vincent (1982), ‘A Theory of Disagreement in Bargaining’, 50 Econometrica, 607. Cumberland, John (1981), ‘Efficiency and Equity in Interregional Environmental Management’, 2 Review of Regional Studies, 1. Dahl, Robert (1956), A Preface to Democratic Theory, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Dahl, Robert and Tufte, Edward (1973), Size and Democracy, Stanford, CA, Stanford University Press. David, Charles E. and Lester, James P. (1989), ‘Federalism and Environmental Policy’, in Lester, James P. (ed.), Environmental Politics and Policy: Theories and Evidence, NC, Duke University Press, 57-59. De Condorcet, M. (1785), ‘Essai sur l’Application de L’Analyse à la Probabilité des Decisions Rendues à la Pluraliste des Voix’, Paris. Easterbrook, Frank (1983), ‘Antitrust and the Economics of Federalism’, 26 Journal of Law & Economics, 23-50. Ellickson, Robert (1979), ‘Public Property Rights: Vicarious Intergovernmental Rights and Liabilities as a Technique for Correcting Intergovernmental Spillovers’, in Rubinfeld, Daniel (ed.), Essays on the Law and Economics of Local Governments. Epple, Dennis and Zelenitz, Alan (1981), ‘The Implications of Competition Among Jurisdictions: Does Tiebout Need Politics?’, 89 Journal of Public Economy, 1197. Finifter, Ada W. (1970), ‘Dimensions of Political Alienation’, 30 American Political Science Review. Fischel, William (1975), ‘Fiscal and Environmental Considerations in the Location of Firms in Suburban Communities’, in Mills, Edwin and Oates, Wallace (eds), Fiscal Zoning and Land Use Controls, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books, 119. Fitts, Michael and Inman, Robert P. (1992), ‘Controlling Congress: Presidential Influence in Domestic Fiscal Policy’, 80 Georgetown Law Journal, 1737. Frug, Gerald (1980), ‘The City as a Legal Concept’, 93 Harvard Law Review, 1059. Gramlich, Edward M. and Laren, Deborah S. (1984), ‘Migration and Income Redistribution Responsibilities’, 19 Journal of Human Resources, 489. Gramlich, Edward M. and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1982), ‘Micro Estimates of Public Spending Demand Functions and Tests of the Tiebout and Median Voter Hypotheses’, 90 Journal of Political Econonomy, 536. Greenwood, Michael J. (1986), ‘The Factor Market Consequences of U.S. Immigration’, 24 Journal of Economic Literature, 1738. Haller, Hans (1986), ‘Noncooperative Bargaining of N 3 Players’, 22 Economic Letters, 11. Hoffman, Elizabeth and Spitzer, Matthew L. (1982), ‘The Coase Theorem: Some Experimental Tests’, 25 Journal of Law and Economics, 73-98. Holmstrom, Bengt (1985), ‘The Provision of Services in a Market Economy’, in Inman, Robert (ed.), Managing the Service Economy: Prospects and Problems, Cambridge, MA, Cambridge Univ Pr, 183p.
9700
Federalism
689
Inman, Robert (1987), ‘Markets, Government, and the New Political Economy’, in Auerbach, Alan and Feldstein, Martin (eds), Handbook of Public Economics, Vol. II, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Inman, Robert P. (1990), ‘Public Debts and Fiscal Politics: How to Decide’, 80 American Economic Review, 81. Inman, Robert and Fitts, Michael (1990), ‘Political Institutions and Fiscal Policy: Evidence from the U.S. Historical Record’, 6 (Special Issue) Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 79132. Inman, Robert P. and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1996), ‘Designing Tax Policies in Federalist Economies: An Overview’, 60 Journal of Public Economics, 307. Kalt, Joseph and Zupan, Mark (1984), ‘Capture and Ideology in the Economic Theory of Politics’, 74 American Economic Review, 279-300. Kolstad, Charles and Wolak, Frank (1983), ‘Competition in Interregional Taxation: The Case of Western Coal’, 91 Journal of Political Economy, 443. Krehbiel, Keith (1992), Information and Legislative Organization, Ann Arbor, The University of Michigan Press. Kreps, David and Wilson, Robert (1982), ‘Reputation and Imperfect Information’, 28 Journal of Economic Theory, 253. Ladd, Helen F. and Yinger, John (1989), America’s Ailing Cities, Baltimore, Johns Hopkins University Press. Levmore, Saul (1992), ‘Bicameralism: When Are Two Decisions Better than One’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 145-162. Lowi, Theodore J. (1969), The End of Liberalism, New York, Norton. Martinez-Vasquez, J. (1994), ‘The Challenge of Expenditure-Assignment Reform in Russia’, 12 Environment and Planet, 277. McConnell, Kenneth and Schwab, Robert (1990), ‘The Impact of Environmental Regulation on Industry Location Decisions: The Motor Vehicle Industry’, 66 Land and Economics, 67. Mill, John Stuart (1960), ‘Representative Government’, in Three Essays: On Liberty, Representative Government, The Subjection of Women, London, Oxford University Press Nagel, Jack (1975), The Descriptive Analysis of Power, New Haven, Yale University Press. Nagel, Jack (1980), Participation, Englewood Cliffs, NJ, Prentice Hall. Niou, Emerson and Ordeshook, Peter (1985), ‘Universalism in Congress’, 29 American Journal of Political Science, 246. Oates, Wallace E. (1972), Fiscal Federalism, London, Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. Oates, Wallace E. and Schwab, Robert M. (1986), ‘Economic Competition Among Jurisdictions: Efficiency Enhancing or Distortion Inducing?’, 35 Journal of Public Economics, 333. Olsen, Mancur (1965), The Logic of Collective Action, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press Ordeshook, Peter and Riker, William (1973), An Introduction to Positive Political Theory, NJ, Prentice-Hall. Pateman, Carole (1970), Participation and Democratic Theory, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
690
Federalism
9700
Pauly, Martin (1970), ‘Optimality, “Public”’ Goods, and Local Governments: A General Theoretical Analysis’, 78 Journal of Political Economy, 572-586. Pestieau, Pierre (1977), ‘The Optimality Limits of the Tiebout Model’, in Oates, Wallace (ed.), The Politics of Fiscal Federalism. Polinsky, A. Mitchell (1980), ‘Resolving Nuisance Disputes: The Simple Economics of Injunctive and Damage Remedies’, 32 Stanford Law Review, 1075-1112. Revesz, Richard (1992), ‘Rehabilitating Interstate Competition: Rethinking the “Race-to-the-Bottom” Rationale for Federal Environmental Regulation’, 67 New York University Law Review, 1210-1255. Riker, William (1964), Federalism: Origins, Operation, Significance, Boston, Little, Brown, and Co. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1981), ‘Does Federalism Matter? Political Choice in a Federal Republic’ , 89 Journal of Political Economy, 152-165. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1994), ‘Environmental Policy and Federal Structure: A Comparison of the United States and Germany’, 47 Vanderbilt Law Review, 1587-1622. Rose-Ackerman, Susan and Mashaw, Jerry (1984), ‘Federalism and Regulation’, in Eads, George C. and Fix, Michael (eds), The Reagan Regulatory Strategy: An Assessment, Washington, DC, Urban Institute Press, 111-152. Roth, Alvin (1985), ‘Towards a Focal Point Theory of Bargaining’, in Roth, A.E. (ed.), Game Theoretic Models of Bargaining, Cambridge and New York, Cambridge University Press Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1987), ‘The Economics of the Local Public Sector’, in Auerbach, Alan and Feldstein, Martin (eds), Handbook of Public Economics, Volume II, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 571-645. Rubinstein, Ariel (1982), ‘Perfect Equilibrium in a Bargaining Model’, 50 Econometrica, 97-110. Samuelson, Paul (1954), ‘The Pure Theory of Public Expenditure’, 36 Review of Economics and Statistics, 386-389. Schumpeter, Joseph (1943), Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, New York, Harper and Row. Schwartz, Thomas (1989), ‘Representation as Agency and Pork Barrel Paradox’, Mimeo, UCLA. Silberman, Jonathan and Garey Durden (1976), ‘Determining Legislative Preferences on Minimum Wage: An Economic Approach’, 84 Journal of Political Economy, 317. Shepsle, Kenneth (1979), ‘Institutional Arrangements and Equilibrium in Multidimensional Voting Models’, 28 American Journal of Political Science, 27. Smith, Adam (1776), An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. Stigler, George (1971), ‘The Theory of Economic Regulation’, 2 Bell Journal of Economics and Managment Science, 3-21. Tiebout, Charles (1956), ‘A Pure Theory of Local Expenditures’, 64 Journal of Political Economy, 416-424. Weingast, Barry (1979), ‘A Rational Choice Perspective on Congressional Norms’, 23 American Journal of Political Science, 245. Weingast, Barry R. and Marshall, William (1988), ‘The Industrial Organization of Congress’, 96 Journal of Political Economy, 132.
9700
Federalism
691
Wildasin, David E. (1986), Urban Public Finance, Chicago, Adademic Publishers, Hartcourt Press. Williams, Alan (1966), ‘The Optimal Provision of Public Goods in a System of Local Governments’, 74 Journal of Political Economy, 18-33. Williamson (1985), The Economic Institutions of Capitalism, New York, The Free Press. Wittman, Donald (1989), ‘Why Democracies Produce Efficient Result’, 97 Journal of Political Economy, 1395-1424.
9800 INTERNATIONAL ORGANIZATION Alexander Thompson and Duncan Snidal University of Chicago © Copyright 1999 Alexander Thompson and Duncan Snidal
Abstract From the principle of state sovereignty to United Nations bureaucracies, international relations are organized by a variety of norms and institutions. After tracing the history of international organization (IO), as well as the intellectual development of its study, we conceptualize IO in terms three levels of formality: IO as formal organization, IO as regime, and IO as ordering principle. We emphasize rationalist approaches - including cooperation theory, associated theories of regimes, and the new institutional economics - as the ones most closely connected to law and economics. After discussing this broad perspective, we consider emerging approaches to international institutional design. Overall, we document a convergence among economists, political scientists and international legal scholars reflected in methodological approach and substantive interests. JEL classification: K33, A12, D70, F02, D23 Keywords: International Organizations, Regime Theory, New Economics of Organization, Cooperation Theory, Institutions, International Politics
1. Introduction The modern history of international organization (IO) reflects an uneven development of both the practice and concept that go under that name. The term is used in differing ways and we apply it to both IO conceived as formal institutional organizations and in a more general sense of order creation. Furthermore, international organization includes not only interstate arrangements but, increasingly, arrangements among non-governmental and transnational actors. Thus, the landscape of international organizations (IOs) includes both inter-governmental organizations (IGOs) and international non-governmental organizations (INGOs). International organization is clearly a very broad concept, which has evolved with the practice of various forms of international governance. Our main task here is to chart the theoretical development of understanding about IO. We emphasize approaches that are
692
9800
International Organization
693
most relevant to international law and economics, while noting important contributions and challenges posed by alternative perspectives. After a descriptive summary of the history and evolution of IOs, we discuss three general conceptions of IO as formal organization, as international ordering principle and as international regime. Cooperation theory then provides a theoretical bridge from the realist ordering principle of anarchy to the neoliberal argument regarding the role of regimes. In turn, elaboration of regime analysis has laid the ground for a reintegration of international law and international relations (IR), an incorporation of various forms of new institutional analysis, a closer concern for specific institutional design principles and, finally, to a new appreciation of the role of formal institutions which had long ago been abandoned in theory if not in practice. Finally, we note the challenges posed by other traditions of international organization and indicate promising future directions for productive theorizing.
A. A Brief History of International Organization 2. Westphalia to Vienna The signing of the Peace of Westphalia in 1648, reinforced by the Treaty of Utrecht in 1713, established the principle of national sovereignty, thereby placing the states of Europe on equal legal footing. This notion of sovereign equality - endowing each state with territorial integrity and the right to conduct domestic and foreign affairs without outside intervention - represents the first real ordering principle among states. After Westphalia, ‘decentralized control by sovereign states’ (Falk, 1969, p. 69) provided the basis for a horizontal international order critical to the subsequent development of international organization. However, it was not until the nineteenth century that actual international organizations began to appear in significant numbers. Though the advent of states as sovereign political units was an important step, preconditions for the creation of IOs were not met during the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. For example, there was insufficient contact between states, there was little recognition of problems arising from interdependence among states, and there was no perceived need for institutionalized mechanisms to manage international relations (Claude, 1964).
694
International Organization
9800
3. Vienna and the Nineteenth Century The first serious attempt at formal international organization arose with the Congress of Vienna (1814-1815), which established diplomatic foundations for a new European security order following the devastation of the Napoleonic Wars. Some credit the resulting ‘Congress system’ as a fundamental turning point in the conduct and organization of international relations (Schroeder, 1994). It created a more systematic and institutionalized approach to managing issues of war and peace in the international system. The principal innovation at Vienna was that representatives of states should meet at regular intervals not just in the wake of war - to discuss diplomatic issues. Accordingly, four major peacetime conferences were held between 1815 and 1822. After this period, the aspirations of the Congress system gave way to a more informal regime. As characterized by one historian, ‘A looser association of the Great Powers continued in existence - an attenuated Congress system limited to dealing with problems as they arose, not seeking to anticipate them or to iron them out of existence’ (Hinsley, 1963, 213). This ‘Concert of Europe’ featured sporadic gatherings throughout the century, mostly in response to wars: Paris in 1856, Vienna in 1864, Prague in 1866, Frankfurt in 1871, Berlin in 1878, Berlin in 1884-1885, and The Hague in 1899 and 1907. These last two conferences went so far as to establish panels of arbitrators to settle international disputes and produced a Convention for the Pacific Settlement of International Disputes. These are the earliest examples of formal IOs designed to manage security issues. The result of the Concert was, indeed, quite a long period of relatively peaceful interstate relations among the great powers of Europe. Many of the most dramatic developments in international organization during the nineteenth century were not related to the goal of averting war but to an emerging mismatch between the geographic scope of problems versus the scope of state authority. The technological changes brought on by the Industrial Revolution - especially in communication (telegraph) and transportation (steamship and railroad) - created an interdependence among states that required more stable forms of cooperation. A new set of IOs was created to manage international economic transactions which were an increasingly important aspect of interstate relations but were difficult for national governments to manage on a unilateral basis (Woolf, 1916). To facilitate shipping and international trade and to regulate traffic, the littoral states of the Rhine established the Central Commission for the Navigation of the Rhine in 1815 at Vienna. Similar commissions were established for the Danube (1856) and Elbe (1821) rivers. The Zollverein, a customs union of Germanic states established 1834, was the first effort at international economic integration and governance in Europe. A related set of IOs, the Public International Unions, was also a response to technological change. These were concerned primarily with nonpolitical,
9800
International Organization
695
technical matters, and included the International Telegraphic Union (1865), the General (later Universal) Postal Union (1874), the International Union of Railway Freight Transportation (1890), and the International Bureau of Weights and Measures (1875). Some of these organizations had elaborate institutional frameworks, including permanent bureaus that represented forerunners of secretariats (Archer, 1983, p. 12). The ultimate purpose of these IOs was to facilitate international trade by establishing market rules and standardization. It should be noted that the improved technology that increased the need for coordination among states also made communicating and convening easier, thus facilitating the process of organization.
4. Versailles and the League of Nations The periods following the two World Wars saw the greatest proliferation of institutions. Heads of state and diplomats met in 1919 at the Versailles Peace Conference to create a global security IO in the League of Nations. This was the first attempt at collective security - that is, an institution operating on the notion of all against one (Claude, 1962; Kupchan and Kupchan, 1991). Under Article 16 of the League Covenant, all member states were required to come to the aid of a member that was the victim of military aggression. The League was overwhelmingly concerned with fostering peace, though economic and social issues did receive secondary attention. The Covenant further established the Permanent Court of International Justice, the first attempt to create a global forum of justice and predecessor to today’s International Court of Justice. All members participated in the General Assembly, while a separate League Council - consisting of five permanent members (the United States, Britain, France, Japan, Italy) and several rotating members - guided the operation of the organization. Versailles also represented the first instance of widespread participation by national and transnational private interest groups in a large interstate conference. Though the nineteenth century saw the formation of a number of INGOs - concerned with humanitarian, religious, economic, educational, scientific, political, and other matters - it was rare for private organizations to sit at the table next to governments. Two products of this non-governmental participation at Versailles were the establishment of the International Labor Organization and a more formal partnership between member states and the Red Cross (already founded in 1864). Though President Woodrow Wilson was its chief proponent, the United States never joined the League. Due largely to the lack of US participation, the organization never lived up to its promise. It successfully resolved some small military conflicts, but the Covenant was frequently violated and other
696
International Organization
9800
mechanisms for resolving disputes were employed at least as often. In the end, of course, the League was not able to avert World War II. Nevertheless, the League of Nations is an important marker in the history of international organization as an attempt to forge a new international order based on a formal institution with universal membership.
5. Post-World War II International Organization The architects of the postwar system set out to establish an extraordinarily ambitious framework of positive international law and institutions. Though the number of formal IOs increased from about 50 to 80 during the interwar period, in the enthusiasm of the early postwar period they were created on a wide scale until they numbered over 600 by 1980 (Wallace and Singer, 1970; Jacobson, 1984). The most important was the United Nations, whose basic structure was decided by the US, the United Kingdom, the Soviet Union and China at the Dumbarton Oaks meeting of 1944 and the 1945 Yalta Summit. The drafters of the Charter, signed at the San Francisco conference of founding members in June 1945, were conscious of the limits inherent in the idealism of the League of Nations. Rather than count on collective security, ‘the UN was to be primarily a peace and security organization based on the concept of the Four Policemen, that is, the USA, USSR, the United Kingdom and China as protectors against a recurrence of Axis aggression’ (Archer, 1983, p. 24). Abstinence from unilateral use of force remained the main driving principle, however, and the Security Council was entrusted with primary responsibility for authorizing and overseeing military action. The reality of the Cold War dashed these expectations and rendered the UN ineffective, though not irrelevant, in global security affairs. But demand for an expanded range of UN security services has re-emerged in the post-Cold War era and, despite some failures in recent years, the UN is playing an increasingly important security role (Roberts, 1993; Koskenniemi, 1996, pp. 456-460). The United Nations is divided into six principal organs, though the General Assembly is clearly ‘first among them’ (Peterson, 1986). Of the other five, the Secretariat, the Trusteeship Council and the Economic and Social Council report to the General Assembly. The Security Council and International Court of Justice have limited mandates, the former dealing only with situations related to the outbreak or potential outbreak of war, and the latter ruling on legal questions brought to it by member states or other UN bodies. These central components of the UN are surrounded by a cluster of functional agencies, including the International Labor Organization, the UN Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization, the World Health Organization and the Food and Agricultural Organization. Over the years, there has been a steady
9800
International Organization
697
proliferation of specialized and affiliated agencies, many designed to deal with development issues (Feld and Jordan, 1988, pp. 19-20; Schachter and Joyner, 1995). Another set of organizations was created during and following World War II, for the purpose of avoiding economic conflict by, especially, maintaining currency stability and free trade. The Bretton Woods monetary system established the US dollar as the central currency; other currencies would be valued according to the dollar, which in turn was pegged to gold. Two formal IOs were created as part of this system: the International Monetary Fund was charged with monitoring balance of payments while the World Bank supervised economic development and postwar reconstruction. The General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade (GATT) was established in 1947 to maintain open trade based on the principle of non-discrimination. It was replaced in 1995 by the more encompassing and centralized - for instance, it contains strengthened dispute settlement procedures - World Trade Organization. These economic organizations were established as universal in principle but, in fact, began as closely held institutions of the Western powers. Their universality was overshadowed by the Cold War and, to a lesser extent, by North-South distributive conflicts (Krasner, 1985). These institutions have become more inclusive over time, but effective control - both formal and informal - remains in Western hands. A further striking development in international organization in the postwar period has been the rise of regional IOs (Taylor, 1993; Nye, 1968). Some perform a range of functions within a given geographical area (the Organization of American States, the Organization of Central American States, the Arab League, the Organization of African Unity, and the Association of South East Asian Nations). Others are specifically security-related, such as the North Atlantic Treaty Organization, the Organization for Security and Cooperation in Europe, and the now defunct Warsaw Treaty Organization. The largest number are economic, including the European Free Trade Association, the North American Free Trade Agreement, the Southern Cone Common Market, the Council for Economic Assistance (formerly the Council for Mutual Economic Assistance), the Andean Common Market, and the Asian-Pacific Economic Cooperation. Of this last category, the European Union (formerly the European Community) has the most developed set of institutions in terms of economics (Eichengreen and Frieden, 1994; Kenen, 1995), law (Armstrong and Bulmer, 1998; Burley and Mattli, 1993; Garrett, 1995), security (Kupchan, 1997) and politics (Moravcsik, 1998; Nugent, 1994).
698
International Organization
9800
6. Recent Trends in IO Despite the frequent assumption that IGOs rarely die once created, fully one-third of the organizations that existed in 1981 were defunct by 1992. Many of those that became inactive were in the former Eastern bloc or were regional development organizations in the developing world. In the 1981-1992 period there was also a ‘growing polarization between powerful countries - dominated by the literate, wealthy, and democratic - that establish and control IGOs and countries whose populations and governments are badly off and increasingly disengaged from international organizations’ (Shanks, Jacobson and Kaplan, 1996, p. 594). Parallel to the growth in governmental organizations has been a rapid proliferation of international non-governmental organizations (Skjelsbaek, 1971; Willets, 1982; Castermans et al., 1990; Weiss and Gordenker, 1996; Charnovitz, 1996). The growth in private international associations matched that of public international unions in the second half of the nineteenth century, and has surpassed it in the twentieth century. Indeed, since the late nineteenth century there have been more INGOs than NGOs in existence. From 176 in 1909, there were 1,255 INGOs in 1960 and are now more than 5,500 (UIA, 1997/98, Table 2, Appendix 3). Although these organizations cover countless functional areas, the most important categories are commerce and industry, technology, science, and health and medicine, and human rights. In terms of geographical distribution, almost half were founded in Europe; Africa and Asia account for the greatest number in the developing world (UIA, 1997/98, Table 6.2, Appendix 3). Today, IOs range in size from small consultative organizations such as the Northwest Atlantic Fisheries Organization to very substantial bureaucracies like the World Bank or European Union with elaborate administrative structures, large budgets, many employees and extensive operational capacities. There has also been a striking, though uneven, development of international judicial bodies, most recently reflected in war tribunals for the former Yugoslavia and Rwanda and in the creation of an International Criminal Court. As this historical summary makes clear, international organization has generally been a response to or manifestation of deeper changes in international relations, not a driver of these changes.
B. Conceptual Approaches to IO The theory and practice of IO have developed together in the modern era, and especially in the post-World War II period. One consequence of this progressive development is substantial ambiguity in what we mean by ‘international organization’ since the practice and concept have co-evolved over time. A
9800
International Organization
699
compensating virtue is that we have developed a richness in terms of different possibilities for organizing international behavior and in terms of different ways of thinking about it. It is useful to distinguish three different conceptions of the term.
7. IO as Formal Organization The most familiar and straightforward definition of international organization is as formal organizations, usually among states or with states selecting representatives. As noted above, the Congress of Vienna (1815) established the Rhine Commission as the first formal IO, but not until the last third of the nineteenth century did IGOs begin to proliferate rapidly to facilitate expanding commercial and other forms of interdependence among European states. In the current period, formal IOs are exemplified by the United Nations and its agencies, as well as a host of functional and regional organizations. While early discussions can be found in the writings of Dante Alighieri ([1314] 1957), Henri de Saint-Simon ([1825] 1952), Jeremy Bentham ([1786-89] 1927) and Immanuel Kant ([1784] 1914), the study of formal organizations took off in the early twentieth century, especially as the debacle of World War I led to the creation of the League of Nations. The interwar analysis was heavily descriptive and normative and focused on the legal and organizational structure of emerging or proposed institutions (Yalem, 1966). It suffered from a relative neglect of the actual incentives of states, including their reluctance to transfer sovereignty to federal or supranational organizations. This led to its being labeled as ‘idealistic’ in distinction to the ‘realist’ account of international life as being fundamentally driven by the harsh realities of power politics (Carr, 1939; Morgenthau, 1948). Realism continues to view power, not institutions, as the key organizing principle of international affairs, and is skeptical of any significant role for formal organizations. Despite the failure of the League, the concern for international organizations carried through World War II, although it was significantly changed by David Mitrany’s ([1943] 1966) ‘functionalist’ theory. Technological advancements and the desire to promote welfare concerns were seen as creating a need for interstate cooperation that required both international governmental organizations and non-governmental organizations to manage the necessary technical cooperation. The theory further emphasized the important role of professionals within those formal organizations in effecting international cooperation. ‘Neofunctionalism’ extended this argument by suggesting that successful collaboration in one area would increase the benefits of cooperation in related areas, and generate joint pressure from domestic interest groups and international officials to extend the realm of cooperation (Haas, 1964; Lindberg and Scheingold 1971; Nye, 1971; Groom
700
International Organization
9800
and Taylor, 1975). This ‘spillover’ would then provide the motor for broad international, and especially regional, integration, as exemplified by the development of the European Community. Although this body of literature never took off (see Haas, 1975), it represented an important move away from description towards a theoretical analysis whose ideas continue to be echoed in contemporary discussions. While these theories argued that formal IOs could perform functions that would lead them to acquire authority, subsequent theory focused on how increasing interdependence was eroding state sovereignty. This trend has not been monotonic, as illustrated by high levels of pre-World War I economic interdependence that declined precipitously in the interwar period and were only surpassed well after World War II. Nevertheless, long-term and increasing interactions among states in all fields of activity - including health, technology, security, environment, culture and economics - mean that even the most powerful states are sensitive to occurrences elsewhere and cannot always achieve their goals by themselves. Small states that are dependent on larger states have even stronger reasons to seek support from such organizations. Moreover, this interdependence takes increasingly complex forms, including the increase in the number of significant transnational actors such as multinational corporations and environmental groups (Keohane and Nye, 1972, 1977). These changes have increased opportunities for formal international organizations but have not necessarily increased the willingness of states to transfer political authority to them. Indeed, formal international organizations had come to be viewed unfavorably from both practical and theoretical standpoints until quite recently. From a practical perspective, IOs have not always lived up to the high expectations they have raised. This was true with the League of Nations in the 1930s and with the United Nations by the 1970s when the General Assembly and various UN agencies seemed to have become little more than forums for ideological debate (between North and South and between East and West). In the 1980s the UN system faced open hostility from the United States, its most powerful member. Similarly, the high expectations for the European Community appeared to have stalled in this period - both within Europe itself and with regard to transferring the regional community model elsewhere. In fact, many formal IOs continued to play an important role throughout this period (Karnes and Mingst, 1990). Economic organizations were instrumental in the performance of the global economy, while NATO was the most institutionalized, and probably the most successful, alliance. In the post-Cold War years, formal organizations have experienced somewhat of a renewal. There has been an effort to make better use of existing organizations as the United States did with the United Nations during the Gulf War, to change organizations such as NATO to address a different set of
9800
International Organization
701
problems, and to expand the venue of organizations such as the World Bank to address new issues, including the environment. Skepticism regarding the effectiveness of formal IOs is neither over nor unwarranted, but there is new interest in pursuing the possibilities of IOs ranging from the European Union to the World Trade Organization The theoretical literature is experiencing a similar sharp turnaround from the preceding decades where, in the words of one commentator, there ‘has been the steady disengagement of international organization scholars from the study of [formal] organizations, to the point that today one must question whether such a field even exists any longer except in name’ (Rochester, 1986). This new attention to IOs should not be understood as a continuation of the earlier tradition, however, but as a reconstitution of a substantive interest, now on stronger theoretical footings. On the one hand, the new literature is decidedly non-idealist and questions of enforcement of agreements and incentives to obey institutions are key concerns of its proponents. On the other hand, the literature is theoretical as it seeks to move well beyond the institutional-descriptive accounts that dominated much of the earlier literature. Indeed, if anything, it can be criticized for being too abstract such that it has lost sight of many of the real institutional variations, including formal IOs, that it should seek to explain (Abbott and Snidal, 1998). Legal scholarship, especially the doctrinal analysis of the rules and outputs of formal IOs, has continued to provide a rich description of the institutional forms and details of IOs. Although largely non-theoretical (see Virally, 1972 for a partial exception), its implicit emphasis on problem-solving states is highly amenable to rationalist theoretical development. This work examines how similar problems are addressed under different IO arrangements (Amerasinghe, 1996; Dupuy, 1988; Kirgis, 1993) and the best is comparative (Schermers and Blokker, 1995). An especially promising recent development discussed below is the reuniting of the legal concern with detailed arrangements and more theoretical developments in economics (Trachtman, 1996) and international relations (Abbott, 1992; Slaughter, Tulumello and Wood, 1998). Finally, the emphasis on formal IOs represents a very narrow view of the forms of, and possibilities for, international governance. Indeed, the failure of the ‘classic’ IO model to live up to an exaggerated promise of managing international affairs in a relatively depoliticized and expert manner has led to its disrepute in many quarters. Improved understandings of governance suggest that formal organizations are only one among numerous institutional possibilities.
702
International Organization
9800
8. IO as Ordering Principle If formal organization provides a narrow view of international organization, the most expansive definitions of international organization are framed in terms of broad ordering principles of the international system. We focus on two here: the realist conception of self-help in anarchy and the English school view of ‘society’. We do not consider other ordering principles such as Marxist theories of imperialism (Lenin, [1917] 1939) or of a ‘world capitalist system’ (Wallerstein, 1979), although the economic logic they describe certainly constitutes an alternative international ordering principle. The two we do consider play a central role in debates regarding the nature of international organization and pose major alternatives to regime theory which we consider below. Self-Help in Anarchy The traditional realist view centers on sovereign territorial states in a state of anarchy, with Thomas Hobbes as the relevant intellectual hero. Anarchy is defined primarily in terms of the absence of central authority, not necessarily in terms of war (Milner, 1991, offers a valuable discussion of different meanings of anarchy). However, the realist view does imply that international politics is inherently competitive and conflictual, that survival is the primary goal of states, and that relative power is of central importance.Waltz (1959, 1979), the most influential contemporary realist commentator on anarchy, emphasizes that the fundamental difference between domestic and international politics is that the former is hierarchic while the latter is irreducibly anarchic. This creates some irony with respect to realist reliance on Hobbes as their intellectual forebear since they part ways with him on his central conclusion that actors in a dire state of anarchy would choose a Leviathan, and thus transform anarchy into hierarchy. The best explanation for states’ failure to do so is that international anarchy is not as brutish as Hobbes’ vision of domestic anarchy (Beitz, 1979). Nevertheless, given the absence of central authority, the key realist ordering principle is self-help: states must take care of themselves (Waltz, 1979). Security is seen as the overwhelmingly central problem and balance of power provides the unique source of international order. Thus a central focus of realist theory is the relation between the distribution of power and international outcomes, including but not restricted to war - although there are sharp debates over the precise impact of different power distributions (Kaplan, 1957; Gilpin, 1981; Waltz, 1979). Power and security considerations are further seen as the deep source of states’ attitudes towards, and arrangements for, other (secondary) issues such as economics, human rights or environment. Thus lower-order institutions - including formal organizations and regimes - are seen as largely epiphenomenal, with the organization of the system explained largely by the balancing of power among states (Mearsheimer, 1994/95; Wight, 1973)
9800
International Organization
703
International Society A very different tradition in the international relations field, inspired by Hugo Grotius ([1625] 1925), focuses on the system of states as an ‘international society’ that contains persistent elements of order (Bull, 1977; Wight, 1977). According to Bull (1977, p. 13), the most prominent member of this English school, ‘states form a society in the sense that they conceive themselves to be bound by a common set of rules in their relations with one another, and share in the working of common institutions’. This framework of rules and institutions guides state behavior in patterned ways. Similarly, Finnemore stresses the notion of ‘norms as social structure’. States, embedded in a dense network of social relations that shape their judgments, define their interests according to ‘internationally shared norms and values that structure and give meaning to international political life’ (Finnemore, 1996a, p. 3). The simple notion of anarchy thus cannot capture the richness and order of the international system. Even in settings of intense security competition such as the Cold War, mutual understandings and ‘rules of the game’ can provide considerable stability (Gaddis, 1987). Members of this school have used its insights to critique the rationalist underpinnings of regime theory (next) for failing to capture many of the dynamics of international cooperation and organization. States abide by rules and norms, even when it is not in their material interest, because they have a long-term interest in the maintenance of a ‘law-impregnated international community’ and share a sense of ‘moral community’ (Hurrell, 1993). This work, however, has generally attempted to integrate regime theory into the study of international society, arguing, for example, that functional theories of regimes are largely accurate but that international society is a precondition for their development (Buzan, 1993). Hurrell (1993) suggests that the field of international law can provide a bridge for understanding the interaction between normative structure and self-interested cooperation. This recognition that regime theory and the notion of a norm-laden international society are not mutually exclusive offers a promising path for future work in the study of IO and cooperation more generally.
9. IO as Regime Between the narrow understanding of formal organizations and the extremely broad understanding of ordering principles lies the concept of ‘international regime’, which has become the most widely used approach to international organization. Regime theory is premised on the twin observations that international politics is highly interdependent (Keohane and Nye, 1977), thus implying mutual interests in cooperation, and that ‘international behavior is
704
International Organization
9800
institutionalized’ in a variety of ways (Ruggie, 1975, p. 559). There is agreement over these empirical phenomena, but the approach includes a diverse set of theoretical and methodological orientations. While there is no theoretical consensus, there has been wide adherence to a ‘standard’ definition of regimes as ‘sets of implicit or explicit principles, norms, rules and decision-making procedures around which actors’ expectations converge in a given area of international relations’ (Krasner, 1983, p. 2). This very broad conception of regimes includes the endpoints as well as the vast middle ground between formal organizations and broader ordering principles in international relations. The definition of regime has been criticized as being expansive to the point of vagueness (Strange, 1982). An unfortunate consequence is that an inordinate amount of effort has been expended in arguing about whether or not there is an effective regime in a particular area. The corresponding virtue is that this broad definition allows for a broader view of governance possibilities than is suggested by the narrower concern with formal institutions. The various categories in the definition also point towards a greater level of specificity than is often achieved by more ethereal discussions of ordering principles. Finally, the breadth of the definition leaves room for a plurality of approaches - liberal as well as realist, rationalist as well as constructivist. This has provided some unity to the field despite the diversity of approaches sometimes employed. Regime ‘theory’ is confusing insofar as it refers to a body of literature including a wide range of different approaches and theories. Nevertheless, the most substantial vein of regime theory relies on rational choice understandings of state behavior, where states are viewed as unified, self-interested actors (Hasenclever, Mayer and Rittberger, 1997). We emphasize rationalist approaches for this reason and because they are closest to the law and economics tradition. Rational regime theory was a natural outgrowth of the increasing propensity among IR scholars, beginning in the 1970s, to theorize international cooperation problems as analogous to ‘market failure’. They used a public choice approach to problems such as public goods provision and externalities at the international level (Russett and Sullivan, 1971; Ruggie, 1972; Snidal, 1979; Fratianni and Pattison, 1982) and applied Coase’s theory of property rights to the process of international organization (Conybeare, 1980). But the most important move in the literature emerged from the ‘folk theorem’ of economics and its result that decentralized cooperation can be an equilibrium outcome when a circumstance is repeated through time. This provided a response to the realist claim that the lack of centralized authority in anarchy prevents international cooperation. Indeed, by taking a Hobbesian specification of anarchy as akin to a prisoner’s dilemma (Taylor, 1976), international relations theorists began to develop a theoretical argument that cooperation was not only possible in realist anarchy, it was in some sense likely (Axelrod, 1984). Thus the title of Kenneth Oye’s (1986) Cooperation Under Anarchy
9800
International Organization
705
reflected the emerging synthesis in the literature that international order did not require centralized institutions. The articles in Keohane and Ostrom (1995) provide a recent elaboration of this perspective. Cooperation theory has been challenged in several important ways, especially by disputing whether its underlying assumptions truly apply in international relations. Possibly states, or their leaders, are not properly characterized as rational agents with the capacities or inclinations necessary to maintain decentralized cooperation. An alternative, more realist critique is that states as rational actors seek goals such as power that are different from the goals of economic actors who seek wealth. This latter position has been formalized as the claim that because states seek ‘relative gains’, cooperation is limited in international affairs (Grieco, 1988), but this argument has been countered by analyses demonstrating that these limits are not great (Snidal, 1991; Powell, 1991). An alternative and more telling criticism of rational cooperation as a theory of international organization is that it has at best a very thin view of institutions. Thus cooperation theory provides a substitute for the need for international organization as centralized enforcement, but it does not provide an account of why any substantial international organization is needed at all.
C. Contemporary Theoretical Approaches to IO 10. Rationalist Regime Theory The seminal work for the study of rationalist regime theory is Robert Keohane’s After Hegemony (1984). The book explains the continued existence and increasing strength of international institutions in the wake of declining American hegemony. Drawing on rational choice logic and microeconomic theories, Keohane offers a functional theory of international regimes - in other words, the anticipated benefits to states explain the persistence of the regime and compliance with its rules. ‘Political market failure’ is a central notion in Keohane’s analysis: ‘Like imperfect markets, world politics is characterized by institutional deficiencies that inhibit mutually advantageous cooperation’ (1984, p. 85). While bargaining could in principle correct these failures (Coase, 1960), Keohane argues that the underlying conditions for Coasean logic to operate - well-defined property rights (that is, a legal framework), perfect information, and zero transactions costs - do not naturally exist in the international system. Regimes, then, serve to fill in these gaps to facilitate cooperation among states on a decentralized basis. Moreover, ‘[b]y clustering issues together in the same forums over a long period of time, they [regimes] help to bring governments into continuing
706
International Organization
9800
interaction with one another, reducing incentives to cheat and enhancing the value of reputation. By establishing legitimate standards of behavior for states to follow and by providing ways to monitor compliance, they create the basis for decentralized enforcement founded on the principle of reciprocity’ (Keohane, 1984, p. 145; see also Keohane, 1986). In short, states find it much more efficient to operate within multilateral institutions than to generate cooperation through countless bilateral agreements (Aggarwal, 1985). And since the cost of dealing with an additional issue is much less within a regime, this may explain why they strengthen and expand in scope over time. Much of the early regimes literature focused on explaining why states create international regimes and demonstrating that they ‘matter’, that is, that they influence state behavior in a meaningful way. From the beginning, however, regime theorists were addressing issues such as why regimes change or evolve (Young, 1982; Lipson, 1982; Aggarwal, 1983) and how to measure a regime’s effectiveness (Young, 1992; Haas, Keohane and Levy, 1993; Bernauer, 1995). They are also concerned with why regimes take particular forms, such as bilateral, minilateral or multilateral (Yarbrough and Yarbrough, 1992; Ruggie, 1993a). In addition, the application of regime theory has been expanded to a wide variety of issue-areas, including international security (Jervis, 1982; McCalla, 1996), trade (Finlayson and Zacher, 1981; Aggarwal, 1985; Yarbrough and Yarbrough, 1987), finance (Cohen, 1982; Lipson, 1985), human rights (Donnelly, 1986), telecommunications (Cowhey, 1990: Zacher, 1996; Sandholtz, 1993), and the environment (Young 1989, 1994; Young and Osherenko, 1993; Haas, 1993; Haas, Keohane and Levy, 1993). International legal scholars have increasingly used regime theory to better understand issues such as international trade law, arms control agreements, and the law of treaties (Abbott, 1985; Abbott, 1993; Smith, 1991; Setear, 1996; see also Aceves, 1997). Scholars in the regime tradition have also used alternative terminology, including institutions, multilateralism, and governance systems, to describe phenomena of international organization that exist between formal organizations and broader elements of order in the international system. Works centered around the construct of ‘international institutions’ are closely tied to regime theory and tend to either subsume the concept of a ‘regime’ (Haas, Keohane and Levy, 1993, p. 5) or employ a definition that is virtually synonymous with the earlier Krasner definition (Young, 1989, pp. 5, 32). Multilateralism has been described as an institutional form that orders state behavior on the basis of generalized principles of conduct (Ruggie, 1993a). However, there is a distinct body of work that relies on the notion of ‘governance without government’ (Rosenau and Czempiel, 1992; Young, 1994). ‘Governance’ is distinct from ‘government’ in that rules are obeyed not because they are backed by the threat of force; rather, it is the perceived legitimacy of rules that leads to compliance (Franck, 1990, 1995; Young, 1979). Actors in the international system recognize certain norms and rules of
9800
International Organization
707
conduct and feel compelled to oblige by them. Governance, then, is ‘order with intentionality’ (Rosenau, 1992, p. 5). This normative theory of international organization is thus different from earlier, interest-based theories of international regimes, though their predictions about order are similar.
11. New Institutionalism A subsequent wave of scholarship studies international organization through the lens of the ‘new institutionalism’ within several social science fields, including economics (Williamson, 1985; Eggertsson, 1989; Furubotn and Richter, 1991, 1997), sociology (Powell and DiMaggio, 1991), and political science (March and Olsen, 1989; Moe, 1984). Important works, for example, have attempted to apply the sociology of organizations to IOs, describing them as ‘live collectivities interacting with their environments’ that ‘tend to become infused with value’ (Ness and Brechin, 1988, p. 247; see also Finnemore, 1996b, and Young, 1994). Armstrong and Bullmer (1998) use historical institutionalism to explain the development of the Single European Market in terms of the interaction between law and politics. The largest body of literature has begun to integrate the ‘new economics of organization’ (NEO) - also referred to as ‘new institutional economics’ or ‘transaction costs economics’ - into the study of international organization. In the early 1990s, economists began to notice ‘striking parallels between the central questions of NEO and those of international relations’ (Yarbrough and Yarbrough, 1990). Both literatures focus on the need to establish institutions to facilitate cooperation when independent actions would produce sub-optimal outcomes. Oliver Williamson, for example, stresses the ‘feasibility of crafting superior ex ante incentive structures’ to promote cooperative behavior (1985, p. 204). Thus, firms arise as a form of private, hierarchic ordering within a market that lacks formal organization or authority (Williamson, 1975, 1985). The emphasis is on non-governmental forms of managing such problems as the provision of public goods and the guarantee of property rights. An important aspect of this NEO wave is an attempt to theorize about the organizational design of international institutions rather than treating them as black boxes. The assumption is that states do not simply follow the dictates of formal organizations - rather, they create institutions with specific design features intended to be the most effective and focus on the variety of institutional forms that result. In their study of international trade liberalization over time, Yarbrough and Yarbrough (1992, p. 19) show that ‘[i]nstitutional variety ... (reflects the efficacy of alternate governance structures for different types of trade transactions in different political and economic environments’.
708
International Organization
9800
Lake (1996) presents a theory of contracting whereby organizational choice in security relations - which varies on a continuum from anarchic alliances to hierarchic empires - is determined by considerations of transaction costs and the expected costs of opportunism. International lawyers have similarly applied transaction costs economics to explain various governance structures in the international system (Aceves, 1996; Trachtman, 1997). Even the existence of sovereign territorial states themselves, as a form of international institutionalization, has been explained through this lens (Spruyt, 1994). Though NEO writers tend to focus on formal IOs, this approach is far more theoretical in its objectives than the earlier legal-descriptive tradition in the field of international law. Formal rules are only one aspect of IOs according to the NEO school and they are not the most important determinant of state behavior: ‘From the NEO perspective, concentration on formal legal structures may prove not only incomplete but also misleading, since the effective enforcement of rules assumed by the formal approach is often missing, particularly in international relations’ (Yarbrough and Yarbrough, 1990, p. 257). Informal institutions and behavioral norms play a prominent role. Much like regime theory, then, NEO applications to IO suggest that the stark dichotomy presented by some IR scholars between a hierarchic and ordered domestic arena and an anarchic international order is misleading.
12. Micro-Design In much the same spirit as NEO, other international relations and legal scholars have focused on what might be called the micro-design of IOs and international treaties. These writers go beyond explaining the general demand for international regimes (Keohane, 1982, 1984) and focus on the demand and effectiveness of particular regime design features. Though they typically concentrate on formal IOs, they use the detailed study of these organizations to draw broad theoretical implications about international cooperation in a manner that is consistent with the goals of regime theory. One important vein of this scholarship begins with the assumption that compliance with international agreements is generally high, and that violations are the result of legal ambiguities, inadvertence, or the incapacity of states to comply rather than calculated, self-interested ‘cheating’ (Chayes and Chayes, 1993, 1995; Mitchell, 1993). Moreover, the incidence of this non-compliance is largely a function of how international treaties and regimes are designed, and thus regime effectiveness can be improved when certain institutional features are present (Mitchell, 1994a, 1994b; Sand, 1990). The resulting theories are thus prescriptive as well as descriptive.
9800
International Organization
709
A related literature explains why particular design features or levels of institutionalization are chosen (Sykes, 1990; Lipson, 1991; Staiger, 1995; Mansfield and Milner, 1997) through consideration of the relative bargaining power of states (Garrett, 1992), of domestic factors influencing institutional design (Cowhey, 1990), and of the specific features of the international problems that states face (Kahler, 1996; Koremenos, Lipson and Snidal, 1998). Downs and Rocke (1995, p. 77) argue that uncertainty about future demands from domestic interest groups leads policymakers to design institutions with ‘sanctions for noncompliance that are low enough to allow politicians to break the agreement when interest group benefits are great, but high enough to encourage states to obey the agreement most of the time and thereby prevent trade wars’ (Graber, 1999). So while these institutions may seem inefficient in that noncompliance is not severely punished, they are in fact an optimal outcome in light of the domestic uncertainty that exists. Finally, other micro-design theorists revert to simple functionalism to explain certain designed features. Garrett and Weingast (1993), for example, argue that the design of the European Union’s legal order is accepted by governments because it serves to mitigate various ambiguities that make cooperation difficult, namely, incomplete contracting and monitoring problems.
13. Critiques The Realist Critique From its inception, regime theory and its successors have been criticized by ‘realist’ theorists of international relations arguing that international institutions simply do not ‘matter’ in any meaningful way. According to the conventional structural critique, regimes have little or no independent effect on state behavior, especially when it comes to important economic and power relationships (Strange, 1982). Regimes, and international cooperation more generally, are readily upset by the logic of security competition because states have an overwhelming concern with power and survival. As a result, regimes are epiphenomenal to international politics: sustained cooperation can only exist when it is consistent with power politics considerations (Gowa, 1994). This logic does not preclude the establishment of cooperative institutions, including military alliances, to satisfy short-term interests, but such forms of organization are merely ‘temporary marriages of convenience’ (Mearsheimer, 1994/95, p. 11). Not all realists are so pessimistic. Glaser (1994/95) begins with the basic assumptions of structural realism and shows that discord is not the logical consequence under a wide variety of conditions. Institutions that provide information and reduce transaction costs, in particular, are not inconsistent
710
International Organization
9800
with the exigencies of security competition, though in the end cooperation will normally be based on ad hoc agreements rather than more formal organization. Globalization Building from past work on ‘transnational relations’ (Keohane and Nye, 1972) the literature on globalization stresses the large and growing number of non-state actors in the international system, such as firms, private associations, and religious groups (Cerny, 1990; Krugman, 1995; Risse-Kappen, 1995; Gupta, 1997). The fact that economic and other transactions increasingly take place without regard to national boundaries has important implications for international politics (Rodrik et al., 1998). One conclusion drawn by globalization theorists is that the traditional state has become structurally inappropriate as a political unit, leading some to consider whether globalization has gone too far (Rodrik, 1997). In terms of international organization, Philip Cerny argues that the ‘residual state’ will no longer be the most important entity driving collective action in the international system and will not be able to provide global public goods, such as the regulation of the world market (Cerny, 1995; see also McGrew and Lewis, 1992; Ruggie, 1993b; Strange, 1996). The result may be increased reliance on private sources of governance that are more flexible and appropriate, such as interfirm alliances (Dunning, 1997) and international non-governmental organizations. Constructivism A major limitation of rational regime theory is that it takes both states as unitary actors and their interests as unproblematic. Some ‘bottom-up’ efforts rectify this situation by incorporating a richer rationalist view of the domestic constraints that states face, notably the ‘two-level games’ of Putnam (1988) and Milner (1997). Nevertheless, constructivism and other knowledge-based theories argue that the identities and interests of the actors, and how these are determined by the nature of the international community and its institutions, need to be explained rather than assumed (Wendt, 1994; Biersteker and Weber, 1996; Katzenstein, 1996). Some of these approaches can be readily accommodated by rational regime theory insofar as they provide a complementary analysis of why states have particular goals and beliefs (Haas, 1993; Goldstein and Keohane, 1993), or of how particular outcomes become focal points (Garrett and Weingast, 1993). Other approaches are more sharply contradictory to rational approaches. In part, this is because many constructivists reject the typically positivistic premises of rational regime theory, but fundamentally it is because they reject its individualism. They want to explain international arrangements from a ‘top-down’ perspective that examines the broader normative structures that constitute international ordering principles (Kratochwil, 1989; Wendt and
9800
International Organization
711
Duvall, 1989; Finnemore 1996a; Arend, 1998). The broadness of regime theory will allow it to incorporate some of these ideas; the rationalist stream of the theory will rework some of them in terms of its own conceptions of beliefs and information, though surely not to the full satisfaction of constructivist critics. While no agreed synthesis will emerge, the tension between the two approaches is likely to be mutually improving (Hasenclever, Mayer and Rittberger, 1997).
D. Conclusion Theorists and practitioners have employed a number of differing conceptions of ‘international organization’. These conceptions can usefully be thought of as falling into three categories: IO as formal organization, IO as ordering principle in the international system, and IO as regime. The last of these categories has received the most attention recently and has involved a high degree of fruitful theorizing about IO and international cooperation more generally. Political scientists who study IO have begun in recent years to return to the study of formal organizations, though this time they have done so with explicitly theoretical intentions (Snidal, 1997). At the same time, international legal scholars have sought to meet IR theorists halfway. The result is a self-conscious effort from both sides to integrate the two fields (Abbott, 1989; Burley, 1993; Keohane, 1997). In his treatment of the negotiations on dispute resolution in the Uruguay Round of GATT, for example, Abbott (1992, p. 112) recognizes that ‘meaningful analysis of matters like these requires a theoretical framework’. Burley (1993, p. 222; Slaughter, Tulumello and Wood, 1998) offers an historical account of the interaction of the law and IR literatures and suggests some ‘components of an institutionalist interdisciplinary dialogue’. This ‘dual agenda’ includes the study of organizational design, compliance, and international ethics. The overlap between this agenda and much of the NEO agenda is obvious, and this suggests that the future of IO scholarship will be more interdisciplinary than ever before. Indeed, common concerns and methodology among political scientists, legal scholars and economists increasingly characterize the IO literature. More than ever before, international legal scholars are using modes of analysis drawn from political science and economics to understand international organizations and law (Bhandari and Sykes, 1997; Mock, 1992; Shell, 1995; Aceves, 1996; Chong, 1995; Colombatto and Macey, 1996; Setear 1996). This interdisciplinary movement is clearly evident in substantive work on compliance with international rules and on dispute settlement. Scholars from various traditions have come together to understand why nations comply with international law and institutional rules (Mitchell, 1994a; Keohane, 1992; Downs, Rocke and Barsoom, 1996; Cameron, Werksman and Roderick, 1996;
712
International Organization
9800
Chayes and Chayes, 1995; Franck, 1990, 1995; Koh, 1997), as well as the development of supranational adjudication in international organizations (Hefler and Slaughter, 1997; Horlich and DeBusk, 1993; Hudec, 1990; Jackson, 1994; Kovenoch and Thursby, 1992; Pescatore, 1993; Yarbrough and Yarbrough, 1997). Through this intellectual interaction, the study of international organization, like the practice of international governance itself, is becoming more energized and, one hopes, more sophisticated.
Acknowledgements We thank two anonymous reviewers for valuable comments.
Bibliography on International Organization (9800) Abbott, Kenneth W. (1985), ‘The Trading Nation’s Dilemma: The Functions of the Law of International Trade’, 26 Harvard International Law Journal, 501-532. Abbott, Kenneth W. (1989), ‘Modern International Relations Theory: A Prospectus for International Lawyers’, 14(2) Yale Journal of International Law, 335-411. Abbott, Kenneth W. (1992), ‘The Uruguay Round and Dispute Resolution: Building a Private-Interests System of Justice’, 1 Columbia Business Law Review, 111-149. Abbott, Kenneth W. (1993), ‘Trust but Verify’: The Production of Information in Arms Control Treaties and Other International Agreements’, 26 Cornell International Law Journal, 1-58. Abbott, Kenneth W. and Snidal, Duncan (1998), ‘Why States Act Through Formal International Organizations’, 41(1) Journal of Conflict Resolution, 3-32. Aceves, William J. (1996), ‘The Economic Analysis of International Law: Transaction Cost Economics and the Concept of State Practice’, 17 University of Pennsylvania Journal of International Economic Law, 995-1068. Aceves, William J. (1997), ‘Institutionalist Theory and International Legal Scholarship’, 12 American University Journal of International Law and Policy, 227-266. Aggarwal, Vinod (1983), ‘The Unraveling of the Multi-fiber Arrangement, 1981: An Examination of Regime Change’, 37 International Organization, 617-645. Aggarwal, Vinod (1985), Liberal Protectionism: The International Politics of Organized Textile Trade, Berkeley, University of California Press. Alighieri, Dante ([1314] 1957), On World Government (trans. by Herbert W. Schneider, 2nd rev. edn), New York, Liberal Arts. Amerasinghe, Chittharanjan (1996), Principles of International Law of International Organizations, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Archer, Clive (1983), International Organizations, Winchester, Allen and Unwin. Arend, Anthony Clark (1998), ‘Do Legal Rules Matter? International Law and International Politics’, 38 Virginia Journal of International Law, 107-153. Armstrong, Kenneth and Bulmer, Simon (1998), The Governance of the Single European Act, New York, Manchester University Press.
9800
International Organization
713
Axelrod, R. (1984), The Evolution of Cooperation, New York, Basic Books. Beitz, Charles R. (1979), Political Theory and International Politics, Princeton, Princeton University Press. Ben-Shahar, Omri and Rottem, G. (1996), ‘The Credibility of International Enforcement’, in Brown-Weiss, E. and Jacobson, H.K. (eds), Compliance with International Environmental Agreements, Transnational Press. Bentham, Jeremy ([1786] 1927), Plan for a Universal and Perpetual Peace, London, Grotius Society. Bernauer, Thomas (1995), ‘The Effect of International Environmental Institutions: How we Might Learn More’, 49 International Organization, 351-377. Bhandari, Jagdeep S. and Sykes, Alan O. (eds) (1997), Economic Dimensions in International Law: Comparative and Empirical Perspectives, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Biersteker, Thomas and Weber, Cynthia (eds) (1996), State Sovereignty as Social Construct, New York, Cambridge University Press. Black, Cyril .E. and Falk, Richard A. (eds) (1969), The Future of the International Legal Order, Vol. 1 Trends and Patterns, Princeton, Princeton University Press. Bull, Hedley (1977), The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics, New York, Columbia University Press. Burley, Anne-Marie (1993), ‘International Law and International Relations Theory: A Dual Agenda’, 87 American Journal of International Law, 205-239. Burley, Anne-Marie and Mattli, Walter (1993), ‘Europe Before the Court: A Political Theory of Legal Integration’, 47 International Organization, 41-76. Buxbaum, Hertig and Hirsch, Hopt (eds), European Economic and Business Law, Legal and Economic Analyses on Integration and Harmonization, Berlin, Springer, 401 p. Buzan, Barry (1993), ‘From International System to International Society: Structural Realism and Regime Theory Meet the English School’, 47 International Organization, 327-352. Cameron, James, Werksman, Jacob and Roderick, Peter (eds) (1996), Improving Compliance with International Environmental Law, London, Earthscan Publications. Carr, Edward H. (1939), The Twenty Years’ Crisis, 1919-1939, London and New Jersey, Zed Books. Castermans, G. et al. (eds) (1990), The Role of Non-Governmental Organization in the Promotion and Protection of Human Rights, Boston, Kluwer Law International. Cerny, Philip (1990), The Changing Architecture of Politics: Structure, Agency, and the Future of the State, London, Sage. Cerny, Philip (1995), ‘Globalization and the Changing Logic of Collective Action’, 49 International Organization, 595-625. Charnovitz, Steve (1996), ‘Participation of Nongovernmental Organizations in the World Trade Organization’, 17 University of Pennsylvania Journal of International Business Law, 331-358. Chayes, Abram and Chayes, Antonio Handler (1993), ‘On Compliance’, 47(2) International Organization, 175-206. Chayes, Abram and Chayes, Antonio Handler (1995), The New Sovereignty: Compliance with International Regulatory Agreements, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Chong, Howard F. (1995), ‘An Economic Analysis of Trade Measures to Protect the Global Environment’, 83 Georgetown Law Journal, 2131 ff. Claude, I.L. (1962), Power and International Relations, New York, Random House.
714
International Organization
9800
Claude, I.L. (1964), Swords into Plowshares, 3rd edn, London, University of London Press. Coase, Ronald H. (1960), ‘The Problem of Social Cost’, 3 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-44. Cohen, Benjamin (1982), ‘Balance-of-Payments Financing: Evolution of a Regime’, 36(2) International Organization, 457-478. Colombatto, Enrico and Macey, Jonathan R. (1996), ‘A Public Choice Model of International Economic Cooperation and the Decline of the Nation State’, 18 Cardozo Law Review, 925-956. Conybeare, John (1980), ‘International Organization. and the Theory of Property Rights’, 34 International Organization, 307-334. Cowhey, P. (1990), ‘The International Telecommunications Regime: The Political Roots of International Regimes for High Technology’, 44 International Organization, 169-199. Cox, Robert W. (1996), Approaches to World Order, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Cox, Robert W. and Jacobson, H.K. (1974), The Anatomy of Influence: Decision Making in International Organization, New Haven, CT, Yale University Press. Donnelly, Jack (1986), ‘International Human Rights: a Regime Analysis’, 40 International Organization, 599-642. Downs, George and Rocke, David (1995), Optimal Imperfection? Domestic Uncertainty and Institutions in International Relations, Princeton, Princeton University Press. Downs, George, Rocke, David and Barsoom, Peter (1996), ‘Is the Good News about Compliance Good News about Cooperation?’, 50 International Organization, 379-406. Dunning, John H. (1997), Alliance Capitalism and Global Business, New York, NY, Routledge. Dupuy, Rene Jean (ed.) (1988), A Handbook on International Organisations, Hingham, MA, Kluwer. Eggertsson, Thrainn (1989), Economic Behavior and Institutions, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Eichengreen, Barry and Frieden, Jeffry (1994), The Political Economy of European Monetary Unification, Boulder, CO, Westview Press. Falk, Richard A. (1969), ‘The Interplay of Westphalia and Charter Conceptions of International Legal Order’, in Black, Cyril E. and Falk, Richard A. (eds), The Future of the International Legal Order, Vol. 1 Trends and Patterns, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 32-72. Fearon, James (1998), ‘Bargaining, Enforcement, and International Cooperation’, 52 International Organization, 269-305. Feld, Werner J. and Jordan, Robert S. (1988), International Organizations: A Comparative Approach, 2nd edn, New York, Praeger. Finlayson, Jock and Zacher, Mark (1981), ‘The GATT and the Regulation of Trade Barriers: Regime Dynamics and Functions’, 35(4) International Organization, 561-602. Finnemore, Martha (1996a), National Interests in International Society, Ithaca (NY), Cornell University Press. Finnemore, Martha (1996b), ‘Norms, Culture, and World Politics: Insights from Sociology’s Institutionalism’, 50(2) International Organization, 325-348. Franck, Thomas M. (1990), The Power of Legitimacy among Nations, Oxford, Oxford University Press.
9800
International Organization
715
Franck, Thomas M. (1995), Fairness in International Law and Institutions, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Fratianni, Michele and Pattison, John (1982), ‘The Economics of International Organizations’, 35 Kyklos, 244-262. Furubotn, Eirik G. and Richter, Rudolf (eds) (1991), The New Institutional Economics, College Station, TX, Texas A & M University Press. Furubotn, Eirik G. and Richter, Rudolf (1997), Institutions and Economic Theory: The Contribution of the New Institutional Economics, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press. Gaddis, John L. (1987), The Long Peace: Inquiries into the History of the Cold War, New York, NY, Oxford University Press. Garrett, Geoffrey (1992), ‘International Cooperation and Institutional Choice: The European Community’s Internal Market’, 46(2) International Organization, 533-560. Garrett, Geoffrey (1995), ‘The Politics of Legal Integration in the European Union’, 46 International Organization, 533-560. Garrett, Geoffrey and Weingast, B. (1993), ‘Ideas, Interests, and Institutions: Constructing the European Community’s Internal Market’, in Goldstein, J. and Keohane, R. (eds), Ideas and Foreign Policy: Beliefs, Institutions, and Political Change, Ithaca, NY, Cornell University Press, 173-206. Gilpin, Robert (1981), War and Change in International Politics, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Glaser, Charles (1994/95), ‘Realists as Optimists: Cooperation as Self-Help’, 19 International Security, 50-90. Goldstein, Judith and Keohane, Robert O. (1993), Ideas and Foreign Policy: Beliefs, Institutions, and Political Change, Ithaca, NY, Cornell University Press. Gowa, Joanne (1994), Allies, Adversaries, and International Trade, Princeton, Princeton University Press. Graber, Lloyd (1999), Ruling the World: Power, Politics and the Rise of Supranational Institutions, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press, forthcoming. Grieco, Joseph (1988), ‘Anarchy and the Limits of Cooperation: A Realist Critique of the Newest Liberal Institutionalism’, 42 International Organization, 485-507. Groom, A.J.R. and Taylor, Paul G. (1975), Functionalism: Theory and Practice in International Relations, London, University of London Press. Grotius, Hugo ([1625] 1925), De Jure Belli ac Pacis, trans. Francis W. Kelsey, Oxford, Clarendon. Gupta, S. (ed.) (1997), The Political Economy of Globalization, Boston, Kluwer. Haas, Ernst B. (1958), The Uniting of Europe: Political, Social and Economic Forces, 1950-1957, Stanford, Stanford University Press. Haas, Ernst B. (1961), ‘International Integration: The European and the Universal Process’, 15 International Organization, 366-397. Haas, Ernst B. (1964), Beyond the Nation-State: Functionalism and International Organization, Stanford, Stanford University Press. Haas, Ernst B. (1975), The Obsolescence of Regional Integration Theory, Berkeley, University of California Press. Haas, Peter (ed.) (1993), Knowledge, Power and International Policy Coordination, Columbia, SC, University of South Carolina Press.
716
International Organization
9800
Haas, Peter, Keohane, Robert O. and Levy, Marc A. (1993), Institutions for the Earth: Sources of Effective International Environmental Protection, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Hasenclever, Andreas, Mayer, Peter and Rittberger, Volker (1997),Theories of International Regimes, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Hefler, Laurence and Slaughter, Anne Marie (1997), ‘Toward a Theory of Effective Supranational Adjudication’, 107 Yale Law Journal, 273-391. Hinsley, Francis H. (1963), Power and the Pursuit of Peace: Theory and Practice in the History of Relations between States, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Horlick, Gary and DeBusk, Amanda (1993), ‘Dispute Resolution under NAFTA: Building on the U.S.-Canada FTA, GATT and ICSID’, 27, Journal of World Trade, 21-41. Hudec, Robert E. (1990), ‘Dispute Settlement’, in Schott, Jeffrey (ed.), Completing the Uruguay Round, Institute for International Economics, 180-204. Hurrell, Andrew (1993), ‘International Society and the Study of Regimes: A Reflective Approach’, in Rittberger, Volker (ed.), Regime Theory and International Relations, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 49-72. Jackson, John (1994), ‘The World Trade Organization, Dispute Settlement, and Codes of Conduct’, in Collins, Susan and Bosworth, Barry (eds), The New GATT, Washington, Brookings Institution. Jacobson, H.K. (1984), Networks of Interdependence: International Organizations and the Global Political System, 2n edn, New York, Alfred A. Knopf. Jervis, Robert (1982), ‘Security Regimes’, 36(2) International Organization, 357-378. Kahler, Miles (1996), International Institutions and the Political Economy of Integration, Washington, Brookings Institution. Kant, Immanuel ([1784] 1914), Eternal Peace and Other International Essays (trans. by William Hastie), Boston, World Peace Foundation. Kaplan, Morton (1957), System and Process in International Politics, New York, Wiley. Karnes, Margaret and Mingst, Karen (1990), The United States and Multilateral Institutions, Boston, Unwin Hyman. Katzenstein, Peter (1996), The Culture of National Security, New York, Columbia University Press. Kenen, Peter (1995), Economic and Monetary Union in Europe: Moving beyond Maastricht, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Keohane, Robert O. (1982), ‘The Demand for International Regimes’, 36(2) International Organization, 325-356. Keohane, Robert O. (1984), After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Economy, Princeton, Princeton University Press. Keohane, Robert O. (1986), ‘Reciprocity in International Relations’, 40 International Organization, 1-27. Keohane, Robert O. (1992), ‘Compliance with International Commitments: Politics within a Framework of Law’, 86 American Society of International Law Proceedings, 176-180. Keohane, Robert O. (1997), ‘International Relations and International Law: Two Optics’, 38 Harvard International Law Journal, 487-502. Keohane, Robert O. and Nye, Joseph (eds) (1972), Transnational Relations and World Politics, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Keohane, Robert O. and Nye, Joseph (1977), Power and Interdependence: World Politics in Transition, Boston, Little Brown.
9800
International Organization
717
Keohane, Robert O. and Ostrom, Elinor (1995), Local Commons and Global Interdependence: Heterogeneity and Cooperation in Two Domains, Thousand Oaks, California, Sage. Kirgis, Frederic L. Jr. (1993), International Organizations in Their Legal Setting, 2nd ed, St. Paul, West Publishing Company. Koh, Harold (1997), ‘Why Do Nations Obey Inernational Law?’, 106 Yale Law Journal, 2598-2659. Koremenos, Barbara, Lipson, Charles and Snidal, Duncan (1998), Rational International Institutions, Unpublished Manuscript. Koskenniemi, Martti (1996), ‘The Place of Law in Collective Security’, 17 Michigan Journal of International Law, 455-490. Kovenoch, Dan and Thursby, Marie (1992), ‘GATT, Dispute Settlement and Cooperation’, 4 Economics and Politics, 151-170. Krasner, Stephen (1983), International Regimes, Ithaca, NY, Cornell University Press. Krasner, Stephen (1985), Structural Conflict: The Third World Against Global Liberalism, Berkeley, University of California Press. Kratochwil, Friedrich (1989), Rules, Norms, and Decisions: On the Conditions of Practical and Legal Reasoning in International Relations and Domestic Affaris, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Kratochwil, Friedrich and Ruggie, John G. (1986), ‘International Organization: a State of the Art on an Art of the State’, 40(4) International Organization, 753-776. Krugman, Paul R. (1995), ‘Growing World Trade: Causes and Consequences’, Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 327-377. Kupchan, Charles (1997), ‘Regionalizing Europe’s Security: The Case for a New Mitteleuropa’, in Mansfield, Edward and Milner, Helen (eds), 209-239. Kupchan, Charles and Kupchan, Clifford (1991), ‘Concerts, Collective Security, and the Future of Europe’, 16(1) International Security, 151-198. Lake, David (1996), ‘Anarchy, Hierarchy, and the Variety of International Relations’, 50(1) International Organization, 1-34. Lenin, Vladimir I. ([1917] 1939), Imperialism: The Highest Stage of Capitalism, New York, International Publisher. Lindberg, Leon N. and Scheingold, Stuart (1971), Regional Integration: Theory and Research, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Lipson, Charles (1982), ‘The Transformation of Trade: the Sources and Effects of Regime Change’, 36 International Organization, 417-455. Lipson, Charles (1985), Standing Guard: Protecting Foreign Capital in the Nineteenth and Twentieth Centuries, Berkeley, University of California Press. Lipson, Charles (1991), ‘Why Are Some International Agreements Informal?’, 45 International Organization, 495-538. Mansfield, Edward and Milner, Helen (eds) (1997), The Political Economy of Regionalism, New York, Columbia University Press. March, James G. and Olsen, Johan (1989), Rediscovering Institutions: The Organizational Basis of Politics, New York, NY, Free Press. McCalla, Robert B. (1996), ‘NATO’s Persistence after the Cold War’, 50 International Organization, 445-475. McGrew, Anthony and Lewis, Paul (1992), Global Politics: Globalization and the Nation-State, Cambridge, MA, Blackwell.
718
International Organization
9800
Mearsheimer, John ([1994/95), ‘The False Promise of International Institutions’, 19 International Security, 5-49. Milner, Helen (1991), ‘The Assumption of Anarchy in International Relations Theory’, 17 Review of International Studies, 67-85. Milner, Helen (1997), Interests, Institutions and Information, Princeton, Princeton University Press. Mitchell, Ronald B. (1993), ‘Compliance Theory: A Synthesis’, 2 Review of European Community and International Environmental Law, 327-334. Mitchell, Ronald B. (1994a), Intentional Oil Pollution at Sea: Environmental Policy and Treaty Compliance, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Mitchell, Ronald B. (1994b), ‘Regime Design Matters: Intentional Oil Pollution and Treaty Compliance’, 48 International Organization, 425-458. Mitrany, David ([1943] 1966), A Working Peace System: An Argument for the Functional Development of International Organization, Chicago, Quadrangle Press. Mock, William B.T. (1992), ‘Game Theory, Signalling, and International Legal Relations’, 26 George Washington Journal of International Law and Economics, 33-60. Moe, Terry M. (1984), ‘The New Economics of Organization’, 28 American Journal of Political Science, 739-777. Moravcsik, Andrew (1998), The Choice for Europe: Social Purpose and State Power from Messina to Maastricht, Ithace, NY, Cornell University Press. Morgenthau, Hans (1948), Politics Among Nations, New York, Alfred A. Knopf. Morrow, James (1994), ‘Modeling the Forms of International Cooperation: Distribution versus Information’, 48 International Organization, 387-424. Ness, Gayl D. and Brechin, Steven R. (1988), ‘Bridging the Gap: International Organizations as Organizations’, 42(2) International Organization, 245-273. Nugent, Neill (1994), The Government and Politics of the European Union, Durham, NC, Duke University Press. Nye, Joseph (ed.) (1968), International Regionalism, Boston, Little Brown. Nye, Joseph (1971), Peace in Parts: Integration and Conflict in Regional Organization, Boston, Little Brown. Oye, Kenneth A. (ed.) (1986), Cooperation under Anarchy, Princeton, Princeton University Press. Pescatore, Pierre (1993), ‘The GATT Dispute Settlement Mechanism’, 27 Journal of World Trade, 5-20. Peterson, M.J. (1986), The General Assembly in World Politics, Boston, Unwin Hyman. Powell, Robert (1991), ‘Absolute and Relative Gains in International Relations Theory’, 85 American Political Science Review, 1303-1320. Powell, Walter W. and DiMaggio, Paul J. (1991), The New Institutionalism in Organizational Analysis, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Putman, Robert (1988), ‘Diplomacy and Domestic Politics: The Logic of Two-Level Games’, 42 International Organization, 427-460. Risse-Kappen, Thomas (1995), Bringing Transnational Relations Back In: Non-State Actors, Domestic Structures and International Institutions, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Roberts, Adam (1993), ‘The United Nations and International Security’, 35(2) Survival, 3-30.
9800
International Organization
719
Rochester, J. Martin (1986), ‘The Rise and Fall of International Organization as a Field of Study’, 40(4) International Organization, 777-813. Rodrik, Dani (1997), Has Globalization Gone Too Far?, Washington, DC, Institute for International Economics. Rodrik, Dani, Obstfeld, Maurice, Feenstra, Robert and Williamson, Jeffrey (1998), ‘Symposium on Globalization in Perspective’, 12(4) Journal of Economic Perspectives, 3-72. Rosenau, James N. (1992), ‘Governance, Order, and Change in World Politics’, in Czempiel, Ernst-Otto and Rosenau, James (eds), Global Changes and Theoretical Challenges, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books, 1-29. Rosenau, James N. and Czempiel, Ernst-Otto (1992), Governance Without Government: Order and Change in World Politics, Cambridge Ontario, Collier-MacMillan. Ruggie, John G. (1972), ‘Collective Goods and Future International Collaboration’, 66 American Political Science Review, 874-893. Ruggie, John G. (1975), ‘International Responses to Technology: Concepts and Trends’, 29 International Organization, 557-583. Ruggie, John G. (1993a), Multilateralism Matters: The Theory and Praxis of an Institutional Form, Columbia University Press. Ruggie, John G. (1993b), ‘Territoriality and Beyond: Problematizing Modernity in International Relations’, 47 International Organization, 139-174. Russett, Bruce M. and Sullivan, John D. (1971), ‘Collective Goods and International Organizations’, 25 International Organization, 845-865. Saint-Simon, Henri de ([1825] 1952), ‘On Social Organization (trans. F.M.H. Markham)’, in Markham, F.M.H. (ed.), Henri Comte de Saint-Simon (1760-1825): Selected Writings, Oxford, Basil Blackwell. Sand, Peter H. (1990), Lessons Learned in Global Environmental Governance, Washington, World Resources Institute. Sandholtz, Wayne (1993), ‘Institutions and Collective Action: the New Telecommunications in Western Europe’, 45 World Politics, 242-270. Schachter, Oscar and Joyner, Christopher (eds) (1995), United Nations Legal Order, 2 vols., Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Schermers, Henry and Blokker, Niels (1995), International Institutional Law: Unity within Diversity, 3rd edn, The Hague, Mouton. Schroeder, Paul W. (1994), The Transformation of European Politics, 1763-1848, Oxford, Clarendon. Setear, John K. (1996), ‘An Iterative Perspective on Treaties: A Synthesis of International Relations Theory and International Law’, 37 Harvard International Law Journal, 139-229. Shanks, Cheryl, Jacobson, H.K. and Kaplan, Jeffrey H. (1996), ‘Inertia and Change in the Constellation of International Governmental Organizations, 1981-1992', 50(4) International Organization, 593-627. Shell, Richard G. (1995), ‘Trade Legalism and International Relations Theory: An Analysis of the World Trade Organization’, 44 Duke Law Journal, 829-927. Shermers, Henry and Blokker, Niels (1995), International Institutional Law: Unity within Diversity, 3rd edn, The Hague, Nijhoff. Skjelsbaek, Kjell (1971), ‘The Growth of International Nongovernmental Organizations in the Twentieth Century’, 25 International Organization, 420-442.
720
International Organization
9800
Slaughter, Anne-Marie, Tulumello, Andrew and Wood, Stepan (1998), ‘International Law and International Relations Theory: A New Generation of Interdisciplinary Scholarship’, 92(3) American Journal of International Law, 367-397. Smith, Edwin M. (1991), ‘Understanding Dynamic Obligations: Arms Control Agreements’, 64 Southern California Law Review, 1549-1606. Snidal, Duncan (1979), ‘Public Goods, Property Rights, and Political Organization’, 23(4) International Studies Quarterly, 532-566. Snidal, Duncan (1985), ‘Coordination versus Prisoners’ Dilemma: Implications for International Cooperation and Regimes’, 79 American Political Science Review, 923-943. Snidal, Duncan (1991), ‘Relative Gains and the Pattern of International Cooperation’, 85 American Political Science Review, 701-726. Snidal, Duncan (1997), ‘International Political Economy Approaches to International Institutions’, in Bhandari, Jagdeep S. and Sykes, Alan O. (eds), Economic Dimensions in International Law: Comparative and Empirical Perspectives, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 477-512. Spruyt, Hendrik (1994), ‘Institutional Selection in International Relations: State Anarchy as Order’, 48 International Organization, 527-557. Staiger, Robert (1995), ‘International Rules and Institutions for Trade Policy’, in Jones, Ronald and Kenen, Peter (eds), Handbook of International Economics, Vol. 2, Amsterdam, North-Holland. Stein, Arthur (1982), ‘Coordination and Collaboration Regimes in an Anarchic World’, 36 International Organization, 299-324. Strange, Susan (1982), ‘Cave! Hic dragones: A Critique of Regime Analysis’, 36(2) International Organization, 479-498. Strange, Susan (1996), The Retreat of the State, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Streit, Manfred E. and Voigt, Stefan (1996), ‘Toward Ever Closer Union - Or Ever Larger? Or Both? Entry to the European Union from the Perspective of Constitutional Economics’, 16 International Review of Law and Economics, 385-388. Sykes, Alan O. (1990), ‘Mandatory Retaliation for Breach of Trade Agreements: Some Thoughts on the Strategic Design of Section 301', 8 Boston University International Law Journal, 301-331. Taylor, Michael (1976), Anarchy and Cooperation, London, Wiley. Taylor, Paul G. (1993), International Organization in the Modern World: The Regional and Global Process, New York, Pinter Publishers. Trachtman, J.P. (1996), The Theory of the Firm and the Theory of International Economic Organization: Toward Comparative Institutional Analysis, Unpublished Manuscript. Trachtman, J.P. (1997), ‘Externalities and Extraterritoriality: The Law and Economics of Prescriptive Jurisdiction’, in Bhandari, Jagdeep and Sykes, Alan (eds), 642-683. Union of International Associations (UIA) (Multiple dates), Yearbook of International Organizations 1997/1998, Munich, K.G. Saur. Virally, Michel (1972), L’Organisation Mondiale (Global Organization), Paris, Armand Collin. Wallace, Michael D. and Singer, David J. (1970), ‘Intergovernmental Organization in the International System: A Quantitative Assessment’, 24 International Organization, 239-287.
9800
International Organization
721
Wallerstein, Immanuel (1979), The Capitalist World Economy, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Waltz, Kenneth N. (1959), Man, State and War, New York, Columbia University Press. Waltz, Kenneth N. (1979), Theory of International Politics, Reading, MA, Addison-Wesley. Weiss, Thomas G. and Gordenker, Leon (1996), NGOs, the UN, and Global Governance, Boulder, CO, Lynne Rienner. Wendt, Alexander (1994), ‘Collective Identity Formation and the International State’, 88 American Political Science Review, 391-425. Wendt, Alexander (1998), Social Theory of International Politics, Unpublished Manuscript. Wendt, Alexander and Duvall, Robert (1989), ‘Institutions and International Order’, in Czempiel, Ernst-Otto and Rosenau, James (eds), Global Changes and Theoretical Challenges, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books, 51-73. Wight, Martin (1973), ‘The Balance of Power and International Order’, in Alan, James (ed.), The Bases of International Order, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 85-115. Wight, Martin (1977), Systems of States, Leicester, Leicester University Press. Willets, Peter (1982), Pressure Groups in the Global System: The Trasnsnational Relations of Issue-Oriented Non-Governmental Organizations, New York, St. Martin’s Press. Williamson, Oliver E. (1975), Markets and Hierarchies: Analysis and Antitrust Implications, New York, NY, Free Press. Williamson, Oliver E. (1985), The Economic Institutions of Capitalism, New York, NY, Free Press. Wittman, Donald A. (1991), ‘Nations and States: Mergers and Acquisitions; Dissolutions and Divorce’, 81 American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings, 126-129. Woolf, Leonard (1916), International Government, 2nd edn, London, Allen and Unwin. Yalem, Ronald J. (1966), ‘The Study of International Organization, 1920-65: A Survey of the Literature’, 10 Background, 1-56. Yarbrough, Beth V. and Yarbrough, Robert M. (1987), ‘Institutions for the Governance of Opportunism in International Trade’, 3 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 129-133. Yarbrough, Beth V. and Yarbrough, Robert M. (1990), ‘International Institutions and the New Economics of Organization’, 44(2) International Organization, 235-259. Yarbrough, Beth V. and Yarbrough, Robert M. (1992),Cooperation and Governance in International Trade, Princeton, Princeton University Press. Yarbrough, Beth V. and Yarbrough, Robert M. (1997), ‘Dispute Settlement in International Trade: Regionalism and Procedural Coordination’, in Mansfield, Edward and Milner, Helen (eds), 134-163. Young, Oran R. (1979), Compliance and Public Authority: A Theory with International Implications, Baltimore, MD, John Hopkins University Press. Young, Oran R. (1982), ‘Regime Dynamics: the Rise and Fall of International Regimes’, 36 International Organization, 277-297. Young, Oran R. (1989), International Cooperation: Building Regimes for Natural Resources and the Environment, Ithaca, NY, Cornell University Press. Young, Oran R. (1992), ‘The Effectiveness of International Institutions: Hard Cases and Critical Variables’, in Czempiel, Ernst-Otto and Rosenau, James (eds), Global Changes and Theoretical Challenges, Lexington, MA, Lexington Books. Young, Oran R. (1994), International Governance: Protecting the Environment in a Stateless Society, Ithaca, NY, Cornell University Press.
722
International Organization
9800
Young, Oran R. and Osherenko, Gail (1993), Polar Politics: Creating International Environmental Regimes, Ithaca, NY, Cornell University Press. Zacher, Mark with Sutton, Brent (1996), Governing Global Networks: International Regimes for Transportation and Communications, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.